LIBRARY OF CONGRESS. UNITED STATES OF AMEEICA. iHri Digitized by the Internet Archive in 2011 with funding from The Library of Congress http://www.archive.org/details/freedomofmindinwOOhaza WORKS OF Eotolanti (Siisan |)a^arU. Edited by his Granddaugliter Caroline Hazard. In four volumes, crown 8vo, each, $2.00 ; the set, JS.oo. ESSAY ON LANGUAGE AND OTHER PAPERS. New Edition. With Portrait. FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING; or, Every Being that Wills a Creative First Cause. New Edition. TWO LETTERS ON CAUSATION AND FREE- DOM OF MIND IN WILLING, addressed to John Stuart Mill, etc. New Edition. ECONOMICS AND POLITICS. HOUGHTON, MIFFLIN AND COMPANY, Boston and New York. FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING OR X EVERY BEING THAT WILLS A CREATIVE FIRST CAUSE ROWLAND GIBSON HAZARD, ll. d. -s^l EDITED BY HIS GRANDDAUGHTER CAROLINE HAZARD VjrA5H!N6T5^ BOSTON AND NEW YORK HOUGHTON, MIFFLIN AND COMPANY ^. Copyright, 1864, 1889, and 1892, by D. APPLETON & CO., CAROLIISnE HAZARD, AND ROWLAND HAZARD. All rights reserved. The Riverside Press, Cambridge, Mass., U S. A. Printed by H. 0. Houghton & Company. EDITOR'S PREFACE. This book owes its origin, as my grandfather was always glad to say, to his friendship and conversa- tion with Dr. Chanuing. Some time previous to 1840 Dr. Channing directed his attention to Edwards and the problems of Free Will and Necessity, asking him to prepare an argument which should logically refute that of Edwards. This, encouraged by Dr. Chan- ning, he consented to undertake. " My progress in it was slow," he writes, " perhaps the slower because I soon concluded that all the advo- cates of freedom had virtually given up the philosoph- ical argument and fallen back, either on revelation or their own consciousness — which weighed nothing with those who questioned the supreme authority of the Bible, or asserted their consciousness was not that they acted freely but the reverse. Hence I resolved not to read, lest I should get into these ruts of thought, which evidently did not lead to the point I wished to reach, but would first try to work out the problem in my own way. From Edwards I learned what the questions were, and began to think about them in my usual desultory way as I was travelling about, or in such leisure moments as I could spare from my I'egu- IV EDITOR'S PREFACE. lar business, and became more and more interested in the pursuit." My grandfather spent ten consecutive winters at the South, the last of which was 1842-3. After several years of thought, in 1843 he considered him- self prepared on all the principal points of the argu- ment. His notes were full and complete, and needed only arranging and rewriting, when by an unfortunate accident he lost them all. A steamer upon which he travelled from Mobile to New Orleans ran aground, and the passengers were transferred, leaving their baggage. My grandfather never recovered his trunk which contained his notes. He learned that it had been stolen, and in New Orleans discovered a bit of clothing embroidered with his initials by his mother. He never found a trace of the papers, and finally con- cluded they had been burned. This was a great blow to him. Dr. Channing was no longer living to en- courage him, his business was pressing, and it was not until 1857 that he returned to the work which ended in the publication of this volume. His mind pro- gressed during the years he was not actively engaged upon these problems, and when the book was finally finished he considered it had gained much by the delay. He had also the assistance of his eldest son in reading the proof, and perfecting the form ; an assistance impossible at the earlier period. The book which began in the fi'iendship of Dr. Channing, ended by winning that of John Stuart Mill. " We often think and talk of you," writes EDITOR'S PREFACE. V Mr. Mill from Avignon, in November, 1865, "both at Blackheath and here where we first saw you." Of the book Mr. Mill writes : " It is very clearly thought and expressed, and draws some metaphysical distinc- tions which though quite correct are often disre- garded ; for instance that fundamental one between volition and choice." Later he writes : "I do not mean any compliment in saying that I wish you had no-thing to do but to philosophize, for though I often do not agree with you, I see in everything that you write a well-marked natural capacity for philosophy." The volume was published in New York by D. Ap pleton & Co. in 1864, and passed to a second edition in 1866. The changes made in the present edition were all indicated by my grandfather in the annotated copy which he kept beside him. They will be found chiefly in the latter part of the first book, and are all in the direction of clearness and simplicity. Oakwoods in Peace Dale, R. I., November, 1888. AUTHOR'S PREFACE. The public mind is at present so engrossed with other pursuits, and so satisfied with its progress in them, that there is little room to hope that it will bestow much attention upon the subject of this volume. Physical Science and Material Progress are now the absorbing objects of effort. To these all utility is ascribed, to the exclusion of the Metaphysical, which lies under the imputation of being both uninteresting and useless. Why this opprobrium and whence the general neglect, the absolute indisposition, to inquire into the struc- ture and conditions of our spiritual being, which, as the source of all our power and all our enjoyments, one might naturally suppose would most interest us, and at the same time, by its mystery, most excite our curiosity ? That the discoveries in Physics, so varied and so magnificent, have largely contributed to our material comforts, have feasted the intellect and even regaled the imagination, is undoubtedly one cause of this neglect of the science of mind. But there are other reasons, Vlll AUTHOR S PREFACE. among which. A^e may mention the real difficulties of the subject. These are of two distinct kinds ; first, those of ascertaining the truths ; and second, those of imparting them after they have been ascertained. The first of these are, in some respects, peculiar. We want to examine that which examines ; we want the mind to be employed in observing its own action, i. e., we want it to be doing one thing when it is of necessity doing another. A further difficulty, even in the investigation of the phenomena of mind, arises from the fact that the language applied to metaphysical science is very imperfect as an instrument of thought. The science of mind has very little language of its own, and in adopting for it what has been formed and fitted to another department of knowledge, much con- fusion and error result. The ambiguity, or various mean- ings of the terms, so often mislead the investigator himself, that he is not unfrequently obliged to rehnquish the instrumen- tal aid of words, and directly examine his original ideas and conceptions of the subjects of inquiry. The difficulty of imparting the results in a language so imperfect is obvious, and is increased when it has been discarded in reaching them. But, with aU this inappreciation of its benefits and all its recognized difficvdties, Metaphysics has its peculiar attractions. The questions of every child, the yearnings of the advdt, though in expression only occasionally gleam- ing through the settled gloom of discouragement and de- spondency, still manifest the fervid curiosity in regard to that mysterious invisible^ which knows, thinks, feels and AUTHORS PEEFACE. IX acts ; and even in those too busy, too shiggisli, or too hopeless to put forth an effort to gratify it. The reason of its being neglected lies not so much in its want of attraction, as in the prevailing idea of its in- utility ; and this idea, though now magnified by temporary causes, has a foundation in the fact, that no investigation of the nature of our faculties and powers, mental or physi- tjal, is essential to that use of them which our early exist- ence demands. For this we have the requisite knowledge by intuition. "We can use our powers without studying either Anatomy or Metaphysics. It is not, then, surpris- ing that we should early direct our attention to the study of those extrinsic substances and phenomena of which more knowledge is obviously and immediately useful. The want of satisfactory results has also had its influence ; and per- haps there is no question, the discussion of which has tended more to bring upon Metaphysics the reproach of being unfruitful, than that of the " Freedom of the Will." The importance of removing this grand obstruction to the progress of ethics and theology, is appreciated only by those who in their researches have encountered it. They alone have caught glimpses of the radiant fields of specu- lation which lie beyond ; and most men regard the specu- lations upon it, not only as having furnished no new truth, but as having obscured what was before known. Whatever opinion may be formed of the success or failure, of my effort to elucidate this subject, I trust it wiU be admitted, that the arguments I have presented, at least, tend to show that the investigation may open more elevated X AUTHOR S PREFACE. and more elevating views of our position and our powers ; and may reveal new modes of influencing our own intel- lectual and moral character, and thus have a more imme- diate, direct, and practical bearing on the progress of our race in virtue and happiness, than any inquiry in physical science. Peace Dale, R. I., 1864. CONTENTS. FXaG Introductory Essay. The Philosophical Writings op Row- land G. Hazard. By George P. Fisher, D. D., LL. D. xv BOOK I. FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. CHAPTER I. Of the Existence of Spirit 1 CHAPTER II. Of the Existence op Matter ...... 5 CHAPTER HI. Of Mind 9 CHAPTER IV. Liberty, or Freedom , , 19 CHAPTER V. Of Cause 21 CHAPTER VI. Of the Will 24 CHAPTER VII. Op Want .27 CHAPTER VIII. Of Matter as Cause .32 xii CONTENTS. CHAPTER IX. Of Spirit as Cause ,. , . .42 CHAPTER X. Freedom of Intelligence 51 CHAPTER XI. Instinct and Habit 98 CHAPTER XII. Illustration from Chess 126 CHAPTER XIII. Of Want and Effort in Various Orders of Intelligence . 136 CHAPTER XIV. Of Effort for Internal Change 145 CHAPTER XV. Conclusion 161 BOOK II. review op edwards on the will. Introduction 173 CHAPTER I. Edwards's Definition of Will 177 CHAPTER II. Liberty as defined by Edwards 201 CHAPTER III. Natural and Moral Necessity 204 CHAPTER IV. Self-Determination . . . . . . . . 233 CONTENTS. xiii CHAPTER V. No Event without a Cause 240 CHAPTER VI. Of the Will's determining in Things Indifferent . 259 CHAPTER VII. Relation of Indifference to Freedom in Willing . . 284 CHAPTER VIII. CONTINGENCE 313 CHAPTER IX. Connection of the Will with the Understanding . 323 CHAPTER X. Motive 327 CHAPTER XI. Cause and Ef»fect . . . . . . . . . 364 CHAPTER XII. God's Foreknowledge 384 CHAPTER XIII. Conclusion 401 INTRODUCTORY ESSAY. THE PHILOSOPHICAL WRITINGS OF ROWLAND G. HAZARD. BY PROFESSOR GEORGE P. FISHER, D. D., LL. D. Mr. Gladstone, in his article on Macaulay, says of Lord Bacon that "in his speculations he touched physics with one hand and the unseen world with the other." I have been struck with this exjDression as not inapplicable to the author whose writings form the subject of the present paper. It is not always the case, to be sure, that an interest in both realms, the physical and the metaphysical, is accompanied by a corresponding aptitude for the study of both. Re- specting Bacon himself, it is well known that his practical skill in the field of natural science was not commensurate with his interest in the subject and with his lively sense of its importance to the wellbeing of mankind. No one will doubt, at the present epoch, that it is, in a signal degree, of advantage to an in- quirer in the department of mental philosophy to be possessed of an inborn taste and capacity for mathe- matical and physical researches, and of such knowl- edge as qualifies him to reason correctly on this class of topics. Such a diversified taste and ability charac- XVI INTRODUCTORY ESSAY. terized the author a portion o£ whose works form the subject of the present essay. Nor does this statement do justice to the versatility of his talents. His life was sjDent in manufacturing and mercantile pursuits, in reference to which he manifested an extraordinary judgment, as was evinced by his success. He carried into his reflections upon the problems of political economy his mingled genius for abstract reasoning and for practical affairs. In the financial exigencies that arose during the civil war in the United States, his published observations were shown to be sound and valuable, and, on more than one occasion, exerted a decided and salutary influence upon the proceedings of Secretaries of the Treasury. It deserves to be mentioned that Mr. Hazard arrived at his conclusions on some of the most important economical questions without having read Adam Smith, and, in later years, found no cause to abandon the opinions to which his thoughts and observations had led him. He was too busy a man to read many books. But, fortunately, he did not lack the courage to think for himself, and to confide in the results of his own meditations. Chan- ning, referring to Mr. Hazard's " Essay on Language," speaks of him as " a man of vigorous intellect, who had enjoyed few advantages of early education, and whose mind was almost engrossed by the details of an extensive business," but " who composed a book, of much original thought, in steamboats and on horse- back, while visiting distant customers." This refer- ence to Mr. Hazard's early education might suggest an error in regard to his youthful training. This was not wanting in thoroughness as regards mathematics and the most important English branches. In the INTRODUCTORY ESSAY. XVll schools which he attended, classical studies were not pursued ; but the intellectual discipline imparted was, of its kind, of a high order. Our author is not to be counted among- " self-taught " men in the technical sense in which that epithet has come to be used. He never went through the curriculum of a college ; but the fact especially worthy to be noted is that he was one of those men who, partly from circumstances, but quite as much from their native intellectual character, would not be aided, but would rather be embarrassed, by the reading of many books. That his mind was one of marked originality was obvious to all who were brought in contact with him. He took hold of the questions that interested him with a strong grasp, and subjected them to a searching analysis. A busy Khode Island manufacturer, his remarks on controverted themes of philosophy elicited praise for the ability which they displayed, from John Stuart Mill ; and this, notwithstanding that Mill's cardinal tenets were opposed by him. The peculiarity of Mr. Hazard's position accounts for the circumstance that, while his talents and his writings have been highly appreciated among us by a considerable number of persons who are fully competent to form a right estimate of their merit, they have not become very generally known. He was allied with no school of theological opinion. He wrote in behalf of no tenets which are adopted as the creed of a party. He engaged in no public con- troversy which had drawn to itself general attention. These facts, although they were not without influence for good as regards the tone of his writings, operated, to a certain extent, to prevent a widespread attention to them, at the time of their publication. Of the XVlll INTRODUCTORY ESSAY. strictly metaphysical works, the " Freedom of the Mind in Willing" (embracing a Review of Edwards) was published in 1864. In 1869, there appeared the vol- ume entitled " Two Letters on Causation and Freedom in Willing : with an Appendix on the Existence of Mat- ter and our Notions on Infinite Space." These letters were addressed to John Stuart Mill, and the first of them, written in 1866, had the advantage of being dis- cussed by Mr. Hazard with Mr. Mill in personal inter- views. In 1883, he put forth a summaiy view of his leading ideas respecting the will and cognate topics, in the form of two discourses, bearing the title " Man a Creative First Cause." They were delivered in 1882 at the Concord School of Philosophy. In the explanation which I propose to present of Mr. Hazard's system in its main features, it will be convenient to set forth its relation to the doctrines of three writers, by whom, more than by others, he was stimulated to write, and some of whose most important doctrines he undertakes to confute. These are the fa- mous theologian of New England, Jonathan Edwards, whose book on the will was always regarded as a mas- terpiece of logical acumen, which it was more easy to protest against than to answer ; John Stuart Mill, who exhibited, in his Logic and elsewhere, the principles of the " assoeiational philosophy," with philosophical necessity as one of its corollaries ; and Sir William Hamilton, the representative of the Scottish philosophy as modified by the influence of Kant. Mr. Hazai-d wrote acutely in reply to Herbert Spencer, on the question of the reality of things external, the world of matter, and on the question whether we can conceive of infinite space. But the discussions of Mr. Hazard INTRODUCTORY ESSAY. Xix have for their principal subject the Will and its Free- dom ; and it is with reference to the three eminent authors whom I have first named fcliat they may be conveniently reviewed. It does not detract from the originality of Edwards that arguments which he brought forward in support of the doctrine of philosophical necessity had been em- ployed by writers before him. He was charged with agreeing with Hobbes, but he remarks somewhere that he had never read Hobbes. Dugald Stewart appears to have thought that Edwards borrowed from Collins, and Sir William Hamilton had tbe same impression. It is not probable, however, that Edwards had ever seen a copy of Collins's work on Liberty. The coin- cidence of the reasoning of the New England meta- physician with that of the two authors just named can be easily accounted for, since all acute logicians who defend the necessitarian thesis must resort to substan- tially the same considerations in maintaining it. It was Locke who communicated the strongest stimulus to the mind of Edwards. From Locke's chapter on "Power " he derived fruitful suggestions. Locke him- self modified his views, in the second edition of his treatise ; and in his correspondence with Limborch he confessed that while he believed in human freedom, how it could exist was to him an insoluble problem. The principal argument of Edwards, like that of necessitarians before him, was built on the principle of causation, and consisted in the unflinching applica- tion of this law to the phenomena of the will. That every event, every change, must have a cause, is the postulate. The choice of one thing rather than an- other is an event. It will not do to say that the choice XX INTRODUCTORY ESSAY. of a instead of 6 — when both are eligible — is owing to the power of the will to choose — to the power of choice. The thing to be accounted for is the specifi- cation of the choice — the election of a and the rejec- tion of h. There must be a cause for this direction of the choice ; otherwise, there is a causeless event ; and if there can be one causeless event, there can be a million ; the universe may be without a cause. Ed- wards presses upon those who deny his position the alternative of atheism. Assuming that every volition is made to be what it is by some causal agency, Ed- wards finds this to be the motives in the mind which precede the act of choice. The antecedent state of feeling, in particular the mind's view of " the greatest apparent good " in prospect, is the " strongest motive " : it has an effectual " previous tendency " to determine the will. This motive is held to be a proper cause. The difference between causation in the will's action, and causation in the external world of matter, is said to consist chiefly, not in the mode of connection be- tween antecedents and consequents, but in the nature of the things connected. In the case of the will, it is states of mind ; in the world without, it is things ma- terial. Liberty, according to Edwards — and in this he follows Locke — is the power of doing as one chooses, or of carrying out, without any successful hindrance, the will's act. There is no necessity, strictly speaking, in choice, since there is no counter-choice, which would be in the nature of things impossible. No matter how the choice or voluntary inclination comes to be, as long as one does not will against his will — an absurd supposition — one has all the free- dom that can be imagined to exist. We are respon- INTRODUCTORY ESSAY. XXI sible for our choices, since morality belongs to them, or their own nature, and not to their causes. They are right or wrong, be the genesis of them what it may. This, in brief, is the course of Edwards's reasoning. John Stuart Mill was a champion of views akin to the philosophical tenets of Hume. Power is elimi- nated from the idea of cause. The relation of cause and effect is declared to be nothing but a relation of invariable succession. The same antecedents are known by experience to be followed by the same con- sequents. We give the name of cause to the ante- cedents, collectively taken, of any phenomenon. To none of these is anything like efficiency to be attri- buted. This is all that is signified by causation in the material world. Nothing more is true in the sphere of mental action. As concerns the will, what we call " choice " or " volition " takes place according to a fixed law. Subtract from the " strongest motive " of Edwards the element of power, and retain the in- variableness of connection, and we have left the sub- stance of Mill's doctrine. There is no " necessity," properly so called. Mill teaches ; for there is no such thing as coercion, constraint, agency, power, in the universe. They have no reality either within the mind or without it. The relation of cause and effect is sim- ply a relation of before and after — nothing less and nothing more. As the antecedents in the form of per- ception, desire, involuntary dispositions, and emotions, vary, the resulting — that is to say, the subsequent — volitions will alter. In the philosophy of Sir William Hamilton, " cause " is a term which denotes simply the incapacity of the finite, human mind to conceive of a new beginning, — Xxii INTRODUCTORY ESSAY. of any reality which had not, in some form, a previous existence. " Cause " is thus made to be a notion re- sulting from a certain mental inability. On the ques- tion of liberty and necessity, Hamilton pronounces both to be eqvially inconceivable. Freedom of will, since it implies the possibility of a new beginning, a something not evolved necessarily from a previous reality, is inconceivable. On the other hand, necessity is equally inconceivable ; for the alternative of freedom is an infinite series of antecedents, each contained potentially in its predecessor ; and we cannot think an infinite series. But there must be either liberty or necessity, and we must, therefore, believe in one or the other. We believe in freedom, because the testimony of conscience is on that side. We accept as true a proposition the possibility of which we cannot under- stand. Our sense of personal responsibility, with the feelings of self-approbation, remorse, etc., bears witness to the fact of our personal freedom, unintelligible as that fact is to the conceptive faculty. In meeting the reasoning of the necessitarians, Mr. Hazard saw distinctly where the battle-ground really lies. He saw that the contest hinges upon the views taken of causation and of what is meant by power. Shall we take our ideas relative to causation from the material world, and from the popular notions of power as there exerted ? If so, the necessitarians will have their own way. Or shall we look within, and find in our mental experience causal agency in the only shape in which it is directly known to us ? This last course is the only one which can yield trustworthy results. Mr. Hazard brings forward convincing proof that our notion of causation arises from our conscious, volun- INTRODUCTORY ESSAY. Xxiii tary efforts, producing muscular exertion. Mill made use of the argument o£ Hamilton, that this cannot be the case, since between the volition and the motion of the arm there interpose links of cause and effect of which the mind, in the act of will, can have no cogni- zance. In reply, Mr. Hazard denies that such a cog- nizance of the intervening process is requisite, inas- much as the knowledge that the given effect will be produced as a consequence of volition is instinctive, and without this innate knowledge the putting forth of such a volition would be inconceivable. Mr. Hazard's discussion of this point is one of the most cogent and conclusive portions of his metaphysical writings. As to the nature of the material world, Mr. Hazard was disposed to favor the Berkeleian hypothesis, and to hold that sense-perceptions are purely mental, being impressed upon us by a supreme Will, acting accord- ing to a uniform method. But, granting the objective reality of matter, we must find all its causal agency in its motion. Its motion has been eternal, or it has been communicated to it from without. Whether, if once set in motion, matter would continue to move of itself, is an unsolved question. If it were endowed with a power to move, being unintelligent, it could have no tendency to move in one direction rather than another. If it is assumed to have been always in motion, still it is inconceivable that matter should be the cause of in- telligence. How can that which does not know create the power to know ? The result of Mr. Hazard's rea- soning on this subject is the conclusion that all power proceeds originally from a supreme intelligence. Mind, as we know from our own consciousness, is pos- sessed of original, causal agency. Its sensations and XXIV INTRODUCTORY ESSAY. emotions are not subject to will. Neither is its knowl- edge ; although by will we can produce the conditions favorable to the acquisition of knowledge. The mind has but one real faculty, or power, to do anything, and this faculty is the will. Through this faculty the mind puts forth effort. The object of every act of will is to produce some effect in the future. Its immediate ob- ject is to influence mental activity, or to move the body. Respecting the nature of the will, the gist of Mr. Hazard's doctrine is in the proposition that the mind has the jjower to begin action, certain conditions being present. The fortress in which necessitarians place themselves is the alleged impossibility that a begin- ning of action, or a power to begin action, shovJd ex- ist. Nothing can move, unless, and so far as, it is itself moved. This is the position of Edwards ; the opposite is one of the " inconceivables " of Hamilton. Were it tenable, Mr. Hazard contends, there could be no real cause ; there would be the transmission, or flowing down, of power — of power having no source. Power, if real, is in its nature aboriginal. To be sure, power is given to the creature by the Supreme Cause ; but when it is given, the creature is himself consti- tuted a creative cause, supreme within his own limits. The " conditions " of the exercise of the creative hu- man will are want and knowledge. Something is wanted ; there is a perception of the methods of ob- taining it. But knowledge and want, neither of them, nor both together, exercise power. They have no efficiency. They do not govern the mind in willing. The mind, through a capacity belonging to it, puts forth effort to satisfy a want. To say, as Edwards does, that it is determined, moved, caused to begin INTRODUCTORY ESSAY. XXV this effort, is to contradict consciousness. To say that such an effort is an effect without a cause, is to ignore the fact that the mind is itself a cause, in the full sense which belongs to the term. It is not a case of some- thing beginning to be where there was nothing before it to give it being. The mind was there with its self- active power of putting forth effort. In reply to the assertion of the uniformity of the action of the will under like antecedents, which is made by such writers as Edwards on the one hand, and by such writers as Mill on the other, Mr. Hazard ingen- iously argues that such uniformity is not less consistent with liberty than with necessity. The mind va2ij freely direct its action, and yet always direct it in the same way. For example, if I go from my dwelling to the post-office every day in the year, and each time take a direct and easy way, instead of a circuitous and diffi- cult one, this circumstance affords no proof that I do not elect the path with perfect freedom. Mr. Hazard does not consider himself obliged to deny the truth of the proposition that the same mind in the same cir- cumstances would certainly act voluntarily in the same way. Yet he holds that where there is a reason for selecting one of several objects, but no reason for se- lecting one of them rather than another, the mind still can put forth its voluntary effort and take one arbi- trarily, or frame to itself a perfectly arbitrary rule for the regulation of its action. In reply to the statement that the mind cannot act without motives, Mr. Hazard says : "I do not assert that the mind's effort springs into existence contin- gently, but admit that it always perceives some in- ducement to make the effort, and have no objection to XXVI INTRODUCTORY ESSAY calling this inducement a motive." ^ But whatever these inducements be, the mind still controls its action. " The mind's state of desire is only one of the ele- ments, in a combination of things and circumstances, in the perception of which and of their relations, the mind finds a reason for acting and for the manner of acting ; but no one of these elements, nor any combi- nation of them, can devise the plan of action to reach the desired result, or can act it out when devised." ^ The actor is not the " inducement ; " it is the mind, planning and putting forth effort of itself. Mr. Hazard, by his own reflections, arrived at a view of the constitution of man as a voluntary agent, which does not differ essentially, in its general outlines, from the doctrine of the famous metaphysician, Dr. Samuel Clarke. This doctrine Clarke sets forth in his Re- Tnai'ks on Collins's book. He there asserts that there exists a principle of self-motion in man, a power of initiating motion, or of voluntaiy self-determination. This power is not determined as to the mode of its exertion by anything but itself; that would involve a contradiction. It is self -moving. It is absurd, Clarke affirms, to attribute efficiency to the mental states called motives. If they had efficiency, man would be like a clock, or a pair of scales endowed with sensation or perception. He would not be an agent. What we call motives are bare antecedents, or occa- sional causes. The opposite supposition Clarke shows to involve an infinite regress of effects with no cause at all. Moreover, uniformity of action does not imply a necessity in the connection of the act with its ante- cedents. " The experience of a man's ever doing what ^ Causation and Freedom in Willing, p. 153. INTRODUCTORY ESSAY. XXVU lie judges reasonable to do, is not at all his being under any necessity so to do. For eoncomitancy in this case is no evidence at all of physical connec- tion." 1 According to Mr. Hazard, the " motives " which constitute the " inducement "to an act of will being the reason, but not the cause of the act, the mind is perfectly free in willing — free, because by its own power exclusively it initiates the act. The conditions precedent are want and knowledge. " Dispositions," "inclinations," desires, etc., so far as they are con- nected with a voluntary act, are resolvable into " want." I want to obtain an object, I discern how to obtain it, and I put forth the effort requisite to the end in view. It is said, however, that the act being thus connected with a preceding want, is really tlie result of my char- acter, and, on this account, freedom is sometimes denied. This brings us to another point in Mr. Haz- ard's view of the subject, and one of fundamental importance. In answer to the objection just stated, he affirms that although the character of a man is manifested in his efforts, is indicated and represented by them, his freedom is not thereby affected ; nor " is it material to the question of freedom how the being came to be as he is ; whether his own character has been the result of his own efforts or of other power or circumstances." ^ Enough that he controls his own action. He alone is the actor. It does not militate against freedom that his willing varies with and con- forms to his character. Nevertheless, the question is yet of the highest importance, how he came by his ^ Remarks, etc., p. 25. 2 Man a Creative First Cause, etc., p. 289. XXVlll INTRODUCTORY ESSAY. character, or what power he has over it. What con- trol has a man over the " want " which is the occasion of acts of will, and to which they do actually conform ? This control is indirect, but it is decisive. Man has full power, by voluntary action, to increase his knowl- edge, and to modify the perceptions out of which want arises. " There may have been moral wrong in the acquisition of any knowledge or in the omission to ac- quire any, which required an effort. Such acquisition or omission may have been counter to his conviction of right. There can be no moral wrong in the acquisi- tion of that knowledge which he unintentionally ac- quires by observation." Where his moral nature is defiled, " the polluting arose from the previous effort to acquire, or, negatively, from not making the effort to prevent acquiring," etc. If a want is natural, there may be a moral wrong in entertaining it, in cultivating it, when it is within our power to direct the attention to something higher. This control which the mind can exercise over the attention is an essential element of human responsibility. We are able, especially at intervals when sensual appetites are not craving their objects, to fill our thoughts with ideals of noble and holy action, and thereby to arm ourselves beforehand for the conflict with temptation. The attentive reader of Mr. Hazard's writings on the subject which we are considering, will observe — what it is possible to overlook — that in all cases of moral action the " want " which constitutes character, and which leads to particular acts of will conformed to it, involves intention. It includes a determination to seek the object, or to produce the effect, to which the subsequent acts of the will — subsequent in the order INTRODUCTORY ESSAY. Xxix of nature, if not in time — are directed. " Voluntary- actions," he says, " are but indices of the intentions, and it is in the intentions that the essence of virtue inheres." ^ We are free because these intentions, be they morally right or the opposite, are our own crea- tion, and they are subject to change if we adopt the means which it is within our power to adopt. There are passages in which Mr. Hazard appears to call in question the " power of contrary choice." But these passages, when they are closely examined, will be seen to affirm simply the incompatibility of two antagonistic exertions of will at the same moment. "Any necessity that there is that the acts or efforts of a virtuous jjerson must be virtuous, is only that which arises from the impossibility of his being both virtuous and vicious at the same time, or in the same act." ^ " The advocates of necessity often ask if a man could will the contrary of what he does will. I would say that he could if he so decided : but it would be a con- tradictory and absurd idea of freedom, which for its regulation would require that one might try to do what he had determined not to tiy to do." Here the terms " decided " and " determined " denote the intention or purpose which the mind forms antecedently (in the order of nature) to the voluntary efforts to carry it out. That these efforts cannot but conform to the decision which gives rise to them, is what Mr. Hazard means when he denies a power of contrary choice. The absence of such a power, in this understanding of it, is what proves freedom. That he holds that the mind could have chosen otherwise than it actually ^ Freedom of the Mind in Willing, etc., p. 155. ■^ Causation and Freedom in Willing, etc., p. 141. XXX INTRODUCTORY ESSAY. chose, is rendered evident in many of our author's statements. Thus, in speaking of the gratification of a want that ought not to be gratified, he says : " God never permits such action without a monition through the moral sense, warning us to refrain from the mu- tilation or degradation of our being, and suggesting search of that knowledge which, by a faith in the wis- dom and goodness of the Supreme Intelligence, intui- tive or early acquired, we know will reconcile gratifica- tion and duty." ^ Speaking of a wrongdoer, the author says : " He must have been able to will rightly, for the knowledge, which is the only limit to this ability, em- braced all that was essential to action morally right." Much stress is laid upon " the preliminary examina- tions which We make for the purpose of determining our actions." The object of them often is " to test the expediency " of a change in the existing " incli- nations." Moreover, Mr. Hazai'd emphasizes the fact that " there may be conflicting inclinations, desires, and aversions, among which we must, by the prelimi- nary examination, make our choice." It is not " till the disposition, inclination, and desires have thus cul- minated in a preference or choice to try to do, that they have any immediate relation to the particular action," ^ etc. The fact that in determining to aim at any object, in deciding which of two or more conflict- ing impulses shall be complied with, the mind controls its own action, is equivalent to the assertion that it could have formed a purpose the opposite of that which it actually forms, and in pursuance of which its particular efforts, or acts of will, are put forth. Mr. ^ Freedom of the Mind in Willing, p. 306. 2 Causation and Freedom in Willing, p. 146. INTRODUCTORY ESSAY. XXKl Hazard gives the name of " choice " to the knowledge of this vokmtary inclination, or want ; and this pecu- liar use of terms has led some to conclude that the voluntary element is excluded from it. But while there are " wants " which are instinctive, and of course involuntary, that " want " which constitutes, at any time, the character of a man, owes its distinctive char- acteristic to his voluntary action. It is another name for habitual intention. The fundamental point of Mr. Hazard's criticism of Edwards is fully established. It must be allowed that his confutation of that conception of the Will which underlies the reasoning of the great theologian is sound and conclusive. When Edwards wrote, the idea of voluntary action which he propounded could be entertained without the practical dangers now seen to flow unavoidably from such a theory. At present that theory is likely to lead its advocates by a short road into Pantheism. If we would adhere firmly to a faith in the personality of man — without which the person- ality of God must be given up — we cannot surrender our faith in the self -active nature of the human mind — in its power to initiate and control its voluntary action. The proposition that man is a creative first cause will appear to some bold and startling. But the corre- late, be it remembered, as regards human action, is personal responsibility: man must himself originate the conduct for which he is blamed and deserves pun- ishment. Is it said that Mr. Hazard's conception limits the divine omnipotence ? But this limitation, on the part of God, is self-imposed. He abstains, by his own choice, from the exertion of his power, so far as is requisite, in order that man shall act freely. A XXXU INTRODUCTORY ESSAY. self-limitation of this kind on the side of the Deity does not lower, but rather exalts our idea of Almighti- ness. In Mr. Hazard's doctrine, moreover, room is made for the phenomena of habit. In a certain sense and to a certain degree, by a continued exertion of will in a particular direction, a free agent may lay fetters on himself. In the confutation of Edwards, Mr. Hazard is obliged to consider his argument for necessity which is based on the foreknowledge of God. There is no room for foreknowledge, Edwards contends, except where there is predetermination. The government of the world, he tries to show, is contingent on the truth of the necessitarian hypothesis. To this Mr. Hazard answers, in the first place, that an omniscient being can foresee all the possibilities of human action, and the results in every case, so that, if not possessed of a prescience of volitions, he can, without deliberation or delay, adapt his own action to whatever occurs. If the created being acts or refrains from acting, and on •whichever side his volition may lie, the Ruler of the imiverse can instantly meet the results by an appro- priate exertion of his own power. The illustration of Mr. Hazard is drawn from the chess-board. A player, if a perfect master of the game, has in reserve a move to correspond to whatever move his antagonist may choose to make. The former is never taken by sur- prise ; the result, so to speak, is always in his hands. Now it may he that the Creator of free beings, as he puts a limitation on his own power in giving them scope for the exercise of their freedom, chooses to re- sign to this extent his own foreknowledge. " Whether a free volition ever can be infallibly foreknown may INTRODUCTORY ESSAY. XXXlll be doubted." ^ Another solution of the difficulty is in the theory that foreknowledge is an independent attri- bute of the Deity, and that his foresight is, therefore, not dependent on his control of free actions. Armin- ian theologians have generally adopted this opinion, which Mr. Hazard neither sanctions nor denies. He insists that the volitions of men are to such an extent the reflex of their characters, that when their charac- ters and habits are known, their conduct, although free, is capable of being anticipated. As far as the foreknowledge on our part of what other men will do is concerned, it is just as great under the conception that they act freely, as it would be if necessity gov- erned them. The idea that, because volitions are free, they are chaotic, utterly void of uniformity, is a mis- taken one. In order to complete our exposition of Mr. Haz- ard's doctrine concerning the Will, it is requisite to notice the very interesting explanation given by him of the phenomena of instinct and habit. There is here, he contends, no exception to his main proposition that all our actions are efforts, self-directed by means of our knowledge to the gratification of a want. The fact in the case of instinct is, not that the Will, the voluntary exertion, is absent, but that the hnowledge by which the will is directed is innate. On no other supposition could we account for the direction of the muscles of an animal — for example, in seeking a sup- ply of food from its parent, prior to any acquired knowledge of the source of that supply. In particular, self-activity prior to birth implies an implanted knowl- edge. On no other supposition, it is evident, could 1 Man a Creative First Cause, etc., p. 290. XXXlV INTRODUCTORY ESSAY. muscular movements involving a plan be explicable. In the case of instinctive action, we do not ourselves devise the plan, but work according to a plan framed for us and innate. The solution of the problem of hahity when we understand the nature of instinct, becomes easy. Everybody knows and admits that the action of habit is analogous to instinctive action. When we have once formed a plan and are so familiar with its successive steps that we can apply it by rote without thinking of its rationale, action conformed to it is immediate. It takes place with the promptitude of an instinct. This is expressed in the proverb, " Habit is second nature." Thus we see that ra- tional, instinctive, and habitual actions belong under one category. They are all efforts of a conative being, impelled by its want, and directed by its knowledge to the end sought. The difference between these several kinds of action is in the way in which the requisite knowledge is acquired. In the case of instinct it is imparted from without in the creative act ; in the case of habit it is acquired by the agent and lodged in the memory which does its work with the quickness and almost with the precision of instinct ; in the case of the intelligent action of man, which is not habitual, it is gained by more or less investigation and reflection. It may be added that this idea of the nature of in- stinct, while it appears to solve a fact in nature which has baffled so many attempts to explain, affords a striking proof of an Intelligent creator. For how could the knowledge of the animal, on which instinc- tive action is based, spring into being except through the agency of a cause itself endued with knowledge ? After the foregoing statements, it is not necessary INTRODUCTORY ESSAY. XXXV to add that Mr. Hazard is deeply convinced of the truth of Theism. In his conception of voluntary ac- tion as the very source of our conception of power and causal agency, and in his earnest repudiation of every thing" which would undermine freedom, he lays a solid foundation for the belief in a personal God. The ground of all changes is found in will. The ideal theory of matter, although not required by his philos- ophy of the will, stands in close connection with it. Power is made to belong exclusively to sjDirit, — to God, the infinite Spirit, and to his rational creatures, whom, by a voluntary self-limitation on his part, he has made, within their own limited spheres, supreme crea- tive agents. The ablest defenders of theism at pres- ent, as, for example, Mr. James Martineau, rest their cause on ideas respecting the will and the nature of causation not dissimilar from those which Mr. Hazard presented, many years ago. At the same time, Mr. Hazard admits the significance and importance of habit. He finds room in his system for divine influ- ence in aid of human efforts at self-emancipation. The enlightenment of the mind which precedes moral action, and is an index of what it will be, may be in- creased by divine agency. Of the need and value of this agency in the reformation of character, Mr. Haz- ard, in different places, speaks in the most serious tone. His writings are everywhere characterized by a dignified earnestness, and a spirit of reverence. They are marked by an absolute candor. There is never any disposition to evade an issue, or to dispose of an opponent by any other means than fair and courteous argument. Mr. Hazard was too sincere and too confident of the strength of his positions to resort XXXVl INTRODUCTORY ESSAY. to controversial arts. He was a philosopher in the etymological sense of the term : he was a lover of truth. I can say sincerely that a recent re-perusal of his writings has impressed me more than ever not only with the intellectual penetration which they evince, but equally with the fairness with which the themes of which they treat are handled. It is not that sort of fairness which is the product of neutrality or indif- ference. There is no lack of a profound interest in the questions discussed. It is the fairness of a mind which is protected by a love of equity from seeking an undue advantage at the expense of an adversary, and relies with no misgivings upon the weapons of reason. BOOK I. FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLI BOOK I. FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING, CHAPTER I. OP THE EXISTENCE OF SPIRIT. EvEKY argument has its postulates. We cannot reason from the known to the unknown, unless some- thing be first known. Of all that we believe, nothing is more certain than the existence of belief itself, consti- tuting knowledge : and, of this knowledge the belief that there is some existence which believes, stands in the first rank ; and, next in order, a belief in a plurality of existences, which, of necessity, implies that each of the existences, constituting this plurality, has peculiar and distinguishing characteristics, otherwise it would be identical with some other existence. It would not add to the number of existences ; and, if none possessed dis- tinguishing attributes or conditions, there could be only one existence. In such case, if space is a necessary exist ence, all other existence would become impossible. Even if space were homogeneously filled, that which fills must, in some way, be difi^erent from that which is filled. Time itself would be excluded. It may then reasonably be as- 2 FRKEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. snmed not only that the belief in the plurality of exist ences itself exists, but that it is well founded. In this plu- rality there is nothing of which we have more convincing proof than of the existence of sensation, emotion, want, and of effort to supply want, of all which we are conscious. Perhaps we cannot logically deduce from this any separate existence, which knows, feels and acts, but it is at least certain, that this knowledge, sensation and effort are, in some way, so far associated as to justify us in speaking of them as one combination ; and, in doing this, each individual combination of them is denominated a spirit, an intelligence, mind, or soul, of which the attri- butes of knowing, feeling and acting are distinguishing characteristics. As present with this mind, or soul, yet distinct from it, we associate the idea of a particular form, which, with the soul, constitutes what each ex- presses by the term, " I." This idea of form is not essen- tial to our conception of mind, or spirit, the attributes of which may be conceived of as entirely independent of such association, or as purely intelligent being, or beings. Among our sensations are some which each indi- vidual finds he can himself produce. He can, by cer- tain efforts, produce the various sensations known as muscular movements, the sound of a bell, &c. ; and hence knows his own power to produce effects. But he finds the sensation is sometimes produced without any effort of his own, and hence he infers a cause, or power without himself; and most naturally attributing the effect to a power similar to that which in himself pro- duces similar effect, — to another finite intelligence, — he gets the idea of the existence of other finite minds. It is, perhaps, hardly necessary here to remark, that although through the sensations of sight we may have OF THE EXISTENCE OF SPIRIT. 6 an immediate perception of other forms like our own, still, the belief that other similar heings are associated with, or represented by such forms, is an inference from the visual sensation, in connection with other facts. We draw no such inference from our image in a mirror, or from any other object known to be lifeless, however nearly resembling the human form. But, among oiir sensations, are some, which we find we have no power to produce, or very insufficient power ; and hence we infer the existence of a power without ourselves, greatly exceeding our own ; so in- comparably surpassing it, that we term it infinite. Strictly speaking, the evidence as first presented to us, only proves the existence of a power capable of pro- ducing the sensations of which we are conscious ; but every new observation revealing greater and greater power, and power far beyond what we had previously conceived, lays the foundation for a belief that the power is unlimited, and that any apparent limitation to it is in our own finite powers of observation and con- ception. Or, to put it in another form, the constant efiect of the enlargement of our own observations and conceptions having always been to make the limit of this external power appear more remote, there is no reason to suppose that a further enlargement of tliem, to any finite extent, would bring us nearer to that limit ; and hence, so far as our experience goes, we may, if not with strict logical accuracy, yet without danger of its leading us into philosophical error, apply the term infinite to the Supreme Intelligence. A power, which can accomplish everything conceivable to us as within the province of power, is, to us, the same as if it were infinite. It has, for us, no conceivable limit. 4- FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. The inference, by which the finite intelligence argues the existence of other similar intelligences, is not one of absolute necessity ; for all the phenomena, — ^the sensa- tions, — which he ascribes to their agency, may be pro- duced in him by the Infinite, — the greater including the less. But the exhibition of weaknesses and imper- fections like his own, and which are incompatible with the Infinite ; and the repeated coincidence, or frequent association of these phenomena with the presence of forms similar to, yet differing more or less from that which he associates with his own being, and in which changes resembling his own external actions take place, give preponderance to the hypothesis of the existence of other and numerous finite intelligences, distinct from his own. In the absence of any reason to the contrary, it is rational to suppose things really to be as they aj^ear to be. So far, then, we may be said to have arrived at the knowledge of the existence of our own finite intelli- gence ; of other similar finite intelligences ; and of the Supreme, or Infinite Intelligence. We have come to know ourselves, our fellow beings, and G-od, as powers producing certain efl'ects, as being Cause. CHAPTEE II. OF THE EXISTENCE OF MATTER. "We know notliiEg of matter except by the sensations, wMch we impute to its agency, mediately, or imme- diately ; and as those sensations can exist in the mind without the intervention of the external, material forms, or forces, to which we impute them, the sensations are not conclusive evidence of any such external existence. In dreams, and especially in nightmare, we have as vivid sensations of what we afterward find had no cor- responding external materiality, as we ever have under any circumstances. If this arises from the excited action of our own memory and imagination, it merely proves that the mind, under certain conditions, has a power of reproducing what has befoi'e been impressed upon it by some external power, and at the same time of vary- ing the combinations in which they before existed. This does not conflict with the position that, as the sensations may exist without the intervention of matter, the sensations are not evidence that matter exists. All the sensations which we attribute to matter, are as fully accounted for by the hypothesis that they are the thought, the imagery of God directly imparted, or made palpable to our finite minds, as by the hypothesis of a distinct external substance, in which He has TREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. moulded this thought and imagery. If God, with design, created or fashioned matter in the forms pre- sented to us, then these forms are but the result of thoughts and conceptions existing, or which existed in His mind ; and the only question is, does He impart or impress them directly and injmediately upon our finite minds ; or indirectly and mediately, by first writing, picturing, moulding, or carving them out in a distinct substance called matter? In either case it is to us eqviaWj real / the sensations, by which alone we know these, to us, external phenomena, being the same. The hypothesis that the material forms are but the imagery of the mind of God made palpable to us, is the more simple of the two, and makes creative at- tributes more nearly accord witli powers which we are ourselves conscious of exercising. We cannot infer the existence of matter as an en- tity distinct from spirit, from any necessity of spirit for something to act upon ; our conceptions of it serv- ing for this purpose, as well as any such distinct exist- ence could do ; and, indeed, being all tliat we can employ the faculties and attributes of spirit upon. The whole science of Geometry, which, beiug the science of quantity, or extension, — one of the attributes of matter, — may be deemed as emphatically a materia] science, is entirely founded on such conceptions ; and, in fact, on such conceptions as we get no accurate sen- sations of from without ; for, not to insist that no one ever had a sensation of such abstractions as a mathe- matical point, or line, we may assert that no one ever had a sensation from matter of a perfect mathematical form, for instance, of a perfect circle. It is a concep- tion of the mind, and for the purposes of mathematical OF THE EXISTENCE OF 3IATTER. 7 reasoning, is a creation of the mind, brought into exist- ence by actualizing this conception in a definition ; and for these purposes, whatever conforms to that definition is a circle, and what does not so conform is not a circle. The reasoning is wholly based on the de/fmition of our conceptions of form, and not on any actual existence, or sensation of such forms in matter, which are never sufficiently accurate to rest such reasoning upon ; and hence, mathematics is really a hypothetical science, and would be equally true if there were no material forms even bearing any resemblance to the conceptions of the mind brought out in its definitions. The science of mechanics, too, is founded on our conceptions of resist- ance and forces, as solidity, inertia, momentum ; and does not involve the question as to what these forces really are.* To adopt the hypothesis, that our sensations of what is external are but the conceptions of God, made directly palpable to us, and ignore matter entirely, would free the subject of the freedom, of intelligence from some apparent, if not real diflflculties ; and would, at the same time, avoid much confusion, which I apprehend has been occasioned by the close and various associa- tions of matter with spirit. We should then have only to consider the action of intelligence in its finite and infinite forms. But as either hypothesis accounts for all the phenomena, the fact that one is more simple and that it makes the process of material creation more com- prehensible to us is not, perhaps, even with our expe- rience in dreams, a sufiicient reason for presuming that mattei does not exist as an entity distinct from mind * See Appendix, Note I. at the end of the volume. 8 FKEEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. aud with the properties which our sensations indicate. We may remai'k, however, that, supposing the In- finite Intelligence to fashion and control this matter, it would make no difference as to the question of our freedom ; for, in that case, the real phenomena would be the same, — the thought and imagery of the mind of God — and the only question would be as to which of the two modes He has adopted in communicating that thought and in making that imagery palpable to us. We may further remark that, with the testimony of our senses on the one hand, and on the other, the considera- tion that the imagery of the mind of God is not in it- self intelligent, but an effect of intelligence in action, we may assume, in either case, that matter is in itself unintelligent and inert. Admitting, then, for the pur- poses of the argument, the existence of matter as dis- tinct from spirit, we will, in a subsequent chapter, in- quire how far it can produce effects, or be cause. CHAPTEK III, OF MIND. Mind lias feeling, knowledge, volition. It is suscep- tible of sensation and emotion ; has a simple perceptive attribute by which it directly acquires knowledge ; and a faculty of will, through which it manifests its power to produce, or to try to produce change. Our sensations and emotions are not dependent upon the will. We hear the sound of a cannon, whether we will to hear it or not ; and can neither avoid, nor pro- duce the emotions of joy or sorrow by merely willing it. We may, by eftort, bring about the conditions pre- cedent to a particular sensation or emotion ; but, the conditions being the same, whether they exist by our own act, or from some other cause, makes no difference as to the effect.* Our knowledge is also independent of the will. We cannot know, or believe anything by simply willing to know, or believe it. If I have a sen- sation of seeing a tree, I cannot by any act of will be- lieve that I have no such sensation, or that I have the sensation of seeing a rock instead. So, too, if in the relations of my ideas, I perceive certain truths, as that 2 + 2 =: 4, I cannot at will disbelieve or not know such * See Appendix, Note II. 1* 10 FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. truths. By will I can bring about the conditions favor able to the increase of knowledge, but I cannot thus determine what shall become known. I maj, by effort, remove an external obstruction to sight and thus be en- abled to see what was behind it ; but I cannot, by will, determine what it is that I shall then see. So also I may by effort arrange and compare my ideas, so that some truth, which before was hidden, will become ob- vious ; but I cannot will what that truth, when discov- ered, will be. In both of these, uud in all other cases, the discovery of the objects, or of the abstract truths, and the consequent addition to our knowledge, is, in the last analysis, a simple mental perception y and all our efforts to acquire knowledge are only to make such external changes in matter, or so to arrange our ideas, as to bring the truth within reach of the simple percep- tive attribute of the mind. From the foregoing it appears that feeling, whether in sensation or emotion, is rather a property, or suscep- tibility, than a faculty of being. So also the ability to acquire knowledge is a capacity, or a sense, rather than a faculty. Our sensations, emotions, and knowledge, at the time being, are actual present existences, in common with all others now actually existing, — independent of the will. Having become existent, whether by the agency of will, or otherwise, such existence cannot, by will, be changed, in the present, any more than what existed in the past can be so changed. Whenever we seek to pro- duce any change, it must be with reference to the future, and this is always by will. Whenever by the exercise of our own power we try to influence the course of events, we will. When by effort we recall the knowl- OF MIND. 11 edge of tlie past, the reGolling is still an e\&\\ifut/ure to the eifort. There are other attributes, or modes of mind, which are often spoken of as if they were distinct faculties, or active agents, having j^ower of themselves to do certain things. In this category we may embrace memory, judgment, reasoning, imagination, conception, and per- haps, also association. These are all names of some form of knowledge, or of some mode of mental action to acquire, or reproduce it. The forms of knowledge, to which they are applied, are actual present existences, not subject to the will. Our memories of the past, our observation of the present, and our anticipations of the future are all, when reached, but present knowledge. When, from any cause, the knowledge of the past, the present, or the future is perceived by the mind, it is a simple mental perception, When we make effort to produce such changes, internal or external, as will bring any knowledges within the mind's view, it is an act of will, a trying to do something. So that, in all cases, the names of these supposed faculties only indi- cate actual existing knowledge, or its acquisition by simple mental perception, or by acts of will to produce those changes which will bring knowledge within reach of this simple mental j)erception. These acts of will differ from each other either in their mode, or in their object. Memorj", for instance, is but a condition, and a necessary condition, of knowledge of the past. With- out it such knowledge could not exist. In this sense it is only an expression of one form of our knowledge. To say, I remeniber an event, is to say, I know an event in the past. If, from any cause, an event of the past comes before the mind it is then a simple mental per- 12 FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING ception. When we make effort to bring an event of the past into the mind's view we call it an exercise, or effort of memory, and this, of course, is an act of will, a trying to do this thing. So likewise the term judgment may express the mind's conclusion as to the equality, or inequality of one thing, or method as compared with another ; or as to the truth, or error of a proposition. And such con- clusion is a simple mental perception ; while any effort in comparing, examining, &c., by which we seek to bring about the conditions favoring such perception, is called an exercise, or effort of judgment, which, is an- other act of will. The same may be said of reasoning, imagining, con- ceiving, &c. In the sense in which these are spoken of as faculties, or powers, they are but names of varied modes of effort, or of efforts for different ohjects^ made by the same uiiit-mind, manifesting its power to pro- duce change by its efforts, or acts of will. Whether these supposed faculties are but names of varied acts of will, or otherwise, does not really affect the question of the mind^s freedom in action ; for, whether it act by a faculty called will, or by a faculty called judgment, would not affect its freedom in action so long as the faculty by which it thus acted pertained to its own being. If the question were, whether the will, considered as a distinct entity, were free, it might become important to inquire if there were any coordinate powers of mind by which it could be con- trolled. The introduction of these supposed faculties, as distinct powers, does, however, tend to complicate and confuse the argument as to the mind's freedom. In confirmation of the views already stated, it may be ob- OF MIND. 13 served, that if acts of will are but efforts of the mind, and these faculties are exerted by the miud, it foUowa that they but indicate, or name different acts of will, or efforts of the same unit power — mind. In further illustration that they are bnt names of these varied efforts, I would remark, that the immediate object of every act of will is to move some poi'tion of the body, or to influence mental activity. In either case we are conscious only of the effort and the effect, and though we speak of bodily and mental efforts, we still recognize them all as efforts of the mind. In so speaking, we distinguish them not by the active agent, which is the same in all, but by the imTnediate object of the effort, or by the subjects of it, which, in some cases, are but instruments to accomplish remoter ob- jects. Thus, when movement of the body, or of any portion of it, is the object, we speak of bodily, or mus- cular effort, and subdivide into efforts of the hand, the foot, &c. ; while those efforts, of which the mind is the subject, we designate as mental efforts ; and, as in these we are not conscious of distinct members as the suhjects of our action, we subdivide, or classify by the objects sought, as efforts of memory, of judgment, of imagina- tion, &c.