kV •/>. v ^V ^ ^ *° ^ ^ ,/ % \-' A 9 " C ^ ry ' . if*- ^ v* ^ > o^" a\ ^ \ o o. +*. **' ^ ^ V\ " V ,^ x c / ^ * «*• 50 \ v ./> • >* A \ A 9* * ,0^ o x ^ -^ ^ * -* V ^ V*' PSYCHOLOGY, OR, ELEMENTS NEW SYSTEM OF MENTAL PHILOSOPHY, ON THE BASIS OP CONSCIOUSNESS AND COMMON SENSE. DESIGNED FOB COLLEGES AND ACADEMIES. BY S. S. SCHMUCKER, D.D., PROFESSOR OF CHRISTIAN THEOLOGY IN THE THEOLOGICAL SEMINARY, GETTYSBURG. SECOND EDITION, MUCH ENLARGED. NEW-YORK: PUBLISHED BY HARPER & BROTHERS, NO. 82 CLIFF-STBEET. 1844. «££ Entered, according to Act of Congress, in the year 1842, by Harper & Brothers, In the Clerk's Office of the Southern District of New-York. M PREFACE. As the following publication proposes a system of mental philosophy in some degree new, a few words in regard to its origin may be due alike to the writer and the reader. In general, it owes its existence to the author's desire to promote the cause of truth and science. That cause he regards as identified with the happiness of his fellow-men and the glory of his God. At an early age, he was deeply impressed with the conviction, which no re- flecting mind can fail to feel, that mental philosophy is properly the basis of all science, and that a cor- rect acquaintance with the properties and operations of the mind, would not only facilitate our progress in the study of every department of truth, but, what to him was a matter of supreme importance, would also enable us to acquire a more correct view of the moral condition of the soul, and shed abundant light on some of the practical doctrines of Revelation. This latter consideration is men- tioned here, because it was really the writer's prin- cipal motive for pursuing this subject, although he has by no means mingled religion with metaphys- ics in the following treatise ; on the contrary, his A 2 VI PREFACE. investigations of the one were conducted altogether independently of the other. About sixteen years ago, having been called to take charge of a theo- logical seminary, he felt it a duty to devote par- ticular attention to his instructions in this depart- ment, and formed a resolution, which has doubtless had some influence on this system. He had con- siderable acquaintance with the patriarchs of Brit- ish metaphysics, Locke, Reid, Stewart, and Brown, as well as with some few German authors ; but neither of them seemed to present an entirely nat- ural and satisfactory exhibition of his own mental phenomena. He then resolved to study exclusively his own mind, and for ten years he read no book on this subject. During this period, he spent much of his time in the examination of his own mental phenomena, and having travelled over the whole ground, and employed the leisure of several addi- tional years to review and mature his views, he now presents to the public the following outline of a sys- tem, as in all its parts the result of original, analytic induction. That he regards it as a more natural, faithful, and intelligible exhibition of the operations of his own mind than is contained in any other work which he has seen, he will not dissemble. Since the features of his own system have been settled, the writer has looked at various other works, and found much that is valuable, especially in the re- PREFACE. Vll cent publications of his own countrymen, Professors Upham, Day, Tappan, and others, yet nothing which seemed to invalidate his system, or render dubious the propriety of its publication. As this work is designed, not only for intelligent popular readers, but also for use in colleges and academies, the author has abridged his manuscript, and made it sufficiently brief to leave ample room for the explanatory observations of the professors and teachers, as well as written exercises of the students. For an experience of more than twenty years in teaching has convinced him, that the most successful method of imparting a thorough knowl- edge of such subjects, is to combine with a brief text-book the explanations and illustrations of thein- structer, and, at the same time, to require the stu- dent to exercise his pen in preparing either essays on the most prominent topics, or an analysis, or a regular compend of the whole. After frequent solicitation from those who heard the author's lectures, and from some other gentle- men of high literary and scientific rank who exam- ined the manuscript, this work is at length submitted to the public, with an earnest solicitude that it may subserve the cause of truth and human happiness. The author does not flatter himself that his views on all the topics discussed, have reached entire ac- curacy ; he will thankfully receive and carefully Vlll PREFACE. weigh any suggestions which may be made, espe- cially if presented in the spirit of benevolence or of literary comity. If the map of the human mind here presented is found to be more faithful and intelligible than those heretofore in use, if it tends to make perspicuous a subject hitherto proverbially abstruse and obscure, it will doubtless find friends, and the author will rejoice in the assurance that he has not toiled in vain. Of the salutary influ- ence of the principles and results attained, on the grand interests of fundamental Christianity, he en- tertains no doubt. The influence of the views here presented on lo- gic, rhetoric, and a number of related sciences and topics, will be evident to the scientific scholar. Perhaps at a future day some of these relations may be prosecuted by the author, if his health and numer- ous other duties will permit. With these remarks the work is now commended to the blessing of God, and the favour of the friends of true philosophy and religion. S. S. SCHMUCKER. Theological Seminary, » Gettysburg, Pennsylvania. > SECOND EDITION. In preparing for the press this enlarged edition of his Mental Philosophy, the author faithfully avail- ed himself of the suggestions of the principal re- views of the work which have met his eye. Among these, that in the American Biblical Repository, by the distinguished President of Pennsylvania Col- lege, exhibited the greatest familiarity with the sub- ject and with the work, and presented the most numerous suggestions for its enlargement. To that gentleman, as well as to the reviewers in the Meth- odist Quarterly Review, and the New World, and others, the author takes pleasure thus publicly to acknowledge his obligations. In all cases he has carefully weighed their suggestions, and, in most instances, been led to make some farther illustra- tions or additions, which, he trusts, will contrib- ute to the value of the work. He has been happy to find in these writers but little dissent from his general system. The principal topics on which he has made additions, amounting in all to about one third of the whole work, are the following : the classification of the different objects or entities in PREFACE. the universe ; the subject of mnemonics, or the art of improving and aiding the memory ; the pro- cesses of perception and sensation through the bod- ily organs, and the different theories for their ex- planation ; the different classes of feeling, especial- ly the intellectual and moral emotions ; the nature of analytic reasoning, and laws of human belief; imagination ; and the operations of conscience. The work is again commended to the blessing of God and the favour of the public. May, 1843. CONTENTS. INTRODUCTION. Page On the Methodology of the Science, and the several Points of Difference between Mathematical and Metaphysical Reason- ing 13 Definition. Sketch of the Different former Systems : the com- mon division into nine faculties, referred by Reid to two classes, the Intellectual and Active Powers ; by Stewart to three classes, Intellectual, Active, and Social Powers ; and by' Brown to External and Internal States of the Mind . . 25 The German Division, into Sensibilities, Understanding, and Will, substantially adopted by Upham 26 Different System proposed in this Work, into, 1. Cognitive, or those Phenomena of the Mind which are Knowledge, our Cognitions, not including many Operations of the Intellect ; 2. Sentient Phenomena of Mind, including Sensations, Feelings, Emotions, and, in part, Passions ; and, 3. Active Operations, including not only the Will, but also a large part of what, in the other Systems, is embraced under the Intellect or Under- standing 27 PART I. COGNITIVE IDEAS. CHAPTER I. Of Objective Entities ; that is, of the Universe itself, and all the various Objects and Existences constituting it, in themselves considered — Their Objectivity ; that is, their Real Existence — Their Division into Classes 39 CHAPTER II. Of our Cognitive Ideas as Mental Representatives (not images) of all the different Objects or Existences known to us in the Universe — Exact Nature of these Ideas — Criteria for Distin- guishing Ideas of the Cognitive Class — Nature and Sources of Error in our Cognitive Ideas or Knowledge — Ancient Realists and Nominalists— German Realism and Idealism — Transcendental Idealism of Kant — Division of these Ideas, 1. Into Individual and Relative Knowledge; 2. Into Retro- spective (memory, voluntary and spontaneous— mnemonics), present (consciousness), and prospective knowledge (bases of the latter are, Analogy, Causation, and Revelation) . . 69 CONTENTS. CHAPTER III. Page Organic Process by which we obtain these Ideas — Nervous Connexion between the different Organs of Sense and the Brain — Phrenology. 1. Sense of Vision. The Eye, descrip- tion of— Of which Ideas the Eye is the Organ of Perception, and of which not — Of Colour, Shape, Extension, Direction, apparent and relative Size — Feelings accompanying these Perceptions. 2. Sense of Hearing. The Ear, description of — Conductors of Sound, or, rather, of Atmospheric Vibrations — Number of distinguishable Sounds — Relations of Sound, Con- cords, Discords — Their Nature— Difference between our Per- ceptions of Sound and the Feelings accompanying them. 3. Sense of Touch. The Organ itself— Of the Ideas acquired by Touch — Solidity or Fluidity, Shape, Extension, Smoothness or Roughness, Heat or Cold — Whether all resolvable into Resistance and Extension. Externity : Improvements of this Sense — Sanderson — Institutions for the Blind substitute the Sense of Touch for that of Vision. 4. Sense of Tasle. The Organ of Taste — The Wisdom of its Location— Per- ceptions of Flavour, and Feelings connected with them — Great Variety of Flavours — Mode of Distinguishing them in Language. 5 Sense of Smell. The Organ described — Our Knowledge of Odours — Great Variety — In what the Odour objectively consists — Feelings connected with the Percep- tion of Odours —Improvement of the Senses generally — Cases of Mitchell, Dr. Moyse, &c. Different Theories on the Mode of Reciprocal Influence of Body and Soul in general. Theory of Occasionalism — Of Leib- nitz's Pre-established Harmony — Des Cartes's Theory — New- ton's View — Dr. Hartley's Theory of Nervous Vibrations in particular. Result of the Whole 105 PART II. OF SENTIENT IDEAS. Definition of Feelings — Criteria by which this class of Ideas is distinguished 146 CHAPTER I. Classification of Feelings, into Individual and Relative. The Individual class embraces, 1. Sensations, or those Feelings consequent on Perceptions by the Senses. 2. Some Emo- tions, intellectual, as Emotion of the Sublime, of the Beauti- ful, the Ludicrous, of Surprise, of Wonder, &c. — Moral Emo- tions, or those Feelings included in the Operations of Con- science. 3. Some of the Affections — Pleasant Affections, Painful Affections. 4. Feelings connected with our Bodily Appetites. CONTENTS. P»«e Relative Feelings, including, 1. Benevolent Feelings — as Friend- ship, Benevolence, Gratitude, &c., Filial. Parental Love, Love to God. 2. Malevolent or Defensive Feelings — as Anger, Hatred, Ingratitude, Cruelty, &c. 3. Sympathetic Feelings — as Pity, Condolence, Compassion, and Sympathy of various kinds. 4. Antipathetic Feelings — as Envy, Jealousy, Horror, Disgust, Indignation, &c 149 Other less valuable Divisions of Feeling, into Sensuous, Intel- lectual, and Moral — into Present, Retrospective, and Pro- spective . . . . . . . . . . 