Class. Book_ Digitized by the Internet Archive in 2011 with funding from The Library of Congress http://www.archive.org/details/socialphilosophy01cair THE SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY AND RELIGION OF COMTE. L THE SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY AND RELIGION OF COMTE. BY EDWARD ' CAIRD, LL.D., PROFESSOR OF MORAL FHILOSOPHY IN THF. UNIVERSITY OF GLASGOW. b o NEW YORK: MACMILLAN AND CO. 1885. A "5^. *p£iiratcfc, WITH AFFECTION AND ESTEEM, MY FRIEND AND COLLEAGUE JOHN NICHOL. CONTENTS. Preface, CHAPTER I. GENERAL ACCOUNT OF COMTE'S PHILOSOPHY. Gomte's fundamental principles — Their bearing on his view q/"-- history — Decay of theology and of the social system founded on it — Metaphysic, its strength for destruction and weakness for construction — It prepares the way for positive science, on ivl „ the social system of the future must be based — Necessity for a new religion based on science — Humanity the true object of worship— The social system corresponding to the religion of Humanity — Man's intellectual and moral powers evolved in conflict with nature — The nature of the social organization and the three forms of society, the Family, the State, and the Church — The Priesthood of Humanity and its office, - 1-55 CHAPTER II. THE NEGATIVE SIDE OF COMTE's PHILOSOPHY — HIS OPPOSITION TO METAPHYSIC AND THEOLOGY. Growth of a new view of the social organism opposed at once to Individualism and Socialism — Comte and the German Idealists — Meaning of his attack on Metaphysic — His re al agreement with modern meta physician s — He adopts Locke's principles as to knoivledge, yet is opposed to the Individualism of Locke's French disciples — He attacks Realism as a Nominalist and Nominalism as a Realist, and is really guided by a higher principle than either — His mistaken attitude towards th & Critical Philosophy — Relation of Philosophy to Science — It makelTmen conscious of their guiding yrinciyles — Comte' s consciousness of the categories /hat guide /its thought — Con sequent defects in his view of the development of Religion, of Philosophy, and of Science. — Mr. Spencer's criticism and Littre"s ansioer — Ambiguity in the opp>osition between the universal and the particular, 56-111 viii Contents. CHAPTER III. THE POSITIVE OR CONSTRICTIVE SIDE OF COMTE'S PHILOSOPHY — HIS SUBSTITUTES EOR METAPHYSIC AND THEOLOGY. His recognition of the need of substitutes for Theology and Meta- physic — His assertion that his philosophy is relative and subjec- tivp^Double meaning of the relativity of knowledge as involving ie assertion or the denial of real or absolute knowledge — Collision of Comte's earlier and later views on this point — Comte's subjective synthesis not subjective in the sense of Indi- vidualism, nor yet in the sense that a conscious subject is im- plied in all objects — His compromise between these opposite theories — His doctrine that man sees the world in ordine ad hominem but not in ordine ad universum — Impossibility- of separating nature from man and of criticising the whole system to vihich man belongs — Defects of Comte's religion"" according to his own idea of religion — Schisms in the school of Comte, 112-176 CHAPTER IV. COMTE'S VIEW OF THE RELATION OF THE INTELLECT TO THE HEART — ITS EFFECT ON HIS CONCEPTION OF HISTORY AND OF THE SOCIAL IDEAL. The necessity for unity in man's intellectual and moral life — Nature of the conflict between the intelligence and the heart — It is really a conflict of intelligence with itself — Criticism of Comte's doctrine that the intelligence must he subjected to tin- heart — Its effect upon his conception of history, especially of the history of Christianity — The two elements in Christianity, their conflict and reconciliation in its development — The nega- tive tendencies of mediaeval Catholicism and the positive ten- dencies of the modern era — Comte's imp erfect conception of the Reformalmi and the Revolution — His restoration of the mediaeval ideal — His general position as a Philosopher. 177-249 PREFACE. This volume consists of a series of articles which have already appeared in the Contemporary Re- view, and which the proprietors of that review have kindly permitted me to republish. A few paragraphs have been re- written, and a few verbal changes introduced to remove obscurity or in- accuracy, but the general substance of the articles remains unaltered. In the following exposition and criticism of Comte's philosophy I have considered it mainly, though not exclusively, in its ethical and religi- ous aspects. I have not attempted to deal with the detailed discussion of the nature and methods of the sciences contained in the Philosophic Posi- tive, except in so far as is necessary for the understanding of the Politique Positive, in which x Preface. the social and religious aims of Comte's philosophy are for the first time explicitly stated. Not, indeed, that there is any very marked division between his earlier and his later treatises. The changes observable in the latter do not amount, as has sometimes been represented, to a sudden revolution, but are rather the last develojnnent of tendencies which had been gaining ground in Comte's mind as his work advanced, and gradually carrying him away from his original principles, or at least greatly modifying their first signi- ficance. I have preferred, however, to confine myself, in the main, to the social philosophy of Comte and the restoration of religion connected therewith, partly because I have not sufficient scientific knowledge to estimate the value of his critical review of mathematics and physics, chemistry and biology, and partly because, so far as I know, there has been very little serious criticism of that part of his work which he regarded (I think justly) as the most important and original. In his earlier treatise, or at least in the greater part of it, Comte was working upon lines which are common to him with all the . representatives of what in the last century Preface. xi was termed " Enlightenment," and now most often goes by the names of " Positivism " or " Agnosticism." But the distinctive peculiarity of Comte is that he does not stop at that negation of metaphysics and theology which is characteristic of this school, hut that Ids Posi- tivism reproduces both, though in a new form. It is, indeed, just this new element in Comte which gives a truly " positive " meaning to his well-known law of development, which in its first form might more truly be described as " negative." For in that form all that it dis- tinctly tells us about the development of the human mind is that man once believed in theo- logical or metaphysical fictions, and that he has now ceased, or is gradually ceasing, to believe in them. In his later writings, however, Comte has come to see that both theology and meta- physics are based upon perennial wants of man's spiritual nature, wants which, as man, he cannot but feel, and for w T hich a real and not merely a fictitious satisfaction can be provided. He teaches us, therefore, to regard the progress of man as a true development, in which the passing away of the first forms of his higher life is incidental xii Preface. to the further manifestation of the spirit, which was once expressed in them. Hence the last or " positive " stage of thought is conceived to be a negation and abolition of the past in which all that gave the past its value is reaffirmed and maintained. It is a higher "positive," which is reached through the negation of the lower, but it is itself a great deal more than that negation. Now, the ultimate interest of Comte's philo- sophy lies in the success or failure of this attempt of his to find a new satisfaction for those higher wants of humanity, which Theology and Metaphysic, or, as I should prefer to say, Eeligion and Philosophy, have so long been supposed to satisfy. It is not difficult to describe, at least in general terms, what these wants are. Philo- sophy professes to seek and to find the principle of unity which underlies all the manifold particu- lar truths of the separate sciences, and in refer- ence to which they can be brought together and organized as a system of knowledge. And Eeli- gion, while it also is concerned with an absolute principle of reality, differs from Philosophy mainly in this, that it is not merely or primarily theo- retical. For Eeligion what is required is such Preface. xiii a conviction as to the ultimate basis of our existence as shall enable us to find therein at once an adequate object of affection and a sufficient aim for all our practical endeavours. Now a scientific Agnosticism, such as is common at the present day, means either that there are no such wants in man, or that, if they exist, no provision is made for their satisfaction. Such an Agnosticism could scarcely find a better expres- sion for itself than the Comtean law of intellec- tual development ; for, as that law is commonly understood, it implies that the whole progress of man has been just his gradual awakening to the necessity of renouncing all effort to pene- trate to the reality which is hidden behind the veil of phenomena. On this view, it is vain for man to ask any longer the question of Philo- sophy, or to attempt to find a support for his life in the faiths and hopes of religion. Man is but a link or a series of links in the endless chain of phenomenal causes ; his utmost knowledge cannot reach beyond the relations of particular things to each other and to his own particular existence, and whatever he may desire, to these relations he must be content practically to limit xiv Preface. himself. Tecum hdbita et noris quam sit tibi curta swpellex. Now the peculiarity of Comte's position is that he admits the principle on which this Agnostic view is based, and yet at the same time rejects the conclusions which are usually and naturally drawn from it. He accepts the situa- tion as he understands it. He admits and contends that Philosophy is defeated in its attempt to reach an absolute principle — a principle of unity, which is at once the real or objective centre of the universe, and the subjective centre for our knowledge of it. He admits and con- tends that there is a great gulf fixed between the absolute reality of things and our conscious- ness of them. ' Nevertheless, he holds that, in a sense, we may still aspire to that encyclopaedic or universal view of things which Philosophy pretended to give ; for, though we cannot reach an objective principle of unity in things, we can still gather knowledge to a subjective centre, by regarding all things in relation to our own needs and uses. This, however, does not mean that we are to view everything in relation to our own individual pleasures and pains. For the indi- Preface. xv vidual is essentially related to his race, or rather, as we should say, that the " individual man is a mere abstraction, and that there is nothing real but Humanity." Hence, in knowledge and in feeling we are carried beyond ourselves ; and as in our moral life we can rise from egoism to altruism, so in our intellectual life we can learn to regard the world from the point of view, not of the individual, but of the race. And the same change brings with it the restoration of religion. The " objective " or absolute God, the God who made all things work together for good to His creatures, has disappeared with the fictions of childhood. But His place has been taken by Humanity, conceived as a great providential existence, which sustains and controls the life of the individual man, and in which he finds a sufficient object for all his devotion. Looking to this Great Being, man need not feel the want of any other God. He has before his eyes One who can help him and whom he can love and serve. Or if he should still feel something wanting, as an object of worship, in a Being who is not the Absolute Being, he is at liberty to indulge in the poetic illusion which makes xvi Preface. Nature, as well as Humanity, the friend of man. If he does so, however, he must remember that he is yielding to an illusion, which is not sup- ported by anything we know of Nature ; for Nature, apart from the action of man upon it, shows itself as a mere fatality, which is altogether indifferent to his weal or woe. Even this short sketch of Comte's system — for the detailed exposition of which the reader is re- ferred to the following chapters — may suffice to show where the vital spot, the Achilles' heel, of Comte's philosophy lies. It lies in the idea of a " subjective synthesis " or relative centre of know- ledge. This idea for Comtists is the articulus stantis vel cadentis philosophiae. If this central principle can be securely defended, it matters little to the orthodox Positivist how many of the subordinate elements of Comte's thought may have to be abandoned or modified. If it has to be surrendered, however numerous and valuable may be the separate truths and suggestions which are discoverable in every part of Comte's works, his philosophy as a whole must be given up. From what I have read of the works of Comte's most zealous and discerning followers, I am dis- Preface. xvii posed to think that they would be ready to accept this issue. Now Comte's position has generally been attacked, if one might so express it, from the rear, i.e., by those whose views accord most with his earlier doctrine expressed in the Philosophic Positive, and who regard him as abandoning the true Positivism when he admits any philosophical or religious synthesis whatever, whether subjective or objective, whether relative or absolute. It is in this way that Comte was assailed by Littre, the most eminent of his French disciples, and it is in this way also that he was criticised by Mill and Lewes, who, without being strictly his disciples, accepted most of the leading ideas of his earlier work. If there is any novelty in the criticism contained in the following pages, it is that it starts from the opposite point of view, and seeks to show that the true synthesis of philosophy must be objective as well as subjective, and that there can be no re- ligion of Humanity which is not also a religion of God. And this means that it is logically impos- sible to go beyond the merely individualistic point of view with which Comte started, except on the assumption that the intelligence of man is, or xviii Preface. involves, a universal principle of knowledge. The same arguments, in fact, which break down the division between man and man, break down also the division between man and nature ; for, if all Humanity be considered as organically united, it becomes impossible not to recognize in nature an essential relation to man, which makes it in some sense a part of the same organism. The history of the development of Comte's thought is itself, as I endeavour in the sequel to show, an evidence of this principle : for it is the history of a development which ends by all but retracting the negations with which it begins. And when, in his Synthase Subjective, Comte sanctions the poetic treatment of Space and the Earth as divine friends of man, and members of a kind of Trinity in which Humanity is the third person, he comes very near to a complete return upon himself. It has, indeed, been contended by Dr. Bridges # that this is but the ordinary license of poetry, such, for instance, as we find in Shelley's Earth- hymn in the " Prometheus Unbound." " Sup- posing any one had taken Shelley seriously to task for maintaining; that the Earth is alive, should * Unity of Comte's Life and Doctrine, p. 60. Preface. xix we not think him curiously dull and pedantic ? " True, it may be answered : but, supposing any one had maintained that the earth is not in any sense the expression of that spiritual principle which expresses itself in a higher way in living beings, and above all in man, and that, therefore, there is nothing but fiction in the ascription of life to it, should we not be entitled to say that he had lost hold of the sense in which poetry is truth ? Should we not consider that he had degraded poetry from a sensuous and therefore partly fictitious presentment of ideal truth, into a mere plaything of fancy which bodies forth things that are not as if they were ? In Comte's case the interest of the poetic fiction consists in this, that it was the imaginative anticipation of a truth towards which he was moving, but which he had not distinctly recognized. His imagination had already emancipated him from the limits of those earlier opinions of his, which still held good for his understanding. If he had taken one step farther, the wheel would have " come full circle," and he would have restored both Theology and Philosophy to the place from which he expelled them. He would have xx Preface. " burnt what he had adored, and adored what he had burnt." I cannot say so much in criticism of Comte's views without adding — what every new reading of his works, and especially of the Politique Positive makes me feel more strongly — that the value of his teaching is by no means to be estimated by its mere logical result. Whatever may be said of his philosophy as a whole, he possessed that unmistakeable instinct for truth which renders even the errors and inconsistencies of men of genius more instructive than the most unexceptionable reasonings of many judicious persons, who follow the beaten tracks of thought and, therefore, " need no repentance." Erratum.— Page 56, Contents, 6th line, for Religion read Realism. THE SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY AND EELIGION OF COMTE. CHAPTER I. GENERAL ACCOUNT OF COMTE'S PHILOSOPHY. Comte's fundamental principles — Their bearing on his view of history — Decay of theology and of the social system founded on it — M eta-physic, its strength, for destruction and weakness for construction — It prepares the way for positive science, on which the social system of the future must be based — Necessity for a new religion based on science — Humanity the true object of worship — The social system corresponding to the religion of Humanity — Man's intellectual and moral powers evolved in conflict with nature — The nature of the social organization and the three forms of society, the Family, the State, and the Church— The Priesthood of Humanity and its office. It is impossible to understand the errors of a great writer unless we do justice to the truth which underlies them. In judging of Comte's philosophy, and especially of his social philosophy, this law of criticism has often been neglected, even by those who, from their general philosophi- cal point of view, might seem best qualified to __ 2 The Social Philosophy of Comte. appreciate him. Disagreeing as I do with many of his conclusions, I cannot hope to be entirely successful in doing him justice. But the attempt to do so may have its use, if only in bringing to light the relationship of philosophies which are commonly regarded as having no connection with each other. The spirit of the time is greater than any of its expressions, and it moulds them all, under whatever outward diversity of form, to a common result. If there is anything which the history of philosophy teaches with clearness, it is that contemporaneous movements of the human spirit, even those which appear to be most inde- pendent or antagonistic, are but partial expressions of a truth which is not fully revealed in any one of them, and which can be adequately appreciated only by a later generation. The present is said to be par excellence the age of historical criticism ; but the historical imagination is worth little if it does not enable us to discover identity of nature under the most varied disguises, and, instead of being confined to the formula? of any one philo- sophy, to remould and renew our own ideas by entering into the minds of others. In order to prepare the way for a just appreciation of the Relation to Rousseau. 3 teaching of Comte, I shall, in this chapter, give a short sketch of his philosophy (and more particularly of his social philosophy) as far as possible from his own point of view, reserving for subsequent chapters what I have to say in the way of criticism. There are two main thoughts which rule the The two loading mind of Comte, and are the sources of most of 1 q^^ the peculiarities of his system. The one is, " the law of the three stages " ; the other is the sub- ordination of science to man's social well-being, or, as he expresses it, of the intellect to the heart. The first of these thoughts embodies his criterion of knowledge ; the second is the prin- ciple by which he seeks to systematize knowledge, and to estimate the relative value of its parts. The relation of these two points in the mind of Comte will be best understood if we recall his historical position and the early course of his mental development. As with most educated Frenchmen of his time, Comte's first thoughts on social politics were suggested by the Revolution ; and his youthful connection with St. Simon showed that he shared in that reaction against the individualistic philosophy of the Eighteenth 4 The Social Philosophy of Comte. Century, which gave rise to so many socialistic and communistic theories. In the school of St. Simon, Comte learned the falsehood of the gospel f of Eousseau — that last quintessence of the philo- ; sophy which found reality only in the individual, and which, therefore, idealized the natural man as he is apart from, and prior to, all society, and regarded all social influence as deteriorating from his original purity. The hollowness of that theory had been written in letters of blood on the page of recent history, and that too plainly to be ignored by the most hopeful theorist on social subjects. Nor could any one who had read it there, fail to perceive also the less striking failure of the same doctrines in their economical form. The liberation of the individual had not brought to man political salvation, but had rather revealed his essential weakness when emancipated from the restraints of social order. " Laissez faire " had not, as was expected, introduced an economic millennium ; but had rather given rise to a struggle of interests, which, if not moderated by any higher principle, might end in the dis- solution of society. Hence the mere irrational movement of reaction drove the mass of men to Relation to the Socialists. 5 bind again upon themselves the fetters which the Revolution had broken, and taught those who, like De Maistre, represented the ideas and interests of the past, the speculative strength of their position. De Maistre saw clearly that mere individualism is anarchy, and that the moral education of man is possible only through some binding social force. Nor was it difficult for a skilful special pleader like him to confound this truth with the doctrine that the only safety for civilization lay in a renewed submission to the mediaeval order of Church and State. On the other hand, men who were too much imbued with the modern spirit to be moved by this reactionary logic, were led to detach the social- istic idea from the special form it had taken in past history, and to seek for some new form of political organization, in which individual freedom should be again subordinated to social order. Such men were St. Simon and Fourier— not, in any sense, great or comprehensive thinkers, but writers who were effective and influential for the moment simply because they represented the abstraction which was then rising into favour, and which had at least this to recommend it, I The Social Philosophy of Comte. that it was the opposite abstraction to that of the Revolutionists. Comte was too robust and manysided to remain long under the influence either of the concrete or of the abstract reac- tionaries — either of those who sought to return to the form, or of those who sought to return to the spirit, of the past. But his temporary subjection to St. Simon, and his ultimate revolt against him, help us in some measure to under- stand that double movement of thought out of which his system sprung. His subjection in- dicated that he had seen the insufficiency and unreality, the abstract and unhistorical character, of the gospel of mere rebellion. His emancipa- tion from St. Simon indicated his discovery that the simple repression of rebellion, the mere closing up of the ranks of society under a social despotism, was an utterly inadequate solution of the difficulty. The problem before him, therefore, was to do justice to the element of truth in each of these movements — to the social impulse on the one hand and to the critical movement of intelligence on the other, — and to reconcile them in a higher unity. Socialism had taught him that social enthusiasm might be separated from The Need for a Theology. 7 the religious and political institutions on which it had rested in the past ; and the progress of science seemed to teach him that intelligence has a constructive as well as a critical influence. The solution, therefore, was simply to take the former, as determining the end and goal of all practical effort ; and the latter, as teaching us the proper means for its attainment. The en- thusiasm of humanity guided by science, science directed so as to secure the highest happiness of humanity, were thus the two ideas by which the course of his thoughts was determined. In the first place these ideas gave to Comte JJyJ^Jf what seemed to him a perfect key to the history history of the past. Man he conceives of as a being who at first is divided between weak social tendencies which bind him to his fellows, and strong selfish, or, as he calls them, personal instincts, which make him their rival and their enemy ; yet without the triumph of the former over the latter there can be no security for his welfare or even for his existence. This triumph of social sympathy is the first necessity of civil- ization ; and in an early age any theory of life must be welcome which promises to secure it. —Mi 8 The Social Philosophy of Comte. The first social leaders of mankind, even if such an idea could have presented itself to them, could not wait with patience till experience had revealed to them the true nature of man and the world he lives in. Their ignorance and their benevolent haste to organize society, and to bind men together in the bonds of a definite faith, made them eagerly grasp at the first explanation of the universe which imagination suggested ; and that first explanation was of course anthro- pomorphic. "As they watched nature, as their eyes wandered over the surface of the profound ocean, instead of the bed hidden under the waters, they saw nothing but the reflection of their own faces.""" Hence the first moral order and social discipline established among men was based upon a theological explanation of the universe. Nor did the insecurity of the founda- tion seem for a long time to interfere with the firmness of the superstructure. The union of men was like the union of an army — a union of men bound together for life and death, though the bond that united them was but a fairy tale. Yet, in the long run, it was impossible that * Turcot. Development of Theology. J> criticism should not make itself heard. Ad- vancing experience, as it disclosed that the world is no plaything of arbitrary wills but an order of fixed law, gradually limited the free play of imagination, and removed the gods to a greater and greater distance. AVhen, therefore, pheno- mena were seen to group themselves in large genera, with permanent attributes and relations, Polytheism rose out of Fetichism ; and when the idea of the unity of the world, and of the general persistency of its laws, began to prevail, theology was inevitably reduced to the conception of one overruling will which, directly or by its ministers, controls the whole movement of things. Up to this point the theological form of thought per- sisted : in one point of view it might even lie said that, up to this point, it was strengthening- its hold upon men. For, every successive con- centration of the divine power made the idea of it a firmer and more comprehensive bond of social order, until at length the levelling and organizing genius of Eome laid the foundation of the universal empire, and Christian Monotheism broke down the walls of division between races and nations. 10 The Social Philosophy of Comte. The But this, apparent advance of the theological decay of r± ° theology, gp^it was illusive, for it was really due to an intellectual movement, which must, in the long- run, prove fatal to that spirit. The concentration of Fetichism into Polytheism, and of Polytheism into Monotheism, was really the gradual with- drawal of theology from the explanation of the universe, till, finally, it was driven to its last stronghold, its most general and abstract form. Hence the hour of its greatest social triumph was that which preceded its decisive fall. The same growing perception of the order of the world under general laws, which had forced the theologian first to substitute a limited for an indefinite number of divine wills, and then to substitute one will for this limited number, necessarily and inevitably awakened a doubt whether there is in nature any indication of will at all. Monotheism had represented the world as a general order of fixed laws, only interrupted by exceptional miracles ; but in- creasing knowledge made miracles more and more incredible, till at last the theologians were re- duced to the assertion that their God had once performed them, but that he performed them Victory of Metaphysic. 11 no longer. When this point was reached, it was not difficult to see that the whole anthro- pomorphic explanation of things was on the eve (if disappearing. A God, who was nearer man in the past than he is in the present, could not he the God of the future. But even before this period, the growing weak- And of the A social order ness of the theoretical basis of belief had begun withit** to affect the practical life of men. The social order was built upon theology, and therefore the advance of the critical spirit w r as continually loosening its foundations. Hence the fierce hostility of the representatives of that order to the freedom of the intelligence. That hostility, however, is to be attributed not so much to their indignation at unbelief in itself, as to their alarm at the dissolution of social order which was its practical result. Nor was it altogether inexcus- able, so long as the assailants of the old faith were unable to propound any theoretical prin- ciples which could be made the basis of recon- struction. Now the metaphysical principles to which these assailants appealed were really negations pretending to be affirmations, the purely negative character of which must reveal itself 12 The Social Philosophy of Comte. as soon as their victory was achieved. Men in whom the practical and organizing impulse was strong, who felt the necessity for a moral order, could not but see that such ropes of sand were no real substitute for the old framework of social and political life, and they were therefore tempted to shut their eyes to the intellectual claims of a truth which could be fertile only in destruction. Thus arose that fatal division between the heart and the intellect which has lasted down to the present day, and which must last till the intellect shows itself capable of producing a system which can more securely sustain the social order, and more completely satisfy the affections and spiritual aspirations of men, than the fictions of theology. The The truth of this view will be more clearly metaphysi- ^thought, seen if we examine the nature of that intermediate system of critical thought which was the great weapon of attack upon theology. This system was, in fact, only the last abstraction of the theological anthropomorphism itself. As in 6ne department of human thought after another the knowledge of the uniform and unchangeable order of things prevailed over the conception of accident Weakness of Metaphysic. 13 and arbitrary change, the idea of will became attenuated, until it ultimately disappeared alto- gether from the explanation of nature. But it left behind a kind of spectre of abstraction. Instead of being dominated by gods, phenomena were supposed to be dominated by essences and powers, which, however, were merely abstract repetitions of those phenomena. How abstrac- tions came to be thus substantiated as real entities, separate from the phenomena in which they were manifested, might be difficult to under- stand, if we did not remember that they were but the residua of what had once been individualized pictures of imagination. The essences of the Schoolmen were but the dry bones of the living- creatures of poetry which the understanding had slain. " The human mind," as Mill puts it, " did not set out from the notion of a name, but from that of a divinity. The realization of abstractions was not the embodiment of a word, but the dis- embodiment of a Fetich." Really, therefore, these essences and powers were nothing more than the pure abstractions, and therefore only the negations, of the gods whose places they took. They had no positive content of their own. As mere 1 4 The Social Philosophy of Comte. negatives they had no value except in relation to the corresponding affirmatives, although in the first instance imagination was strong enough to give them the semblance of positive principles occupying the place of the beliefs they expelled. And it was just this temporary illusion which made them such powerful weapons of destruction. For the revolutionary passion can never be sus- tained by negations which it recognizes as such. It is impossible to march with enthusiasm to the attack upon the institutions of the past, without the conviction that there is something more to be gained than the destruction of those institutions. Develop- The metaphysical philosophy, as the necessary physic, forerunner of the philosophy of experience, gradu- ally extended its destructive power over all branches of human knowledge. At first " it laid its hand on the sciences that deal with inorganic nature, and of these, first of all on those that deal with the phenomena furthest from man, and least subject to his control. For man discovers that the phenomena of the heavens are not ruled by arbitrary will, long before he discerns the absence of caprice from the general course of nature. In like manner, he is sensible that The Idea of Nature. 15 inorganic tilings have fixed and unchangeable relations, while as yet the spontaneity of animal life seems to he as unlimited as that which he attributes to his own will. And only last of all does it dawn upon him that his own life also is limited and controlled by something, which is neither his own will nor the will of a being like himself whom he can propitiate or persuade — something which is both within and without him, to which he must conform himself, seeing it will not conform to him. The last substantiated abstraction, therefore, which is put in the place of the divine powers, is Nature. And Nature is only a name for the general course of things, though it is regarded by metaphysics as existing apart from and controlling them. But as Nature succeeds to the place of a Clod whom men were conceived to be bound to obey, but able arbitrarily to disobey, so it is represented as the source of a law distinct from the actual course of human life, and to which it does not necessarily conform. The law of nature, in this view, is a law written on man's heart, but not necessarily realized in his actions. In truth, however, it is but the negation of that order of social life which was based upon 1G The Social Philosophy of Comte. the theological idea, though its negative character is necessarily hidden from those who believe in it. its power This becomes evident whenever we examine for de- struction, the main articles contained in this supposed law of nature. For these are simply negations of different parts of that social order which was based upon theology. The first of these articles is the right of private judgment — that is, the right of every individual to emancipate himself from all spiritual authority, and to judge of everything for himself. This principle is merely " a sanction of the state of anarchy, which inter- vened between the decay of the old discipline and the formation of new spiritual ties." In other words, it is not a new principle of order, but the abstract expression of the ungoverned state of mere individual opinion, " for no association what- ever, even of the smallest number of persons and for the most temporary objects, can subsist without some degree of intellectual and moral agreement between its members." In the next place, among the articles of the law of nature, stands the doctrine of equality, which has a meaning only as the negation of the old hierarchy, the old social and political order, but which, taken absolutely, The Formulas of Anarchy. 