* By the phrase bodily effort we cannot mean to as- sert that the body is an active agent, itself making effort, but only that its movement is the object of the mental effort; and, in as close analogy to this as the case permits, the expressions, efforts of memory, of judgment and imagination, &c., only signify that the object of the effort is to remember, to judge, to imagine, * See Appendix, Note III. l-± FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. (fee. In all, we recognize but varied efforts, or efforts for different objects, by the same unit-mind, without the intervention of any other poM'ers ; and all these efforts are but manifestations of the mind's action, va- ried m conformity with the objects, or changes it seeks to produce. It may be objected to this dispensing with these alleged faculties, and eonsidei-ing them merely as names designating different modes of effort, or efforts for dif- ferent objects, that they sometimes seem to act of them- selves. Of this, memory is the most marked example. Our memories seem to rise unbidden before us, and in an order which we do not control. JSTom-, as a present sensation is known by means of simple mental percep- tion, without effort, it may so happen that the circum- stances, which exist without our agency, may also bring the knowledge of the past within the reach of this same perception. This appears to be effected mainly, if not wholly, by means of association, which is an ar- rangement, or classification of our knowledge in con- formity to some observed relation, as that of cause and effect, or of antecedent and consequent ; or of some re- semblance, in which last may be included similarity as to time, or place ; and, by a slight extension, this will also embrace contiguity in time and space. But what- ever the rule, or principle of association, it seems that through it, an idea, or sensation in the present may suggest others in the past without any effort. The sen- sation I now have of a tree in sight recalls, or causes me to remember a sensation I had last week of a tree then in sight ; and this again suggests the fruit I saw upon it, &c. In this case, through external agencies- agencies not of the mind — the past knowledge has been OF MIND. 15 brought within reach of the simple mental perception. As in the case of simple sensation, the mind has been the recipient of knowledge without any active agency of its own ; and hence the case afibrds no ground to suppose an active agency in its memory, or in any other of its attributes. These views seem to justify the conclusion that the mind has but one real faculty, or power to do anything, and this faculty is designated by the term will ^ that with this power it has a susceptibility to feeling, and also a capacity, or sense of simple mental jDerception, through which it becomes the recipient of knowledge ; and that all knowledge, whether the result of prelimi- nary efibrt, or otherwise, in the last. analysis is a simple perception of the mind, and that all preliminary effort for its acquisition is only to bring about the conditions essential to such perception. We know that we have certain sensations without eff'ort. We attribute some of these to the instrumentality of the bodily senses ; but the sensation is in the mind ; and it is not the bodily sense that Jcnows of its existence. Nor does it require any act of will to know it ; on the contrary, we cannot, by will, avoid know^ing it. Here then is a faculty, or capacity of knowing ; of simple mental per- ception, or assimilation, as independent of the will as sensation itself. To proceed one step further; it is not the l)odily sense which knows the difftrenoe between the sensations of black and white ; or of sound and color ; and we still are not conscious that to know this requires any effb]'t. If we regard general and abstract ideas, in- stead of sensations, we may perhaps without previous effort know that what is, is ; that the whole is greater 16 FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. than its part ; that two parallel lines cannot cross each other ; but we do not thus know that all the angles of every plane triangle are eqnal to two right angles ; to ascertain this, requires effort.* There must then some- where be a point at which acts of will become neces- sary to our acquisition of knowledge ; but the mind cannot by such action determine, or vary the facts, or its own conclusions in regard to them. If it could, it would then have no idea of absolute truth. The last result ; the finality of the process — the assimilation — being thus independent of the will, must come by the attribute of knowing, i. e. by simple mental percep- tion ; and the object of the effort of the mind is to re- call and so vary and arrange either its previous knowl- edge, or things external to it, that the truths sought will come within the range and scope of its simple per- ceptive power ; such effort, however, is not always needed, sensation sometimes performing this office, or the truths being in themselves obvious to simple per- ception, without effort. For instance, if an effort to remember is the effort to find some idea, which by as- sociation will recall, or lead through other associations to some particular knowledge of the past, this sugges- tive idea may sometimes be brought to mind by exter- nal events through sensation, without our effort ; or it may arise in some train of thought, which we are pur- suing for another purpose, without any intention or any effort to recall the past knowledge. In both cases the knowledge of the past is brought within reach of the mind's simple perceptive sense without effort for that end ; and the memory appears to act spontaneously as an independent power. The facts, however, do not * See Appendix, Note IV. OF MIND. 17 really conflict with the hypothesis that what we term an effort of memory is but a mode of effort of the miud, and that, in its efforts for recalling the past, prying into the future, or investigating abstract truth, it but exerts its own unit-power in different modes, and does not put other powers in action for that purpose. When, for the purpose of ascertaining truth, or of determining action, we call up and examine other knowledge, we deliberate ; and any conclusion, to which we thus come, is a judgment. This process may involve a secondary one of examining, or comparing various simple perceptions, which have resulted from various views of the subject, or from views of different portions of it. We often, and sometimes from the urgencies of the case, examine very hastily, while at others we do it very thoroughly. This leads us to speak of hasty con- clusions and deliberate judgments, the latter being the result of the more full examination of our knowledge relating to the subject. Though this judgment is a re- sult of an effort in the examination of our knowledge, it is immediately incorporated with and becomes a por- tion of it ; in this respect not differing from facts, or any other addition to our knowledge, acquired by mere observation, or simple mental perception without pre- vious effort. From the nature of the examination, or of the subject itself, these judgments vary from the slightest shade of probability to that of demonstrative certainty ; and induce various grades of belief, from that of mere conjecture to confirmed knowledge ; but, such as they are, we are often obliged to act upon them from want of time, or of ability to obtain better. Of knowledge, obviously an important element in all intelligent cause, I will further remark, that I deem 18 FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. the term, in strict propriety, applicable only to those ideas, or perceptions of the mind of which we enter- tain no doubt ; and that it is applicable to such, even though they are not conformable to truth ; for, if we cannot say that we know that of which we have no doubt, there is nothing to which we can apply the term, and it is useless. This is liable to the objection that we may Tcnow what is not true. Knowledge is a certain condition of the mind ; and there is no difi'erence in this condition, whether we have an undoubted belief that 7 X 6 = 41, or that 2x2 = 4; the knowledge that 2x2 = 4, and th.Q fact that 2x2 = 4, are distinct ; and to make the latter a condition of the former is to define, or describe one thing, by attributing to it what belongs not to it, but to another distinct thing, which is unphil- osophical, and leads to confusion. When, however, I speak of the use which the mind makes of its knowledge in connection with its faculty of will, it is generally more convenient to embrace, in the one term, all its opinions and beliefs of every grade of probability, which, in the absence of certainty, it is often obliged to make the basis of action ; and, in such cases, I use the term with this latitude. Metaphysical certainty applies to that order of ideas and perceptions, or to that order of expressions, which we pei'ceive to be necessarily true in their own nature, and the denial of which involves an absurdity, or con- tiadictiou. CHAPTER lY. lilBEKTT, OB FKEEDOM. These terms are, perhaps, as well understood as any by which we could directly define them. The opposing terms are compulsion, control, con- straint and restraint ; and when the term necessity, as the antithesis of liberty, or freedom, is applied to the action of the mind in willing, it must imply that such action is compelled, controlled, constrained, or restrained. The question may arise, whether that which con- trols itself is free, or whether the fact of its being controlled, even though by itself, renders it not free. This question, in our present inquiry, concerns the action of the mind in willing ; but we may say, generally, that everything, in moving, or in acting ; in motion, or in action, must be directed and con- trolled in its motion, or in its action, by itself, or by something other than itself; and that, of these two conditions of every thing moving, or acting ; or in motion, or action, the term freedom applies to the former rather than to the latter ; and if the term freedom does not apply to that condition, it can 20 FEEEDOM OF MIND IN WLLLmG. have no application to the acting, or the action of anything whatever. And hence, self-control is but another expression for the freedom of that which acts, or of the active agent ; and this is in conformity to the customary use and the popular idea of the term freedom. CHAPTER V. OF CAUSE. The word Cause is variously used. I shall use it, m what I deem its most popular sense, as meaning any- thing which produces change. In this sense, four dis- tinct kinds of causes are conceivable : First, such as are both unintelligent and inactive ; as a rock, which arrests the motion of a moving body, causing it to stop, or alter its direction. These we will call inept causes. Secondly, unintelligent, but active causes ; as a heavy body in motion, moving others in its course, but which does not intend, or know the effects it produces. These are motor causes. Thirdly, causes which produce changes by their activity, and which are not only conscious of the clianges, when produced, but can anticipate the effects of their activity, yet do not plan, or design the means, or modes of producing these effects ; as the lower forms of intelligent agents. These are instinctive causes. Fourthly, causes which produce changes by their activity, and not only anticipate and know the effects of their activity, but design and form plans to produce them. Of these God is the type. They are originat- ing^ or designing causes. 22 FEEEDOM OF MIND IN" WILLING. "We might have divided the third class, making two others, one merely knowing the effects after they oc- cur ; the other only anticipating them ; bnt as we know of none in which the two are uncombined, there is no necessity for including them in our classification. I mention the four varieties, just named, as conceiv- ahle and as embraced in the popular notion of cause. Whether they are all real causes may be a question for further inquiry. We have then, of material causes, two kinds, inert and motor. The inert becomes cause only by being first acted upon by the active, or motor cause. Each motor may also be inert cause in relation to other mo- tor causes, as when one motor impinges against another, the effect, in some cases, may not be influenced by the motion of this other, but be the same as if it were inert. We b-ave of intelligent causes also two kinds, the instinctive and the designing. The former of these also becomes cause only by being first acted upon by the latter. The instinctive must first be infoi'med by the designing cause, before it can become cause itself. The designing may include, or be associated with the in- stinctive ; and, sometimes acting without exercising the faculties by which it is cajpahle of designing, manifest itself at such times only as instinctive cause. A definition, or statement is sometimes spoken of— I think improperly — as a cause, of which the logical consequence is the efl'ect ; as, for instance, the equality of the four sides of a square causes those opposite each other to be parallel. Such consequences are necessary, self-existent, or co-existent truths ; which are found, or discovered, and not caused. OF CAUSE. 23 When we speak of time's changes, the expression is ellipticaL We do not mean that the changes are effected by time itself as a canse ; but by those causes of which the effects are gradual, and percep- tible only after the lapse of some considerable periods of time. CHAPTER YL OP THE WILL. It is not unusual to speak of the will as a distinct entity, possessing and exercising certain powers. This produces much confusion in the argument on the " free- dom of the will." It is obviously the mind that wills, as it is the mind that thinks ; and we might with as much propriety speak of a thought, which thinks, as of a will, that wills. In treating of mind (Chap. III.) I have already stated that there is a passive state, in which, without any active agency of its own, it may be the subject of sensations, and the recipient of knowl- edge. Also, that in another condition it seeks, or en- deavors to' produce change by the active exercise of its power. In this the mind is said to will. Of these two conscious states of its existence, that of activity — that in which it strives to produce change — is a state of will- ing. The mind's willing, or its act of will, then, is the mind's effort ; and Will is the power, or faculty of the mind for effort. It is not a distinct thing, or in- strument, which the mind uses, but is only a name for a power, which the mind possesses; and an act of will is that action, or mode in which intelligence exerts its power to do, or to try to do, and manifests itself as cause. The willing, or act of will, is the condition ot OF THE WILL. 25 the mind in efi'ort, and is the only effort of which we are conscious. In each individual the efforts are all by the same active agent — by the intelligent being — by the mind — but are classified as bodily and mental efforts ; the former being subdivided into efforts of the arm, the lungs, &c. ; and the latter into efforts of memory, of judgment, of imagination, &c.* Mind — intelligence — has no property, or attribute by which it can be inert cause. It may be the passive subject of change by other active agencies, but can it- self be the cause of change only by the exercise of its power, i. e. by an effort. The existence of any mind with certain powers, may be among the circumstances which other intelligent agents take into consideration in their action, but it is only by its own effort that itself can do anything — that it can of itself produce any change, or be cause, f The mind has two very distinct spheres for the exer- cise of its activity — for its effort. In one it seeks to acquire knowledge ; in the other to mould the future. In the first it analyzes, combines and compares its ideas; observes the present external ; recalls the past, and, by this use of its present knowledge, acquires more. It can thus not only learn abstract truths, but is enabled, with more or less of certainty, to anticipate the course of events, and to perceive in what it would, by effort, try to alter that course. In both cases it seeks to affect the future ; but in one case the effect is confined to changes in its own knowledge, to ascertain, or find what now is, has been, or will be ; in the other, it seeks to affect the succession of events, to change what now is and influence what will be. * See Appendix, Note V. f See Appendix, Note VI. 2G FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. By means of its prophetic power, the mind reaches into that future in which by effort it seeks to produce effects. The success, or failure of the effort, however, cannot in any way affect the effort itself, which already has been. To the effects which the mind, by its ac- tivity, or effort, produces, it has the relation of cause, whether these effects were, or were not intended. By its influence upon the future, however proximate, by its active agency in creating that future, mind mani- fests its originating, creative power. In this, its finite sphere, every finite intelligence, of every grade — having the faculty of will — is a finite first cause, as the Su- preme Intelligence is Infinite First Cause, in its sphere of the infinite. The inquiry as to the truth of this po- sition is involved in tbe question, does the finite vntelli- gence will freely f which we are hereafter to examine. CHAPTER YII. OF WANT. The term want is probably better understood than any word, or phrase, which we could select to define, or explain it. Nothing is better known to us than onr wants. "We must, however, in the use of the term, carefully distinguish between the want and the thing wanted ; between that present feeling, or condition, which is a state of want, and which we already have, and tliat which will gratify the want, and which, as yet, we have not. It is to the present condition, that I apply the term. We feel a painful sensation, or emo- tion, and want such change as will give relief. We find that we are ignorant on a point upon which knowl- edge is, or may become useful, and we want to know ; and when, either from past experience, or intuition, we are conscious of the absence of a sensation, we may want that sensation, A sensation, or emotion is not, in itself, a want ; it may exist withont any corresponding want. We may be content with it as it is. I^or is the perceived ab- sence of a sensation, or emotion, of itself, a want ; for we may be content with such absence. To get rid of an unpleasant sensation, which we have, or to induce an agreeable one, which we have not, are often the 28 FKKEDOM OF 3HIND IN WILLING. things wanted, but are not themselves the want. We have the sensation of hunger, and want food, but nei- ther the sensation, nor the food is itself the want. In this case tlie food is the thing wanted, and the sensation is one of the conditions which causes us to want. This sensation, or emotion, in this, as in other cases, is to us an extension of knowledge, which requires on our part no effort. That the idea of change is essential to tbe want is very obvious in cases in which some absent sensation is the thing wanted. When a present sensation is the subject, the want must either be to continue, to discard, or to modify that sensation ; and even the want to con- tinue requires the knowledge, or idea of possible change. So, too, an emotion is not in itself a want ; a joy, which so satisfies the mind that it neither desires, nor thinks of change, cannot be said to be a want. And there is a grief — a holy and unselfish grief — of the elevating and hallowing influences of which we are so conscious, that we would not banish, or modify it. Our admira- tion may be so pleasurably excited by what appears to us already perfect, that no change is suggested, or wanted in the sensation, or the object. Wonder, of itself, in- volves no idea of change, and no want ; and, under the emotion of awe, we reverently shrink from all thought, or anticipation of change. Want involves an idea of change. We must, at least, be able to conceive that by some change in what exists, the pain we feel will be discarded, or the knowl- edge which we seek, or the pleasure we covet be ac- quired ; though we may not know by what means the desired change is to be effected. The existence then, of this idea of change, seems id OF WANT. 29 all cases to be an essential element of want. A man, entirely satisfied with things as they are, cannot prop- erly be said to have a want. It is true, we say, that such a man wants things to remain as they are. The expression is really equivalent to saying he wants noth- ing, i. e. does not want — he is content. If it really expresses any want, it is the want of such change as will ensure things remaining as they are, and relieve him of any apprehension that they may not so remain. Tins can amount to no more than that, to make certain the continuance of some things as they are, he wants change in some other things ; which is to say, he is not satisfied with things as they are. It may be convenient to classify wants into primary, or those the gratification of which is the final object, or end in view ; and secondary, or those which relate only to the intermediate means of snch gratification, and to what is not in itself wanted. A man, in imminent dan- ger, to get to a safe place, may want to walk, though every step is painful: to reach the place of safety is the primary want ; to walk, in such case, the second- ary. The lust of power is, perhaps, always a second- ary want ; being wanted not for itself, but as a means of gratifying other wants. These secondary wants, however, seem also to belong to the mind's perception of the means of gratifying its primary wants, and, as such, may with as much propriety be classified with its knowledge as with its wants. They are knowledge, or at least belief, that by some act, perhaps not in it- self wanted, that which is wanted may be attained. Again, wants may be divided into natural, acquired and cultivated. Natural wants aie those which are innate, constitutional. Hunger, or the want of food is 30 FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. a natural want. But we may want to be liuagry for the sake of the enjoyment which attends its gratifica- tion ; and this want to be hungry, supposing it to grow out of the acquired knowledge that hunger is a basis of the enjoyment, may be said to be an acquired want. If we take exercise, or adopt other means to induce the want of food, such want may be said to be a cultivated want ; and from this low, material form, our cultivated wants may rise to the most ethereal aspirations of our aesthetic, moral and religious nature. We speak of them merely as cultivated, for they still have their root in the constitution of our being ; and we only use our knowledge of means to bring them out, or give them vitality and force, when they would, otherwise, be dor- mant or sluggish. That which we have spoken of as a secondary want, is a consequence of our perception of what is necessary to gratify a primary want ; and is thus the offspring of the primary want, and the knowledge of the means of gratifying it. As our primary wants and knowledge may exist without our volition, the conse- quent secondary want also may. We cannot, by an act of will, directly change the perceived fact, or our knowledge of the means essential to a particular result. The natural, or innate want is obviously not an effect of volition. An acquired want must result from some increase of knowledge. If we made efibrt, and increased our knowledge for the purpose of acquiring this want, we must have previously wanted it, and the acquired want, in such case, was, before its acquisition, the thing wanted, and not the want which we sought to gratify. If we accidentally acquired such want without OF WANT. 31 intending it, it has come witliont our v/ilKng it ; and though it may have been a consequence of our efforts for some other purpose, it is such a consequence as we did not foresee, and for which we liave made no effort. It may be such a result as, had we foreseen it, we would have opposed ; but not having foreseen it, it is an effect, which we have neither favored, nor opposed. As the influence of an actually existing want upon the will is not varied by the source, or cause of its existence, it will not, in treating of it in this connection, often be necessary to allude to these distinctions. CHAPTER YIII. OF MATTER AS CAUSE. Whatevek changes take place in matter must arise from its motion, either massive, or atomic. But matter has no power to move itself ; and lience cannot become cause of such change, except by first being in motion ; and, even if imbued with locomotive powers, would have no knowledge to direct its movements to produce any gwen effect ; and, if possessing both these attri- butes, being destitute of sensation and emotion, would have no inducement to make effort to produce any ef- fect, supposing it also to liave a faculty of will. It is plain then, that matter cannot be an originating cause, even of its own movements ; and hence, if changes in it ever had a beginning, they must have originated with intelligence. I say, if they ever had a beginning ; but we have still to inquire whether matter, even if or .e put in motion, could pi-oduee effects, or change other matter, or be affected, or changed by other matter, from the mere circumstance of its being itself in motion ; in short, whether, in motion, matter becomes cause^ origi- nating effects, or prolonging, or extending the effects of any intelligent action, which may have put it in mo- tion. The mere change of place by motion* cannot * See Appendix, Note VII. OF MATTER AS CAUSE. 33 be considered as an effect of motion, bnt, rather, as tlie motion itself. If it is an effect of motion, cause and effect are here blended in one. The only reason why matter in motion can become cause of any other effect than that which took place immediately on the com- mencement of its motion, is, tliat by time and motion the circumstances become changed, though matter can- not intend, or know of this change. If, with motion, it can become cause, then, though it never could have commenced its own motion, yet, as in considering intel- ligence as cause, we are obliged to regard it, in the ab- stract, as a necessary existence, which had no beginning, so we might also suppose that matter had been in mo- tion from eternity, and hence always had in itself caus- ative power. Whether matter in motion, can of itself produce ef- fects, seems to depend inainly on another question, viz.: Does matter in motion, of necessity, have a tendency to continue in motion, or to stop the moment it is relieved from all impelling power ? If I throw a ball, after it leaves my hand I can no longer control it ; I make no effort to control it ; it continues to move even though my attention is wholly withdrawn from it. But whether it does so move, because to stop requires change which, being mere matter, it cannot effect ; or whether it continues to move in conformity to a law, which the Supreme Intelligence has adopted for its own govern- ment, and by which, in certain cases, it uniformly exe- cutes the decree, or causes certain effects to follow the effort of the finite mind, even after that effort has ceased ; in brief, whether it continues to move by its own inherent material force, or by the action upon it of 2* 34: FKEEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. an invisible intelligence, or cause, is a question, which I can find no means of determining. A particle of matter can begin no change in itself. When put in motion does it require change in itself to stop, or to continue its motion ? If the former, then a moving body has in itself the amount of power which is required to stop it ; and when it comes in collision with another body, as the two, by a law of metaphysi- cal necessity, cannot occupy the same space, some effect must be produced ; for instance, if moving in opposite directions, in the same line, one must be stopped, or turned back, or if the forces are equal we may, perhaps, infer that both must of necessity stop. The ball thrown obliquely, after leaving my hand, if in vacuum, moves in a parabolic curve; or if resisted by the air, in an irregular curve. This, in either case, involves a continued cham,ge of direction, and it may be asked how matter, undirected by intelligence, can con- form its changes of direction to these curves, or indeed, how change its direction at all ? If, however, matter in motion has power to stop, retard, or change the motioa of other bodies ; or is liable to be stopped, retarded, or changed by them, it is conceivable, as has been sug- gested, that such change may be produced, and the pro- jectile kept in the particular curve by particles of mat- ter moving through space, and impinging on one side of the projectile, while the earth protects the other side from similar influence ; once admit the self-existent, or inherent force, and its application is quite conceivable. The line of motion is changed from the parabolic to the irregular curve by the body itself impinging against the particles of the atmosphere. As any force of matter in motion depends upon its OF MATTER AS CAUSE, 35 supposed tendency to continue in motion ; and it being evident that some of the bodies, coming in direct oppo- sition to each other with equal force, must be stopped ; and that matter has no power to put itself in motion again, it follows that the power of that portion thus stopped is annihilated ; and the power of matter being thus continually diminishing, must, with sufficient Urae^ be eventually destroyed, or, at least, be reduced to an infinitesimal quantity.* But, if matter is an originating cause, or power, in- dependent of intelligence, it must, as we have before shown, be so in virtue of having been in motion from all eternity ; and hence, there having been sufficient time, its power, from the cause just mentioned, must have been destroyed. It follows then, that any power which matter may now have, in consequence of its being in motion — supposing it to have any — must be either the result of its having been put in motion within a finite time by intelligence, or from intelligence subse- quently sustaining and renewing the motion, which may have been from eternity.f If this supposed power of matter in motion were left to act uncontrolled by intel- ligence, its blind activity would accelerate its self-de- struction, and must, in some instances, counteract itself by opposition, while in others its effects would be in- creased by co-operation of the forces. The observed uniformity of material effects is inconsistent with this blind exercise of power ; indicating that, even if matter now has, or has had power of itself, as cause, to produce effects, it has been subjected to an intelligent control — to a designing cause — and that all such effects are now the result of intelligent action. * See Appendix, Note VIIL f See Appendix, Note IX. 36 FKEEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. The argument on this point may be thus stated : admitting the existence of matter as a distinct entity ; and that it has always existed, we know, as a fact of observation, tliat the motion of one portion is always affected and often destroyed in producing effects upon other portions. Now, further admitting, that its origi- nal state was that of motion, it must always have been with its present conditions, or the original conditions of its motion must have been changed. If it com- menced with the present conditions, which would con- tinually lessen its motion, then, with sufficient time, and an eternity must be sufficient, its motion would be destroyed, or reduced to an infinitesimal and inappre- ciable quantity ; and hence, on this supposition, the in- terference of some other — of intelligent cause — must have been necessary to sustain anj appreciable power in matter, as cause. And if we adopt the other hypothesis, that its mo- tion was originally subject to other conditions than those which are now observed, then this change in its conditions, or mode of action, could not have been effected by matter itself, but must be attributed to in- telligence, as the only other conceivable cause. So that, whether matter in motion was, or was not, origi- nally subject to its present conditions, its present in- fluence, by means of motion, must result either from intelligence sustaining its motion, or from its controll- ing that which is inherent. And, except on the hypo- thesis that the tendency of matter once put in motion is to continue in motion and n(jit to stop, this control by intelligence must be direct and immediate ; for upon no other hypothesis can intelligence make matter a means of producing or even of prolonging effects, after OF MATTER AS CAUSE. 61 its own action upon it is discontinued. The matter would stop when that action left it, and no change would take place in it till further action of intelligence again moved it. JSIor, without the further hypothesis that the effects of matter in motion are necessary, can we either sup- pose that without the power of selection — without pur- pose — these effects would either be uniform, or yet vary in any respect. They must arise from the neces- sities of the case ; as, for instance, the impossibility of two impinging bodies occupying the same space ; and some effect must thus be absolutely necessary,- or none would be produced. Still, as in most, if not all con- ceivable cases, more than one effect seems possible, as when two bodies impinge, both may stop, or one turn back ; some power which can select, seems essential to the uniform ordering of the effects. This consideration exj)oses one difficulty in supposing that which is unin- telligent to be cause at all ; or to be anything more than an instrument used by an intelligent cause. Nor could intelligence make matter cause, or increase its causative power, and make it capable of selecting its own effects, or of beginning a change, or a series of changes, by impressing laws upon it for its govern- ment ; for, to be governed immediately by law, pre- supposes a knowledge of the law, i. e., intelligence on the part of the governed. If all matter were at this moment quiescent, it could not of itself, in virtue of any law, begin a change. To do this it must move itself. But more especially could it not so move itself as to produce a particular effect at a particular time. This would require it not only to have power to move itself, but to know when to move. 38 FREKDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. and how to direct its movement ; all which, as matter is inert and unintelligent, is contradictory, and hence impossible even to infinite power. All that can be meant when we refer an event to the " nature of things," or to the " laws of nature " is, that the intelligence, which causes these events, is itself the subject of laws, under which it acts uniformly in its changes of matter ; and all those changes in matter, which begin to be, must be attributed to the action of spirit ; and, of course, such of them as are not caused by a finite, must be referred to the action of the Infinite Intelligence. And however difficult the conception may at first ap- pear, there seems no way to avoid the necessity of this constant exercise of creative energy to begin change, or produce uniform results ; or the conclusion that every particle which floats in the breeze, or undulates in the wave ; every atom which changes its position in conformity to the laws of electrical attraction and re- pulsion, or of chemical affinities, is moved, not by the energizing^ but by the energetic will of God.* From these views we may infer that matter cannot, without the aid of intelligence, be an active cause even of changes in itself. It can produce no activity in itself, and any imparted activity is diminished in producing effects ; nor can it, even if in virtue of a derived ac- tivity it becomes an active cause, select and effect such changes as will conform to the will and wants of intelli- gence ; nor yet directly impart activity to it as one body appears to do in regard to another ; though, as desirable, it may be the object, and, as admitting of desirable changes in itself, it may be the subject of intelligent action. Any observed changes of matter * See Appendix, Note X. OF MATTER AS CAUSE. 39 vary the circumstances presented to the intelligence, which, in virtue of its power to judge of and to con- form to these circumstances, varies its action accord- ingly. In this way, one intelligence havhig the power to produce changes in matter, may, by such changes, influence the action of another intelligence ; but, in such case, matter is but a means, a mere instrument, by which one intelligence communicates with, or produces effects on another, and not a cause of those efiects.* It is true that we loosely speak of matter, or of cir- cumstances, as cause ; and to this we have been led by observing the uniformity with which certain phenomena follow certain conditions, or changes of matter. We generalize the facts, deduce the law, and then ascribe directly to that law what we should ascribe to the in- telligence whose uniform action makes, or is the ground of our inferring, the law. Science has now made us so familiar with these generalizations, called secondary causes, that we habitually accept them as the ultimate of our inquiries, without tracing them to a first cause, that can begin a sei-ies of effects. Even su]3posing that matter has been in motion from all eternity ; that the tendency is to continue in motion and not to stop ; and consequently that it has power to produce effects, and that this power continues undiminished througli all time ; still, as these efiects must be necessary efiects, and matter has no power to vary them, they may be of necessity, as they are in fact, uniform, not less so than if produced in conformity to the laws, which the Supreme Intelligence, on the other hypothesis, has adopted for his government of matter ; and hence, by observation, we may learn * See Appendix, Note XI. iO FREEDOM OF MIND DST WILLING. equally well to calculate on the certainty, or proba- bility of the etf(!cts ; and, as in either case they make but a part of the circumstances on which the finite in- telligence acts, whether the causes of these circum- stances are material or intelligent, can make no difter- ence to the intelligent cause, which is to act in con- junction with such other causes, or in view of the changes by them, which it can anticipate. The change of circumstances actually produced, or expected, will have the same influence on the mind in willing, or upon its freedom in willing, if produced by the one cause as if by the other. If all matter were quiescent, then the action of in- telligent cause to produce change on it would be to move it. If it were in motion, producing changes in an established order, which the acting intelligence could anticipate, then the action of the intelligent cause must be to vary this established order ; and the problem, as to its proper action to produce a given result, becomes more difficult and intricate, requiring the exercise of more contrivance, or of judgment to determine that action ; but whether that established order of external changes arises from the necessary eflects of matter in motion, or from the free efforts of some intelligent cause, designing such uniformity as will admit of its effects being anticipated, can make no diflference to the intelligence, which makes effort; to vary that known established order. Again, if all matter were quiescent, it could not begin motion in itself, and, of course, could not be cause. If it were in motion, it could not determine or select its own effects, and if certain consequences of necessity resulted, it would have no power to vary, or OF MATTKE AS CAUSE. 41 to produce changes in those consequences, and so far could not be cause. That which produces effects, which it cannot but produce, must be constrained to produce them by some power which it cannot control ; and, in such case, the power which constrains is more properly the cause, and the subject which is constrained, its in- strument. It appears, then, that matter cannot possibly be cause, except by means of motion ; and whether it can then become cause depends upon the question, as to its tendency to continue in motion, or to stop, which is undetermined. But if, with motion, it has power to effect change, still, every application of that power to an effect, diminishes it ; and as to make matter an inde- pendent cause, and not merely an instrument used by some other cause, we must consider it as having been in motion from all eternity, this diminution by use must have exhausted its causative power ; and further, that in any event, if matter be quiescent, or if it be in motion, producing changes in a necessary estab- lished order, it cannot be a cause of changes either in that quiescent, or yet in the established order of changes ; or begin any new series of changes ; and that, to effect such changes, or to begin any new series of changes, spirit is the only competent power or cause. CHAPTER IX. OF SPIRIT AS CAUSE. In postulating thought and effort, we have already assumed the inherent activity of spirit, that is, its power to produce changes, or, at least, to endeavor to do so. If we have now shown that matter caimot, in the proper sense of the word, be cause, or have an inherent and inhering power to produce change, or that it could not retain such power ; and that it cannot originate or begin a series of effects, or, of itself, have retained any power to continue an established series, or yet to alter such established series ; we must infer that spirit, if not the only real, is an indispensable cause. The question next arises, whether this causative power of spirit is all concentrated in one Supreme Intelligence, or whether there is a sphere in which the finite intelligence is also an active, originating cause, using its attributes to create, or change, uncontrolled by the Infinite, or any external power. This question is closely connected with the main question which we are to consider, and, at this stage of the ai'gument, we can only state our position, viz. : That one Supreme Intelligence has power, and, if He chose, might exert the power to create and sustain all that exists in the sphere of the infinite. But that, OF SPIEIT AS CAUSE. 43 within this infinite sphere, He has allotted a finite sphere for the action of finite intelligences ; that He has adapted that sphere to tlie action of such finite in- telligences, by furnishing it with circumstances, and by conforming His own actions to such uniform modes, that the finite intelligence, acting either through the power of the infinite tlms uniformly exerted, or with reference to His futnre action, may be able to anticipate the result of its own efforts, and to direct those efforts, or to will, accordingly. The human intelligence thus acts freely with the assent and co-operation of the in- finite ; unaided by wliich, though possessed of powers similar to the infinite, its action would be restricted within very narrow limits. Let us more particularly note this similarity of kind and variation in degree. God is omnipotent ; man has finite power. God is omniscient ; man has finite knowledge of the present and past, and can, in some degree, anticipate the future. G od is omnipresent ; man has faculties by which lie can make everything within his finite sphere of knowledge, past, present, and future, present to himself ; and, therefore, may be said to have a finite ^Dresence commensurate with his knowl- edge, i. 6., man has a finite presence, which has the same relation to omnipresence, that his knowledge has to omniscience."* God has a creative power, and this seems to be fully embraced in the faculties of thought, imagination, and conception, with, the power of fixing the thoughts, imaginings, and conceptions, in His own mind, and making them palpable to others, either im- mediately, by transferring this thought and imagery directly to finite minds, or mediately, by depicting oi *■ See Appendix, Note XII. 4:4: FREEDOM OF ISOND IN WILLING. forming them in matter, and thus making them palpa- ble to other intelligent, percipient beings. If matter, as a separate substance, exists, and was not created by, but is co-eternal with intelligence, then all the creative power of God, as manifested in the material universe, may be confined to mere changes in matter ; and man has the same power in a finite measure. If there is no such separate existence as matter, then material crea- tion is but the imagery of the mind of God made palpa- ble to us ; and man here, also, has the same creative power in a finite measure. The creation of matter, as a substance distinct from spirit, seems to be entirely beyond the power of man. He has no faculty even to conceive of any possible mode of such creation. But, as all material phenomena can be as well accounted for, without supposing matter to be created, by either of the two modes just suggested, i. e., either by considering matter as co-external with spirit, or as an emanation, or a mere efiect of the action of intelligence, we cannot, from its existence or phenomena, infer that it was created. And if we cannot conceive of any possible mode of its creation, nor infer such creation from its existence, nor from any of the phenomena of its exist- ence, we can have no proof that any being possesses the power to create it ; and the phenomena of the material creation furnish no proof of any great attri- bute of the Infinite mind, which is not also found, in some degree, in the finite. Whether, then, we adopt the one or the other of the two hypotheses of creation just alluded to, the creative power of any being, so far as we can have any knowl- edge of it, is all embraced in these two powers, to both of which knowledge is a prerequisite, — first, that of OF SPIKIT AS CAUSE. 45 thinking, imagining, or conceiving the forms, appear- ances, relations, and changes, which constitute creation : and secondly, that of impressing these forms, and ap- pearances, and relations, and changes upon its own and upon other minds. Tlie finite mind has both these powers in a limited degree, and, we should say, the latter in less proportion than the former. The finite intelligence can collect all within its sphere of knowledge, and, by analyzing and recombining, form for itself such a nev/ creation at will, as, on delibera- tion, its judgment or fancy may dictate. It forms this creation first in idea, in its own mind, and then decides whether or not to make further efi'ort to give perma- nency, or outward actuality, to these internal creations. The limit of its knowledge is the boundary of that finite sphere, in which the finite intelligence, with its co-ordinate finite presence, is creative with its finite power and its fallibility, as the Supreme Intelligence, with its omnipresence, its infinite power and its infalli- bility, is creative in its infinite sphere. Every time a finite intelligence, by an act of will, forms a conception of thought, things, and circumstan- ces, in new combinations, or in new relations ; that is, every time, by effort, he conceives change in the phenomena within his finite sphere of knowledge, it is to him a new creation of his own, which, by other efforts, other exercise of will, other creations, he may, at least in some cases, make palpable or depict to other intelligences. I will add that this creative power is exerted by the finite in the only way in which we can conceive of its exercise by the Infinite Intelligence, and under the same conditions. Either must exert the power from a desire 46 FEEEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. to produce some change, from a feeling of want. By means of its knowledge, or by the exercise of its know- ing faculties, it is enabled to form conceptions of the effects of its contemplated efforts before it puts them forth, and to vary these conceptions till it finds one adapted to the want ; and, in the case of the finite mind, one which it su]jposes is within the scope of its finite means and power to actualize by its finite efforts. This often makes a very complicated problem, in which all the powers of the mind find an appropriate and im- proving exercise. It is in the mind's preconceptions of the effects of its efforts, in relation to its previous wants, that it finds the reason for its action. It may be said, that the creative power in finite in- telligences is of a secondary character, and limited to producing changes, or new combinations, in the crea- tions of the Supreme Intelligence. In regard to mat- ter, if a distinct entity, tliis is merely saying that we mould our thoughts, or conceptions in the same mate- rial which God has previously used for a like purpose. Any of us can imagine a landscape, and vary it as we choose. We can even imagine a universe, and one varying from that which is the subject of our observa- tion. We can conceive of one in which all the bodies should be in the form of cubes, cones, double cones, or prisms, &c., &c., and all stationary, or moving in orbits, hexagonal, or epicycloid al, &c., &c. ; and this, for the time being, is, to him who conceives it, a new creation, perhaps distinguishable from that creation which, not resulting from his own efforts, is without him, only by the fact that one is subject to be changed or annihilated by his own effort or will, or by his ceas- ing to will, and the other is not. It" the material uni- OF SPIRIT AS CAUSE, 47 veyisri in but the thouglit and imagery of the mind of God, made directly palpable, it no doubt is in the same manner subject to change and annihilation by an act of His will, or a suspending of it. So far as the indi- vidual is concerned, the imagery, which he, by his finite powers, has willed into existence, is, while he so wills its existence, a real creation.* But when we at- tempt to transfer this imagery of our own to other minds, we find that our power of doing so is very limit- ed in regard to the amount of imagery we can so trans- ■ fer ; the completeness or precision of the transferred images, and the number of other minds upon which we can impress them. Though we may have created the imagery by a direct act of will, we cannot thus transfer it to other minds, but only by slow, circuitous and ten- tative processes or eiforts ; some, however, doing it with much more facility than others. We can, by eftbrt, change matter with more or less of accuracy, in conformity to certain ideas in our minds ; and the change, under certain conditions, will be im- pressed on the minds of some others. The rudest and least gifted intellect can do something of this ; while superior genius is able, not only to conceive of the grand, the beautiful, the tranquil, or the terrific, but to make these creations recognizable and enduring by so portraying them in language, picturing them on can vas, or carving them in marble, that they will long be palpable to many other minds. But, to make the con- ceptions of a Raphael thus palpable, requires an almost countless number of efibrts, before the pre-requisite con- ditions, by which it is perfected and exhibited on the * See Appendix, Note XIIl. 48 FREEDO:*! OF MIND IN WILLING. canvas, are completed — before his creation becomes a palpable, tangible reality to other men ; though superior intelligences may have perceived the oi'iginal forma- tion, as it existed in his mind, without the aid of the external means, by which it penetrates through our ob- tuseness. The Unite intelligence may create new forms and new combinations. It can conceive a pleasing land- scape, and therein create not only new combinations, but new thouglit and new beauty, and exhibit it to others. The poet, through the medium of language, does this. The painter, with his pencil, also. The florist, with his spade, does the same. All create new forms, new combinations, new beauty ; and, by their different modes, impress their creations on other minds. The efforts of the florist are most palpably made in reference to the aid of the Supreme Intelligence, acting by uniform modes, of which he has acquired a knowl- edge, and by which liis own designs are executed, — his finite efforts made eflective. But the painter is really hardly less dependent upon this same extrinsic aid, for the successful exhibition of his ideal creations, in a tangible form, to others. The poet, though still dependent on this uniformity for the means of making his conceptions palpable, seems to be less so than either of the others. There is less intervening between his conceptions and our percep- tions of them. He issues the fiat, " let there be light," and his creation flashes upon us. It is in the purest forms of poetry — those in which the words seem to vanish and leave the unalloyed thought and imagery of the poet, as if flowing directly from his mind OF SPIRIT AS CAUSE. 49 to our own — tliat we can most readily realize that mode of creation in the Supreme Intelligence, which we have supposed to be a direct impression of the creative conceptions of the Infinite upon the finite mind. Whether our mental creations ai*e made palpable by means of some direct, but unperceived connection be- tween our eftbrts and their outward manifestation, or through the uniform modes of God's action, is not 'material as to the question of our power to make them manifest. If such manifestation only follows our efforts, it identifies the power to froduce the effect, with oui power to 7nake the effort. But the finite mind, in its present condition, can thus impart, and give, even a qualified durability to a very small portion of its con- ceptions. Whether, in a farther stage of its progress, this means of imparting to othei-s will be increased, as its present disproportion to our powers of conception would seem to indicate, is a question not within the scope of our present inquiry ; and we content ourselves with the conclusion, that here and now, the finite mind of man, made in the image of God, has finite powers corresponding to omnipotence, omniscience, omnipres- ence, and other creative attributes of the Infinite ; and, so far as we can know, exerts these powers in the same mode and under the same conditions ; that is,, it has wants, it has a faculty of efibrt, or will, by which to endeavor to gratify those wants ; and it has knowledge, which enables it to form preconceptions of the future efi'ects of those eff'orts, and to judge as to what effort to make, and thus determine that effort and the consequent effect, as in itself a ceeative first CAUSE.* * See Appendix, Note XIY. 50 FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. Whether the finite mind, in the exercise of these powers, Is independent of, or is controlled by the In- finite, or by other powers, or forces, is a question in- volved in that of the freedom of the mind in willing, which we will now proceed to consider. CHAPTER X. FKEEDOM OF INTELLIGENCE. As the will is veiy frequently spoken of as a distinct entity, so, as a logical consequence, it is not uncommon to speak of the " freedom of tlie will." This opens the way for the argument, that the will is dependent upon, and is controlled by the mind ; and, hence, is not free, producing much confusion ; whereas, the real question, and that which involves the inq)ortant consequences of human responsibility, regards ordy the freedom of the being that wills — whose responsibility is supposed to be affected by the condition of freedom, or necessity. The inquiry should tlien be, not is the will free, but, does the mind, the soul, will freely ? In reference to this question, it is not material whether the effect we seek to produce when we will, follows our volition, or not. We may not have the power to do what we w^ill, and yet may freely will to do. There may be no such connection as we supposed between the volition and the intended result ; our knowledge may have been deficient, our deductions erroneous. If that result was in any degree dependent on other causes or forces, as the motion of matter, or the action of other intelligences, we may have been mis- taken in our anticipations of those movements or ac- 52 frei':dom of mind in willing. tions ; or have made wrong inferences, as to their in- fluence or effects. However this may be, it is manifest that the subsequent result cannot control the volition, which already is, or has been ; the actual effect cannot control its cause, aftei that cause has been exerted. Of that mysterious connection between the effort and its consequences, we know nothing beyond the fact that, under certain conditions, the latter more or less uni- formly follow the former. If, in a normal and natural condition of my being, I will to move my hand, it moves. If I will to throw from it a ball, the ball moves and even continues to move after my mind has ceased to act in regard to it. I^ow, whether the move- ment of my hand, and of the ball, while in it, arises from some direct, but latent connection between my mind and my hand ; and whether the ball continues to move, after my mind has ceased to will in regard to it, in virtue of some power inherent in matter or some necessary principle of motion ; or whether, all beyond my willing is to be ascribed to the action of some other intelligence, ever present and ever active and efficient, are questions which I have already alluded to as unde- termined. The last we know of our own agency in producing change, is our act of will, or effort to effect it. We know that the change follows this willing with more or less of certainty ; but why it so follows we do not know. We may intuitively or experimentally fore- know what effects will probably follow certain efforts but, beyond the effort, we know nothing of ourselves as the cause of these effects. For every intelligent act, or every act of an intelli- gent being, as such, there must be an object, a reason for its acting, rather than its not acting. To suppose in- FEEEDOM OF IJSfTKLLIGENCK. 53 telligeiice to act, and yet not know an j object or reason for its acting, is to suppose it to act without intelli- gence, and if there is no intelligence involved, or (con- cerned in the act, the action, if any there can be, must be wholly independent of the intelligence ; or, which is the same thing, of any exercise of intelligence by the hitelligent agent or being ; wliich, in the case of its willing, would involve the contradiction of its being passive in its own action. It would also make a case in which that which is unintelligent moves itself. To suppose any being to will any particular act, and yet know no reason or object for that act, is either to suppose a change, or an efiect, without any cause ; or that this act of will is directed by some cause, without the being that wills. But, as will hereafter more fully appear, there is no possible way in which any power, external to the agent that wills, can affect the dirc^'tion of this willing, except by causing him to know some reason, or object for such direction. Intelligence in acting, then, must have an object. The object of its action must be an effect which it wants to produce. The mind, acting intelligently, will not make an effort, or will to produce an effect, which it does not want to produce. Every volition, then, must arise from the feeling or ]Derception of some want, bodily, or mental ; otherwise there is no object of effort. This want may be that of food, of knowledge, of muscular movement, or of mental effort, in some of the various modes before indicated, or merely a want of change from the present state of things. But though the want suggests change, it does not indicate the mode of effecting it. A mere sensation, or perception, attended by a 54 FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. desire for change, but with no knowledge as to the mode of producing that change, points equally in all directions, furnishing to the mind no indications of the means of effecting the change. It, so far, furnishes no ground or reason to the mind to suppose that effort is the means, or that any particular effort will tend to the desired effect, any more than to the contrary. The mind must have some additional knowledge as to the mode. With the want, which, as before stated, is com- pounded of feeling and the knowledge that some change is desirable, must be associated the further knowledge of what change, and the means of effecting that change. The knowledge that effort is the means by which we must effect change generally, is innate ; as probably also all that knowledge which is essential to existence, and especially that which is thus essential in the earlier stages of being. If the first want is that of breath, or of food, the knowledge of the means of gratifying it probably accompanies the want. The infant breathes, and knows, at least, how to swallow, if it does not also know how to find the source of its nourishment in its mother's breast, and later in life want is developed, with which, without any agency of our own, is as- sociated the knowledge of the mode of its gratifi- cation. Again, as the circumstances under which the want may exist may be very different, thei-e must be some power of adaptation to them. Suppose, for instance, a man being hungry, knows that by walking a few steps to the north he can find bread to relieve his want ; but he becomes hungry when he is in a different position, requiring liiin to walk a few steps south to get the bread. The first step, in such cases, when the know!- FKEEDOM OF INTELLIGENCE. 55 edge is not an immediate mental perception, is to ex- amine the circumstances. This is a preliminary efi'ort of the mind to obtain more knowledge with which to direct its final action. But this efi'ort also requires some previous knowledge. We must know something before we will to know more. As preparatory to such eflbrt, we must at least know that more knowledge is desirable, and that to examine is tlie mode of acquiring it. And this previous knowledge must eitber be intui- tive, or acquired through the senses without effort. In the latter case its acquisition would be merely acciden- tal, and the mere passive observation of events is so en- tirely different from an effort to examine, that tlie latter could never be inferred or learned from the former ; and if so, then the knowledge that we must examine the circumstances, in order to know how to adapt our final effort to them, is probably intuitive. If it is not, the infant, in seeking its mother's breast, must do it by knowledge imparted to it in each particular' case as it occurs, and adapted to the peculiar circumstances of that case. If we suppose it only to know the mode of muscular movement, and that, under any circum- stances, it may succeed, by moving its head, or turn- ing its eyes, first in one way and then in another, till it finds the right direction, such movements of the head, or of the eye, are but modes of examining the circumstances in regard to which there must have been some pre-existing knowledge, at least, that by snch movements there is a possibility of finding the object sought, i. e., must know that an effoi't to examine is the mode of attaining its ob- iect. If the mind has no knowledge in any degree, — no expectation — that by effort it can accomplish the 56 FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. object, it is, to it, the same as if it had no object of its effort. It may be only the knowledge, that we need more knowledge properly to direct the effort to gratify the want, or that, by effort, we may possibly effect some change, which change may possibly be a desirable one. With such certainty, probability, or hope, we make the efibrt, i. e., we will. We have here, then, in want and knowledge com- bined, the source in which volitions originate, and the means by which mind, in virtue of its intelligence, gives them direction. Without want, the mind would have no object to accomplish by effort ; without knowl- edge, it would have no means of directing its efforts to the accomplishment of that object. Without want and knowledge, the mind would never manifest itself in effort, or self-action ; and hence, if without them it could be cause at all, it would be only blind cause, like matter. Its want furnishing an object of action, and its knowledge, enabling it to determine ^<:7Aa^! action, are all that distinguish the mind from unintelligent cause, or force ; for even if without them it could will at all, it would will blindly, as matter moves, and without any more reference to its effects. As want is compounded of feeling and knowledge, these sources of volition are resolvable into an intelligent or knowing being, with a faculty of will and a susceptibility to feeling ; in other words, into a cause^ which itself perceives the effect it would produce, i. e., what it would do, or at least try to do ; knows the means, and is conscious of its ability to do, or to try to do it ; and at least believes that its effort may ])ossibly be successful. The want does not, generally, arise from our voli- tion. We may want, we do want, without effort to FKEEDOM OF INTELLIGENCE. 