150 Discussion of the different Branches of the above Classification 151 CHAPTER H. Of the different Tendency of Entities, or the various Objects in the Universe, to excite Feeling 178 CHAPTER III. Susceptibility of the Mind for Feeling — its various Degrees, and the Laws of their Operation 185 PART III. 4.CTIVE OPERATIONS. CHAPTER I. Criteria by which the Active Operations are distinguished from all other Mental Phenomena. Materials on which our Active Operations are performed, are External Objects of the differ- ent classes, past Mental Phenomena of every class, and the Natural Signs by which these Ideas are expressed . . 199 Division and Discussion of the Five Active Operations : I. Inspection. Its Nature, Objects, &c, includes the Active Processes of Perception, Consciousness, Conception, Judgment, Recollection, Analytic Reasoning, and the Impulsive Element of Conscience— Act of Memorizing explained 203 Fundamental Laws of Human Belief Enumerated . . 213 II. Arrangement. Definition of this Active Process. The Purposes aimed at in Arrangement .... 218 Various Principles according to which the Process may be conducted. Arrangement embraces the Processes of Comparison, different Arithmetical Processes, Classifi- cation, Mental Associations based on any Natural Prin- ciple or Affinity, Composition of Music, and Synthetic Reasoning. Nature of Evidence Objectively and Sub- jectively considered — Syllogisms, the Nature of . . 222 III. Modification. Definition — Objects of this Process. It embraces Abstraction, Generalization, Imagination, Xll CONTENTS. Fag* Fancy ; its results are Geometrical Axioms, Metaphysi- cal Axioms, Mathematical Truths, Moral general Truths or Principles (the fallacy of Kant and other writers, particularly in Germany, who regard these general truths as a priori knowledge), Works of Fiction in Wri- ting, Painting, Sculpture, &c. IV. Mental Direction of our Physical Agency described — Its different Kinds — Its several Concomitants. V. Intellectual Intercourse with other Minds. Philosophical Nature of, described. 1. By Articulate Sounds — Nature of Oral Language— Connexion between Words and Ideas — How far Language is of Divine Origin. 2. By Ges- tures and Features of Countenance. 3. By Written Signs — Alphabet of Chinese, of the Cherokees — Arith- metic Figures — Musical Notes — The Complex Opera- tion of Composition described. Attention— why not a separate Power of the Soul. CHAPTER II. Mode of Occurrence of the Five Active Operations is twofold : 1. Voluntary— Proof of Man's Voluntary or Moral Agency : Motives — The Will — Two Constitutional Inclinations of the Soul ; the first, to Obey the Physical, Intellectual, and Moral Fitness of Things, Conscience— The second, to pursue our Well-being or Pleasure— The latter Incli- nation stronger in Man since the Fall— Different Modi- fications of these Constitutional Inclinations : love of Life, of Property, of Power, &c. — Desires : their Differ- ence from Feelings. 2. Spontaneous Occurrences of the Active Operations — Dif- ference between Spontaneous and Voluntary Action — Laws of the Spontaneous Active Operations — Laws of Association — Why we are responsible also for our Spontaneous Action Pragmatic View — Dreams 289 Recapitulation, for Reviews and Examinations . . 295 INTELLECTUAL PHILOSOPHY. INTRODUCTION. It has long been a subject of remark, that while the science of mathematics, which discusses the properties and relations of space and number, is ac- companied by the most conclusive evidence, and bears conviction with it at every step of its prog- ress, the philosophy of the mind still remains en- veloped in comparative darkness and uncertainty, after the intellect of ages has been expended in its investigation. The question arises, Are not both similar in their nature, and alike susceptible of de- monstrative discussion ? It seems evident, that they are not precisely alike, and yet much of the ob- scurity enveloping mental science, doubtless arises from the unphilosophical manner, in which its in- vestigations have been conducted, and the inappro*- priate style in which the result of them has gener- ally been recorded. The superior force of mathe- matical reasoning, arises from three sources. First, from an intrinsic difference in the nature of the sub- jects discussed. Secondly, from the more rigidly an- alytic method of investigation, pursued in the math- ematics. And, thirdly, from a less elegant, indeed, but more precise and perspicuous method of con- veying to others the knowledge we have acquired. B 14 INTRODUCTION. A distinguished and popular writer* of the pres- ent day, alleges the difficulty of ascertaining with pre- cision the operations of other minds, as a prominent cause of the uncertainty of mental science. But this appears to us to be an erroneous view. All minds are, in healthy subjects, constituted essen- tially alike ; and as every student of this science has access to the phenomena of his own mind, he can draw from this source abundant materials for the examination of any and of every aspect of the subject. We have, moreover, the candid testimo- ny of a multitude of writers on these topics, each presenting the details of his own mind ; so that this science need not labour under obscurity for want of the experience of different and independent witnesses. The testimony of consciousness in re- gard to our individual mental operations separately considered, seems also to be distinct and satisfac- tory. And the testimony of others concerning the clearness of their consciousness, coincides with our own experience. But when we attempt to trace the unknown cause of these operations which lies behind them ; or to determine and systematize their relations to each other, which are often diversified and obscure, we encounter difficulties on every side. And these difficulties encumber the investi- gation of our own mental phenomena, as well as those of others. It is indeed true, that in morbid mental action, the operations of different minds are very diverse, and the careful collation of these diversified phases * Dr. Abercrombie on the Intellectual Powers, p. 15, 16, Harpers' ed. METHODOLOGY OF THE SCIENCE. 15 of mental obliquity, is interesting to the student of mental science and essential to the physician ; but the true intellectual system must be deduced from the phenomena of mind in its ordinary, its healthy condition. We return therefore to the position, that the causes of superior lucidness awarded to mathematical science are chiefly three. The first of these causes, namely the intrinsic difference between the subjects discussed in these sciences, is derived from the Author of our being. We are so constituted that the properties and espe- cially the relations of space and number, are more clearly apprehended by us than those of mind. Yet this difference is not so great as might, at first view, be supposed. Much of it arises from the fact, that from our earliest years we are engaged every hour in perceiving and judging of space and num- ber, while the phenomena of the mind are seldom thought of until we reach the years of maturity, and then generally at short periods as subjects of theo- retical study. Our perceptions of the former are therefore improved in an incalculably higher degree than our views of the latter. The second source of superior clearness has been stated to be a more rigidly analytic method of in- vestigation. This has led to greater improvements in these sciences, and hence the evidence attending their discussion is also greater. The fact that a better method of philosophizing has usually been pursued in the mathematical sciences is not alto- gether adventitious. We believe it to be chiefly owing to the peculiar nature of the properties and 16 INTRODUCTION. relations of space and number, and to the fixed and simple nature of mathematical language, which consists chiefly of a few figures and signs, and a small number of well-defined words, while it wholly rejects the flowers of rhetoric. The same method of inductive investigation is the only one, by which real progress can be made in mental science, or in any other department of human knowledge. It will appear more clearly in the sequel, that all those of our ideas which are knowledge, are mental representatives of entities ; i. e., of things, and their relations, existing in na- ture ; and can be obtained, originally, in no other way than by the careful examination of entities themselves. Hence, however knowledge already acquired may afterward be combined and arranged, the only accurate method of obtaining its original elements is by patient successive examinations of those entities of which we wish to obtain a knowl- edge. After such a careful examination of all the facts in the case has been made, and we have thus obtained accurate mental representatives of them all ; then, and not until then, can we with certainty decide, whether or not any supposed property or law belongs to them all. That method of philoso- phizing, therefore, which affirms a general law after the examination of a few facts, must forever be inse- cure, and tend to obstruct the progress of any science. The third source of the superior lucidness of mathematical discussions, is the simple, literal, concise style, in which they are recorded for the instruction of others, and the specific numeric no- NATURE OF MATHEMATICAL REASONING. 17 tation of every item of knowledge obtained. It will hereafter appear more clearly, we trust, that one of the jaiost prolific sources of error in human knowledge, is the use of language which does not express our ideas with entire, specific exactness. But mathematical language, consisting of a few figures, letters, and signs, and a small stock of well- defined words, the same idea is almost universally designated by one and the same term. No attempt is made to avoid the repetition of the same word in the same sentence, however often the same idea may recur ; and the man would expose himself to ridicule, who should attempt to imbody the demon- strations of Euclid in profuse and florid language. Hence arises a degree of perspicuity of style never attained and rarely aimed at in the discussions of any other science. Nor is the precise separation of each item of knowledge from every other, and its numerical notation unimportant. It enables the reader to know exactly how far an author has succeeded in establishing the positions assumed, and of which of them the evidence is inconclusive. Thus, those positions, the demonstration of which appears conclusive to all, become a common stock of knowledge. On these others can build, assu- ming them as correct, and can then direct their at- tention to positions yet doubtful. The same inflexible precision of style and the distinct separation of the items of our knowledge would doubtless tend in a high degree to advance the science of mental philosophy ; and ought, so far as the different nature of the subjects will admit, B2 18 INTRODUCTION. certainly to be introduced. Yet, if even equal pre- cision could be attained, the style of discussion in Mental Philosophy would still be far more copious and diversified, because the subjects of which it treats are incalculably more numerous and difficult. The question here arises, What is the exact na- ture of the demonstration and proof in mathemat- ics, and what in mental science ? If a writer wishes to produce conviction, which of his ideas relating to the subject under discussion, should he exhibit to his readers in the language just recommended, and what active operation of mind must he per- form ? — Geometry discusses the properties and re- lations of space. Demonstration in this science sometimes consists in bringing the several diagrams or figures, between which any relation is affirmed, or in supposing them to be brought into such local contiguity as will enable the eye to perceive the relation at a glance. Such is the nature, e. g., of the demonstration of the theorem of Euclid known as Prop. IV. of Book I., viz. : If two triangles have two sides, and the included angle of the one equal to two sides and the included angle of the other, they must be identical or equal in all respects. For it virtually consists in supposing one of the two figures to be placed upon the other, and then con- ducting the eye through the successive survey of its several parts ; and it is found that in this survey the mind intuitively perceives the coincidence of each. Sometimes the demonstration consists in reducing the diagram into such other elementary figures by additional lines, &c, as are intuitively discovered MATHEMATICAL DEMONSTRATION. 