17 is the negation of all order whatever. For if society is anything more than a collection of unrelated atoms, if it is an organic unity, it must have different organs for its different functions; and it is as impossible that these organs should all be equal, as that they should all be the same. This doctrine, therefore, is but the abstract procla- mation of social anarchy. To these articles are commonly added the doctrines of national indepen- dence, and of the sovereignty of the people. The former is nothing more than the negation of that spiritual supremacy of the Church, which in the Middle Ages mediated between the nations of Europe and made them one community ; but, taken absolutely, it would imply national isolation and international anarchy. The latter is the transfer- ence to the governed of that fiction of divine right which was formerly supposed to reside in the governor, and it has no meaning except as the negation of that fiction. For the people can- not rule themselves ; and even to make them choose their ruler, that is, to make the inferior and less wise choose the superior and wiser, can- not be regarded as more than a provisional ex- pedient for anarchic times. 18 The Social Philosophy of Comte. its weak- The articles of the law of nature, then, like all ness for tfon Struc ' metaphysical principles, are merely principles of insurrection and revolt. They have no positive validity ; for they are just the ultimate abstrac- tions, or, so to speak, the speculative phantoms of the system which they destroy. As it is said that a man dies when he has seen his own ghost, so, according to Comte, the destroyer of theology is just the ghost of itself, raised by abstraction. But the ghost also vanishes when its victim is fairly buried, leaving the field to the growing strength of positive science. it prepares Positive science, then, is the real cause of all the way for science intellectual progress, its advance constitutes the nisus formativus that is concealed beneath the surface struggle of theology and metaphysics. For even in the earliest theological era, there was a certain element of positive science, that is, of knowledge of the permanent relations of things. The most arbitrary will is not all arbitrary, but presupposes something of a fixed order without or within, and therefore the anthropomorphic analo- gies by which phenomena were interpreted, still left some space for the idea of law. And this space was continually being widened, at the Metaphysie Allied with Science. 1<) expense of the arbitrary and the accidental. While metaphysics seemed simply to be substi- tuting one transcendent explanation for another, it was really disguising the abandonment of all transcendent explanations whatever, and the introduction of positive explanations in their place. The doubts expressed in the metaphysical criticism were really due to a growing sense of law, which, when it became clear and self-con- scious, produced the positive philosophy. Hence there was, for a long time, an intimate alliance between the scientific and the metaphysical spirit, though the former was merely " critical" and the latter " organic" And this alliance was the more easily maintained, because, in the first instance, neither the negative character of the former nor the positive character of the latter was distinctly discerned. Metaphysic was not seen to be merely " critical," because its abstractions were taken to be real entities. And science could not be seen to be " organic," that is, to contain the principle of a new organization of society, till it rose from the contemplation of the inorganic world to the study of life, and especially of human life. His- tory, however, shows that science has always 20 The Social Philosophy of Comte. reaped the fruits of every victory won over theology by metaphysic, and on the other hand that metaphysic has never succeeded in maintain- ing any position against theology, which has not soon been occupied by science. The great metaphysical movement of the Greeks left for its sole permanent result the sciences of Geometry and Astronomy ; while their premature specula- tions on Psychology and Sociology were suppressed or forgotten by the mediaeval church, which directed all the intelligence of the world to the practical work of civilizing and organizing men by means of the monotheistic idea. When thought was again awakened, the abstract metaphysic of the Schoolmen was only the forerunner of the renewed study of natural science, especially of Physics and Chemistry, which at first appeared under the forms of Astrology and Alchemy ; and the victory of Nominalism over Eealism, in which the scholastic philosophy ended, was the indica- tion of another triumph of the scientific spirit. For Nominalism is simply the negation of that tendency to personify abstractions, which is the essence of metaphysic. Finally, as a con- sequence of that development of science which Science at War with Metapkysic. 2L culminated in Newton, metaphysic ceased to apply its method to the external world, and confined itself to the sphere of Biology and Sociology, from which it is now being gradually driven. In the last of these applications, its power for criticism and destruction, and its weak- ness for reconstruction and reorganization, were proved by the decisive experiment of the French Revolution, in which the ideas of the rights of man and the law of nature were tried and found wanting. Since that time political life has fluc- tuated between the theological and the meta- physical principles, and therefore between the opposite dangers of reaction and revolution, find- ing no security for order but in the former, and no security for progress but in the latter. But the advance of Sociology into the positive stage, which has been inaugurated by Comte, has, in his view, shown that the opposite interests of order and progress may be equally secured, if only we base both upon a knowledge of the laws by which the existence and activity of man are ruled, and not on the fictions of the imagination, or on the still emptier fictions of the understanding. 99 The Social Philosophy of Comte. on science The aim of the future, then, is one with the the social thffuture a i m °f ^h.e past. That social passion which in all must be . . based great constructive periods 01 human history, and especially in the Middle Ages, took hold of theo- logical beliefs and made them a means to organize and discipline mankind, is still to be the guiding motive of all speculation and action. But the system of thought which it uses for this end must inevitably be changed. Eenouncing the theological and metaphysical interpretations of things, which have been proved to be either inconsistent with facts or at least incapable of being verified by facts, we must now base our effort to improve man's estate upon the laws of the resemblance, the coexistence, and the succession of phenomena as these are determined by science. And on the other hand, as we recognize that all the sciences tend to lose themselves in the multiplicity of a universe, where every path leads to the infinite, we must seek also to organize and discipline the hitherto dispersive efforts of science, so that they may be directed entirely to the relief and further- ance of man's estate. In this way scientific knowledge and social benevolence will act and react, at once limiting and supporting each other, A Wise Agnosticism. 23 and amid all the darkness of a universe which absolutely is unknowable, and, even relatively to himself, is only partially knowable, man can yet give a kind of unity and completeness to his transitory existence. For all he needs to know is that which experience has constantly been teaching, the uniformity and constancy of the laws of phenomena, By means of this know- ledge, so far as he can obtain it, and without any need to penetrate into the transcendent causes of things, he can foresee many phenomena, like those of the heavens, over which he has no control whatever, and also many phenomena, like those of his own nature and his immediate environ- ment, which he can, to a certain degree, change and modify. And thus he can learn, with con- tinually growing certainty, what are the means he must use to bring within his reach the highest good which the system of things allows him to attain, detaching his thoughts and interests more and more from the unfathomed abyss beyond, which he now knows to be by him unfathom- able. Is it, then, possible for men to sketch out the Necessity for a new programme of an existence limited to this " bank religion • 24 The Social Philosophy of Comte. and shoal of time," to conceive it as a complete system in itself, and r6-organiser sans Dietc ni roi, par le culte sysUmatique de VhumaniU? Can they, surrendering the belief in " a Divinity that shapes their ends, rough hew them how they will," " constitute a real providence for themselves, in all departments, moral, intellectual, and ma- terial" ? Comte answers that they can; and in the " Politique Positive " he tries to exhibit the main outlines of that social system of the future by which this end is to be attained. Religious His starting point is — strange as at first it basis of life - may seem — the idea of religion. " Since religion embraces all our existence, its history must be an epitome of the whole history of our development." Beneath and beyond all the details of our ideas of things, there is a certain " esprit d'ensemble," a general conception of the world without and the world within, in which these details gather to a head. If this conception or picture be co- herent with itself, and if at the same time it be such as to present an object on which our -affec- tions can rest, and an end in the pursuit of which all our powers and capacities may be exer- cised, then our life will have that unity and con- Religion gives Unity to Life. 25 sistency with itself which is necessary for the highest efficiency and happiness. Such a har- mony of existence, in which all its elements are fitly co-ordinated, is what, in Comte's view, con- stitutes a religion. And, since man is both an individual and a social being, this harmony is seen to involve two things. It involves a sub- ordination of all the elements of man's individual nature to some ruling tendency, and it involves a certain adaptation of men to, and a combination of them with, each other. Further, this harmony of humanity with itself must also be a harmony of man with the world in which he exists. In other words, the individual can attain his highest perfection and happiness only in so far as he is, at once and by virtue of the same principle, in har- mony with the world, with his fellow-men, and with himself. Now, this harmony cannot be produced by the Elements ■*■ necessary sway of personal or egoistic motives ; for these r°[i^ on . are in fatal disagreement with each other, and they set each man in antagonism to all other men, and even to the natural conditions of his own existence. The regulation and harmonizing of the nature of the individual man, therefore, 26 The Social Philosophy of Comte. implies his attachment or self-surrender to that which is without him, and to which he is neces- sarily related — to some object in that world of persons and things which hems him in on every side, and which must needs be his enemy so long as he is ruled by egoism. Further, if the prin- ciple of religion is thus to be found without and not within the individual man, it must be found in some object to which he submits as a superior power, and on which, at the same time, his affec- tions can rest. Submission and love are both necessary to religion, for if we have merely the former, the utmost we can feel is resignation to a fatality ; and this, though it involves a certain limitation of the selfish tendencies, can never overcome them, or substitute a new motive for them. To retain the energy of egoism and com- bine it with resignation to a power greater than ours, we must love that power to which we sub- mit. Finally, this submission and self-surrender must be consistent with a certain relative sense of independence, for no feeling is really powerful which does not result in action. Hence, to sub- mission and love, we must add the belief that we can make ourselves useful to that Beino- to whom Three Elements of Religion. 27 we submit and whom we love. Only thus, when veneration for that which is above us, is com- bined with love for that which is the constant source of good to us, and with benevolence to- wards that which needs our help,"" can we rise above the unreal and imperfect unity of selfish- ness into the perfect unity of religion. Or, to put it more shortly, in Comte's own language, " the principal religious difficulty is to secure that the external shall regulate the internal with- out affecting its spontaneity " ; to secure, that is, that the free subjective principles of love and benevolence shall attach to the power to which we believe our existence to be subordinated. For if our faith be not one with our love, or if our love be not a principle of activity, we cannot be, in the full sense of the word, religious. Now the difficulty of attaining such a har- Scientific " basis for mony or unity of existence cannot but be obvious religion. to those who live in a period when " the intelli- gence is in insurrection against the heart ; " when what men desire and love is not by any means one with what, on the authority of science, they believe. If, however, we follow the course of * Cf. Goethe's " Three Reverences." 28 The Social Philosophy of Comte. advancing knowledge, we shall see that this state of things is merely temporary, and that completed positive science gives us back all that in the course of its development it seemed to take away. Science, indeed, from its very dawn, when it dis- covers that there is a fixed order and law in the movement of the heavenly bodies, gives support to one element of religion, the sense that we are in the hands of a superior power. It reveals to man an ultimate necessity which bounds and de- termines his life — a necessity which, from the nature of the case, he cannot modify. And as the idea of law is gradually extended to physical, chemical, and vital phenomena, this necessity is seen to limit and control him on every side. Phenomena, therefore, can no longer be regarded as the expressions of the wills of fictitious beings endowed with the qualities most admired in humanity, and therefore capable of being loved. And the natural effect of this is to reduce religion into a mere resignation to an irresistible fate, which is incapable of awaking or responding to human affection. With the rise of sociology, however, science changes its aspect, and begins to restore to us more than all that was contained in Sociology and Religion. 20 the dreams of mythology which it has destroyed. For this culminating' science teaches us to regard the whole race of man as an organic and self- developing unity, in which we, as individuals, arc parts or members. Between our own life and the merely external necessity of nature we see a spiritual power which modifies it and adapts it to our wants. Between the individual and the world stands humanity, and the " main pressure of external fatality does not fall upon the former directly, but only through the interposition of the latter." In passing through this medium, brute necessity is changed more and more into a saving providence. To be convinced of this we need only to observe that, after we go beyond the fixed order of the celestial system, which is the ultimate necessity of our lives, and which lies entirely beyond the reach of our interference, we come upon various orders of phenomena — phys- ical, chemical, and vital — which are capable of modification, and are continuously subjected to it by man, and even by plants and animals. So soon as life begins, order becomes the basis of progress : for the living being not only adapts itself to the medium in which it lives, but con- 30 The Social Philosophy of Comte. tinually reacts upon that medium, in order to render it more suitable for its wants ; (and in the case of man, inasmuch as his existence has a con- nection and a continuity that binds the whole race together through the long succession of as;es, this reaction is cumulative. The life of the indi- vidual in any age is what it is, by reason of the whole progressive movement of humanity ; and the later the time of his appearance the more he owes to his race. " The living are always more and more dominated by the dead." On this great benefactor, therefore, his thoughts can rest, as a power which moderates and controls his whole life, and which controls it not merely as a fate to which he must resign himself, but as a providence to which his love and gratitude are due. Nor will such feelings be less powerful because this Providence is one which he can serve, and which needs his service. Hence he is led to contemplate his life in all that makes it worth living, as the gift of a " Grand Etre," to whom during his short term of earthly years it is his highest virtue to devote himself, and with whom it is his final reward to become incor- porated. For his " objective " or actual existence Religion of Humanity. 31 in time has no valuable result, unless it add to the "subjective" existence of humanity, the influences and memories which mould for good the lot of subsequent generations. His religion, in short, is to consider himself as a useful link in the chain between the past and future of the race, a soldier of humanity in the continual struggle whereby it adapts itself to its sphere of action, and its sphere of action to itself, so as to realize an ever richer and more harmoni- ous social existence. It is true indeed that Humanity has no abso- Humanity the only lute power, that it is hemmed in by a fatality true God - which it can only partially modify. " This im- mense and eternal Being has not created the materials which its wise activity employs, nor the laws which determine the results of its action." But it is as vain to attempt to raise our hearts beyond this immediate benefactor, as to carry the mind beyond the circle of experience within which it is necessarily enclosed. Nay, it is not only vain, but hurtful. " The provisional regime which ends in our day has only too clearly manifested the gravity of this danger, for during it the greater part of the thanks addressed to the 32 The Social 'Philosophy of Comte. fictitious Being constituted so many acts of in- gratitude to Humanity, the sole author of the benefits for which thanks were given." " If the adoration of fictitious powers was morally indis- pensable, so long as the true ' Grand Etre ' that rules our lives could not clearly manifest himself, now at least it would tend to turn us away from the sole worship that can improve us. Those who would prolong it at the present day are for- getting its legitimate purpose, which was simply to direct provisionally the evolution of our best feelings, under the regency of Goal during the long minority of Humanity." Of this worship, the Christian doctrine of the incarnation might be regarded as an anticipation, and still more per- haps the mediseval worship of the Virgin^ for women, as the sex characterized by sympathy, are the fit representatives of Humanity. They mediate between Humanity and man, as Hu- manity mediates between man and the worlcL- The social But the worship of Humanity is only the system based on general principle from which the new life of religion. (l g oc i ocraC y " mus t spring, it is not " Sociocracy " itself. We have therefore to inquire what is the order of life that corresponds to this new religion. with iture. Man and Nature. S3 I Lav does it modify our ideas of the relation of men to each other and to the world? And what light does it cast upon the various forms of social existence, upon the Family, the State, and the Church ? I can only give a brief resume of Gomte's answers to these questions. All e£vftiss#i©» or improvement depends ulti- Man in conflict mately on man's control over material resources, w over the powers and products of nature. And, on the other hand, it is the reactive influence upon himself of the effort by which he appro- priates and adapts these resources to his purposes, which first civilizes and educates him. Man can only conquer nature by obeying her laws, and to obey these laws he must know them. Hence it is the necessities of the practical life which excite the first efforts after scientific knowledge, and it is under the pressure of the same necessi- ties that man first learns to surrender self-will to the discipline of regular labour, and of co-opera- tion with his fellows. "We might indeed imagine a different kind of education for the human race. If mankind generally, like some of the richer classes, were placed in circumstances in which, without effort or struggle, they could at once w 34 The Social Philosophy of Gomte. satisfy all their natural wants and desires, we might imagine that social sympathies and intel- lectual tastes would soon prevail over all the personal or egoistic tendencies. For though the latter were at first far the strongest, they would gradually die out for lack of occasions for exer- cise. Losing thus the powerful stimulus of self- interest, which drives us to investigate the laws of nature, the intellectual activity of such beings would take an aesthetic direction, and would be devoted mainly to the task of providing forms of expression for the social sympathies. These social sympathies would become intense, for they would occupy the whole of life. But they would in the first instance be confined in the circle of the family ; for the social life of States gains its principal interest from the ever-widening co- operation which is required in the struggle for •existence against external difficulties. The nat- ural creed of men would be an aesthetic Fetich- ism ; and this, in the course of time, when men had learned to distinguish between action and life, would be changed into Positivism without needing to pass through the long intermediate stages of theology and metaphysics ; while, in A Beneficent Necessity. 35 the practical life, the affection of the family would broaden to the love of humanity, omit- ting the middle term of nationality. Finally, as the heart and the intelligence would continu- ally gain a more marked ascendency over the practical activity, it would be natural that the spiritual power should rule the temporal, and that women should have the supremacy over men. This ideal, however, only serves to illustrate by uses of this con- contrast the real course of things, which indeed flict - continually advances towards the same goal, but by a far longer and more stormy path, a path not of untroubled and peaceful growth, but of conflict, division, and pain. We shall find, how- ever, as a kind of recompense for this hard pro- cess of mediation, that the final reconciliation of humanity with the world and with itself is far more perfect and conclusive, as it is a reconcilia- tion which subordinate^, while it satisfies, all the different elements of his nature. For a " sociality," reared on the basis of a fully developed yet con- quered " personality," is a far higher ideal than such an imagined paradise, in which the struggle for existence, with all the intellectual and physical lines his moral nature 36 The Social Philosojihy of Comte. exertion which it involves, would be made un- necessary, it awakens Our personal tendencies are strongest at first, and discip- and in their direct action they might lead, and do indeed often lead, to a sacrifice of society to the individual, and to the development in him of an extravagant pride and self-will, by which both heart and reason are corrupted. But man soon finds that he must stoop to conquer ; that he must submit his action to the laws of nature, if he would make nature the servant of his pur- poses ; that he must himself be instrumental to the well-being of others ere he can make them instruments of his own well-being. And in this submission of caprice and passion to reason and law, and of his own life to social ends, he gradually developes his intellectual powers and social sympathies till they gain a supremacy over those egoistic tendencies to which in the first instance they were subordinated. The highest ideal of man's life is to systematize this spon- taneous process, and to turn into a conscious aim that moral and intellectual discipline of his nature, which in the past has been the unfore- seen result of his effort after personal ends. We Necessity makes us Free. 37 must, however, remember that this result would not have been possible unless the beginnings of these higher tendencies had existed in man from the first. No empirical process could ever have developed social sympathies in him, if he had been by nature utterly selfish, any more than it could have produced reason in a being who was devoid of even the germ of intelligence. But the whole history of human progress is just an account of the process whereby feeble social affections, using as a fulcrum the outward neces- sities of man's life, gradually secure to themselves the direction of all his activity. " The principal triumph of humanity consists in drawing its best means of perfecting itself from that very fatality which seems at first to condemn us to the most brutal egoism." For, " so soon as the personal instincts have placed us in a situation proper to satisfy our social tendencies, these, in virtue of their irresistible charm, commonly guide us to a course of conduct which they could not have had at first the force to dictate." These principles find their illustration in cer- Economical . , T . . . and social tain economical truths. in most conditions m progress. which human beings are placed, the individual is 38 The Social Philosophy of Comte. capable of producing more than is immediately necessary for his wants ; or, in other words, of accumulating wealth. Such accumulations make social existence possible, and coming, by gift or conquest, into the hands of the heads of society, become the means of realizing a division of labour, and providing the different classes of labourers with sustenance and instruments of production- Division of labour, again, while it secures increased efficiency, makes continually greater demands upon science for guidance, and thus stimulates the development of the intellectual life. Thus the hard external conditions under which man has to seek the satisfaction of his wants become a beneficent necessity, which forces him to increase his knowledge, and to co-operate with an ever-widening circle of his fellow-men. This co-operation, indeed, is not always conscious ; and, even when it is con- scious, it is not necessarily accompanied by social sympathy, as is shown by the fierce industrial struggles of capital with labour at the present day. Yet it is inevitable that it should in the long run produce a sense of the solidarity of mankind. " As each one really The Forms of Social Life. 39 labours for the others, in the end he must ac- quire the consciousness that he does so labour," and the consciousness of being a part in a greater whole must produce a willingness to serve it and live for it. Thus, a movement beginning in the reactive influence on man's activity of the phy- sical conditions of his life, extends its effects gradually to his intelligence and his heart, so that the order of the elements of his nature becomes, as it were, inverted ; the first becomes last, and the last first. And, instead of the self- concentration of the savage, we have the develop- ment of a social impulse, which begins by setting the family before the individual, which goes on to set the state before the family, and which must end in setting humanity before all. The way in which this movement is accom- ]^ e n ^ l lf society plished, and the form of social life in which it ' must result, are determined by principles that have already been suggested. The abstract ele- ments of human life, of which we are to take account, are material, intellectual, and moral force, corresponding respectively to the will, the intelli- gence, and the heart. And these again correspond to three forms of association among men — the 40 The Social Philosophy of Comte. State, the Church, and the Family ; three partial societies, in the union of which alone man can attain the complete satisfaction of his complex being. It is scarcely necessary to intimate, however, that this general correspondence of the abstract and concrete divisions is not meant to imply that any one of these forms of society is purely material, purely intellectual, or purely based upon affection. ' The great whole of the universal society is made up of parts which are like it, and are themselves wholes ; and in every one of them we can make a division of material, intellectual, and moral powers. Still, with this reservation, we may say generally that the bond which holds the family together is one of affec- tion ; that the bond of the state is one of action, or material purpose ; and that the bond of hu- manity is the spiritual bond of intelligence. And further, that, as in the Family the tone and temper of the whole society is determined by the women, so the tone and temper of the State is determined by the practical classes, warlike or industrial ; and the tone and temper of the Church by the priest- hood, theological or scientific.,,- It is one main design of Comte's sociology to organize and put Principles of Social Union. 41 in their proper relation to each other the three great social powers, which have successively es- tablished their claims in the long history of human development. The dawn of civilization saw the organization of the family, under the guidance of Fetichism. Polytheism taught men to combine in a civil society, under the guidance of a power in which temporal and spiritual au- thority were confused together. Finally, Mono- theism separated the secular and spiritual powers, and established a certain provisional equilibrium between them. Metaphysic was powerful only to destroy ; but by sapping the foundations of the theological system it prepared the way for Positivism, by which Family, State, and Church are finally to be distinguished and harmonized, or fixed in their proper organic relations to each other, so as to preclude for ever their warfare or intrusion upon each other's provinces. In determining the nature and relation of these The organi- three forms of social union, Comte lays down two gg^ 1 principles. The first is, that there can be no society without a government, any more than there can be a government, or effective power among men, without a society. " A true social 42 The Social Philosophy of Comte. force is the result of a more or less extended co-operation, gathered up into an individual organ." It is a result in which many are con- cerned, yet which finds its final expression through the will of one. As to the former point, that a social basis of force is necessary,. Comte says that " there is nothing individual, except physical force," and even physical force is very limited when it is merely individual. Every other kind of power, whether intellectual or moral, is essentially social, dependent on the co-operation of many minds in the present, and generally also on a slow accumulation of energy in the past. As Goethe said, " It is not the solitary man that can accomplish anything, but only he who unites with many at the right time." Nor, on the other hand, can we have social force without government. The concurrence of many can never be really effective, until it finds an in- dividual organ to gather it up, and concentrate it to a definite result. Sometimes the individual comes first, fixes his mind on a determinate pur- pose, and then gathers to himself the various partial forces which are necessary to achieve it. More often in the case of great social movements, Natural and Spiritual Rule. 43 there is a spontaneous convergence of many par- ticular tendencies, till, finally, the individual appears who gives them a common centre, and binds them into one whole. But in all cases the effective co-operation, the real social force, is not present till it has thus concentrated and individualized itself. The second principle is one that has been outward subordina- already illustrated. It is, in Comte's view, the ^° f t0 law of the world that the higher should imme- diately subordinate itself to the lower. Thus the organic finds its life controlled and limited by the inorganic world, and man has to work out his destiny in submission to all the necessi- ties, physical, chemical, and vital, which are pre- supposed in his existence. The higher, therefore, can overcome the lower only by obedience ; if it is to conquer, it must at least " stoop to conquer." And this law holds equally good in the case of the social life of man. As it is the satisfaction of material wants that is, and must be, the first motive of his life, so it is in the effort to main- tain his outward existence, and to employ the re- sources of nature for the satisfaction of his desires, that his powers are first excited and disciplined. <•«■ 44 The Social Philosophy of Comte. Hence it is the practical activities — military or industrial according to the state of civilization — which must bear the immediate rule in his life ; not because they are the highest, but be- cause they are the indispensable basis of every- thing else. Moral and intellectual influences can only come in afterwards, in the second place, to modify the ruthless energy of the practical life. They are essentially restraining, correcting, guid- ing, and not in the first instance stimulating or originative forces. It is when they act in this indirect way that they are really most efficient, and their direct action, if it were possible, would defeat itself. Their purity cannot be secured except by their withdrawal from the sphere of action and command ; their power is dependent on their self-abnegation and rejection of imme- diate authority and rank. They cease to in- fluence men when they begin to dominate. jSTay, even if their purity were secured, and they could reign without rivals, we have seen that they would produce a less beneficent result than when they come in as moderators. The purely " altruistic " and intellectual being, in , whom personal motives did not exist, would Woman and the Family. 