5Y want. The mind could not begin its action by willing a want, unless there was first a want of that want. As already shown, without some want to be gratified by its act of will, the mind would not will at all. It would not will for the mere purpose of exercising its will, unless such exercise of will were itself a previous want ; the want must precede the action of the will to gratify it, and must, in the first place, come by the act of God, immediately, or mediately through the constitu- tion of our being. As we may want without efl:brt, so also we may hnow that we want without effort, for we cannot want without knowing it. It has before been shown that the want itself involves the knowledge of a desirable change, and that some of our knowdedge, and especially some of that which we acquire through the senses, comes to us not only without effort, but could not be prevented by our direct effort. Any intuitive knowledge which we may have, must also exist in us without effort to obtain it. To these pre-requisites of effort — want and knowl- edge — no antecedent effort, then, is necessary. They may both exist without it. We cannot directly will either ; but may will to use means by w^hich to produce them in us. It is not necessarily, by an act of will, that we see and thus hiiow that a heavy body is aj)proaching us, or that we hnoro that we are in danger fVom it, or that we want to avoid it, or that we Ti,noiD the means of avoiding it, and how to adopt the known means, i. e., to make an effort to move. With such knowledge and want, tlie first effort of the mind may be to make the bodily movement ; but, if we suppose it not yet to know in which direction to move, but to know that the mode of learning this is to examine the circumstancefs, 3* 58 FEEEDOM OF MIND IN "WILLING. i. e., by further observation or reflection, then its first effort will be to examine. A want may itself be the object wanted ; we may v)ant a want, as we wmit an apple ; and the want that already is, may be tlie occasion of our willing in regard to the attainment of the want, which is the ob- ject desired ; as the want of the apple is the occasion of the effort to obtain the apple. For instance, we may want to be hungry, i. e., want to want food, that we may enjoy the pleasure which arises from gratifying hunger. In such case we must disti^iguish between the secondary want, which, like the apple, is but the object of our effort, and that primary want, which excited us to make the effort, and for the gratification of which the secondary is required. As the apple is not itself the want, but the thing wanted, so also, in the case just supposed, the hunger, or want of food, is not itself the want, but is the thing wanted. But, though we do not make, or cause, this primary or exciting want, it is our want that we feel, and not the want of another. The same of knowledge ; we do not make the fact, or the truth, or the evidence of it. The most we can do is to seek that which already is ; and the moment we find, or know it, it is our knowledge, let the source from wlience derived be what it may. For intuitive knowl- edge we do not even have to seek. The want is, while it lasts, a fixed existence in the mind, demanding effort for its gratificatioiQ or relief.* The knowledge becomes a portion of the mezital appa- ratus, by which the mind directs its efforts ; every in- crease of its knowledge increasing its means of accom- plishing its purposes and enabling it to direct its efforts * See Appendix, Note XV. FKEEDOM OF INTELLIGENCE;. 69 with less of fallibility to the desired results. To nial^e knowledge most available, or useful, often requires thought, reflection, or deliberation in its application. An exciting want may be accompanied witli a con- sciousness that our knowledge is hisuflicieut, and, in such case, the secondary want of more knowledge inter- venes. We want to ascertain the circumstances, or the best mode of proceeding under them, and our effort is first directed to obtain this knowledge. We examine, we deliberate^ and thereby reach a conclusion or judg- ment. These judgments are but the knowledge, certain or otherwise, as to what is, or what we should do ; ac- quired by preliminary efforts for this object. We ob- serve, we examine, and so arrange our ideas, that the knowledge sought may come within the scope of simple mental perception. As a basis of the whole proceeding, however, there is always a want ; and, of course, with this want as one of its elements, some knowledge (at least the knowledge that by effort more knowledge may be obtained) which required no effort. The feeling, which is one element of the want, is constitutional ; and the knowledge, which is the other element, is in the first instance either innate, or acquired by simple perception, without effort. The preliminary efforts of the mind to obtain knowledge to use in directing its final effort, are but parts of a plan, embracing a series of efforts, to accomplish the final end it has in view. As preliminary to that final act of will, or series of acts, by which the primary exciting want is to be grati- fied, the mind may have to decide — 1. Between its conflicting wants. 2. Between various objects ; the obtaining, or efi'ect- ing some one of which is essential to the gratification 60 FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. of its want ; and tliis is always a change, or eflect to be produced in the future. 3. Among various possible, or conceivable, modes of producing this effect in the future. 4. Whether to make the effort to produce the effect, or not ; and then, if the mind so decides, it proceeds to make the effort in conformity to the preferred mode to produce the selected effect, to gratify the chosen want. The preliminaries, as above, may be settled in other order, and may not all of them be requisite to every final act of will. The fourth decision seems to be very closely associated with the final act of will ; and, per- haps, liable to be confounded with it. But a decision or judgment is but a particular form of knowledge, which is often the result of acts of will, but cannot it- self be such act, or effort. The final act of will comes after the decision to do. If the process ends with the decision to do, there is no room for the willing by the mind, to do that which it has thus decided to do ; and the whole matter is as completely ended by a decision to do, as by a decision 7iot to do. Tlie difference in the two cases is, that a decision to do is followed by a fur- ther action of the mind to execute its decision and effect change in the future ; and a decision not to do is a finality, leaving the mind in a state of quiescence, and not of action. If the decision is itself the act of will, we have nothing to mark the difference in the subsequent mental conditions of action in the one case, and of re- pose in the other. We may suppose a being to know that there are, or may be, several modes of gratifying a want, and yet not know that there is, or may be, a choice among FREEDOM OF INTELLIGENCE. 61 them. Such a being would, no doubt, on feeling the want, adopt the first means it perceived of gratifying it, as though it knew and could know no other. If, in so doing, it adopted the worst mode, it would have been better not to have known it. We all know that this disadvantage sometimes occnrs to us when acting too hastily, without sufficient deliberation, and this expe- rience teaches us the necessity of deliberately examin- ing the facts and the probable results of action, before we act. In the same way, too, we learn that of several wants there may be a clioice as to the order in which they shall be gratified, or whether they shall be grati- fied or not. Hence, from experience, or that knowl- edge which comes after effort, we learn the importance of using, before an effort, what knowledge we then have ; and thus, with the want and knowledge which alone were sufficient to enable the mind to will, and to will intelligently, is associated deliberation, which is a preliminary effort of the mind to obtain more knowl- edge to enable it to will better and more intelligently in its final action, i. e., to produce the desired result of gratifying the want more certainly, more fully, or with less collateral, or consequential disadvantages. Delib- eration being thus but the application of our knowl- edge, in an effort to obtain more knowledge, cannot be considered as a new, but as the same element, used in a preliminary, or intermediate effort, induced by the want of more knowledge. In its every act of will not purely instinctive, or habitual, the mind applies its knowledge, or some of its knowledge, in devising, or adopting a mode of gratifying its want ; and must take some time to make the application at all ; * and the ex- * See Appendix, Note XVI. 62 FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. tended deliberation is only devoting more time to make that application more perfect, or to obtain more knowl- edge to apply. The deliberation is only an examination of our knowledge, generally resulting in a judgment, but is sometimes fruitless. It may be exhaustive, but more frequently it is not, and the quantity of time which shall thus be devoted, in any case, is also a mat- ter for the mind to judge of and to decide, at any point, by the knowledge which it then already has. If we want food, it will not be advisable to spend a month in considering whether it is best for us to eat beef, mutton, or venison ; and yet, perhaps, less time would not suf- fice for a thorough examination. In such cases, the mind judges for itself, bestowing such time as, under the circumstances, seems to it desirable ; the exercise of a proper judgment, in this respect, combining prudence with decision. That the mind has the power to arrest its impulse to gratify its want by the first means it per- ceives, to consider or examine whether there are not better means ; or whether it is proper that tlie want be gratified at all, by whatever means it may have at command ; is a very important fact, making, perhaps, the foundation of one essential difi'erence between in- stinctive and rational action. In turning from the want, knowledge, and the appli- cation of the knowledge, or deliberation, which precede, to that effect, which the mind seeks to accomplish by its effort, constituting its object, we may remark, as an ob- vious fact, we might say, a truism, that we do not onake any effort for what already is. Hence, a beginning, or a design to do what might not otherwise be done ; an endeavor, or attempt to bring to pass what before was not ; to originate some change, which otherwise might FREEDOM OF INTl'XLIGENCE, 63 Qot occur, seeiils involved in tlie very idea of eftbrt. In this view, every volition is an exercise of the creative power of the intelligence that wills ; and when success- ful, results in a creation, formed, with more or less skill and wisdom, from tlie unarranged materials existing in the chaos of circumstances, which this same intelligence perceives, examines, compares, analyzes, and combines in idea, before its final volition is decided upon, — before it determines by what actual construction of these ma- terials it can best effect its purpose, — by what means it can best gratify, or relieve the want, which excited it to action. We have seen that the finite intelligence has all the powers essential to creative action, and also the knowl- edge required to direct these powers. Hence it may of itself use them with intelligent aim. To direct our first efforts, we have sufficient intuitive knowledge, and when this, with any accumulations passively acquired by the knowing sense through external sensation, will not avail, we know that the mode of obtaining more is by an effort to examine. Among the circumstances, the examination of which by the mind may be essential to its proper exercise of these powers, must be included not only the actual present existences around us, but our recollections of past observation and reflection ; our anticipations of the future ; our knowledge of the experience of others and of what others may be doing, or expected to do ; and, especially, of those laws, or uniform modes, by which the Supreme Intelligence regulates His acts of change ; and by, or through, or in conformity to which our own volitions are made effective. Among the circumstances, our opinion as to our ability to execute this or that de- 64 FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. sign, will largely influence us as to tlie effort we con- clude to make. Whether that opinion is, or is not cor- rect, is not material to its influence on the volition. The mind will, in this respect, be influenced in its ac- tion by the internal existing belief, — the present known — and not by the external future faot^ which is unknown, perhaps unanticipated, or even disbelieved. We never will to do, what we know we cannot do. To will an act, I must first linow what act to will. If no particular act appears to me as better adapted to pro- duce the desired efi*ect than another, there is no reason why I should adopt one act rather than another ; and, in such case, my knowledge would only indicate trying any act out of the infinite number of conceivable acts. But, if I know that there is no act that will produce that effect, there is no reason why I should will at all. I could just as well will without any want, as to will when I knew the act of will would have no influence on the want. Under such circumstances there can be no decision of the mind to act, and nothing to be executed by an act of will. The decision to v/ill, is a portion of the mind's knowledge ; and to say one cannot decide to will to do what he knows that he cannot do, is merely saying, that he cannot reconcile the contradiction, and know that he will do what at the same time he hnoius he cannot do. The effort, or trying to do, involves some expectation of doing. If I know the nature of the act. which, if my power were sufficient, would produce the efl'eet, but know that my power is not sufficient, I know that willing such act cannot avail. I, in effect, know that it will no more produce the effect, than any other act, however difi'erent its nature. Under strong im- pulse, men sometimes seem to make efforts which they FREEDOM OF INTELLIGENCE, 65 know will be insufficient to procluco the desired effects. Strong emotion often finds relief by expression in unavailing words ; and a like relief is derived from expression in unavailing action. Sucli relief may be the end rationally designed, or, perhaps, in such case, action is instinctive. If a friend asks me to push aside a mountain of granite, I say I cannot do it ; and if, in compliance with his request to try, I pnsh against it, I still do not will to move it ; but the whole object of my effort, and what I will, is to push against it to please him, and this I pre-perceive to be possible. A man, who can demonstrate the impossibility of duplicating the cube, or of contriving a perpetual motion, may yet will to exercise his wits upon these problems. His effort, however, is not to solve the problems, but, per- haps, by exercise to improve himself in geometry and mechanics ; or to amuse himself thereby. Sometimes persons, in moments of frenzy or desperation, appear to attempt impossibilities. This appearance may arise from various causes. In a pressing exigency, when there is nothing bnt what is highly improbable, things highly improbable may be attemjDted. This is ex- pressed in the ancient adage, " A drowning man will catch at a straw." Or, the object sought may have taken such strong hold on the imagination, or may so exclusively absorb the attention, that the obstacle to its attainment, the impossibility, though ever so palpable to others, is overlooked by the actor. A man in battle, surrounded by an army of his enemies, may act as if to cut his way through them, rather than passively meet the fate he knows to be inevitable ; but, in this case, what he really seeks and wills is not to cut his way through the army, but something else ; perhaps to de- 66 FREEDOM OF MTND IN WILLING. stroy as many of the enemy as possible ; or to get tliat relief, which effort gives by its excitement and by with- drawing his thoughts from his impending doom. Again, the hahit of resistance, or of effort in similar, though less hopeless cases, may have its influence on the action willed. (Of the influence of habit, I shall have occasion to say more hereafter.) So, too, it seems certain, that our belief as to the degree of certainty with which we can attain an object, is one of the circumstances gen- erally taken into the view of the mind in forming its judgment as to what it will try to do, or in what mode it will attempt it. The mind may not always adopt the easiest mode of reaching the ultimate object of its effort. It may be indifferent as to the amount of effort, and hence not seek the easiest mode ; or it may prefer to make more effort than is necessary, and adopt tlie mode which will embrace this intermediate with the ultimate object ; but it mnst always seek to adopt a mode by which what it wants will be accomplished ; and, in do- ing this, the mind must itself judge of the mode, or modes, which it knows, or which, when not immediately apparent, it finds by a preliminary act of search, and, in view of all the circumstances, including its own power, and the pleasure or pain of exercising that power, decide whether to adopt any one, and, if so, which one. These views sliow the necessity of want and knowl- edge as pre-requisites to any effort of the mind. It is, perhaps, sufticiently evident that the mind will make Qo efibrt to do anything which it does not want done ; also, that it will make no effort to do what it wants done, if it knows that such effort will not produce any desirable result ; or even when, without this negative FREKDOM OF INTELLIGENCE. OT certainty, it has no affirmative faitli, or hope of such a result. But, more fully to explain, let us suppose another case. A man feels a sensation, and with it has certain knowledge, constituting a want, say of food ; the intui- tive knowledge which, in the first stage of his existence, indicated the mode of gratifying this want, no longer avails him, and his acquired knowledge must be brought into requisition. But he knows of no way of minister- ing to the want by a direct act of will. He knows that this is impossible, and he now wants to make such effort as will lead, though indirectly, to the desired result. He l&nows that, by examining the circumstances, the means may, perhaps, be found ; and he now wants to examine. This he has the power to do, and on doing it, he finds, from immediate perception, or from the memory of previous perceptions, that there is bread in the baker's shop over the way, or, at least, a probability of its being there ; but he knows of no way of obtaining it by a direct act of will, without being first near to it ; and he now wants to be at the baker's shop ; still, he knows no mode of accomplishing this end by a direct act of will ; but he knows that by a direct act of will he can make and govern the movements of his limbs so as to walk there ; and he now wards to walk there. To meet this want, he has the requisite knowledge and power ; he can will and successively continue to will the movements necessary to walk, and commencing with these, he goes through the several stages of mov- ing himself to the baker's shop, obtaining the bread and applying it to relieve his sensation of hunger. At every stage there was a want demanding effort, but no direct effort to relieve or gratify tlie want, until it was re- 68 FREKDOM OF MIJN'D IN WILLING. duced to one in which thei-e was corresponding Tiiwiol- edge — knowledge of a means, of a plan, by which a so- ries of acts of will, in proper oj-der, would accomplish it. The wants, which arise in forming this plan, are all sec- ondary wants, and may be embraced in the want of the mind to apply its knowledge, or to obtain more knowl- edge to apply. The contrivance, or design, by which the finite mind finds means to reach indirectly, what it cannot by a di- rect act of will, is one mode in which it manifests its creative ]30wer. It is conceivable, that a man with his mind engrossed by some absorbing subject, and at the same time feeling hungry, might have his notions so confused as to move his teeth to chew before he put the food between them. Perhaps most persons have experienced something analogous to this, and all can readily perceive how abortive such efforts must be. Hence we see that, to produce any given efi'ect, it is important that the efforts should be in conformity to some pre-existing plan or design. A single want may thus require not only a number of acts of will, but that they shall be in a certain consecutive order ; and a lit- tle system, as clearly manifesting the orderly arrange- ment of designing cause, as our planetary' system, be created before the original want, which induced the effort, is gratified ; these little separate systems, going to form that universe which every man, by the exercise of his creative powers, is gradually constructing, and in which, as in the stellar universe, some of its consti- tuent parts are continually being formed, while others, having fulfilled the purposes of their existence, are oblit- erated. If, in the case just stated, we suppose the man to know, not that there is bread over the way, but that FREEDOiSr OF INTliLLIGKNCE. 69 there is a baker's shop a short distance in one direction, where there may be bread ; and anotlier shop, farther off, in anotlier direction, where there is a greater prob- ability of finding it ; also, that in another place beef may be had, and fruit in another, then the judgment must be exercised ; the mind must seek, by examina- tion, to find the best mode of effort to get the bread, or to determine whether, in view of all the circumstances, the effort should not be to obtain the beef, or the fruit instead. In such case there is more extended delib- eration. We have already remarked that we do not make effort, or will as to what now is ; neither do we w^ill as to what is past. The object of our effort is always to influence that which is to be — -to produce some effect iu the future. What already is, or has been, has no other effect upon our decision as to the effort to be made, than as our memory of the past and perceptions of the present inci'ease the knowdedge by which we are better enabled to judge as to what effects we should seek to produce in the future, and add to our power and means to produce them. In other words, this knowledge ena- bles the mind to form those preconceptions of the effect of an}' contemplated effort, which are essential to its decision, or judgment, as to what effort it should put forth. The object of willing being always to produce some change in the future, this preconception of the effect of the willing on that future is obviously a very important element. If a man coidd not anticipate some desirable change as the result of his effort, he would not, as a rational and intelligent being, put forth the effort. Pie could have no object of effort and no reason for making it. To will, then, requires that, b\ 70 fei-;edom of mind in willing. means of our knowledge of the past and present, intui- tive or acquired, we be able to obtain a prophetic view of the fnture. This is true of the effort to form these preconceptions. When they are not obvious to simple mental perception, effort is required to form them, and the mind must have some faith, that by effort in exam- ining, it can get the foresight — the knowledge required to form them, or so arrange its knowledge that such preconceptions will become apparent. The knowledge, that by examination we can get the knowledge requi- site for action, as before suggested, is essential to our first actions, and is probably intuiti\^e. As a conception, poetic or logical, of the effects of any contemplated efforts upon the future, is thus essen- tial to the effort, a being, with only sensation and a knowledge of the past and present, would not will. It is only by the God-like power of making the future present, that intelligence. Infinite, or finite, in the exer- cise of its will, becomes creative. By means of this power of anticipating its effects, the mind, in willing, is influenced by the anticipated creations of its own ac- tion, while those creations are still in the future, mak- ing a very broad distinction between intelligent and any conceivable unintelligent cause. It is this fact, that intelligent cause is influenced by its preconceptions of its own effects, that fits it for flrst CAUSE ; for that which is thus, as it were, drawn forward by the futnre, needs no propulsion from the past ; that which i>: moved by inducements before it, does not need a motive influence behind it ; that which acts from its owm internal perception of the effects of its own action upon its own internal, existing want, does not require to be first acted upon by extra- FBEEDOM OF INTELLIGENCE. Yl neous, external forces. It is essential that the want ex- ists, but not material to the action liow it came to exist. If the mind is moved to exert its causal influence in acts of will, bv the consideration of the effects which will succeed^ and not by what has jpreceded its action ; it cannot, up to the point of effort, but be a first cause, and, as such, an independent power, freely trying to do its finite part in that creation of the future, which is the object of its effort. In the jpast it has acquired the knowledge which aids its judgment as to the effect of any contemplated action under the present circum- stances. The problem which the mind has to determine, in such cases, and which the mind alone must determine, is this : given, a certain want, or, which is the same thing, a certain change to be wrought out in the future ; and, with this, certain facts, constituting whatever knowledge the mind has from memory of the past, or observation of tlie present, including, of course, all in- struction, from any source, human or Divine, up to the moment of deciding ; to determine by what change in the future the want may be gratified ; and then by what effort, or series of efforts, this gratifying change may be effected. If the want and the existing circum- stances, or facts, were not already fixed and determined, and, as such, not subject to the will, we should have, for finding the required volition, only variable and un- known data. There would be nothing fixed, or known as a basis of calculation, and the problem would be as indeterminate as that of constructing a triangle with three unknown sides. If the want were not fixed, the problem would still be indeterminate. The mind, that does not know what it wants, is not prepared to deter- 72 FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. mine its action. Or, if we suppose tlie want and the knowledge of it to be fixed, but all other knowledge to be dependent on the will ; then the mind would, by an act of Mall, have to fix this other knowledge of the past and present before it could make it available in deter- mining its course as to the future. The mind, in such case, would have to assume the facts and truths, by its own creative acts for its present purpose, make tliem fact and truth in some fixed form ; it would be acting upon an assumed basis, u^jon mere hypotheses, and the action founded upon such assumptions might prove to have no adaptation to tlie actual existences. No sane man would, from such process, expect other than im- aginary or hypothetical results, admitting of actual ap- plication only w^hen the actual existences happened to correspond with tlie assumed hypotheses. He might, in this way, plan action withont reference to any actual, existing circumstances, or to any changes, which other causes might be affecting ; but the chance of his plan being applicable to the actual existences, would be in- conceivably small. With the want and knowledge both given, the mind has only to determine their rela- tions to the conteuiplated acts, to make the problem analogous to that of constructing a triangle, knowing two sides and their relations to the other. It be- comes a determinate problem, but it is the mind's knowledge, including that of its want, which thus makes it determinate ; and the mind itself, by the use of its knowledge, actually determines it. If we do not know the existing facts or circumstances, which relate to onr action, we seek by a preliminary act to find tliem. The mind may be in doubt as to some, or all of the data, or knowledge, upon which it bases its con- FREEDOM OF INTELLIGkNCE. 73 structions ; and, so far, the result will be doubtful and the problem be determinate only within the limits of certain probabilities ; or it may be mistaken in the data, either as to the facts, or the relations, and, so far, the result may be erroneous, and tlie act of will have no tendency to produce the expected result ; or there may be a want of power to produce the effect willed. However this may be, however perfect or imperfect the solution — the mind, with such means as it has, must it- self resolve this problem, growing out of the relations, indicated by its own knowledge, between its own want and the concej^tion which it forms of the future effect of certain of its own acts of will, and determine the re- sult or act of will, or that result, that act of will, will not be determined, l^o other power, material or intel- ligent, could possibly determine it withont knowing both the want, and the perception of the relation between the contemplated action and the want, which exist in the mind of the agent willing. This could be only by one who knows all our wants, " to whom all hearts are open, all desires known." On this point, of the pos- sible control of the finite will by the Supreme Intelli- gence, we have ah-eady made some suggestions, and shall consider it more fully in another place. From the views just stated it appears that, if the want and knowledge of the mind were subject to, in- stead of being independent of its will, they would have to be fixed by specific acts of will before any other act of will could be determined ; and the fact that the want and knowledge of the mind are not subject to the control of its will, instead of involving necessity as at first glance one might suspect, is really essential to the freedom of the mind in determining its action ; or 4 74 FKEEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. at least, facilitates the exercise of that freedom. That we have want, know our want, and the means or mode of gratifying that want, cannot militate against our freedom in the use of that knowledge, to gratify the want. The want is the original incentive to that effort, the direction of which the mind determines by me.ans of the relations which it perceives between its wants and its preconceptions of the future effects of this effort ; among such conceptions selecting, or choosing, for ac- tualization, that one which, in its view, is best adapted to its purpose of gratifying, or relieving the want. It is in the forming of such preconceptions, as Avill prob- ably answer the purpose, in the accuracy of these pre- conceptions, or their conformity to the effects that will actually be produced, and in selecting among them, that the mind manifests its ability in action. Whether or not these preconceptions are realized by the power of the mind in effort, is not material. It is sufficient that its effort is a pre-requisite to such realiza- tion. Up to the point of and including the effort, the finite mind, in its own sphere, so far as we can know, exerts its creative powers in the same way as the Infi- nite, and as freely. It has a want ; forms a preconcep- tion of what changes will gratify the want ; what effort, or succession of efforts, will produce these changes ; and makes the efforts, or wills these changes. The only ne- cessity or restraint, differing from that of the Infinite, which the finite mind is under, arises, not from a dift'er- ence in the kind, but in the limited quantity of its power. It cannot do what it has not power to do ; it cannot act from considerations, which it does not per- ceive or apprehend ; or upon knowledge which it doea not possess ; i. * See Appendix, 'N'ote XIX, 102 FRKEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. served that, wlien at one time I willed to move my hand, it did move ; I may, from association, expect, or, having some previous idea of the uniformity of cause and effect, infer that when again I repeat the effort, the effect may be the same ; whereas, the knowledge that willing the movement of the hand is the way to move it, may be directly imparted intuitively. In the former case I have to devise the plan to reach the end from my own knowledge ; in the latter, the plan of effort is previously devised for me. The sphere of effort, as also of freedom, in a being with only one want and one known means of gratifying it, would be limited to grati- fying its only want in the only mode known to it, or not gratifying it at all. It is still a sphere commensu- rate with knowledge. The gratification of its want W'Ould still depend on its own effort, without which its want w^ould not be gratified. To reduce this to its low- est terms, we must suppose the being having only one w^ant and an intuitive perception of only one mode of gratifying it ; also to have no knowledge — no thought — that it may possibly be better not to gratify it. If, in this hypothesis, we increase the number of wants, and suppose that only one of them arises at a time, it makes no material difference. In each case, as it oc- curs, it is still one want, one known mode of change, and no knowledge, or thought that it may be better not to adopt that mode, or to make no effort to produce that change. If more than one want arise at once, or if the being knows of more than one mode applicable to the want, it must select among them ; it must com- pare and judge, requiring that mode of effort, which is known as an exercise of the rational faculties ; but, under the condition above named, no comparison is in- INSTINCT AND HABIT, 103 stituted ; there is no occasion, no room for the exercise of the rational faculties. Now all animals, so far as we can ascertain, come into existence with wants, and some one Icnown mode of gratifying each want, and no thought that it may be better not to gratify it ; and hence, re- quiring no additional knowledge to direct its effort, and of course no exercise of the rational faculties, no delib- eration to obtain it ; and this is instinct. Instinctive action still involves a free effort of intel- ligence, though it precludes the exercise of the rational faculties in devising the mode of effort, or in selecting from different modes already devised by itself, or by others. Having the want, the requisite knowledge of the means, and the power to use the means, or to make an effort, it makes that effort. The effort in such case is spontaneous ; no deliberation being required ; but there is still an effort. It may, perhaps, be certain, that under those conditions such being will make the one particular effort, the only one known to it ; but this is not because it is constrained to uiake, but, because it is in no way restrained from making such effort. It feels the want, has the power to gratify it, knows how, and being free to exert its power, does itself exert it. The effort still is the actual, the uncontrolled, the free effort of the being that mtikes it, and without which effort the effect would not be produced. That it has no knowl- edge of any other effort, does not affect its freedom in making that which it does know. It is not as in the case of matter which some other power has put in mo- tion and directed — the freedom of which, if it can have any, consists in the absence of any obstruction, or coun- teraction — for in instinctive action intelligence still uses and directs its own powers, and, without such self- 104 FEKEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. movement, there would be no exercise of its powers. That the knowledge bj which it directs such exercise or ejffort is intuitive and not acquired, cannot aifect its freedom in using its knowledge for directing its efforts, or for any other purpose. In either case, once in pos- session, it is equally knowledge, and the mind's own knowledge. An act of will is tlie primary self-move- ment of the mind, and not an antecedent cause of it. The effect, or sequence which it, as a first cause, produces, is some change of body or mind. In an act of will or effort, the agent, even when he knows only one mode of action, is free in a different and wider sense than that of not being counteracted in an action which some external power has imposed upon him. The agent willing is free to make and to direct the effort which it does itself make. If there be nothing in existence bnt himself acting through his will, and his want and knowledge, which are independent of his will, the efibrt may yet be made. The want itself cannot know, or apply the knowledge. The knowledge itself cannot know the want and adapt the effort to it, nor could both combined. This must be done by some- thing which is not only conscious of both the want and the knowledge, but is capable of perceiving the rela- tions between them, — by the intelligent being, — and, as there is no other existing activity (for by our hypothesis there is no other existence of any kind but the one active being, the want, and the knowledge), the act must be wholly its act ; and, there being no other power, it must act without restraint or constraint, it must act freely. Under our theory of instinctive action, the knowledge being reduced to the least quantity with which will is compatible, the spheres of freedom and INSTINCT AND HABIT. 105 of will there reach their least assignable limits, but are still coexistent ; and, like the decreasing quantities of the differential calculus, retain their relations to each other, even in their infinitesimal forms ; and when free- dom vanishes, the will of necessity vanishes also ; and this occurs when the knowledge of the future is reduced to zero, admitting of no preconception of any change to be willed, or made the object of effort. It will be ob- served, then, that the only essential difference between the ohserw able phenomena of mechanical and of instinct- ive action, arises from the incorporation into a vital be- ing of one iota of knowledge, — the knowledge of one means corresponding to one want. Without this, even if a being had sensation and memory, its instinctive movements must be produced without any effort of its own by some external power ; and, whether the subject thus moved be that of being with spirit, bones and muscles, or that of stars and planets, such movements are purely mechanical. Tlie proximity of the two, sep- arated only by this single step, has caused confusion in regard to them, and led some to doubt, whether what we class as instinctive actions are not, really, mechanic- al. And it seems quite conceivable that the first instinct- ive movements, as, for instance, that of the infant in obtaining food, are not preceded by any act of its will, but that all the movements of its muscles to that end are as immediately produced by the Supreme Intelli- gence, without the action, prior or present, of the in- fant's own will, as are the beginning of movements in lifeless matters ; that these first motions of the infant may be but God's teaching ; his mode of practically and directly imparting the knowledge, which is essen- tial to its existence, till, by imitation, or other means, 106 FRhEDOM OF MIND IJST WILLING. it learns to evoke, or to invoke the same effects by its own elforts ; as a tutor, with his own hand, sometimes guides that of his pupil, to teach him how to write. If it has not the knowledge that it can will, and also how to will, by intuition, it must, in some way, acquire it before it can itself will, either freely or otherwise. It seems quite conceivable that this and other intuitive knowledge may be thus practically taught us, and es- pecially in regard to our bodily movements ; and yet, on closer examination, we may find that this is jpraxiti- cally impossible^ and that such knowledge must be taught, or must consist in an idea^ or conception of the mode directly im/parted as such^ and not derived from the observation of external movements of our own bodies, or those of others. The moving of the hand by external force is so entirely distinct from the internal effort to move it, that the knowledge of the latter could no more be obtained from the former, than the idea of weight from color. Nor could I ever learn to move my hand by will, from seeing another person move his hand, — for the process of will by which he does it, is not cognizable by the senses through which alone I could learn it in observing the external. All that I could possibly learn from seeing another person move his hand, by will, or from having my own hand moved by a force exerted through the will of another, would be the velocity and direction of its movements, and not the process of will by which it was so moved. Still less could I get this idea of movement by will, irom any movement of my hand by an external force, which I did not refer to any act of will whatever. Nor can the mind first get this idea by the application of its reason to such external phenomena ; for no one has ever yet TNSTINCT AND HABIT. 107 discovered any rational connection between the effort and the movement. The mind, then, does not get this knowledge of mnscnlar movement at will, by observation, and must get it by intuition ; and by it we know only the fact without any rationale of it. It must be an ultimate idea directly imparted to us, and we may, with the first want of muscular action, be supposed to know the mode as well as at any subsequent recurrence of such want. There is nothing gained by supposing the first muscular movement to be mechanical, or the effect of external power. The facts in regard to a want which comes into existence after we have become capable of observing, confirm the conclusion that such knowledge is direct- ly imparted to us, and that all that is voluntary in sub- sequent action, is voluntary in the first instance ; that it is our effort, and is not the direct eff'eet of the exter- nal power which imparts this knowledge. The change in our knowledge is only a reason for changing our own efiPorts. By the same mode of reasoning it may be shown, that we must also intuitively know the mode of putting our mental faculties in action ; and as every effort we make is, in the first instance, to affect some portion of either our body or mind, we are justified in regarding all these early actions, which we term instinctive, as the consequence of the effort of the being to gratify its want by a mode intuitively known to it; and with a preconception, at least, of the proximate elfects of that effort ; and hence, as really voluntary and not mere mechanical acts, from which, indeed, they are sufficient- ly distinguished by the existence of the effort and its prerequisites, want and knowledge. 108 FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. If there are any such movements of the body pro- duced bj external power, as have just been mentioned as conceivable, thej are as purely mechanical as those of inert substance. In nature, when God works out his own plan, the action is called mechanical. When he imparts the knowledge of a plan to a finite being that works it out, the action of this being is instinctive. The uniformity and symmetry which we see in crys- tals, are God's perfect work, and rank with the mechan- ical. The bee, in forming its cells, though it executes with less nicety and precision, works from a plan equal- ly uniform and equally symmetrical, which God has furnished to it, and its action is instinctive. It knows the plan, but probably does not know why it is prefer- able to others. Some of its advantages were unknown, even to scientific men, until revealed by the application of the differential calculus. We have, then, incorpoi-ated in our beings, in the first instance, the power to will ; the want, which re- quires the exei'cise of that power ; and the knowledge which is requisite to its early and very limited exer- cise ; also the knowledge that by will we can put in exercise those mental faculties by which m'c may come to more perfect knowledge, which sometimes itself gratifies the want and at others reveals the action appo- site to the want. We also thns have the knowledge of the first step into the external by muscular action. The power to will, a want, and corresponding knowl- edge of means to gratify it, are constitutional elements of every creatui-e that wills ; and such creature can at once will, and will freely, because it is constitutionally such a creature as it is. INSTINCT AND HABIT. 109 Instinct may teach the infant only sufficient to en- able it to come within the reach of easy effort to accom- plish its object; and this may be designed to induct it into a habit of making effort, thus subserving a double purpose. If this be so, it will not materially vary the previous results. The instinctive actions, then, being voluntary, in what respect do they differ from other acts of will? The whole phenomena of most voluntary actions, as ob- served in the adult man, are embodied in the want, the knowledge, including the preconception of the future, the deliberation, the volition, and the effect. The dis- tinction we are seeking is not in the faculty of will it- self; we have not two wills. It is not in the want, for the same want may often be equally gratified by the instinctive, or by other modes. It cannot be in the vo- lition, for the same volition may arise in instinctive, as in other modes. It must then be in one or both of the other two elements— deliberation and knowledge, that is, in knowledge itself, or in the mode of obtain- ing, or of applying it. Now, one of the most obvious peculiarities of instinctive action is the absence of de- liberation, or of any exercise of the judgment, or ra- tional faculties, in devising or selecting means ; and this condition of absence, as we have just shown, can be perfect only when the knowledge of the mode of action is intuitive. In further confirmation of this we may remark that if, on any particular occasion for action, we have not the requisite knowledge, we must, in some way, acquire it ; and in its acquisition, or in its application, or in both, must use our rational faculties.* We have also * See Appendix, Note -IX. 110 FREEDOM or MIND IN WILLING. shown, that the mode of producing bodily movements by will, must be intuitively known ; and that this knowledge is simply of the fact, without any such ra- tionale of it as will enable us to vary the mode by any mental process. We know but one mode, and this knowledge is intuitive. In the first applications of this knowledge, we do not know that there may be some reason for not making the movement, and such action then is purely instinctive. As, in our efforts to produce external changes, we always begin with bodily move- ments, they form the substratum of our plans of action for such changes. In these plans we subsequently learn rationally to combine muscular movements to produce desired results, for which our intuitive knowledge is insufficient. Our plan may embrace certain particular movements, the order of which we arrange ; but we do not attempt to arrange, or plan the mode of producing these particular movements. When, subsequently, we have learned to look about us to see if there is sufficient reason for not making the contemplated movement, and have decided that there is not, we are in the same con- dition as if we had no knowledge, no thought, that there might possibly be such reason. In the last analysis, the bodily movement itself is always instinctive ; there is no plan, no deliberation, no exercise of judgment, as to the mode of making it ; but only as to the particular movements, or series of movements, to be effected by the known mode ; and the intuitive knowledge that by will we can produce muscular movement, is the starting point of all our efforts for external changes. From this one common point both instinctive and rational actions take their departure. In the instinct- ive, the plan of action, or the successive order of the INSTINCT AND HABIT, 111 series of volitions required to produce tlie intended re- suit is also intuitively known, is so imparted, either mediately or immediately, tliat it is the same as if in- corporated in tlie being, and requires no rational process to ascertain it. The whole plan may be known at once, or only each step, singly, as it is reached. In either case it still requires the exercise of the will to act out the plan thus furnished to it, without which the knowl- edge even of the whole plan, though associated with a want demanding its execution, would not avail. The kid, the moment it is born, can rise upon its feet and go directly to the food its mother supplies. It must not only know that by volition it can produce muscular movement, but it must know what particular movements to make, and the order of their succession. It works from a plan furnished to it, and not designed or contrived by itself. As, by its Mall, it still produces effects in the future, it is creative, but in an inferior de- gree. It creates, as the most untaught laborer, who re- moves the earth from the bed of a canal, has an agency in creating the canal, though he acts only under the di- rection of the superior intelligence, which designed and comprehends the whole structure. The inferior free agent, while executing all within its own sphere of ac- tion, — all the plan which itself for 7ns, or apprehends-^ may subserve the purposes of a superior intelligence and help to execute its higher designs. But the intui- tive knowledge of a mode of producing bodily move- ment, except when mere bodily movement is itself the primary want, would answer no purpose unless the knowledge of the particular bodily movement, or series of movements, required to reach the end, is superadded. If this is intuitive also, requiring no exercise of the ra- 112 FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. tional faculties, no deliberation as to the plan, or order of successive efforts, then the action, or series of actions, is purely instinctive. But to shnt out all ground, for the exercise of the rational faculties, there must, as be- fore stated, be only one want, one known mode of grat- ifying it, and no knowledge or thought that it may pos- sibly be better not to gratify it. If we. suppose an intuitive knowledge of two or more modes of gratifying the same want, or that there are conflicting wants^ we have a case for the exercise of the judgment. In the former of these cases, the mind may be said to be confined to the two or more modes. It has not designed or planned either of them ; but it may design and plan, and must decide as between them; and then the subsequent action becomes, so far, a lational one; and, if the decision is not immediately obvious to the knowing sense, deliberation — effort to examine and obtain more knowledge — with consequent delay, becomes an element in the mental process of de- termining the final efl'ort. The same is obvious in the case of conflicting wants ; and we may remark that any indisposition to the efibrt, or a disposition to be passive and inert is a conflicting want. When the plan of action was before unknown, and yet is obvious to simple mental perception, without pre- liminary effort to acquire it, the case approaches very nearly to that of action from a plan intuitively known, if, indeed, it can be practically distinguished from it. Another easy divergence, from the purely instinct- ive, seems to be that in which the knowledge of the required change, or series of changes, instead of being intuitive, is derived from the simple observation of such external chanares, or movements as we can see others INSTINCT AND HABIT. 113 make, requiring only to be imitated. This differs from the intuitive, in requiring an effort of attention to ob- serve tlie movements or their successive order ; and an exercise of the rational faculty to infer, that as we have the power to move our muscles, we may there- fore be able to make similar movements, and that they will lead to similar results. We might thus learn to apply our knowledge of muscular movement by will ; though, as already shown, we never could acquire this knowledge by merely observing others. As distinguishing features of instinctive action, we have, then, the absence of any plan, design, or contri- vance, on the part of the active heing^ to attain its end ; and, in place of such contrivance of its own, the knowl- edge of a plan directly imparted to it, ready made, re- quiring no contrivance of its own, and no deliberation. The circumstances under which such actions are most conspicuous, perhaps the only cases of purely in- stinctive action in human beings, occur in the infant, when its whole attention is absorbed by the want of the moment, when its knowledge is limited to its intuitive perception of only one mode of gratifying that want, and it has yet no thought tliat it may be better not to gratify it. In brutes it continues more prominent, be- cause they learn less of other than the intuitive modes. It seems, too, not improbable that, with the deficient ability to plan rational modes of action, the necessities of existence may require an increase of the intuitive modes ; but if our distinction is welJ founded, we cannot deny rational actions to most of the inferior animals, or even that a large portion of their actions are of this class, though more alloyed with the instinctive, than those of man. The hungry dog, acting instinctively, would not 114 FRERDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. hesitate to seize tlie joint of meat he sees before him in his master's kitcheii ; but he learns that, in the presence of the cook, the effort to get it maj be unsuecessfnl, or be attended with unpleasant consequences, and he gov- erns himself in conformity to this acquired knowledge, including his consequent preconceptions of future effects, and foregoes the effort to appropriate the meat. If, in view of the circumstances, he plans to wait the absence of, or in some way to induce the cook to let him have the meat, he exhibits still more of rational design than by temple forbearance. Though instinctive action is thus less conspicuous, as the acquired knowledge in- creases, it is conceivable that a being with any amount of such acquirement may act without using it to contrive means, and may wholly disi-egard any plan it may have previously contrived for similar occasions. In man, a want may be so imperative or so absorbing as to ex- clude all others ; and also all comparison of the differ- ent modes of gratifying it ; and all deliberation as to whether to gratify it or not ; and, in such cases, he acts as a being having only one want, one means of gratify- ing it, and no knowledge or thought that it may be bet- ter not to gratify it ; if the one known means has to be found, the action is a rational one ; but if it is intui- tively known, all the conditions of purely instinctive action are fulfilled. Cases in which our rational actions thus approximate more or less nearly to the instinctive, occur when we are under the influence of some absorb- ing passion, as, for instance, of fear excited to tei'ror, in sudden fright, and we yield to the impulse to flee from whatever has terrified us. If, in so doing, the mode is immediately perceived, or if it is a i-esult of our own efforts in searching out and designing a plan of action, mSTIXCT AND HABIT. 115 but, under tlie excitement, so instantaneously formed and applied that the element of deliberation is very minute, the action will be liable to be confounded with the instinctive, though properly belonging to the rational. That we flee from danger, and not toward it, indi- cates the formation of a jplan of ^aWoxi. founded on our perception of the circumstances. We may intuitively know that to avoid being burned we must move from the fire, and how to so move ; but we must still per- ceive — know — where the fire is, and the combination of the two knowledges may be by a rational process. In other words, the knowledge of the general facts may be intuitive, and their application to particular cases ra- tional. In running from a fire, we may fall down a precipice of which we well knew, but did not take time to embrace the knowledge in our deliberation, or use it in the preconception of the effects of our action.* When we are conscious of forming the plan of action at the moment, ho^^^ever quickly, we are in no danger of con- founding it with the instinctive. The distinction, how- ever, is practically not always obvious, and especially in those cases in which the plan of action is easily and quickly formed. The movement of the jaw, to relieve the pain occasioned by -the pressure of a person's own teeth on his finger, would, no doubt, be deemed by some an instinctive action ; but there have been cases of idiots who did not know enough to do this, though they had all the intuitive knowledge requisite to make the movement, as evinced by their voluntarily making it whenever they ate ; showing that, at least in them, an inference from the peculiar circumstances of the case * See Appendix, Note XXI. 116 FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. — more knowledge — was required to enable them to apjply their intuitive knowledge of tlie mode of moving the jaw, in such way as would relieve the pain of the linger. It may be as difficult for such an idiot to form a plan for extricating his finger, as for a horse to plan to extricate liis foot when it gets entangled in the hal- ter. The pain being in his finger, he, not improbably, seeks to move and thus to effect change in it, as the horse pulls on his entangled foot for relief; in both cases, from not knowing jp^ans adapted to the circam- stances^ aggravating the difficulty. In such persons, the intuitive knowledge may be less than in some others ; but i\ie particular point at which the intuitive must be aided by the acquired, is not material to the illustrar tion.* Though, in terms, the rational may be clearly de- fined by the formation of a plan of action by the active being ; and the instinctive, by the plan of action being furnished to it by intuition, ready formed ; yet prac- tically we do not always readily perceive the exact boundary between them.f They are often blended, and perhaps the rational always embraces something of the instinctive. We may rationally plan a series of suc- cessive musculai' movements in a certain order, but, as before stated, the mode of making each of the move- ments by will is always instinctive. The same rule will also apply to the use of our mental powers by a j^re^ arranged plan. The mode in which the knowledge of a plan of ac- tion is acquired does not affect the action itself. Once acquired, whether by the teachings of the Infinite, oi- of a fi.nite intelligence, or by our own rational investiga- * See Appendix, Note XXII. f See Appendix, .Note XXIU. INSTINCT AND HABIT. 117 tioii, or by simple perception, tlie acting from it is tlie same ; and, having memory, we can repeat or reenact the same, by mere association with onr wants knowing when to repeat it. The instinctive and the rational both admit of being thus repeated by memory and mere imitation, though neither memory nor imitation could have had any part in our iirst instinctive actions, for there were then no' actions to remember or to imi- tate ; and when ever the young intelligence begins to work by memory of a plan adopted in previous acts, instead of one known by a direct intuition applicable to the case, it begins to be the subject of habit. The same of those actions which we have ourselves designed, how- ever complicated, however much contrivance and inge- nuity they may have originally required, when, after frequent repetition, we perforin them in proper order by memory instead of by a reference to the original reasons of that order, they, too, have become habitual. The peculiar characteristic of habit seems to be that we become so familiar with the plan by which the de- sired result is to be reached, that, at every stage of it, we know what to do from what has already been done, and do not have to form a preconception of the future, or, at most, not more of it than the next immediate act, or even recur to any preconception previously formed of it ; we do not have to perceive the connection of the immediate act contemplated with the end sought. "We may merely recollect that, on previous like occasions, we did thus or so with satisfactory results ; and that, after such an act, such another act immediately follows. We do it by rote. Suppose a man, who is accustomed to walk in a certain path from one place to another, wishes to go to some other place, requiring him to di- 118 FREEDOM OF MIND IN "WILLING. verge from tlie familiar teack. If, on reaching the point of divergence, he fails to look at the portion of his plan, which is jet in the future, but, as on former occasions, directs himself in each successive act by refer- ence to the preceding one, or by mere association with it, he will take the old path, and will not discover his mistake until he looks to the future and refers to his preconception of the result intended, and of the means of attaining it. This habitually pursuing an old plan when a new one had been designed, is matter of common ex- perience. As a consequence of this working from mem- ory of an old plan, instead of one newly formed for the occasion, there is in habitual action little, if any, need of deliberation, or for the exercise of the rational faculties. As, in the case of instinctive action, there is also in the habitual, a plan ready formed in the mind, and though it may be there, by our own previous efforts, instead of by intuition, it subserves much the same purpose. Perhaps the only essential difi'erence is, that the intui- tive knowledge may embrace that of the occasions for adopting the particular plan ; and in adopting our own previously formed plans, we have always to determine by an exercise of judgment the proper occasions for their application. This, however, as already suggested, may sometimes be necessary also in regard to the appli- cation of a mode, or a series of actions intuitively known as the means of reaching an end ; and in the habitual, after we have decided to adopt the mode, or series, we pursue it without further deliberation, or exercise of the judgment in going through the successive steps. Again, as before observed, the occasion upon which to use a known plan, either intuitive or acquired, may be sug- gested by its mere association with recurring circum- INSTINCT AND HABIT. 119 stances, and, if that examination of our knowledge, which results in a judgment, is an element of associa- tion, such examination, or exercise of the rational facul- ties in comparing and judging is often so slight, or so instantaneous as to be almost unnoticeable. We ob- serve, then, how nearly habitual action brings us back from the rational to the instinctive ; and in this we may find the significance of the common saying that " habit is second nature." The instinctive also resembles the habitual in this, that it is not essential in either that we should ever know, at one time, any more of the plan than the connection between the action just done and the one next in order. The bee, when it has construct- ed one side and one angle of its cell, need not knuw that it will require five more such sides and angles to com- plete it. The most that is essential to its subsequent ac- tion is the knowledge that the next step is to make an- other like side and angle ; and so in the habitual, all that is requisite is the recollection of what action comes next, and then again the next. We find another similarity in the fact that, in re- sorting to an habitual mode, even though originally ac- quired, and especially if then adopted after full deliber- ation, the mind may again use it, as if it were the < nly one possible; just, as in the first instinctive action, it adopts the one and only known mode, which it has by intuition. With these points in common, the instinctive may glide easily into the habitual. By repetition in practice, the memory of the consecutive order of the ac- tions may take the place of the direct knowledge of that order.* Though more unlike, rational actions become habit- * See Appendix, Note XXIV. 120 FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. ual by tlie same process — by the repetition, on like oc- casions, of the series of efforts embracing the phm of ac- tion, till we distinctly remember the routine of the suc- cessive efforts, and can go over them in the same order, without reference to the end or the reason of such or- der. In the habitual, as already intimated, the mind may determine each successive action, not by its per- ception of its connection with the future,- but by associa- tion with that which is past ; and this analogy of such actions to the movement of a material body by a force behind it, without itself perceiving its course in the fu- ture, has probably favored the popular application of the term mechanical to habitual actions, which was naturally enough suggested by the comparatively small amount of mental efibrt they require. It is obvious that a very large proportion of the ac- tions of adults are habitual, and that our rational ac- tions, in becoming habitual, approach so nearly to in- stinctive, is probably one cause of that difficulty in distinguishing the instinctive from the rational, which is so general ; a difficulty which may be further in- creased by the instinctive also actually becoming habit- ual, the two thus blending together and becoming un- distinguishable in one common reservoir, from which the main current of our actions subsequently flows, and through which it is often difficult to trace their respect- ive sources. Customary or imitative actions also belong to this group. When we do anything merely because it is customary, we adopt the plans or modes of action which we have seen others adopt, without ourselves contri-S'ing, and sometimes without even perceiving the reason why others have adopted tliem. In regard to in- INSTINCT AND HABIT. 121 still ctive, habitual, and customary actions, the question may arise whether it may or may not be better to class those in which we perceive the reason of the plan at the time of action, with the rational actions. There is evidently, in this, a distinction for which philosophical accuracy requires a corresponding difference in ex- pression. To recapitulate ; mechanical action, or material movements and changes, are either God's action, imme- diate or mediate, upon his own plan — a part of his rational actions ; or, as seems to be conceivable and more in conformity to the popular idea, the necessary consequences of blind causes, as of matter in motion, which can have no plan. Instinctive actions are the efforts of a finite intelli- gent being, conformed by its intelligence to the plan which God has furnished, or furnishes to it, ready formed. Rational actions are the efforts of an intelligent being, finite or infinite, in conformity with a plan, which itself has contrived, by means of those faculties, which make a part of the constitution of its being, de- rived or underived. Customary or imitative action is the action of a finite being in conformity to a plan which it has derived from its observation of the action of others. Habitual action is the action of a finite, intelligent being, in conformity to a plan which it has in its mind, ready formed, with which practice has made it so familiar, that each successive step is associated with, and is suggested by those which precede it, requiring no examination as to its influence, or its connection with the desired end, or effect in the future ; whether 6 122 FEEEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. that plan was originally instinctive, rational, or cus- tom arj. In regard to habit, I would farther remark that it has, in some respects, the same relation to action, that memory has to knowledge. They are both retaining powers. As memory of the results of former investiga- tions, or of former observation, obviates the necessity of repeated investigation or observation to enable us to know, so habit obviates the necessity of examining as to the probable result of the dijS'erent proposed actSs or of repeating the experiments required in the first action, and which, with the caution then requisite, rendered it slow and tedious, compared with the facility acquired after practice has made us familiar with the order of the successive efforts, and rendered us fearless of any latent consequences, the apprehensions of which, in the first instance, would induce careful examination of our preconceptions of the future effects. Habit seems to be mainly dependent on memory and association. The first time certain circumstances occur, if we have not the knowledge of the mode of action intuitively, we have to examine, compare, judge, and perhaps resort to ex- periments as to how we shall act ; when they recur, we may adopt the former modes implicitly, if the result was then satisfactory, or with such modifications as ex- perience may suggest ; and repeat the experiments, with variations, till we have got what we deem the best. When, from the plan adopted on a former occa- sion, gratification has resulted, a recurrence of similar circumstances suggests, by association, the want of like gratification. This want is also intensified, not only by the recollection of the former pleasure, but the mind, being relieved from the labor of a particular examina- INSTINCT AND HABIT. 