19 by the eye to possess the property in question, and which exemplify some of those self-evident cases termed axioms. Axioms in Geometry consist of generic affirmations of certain facts or properties of space which are intuitively perceived to be true in individual and specific familiar cases. E. g., the axiom — things equal to the same thing are equal to one another — is first learned from the observations of early life. We perceive in the familiar objects around us which we touch, see, and handle, that if any two of them are equal or like to a third, they are also, in the same respects, like each other. The observation is extended from one case to another, until, finding no exceptions to it, we set it down as a universal maxim, and confidently employ it as one of the instruments of reasoning. This is the case with other axioms. In arithmetic the same obser- vation is intuitively made in reference to small num- bers, and gradually extended to large ones, in re- gard to which the mind could not intuitively see its truth, but, after the preliminary process, confident- ly and safely assumes it. When small numbers are added together, the mind can intuitively perceive the truth of the sum total. Thus, that 2 + 3=5, every one can perceive to be true. But when large numbers, extending to many figures, are added, the mind cannot see the truth of the sum total by comparing the entire num- bers. We are certain of its accuracy only by suc- cessively going through the addition of each fig- ure, and knowing that this operation has been ac- curately performed. So, also, when the multiplica 20 INTIIOBUCTIOX. tion or division of small numbers is performed, the mind intuitively perceives the accuracy of the op- eration ; but in large numbers our perception is in- distinct. Our confidence in these cases rests on our assurance of the accuracy of the rule or mode of operation, which assurance is acquired in the case of small numbers. The same is the case with the arithmetical proportions, e. gr., 1 : 3 : : 2 : 6, &c, The ocess of reasoning in mental science is en- tirely different. The items of proof and the sub- jects of discussion are all mental phenomena, of which each individual must judge for himself by the testimony of his own consciousness. The art of un- derstanding the subject well, and of writing upon it lucidly and conclusively, consists in the habit of care- fully studying the operations of our own minds, and of clothing the result of our observations in such perspicuous and appropriate language, as will most successfully conduct our readers or hearers through the same process on the points in question. Discus- sions on this subject are successful in producing con- viction, just in proportion as they enable the reader to verify the writer's assertions in his own mind. The reader's own consciousness must respond at every step to the truth of the positions advanced ; and conviction terminates, as soon as the response is doubtful, or the reader cannot perceive, in the op- erations of his own mind, the truth of the author's assertions. THE SUBJECT MATTER AND DIVISIONS MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. Mental Philosophy may be defined to be that science which discusses the properties and opera- tions of the human soul. Other objects, that is, entities, in the universe, are also the subject of in- vestigation ; but only in as far as their influence on the phenomena of mind is concerned. Thus, in treating of some of our ideas, we find them to be mental representatives of external objects around us, and we are necessarily led to examine those ob- jects or entities, to ascertain what we may and do know of them, and what is the process by which, through the bodily organs, we obtain this knowledge. This science was formerly termed Metaphysics, a term barbarously derived from the Greek, in which its appropriate primitive metaphusike (jiera. (pvoLicog, .7}, -ov) is not found. It is supposed to have originated from the misapprehension of the inscrip- tion on a work, consisting of fourteen books, con- cerning which it is doubtful whether, at least in their present form, they belong to the productions of Aristotle, among which they are found. It is an ancient, though not perfectly substantiated opinion, that Andronicus of Rhodes, who arranged the 22 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. works of Aristotle into classes, after he had thus as- sorted the books on logic, ethics, and physics, pla- ced together several disconnected tracts on differ- ent subjects, and endorsed them " meta taphysica" (to be placed or read, after the works on physics). Subsequently the discussions contained in those books, were united into a science, which from the above inscription was termed Metaphysics ; because it succeeded, or because it went beyond physics. The term Anthropology is used especially in Ger- many, to designate that science, which discusses the nature of man, as consisting of a body and mind, and especially the influence of the former on the latter. It is sometimes divided into Somatology and Psychology, the former embracing all those bodily peculiarities and circumstances, which are supposed by some writers to exert an influence on the mind. In this department much that is fanciful and ridiculous has been written. By Psychology is meant everything, that appro- priately belongs to the discussion of the nature, structure, and operations of the mind, exclusive of Logic, which is a more extended exhibition of the laws of the mind in one branch of psychology, namely, the process of reasoning. It is this latter science which we propose to discuss on the present occasion. An important preliminary question here arises, What are the proper materials which ought to be embraced in this science ? These we maintain are, not so much the supposed faculties, of which we know nothing directly, but the known phenomena DIVISIONS OF THE MIND. 23 of the mind, and all those other known entities or existences, which exert an influence upon these phenomena, or are concerned in their production. The proper basis for a division of mental phenome- na is another important aspect of our subject. We suppose it evident that any correct classification of mental operations, must be based on those phenom- ena of mind, which are known to us, and not on unknown and supposed faculties or essence of the mind. The divisions adopted in the various systems extant are numerous. The first and most general- ly received in the English philosophical world, is that into about nine faculties of the mind. This di- vision was in the main adopted by Dr. Reid, Mr. Stewart, and the other principal metaphysicians in England and America, until the recent introduction of Dr. Brown's system, which has gained many ad- mirers. "We shall first specify some of these divisions and definitions which have heretofore been received. The mind has usually been divided into the follow- ing faculties : 1. The faculty of perception, which is regarded as that inherent part of the original constitution of the soul of man, by which he obtains knowledge of external objects, through the instrumentality of his bodily organs. 2. The faculty of consciousness is that power of the soul of man by which, according to Dr. Reid, he has " immediate knowledge of all his present thoughts, and purposes, and, in general, of all the present operations of his mind." 24 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. 3. The faculty of conception is that power of the soul of man by which he has knowledge of things not perceived through the instrumentality of his senses ; or, according to Stewart, it is " that power which enables the mind to form a notion of an ab- sent object of perception, or of a sensation which it has formerly felt." 4. The faculty of judgment is that inherent pow- er of the soul by which we decide that any propo- sition is true or not true. It is also termed the fac- ulty of understanding. 5. Memory is that faculty of the soul by which we have a present knowledge of our past mental operations. 6. By the faculty of reasoning is commonly meant that inherent power of the soul by which we infer conclusions from premises. " Reasoning," says Dr. Reid, " is the process by which we pass from one judgment to another, which is the conse- quence of it. In all reasoning, therefore, there must be a proposition inferred, and one or more from which it is inferred." 7. The faculty of conscience has by some been considered as that power of the soul, by which we experience either remorse or self-approbation on a review of our conduct ; while others regard it " as that internal sense which decides upon the moral character of actions." 8. The faculty of feeling is that power of the soul, by which we experience sensations or feelings and emotions. 9. The faculty of volition is that power of the VIEW OF FORMER SYSTEMS. 25 soul by which we choose, determine, resolve, pur- pose, or will to perform or not to perform any contem- plated action, of which we judge ourselves capable. The general division of these powers adopted by Dr. Reid was into two general classes, viz. : First. Intellectual Powers. Secondly. Active Pow- ers. By intellectual powers he means those powers by which we perceive objects and conceive of them ; and remember, analyze, or combine them, and judge or reason concerning them. By active 'powers he understands all those pow- ers of the soul which lead to action, or influence the mind to act, such as appetites, passions, affec- tions, &c. Mr. Stewart, the successor and commentator of Dr. Reid, divides the powers of the mind into three classes. First. Intellectual. Secondly. Active or Moral. And, thirdly, Social Poivers ; which latter belong to man as a member of political society. The last division, which has obtained much cur- rency in the English philosophical world, is that of Dr. Brown, who divides the powers of the soul into two classes, and designates them by the terms Ex- ternal and Internal affections or stales of the mind. This division appears to bear a distinct affinity to the old classification into sensations and reflections, although Dr. Brown expends not a little labour in refuting that ancient division. The external af- fections Dr. Brown has subdivided according to the organs of sense which are employed in their C 26 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. production, viz., Smell, Taste, Hearing, Touch, and Sight. These he denominates the more definite external affections, while he makes another class of a less definite character to embrace hunger and muscular pleasures and pains. The internal af- fections he subdivides into two orders. Order I. embraces the intellectual affections. Order II. } the emotions. Order I. embraces, First. Simple suggestion. Secondly. Relative suggestion, or feelings of rela- tions. Order II. he divides into, First. Immediate. Secondly. Retrospective. And, thirdly, Prospective Emotions. In Germany, a different division of the powers or faculties of the mind has, for some time past, been adopted by many writers on psychology. " The greater part of psychologists," says Profes- sor Fischhaber, " have arrived at the conclusion, that the soul of man possesses three principal pow- ers or faculties, viz., the power of sensibility (Ge- fuhlsvermogen), the understanding or intellect in- cluding the various operations of what are termed the intellectual powers (Vorstellungsvermb'gen),and the will (Begehrungs or Willensvermogen)." This division, which is in many respects a very good one, has been substantially adopted by that excellent writer of our own country, Professor Upham, if we may judge from a brief notice of his recent work which we have seen. He, however, very properly changes the order of these faculties, placing the in- tellect first, which some of the Germans had as- signed to the middle ; and by the introduction of OUTLINE OF THE NEW SYSTEM PROPOSED. 