45 have a less exalted ideal of life set befor< him than one in whom the personal motives exist in all their energy, but are remoulded in conformity with social interests. On this basis we have to consider the order The Family, of the Family, the State, and the Church. The family is the first instrument of man's social education. It takes him at the lowest point, to raise him to the highest. Its life is the " only natural mediation which can habitually disengage us from pure personality, to raise us gradually to true sociability." In it the man, according to the above principle, must bear rule, though it be the woman, who, "par I'affectueuse reaction du conseil sur le commandcmcnt" ultimately deter- mines the spirit of the society. A shadow also of the other spiritual power, the power of intelli- gence, often appears in the family, especially in the early patriarchal societies, in the customary authority given to the moderating counsel of the elders who are beyond the age for active service. The State is the peculiar sphere of the active The state. or secular power, which, after being military, has now become distinctly industrial. During the 46 The Social Philosophy of Comte. military stage, the harmony of the different classes in the State was less difficult to preserve, seeing that common danger bound together the soldier classes, and confirmed their fidelity to their leaders ; while, in general, the industrial offices were committed to slaves or serfs, who were deprived of all political power. The change to an industrial order of political life brings with it many dangers to the unity of the State, especi- ally as it has taken place at a time when the old theological basis of belief is undermined. Hence the already difficult task of organizing society, on the basis of individual freedom and without the external pressure of danger, is rendered still more difficult. The capitalists, who are the natural leaders of an industrial society, have often been wanting in the con- sciousness of their social function, and in their conduct towards their workmen, and towards each other, have been given up to the action of personal motives. On the other hand, the labourers, or " proletaires," filled with the new sense of independence and excited by revolu- tionary doctrines of individual right, have lost the sense of loyalty, and have filled their minds Church and State. 47 with Utopias of equality, which really involve the negation of the division and co-operation of labour — i.e., of all social organization. The aim of all social reform, therefore, must he to bring hack that willing subordination to leaders inspired by the sense of social duty, which characterized the military regime in its best form. But this, in the decay of theology, and the consequent loss of influence by the Catholic Church, requires the development of a new social doctrine based upon science, and the rise of a new spiritual power to teach and apply it to modern society. The State cannot be perfectly organized without the revival of the Church, for it is the wider spiritual unity of humanity that alone can give renewed strength to the bonds of material order in the State. The great achievement of the Middle Ages The church, was the separation of the spiritual from the temporal power. This has often been taken as a historical accident, but really it was the necessary expression of the true relation of theory and practice, which, in their demands and re- quirements, are essentially opposed, and which therefore cannot be fully developed except in 48 The Social Philosophy of Comte. '-. relative independence of each other. Theory is general, and cannot attain its highest point unless it is universal. Practice is particular, and its greatest success is the fruit of concentration upon special circumstances and objects. Theory there- fore becomes stunted, and loses its freedom and impartiality, if it is brought into close connection with the narrower aims of the outward life. Practice, on the other hand, loses little by the egoism of personal will and desire, and, indeed, within proper limits requires it. To gain the full benefit of this distinction, we must adopt with all its consequences the mediaeval division of clergy and laity, Church and State. On the one hand, therefore, we must reduce the State to the dimensions of a city, with its proper complement of rural domain, " for experience has proved that the city, when completed, and sufficiently supported by material resources, is the largest political society that can be produced and maintained without oppression " ; as it is also the society which secures the most definite and specialized reaction of man's social activity on the physical medium by which he is sur- rounded. Further, within the city so constituted. The Social Order. 4Q we must have as intensive a division of labour as possible, the government being concentrated in the hands of those capitalists whose occupa- tions are of the greatest generality (i.e., the bankers) ; the other capitalists (merchants, manu- facturers, and agriculturists) taking their rank according to the same principle ; and the pro- letaires following, organized in fraternal equality. Finally, the various offices are to be handed down from one generation to another according to the principle of " heredite* sociocratique," each official choosing his successor, subject to the approval of his superiors ; for this, and not the anarchic principle of the choice of superiors by inferiors, is the true modern principle of govern- ment, which succeeds to the old method of inheritance by birth. On the other hand, the order of the priesthood is to be in everything the exact opposite of the order of the laity. In the first place, motives of personal interest are to be excluded, so far as possible, from their lives. There is to be no competition of trade among them, but all spiritual work is to be paid by salaries from the public, and these salaries are to be fixed at so low a rate, even D •50 The Social Philosophy of Comte. in the case of the highest members of the order, that there shall be no inducement to enter the order from motives of cupidity. In the second place, although there will necessarily be a certain subordination of rank, in order to secure discipline and combined action, and all the priesthood will be arranged in a hierarchy under the "grand Pretre de l'Humanite," yet there must be no specialization of function, or division of labour among them. The modern anarchy of science is, as Comte maintains, due to the fact, that scientific men are mostly specialists ; and his priests there- fore are to be trained in all science, from mathe- matics, through physics, chemistry, and biology, to sociology and morals — for which last all the other sciences are to be regarded, as preparatory. In this way the "esprit d'ensemble" will prevail among them, and science will be preserved from its present uncertain aberrations into regions from which no gain can be brought back for the fur- therance of humanity. Nay, Comte appears to regard even the separation of Art from Science as a step toward anarchy, and demands that his priesthood should be the artistic as well as the philosophic teachers of men. At the . same time The Work of the Priesthood. 51 they must avoid, as the most fatal source of cor- ruption, all tendency to interfere more directly in practical affairs. Their business is to "modify the wills, without ever commanding the acts of men," and they cannot preserve the universality which is their characteristic without a complete renunciation of the right to compel. The farthest point to which they may go in this direction, is to excommunicate, or affix a social stigma on offen- ders ; which, however, in a positivist society, will be a sufficiently severe punishment. Such a priesthood will be the natural repre- The priest . • r> i • hood of sentatives of the unity or solidarity of mankind, as humanity, opposed to the particular interests of individuals and classes. They will also be the represen- tatives of the continuity of the life of humanity, in the past and the future, as opposed to the excessive claims of the present hour. It will be their duty to make men conscious that their occupations are social functions, and that every- thing that is valuable in their lives has been gained for them by the long-continued labours of humanity, whose gratuitous gifts it is their highest privilege to preserve, and hand down increased by their own contributions to posterity. The 52 The Social Philosophy of Comte. clergy will thus be, as in the old system, the natural allies of the women; for what they have to do is simply to generalize and support, by a complete scientific view of the world and of human life, those lessons of the heart which are first learned by man in the narrower circle of the family. By their encyclopaedic view of know- ledge, the intelligence, which under the dispersive regime of science has become a rebel against the heart, is to be brought back to its allegiance, and the civic and human relations to be reconstituted on the type of the family. Thepracti- In impressing such a view of life upon man- calworkof r O JT the chmcb. kindj the p ositivist Church will avail itself of all the aids of art, and will use the power of imagin- ation to fill up those voids and imperfections which sober science undoubtedly leaves in our knowledge of things. For it is the function of poetry not merely to give body and substance to the necessarily abstract ideas of science ; it may even, justifiably, outrun the possibilities of know- ledge, though in that case we must not forget the unverified nature of the illusions to which we yield. In the first of these uses Art will give precision and force to the worship of Humanity, Poetry and Truth. 53 or of its representative — Woman. It will provide language for those exercises of prayer and praise, by which we make vivid and real to ourselves our union with others, and dedicate ourselves to a life of " Altruism." It will thus intensify and deepen the subjective life, through which past humanity lives in us, and enable us to look forward with joy to our only personal reward, that of being incorporated in Humanity, and living again in the subjective life of others. For " toute Ve'ducation liu maim doit preparer ehacun a vicrc pour autrui, " the dynamic laws of weight would still be unknown to us, unless we had first abstracted all consideration of the resistance, or the motion, of the atmosphere or other medium." The science of political economy is based on an effort to isolate, so far as is possible, the econo- mical from all the other conditions of social life. In short, all the separate sciences, in this point of view, are abstract ; and they tend to become more and more abstract as the scientific division of labour increases. That is, they tend to con- fine themselves to the investigation of certain Philosophy corrects Abstraction. 87 definite relations of objects, leaving out of ac- count all their other relations ; or (what comes to much the same thing) to the examination of certain definite objects, without taking into account their manifold relations to other objects. Now, as Comte himself says, " these preliminary simplifications without which there could be no such thing as science in the true sense of the word, always involve a corresponding process of recomposition, when prevision of actual fact is called for." To attain a complete view of the truth, we must return from the abstraction of the isolated sciences to the unity of nature, in which all these separate objects and relations are brought together, and in which they modify and determine each other. And philosophy only goes a step farther in the same direction, when it corrects that abstraction from the thinking self, the unity of knowledge, which is common to all the sciences. The only difference is, that the abstraction of science from the unity of the objective world, as it is the result of a definite act of thought, is generally conscious ; while the abstraction which philosophy seeks to correct is generally unconscious. The geometrician cannot 88 The Social Philosophy of Comte. but see that there are other than spatial con- ditions of existence, and that, for his own pur- poses, he has left all such conditions out of account. But it is quite possible, as every day's experience proves, to investigate the laws of the intelligible world, without ever adverting to its necessary relation to the intelligence, and without being conscious of the abstractness of a view of things, in which this relation is left out of account. Philosophy, therefore, has to detect and bring to the light of day certain facts or relations which enter into the constitution of things, which indeed are presupposed in all our consciousness of them, but which, never- theless, generally escape without notice. Of this work of philosophy or metaphysics, how- ever, Comte has no idea, or he confuses it with the methods of an empirical psychology, which, by an opposite abstraction, would separate the thinking mind from the world to which it is related. But the method of philosophy is not mere abstraction ; it is rather, if the expression may be allowed, concretion. Philosophy, as Hegel said, is " thinking things together " — i.e., thinking them in a unity that transcends Philosophy is Self-consciousness. 89 and explains their differences ; or, if it ever abstractly considers the unity and movement < )f thought in itself, it is only (as geometry abs- tractly considers the relations of space) in order more surely and clearly to discern that unity and movement in all the objects of thought. It is to Kant, principally, that this new way ^^ Ac of stating the problem of philosophy is due ; but S^otus guiding it would be altogether a mistake to suppose that principles, he essentially 'changed the problem itself. Meta- physicians, from the time of Socrates and Plato, have always sought to get beyond the presuppo- sitions of the ordinary consciousness, and to re- mould that consciousness by bringing to light the principles upon which it rests. One of the best definitions that has been given of philosophy is " clear self-consciousness." And it is, indeed, just this character of metaphysical thought which renders plausible Comte's attack upon it. It is in the metaphysical writers of the past that we can most clearly discern the errors of the past, for by these writers the errors of the past are not merely implied and presupposed, but explic- itly stated. Hence such writers are continually suffering from that natural illusion by which we DO The Social Philosophy of Comte. take, as the prominent representatives of an idea or tendency of thought, those authors by whom it has been most distinctly expressed ; whereas it is rather they who first enable us, even if they do not enable themselves, to see the limitations of that idea or tendency, and to transcend it. But as it is in the metaphysicians that we find the clearest and most definite expressions of those defective principles of past thought which we are seeking to transcend, it is not unnatural that we should attribute the defect itself to metaphysic. What, however, is really due to metaphysic is not the error, but rather that clearness and de- finiteness of its expression which makes our re- futation of it and our higher point of view pos- sible. Thus the limit of Greek thought, the point at which, by its own development, it falls into error and self-contradiction, would have been by no means so easy to discern, if its presup- positions had not been raised into ideal clearness in the works of Plato and Aristotle. The indi- vidualism of the Stoics and Epicureans gives us a key, which we would otherwise want, to those new experiences of independence and isolation which came to men under the Empire of Borne, after Philosophy and Progress. 91 the breaking up of the ancient municipal organ- ization of social life. Descartes and Spinoza re- veal the open secret of that new view of the relation of man to God, which was partly ex- pressed by Luther and Calvin, and which was so powerful in moulding the political and social life, especially of Protestant countries, and in awak- ing in them a consciousness of individual and national independence, combined with a still more intense consciousness that the individual is noth- ing, except as the servant of a higher power. Hence it was in a criticism of these philosophies that Locke and Leibnitz found the starting-point for their fuller assertion of the claims of the indi- vidual. Finally, it is through a struggle with Individualism, especially in its fullest expression in Hume and Rousseau, that Kant and his sue- cessors in Germany, and Comte in France, were led to that higher organic idea in which the indi- vidual and universal cease to be opposed to each other as reality to fiction, and come to be re- garded as different but complementary aspects of reality. If we no longer say, "The universal alone is real, and the individual is an abstrac- tion ; " or, " The individual alone is real, and the 92 The. Social Philosophy of Comtc. universal is a name ; " but, " The individual is real, but only as the realization of the universal, and the universal is real, but only as manifesting itself in the individual," it is due to the whole past movement of philosophic thought. Nor, again, would it be difficult to show that the suc- cesses or failures of science at different times were closely connected with the sufficiency or insufficiency of the ultimate principles of think- ing then acknowledged or presupposed. For it is the development of man's spirit which en- ables him to ask and to answer new questions in regard to the world of objects ; nor can his growing knowledge of that world be separated from his growing consciousness of himself. To one who regards metaphysic from this point of view, its continual apparent failures will be as little suggestive of a despair of philosophy as the fall of the Greek State, or of the feudal system, is suggestive of a disbelief in the possibility of social and political life. It may even be said that no stage of culture, no limited form of human thought or existence, is ever completely exhausted and transcended, till it has risen to a clear consciousness of itself in a metaphysic, or Metaphysic of Positivism. {)'■> something' of the nature of a metaphysic. It is the disentanglement of the principle, the cen- tral idea, the fundamental category, which has pre- viously ruled men almost without their knowing- it, that first enables them to see its value and relation to that unity of the whole, with which it was necessarily confounded so long as it re- mained merely a moving force in the depths of the popular mind. Comte himself was meta- physical, in so far as he sought to transcend the one-sided and imperfect categories of earlier philosophy, and to reconcile them by means of a higher thought. His defect lay in this, that he was not metaphysical enough, that his analysis of his own thought was imperfect, and that la- was therefore the instrument of a movement of human intelligence, of the meaning of which lie was never clearly conscious. Otherwise he would have perceived that his " positive " stage was not simply a negation of the metaphysical and theological stages which preceded it and a return to fact and experience, hut that it was essentially a new reading of experience, which implied, therefore, a new form of metaphysics and theology. 94 The Social Philosophy of Comte. Comte's It is this unconsciousness of his own fuiida- unconscious- . . nessofws mental categories, which explains Comte s radical own guiding principles, misconception of the whole history of theology and metaphysics. The third stage of Positivism is not the unity which transcends, while it re- conciles, the previous stages of human develop- ment ; on the contrary, it involves the total re- nunciation of those principles of thought which had prevailed during the two previous stages. According to this view, all that we can say is, that a germ of positive thought existed from the first, and that, by its development, theology and meta- physics were gradually driven from the whole sphere of knowledge. Positivism is thus the concentration of human thought within certain limits, which at first it did not respect, but which it gradually learns to be, for it, impassable. And the only result of the process is, that the whole field of the non-phenomenal is abandoned to poetry, which is still to be permitted under certain restrictions to fill up the vacant spaces of the unknowable with shapes drawn according to our wishes. Theology and metaphysics are but more or less thinly disguised anthropo- morphisms, which once subserved a social pur- Development by Negation. 95 pose, and which apart from that purpose have no value for the intelligence; nor is there any element of truth in them which needs to be preserved under the new intellectual regime. Their history was not a development, but a purely negative pro- cess — a process whereby they became attenuated and dissolved, until the rich concrete meaning of the first Fetichism had entirely disappeared in the negations of the revolutionary philosophy. Mono- theism, the last religion, was but the bare ab- stract residuum of theology, as the idea of Na- ture was the last abstract residuum of meta- physics. And the whole result of the long striving of human intelligence to penetrate into the absolute is merely the knowledge of its own limits. Now, it is not too much to say that this view consequent defect in hi; involves a fundamental misrepresentation, and ^kj- the . f. i . • ment of even inversion, of the whole history ot religion religion and philosophy. Its plausibility at first sight arises from a common confusion as to the idea of abstraction. In one sense it may be said that there is no one so concrete in his view of things as the child or the savage ; in another sense, it may be said that there is no one so abstract. 96 The Social Philosophy of Comte. The mind of the child clings to the immediate images of things; it cannot rise above their pictured presence in space and time ; it cannot sever them in thought from their immediate surroundings. On the other hand, the child's thought is abstract and simple ; it confuses all things together ; it scarcely distinguishes at first between animate and inanimate, between man and animal. With Comte we may call the child a Fetichist ; not because his imagination raises all things to the level of man, but because he still lives in a simplicity or confusion of thought for which there are no distinct differences of level. On the other hand, as the child advances to maturity, the pictures of sense may partially fade, but his ideas of things become more com- plex and adequate. It ceases to be impossible for him to separate objects from the definite cir- cumstances of space and time, in which they have been at first perceived ; but at the same time, his knowledge of those objects, in their unity and difference — their permanent nature and their manifold phases and aspects — is continually growing. If, therefore, the movement of his thought, in one point of view, is toward greater Development of Religion. 97 generality and abstractness, in another point of view it is toward greater particularity and con- creteness. To use a favourite modern phrase, the development of human thought is by differen- tiation and integration, by induction and deduc- tion at once. Now Comte's history of theology and metaphysics is greatly distorted by the fact that he detects in it only a movement of general- ization and abstraction ; and not also a move- ment towards greater complexity and complete- ness. Yet, even a superficial glance at the de- velopment of religion is enough to let us see that the Christian idea of God in man is less simple and abstract than Jewish Monotheism or Oriental Pantheism. If indeed, we were to judge of a religion by mere wealth of fantastic sensuous symbolism, it might seem possible to regard the earliest religions as the richest; though even this might be disputed, seeing that the fancy of the savage Fetichist, while capricious and wayward, is at the same time singularly monotonous and uninventive. But to any one who would classify religions according to the complexity and depth of the thought involved in them, it must be apparent that they become G 98 The Social Philosophy of Comte. more full and definite — not more vague and simple — as time advances. Their progress to- ward greater universality is at the same time a progress toward greater specification. In the Indian faith we discern, from very early times, the presence of an idea of the divine unity. But it is a vague and abstract idea, and for that very reason it stands side by side with, or produces, a lawless Polytheism, in which there is neither method nor meaning ; which, as Goethe says, does not subserve the true purposes of a religion, since it adds another chaotic element to life, instead of supplying a guiding principle through all its confusion and difficulty. In the Jewish religion we have a true Monotheism, in which the unity is no longer that of an abstract sub- stance, but of a spiritual or self-conscious being — a personal will which manifests itself in a definite purpose, in a moral government of men and nations. In Christianity, finally, we have the idea of a God, who is not merely an absolute substance — not merely a Creator and Euler of the world, but a self-revealing Spirit ; a Spirit who reveals himself in, as well as to, his crea- tures — an idea which combines in one the earlier Development of Philosophy. 99 Pantheistic and Monotheistic conceptions. To regard the process in which these are three of the main stages as merely a process of abstrac- tion and negation is surely to take a most ex- ternal and superficial view of it. The truth is, that this and the similar sketch in Hume's " Dia- logues on Natural Eeligion " are rather based on a preconceived theory as to the development of human thought in religion, than on the phe- nomena of religious history. And in Comte's " Social Dynamics," he has frequently to mention facts which are altogether inconsistent with it, Nor is Comte's view of the history of meta- Defect in his view of the physic less fictitious and inaccurate. According deve , lo P; x u o ment uf to that view, the earliest philosophies ought to P BS ° P y " be the most concrete and complete, and the latest, the most simple and abstract ; but the very reverse is the fact. It is in the dawn of speculation that men are content to explain the universe by such abstractions as " being " and " becoming." The ancient philosophy contrasts with the modern, as simple with complex ; fur while the former is occupied with ques- tions about "the one" and "the many," the " universal " and the " particular," the latter is 100 The Social Philosophy of Comte. concerned from the first with the relations of self-consciousness to the objective world. Again, confining ourselves to modern phil- osophy, we find the abstract Universalism (if we may use the expression) of Descartes and Spinoza, yielding in the next generation to two opposite forms of Individualism, and ending in the attempt of Kant and his successors " to read Locke with the eyes of Leibnitz, and Leib- nitz with the eyes of Locke,""* and (we may add) to unite the elements of truth in both by a deeper view of the principle imperfectly ex- pressed in Spinoza. In short, the whole move- ment of philosophy is a movement towards a more complex, and at the same time towards a more systematic, view of the world. Philo- sophical thought is ever seeking on the one hand to distinguish, and even to oppose to each other, the different sides of truth which were at first confused together ; and again, on the other hand, to show that what were at first supposed to be contradictory, are really complementary, aspects of things. This ]3rogress of philosophy by differentiation and integration * Green's Introduction to Hume. Development of Science. 101 Oomte's theory does not explain, but it explains him. For, as has been indicated, Comte's whole view of the relation of the individual to society, and of the present to the past, manifests that same effort to concentrate and combine in one different and even opposed motives of thought which is shown in the idealistic philosophy of Germany. Only, as Comte is not conscious of this affiliation of his thought, but, on the contrary, supposes Positivism to be the simple negation of metaphysics, his possession of the higher idea shows itself, not in a new metaphysic, but only in a better comprehension of the social life and development of the race. Hence, also, he sees no positive connection between his own specula- tions and the previous history of philosophy, but connects it solely with the past progress of physical science. This inadequacy of Comte's view of the his- Defect in J- J his view of tory of philosophy and theology leads to an£° n ^ elop - opposite inadequacy in his view of the history of science. As the former is conceived by him to be a mere process of abstraction, which ends in nothing, so the latter is conceived by him — at least, in his first general account of it — purely 102 The Social Philosophy of Comte. as a movement from the abstract and general to the concrete and particular. There are thus two laws for the progress of the human mind — the law of its progress to science, and the law of its progress in science. The progress to science is merely the gradual destruction of the imaginative synthesis in which civilization began ; the process in science consists in the gradual building up of the scientific synthesis in which civilization must end. Science begins with the consideration of the simplest and most abstract relations of things, with arithmetic and geometry, and it ends with the investigation of their most complex and concrete relations^jwith sociology and morals. This, with slight modifica- tions, is the historical order of the genesis of the sciences, and, what is even more important in Comte's eyes, it is the order of their logical de- pendence or filiation, and therefore the order of a duly arranged scientific education. For each of the successive sciences — mathematics, astronomy, physics, chemistry, biology, sociology, and morals — includes a deductive part, in which it depends on previous sciences, and an inductive part, in which it makes a fresh start from experience Mr. Spencer's Criticism. 108 for itself; and therefore no one can be fully equipped for the investigation of the more com- plex, who has not made himself master of the laws of the simpler, phenomena. Like Plato, Comte would write over the portals of science, [xr] ayewiueTprjTos eicrirco, and he would add, — Let no one enter upon the study of chemistry who is not a master of the principles of physics ; upon the study of biology, who is not a master of the principles of chemistry ; nor upon the study of sociology, who is not a master of the principles of all the previous sciences. This view of the historical and logical filiation Mr. spencer's criticism of of the sciences has been attacked with consider- that view - able force in an Essay by Mr. Spencer upon the " Genesis of Science." In that Essay, Mr. Spencer points out, what, indeed, Comte himself had very fully acknowledged, that Mstoriccdly every science in turn has been an instrument in the development of the others. Even in the time of Aristotle politics and biology had made no inconsiderable advance, while as yet physics and chemistry could scarcely be said to be in existence. And this is only what was to be expected, for some knowledge of the conditions 104 The Social Philosophy of Comte. of social order is a practical condition of the development of any other kind of science ; and the necessary art of medicine forced men at a very early period to pay some attention to phy- siology. Astronomy had to wait for optics to furnish it not only with instruments but with definite conceptions of the dispersion and refrac- tion of light ; and physical investigation could not proceed very far without some kind of solution of biological and even psychological questions in relation to sense perception. It was the advance of geometry that led to the invention of algebra, and the transcendental analysis of Newton and Leibnitz was directly suggested by the problems of physics. These and many other facts of the same kind seem to show that a serial arrangement of the sciences misrepresents at once the historical order of their development and the logical order of their dependence. And in both points of view it would be nearer the truth to regard the dif- ferent sciences (as Cointe himself sometimes re- gards them) as "les diverses branches d'un tronc unique." For this " suggests the facts that the sciences had a common origin, that they have been Littre's Defence of Comte. 105 developing simultaneously, and that they have been from time to time dividing and subdivid- ing." Yet even this metaphor is inadequate, for " it does not suggest the yet more important fact that the divisions and subdivisions thus arising do not remain separate, but now and again re- unite in direct and indirect ways. They inos- culate ; they severally send off and receive connecting growths ; and the intercommunion has been ever becoming more frequent, more intricate, more widely ramified. There has all along been higher specialization that there might be a larger generalization ; and a deeper analysis that there might be a better synthesis. Each larger generalization has lifted sundry special- izations still higher; and each better synthesis has prepared the way for still deeper analysis.""" To these objections, Comte would probably -^^0°^ have answered,! as Littre has answered for him, tSpencer - that there is a difference between the determi- nation of some of the laws of a particular class of phenomena and the constitution of a science of these phenomena ; and that a science cannot * Spencer's "Essays," i. p. 145. tCf. Pol. Pos. i., Introduction Fondamentale passim. 106 The Social Philosophy of Comte. be regarded as constituted till its inductive and deductive parts are separated. It cannot be denied that physics involves all the relations discussed in mathematics, and something more ; that chemistry involves all the relations dis- cussed in physics, and something more; that biology involves all the relations discussed in physics and chemistry, and something more ■ and that sociology involves the relations dis- cussed in all the previous sciences, and something more. Now, it is a hopeless task for the weak human intellect to deduce this "something more" in the more complex, from the principles of the less complex sciences, even if absolutely such a deduction is possible. Hence we cannot regard a science as constituted, until its special subject- matter has been separated from the subject-matter of the simpler sciences, and until, in relation to that subject-matter, certain laws have been de- termined which cannot be deduced from the principles of those sciences. Thus, in Comte's opinion, biology was not constituted as a science until, in quite modern times, the phenomena of life were seen at onCe in their relative depend- ence on, and their relative separation from, The Universal and the General. 