123 tion of tlie means and of devising a plan ; and also from apprehension as to nnseen consequences, wliich rendered circumspection necessary in tlie first instance, may direct its attention to tlie expected gratification, and be almost exclusively absorbed by it.* In regard to any action requiring several successive eflforts, as, for instance, walking, a man with fall strength, unless knowing by intuition not only the mode of making the particular muscular movements, but their proper respect- ive order and force, would, probably, in a first eff'ort to walk, have to proceed very slowly, giving a con- scious, attentive, tentative effort to each movement, and perhaps then not always succeed in practically doing as he desired ; but, by repeated experiments, he learns the proper order and degree of the movements, and by repetition becomes able to make them without any conscious thought as to the order, degree, or result, each effort suggesting the succeeding one, as a letter of the alphabet, after much repetition, suggests the one which follows it. If, by memory, we retained the knowledge of the letters of the alphabet and of their order of succession only long enough for the occasion, we should have to relearn, every time we had occasion for such knowledge ; and but for the retaining power of habit, we should have either to study or experiment in regard to every particular act, not instinctive, and as to the order of any instinctive series of actions, as often as the same might be required to reach the desired re- sult. Habit is but a substitution of the memory of for- mer results of investigation, and ex]:)erience for present investigation and trial ; those former results being sug- gested by association with like circumstances. In other * See Appendix, Note XXV. 124 FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. words, it is memory, aided by association, and applied to actions, when like occasions for them recur. In cases to which it is applicable, habit thus relieves the mind of nearly all the mental labor requisite to action — that of investigating the circumstances and forming its creative preconceptions in the future, and thus facili- tates our advancement in action ; making it easy for us to do that which we are accustomed to do, whether right or wrong. While habit thus facilitates effort, it also enables us readily to select from among passing occurrences those which require attention or effort, and to dismiss others almost without notice. When we have no special occa- sion to know the hour, the striking of a clock, which is constantly repeated within our hearing, makes so little impression, that it is not recollected a moment after- wards. We know from repeated observation that we need not attend to it. It awakens no interest, no want, in us. Ask a man who has just looked at his watch, for the time, and, in a majority of cases, he cannot tell you. He liahitually saw the time, as indicated on the dial plate, and inferred that the hour of his engagement had not yet arrived, or found that it suggested nothing to be done, and immediately dismissed the whole mat- ter. He can give no account of what passed in his mind. Perhaps a little more of memory of the pro- cess so instantaneous would reveal to him that he merely saw that a certain hour had not arrived, rather than what the present time was. The want for which lie made the effort to look at his watch was satisfied by the former, and he had no interest to know or to retain the latter. That habit especially applies to those actions which I'NSTINCT AND HABIT. 125 we have most frequent occasion to perform, increases the benefits we derive from it. It seems, however, to be frequently regarded as a vicious element of mind. This, probably, often arises from only looking at its power to perpetuate or facilitate actions which are wrong, overlooking its influence on those which are right, and may be confirmed by the further considera- tion, that retaining the old habit enables us to dispense with new acquisitions and with new eflbits, thus foster- ing indolence ; and that which legitimately furnishes the great means of progress in action, thus perverted, enables a man to forego the efforts, which are the very germs of this progress. He has become familiar with one course of action — Tiahit has made it easy to him ; it no longer requires the examination, the experimental efforts, the circumspection, which are necessary to learn and apply new methods. He has also learned the grati- fication arising from the habitual course, and does not know, and does not seek to know, that by pursuing a different course he may obtain a higher, more perma- nent, or more unalloyed gratification, or, at least, has not so brought the knowledge home to his affections, and into such practical form, as to induce a want for such higher gratification. Being slothful, the higher and higher wants, which with efforts for progress are continually evolved in the mind, are undeveloped, and remain in their original chaotic state, witliout the sphere of his efforts, in a region which he has never at- tempted to penetrate, and, by the exercise of his crea- tive powers, to reduce to order. CHAPTER XII. ILLUSTRATION F K O M CHESS. As a partial illustration of some of the foregoing views, let us suppose two persons, A and B, to be en- gaged in playing chess ; and as there is no conceivable necessity for swpposing any other intelligence to do, or to have done, anything in relation to the game, we may, so far as the players and their efforts are con- cerned, assume that none others exist. The players have no intuitions of the game ; but the knowledge of its laws, indicating what moves can and what cannot be made, having been taught them by others, without any contrivance of their own, is somewhat analogous to that intuitive knowledge which is the foundation of our early actions ; and the unreflecting spontaneity with which a young player avails himself of an opportunity to take a valuable piece, without reference to future consequences, has some resemblance to instinctive, un- dellberative action. The first move to be made by A is, so far as the position of the pieces is concerned, to be made under precisely the same circumstances as has been every other first move, which he has ever made, and he may now make liis habitual move without rein- vestigation, and each player continues to do this until the combinations become such that past experience can no longer avail. Or either may try an entirely new ILLUSTRATION FROM CHESS. 127 first or ^subsequent move, and test its advantages. In any case, however, botli the players soon come to new or unremembered combinations. A lias just moved, and may be supposed to be passively waiting the move of B, who is now the only active intelligence, and is to will his next move in view of the new circumstances which the last move of A has presented, and which cir- cumstances cannot now be changed until after himself wills and makes his move. His primary want is to checkmate his opponent ; but, in view of the circum- stances^ he knows that, in conformity with the laws of the game, he cannot gratify this want by any move now possible. He then wants to make the move which will most tend to checkmate. This secondary want in- duces him to make an effort to ascertain what move will best fulfil this condition. He examines, he delib- erates — that is, he makes an effort to obtain more knowledge, with which to direct his final effort, or move ; and then, by means of his knowledge of the present position of the pieces, and his power of forming an idea of the future, including his conjectures of the subsequent move of his opponent, he compares his pre- conceptions of the possible or probal)le result of various moves ; and having, by that use of his knowledge which results in a judgment, selected among them, wills, or puts forth the final effb)-t in conformity to that judg- ment. He does not fully examine all the possible re- sults of every possible move. This would make the game insufi'erably tedious, indeed, impossible to be played in a lifetime ; but the time he will give to de- liberating is also a matter for him to judge of, or decide by his knowing faculty ; and, in fact, he often moves with a consciousness that his examination is very im- 128 FEEEDOM OF MIND IK WILLING. perfect. Of two or more moves, he may not have de- cided wliich is best ; but, the fact is, he does decide to adopt one, and as, by the liyj^othesis, there is no other existing intelligent activity to decide for him, he must, in such case, himself decide which to adopt. So far as his present volition and act are concerned, it is the same as if he had never before willed or acted. That he has contributed, by his previous moves, to make the circumstances as they are, does not now affect the con- siderations by which his present move is to be deter- mined. For the purposes of this action, he begins with the circumstances as they now are, and is precisely in the same situation as if he found the game in that con- dition and was (being already possessed of the same knowledge of the past and present, and with the same power of anticipating the future) to move for the first time. Every time he wills, or puts forth an effort, making or planning a move, is a new and distinct exer- cise of his creative energy ; and the effect is a new crea- tion, evolved from the new circumstances, sometimes getting existence only in the conception of his own mind, and sometimes actualized, or made palpable to others, in the altered position of the piece moved. We might suppose a more complicated game, in which several persons moved at the same time on one side, each having to take into account not only the probable future moves of the several opponents, but, also, the simultaneous moves of his several coadjutors ; and this would more nearly resemble the complicated game of real life. But though, in real life, many may move at once, yet, to each individual, certain circum- stances are presented for him to act upon at the mo- ment of willing ; and whether, at that moment, these ILLLSTEATION FEOM CHESS. 121) circumstances are iixed, or are still flowing by tlie in- fluence of some otlier intelligence or force, is but a cir- cumstance to be taken into view in willing, as also the anticipated future action of other intelligences ; as the future possible or probable moves of one party at chess are taken into account by the other in determining his own move. If we look for the cause of the move, we refer it immediately to the will of the mover ; and if we seek the reason why he willed this and not some other move, we may, in most cases, by making such an examination of the circumstances as we suppose he made prior to moving, form a conjecture, in some cases amounting almost to certainty, in others only to the smallest degree of probability ; while, in some instances, we may fail to discover a probable or even a supposable reason. The same thing occurs in real life, showing that we diff'er in our knowledge, or come to difierent conclusions from the same premises. One man may better understand the game of life, or see farther or more clearly into the future, than another. Some can successfully compete with several skilful chess players, or can ably direct several distinct games at once ; and so some men are a match for many others in some of the rivalries of active life, and accomplish their ends in competition with numerous opponents. In a game of diplomacy, a Talleyrand or Metternich would succeed against most men, many men combined, or in separate games with each at the same time. And a Being of in- finite power and wisdom would accomplish His pur- poses, though opposed by any number of finite intelli- gences, all exerting their finite power as freely as He His infinite. To one uninstructed, the chess board with a game 130 FREEDOM OF MIND IN AVILLING. partly played out, would appear a mere confusion, without any more arrangement than a child discovers in the position of the stars ; and the moves would seem to him as arbitrary and erratic as the motions of planets and. comets did to tlie early pastoral astronomers ; but on ascertaining and applying the laws of the game, the element of design immediately appears, and an harmo- nious system is evolved from the apparent chaos. It is a creation — a very tiny creation — in which the finite intelligence has as freely exerted its creative power in devising and assigning the laws of the movements of the game, and in moving the pieces in conformity to those laws, as the Supreme Intelligence exerts its in- finite power in making laws and moving the universe in conformity with them. The inventor of the game has, in fact, created another sphere for the exercise of human activity ; like the great sphere of God's crea- tion, conditioned by certain laws, which, for the pur- poses of the game, must be regarded as inviolable as if decreed by infinite wisdom, and enforced by infinite power. It is a sphere in which many of the same pro- cesses of mind, which are common in active life, are brought into play, and in which are formed habits of effort, of deliberation, or the investigation of intricate combinations, preparatory to action ; and perseverance in effort under circumstances apparently the most hope- less ; and in which many of the emotions of real life, as hope, fear, despondency, the feeling of disappointment, the sense of superiority, the humiliation of defeat, the pride of victory, also have place.* If we suppose only one intelligent being to be en- gaged in the game, with an automaton chess player so * See Appendix, Note XXVI. ILLUSTRATION FROM CHESS. 131 contrived that the automatic moves will be in conform- ity with the laws of the game, we shall have a case analogous to that of the finite intelligence acting with reference to the anticipated action of the infinite, uni- formly conforming to certain laws, the consequences of which can be only partially known, or vaguely antici- pated by the finite. But for this uniformity in the Di- vine action, our position, in the efforts of life, would be- that of a person who should attempt to play chess with one who was wholly regardless of the laws of the game. In such case, all efibrt in investigating, planning, de- signing, and moving would be useless ; the game would be impossible. And so in the ajQPairs of real life ; but for the recognized uniformity in the action of the Su- preme Intelligence, there would be no reason or ground for the efforts of finite free agents. In chess it often happens that, in conformity with the rules, only one move is possible ; for instance, when the king must be put out of check, and there is only one move by which it can be done. This resembles some cases of supposed necessity in the voluntary efforts of real life. By the laws of the game, the player is con- fined to one move, and has no liberty to will auy other. But there is no conceivable case in which the mind is, or can be, compelled to will at all, and this apparent want of liberty or analogy to it, in chess, is merely an inability in the agent to conform to laws which he has- voluntarily adopted for his own government, and, at the same time, not to conform to them ; w^hich, so far from detracting from a man's freedom in determining his own volitions, is essential to it ; for if, at the same moment that he either decided or willed to conform, he could also decide, or will, not to conform, and the two 132 FEKEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. mental efforts were to go forth simultaneously, bis power would be completely neutralized. It is a mere inability to work contradictions, and cannot even be re- garded as a deficiency of ])ower^ for no increase of pow- er tends to give sucb ability. In the case supposed, the effort of the player to make a particular move is made to depend on his knowledge of the laws of the game, and any other knowledge which may lead him to want to conform to them ; and such government of himself to gratify this want, by the aid of any knowledge he may have, does not make a case varying from those which we have before considered. The laws of the game are certainly not more obligatory upon him than the just demands of his country, or the laws of God, or his own convictions of right. In all such cases, the ex- istence of such obligation, or of any conclusions, or in- ferences from them, are but circumstances to be consid- ered by the mind in determining its efforts ; but do not affect its freedom in making the efforts, the making, or not making of which still depends on itself. The memory of the conclusions of former examina- tions of the circumstances, of which these laws form a portion, may enable a man to dispense with present ex- amination, and act from habit. In chess, each player tacitly pledges himself to conform to the laws of the game ; and a man, on full deliberation, may resolve al- ways to conform his efforts to the laws of God, and, in both cases, his compliance may become habitual, so that he ceases to deliberate, or to form new plans of ac- tion, spontaneously adopting the old ; but this substitu- tion of the result of a former for a present examination, does not conflict with freedom, but is itself an act of freedom. If the mind's predetermination to be gov- ILLUSTRATION FROM CHESS. 133 erned by certain laws, or in certain circumstances to act in certain uiiiform modes, could be regarded as a voluntary curtailment of its liberty, that which was thus abandoned could be voluntarily resumed, and the mind, by its own act, regain its entire freedom ; but the free- dom of the mind is as apparent in the voluntary curtail- ment, as in the reextension of its sphere of effort. But, in adopting such laws or modes, the mind does not, by its free effort, curtail its freedom, but uses its knowl- edge of general rules to lessen the delibei-ation required in each particular case as it occurs, or to direct its efforts in cases for which its knowledge, if it did not embrace these laws, or general rules, would be wholly inadequate. That God wills to conform His action to certain laws or uniform modes, does not impair His freedom. In regard to the influence of law on individual ac- tion or effort, we would remark generally, that matter cannot know the law, and, therefore, cannot govern it- self by law ; that an intelligent being, knowing the law, and not willing to be governed by it does not so govern himself; but that, in both instances, the move- ments or actions of the matter, or of such non-willing being, if made to conform to the law, must be so con- formed by some external power, to which the law is a rule of action. If the intelligence making or promul- gating the law enforces it by an exercise of its own power, then the law is only a law to itself, and the will of a controlled being has no part in it, and has no more to do with the result of a law thus enforced, than a heavy stone has to do with the effects of gravitation. A law made by one being for the government of an- other, and not enforced by direct application of power, 134 FREKDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. must depend for its efficiency upon the will of that other. He may will to obey it, because, having exam- ined the particular law, he deems it good in itself; or because it is dictated by a being in whose wisdom and beneficence he confides. In the latter case he adopts the rule, because he perceives that it is a particular case of a more general rule, on which he has before decided. In all cases of government by law, we are influ- enced, not by the existence of the law, but by our pre- conceptions of the effects of breaking the law, or of con- forming to it. It may be that we perceive it will grieve or offend one whom we love ; or it may be the consideration of more direct personal consequences, dis- tinctly and directly apprehended, or inferred from the attributes of the law-maker. The knowledge of the law is always such an addition to our knowledge as enables us better to preconceive the future, and especially in regard to what others, in certain contingencies, will do ; but, in the mind's application of this knowledge, to de- termine its own efforts, there is nothing conflicting with its freedom in willing. If it wills in conformity to the law, it is just as free as if it wills in opposition to it. The word laio^ in such connection, seems to be used in two distinct senses ; the one indicating a rule by which causes are governed in producing effects ; the other ex- pressing a mere uniformity of such effects. But the observation of this uniformity of effects is perhaps but a mode in which we learn the law of the cause which produces them ; as, for instance, by our observation of the changes in the material universe, we come to know the laws which God has adopted for His own govern- ment in producing these changes, and the two senses of the term become blended in one. But be this as it ILLUSTRATION FKOM CHESS. 135 may, the knowledge of such laws, whether they are the mere uniformity of the effects, or those invariable rules or modes which an intelligent cause adopts in produc- ing them, enables us better to preconceive the effects of our efforts, and, of course, to determine them more wisely ; or, at least, more certainly to produce the efl'ect intended. CHAPTER XIII. OP WANT AND EFFORT IN VARIOUS ORDERS OF INTELLIGENCE. From the foregoing views it follows that want, often regarded as a weakness, or defect, is really requisite to all but the lowest forms of animated existence. It is necessary to all intelligent activity, and hence, essential to all the enjoyment which arises from the exercise of our faculties and from that conscious progress, or that satisfaction in the performance of duty, which attends our proper efforts. It is necessary to elevate us above the condition of mere sensitive and sensuous being; and, as no intelligent being will make effort to do what he does not want to do, it is thus necessary, with a meta- physical necessity, which even Omnipotence could not obviate. If these views are well founded, God Himself can- not be active, or make any progress, or produce change in anything except by being the subject of want ; and, in every order of intelligent being, to want is as essen- tial to the exercise of a free creative energy, as to know. This imputation of want to the Supreme Being, to some may seem irreverent, and especially to those who habitually regard it as an imperfection. Let such con- sider that we know God onl}^ by the attributes which He manifests in action, or by the effects of His action ; OF WANT AND EFFORT. 137 that we cannot conceive of Him as destitute of quali- ties ; and that the simplest and most evident affirma- tion which we can make, toucliing the exercise of His active power, is that He doeth that which He wants to do. Nothing, bj the mere fact of existence, can be a cause of any effect after such existence began ; for all the eifects of which its mere existence is the cause would take place the instant it came into existence, and all its causative power would then be exhausted and cease. Tt could produce no further changes even in itself; and hence, a sole first cause, without any want to excite it to effort, would immediately on com- ing into existence, become inert. Such existence, then, would not act on anything, but would become mere material to be acted upon. It is only by the faculty of effort that intelligence rises above this condition ; and this faculty, to be avail- able for such elevation to us, without direct, extrinsic aid, must either be continuous, or we must have a re- taining, internal power, with some adaptation to put this retained power in action. In mind, one or the other of the required conditions is fulfilled by the con- stant, or by the recurring influences of want, whicli is the only mode kno^vn to us, and perhaps the only one which is conceivable, for exciting the voluntary action of an intelligent being, and moving it from a quiescent state. If we ever become quiescent, we cease to be cause, and this want nmst then become manifest by some change effected by some active cause without us, the effect of which, from the constitution of our being, we may recognize without effort of our own ; and the fact is, we cannot always prevent such cognition. If J38 FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. our mental activity ever entii-ely ceases, it must then be as if we liad no mind, and w^e must be re-minded before we can again become an active cause ; and this, as before suggested, may be done by want in us, pro- duced by causes to the action of which our own efforts are not essential. If matter in motion is cause, its power, while it has any, is continuous and ready to be exerted whenever the occasion for it occurs. Being unintelligent, no ap- plication of self-moving power to it is possible ; having no mind, it cannot be r«-minded. It must be true of every intelligence, of whatever order, that if its activity entirely ceases, it cannot, of itself, put itself in action, till some extrinsic activity has, in some way, acted upon it ; and the only condi- tion upon which a sole First Cause could entirely sus- pend activity, without annihilation, would be by its first creating other cause, which would continue to be active independently of the creative cause, and which, by producing some subsequent change, would react upon and arouse the now dormant cause which by previous activity created it. There is, however, no reason to suppose that the supi'eme First Cause ever becomes quiescent ; and it is even doubtful whether the finite mind ever does. It is only certain that we do not always remeinber in what we were active, or that we were active in any wise. No intelligent being can do anything unless it makes effort to do something. It may try to do one thing and really do something else. A man may attempt to take a flower ; and, for that purpose, by the requisite voli- tion move the hand, but, instead of reaching the flower, may overturn a vase, which he did not observe. His OF WANT AND EFFORT. 139 plan did not embrace all the essential facts, or circum- Btances ; his knowledge, at least as applied, was defect- ive, and the effect did not conform to the preconception. Still, but for the effort to reach tlie flower, he would not have overturned the vase. If his power does it and yet he does not exert his own power, the power must exert itself, or be exerted by something without him and not of him ; and, in either case, it is not his power, and he has no agency either in putting forth the power, or in producing the effect. He does not even make the signal for some other cause to put the power which produces the effect into action. If, then, the power of an intelligent being is put forth at all, it nmst be by the being to which such power pertains ; and the con- dition which makes the difference between the non- exercise and the exercise of its power is that of effort ; and hence, its effort is necessary to its doing or being the cause of anytliing, even of that which it does not intend to do. But, when an intelligent being makes an effort to do somethi?) g, it is with an intent and design to do it ; and it will not try, endeavor, make effort to do anything which it does not wmit to do. So that, the want to do something is essential to its doing anything, even that which it does not want to do. But, though the want rouses the mind to effort, it does not make or direct the effort. The intelligent agent that perceives the relation of the anticipated sequences of the effort to the want, must do this ; though, without the want, these sequences Avould not be sought. If Napoleon, on the morning of the battle of Austerlitz, had not been aroused from his slumber. he would not then have fought that battle ; but the page, the drum-beat, the cannon's roar, or the want of 14:0 FKEEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. food, of activity, or of gloiy, which aroused him, had nothing to do with the direction or order of the battle. So the want arouses the mind to effort, but does not, and, being unintelligent, cannot direct, or even indicate, what effort. This must be determined by the mind, which uses its knowledge, intuitive or acquired, for that purpose.* But, admitting that want is in all cases a necessary prerequisite to effort, some may suppose that effort is a condition of cause only in a finite being ; and that infinite power accomplishes its ends without effort. Such, however, do not imagine that He produces effects or changes without an act of His will ; and, if our defi- nition of will is correct, this is an effort. To suppose any intelligence to become the cause of any change without some action of its own, is to suppose intelli- gence to be cause and a necessary cause, merely in virtue of its existence. But all the effects of such a cause must be simultaneous with its existence, and its causative power must cease at the moment of its birth. Now, at any given moment of time, all the causes which can influence the immediate succession of events must exist ; and, if the effects of all these causes are necessary consequences of their existence, then these effects must all be coexistent with such existence ; and, even if we suppose one or more of these effects to be the creation of a new cause, if -^'^^ eflects, too, are neces- sary consequences of its existence, they, also, would be coexistent with its creation ; and the causative power of the first cause, with that of all subsequent created causes, would be exhausted at the same instant and no effects could be produced in the future. Hence the necessity * See Appendix, Note XXVII. OF WANT AND EFFORT. 141 of some cause, the efi'ects of whicli do not, of necessity, result from its existence^ but which retains a power of producing change that it does not, of necessity^ exert at the instant — which is not cause merely in virtue of its existence. Matter, retaining, or extending its power in time by means of motion ; and intelligence, with power which it puts in action when it perceives a reason, or has a want ; are the only such conceivable causes. Of these, we have already shown that intelligence, in its powers of effort and of preconception, has a special adaptation to future effects ; and that matter in motion can now be, at most, only its instrument in producing these effects. That God, with His infinite attributes, exists cannot, as already shown, of itself, be a cause of any changes subsequent to the commencement of such existence ; and hence, if such existence embraces a past eternity, His mere existence cannot, of itself, be, or ever have been, the cause of anything which has had a beginning. If the power exerts itself without any effort of the being of which it is an attribute, then that being has no more agency in producing the effect, than if it took place without any exercise of its power whatever. There must be a distinction between that condition of any being, finite or infinite, in which it actively produces, or endeavors to produce change ; and that condition of repose, in which, satisfied with things as they are, or as it perceives they will be, by the agency of other causes, it remains inactive and has no agency in producing change. The former must he a condition of effort. If, in the Supreme Being, there is no such distinction, then the efiects must be independent of His 142 FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. action and are not caused by Him, for they come to pass as well without as with His action. Hence, what- ever has its origin in His agency must require His effort. Much of the reasoning w^hich I have just before this applied to show tlie necessity of effort to the producing of any effect by a finite being, as man, is applicable to any order of intelligent being. The Infinite, however, would never, by its effort, produce effects counter to its intention ; although, through self-active free agents of its own creation, it might be the remote cause, or rather the cause of the cause, of what it did not decree, or even foreknow. The idea that Omnipotence may be creative with- out effort is, perhaps, induced by observing that with every increase of our own power we accomplish any given work with less effort ; and it seems to be a mathe- matical deduction, that M'hen the power becomes infi- nite, the effort must become nothing. But if the mag- nitude of the effect, or the power required to produce it, keeps pace with the magnitude of the power appli- cable to its production, no such consequence is deduci- ble from increase of powder. We look upon ISewton and Napoleon, each in their respective spheres of action, as having had more power in themselves than most men ; but no one supposes they made less effort. On the contrary, M^e are apt to consider the efforts of such men as commensurate with the effects of the exercise of their powers. So, also, if the works of a being of infinite power are infinite, there is at least no reason to suppose that His efforts are not as great as those of a being of finite power producing finite effects. Even Omnipotence has its bound in the absolutely impossible; OF WANT AND EFFORT. 143 and there may be effects, just witliin the verge of possi- bility, approaching so near the impossible as to task even infinite power to accomplish them. There is, however, in the case supposed, no power at all without the eftbrt. If we should speak of a dormant power, we could only mean, not that there is now power, but that there would be power if exerted ; i. e.,m a self-active being, with effort there would be power ; and attribut- ing Omnipotence to any being could only mean that the efforts of such a being may be all-powerful. Effort, then, to which want and knowledge are pre- requisites, is an essential element of a creative being ; and He who governs and controls all the " vast, stu- pendous scheme of things," and reconciles the various and conflicting efforts of numberless free agents in har- monious results, cannot be an inert being, passively looking upon the gradual development of His designs, but must put forth an active energy, must make effort, — must will these results. We have already remarked that want involves the idea, or knowledge of future change, though not of the means of producing change. Want, then, which, in the system we are assei-ting, lies at the foundation as a pre- requisite of effort or will, is also the first incipient, chaotic, but still inchoate stage of those preconceptions of the future by which the mind eventually determines these efforts ; and the want thus has with it the genu of the element of its own gratification. In this we may recognize something of that harmony, or unity which usually pertains only to truth and which ever marks the designs of Infinite Wisdom. But, for the gratification of the want, the mere knowledge tbat change is necessary is not suflBcient. We must know what chaug-e ; and, however small and 144 FEEEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. simple tlie want, or however easy and obvious the means, a creative preconception of them is required. I am hungry, and seek to gratify the want for food. I see bread before me, and know that, by various move- ments of my hand, mouth, tongue, &c. &c. in a certain consecutive order, and only in that order ^ the want may be gratified. I may want a house to give me shelter, and for this a more complicated creation must be designed and a more extended creative power must be put forth, and with the same regard to the order of the efforts, to actualize the creative conception. Still, the mind could design or form such creation within itself, and will, or make effort, to actualize it without itself, if there were no other intelligence or power in existence, or if all other existence were entirely passive ; and hence, feel- ing the want and having the knowledge required to de- termine the mode of gratifying it, could by its own in- herent powers, unaided and unrestrained by any other power, determine, or put forth a corresponding volition, could will the creation it has conceived, and, if there is a direct connection between its volitions and their sequences, the mind can thus actualize its conceptions in a real external creation. ]S^or, so far as relates to the act of will itself, is the mode of that connection im- portant. If the mind only knows that the consequences will, or may follow its volitions, this knowledge is a sufficient basis for its own effort ; for an effort directed by its use of its own knowledge is self-directed and therefore free. Whether there is any direct connection between volition and its final sequences, is a question which we have already considered, though more espe- cially in relation to external phenomena. The same question arises in regard to internal changes, and this will be considered in the next chapter. OllArTER XIV. OP EFFORT FOR INTERNAL CHANOB. In regard to the relation of effort to mtornal changes ; as, can we of ourselves put our internal pow- ers in action ? or, can we repent of evil and change our affections and dispositions solely by our own efforts? we will first remark that, though we may very reason- ably suppose that our own mental efforts are more closely connected with mental than with external ma- terial changes, still, as it appears not improbable that our efforts are made effective in the external by the intermediate agency of the Omnipresent Intelligence, so, in like manner, it may be that the Divine influence is necessary to give eflicacy to our efforts for internal change. The question here raised is whether the se- quences of volition are the immediate effects of our effort to produce them, or if there is some intervening power or cause, to the action of which our own efforts are either necessary, or uniform antecedents. In both cases, however, the important fact that our efforts are necessary antecedents or conditions precedent to the changes is known, and furnishes a good foundation for effort, let the subsequent effects be brought about as they may. If the effort is essential to a desirable result, 1 14f) FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. the reason for the efibrt is the same, whether the result be proximate or remote. Though this is all that is strictly within the scope of our present inquiry, yet, as germane to the subject, we may be permitted to re- mark, that the action of those internal faculties by which we do follows our efforts to use them to increase our knowledge, or to effect other internal change, as uniformly as the bodily movements follow our efforts to produce external change ; the cionnection between the effort and the sequence of it is in both cases equally uniform a,iid equally inscrutable. External circum- stances may affect us both internally and externally, may produce sensation and emotion ; and may, also, move our bodies without our volition and even against it. We cannot directly will a change in our mental affections any more than we can directly will Avhat are termed bodily sensations. We cannot directly will the emotions of hope, or fear, or to be pare and noble, or even to want to become pure and noble, any more than we can directly will to be hungry, or to want to be hungry. If we want to take food we are already hun- gry, and if we want to perform pure and noble actions and to avoid the impure and ignoble, while this want, or disposition prevails, we are already pure and noble. If we want to be hungry, i. e. want to want food, and know that by exercise, or by the use of certain stimulants, or by other means we may become hungry, we may by effort induce this, in such case, a cultivated want ; and if we want to want to be pure and noble and know the means, we may, in like manner, by effort gratify the ex- citing want, and induce the want, which in such case is a cultivated want, to become pure and noble. OF KFFORT FOR INTKRNAL CHANGE. 147 If, from seeing the pleasure which admiring a beau- tiful flower affords to others, or from any other cause, we want to admire it, we would readily perceive that some additional knowledge is essential to that end ; and that the first step is to find, by examination, what in it is admirable. To examine, then, becomes a secondary want, and we will to examine. The result of this ex- amination may be, that its before unknown beauties excite our admiration and make it, or the gazing upon it, an object of want ; so we may also will to examine what is pure and noble till its developed loveliness ex- cites in us, or increases, the want to be pure and noble, and induces a correlative aversion to what is gross and base. It may be that increasing our knowledge of the flower will have an opposite eflPect, and produce disgust, or confirm our indifference. We cannot, by will, de- termine what the knowledge, or the effect of the knowl- Q,(Xgome pa7^tiGular act. NO EVENT WITHOUT A CAUSK. 249 by means of its knowledge. In such case, however, the active nature is not the cause of the soul's acts, but is only the soul's ability to act, in itself as passive as the abili- ty to smell. By means of the combination of the soul's ability to be active with its knowledge as a means of directing that activity, it becomes itself cause, or can produce change, whenever the " occasion is given / " that is, when it wants to produce change, and knows some means of doing it by its power to act. If the willing is not, in fact, the soul's only activity, it is con- ceivable that it might be, and in that case we might say the mind is active in willing ; or that, in willing, it is active; the willing being no more the efiect of its ac- tivity, than the activity is of its willing, nor one the cause of the other, any more than the other is the cause of it. It raises the same question as that to which we before alluded, as raised by Edwards's changing the word IN to BY in his first section (Part II.) on self- determination. In this aspect, the mind in willing, has a striking analogy to that of a body in motion. In de- fining Avill, I have, in explanation, said that it is the " mode in which intelligence exerts its power ; " and that " the willing is the condition of the mind in effort ; and is the only efibrt of which we are conscious." So of a moving body, motion is the mode in which it ex~ erts its power and is the condition of a body in chang- ing place. Activity is the mode in which spirit, or matter, exerts its power. In the case of intelligence this is manifested in willing ; and in that of matter by moving, or changing its place ; and though the body may move in moving, it cannot move hy moving ; for this making its move the cause of its moving or change of place, or the change of place the cause of its moving, 11* 250 EEVIEW OF EDWAEDS ON THE WILL. implies that, that which is thus deemed the cause is prior to the other ; but, as before intimated, they are really the same thing ; and hence, to make one the cause of the other, is to make a thing the cause of it self. So, also, if the willing by the mind is but a cer tain activity, that activity cannot be the cause of the willing, nor the willing the cause of the activity ; for this activity and the willing are one and the same thing, or express the same condition of the mind. The logic by which Edwards, in such cases, makes his favorite re- ductio ad absurdum, in an infinite series, may be ap- plied to any case, in which two equivalent terms, ex- pressing action, are used to define each other ; as, for instance, the mind is in a certain way active in willing ; or, in willing is in a certain way active ; or the mind wills in choosing, or chooses in willing y choosing and willing being taken, as in Edwards's system, as equiva- lents ; or a body moves in changing its position, or changes its position in moving. Between either jDair of equivalents substitute by for in, making one the cause of the other ; and then, being really the same thing, they must be simultaneous, and thus the cause must be both before and at the same time ; or, each may in turn, with equal reason, be alternately made the cause, and then the infinite series, admitting of no beginning or first action or cause, is reached. When Edwards says, " the question is not so much. How a spirit endowed with activity comes to act, as why it exerts such an act and not another, or why it acts with a particular determination ; " he really raises the main question as to whether the mind in willing a certain act, rather than any other of the many conceiv- able acts, is constrained to determine to adopt that act NO EVENT WITHOUT A CAUSE. 251 bv power extrinsic to itself; for, if the determining or controlling power is not extrinsic to itself, it determine? and controls itself in the act of will, which, as we have already shown, is only another expression for its free- dom in willing. He subsequently puts the question in this form : " Why the soul of man uses its activity as it does," admitting that it is the soul, which uses its ac- tivity, but still leaving open the question as to whether, in such use, its act of volition is constrained by some ex- ternal power, or is its own action induced by considera- tions or causes within and of itself. If it is asked why God did not make 2 + 2 = 5, we can say that He may not have had any want to do it, and hence, would not make any effort to that end ; and further, that even with such want, the thing would have been impossible. The impossibility of reconciling contradictions is a condition of action, even to Infinite Power.* If asked, why He made the earth to revolve in a particular orbit, rather than in any other of the infinite number conceivable, we can only say, that He nmst have determined this from considerations purely His own, from His own perception or knowledge of its fitness, in other words, that it was self-determined. There may have been conditions required by His want to create and by what already existed. For instance, if matter was already in motion, and in virtue of its motion, was an extraneous blind power or force, it would furnish certain circumstances to be dealt with. It is conceivable that there may have been only the one particular orbit, which would fulfil the pm'poses of the Creator, and at the same time conform to the other or external conditions. The perception or the * See Appendix, Note XXXIX. 252 REVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. knowledge of this fact, must be the immediate reason for the selection and subsequent effort ; and this knowl- edge may have been the result of previous effort, or series of efforts, springing directly out of the want and such perceptions or knowledge as required no previous act of will. All such knowledge, combining with the knowledge of existing external and internal conditions, makes the sum of the circumstances which the mind has to consider in its decision as to its action, and which the mind alone can decide upon. If there is no application of knowledge required, the effort would be but that of a blind cause, which is to say, there could be no effort. To suppose that no effort is required, is to suppose that the conditions may themselves produce the effect. If the conditions them- selves necessitate one certain volition, then, as the abso- lute conditions at any moment are the same to all, all must have the same volition at the same moment, and if a volition is one of the necessary effects, not of all ex- isting conditions, but of those only of which the mind willing is cognizant, then, at the very moment in which the mind recognizes that such conditions exist, and is thus prepared to direct or to select its act in conformity with this new knowledge, the volition and any neces- sary sequence of it must already have been ; for, by this hypothesis, the mind's action, even in examining, is not essential to the direction of the act, which is con- trolled by the pre-existing and extrinsic conditions, all the effects of the mere existence of which must already have been brought about. If the volition in each being, varies with the particular conditions of which it is cognizant, there must be something which knows what conditions are recognized, and adapts the volition NO EVENT WITHOUT A CAUSE, 253 to tliem, and if it be admitted that these conditions in- clude the circumstance that the mind itself perceives and conforms its act to them, then the mind, by that process, does determine its own act, and of course is free in that act. The examination by the mind, of the con- ditions under which it is about to act, is a preliminary effort to obtain the knowledge by which to direct its final action ; and its first act of examining is directed, not by the conditions, as yet unknown, but by means of its knowledge, intuitive or acquired, that such examina- tion is a proper preparation for further action. It feels a want and knows that the best mode of proceeding to gratify or to determine whether to gratify it or not, is to examine ,' and, liaviiig this want and this knowledge of means, it directs its action accordingly, i. e. on recog- nizing the want, it begins its action by an examination. If it already has a knowledge of the means by former experience, or by intuition, and has no expectation of finding any better means, it needs to examine only so far as to ascertain the existence of tlie circumstances, or conditions, which make the occasion for the application of such knowledge. If, in such cases, the mind acts directly upon its intuitive knowledge of the mode, or means, its action is instinctive ; but if it acts from memo- ry of past experience its action is habitual. It is mani- fest that the pre-existing and extrinsic conditions do not influence the volition, except as they may arouse want, or contribute to the knowledge by which the mind is enabled to decide what it will do, in regard to that want. If, to the question proposed by Edw^ards, " why the soul of man uses its activity as it does," it should be replied, that intelligence, from its very natnre, has a 254 REVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. faculty to determine, or to direct its activity, it would be in conformity to his own previous statements, that the mind has a faculty by which it wills, and that ar act of volition is a determination of the mind. If, there- after, he asks for a cause of the determination of the de- termination, or volition, it is like asking for the end of the end ; and to make a case analogous to that by which he has just argued that the nature of the activity of the soul cannot be the cause of its determination let it be asked, what is the cause, or reason that, a iinite right line has an end ; and let it be replied, that a finite line is limited in its nature and that, on this, the end or " thing so depends, that it is the ground and reason, either in whole, or in part, why it is rather than not, or why it is as it is rather than otherwise," and that this " truly belongs to the reason, why the proposition which affirms that event (or thing), is true ; " and there- fore this is the cause of the end. To tliis reasoning it might be objected that, the line's limited nature can- not be the cause of its having an end, because the cause must be exerted before the efi'ect ; and its limited nature can have no efi'ect, as cause, till it is exerted ; but the exercise, or application of its limited nature is a limit, or end ; and this exercise, or application must be before the limit, or end ; but the limited nature arises from there being a limit, or end ; and therefore, it must be before the limit, or end : and hence, cannot be the cause of the end : and this is parallel to Edwards's saying, " But the exercise of his activity, is action ; and so, his action, or exercise of his activity must be prior to the effects of his activity," &c. (p. 64), and to the reason- ing, which follows it. In the same way, too, it may be Baid that, the existence of the line is not a cause, or NO EVENT WITHOUT A CAUSE. 255 reason wlij tlie ends of the line exist ; because, if so, the existence of the line must be before the existence of its ends, which again is absurd. But the existence of the line and its being finite, are the only two things or conditions upon which the existence, and even the manner of the existence, of the ends depend. If it now be said that the existence of the line and its limited nature are not cause, under Edwards's definition, for the reason that it requires that cause should be antecedent to the efl'ect ; then, it follows, that the existence of the end and the manner of the end may be determined by what, under Edwards's definition^ is not a cause ; which renders nugatory all his argument that the will must be determined by such a cause ; for that, he makes but one inference from his general proposition, that every- thing which begins to be, must have such a cause.* But it cannot be urged that, under Edwards's definitions, anything is not a cause, for the reason that it is not antecedent to the efi'ect ; for he thus defines what he means by being antecedent : " To say, it is caused, influenced and determined by something, and yet not determined by anything antecedent, either in order of time or nature, is a contradiction. For that is what is meant by a thing's being prior in the order of nature, that it is some way the cause or reason of the thing, with respect to which it is said to be prior " (p. 52). So that, a thing being prior to another, or not, may depend on the fact of its being the cause of that other, or not ; and hence, whenever Edwards argues, as he frequently does, that one thing cannot be the cause of another, because it is not prior to it, he begs the question ; for, under his definition, its being prior or * See Appendix, Note XL. 256 REVIEW OF EDAVARDS OX TUE WILL. not, depends on whether it is the cause or not. Its being eau&e depends upon its being antecedent ; and its being antecedent depends upon its being cause. I have thus commented upon that portion of his argument which relates to cause, not so much to dis- prove its particular results, as to show generally, that the consequences, deduced from such a definition of cause, are not reliable, and really prove nothing. It must be borne in mind, that I do not deny the positions of Edwards that every event, which begins to be, must have a cause ; or the necessary dependence of that event upon its cause ; which I have endeavored to show, in their proper application, prove that the mind, itself being cause, wills freely. The prevailing tend- ency of most men to apj:)ly the results of tlieir observa- tion of the connection of cause and eftect in the ma- terial, to the spiritual, leads them to seek a cause, in thepast, for every change, and hence, 1o overlook the important fact, that intelligence, in virtue of its power to anticipate its effects in the future, is a Jlrst cause. We may follow the course of cause backward through a train of consecutive consequences and antecedents, till it comes to an intelligent will, as a first cause, when it doubles on its track and the reason of its action (the efl^'ect it preconceived) is found in the line over which we have been pursuing it ; thus eluding those, who still look for it beyond or in the past. Every act of Avill is the beginning of a series of which all the other terms are in the future ; and all its connection with the past is but the knowledge, whicli the mind uses in directing its own action, as an intelli- gent cause of future eflfects ; and this knowledge, at the time of the willing, is in the mind's view, is then in the NO EVICNT WIIHOUT A CAUSE. 207 present and not in the past. If from an intelligent being w^e cut off, or annihilate all the past, or if to such being there never had been any past ; if it came into existence with want, and the knowledge of the mode of gratifying that want by acts of will or effort having reference only to the future, it conld still determine and direct its efforts as well as if it were conscious of a past in which it had obtained some or all of this knowledge. It may be said, that a being's coming into existence with such want and knowledge^ is an event which must have a cause in the past, with which it is necessarily connected and which determines the manner and mode of its existence ; but this does not affect tlie question of its freedom. If, from any cause, a being has come into existence with power to control and direct its own efforts, such being is free in such efforts, so that the question, is such being free, is not affected by the cause through which it came to exist. If it be said that the want and knowledge, which are necessary conditions of such a being, control the act of will, it may be replied, that neither of these, nor both combined, can make effort or will, unless they constitute the intelligent being that wills ; and, in that case, they also constitute a free agent. If every act of will is determined b}' the whole past, then that whole past is the cause of such act of will ; and being, at every instant, the same to all, if the same causes necessarily produce the same effects, every mind would will at the same instant and will the same thing. If the act of will in each is determined by that portion of the past of which he is cognizant, then there must be something to adapt the act, in each case, to this varia- tion in the knowledge of the past ; and this can only be 258 REVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. done bj something which knows what this portion of the past is to which the act of will is to be adapted. This the " past" or other unintelligent cause cannot do. We shall have occasion to notice this supposed de- pendence of volition on a cause in the past, in examin- ing other portions of Edwards's argument, and espe- cially that in which he treats of motive as such a cause. CHAPTEE YI. OF THE WILL DETERMINING IN THINGS INDIFFERENT. Edwards says, " A great argument for self-deter- mining power is the supposed experience we univei'sally have of an ability to determine our wills, in cases wherein no prevailing motive is presented. The will, as is supposed, has its choice to make between two, or moi-e things, that are perfectly equal in the view of the mind, and the will is apparently altogether indifferent ; and yet we find no difficulty in coming to a choice ; the will can instantly determine itself to one, by a sovereign power, which it has over itself, without being moved by any preponderating inducement." (Sec. 6, p. 73.) This mode of stating the case seems to be warranted by the extracts which he makes from the writings of some of his opponents, but I think it is not well stated. Among other objections, it supposes the 'will to choose and, also, virtually assumes that the mind determines its act of will by a previous act of will ; and, as in Edwards's system, an act of will and choice are the same, it is not difficult under it to elaborate much absurdity from such a statement. In putting their argument into his own terms, he makes them say, that the will is apparently 200 REVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. altogetlier indifferent, and yet, we find no ditficulty in coming to a choice. Now, if will and we are not the same thing, if he does not embrace our whole being in will, this is merely saying that A is indifferent, and yet J3 finds no difficulty. In reply to one whom Edwards supposes to advocate the position as above stated, he says, " The very supposition which is here made, dii'ectly contradicts and overthrows itself. For the thing supposed, wherein this grand argument consists, is that among several things the will actually chooses one before another, at the same time that it is perfectly indifferent ; which is the very same thing as to say, the mind lias a preference at the same time that it has no preference." (Sec. 6, p. 74.) And again, " If it be pos- sible for the understanding to act in indifference, yet to be sure the will never does ; because the will's begin- ning to act is the very same thing as its beginning to choose or prefer. And if, in the very first act of the will, the mind prefers something, then the idea of that thing preferred does, at that time, preponderate or pre- vail in the mind ; or, wliich is the same thing, the idea of it has a prevailing influence on the will. So that this wholly destroys tiie thing supposed, viz. : that the mind can, by a sovereign power, choose one of two, or more things, which in the view of the mind are, in every respect, perfectly equal, one of which does not at all preponderate, nor has any prevailing influence on the mind above another." (Sec. 6, p. 76.) The whole force of this objection is subsequently more concisely thus stated : " To suppose the will to act at all in a state of perfect indifterence, either to deter- mine itself, or to do anything else, is to assert that the mind chooses without choosing " (sec. 6, p. 77) ; and OF WILLING IN THINGS INDIFFERENT. 261 he might have added, in view of his definition, that this is to wasert that there is an act of the will, when there is no act of tlie wilL His opponents, however, taking his own statement, really make no such asser- tion ; and it is obvious that these objections to them, repeated as thej are in various forms, are but logical deductions from the assumption that the choosing by the mind is an act of will, or that an act of will and choice are identical ; upon which I have already com- mented. In Edwards's statement of the views of his opponents, as quoted at the commencement of this chapter, it is not clear what is meant by the phrase, " self-determining power." If it means only self-deter- mining power of the will, or that the mind determines its acts of will by other acts of will, it is, as before stated, wholly irrelevant to my position, which does not rest upon, or involve that dogma ; but if, as some of the subsequent remarks indicate, it also means a power in the mind to control its acts of will, it is proper that we should notice the arguments which deny this. In view of these several objections to the statement, as made by Edwards, I think the argument would be more fairly stated thus : A great argument for the self- determining power of the mind is the supposed expe- rience we universally have of an ability to will in cases where the mind is indifferent as to the several objects of choice, and has no preference among the several movements or modes by any one of which it perceives that it can accomplish some one of the several objects among which it is indifferent as to which one. This statement excludes all preference among several objects, some one of which it is desirable to obtain or to accom- plish ; also, all preference as to several modes of obtain- 262 EEVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. ing or accomplislung that object, some one of which must be adopted in order to accomplish it. It will be perceived that if the statement went farther than this, and made the mind also indifferent as to the accom- plishment of this one object, that, then, the mind would have no inducement in the premises to act, no want, and in such case there would be no act of will to reason about ; and if it went farther in another direction, and made the mind also indifferent as to its willing or not willing, thus assuming that it can have no preference even in that act, it would, in view of Edwards's defini- tion, entirely shut out the admitted act of will in the premises, and exclude the very question, which he really raises in this connection, viz. : how that act of will, or preference, or effort, which we put forth to make this movement or action, by which to obtain the object, is determined when there are several such ob' jects and several such movements all equal in the mind's view, and among which it has no preference and can find no ground for any. It would virtually assert that the mind did not, in such case, will at all ; and especially would it do this, under the system of Ed- wards, which makes preference and will the same. In the system I have advanced, this same result would also be reached ; for, if the mind is indifferent as to whether to will or not, it has no want to will ; or, at least, none which is not neutralized by a conflicting want, and it will not will. The statement I have suggested then, affirms all the indifference in regard to an act of will, which it can, without being self-contradictory. To illus- trate the statement, suppose a man wants only one egg of which there are several before him, each in his view equally good and equally easy to be obtained ; no OF WILLING IN THINGS INDIFFERENT. 