27 Dr. Brown's system of suggestions, and of his own numerous investigations on other important aspects of the subject, he has doubtless prepared a work of high and lasting merit. After mature deliberation, we are unable to adopt either of these divisions, although each of them con- tains much that is true and useful ; but we propose another which appears to us more simple, more nat- ural, more clear and intelligible, and more accu- rately conformed to the known phenomena of mind. This is a threefold division, into I. Cognitive ideas. II. Sentient ideas. III. Active operations. When we strictly contemplate the phenomena of mind, apart from the powers from which they re- sult, we perceive no other differences of a generic character between the intrinsic nature of our ideas themselves, than a threefold one. They are all, in their own nature, either knowledge, or they are feeling, or they are action. Let the reader verify the truth of this assertion by an examination of his own mental phenomena, and he will be the better qualified to judge of its accuracy, and to enter into the subsequent discussions. Let him take any one within the wide range of his thoughts, and upon examination it will be found that it is in its nature either knowledge of something in the external uni- verse or in the regions of mind, or it is a feeling pleasant or painful, or it is an active process of some kind or other, in which his mind was engaged. 28 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. Thus, when we examine the ideas designated by the terms tree, stone, horse, water, air, electric fluid, mind, deity, &c, we find them to be our knowledge of certain objects in creation, whose ex- istence we believe, because we have, in various ways, ascertained some properties of each. Other terms, such as joy, contentment, hope, sorrow, love, friendship, gratitude, hatred, anger, condolence, pity, envy, jealousy, &c, all express, not knowl- edge, but feeling ; that is, a certain sentient state of the mind, either pleasant or painful, terminating ei- ther on ourselves or on others. While a third class of terms, such as, to examine, to inspect, to arrange, to classify, to speak, to walk, all imply ac- tivity^ and, indeed, are most prominently distin- guished from the other by the circumstance of their being in their own nature different species of activ- ity. The only method by which each individual can acquire a correct idea of the difference between these three kinds of ideas or mental phenomena, is by examining the testimony of his own conscious- ness. These ideas, whether cognitive, sentient, or active, are in their elements simple ideas, and no definition can explain them without the testimony of consciousness. This triple division is marked out by criteria, whidfa we shall more fully discuss when we enter upon the separate consideration of each individual class of our ideas, when we think it will be clear- ly seen that all our ideas are resolvable into these three classes, either as leading ideas, or appenda- ges of such as are. OUTLINE OF THE NEW SYSTEM PROPOSED. 29 This system differs from the one last mentioned in its essential features. (a.) They differ in the principle on which they are constructed, the former being a division of the supposed faculties or powers of the mind, of which we have no immediate knowledge ; while the one we propose is strictly a division of the operations of the mind, actually and immediately known to us by consciousness. As we know nothing certainly of the mind except its operations, it seems to be more philosophic and safe to base our divisions on these operations, and in a great measure limit our discussions to them. This feature of diversity is applicable only in part to the excellent work of Professor Upham, who carefully distinguishes between the faculties of the mind and its operations, or, as he terms them, states ; yet even he, in his general nomencla- ture, divides his subject into the states referring to the Intellect, the Sensibilities, and the Will, by which latter terms we understand him to mean not operations of the mind, but powers or faculties. He is thus led, like his predecessors, to class to- gether, under one head, operations which are gen- erally different in themselves, namely, such as are cognitive, with some which are sentient, and others that are active. (b.) These systems differ in the lines of division actually adopted by them, and in the operations of mind severally assigned to each. The first division of the former system embraces all the operations both of our first and third divisions, excepting only C 2 30 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. a subdivision of our third, namely, the voluntary- mode in which our active operations sometimes oc- cur ; and that which forms but a subdivision of our third division, constitutes the whole of it in the other system. (c.) It will also be found, upon examination of the contents of their different parts, that the two systems diverge materially from each other. Our view of the entire mass of the active op- erations of the mind, as resolvable into five ge- neric active processes, is, if we mistake not, new ; nothing resembling it being found, as far as we know, in any other work. In our representation of the will, and its relation to the activity of the soul, and also in regard to the spontaneous portion of our mental activity, our investigations conducted us to some peculiar results. But we prefer to let the learned reader, who is familiar with other sys- tems, judge for himself how far ours differs from those that have preceded it, and what may be its value, either as a whole or in its particular parts. In pursuing our investigations, we have been anx- ious that they might conduct us along the paths of truth, regardless of the question whether we agreed with our predecessors, or differed from them. OUTLINE OF THE NEW SYSTEM PROPOSED. 31 ON THE EXTENT OF THE SEVERAL PARTS OF THIS THREEFOLD DIVISION. I. The extent of the cognitive class of ideas. This class, we suppose, embraces, First. "What, are termed Perceptions, which are, by the definition itself, evidently " knowledge of external objects obtained through the instrumental- ity of our bodily organs." Secondly. Our acts of Consciousness, According to the old definition of consciousness, as being our knowledge of all our present mental operations, the very existence of this operation has been denied, and not without at least partial grounds. May not the whole difficulty of writers on this subject have arisen from their not observing the grand threefold division of all our mental operations on which our system is founded ? Of the first class of our ideas, viz., the cognitive class, it may justly be said that they could scarcely be considered as knowledge at all, if we did not know them at the very moment in which they are attained. As to the second class, that of our feelings, the case is somewhat diverse. Yet certainly we have a knowledge of them, that is, are conscious of them, and can distinguish our knowledge of the feeling from the feeling itself, the very moment after it occurs. In reference to the third class, it seems, at all times, a matter of great facility, to discriminate between an active opera- tion, which we are performing, and our knowledge of the fact, that we are, at present, engaged in it, and 32 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. of the nature of the operation itself. It is by con- sciousness that we have a knowledge of all the op- erations of our mind. It is, therefore, an exten- sive source, or rather department, of our knowl- edge. It embraces our knowledge of all the so- called internal states of the mind. Thirdly. Our conceptions also manifestly belong to the cognitive class of ideas. It cannot fail to be perceived, that every conception which we have, is a conception of something, is knowledge. It has indeed been maintained, that our conceptions are " knowledge, not obtained through our bodily or- gans." This, so far as their original elements are concerned, we are compelled to regard as errone- ous. Our system leads us to a different opinion; yet, as this subject will meet us at a future stage of our discussions, we shall not now enter on it. Con- ceptions are evidently knowledge of relations, ab- stract truths, &c, and thus belong to the cognitive class of our ideas. Thus our idea of virtue is termed a conception ; and when carefully analyzed, we find it to be a cognitive idea of the relation of agreement, between certain actions and the law of God, or standard of right. Again, we are said to " conceive" the meaning of general propositions. Our idea of the proposition : virtue is productive of happiness, is termed a conception. When ex- amined, this idea is a cognition of the fact learned by experience or observation, that actions of a given kind are productive, of happiness. The cases in which this truth is witnessed, are all individual, but by a mental process of frequent occurrence, here- after to be explained, which we term Modification, OUTLINE OF THE NEW SYSTEM PROPOSED. 33 we omit the individual actions, or subjects of the proposition, and employ the general term, virtue, embracing them all. Of this general term virtue we affirm the predicate of the proposition, affirm the relation of causation, our idea of which is cog- nitive, and was learned from individual cases. • Fourthly. It embraces our judgments : for what are they but a knowledge of the relations between propositions ? Fifthly. It embraces our recollections. These are nothing else than retrospective knowledge, as will easily be perceived by all. Sixthly. It embraces the results of reasoning, such as belief, &c. The process of reasoning is itself an active operation, and belongs to our third class ; but the result of the process is a distinct thing. It is conviction of the truth or falsity of some alleged truth, it is belief. This belief, or conviction, is evidently cognitive, it forms an item in our stock of knowledge. Seventhly. It embraces the dictates or decisions of conscience, which are nothing else than the re- sults of our judgment concerning the propriety or impropriety of our own conduct. As acts, or rather the results of judgment, are evidently cognitive, the dictates of conscience are in part also of the same nature. Yet there is also obviously some- thing active about the dictates of conscience. They contain not only a cognition of duty, but also an impulse to obey it. This impulse is active, and will be discussed in the third general division of our subject, when we treat of our first Constitutional Inclination. 34 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. II. On the extent of sentient ideas. Some objection might, at first view, be made to the use of the term ideas, as expressive of this second class of mental phenomena, our feelings. We therefore request the reader to recollect that, throughout this work, we employ the word idea, not in its ancient Platonic sense, to signify the supposed external and immaterial forms of things ; nor with the Peripatetics, to designate certain forms, phan- tasms, or sensible species emanating from all ex- ternal things, and serving as the object of percep- tion to the mind ; but we use it in its popular sense, sanctioned by the usage of the present age, to sig- nify any and every mental operation or phenomenon of which we are capable, and purely and exclusive- ly the mental act. " In popular use," says the dis- tinguished American lexicographer Webster, " idea signifies notion, conception, thought, opinion, and even purpose or intention." In like manner, when, in the sequel, we speak of the mind's reflecting on any particular idea, we again disclaim the belief of any images or species of objects, and mean simply the past operations of the mind itself. This class embraces what are usually termed, first, Sensations ; secondly, Emotions ; thirdly, Af- fections ; fourthly, Passions, to a certain extent. Sensations have been regarded as the feelings which are connected with the perceptions of exter- nal objects. They are simply pleasant or painful, and evidently they are sentient in their nature. The SKETCH OF THE NEW SYSTEM. 35 term sensation, in our language, as well as the corre- sponding word, sensus, of the Romans, and alaBr]\ia of the Greeks, is used with considerable latitude, as designating both the cognitive and sentient result of the action of our bodily organs ; that is, as indica- ting both the perception of external objects obtained through the senses,"and the feelings attending them. In the classification here proposed, we employ the term in the latter, which must doubtless be admit- ted to be its most appropriate signification. The perceptions of external objects obtained through this source, are discussed in the cognitive depart- ment of our work, because they are obviously knowledge. Sensations have also sometimes been defined " as states of mind immediately succes- sive to a change in some organ of sense, or, at least, to a bodily change of some kind;" but this definition is also applicable to perceptions. By Emotions are indicated feelings consequent on other mental operations than present perceptions of external objects ; yet this distinction is not uni- formly observed by the best writers. On the con- trary, the term emotion is often used for a complex operation of the mind, in which, though feeling of a particular species preponderates, a cognitive ele- ment is also clearly included, as will, we think, ap- pear when the emotions are particularly discussed. Emotions may justly be considered as subsequent to our intellections, and prior to the desires and other active processes connected with them, or with the intellections to which thev succeed. 