107 physical and chemical phenomena. Nor could sociology be constituted as a science until, by Comte himself, the law of social development was determined, and the phenomena of human life were thereby separated from phenomena of life in general, which fall under the province of biology. In this sense, therefore, it is argued that the historical and the logical order of the sciences are coincident ; and that, while it is quite true that the advance of one of the simpler sciences is often stimulated by recpaire- ments of the more complex sciences, it is equally true that the more complex science has to wait for the development of the simpler science, ere it can rise above its first empirical stage. It would be beyond the scope of this volume, Ambiguity of the opposi- even if it were in the power of the writer, to {jj^J^raai discuss in all their bearings these different views particular, as to the arrangement of the sciences ; but it may be remarked that the most important of Mr. Spencer's objections are directed, not against the specific account which Comte gives of the his- torical and logical relations of the sciences, but rather against his assertion that science pro- gresses from the general to the particular, from 108 The Social Philoso r £jhy of Comte. the abstract to the concrete. That progress, he maintains, is " at once from the special to the general, and from the general to the special." If arithmetic comes before geometry, and geo- metry before physics ; on the other hand it is equally true, that geometry comes before algebra, and algebra before transcendental analysis, in which mathematics reaches its highest general- ization. The " special " geometry of the ancients is contrasted by Comte himself with the " gen- eral" geometry of the moderns, and the New- tonian theory of gravitation was more general than the laws of Kepler, by the aid of which it was discovered. Now, looking at such illustra- tions as these by which Mr. Spencer supports his case, we cannot but think that the controversy really turns upon the ambiguity of " general " or " abstract," to which reference has been made ; and that in spite of what both Comte and his critic have said about the different meanings that may be given to these words, neither of them has consistently kept in view the difference between the " general " with which science be- gins, and that with which it ends. In one sense of the word, transcendental analysis is The Universal as Principle. 10D more "general" than arithmetic and algebra, but in another sense it is more specific. For transcendental analysis includes and explains both arithmetic and algebra, and casts its light even beyond their sphere ; but it does so, not by becoming vaguer and less definite, but quite the contrary. It is a universal that does not leave out of account the differences of the par- ticulars included under it, but rather determines them more fully. And the same thing may be said of the laws of Newton as contrasted with the laws of Kepler. It is easy enough to reach the general, if all that is wanted is a common element ; for in that case we need only to ab- stract from everything but the simple idea of " being," and we have at one step reached the top of the logical tree of Porphyry, the highest universal of thought. But the universal of science and philosophy is something different from this ; it is not merely a generic name, under which things are brought together, but a principle which unites them and determines their relation to each other. It is a unity, the thought of which does not exclude, but rather is correlative with, a knowledge of the differences. 110 The Social Philosophy of Comte. In this point of view the Platonic view of science, as a search for unity and the universal, and the Aristotelian view of it as a search for difference and the particular, are but opposite sides of the shield of knowledge, which cannot be separated from each other. Now the defect of Comte's general description of the progress of science is, that he has chosen to look solely at one side of the shield, and to regard it merely as a movement of specification ; and the conse- quence is, that in the sequel he is obliged continually to correct himself, and to observe in particular cases that it involves also a move- ment of generalization. Mr. Spencer sees both sides, and therefore progress is for him a move- ment at once of differentiation and integration ; yet in his criticism of Comte, and in his " First Principles," there are passages in which he seems to confuse the universal of science with a mere abstraction or logical genus, and to overlook the essential correlativity and inter- dependence of the two opposite movements of thought* The defects of both writers, however, * Mr. Spencer, it may be remarked, takes, like Comte, a negative view of the progress of religion, and to him, Comte's Negations. Ill lie mainly on the metaphysical side ; in their analysis of the idea of development more than in their application of it. And it is the power and fertility of resource with which they apply it to life and history, which gives them, and especially which gives Comte, a claim to an important place among modern philosophical writers. In this chapter I have tried to trace to their origin Comte's ideas of social and intel- lectual development, and to examine the motives winch led him to reject theology and metaphysics, as legitimate forms of science. In the following chapter I shall go on to consider more carefully the subjective synthesis by which he would supply their place. therefore, the last religion is the worship of the Un- known, and, indeed, of the Unknowable. But Comte practically retracts this view when he makes the worship of Humanity the last form of religion. 112 The Social Philoso'phy of Comte. _ CHAPTEE III. THE POSITIVE OK CONSTRUCTIVE SIDE OF COMTE'S PHILOSOPHY HIS SUBSTITUTES FOR METAPHYSIC AND THEOLOGY. His recognition of the need of substitutes for Theology and Meta- physic — His assertion that his philosophy is relative and subjec- tive — Double meaning of the relativity of knowledge as involving the assertion or the denial of real or absolute knowledge — ■ Collision of Comte's earlier and later views on this point — Comte's subjective synthesis not subjective in the sense of Indi- vidualism, nor yet in the sense that a conscious subject is im- plied in all objects — His compromise between these opposite theories — His doctrine that man sees the world in ordine ad hominem but not in ordine ad universum — Impossibility of separating nature from man or of criticising the whole system to which man belongs — Defects of Comte's religion according to his own idea of religion — Schisms in the school of Comte. In the preceding chapter I have tried to explain how Comte was led to treat Metaphysics and Theology as merely transitional forms of human thought, and to show that this view not only in- volves a false conception of their nature, but also His View of Development. 113 necessitates an entire misrepresentation of the course of their historical development. To re- gard the history of Metaphysics and Theology as a purely negative process, by which the first con- crete fulness of religious conceptions was gradually attenuated till nothing remained but the bare ab- stract idea of Nature, and, on the other hand, to think of the history of science as the correspond- ing positive process, by which the mind of man advanced from the general to the special, from the investigation of the simplest numerical and spatial relations of things to the knowledge of the complex social nature of man — this is a view of man's intellectual history, recommended by its simplicity and clearness, as well as by its corre- spondence with the most popular philosophy of the present time. But, as we have seen, it in- volves a one-sided conception of the movement of human thought in its scientific, and still more in its theological and metaphysical, aspects. Comte himself enables us to see that his first description of the history of science is incomplete, if not mis- leading; and that its movement is towards greater generality as well as towards more definite speci- fication. Now, as Metaphysic is only the clearest H 114 The Social Philosophy of Comte. form of self-consciousness, and as man's conscious- ness of himself deepens and widens with his con- sciousness of the objective world, we might ex- pect to find that Metaphysic also develops at once towards the universal and towards the particular; and when we look at the facts of the history of Philosophy we find this expectation amply realized. Nor is it otherwise with religion — which is to the heart and the imaginative intuitions of man what philosophy is to his self-conscious intelligence ; for the latest religion is at once the deepest and the richest, the most complex and the most universal. Need of sub- We cannot, however, give a completely satis- stitutes for ™id a theo- ic factory answer to Comte's criticism of Metaphysics and Theology without considering more fully the substitutes which .he would put in their place. For Comte is not simply an Agnostic; he does not deny the reality of the wants which Metaphysics and Theology have hitherto striven to satisfy; nor does he hold that these wants are, by the nature of things and of the human intelligence, for ever precluded from satisfaction. He does not, like some modern writers, reduce philosophy into a consciousness of the limits of the human mind, and relioion into a vasme awe of the Unknowable. Need of Philosophy and Religion. 115 On the contrary, lie holds that Positivism for the first time supplies complete satisfaction to all the tendencies of the many-sided nature of man, whereas all earlier systems had been obliged to purchase one kind of culture at the expense of another, — -to gratify the affections by the sacrifice of intellectual freedom, or to cultivate the intelli- gence to the neglect of the claims of the heart. To the Metaphysician he grants the necessity of a systematizing of knowledge in relation to one general principle, which shall furnish at once its first presupposition and its end. To the Theo- logian he grants that that inner harmony with self and with the world, which we call religion, can only be secured by a firm belief and trust in some " Grand Etre " who transcends and compre- hends our narrow individuality, " in whom we live, and move, and have our being." But while (in opposition to the tendencies of that scientific empiricism, to which the name of Positivism is usually given) Comte thus recognizes those claims of the intelligence and of the heart for which Philosophy and Theology had tried to provide, he still adopts as his own the empiricist condemnation of both, and seeks to show that, on the basis of 11 G The Social Philosophy of Comte. empiricism itself, we may secure the complete satisfaction of all our spiritual wants. It is to this claim of Comte, to occupy" in the name of Science the place from which Theology and Meta- physics have been expelled, that we must now direct our attention. Distinctions The contrast which Comte draws between his of subjec- jective, d r°ia- own philosophy and religion, and those of his pre- absoiute. decessors, is expressed in the words " relative " synthesis and " subjective." His purpose, he tells us, is a " subjective synthesis," while his prede- cessors had aimed at an " objective synthesis " — i.e., they had endeavoured to comprehend the world in itself, by carrying its phenomena back to an objective principle to which they are all equally related, and of which they are all the manifestations ; while he is content to take his stand on the subjective unity of the human race, a unity which has grown out of the con- scious or unconscious co-operation of all past generations, and which now manifests itself in the love and reverence of men for each other, and for the Grand Mre, Humanity, that compre- hends them all.*"" For the existence of this * I need not do more than refer to Comte's view of Relativity of Knowledge. 117 Great Being is a fact which we can empirically verify, although we are totally unable to discover the meaning of that wider objective fatality, to which ultimately the fortunes and life of man- kind are subjected. Again, Comte contrasts his own philosophy with that of his predecessors, as " relative " with " absolute." By this he means that Positivism does not seek to base itself on absolute knowledge, i.e., on that knowledge of nou- menal causes which was claimed by metaphysic, but merely on a knowledge of the laws of phe- nomena, and that, therefore, the only centre to which our knowledge can be referred and by re- ference to which it can be organized is the rela- tive centre of Humanity and not the real or abso- lute centre of the universe. Comte also often uses the word " relative " in a slightly modified sense to indicate that his philosophy takes due account of all the various conditions under which human- ity progresses towards its ideal, and does not seek to set up an absolute standard of perfection with- out reference to the necessary limitations of each stage of development. Now, as it is always best Humanity as " incorporating" only its best members with itself. Something will be said of this below. 118 The Social Philosophy of Comte. to criticize a writer by reference to his own prin- ciples and aims, I shall attempt to show that the main errors of Comte arise from his being not " subjective," not " relative " enough, even in the sense which he himself gives to these words. He is not " subjective " enough ; for in the develop- ment of his theory he admits a kind of separation between thought and existence, which a logical development of his own principles must have led him to reject. And he is not " relative " enough ; for he starts from philosophical principles which involve the denial of any necessary connection between man and the world, and even between the different elements in the nature of man, and he ends with a religion in which poetry is di- vorced from truth, and truth from poetry. Ambiguity In the first place, however, it is necessary to in the idea of relativity, dear up a certain ambiguity as to the idea of relativity. It is a commonplace of the sensation- alist and empiricist school at the present day, that we are confined to the knowledge of phenomena, and cannot rise to the knowledge of noumena, or things in themselves. Comte usually expresses this idea by saying that science is limited to the investigation of the laws of phenomena, and that Two Views of Relativity. 119 it was the error of Theology and Metaphysics to seek to determine their causes. When, however, we try to ascertain the exact force of this opposi- tion, we find that it may have two distinct mean- ings. For it is one thing to say, that Theology and Metaphysics gave false answers to a legiti- mate question, which was afterwards more cor- rectly answered by science ; and it is quite an- other thing to say that they attempted to answer a question different from the question of science, and which it is beyond the powers of the human mind to answer. Now, Comte sometimes speaks as if the error of the Theologians were simply that they sought to explain all phenomena by re- garding them as the expressions of divine wills and intelligences analogous to our own ; and as if DO / the error of the Metaphysicians were simply that they repeated this explanation in a more irra- tional form, substituting personified abstractions for Gods. At other times, he speaks as if the error of Theology and Metaphysics were that they attempted to determine the real nature of things, which can be known by us only in their phe- nomena. On the former view, Theology and Metaphysics are provisional hypotheses, in rela- 1 20 The Social Philosophy of Comte. tion to the objects of experience, which disappear when it is discovered, that many of these objects, which were at first assumed to be like man, are in many ways unlike him. On the latter view, they are pretended sciences, which do not relate to the phenomenal objects of experience at all, but to certain realities, supposed to be beneath or be- hind them. When we disentangle these two dif- ferent views from each other, we find that they do not rest on the same logical basis, and that they do not by any means imply each other. The former view implies only that our ideas of the world are confused and imperfect, and require to be continually corrected by fresh thought and experience. The latter implies that there are cer- tain objects other than phenomena, the existence of which we know, but the nature of which we gradually discover ourselves to be incapable of de- termining. It implies, in fact, that our intelli- gence can discern its own limits, or, what is the same thing, can know that there is something beyond those limits. Now while, with certain modifications we might not hesitate to grant the truth of the former of these doctrines, we should require some proof of the latter, or even of its Things in Themselves, 121 logical possibility. For by it we are brought face to face with the difficulty of conceiving how we should be able to ask questions, which— not from external circumstances, but from the essential na- ture of our intelligence — are altogether unanswer- able, and which therefore, we can say with cer- tainty, we shall never be able to answer. This, which Mr. Spencer attempts to prove — by very inadecpLiate reasonings as it seems to me — Comte assumes without any proof at all. Hence, while he pretends to renounce metaphysics, he has com- mitted himself to one of the most indefensible of all metaphysical positions. For the assertion that we know only phenomena, has no meaning except in reference to the doctrine that there are, or can by us be conceived to be, things in themselves — i.e., things unrelated to thought ; and that, while we know them to exist, we cannot know what they are. Now this dogma is simply the schol- astic realism, or what Comte calls metaphysics, in its most abstract and irrational form. It is a residuum of bad metaphysics, which, by a natural nemesis, seems almost invariably to haunt the minds of those writers who think they have re- nounced metaphysics altogether. 122 The Social Philosophy of Comte. idealistic The authority of Kant is often quoted in sup- view of the relativity of p 0r t f the doctrine of the existence of things in knowledge. r ° themselves : indeed, it seems to be the doctrine which is most generally associated with his name. But, in spite of some ambiguities, Kant was pre- cisely the writer who, by the general direction and tendency of his thought, did most to free modern speculation from such an illusion. For it was his main aim and purpose to show that the determination of objects as such, is possible only in relation to the unity of apperception, or, in other words, of self-consciousness, and by means of certain universal principles of thought which he calls the Categories. Kant, indeed, says that the objects thus known are merely pheno- mena, and that things in themselves are unknow- able. But even things in themselves are not, in his view, altogether out of relation to conscious- ness. They are thinkable, though they are not knowable ; we have a consciousness of them through the ideas of reason, though they are not objects of experience ; and our moral life, bringing with it a consciousness of freedom, turns the thought of them into a conviction of their reality. Further, the later German phil- Idealistic View of Relativity. 123 osophers, who sought to develop the principles of Kant to further issues, and to clear away the inconsistencies of his first expression and appli- cation of them, found it necessary to bridge over the gulf, which Kant had left, between faith and reason, between nouniena and phenomena. Ac- cordingly we find them insisting upon the correlation between object and subject, and pointing out that, if this correlation be taken strictly, it is a false abstraction to speak at all of tilings in themselves which are not relative to thought, or of a iioumenon which is a mere negation of the phenomenal. There can be no absolute opposite or negative of that unity of thought and being, which is presupposed in all knowledge and experience, and even to speak of its existence is to use words without meaning. As Heine says, " The distinction of objects into phenomena and nouniena, i.e., into things that for us exist, and things that for us do not exist, is an Irish bull in philosophy." Comte some- times, especially in the Politique Positive, comes near to the perception of this truth, but his full apprehension of it is prevented by the presuppo- sitions from which he started, and from which he 124 The Social Philosophy of Comte. could never completely free himself. Thus, in a passage quoted in the previous chapter,* Comte's idea seems to be that the images of things — individual objects as such — are immediately given in sense ; that the mind reacts, in the processes of abstraction and generalization, to raise perception into knowledge ; and that this knowledge, just because of its generality, is sub- jective or relative knowledge. Now this seems to be only a revival of Locke's view that general ideas are necessarily fictitious, because they are the " work of the mind." Yet, in the same paragraph Comte goes on to speak as if the one defect of our knowledge, which prevents it from being adequate to reality, were that our point of view is not quite universal, and that we are incapable of entirely freeing it * In Pol. Pos. i. 439, Comte seems to come still nearer to the Kantian principle that all existence is existence for a conscious self, but (1) he confounds this principle with the idea that there is an action and reaction between sub- ject and object, which are identified with the organism and the environment respectively ; and (2) he does not draw the necessary inference that the thing in itself is a fiction of abstract thought, or, in other words, that there is no meaning whatever in speaking of an existence which is not relative to the thinking self. Cf. Pol. Pos. iii., p. 18 seq. Uncertainty of Comte's Language. 125 from what is subjective. By comparing our views with those of other men, we can rise above individual and national prejudices, but we cannot free our views from those idola tribus, which are common to the whole human race, because we are unable to establish an)' satisfactory com- munication with the animals. Whatever may be thought of the last suggestion, the passage at least shows a view of the hindrances to knowledge which is not consistent with any absolute divi- sion between phenomena and noumena. For, if man can escape from the necessity of viewing things in online ad individuum, i.e., in relation to his individual self, he is at least on the way towards regarding them in online ad universum. This point, however, will be considered below, when we come to treat more directly of the sense in which Comte's synthesis is " subjective." Here we need only call attention to the differ- ence of this view from that which is suggested by other passages (especially in his exposition of the " law of the three stages") in which the know- ledge of relations of phenomena is contrasted with the knowledge of causes. From such passages we should gather that causes belong to an order of 126 The Social Philosophy of Comte. reality, which is absolutely hidden from us, and to the knowledge of which all our acquaintance with phenomena does not enable us to make any approximation. meiXor Tne truth seems to be fchat the absolute dis- itseif, is tinction of phenomena and noumena — resting really the universal, ag j^ joes on an i rra tional separation between thought and being— is tenable only from the point of view of a philosophy which regards the individual as the. only reality, and the universal as a name or an abstraction. From the point of view of Individualism, it was natural and even necessary for Comte to assail a metaphysic which claimed to apprehend a reality beyond and beneath the phenomenal individuals and their external relations to each other, and which found in this reality the vera causa of all pheno- menal existence. It was natural for him to maintain that such reality is unknowable for us, and that the general terms which seem to express it are mere collective names for indi- viduals, or, at best, abstract ideas of elements common to many individuals. and, there- But when Comte had so far changed his point of fore, can be ox known. v i ew as to hold that " man is a mere abstraction, Causes and Laws. 127 and that there is nothing real but humanity," he had lost the right to use such language. He had seen that the individual is an abstraction, and he was even in danger of forgetting that the mere universal is an abstraction also. Now modern metaphysic, by showing the relativity of objects to a thinking subject, has banished the idea of real entities, or things in themselves, lying behind and beyond the phenomena ; and, at the same time and by the same process of rea- soning, it has proved that the individual can- not be separated from the universal, any more than the universal can be separated from the individual. In other words, it has proved that the world cannot be conceived in the spirit of abstract nominalism as a collection of in- dividual objects and events, related merely as similar or dissimilar, or co-existent or successive, any more than it can be conceived in the spirit of scholastic realism, as a mere phenomenal appearance of certain noumenal substances, which correspond to general terms. From this point of view, the universal is at once a law and a cause ; for it is a principle of unity, which manifests itself in the differences of particulars, 128 The Social Philosophy of Comte. and through their relations binds them into one individual whole. If Comte had realized the meaning of the categories by which he was really guided, he must have altered his whole conception of the relation of metaphysic to positive science. For it was his own best achievement to apply this idea of the unity of the universal and particular to one great depart- ment of science. It was to show that society, whether in the form of the family, of the nation, or of humanity, is not merely a collection of similar individuals, but a unity of organically related members ; and that its development is not merely a succession of events, but the evolu- tion of one life which remains identical with itself through all its changes. And in this he was not refuting metaphysic, but following di- rectly in the course of the great metaphysicians of the preceding generation. It might, indeed, be shown, that none of the greatest names in philosophy — not Plato or Aristotle, not Spinoza or Leibnitz — was, strictly speaking, either a scholastic realist or a scholastic nominalist, though in all before Kant there were tendencies to one or other of these extremes. But the The Subjective Synthesis. 120 idealistic movement that took its origin with K an t — and which Comte should have criticized, if his criticism on metaphysic was to be, accord- ing to his own frequent phrase, " on the level ol his age " — had set before itself as its distinctive purpose and aim, to transcend this opposition. In that philosophy Comte would have found just what he wanted — a way of asserting the reality of the universal, which should not involve the denial of the reality of the individual. For want of this principle, the end of his system conies into contradiction with its beginning. For while Comte begins with a vehement denial of the universal as existent in itself, — a denial which is expressed in the individualistic lan- guage of the school of Locke, — he ends with an equally vehement assertion of the social uni- versal against the individualism of Rousseau. And his "subjective synthesis," even its latest form, is embarrassed by hesitations and incon- sistencies, which are due mainly to his inability to shake himself free from that implicit nom- inalism with which he had started. It is to this last point that we must now His subjj£; sis is not direct our attention. What does Comte mean sensational- 130 The Social Philosophy of Comte. by saying that the ultimate synthesis of know- ledge is " not objective but subjective " ? If we took the words in their most natural meaning, we should be led to suppose that Comte held that theory of subjective individualism, which was the logical result of Berkeley's so-called idealism, and the basis of the scepticism of Hume. Among later writers this theory has been most fully expressed in some of the works of J. S. Mill, and it is still offered by Mr. Spencer and Professor Huxley as one of the two alternative theories (the other being materialism) between which philosophy must for ever fluctu- ate. According to this view, the individual directly knows nothing except the states of his own subjectivity ; or, if he seems to know any- thing else, it is through a process of association, the result of which can never be verified, seeing that no one can go beyond the bounds of his own consciousness. Now it is obvious that, if this be the truth, " the subjective " and " the individual " go together and imply each other ; for, if we cannot transcend our own individuality, so as to apprehend other things, or come into communication with other beings, then we must Tlte Subjective which is Objective. 131 live a purely subjective life. And if, on the other hand, it can be shown that we know other tilings and beings as directly and immediately as we know ourselves, then our subjectivity is no longer a limit to us, but a "subjective synthesis " may be at the same time " objective." Now, it was one of the principal results of the German idealism to show that this latter view was the true one, and that thought is not merely a state of the individual subject as such. To speak of the consciousness of the individual as limited to the apprehension of his subjective states, is, indeed the reverse of the truth ; for jhe co n- sciousness of self implies the conscious ness of the not-self, and grows with it, and by moans of it. Wo are " a part of all that jye have kn own.'Land all that we have known is a part of us. Our life widens with our world, and is indeed the same thing from an opposite point of view. When we realize this correlativity of subject and object in knowledge, we can no longer contemplate a thinking being as merely one individual among the other individuals of the world. We are forced to recognize that the consciousness of self lifts him to a universal or central point of view, \ 132 The Social Philosophy of Comte. — a point of view which is central, not merely in relation to his own feelings and states, bnt central also in relation to the objective world. The being who knows himself as an individual is, for that very reason, not merely individual ; he can know a reality, which is not merely that of his own subjective states or sensations, and he can identify himself with an end, which is not merely his own expected pleasure. The possi- bility of an intellectual life for us, indeed, lies just in this, that we can regard — nay, that to a certain extent we cannot but regard — our own individuality from an " objective " point of view, — a point of view in which it has no more importance than other individualities ; or in which, at least, all its importance is derived from its relation to the whole of which it is a part. And the poet who said, — " Unless above himself he can Exalt himself, how mean a thing is man ! " had truly discerned that moral life also is dependent on the transformation of man's in- dividuality by this universal consciousness with which it is linked and bound up. The Subjectivity of Man. 133 Now this view of self-consciousness, as objective Nor yet is it idealism. in spite of its subjectivity, universal in spite of its individuality, necessarily leads to a conception of man, not merely as one of the many existences in the manifold universe, but as the. existence in which all the others are summed up, and through which they are to be explained. On one side of his being, indeed, we must regard him as a "part of this partial world,"* and, in this point of view, we can understand his life only in relation to the other things and beings which limit him on every side. Nay, as he is the most complex and dependent of existences, we can only rise to a satisfactory knowledge of him, after we have laid a basis for this knowledge, in the study of the simpler phenomena of the organic and inorganic world. But, on the other hand, the possibility of all this objective science — of the knowledge by man of that which is not man — lies in this, that he is not merely part of the whole, — not merely the most complex existence in the world, — but that the universal principle, the prin- ciple which gives unity to the world, manifests itself in him. It is because, as has been said, * Cf. Green's Introduction to Hume's Works, § 152. 134 The Social Philosophy of Comte. " Nature becomes conscious of itself in man," that man in his turn can read the open secret \ of Nature. In spelling out the meaning of nature and history, he is taking the true way, and indeed the only way, to the knowledge of himself; but this knowledge would be to him impossible, if the self-consciousness that makes him man were not also the principle of unity in the objective world. Comte himself has an obscure perception of this truth when he says vthat, " strictly speaking there is no phenomenon within our experience which is not in the truest sense human ; and that, not merely because it is man that takes cognizance of it, but also because, .... from a purely objective point of view, man sums up in himself all the laws of the world, as the ancients truly felt." * If Comte had only brought together the subjective and the objective unity — the unity of knowledge, and the unity of exist- ence — both of which he here finds in man, and if he had recognized the necessary relation of the two, he would have reproduced the highest lesson of /German idealism. For that lesson is that the subjective unity, the unity of self- *Pol. PosOvJ.81; Transl. 161. Microcosm and Macrocosm. 135 consciousness, which is presupposed in all know- ledge or experience of the world, must at the same time be regarded as the objective principle of its existence. The macrocosm, to use an ancient conception, of which Comte somewhere speaks with approval, can be comprehensible only to the microcosm, which finds in the great- world the means of understanding itself, just l because in another way it has in itself the key for the understanding of the world. Man can know that which is not himself, because from another point of view there is nothing in which he does not, or may not, find himself^ It follows from this that the last science, the For idealism does not science of man, in so far as it is also the ^SSS , ., to the science of mind, cannot merely be built upon objective. and added to the physical and natural sciences, but must react upon them and transform them. For, though the knowledge of man presupposes the knowledge of nature, yet, on the other hand, the knowledge of nature which we get, when we abstract from it its relation to man, is imperfect and incomplete. The true idea of nature cannot be attained except when it is viewed in relation to that being who is at once its culmination and 136 The Social Philosophy of Comte. its explanation. Or, to put this in another point of view, the intelligence which appears in man is presupposed in every object of the intelligible world. Self-consciousness is not, therefore, an episodic appearance in a world, which is unpre- pared for it, and which might exist, or be under- stood, without it. It is the revelation of the meaning; of all that went before. What Dr. Tyndall has stated not long since as the modern view of Materialism, that matter contains in itself " the promise and the potency" of life and even of mind, may be willingly accepted as an expression of their own doctrine by Idealists ; for the converse of this proposition is, that mind is the " realization," and therefore the only key to the ultimate nature, of matter. Hence all the sciences which treat of the mathematical, physical, chemical, and vital relations of things, must be regarded as hypothetical and based upon abstraction ; for thought, spirit, mind, is implied in all such relations, nor can a complete or adequate conception of them be attained, until we have regarded the self-consciousness that makes us men as, in this point of view, not only the last, but also the first, not merely Idealistic Tendencies in Comte. 