263 choice either in the eggs, or in the several inovoments, or actions necessary to obtain some one to gratify tlie want ; and yet the mind does will one of the many equal movements or actions, to obtain one of the many eggs, wliich are all equal in its view, and thus gratifies its want to have some one of them. It cannot be in- tended by the advocates of a self-determining power of the mind to say, that the mind determines to will when it has no object in willing ; when it has no de- sire to produce any effect and is wholly indifferent as to exercising its will ; and yet, the last objection quoted from Edwards, seems to assume that some of them take this position. If he merely refutes this position, as thus assumed, it cannot affect the system I have stated in Book First, for such an indifference wholly excludes the existence of a want, which, in that system, is a pre- requisite of the action of the mind in willing ; and, of course, in it, volition is precluded when there is no want. And if, when Edwards argues that the mind cannot wiD in a state of indifference, he means that it cannot will when there is not only no choice as to the several objects, or the several actions presented, but, also, no choice as to whether it acts at all in regard to any one of the equal objects or actions, he merely as- serts that the mind cannot will when it has no want for will, or cannot exert its power to influence the future when it does not want to exert it ; and, in this, the ad- vocates of freedom certainly need not differ with him. The particular cases which he cites, however, do permit the existence of such want, and, in other respects, con- form to the supposed indifference as I have stated it. He admits too, that in such cases, the mind does ac- tually will ; and to get over the difficulty, which, under 264 REVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. his system, arises from tlie existence of a volition, wlien there is nothing in the mind's view, no motive, to in- duce ih.Q j>artic alar preference^ which, by his theory, is that volition, he supposes the mind itself to devise a way of getting itself out of this state of indifi'erence, or this equilibrium, as to the objects of choice ; and thus to obtain the preference — the volition — which he admits does occur. He says : " Tlius, supposing I have a chess board before me ; and because 1 am required by a superior, or desired by a fi'iend, to make some experi- ment concerning my own ability and liberty, or on some other consideration, I am determined to touch some one of the spots or squares on the board with my finger ; not being limited or directed in the first pro- posal, or my own first purpose, which is general to any one in particular ; and there being nothing in the squares in themselves considered, that recommends any one of ail the sixty-four more than another " (pp. 77, 78). The ditficulty here presented is, that the mind has determined to touch some one of the sixty-four squares, but perceives no ground of choice, and hence, cannot choose between them, or will to touch any one. To get over this difficulty Edwards goes on to say, " In this case, my mind gives itself up to what is vulgarly called accident, by determining to touch that square, which happens to be most in view, which my eye is especially upon at that moment, or which happens to be then most in my mind, or which I shall be directed to by some other such like accident. Here are several steps of the mind's proceeding, though all may be done as it were in a moment ; the first step is its general deter- mination, that it will touch one of the squares. The next step is another general determination to give itself OF WILLING m THINGS INDIFFERENT. 2G5 up to accident, in some certain way ; as to toucli that which shall be most in the eye or mind, at that time, or to some other such like accident. The third and last step is a jpa/rticular determination to touch a cer- tain individual spot, even that sqnare, which, by that sort of accident, the mind has pitched upon, has actually offered itself beyond others." (Sec. 6, p. Y8.) In a note, he defines " what is vulgarly called accident," as " something that comes to pass in the course of things in some affair that men are concerned in, unforeseen and not owing to their designs." The object of this posi- tion seems to be, to show that, in such cases, admitting that the mind does will, yet it does not determine its own act of will, or preference ; but, that the act is de- termined by something extraneous to the mind and which, by it, is " unforeseen and not owing to its de- sign," and, if it could be established that the will, in such cases, is determined hy force of this " something," over which the mind has no control, it would seem to establish necessity at least in such cases. The argu- ment, however, appeal's to be unfortunate in many re- spects. While denying that the mind can by its own action, and without this " something," over which it has no control, get itself out of this state of indifference, it begins by showing how it can do so ; for when it says, " in this case the mind determines to give itself up to what is vulgarly called accident," it is the mind that does it. And more especially is it intended to deny, that the mind can get itself out of this dilemma by an act of volition. But in Edwards's system, and in any system to be of any avail, this determining of the mind " to give itself up to what is vulgarly called accident," must either be itself a volition, or be followed 12 266 REVIEW OP EDWARDS ON THE WILL. by a volition of that mind, whicli is thus made to get itself out of a state of indijfterence by means most espe- cially denied to it. That it does this by its own act of will, cannot, of course, be an argument against the liberty of the mind in willing. I have before remarked that the mind's forming a plan, in which, by successive acts of will, in a certain order, it reaches ends which it cannot reach by a direct act of will, is one of the ways in which it manifests its creative power ; and if, in cases of indifference, like those above cited, it plans to do that by indirection which it cannot do directly, it no more militates against its freedom, than does its succes- sive acts in obtaining, chewing and swallowing food to satisfy the hunger it cannot appease by a direct act of will. But it does not apppear to be at all certain, that the mind, in this case, is under any necessity to adopt this indirect mode, or even that it is thereby relieved of any of the supposed difficulty of willing directly. Even if the mind in willing, or choosing the particular square, is determined by the accident ; still, in determining to give itself up to accident, it is not determined by the accident ; for the accident itself is not yet determined, and may not even be in the view of the mind, which Edwards holds to be essential to every motive ; and hence, if the mind does not directly determine to give itself up to the accident and thus determine its own act, instead of the one question, as to how the mind determines the particular square, we have two other questions, firstly, how the mind determines to give itself up to accident, and, secondly, how it determines the particular accident by which its choice of the square is to bt' determined. By the hypothesis, the only object OF WILLING IN THINGS INDIFFERENT. 267 the mind can have in giving itself np to the accident is to determine thereby which particnlar sqnare it will toncli ; and there must be many of these accidents among which the mind can have no possible preference, as one will answer the purpose exactly as well as another ; and the question arises, how the mind can prefer or choose one of these rather than another, any more than it can prefer or choose one of the sixty-four squares of the chess board. The mind's ability to make such choice, cannot arise from the nature of the acci- dent ; for, if we conceive of two accidents exactly oppo- site in their nature in every respect, still one will answer the purpose just as well as the other. It may be the passing of a cloud ; the shooting of a star ; the advent of a comet ; or the not happening of any of these events. That the occurring of one accident may be more agreeable than another can be Jio reason for the selection, for such selection lias no more influence to cause it to occur, than to cause it not to occur. As to the place of its occurrence, it is only essential to the purpose intended, that it should be within the limits of the mind's observation ; as to time, it is conceivable that the mind may have a preference ; it may prefer to be out of the state of indifl'erence as quickly as pos- sible, and hence, prefer to select such an accident as its knowledge indicates may soonest happen ; but if the application of this knowledge, by the mind, is not precluded by the condition that this accident is " some- thing unforeseen and not owing to its design," still, even with such conditions, there must be a great num- ber of such accidents, the chances of an early occur- rence of which are in the mind's view just equal ; and hence affording no ground of preference among them 2()8 REVIEW OF EDWAKDS ON THE WILL. in this respect. The ground of preference cannot be in the effect of the accident, not even in the preconcep- tion of the effect, for tlie only effect that can come into notice at all, is the determining that, in regard to the determination of which the mind is indifferent ; and tliis consideration of itself seems to preclude all ground of preference among the conceivable accidents, except that in regard to time, as just mentioned ; and, any such preference must, under Edwards's system, be an act of will ; and determination of a subsequent act of will by it would be the will's determining itself, which is the thing he denies. But, however this may be, it is certain that the mind may be as indifferent as to the selection of a particular accident from among a number of accidents, any one of which will answer its purpose equally well, as it can be in regard to the particular square on the chess board ; and hence, will be as un- able to determine the particular accident to be selected for use, as to determine the particular square to be touched, and we have a recurrence of the difficulty in the very means devised to surmount it. In the particular case which Edwards selects, he seems to avoid some of these difficulties. He says, " by determining to touch that square which happens to be most in view, which my eye is especially upon at that moment," &c. &c. This, however, is not such an acci- dent as lie defines, " as unforeseen," for it has already OGGurred^ is seen, and is a part of the certain knowledge of the mind ; and if he should adopt such events, instead of the accidents just considered, and thus avoid some of the difficulties which arise with them, he would im- mediately encounter another ; for, if the certain knowl- edge of the mind can be used, in place of the accident, OF WILLING m THINGS LNDIFFEEENT. 269 to determine tbe cuse of indifference, one can as well Bay, I will touch a certain square because 2 + 2=4, as because loy eye happens to rest ujDon it ; for, if the indifterence actually existed while the eye was thus rest- ing upon it, that fact, of itself, could not prevent the in- difference any more than the fact that 2 + 2=4, could prevent it ; and the same of any other fact known at the time of the indifference. If I know that by accident 1 cut my finger yesterday, it will no more help me out of a present case of indifference, than any other known fact. I know that on the chess board there is a square in one particular corner, and I can just as well determine to touch that particular square without the knowledge of any previous accident as with it. To do this, one of the preparatory steps is to direct the eye to that square, and, when the indifference is only as to what square is touched, selecting one to which the eye is already di- rected, saves one preparatory step in the process ; but, if this is the consideration which prevails, then it ceases to be a case of indifference ; for the mind, though still indifferent as to the sqttare touched, is not indifferent as to the action in touching. Among the circumstances already existing, and in that examination of them, which the mind habitually, and perhaps, in the first instance instinctively makes, it then perceives a reason for oni' act rather than any other, and it is not such a case of in<.:if- ference as the argument supposes ; it does not differ fr^^m cases comprehending a large proportion of those practi- cally arising, in which the mind by a ] relinunary par ticular effort examines before it decides, or even inclines to any particular final action. But, be this as it may, it must be admitted that an event of which the exist- ence is already certain is not su(;h an accident as Ed 270 REVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. wards contemplates or deiines ; and, if he means that the movement of tlie eye is to be subsequent to the de- termination of the mind to give itself up to the acci- dent of its movement, then he has selected an event which is dependent on that mind's will, which it can foresee and must design ; and the difficulty is solved hy the mind's own self-determined act of will. It is making the act of the mind in willing to touch a particular square, depend upon the act of the mind in willing the movement of the eye ; and such a solution of the diflfi- culty becomes an argument for the self-direction or free- dom of the mind in willing. If it be said that the movement of the eye, though the efi'ect of design and volition, is still so far accidental that the mind can direct it to the board without direct- ing it to any particular square, the same may also be said of the movement of the finger. Why not, then, make the movement of the iinger, in the act of touching it, the means of determining? I apprehend that the movement of the eye has been selected rather than that of the finger, only because we are less sensible of the uncertainty of a muscular eifort upon the hand, than upon the eye. The movement of either to a particular point, requires care ; and to do it with facility, that skill or ready apprehension of the required muscular movements and their successive order, which results from practice, inducing habit. It must be learned. The child is not at once able to direct the movement of its hand to a particular spot ; and though we may learn to do it with great certainty and facility, we never do it without some care and attention. We learn about what amount and what kind of muscular movement are required to move the hand to a particular point, but OF WILLING IN THINGS INDIFFERENT. 271 still, we are generally obliged to watch the result and to modify the movement as it approaches the destined spot. This is evident from the fact that if we close one eye, so that we cannot so readily see the position of the finger and measure the relative distances of it and tlie spot to be touched, we must move it much more slowly as it approaches the spot, than we need to do with both eyes open, or we shall be very liable to miss it alto- gether. The movements of the eye are, no doubt, sub- ject to a similar uncertainty and require similar care properly to direct them, though such care is less ob- servable than in the case of the finger. If, on the other hand, it be said that the movement of the finger is too certain and, therefore, not sufficiently accidental to answer the purpose of the mind in getting itself out of a state of equilibrium, it may withhold this care; or the eyes may be partially or wholly closed, and thus any required degree of uncertainty obtained in the movement of the finger. The movement of the finger thus, under certain obtainable circumstances, partakes as much of the nature of an accident as the movement of the eye; and hence, Edwards might as well have made the movement of the finger and its resting on a particular spot the reason for touching that spot, as to have made use of the movement of the eye for that pui'pose ; and this would be to make the mind determine the act of touching in the act of ti^oching ; or to determine its act directly instead of indirectly through, or by another act; and this, -so far as the act has reference to touching a particular square, excludes Edwards's idea that the act is determined by that " mo- tive," which " has some sort or degree of tendency or advantage to excite the yvWl previous to the effect." 272 EKVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. It is liowever olivions that the jBnger, in its approach to, or in its first contact with the board, may come into a position, wliich, in the view of the mind, is just equal as to some two, or some four squares, and that the same is also true of the eye ; and hence, in either case, the difficulty of indifference may again occur ; and Edwards has evidently selected that, which, so far as it is an accident, is liable to the difficulty of indifference in its application, even after the difficulty of indiffisr- ence in selecting it has been sui-mounted. But, sup- posing the difficulty of indifference in selecting the acci- dent to be gotten over, and that, in some way, the mind " has pitched upon " " that sort of accident " by which " a certain individual spot " " has actually offered itself beyond others ; " in what way does the " accident," a passing cloud, for instance, determine the particular square to be touched, or the action by which it is to be touched? In what way can it be cause at all, and, es- pecially, in what way can it be the cause of the deter- mination by the mind to touch a j>articiila)' square, or of its act of will to touch, or of its cJiocsing or prefer- ring a particular square to be touched ? There mani- festly may be nothing in the event or accident itself, tending to such effects or results any more than there is in the fact that 2 + 2 = 4; as well suppose the square itself to determine, as the event itself to deter- mine. There is evidently no less difficulty in selecting one particular accident from among myriads of acci- dents, all equal for its purpose, than in selecting one particular square from the sixty-four, all likewise equal. There is then no more difficulty in selecting the square, than in selecting the accident, to say nothing of the difficulties of indifierence, before suggested, in applying OF WILLING m THINGS INDIFFERENT. 273 the accident after it is selected. It is obvious that the whole causal efficacy in the case must subsist, not in the event, or accident, but in some rule which the mind itself makes in the pi-eniises ; as, for instance, that if the cloud passes easterly a certain square shall be touched ; and if westerl}^, then another certain square. Such a rule would conform to Edwards's hypothesis " that it will touch that square, which happens to be most in view," &c. But how does the mind determine this rule as to the square to be touched ? It has no less indifi'erence and no more preference as to which of the sixty-four squares each division of the rule shall be ap- plicable, nor to which two of the sixty-four the whole rule shall apply, than it has as to which one shall be touched. Again, supposing this difficulty surmounted ; if the mind makes a mere arbitrary rule, that, if the cloud passes easterly it will touch a certain square, and, if westerly, another certain square, being still indiifer- ent as to which of tlie squares is touched, it can cer- tainly just as well make the rule that, if it passes west- erly, the same and not another certain square is to be touched, thus making it certain that, let it pass which way it will, one particular square is to be touched ; and this being the same as determining, in any event^ to touch one certain square, it follows that the event and the rule of its application may be dispensed with alto- gether ; or, in other words, the mind can as well direct- ly determine the particular square to be touched, as it can the particular square to the touching of which the event and rule shall apply when it is indifferent as to which it will touch ; and, consequently, as to which the event and rule shall apply. Suppose, however, we in some way overcome all these difficulties of making 12* 274 KEviEw or edwaeds on the will. and applying a rule to a certain square in preference to other squares, when, by the hypothesis, there is not and canuot be any ground for such preference, and that the rule is actually made and applied, the whole efficacy, the whole causative power or influence to determine the mind in willing to one particular square, is in the mind's making the rule and abiding by it ; or, which is the same thing, the mind's governing itself by an ar- bitrary rule of its own creation, which is to assert for it a freedom equal to that of Omnipotence. It is a free- dom apparently even beyond that which I have asserted for it, in governing itself by the knowledge, intuitive or acquired, which it has merely found and has not itself created ; and the mind, in the supposed indirect mode of determining in cases of indiiference, would exhibit not only nioi'e creative power and more contrivance, but give stronger expi'ession of its freedom than it could do in difectly deteimining its acts of will in such cases. Again, the rule, even after it has been created by the mind, has in itself no causative power. It is the mind's abiding by it and thus executing it, that gives it all its efficacy and causality ; and hence, the hy- pothesis of Edwards, that the mind gives itself up to accident, if true, only proves that the mind adopts a course by which it determines its own volitions under the circumstances which are supposed to present the • greatest difficulties to its so doing ; and by a means as arbitrary and self-originated, as a direct determination of the act of willing to touch the particular square would be ; and notliiug is lost to tlie argument in favor of freedom, or gained to that in favor of necessity by the indirection. The supposed cases of indifference, however, do seem OF WILLING Dif THINGS INDIFFERENT. 275 to militate against the tlieorj of Edwards, for they ad^ mit an act of will, when there is nothing without the mind, and bo previous bias or inclination in it, to direct its action. All that Edwards calls motive is, there- fore, excluded bj the hypothesis ; and his attempt to bring in some extraneous event, and thus get a con- sh'UGtive motive, entirely failing, the whole decision has to be referred directly to the intelligence that wills, act- ing without that preference or choice in regard to the objects presented, which usually is a portion of the knowledge by which the mind determines its action. So far as relates to a particular square or act, neither the motive which in his system is essential to the will- ing, nor the preference which, in it, is the willing itself, appears to have any existence, or to be possible in his supposed cases of inditference. The argument of Ed- wards assumes that it is necessary that the mind should not only choose to touch, but that it should also choose among the ohjects of touch. In his system, to will is to choose, and there can be no act of will but as an act of choice. If this choice must be a choice among the ex- trinsic ohjects of effort, in the sense in which he applies it to the square of the chess board, then a man never could thus will, when there was only one such object ; a man could not will to take one egg unless there were at least two eggs to choose from, for with less than two, there could be no choice among the objects of choice. It not only is not necessary to the linal action to de- liberate and decide, or to choose among ohjects which we immediately perceive to be equal, but it is not ne- cessary that we should so choose among those in which we know or suppose there is a difference. I may, with my eyes open, thrust my hand into an uncovered basket 276 REVIEW OF EDWAEDS ON THE WILL. of apples with as little regard to selection as if a cover, or my eyelids concealed tliem from my sight. In such cases, and in cases in which there is obviously no choice, I take as if there were but one, without choice, and be- stow no more care upon the act than is necessary to di- rect my hand to the mass, and not to grasp more than one. In reference to the bearing of the views, elicited in Book Fii'st, upon such cases of indifterence, I would ol)- serve that, in the case we have been considering, the want to touch one and only one of the squares, is the whole ground of the mind's acting at all ; that delibera- tion is not, perhaps, entirely excluded ; but that, at the moment of commencing the examination, the mind per- ceives that there is no dill'erence in the objects present- ed ; and hence, dispenses with any further exercise of its power of comparing and judging ; it being, as before stated, for the mind to decide, by the exercise of its judgment, how Jong it will examine a subject before de- ciding its final action in regard to it. That it must pos- sess the power to thus end an examination and to judge of how far it will examine, is evident in almost every act of will, and even in cases of inditference, which, comparison as to the objects being useless, seem more nearly to exclude the exercise of the judgment than any other. For instance, in the act of touching a square on the chess board, the movements of the hand by which this may be accomplished are absolutely in- iinite, for there is no limit to the straight, curved and zigzag lines by which the hand may be moved to the board ; and if the mind must examine each one and compare it with the others before it decides in which one it will move its hand to the board, it would never or WILLING IN THINGS INDIFFERENT. 277 get ready to will to move at all ; and as it does will, it must have the power to will, not only without choos- ing among all the objects of choice, buo even without that examination and comparison which are essential to choosing among them all. The fact seems to be that the mind having perceived some mode of action, which will gratify its want, determines of itself by the pre- liminary exercise of its judgment, whether to adopt that mode, or look further for a better mode before adopt- ing it ; and that it often acts in doubt as to whether it has made a sufficient examination. How much time may be devoted to such examination, as already stated, is a matter of which the mind, in view of the circumstances, must judge. A man who has not long fasted, may seek the stalled ox and pass the dinner of herbs, which one famishing with hunger could not prudently do. When the mind comes to the conclusion — judges or knows — that the chances of advantage by further ex- amination are balanced by the chances of disadvantage from the incident delay, it will cease to examine and will decide and act with such knowledge as it has ; but more especially, as in cases of inditference, when it knows that no examination will i-eveal anv advantag-e, will it cut off the examination and immediately determine its action. It would seem to be natural, or in conformity to that constitution which God has given to the finite mind, that it should will immediately on perceiving any mode of gratifying a want that it feels ; though it is quite conceivable that the knowledge of deliberation as a means of adapting its acts to cii-cumstances, or as essential to safety, may be intuitive. An animal with only one want and with no other knowledge than that of oi.e means of gratifying it, would immediately will ; 278 REVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. but in a being with conflicting wants and a knowledge of various modes of gratifying them, and also of various consequences of the gratification, to will becomes a more complicated matter. Even then, as before suggested, want may become so imperative, as in the case of im- minent danger, sudden and violent excitement, and of appetites habitually um-estrained and nurtured into passion, that it shuts out all secondary considerations, all the results of its acquired knowledge and experience, all deliberation as to consequences ; and acts as if it knew but the one want and the one mode of its gratifi- cation ; and in such case, is reduced to a condition simi- lar to that of an animal with mere intuitive knowledge and consequent instinctive action. But it may be as- serted as a matter of fact, that in most cases the human mind avails itself of a variety of knowledge in the mode of gratifying its wants ; and especially of its past ex- perience as to the subsequent eliect of different modes, which requires examination and an exercise of its powers of conceiving, comparing and judging ; and this exami- nation is an element which the mind itself, in virtue of its intelligence, its knowledge, intuitive or acquired, in- troduces between its want and its final action.* But in a case in which, by the hypothesis, there can be no difference in the proposed modes of gratifying the want and no use in such examination, the mind in recogniz- ing this fact, dispenses with the examination ; and thus instead of adding a new process to aid its determina- tion in such cases, as Edwards supposes, it merely omits, wholly or partially, one to wliicli it is accustomed to resort in other cases. Tlie mind wanting to touch one of the squares and perceiving that there can be no * See Appendix. Note XLI. OF WILLING IN THINGS INDIFFERENT. 279 preference between them, omits the preliminary effort to judge and decide as to such preference, and decides arbitrarily as between them, or as to some known modes by which the finger can be placed on some one of these squares without having found any ground for preference, for the reason that such a decision is neces- sary to gratify its want. In otlier cases the mind may be aware that tliere may be reasons for one act rather than another, which it cannot take time to ascertain, because of the necessity of immediate action ; or will not, because in its judg- ment, the time requireci can be more advantageously employed ; and it cuts short the deliberation, deciding with such knowledge as it has. In the case of indiffer- ence we cut short this deliberation the moment we per- ceive that it cannot possibly reveal any new or better ground of action, and determine the matter in a direct act of will. It may be said, that at the moment of coming to the decision not, or no longer to deliberate, s)me one square must be in the mind's view, or which, as Edwards supposes, "the eye is especially upon at that moment." But suppose the attention or the eye is at that moment directed to the line common to two, or to the point common to four squares, it is still a case of indifference, to be determined by the direct and arbi- trary act of the mind, when there is nothing external to it to control or direct, or even influence its choice or its effort, making a strong case of the exercise of its free creative power, as an originating first cause of change in the future ; and as already stated, if the mind does this, as asserted by Edwards, by means of an ar- bitrary rule of its own making or adopting, it is a still stronger manifestation of its power and of its freedom. 280 REVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. It may not be wholly irrelevant here to observe that these supposed cases of selecting in things indifi'erent are somewhat analogous to that we have before sug gested, in which the mind wants to will for the mere exercise of its faculty of will, without reference or pi'eference as to what it wills ; and as, in that case, after deciding to gratify its want, there is neither object, present or future, nor mode of obtaining the object be- tween the want and the willing, which is itself the object, there is no room for deliberation between, and the want to will is gratified by a direct act of will, without the preliminary processes of comparing and judging to select among the objects and modes. So, in the case oiindifference as to the object and the modes of attaining it, the mind having determined to attain one of the objects, by one of the modes, as soon as it perceives that, as supposed, there is really nothing to examine, no room for deliberation between its want to touch ^\i.d its will to touch, nothing but this act of will needed between its want and the effect, which is to gratify its want ; it wills directly in the premises. It may throw some further light on this curious problem to remark that Edwards's hypothesis of an ar- bitrary rule in these cases of indifference seems to de- rive some plausibility from an apparent analogy to the deciding between two parties having equal rights. For instaace, two persons have equal claims to some- thing which is indivisible and must be possessed wholly and at all times by one and not by the other, any divis- ion of the substance of the thing, or of the time of its possession destroying its value. In such cases the cir- cumstances suggest a decision by what Edwards calls accident ; something which neither of the interested OF WILLING I3Sr THINGS INDIFFEKENT. 281 parties can foresee or control, as the drawing of lots, throwing of dice, &c. ; but here the elements of justice and of two conflicting wills to be reconciled, really make all the necessity for resorting to an accident which is beyond their prescience and control, that each may have, under the rule adopted, an equal chance. If the matter were referred to one other will, to an im- partial judge, the action of whose mind, in such case no human intelligence could prognosticate, his decision, or rather his action, a mere arbitrary act of his will — there being by the hypothesis no possible reason why he should decide one way rather than another, — would be such an accident as Edwards suggests, and do just as well as drawing lots, or throwing dice. If the judge should order the case decided by lot, he would still have to make an arbitrary rule, as that he who draws number one shall have the thing ; or that he who draws number two, shall have it. It is evident that he could just as w^ell decide between the two equal claimants, as between the two equal rules. He must resort to this mode then, not because it is any easier, but for some other reason, as, for instance, to satisfy the parties or himself, that the decision is impartial, or that each really had an equal chance ; or to avoid the unpleasant duty of depriving, by his own direct act, one or the other of his equal right. The analogy, then, furnishes no ground for the supposed necessity of re- sorting to an " accident " to determine the will in cases of inditFerence, where there is no question of per- sonal right or interest. Still another reason for the supposed difhculty, or inability of the mind to deter- mine in cases of " indifference," as urged by Edwards, is its apparent analogy to cases of mere matter, kept at 282 KEVIEW OF EDWAKDS ON THE WILL. rest by external forces acting equally upon it in all directions. An argument from such analogy really begs the question ; for the only reason why mere mat- ter is thus kept at rest is that it lias no self-moving power or faculty within it, no means of moving itself, which is the very thing asserted and denied of intelli- gence or mind, in this controversy as to its freedom in willing. If we suppose mere matter to have a self-im- pelling force imparted to it, by motion or otherwise, then, if acted upon equally in all directions by other forces, it moves by its self-impelling force, precisely as if these other equal and conflicting forces were annihi- lated ; they neutralize each other. And so, if the mind has a self-determining power in itself, then, if equally acted upon in all directions by external forces, its in- ternal force would be unimpaired, and the moment it knows that the various objects or modes of its action presented to it are all exactly equal, it decides among them as readily and as easily as if there were only one such object or mode, and the sole question was as to adopting it, or not acting at all. We before reached this same result which seems to be attested by observa- tion, indicating the existence of su(;h a power. A man wanting one egg, and having decided to gratify the want, may particularly examine every one of a number before him, and having satisfied himself that, so far as he can know, all are equal, he takes one without further hesitation. Among the infinite modes of taking it, he decides among those apparently equal, in the same way. So, also, a man wanting to touch one of the squares on the chess board, has already, in virtue of the constitution of his being, his faculty of effort, his want and his knowledge, a certain inherent force which is not OF WILLING IN THINGS INDIFFERENT. . 283 ajffected by the presence of sixty-four sqii:ires in all respects equal ; and the moment he perceives their cer- tain equality, he touches one of them as readily as if there were only one to touch, having first decided to touch one rather than not to touch. If there were only one, the same supposed difficulties might arise as to what particular spot upon that one to touch ; or by which of the infinite lines of movement to approach it. In all these cases, as already intimated, it is not neces- sary that the mind should even ascertain that the ob- jects and modes are all equal ; but only, that the chances of advantage by its finding any ground of preference or otherwise, are, in its judgment, not suffi- cient to warrant the application of further time and labor to the investigation. CHAPTER VII. KELATION OF INDIFFERENCE TO FREEDOM IN WrLLING. In his seventh section (Part II), Edwards considers the notion of " Liberty of Will consisting in indiffer- ence," using the term indifference as directly opposed to preference. He argues that " to make out this scheme of liberty tlie indifference must be perfect and absolute. * * * Because, if the will be already in- clined before it exerts its own sovei'eign power on itself, then its inclination is not wholly owing to itself" (p. 85). By will Edwards asserts he means the soul willing (p. 43 j. He also makes inclination, choice and preference each synonymous with act of will (p. 2). The statements on the same page with the above quotation also clearly show that Edwards liere uses the terms inclination, choice and preference as synonyms, viz. : " Surely the will cannot act or choose contrary to a remaining prevailing inclination of the will. To sup- pose otherwise, would be the same thing as to suppose that the will is inclined contrary to its present prevail- ing inclination.^ or contrary to what it is inclined to. That which the will chooses and prefers, that, all things considered, it preponderates and inclines to. It is RELATION OF INDIFFEKENCE TO FREEDOM. 285 equally impossible for the will to clioose contrary to its own remaining and present preponderating inclination, as it is io) jprefer contrary to its own y^q'&qwX. jpreference^ or choose contrary to its own present choice " (p. 85). By substitution of these equivalents, the argument just quoted will stand thus : Because^ if the soul willing he already willing, hefore it exerts its own sovereign power on itself, then its willing is not wholly owing to itsef. It is obvious that such statements must be fruitless. But farther, by the will exerting its owai sovereign power on itsL'lf, he nmst mean the smil willing, exerting, &c. ; and the argument then amounts only to this : Because if the soul %Lnlling he already willing hefore it wills, then its willing is not wholly owing to itself j that is, if the soul wills when it is not willing, or does not will, then its willing is not wholly owing to itself. The inference which Edwards himself draws from these positions is : " Therefore, if there be the least degree of prepond oration of the will, it must be perfectly abol- ished, before the will be at liberty to determine itself the contrary way;" which, though somewhat obscured by introducing new terms, as prepouderation for incli- nation, really, under his definitions, only asserts that, while the soul is in any degree willing one way, it can- not be willing the contrary way. Throughout this sec- tion there is much confusion and sophistry from using the term inclination as identical witli will, and yet as something which goes before and influences the will. Th.e same, to some extent, may also be remarked of the terms choice and preference. This confusion is further increased by the frequent use of the' term will, as a synonym for mind or soul. After assuming " as an axiom of undoubted truth that every free act is done in 286 KEVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. a state of freedom and not onlj after sucli a state," he says, " Now the question is, whether ever the soul of man puts forth an act of will, while it yet remains in a state of liberty, in that notion of a state of liberty, viz. : as implying a state of indifference, or whether the soul ever exerts an act of choice or preference, while at that very time the will is in a perfect equihbrium, not in- clining one way more than another. The very putting of the question is sufficient to show the absurdity of the affirmative answer ; for how ridiculous would it be for anybody to insist, that the soul chooses one thing before another, when, at the very same instant, it is perfectly indifferent with respect to each ! This is the same thing as to say the soul prefers one thing to another at the very same time that it has no preference. Choice and preference can no more be in a state of indifference, than motion can be in a state of rest, or than the pre- ponderation of the scale of a balance can be in a state of equilibrium. Motion may be the next moment after rest ; but cannot co-exist with it, in any, even the least part of it. So choice may be immediately after a state of indifference, but has no co-existence with it ; even the very beginning of it is not in a state of indifference. And therefore, if this be liberty, no act of will in any degree, is ever performed in a state of liberty, or in the time of liberty " (p. 88). This portion of the argument now stands thus : The soul of man never puts forth an act of will while it is in a state of indifference, or not choosing or preferring ; for this is to will when it does not will ; and as, if the freedom of the act of will con- sists in indifference, the act of will must be in the time of sucli indifference, there can be no such free act of will. If .any, using the terms in the sense that Ed- RELATION OF INDIFFERENCE TO FREEDOM. 287 wards u-ses them, have asserted such freedom, i. e., that the freedom of the mind in willing consists in its will- ing when it is in a state of indiflPerence, or not willing at all, their position is sufficiently refuted. Edwards also considers the position of those who, " to evade the reasoning should say that, the thing wherein the will exercises its liberty, is not in the act of choice or pre- ponderation itself, but in determining itself to a certain choice or preference ; that the act of the will M'herein it is free and uses its own sovereignty, consists in its causing or determining the change, or transition from a state of indifference to a certain preference, or deter- mining to give a certain turn to the balance, which has hitherto been even " (p. 90). This is only a particular case of the general proposition just mentioned, involv- ing, under Edwards's definition, the same absurdity of the mind's willing the " change or transition," when, being in a state of indifference, it is not willing at all ; and so far this argument only proves that the mind cannot both v/ill, and not will, at the same time, which no one will dispute. Edwards further asserts that a free act of will can- not " directly and immediately arise out of a state of in- difference," Now, under his definitions, every act of will, choice or preference, which begins to be must spring directly from a state of indifference ; for, as he uses the terms, the mind must be either in a state of indifference or of preference, and never can be in both ; so that, the instant it ceases to be in one of these states, it is of necessity in the other ; and if any particular preference was not preceded by a state of indiffer- ence as to what is thus preferred, the mind must ahvays Iiave had that preference and been engaged from all 288 KEVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. eternity in that act of will, which, in Edwards's system, is designated by this particular preference. It is evi- dent that no such act of will is possible to a being, whose existence has had a beginning ; and as, nnder the assumed conditions, every other act must have sprung directly from a state of indifierence, when it rs proved that 2^ free act of will cannot directly and immediately spring out of a state of indifference, it will also have been proved, under these detinitions and assumptions, that no free act of will is possible to a being whose past existence has been finite. Edwards thus attempts this proof: "If any to evade these things should own that a state of liberty and a state of indifference are not the same, and that the former may be without the lat- ter, but should say that indifFeren(;e is still essential to the freedom of an act of will, in some sort, namely, as it is necessary to go imnuidiately hefore it j it being es- sential to the tVeedom of an act of will that it should directly and immediately arise out of a state of indiff'er- ence ; still this will not help the cause of Arminian liberty, or make it consistent with itself. For if the act springs immediately out of a state of indifr'erence, then it does not arise from antecedent choice or prefereiice. But if the act arises directly out of a state of indiffer- ence, without any intervening choice to choose and de- termine it, then the act, not being de-termined by choice, is not determined by the will ; the mind exercises no free choice in the affair, and free choice and free will have no hand in the determination of the act, which is entirely inconsistent with their notion of the ft-eedom of volition " (pp. 91, 92). It will be observed that this argument assumes that choice is a necessary element 01 free will, and is that element which distinguishes it EELATION OF INDIFFERENCE TO FREEDOM. 289 from unfree will, wliich, if asserted generally and taken in connection with tlie assertion of Edwards that, " to will and to choose are the same thing " (p. 91), is anal- ogous to saying that water is a necessary element of hot water, and is that element which distinguishes it from cold water. That the free act of will must be im- tnediately preceded and determined by choice is here assumed ; and this, if choice is also deemed an act of will, involves the notion, attiibiited by Edwards to the Arminians, that a free act of will must be determined by a preceding act of will ; and hence, Edwards's in- ference that the position, that a free act of will is im- mediately preceded by indifference and not by choice or act of will, is inconsistent with their notion of liberty. It is obvious that this reasoning is directed only against those who assert that a tree act of will must co-exist with, or " immediately arise out of a state of indiffer- ence ; " and that it avails even as against those, only on the assumption that indifference is that state of the mind in which it has no choice or preference ; that choice is a necessary antecedent and the immediate an- tecedent difree will ; and tliat to will is the same thing as to prefer or choose. I infer, from Edwards's statements, that the Ar- minians hold that the choice of the mind, is a pre- requisite of a free act of will ; and yet that choice and act of will are the same ; and thus, in asserting the mind's freedom in willing, were forced to the position that the freedom was exercised in a state preceding that of choice ; a state, which was not that of choice ; and consequently, in his and their use of terms, was a state of indifference. As I do not assert what this argument opposes, and deny some of the propositions which are 13 290 EEVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. essential to its conclusions, it has little application to mj positions. I see no objection to Edwards's use of the term in- difference, as the antithesis of choice or preference, but I hold that every act of will is imtnediatelj preceded by a perception, by the knowledge that such act will, or may produce the effect wanted ; and this perception or knowledge may be a preference or choice, as among various modes of action, or as between action and non- action ; that, except in those cases of hasty action in which at once perceiving that a certain action will pro- duce a certain desirable result, we adopt it without stopping to compare it with other possible modes of action, or with non-action, this perception is a choice or preference, and hence, for the purposes of this argu- ment, Edwards's assumption that a free act of will is an act of will which is preceded by the mind's choice or preference, and is in conformity to such choice, may also be admitted. But, then, such a perception, choice or preference, is not an act of will, but knowledge ; and this knowledge or choice, is not a distinct power or entity, which itself determines the act of will, but is merely that acquisition by which the mind determines its act, in adapting it to the desired end ; and the free- dom of the mind in such case consists as before ai-gued, in its determining its own acts by means of its own knowledge. This addition to our knowledge is always an immediate perception, but may have required pre- liminary acts of will to make it obvious to the mind's knowing sense. It may be the result of an effort, in or by which the mind compares various things or modes, till it judges or decides among them, that is, perceives or knows which is best ; but the effort and the decision RELATION OF INDIFFEKENCE TO FliEEDOM. 291 or judgment which is its result, are two distinct and verj different things ; the effort is an act of will and, in this case, the result is a choice. The form in which an admission that choice is a necessary antecedent oi free will, could be most plausi- bly used against the freedom of the mind in willing, seems to me to be this : Even supposing the mind's choice to be something distinct from its act of mm'II, still the choice in that case, is the result of a comparison, which was itself an act of will, and, if a free act, must also have been preceded by a choice, which, in turn, must be the result of a previous act of will, and so on ad infinitum, leaving no possibility of a first free act. It will be observed that this argument is the same as that of Edwards, except that, instead of making choice itself an act of will, it makes it the result of an act of will and avails only on the assumption that every choice requires an antecedent act of will. This assumption I deem unfounded. When I, at the same time, see an ox and a mouse, I know at once without any effbrt or act of will, that the ox is larger than the mouse. It is a fact obvious to simple perception requiring no prelimi- nary eff'ort to arrange either objects or ideas to make it apparent. In the same way I may at once perceive that one thing is better than others ; and when I thus perceive that one thing is hetter adapted to my want than others, and that it is better to have, than not to have it, it is a choice of that thing, which is t aus recognized by the mind's sense of knowing, without any prelimi- nary effbrt ; and such choice, even under our admis- sion, may be the basis of free action. But it does not appear ertain that choice, either as the result of an act of the will in comparing, or even as 292 EEVII'IW OF EDWAKDS ON THE WILL, a simple perception of the mind, is a necessary ante- cedent to a free act of will. The mind may perceive some good result of an effort, and make that effort with- out comparing it with other efforts, as we may decide to take an apple immediately before us, without coni- panng it with others in the same basket. In walking, for instance, a man, liaving by previous action decided, knows that he wants to move in a certain direction, and that the mode of doing it is at each point of his prog- ress to take another step in the same direction. The facility with which a man in walking thinks of other subjects, and the little interruption of his thoughts, seem to indicate that he does not, at each act of will, or effort to take a step, without which the step would not be taken, compare the act of stepping in a certain direction with tliat of stepping in other directions, or with the swinging of the arms, or any other conceivable act, or even with not acting at all ; but, as before sug- gested, acts imniediately upon the perception, the knowledge, that such act tends to a desirable result. The essential element or fundamental condition of free action is not that it is chosen, but that it is self-direct- ed ; and it would be proper to bear this in mind even if it should on investigation appear that choice of the action is still an essential element of this self-direction, because choice has a more general application, signily- ing selection among other things, as well as acts of will ; and hence, even if choice is always the immediate ante- cedent of free action, a free action is not always the immediate consequence of choice ; and this even though the mind in choosing always has a view to future ac- tion, either proximate or remote. The latter portion of his seventh section (Part II.) INDIFFEEENCE TO FREEDOM IJST WILLING. 293 Edwards devotes to those who " should suppose that these difficulties may be avoided by saying that the liberty of the mind consists in a power to suspend the act of the will, and so to keep it in a state of indiffer- ence until there has been opportunity for consideration ; and so shall say * * * that liberty consists in a power of the mind to forbear or suspend the act of volition and keep the mind in a state of indifference for the present, until there has been opportunity for proper de- liberation," (P. 92.) Edwards ass nnes that those who say this, mean to assert that this power to suspend its volition is the only liberty of the miud in willing ; and argues as if they had said, the liberty of the mind con- sists in its actually susjMndlng the act of the will. He further assumes that " this suspending volition, if there l)e properly any such thing ^ is itself an act of volition," and, on these assumptions, his argument runs thus : the only free volition is the volition to suspend an act of will, and the freedom of this volition, in turn, consists in a volition to suspend it, and so on ad infinitum, ad- mitting of no first free act of will. This reasoning, availing only against those who assert that the 07dy liberty of the mind in willing consists in its suspending its act of will, and then being also founded on assump- tions which do not enter into nay system, and which I deem erroneous, does not really affect the argument I have presented in favor of freedom. Edwards in the above quotation seems to question " if there be prop- erly any such thing" as " suspending volition," and, if there is, asserts that the suspending " is itself an act of volition." The question, can the mind suspend voli- tion, really involves that of its ability to determine as to whether to act, or not to act. For, if the mind cannot 294: KEVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. even suspend a volition, it must, of course and of neces- sity, make or have the volition and have it immediately. On the other hand, if it has power to suspend volition, it must be for an indefinite time, otherwise there is a time when it has not power to suspend, and power to sus- pend for an indefinite time is power not to put forth nor have the volition at all. On the first hypothesis, when there was only one cause, and that cause then able to produce all the eft'ects it has since produced, as, if omnipotent, it must have been — and if suspending volition involves such contradictions as Edwards sup- poses, even omnipotence could not suspend its voli- tion, but must immediately have actually created and done everything possible. And, if a part of this doing was the creating of other causes acting by will, they, too, at the same instant, must have exhausted all their causative powder, making all cause end the instant it came into existence, or the moment the first cause of all acted. As the influence of matter, if made cause by being in motion, may be retained, or continued in time, from the circumstance that to move from one point of space to another requires time, so the influence of spirit, as cause in virtue of its intelligence, is continued in time from the circumstance that, by its intelligence, it may think, examine, compare, and judge, or decide as to the proper time of ending the preliminary examina- tion, and proceed to the flnal action.* The assertion that " suspending volition is itself an act of volition," I deem unfounded ; but Edwards thus attempts to prove it : " If the mind determines to suspend its act, it de- termines it voluntarily ; it chooses, on some considera- tion, to suspend it. And this choice or determination ♦ See Appendix, Note XLlI. INDIFFERENCE TO FREEDOM IN WILLING. 295 is an act of the will ; and indeed it is supposed to be so in the very hypothesis ; for it is supposed that the lib- erty of the will consists in its power to do this, and that its doing it is the very thing wherein the loill exercises its liberty. But how can the will exercise liberty in it, if it be not an act of the will ? The liberty of the will is not exercised in anything but what the will does." (Pp. 92, 93.) There is a covert sophistry in this, growing out of using the term will as synonymous with mind. The latter portion shouldread thus : " for it is supposed that the liberty of the mind consists in its power to do this, and that its doing it is the very thing wherein the mind exercises its liberty. But how can the mind exercise liberty in willing, if it be not in an act of will ? The liberty of the mind is not exercised in anything but what the mind does;" which would prove nothing against the mind's freedom in willing. In regard to this last-quoted assertion, as thus altered, we may observe that Edwards's own remarks in declining will, lead to the conclusion that the mind's liberty may be as much exercised in that which it refuses, as in that which it chooses, and, of course, as nmch in that which it refuses to do, as in that which it chooses to do ; in what it does not will as well as in what it does will. It will be observed that Edwards's proof of the as- sertion that suspending volition is itself an act of voli- tion rests directly and wholly on the assumption that the mind's choice is the same as its act of will ; and if I have succeeded in showing that this is an error, then, not only the above-mentioned assertion, but this whole argument of Edwards against the freedom of the mind m suspending volition, is shown to be fallacious. I would, however, further remark upon it that, if to sus- 296 REVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. pend the mind's act of will requires an act of wiU of any kind, free or unfree, tlien once the mind is in ac- tion it never can suspend action, or cease to act ; for every act must continue till there is another act to sus- pend it. But even if, against all experience, this be ad- mitted, it still would not prove that the mind is not free in its every act of will ; for it is conceivable that the mind may be under a continual necessity to act, and yet that itself as continually directs its every act, and is consequently free in such act. For aught that appears in the argument, if it could will at all, it might still freely will to suspend willing, though its eftbrts be found to be unavailing. If, for want of a known mode, or any other reason, we could not thus v.'ill at all, then, as it is manifest that we might still, as the result of a comparison of willing with not willing, prefer or choose non- willing, the choosing^ which is possible, cannot be the same thing as the willing, which on this hypothesis is impossible; and the main foundation of the argu- ment is thus destroyed by another essential support of it. The assumption of Edwai-ds, as above stated, would however admit of oidy the one act suspended, and a series of acts each merely suspending the preceding one ; and each of those acts, as his argument virtually as- serts, must be without the preliminary act to consider, or get any new knowledge ; for this would not be an act to suspend the prior act. The uiind's sphere of action would thus be curtailed to very narrow limits. That when we perceive that a contemplated effort may be better made at some future time, we may, in con- formity to this perception, delay action till then, is a matter of fact, which I presiime will be admitted, and hence, in this sense, a contemplated act of will may be INDIFFEEENCE TO FREEDOM IN WILLING. 297 suspended. In such case, we may have compared the advantage of present with future action, and come to a conclusion, a decision in favor of the latter, i. e., that at a certain time, or when another expected event occurs, we will make a certain eflPort ; but such decision is not itself the future effort, l)ut only present knowledge re- garding that efibrt. But we may thus suspend for an indefinite time, or for all time, and thus wholly aban- don and contemplated volition, or any portion of an act or series of acts. To will to suspend an act of will is then the same as willing not to will, either for the time being, or at all. Indifference being that condi- tion of the mind in which it is not willing, to say that the mind wills to keep itself in this condition is to say that the mind wills not to will, which, if asserted gen- erally, involves the absurdity of supposing that, for the mind to cease willing, or not to will, it must still will ; that after having once willed, non-willing is still only another willing. The assertion that the mind cannot suspend its willing by an act of will, if made in general terms and as applicable to all willing, must be as true as that thought is not suspended by thinking, or motion by moving. This all amounts to saying that we cannot do a thing by not doing it, or by doing the contrary to it. But, even if it be admitted that, in this general sense, the mind can only suspend its willing by willing to suspend, it would be a sufficient answer to this position to say that the mind never wills thus generally • never wills will, but always, when willing, wills some partic- ular act ; and that, though it cannot stop action by act- ing, it can still, even while acting, suspend one partic- ular act by directing its power to another particular act, as, even though we could not stop moving, we 13* 298 EEVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. might still suspend motion in one direction by moving in another. The liberty of tlie mind in directing all ita actions might thus still be maintained under the hy- pothesis, that to suspend action generally^ required an act to suspend, though the exercise of liberty as to acting, or not acting, might then be denied. But the particular jurisdiction of the mind, which is questioned by this denial of its power to suspend willing, is not derived from any negative attribute of its power not to loill, but from its positive ability to will, which is its own effort, or the exercise of its own power ; and with- out such exercise there is no act of will. The mind has then only to refrain from any positive effort, which it will do whenever it sees reason for it, and the condition of non-action, or general suspension of its willing, is reached. To suppose the mind to will when itself does not will — and this non-willing is its condition when- ever it does not perceive any object, or reason for will- ing — involves the hypothesis that it is compelled by some extraneous power to will ; and tliis, again, as be- fore shown, involves the contradiction of supposing it to will, when it is not willing, when it is not exercising its power, or making any effort whatever. If the mind, by extrinsic power, can be moved to will, when itself perceives no reason for such willing, it is not, in such case, either an intelligent or willing agent any more than an axe or other instrument, which is moved by extrinsic effort directed by extiinsic intelligence. From these general considerations, turning to par- ticular or individual acts of will, in which alone they can fiud practical application, we woidd remark that, by the phrase " suspending an act of will " cannot be meant suspending an ac't, or that portion of an act, or INDIFFERENCE TO FREEEOM IN "WILLING. 2d9 of a series of acts already accoiiiplislied ; nor can it apply to an act of which the mind has yet had no idea, but mnst have reference only to such acts as the mind has already contemplated and intended, determined, or chosen to do. But here, under Edwards's definitions, it may be said that what has been chosen has already been willed, and hence the willing it could not be sus- pended. The fallacy of this position, resting on the assumed identity of choice and will, has already been exposed. But further to illustrate : suppose a man is reading aloud, and has already pronounced the first syl- lable of the word " gallows," when a man suddenly enters whose father was hanged. The reader may then perceive a reason for suspending the act of pronouncing the last syllable, and do so. His knowledge is altered, and he conforms to it by suspending or abandoning the act he intended. The same thing occurs w^ienever by any change ol knowledge he pej'ceives, not, as in the case just mentioned, that the contemplated act will be injurious, but merely that it will not be in any wise beneficial ; there is then no perceived or known reason for action, and without such knowledge, an intelligent being does not exert its power to produce change. Again, suppose that, when the reader had pronounced the first syllable, a man enters, whose presence suggests no direct reason for not finishing the word, but with whom he has urgent business ; he may, for this reason, suspend the contemplated act to finish the word, that by another act he may attend to something more press- ing. In this case one act is suspended to make room for another act. The mind suspends its intended act, in the first instance above stated, because it perceives a reason against such action. In the second instance, 300 REVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. because it j^erceives that there is no good reason for the act ; and in the third instance, because it perceives there is a reason for preferring another act. Whether, in this last case, the suspension of the one act is the conse- quence of the other act, or only a necessary preliminary to it, may be a question ; if the former, then the mind suspends the first act hy, or as a consequence of its second ; and if the latter, it first suspends one act, ceasing to act in it, that it may afterward do another. The question is not here material, as the first contem- plated act of will is in either event suspended. If this suspension is a consequence of the mind's effort to do something else, the doing something else is a mode in which the mind, by its own action, suspends a contem- plated volition ; and if there is a preliminary act sus- pending this contemplated volition, then the mind thus suspends because, in the more urgent demand for an- other act, it perceives a reason for such preliminary act to suspend ; and then, in the instances above stated, the third becomes the same as the first, in which the mind suspends an act because it perceives a reason for such suspension. All these reasons may be simple per- ceptions of the mind, without any effort to reach them ; and when the mind perceives a reason for iiot acting, it can, in the aggregate of its knowledge, perceive no rea- son for acting ; and when it does not perceive a reason to act it does not act ; and not to perceive a reason re- quires no act, so that this suspension may take place without an act to suspend. As already shown, to will to suspend an act of will IS equivalent to willing not to will. We have also stated that a man never wills to will generally. If the will is a faculty for which the mind wants exercise, it INDIFFERENCE TO FREEDOM IN WILLING. 