36 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. Affections is a terra applied to emotions of a pleasant character. Passions also are regarded as emotions, but of a painful kind. Yet as all emotions are feelings of some kind or other, it is evident that they all belong to the second class of ideas according to our divis- ion, except in as far as passions fall within the depart- ment of our periodical appetites, in which case they are active in their nature, and are discussed in the third part of this work. Our own division of the feelings is different, as will be seen in the second part of this work, where other definitions of them are also given. III. On the extent of active operations. This class embraces what are usually denomi- nated, First, Volitions, in which is comprehended the whole extent as well as every variety of the direct action of the will. Secondly, those operations of the mind termed processes of reasoning, but not their results ; for the results of reasoning are knowledge, or conviction, or belief, and therefore they belong to cognitive ideas. Thirdly, the act of memorizing, and not its re- sults ; that is, the process of mental effort, by which we impress upon our memory the contents of any portion of a book or manuscript, or of a discourse which we have heard. But the impression itself thus made upon the mind is cognitive. SKETCH OF THE NEW SYSTEM. 37 Fourthly. The intellectual act of communicating our thoughts to others, either orally or by letter. Fifthly. Some other active processes, the nature of which will hereafter be more fully explained. When we term the third class of mental opera- tions active, we do not wish to convey the idea, that the soul itself, in acquiring either knowledge or feeling, is in a state of entire passivity ; for there is, doubtless, activity in the soul during all its opera- tions. But, it must be remembered, we are here classifying and characterizing the ideas or operations of the mind, and not the powers of the mind itself. Our division is a classification, not of the activity of the soul itself, but of the results of its agency. The soul is often voluntary and active in seeking the excitement of feeling ; yet the feeling itself, thus excited, seems to be in its own nature merely sentient. It is in itself simply pleasure or pain. Thus also the act of acquiring knowledge by in- spection is active, and often even voluntary ; but the ideas acquired, the knowledge obtained, is not active ; but consists simply of mental representa- tives of entities, and is best characterized by the term cognitive. These ideas are simply knowledge and nothing more. As all the ideas or operations of the mind thus resolve themselves into three classes, viz., Cogni- tive, Sentient, and Active, the entire science is most aptly divided into three general parts, one of which is devoted to each of these classes of mental oper- ations. D 38 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. PART I. COGNITIVE IDEAS. It is evident, even on a superficial survey of those ideas which are knowledge, that at least some of them, especially such as relate to material ob- jects around us, are mental representatives of things, or subsistencies, or entities, which exist without the mind. Thus, no one can doubt, when reflecting on his idea of an orange, that the fruit, of which the idea in question is the representative, had a real existence ; for he has often handled, tasted, and eaten it. In short, when we carefully examine our cognitive ideas, and the source whence we derive thern, we find that they are acquired through the me- dium of certain parts of our body, called organs of sense ; and from the operations and powers of mind, of which all men are possessed. We see, also, that our mind, which perceives, and the organs, through which it perceives, are not in themselves sufficient to furnish us with these ideas. It is farther ne- cessary, that the organs of sense be brought into a particular relation to certain external objects. This relation is either that of actual contact, as in the case of touch and taste, or, it consists in bringing the organ into the direction of the object, with no- thing intervening which prevents the rays of light from being reflected from that object to the eye ; OBJECTIVE ENTITIES. 39 or it consists in a relation of proximity to the ob- ject, so that the vibrations of the air may be con- veyed to the ear, as in sound. We, therefore, here clearly perceive three distinct things : first, the ex- ternal entity, or object, of which our cognitive ideas are the mental representatives or knowledge ; sec- ondly, the knowledge itself, or the representatives, or ideas, which we have of external objects ; and, thirdly, the organic process, by which we obtain our ideas, or knowledge. The discussion of each of these three things will therefore appropriately form a subdivision of this part of our subject. CHAPTER I. OF OBJECTIVE ENTITIES AS SUBJECTS OF OUR KNOWLEDGE. Before entering on the discussions of this chap- ter, we premise an explanatory remark relative to our use of the word entity. This term, long since naturalized in our language, Ave use with more than ordinary frequency, because its signification is more generic than that assigned by usage to the words more commonly employed, such as thing, substance, &c. The latter are ordinarily restricted, in the popular mind, to material objects, and pre- sent some difficulty, as they excite in the mind the impression of inaptitude when applied to some oth- er subjects of our knowledge. In the progress of our discussions, we need a term of such latitude of import as to be applicable to any and every reality 40 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. in nature. Such is the term entity, in the caption of this chapter, which signifies anything that has existence, and, therefore, answers our purpose. But we proceed with the discussion of the pecu- liar topic of this chapter. It is indeed true, that in all our reflections on the properties of objects around us, it is not the objects themselves, but only our ideas or mental representatives of the properties of those objects, which are the immediate subjects of observation to the reflecting mind. But it may be asked, What evidence have we that anything beyond our ideas has a real existence ? How do we know, that such a thing as even the material universe does actually exist ? To this we reply, that if we were deprived of the power of bodily action, and capable of performing no other mental act than that of reflec- tion, and what we, in the sequel, term the process of Inspection, it might indeed be impossible for us to establish the objectivity of external objects, that is, their real existence, out of, and independently of the percipient mind. But, when we can take a sup- posed object or entity, such as an apple, into our hands, and perceive that it has weight ; when we feel its shape or relation to space ; when we take a knife and cut it in pieces, and eat it, we constitu- tionally judge it to be different from our idea of an apple, in which idea, we cannot perceive either weight, or shape, or divisibility, or capability of be- ing eaten. Moreover, all these operations may be performed with closed eyes upon an apple which we never saw, and of which identical apple, there- fore, we never had and can never acquire any far- OBJECTIVE ENTITIES. 41 ther idea than is obtained by touch and taste. In short, whenever we are using our bodily organs in touching, tasting, seeing, hearing, or smelling any object, then the external object itself, either direct- ly, or mediately, and not our idea of it, is the sub- ject of the operation. But as soon as we reflect on some idea, formerly obtained through our bodily organs, this idea, and not the entity itself, is the subject of the operation. During this reflection, we neither do nor can use the bodily organ ; for if that organ be employed, and the attention of the soul be directed to it, the act of reflection immedi- ately terminates. We therefore, through the in- strumentality of our senses, perceive in external en- tities properties entirely different from those of an idea ; and we also judge that the entity or substra- tum to which they belong is a different one ; we judge that the external entities are possessed of real objectivity, that is, have an actual existence out of our minds. As to the accuracy of this judgment, it would be equal folly either to question it, or to attempt its confirmation by fine-spun trains of ab- struse ratiocination. All mankind constitutionally believe the well-ascertained testimony of their sen- ses. Not even the veriest skeptic can bring himself to doubt it in the affairs of practical life. Who ever heard of one that would walk into a fire which chanced to be in his way, believing that what ap- peared to be a burning pile, was only an idea of his mind ? Or who among these doubting philosophers did not instantly forget his sophistical reasoning and step aside, when he saw a serpent, or any oth D 2 42 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. dangerous object in his path ? In like manner, all men, by a similar necessity of their mental struc- ture, judge that combinations of properties which are entirely different from each other, appertain to different substrata or subjects. Can any person, when contemplating the properties of a stone which he has in his hand, believe them to be parts or properties of a feather, that happens to be lying on it ? Neither can any man, while true to the dic- tates of common sense, believe them to be mere ideas or properties of his own mind, or of that of another. The universe, as known to us, consists of nothing else than infinitely various combinations of proper- ties and their relations. We may select any object we please, throughout the whole range of the uni- verse, and this remark will be found to hold good. Examine a tree, a stone, a flower, a gas, a mind, and it will be perceived that all the knowledge we possess of them is knowledge of their properties and relations. Thus of any particular stone, we know its colour, its shape, its gravity, its divisibili- ty, &c. ; but what the stone is, beyond its proper- ties, we know not. We may analyze it, and re- duce it to its constituent simple substances, but, in this respect, nothing is gained by the process; for each individual element is, like the compound, known to us only by its properties. Of gases also our knowledge is a knowledge of mere properties. Take, for example, our atmosphere, which is com- posed of two gases, oxygen and nitrogen, or, as the older chemists termed if, azote. We do not see it, OBJECTIVE ENTITIES. 