137 the end, but also the beginning of nature. In this sense the analytic separation of the sciences from each other and from thought must be modi- fied and corrected in a final synthesis, which will indeed be " subjective," in so far as it brings into view the unity of the subject presupposed in all knowledge. But to one who has understood the full meaning of the process, this " subjective synthesis " will also be objective ; and, indeed, it alone will be able to vindicate, while it explains, the limited objectivity of the other sciences. No w__it is Comte's merit that he altogether He ends, therefore, in repudiates that false subjective synthesis, which na < [° i r :ipro ' was the natural result of the principles of Locke and Berkeley. Rejecting the doctrine that what we know immediately is only the states of our own consciousness, he takes his stand at an objective point of view, and arranges the sciences in an objective order, which begins with the inorganic world, and ends with man as the most complex of all existences. On the other hand, it is also his merit that he sees the necessity of that true " subjective synthesis " which arises from the reaction of the last science, the science of i 138 The Social Philosophy of Comte. man, upon those that went before it ; or, in other words, from the perception that man is not merely the end, but also in a sense the begin- ning of nature. But this ultimate correction and re-organization of science from a subjective point of view appears in Comte in a distorted and imperfect form, in a form that leaves " sub- jective " and " objective " synthesis still opposed to each other, or only gives room for an artificial or external reconciliation between them. For Comte (in spite of all he says of relativity) does not clearly recognize the subjectivity implied in our first objective knowledge of the world;* and, hence, when he introduces the subjective side of that knowledge, he seems to be starting from a new and independent point of view, and not simply to be bringing into clear consciousness what was presupposed in the previous movement of thought. In other words, the subjective syn- thesis of Comte does not arise from a perception that the subjectivity of men is universal, and therefore objective. On the contrary, he denies the possibility of discovering any principle of unity in the objective world, and maintains that * Pol. Pos. i. 420. The Subjective Principle. 139 the objective sciences, when left to themselves, tend towards the " divagations indefinies " of a wayward and lawless curiosity. Hence the principle of unity, which is necessary to bring order and system into our knowledge, must he imported into these sciences from without. On this view, we can organize knowledge only in reference to a subjective principle supplied by the altruistic affections, — affections which bind men together so as to make all humanity through all space and time into one great organism, and which thus supply a definite end and aim to all the intellectual, as well as to all the active, energies of the individual. This subjective principle, in Comte's view, has been the unconscious stimulus of all the efforts of the social and intellectual leaders of men in the past; it has been the source of all that organized co- operation of families and nations on which man's physical and moral progress has depended. Positivism has only to make it into the direct aim and conscious purpose of human endeavour, and thereby to check that vain and wasteful application of man's limited powers, which has prevailed in the past, especially during the 140 The Social Philosophy of Comte. revolutionary period of transition, now coming to an end. Hence Comte condemns, not only the metaphysicians, who search into things altogether out of the reach of man, but also the scientific men, who seek to extend the knowledge of their special subjects indefinitely in every direction, suggested by an empty curiosity, without regard to the practical end of all science. The Mathe- matician, who wastes himself in the discovery of forms and methods which have no relation to the requirements of physics; the Biologist, who specu- lates on the origin of species, forgetting how little light such inquiries can throw on the develop- ment of man ; even the Sociologist, who pursues remote investigations into the history of climate and race, " before such studies are made neces- sary by the practical difficulty of extending the civilization of the West, regenerated by Positiv- ism, to the populations that are less advanced in civilization " — are all brought under the Comtist anathema, as guilty of wasting the small powers of man on questions which are not imme- diately necessary or useful. " The public and its teachers should always refuse to recognize investigations which do not tend either to deter- Knowledge not an End in Itself. 141 mine more precisely the material and physical laws of man's existence, to throw greater light on the modifications which these laws admit, or at least to render the general method of investi- gation more perfect," " It is necessary that the sciences should in the first instance be studied independently; but this study should in each case be carried only so far as is necessary to enable the intellect to take a solid grasp of the science next above it in the scale, and thus to rise to the systematic study of Humanity, its .inly permanent field."* On this principle, the priests of Positivism are not to be specialists ; nor, indeed, are any of them to devote their lives to scientific investigation alone ; except, it may be, a few distorted and unbalanced natures, in whom an abnormal tendency to intellectual pursuits has stunted the growth of the moral sympathies. To make scientific men renounce the intellectual life as an end in itself, and to direct all their energies to the solution of those problems which seem to have most immediate relation to the improve- ment of man's estate, is one of the main objects which Comte has in view in restoring the spiritual * Pol. Pos. i. 370, 383. 142 The Social Philosophy of Comte. power. A free development of each science for itself apart from the rest, and a free develop- ment of science as a whole, without reference to action for ends determined by social sympathy, are equally opposed to the Comtian ideal. The world and all objects in it are to be regarded by the Positivist merely as means, which we seek to know not for themselves, but only in order that we may use them for a predetermined end. For, according to Comte, the energies of the intelligence run to waste except when they are directed by an esprit d'ensemble, and the only totality, with reference to which such systematic direction is possible, is the " subjective " totality of humanity, comte I have already indicated to some extent the admits a principle in grounds on which I would criticize this theory man which ° ^ indi'viduai! 5 of " subjective synthesis." It implies, for one thing, that there is no natural convergence of the sciences, due to the unity of the parts of the intelligible world with each other and with the intelligence ; but that the synthesis of know- ledge is artificial, and forced upon it from with- out. Man, in Comte's point of view, is not a microcosm, who finds himself again in the macro- The Social Point of Vieiv. 143 cosm. He is like a stranger in a foreign country, who seeks to arm himself with such fragments of knowledge about it as are necessary for his protection and his own private ends. Yet this statement, without qualification, would not he altogether just to Comte ; for, in his view, the individual man does find himself in the presence of one " object," which is also " subjective," — of one Great Being, whom he has not to treat as an external means to ends of his own, but rather in whom he has to find his own end. The synthesis of knowledge, therefore, is not subjective so far as Sociology and Morals are concerned, whatever it may be in regard to the other sciences. The unity, in reference to which knowledge is to be organized, is not merely the unity of man's nature as an individual, but rather as a " collective " being (a bad adjective surely to apply to mankind, when they are regarded as " members one of another "). Comte thus repeats the " homo mensura " in the sense that Humanity is for each man the measure of all * The distinction made in the Politique Positive be- tween Sociology and Morals, depending as it does on the opposition of the intellect to the heart, will be dis- cussed afterwards. 144 The Social Philosophy of Comte. things (though things in themselves escape all our measuring). We can transcend ourselves so far as to take the point of view of humanity, though not so far as to take the point of view of the objective unity of the world. Nay, it may even be said that we must so transcend ourselves, for Comte denies that the individual can separate himself from his race, except by a forced and illegitimate abstraction. " Man, as an indivi- dual," he declares, " cannot properly be said to exist except in the too abstract brain of modern metaphysicians ;" and the same principle on its ethical side leads him to condemn the doctrine of absolute personal rights, and to say that " individuals should be regarded not as so many distinct beings, but as organs of the one Great Being." According to these principles it would be impossible for us either to know our- selves as men, or to live a life in accordance with our nature, if we were confined within the limits of a purely individual conscious- ness. Our consciousness of ourselves is essen- tially social, and the individualistic point of view is the result of a false abstraction, which can never be more than a partial abstraction. Man and Nature. 145 For, strive as we will, we cannot in thought, any more than in reality, isolate the individual from society, without at the same time taking from him all that characterizes him even as an individual. To speak, therefore, of knowing man, except as a member of the family, of the nation, of the race, is irrational. The science of man would be impossible if we were not able to get beyond our individuality, and to look at it, as well as at all other individualities, from the point of view of humanity. To such a conception of the essentially social Yet t s not a universal nature of man few, at the present day, would principle, object. But a "metaphysician" might wish to carry it a little farther, and to recognize not only the essential relation of man to man, but also the essential relation of man to the universe. If it is a fiction of abstraction to separate the individual from society, is it a less fiction to isolate him from the world in which he lives, and in relation to which all his powers and tendencies have been developed? Can we really apply the idea of i organic unity to the life of man without extending it so as in some sense to include also the environ- ment in which that life develops ? To ask what K 146 The Social Philosophy of Comte. man would have been in a different world is surely as absurd a question as to ask what he would have been had he not lived with his fellow-men. If it be allowed and asserted that the objective or universal point of view is possible, or even necessary, in relation to humanity, there seems to be no good ground for denying that it is possible and necessary in relation to the uni- verse. Once admit that the individual can, and even must, so transcend his own indi- viduality as to regard himself as part of a greater whole and to measure his actions by another standard than his own pleasures and pains, and you are no longer free to reject the possibility of an objective synthesis. If the relativity of man to man makes it impossible to know him except from the point of view of humanity, the relativity of man to the world makes it impossible to know humanity except from the point of view of the unity of the whole. To stop short at the universal of humanity is a mere compromise, which, like many compromises, is less rational than either of the extremes between which it stands. All knowledge implies the universality of thought, The Universality of Thought. 147 ■i.e., it implies that man, as a thinking being, can, and indeed must, apprehend the world from a subjective, which is also an objective point, of view. For man's consciousness of himself is at the same time a consciousness of the not-self, and of the unity to which both these correlative elements belong. From the dawning of self-con- sciousness he is thus lifted above his own separate and partial existence as an individual ; he lives a life which is not merely his own life, but the life of the world. He is, and can become more and more completely, the organ of that universal spirit which transcends and includes all things, which " Lives through all life, extends to all extent, Spreads undivided, operates unspent." It is this that makes him capable of science, or morality, or religion ; for in so far as he speaks his own words, or does his own deeds, or thinks his own thoughts, he speaks and acts and thinks folly and evil ; and it is only in so far as he becomes the instrument of some universal power or interest, that his individual action, or thought, or utterance can have any dignity or value. It shows an imperfect appre- 148 The Social Philosophy of Comte. hension of this truth to say with Comte that Humanity and not God is the universal power in whose service the individual is to find spiri- tual freedom ; and that, therefore, the ultimate synthesis must be subjective and not objective. For the only philosophical difficulty is to con- ceive how man can transcend his individual subjectivity at all ; and, if that is shown to be for him possible, and even necessary, there is no reason whatever to deny that he can and must rise to the knowledge of God, the absolute or objective unity of the world, comte's Comte, however, is hindered from recognizing changing relatione? tn ^ s truth by another class of considerations. man. In opposition to that external optimistic tele- ology, which was so common at the end of last century, and at which the Encyclopedists aimed so many blows, he was led in his Philosophic Positive to dwell upon the fact that, from the point of view of human happiness, the arrange- ments of the universe, astronomical, physical, and biological, are anything but perfect. Poetry, indeed, may be allowed to imagine that the powers of nature are the friends of man ; but Science, according to Comte, must recognize that A Beneficent Necessity. 140 the world in which man's lot is cast is far from furnishing the best conceivable sphere for his existence and development ; and that it has only become so favourable to his progress as it at present is, by the long " providential action " of man himself. At this point, however, there is a crossing of opposite lines of thought in Comte's philosophy. For it is one of the leading conceptions of the Politique Positive that the influence of an external limiting fatality, which forces upon man the surrender of his natural self-will, was the necessary condition of the development of all his higher powers of intelligence and heart. Comte is never weary of showing that the growing preponderance of the altruistic affections, which alone can give unity to human life, is dependent upon the existence of those limits which are put upon the desires of man by the external world. " Without this continual ascendant," he declares, " man's feelings would become vague, his intelli- gence wanton, and his activity sterile. If this yoke were taken away, the problem of human life would remain insoluble, since altruism could never conquer egoism. But assisted by the 150 The Social Philosophy of Comte. supreme fatality, universal love is able habitu- ally to secure that personality should be sub- ordinated to sociality. The sophisms of human pride cannot hinder the positive spirit from recognizing that all revolt springs from egoistic impulses. A forced submission tends indirectly to make altruism prevail by the very fact that it represses egoism. But this moral reaction is supremely efficacious when obedience becomes voluntary, because then sympathy is directly de- veloped, and no jarring emotion any longer hinders us from getting the benefit of our subjection."* From this point of view the external fatality can no longer be called unfriendly, or even indifferent to man ; or rather its immediate appearance as his enemy is the condition of its being, in a higher sense, his friend. Kant, in his short treatise on history (with which Comte was ac- quainted, and which probably had no little influence upon the Politique Positive), applies a similar thought to the struggle and competition of mankind with each other. The very selfish rivalry of men, he contends, is in the long run the means *Synthese Subjective, p. 16; cf. Pol. Pos. i., p. 414, seq. and above, p. 36. Good out of Evil. 151 of developing a higher sociality than could have existed among a race of beings with whom per- sonal feeling was at first less intense. Egoism itself becomes the means of elevating men above egoism. Thus in both cases, conditions which, in the first instance, seemed to be hostile to the intellectual, and still more to the moral, development of man, become, because of the inner reaction which they call forth in his nature, the best means to that development. " Out of the eater comes forth meat ; out of the strong sweetness." On such a view it seems a fair criticism to make that it looks very like a proof that those things which seem in the first instance to be evils, and which, indeed, taken by themselves, arc evils, are the necessary, though neg- ative, conditions of higher good. But a negative condition is still a condition, and the gods are not envious because they refuse man a lower good in order to make him seek one which is higher. No conclusion unfavourable to Optim- ism, in any high sense of the word, can be founded on the fact that the world is not arranged for the immediate happiness of man, if that immediate happiness would have been 152 The Social Philosophy of Comte. purchased by his moral degradation ; or even if it would have been less powerful to call forth the higher energies of his nature. If the noblest love is a transmuted and transcended egoism, then even an infinite benevolence would not seek directly to stop the unlovely and selfish struggle which darkens and poisons the life of man on earth. The best kind of optimism — the optimism, if we may so term it, of the deepest and tenderest spirits who have called themselves Christian — has not been based upon a shallow and imperfect view of the misery, still less of the moral evil, of man's life. Bather it has been attained through the clearest per- ception of both. It has been an Optimism that " descended into the grave " of human happiness, and even, if we might so interpret the creed of Christendom, into the " hell " of human guilt, that it might rise again " leading captivity captive." ' And Comte, who in his primary opposition to theology and metaphysics, had rejected all absolute or theological conceptions of the world, is led by the natural development of his thought to find a higher design in the * Cf. Von Hartmann's Selbst-zersetzung des Christenthums. Optimism Rational — In what Sense? 153 immediate negation of design, and to extend to the universe that idea of unity which in the first instance he had applied only to humanity. But, as he could never quite forget the nega- tions with which he had started, his recognition of this unity was imperfect, and he was ulti- mately forced to cast upon poetry the office for which science seemed to be inadequate. The truth to which these inconsistencies of The irra- tionality of Comte point, is, that all criticism of the whole ggJSS?" system of things to which we belong is, from a truly " relative " point of view, irrational. For the critic, and the standard by which he criti- cizes, cannot be separated from that system. To criticize things as particulars is not unreason- able, because we can test the particulars by the universal ; but to criticize the general system of which they and we are parts, and by which our development — and of course among other things, the development of our moral standard — is made possible, is to stand on our own heads and to leap off our own shadow. If, indeed, we could assume an individualistic point of view, if we could isolate ourselves at once from the world which is our only sphere of activity, and from 154 The Social Philosophy of Comte. the social life of the race which is the source of all our culture, we might then take the pleasures and pains, the feelings that belong to us as sensitive individuals, as a standard by which to criticize the world. But in any other point of view, criticism is possible only as a reference of the individual to the universal, of the part to the whole, of the various elements and phases of the system of things to the idea, which forms the unity of that system and the principle of its development. It has often been pointed out that a logical scepticism cannot be universal, for every intelligible view of things implies an ultimate unity of thought and of existence, of the esse and the intelligi. Doubt must rest on a basis of certi- tude, or it will destroy itself. But it is not less true, though it is less frequently noticed, that all criticism of the world, while it detects evil in particular, implies an ultimate optimism. For, if such criticism pretends to be more than the utterance of the tastes and wishes of an individual, it must claim to be the expression of an objective principle — a principle which, in spite of all appearances to the contrary, is realizing itself in the world. If, as Hegel said, Subjective Criticism of Life. 155 the " history of the world is the judgment of the world," then, conversely, every true moral judg- ment is an anticipation of history: it is a discovery of the hidden forces that are already working out their triumph in the world, even by means of that which seems most to oppose them : it is a prophetic sympathy with the "spirit of the years to come," which is " yearning to mix itself with life." It is this objective character which often makes tire words of genius carry with them such weight and power. " He spake as one having authority and not as the scribes," could be truly said only of one, whose speech was like some natural force in its independence of merely indi- vidual and of temporary influences. On the other hand, it is the limited and subjective character of many of the ordinary moral judgments of men — of much of their fault-finding with the condi- tions of existence, the defects of their neighbours, and the errors and evils of the time — which makes us treat such judgments with indifference. We feel that they are in great part the expression of personal likes and dislikes, though clothing themselves in the lion's skin of a moral censor- ship ; and that the only answer which they de- 156 The Social Philosophy oj Comte. serve is, that " there is no disputing about tastes." Much of the superficial pessimism of our day is the offspring, not of deep sympathy with the real evils of humanity, but of a weakness of moral fibre, which might tempt us to cut the knot of difficulty with the apparently unfeeling words of St. Paul, " Shall the thing formed say to him who has formed it, Why hast thou made me thus ? " But there is another moral judgment than this, which is not the mere expression of the tastes and wishes of individuals, but of the inner law and the necessity of things, or in other words of the universal spirit of man, which in the long struggle of development is becoming more and more clearly conscious of itself and of the law of the world. It is only as the organ of this spirit that the individual can claim to "judge the world"; nor can he make that claim without taking up the ground of a philosophical optimism, and acknowledging that the " soul of the world is just." For the sentiment or idea of good implied in such judgment, must either be the last result of the development of man in the world — in which case the system of things which conditioned the result cannot be criticized by it ; or it must be Objective Criticism of Life. 157 the pure utterance of individual feeling, in which case it has no objective value whatever. To sup- pose with Comte that it is objective, as being something which belongs not to the individual but to the race, yet subjective, as being something that belongs to human nature and not to the na- t ure of things in general, is a hopeless attempt to combine in one two inconsistent points of view — the point of view of the philosophy of Locke, by which the^individual consciousness is conceived as confined to the apprehension of its own states, and the point of view of modern idealism, accord- ing to which the consciousness of the thinking subject, as such, is universal and objective. At this point it may be useful to look back summary of Comte's iu- and to sum up the various contradictions, or let consistencies us rather say, the various forms of the same con- tradiction, which appear and reappear in different parts of the system of Comte. Beginning with the rejection of metaphysics, because it treats universals as real entities, and with the in- dividualistic definition of science as having to determine only the successions and resemblances of phenomena, Comte soon has to point out that in sociology and even in biology we have to 158 The Social Philosophy of Comte. deal with existences whose parts and successive phases are indefinable, except in and through the whole to which they belong. Beginning with objective science, and thus unconsciously assuming that the subjectivity of thought is not inconsistent with the knowledge of objects as such, he ends by asserting that only a " subjective synthesis " is possible. Yet this subjective syn- thesis is itself objective, for its point of view is determined, not by the sensations and feelings of the individual subject as such, but by the idea of humanity as a corporate unity. Thus the oppos- ition between subject and object reduces itself to a dualism between the world and man. Hence, in place of the worship of God, the absolute unity to which all thought and existence are referred, Comte would substitute the worship of Humanity, " the real author of the benefits for which thanks were formerly given to God." Finally, even this dualistic view of the world is practically withdrawn. For the negative relation of the external fatality to man's immediate wishes, is proved to be instrumental to his ultimate attain- ment of a still higher good. And, as if this were not enough, poetry is called in to give complete- The Idea of Religion. 159 ness to the synthetic view of the world, and to reconcile the two independent sentiments which must combine in order to produce a religion, sub- mission and love. For, although Comte at first thinks it sufficient to say that the necessity of nature is mediated to us by Humanity, yet in the end he feels that there will be an essential imperfection in his religious system, if it cannot identify the ultimate fatality to which we must submit with the Great Being whom we are to love and serve. On this point a few additional remarks may be useful. Comte defines religion (and we cannot but ac- Defocts of knowledge the substantial truth of the definition) gi<>n accord- ing to Iris own as the concentration of the three altruistic affec- lde;L " f lt- tions — of Eeverence towards that which is above us, Love towards that which helps and sustains us, and Benevolence towards that which needs our aid. It is impossible to give the highest unity to the inward and outward life of man, except by devo- tion to a Being in relation to whom these three affections are identified. Nor can it be denied that a faith, which has more or less perfectly fulfilled these conditions, has been the mainspring of hu- man life in all those periods of history in which 160 The Social Philosophy of Comte. man has shown the highest powers of his spirit. " The deepest, nay, the one theme of the world's history," says Goethe, " to which all others are subordinate, is the conflict of faith and unbelief. The epochs in which faith, in whatever form it may be, prevails, are the marked epochs of human history, full of heart-stirring memories, and of substantial gains for all after-times. On the other hand, the epochs in which unbelief, in whatever form it may be, gains its unhappy victories, even when for the moment they put on a semblance of glory and success, inevitably sink into insignificance in the eyes of a posterity which will not waste its thoughts on things barren and unfruitful." The tenderest harmo- nies of affection, the highest achievements of passionate energy, the deepest glances of insight into men and things, the greatest powers of inspired utterance, cannot be reached except by minds which are consciously at one with themselves and with the law of the universe ; and this oneness is what we call a religion. Man can do his best work only when he feels that he is the organ or instrument of a power or spirit which is universal, and therefore irresistible; which The Religion of Humanity. 161 embraces and subordinates even that which seems to resist it. Whether such a faith in its widest sense is still possible to man, or whether Christ- ianity is the last vanishing form of it, and we have now to look about for such substitute for it as may still be within our reach, may be a ques- tion. But it can scarcely be questioned, that the Comtist-, worship of Humanity is only such a substitute, and not the thing itself. Religion, as Comte himself maintains, implies a combination of spontaneity in the worshipper with complete sub- mission and self-surrender to the higher power that controls his life — a combination which can be attained only by one who loves the power to which he submits. But man's life is ultimately limited and determined by cosmical and physical conditions, and in these Comte sees only a fatality which cannot possibly be made the object of love. This difficulty, as we have seen, he tries to escape by showing that the ultimate fatality is mediated to us by Humanity, which, in the long process of its history, has been gradually adapting the sphere of our existence to our physical and moral neces- sities. He feels, however, that this is only a partial answer, and that the idea of an indifferent 162 The Social Philosophy of Comte. outward necessity must be a hindrance to the perfect combination of submission and love. Hence he calls in the aid of poetry to revive the spirit of Fetichism, and to reanimate the dead world by the image of benevolent divine agencies. " The Cultus of Space and of the Earth, complet- ing that of Humanity, makes us see in all that surrounds us the free auxiliaries of Humanity." Comte therefore ends in what some one has called the system of " spiritual book-keeping by double entry," in which imagination is allowed to revive, for practical purposes, the fictions which science has destroyed. In this way poetry has not merely to give sensuous form and life to our creed, by enabling us to see in the part what reason could otherwise find only in the whole ; it has also to supply the defects of a truth which is too hard and painful to satisfy the heart of man. It has to make us forget in our worship the dualism of Nature and Humanity, and to reconcile us to Fate by giving it the semblance of a Providence. It is obvious that poetry is thus made into a kind of deliberate superstition, which stimulates the outflow of religious feeling by hiding from us, for the moment, the realities of our position. But An Artificial Religion. 103 the explanation is that Comte was driven by the ultimate development of his own thought to seek for a kind of unity in the universe, which yet he could not admit without recognizing the error of his original presuppositions. There is a certain irony of fate in the process of unconscious dialectic, by which Comte, the enemy of theology, was led to set up that strange "Trinity in Unity," which is the last word of Positivism. In Comte's re-construction of religion there rts artificial character. seems to be something artificial and factitious, something " subjective," in the bad sense. It is a religion made, so to speak, out of malice prepense. " We have derived," he seems to say, " from the experience of our own past and of the past of hu- manity, a clear idea of what a religion should be : and we also know from the same experience that, without a religion, we cannot have that fulness of spiritual life of which we are capable. Go to, let us make a religion, as nearly corresponding to the definition of religion as modern science will permit. ' Gather up the fragments that remain, that noth- ing be lost.' God, the Absolute Being, is hidden from us, but Humanity will serve for a ' relative ' or ' subjective ' kind of God : or rather not Hu- 164 The Social Philosophy of Comte. inanity, but the selected members of the race, whose services entitle them to our recognition, and whom therefore we incorporate in the ' Great Being.' And as for the inscrutable fatality that bounds all our views, and on which in the last resort the fate of humanity must depend, to it we can but submit, or (since such a separation of submission from love is so far irreligious) we can invoke the powers of imagination to hide it from our eyes. To Humanity, as represented to us by the good and wise of the past, we can present the old offerings of praise and prayer, in a spirit that is perfectly disinterested ; for we have no reason to believe that they exist except in our memory of them, or that the ' Great Being,' in whom they are incorporated, has any gift to bestow upon us in the future except a similar life in the memory of others. For, after all, the ' Great Being,' who alone makes things work together for our good and whom alone we can love, is not absolute or objec- tive ; and of the real Absolute Being or Principle of the Universe, we know nothing, except per- haps that He or It is not what men call good." a relative I n the earlier part of this chapter I have tried religion is no religion, to show that Comte's view of the limits of know- Meligion must be Absolute. 