30 1 may seek to gratify that want, but, in doing so, must will, not generally, but some particular act. This posi- tion is easily brought to the test of experiment. There is obviously no way in which the mind can will gen- erally. Will is the mode in which the mind manifests its power ; and to will generally would be to exert power for no object and with no preponderance in one direction rather than another, which would be to exert it equally in all directions ; and power exerted equally in all directions must neutralize itself, and there would then be no manifestation of power whatever in any direction. So far from the mind's being able to will thus generally, it cannot even will distinct genera of acts. If we want and even decide upon or choose bodily movement generally, we must know what por- tion of the body to move and in what direction, before w^e can will the movement. To will movement in no direction, or equally in all directions, would be to will no movement. If we want to reason, we must know something to reason about, and, at each step of the rea- soning, must get a perception, find — not make — the logical sequence. Nor do we ever will to will a partic- ular act, but directly will the act. To say a man wills an act of will^ or thinks thoughts, or knows knowledge, expresses no more than to say he wills^ he thinhs, he hnows. To will to will is to make effort to make eftbrt, i. e.^ to do the thing to be done in order to the doing it. The nearest approach we can make to willing to will, is when we want exercise for the faculty of will, i. e., to exert our power without reference to any benefit to be derived from the effort ; as we may want exercise foi the body without any reference to any ulterior result. If we want such exercise for the will, and especially if 302 KEVIEW OF EDWAKDS ON THE WILL. we want that peculiar exercise of selecting objects or acts arbitrarily, without a preliminary act to compare, or judge of consequences, we will, in gratifying such want, display the characteristics of caprice. We, how- ever, still directly will particular acts, and do not merely will to will. The mind, then, in no case, either general or particular, wills to will ; and for stronger reasons it does not will to not will. To will not to will, in a general sense, would be doing a thing in order not to do it ; and, in regard to a particular act, the mind may decide not to do it, and not doing re- quires no effort. The mind's act of will is based di- rectly upon its perceptions of a reason for such act ; and its non-action results from its not perceiving any reason to act, or from its perceiving a reason to suspend any contemplated act. In all these cases, it is tiie intelligent being that governs ; in all, the mind, by means of its knowledge, determines how to act, or wliether to act or not. To suppose that to suspend an act of will, or to stop willing, requires an act of will, or, in other words, that to stop making effort requires an effort, is to sup- pose some power acting on the mind to cause it to will. But the only other things necessarily involved in its volition are its want and its knowledge : neither of these, as distinct entities, can, singly or combined, will, or direct the act of will ; this must be done by the mind, the active being, that wants and knows. But even sup- posing a power to inhere in this want and knowledge to produce an act of will, the moment the want ceases, or the moment the knowledge changes and the mind perceives that the contemplated act will not tend to gratify its want, such power ceases ; and, in that case. INDIFFERKNCE TO FKEEDOM IN WILLING. 303 the contemplated act of will would be suspended, not by an act of will, but simply by non-action. If the knowledge is so changed that the mind, instead of merely perceiving that a contemplated act will not effect its object, or is not preferable to non-action, or perceives that another act is preferable, then still, as re- gards the first contemplated act, there is only non- action, and not an act to suspend it before the other act becomes possible, I would here further observe, that a want demand- ing effort may be more than neutralized by the simple perception that repose is more wanted, and no effort be made, the mind still conforming its conduct to its knowledge. We always will, put forth our powei*, make effort for some object, and this object always is to make the future different from what it otherwise would be. If we already are not willing^ we do not will not to will, for we seek no change in that respect. Even if, in such case, we could conceive that there might still be a want not to will, what we want already is, and no effort is required to gratify the want. If we are willing^ we cease the willing, we cease to make effort, as soon as the end is accomplished, or as soon as we j)erceive any other sufficient reason for ceasing ; and without a special effort to cease making effort, without a special act of will to stop willing. So far from our willing not to will, it is, at least, very doubtful whether we ever will, or ever can will not to do, or not to try to do. We will to do something, and not to do nothing. If the case of willing not to do differs from that of will- ing not to will, or is anything more than a particular case of it, still, either generally, or in each particular case of doing, it may be said that, if we already are not 304 RKVIKW OF EDWAKDS ON THE WILL. doing, we do not will non-doing, for we seek no change in that respect, and the argument we have just stated in regard to willing not to will, applies to willing not to do, both generally and in any particular case. When the question is between doing one thing or another thing, we seek knowledge, and our conclusion is a choice, a decision as between them ; and when it is between doing and not doing anything, we also choose, decide, as between doing and not doing ; but in neither case is the decision, the conclusion, or choice itself, the act of will, or the trying to do, but only the knowledge, found by a preliminary act for that purpose. In the lirst case we have found — come to know what to try to do ; and in the second, we have come to know whether to try to do, or to refrain from trying to do ; and if the decision is in favor of the latter, that knowledge ends the matter. In this the mind conforms to its knowledge, its decision, by refraining from further action. In all these cases, the decision of the mind may be the result of previous effort to obtain knowledge; but if the ques- tion arises as between action and non-action generally, or even as between a particular act and such non-action ; i. e., whether, when a case arises in which we perceive action may in some respects be advantageous, we will give any attention, any thought whatever to it ; the decision of such question must be an immediate percep- tion of the mind ; for any preliminary effort to obtain more knowledge, including any effort to recall and apply what we know, or to arrange it so as to aid our perception, is another action, manifesting that the mind has already decided, in view of the premises, to act. The whole phenomena in such case is perhaps expressed by saying, the mind immediately perceives, knows, INDIFFERENCE TO FREEDOM IN WILLING. 305 without effort, Avliether action or repose suits it best ; and its freedon), in this, as in other cases, lies in its abil- ity to conform itself to this knowledge, without extrinsic constraint or restraint. Hence, even if it could be shown that this question, as betM^een action and non- action, arises with eveiy want or occasion for action, it would not argue necessity, for the mind still decides the question with such view, such knowledge, as it already has ; and, in so doing, determines upon its own action, or non-action ; and the arising of *iuch question only furnishes an occasion for the exercise of its liberty, in exerting, or not exerting its powers, as the question between various acts furnishes the occasion for the ex- ercise of its liberty in directing its efforts ; though the latter case admits of preliminary effort to discover the mode or direction, while the former does not ; non-ac- tion has no mode or direction. I have before suggested that the choice by the mind may be its immediate perception that one thing is bet- ter than another. If, however, the decision of the ques- tion between action and repose, involves a conjparison, requiring preliminary effort, then the non-action of the mind, or its refraining from action in such cases, must always arise from an immediate perception of some positive and not comparative advantages, or disadvan- tages of repose, or of action. In themselves, repose or action may be either pleasurable or painful. It ap- pears, then, that though the mind can both will and suspend its act of will, or not will, it requires no dis- tinct act of will, either to will, or not to will ; that, in willing, it directly wills the particular act, and does not first will to will it ; and that, in not willing, it as di- 300 RKVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. rectlj refrains tVoiii the particular action, and does not will not to will it : it merely does not act at all. If our action is to be reenforced, strengthened, or made persistent, it is not by williug to will, but by means of knowledge, which may be iuculcated by others, or found by our own efforts and dwelt upon till our perceptions of the benefit or pleasure expected from the act become so vivid, that a want, not in it- self urgent, glows in desire, or is inflamed to passion ; and the mind then wills without reference to any collat- eral or remote consequences, and without comparing the advantages, which so absorb it, with those which might be derived from other action, or from non-action. Those cases of action in which the mind is absorbed by one view, or one object, though the absorption is the result of its previous action, or attention, or thought devoted to the subject, become, in some respects, similar to those in which the mind acts on an immediate per- ception, without seeking more knowledge to direct its action. In them it has sought more knowledge, but only in one direction, and still acts upon a single idea. It is in such cases that the aid of others, in presenting their views and imparting their knowledge, may most obviously be useful ; and especially in those cases in which the absorbing object, or the immediate percep- tion, upon which the mind is about to act, is the grati- fication of some want which ought not to be gratified. When this is in conflict with our own knowledge of what is morally right, it becomes so important, that God never permits such action without a monition through the moral sense, warning us to refrain froin the mutilation, or degradation of our beiug, and sug- gesting search of that knowledge, which, by a faith in RELATION OF INDIFFERENCE TO FREEDOM. 307 the wisdom and goodness of the Snpreme Intelligence, intuitive, or early acquired, we know will reconcile gratification and duty. There are some cases in wliicli the mind really de- cides its action upon an immediate perception of the gratification to be derived from such action, and still, to avoid the painful sensation of self-reproach in do- ing what it knows to be wrong, seeks by preliminary act to find reason to reconcile the act with its sense of duty ; and, for this purpose, by its power to direct its efforts, seeks the arguments which favor, and excludes attention to those which oppose the act ; or it may do the same thing to find a reason to convince others, and thus avoid or mitigate their censure. Such dis- honest mind, in the first case, makes the vain effort to deceive itself. In the latter case, it seeks to deceive others ; and in this may possibly succeed. The reasoning of Edwards, which we have just been considering in this chapter, has little bearing upon my position, except that his denial of the liberty of the mind to suspend a volition, denies the mind's liberty in this one particular. This denial is associated with indifference only by the assertion of his opponents that the object of the suspension is to keep the mind " in a state of indifference until there has been opportunity for consideration." This, on the grounds I have stated, is merely to say, until there has been time to obtain more knowledge ; and, if that knowledge is sought by effort, it is only one case of the mind's suspending one act of will to make room for another. It was not, then, im- portant to my own position to have thus followed the whole of this argument " concerning the notion of the liberty of will consisting in indifference ; " but the ex- 308 REVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. am illation may serve to illustrate my own views, and at the same time to show how thoroughly the reasoning of Edwards is based on his two irreconcilable deiinitions, the one making choice tlie act of will, and the other making it the result of a comparative act, which is only knowledge sought and obtained by that act. As before observed, he also confounds the choice with the act of comparing of which it is the result ; and thus produces additional confusion and error. I may further remark that, in conformity to his assumption that to choose and to will are the same, he inverts his definition, and in- stead of making the " will that by which the mind chooses," makes the choice that hy which the mind loills. No real progress could logically be made by this use of identical terms, and it is only by using one of them in a different sense, or as both identical and not identical with the other, that any conclusion, beyond what is, is, can be reached, and then with all the lia- bility to error involved in the double and incompatible definitions. There is, however, in this word indifference, as used by Edwards to denote that state in which we are not willing and have no choice, an important significance, indicating the point of the mind's departure from the passive to the active condition. In profound sleep it is tlms indifferent, and being then unconscious of any want, or any reason for willing, it does not will ; and any change which takes place in itself, or in other things, must then be produced by other agencies. Its waking, or being roused from this unconscious state, must be brought about by agencies external to itself. It must, however, be still susceptible, at least to some sensations, for it cannot change itself; and if it could RELATION OF INDIFFERENCE TO FRKEDOM. 309 not know any changes produ(3ed by extraneous agen- cies, it never could be awakened. The sensation could produce no effect upon the mind until the mind recog- nized it. If this passive sta.te is not itself profound sleep ; if, when awake, the mind is even entirely inac- tive, its condition can then vary from that of profound sleep only in its greater susceptibility to the effects of extrinsic activities. Without action it cannot change either its own passive condition or anything else. It may, however, in its passive condition, be acted upon, and the first step in this change from the passive to the active condition is a joerception of some change ; and in its feelings or perceptions growing out of such change, it may find reason for acting itself. If this change is from a satisfied condition to that of a want, for instance, to that of hunger, or thirst, arising withont onr volition, we act in reference to its relief. When we ai-e fatigued and need sleep, we require greater inducements to act, and in proportion to our exhaustion ; for this exhaus- tion is a reason or want not to act, and must be over- balanced by a counter reason or want ; but so long as we are conscious, so long as we Tcnow^ we can, for j^er- ceived reason, resist the change to sleep, or seek to pro- duce some other change, though, from causes beyond our control, we may not have the power ; from exhaus- tion, the instruments of the mind may have become too weak, as a decayed lever will not, by the application of the same power, raise the weight for which it once would have sufliced. Bnt, with every change about us, we either intuitively or habitually know that some action on our part may be required to avail of benefi- cial, or to protect ourselves from evil consequences ; and we usually give enough effort by thought, to every 310 REVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. such change, to enable ns to form a judgment, some- times a too hastj one, as to tlie necessity or expediency of further effort, by thought or otherwise. The effort of the mind, by thought or observation, to find what is transpiring and what further efforts the changes around it may require, is called attention ; and this generally marks the first change from the passive to the active mental condition. It does not, however, always require an effort of any kind to know the changes which are taking place. It requires no effort to know the sensation, which itself is a change indicating some other change. We know we are hun- gry, and we hear the discharge of a gun, without effort ; and with the sensation, the knowledge, not only as to whether the change indicated by it demands effort, or not ; but, if it does, the knowledge of the particular effort demanded may be an immediate perception, with- out any preliminary effort ; and, if this ever happens, the mind's activity then commences with the effort, the reason for which is thus perceived without a prelimi- nary effort of attention iu examining the changed or changing events. The circumstances most favorable to this immediate perception of the requirement or non- requirement of effort, are when the change is one of frequent occurrence, so that the application of our knowledge has become habitual, and especially when the change is one in which we perceive and have usual- ly before perceived no reason for effort. In such cases it may be difficult to determine whether the decision is an immediate perception, or the result of an effort ; but the probability seems to be that, with observed change, the mind generally puts forth an effort of attention to hnd if any action, or change of action, is thereby RELATION OF INDIFFERENCE TO FKEEDOM. 311 required, and if not, that it again relapses into a state of repose, or resumes its previous course of action. It thus suspends one action, till, by another, it ascertains whether the changed circumstances require the first to he longer delayed, or wholly abandoned. In cases like those just alluded to, the time and effort required for this are hardly appreciable, and if we are, at the mo- ment, conscious of an effort, it is presently obliterated from the memory. The striking of a clock, which, a moment afterward, we are unconscious of having heard, is a familiar illustration. The striking has be- fore frequently occurred, and, with exceptional cases, as when marking that the time for some action has arrived, we have in it found no reason for effort. But the mind must have recognized the sensation at the moment, for it would have heard the faintest whisper ; nothing external to the mind causes it to hear the one and not the other, and itself could not make this dis- tinction without first knowing what it was distinguish- ing between. The sensation produced by the striking has furnished no ground for action, has given us neither pleasure nor pain ; we have not even drawn any infer- ence from it as to the time, present or past ; and the whole phenomenon is thus reduced almost to nothing- ness, leaving very little that could be remembered, and this so isolated, so free from association with other knowledge, that it is immediately left out and lost. The striking of a clock, leaving a sensation which merely marks the passage of time, is in some respects peculiar. Our mere progress through time has little more effect upon us than our movement with the earth through space, which, even when recognized, does not usually induce any effort, though, as in the exceptional 312 REVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. cases in regard to the striking of the clock, the infer- ences from it, as that short days and cold weather are approaching, may be a reason for some effort, or change of effort. The constant murmur of the forest, or the roar of ocean, thougli indicating no such change as calls for action, and seemingly unheeded by those ac- customed to it, is yet recognized by the mind ; for if it suddenly ceases we know it, and we could not know of the cessation of the sound, without first knowing the sound that ceased. In such cases, the sensation not only does not indicate any change requiring action^ but the continuous monotony of sound is an assurance to the mind that, so far, no such change is taking place. This partially relieves the mind from its wonted watch- fulness in regard to the external, and favors its becom- ing absorbed in reverie, or concentrated upon abstract speculation. CHAPTER VIII. CONTINGENCE. In the eighth and ninth sections of Part II., Ed- wards, treating of " the supposed liberty of the will as opposite to all necessity," and " the connection of the acts of the will with the dictates of the understanding," says : " I would inquire wliether there is, or can be any such thing as a volition whicli is contingent in such a sense, as not only to come to pass without any neces- sity of constraint, or coaction, but also without a neces- sity of consequence, or an infallible connection with anything foregoing " (p. 96) ; and soon after, referring to this, says : " And here it must be remembered that it has been already shown, that nothing can ever come to pass without a cause, or reason why it exists in this manner rather than another ; and the evidence of this has been particularly applied to the acts of the will. Now, if this be so, it will demonstrably follow that the acts of the will are never contingent, or without neces- sity, in the sense spaken of; inasmuch as those things which have a cause, or reason of their existence, must be connected with their cause. This appears by the following consideration : for an event to have a cause 14 314 REVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. and ground of its existence, and yet not be connected with its cause, is an inconsistence " (p. 96). He then proceeds to prove this last proposition. Admitting it, still, as already intimated in my remarks on " No Event without a Cause " (Part II., Sec. 3), if mind itself is the cause of the event, it only proves in reference to such events, " the acts of the will," that they are con- nected with the mind, but does not at all tend to show whether that mind, the active power, which produces them and is their cause, acts freely, or otherwise. It is a mere abstract proposition involved in the notions, or definitions of cause and effect, and just as true of one kind of cause as of another ; and hence, indicating no distinguishing quality or property of that cause ; of course this cannot indicate whether that cause is free or not free. That mind may be such a cause, and espe- cially under the great latitude with which Edwards says he uses the term cause, I trust I have already suffi- ciently shown. At the commencement of section ninth, he thus re- iterates the conclusion at which he ari-ives in section eighth, and applies it to his argument : " It is manifest that the acts of the will are none of them contingent in such a sense as to be without all necessity, or so as not to be necessary with a necessity of consequence and connection ; because every act of the will is some way connected with the understanding, and is as the great- est apparent good is, in the manner which has already been explained ; namely, that the soul always wills, or chooses that which, in the present view of the mind, considered in the whole of that view and all that be- longs to it, appears most agreeable. Because, as was observed before, nothing is more evident than that, CONTINGENCE, 315 when men act voluntarilj, and do what tliey please, then they do what appears most agreeable to them ; and to say otherwise would be as much as to affirm that men do not choose what appears to suit them best, or what seems most pleasing to them ; or that they do not choose what they prefer, which brings the matter to a contradiction " (p. 100). So far as regards the volition, this contradiction appears only when will and choice are deemed iden- tical. I do not mean to assert or to deny that " acts of the will are none of them contingent," in some of the various senses in which that term seems to be used. If the above argument only implies that acts of the will, taking will to be a distinct entity, capable itself of action, are necessary because they " in some way are connected with the understanding, and are as the great- est apparent good is," I shall only object that, there is no such will and no such acts of will to be subject to such necessity ; or, if the argument implies that the will, considered as a mere faculty of the mind and itself incapable of action, is not free because it is controlled by the mind, then it does not even tend to prove any necessity of mind in willing ; but is one step toward the proof of its freedom. But if, by the acts of the will, Edwards means, as he repeatedly claims to do, " the acts of the mind or soul in willing," then the argument is self-contradictory and absurd ; for, as before observed, the understanding, in his system generally, and espe- cially in its present application, embraces all the powers and faculties of the mind, except that of the will ; and hence, to say that the Tnind, in the act of willing, does not will freely, or acts from necessity, because the act of will is, in some way, connected with the understand- 316 KEVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. ing, is to say that the mind, in the act of willing, does not act freely because the act of willing is, in some way, connected with the mind, which is absurd. And to say that, in the act of willing, the mind does not act freely, because every act of its will is in conformity to its views of the greatest apparent good, or because it " always wills, or chooses that which in the present view of the mind " " appears most agreeable ; " and that this is so, because when men act voluntarily and do what they please, then they do what appears most agreeable to them, is contradictory. It is, in effect, saying that the mind does not act freely in willing, be- cause, in willing, it cannot do otherwise than direct its own action, which is to act freely ; and hence, is subject to this necessity^ or is constrained to be free in its action. It is like saying, freedom is not free, hecause it cannot l)e otherwise than free / and hence, is subject to the necessity, or is constrained to be free ; and this is as- serting that, what is, is not ^ and that it is not for the very reason that it is ; than which, I apprehend, it would be dilBcult to involve more absurdity and con- tradiction in the same space. All those arguments which attempt to prove necessity from the dependence of the act of will upon other faculties of the mind, among them that quoted from Edwards (p. 96), more or less involve this absurdity. If the object were to prove that the ivill itself as an entity, distinct from the willing agent, is not free, because the will is de- pendent upon and controlled by the willing agent, the argument would be valid ; but Edwards avows that, by will he means the " soul in willing ; " and that such willing is dependent upon and controlled by the soul, or by the understanding, whether viewed as a distinct CONTINGENCE. 317 portion of the mind, or as a mere mode of its effort, goes to prove the freedom of tlie soul in willing. In section thirteenth, he applies a similar course of reason- ing, or an extension of it, to show that, even if the will itself is the cause of the acts of the will, still the will is not free, because being an effect it must still be con- trolled by its cause, though that cause be itself; that is to say, if the will, as cause, controls itself, it is not free, which confounds all distinction between what is free and what is not free. For, as 1 intimated in defining freedom, if that which controls itself is not free, and it must be admitted that, that which is controlled by something else is also not free, then, as everything in action mast either control itself, or be controlled by something besides itself, there is no such thing possible as free action ; and the term free being wholly un- meaning in such application, we could then as well reason about violet, or triangular time, or dxfg will, as about iYQQ will. The fallacy of this, and of the argu- ment before quoted from Edwards (p. 100), is in the assumption that, wJiatever is directed and controlled in its movement or action is not free / and, as evei-ything that moves or acts, must be directed and controlled in its movement or action, either by itself, or by some- thing else, it follows, from this assumption^ that noth- ing can be free. If it directs and controls itself, it is still directed and controlled ; and hence, under this assumption, not free ; and if directed and controlled by something else, it is not free in the accepted notion of freedom. If it be granted that that which dii'ects and controls its own movement or action is free, the argument as against the freedom of the mind in the act of willing wholly fails. The argument in section thir- 318 EEVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. teenth is, then, obviously and wholly fallacious ; and, also, as before intimated, that quoted from page 100. At most, they only tend to prove that the will, consid- ered as a distinct entity, is not free ; and not that the active agent, the mind willing, is not free ; but, on the contrary, both of those arguments go to show, or admit that mind, in willing, controls its own act of will, which, as before shown, is but another expression for the freedom of the mind in willing. The position here, as elsewhere, really taken by Edwards, or involved in his arguments is, that every event is an eflPect of some cause on which it is dependent and by which it is con- trolled, and, therefore, a necessary effect / that volition is an effect of which the action of the mind, in willing, is the cause ; but, instead of inferring that the effect^ the volition, is necessary, he infers that the cause, the action of the mind in willing, is necessary, which is wholly illogical. He generally speaks of the freedom of the will, and not of \\\q. freedom of the mind in will- ing, though he asserts that by the former he means the latter, and occasionally expresses it, or its equiva- lent, as, " The question is wherein consists the minWs liberty in 2iiij particular act of volition ? " (p. 95). The utter futility of all attempts to reach any new truth by reasoning on the statement we have quoted from page 100, may be shown by substituting in it the word " choice," wherever its admitted equivalents are used, which would make the latter half of it read thus : ' Because, as was observed before, nothing is more evident than that when men act as they choose, and d-o what they choose, then they do what they choose / and to say otherwise would be as much as to affirm that men do not choose what appears to suit them best, or CONTINGENCE. 319 what they choose, or that they do not choose what they choose ; " or thus, the argument of Edwards, as there stated is, " that the acts of the will are none of them contingent," &c., " because every act of the will is some way connected with the understanding," &c., and " the soul always wills or chooses that which, in the present view of the mind, * * * appears most agreeable." But, as he says, " an appearing most agreeable and the mind's prefen-ing or choosing, seem hardly to be prop- erly and perfectly distinct," and elsewhere identifies will and choice with what is most agreeable or most pleasing, the above argument merely amounts to saying that acts of will are none of them contingent, because the mind wills what it wills. The question which Edwards asks as to a volition having " an infallible connection witli anything fore- going " (p. 96), has already been considered. The argu- ments I have adduced go to prove that, even admitting the hypothesis that the mind has other faculties which influence the will and yet are independent of it, which Edwards seems to adopt, his reasoning does not estab- lish necessity ; for in this case the mind still controls its own action. If, however, the action of those other faculties requires an act of will, then the act of will which they influence, is really influenced by the mind's previous act of will ; and the same, if such faculties are, as I have supposed, only varied modes of effort or will ; or efforts or acts of will for varied objects. In either case this would be influencing or determining the final act of will by a preliminary act of will, and if this were the end of it, the final act of will would be determined by a previous act of will, and the active agent, whether it be the mind, or the will itself, thus 320 EEVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE AVILL. determining its own action, is free ; but in all such cases, we must trace the series of efforts back to an exciting want and 'd^ perception of some mode of trying to gratify it, wliich are independent of the wilL If by such other faculties Edwards means the capacity for simple perception, then it is the mind directing itself, not by means of such capacity itself, but by means of t\\Q knowledge which it acquires through this capacity, which brings the whole matter to our position, that the mind directs its efforts to the gratification of its want by means of its knowledge. The argument of Edwards seems to assert that any fi'cedom in willing is impos- sible ; but it might, with more reason, be asserted that all cause is free and cannot even be conceived of as otherwise than free. If I direct and control the move- ment of a ball, and, while so directed and controlled, it impinges against and aff'ects another body, I, and not the ball, ain the cause of that effect. - If I throw the ball, and, after I have withdrawn all effort from it, it continues in motion by a principle inherent in matter itself, and not by the will, or effort of any other being, then, that which makes it cause is its own motion, which is not restrained, constrained, or in any wise interfered with, till it comes to produce an effect^ by coming in collision with some other body, or in conflict with some other force ; and then comes the trial, as to what, as a consequence of its own free movement, it has power to accomplish. If matter is ever cause, the motion, the activity^ which constitutes its only con- ceivable causative power, must be uncontrolled ; so the effort, through which the mind has causative power, must also be free from external control, even though the effect be frustrated by some other power ; and, the CONTINGENCE. 321 moment matter is controlled in its movement, or mind in its effort, by some other power, it ceases to be cause, and becomes only an instrument, used by tlie power which controls it, which is then the real cause. In either case, too, it is only when it comes to the effect, that the causative agent can be frustrated or controlled in its action for want of sufficient force or power ; but this cannot affect it's, previoits condition as cause — cannot change its previous freedom of motion or of effort. There is, however, this essential difference between the two cases ; that, although the movement of the matter in m^otion, till it comes to produce its effect, is free in the sense that it is not impeded or controlled by other external force at the instant, its freedom stops here, and it has no power, no liberty, to control itself. It cannot alter any direction given to it ; and, if such direction has no extraneous cause, it must have been from eter- nity, and every successive motion have been controlled by past movements ; there never could have been any initial force or movement which was self-controlled and directed, for matter never could begin to move itself. The term liberty, in the sense in which we apply it to intelligent cause, seems inapplicable to matter ; for all its freedom consists in not being impeded in doing that which some other force has compelled it to do. It has no self-control. A body now moving is, therefore, rather an instrument, by which some prior cause ex- tends its effects in time, than a cause itself; or, more properly, a link in a chain of instrumentalities, which cannot be traced to any beginning, or real cause in matter, for it never could have directed or moved itself. On the other hand, mind, perceiving the future varies 14* 322 REVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. Its efforts from consideration of the future effects, and thus escaping the control of the past, acts as jmal cause, making such efforts as it perceives in ad- vance to be requisite to the future effect it seeks to produce. CHAPTEE IX. CONNECTION OF THE "WILL WITH THE UNDERSTANDING. In the preceding chapter I have ah-eady noticed some of Edwards's remarks ujjon the connection of the will with the understanding, and will now observe that, if will is choice, it cannot always, as Edwards asserts, "follow the last dictate of the understanding," which itself may be a choice ; and, of course, by his definition, in such case the last dictate would itself be the willing. On this point I would further remark, that this last dic- tate is often neither a choice, nor an act of will, nor fol- lowed by an act of will. If we investigate abstract truth, the last dictate of the understanding is that the result is so, or so ; or, perhaps, that it is yet undeter- mined ; and, in either case, no volition follows. Sap- pose, for instance, we want to ascertain the quantity in 3x7, and, having aj plied the proper modes, rest in the conclusion that it is 21. We have, in this result, a last dictate of the understanding, but no volition, or act of will follows : the matter is finished, there is no further 'oant and no further effort j for the want was merely to obtain, and is fully gratified by obtaining, this " last dictate of the understanding." In regard to our actions, however, the object of examination is always to deter- mine either between different modes of acting, or be- 324 REVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. tween acting and not, acting ; and, in either case, the result, or last dictate of the understanding, is always a choice or i3reference as to that particular action, or as to action or non-action ; and hence, as the choice or preference cannot follow itself, it is evident that, if this choice is the act of will or volition, it never follows the Jast dictate of the understanding. But even admitting that Edwards means that the will — volition — which always follows the last dictate, is something distinct from that last dictate or choice of the understanding, still, as the understanding, in his system, embraces cer- tain faculties which pertain to mind, it merely follows that the mind exerts some of its other faculties in order to an exercise of its will, or to decide what the exercise of the will shall be. But this involves the absurdity of supposing that, before an act of will there must always be an act of will ; for this preliminary exercise of the other faculties must be by an act of will ; and even if this were possible, it would argue nothing against either the freedom of the mind in willing, or its own, or even the will's self-determining power, but quite the contrary. In reply to Dr. Whitby. Edwards thus applies the doctor's admission that the will follows the last dictate of the understanding : " For if the de- termination of the will, evermore, in this manner, fol- lows the light, conviction, and view of the understand- ing, concerning the greatest good and evil, and this be that alone which moves the will, and it be a contradic- tion to suppose otherwise ; then it is necessarily so, the will necessarily follows this light, or view of the under- standing ; and not only in some of its acts, but in every act of choosing and refusing. So that the will does not determine itself in any one of its own acts, but all its CONNECTION OF THE WILL WITH THE UNDEKSTANDING. 325 acts, every act of choice and refusal depends on and is necessarily connected witli some antecedent cause, which cause is not the will itself, nor any act of its own, nor anything pertaining to that faculty ; but something belonging to another faculty, whose acts go before the will in all its acts, and govern and determine them every one " (p. 104). Here it is evident that Edwards makes the will a distinct entity, tlie freedom of which, and not the freedom of the mind in using or exercising it, is the matter in question ; and that he also treats the understanding as if it were also an entity distinct from mind ; and, as a distinct power, controlling the distinct entity of will ; arguing that the will is not free, because it is controlled by the understanding ; which is more erroneous than to assert that it is not free because of its dependence on the action of the mind through its other faculties ; and this attempt to prove, not the mind in willing, but the will, as distinct from mind, neces- sitated, and thus necessitated because of its subjection to the mind's control, pervades the section. Upon such reasoning I have already sufficiently commented, and shown that it really confirms, or assumes, the freedom of the mind in willing. In regard to what is said by Edwards (Part II., Sec. 9) of the necessity of an act of will to attention hy the mind, I would remark that it is not an act of will by which, when the eyes are open, we see the sun and other external objects and their relations. The external objects cannot compel, or cause an act of will, producing that attention by which these objects are themselves first recognized ; for they could produce no eS'ect on the mind to make it will, or do anything whatever until it recognized them. So also it may not be by an 326 REVIEW OF EDWAKDS ON THE WILL. act of will that the raincl, wlien aroused and made sensible by want, perceives its knowledge, now present to it, and the relations of that knowledge, intuitive or acquired, to its want, also present with its knowledge, and all in the mind's view. I do not, however, deem it important to the views I have put forth, whether the mind, when aroused from a state of inactivity by a want, begins by an effort to get the requisite knowl- edge to gratify the want, or by a Simple perception of that knowledge ; it may begin in either mode, and sometimes in one and sometimes in the otlier. In the ease of instinctive action, it is probably always a mere perception of its intuitive knowledge, and of the rela- tions of that knowledge to its want, naturally asso- ciated ; and, in the case of habit, similar perceptions of its knowledge, artificially associated with its want by repetition. In other cases, the mind may have to make an (effort to find in its memory, or even newly and for the first time to obtain, the knowledge essential to the gratification of its want. Its intelligence enables it to conform its action, in this respect, to the existing cir- cumstances ; and, by effort, to put that portion of its body or that faculty of its mind in action, which, in view of existing circumstances, it perceives to be best for accomplishing its object. This whole matter of the will's following the last dictate of the understanding amounts then merely to this, that often, when the mind loants to produce any change, it makes preliminary effort to obtain knowledge as to the mode of producing such change, or obtains it by simple perception, and then determines its action by means of such knowledge, which, as we have already shown, is acting freely. CHAPTER X. MOTIVE, One argument of Edwards, and, perhaps, that which he most rehes upon, may be thus stated : There is no event without a cause ; the determination of an act of will is an event, and must have a cause ; this cause must be motive, for without motive the mind would have no inclination or preference toward anything ; and, as the cause must of necessity produce one certain effect and no other, the act of the will is, of necessity, deter- mined by the motive to be one particular volition, and can be no other. He not only makes motive determine the will, but he makes it the cause of the act of will itself. We give his own words from the commence- ment of section tenth : " That every act of the will has some cause, and consequently (by what has been already proved) has a necessary connection with its cause, and so is necessary by a necessity of connection and conse- quence, is evident by this, that every act of the will whatsoever is excited by some motive ; which is mani- fest, because, if the will, or mind, in willing and choos- ing after the manner that it does, is excited so to do by no motive, or inducement, then it has no end, which it proposes to itself, or pursues in so doing ; it aims at nothing and seeks nothing. And if it seeks nothing. 328 REVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. then it does not go after anything, or exert any inclina- tion or preference toward anything ; w^liich brings the matter to a contradiction ; because for the mind to will something, and for it to go after something by an act of preference and inclination, are the same thing. " But if every act of the will is excited by a motive, then that motive is the cause of the act of the will. If the acts of the will are excited by motives, then mo- tives are the causes of their being excited ; or, which is the same thing, the cause of their being put forth into act and existence. And if so, the existence of the acts of the will is properly the effect of their motives. Mo- tives do nothing as motives, or inducements, but by their influence ; and so much as is done by their influ- ence is the efiect of them. For that is the notion of an effect, something that is brought to pass by the influ- ence of another thing. " And if volitions are properly the efl'ects of their motives, then they are necessarily connected with their motives. Every effect and event being, as proved be- fore, necessarily connected with that wliich is the proper ground and reason of its existence. Thus it is manifest that volition is necessary, and is not from any self- determining power in the will." In passing, I would remark upon this statement, that when in it Edwards says, " for the mind to will some- thing, and for it to go after soTnething ly an act of preference and inclination, are the same thing," he, in fact, materially varies his definition of will, under which !ie could only say, " for the mind to .will something, and to prefer something, are the same thing ; " and the addition makes the act of choosing or preferring, mclude the going after the thing chosen or preferred^ MOTIVE. 329 and is one of many instances of the difficulty to which he is reduced, from not recognizing, by a distinct term, that action of the mind, which sometimes follows its clioice, and Mdiich I have called effort j and which he here virtually admits as coming between the choice and the effect, and characterizes as " the going after the thing chosen," and by the remarkable expression, " exert- ing a preference," In this case, the proof " that every act of the will has some cause," or that every act of the will, wha-tsoever, is excited by some motive, rests en- tirely on this new assumption, but for the interpolating of which, the reasoning would be utterly futile, I do not, however, mean to question these propositions when the term motive is properly applied, but will here re- mark that his statement does not warrant all the in- ference he draws. If, as he says, " every act of the will is excited by motive," which " is the canse of its being put forth into act and existence," and then further admitting that motive is some power, or cause not of the mind, it would still only follow that some act of will is put forth, and not that what that act of will shall be is thus determined ; " not that it is in such a direction rather than another," Again, if the act of will is " 23ut forth," tliere must be some active agent to put it forth, Edwards virtually assumes tliat the mo- tive is itself the active agent directly producing acts of will ; and having thus put it in the place of the mind, arrives at conclusions, which really apply to mind, and prove that it is the cause of its own volitions and, of course, is free. If the motives, whatever they are, do not directly produce or control the acts of will, or do not directly act with irresistible force upon the will as a distinct entity, but are only indncements to the mind 330 REVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. to " put forth " some volition, then it may still be for the mind to determine whether to yield to those induce- ments, or to which of numerous inducements it will yield, or in what way it will " go after something," or whether it will go after it at all, which would still be to determine its own action ; and by its intelligence con- form that action to the existing circumstances, which motive, as a distinct entity, or any other blind cause could not do. In noticing some portions of this argu- ment, I may attempt to sliow that even upon Edwards's own definition, that " volition is choice," it is fallacious. As to what determines the will, he says, " It is that motive^ which as it stands in the vieiv of the mind is the strongest^ that determines the will^'' (p. T.) He also says, " By 'motive^ I mean the whole of tliat which moves, excites, or invites the mind to volition, whether that be one thing singly, or many things conjunctly." (p. Y.) He previously says, " The will is said to be de- termined, when, in consequence of some action, or in- fluence, its choice is directed to and fixed upon a par- ticular object. As, when we speak of the determination of motion, we mean causing the motion of the body to be such a way, or in such a direction rather than an- other." (p- 6.) The word '''■ aot'ion'''' here seems to be superfluous ; for, if the action does not influence the will it has nothing to do with it ; and if it does, it is an in- fluence. Tiie above statements then assert that the motive which moves, excites, or invites the mind to volition, determines the will, and identify motive and influence. The phrase, " the wdiole of that which moves, excites, or invites " must include everything past, present, or future, which has any possible influ- ence on the mind in willing Tliei-e is an apparent limi- MOTIVE. 331 tation in the statement that, it must " stand in the view of the mind ; " but as Edwards says, " Nothing can in- duce, or invite the mind to will, or act anything, any further than it is perceived," this apparent limitation only excludes what does not influence, and still leaves the phrase to include all that does influence the mind in willing. This definition of motive then amounts simply to this : that whatever influences the mind in willing is a motive ; and what does not influence it is not a Tnotive. There is, also, the condition that it must be the " strong- est motive," and this, of course, must mean that mo- tive, which has the most influence on the mind in will- ing. The whole of the three statements, then, as quoted, and especially if taken in connection with his idea that injiuence is that which produces an effect, amounts to this, that the mind, in willing, is influenced by that which most influences it to will, or that the mind, in heing moved to will — we must use this form of expression if it does not move itself — is moved by that which moves it, or is moved in the direction in which it is moved by that which moves it in that direc- tion ; or that the mind in willing, " the will," is deter- mined by that which determines it. The whole state- ment amounts to nothing, ending where it began. It is as impossible, logically, to deduce any new truth from such statements and definitions as from the expression " whatever is, is." In this instance we learn from them, in the first place, that the will is determined by that which influences it ; next, that what so influences it is a certain motive ; and when we inquire what a motive is, we are told that it is anything and everything which influences the will. It seems to be an unsuccessful at' 332 KEVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. tempt to apply the mathematical mode, and make the definition give existence to the thing defined, instead of desciibing something which ah-eady exists. But, in this case, we have to deal with realities and not with mere hypothesis. The argument, as Edwards states it, really fixes nothing, determines nothing ; it confirms nothing, it opposes nothing. If, as some of his oppo- nents assert, the will determines the will, then that strongest motive, which moves the mind to will, is the will itself; and, under hi? definition, the only way in which it can be showii that the wnll itself is not such a motive, or that it does not conform to his definition of it, is to show that the w'lil itself does not determine the will ; and, having done thlt^, there is no need of trav- elling backward to apply the rale that the will is de- termined by the strongest motvvc, to prove that the will does not determine itself; foi- that is then already proved, and nothing is gained i.u the argument by the introduction of the motive. So, also, if it be asserted that the mind, by means of its knowledge, or by any other mean?, determines its acts of will, this is to assert that the mind, by such means, becomes such a motive as Edwaidf^ defines ; and this assertion, if sustained, would make hio own posi- tions proof of the freedom of the mind in willing ; for if the mind determined its own acts of will, it .\o not im- portant to the question of its freedom by what means it does it ; and the assertion would only be proved or dis- proved as in the former case, by first proceeding with- out any reference to the general idea or definiti'^i of motive.* And, if it were asserted that anything' dse * See Appendix, Note XLIII. MOTIVE. 333 determined the will, the introduction of motive, as thus defined, would really avail nothing to prove or dis- prove it ; for, in every case, under Edwards's definitions, the only way to prove that this anything is, or is not the strongest motive, is first to ascertain whether it does, or does not determine the will. Whether, then, this notion of motive sustains freedom or necessity, depends on the character of the motive ; which does not appear in the definition. The difficulty is a radical one, and arises from defining " strongest motive " not by what it is, or must be, but by something that it may, or must do, doing which it is the strongest motive, but otherwise it is not the strongest motive. Let one take what position he may as to what determines the will, he need not deny that it is the " strongest motive " that determines it, i. e. as Edwards defines " strongest mo- tive ; " for, to assert that anything/ whatever determines the will, is to assert that this anything exactly corre- sponds to Edwards's definition of" strongest motive," for there must then be asserted of it the only distinguish- ing characteristic, which he attributed to the " strongest motive," viz. : that of determining the will. If freedom determines the will, then freedom is the strongest mo- tive ; if necessit}^ determines the will, then necessity is the strongest motive ; and we have only got a new name ready for whatever is proved, or proves itself to be en- titled to it. As a philosophical discovery of what deter- mines the will, it is much as if a man should say, " I have invented a machine by which men can fly. My invention consists in such a combination and applica- tion of mechanical motors, as will enable men to fly ! " Nor would it much enhance its merit, if he should add, " The mechanism of this, my invention, must he visible^ 334 EEVIKW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL, or he known to the man wlio is to fly ; and, of tlie different kinds of motors, that which is the strongest, or which appears to him the strongest, or which by its effects proves itself the strongest, must be used." An inven- tor could hardly hope to obtain a patent upon the merits of such a specitication. On reading it, a man would be very apt to think that this gave him very little aid in designing and constructing a flying machine, but really left it all for him to find out for himself. The same of the motive, one of the difficulties in the specifi- cation of which, as already intimated, is, that it does not really define what the motive is. Edwards says, " It must be something that is extant in the mew or appre- hension of the understanding^ or perceiving faculty " 'J). 7). It is obvious that, to conform to this definition, and, at the same time, admit the deduction of neces- sity, the motive must be something, which not only is not controlled by the mind, but which in some way has power to control it. But why, then, is it essential that it should be " in the view of the mind," and why, if not in view of the mind, is it wholly without influence ? If the flying machine just alluded to, is to be used by some agent or power extrinsic to the man who flies, and he is to be taken up by it, and carried through the air without any agency of his own, there can be no possible necessity that he should see or feel the machine when he is being moved by it. The effect would be accom- plished just as well if his eyes were closed, or he asleep and wholly unconscious of its action, And, if this mo- tive is something, which is itself to move the mind to will and not something which the mind is to use to move, or direct its will, there can be no necessity that it should " be in the view of the mind ; " and such ne- MOTIVE. 335 ' cessity indicates that the mind must use tlie motive to determine its will, and not be used or determined by- it ; that the power is in the mind, or active agent, and not in the motive, which is only something which that agent perceives or knows. Again, this motive must also be one particular mo- tive. The motives may be numerous, but only one, simple or complex, ?'. e., made up of " one thing singly, or many things conjunctly," determines the will. I^ow, this prevailing motive is not that which from anything in itself is the strongest, but that which in the view of the mind is the strongest. As the motive cannot itself determine that it is the " strongest motive," and, more especially, that in the view of the mind, it is the strong- est, this must mean that the motive, which the mind perceives or judges to be the strongest, determines the will. But, if the mind, by the exercise of its faculty of judging, or by its capacity to perceive, acquires that knowledge by which itself determines the strongest motive, and the strongest motive determines the will, then the mind, in fact, determines the will ; for to de- termine the strongest motive is to determine which motive shall prevail ; and, without such exercise of judgment, or such application of our knowledge, the motive would have no power and would not prevail. But the mind determining itself in willing, by meana of its intelligence, or by the exercise of any of its facul- ties, is only another expression for the freedom of the mind in willing. It is very certain that the motive can- not itself determine that itself is the strongest motive, unless it be an intelligent being with faculties for per- ceiving, comparing, and judging, and if, in that case, it is the same being whose will is to be controlled, then 336 REVIEW OF 3.DWARD8 ON THE WILL. that being, as its own motive, directly controls its own will, and hence wills freely. It cannot be another in- telligent being that determines which is the strongest motive, for then, it is not " in the mind's view " of the one to be influenced, and on him has no influence. If this other being has determined which is the strongest motive, it must still be so presented to the mind of the one to be influenced by it, that he shall also perceive and decide or judge that it is the strongest, or it can have no influence in determiiiiiig his will. To compare and determine which is the strongest of several motives fre- quently requires a preliminary effort, or act of will, and the " strongest motive " is not effective till this is done, and we may then have a series interminable unless ter- minated by a simple mental perception requiring no preliminary effort. If it be said that one having ascer- tained which is the strongest motive, may thereby directly control the will of another, who has not ascer- tained it, we reply that the controlled will, though in another, is really then the will of the controlling being, and the controlled has no will in the matter to be con- trolled. If the one being indirectly influences the other, by so changing the circnmstances that the latter will perceive a certain motive to be the strongest, then this other is still influenced by his own perceptions, his own knowledge, which, as before shown, does not conflict with his freedom in willing. Or, if the one, in any way, changes the mind's view of the other, with or without changing the circumstances or object viewed, then the mind influenced is still governed by its own views, its own perceptions, own knowledge, otherwise the change in its views would not influence it in willing ; so that, if such a motive as Edwards suggests be really found, MOTIVE. 337 it will not militate against the position that, if the mind wills, it must will freely. When Edwards says, " An act of the will is the same as an act of cJioosing or choice " (p. 1 ), and that " the will is always determined by the strongest mo- tive " (p. 8), which again is that " which, as it stands in the mind's view, suits it best and pleases it most " (p. 9), he, in efi'ect, says, that the choice is determined by a choice, if not by the same choice, which is itself determined ; for that " which suits the mind hest and pltases it mod^'' must, as he asserts, be that which the mind })refers or chooses, rather than that which does not suit it so well, or please it so nnich ; and, as he says, the will is always so determined, we have either the act of will or choice always determining itself; or every act of will or choice, determined by a preceding act of will or choice, ad infinitum / for, if each choice in the chain does not determine itself, it must, under these statements, be determined by some preceding choice or preference for that " which, in the mind's view, suited it best," &c., constituting the determining motive. That the mind has in itself, or in its own view, a motive for action, is no reason that it does not act freely ; but rather the contrary, as without motive, adopting Edwards's view of it, the mind could not be said to decide as to its own actions, having no reason whatever to make such decision one way rather than another, or to decide at all ; and hence would not will at all, freely or otherwise. Motives, then, being neces- sary to the mind's willing freely, cannot, merely in vir- tue of their existence, be a reason why it does not will freely. The existence of that thing, which is a neces- 15 338 REVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. sary condition to the existence of something else, can- not, of itself, be a reason why that sometliing else does not exist, but, on the contraiy, prepares the way for its existence. To have shown that the mind wills without any motive, would have better subserved the argument for necessity. These views and objections are suggested by Ed- wards's definition of motives and his remarks upon them ; and seem to show that they admit of no such application to the mind in willing as can furnish a foundation for necessity ; and that, in attempting so to apply them, he involves views contradictory to his own positions, and which, virtually, or by implication, affirm freedom. If this is asserting too much for the argu- ment which we have just presented, we think it will not be denied that whether the motives prove neces- sity or freedom, must, as before stated, depend on their character. Hence it becomes important to know what they are, that their character may be ascertained ; and, if Edwards had in view some actual motives, which would make this important link in his argument, it is much to be regretted that he did not so define them, that others could readily find and test them. If he had any idea of such, liis definition, as before shown, will give us little «id in finding them ; and the illustrations he subsequently uses do very little to relieve us from the difficulty of searching them out in that almost boundless expanse, " the whole of that, which moves, excites, or invites the mind to volition," limited only by the one condition that it is " in the view of the mind." This may embrace everything of which the mind has cognizance, within or without itself, making it difficult to' examine the whole ground ; but, by a MOTIVK. 