43 but we feel its resistance when walking against a strong current of air, or, as it is termed, wind. We observe its solidity, for we see that water is exclu- ded by it from any confined vessel or receiver. So, also, we learn its elasticity, its ability to support combustion, and various other properties ; but what either nitrogen or oxygen is, beyond these proper- ties, we know not. And so of mind also ; we know its properties or phenomena, its capacity for knowl- edge, for feeling, for active operations, and its sus- ceptibility of being influenced through bodily or- gans ; but what the mind is, beyond these suscep- tibilities or properties and phenomena, no man can tell. Again ; every such combination of properties, as found in nature, is individual ; that is, it is in some respects different from all others. No two stones, or two trees, or any other two objects, are exactly alike, in regard to all their properties, and to every particle of matter contained in them. Still, many combinations have the greater part of their properties in common, and differ only in the residue. Thus, many animals resemble each other in having four legs, others in having two ; some by eating flesh, and others grain or grass ; some by bringing forth their young alive, and others by incubation. In the vegetable kingdom, some plants have their stamens and pistils visible, others nol,, they being too small to be observed by the na- ked eye. In the former of these classes, termed phenogamous, the different plants differ in the num- ber of their stamens, from one to ten. And thus, 44 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. by their various points of agreement in- stamens, pistils, &c, they are arranged in botany. Finally ; the various gradations of similarity in all different entities form a just basis for their classi- fication. On such a classification is human lan- guage founded. No language has a specific name for every separate object, for every individual tree, or stone, or leaf, or flower. Human language ordinarily has words merely to express, First, our ideas of each property of entities, such as black, white, soft, hard, heavy, &c. ; but there is not a separate name for these properties as found in different objects or entities. No matter what be the entity in question, there is ordinarily but one name for one property, no matter how many enti- ties possess it in common. Secondly, words to express our aggregate idea of each species of combinations, as stone, tree, bird, fish, &c. Thirdly, words for our ideas of some other clas- sifications and abstractions still more generic, such as quadrupeds, bipeds, graminivorous, carnivorous, viviparous, oviparous, &c. Fourthly, to express our ideas of the relations of the different objects or entities in nature, such as similarity or diversity of colour or shape in two balls, contiguity or distance between two objects, as to place, or time, &c. On the different degrees of similarity observable in the various combinations of properties found in nature, that is, on the different degrees of similar- OBJECTIVE ENTITIES. 45 ity in the objects around us in the world, different classifications have been based. Sometimes, all things are spoken of as divisible into matter and mind. This division is good so far as it goes ; but, as we shall see in the sequel, is not sufficiently pre- cise. Such entities as can be chemically analyzed, have also been reduced to their elementary sub- stances, and arranged according to them. Yet as chemical analysis cannot reach all objects in na- ture, such as mind, &c, this classification must omit some entities of which we have mental repre- sentatives, would omit some of the subjects of our cognitive ideas. However accurate and adequate this division may be for the purposes of physical science, we need another more comprehensive, for the more general purposes of mental philosophy, in which every object in nature, of which we have any knowledge, however slight or limited that knowl- edge may be, claims some attention, and is entitled to a place. In all our reflections on absent entities, and our attempts to classify them, our ideas of their proper- ties, and not the properties themselves, are the sub- jects of our attention. "We spend our whole life in acquiring mental representatives of the different entities or objects in the universe ; but as only a small portion of them can at any time be present before us, we cannot classify these objects them- selves in any other way than by comparing and ar- ranging the ideas of them thus obtained. In endeavouring to make a classification of all known existences or entities, by examining our cog- 46 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. nitive ideas, we must be careful to make thorough work. We must summon before us the whole mass of our knowledge, the entire aggregate of all our cognitive ideas in every department of science, physical, intellectual, and moral. We must, as it were, assemble our ideas of the heavens, and the earth, and all the different objects known to be in them : not only of those objects of which we have personal knowledge, but also of all others, whatev- er be the means by which we become acquainted with them. Our ideas of God, of angels, of dev- ils, of space, of time, of number, of virtue, of vice, of similarity, of diversity, of analogy, of fitness, of causation, and of every species of agency, mechan- ical, instinctive, and voluntary or moral, must all be taken into account. We may review the con- tents of the most extensive libraries, including dis- cussions on every conceivable subject in the wide range of human knowledge, and every idea we meet, which is of a cognitive character, which is in its nature knowledge, must be embraced in our classification. Numerous and complicated as this immense mass of ideas would at first view appear to be, on a closer examination they will all be found to resolve themselves into three generic classes ; they are ei- ther ideas of substantive objects, of objects to which a combination of properties appertains ; or they are ideas of these individual properties themselves ; or, thirdly, they are ideas of relations which exist between several such substantive objects or enti- ties as wholes, or between the properties belonging to them. OBJECTIVE ENXlXiES, 47 After we have removed from our view the latter two classes of ideas, namely, those which are mere individual properties, and those which are relations ; and inquire into what general classes may those substantive entities or objects be reduced, to which these properties and relations belong, we arrive at something like the following list of* objects : Solids ; Liquids ; Gases ; the Ethereal or Inco- ercible fluids, such as Light, Caloric, Electric Fluid, Magnetic Principle ; Mind; Spirit; Glorified Bod- ies ; Deity ; together with Time, Space, and Num- ber, which are peculiar in their nature. The pre- cise number of these classes is not at all material to our system ; it can be increased or diminished as the future investigations of science may dictate. This division we do not propose for the purposes of the physical sciences ; but of metaphysical : not as adapted to sciences whose discussions are confined to material objects ; but to mental philosophy, which requires an enumeration of all the objects in ex- istence, of which we have any, even the slightest knowledge, of which Ave possess any cognitive ideas whatever. Having thus obtained an enumeration of the ob- jects in existence, of which we have some knowl- edge, some cognitive ideas, that is, an enumeration of the objects to which the combinations of proper- ties belong, which are found coexisting in nature, let us examine more closely these individual prop- erties, that we may more accurately determine their nature. 48 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. Of solid bodies we find the properties to be such as length, breadth, divisibility, colour, vis inertias, gravity, solidity, &c. In regard to other proper- ties, such as malleability, solubility, &c, solids may be subdivided into different classes. No one of these properties is ever found existing alone. There are always several of them found together, and these coexisting properties we constitutionally attribute to one object, as the properties of such object. Thus, with our bodily organs, we perceive a combination of properties, rotundity of shape, solidity, colour, &c, and to the object to which we judge these properties to appertain, we give the name ball. But we know nothing about the ball itself, beyond its various properties. Liquid substances, such as water, milk, &c, pos- sess many of the properties of solids, excepting al- ways solidity itself. They exhibit very little resist- ance to the touch, yet enough to inform us of their presence by that organ alone, independently of col- our. They cannot be accumulated, unless they are confined by some vessel, nor be made to retain any particular shape, except that of the vessel in which they are contained. Gases, or aeriform fluids, are in most cases invisi- ble ; but their existence is learned from other senses, such as touch and smell. No man can doubt the re- ality of the atmosphere, when he feels the impulse of a strong wind, and attempts to walk against it ; or when he witnesses the effects of a hurricane, overturning houses and prostrating the loftiest oaks of the forest. OBJECTIVE ENTITIES. 49 Of the existence of light, we are convinced by the testimony of sight, by the different impression made on this organ by light, and its absence, dark- ness. In the same way we learn the other proper- ties of light, its different colours, its qualities of re- flection, refraction, its motion, &c. Caloric is, indeed, invisible, but its properties, and, consequently, its reality, we learn from the sense of touch, and from the various visible effects which it produces on other bodies. Thus also the Electric Principle, which probably stands connected with some common basis of light, caloric, and magnetism, is also invisible ; but its existence is demonstrated by the interesting and important phenomena which it produces. Of these phenomena we have certain knowledge by our sen- ses, and cannot doubt whether they belong to some cause, or object, by which they are produced. The principle or fluid of Magnetism is likewise not visible to human eyes, but its existence is ad- mitted, as the cause or agent, to which we must as- cribe a distinct class of phenomena, well ascertained by the testimony of our senses. Of Mind we learn the existence in various ways. We are conscious of the operations of our own minds. We know, too, that our bodies are to a certain degree under the control of our minds ; and that certain definite actions of our bodies are con- sequent on the purposes of our minds to perform them. Now, as we perceive, in the bodies of all other persons, actions of the same character, actions as evidently and systematically adapted to intelli- E 50 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. gent ends, as those which in ourselves we know to result from the volitions of our minds ; we reason- ably infer, that in others, also, there is a mind con- nected with the body. This inference is the more irresistible, as we cannot perceive in matter, under any circumstances, any properties which bear the slightest resemblance to an approximation to the nature or powers of mind. On the contrary, all that we know of the one, is different from all we know of the other. Nor is it only in the case of man that we infer the existence of mind from the actions of the body. In the case of all animals, we infer the existence and the grade of intellect pos- sessed by them, from the various degrees of intelli- gence, design, and forecast, inferable from their bodily actions. The properties of mind are knowledge, feeling, and action ; or cognition, sensibility, and activity, together with susceptibility of influence from bodily organs. Every mental operation is either knowl- edge, feeling, or action ; but no simple operation consists of several or all these properties together. It has been customary to consider the phenomena of mind, as generally different from the phenomena of other entities, in their relation to our minds as subjects of knowledge. This habit we are com- pelled to regard as incorrect. We know generi- cally just as much about one entity as about another, that is, we know certain properties of each, and these properties are the subjects of our ideas about them respectively. This much also we know about mind, and more we do not know of anything else, OBJECTIVE ENTITIES. 