1(J5 ledge cannot be maintained except on principles which would be fatal to the existence of know- ledge altogether ; and, on the other hand, that the possibility of a subjective synthesis, such as he demands and supposes himself to have achieved, wtould involve also the possibility of an objective or absolute synthesis. Here I wish only to point out, that if Comte's general view of things be admitted, religion, according to his own definition of it, is impossible. A " relative " religion is not a religion at all : it is at best a morality, trying to gather to itself some of the emotions which were formerly connected with religious belief. If there is no warrant for the Christian faith which finds God in man, and man in God, which makes us regard the Absolute Being as finding his best name and definition in what we most reverence and love; or, what is the same thing from the other side, makes us see in that growing idea of moral perfection, which is the highest result of human development, the interpretation or revelation of the Absolute ; then we must give up the hope of the renewal of religion, and of that har- monious energy to which religion alone can 166 The Social Philosophy of Comte. awake the soul of man. In this point of view Mr. Spencer and Comte seem to divide the elements of the truth between them, Mr. Spencer, regarding the Absolute as unknowable, and perceiving that religion implies a relation to the Absolute, reduces religion to the bare feelings of awe and mystery. Comte, also re- garding the Absolute as unknowable, seeks to find an object nearer home for the emotions that hitherto have been directed to God. But the religion of Mr. Spencer, if it ever could become a reality, would be a renewal of the superstitious pantheism of India, the worship of a power without moral or spiritual attributes. And the religion of Comte could scarcely be- come more than a pious aspiration, unless the poetic license of worship were carried to the point of self-deception. Of this Comte seems to be partially aware, when in his latest works he insists so strenuously on the theme that art, rather than science, is the true field for man's intelligence, and that it is a desirable and useful thing to allow our minds to dwell on ideal conceptions, which are beyond the reach of scientific proof, provided these conceptions are Poetry and Truth. 167 favourable to the development of altruistic senti- ment. " The logic of religion," he declares, " when freed from scientific empiricism, will not restrain itself any longer to the domain of hy- potheses winch are capable of verification, though these alone were compatible with the Positive preparation for it. It must in the end find its completion in the domain, much wider and not less legitimate, of those conceptions which, without offending the reason, are peculiarly suited to develop the feelings. Better adapted to our moral wants, the institutions of true Poetry are as harmonious as those of sound Philosophy with the intellectual conditions of the relative synthesis. They ought therefore to obtain as great extension and influence in our efforts to systematize our thoughts ; and Positivism permits of their doing so without any danger of confusion between the two dis- tinct methods of thinking, which it openly consecrates, the one to reality and the other to ideality." # Is it possible to express more clearly a desire to combine the advantages of believing, with the advantages of disbelieving, * Synthese Subjective, p. 40. 168 The Social Philosophy oj Comte. in the accordance of objective reality with our highest feelings and aspirations ? But a worship of fictions, confessed as such, is impossible. Art, indeed, is kindred with Eeligion ; and Art, as Plato said, is " a noble untruth." This, however, means only that Art is untrue to the immediate appearances of things, in order that it may sug- gest the deeper reality that underlies them. But, in Comte's view, the service of imagination is to supply wants of the heart, which cannot be supplied by reality, either in its superficial or in its deeper aspect ; it is to nurture our moral nature on conceptions that are purely fictitious. It is not difficult to prophesy that the schism of the head and the heart thus introduced must end in the sacrifice either of the one or of the other ; either in the dogmatic assertion of the optimism of poetry, or in a violent recoil from it, which will separate, not only man from the world, but also the individual from the race, and which must ultimately reduce Humanity from an object of worship into a purely moral ideal. For religion, as Comte himself rightly saw, cannot exist except where thought and feeling, intelligence and heart, are The Religious Consciousness. 1G9 harmonized, in a consciousness of the highest subjective ideal, as being at the same time the ultimate objective reality. What, indeed, is the use of religion, if it does not plant our feet upon the Bock of Ages," but leaves us still on the " sandbank " of the contingent and the temporal ? " All the nations," says Hegel, "have felt that the religious consciousness was that in which they possessed truth, and it is for this reason that they have ever regarded it as that which gives dignity and consecrated joy to their lives. All that awakes doubt and anguish, all sorrow and care, all the limited interests of finitude, the religious spirit leaves behind on the sandbank of time. And as, on the highest top of a mountain, removed from definite view of the earth below, we peacefully overlook all the limitations of the landscape and the world, so, to the spiritual eye of man in this pure region, the hardness of immediate reality dis- solves into a semblance, and its shadows, differ- ences, and lights are softened to eternal peace by the beams of the spiritual sun." If we cannot any longer have this consciousness of things sub specie ceternitatis, — in that highest of Comte. 170 The Social Philosophy of Comte. truth and unity in which all difficulties and dissonances are lost, — -without self-deception, it would be better for us to forswear it alto- gether than to connect our highest feelings with a poetic illusion. schisms in It is a natural question to ask whether the school and how far the history of Comte's philosophy illustrates any of the difficulties and contradic- tions which we have found in the writings of its author. The first schism in the ranks of those who are commonly called Positivists was that which is connected in France with the name of Littre, perhaps the most distinguished of Comte's disciples ; and in England, with the names of Mill and Lewes — who, however, were never, strictly speaking, his disciples at all. These writers broke away from Comte, whenever Comte decidedly broke away from the individualistic philosophy of the last cen- tury. In their eyes Comte's great achieve- ments were the law of the three stages of mental development and the arrangement of the sciences ; and if they accepted his sociolo- gical speculations — even those which appear in his first great work — it was with many reserves. Mill and Littre. 171 Mill regards Comte's continual denunciation of metaphysics as objectionable, so soon as lie finds it to be directed against the individ- ualists * as well as against the scholastic realists ; and he thinks Comte's " inordinate demand for unity and systematization " only an instance of " an original mental twist very common in French writers, and by which Comte was dis- tinguished above them all."t Littre finds little to object to in Comte's first great work, and is not unwilling to admit that the "individual man is an abstraction, and that there is nothing real but humanity ; " but he recoils when Comte begins to speak of the " Great Being," and to change his philosophy into a religion. Both attack the " subjective synthesis " as a new variety of metaphysics, seeing clearly that, as Comte states it, it involves a desertion of the point of view of science ; and neither of them is able to admit any other point of view from which the subjective unity might itself be seen to be objective. A less important schism has recently t occurred Mr.congreve 1 J + and M. Lafitte. * Mill's Comte and Positivism, p. 73. t Id. p. 140. X Written in 1879. 1 72 The Social Philosophy of Comte. within the Positivist Church, or, in other words, among those who accept the system of Comte in its entirety, as a religion no less than as a philosophy. Mr. Congreve, and those who think with him, have broken away from the general body of Positivists under M. Lafitte, who was appointed to be its head, or, at least, its pro- visional head, after the death of Comte. The difference, however, is one only of policy, and not of principle. " There exists no difference," says Mr. Congreve, " in regard to the doctrine, taken as a whole ; it is only as to the manner of presenting that whole that we are, at variance." At the same time this " schism," though, as M. Lafitte says, it is not a "heresy," might easily lead to one, if there be any truth in what has been said above as to the ultimate opposition of poetry and philosophy in the sys- tem of Comte. M. Lafitte contends that the Positivist priesthood should, in the first instance at least, seek to address the heart through the intelligence ; " for it is clear that their direct sentimental (or moral) action would want a basis, and could indeed have no serious result, unless general opinion had previously been Methods of Religious Teaching. 173 modified to a certain degree by Positive teaching." On the other hand, Mr. Congreve argues that Positivism rnust triumph in the first instance, like Christianity, by a direct " appeal to the women and the proletaries " ; which means that an effort must be made to influence " the heart," without waiting for the intelligence ; and that, in the words of Comte himself, the "weapon of persuasion is to be used in preference to that of conviction." " What we seek to constitute," says Mr. Congreve, # " is a union of the faithful, a Church in the highest sense of the term, i.e.. a society in which the religious element will preponderate ; will, indeed, be so decisively and boldly emphasized, as to leave no doubt of our intentions; a society which can rally to itself all who feel the need of shelter or sup- port, of the consolation of an active and sym- pathetic faith. It is thus that we conceive ourselves bound to commence the preaching of Humanity, as a principle of union, with the view of gathering together a solid body, made up mainly of the women and the populace, * I translate from the French, as I have not seen the English edition of Mr. Congreve's circular. 174 The Social Philosophy of Comte. which may serve as a foundation for the rest. In this body the order of instructors could find their support (and by an order of instructors I mean naturally a priesthood and priests, and not, what seems to be offered in its place, pro- fessors and a professoriate), as, on the other hand, without the stimulating reaction of such an audience, they would want a solid basis as well as a sphere of activity." It would be an impertinence for any one who is not a member of the Positivist Church to say anything on the personal or semi-private questions, which are necessarily involved in such a division as this between those who are otherwise united. But there can be no intrusion in saying, that if Positivism is ever to become an effective Church, it must find some such direct way of addressing the people as Mr. Congreve sug- gests, without waiting for those who have time to be instructed in the principles of the six or seven sciences of the Positivist system ; and Mr. Dix Hutton* has sufficiently shown that * I have to offer to Mr. Dix Hutton my best thanks for his courtesy in furnishing me with copies of the circulars and letters of himself, of Mr. Congreve, and of The Heart and the Head, 175 Comte himself would have approved of such a policy. " God hath chosen the weak things of the world to confound the mighty;" and it may be safely said that no great moral or spiritual movement will ever be accomplished, if its leaders wait till they have convinced the mass of the educated classes. The only ques- tion which suggests itself to one who has considered the difficulties of the " subjective, synthesis " is, whether the appeal made to the heart would not necessarily contain elements which afterwards it would be impossible to justify to the head. For if it were so, " the old quarrel of the poets and the philosophers," of faith and reason, would repeat itself again in the Positivist Church, and it would not be less bitter from the fact that that Church was founded expressly with the design of putting an end to the quarrel altogether. Can there be a division of the intelligence against Thc heart and the the heart, which is not more properly described head, as division of the intelligence against itself ? This is a question which is inevitably suggested M. Lafitte, on the subject of the division among the Positivists. 170 The Social Philosophy of Comte. by the whole tenor of Comte's later works. In my final chapter I shall say something upon this question, and shall then try to show how Comte's defective answer to it naturally led to other defects in his view of the history of the past, especially of Christianity, and also in his view of the social ideal of the future. The Subjective Synthesis. 177 CHAPTER IV. oomte's view of the relation of the intellect to the heart its effect on his conception of history and of the social ideal. The necessity for unity in man's intellectual and moral life — Nature of the conflict between the intelligence and the heart- It is really a conflict of intelligent with itself— Criticism oj Comte , s doctrine that the intelligence must he subjected to the heart — Its effect upon his conception of history, especially of the history of Christianity — The two elements in Christianity, their conflict, and reconciliation in its development — The nega- tive tendencies of media-ral Catholicism and the posit ire ten- dencies of the modem era — Comte's imperfect conception of the Reformation and the Revolution — His restoration of the med'mval ideal — His general position as a Philosopher. In the last chapter I considered the subjective synthesis of Comte, or in other words, his attempt to systematize human knowledge in relation to the moral life of man. For it is his view, as we have seen, that science can never yield its highesl fruit to man unless it he systematized — i.e., M 178 The Social Philosophy of Comte. unless its different parts be connected together and put in their true place as parts of one whole. Scattered lights give no illumination ; it is the esprit d'ensemble, the general idea in which our knowledge begins and ends, that ultimately deter- mines the scientific value of each special branch of knowledge. But while synthesis is necessary, it is not necessary, according to Comte, that the synthesis should be objective. The error of mankind in the past has been that they sup- posed themselves able to ascertain the real or objective principle, which gives unity to the world, and able, therefore, to make their system of knowledge an ideal repetition of the system of things without them. Such a system, how- ever, is entirely beyond our reach. The con- ditions of our lot, and the weakness of our intelligence, make it impossible for us to tell what is the real principle of unity in the world, or even whether such a principle exists. The attempts to discover it, made by Theology and Metaphysics, have been nothing more than elab- orate anthropomorphisms, in which men gave to the unknown and unknowable reality a form which was borrowed from their own nature. They Hoiu to Systematize Knowledge. 179 saw in the clpuds about them an exaggerated and distorted reflection of themselves, and regarded this Brocken spectre as a controlling power whose activity was the source and explanation of everything. Positivism, on the other hand, arises whenever men come to recognize the nature of this illusion, and to confine their ambition to that which is within the limit of their intelligence. All that we can know is the resemblances and successions of phenomena, and not the things in themselves that are their causes; and if we seek to find a principle of unity fi >r these phenomena, we must find it in ourselves and not in them. We must organize knowledge with reference to our own wants, rather than with reference to the nature of things. We must regard everything as a means to an end, which is determined by some inner principle in ourselves — not as if we supposed that the world and all that is in it were made for us, or found its centre in us — but simply because this is the only point of view from which we can syste- matize knowledge, as it is indeed the only point of view from which we need care to systematize it. 180 The Social Philosophy of Comte. Necessity of It may be asked why system is necessary at unity and system. a r^ w ] 1 y we s i 10u i(j no £ De content with a frag- mentary consciousness of the world, without attempting to gather the dispersed lights of science to one central principle. To critics like J. S. Mill Comte's effort after system seems to be the result of an " original mental twist very common in French thinkers/' of " an inordinate desire of unity." " That all perfection consists in unity, Comte apparently considers to be a maxim which no sane man thinks of questioning: it never seems to enter into his conceptions that any one could object ab initio, and ask, why this universal systematizing, systematizing, systematizing. Why is it necessary that all human life should point but to one object, and be converted into a system of means to a single end?"* To this Mr. Bridges answers that unity in Comte's sense is " the first and most obvious condition which all moral and religious renovators, of whatever time and country, have by the very nature of their office set them- selves to fulfil." -j- In other words, all moral and spiritual life depends upon the harmony of the * " Comte and Positivism," p. 140. + " The Unity of Comte's Life and Doctrine," p. 26. The Weakness of Douht. 181 individual with himself and with the world. A divided life is a life of weakness and misery, nor can life be divided intellectually, without being, or ultimately becoming, divided morally. Such unity, indeed, does not exclude — and in a being- like man who is in course of development cannot altogether exclude — difference and even conflict. In the most steadily growing intellectual life there are pauses of difficulty and doubt ; in the most continuous moral progress there are con- flicts with self and others. But such doubts and difficulties will not greatly weaken or disturb us, so long as they are partial, so long as they do not affect the central principles of thought and action, so long as there is still some fixed faith which reaches beyond the disturbance, some cer- titude which is untouched by the doubt. If, however, we once lose the consciousness that there is any such principle, or if we try to rest on a principle which we at the same time feel to be inadequate, our spiritual life, in losing its unity or harmony with itself, must at the same time lose its purity and energy. It must become fitful and uncertain, the sport of accidental influ- ences and tendencies; it must lower its moral 182 The Social Philosophy of Comte. and intellectual aims. This, in Comte's view, is what we have seen in the past. The decay of the old faiths, and of the objective synthesis based upon them, has emancipated us from many illusions, but it has, as it were, taken the inspira- tion out of our lives. It has made knowledge a thing for specialists who have lost the sense of totality, the sense of the value of their particular studies in relation to the whole ; and it has made action feeble and wayward by depriving men of the conviction that there is any great central aim to be achieved by it. And these results would have been still more obvious, were it not that men are so slow in realizing what is involved in the change of their beliefs ; were it not that the habits and sympathies developed by a creed continue to exist long after the creed itself has disappeared. In the long run, however, the change of man's intellectual attitude in relation to the world must bring with it a change of his whole life. Ceasing to have faith in the creed which once reconciled him to the world and bound him to his fellows, he must be thrown back upon his own mere individuality, unless he can find another creed of equal or The Weakness of Individualism. 183 greater power to inspire and direct his life. And mere individualism is nothing but anarchy. This, indeed, was not seen by those who first expressed the individualistic principle ; on the contrary, they seemed to themselves to find in the assertion of individual right, not only an instrument for destroying the old faith and the old social order, but also the principle of a better faith, and the means of reconstructing a better order of life. But to us who have outlived the period when it could be supposed that the destruction of old, involves in itself the con- struction of new, forms of life and thought, it cannot but be obvious that the principles of private judgment and individual liberty are noth- ing more than negations. For, as the real problem of our intellectual life is how to rise to a judgment which is more than private judg- ment, so the real problem of our practical life is how to realize a liberty that is more than individual license. Hence it is that Comte speaks of the last three centuries as a period of the insurrection of the intellect against the heart, an expression by which he means to indicate at once the gain and the loss of 184 The Social Philosophy of Comte. the revolutionary movement : its gain, in so far as it emancipated the intelligence from super- stitious illusions : and its loss, in so far as it destroyed the faith which was the bond of social union, without substituting any other faith in its room. At the same time, this expression points to a peculiarity of Comte's Psychology, which affects his whole view of the history, and especially of the religious history, of man ; and which it is therefore necessary to subject to a careful examination. Possibility I s ^ possible for the intellect to be in insur- of conflict . ... - , between rection against the heart { In the sense already inteliectand heart. indicated this is possible. It is possible, in short, that the moral and intellectual spirit of a belief may still control the life of one who, so far as his explicit consciousness is concerned, has renounced it. Eooted as the individual is in a wider life than his own, it is often but a small part of him- self, that he can bring to distinct consciousness. Further, so little are most men accustomed to self-analysis, that they are seldom aware what it is that constitutes the inspiring power of their beliefs. Generally, at least in the first instance, they take their creed in gross, without distinguish- The Heart against the Head. 185 ing between essential and unessential elements. They confuse, in one general consecration of re- verence, the primary principles, which give it its real spiritual value, and the local and temporary accidents of the form in which it was first pre- sented to them ; and they are as ready to accept battle a Vovtrance for some useless outwork as for the citadel itself. And, for the same reason, they are ready to think that the citadel is lost when the outwork is taken ; to suppose, e.g., that the spiritual nature of man is a fiction, if he was not directly made by God out of the dust of the earth, or that the Christian view of life has ceased to be true, if a doubt can be thrown on the possibility of proving miracles. Yet, however little the indi- vidual may be able to separate the particulars which are assailed from the universal with which they are accidentally connected, his whole nature must rebel against the sacrifice which logical con- sistency seems in such a case to demand from him. It is a painful experience when the first 1 ireak is made in the implicit unity of early faith, and it is painful just in proportion to the depth of the spiritual consciousness which that faith has produced in the individual. Unable to separate 186 The Social Philosophy of Gomte. that which he is obliged to doubt from that in which lies the principle of his moral, and even of his intellectual, life, he is " in a strait betwixt two " ; and no course seems to be open to him which does not involve the surrender, either of his intellectual honesty, or of that higher conscious- ness which alone " makes life worth living." Such a crisis is commonly described as a division be- tween the heart and the head, because in it the articulate or conscious logic is generally on the side of disbelief, while the resisting conviction takes the form of a feeling, an impulse, an intuition, which the individual has for himself, but which he is unable to communicate in the same force to another. And, as such feelings and intuitions of the individual are necessarily subject to continual variation of intensity and clearness, so the struggle between doubt and faith may be long and difficult, the objections, which at one time seem as nothing, at another time appearing to be almost irresistible. Not seldom the result is a broken life, in which youth is given to revolt, and the rest of existence to a faith which vainly strives to be implicit. There is, indeed, no final and satisfactory issue from The Heart Wiser than the Head 187 such an endless internal debate and conflict, until the " heart " has learned to speak the language of the " head," — i.e., until the permanent principles, which underlay and gave strength to faith, have been brought into the light of distinct conscious- ness, and until it has been discovered how to separate them from the accidents, with which at first they were necessarily identified. The hard labour of distinguishing, in the traditions of the past, between the germinative principles, out of which the future must spring, and those external forms and adjuncts, which every day is making more incredible, must be undertaken by any one who would restore the broken unity of man's life. We begin our existence under the shadow and in- fluence of a faith which is given to us, as it were. in our sleep ; but in no age, and in this age less than any other, can man possess spiritual life as a gift from the past without reconquering it for himself. In this sense, then, we can understand how i !c:l i nature of the Cointe might speak of an insurrection of the in- opposition, telligence against the heart, which must be quelled ere the normal state of humanity could be re- stored ; for this would be only another way of 188 The Social Philosophy of Comte. saying that, in the modern conflict of faith and reason, the substantial truth, or at least the most important truth, had, up to Comte's own time, been on the side of the former. In this view, the deep unwillingness of those nourished in the Christian or Catholic faith to yield to the logical battery of the Encyclopaedists was not merely the result of an obscurantist hatred of light ; it was also in great part due to a more or less definite sense of the moral, if not the intellectual, weakness of the principles which the Encyclopaedists maintained. For,, while the insurrection was justified in so far as it asserted the claims of the special sciences, it was to be condemned in so far as it involved the denial of all synthesis whatever, and also in so far as it was blind to the elements of truth in the imperfect synthesis of the past. It thus tended to destroy the spirit of totality and the sense of duty (/ 'esprit d'ensemble et le sentiment clu devoir).*' It practically denied the existence of any universal principle which could connect the different parts of knowledge with each other, of any general aim which could give unity to the life of man. Its analytic spirit was fatal, not only to the fictions *Pol. Pos. iii. 499 : Trans. 419. Can Heart contradict Head? 189 of theology, but also to that growing consciousness of the solidarity of men of which theology had been the accidental embodiment. The reluctance of religious men to admit the claims of what ap- peared to be, and, indeed, to a certain extent was, light, was thus due to a more or less distinct per- ception that their own creed, amid all its partial errors, contained a central truth more important than all the partial truths of science. In clinging to the past they were preserving the germ of the future, and the final victory of science could not come until this germ had been disengaged from the husk of superstition under which it was hid- den. Till that was done, the logic of the heart in clinging to its superstitions was better than the logic of the head in rebelling against them. In other words, the implicit reason of faith was wiser than the explicit reason of science. But this is not all that Comte means. For him Feeling apart from intelli- the appeal to the heart is not merely the appeal to g^g^Se feelings and intuitions, which are the result of the past development of human intelligence, ami especially of the long discipline by which the ( Jhristian Church has moulded the modern spirit ; it is an appeal to the altruistic affections, as ori- 190 The Social Philosophy of Comte. ginal or " innate " tendencies in man which are altogether independent of his intelligence. It is not that the reason of man often speaks through his feelings, but that feeling and reason have in themselves different, and even it may be opposite voices. In this sense, the attempt has often been made in modern times to stop the invasions of critical reflection by setting up the heart as an independent authority. From the Lutheran theologian who said, " Pectus theologum facit" down to the poet of In Mcmoriam, appeals have constantly been made to the feelings to resist the intrusion of doubt : — " If e'er when faith had fall'n asleep, I heard a voice, ' believe no more ' . . . A warmth within the breast would melt The freezing reason's colder part, And like a man in wrath, the heart Stood up and answered, ' I have felt ' : " Such appeals, however, cannot be regarded as other- wise than provisional and self-defensive. " The heart knoweth its own bitterness, and a stranger doth not intermeddle with its joy ; " but just for that reason it has no general content or indepen- dent authority of its own. Whether the phrase "I feel it" mean little or much, depends upon the The Heart by itself says Nothiny. 191 individual who utters it. It may bo the con- centrated expression of a long life of culture and discipline, or it may he the loud but empty voice of untrained passion and prejudice. The "un- proved assertions of the wise and experienced," as Aristotle tells us, have great value, especially in ethical matters ; but it is not because they are unproved assertions, but because we know that the speakers are wise and experienced. To appeal to the heart in general, without saying " whose heart," either means nothing, or it means an appeal to the natural man, i.e., to man as he is before he has been sophisti- cated by culture and experience. But of the natural man, in this sense, nothing can be said. The farther we go back in the history of the individual or the race the more imperfect does their utterance of themselves become ; and when we reach the beginning, we find that there is no manifestation or utterance at all. The natural man of Eousseau was simply an ideal creation, inspired with that intense and even morbid consciousness of self and that fixed resolve to submit to no external law, which were characteristic of Eousseau himself, and which in 192 The Social Philosophy of Comte. him were the last product and quintessence of the individualism of the eighteenth century. The simplicity of this ideal figure is not the first simplicity of nature, but the simplicity of a spirit which has returned upon itself and asserted itself against the world; a kind of simplicity which never existed, at least in the same form, before the great Protestant revolt. The unhis- torical character of this idea becomes doubly evident when we find that, as time goes on, and the spirit of the age alters, the qualities of the natural man are also changed. To St. Simon and Fourier, as to Rousseau, man is good by nature, and it is bad institutions or bad ex- ternal influences which are the source of all the ills that flesh is heir to. But while to the latter the natural man is a solitary, whose chief good lies in the preservation of his independence; to the former he is essentially social, and what is wanted for his perfection and happiness is only to contrive an outward organization in which his social sympathies shall have free play. Comte, as we might expect, rises above these imperfect theories, in so far as he refuses to attribute all the evils of humanity to its external The Natural Man. 193 circumstances ; but he does not free himself from the essential error which was common to them all, the error of seeking for the explanation of the higher life of humanity in the feelings of the natural man — feelings which are prior to, and independent of, the exercise of his reason, and which supply all the possible motives for that exercise. There are, in his view, two sets of " innate " feelings or desires, between which man's life is divided — the egoistic and the altru- istic tendencies, each separate from the others as well as from the intelligence, and having its "organ" in a separate part of the brain. The egoistic feeling's at first exist in man in far greater strength than the altruistic; but by the reaction of circumstances, and the influence of men upon each other, the latter have in the past gradually attained to greater power; and it is the ideal of the future to make their victor)' complete. Meanwhile, the intelligence is neces- sarily the instrument of desire, and its highest good is to be the instrument of altruistic as opposed to egoistic desire. For it has at best only a choice of masters, and the emancipation of the intelligence from the heart could mean N passion. 194 . The Social Philosophy of Comte. only its becoming a slave of personal vanity.* Comte's appeal, therefore, is still to the natural man, or rather to one element in him, which, however, as he acknowledges, is never so weak as it is in man's earliest or most natural state. Hume's view The psychology implied in this theory is sub- of the rela- tion of rea- stantially that which found its fullest expression son and « *- in Hume's "Treatise on Human Nature." Hume, with that tendency to bring things to a distinct issue which is his best characteristic, declares boldly that " reason is and ought to be the slave of the passions, and can never pretend to any other office than to serve and obey them." The pas- sions or desires are tendencies of a definite char- acter which exist in man from the first ; the awaking intelligence cannot add to their number, or essentially change their nature. It can only take account of what they are, and calculate how best to satisfy them. "We speak not strictly and philosophically when we talk of the combat of reason and passion," for while reason determines what is true and what is false, it sets nothing before us as an end to be pursued and avoided. It does not constitute, and it cannot transform, *Pol. Pos. i. 421. The Subordination of Reason. 