339 elassificatiou of the objects, some approximation to it may be possible. Before attempting this, however, we will remark that Edwards, warranted perhaps bj the latitude of his definition, uses the term motive in two very different senses ; sometimes as meaning the mind's view of any objects or things, and at others, any objects or things which the mind views. His definition, " By motive I mean * * * one thioig singly, or many things conjunctly," favors the latter, as also the expression, " a motive is something which is extant in the view or apprehension of the understanding, or per- ceiving faculty." And when he says, " the will is de- termined by that motive, which, as it stands in the view of the mind, is the strongest," we should hardly sup- pose him to mean that the view of the mind is itself the motive that s'ands in the view of the m.ind. This could only mean, that the mind views what it views, or that it views another of its views. But he subse- quently says, " if strict propriety of speech be insisted on," the act of volition itself is always determined by that in, or about the mind's view of the object^ which causes it to appear most agreeable " (p. 11), i. «., not by the object^ but by the mind's view of it ; and again, " the idea of the thing preferred has a prevailing influence " (p. Y6), and still more strongly to this point, " the will is akoays determined by the strongest motive^ or by that VIEW of the 7nind, which has the greatest degree of jprevious tendency to excite volition " (p. 16). Here, as he cannot mean that the view of the mind is some- thing else thsn the strongest motive, which may also determine the will, motive has got to be nothing else but a view of the mind. It may be said that this ex pression is elliptical, as there must be something which 340 REVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. tlie mind views. Still there remains the important dis- tinction between the mind's beina; influenced in willing by its view of the object, or by the object viewed. Con- founding the two in the one word " motive^'' leads to much confusion in Edwards's argument, but as he really thus uses it, we must, to give all the scope he assumes for his position, concede to him the double meaning, and consider motive as embracing not only the mind's view of objects, but also the objects viewed. But to return : asserting that the volition is deter- mined by the view of the mind, let that which is viewed be what it may, is merely saying that the mind, in willing, is determined by its own views ; and, as it must be the mind itself which makes the application of these views, it is saying that the mind determines its own act of will by means of its own views, which is but another expression for its freedom in willing ; so that, if the essence of the motive is in the vietv of the mind, the influence which Edwards ascribes to the motive confirms the freedom of the mind in willing ; and it would not be necessary to inquire as to the objects viewed. If, however, it be said, that although the mind in willing determines itself by its own view, yet the object viewed is essential to that view, and, therefore, essen- tial to the determination ; it may, in conformity with the views I have asserted, be replied that, to have any influence, the object which the mind views must either be its own want, or an object which may be selected to gratify that want, or some knowledge to enable it to decide as to that selection and its subsequent action. If it is a want, it furnishes a foundation for action to gratify it ; if it is an object of choice, it adds to the sub- MOTIVE. 341 jects from among which the mind may select to gratify the want. If it is knowledge of any kind, it adds to the power of the mind to adapt the objects of choice to its wants, enabling it to decide more intelligently or wisely as to its own acts. The first furnishes the occa- sion or opportunity for the act of will ; the two last are merely cases of the knowledge of the mind being in- creased, either as to the objects wanted, or the means of obtaining them, by which freedom in willing is facil- itated, and its sphere of action enlarged. In regard to the other position, that the motive is the ohject viewed^ Edwards admits that the object itself, un- less in the vieio of the mind, can have no influence. He says : " Nothing can induce, or invite the mind to will, or act anything, any further than it is perceived, or is some way or other in >!ie mind's view ; for what is wholly un- perceived and perfectly out of the mind's view, cannot affect the mind at all " (p. 7). These views of the mind, of any objects or circumstances whatever, are, as just stated, but portions of its knowledge of things, upon which to exercise its powers to produce change, or of truths enabling it to exercise these powers intelli- gently ; and, as such, are essential to such exercise. Without them it would not make effort, or will at all ; and the existence of the things viewed or objects of effort, or of the mind's view, or knowledge in regard to them, which thus facilitates and aids the mind in will- ing, cannot be a reason why it does not will freely. The power existing in the mind to avail itself, in its contem- plated action, of certain cor)ceivable objects or circum- stances, may be limited or made nugatory in conse- quence of those objects and circumstances being absent, or, from any cause, unattainable; but this does not pre- 342 REVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. vent its willing freely in regard to those which it deems attainable. Suppose, for instance, a man is huQgry and seeks to gratify his want for food. He knows that for copper he can obtain food ; for silver, better food, and, for gold, the best, or that food which he likes best; but he perceives that the present circumstances are such that he cannot obtain the gold ; only silver and cop- per are possible. He acts just as freely in the prelim- inary effort to ascertain which of these two it is best to strive for, and in his subsequent efforts to obtain and ap- ply the one selected by the preliminary act, as he woidd have done had all the three been attainable. His free- dom consists, not in his having power to make the cir- cumstances already existing different from what they are at the time, which is a contradiction, and hence not within the province even of Infinite Power to accom- plish, but in directing his efforts, by virtue of his own intelligence, to effect desii'ed changes among the circum- stances as they are at the moment of his action. If the circumstances had been different, he might have acted differently, and yet have willed freely, because — and even supposing the same circumstances to necessarily produce the same effect — a free act of will may be as different from what it would be under different circum- stances, as if it were necessitated by the circumstances ; and no inference against its freedom can be drawn from this variety of action under different circumstances. If the power to effect the change were directly exerted by the circumstances, it would argne in favor of necessity ; but as theae circumstances can only change the knowl- edge of the mind — the mind's view — wliicli the mind must itself apply in its action, it argues self-government or freedom. In this latter case, the influence of the MOTIVE. 343 motives amounts only to the mind's applying its knowledge and efforts to make these circumstances subservient to its own designs, and thus available in gratifying its wants. To say that the mind does not will freely because various objects of effort exist, and the mind has the faculty of perceiving, or of finding reasons for preferring one or more of them to others, and has a motive to act in conformity to that prefer- ence ; is to say, that the mind does not act freely, be- cause it has the opportunity and ability to choose its action, and to conform its action to such choice. It is obvious that this variety of objects or of circumstances is essential to the preliminary effort of the mind in choosing. It wants to produce a certain efiect in the future. If the mode of doing it is not already known, or immediately perceived, it examines, i. e., makes a preliminary effort to find a mode ; and if more than one mode is found, it compares and ascertains which is pre- ferable ; it chooses among them ; and may then, by 3^et another preliminary act, ascertain whether action or non-action is preferable ; it chooses as between ac- tion and non-action. In all these preliminary efforts it has obtained only knowledge ; and if having chosen thus to act, it does not so a<;t, or make such effort, it must be because it is constrained or restrained from controlling and directing its own action. But no exter- nal power can control or restrain the effort, though it may frustrate the design and defeat the object of it. Much that I have before said of the relation of circum- stances to the mind in willing, is especially applicable to preliminary efforts of the mind in choosing ; and all goes to show that volition, both as a final act and as a prelitninary, by examination, to cho'co, is an original 344 REVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. act of the mind, which, but for its action, would not be ; and which might be, though there were no ac- tivity or power besides itself in existence at the time of such choice, or such volition ; and hence, nothing to constrain and nothing to restrain or limit it but the consciousness of its own finite nature. And, even this cannot be said to be a limit to its power of choosing or of willing ; but only a limit to its power of conceiving of things to be chosen or acts to be willed or done, and of its knowledge of modes or means to do them. Whenever it can conceive of anything to be done and that there may be a possible mode of doing it, it can make the efibrt, although, from its finite nature, it is liable to be mistaken in the relation of means to the end ; and to be frustrated in the execution of its design. It is not in the willing to do, but in the doing what we will, that we are liable to be frustated or disappointed by the circumstances which are extrinsic to the mind, and those circumstances which are independent of the mind only fix what the mind is to choose among, and do not influence its freedom in the act by which it chooses among them, nor in its action in regard to at- taining that which is chosen. In seeking for such a motive as Edwards uses in his argument, I would suggest the following classification of the " somethings which may exist in the view of the mind," in which phrase he gives the only clue to his idea of motive. As classing some of these as motives may appear contradictory and futile, I may, in justice to Edwards, observe that many of them are such as he does not seem to contemplate ; though liis definitions and statements are broad enough to cover ev'erything conceivable, and I wish to give to the argument all he MOTIVE. 34:5 can possibly claim for it. I suggest, then, the following objects as possibly coming within his definition of mo- tives. 1. The mind itself. 2. Its attributes, or faculties. 3. Its emotions , ^ . 1 Constituting its feeling. 4. Its sensations. ) 5. Its innate knowledge.* 1 6. Its memories of things and Constituting thoughts in the past. V its 7. Its perceptions of the present, i knowledge. 8. Its conceptions of the future, j 9. Its imaginings. 10. Its associations. 11. Other mind; representing all intelligences, other than the mind to be determined.. 12. The faculties of these oiher minds. ] 3. Its emotions. • 14. Its sensations. 15. Its knowledge, past, present and future. 16. Material phenomena; including any circumstances, which are extrinsic to mind. We will consider these in their respective order. 1. If the mind itself is the motive that determines its own act of will, then, as before shown, the mind in such an act of will is free. 2. If the attributes or faculties of the mind are the motives, then, as these attributes or faculties can do nothing except as they are exercised or exerted by the mind, it must be the mind^ in the exercise of its facul- ties, that determines the will i which, again, would prove the mind's freedom in willing. 3. An emotion, which is not in itself a want, and * See Appendix, Note XLIV. 15* 346 REVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. which does not produce want, is not a motive. As we have ah'eady suggested that no want arises, so no act of will can spring from that joy, which so satisfies the mind that it desires no change, or from that holy and nnseltish grief which it wonld not banish nor modify ; and, of that anguish which arises from the conscious- ness of error, the cause is in the past, and cannot be reached by any act of will ; while admiration, wonder, and awe compose or still, rather than excite, the active faculty. All these but make a part of the past expe- rience, adding to tliat present knowledge which aids the mind in determining its course in tlie future. But with these and other emotions, as love, hope, fear, anger, the mind may have corresponding wants, if only the want to derive pleasure, variety, or excitement from them. These wants, and the sensation or perception of these wants, may induce the mind to act for its own gratifica- tion or relief. But the wants cannot themselves deter- mine that action, for that must depend on the percep- tion by the mind of the means of gratifying the want ; and the perception must include, or be the preconcep- tion of, the relation of the future effect of its own act to its want, which brings it to the case of the mind deter- mining its action by its own view, which we have be- fore considered. If it has no such perception of a means of gratifying the want by an act of will, and that the want may thereby be gratified, there is no act of will put forth ; which shows that the mind, in grati- fying any want which may arise from the emotions, still directs its action by means of its preconception or knowledge of the future effect of its effort, which it only can apply, and hence in such effort acts freely. 4. Sensation, as before stated, may, with knowledge, MOTIVE. 347 produce want, suggesting some change for its gratifica- tion ; or, it may be but a perception of an external fact in the present, involving no want of change in the fu- ture. The effect of want as a motive, and of the inci- dental addition of another fact to our knowledge, have both been already sufficiently considered in their re- spective relations to the determination of the mind in willing, and shown not to militate against its freedom. 5. Innate knowledge is that knowledge which is directly communicated by the Creator to the creature, but, becoming a portion of its own knowledge, in no respect differs in its effects or influence on the will from other or acquired knowledge. That, as suggested in our chapter on instinct, it may be in such a form as not to require any contrivance to adapt it to use, in the act of willing, and thus facilitates the action of the mind in willing, does not conflict with the mind's freedom in the act which is thus facilitated. 6. The mind's memory of the past, including its own thoughts, and embracing, of course, the knowledge of things, events, and abstract truths which it has acquired in that past. The things and events from being in the past, and the abstract truths from their nature, are un- changeable, and hence not subjects for the action of the will, and only make a portion of the knowledge of the mind, by which it is enabled to decide its future course. 7. The result of the mind's perceptions of the present ii a knowledge of existing things. These may admit of a succession differing from themselves — of change —and this change be the object of the mind's act of will ; but the mind will not will, or make effort to change them, unless it has some want to be gratified by such change. The things themselves cannot indi- 348 REVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL, cate what changes will gratify the want, for they cannot even know what the want is. To do tliis requires intel- ligence. To adapt things, or the changes in things, which are effected by volition, to the simplest want, requires not only knowledge, but contrivance, which things have not. For instance, hunger is the want of food in the stomach : we cannot immediately will the food there, but have to apply our knowledge and power of thought or exann'nation, in adapting and devising means and ways of doing it ; even after it is in the mouth, it is not the food that knows that it must be masticated and swallowed, and the order of these two processes. It is the mind's perception, that by the various acts, from the procuring the food to the swal- lowing of it, and by these acts, in a certain order, the sensation of hunger may be relieved, that enables it intelligently to determine its successive efforts to that end ; and this preconception of the effect of its efforts it is enabled to form by its faculty of conceiving of the future — its finite prophetic power — which is aided and rendered less fallible by every increase of its knowledge. In such case, neither the mind's percep- tions nor that which is perceived can determine ; but the perception or knowledge enables the mind to de- termine. 8. The mind's conception of the future is itself a view by the mind, and, as such, embraced in our re- marks on the mind in willing being determined by its own views. We are admitting the largest possible lat- itude to what may be conceived to be motive, but the mind's own view or conception of the future, of some- thing which as yet has no objective reality, but is exclu- sively a view of the mind within itself, seenjs hardly MOTIVE. 349 sucli a motive as Edwards speaks of as " standing in the mind's view ; " for the mind's perception of that future is the mind's view itself, and not something which stands in that view. If this be tlie motive, we need ]iot repeat our reasoning to show that such views of the mind, such motives, are the essential element which enables the mind to determine its own acts of will a3 an independent, creative, iirst cause. The motive cannot be that future which the mind views, for it, as yet, has no actual existence, and can have no influence on the mind except by or through the mind's anticipation of it, which is the mind's view just considered, and makes a portion of its knowledge. 9. The mind's imaginings being such combinations as have no objective existence, past or present, but sup- posed capable of existence, may also be i-egarded as in the future, and be classed with those conceptions which are incipient creations of the mind. Being palpable and tangible to itself, they gratify some want of the mind, as the love of knowledge, the sentiment of beauty, &c. If, for convenience, we take some circumstances of the past, and in imagination vary them, or add some new feature, the new combination really has no past exist- ence, and, as present, exists only as a view of the mind without any objective existence ; and, whether we locate it in the past, present, or future, or give it no particular place in time, makes no more ditference than the loca- ting of a geometrical diagram in time. \r\ l)otli cases they are but constructions, alfording pleasure by their harmony, symmetry, and beauty, or aiding the mind to solve some problem and thus to increase its knowledge. 10. The associations of the mind are only other por- tions of its knowledge, suggested by that portion which 850 KEVIKW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. is immediately in its view ; and, tliough very important in giving the mind a ready use of its knowledge in the formation of its ])lans, whicli ai-e prerequisites of rational action, and yet more especially, in that recalling of former plans, which is the basis of habitual action, still association is but, in this connection, a means by which the mind uses its knowledge in directing its will, and requires here no further comment. 11. Any other mind or intelligence, as a mere object, viewed or apprehended by the mind, can have no influ- ence differing in Mnd from that of the mind's view of any other extrinsic object, and this we have already considered. If this other mind has in it anything which will gratify a want in the mind that views it, this mind may put forth an effort to obtain that thing. We have before considered in a similar connection the case of the will of one mind being controlled directly or indirectly by another mind by means of the exercise of any of its powers, or otherwise, and need not repeat the reason- ing or the result ; and this, with the consideration that those powers cannot exert themselves or have any influ- ence except as exerted by the mind to which they ap- pertain, disposes, also, of 12. The attributes and faculties of one mind, as a motive, determining the will of another mind. 13. 14, 15. The emotions, sensations, and knowledge of another mind can have no iiifluence, except as they are made manifest to the mind to be influenced in that case, becoming but portions of its own knowledge, and, as such, already shown not to interfere with its freedom in willing. We may, however, further remark that the knowledge which one mind acquires from another co- ordinate or like mind, must be of the same character as MOTIVE. 351 that which it acqiiires or has from other sources ; and that the knowledge which the finite mind derives from the Infinite when directly imparted is intuitive ; and when indirectly^ by the written expression of His thoughts in nature, they are but the knowledge of material phenomena or that which is extrinsic to the mind, which belongs under our next and last division. 16. Material phenomena, including any circum- stances which are extrinsic to the mind. Material objects cannot, of themselves, be such a motive, for they may have existed from all etei-nity, and yet never have produced or determined a volition, and even may have been in the mind's view for any length of time and yet never have moved it to will, or determined its will ; but if they are a necessary cause in themselves, then the moment they exist they must produce their effect, or if the additional circumstance that they must be " in the mind's view," makes them the cause of volition in that mind, then, as soon as they are in that mind's view, the volition should follow. That this is not the fact, proves that there is something besides the material object and the fact that it is in the mind's view, which produces the effect, or determines the will. The same is true of extrinsic circumstances, Nor can any changes in these extrinsic objects and circumstances, whether produced by the motion of matter, or by intelligent action, of itself, move the mind to will. Increase or vary the circumstances ever so much, they could no more produce any volition in themselves or in others — a volition having reference to an effect which as yet is not — than the extension of the multiplication table could make it know itself or feel hungry. However blindly active among themselves, they cannot embrace 352 REVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. that design, that intention, to produce a precomjeived result, which is an essential characteristic of volition, and which distino-uislies the action of intellio;cnt from blind causes. For this they avail nothing until the mind uses them as its knowledge to determine its action ; and the mind is itself really the efficient cause of that determination, freely adapting its action to tlje circum- stances in its view. There is, evidently, no way in which these circumstances can directly produce a voli- tion in the human mind, and if they could, it would be the volition of the circumstances, and not of tlie human being. These extrinsic circumstances can influence the mind in willing only as they are perceived or appre- hended by the mind, and, as such, become but a part of the mind's knowledge, and, of course, subject to our previous conclusions, that knowledge, however acquii-ed, is used by the mind to enable it to determine its acts ; and hence, is essential to its freedom in willing ; every increase in knowledge enlarging its sphere for the exer- cise of such freedom. There are vague notions, in the popular mind, in regard to the influence of circumstances upon us, often bordering on fatalism, if not really involving it, and which find expression in sucili phrases as " man is the sport," or " he is the creature of circumstances." One reason for t.liis is, that we are liable to be frustrated by circumstances in the execution of what we wnll. This, it will be observed, is su(;h an efl'ect, after the act of willing, as can have no influence Inickward upon it. I will to walk in a certain direction, but am obstructed by a rushing torrent, which God lias caused to flow there, or by a wall erected thi-ougli human agency. The circumstance prevents my doing what I intended, MOTIVE. 353 and what, from want of sufficient knowledge, I decided to do. The new knowledge thus acquired, leads me to alter my course, and I may never again fall into the same track that I woidd otherwise have pursued. I go on to produce some change, but what that change will be depends upou the use which my mind makes of thip new, combined with its previous knowledge, in direcling its subsequent action. Though I cannot, as now ascer- tained, go in the direction intended, there are still an infinite number of ways in which I can go ; and among these my mind, in virtue of its intelligence, judges which is best. It may do tliis by a preliminary free act, and then, being free, conform its final action to its judgment ; and lience, this influence of cii'cu instances does not argue that the mind does not act freely in willing, but only that it cannot always execute its de- crees ; not that it does not freely try, or make effort, but that its powx^r is not always adequate to the eft'ect designed, or its knowledge sufficient to direct its efibrts most wisely, and the want of freedom, if such this want of power may be termed, is just where Edwards asseits the only freedom of man exists. As the mind's being liable to be frustrated in the execution of what it wills by the existence of circum- stances of which it did not know, is one reason of the popular idea in regard to the influence of circumstances, so, on the other hand, another reason for it may be found in the limitation of the circumstances — in the absence or non-existence of some that are essential to the execution — to the doing what is attempted — or of some which are prerequisites of the eftbrt, which it would or might make, if they were present and avail- able, and for the want of which the mind either does 354 REVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. not will, or wills differently from what it would if thej were present and available as a portion of its knowl- edge. In their absence, the mind knows no mode of obtaining the object for which such circumstances are prerequisite. This does not affect :ts freedom in ^\■illing as to what, under the circumslances, is attainable, but only lessens the sphere in which it can exercise that freedom. This sphere, as before stated, is always com- mensurate with its knowledge ; and it matters not whether the knowledge requisite to any effort — the knowledge of some mode — is deficient, because such knowledge cannot exist, or sim[)]y because it does not exist in the mind. The limitation of the sphere of effort is the same in either case. I may know not only that /cannot now make 2 + 2 = 5, but that it is an impossi- bilit}', and hence, will not seek any mode of doing it. I may also know that I have no knowledge of any geo- metiical process by which to ti'isect an arc, and, as I do not know that this is an impossibility, I may seek to increase my hnowledge^ and by means of such increase devise some mode in conformity to which 1 may direct my efforts to trisect the arc. So that, whether the thing to be done be absolutely impossible, from there being no possible mode of doing it, or only relatively to me impossible, because I know of no way, the for- mula heretofore adopted, tliat the mind''s sphere of free activity^ or for the exercise of its creative jpowers hy will or effort, is commensurate with its Itnowltdge^ covers the whole ground. If the mind of every human being at all times embraced all knowledge, then, all the circum- stances presented to every mind would, of necessity, be the same, but by the limitation of human knowledge different circumstances are presented to different minds. MOTIVE. 355 Of two persons wanting^ a metal, one may have, within his power, head, zinc, and gold ; another Only lead and zinc; hut the hitter chooses and conforms his effort to his choice as freely in i-egard to the two, as the former in regard to the three. If a man with all the natural endowments of Newton, and with his acquired habits of industrious and persevering study, had always lived in the Sandwich Islands, he would not have had, in the surrounding circumstances, the opportunities essential to such discoveries as Newton made. The requisite books and instruments — the means of knowledge — would not have been there accessible, or to him pos- sible; but he would have been equally free by effort to avail himself of such means as w^ere there in his power. The mind varies its own action to conform to the relations which it perceives between the circumstances and the preconception of the effect by which it seeks to gratify its want, and it does this in virtue of that intel- ligence, which, perceiving this relation, makes self- control and freedom, or self-action free from extrinsic control, possible to it. We find then, in all this conceivable i-ange, no mo- tive that so determines the will as to warrant the infer- ence of necessity ; none to which the mind itself is subordinated, or which will admit of dispensing with the mind itself as the cause, which determines its own acts of will. Let us now see if Edwards has himself indicated any 6uch actual motive. In the general statement, already quoted, he affirms that without motive the mind in willing " has no end which it jprojposea to itself, or pur- sues in so doing ; it aims at nothing, and seeks nothing, and, if it seeks nothing, then it does not go after any- 356 REVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. thing.'''' These expressions indicate tliat the essence of the motive is in the end which the mind seeks, some- thing which as yet is not, but which will be the effect of its volition, and that which is in the view of the mind as the motive to the volition, is the idea of the effect of the volition. But the idea or preconception of the effect of a volition could have no influence toward a volition, if the mind did not want to produce the effect it preconceived. The want is the incitement to effort ; and the mind's judgment or knowledge as to tlie adapta- tion of the effect, which it anticipates in the future, to the want and of the effort to the effect, enables it to determine as to the particular effort or volition it will put forth. So, also, in the particular case by which he illus- trates the influence of the strongest motive, he says : " Thus, when a drunkard has his liij^uor before liim, and he has to choose whether to drink it or no ; the proper and immediate objects, about which his present voliti(m is conversant, and between which his choice now de- cides, are his own acts in drinking the liquor, or letting it alone ; and this will certainly be done according to what, in the present view of his mind taken in the whole of it, is most agreeable to him. If he chooses or wills to drink it, and not to let it alone, then this action, as it stands in the view of his mind, with all that belongs to its appearance there, is more agreeable and pleasing, than letting it alone " (p. 10). The expression " between which his choice now de- cides," must mean, between which he hy an act of cJ4ects. 428 APPENDIX. NOTE XIII. P. 47. It seems that by long dwelling on an idea, or from some excited or abnormal sensitiveness of the mind, it sometimes loses the power to change or annihilate its own creations, and they become to it as external realities, producing, if pai'tial, monomania, or, if general, causing one species of insanity. NOTE XIV. P. 49. It may be apprehended by some that this ascribing aUthe crea-- tive powers of Deity to man, in however small degree, may unduly arouse his pride and excite his presumption. If there be such a one, let him essay any comparison, even the most trifling. Let him observe yonder towering elm mirthfully rustling its foliage as if titillated by the awkward attempts of its neighboring spire to appear graceful. Or first looking upon nature, — the great picture which God exhibits to us as His own creation, — turn from it to the most exquisite painting of a Claude Lorraine or a Salvator Rosa, perhaps grouping a few trees, a glimpse of water, a speck of green sward, floating clouds and dubious rays of sunshine, &c., &c., and in the comparison, the works of man, even those which, as the highest efforts of his creative genius, excite our profoundest admi- ration, vvill appear sufficiently Lilliputian, suflficiently paltry and insignificant, not to say mean and even ludicrous, to induce a be- coming modesty, to attemper his pride and humble all that is haughty and arrofiant in his naiure ; and in the comparison he may realize that there is something more than a mere abstraction in the mathematical dogma that no increase of the finite can alter its ratio to the infinite. He may here observe, too, what we have before intimated, that the conceptions of the human mind are more perfect, more Godlike, than the expression. For ourselves, we apprehend no evil tendency in the exaltation of man to the conscious dignity and responsibility of a being endowed with crea- tive power. We believe he is too apt to take debasing views of himself to consider meanness and wrong as appropriate or necessary to his condition and attributable to the natural weakness and imper- fections of his being, rather than to his own agency, or his own neglect properly to exercise the powers he has at command. We be- lieve, too, that it is essential to even an imperfect conception of any one of God's attributes, that we should ourselves possess it in some APPENDIX. 429 measure. Without tliis, \\ e liave no means of estimating the vast diiference, and can no more form even a remote conception of how much greater God is than His creatures, than v^^e can tell the pro- portion lietween seven acres and three liours. The proper effect then of the finite mind having the same attributes, is to enable it to form more adequate conceptions of the Infinite and make itself more sensible of its inferiority ; and if, as we have supposed may be the ca«e, its efforts are made effective through the uniform modes of God's action, the finite becomes wholly dependent on the Infinite for the execution of its designs and for the effectiveneHS of its eftorts; and these considerations, in this connection, are eminently calculated to inspire gratitude and imbue us with humility. NOTE XV. P. 58. As already remarked, a being, satisfied with things as they are, cannot be said to feel a want, and he makes no effort, he does not will any change. If he perceives that causes external to him are doing what he wants done without his agency, then, if his want is o:ily to have it done or to know that it will be done, his want is gratified by perceiving that it will be done. But perhaps he wants to know that it is actually done by these external causes ; and to this end an effort of attention is still required to gratify his want. NOTE XVI. P. 61. Even in cases of instinctive action, though, for reasons hereafter stated, we do not have to seek for knowledge to apply, or even to arrange the order of successive efforts, still it seems impossible that we should conform our action to the perceived circumstances — to the occasion demanding such action — without some intermediate effort, however in&tantaneous it may be, the need of which effort, as already suggested, may be intuitively known. However this may be, we early learn the importance of considering the cir- cumstances before we yield to instinctive impulses, and of ndapt- ing our actions to them, and thus are led to introduce conscious deliberation, either as a wholly new element or as an increase of one already existing, thereby changing the features or character of the action. 4:30 APPENDIX. NOTE XVII. p. 75. Conflicting Wants. — There may be conflicting wants betweea which the mind must decide. If, for instance, a man with only bread and water at command is both hungry and thirsty, he must decide which want he will first make effort to relieve. Or if, with the want to move out of some apprehended danger, there is co-existing the conflicting want of bodily repose, then he must decide between them by a comparison of his preconceptions of the future eff"ects of his conduct. No matter how short the plan of action, or of how few steps it may be composed, he may make the comparison. Even if the conflict is merely between effort and repose, one of the preconceptions being then limited to the mere making of effort, if we perceive in advance that effort will be pain- ful or pleasurable, it furnishes a subject of comparison with the painful or pleasurable effects of not making the effort. It is conceivable that wemaj want not to make any effort, and that, under the influence of this want, we would not examine as to any effort required by any other conflicting want. This is equivalent to supposing that there is no want of change, or that the want of repose is a conflicting and, in the view of the mind, a permanent want. If, with this supposed and eventually paramount want not to act, there is a co-existing, conflicting want, the mind must recognize it, for that which is not recognized by the mind cannot be its want. It cannot then shut out the presentation of the question, or the petition of its other want ; * and its subsequent non-action is proof that it has decided upon it. It is, however, doubtful whether we can ever properly be said to have a want not to act. "We may want to make effort, but there are distinctions between the want to make effort, or the want of effort, and the effort itself. In the first place, the distinction be- tween the want and the thing wanted ; and in the second place, that between the want of effort generally and a particular effort ; we may be disposed to effort and yet some particular efforts be undesirable, and even with this want of effort generally, any par- ticular effort not yet made or determined must be a preconception * The popular idea that the right of petition should be utterly inviolable seems thus to have its origin in the lowest depths of the constitution of our spiritual being. It might be curious to trace out the analogy of its association with the idea of liberty, in its metaphysiral and in Its political lelations. APPENDIX. 431 and not a want. Hence, it can never in the first instance be a con- flicting want, but only one of the modes of gratifying our want of effort, and as such, as just intimated, may come into comparison with other preconceived modes. In other words, what may be represented in terms as negatively a want not to make effort, gen- erally is either the absence of all want, or the presence of the positive want of repose. In the one case there is no disposition or indisposition to effort, and in the other, any such indisposition arises from a preconception that the effort if made will conflict with the want of repose ; and hence, is not the means to be adopted to gratify that want, and is subject to comparison wiih other preconceptions of the eflects of not acting. The forming of the preconceptions of the effect of acting or not acting is itself, for the time being, action ; and if with the want of repose a con- flicting want is actually presented to the mind, it must decide upon it, at least so far as to dispose of it by considering its merits, or deciding not to consider them. Ill the wants of activity and repose we have the last analysis of wants, and here find elements which enter into all our precon- ceptiiins for the gratification of other wants. The pleasure or [)ain of the particular effort, with its anticipated consequences, enters into the comparison of difterent modes of action. If, when wanting re- pose, the pain of effort itself, as perceived in advance, either from its proximity or other circumstance, appears greater than the anticipa- ted or apprehended painful results of not acting, or even just equal to them, no further effurt than that required to ascertain this fact will be made. So, too, if, when wanting activity, the pleasure of effort itself appears to be just balanced by the anticipated conse- quent pain of acting, or by the pleasure expected from not acting, no effort will be made. It is then as if the mind had no want to do, and it will not do. In such cases, though it may still know and enjoy or suffer, it is but the passive subject of changes in its own sensations, produced by other and extrinsic causes in which itself had no agency. From this inert or passive state the mind is aroused to effort by want, which may occur and recur without any antecedent effort ; and then by means of its knowledge, which also may exist without antecedent effort to obtain it, can direct its effort intelligently,. 4:32 APPENDIX. NOTE XVm. P. 88. By memory of a continuity of tliose changes in our sensations, the sense of identity might still he preserved, even though the will and all its pre-requisite processes of thought were annihilated. Without will, we might still know ourselves as the subjects acted upon, but could never know ourselves as cause. If this view is correct, the personal identity does not of necessity inhere solely in the will. NOTE XIX. P. 101. If our first parents had no knowledge of good and evil, in any sense, they must have been in constant communication with God, and as immediately directed and governed by His will as mere matter is. NOTE XX. P. 109. These views are in harmony with one indicated in the last chapter, that deliberation is superinduced upon some more primi- tive mental processes. NOTE XXL P. 115. Many brute animals do not know enough to flee from a fire. The horse will not leave his stall, though the stable is burning about him. We might suppose him palsied by terror ; but if forced away he runs back again. It seems to be a voluntary act, founded on the association of safety with his stall. Children, when frightened, will in like manner run into danger to seek refuge in their mother's arms. NOTE XXII. P. 116. There is no doubt that the intuitive knowledge varies very materially in different animals ; and there is, at least, some ground for supposing that it varies also in the individuals of the same species. It seems, however, certain that in all not higher in the scale of intelligence than man, voluntary action has always its base in the instinctive, though the superstructure which constitutes the plan of action may be wholly rational. This appears from the consideration that the immediate object of every act of will is to produce muscular or mental activity, for which we APPENDIX. 433 only know one mode, and that intuitively, and hence such action is always in itself instinctive. The diiference between the instinctive and the rational is not in the knowledge of the mode of acting, but in the mode by which we came to know the order of the suc- cession of our acts to reach the end sought. In regard to the difference in the iniuitive knowledge of indi- viduals of the same species it may be remarked that it is not only conceivable, but is matter of common belief, that the natural cal- culators, as the term implies, have an intuitive perception of the relations of numbers, or, at least, an intuitive knowledge of some mode of ascertaining such relation, through which they instinctive- ly reach results which others obtain in rational modes only by much time and labor. It is worthy of remark that those who exhibit this knowledge can give no more account of its origin, or even of their mode of obtaining their results, than others can give of their knowledge and modes in regard to muscular movements. If the natural calculator has only such intuitions as enable him easily to form plans by which, with very little effort, he reaches his results, his action is still rational. The amount of his knowl- edge, though it may enable him to make his plans more perfect and in less time, does not affect the nature of the act, which is still in conformity to a plan of his own contriving, using his supe- rior knowledge for that purpose. If he only adopts rules or plans which he finds ready formed in his mind, without any investiga- tion of his own, his action is instinctive. If he knows that, by looking for it in his mind, he will there perceive the result as a man perceives it in a table, without going through any process by any rule or plan, the action approaches as nearly as possible to that produced by an external power, — to mere mechanical action. But, as the action stiU requires an effort to apply the knowledge of this mode of obtaining the result, it is still voluntary and instinctive. So, also, of the natural bone setter. If he has by intuition such knowledge of anatomy as to enable him thereby to form his own pla?is, his action is as rational as if he had learned the same at a medical college. I speak of these phenomena as they exist in popular belief, and have not given to them the examination required to form an intelligent opinion as to their nature or existence. I will, however, observe that it only requires a modified form of one 19 434 APPENDIX. of our senses, an introvei'ted sense of bodily feeling, to enable one to obtain through it, all, and perhaps more than all, the knowledge of the anatomical structure of the system, which can be derived through the sense of sight from dissection, or from the observation of prepared specimens ; and that it does not seem more surprising that some men should intuitively have a knowledge of the relations of numbers and the results of their combinations, than that an ani- mal, blindfolded and carried by circuitous and zigzag routes, should know the direct course back to the point from whence it started. _ NOTE XXIII. P. 116. "Winking the eye when it needs to be moistened is probably in- stinctive. The infant knows wJien and how to do it as well as the adult, and apparently does it with as much facility. In the adult the attention and the effort required to do it being almost imper- ceptible, it is liable to be confounded with the involuntary and mechanical on the one hand, while to the more careful analyst it may appear not certain that it does not belong to the rational on the other. If we do not know that moving the lid will relieve the unpleasant feeling in the eye, we will not will to wink for such purpose, and if under such circumstances the lid moves, its move- ments must be attributed to some cause not of us ; and in such case, is as purely mechanical as the movements of the planetary system,* * The difficulty in applying conventional language to metaphysical inquiries is, perhaps, well illustrated by the fact that the distinction, apparently so broad and palpable as that between mechanical and voluntary, is really not well defined. In some connections the term voluntary would apply only to the volitions. But it has been transferred to the sequences of volitions ; and hence, we say the Tnuseu- lar movement which we will is voluntary ; but, in cases of cramp, or convulsion, it 1b involuntary or not willed. If we conceive of matter as having been in motion from eternity, and as continuing and producing movements and changes of itself, then these movements and changes are undoubtedly mechanical ; but when such changes in matter are produced or directed by a voluntary agent, acting mediately or immediately, their character is more or less changed — we name them from ap- pearances generally — and when we do not recognize the immediate or present .icting of a voluntary agent, we call them mechanical. But how close and how apparent the connection must be before the term voluntary is applicable, does not seem to be well settled. But all movements of matter must probably be referred to the will of an intelligent being ; and if the universe is the material form with which the Infinite Spirit is associated, as the human frame with its finite spirit, the movement of a planet would, in this view, seem to be as much a voluntary movement, as the movements of our feet, when we will to walk. APPENDIX. 435 On the other hand, it may be said that if a finger is suddenly thrust toward the eye the mind may immediately perceive or judge that there may not be time to consider whether it will reach the eye or not. The injury might be done during the time re- quired to consider this ; and hence, it is at once obvious that to insure safety the act of winking must be immediate, without con- sidering any other plan, the future consequences of the action, or even the present necessity for it. Any confidence which we might on reflection have that the finger would not be thrust upon the eye, cannot avail, for the mind has not time to consider this fact. The danger appears imminent and the mind decides almost instant- aneously, but its decisioti may still be a result of the exercise of its rational powers in comparing, &c., or in seeking a mode adapted to the end sougbt, and, if so, its action by a plan founded upon knowledge thus acquired, or even upon knowledge now acquired by immediate simple perception, and not upon an innate knowl- edge of the mode, is a rational action. In further confirmation of this view, it may be said that if the finger approaches the eye slowly, it is not immediately closed ; but the mind then judging that there is time to adopt the usual precaution of examining the circumstances preparatory to action, does examine ; it deliberates as to whether it will be necessary to make any effort to avoid the finger, and if so, what effort. The action must then be in con- formity to its own plan, even though its knowledge of the mode it adopts is intuitive ; for the adopting of that mode is an exercise of its rational faculties, using the intuitive knowledge nf the mode with other knowledge to form its plan of action with reference to a certain future result; and if, when the finger moves slowly, the action is a rational one, it may be difficult to determine at what particular velocity of the finger the action to avoid it becomes instinctive, if it ever does. But our previous reasoning would go to show that if an external object with the velocity of lightning flashes upon the eye, produc- ing pain or apprehension of injury, and we wink for its relief or protection, this may still be a rational action, though it may not be in time for the purpose intended. Whether the action be instinctive or rational^ it may become habitual ; but if the former, nothing is perhaps gained by the 436 APPENDIX. transition to the latter, as it may be as easy for the mind to act from the original intuitive hnowledge^ the innate conception of the mode of relieving or protecting the eye by moving the lid o^er it, as from memory of the practice under the same mode, even after any number of repetitions. It is when we know of various modes of action adapted to the same occasions that habit lessens the time and labor of deciding by furnishing a mode before decided upon under similar circumstances. I have stated what appears to me to be the general rule of dis- tinction between instinctive and rational action. To remove some of the difficulties in applying this rule, to determine to which class certain actions belong, is perhaps rather in the province of the naturalist than of the metaphysician ; and by actual observation they may, perhaps, be able to determine whether the movement of the lid to moisten the eye, or to protect it from external violence, is, in either or both cases, instinetive. I would, further, here sug- gest the question, whether the intuitive knowledge of animals leads them to examine the surrounding circumstances before acting, and to conform their instinctive actions to them before they have learned by exj^erience to do so ? Wliether, for instance, if a kid's first want is to walk to its mother's breast, and water intervenes, it will walk into it, or around it, or not walk at all ? That there is an adaptation of the intuitive knowledge of the modes of instinct- ive action to the peculiar wants of the animal is obvious from numerous facts already observed, as that a chicken will not go into water, while a duckling will immediately embrace the first oppor- tunity of doing so. NOTE XXIV. P. 119. Though this distinction can be conceived of and expressed in terms, it is yet so slight as to raise a doubt as to whether it prac- tically amounts to anything. The diiference in working from direct knowledge, or from the memory of that knowledge, may amount to nothing ; though working from a direct knowledge, or from memory of previous actions, conformed to that knowledge, may. NOTE XXV. P. 123. The influence of this saving of labor in the plan is evinced in the fact that when we have a plan ready formed, which may be APPENDIX. 437 worlr what we call the barbarous sports is not so much the result of that savage state in which the activities have full play in providing for personal defence or security and fir the absolute wants of life, as of that highly artificial condition of society in which larj:e portions of the community are overtasked in mere drudgery, and other large portions relieved from the necessity of laboring for physical existence, without the substitution of intellectual or moral objects of effort. It is only one phase of sensualism. The Eomans, supported in luxury by their slave? and their conquered provinces, with the love of the coarse and intense escit ment engendered in war, would, in times of repose, naturally resort to such exhibitions of effort, intensified to tlie sanguinary and violent. The rude Indian toi'tures his captive to increase his own security, or to re- venge the wrongs of himself or tribe, and not from that mere wan- tonness which is the product of a highly artificial and sensual con- dition of society. NOTE XXVII. P. 140. When the knowledge of means is intuitive, it is so closely asso« ciated with the want, that it is liable to be taken either for a part or for a necessary consequence of it, and thus the knowledge bo confounded with, or attributed to, the want. 438 APPENDIX. NOTE XXVIII. P. 147. Logic. — The knowledge of abstract truth does not necessarily produce any want. It may itself be the object of an eflfort, which may end in gratifying the want which induced it — the want for some particular knowledge (jr trutii. Hence, as a tcant is essential to voluntary action, a mere conviction of truth does not directly demand such action. A man does not will because he is convinced by demonstrative argument that the angles of a plane triangle are equal to two right angles. The fact may gratify a previous want to know, but does not of necessity awaken any new want. A pleasurable emotion attending the discovery of the fact, or the ex- ercise of his powers in making it, may induce a want for the repe- tition of such emotion, nnd corresponding efforts of the mind to produce it. A perception of some prospective application of such knowledge may also do this. So, too, if he is convinced that a certain act is right and proper, it does not influence his will, unless he icants to do what is right and proper. Touch his sensibilities by presenting to him distress, or so portraying it that in imagina- tion it becomes present ; enable him to participate in and to antici- pate the pleasurable emotions of relieving it, and a want to relieve is induced.* Hence it is that mere logical results, however high and holy the truths demonstrated, do not touch the springs of voluntary action. In following the demonstrative argument we but perceive the relations between the terms ; and before they influence effort, we must make an application of such results to actual existence and dwell upon the new relations evolved by the new results, till they take hold of our affections and assume some form of want. The logic which merely demonstrates, however clearly and forci- bly, the advantages of holiness, does not of itself move us to effort. * The high morality, the generosity of the act, in such cases, consist in his deriving pleasure from making others happy, or perhaps a higher morality, a purer disititerest- ertness are evinced in his yielding to an instinctive or innate want to relieve distrfpa \vii;h<>ut any conscious reference to himself, showing that he has not depraved his morel nature, but that its delicate sympathies make the suiferings of others his own ; and re- lieving it in others, ft relief or gratification to himself; while the man who seeks out occasions for the exercise of such beneficent feelings, shows that he has cultivated this Innate want and has come to want the occasions for exercising his generosity, or by vigi- lant examination to relieve himself even from the apprehension that tliere is some 83 yet undiscovered suffering requiring his action to relieve. APPENDIX. 439 For this t]iere must be a want, and to excite such want in onr moral nature, one magnanimous act, one exhibition of tenderness, one manifestation of self-sacrificing devotion to principle, one delineation of true, unselfish love, one image of a Eedeemer by pure and sublime ideas, so elevated above all vulgar passions and resentments as to look down with a divine love and compassion upon those who reviled and tortured Him, may be more efficacious than all the calculations of utility which selfishness has ever sug- gested, or all the verbal arguments, which human ingenuity has ever devised. Hence religion, though she may stoop to meet the attacks of the sceptical logician on liis own ground, has a more congenial ally in taste^ which, in the moral as well as in the physical, is often a precursor and incentive to want ; in the former generally applied to the more refined and cultivated wants of our spiritual being; and the propagandist finds in the beauties of eloquent expression ; in the graces, or the sublimity of poetry; in architectural gran- deur; in lifelike delineations of reality, or of ideal conceptions on canvas ; in sculptured marble, cold and inflexible as logic itself, but still embodying some lofty conception, or some form of beauty ; a more direct and ready emotive influence t'l arouse t':e soul with a sense of its own sublime nature and inspire it with devotional feeling, than it can command from the most towering and most successful efforts of the intellect to demonstrate, in terms, the loftiest problems of humanity. Even in the concord of evanescent sounds, the soul finds an analogy, a moulding or shadowing to the senses, of its own har- monious variety, of its own aspirations, swelling into ecstasy in eflTort and smoothly subsiding into the luxury of contemplative repose. All these manifestations of art may fitly introduce and induce a want for the development and cultivation of those pure and elevated sentiments of which they but give the first suggestive taste ; * and those who have consecrated the power of genius to * I trust that I shall not be suspected of intending lightly to use this word — taste — in a doable sense. To my mind there is a profound significance in such relations of a term as I have here attempted to shadow, showing how deep, in the roinmon reason of man, the roots of liis form of expression may lie; and suggesting that, even if a merely arbitrary term is used, it is gradually fitted and jostled, by this conimon reason, into hartuonlous relations with a whole range of ideas, with only one of which, in its first 440 APPENDIX. the service of ti-utli and virtiae, have ever been assigned a high place among the benefactors of their race, while those who per- vert it to make vice fascinating and seductive, are justly regarded as vilely treacherous to God and man. When, instead of the logical or prosaic mode of examining things by means of the relations of the terms by which we repre- sent those things, we look at the actual existences themselves as recoEfnized by the senses, or as made present to the mind by the exercise of its poetic powers, the things are present, or by a scenic illusion appear so, and, in either case, any fact or relation, which does not harmonize with our views or feelings, presents a want of change to the mind for its action. We may remark that, as it is mainly by means of these same poetic faculties that the future effect of an eftbrt in gratifying the want is made present, we here find the wants and the means of their gratification growing side by side in the same common soil. As before remarked, it is in the accuracy of the preconceptions of the future and a proper selection among them, that the mind manifests its ability in action ; and hence, the poetic faculty, not only by its power to examine the relation of things as they pri- marily and naturally exist, instead of the relation of the artificial terms by which those things are represented; but by its prophetic power of imagining, or conceiving of what does not yet exist, is really the basis of that common sense, which is so useful in the conduct of the atfaii s of life. He, who most clearly imagines, con- ceives, forese s ihe future, is, so far, best prepared to act wisely and sagaciously ; and, in this respect, the man who perceives has the advantage of him who reason^. The logician is proverb-ally liable to great mistakes in practical affairs, to exhibitions of a want of common sense ; but it is not so generally admitted that the poetic faculty corrects, or avoids the errors of the rea'^oning. It seems a desecration to put such noble endowments as our poetic and prophetic faculties to the vulgar, practical uses of daily life. It is taking the lightning from the skies to be the drudge of our workshops; but this is analogous to the influence of electricity, much diluted, in many of the most common and sluggish changes of matter. adaptation, it bad any perceptible affinity; thiit tbis common reason perceives and marks in expression those delicate similitudes of thought, which the reasoning of the philosopher is slow in developing APPENDIX. 441 NOTE XXIX. P. 149. I use the phrases " morally right " and " morally wrong," as applicable to the intelligent being that wills, and not to the good or evil effects of his action generally. Such effects may be injurious when the intentions were most beneficent and morally right and good. NOTE XXX. P. 150. OiST FORMING PeEOONOEPTIONS AND ACQUIRING IdEAS. The forming of a preconception preparatory to action is generally a tentative process; the mind noting what will be the effect of one plan of action, and then varying the plan to obviate some defect, or to ascertain if some other is not better. It may, however, some- times happen tliat the first plan so completely fulfils all the con- ditions required, that no further investigation seems necessary. When the same want has repeatedly existed under the same circumstances, the mind adopts a previous plan from memory and association and acts from habit, saving itself the labor of re- investigation. The investigation, by which the mind determines its preconception, is only one of the cases in which it applies the knowledge it already has to acquire other knowledge. In doing this, it adopts one of two modes. It may examine the facts pre- sented until it is enabled to determine the truth ; or, after a partial examination, it may form an hypothesis, which appears probable, or, at least, possible, and then examine whether such hypothesis is compatible with all the facts. In the former case, the mind does not seek to arrive at a particular idea, but to arrive at truth. In the latter, it seeks to ascertain whether the idea it has formed is true. If the object were merely to get a particular idea into the mind without reference to its fulfilling the conditions required in that idea, as, for instance, its being true, no effort for such object could be made ; for the idea must then be in the mind before the want of it could be determined, and the whole object of the effort would already be accomplished. The want of a particular, definite idea must be a want that is already gratified, and of course is no longer a want. No such want then can exist, and no effort found- ed on such want is possible. We may have an idea, which we perceive is incomplete and not well defined, and want and make 19* 442 APPENDIX. effort to complete it, or to define it more accurately, that is, to get a more full, or more clear and definite idea of the subject. The mind cannot seek a particular, definite idea, or a particular, de- finite preconception ; but it may seek an idea, or a preconception, which will fulfil certain conditions. A man may want to know what the truth is, without forming any definite idea as to what that truth is ; or having formed a definite idea of what it may be — an hypothesis — may want to know if his hypothesis corresponds with the truth. One, who can only count, will know that the product of 7 multiplied by 9 must be some particular number, as yet unknown to him. He wants to know, and, on a partial examination of the facts, he perceives that by the use of his knowledge of counting he can gratify this want to know the product of 7 by 9. He can count out seven piles, each containing nine pebbles ; or nine piles, each containing seven pebbles; and then, counting the whole, arrive at a result without having formed any previous hypothesis as to that result. Here, however, are two preconceptions of the mode to be pursued, making seven piles of nine, or nine piles of seven, so obviously equal, that no one could anticipate which another mind would adopt, or which would be first perceived. The man may, however, — say for the purpose of forming some idea of the number of pebbles required, — prefer to carry his pre- liminary examination farther. In doing this, he may bring in his knowledge that, in counting, he advances by tens and goes over seven of these divisions of ten each in arriving at seventy ; and hence infer that 7x9, being less than 7 x 10, must be less than seventy, and that sixty-nine pebbles will be sufficient; and, com- mencing now with this hypothesis, that sixty-nine may be the product of 7 X 9, he counts out sixty-nine and then makes the experiment to ascertain if he can get just seven piles, of nine each, out of sixty -nine ; and varies the number until he can do so. Though this is not one of them, there are cases in arithmetic and even in geometry, in which the best mode is to begin with an hypothesis and test its truth, or the degree of its variation ; and, in the aflfairs of life, it is generally prudent to test any plan or preconception, as we would a mere hypothesis. They admit of so great variety and the combinations are so numerous, that the application of general rules is not practically reliable. They more APPENDIX. iid nearly resemble the variety and combination of the chessboard, in which it is frequently necessary to consider each of several possible moves and compare the preconceptions of the effects which we perceive would result. It is not unusual to aid these preconceptions by actually changing the place of the piece as pro- posed, and thus get, by immediate perception, what, without such move, is but imagined, or conceived. Pei'sons sometimes, having a vivid conception of the object desired, act hastily to attain it, without having fully matured the plan of the successive efforts required ; and are liable to fail in consequence. Some requisite effort may not have been made at the right time, or in proper order, or may have been overlooked entirely. NOTE XXXI. P. 155. There is no selfishness surpassing that of those who, having through life used all their means to obtain for themselves as much as possible of this world, at the last moment seek, by some judi- cious investment, to make them still available to obtain as much as possible of the next. NOTE XXXII. P. 155. Perhaps these views show the metaphysical root of the theo- logical and popular discussions as to the influence of works. NOTE XXXIII. P. 158. These truths, vaguely existing in the popular mind, or applied with too much latitude, may have furnished a metaphysical origin for the doctrine of " perseverance " ; and the same views, applied to the extermination of the wants morally good, seenf to furnish a similar foundation for the belief that a finite moral being may sink to a condition of degradation from which he has no power to rise ; and from which nothing but a miraculous intervention of Divine power can elevate him. As above intimated, however, there seems to be good reason to suppose that these wants, especially those more elevated, are so rooted in our being, that they can be actually eradicated only with its annihilation ; that even in the lowest stages of depravity, the inferior wants may ever supply temptation and give occasion, on the one hand, for vicious action, or submissive indulgence ; and, on the other, for virtuous efibrt in 444 APPENDIX. resistance ; thus furnisliiug the means and inducement for atiU lower depths of debasement and for more hopeless habitual degra- dation ; and, at the same time, affording the opportunity for re- form, or for progress in virtue, to which all the higher aspirations of our nature will be incentives. To these, the Infinite Intelligence ever present and ever palpable in its effects ; and ever mediately, or immediately in communion with the finite, may add its Divine influence ; and even the aid of one finite being to another be not wholly unavailing in imparting knowledge and exhibiting moral beauty in action, and thus making it a want. NOTE XXXIV. P. 159. Intervals of such calm thought — of repose from the engross- ments and excitements of active temporal pursuits — have ever been deemed conducive to moral well-being, and, when occurring at stated times and places, and especially places set apart for this object, their influence may be enhanced by association and habit. We have stated times to gratify the want of food. NOTE XXXV. P. 165. Man, being constituted as he is, — being what our observatidn of his earliest existence shows him to be, — has the powers and faculties of a first cause. How he became such a being is not within the scope of our inquiry and is probably entirely beyond the reach of the human intellect. Our object is to show what he is, and what capable of, as he is, rather than how he came to be so. NOTE XXXVI. P. 171. I know a man, living on a very sterile tract, which to the most unremitted toil yields only a very meagre subsistence, but who, after considering a proposal of his friends to remove to a productive farm upon which much less labor would have given him abundance, said, " When I think how much work I have done on these gravel hills and stone walls, I cannot bear the thought of leaving them." He but expressed a common sentiment of man- kind, which is as potential in regard to the results of moral culture as of physical labor, and which has a specific influence in produc- ing consistent and persistent effort, and, of course, upon stability of character, giving to that which amidst adversity and temptation APPENDIX. 