51 even of the grossest forms of solid matter. It is, therefore, erroneous to assert, that we know less of the essence of mind, than of the essence of other en- tities. With regard to solids, liquids, gases, &c, we know no more about their essence than about that of mind ; neither do we know less, because the substra- tum, or essence, of all the things or entities in exist- ence, is unknown to us. Our knowledge of each, re- gards only its properties or operations. But in all other entities except mind, men generally agree in admitting that there must be a substratum, to which these properties belong. Some, indeed, attempt a different explanation, by referring the aggregation of these properties into one whole, to a supposed plastic power of the mind {nXag-tfcog, irXaooeiv, to form, to fashion, to make). But we perceive no advantage in this representation, over the old com- mon-sense view, which has prevailed among British metaphysicians, of a constitutional judgment ; and the ideas attached to the phrase "plastic power," are entirely too loose and indefinite for metaphysi- cal purposes. We regard it, therefore, as an intui- tive judgment of the mind, that wherever we ob- serve properties, or operations, they belong to a subject or agent. All languages distinguish mind from its properties, as clearly as they do solids and other entities from their properties. The structure of the human mind seems to require us to^.ippose the existence of such a substratum ; as is evident from the fact, that all languages are constructed on this principle or supposition. As the Author of our nature gave us this mental structure, it is probable 52 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. that such substrata do belong to all entities. In- deed, what are these properties, but properties of the entity itself ? What are they but those aspects of the substratum, which, by virtue of our organiza- tion, are within the reach of our knowledge ? The known properties of any object, such as copper, lead, silver, gold, are the several aspects, in which these metals are perceptible to us, with our present organization. In a different state, with more organs or senses than we now possess, we might perceive additional properties of these metals ; but those properties perceived by us, prove that the subject, or substratum, to which they belong, is actually known to us, as far as these properties extend. Hence, as there is no difference in this respect be- tween mind and other entities, we are compelled to regard the views of Hume and others, who regard the mind as merely a bundle of ideas, and of Brown, who considers all ideas as the mind itself in certain states,* as unphilosophical in themselves, independ- ently of their tendency to foster a skeptical or in- fidel disposition. The habit of regarding the phe- nomena of mind as generically different from those of other entities, has probably arisen in part from the old imperfect division of all entities into matter and mind, into material and immaterial, and from the maxim thence inferred, that mind is indivisible. But the different properties, operations, and powers of the mind, which are the subjects of all the ideas we possess of this entity, are as distinct from each * See some excellent observations on the fallacy of Brown's view, in the Biblical Repertory of Princeton, for 1830, p. 186. OBJECTIVE ENTITIES. 53 other in their nature, as are the different properties of solids and liquids. Hence, it is evidently unphil- osophic to assert, that the unknown, ulterior some- thing, supposed to belong to mind, as the substratum of its phenomena or properties, is or is not possessed of indivisibility. Of Spirits, that is, disimbodied minds, or minds that have never been associated with bodies, our only certain knowledge is derived from revelation ; although tradition and analogy may afford some probable arguments in favour of their existence. The cardinal known distinction between mind and spirit, is the connexion of the former with a body as the organ of its action, and its susceptibility of being influenced by the body in various ways. To this class of entities belong the spirits of departed saints, whose bodies shall slumber in the grave till the resurrection, as also the angels, archangels, and devils ; in short, all created spirits, of which we have any knowledge, or which may exist, unknown to us, in the boundless empire of Jehovah. To Glorified Bodies we assign a separate class, because, although we know only that little about them which the Scriptures teach us, the Apostle Paul evidently represents them as different from all other objects, as " spiritual" bodies (au^aTa nvev- fiariKa), "celestial bodies," and "incorruptible," which predicates necessarily imply an entity radi- cally different from ordinary matter. The Divine Being-, though a spirit, differs from all other spirits, as the Creator from the creature, the Infinite from the finite. The ideas we possess E 2 54 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. concerning God, are derived partly from the works of Nature, and partly from revelation. Mortal eyes have not seen him, mortal ears have not heard him, but that the reality of his existence may be deduced from evidences of various kinds, establishing his agency and attributes, is admitted by all except the atheist. Our knowledge of the attributes and ex- istence of God, so far as it is derived from nature, consists of ideas of virtues, which we observed in good men, separated by a mental process from every imperfection, with which they are mingled in human beings, and elevated to the highest conceivable de- gree. We thus acquire our ideas of the incompara- ble excellences of the Divine Being. Perceiving, in the structure and operations of the universe, the evidences of these incomparable attributes, we con- stitutionally judge (know) that they appertain to some substratum or being- ; which being, we in the same constitutional manner judge to exist. We do not affirm, that we actually obtain our knowledge of the Divine character and existence by such a process of reasoning ; but suppose, that by this pro- cess we can verify and confirm these truths, which are ordinarily taught us by tradition, long before we reach the maturity of mind necessary for such trains of ratiocination. Our additional knowledge, derived from revela- tion, concerning the Divine Being, his works, his will, and his moral government, likewise consists of ideas, the constituent elements of which were originally derived from human beings and human institutions. Through the medium of these ideas, OBJECTIVE ENTITIES. 55 and their various and new combinations and appli- cations, together with anthropopathic representa- tions, the most minute and detailed account of the will, the providence, and the moral government of God is represented to us, and we are instructed by- precept and example, what the Author of our being would have us to do. Whether the human mind, if left wholly to itself, would have discovered the existence of God, from the contemplation of the works of Nature, is some- what uncertain ; as it is much easier to perceive the truth, propriety, and excellence of an invention or discovery after it has been made, than to make it. But there is obviously an aptitude in the human mind to see the evidences of the Divine existence and attributes after they have been revealed to us, which is generally done either by tradition, or the written revelation. That we have some knowledge of Space, Time, and Number will be admitted by all, although the precise nature of these entities has been the subject of much disputation. Into these disputes we shall not here enter ; and we therefore, for the present, leave it undetermined, whether these entities are objective, that is, have existence either out of our minds, as independent entities, or as forms of ex- istence of other entities, or as limitations, or neces- sary forms of our perceptions ; or are mere subject- ive conceptions of the human mind, having no ex- istence out of the mind itself. In regard to space, our ideas of its properties seem to be principally those of length, breadth, divisibility, and capacity. Our ideas of time seem to be r^"-^ 1 * to duration 56 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. (or length), augmentability, and divisibility; while the properties of number seem to be its capability to be added, subtracted, multiplied, and divided. Number comprehends an indefinite series of units. The decimal system of designating and cal- culating numbers is arbitrary, and seems to have been adopted fortuitously. It is neither based on anything peculiar in the intrinsic nature of numbers themselves, requiring ten figures, and calculation by tens, rather than by any other number ; nor is it, by any means, as the ancient Pythagoreans sup- posed, the most perfect system that could be de- vised. The dodecadal (duodecimal), having twelve different figures, would be far more convenient ; as the number twelve can be divided more fre- quently without a remainder, and, consequently, cal- culations by the dodecadal, or duodecimal system, would be far less encumbered by fractions, than when conducted on the decimal plan. The Roman method of quintal calculation, having only five fig- ures, is virtually the same as the decimal. They employed the letters I and V ; and then double V thus I, forming X ; then C (centum) for hundred, M (mille) for thousand, &c. SECTION II. Division of these Classes of Entities. All these classes of entities, when attentively ex- amined, appear to be of two distinct kinds, and may, therefore, with propriety, be referred to two generic classes : I. Absolute (or universal, or subjective). II. Concrete (or individual). DIVISION OF ENTITIES. 57 Absolute entities, are those of which we can con- ceive, without any reference to those of the con- crete class. To this class belong Time, Space, and Number. The properties and relations of the ab- solute entities are, in their very nature, more defi- nite and clear than those of the concrete. They are, moreover, immutable in their character ; hence the sciences discussing these entities, such as arithme- tic, geometry, and mathematics in general, are more certain, conclusive, and immutable. Accordingly, they are termed " exact sciences,' 5 and not with- out obvious reason. Between the absolute or uni- versal entities time, space, and number, the mind perceives some points of difference ; but they are rather specific than general, and all three properly belong to one general class. Concrete entities are those, of which we cannot conceive, except as existing in the absolute class, or, as being related to it. To this class belong Solids, Liquids, Aeriform substances, and, in short, all the different classes of known entities, except Time, Space, and Number. SECTION III. Subdivision of Individual Entities. All entities of every class may naturally be di- vided into substantive, adjective, and composite, be- cause all objects perceived by us in nature, are either entire individual objects, or they are one or more properties of such object, or they are rela- tions of some kind or other, perceived to exist be- 58 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. tween the perceived properties of objects, or per- formed by one entity or another. As every entire individual object has in reality substantive exist- ence for itself, it may, with propriety, be designa- ted a substantive entity. There is an additional ad- vantage in the adoption of this term, which will ap- pear in the sequel, when we make some applica- tion of this subject to the structure of language and universal grammar. A substantive entity, then, is that in which prop- erties cohere, or coexist ; or, we might say, a sub- stantive entity is that to which any number of co- existing properties appertain. Accordingly, every simple substance, or chemical or ential element, sep- arately viewed, as also each aggregate of all these en- tial or chemical elements found coexisting, is a sub- stantive entity ; such as wood, water, tree, horse, &c. These ential elements are known to us only relative- ly ; we know their properties and their relation to time, space, and number, and to each other. In the case of solids and liquids, and such other substances as can be subjected to chemical analysis, the ential elements and chemical elements are the same. But the term chemical, in this application, is not so well adapted to metaphysical purposes, because the usage of our language confines it to a certain portion only of entities, such as solids, liquids, gases, &c. It is not improbable, that all the classes of entities have ential elements, as well as those which chemical analysis can reach ; though of course they are very different from them in their nature. En- tial element is a more suitable term, and designates SUBSTANTIVE, ADJECTIVE, COMPOSITE ENTITIES. 