195 the desires, which are given altogether apart from it : nor is the will anything but the strongest desire. When we say that reason controls the passions what we mean is simply that a strong but calm tendency of our nature, which has reference to some remote object, overcomes a violent impulse towards a present delight ; but for intelligence to contend with passion is, strictly speaking, an impossibility. The modifications which Comte makes in this comte's modification view of motive are comparatively trilling. He vj L . w imK does not, indeed, like Hume, call reason the slave of the passions ; rather he says that " T esprit doit etrc le ministre du cosur, ma/is jamais son eselave;" but this change of language does not involve any important modification of Hume's theory. The intelligence may give the heart much information about the means whereby it may attain its ends, but the ends have to be determined solely by the heart itself. In Comte's language the intellect is a " slave," when theology makes it acknowledge the existence of fictitious supernatural beings whose natures are in accord- ance with our desires, our hopes or our fears ; it is a " master," when it pursues its inquiries into 196 The Social Philosophy of Comte. the phenomena of the objective world, at the bid- ding of an errant curiosity, without reference to the well-being of man ; it is in its true place as a " servant " when it studies the objective world freely, but only with reference to the end fixed for it by the affections. " Z'univcrs doit etre vtvxl%6 non pour hii-mSme, mats pour Vhomme, ou plutot pour VhumaniU ';" and this, Comte thinks, will not be done if the intelligence be left to itself, but only if it be made subordinate to the heart. To say, therefore, that the intelli- gence is not to be a slave but a servant, implies merely that it is to be left free to collect infor- mation about the means of satisfying the desires, without having its judgment anticipated by the imagination or the heart ; but that, on the other hand, it must be kept strictly to its position as an instrument to an end out of itself. For if it once emancipates itself from the yoke of feeling, it soon becomes altogether lawless, and disperses its efforts in every direction in the satisfaction of a vain curiosity. The intelligence, as the schol- astic theologians said, is in itself, or when left to itself, a source of anarchy and confusion ; it must be, not indeed the serva, but the ancilla fidei Tendencies of the Intellect 197 otherwise it will defeat its own ends. The intel- lectual life, as such, is an unsocial, even a selfish existence ; for, as reason is guided by no definite objective aim derived from itself, it must rind its real motive in the satisfaction of personal vanity and self-conceit, whenever it is not subjected to the yoke of the altruistic affections. This theory (which, as we shall see, underlies f£g23* the intellect Comte's whole conception of history) suggests purely dis- ] iersive ? two questions. It leads us to ask, in the first place, whether the tendencies of the intellectual life are thus dispersive and opposed to the social tendencies : and, secondly, whether the social tendencies in the form which they take with man, are not necessarily determined to be what they are by his intelligence. The former ques- tion really resolves itself into another: Is the intelligence of man a mere formal power of apprehending what is presented to it from with- out, so that, when it is left to itself, it can only lose its way amid the infinite multiplicity of individual objects in the external world; or does it carry within it any synthetic principle, any idea of the whole, by which it can reduce to unity and order the difference and confusion of phenomena? 198 The Social Philosophy of Comte. Against Comte's assertion that the natural ten- dency of the intelligence is to lose itself in difference without end, we might quote the well-known saying of Bacon, that the tendency of the " intellectus sibi permissus " is rather to- wards a premature synthesis. "Intellectus hu- manus ex proprictate sua facile svpponit major em ordinem et cequalitatem in rebus quam invenit." Surely, if we may speak of tendencies of the in- tellectual life as separated from the life of feeling, the tendency to unity and the universal belongs to it quite as much as the tendency to difference and the particular ; just as in the life of feeling the tendency to isolation and self-assertion against others is combined with the tendency to society and union with others. From the first moment of intellectual life the world is to us a unity ; subjectively a unity, as all its varied phenomena are gathered up in the consciousness of one self, and objectively a unity, as every object and event is conceived as definitely placed hi rela- tion to the other objects and events in one space and one time. The development of knowledge is, no doubt, the continual detection of new differences and distinctions in things, but the phenomena Analysis and Synthesis. 199 which are distinguished from other phenomena are at the same time put in relation to them. Nor can the intelligence find complete satisfac- tion until this relation is discovered to be neces- sary, and thus difference passes into unity again. Individual minds, indeed, may be more of the Aristotelian, or more of the Platonist, order, may tend more to divide what at first is presented as unity, or to unite what at first is presented as difference. But it is absurd to talk of either tendency as belonging, more than the other, to i he intelligence in itself: seeing that it is as much beyond the powers of thought to conceive of an undifferentiated unity, as to conceive of a chaos of differences without some kind of relation. In this regard, indeed, we may bring Comte as a witness against himself; for, while he declares that the sciences which deal with the inorganic world are mainly analytic in their tendencies, he at the same time maintains that the sciences of Biology, and, still more, of Sociology and Morals, are synthetic, since they deal with objects in which the whole is not a mere aggre- gation or resultant of the parts, but in which rather the parts can be understood only in and 200 The Social Philosophy of Comte. through the whole. Hence it would seem that the dispersive tendencies of science are confined to the lower steps of the scientific scale ; and that the final science admits and necessitates a syn- thesis, which is not merely subjective, but also objective. For Comte does not hold that we are to regard other men merely as means, or to seek to understand them only so far as is neces- sary for the gratification of some desire in ourselves as individuals. We are, on the contrary, to seek to know man in and for him- self ; and when we do so know him, we find that he is essentially social, and that the indi- vidual, as such, is a mere " fiction of the meta- physicians." Here again, therefore, we find that Comte's system ends in a compromise be- tween opposite tendencies of thought. As his subjective synthesis after all was found to be ob- jective, at least so far as mankind were concerned, so in like manner his opposition of the intellect to the heart turns out to be only partial ; for when the intelligence is directed to psychology and sociology, it gives us an idea of humanity, ac- cording to which all men are " members one of another." The warfare of the heart and the Is Altruism innate / 201 intelligence thus resolves itself into another ex- pression of that dualism between the world and man, which we have already considered. The second question — whether the altruistic Are not the social affee- affections of man do not imply, or are not neces- n ^"* n,y' r " i-iiii c i • reason? sarily connected with, the development ot his reason or self-consciousness — is even more im- portant. Comte, like Hume, took all the desires, higher and lower, as tendencies given apart from the reason, which can only devise the means of satisfying them, and is, therefore, necessarily their servant. Reason itself on this view does not essentially affect the character of those tendencies which it obeys. " Cupiditas est appetitus cum ejusdem conscientia" says Spinoza, and immediately he goes on to speak as if the "conscientia" made no change in the character of the " appetitus." But if we think of appetites or desires — some of them tending to the good of the individual, others to the good of the species — as existing in an animal which is not conscious of a self, these appetites will neither be selfish nor unselfish in the sense in which we apply these terms to man. Where there is no ego there can be no alter ego, and therefore neither egoism nor altruism. The con- 202 The Social Philosophy of Comte. sciousness of the self as a permanent unity to which all the different tendencies are referred, and the consequent rise of a new desire for the good or happiness, as distinct from the desires of particular objects, are essential to egoism. The consciousness of an alter ego, i.e., of a community with others which makes their interests our own, and hence the consequent rise of a love for them, — which is not disinterested merely as the animal appetites are disinterested, because they tend directly to their objects without any thought of self, but dis- interested in the sense that the thought of self is conquered or transcended, — is essential to altruism. Each of these tendencies may coincide in its matter, or rather in its first matter, with the appetites ; viewed from the outside, they may seem to be nothing higher than hunger or thirst, and sexual or parental impulse; but their form is different. In becoming combined with self-consciousness, they are changed as by a chemical solvent, which dissolves and renews them ; nay, as by a new principle of life, whose first transformation of them is nothing but the beginning of a series of transformations both of their matter and their form ; so that, in the end, the simple direct ten- Reason as a Social Principle. 203 dency to an object — the uneasiness which sought its cure without reflection either upon itself or upon anything else — is transmuted, on the one side, into a gigantic ambition and greed, which would make the whole world tributary to the lust of the individual, and, on the other side, into a love of humanity in which self-love is altogether transcended or absorbed. Neither of these, how- ever, nor any lower form of either is in such wise external to reason, that we can talk of them as determining it to an end which is not its own. Both are simply the expression in feeling of that essential opposition of the self to the not-self, and at the same time that essential unity of the self with the not-self, which are the two opposite, but complementary, aspects of the life of reason. And the progressive triumph of altruism over egoism, which constitutes the moral significance of history, is only the result of the fact that an individual, who is also a conscious self, cannot find his happiness in his own individual life, but only in the life of the whole to which he belongs. A selfish life is for such a being a contradiction. It is a life in which he is at war with himself as well as with others, for it is the life of a being who, 204 The Social Philosophy of Comte. though essentially social, tries to find satisfaction in a personal or individual good. His " intelli- gence " and his " heart " equally condemn such a life ; it is not only a crime but a blunder. For a spiritual being, as such, is one who can save his life only by losing it in a wider life, one who must die to himself in order that he may live. In the progress of man's spirit, therefore, there is no necessary or possible schism between the two parts of his being ; but, on the contrary, the development of the one implies the develop- ment of the other. It is the more comprehensive idea, as well as the higher social purpose, which always triumphs ; and if what is called intellec- tual culture sometimes seems to have the worse in the struggle for existence, it is because it is a superficial or formal culture, which does not really represent the most comprehensive idea. Bearing of This leads us to observe that the opposition of this opposi- tion on the heart to the intelligence is Comte's key to Conites ° J history. the whole history of the past, especially in rela- tion to religion. Theology is to him a system growing out of a natural, though partially errone- ous, hypothesis, an hypothesis which in its first appearance was well suited to excite the nascent False Synthesis of Theology. 205 intelligence and satisfy the primary affections of man, but which, in its further develop- ment, tended to secure moral and social ends at the expense of truth, and became more and more irrational as it became mure and more useful. Fetichism, the first religion, was the spontaneous result of man's primitive ten- dency to exaggerate the likeness of all things to himself. It is " less distant from Positivity " than any other sort of theology,* for its only error is that it supposes the existence of life wher- ever it finds activity, an error which can " easily be brought to the test of verification " and cor- rected. " We can show it to be an error, and so get rid of it." But Polytheism, seeking for greater generality, refers phenomena, not directly, to beings who are identified with them, but in- directly, to " wills belonging to beings purely imaginary," whose " existence can no more be decisively disproved than it can be demonstrated." Further, Polytheism extends to the order of man's life that kind of explanation which Fetich- ism necessarily confined to nature, because the latter sought to explain everything by man, and * Pol. Pns. iii. |). 85 : Trans, p. 71. 206 The Social Philosophy of Comte. never thought of man himself as requiring ex- planation. But this, while it has the advantage of bringing human life within the domain of speculation, at the same time reduces theology into a palpable instance of reasoning in a circle. For " humanity cannot legitimately be included in the synthesis of causes, from the very fact that its type is found in man." * Last of all comes Monotheism, concentrating still further the theo- logical explanation of the universe, but rendering it still more incoherent and irrational, for " the conception of a single God involves a type of absolute perfection complete in each of the three aspects of human nature, affection, thought, and action. Now, such a conception unavoidably contradicts itself, for either this all-powerful Being must be inferior to ourselves, morally or intellectually, or else the world which he created must be free from those radical imperfections which, in spite of Monotheistic sophistry, have been always but too evident. And even were this second alternative admissible, there would remain a yet deeper inconsistency. Man's moral and mental faculties have for their object to sub- # Pol. Pos. iii. p. 261 : Trans, p. 218. Social Uses of Theology. 207 serve practical necessities, but an omnipotent Being can have no occasion either for wisdom or for goodness." * What reconciles mankind, and especially the Monotheism the great men of light and leading, to these intellectually un- instrument satisfactory conceptions of God, is their practical amty " value in extending and strengthening the social bond. Polytheism was superior to Fetichism, because it lent itself to the formation of that wider community, which we call the State, whereas Fetichism tended rather to confine the sympathies of men to the narrower limits of the family. And Monotheism was the neces- sary basis of that still wider society which binds men to each other simply as men, and apart from any special ties of blood or language. This at least was the case so long as the truth of the unity of humanity had not yet assumed a scien- tific form, and therefore still needed an external support. But when the sciences of sociology and morals arise, this external scaffolding ceases to be necessary, and must even become injurious, as, indeed, Theology at the best is ill-adapted to the social end it has been made to subserve. * Ibid. iii. p. 4.31 : Trans, p. .365. 208 The Social Philosophy of Comte. Though i, in This last point deserves special attention. mJociaf According to Comte, Theology, and above all, Monotheistic Theology, is a system the direct in- fluence of which is altogether unfavourable to the social tendencies, although indirectly, by the course of history, and through the wise modifications to which it has been subjected by the leaders and teachers of mankind, it has become the main instrument in developing altruism. The increas- ing generality of theological belief, indeed, was a necessary condition of the establishment of social unity ; but, by directing the eyes of men not to themselves but to supernatural beings, by making the issues of life turn on the favour or disfavour of such beings rather than on the social action and reaction of men upon each other, and by reducing this world into a secondary position, and subordinating its concerns to those of an- other world, Theology tended to dissolve rather than to knit closer the bonds of society. The relation of the individual to God isolated him from his fellows. Especially was this the case with the Christian form of Monotheism, with its tremendous future rewards and penalties, and the direct relation which it established between the Egoistic Tendency of Theology. 209 soul of the individual and the infinite Being. " The immediate effect of putting- personal salva- tion in the foremost place was to create an unparalleled selfishness, a selfishness rendering all social influences nugatory, and thus tending to dissolve public life." * " The Christian type of life was never fully realized except by the hermits of the Thebaid," who, " by narrowing their wants to the lowest standard, were able to concentrate their thoughts without remorse or distraction on the attainment of salvation." f AVhat else, indeed, but egoism could be awakened by the worship of a God who is himself the supreme type of egoism ? For " the desires of an omnipotent Being, being gratified as soon as formed, can consist in nothing but pure caprices. There can be no appreciable motive either from within or from without. And above all, these pure caprices must of necessity be purely per- sonal; so that the metaphysical formula, To lire in self for self, would be alike applicable to the two extreme grades of the vital scale. The type of divinity thus approximates to the lowest stage * Pol. Pos. iii. p. 41 1 : Trans, p. 348. tlbid. iii. p. 454: Trans, p. 383. 210 The Social Philosophy of Comte. of animality, the only shape in which life is purely individual, because it is reduced to the one function of nutrition." * The natural result of such a religion was, therefore, to discourage the altruistic affections : as, indeed, Monotheism has systematically denied that such affections form part of the nature of man. How its mi- The alchemy which, according to Comte, turned social char- acter was this poison into wholesome food, was found in the neutralized. - 1 altruistic affections of the teachers of mankind, which led them to limit and modify the doctrine they taught, so as to subserve man's moral im- provement. This, however, would not have been sufficient, if these teachers had not at an early period ceased to be a theocracy, or, in other words, if the practical government of mankind had not been wrested from their hand by the military classes. By this change, which con- tained in itself the germ of the separation of the Church from the State, of theory from practice, of counsel from command, the priests, prophets, or philosophers, who were the intellectual leaders of men, were reduced to that position of subordination in which alone * Ibid. iii. p. 446 : Trans, p. 376. Theology subdued to Altruism. 211 (hey can concentrate their attention upon their proper work. For the influences of the intellect, like those of the affections, must be indirect if they are to be pure. "No power, especially if it be theological, cares to modify the will, unless if- finds itself powerless to control action." But when the theoretic class were subordinated to the practical class, they became the natural allies of the women, and, like them, had to substitute counsel for command. At first, indeed, their •subjection was too absolute* for the military aristocracies of Greece and Rome did not leave to the priesthood sufficient independence, or at least sufficient authority, to permit even of counsel. But with the rise of Catholic Mono- theism, supported as it was by a new revelation based upon the idea of an incarnation of God, the separation of Church and State was definitely established, and the intellectual life was put in its proper relation to the life of action. The consequence is that the theological priest- IIow vhvW hood have continually sought to counteract the thebm°£w humanised. natural influences of their doctrine by mak- ing additions which were inconsistent with its " absolute " principle, but which rendered it bet- 212 The Social Philosophy of Comte. ter fitted for the purpose of binding men together. This was especially the case under Monotheism, where, as we have seen, such counteraction was most necessary. From this source arose a series of supplementary doctrines, generally tending to connect God with man, and men with each other. St. Paul, " the real founder of Catholicism," took the first step in reducing Monotheism into a shape in which it could act as an " organic " doctrine : and his successors followed steadily in the same path. If the omnipotence of God raised Him above all human sympathy, and tended to destroy human sympathy in his worshippers, the doctrines of the Trinity and the Incarnation again brought God near to men, and taught them to reverence in themselves a humanity which was raised into unity with God. In the Feast of the Eucharist all men celebrated and enjoyed their unity with this exalted and deified humanity. The same infiuence, in its further development, led to the adoration of the saints, and above all of the Virgin Mother, in whom ■ Christian devotion really worshipped Humanity, in its simplest and tenderest affections. Finally, if benevolent sympathies were denied to nature, St. Paul found a place for them by attri- Nature and Grace. -1\'.\ buting them to grace, "which Thomas a Kempia admirably defines as the equivalent of love — gratw sive dilectio — divine inspiration being sub- stituted for human impulse."* And the struggle between egoism and altruism was expressed in the doctrines of the Fall and Redemption of mankiiid.f Thus the social passion which, according to the theory, could not lie derived from human nature, was conceived to flow from a divine, influence, and became ennobled, at least as a means of sal- vation, in the eyes of those who would otherwise have suppressed it. At the same time, as Comte also contends, these additions or corrections of the original doctrine were inconsistent or imperfect in themselves, and inadequate to the social purpose for which they were destined ; and they naturally disappeared whenever, by the emancipation of the intelligence, the immense egoism, which Mono- theism consecrated in God and favoured in man, was let loose from the bonds in which the Church had confined it. Protestantism was the first in- dication of this change; for Protestantism is hut an organized anarchy, and the only elements of * Pol. Pos. Hi. ]). 447 : Trans, p. 378. t Ibid. iii. p. 40!) : Trans. 346. 214 The Social Philosophy of Comte. order in it are derived from an instinctive conserva- tism, clinging to the fragments of a past doctrinal system which, in principle, has been abandoned- It contains no organic elements of its own — no positive contribution to the progressive life of humanity ; it is simply the first imperfect result of that metaphysical individualism which, in its- ultimate form, freed from all the limits of the Catholic system, expressed itself theoretically in Rousseau and Voltaire, and practically in the French Revolution. The hope of mankind, how- ever, lies in the new synthesis of Positivism, which alone can give due value to the innate altruistic sympathies of man ; for it alone can place on a permanent scientific basis that social order which the mediaeval Church attempted in vain to found on the essentially egoistic and anarchic doctrine of Monotheism. opposition The fundamental conception, then, which under- of elements gtonsofthe ^ es Comte's view of progress is, that every past religion, with the partial exception of Fetichism, has been an amalgam of two radically inconsist- ent elements, of which only one was due to the theological principle itself; while the other was- due, partly to the practical instinct of its priests, Two Elements in Christianity. 215 which led them to modify the logical results of that principle in conformity with the social wants of man; and partly also to their subordinate position, which obliged them to use the spiritual means of conviction and persuasion instead of the ruder weapons of material force. To criticize this theory fully would be to re-write Comte's history of religion. It will be sufficient here to point out that his view of modern history begins in a false interpretation of Christianity, and ends in an equally false interpretation of the Protest- ant Reformation. Christianity from its origin has two aspects or Did this dis- cord exist in elements ; and if we compare it with earlier re- Christianity n ligions, we may call these its Pantheistic and its Monotheistic elements. But these elements are not, as Comte asserts, joined together by a mere external necessity. They are necessarily con- nected in the inner logic of the system ; nor can we regard one of them as more or less essential than the other. In the simplest words of the Gospels we find already expressed a sense of re- conciliation with God, and therefore with the world and self, which is alien to pure Mono- theism, though there is some faint anticipation of 216 The Social Philosophy of Comte. it in the later books of the Old Testament. For a spiritual Monotheism, while it awakens a con- sciousness of the holiness of God, and the sinful- ness of the creature, tends to make fear prevail over love, and the sense of separation over the sense of union. The idea of the unity of the Divine and the Human — an original unity which yet has to be realized by self-sacrifice — and the corresponding idea that the individual or natural life must be lost in order to save it, were pre- sented for the first time, as in one great living picture, in the life and death of Christ. And what was thus directly presented to the heart and the imagination in an individual, was uni- versalized in the writings of St. Paul and St. John ; in other words, it was there liberated from its peculiar national setting, and used as a key to the general moral history of man. The Messiah of the Jews was exalted into the Divine Logos, and the Cross became the symbol of an atone- ment and reconciliation between God and man, which has been made "before the foundation of the world," yet which has to be made again in every human life. The work of the first three centuries was to give to this idea such logical expression as Separation of Church and State. 217 was then possible, in the doctrines of the Incarna- tion and the Trinity. It is true that this idea of the unity of man with God was not immediately carried out to any of the consequences which might seem to be contained in it, Tt remained for a time a religion, and a religion only; it did not show itself to be the principle of a new social <>r political order of life. Rather it accepted the <>ld order represented by the Roman Empire, and even consecrated it as "ordained of God," only demanding for itself that it should be allowed to purify the inner life of men. Such a separation of the things of Caesar and the things of God was i hen inevitable; for it is impossible that a new principle can ever lie received simply and without alloy into minds, which are at the same time occupying themselves with its utmost practical or even its utmost theoretical consequences. In Ibis sense there is much truth in what Comte says about the value of the separation of the spiritual from the temporal authority. The power of directly realizing a new religious principle, just because it draws away attention from the principle itself to 1 he details of its practical application, is likely to prevent that application being either a complete or 218 The Social Philosophy of Comte. even a true expression of the principle. Practical inferences from such a principle cannot safely be drawn by mere logical deduction ; they will be drawn with certainty and effect only by those whose whole spiritual life the principle has remoulded. The decided withdrawal of the Christian Church from the sphere of " practical politics " was, therefore, not merely a necessity forced upon it from without ; it was a con- dition which its best members gladly accepted, because without it the inner transformation of man's life by the new doctrine would have been impossible. If Christianity had raised a servile insurrection it never could have put an end to slavery. Growtii of But while this withdrawal was necessary, it dualism in the middle contained a great danger ; for the inner life ages. o o ' cannot be separated from the outer life without becoming narrowed and distorted. Confined to the sphere of religion and private morality, the doctrine of unity and reconciliation necessarily became itself the source of a new dualism. What had been at first merely neglect of the world was gradually changed into hostility to worldly interests ; and the germs of a positive morality, Medicsval Asceticism. 219 reconciling the flesh and the spirit, which appear in the New Testament, were neglected and over- shadowed in the growth of asceticism. Chris- tianity, even in its first expression, had a negative side towards the natural life of man ; while it lifted man to God, it yet taught that humanity " cannot be quickened except it die." But the mediaeval Church, while it constantly taught that humanity must die to all its natural impulses, had almost forgotten to hope that it could he quickened. Its highest morality — the morality of the three vows — was the negation of all social obligations; its science was the interpretation of a fixed dogma received on authority; its religion tended to become an external service, an opus operatum, a preparation for another world, rather than a principle of action in this. Its highest act of worship, the Eucharist, in which w T as celebrated the revealed unity of men with each other and with God, was reserved in its fulness for the clergy, and even with them was finally reduced to an external act by the doctrine of tran- substantiation, in which poetry " became logic," and in becoming logic, ceased to be truth. ._ „. . , , . . . Unity of the JNow, Comte, seeing the working <>i this two elements in Chris- tianity. s 220 The Social Philosophy of Comte. negative tendency in mediaeval Catholicism, and regarding it as the natural work of Monotheism, is obliged to treat all the positive side of Chris- tianity as an external addition suggested by the practical wisdom of the clergy. St. Paul is supposed by him to have invented (and Comte'! language would even suggest that he consciously invented*) the doctrine of grace, in order to reconsecrate those social affections which Mono- theism, in its condemnation of nature, had either denied to exist, or, what is nearer the truth, had treated as having no moral value. But this only shows how imperfectly Comte had grasped the Pauline conception of the moral change which religion produces. The idea that the immediate untamed and undisciplined will of the natural man is not a principle of morality, and that therefore man must die to live, must rise above himself to be himself, is one which has in it nothing discord- ant with the claims of social feeling. It is the commonplace of every powerful writer on prac- tical ethics, from the Gospels to Thomas a Kempis, and from Luther to Goethe. * Pol. Pos. iii. p. 409 : Trans, p. 346. Self-realization through Self-sacrifice. 221 " Unci .so lang du das nicht hast, Dieses : Stirb und Werde, Bist du nur ein trliber ( !ast Auf der dunkeln Erde,." St. Paul adds that this death to self is possible only to him in whom another than his own natural will lives; "so then it is not 1 that live, but Christ that liveth in me." Conite would accept the words of St. Paul with the. substitution of Humanity for Christ. But either substitution involves the negation of the natural tendencies, whether individual or social, in their immediate natural form ; and Conite himself, when he placed not only the sexual but even the maternal impulse among those that are merely " personal or egoistic," virtually ac- knowledged that the natural or instructive basis of the altruistic affections is not in itself moral.* But because he begins with a psychology which treats the egoistic and altruistic desires, and again the intellect and the heart, as distinct and independent entities, he is unable to do justice to an account of moral experience which involves that they are essentially related elements * Ibid. i. p. 72(5 : Trans, p. .*>G2. 999 The Social Philosophy of Gorate. in one whole, or necessarily connected stages of its development. Their opposi- In the form in which it was first presented, the tion in its development, teaching of Christianity was undoubtedly ambigu- ous, as, indeed, every doctrine in its first and simplest form must be. In that form we cannot, without limitations, call it either social or anti- social ; it is anti-social and ascetic, because of its negative relations to the previous forms of life and culture ; it is social and positive, in so far as in its primary doctrine of the unity of the divine and human — of divinity manifested in man and humanity made perfect through suffering — it contains the promise and the necessity of a development by which nature and spirit shall be reconciled. The progressive tendency of Christendom was based on the fact that from the earliest times the followers of Christ were placed in the dilemma, either of denying their primary doctrine of reconciliation between God and man and going back to pure Monotheism, or of advancing to the reconciliation of all those other antagonisms of spirit and nature, the world and the Church, which arose out of the circumstances of its first publication. And modern history is Development of Christianity. -2-23 more than anything else the history of the long process whereby this logical necessity manifested itself in fact. The negative spirit of the Middle Age, its asceticism, its dualism, its formalism, its tendency to transform the moral opposition of natural and spiritual into an external opposition between two separate worlds, present and future, and thus to substitute " other- wordliness " for worldliness, instead of substituting unwoiidliness for both — all these characteristics were the natural results of the fact that the idea of Christianity, in its first abstract form, could not include, and therefore necessarily became opposed to, the forms of social life and organization with which it came into contact. But while the early Christians looked for the realization of the kingdom of Heaven in some immediate earthly future, and the Middle Age postponed it to another life, Christ had already taught the truth, which alone can turn either of these hopes into some- thing more than the expression of an egoistic desire — the truth that " the kingdom of God is within us." The reaction of the social neces- sities of mediaeval society on the doctrine — which Comte quite correctly describes as leading to the 224 The Social Philosophy of Comte. gradual elevation of humanity and of human interests— found its main support in the prin- ciples of the doctrine itself, so soon as its lessons had been absorbed into the mind of the people. And the irresistible force of the movement, whereby at a later period the intelligence was emancipated from authority, and the claims of the family and the State were asserted against the Church, lay above all in this, that Christianity itself was felt to involve the consecration of human life in all its interests and relations. Luther's appeal to the New Testament and to the earliest ages of Chris- tianity was in some ways unhistorical, but it expressed a truth. Protestantism was not a return to the Christianity of the first century; it was an assertion of the relation of the individual to God, which was itself made possible only by the long work of Latin Catholicism. But the development of a doctrine, if it has in it any germ of truth which is capable of development, involves a continual recurrence to its first, and therefore its most general, expression. The ele- ments successively developed in the Catholic and the Protestant, the Latin and the Germanic Self-realisation through Self-sacrifice. 