445 has been built up by effort, an additional advantage ovei- that which has resulted from opportune circumstances. NOTES TO BOOK II. NOTE XXXVII* P. 201. Edwards adds, in a note, " I say not only doing, but conducting^ because a voluntary forbearing to do, sitting still, keeping silence, &c., are instances of persons' conduct, about which liberty is ex- ercised, though they are not so properly called doing.'''' NOTE XXXYIII. P. 241. This assertion and the necessary connection of effect with cause make everything necessary ; for everything must be em- braced in what is necessary in itself, and what is not necessary in itself; and what is not necessary in itself must have a cause, and hence, as an effect of its cause, becomes necessary, so that what is necessary in itself and what is not, being both necessary, every- thing is necessary. NOTE XXXIX. P. 251. In the same way, there may be things relatively impossible to the finite intelligence, which impossibility, when perceived, pre- vents its efforts to do such things ; but when not perceived, has no such influence whatever, though the effort will stiU be unavailing and the expected effect will not follow it, NOTE XL. P. 255. It is, perhaps, worthy of remark that tho existence and the nature of a finite line are co-existing and self-existing truths (knowledge), which the mind perceives as the reasons of the deter- mination or end ; as the preconception which the mind forms of the effect of its action is rather a reason, which it perceives for the determination of its act of will, than a cause of it. * The foot note on p. 201 refers to Note I. ; it should read Note XXXVII. 446 APPENDIX. NOTE XLI. P. 278. The wise, the prudent, the industrious, especially do this;— the foolish, rash, and indolent decide by virtue of their absolute power 80 to do, without examination. Most men however, by experience, knowing its importance, do more or less examine, and the results of such examination form the reasons for further action or an addi- tion to those reasons, which were immediately obvious. NOTE XLII. P. 294. If it could be shown that cause, or power to produce change, could thus be extended in time, only in the case of matter in mo- tion, and that it, by the changes wliich it produced, called on the active powers of intelligence as a dormant powei-, which must wait such opportunity to become cause ; then, matter in motion would become essential to the activity of spirit, not merely as something to be acted upon, but to enable intelligence to begiu to act and to sustain its action even for-a single moment ; and, in such case, the existence of matter as a distinct entity would be demon- strated, as also, that it must have existed and been in motion from eternity. NOTE XLIII. P. 332. If, as some suppose, the mind has other faculties, as reason, im- aginatiim, judgment, &c., which act independently of the will, then, if such action influences the action of the mind, it is still the mind influencing itself. In the view which I liave presented in Book I., Chap, iii., these supposed faculties are but varied modes of effort, or effort for varied objects ; and any exercise of them bear- ing on subsequent acts of will are but preliminary acts of will, de- termining the final act, which would be the mind's determin- ing the final act by its own preliminary act. In tracing back the series of such acts, we must eventually come to an act which was induced by a want and directed by the mind's knowledge, in the form of an immediate perception of the means of gratifying it. Such immediate perceptions, in the first instance, must be, and in most subsequent cases probably are, of intuitive knowledge, but may be of knowledge acquired previously, or at the instant. The known fact, most frequently, thus perceived and applied to direct an action, is tljat the first effort must be to examine the circum- APPENDIX. 447 stances which, as before intimated, is probably intuitively known. The application of this note to other similar arguments, in which the " other faculties of the mind " are an element, will be obvious without reiterating it. NOTE XLIV. P. 345. In the relation of knowledge to acts of will, it i? not often ne- cessary to distinguish the innate from the intuitive, the important distinction generally being only between that which requires etfort to obtain it and that which does not. In Book I., Chap, xi,, I have argued that our knowledge that the mode of eifecting movement in our own being is by act of will, must be innate. NOTE XLV. P. 365. It is not intended to assert that this knowledge of the fact of uniformity in many cases, may not be intuitive as well as acquired. It is certainly not an idea of universal application, for there are many cases of a frequent recurrence of the same thing, to which , we never learn to apply it; and the intuitive knowledge of the fact tliat in some cases there is a certain uniformity of antecedents and consequences, might be only an innate faith, that God had in such cases established, and would maintain such uniformity, which would be very different from an intuitive conviction that such uni- formity must exist as a condition of metaphysical necessity. NOTE XLVI. P. 379. Though this may be expressed in terms, it does not seem cer- tain tliat any such case can be conceived of as practically arising. It cannot occur in regard to the mind in willing, for there is always the alternative of willing or not willing any action. If one body impinges directly against another, there must be some effect (aa the two bodies cannot occupy the same space, or one extension cannot possibly be two extensions) — non-effect^ in this case, involves contradiction ; but there are still various conceivable effects, no one of which has been ascertained to be the one necessary effect to the exclusion of the others. The observed effect does in fact vary very materially. It is true, it varies only with varied circum- stances, as hardness, inertia, momentum of the impinging body or bodies, &c. ; and then, in reference to these circumstances, with a 448 APPENDIX. uniformity wliich has been well ascertained. But, that this or any other uniformity is of metaphysical necessity, that no power could have made it otherwise, has not yet been demonstrated. NOTE XLYII. P. 386. I have here intended to give all the scope and weight to the positions of Edwards which could possibly be accorded to them. Nor do I perceive that the admissions here made require any ma- terial modification. It may, however, be observed that, in the views I have presented in Book 1., any intelligence may ivfluenee the volition of another by imparting knowledge ; but, as before shown, such influence is possible only because the volition of this other is free. This suggestion can have no place in Edwards's system, because he makes knowledge itself the volition, and we thus find that even this argument on the foreknowledge of God is obscured by the confounding of choice and will. If, however, a being has any intelligence of its own — any knowing sense — even its knowledge cannot be wholly controlled by extrinsic power. A man, with eyes to see and ears to hear, must of himself get some knowledge of the external, and with powers of thought must learn some relations of ideas, and cannot be made by extrinsic power to know or believe that 2 + 2=5. In virtue of his intelligence I;e is so far an independent power ; and though he may be indirectly in- fluenced by knowledge imparted to him, yet even in this he can- not be coerced or constrained. He may be convinced by skilful presentation of truth ; he may be deceived by ingenious falsehood ; and freely acting upon the knowledge thus acquired, his action may be different from what it would be if it had not been inculca- ted. "We may suppose the Supreme Intelligence to resort to the first mode, and by imparting truth influence the action of men, (.r, perhaps, justly withholding divine illumination, permit the pervei-se to believe a lie. The element of want seems to present another possible mode of influencing the human will These, as we have before observed, are in the first instance constitutional, and can be cultivated only through the medium of knowledge, which would bring this mode in the same class of influences as that of knowl- edge itself; and if the constitutional wants are themselves altered by a direct application of power, this would be to change one of the constitutional elements of the being ; and either to partially APPENDIX. 449 annihilate the being, or add to it by a new creation, making a dif- ferent being, another free agent, whose acts might, in virtue of being free, be different from those of the former agent. In none of these modes, then, can the wills of finite intelligent beings be directly controlled even by infinite power or infinite knowledge ; and the prescience of God furnishes no reason to suppose they can be thus controlled. NOTE XLYIII. P. 396. Without entering generally upon a subject for which T am wholly unprepared, I would here merely note the bearing which these views, and some others which I have before stated, appear to have upon the " Science of History." Such a science must have its basis either upon the idea that the events of the future are con- nected with those in the past, as effects dependent on antecedent causes which must produce such effects and no other ; or on the supposition that the Supreme Intelligence brings about results in conformity to certain uniform modes or laws which He has estab- lished ; by the exercise of His power either making all other effort as nought, or so combining the element of His own action with other causes that the composition of the forces will produce cer- tain uniform results, or at least results which may be anticipated. In regard to the idea that the events of the future are a neces- sary consequence of those in the past, our previous reasoning would go to show that, if we eliminate the mere mechanical effects which may result from matter in motion, there is no such connection, and that to produce any such requires the action of intelligent cause. The events of the past have no present existence. They may be remembered by an intelligent being, but such memories are but knowledge of the past, which, like any other knowledge, enables such being to direct its efforts upon the future intelligently. The whole influence of such past is, then, through the volition of an intelligent being. Excluding at any moment the mechanical effects of matter in motion, the whole future must depend on these voli- tions, and the events and circumstances which have already trans- pired have no more tendency to extend tlieraselves into the future than the wall, which the mason, by his own efforts, is raising brick by brick, has to build itself upward. The uniformity of the effects of matter in motion, whether aa 45C APPENDIX. necessary consequences of motion, or as uniform modes of God's action, is established, and furnishes a means of deteruiining from the past something of the future ; but this is limited to the mechan- ical conditions of the material universe, enabling us to anticipate the alternations of day and night and of the seasons — to foreknow the future positions of the planets, and thus to predict eclipses, transits, &c., and so far there is, and has long been, a Science of History. In regard to thus foreknowing the course of events, which, upon the principles I have stated, is the composite result of all intelli- gent activity, or of such results combined with the effects of mat- ter in motion as a distinct cause, grave difficulties present them- selves. If, as I have argued, God, as a necessity in providing for the existence of finite free agents, foregoes the use of His own power to control every event, and even forms no plan of particu- lars in the future, but is ever ready by His own action to modify the effects of the free and independent action of all other intelli- gent beings, then He not only does not foreknow the acts of these finite free agents, but He foregoes the prescience of His own actions, and the student who from past history should seek to deduce these particular future acts, either of the finite or Infinite Intelligence, would be seeking a knowledge which God has pro- scribed even to Himself. In any attempt to solve tlie problem of these particular future events, our data must involve the variable elements of innumerable free wills, each of which may be acted upon and affected by every other, leaving little hope of any solution as to the particular events of volition and their immediate consequences. If it be said that, amidst this almost infinite variety, God yet, by His paramount power, reconciles the diveis influences so as to bring about a har- monious result, in conformity to some design which He has pre- formed, still the particular elements of the combination, including lljs own agency in it, cannot be foreknown ; and in regard to those final or cyclical events, which make a part of this supposed pre- ordained plan, there is manifestly great difficulty. From examina- tion of the past we may learn s ch very general facts as that God is just, that He will punish iniquity, &c., &c., and hence draw very general conclusions as to His future action ; but this still gives APPENDIX. 451 little indication of the particular acts by which these ends will be reached, the time when, or even of the cyclical events by which His justice will be manifested, for there may be many events which so far as we can see, will equally answer the purpose. In this use of His power to do justice or punish iniquity we might expect, not a necessary repetition of former events, hut the exhibition of action reaching the same end, making perhaps historic parallels, of which the events now transpiring in our country, compared with those which attended the exodus of the Israelites, when the Egyptians were afflicted with plague after plague, till they were made willing to let the bondsman go free, seem to be a suiking illustration. Even in this case it is hardly conceivable that the events could have been inferred, with any particularity, from the past. Perhaps the nearest particular coincidence in this case is, that among those most mimediately implicated in the wrong of slavery, it is now asserted that there is hardly a family in which the strife has not brought a death, and then " there was not a house in which there was not one dead." The plague of the locusts devouring the pro- ducts of labor, is easily typified among either of the belligerents and perhaps the rod — the law intended to preserve peace and maintain order and justice — was cast down upon the 'ground and converted into a venomous reptile, in that opinion of our highest judicial tribunal in which it was asserted that, by our fundamental law, as originally intended by its framers, and as it must still be construed, a whole race of men and women had no rights which others were bound to respect. Verily, if such had become our settled principles, there was little reason to expect that the aveng- ing arm of Him whose ears are open to the moan and the prayer of the weak and the oppressed would long be stayed. Such events may indicate general rules or uniformity in God's action; as that the violence and injustice of a people shall react upon themselves, but still throws little light upon the particular modes by whicn the uniform results will be accomplished. Take for instance, as recorded, the most notable event of His special action since the creation of the world — the destruction of our race because of their sorruption. Even supposing that, on a recurrence of such corrup- tion, God would, as an act required by perfect justice, again depopulate the earth, He might still do it by other modes, as fire, 4:52 APPENDIX. famine, pestilence or war. So far, indeed., from our being able from the past to infer that the recurrence of such corruption would be followed by another destroying flood, we cannot even infer that destruction in any form would be resorted to. If there is no change in God, there may be such change in His creatures as will be to Him a reason for a different course of action. Once, among us, the scourge and the gallows were deemed the proper antidotes for depravity ; now milder means, with the school and the lyceum, are relied upon, and this change in our views — in our appreciation of means — may be a reason with God for adopting another mode in which He may correct moral evil by imparting more knowledge to the transgressors, and, in case of a resort to miracle, instead of flood or flame, increase the knowledge of our race, either by His own inmiediate revelations to all, or by inspir- ing e.ome portion to teach new and elevating truth ; or by sending a special agent with extraordinary or even miraculous power to perform this office. On the grounds I have before suggested, such resort to miracle can seldom if ever become a necessity. Among the prominent difficulties which, in the views I have presented, would appear to impede the Science of History, we have the great variety of events which may intervene between the great general results which mark the footsteps of the Deity in time, and which are perhaps required by His attributes ; the uncer- tainty as to the periods between such events ; and that there may be many such results which will fulfil the same intention. In a game of chess it may be pretty confidently predicted that a very skilful player will eventually checkmate one unskilled ; but through what particular moves, or how many of them, it will be done, no human being can prognosticate. If now we suppose that, instead of only one result, the object or end in view of the player is to produce either checkmate or stalemate, or some one of a thousand other conditions, the difficulty of foreknowing the final result is vastly increased. In chess the possible combinations are limited ; but by repetitions of them the moves possible in a single game are infinite. If we suppose the possible combinations of the position of the pieces to number a billion, then when a billion and one moves have been made we know that at least some one combi- nation has been repeated. If we assume an arbitrary limit to the APPENDIX. 453 number of moves in any game, tlien the variations which arise from changes in the order of the succession of the billion possible com- binations will also be limited ; and assuming this to be a trillion, we will know that when a trillion and one games have been played some one of the games has been an exact repetition of one of the others; but who would essay the task to tell, in the first case, what move, and in the second what game, had been repeated ; and yet the attempt to conceive or to state the greater difficulty in foreseeing the results of the acts of innumerable free agents would in itself be bewildering. This main difficulty, arising from the variable element of free volitions, may be thus stated : Excluding, as before, the mechani- cal eifects of matter in motion, the events of the past have no power to generate the future ; but that future is the result of in- telligent power manifested in efforts or acts of will. Intelligence? thus acting, is a cause which does not, on a repetition of the same circumstances, of necessity produce the same effect, or repeat its own action, but may, in such recurrence, try a new mode, produc- ing a different effect. The influence of this variable element of will is further complicated by each individual acting in reference to what he perceives others are doing, or are expected to do, so that the action even of the Supreme Intelligence may be modified by the action of inferior intelligences, down to the lowest in the scale, and may thus be influenced to elect one rather than another of divers cyclical events, any one of which will fulfil His main design. It must also be borne in mind that the object of every effort is to produce an effect in the future, and change that course of events which, but for such effort, would be established by the influence of other causes ; and that efforts which at the time ap- pear to be of little moment often lead to very important consequen- ces. These difficulties appear formidable, leaving little hope that the study of the history of the past will enable us to indicate even any great results by which God, in the exercise of His overruling power, at periods to us uncertain, corrects the aberrations pro- duced by finite efforts, and in the main conforms the course of events and the government of the world to His own attributes. On the other hand, there is encouragement for the prosecution of this lofty science in the fact that every being that wills must have 454 APPENDIX. some perception of the future in whicli there is at least sufficient probability of truth to be the foundation of its action, affording a hope that this prophetic power may be largely increased by study and cultivation. It must not, however, be overlooked, that the probability that the future will conform to our anticipations of it decreases so rapidly, as we increase the distance in time, that our prophetic vision can reach only a very little way into futurity. As favoring the pursuit of this science, I may also refer to the posi- tion which (in the test) I have just attempted to illustrate, that God m;iy govern the world and provide compensation for all the aberrations of finite wills without departing from general rules or uniform modes of action ; and to the previous positions, that, being perfect in wisdom, His actions, under the same circumstances, will be free from the mutations which attend the experimental efforts of less intelligent beings, and that even the imperfect wisdom of finite free agents leads to a partial uniformity in the actions of the individual, while similarity in the natural wants and intuitive knowledge, and identity in the absolute truths from which we de- rive our acquired knowledge, tend to produce a corresponding similarity in the actions of different individuals. These tenden- cies to uniformity encourage the hope that some law or mode of God's action, analogous to that which assures the stability of the material universe, may, within certain limits, regulate the succession of events in the moral. We may also note, that thotigh, in some aspects, the ability which each one has to influence the action of others complicates and obscures the future, in another view it aids us to anticipate it. Our power to influence a future event is so far a power to foreknow it. When the efforts of a large number of persons are directed to the same end, the probability that this end •will be accomplished is increased. When these efforts are intend- ed to influence the volition of numerous individuals, though no one can foreknow the eftect upon any particular one of them, the probabilities are that, for reasons just stated, a large number will be similarly influenced, and, if the efforts have been wisely directed, that the desired result will be reached. In individual action each adopts the mode which his own knowledge, derived in great meas- ure from past experience, suggests. This leads to diversity of action ; and combined action requires a common reason, or at least a common APPENDIX. '155 ground for action, and this can often be found in that common or general experience of which history is the record. Hence the ob- vious application of this science to the enacting of public laws. In those efforts by which we do our part in creating the future, what we most immediately and pressingly want to know is, what next to do, and the farther we can clearly trace the consequences of our efforts, the better are we prepared to decide what to do. It is evident, however, that in tracing out the consequences of an action in all its subsequent ramifications, the problem as to what is best to be done soon becomes so complicated that the time for action would pass before we could thus decide what to do. It seems, however, at least probable, that the more systematic study of the past may enable us better to perform our parts in cre- ating the proxima'e future, may expand our knowledge of the ways of God, and increase our faith in His attributes, and at the same time lead us to some very generic ideas of the modes in which He manifests these attributes in His government of the world ; and these are objects well worthy of our highest efforts. In nearly all our efforts to acquire knowledge, our aim is to find out God's ways, and read His character in His works. The ideas above alluded to, and inculcated in various parts of this work, that in our humblest efforts we are co-workers with God, taking part with Him in the creation of tlie future, and that our ways change His ways, may to some appear irreverent, and even arrogant, but they seem to me to furnish the only rational ground for hope in effort, or trust in prayer, and that by exclud- ing them we would make our noblest efforts and holiest aspira- tions the merest mockery. However hallowing and consoling the reflex influences of devout prayer may be, the belief in a system which would exclude us from all influence upon the future, either by our own direct efforts or by petition to the Sovereign power, making us but the subjects of a rigid and inexorable despotism. Would degrade humanity and involve all the evils of fatalism. ANALYSIS OF CONTENTS. BOOK I. FREEDOM OF MIND IN WILLING. pAoa CHAPTER I. — Of the Existence of Spibit, . 1 Postulates of the argument — Knowledge, thought, sensation, emotion, want and effort recognized as in one combination ; one mind — Each of such combina- tions, associated with a particular form, constitutes what each denominates I —Idea of form not essential to our idea of spirit, or intelligent being — Certain sensations, which we can and do ourselves produce ; some of the same kind, which we know that we do not produce, and, attributing to others, get the idea o./ other finite minds ; and others, which we cannot produce ; and thus get the idea of Superior Power — This power really infinite, or to us the same as If it ■were so — We thus come to know ourselves, our fellow beings, and God, as Cause. CHAPTER II.— Of the Existence of Matter, ...... 6 We know of it only by our sensations— Sensations not conclusive proof of its existence— Sensations may be the thought and imagery of the mind of God drectly imparled to us — In either case they represent His thought, and are equal- ly real — That they are thought and imagery directly imparted to us, the more simple hypothesis, and more in accordance with our own conscious powers — Matter not necessary for Spirit to act upon— This illustrated by geometrical science— To ignore matter would simplify tbe question of freedom of the mind and make creation more intelligible — Not suiHcient proof to warrant this course ; but, in either case, the phenomena are the same, and matter is unin- telligent and inert. CHAPTER III.— Of Mind, Its attributes and its faculty of "Will — Its sensations and emotions not de- pendent on its will — Its knowledge also not so dependent — But act of will may be essential to the acquisition of knowledge— Feeling a property, or suscepti- bility, rather than a faculty — Ability to acquire knowledge a capacity, or sense, tttther than a faculty — Object of act of will always is to produce some effect in 458 ANALYSIS OF CONTENTS. PAGE the future — Supposed faculties of mind, other than will, all but nas es of some form of knowledge, or of some mode of effort to acquire it — All knowledge, in the lat^t analysis, a simple mental perception — Objection, that these supposed faculties sometimes seem to act of themselves, considered — Dednition of knowledge and of metaphysical certainty. CHAPTER IV.— Liberty, ok Fbeedom, .19 Opposing terms, compulsion, control, constraint, and restraint — That which controls its own action, acts freely. CHAPTER v.— Of Cause, . . . . . . 21 Cause used as that which produces change — Four distinct conceivable kinds enumerated — Two of them material, and two intelligent. CHAPTER VI.— Of the Will, 24 Confusion in treating will as a distinct, active entity — Will defined as the power or faculty of the mind for effort — Mind cannot be Inert cause — Mind has two distinct spheres for its activity ; in one, it seeks to learn what is, and in the other to influence the course of events in the future — These connected b}' the mind's prophetic power. CHAPTER VII.— Of Want, 27 The term want used to express the conscious condition of the mind, and not the thi: g wan;ed — A mere sensation, or emotion, or its absence, is not in itself a want — The idea of change an essential element of want — Primary and secondary wants — Natural, acquired, and cultivated wants — Natural wants not the result of vol tio,; — Acquired want results from some increase of knowledge —Influence of want on will not varied by the cause of it. CHAPTER Vlli.— Of Matter as Cause, 32 All changes in matter must arise from motion in it — Cannot move itself, and hence cannot be cause, except by first being in motion — Can it thus be- come cause? If so, as it may have been in motion from eternity, may always have been cause — Other quest' ons upon which this depends— If motion gives it causative power, that power is dimi ished in producing effects ; and hence, in an eternity, must be reduced to an infinitesimal — Matter in motion subject- ed to intelligent control — Matter cannot be made cause by impressing laws upon it — Matter an instrument, a means, by which one intelligence communi- cates with, or produces effects upon another — If matter be cause, its effects cannot affect the freedom of the mind in willing, any more than the effects of intelligent causes can — Action of mind on matter — Independent action of matter. CHAPTER IX.— Of Spirit as Cause, 42 Spirt is an indispensable, if not the only cause — Relations of the finite to the Supreme Intelligence, as cause — Creative powers of the finite mind of man B'miUir t'l ihos.' of the Infinite — Man has no faculty by which he can create, or even co ceive of the creation of matter as a distinct entity, and there is no necuesit.N , or reason to suppose that God has — The human m'nd, within the ANALYSIS OF CONTENTS. 459 PAOG sphere of its knowledge, with a coordinate finite presence, is creative — Its in- cipient creations are conceptions of its own mind — Its creative power exerted In the same manner as that of the Infinite — Creative power of man may be secondary in its character — That is, moulds its coiiccptioiie in the same mate- rial which God has previously used for a lilje purpose — Our own ideal concep- tions distinguishable from the external creation only by their subjection to our will— God's conceptions, or creations, also subject to change or annihilation by His will — Man's limited power to transfer the conceptions of his own to other minds — Finite mind can create not only new forms and new combinations, but new thought and new beauty. CHAPTER X.— Freedom of Intelligence, 61 The question should be, not,/s the icill free t but. Does the mind will freely? — The willing distinct from its sequence or efteet— Connection between volition and its effect — Intelligence must have an object for acting, rather than not act- ing—This object must be an effect which it wdTiis to produce ; must arise from a viant — With this wane must be associated knowledge of the means of its graU iflcation — Action different under different circumstances, and the first step must be to examine, or to ascertain the circumstances, and this fact is probably intuitively known — Want and knowledge the source in which volitions origi- nate and receive their direction — Sources of volition resolvable into an active being with knowledge and want- Want and knowledge may be without voli- tion — A want may itself be the object wanted — We do not make, but find knowledge; and for intuitive knowledge do not have to seek — Deliberation necessary in applying acquired knowledge — Without the knowledge of a choice in meai.s, the first perceived would be adopted — Experience teaches delibera- tion — Delibcrat!o i still but tlie application of knowledge to action — Delibera- tion is the considered application of knowledge, leading t-o a judgment — Time devoted to it de;ided by the mind — Mind can arrest its impulse to gratify its want by the first perceived means, to consider its proposed action — This power makes one distinct'on between instinctive and rational actions — We do not make any effort for what already is — Every effort is a beginning to do, and is an exercise of creative power — Finite mind has creative powers, and capacity to use them — Circumstances, examination of which is essential to proper ef- fort — We never will to do what we know we cannot do — Mind does not always adopt the easiest mode of attaining the ultimate object of its effort — Illustra- tion from the want of food — Efforts must be in a certain order, otherwise abor five — Effects of a series of finite efforts as clearly manifest desgn as the plan etary system — Deliberation illustrated — We do not will as to what is past, but to produce some efteet in the future — Mind forms preconceptions of this future effect of effort — To will requires a prophetic view of the future, making a broad distinction between intelligent and unintelligent cause — The mind's pro- plietic power ttis it for a. first came — The mind must determine what change it will try to produce — For this, if want aiid knowledge were not fixed and in- dependent of will, the data would be insufflcent — If want and knowledge not fixed, the mind must form hypothesis to act upon — No power, ignorant of the want and th« perceptions of the agent, could determine the will of that agent —That want and knowledge are not subject to the will, facilitates the mind in the exercise of its freedom in willing — Whether the mind's preconceptions aro leal'.zed by its own power, not material to the question of its freedom in will- 460 ANALYSIS OF CONTENTS. PAQI Ing— Finite mind exerts 'ts ■jreative power in same manner as the Intin'te — Each, respectively, subject to its own conditions — Conflicting wants and wants jf activity and repose (note)— Supposed commencement of creation— A creative God must make effort — Intelligence a cause, which produces various efiects— Another step in creation supposed — Every creative act a heginning of a new ^realion — Supreme Intelligence acting with coexisting blind cau-os — Acting ilso with coexisting intelligent causes — In either case, must will freely — Amount of its power makes uo ditference to the freedom of intelligent being in willing — Nor does the amount of its knowledge — Hence, the finite intelli- gence may be as free as the Infinite — One Intelligence may shape circum- stances to influence the will of another, which may be ellective if that other acts freely — The period of creation at which the finite mind begins to act does not affect its freedom — Every act of will the same, in some respects, as a first act^Is the finite mind, in willing, controlled by any other power? — Conceiva- ble modes of external control — These modes considered — Influence of other intelligences — Influence of circumstances — If mind wills at all, it must will freely — Same result more concisely reached through the logical relation of terms. CHAPTER XL— Instinct and Habit, \» The sphere of liberty varies in different orders of intelligence — Each equal- ly free in its own sphere of knowledge — Matter has no such sphere, and hence, if it had the essential attributes, could manifest no freedom — Being, with sen- Bation, but no want, could not will — Knowledge, to be available for willing, must extend to the future — The lowest order of intelligence, admitting of will, is that with one want and one known means of gratifying it, and this intuitive — Instinctive action still voluntary and free — And free, not merely as not coun- teracted — In the instinctive, the spheres of knowledge and freedom reach their minimum, but are still coexistent — But for the element of knowledge, instinct- ive action would be mechanical — Conceivable that first instinctive actions may be mechanical — Knowledge that we can will, and how to will, and that by will we can produce change in ourselves, could not be taught by practical exam- ples, but must be intuitive — Hence, not mechanical— All tlie requisites of will incorporated in our being— Instinct may bring the infant within easy effort of its object — Absence of deliberatioa in intuitive action — Muscular action the basis of our plans for external change — Bodily movement always instinctive — This is the point from which instinctive and rational actions take their depart- ure—In the instinctive, not only the mode of making the action, but the plan, the successive order of volitions, is intuitively known — Inferior free agents may still subserve the purposes of a superior — Conflicting modes and wants are cases for the exercise of judgment— Imitative actions diverging from instinct- ive — Distinguishing features of instinctive actiim — Some cases of rational ac- tion liable to be confounded w.th instinctive — When we are conscious of form- ing a plan of action this does not occur — "When we work from memory of a plan, intuitive or acquired, it is habit— Peculiar characteristics of habit — Sim- ilarity of instinctive and habitual action — Analogy of habitual to mechanical action — Rational act'on?, in becoming habitual, approach the instinctive — Cus- tomary actions belong to the same group — Recapitulation of actions, mechan- oal, instinctive, rational, customary, and habitual — Habit has same relation to ANALYSIS OF CONTENTS. 4G1 PAOH astion tliat memory hfiB to knowledge, and depends on memory and associa- tion — ^Tliat habit applies to actions which we have most frequent occasion to perform, increases its benefits, yet often regarded as a vice of the mind— Rea- sons why It id so regarded. CHAPTER XII.— Illustration from Chess, . . . ,126 Known laws of the game somewhat analogous to intuitive knowledge — First moves may be habitual— Subsequently the player deliberately forms precoii oeptions and compares them — Does not examine every possible move, but de- termines how long to examine by an exercise of judgment — Each volit'on to move the same as if ho had never before moved — A mor-'^ complicated gtime supposed, more nearly resemblingthat of reaMife — The skilful succeed against many opponents ; and Infinite Wisdom would accomplish Its end though op- posed by any number of finite intelligences, all acting as freely as itself— The uninitiated see no order or design in the game — It is a creation having its own laws — Automaton chess-player— But for the uniformity of God's actions, the efforts of finite agents would be imijossible — Case in which, by the laws of the game, only one move is possible, and analogous cases in real life — Compliance with the laws of the game, as with the laws of Cod, may become habitual, but this does not conflict with freedom — Influence of law on individual action — The word law, in such cases, used in two distinct senses, but the knowledge of the law, In either sense, important in deciding our efforts. CHAPTER XIII. — Of Want and Effort in Various Orders of Intelli- gence, 13?. Want requisite to all but t1ie lowest forms of animated existence- Imputa- tion of want to the Supreme Being — A sole flrstcause, without want, would im- mediately become inert — Intelligence must have a ret lining power and some adaptation to put its retained power in action — If matter is cause, no applica- tion of a self-moving power to it is possible — If the activity of any intelligence ceases, it cannot put itself in action again — No intelligent being can do any- thing unless it makes effort to do something — Want rouses the mind to effort, but does not direct the effort — Effort the condition of cause in the Infinite as in the finite being — Some cause with power to produce change, which it does n"*. of necessity immediately exert, is necessary— Mind and matter in motion the only such causes conceivable — The existence of God can:iot, of itself, be the cause of anything which ever began to be— Eftbrt makes the distinction be- tween that condition of a being in which it seeks to produce change and that in which it does not — If in the Supreme Being there is no such distinction, all effects must be independent of His action — Reasons why it is tliought Omnipo- teiiCe may produce effects without effort — Omnipotence has its bound in the absolutely impossible — Want has with it the germ of its own gratification — Man may design change, and make effort to actualize his design, though no other intelligence or power in existence — The mode of connection between vo- litiiins and their sequences not important to the act of will, CHAPTER XIV.— Of Effort for Internal Change, 145 Question stated — Do we produce the sequences of volition? — The important fact is. that our volitions are necessary to fhexw— Effects of efibrt for internal 462 ANALYSIS OF CONTENTS. PAoa change as uniform and as inscrutible as for external — We can induce spiritual ay well as physical want, but cannot directly will either into existence— Increas- ing our knowledge the only means for this, and, though it may sometimes have the opposite effect, Is still the only mode^Constitutional occurrence and recur- rence of our spiritual wants — Want the source of effort for internal changes in all intelligent beings— General moral evil and individual depravity — Man's knowledge infallible as to what, for him, is morally right— Directs his efforts for internal change by means of his preconceptions — In forming these, need not recognize existing circnmstances — An advantage of the purely ideal concep- tions — In the moral nature the willing is the consummation, and hence, i-n it, mind is a supreme creative first cause — Distinction between effort in the moral sphere and out of it — A man who does not want to be pure and noble may be- gin with the want to want to be pure and noble — Virtue all lies in the effort, and not in its sequence — Not any present moral wrong in want, or knowledge, and hence all moral right and wrong concentrated in the act of will — Efforts to bo pure and noble may become habitual— We may indirectly discard a want — A being with no want for what is unholy cannot be unholy — Cannot will what is contradictory to its own nature — Though many of our moral wants are in- nate, they may be cultivated, enabling us to influence our moi'al characteristics at their source — Conclusion from the foregoing, that man in the sphei'e of his moral nature is a supreme and a sole creative first cause — Man's will inOnite, but limited in its range, because his power of conception is finite — This power may forever increase — Man responsible and accountable for his acts of will. CHAPTER XV.— Conclusion, 161 Recapjtulaticm of the previous results and leading positions — Wants seem- ingly insignificant may be the basis of contests for the mastery of empires — Man bountifully provided with wants^Physical wants temporary — Made less inconstant by the secondary want of acquisition — They are preliminary to the soul's progress, teaching effort ; though this provision is often counteracted by acquisitiveness with a material bias — Spiritual want essential— Early ideal constructions and influence of the romantic passion — " Castle building" — The interest which attaches to the products of our labor — Influence of wants not left to accidental occurrences — Recurrence of both spiritual and bodily wants amply provided for — Each has within hina-self an inchoate and, to him, a boundless universe, which is his especial sphere of creative action — Construct- ing this universe within himself the principal, if not the sole end of life. BOOK 11. EEVIEW OF EDWARDS ON THE WILL. Introduction, 173 CHAPTER I.— Edwards's Definition of Will, ,177 Edwards's definition of will— He identifies volition with choice and prefer- ince, and willing with cbuoiing and preferring — His definition admits of vari- ANALYSIS OF CONTENTS. 463 PAQIS cua constructions— Confounds the process of choosing with the result ot th« process — ^Also asserts that aa act of choice is a comparative act of the mind — Proof that the comparative act is not itself the act of choice, and that the choice, which in some cases is the result of a comparative act, is not an act of ■wiU, but is knowledge— The choice to will preceding the act of will considertd — Edwards's deiinitions of choice as an act of will, and also as the result of a comparative act, involve an absurdity— In making choice an act of will, he makes it the last act of the mind in relation to the effect intended — Cases mt«itioned by Edwards in which the soul would rather have or do distinguish- able, and the question whether choice is ever an act of will, examined— Ed- wards's use of the word choice confounds the understanding with the will — Further proof that choice is knowledge, and not act of will — Sophism admitted by making choice a synonym for will — Difficulties encountered by Edwards, growing out of his definition — Difference in a man's preferring to walk and preferring to fly— Edwards constrained to admit exertion, but having no space between choice and effect, must crowd it into one or the other — My views ap- plied to explain the difference of the cases of preferring to walk and preferring to fly — Edwards's intention to use the word choice in its popular sense — Reca- pitulation. CHAPTER II.— Liberty as Defined by Edwards, . , , , .201 Edwards asserts that the only liberty in man is power " to cio as he pleases," or " conducting as he wills" — This places liberty in that in the doing of which we are not conscious of having any agency — In this case the mind has no liberty in willing, and the definition begs the question — The hypothesis that the will- ing is itself a doing considered. CHAPTER III.— Natural and Moral Kboessitt, , . . . .204 Edwards's definitions of these terms — Much confusion from vague use of some of the terms— Every intelligent being with will a distinct cause — Hence our will cannot change the course of nature, except by being an independent cause — God's action or the counter-willing of finite minds may, either of them, control or influence the effect intended by another, without interfering with the freedom of that other in willing— The argument is rather against the free- dom of man in doing than in wtVimo-— Edwards's definition admits three dis- tinct Intelligent causes, each acting freely — The term "■necessity'''' used in dif- ferent senses in defining natural and moral necessity — Edwards makes " mo- tive" a cause, producing volition, or makes human volitions the direct action of God — The argument from these definitions stated — The hypothesis, that the same causes of necessity produce the same effects, essen'.ial to it — It assumes that human volitions are a part of a necessary chain of events — Yet asserts that the mind encounters diffisulties in bringing them to pass — The assump- tion that the human will is finite shown to be an error, and especially if it is " cAozce"— Supposed difficulty in willing examined, and found not to be in the willing, but in finding or knowing what to will — The martyr and the craven equally free in willing — Difference in action indicates difference in character — Modes in which we form our own characters and aid each other in doing it — The difficulty spoken of by Edwards consists in the conflict between present pleasure, and right or future good— That a man may will against such convic- 464 ANALYSIS OP CONTENTS. PAO> Mons may prove that he is not pure and wise, but not that he is not free — The particular cases of moral inability stated by Edwards — Examination of those cases— All analogous to those of inability to will, because there is no want — In- ability to will what we do not want to will is not against freedom — No reason to suppose that a /)ret;jo2is bias or inclination will prevail over the present in the act of will— If it does, it is because the biased or inclined mind itself con- trols the act of will — As in the case of "nature of things," Edwards makes "habit" a power, or cause — ISTo certainty and no necessity that habits will continue — Habits of a man influence his act of will only in case he wills freely — Man is said to be a slave to his habits ; reasons why — The argument from moral necessity only proves that a man wills in conformity to what he wills, and natural necessity only implies that he cannot always execute what he wills. CHAPTER IV.— Self-Detekmination, 233 The argument against the self-determining power of the will irrelevant to my position — Edwards's statement of his argument against the soul's deter- mining its volitions in the exercise of its power of willing— From which it can only be inferred, that whatever is true of acts of will is true of acts of choice — Changing the word"«re" to "Jy" vitiates the argument — Confusion from using clioice as the process of choos'ng, and also as the result of the process, and "mind " and " will" as equivalents — Edwards does not recognize mind as cause — There must be something to move the mind, as it does not act without a reason— Edwards finds this prime mover in his "motives ;" I have ascribed it to "want" — Control, by a previous act of will, fatal to freedom in the pres- ent act — Edwards's favorite reductio ad absurdum that a self-determined or free act admits of no first free act, fallacious. CHAPTER v.— No Event without a Cause, 24C Edwards says he applies the word cause to what has no positive influence — This facilitates his proof, but makes it unavailing for his purpose— Edwards's positions being admitted, if mind is itself cause, they prove its freedom in will- ing — He assumes that the cause of a volition must be not only without the vo- lition, but without the mind that wills — If the act of mind, as cause, must have a cause, for tlie reason that everything which beg'ns to be must have a cause, there can be no first act of cause — The soul itself, being the cause of its voli- tions, is not, in them, the subject of effects which have no cause — The question why the soul exerts such an act and not another considered — Examination of Edwards's position that " activity of nature " cannot be the cause why the mind's action is thus and thus determined — This argument also vitiated by cliano-ing in to bt/, or by assuming that of two terms expressii^g the same thing one is the cause of the other — Volition cannot be determined by the "past." CHAPTER VI.— Of the Will's Determining in Things Indifferent, . 259 Edwards's statement of the question imperfect, though warranted by ex- tracts from his opponents — As he .states it, one thing is indiflferent, and anotlier chooses — Other of his arguments founded on h's assumption that will and choice are Identical — His use of the phrase " determining power" ambiguous, applying either to mind or will — Another stateme.it of the argument — Ed- ANALYSIS OF CONTENTS. 46^ PAQIi wards supposes the mind to devise a way of getting itself out of a state of in- diflference, and illustnites by the touching of one of the squares of a chess board — His argument denies tliat the mind can get itself out of a state of indif- ference, yet begins by showing how it can do so — Mind's doing, indirectly by volition, what it cannot do directly, is nor- against its freedom — In this case such indirection (the giving itself up to accident) does not obviate the suppos- ed difl&culty, but increases it — Just as diiScultfor the mind to determine what accident as wliat square of the chess board — Edv/ards might as well have made the movement of the finger as the movement of the eye determine the square to be touched — In either ca»e, the diiBculty of indiflterence may recur — There is the same difficulty of indifference in applying the accident, even if it can be selected — The whole causal etBcacy must be, not in the accident, but in the rule which the mind makes to apply it, in doing which it again encounters indifference— The mind can as well make the rule to touch a particular square without the accident as with it — The whole efficacy of the proposed plan is in the mmiVs governiTig itself by an arbitrary rule which itself has created — The indirection would not aid the argument for necessity, but these supposed cases of indifference militate against it — If choice, among the objects of effort, is essential to will, a man never could will if there was only one object — Not necessary to an act of will that we should select, or choose even, among objects which we know to be different — The bearing of the views elicited in Book I. on this question — Similarity of cases of indifference and those of icanting to will— The apparent analogy of Edwards's mode of deciding them to that of de- ciding between parties having equal claims — But this would as well be accom- plished by a direct act of will — If decided by lot, or accident, an arbitrary rule must still be made — Analogy of the cases of indifference to matter kept at rest by equal counter forces. CHAPTER VIL— Relation of Indifference to Ebeedom in Willing, . 29A Edwards uses the term indifference as directly opposed to preference — His argument against the soul's sovereign power in certain cases, only proves that if the soul wills when it does not will, then its willing is not wholly owiiig to itself — Much confusion from using the term inclination as identical with will, and yet as something which goes before it — Another of his arguments only proves that the mind is not free in wiU'ng when it is not willing at all— And this and the subsequent reasoning only proves that the mind cannot both will and not will at the same time — His statement that a yVee act of will cannot immediately arise out of a state of indifference, considered — He assumes that choice is a necessary element of free will — Argument thus far avails only on certain inadmissible premises, and has little application to my positions — For the purposes of this argument, Edwards's assumption that choice is a pre- requisite of a free act of wiU may be admitted — Form in which this admission may be most plausibly used against freedom — The essential element of free ac- tion is not choice, but self-direction — Suspending volition — Edwards assumes that suspending volition must be an act of volition — If so, the mind never can stop willing, for suspending its willing is only another willing — Even then the mind could suspend action in one direction by acting in another — And liberty in every action might still be maintained — What is meant by suspending an act of wiU — Illustrations from reading aloud —Do we will either to will or not 466 ANALYSIS OF CONTENTS. PAoa to will ? — Ifearest appro:ioh to willing to will is wlieK we want exercise for the faculty of will and act capriciously— Iiidifteronce indicates the point of depart- ure from the pass ve to the active state ; perfect in the non-active state of pro- found sleep — Vigilance of the mind as to changes alsout it which may call for eSbrt— Eflort to find what changes are taking place, or what action these changes require, is attention — To know these changes does not always re- quire effort — Changes often occurring aiid requiring no action, as the striking of a clock, are immediately forgotten — Reason why monotonous sounds favor reverie and the concentration of the mind in abstract thought. CHAPTER VIIL— CoNTiNGBNCE, 3il3 Treated by Edwards in Part II., sections 8 and 9 — If mind is the cause of its acts of will, then Edwards's argument only proves that they are necessarily connected with mind, and not that mind is not free — Edwards absurdly argues that the mind is not free in the act cf willing, because the act of wiU is connect- ed wi'th the mind — His argument also involves the contradiction that mind is not free, because it cannot be otherwise than free — In chapter xiii. applies sim- ilar reasoning to prove that if the will controls itself it cannot be free, because controlled by itself — Fallacy of this and preceding argument — From the posi- tion that every effect is dependent on its cause, Edwards infers, not that the effect, but that the action of the cause is necessitated— Necessary futility of reasoning on his statement, which really only asserts that a man wills what he wills — The hypothesis that there are other mental faculties which influence the will considered in its relation to the mind's freedom in willing — Edwards's artcument denies the possibility of this ; but with more reason it might be said that all cause is of necessity free — Even matter in motion is not constrained or restrained till it comes to the producing of an effect — Any force or power sub- ject to extrinsic control is an implement rather than a cause — Essential difl'er- ence in the freedom of intelligent and material causes. CHAPTER IX. — Connection op the Will with the Understanding, . 328 Sometimes the last dictate is neither an act of will nor followed by an act of will— If will is choice, it never follows the last dictate of the understanding— If it does, still not against the mind's freedom or self-determining power in willing — Edwards attempts to prove that the will, as a distinct entity, is not xree — Act of will not always necessary to the mind's attention — Mind may be- gin by an effort to obtain the requisite knowledge, or may direct its action by a simple perception of it — Edwards's position in regard to the will's following the last dictate of the understanding really confirms the freedom of mind in vvilling. CHAPTER X.-MoTivE, . 327 Statement of Edwards's argument on motive — Varies his definition of will to accommodate the argument— His argument, even admitting his definition of will, is still fallacious— Mis definition of m jtive amounts only to "that which is a motive is a motive" — As impossible to deduce any new truth from such definition as from the expression " whatever is, is " — The argument, as he states it, does not contravene that of his opponents — The difficulty is radical, arising from defining motive not by what it is, but by what it must do — To ANALYSIS OF CONTENTS. 467 PAGE coiiform to tho defluition and admit the dedLC.Iou uf necessity, the motive must control the mind — The motive cannot itself determine that it is the strongest — This must be done hy the intelligent being that wills — His positions involve an infinite series with no beginning — Tiiat the mind has in itself, or its own view, a motive, no reason why it does not act freely — Whether motives prove necessity or freedom must depend on their character or influence — Ed- wards uses " motive" sometimes as meaning the mitid^s mew of an object, ai:d at others the object viewed — The assertion that the mind is governed by its own views afllrms its freedom— The point that, if the mind determines itself by its own view, the object viewed is still essentia, to that view, considered — The ex- istence of objects of choice cannot be a reason why the mind does not will free- ly — Freedom does not imply a power to malie existing circumstances difi"erent from what they are at tlie time — Classifioaliou of objects, which may possibly be motives, uader Edwards's d ;finition — These considered in their order — Vague popular notions in regard to the inSuenoe of circumstances — Particular cases, as stated by Edwards, make motive the mind's view of the future effects of its own action— Inquiry as to the meaning of "previous tendency"— The ar- gument again leads to an infinite series, and makes the act of (will) choice be- fore that by which the mind chooses has acted — In Edwards's system, motive, or previous tendency of motive, must be an act of choice springing directly out of a state of indifterence— Same difliculty in regard to motive which Edwards finds in regard to will— This difficulty attaches to every system which does not recognize a self moving power or cause. CHAPTER XI.— Cause and Effect, ... .... 36* Tlie argument of Edwards assumes that the same causes of necessity pro- duce the same effects— If the same cause never acted twice there could be no applicat'on of the rule— The law is deduced from observation, and cannot be of metaphysical necessity — No reason to suppose the law goes farther than our observatio.. 8 indicate — That there is no general rule without exceptions, con- flicts with it — No reason to suppose that God may not vary from any law of uniformity which he has established for His own government— That He is om- niscient obviates the necessiti/ of trying different modes — In mind, observation does not indicate any such law — To all appearance, different minds act differ- ently, and even the same mind changes its mode in similar circumstances — No case can arise for the application of the rule to mind — Under such rule a sole First Cause never could have produced but one effect— The application of this rule to intelligent cause denies any continuing power to produce changes in the universe — As applied to God, the rule can only mean that He has adopted uni- form rules for His government — The finite mind, after having tried one mode, may, upon the recurrence of the same circumstances, try another — As used by Edwards, the law of cause and effect involves an infinite series with no begin- ning of action— -There must be some cause which has power to change itself as cause, or to vary its effects — Changes in matter must be referred to an intelli- gent will — Some things may have been made not uniform, to vary the prob- lems of life, for the development of the finite intelligence — No difliculty in sup- posing that the finite mind maybe f first or originating cause — If mind is cause, tho necessity of volition as its effect does not prove that mind is not free — The uniformity of God's action is necessary to and argues the existence of 468 ANALYSIS OF CONTENTS. PAoa finite free agents — The argument that, if the same circumstances oocnr a thousand times to mind in the same condition, its action will be the same, ex- amined. CHAPTT^R XII.— GoD'3 Foreknowledge, 384 Edwards argues that the acts of the will must he necessary, because God foreknows them — Unavailing reply to this — An event foreknown by infallible prescience must be as certain in the future as if known by infallible memory in the past, and GoA^e,/oreknoicledge of free volitions Is contradictory — The other link in the argument of Edwards, that God munt foreknow, denied — Edwards's position that, without foreknowledge of men's volitions, God could not be able properly to govern the universe — His argument goes rather to disprove freedom in executing the volitions than in the volitions themselves — God, foreknowing all the effects of human volition which are possible, can provide in advance for any contingence — That He may do this without deviating from uniform modes of action, illustrated by an automatic chess-board — He may also deviate from such uniformity in miracles — And, in many things, we do not know that He has established any uniformity — Foreknowledge, for the purpose of making sea Bonable provision, not necessary when the power is Loiinite — Foreknowledge of God hag the same relntlon to His actions that preconceptions of man have to his. CHAPTER XIII.-O0NCLUSION, ... 401 Recapitulation of the argument — Edwards's eiToneous and incompatible defliiitions of Will and Choice — His favorite reductio ad absurdum and various Boph.tms fnu; ded on these errors— His error in defining Freedom — His argn- menl Irom Moral Necessity and Moral Ii:ability, and supposed difficulties in willing — His argument from the connection of volition with a prior cause— Mo- tive— Habit as a motive — Assumption that the same causes necessarily produce the same eli'ects — IndiiFerence and Contingence — Last dictate of the under- standing — Willing in oases of indiflerence — Foreknowledge — Edwards's idea of it would deprive God of the highest attributes of creative intelligence. I Deacidified using the Bookkeeper process. Neutralizing agent: Magnesium Oxide Treatment Date: Nov. 2004 PreservationTechnologies A WORLD LEADER IN PAPER PRESERVATION 1 1 1 Thomson Park Drive Cranberry Township, PA 16066 (724)779-2111 .>.^'