225 forms of Christianity, were both present in the original germ, and the exaggerated prominence given in the former to the negative side of Christianity could not but lead, in the develop- ment of thought, to a similarly exaggerated manifestation of its positive side. But it is nearly as absurd to say, as Comte does, that the true logical outcome of Christianity is to be found in the " life of the hermits of the Thebaid," as it would be to say that its true logical outfcome is to be found in those vehement assertions of nature — naked and unashamed — as its own sufficient warrant, which poured almost with the force of inspiration from the lips of Diderot. Both extremes are equally removed from that special moral temper and tone of feeling which we call distinctively Christian — the former by its want of sympathy and tenderness, no less than the latter by its want of purity and self-command. Eeassertion of nature through its negation, or to put it more simply, the puri- fication of the natural desires by the renunciation of their immediate gratification, is the idea that is more or less definitely present in all phases of the history of Christianity; and, though sway- 226 The Social Philosophy of C orate. ing from one side to the other, the religious life of modern times has never ceased to present both aspects. Even a St. Augustine recoiled from the Manichseism by which nature was regarded, not simply as fallen from its original idea, but as essentially impure. And, on the other hand, even Eousseau's Savoyard vicar, who freed himself from the negative or ascetic element as completely as is possible for any one still retaining any tincture of Christianity or even of religion, and who insists so strongly on the text that " the natural is the moral," is yet forced to recognize that nature has two voices, and that the raison commune has to overcome and transform the natural inclinations of the individual. In the life of its Founder, the Christian Church has always had before it an individual type of that harmony of the spiritual and natural life, which it is its ideal to realize in all the wider social relations of man ; nor, till that ideal is reached, can it be said that the Christian idea is exhausted, or that the place is vacant for a new reli- gion, — great as may be the changes of form and expression through which Christianity must Egoism and Altruism. 227 pass under the changed conditions of modern life. Thai (unite was not able to discern this, arose, comte'sown dualism. as we have seen, from the fact that he held to a kind of Manichseism of his own. To him the egoistic and the altruistic desires were two kinds of innate tendencies, both of which exist in man from the first, though with a great preponder- ance on tin- side of egoism.* Moral improvement * Comte insists with great force on the danger of taking an organism as the mere sum of its parts, or its life as merely the resultant of their external action and reaction upon each other: but in his psychological analysis, lie often seems to forget this principle. If he recognizes that, as we rise in the scale of animal life, there is a con- tinually advancing differentiation of the simple unity we find in the lowest organisms, he does not always remember that this implies and necessitates a correspondent integra- tion. Hence in the end the unity which he establishes between the different elements, e.g., between the intellect and the heart, or between the egoistic and the social ini- ] raises, is external and artificial. In his Psychology the fact that it is / who think, / who feel, / who desire finds no sufficient place, and, therefore, in his Ethics he can reach no ideal except that of an external harmony of the different faculties and tendencies. Where the primary unity below the difference and conflict of the parts is not recognized, it becomes impossible to see beyond their antagonism to its reconciliation in -Ap'ital unity. See especially Comte's sketch of Psychology in the third chapter of the Introduction Fonclamentnle. Pol. Pos. i. 685, seq. 228 The Social Philosophy of Comte. simply consists in altering the original propor- tions in favour of altruism, and moral perfection would be the complete extinction of egoism (which with Comte would naturally mean the extinction of all the desires classified as personal). Hence there is a somewhat ascetic tendency in some of the ideas of the Politique Positive — i.e., asceticism sometimes appears in it, not simply as a tran- sitionary process through which certain natural desires are to be purified, but as an attempt, so far as possible, to extinguish them. A deeper analy- sis would have shown that the desires in them- selves, as mere natural impulses, are neither egoistic nor altruistic, neither bad nor good ; and that if, as they appear in the self-conscious life of men, they are necessarily infected with egoism, yet that the ego is not absolutely opposed to the alter ego, but rather implies it. A spiritual or self- conscious being is one who can realize his own individual good only as he realizes the good of others : but, in seeking to realize such a good, it is not needful that he should renounce any natural desire as impure; for there is no natural desire which may not become the expression oi the better self, which is ego and alter ego in one. Is Christianity Other-worldliness ? 22U But Comte, unable from the limitations of his psychology to see the true relation of the negative and the positive side of ethics, is obliged to treat the ascetic tendency of Christianity as involving a denial of the existence in man of innate social sympathies ; and on the other hand, to regard the efforts of the Christian Church to cultivate such sympathies, as the result of an external accom- modation. His idea of Christianity practically coincides with the definition of virtue given by Paley; it is " doing good to man, in obedience to the will of Cod, with a view to eternal happi- ness." On this view the Christian life is the pursuit of a selfish end by means in themselves unselfish, or it is selfishness turned to unselfish iiction in view of the pleasures and pains of another world ; and so soon as doubt is cast upon these supernatural rewards and punishments, the false ^diow of benevolence must disappear and leave bare selfishness in its place. Hence Comte is just neither to Catholicism nor to Protestantism; for, while he maintains the former to be only in- directly social, he regards the latter as the first step in a scepticism which, taking away the fears and hopes of another world, must at the same 230 The Social Philosophy of Gomte. time take away all restraint upon selfishness. And, just because he is unable fully to under- stand either the negative spirit of the earlier, or the positive spirit of the later, phase of modern life, he has an imperfect appreciation of that social ideal to which both are tending, and which must combine in itself the true elements of both. Yet we cannot say that he is equally unfair to Catholicism and to Protestantism. It is the temptation of writers on social subjects to be least just to the tendencies of the time which precedes their own, and against the errors of which they have immediately to contend. Hence we are not surprised to find that Comte does more justice to Catholicism than to Protestantism, or to that Individualism which grew out of Protestantism. The Eeformation and what is called in German the Avfkldrvng he regards solely on their de- structive side, as successive stages in the modern movement of revolt, while he fails to appreciate the constructive elements involved in each of them. Hence also, in his attitude towards this threat movement, he all but identifies himself with Catholic writers like De Maistre ; and his own scheme of the future is essentially reactionary. Two Aspect* of Protestantism. 231 The restoration of the spiritual power to its mediaeval position was for Conite a natural pro- posal, because he could see in the Protestant revolt nothing more than an insurrectionary movement, which might clear the way for a new social construction, but which in itself was the negation of all government whatever. But what was Protestantism ? To the Pro- The defects of Protes- testant it seemed to be simply a return to the tautis m. original purity of the Christian faith; to the Catholic, it seemed to be a fatal revolt against the only organization by which Christianity could lie realized. Really it partook of both char- acters. It involved a dangerous misconception of the social conditions, under which alone the re- ligious life can be realized and developed; but it involved also a deeper and truer apprehension of that religion, which first recognized the latent (^ivinity, or universal capacity, of every spiritual being as such, and, which, therefore, seemed to impose upon every individual man the right or rather the duty of living by the witness of his own spirit. Comte saw only the former of these two aspects of it. Hence he regarded the French Revolution as a practical refutation of the individ- 232 The Social Philosophy of Comte. ualism which grew out of the Protestant move- ment, and not, as it was in truth, a critical event, which forced men to distinguish and separate its true from its false elements. He drew from it, indeed, a true lesson — the lesson that the individual as such has no moral or religious life of his own, and that it is only in proportion as he transcends his own individu- ality and lives in the life of humanity, that his spiritual life can have any depth or riches in it. "We are afraid to put men to live and trade each on his own private stock of reason, because we suspect that the stock in each man is small, and that the individuals would do better to avail themselves of the general bank and capital of nations and of ages." The truth expressed in these words was seen as clearly by Comte as by Burke. And because lie saw it, Comte regarded the Protestant In- dividualism, which throws individuals back upon themselves, as tending merely to empty their minds of all real interests, and to deliver them over to their own caprices. Private judgment and popular government were to him only pretentious names for intellectual and ido of itant- Caiholidsm an Imperfect Christian it;/. 233 political anarchy : and his remedy for the moral diseases of modern times was the restor- ation of that division of the spiritual and temporal authorities, which existed in the Middle Ages. There is, however, another aspect of the The good ' £ side' Protestantism and of the apparently anarchical gg doctrines derived from it, to which Comte pays no attention. Catholicism, as we have seen. had developed one aspect of Christianity, until, by its exclusive prominence, the principle of Christianity itself was on the point of being lost. It had changed the division between laity and clergy, world and Church, from a relative to an absolute division; it had presented Christian doctrine, not as something which the spirit of the individual may ultimately verify for itself, but as something which it must submissively accept without any verification. It had made Christian worship into an opus operatum, a work done by the priest for the people, instead (if a means through which the feelings of the people could be at once drawn out and ex- pressed. Now, it is as opposed to these tend- encies that the Protestant movement had its 234 The Social Philosophy of Comte. highest value. Each of the so-called an- archic doctrines, against which Comte protests, has a good as well as a bad meaning. If, e.g., it is nothing less than intellectual anarchy for every individual to claim to judge for himself, on subjects for which he has not the requisite training or discipline, it is a slavery scarcely less corrupting in its effect than anarchy, when he is made to regard the difference between himself and his teachers as a permanent and absolute one. In the former case, he has no sufficient feeling of his want to make him duly submissive to teach- ing ; in the latter, he has no sufficient conscious- ness of his capacity to be taught, to permit a due reaction of his thought upon the matter received from his teachers. Again, the doctrine of the sovereignty of the people is the negation of all government and social order, if it be taken to mean that the uninstructed many should govern themselves by their own insight, and that the instructed few should simply be their servants and their instruments. But where the people are not recognized as the ultimate source of power, where their consent is not in any The Truth in Protestantism. 235 regular way made necessary to the proceedings ol their governors, they are by that very fact kept in a perpetual tutelage, and cannot possibly feel that the life of the state is their own life. Now, the most important effect of the Protestant move- ment was just this, that it awakened in the individual the consciousness of his universal nature, or, in other words, the consciousness that there is no external power or sovereignty, divine or human, to which he has absolutely and per- manently to submit, but that every outward claim of authority must ultimately be justified by the inner witness of his own spirit. The freedom of man consists in this, that his obedience to the State, to the Church, even to God, is the obedi- ence of his natural to his spiritual self. The essential truth of the Reformation lay in its republication of the doctrine that the voice of God speaks not only without but also within us, ami indeed that " it is only by the God within that we can comprehend the God without." And the nations, which had learned that lesson in religion, soon hastened to apply it to the social and political order of life. It is undoubtedly a lesson which is liable to misa] (prehension, as 236 The Social Philosophy of Oomte. may be seen, not only from the tendency of many Protestant sects to put the inner life in opposition to the outer, and so to deprive the former of all wider contents and interests ; but also from the ultimate substitution, by Rousseau and others, of the assertion of the natural, for the assertion of the spiritual, man. By such writers the mere capacity of man for a higher life is treated as if it were the higher life itself : and it is forgotten that the capacity is nothing unless it be realized, and that its realization requires the surrender of individual liberty and private judgment to the guidance and teaching of those, in whom that realization has already taken place. But it is not the less true that the con- sciousness of the capacity, and consequently of the duty, of becoming not merely a slave or instrument, but an organ, of the intellectual and moral life of mankind, is the essential basis of modern life. " Henceforth, I call ye not ser- vants, for the servant knoweth not what his lord doeth ; but I have called you friends," is a word of Christ which scarcely began to be verified till the Reformation. And while its verification can- not mean the negation of that division of labour Comte and Democracy. 237 upon which society rests, — cannot mean that each one should know and judge, any more than that each one should do, everything for himself, it at least means that every power and autho- rity should henceforth be, in the true sense of the word, a spiritual power, and should, therefore, rest for its main support upon the opinion of those who obey it. It is because he has not appreciated this truth that Comte so decidedly breaks with the democratic spirit of modern times, and seeks to set up an aristocracy in the State and a monarchy in the Church. Yet the spirit of the age is, after all, too strong for him, and while he refuses to the governed any regular and legitimate way of reacting upon the powers that govern them, he recognizes that the vbltima ratio, the final remedy for misgovern- nient, lies in their irregular and illegitimate action. As regards the State, he declares that " the right of insurrection is the ultimate resource with which no society should allow itself to dis- pense." * And as regards the Church he says that if " the High Priest of Humanity, sup- ported by the body of the clergy, should go * Of. Pol. Pos. i. 128 seq. 238 The Social Philosophy of Gomte. wrong, then the only remedy left would be the refusal of co-operation, a remedy which can never fail, as the priesthood rests solely on conscience and opinion, and succumbs, therefore, to their adverse sentence." The civil government, in fact, can bring the spiritual power to a dead-lock, by " suspending its stipend, for in cases of serious error popular subscriptions would not replace it, unless on the supposition of a fanaticism scarcely compatible with the Positive faith, where there is enthusiasm for the doctrines, rather than for the teachers."* Comte also desiderates a strong reactive influence of public opinion from the proletariate, by which the officers, both of Church and State, may be kept faithful to their work. But if this is desirable, why should the pro- letariate have no regular means of making their will felt ? An " organic " theory of the con- stitution of society must surely provide every real force with a legitimate form of expression ; if a social theory embodies the idea of revolution in it, it is self-condemned, comte's par- Comte's social ideal is in many respects a close tial revival if the medi- reproduction of the mediaeval system, with its Hval svstem. J- « 7 seval system. * Pol. Pos. iv. 337 : Trans. 2.94. Church and State. 239 regime dispcrsif of feudalism in the world, and its Papal concentration of authority in the church. For him, the establishment of the national State is as great an error in secular politics, as is the increasing division of labour in the spiritual kingdom of science. Still more strongly, if pos- sible, does he reprobate that mingling of the functions of Church and State, that interference of the secular authority with spiritual matters, such as the education of the people and its religious life, which has been the natural consequence of the failure of the mediaeval Church to maintain its old authority. Notwith- standing his worship of Humanity, the idea of a " parliament of man, a federation of the world," by which all the powers of mankind should be united for the attainment of the highest material and spiritual good, lias no attraction for him. To reduce the State to the dimensions of a commune, and to confine it to the care of purely material interests, is his first political proposal. France, England, and Spain (and we may now add Ger- many and Italy) are, in his view, "factitious aggregates without solid justification," and they will only become "free and durable Slates," when 240 The Social Philosophy of Gomte. they are broken up into fragments, each with a population of two or three millions, and a ter- ritory not exceeding that of Belgium or Tuscany. The " West " will thus be divided into severity republics, and the earth into five hundred ; and the main work of the patriciate will be to direct and regulate the industrial life of the community : each member of the banker triumvirate, who are to be at the head of the State, having one of the great industrial departments under his special super- intendence. On the other hand the unity of humanity is to be represented solely by the spiritual power, in whose hands is to be left the whole work of advancing science, teaching the people, and exercising a moral censorship over all Governments and individuals. And while this spiritual power is, for practical pur- poses, to be strictly organized on the model of the mediaeval Church, it is also, like that Church, to remain, for scientific purposes, inorganic. In other words, it is to admit no division of labour in science, but every scientific man, like a mediaeval doctor, is to profess all science, adding to this the priestly office, which, with Comte, includes both the cure of souls and of bodies. Church and State. 241 To criticize the details of this scheme seems separation of spiritual, to be unnecessary after what has been already a ,"^^ ul u " said. It is not to be denied that the division of Church and State in the Middle Ages was a most important and even a necessary condition of progress. Christianity could never have been impressed upon the minds of men, if the concrete application of its principles had been too rapid. The essential condition of such application was that men should not concern themselves too pre- maturely with it. For the consequences of a moral and religious principle cannot be reached by direct logical deduction ; it is like a living germ, in which, by no analysis or dissection, you can discover the lineaments of the future plant. To find out what it really is, or involves, you must plant it in the minds of men, and let it grow. Hence the mediaeval Church was strong in its weakness, and it was its very victories over the temporal power that were its greatest danger, li became corrupt and lost its hold upon the minds of men, just when it seemed to have established its right to an absolute supremacy. Comte, following De Maistre, attaches great importance to the position of the Popes as arbiters between Q 242 The Social Philosophy of Comte. the Sovereigns and nations of mediaeval Europe. But he forgets that in claiming and maintaining this position, the Popes were distinctly ceasing to be a spiritual power, if it be the function of a spiritual power to inculcate principles rather than to use them to solve practical difficulties. A power interfering in this way with the immediate struggle of interests could not but be invaded by the passions they excite, and it was the more certain to be corrupted by these passions, because it conceived them to be evil, and pretended alto- gether to renounce them. The authority acquired by the Church in the Middle Ages might have its value, as an anticipation of the peaceful federation of the nations under one supreme Government, but it was undoubtedly the first step towards the erasing of the distinction between the temporal and the spiritual power. Their neces- The truth* seems to be that the distinction of sary conflict, , , . . -. . , whensepar- secular and spiritual powers, except m the sense already indicated, is essentially irrational, and that the attempt to realize it in practice must involve, as it did involve in the Middle Ages, a continual internecine struggle. To set up two regularly constituted powers face to face with ated. The Secular and Spiritual Powers. 24o each other, one claiming man's allegiance in the name of his spiritual, and the other in the name of his temporal, interests, is to organize anarchy. So long as man's body and soul are insepar- able, it will be impossible to divide the world between Caesar and God ; for in one point of view all is Csesar's, and in another all is God's. In the Middle Ages the conflict of two despot- isms was necessary to the growth of freedom.; but, when government ceases to be despotic, the need for such division of power passes away. The relative separation between the speculative ami the practical classes — between the scientific and moral teachers of mankind, who have to dis- cover and inculcate principles, and the statesmen or administrators, who have to determine what improvements it is possible at a definite time to make in the organization of man's social and political life — is a division of labour which can surely be secured without breaking up the unity of the social body. It is not desirable that the philosopher, or priest, or man of science, should be king, (and we may even acknowledge that, if he were a king, he would probably be a very bad one): on the other hand, it is desirable that he 244 The Social Philosophy of Gomte. should have his due influence, as the teacher of those general truths out of which all practical improvement must ultimately spring. But the natural difference of the tastes and capacities of men should, in a well-organized State, be suffi- cient to secure due influence to those who are the natural representatives of man's spiritual interests (whether they be religious, philosophic, or scientific), without tempting them, from their proper task of discovering and teaching the truth, to the less appropriate work of determining how much of it comes within " the sphere of practical politics." Comte, indeed, by organizing them as an independent power apart from, and outside of, the State, would make such a perversion ex- tremely probable. A hierarchy of priests under a despotic Pope would soon cease to be, in any sense, a spiritual power ; it would degenerate just as the Papacy degenerated in the fourteenth century ; and this would be only the more certain if, by the Comtist denunciation of specialism, the priests were prohibited, in their own peculiar sphere of scientific research, from any division of labour according to capacity. Por by this prohi- bition their attention would be diverted from The Church against the State. 245 inquiries about the truth of their doctrines to their immediate practical application ; not to mention that, in the case of all but a few com- prehensive minds, the natural result would be an omniscient superficiality, which would be the enemy of all real culture. Deprived of its natural object as ° scientific order, the Comtist Priesthood would inevitably throw itself, with all its energy, into the task of directly influencing the practical life of men ; and, if Comte's political ideas were carried out, it would find itself in the presence of a number of communal States, none of them large enough to offer any effective resist- ance. Positivism must indeed alter human nature, if such a priesthood would not seek to make itself despotic, especially if it could wield such a formidable weapon as the Positivist ex- communication is supposed to be.* The truth is that Comte commits the same comte's social ideal error which misled Montesquieu when he sup- 1 1 °g a l n e ^ ly posed that the great security of a free State lay in the separation of the legislative, executive, and judicial powers, — i.e., in treating the dif- ferent organs through which the common life * Pol. Pos. iv. p. 292. 246 The Social Philosophy of Gomte. expresses itself as if they were independent organisms. He forgot that if such a balance of power was realized, the effect must either be an equilibrium in which all movement would cease, or a struggle in which the unity of the State would be in danger of being lost. The true security against the dangers involved, on the one hand, in the direct application of theory to practice, and, on the other hand, in the too great separation of practice from theory, must lie, not in giving them independent positions as spiritual and temporal powers, but in subordi- nating them to the organic unity of the whole society, whether it be communal, national, or universal. And organic unity, though it does not mean any special form of government, means at least two things : in the first place, that each great class or interest should have for itself a definite organ, and should therefore be able to act on the whole body in a regular and constitutional manner, so as to show all its force without revolu- tionary violence ; and, in the second place, that no class or interest should have such an inde- pendent position, as to exclude every legal or con- stitutional method of bringing it into due subor- Comte and Kant. 247 ,/dination to the common good. But Comte, losing ] his balance in his jealousy of the individualistic and democratic movement of modern society, has built up a social ideal, which fails in both these points of views, and which, indeed, is a revival of the inorganic structure of mediaeval society. It would not be fair to conclude these chapters, comte's posi- tion as a which have necessarily been devoted in great part philosopher. to criticism and controversy, without expressing a sense of the power and insight which are shown in the works of Comte, especially in the Politique Positive. Controversy itself, it must be remem- 1 >ered, is a kind of homage ; for, as Hegel says, " It is only a great man that condemns us to the ' task of explaining him." But if we can some- times look down upon such men, it becomes us to remember that we stand upon their shoulders. ( .'< >inte seems to me to occupy, as a writer, a posi- tion in some degree analogous to that of Kant. He stands, or rather moves, between the old world and the new, and is broken into incon- sistency by the effort of transition. Like Kant, he is embarrassed to the end by the ideas with which he started, and of which he can never free himself so as to make a new beginning. Comte, 24-8 The Social Philosophy of Comte. indeed, had only a small portion of that power of speculative analysis which characterized his great predecessor, but he had much of his tenacity of thought, his power of continuous construction; he had the same conviction of the all-importance of morals, and the same determination to make all theoretic studies subordinate to the solution of the moral prob- lem. Also, partly because he lived at a later time, and in the midst of a society which was in the throes of a social revolution, and partly because of the keenness and strength of his own social sympathies, he gives us a kind of insight into the diseases and wants of modern society, which we could not expect from Kant, and which throws new light upon the ethical speculations of Kant's idealistic successors. To believe that his system, as a whole, is inconsistent with itself, that his theory of historical progress is insuffici- ent, and that his social ideal is imperfect, need not prevent us from recognizing that there are many valuable elements in his historical and social theories, and that no one who would study such subjects can afford to neglect them. A mind of such power cannot treat any subject His Position as a Pliilosopher. 24!) without throwing much light upon it, which is independent of his special system of thought, and, above all, without doing much to show what are the really important difficulties in it which need to be solved. And, especially in such subjects, to discover the right question is to be half-way to the answer. Further, as Comte himself somewhere says, it is an immense advantage in studying any complex subject to have before us a distinct and systematic attempt to explain it ; for it is only by criticism upon criticism that we can expect to reach the truth, in which its different sides and aspects are brought to a unity. END. GLASGOW: ROBERT MACLEH08B, PRINTER TO THE UNIVERSITY. New Edition in Preparation. A CRITICAL ACCOUNT OF THE PHILOSOPHY OF KANT: with an Historical Introduction. By Edward Caird, M.A., LL.U., Professor of Moral Philosophy in the University of Glasgow, and late Fellow and Tutor of Merton College, Oxford. AN INTRODUCTION TO THE PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. Third Thousand. Demy Svo. 10s. 6d. By John Caird, D.D., Principal and Vice-Chancellor of the University of Glasgow, and one of Her Majesty s Chaplains for Scotland. "A book rich in the results of speculative study, broad in its intellectual grasp, and happy in its original suggestiveness. To Dr. Caird we are indebted for a subtle and masterly representation of Hegel's philosophy in its solution of the problem cf religion. " In addition to the literary skill which places his propositions in their brightest light, and an earnestness of purpose which at times rises into genuine eloquence, he possesses two qualifications which specially tit him for his work : a spirit of reverence which places him in sympathy with mystical and intentional minds ; and an intellectual vigour which enables him to stand side by side with the ablest thinkers, to view the utmost border of their extended range of vision, and, while he treats them with chivalrous fairness, to grapple with their arguments." — Edinburgh Review. " It is the business of the reviewer to give some notion of the book which he reviews, either by a condensation of its contents or by collecting the cream in the shape of short selected passages ; but this cannot be done with a book like the one before us, of which the argument does not admit of condensation, and which is all cream. . . . The most valuable book of its kind that has appeared." — Mr. T. H. Green in The Academy. " It is remarkable also for its marvellous power of exposition and graceful subtlety of thought. Hegelianism has never appeared so attractive as it appears in the clear and fluent pages of Principal Caird." — Spectator. Demy 8vo. Cloth. Price 12s. 6d. KANT AND HIS ENGLISH CRITICS— a Comparison of Critical and Empirical Philosophy. By John Watson, M.A., LL.U., Professor of Moral Philosophy in Queen's University, Kingston, Canada. " Decidedly the best exposition of Kant which we have seen in Knglish. We cannot too strongly commend it." — Saturday Review. "This book is written with clearness and precision, and the author is thoroughly impregnated with the doctrine which he expounds, and makes it as plain as it can be made without becoming other than it is." — Professor T. H. Green, in The Academy. JAMES MACLEHOSE & SONS, Publishers to the University, Glasgow. london and new york: macmillan and co. PROFESSOR NICHOL'S WORKS. TABLES OF EUROPEAN HISTORY, LITERATURE, AND ART, from a.d. 200 to 1882, and of American History, Liter- ature, and Art. By John Nichol, M.A., Balliol, Oxon., LL.D., Professor of English Language and Literature in the University of Glasgow. Third Edition, revised and greatly enlarged. Royal 8vo. Printed in Five Colours, ys. 6d. " The Tables are clear, and form an admirable companion to the student of history, or indeed to anyone who desires to revise his recollection of facts." — Times. " In a word, the great leading facts of European history for nearly seven- teen hundred years are here compressed with wonderful clearness into a single slim volume. The book is a triumph of systematization ; it embodies the result of great research, and will be found an admirable guide to the student, as well as useful for purposes of rapid reference." — Scotsman. "About as convenient a book of reference as could be found." — Spectator. "To the devotees of literature and history Prof. Nichol's Tables will be simply invaluable." — Leeds Mercury. "These Tables, set out as they are with all the advantages of clear arrange- ment, and of excellent typography, are likely to be most useful." — Pall Mail Gazette. TABLES OF ANCIENT LITERATURE AND HISTORY, from B.C. 1500 to a.d. 200. 4 to. Cloth. 4-r. 6d. " They constitute a most successful attempt to give interest to the chro- nology of literature, by setting before the eye the relation between the litera- ture and the practical life of mankind." — Obseiver. THE DEATH OF THEMISTOCLES and other Poems. Extra f cap. 8vo. ys. 6d. " Dignified, careful, conscientious work throughout." — Saturday Review. "A hymn more solemnly beautiful than ' Donna Vera ' was never chanted to Pallas herself by the most inspired of her ancient votaries." — Glasgow Herald. "Professor Nichol is a master of the English epic metre." — Scotsman. JAMES MACLEHOSE & SONS, Publishers to the University, Glasgow. london and new york: macmillan and co AUG 319^0 L'BRARY OF CONGRESS 020 196 872 liillillilllliis IllliiilillilliliSf 1 illiilfllllllil!:; ig Ij ' ] 1 ! 1 1 I ! 1