59 the substratum, to which any set of properties, found coexisting in any class of entities, belongs. The idea which we have of a substantive entity, is the aggregate of our ideas of all those essential, permanent properties, which are found coexisting in the same entity, and, without any one of which, the residue could not be designated by the substan- tive name, which they collectively bear. If I am asked what idea I have of a stone, a tree, an apple, or an orange, I must admit that my only knowledge of them is knowledge of the properties which habitually belong to them. I perceive their colour, their solidity, their shape, &c, but what their intrinsic nature or essence is beyond these properties, I know not. Thus also no man ever saw, or tasted, or touched a mind. Yet every one is conscious of his own mental operations, knows the phenomena of his own mind, and constitutionally judges, that the mental operations of which he is conscious, must belong to a mental agent, which agent he calls himself. ^ Yet our idea of an object, of a substantive entity, does not embrace every property it may chance to possess. Thus, trees and stones may differ in col- our, shape, or size, and yet be appropriately desig- nated by the same name. Those properties only are embraced in our ideas of a substantive entity which permanently and invariably belong to every individual object to which the name in question can appropriately be applied. If language furnished a word to designate every particular individual tree and stone, then every property and circumstance belonging to each stone or tree, and necessary to 60 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. its identity, would properly be represented by such word. But this is not the character of any lan- guage on earth. Therefore it is our ideas of only those properties common to all the individual trees or stones of a particular species, which form the in- gredients of the collective idea that we attach to a word designating a substantive entity, that is, they are our idea of the substantive entity itself. An adjective entity is any one property of a sub- stantive entity considered individually ; as length, breadth, colour, gravity, or any other known prop- erty. Human language, in most cases, contains words to designate each individual property of an entity of which we have an idea, and also names or words, by which those properties, which are found coexisting, are collectively designated, not, indeed, as individuals, but as entire species, such as stone, tree, house, &c. A composite entity consists of two or more ad- jective entities, viewed together, and considered in regard to some relation subsisting between them. Sometimes, several properties of the same entity, constitute a composite entity, between the parts of which some relation is observed. Thus, different parts of a painting may have different colours, and may be viewed in relation to this difference. These relations of entities exert a very important influence on some of the active operations of the mind, and an acquaintance with them, belongs to the most im- portant branches of our knowledge. These rela- tions are not the properties of either part of the composite entity alone ; nor have they a separate existence of their own apart from the related enti- MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. 61 ties ; but they are relations existing between them, and perceivable by the mind. Still, in this case also, our knowledge is a knowledge of relations which actually exist independently of our minds. Thus, we behold two beautiful, dark, Arabian hor- ses, and perceive a similarity of colour between them. Who can doubt, that this similarity would have existed, whether we had seen it or not ? Or whoever imagined, when contemplating the exact adaptation of the wheels of a watch to act upon one another, that this supposed adaptation existed only in his own mind ? Our ideas of relations, like our ideas of substantive and adjective entities, do not resemble the entities themselves, but are only the divinely appointed mental representatives of them. Yet, the relation of similarity of colour between two gray horses, is as certainly seen by the eyes, as is the colour of either horse alone, and the constitu- tion of our minds compels us to believe the similar- ity of colour between them to be real ; that is, we just as invariably believe our idea of the perceived similarity to be an idea of an objective truth, of a reality, as we do believe our idea of the colour of each horse individually to be such. SECTION IV. Relations of Entities. I. What are the perceptible relations of Absolute Entities to each other ? II. What are the perceptible relations of Con- crete Entities to each other ? III. What are the perceptible relations between Concrete and Absolute Entities ? F 62 RELATIONS OF ENTITIES. The relations which the human mind is capable of perceiving between entities, both absolute and concrete, are exceedingly numerous, and may be variously divided. The following division may serve as a basis of a comprehensive and accurate classification. I. The relations of absolute entities to each other. (a.) Equality, diversity, antecedence, subse- quence, &c, of different portions of Time. (b.) Equality, difference, progression, or ratio, plurality (plus), minority (minus), &c, of different Numbers. (c.) Equality, diversity, contiguity, remoteness, superiority (above), inferiority (below), of different portions of Space. In reference to each of these relations, language embraces a vast multitude of words, expressing them in different methods and different aspects. II. The relations of concrete entities to each other. (a.) Similarity and diversity of any of the different classes of entities, in regard to any one or more of their properties. {b.) Contiguity of any of the concrete entities to each other in regard to Space, Time, or Number. (c.) Fitness, physical, intellectual, and moral. Physical fitness includes the relations which are the basis of beauty, symmetry, taste, &c, in the mate- rial world. To this class must be referred the rela- tions of harmony or discord, perceived between different sounds. The relation exists between the MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. 63 atmospheric vibrations themselves, and even in the vibrating chords which produce the undulations of the atmosphere. The reason why discordant vibra- tions produce unpleasant feelings in us, while those which accord are pleasing, is unknown to us. But these vibration"? themselves are well understood, and their chords and discords are the subject of the most obvious mathematical calculation. Intellectual fitness embraces our perceptions of fitness in the op- erations of the mind, in all the various departments of its agency. Moral fitness embraces all our duties to God, to ourselves, and our fellow-men. They are all fitnesses perceived by the mind to exist objectively between us and God, and our fellow- men. The whole field of moral and religious obli- gation, of philosophic and Christian ethics, is em- braced in this relation. Thus, a dictate of con- science is our knowledge of a composite entity, viz., a law; that is, the expressed will of the law- giver or his acknowledged representative, and some action of a person under obligation to this law. The relation perceived between them, is that of moral fitness or agreement, or of unfitness or dis- agreement. In virtue of our constitutional activity we must act somehow. By inspection we perceive the moral fitness of some actions, viewed in relation to the law, and the unfitness of other actions ; and the first Constitutional Inclination of the soul (see part iii. of this work) urges us to that which is morally fit, which is right. This complex operation, when referring to our own actions, constitutes the dictates 64 RELATIONS OF ENTITIES. of conscience. There is, therefore, in the dictates of conscience, something that is impulsive and something that is judicial ; both a judgment and an impulse, and also a feeling. (d.) The relation of analogy. This relation is based on past experience. The maxim, " Every effect must have a cause," is an analogous judg- ment, resulting from experience. Stated at length, it would read thus : Every effect we ever knew had a cause, hence all others probably will have. (e.) Causation, or agency in general. That caus- ation differs from mere antecedence is evident. They can often be distinguished by the following circumstances : 1. The cause also produces such consequents, under other circumstances ; whereas the mere antecedent, is, on other occasions, and un- der other circumstances, not attended by the con- sequent. 2. By some known, intelligible aptitude in the cause to produce the effect, while this is not found in the mere antecedent. The light and heat of the rising sun, are both antecedents to the melting of the snow on a winter morning. That the heat and not the light, is the cause of the effect, is demonstrated by the fact, that caloric without light will produce the same effect ; as when snow is brought near to a dark but heated stove or other iron; while light, with little or no caloric, produces no such effect, as is exemplified in the case of a candle borne over the snow. Thus also in the ma- chinery of a watch, there is a perceptible adapta- tion between the parts to act upon one another, and to produce the effects for which they are designed. MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. Q5 But even this judgment of perceptible adaptation, is the result of former experience in similar cases. And this experience amounts only to a knowledge of the fact. In any new case, not embracing percepti- ble adaptation on which former experience has in- structed us, our belief of the existence of a causative relation is purely the result of present observation, and strong or weak according to the extent and uni- formity of that observation. These facts appear clearly to prove, that our confidence in the uniform- ity of the operations of nature, and of the relation of cause and effect, is not, as has sometimes been affirmed, an original instinctive principle in the mind ; but is a general abstract belief or confi- dence, derived from our experimental observation of individual cases. Experience teaches us, that the world is governed by general laws, or, rather, that God causes the properties of all objects in our world, to act in uniform ways or modes, termed laws of nature. Many of these we learn in youth. To these laws, we refer all the phenomena, for whieh they will account. If we meet with an event or effect which the known laws do not ex- plain, we look for another law. Thus additional laws are occasionally discovered, and thus our con- fidence in the uniformity of nature's laws, is ac- quired without the supposition of any instinctive, or original, or a priori principle or knowledge in the mind. The relation of causation, or agency, is very comprehensive and embraces three different species : (1.) Mechanical agency. (2.) Instinctive agency. F 2 66 MECHANICAL, INSTINCTIVE, AND MORAL AGENCY. (3.) Rational or moral agency. By Mechanical agency we mean all the unintelli- gent and merely physical changes of inert matter, such as the motions and changes of the heavenly bodies, of solids, liquids, &c. The mechanical changes may be divided into two classes: First, the uniform or universal changes, viz., gravitation, attraction, cohesion, repulsion, &c. These are termed laws of nature, by which phrase, however, cannot properly be meant an agent or cause of ac- tion ; but it is merely a statement of our cognitive idea of a uniform mode of action or of changes ob- served in entities, of which action or changes God is the agent or cause. Secondly, mechanical agen- cy includes contingent changes, such as those ac- tions, motions, or changes which are occasioned by the impulse or influence of other bodies. The second kind of general agency, viz., the in- stinctive, embraces all those actions of irrational an- imals, which result from what is termed instinct, that is, a propensity prior to experience and inde- pendent of instruction ; such as the incubation of hens, &oc. The third species of agency is rational or moral agency. To this class belong all those actions of men, either voluntary or spontaneous, which are free, for which we are accountable, and which may be termed moral actions. This class is of the very utmost importance, and embraces in it the entire field of all that diversified agency, which is pecu- liar to man, as a rational and accountable creature of God. MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. ' 67 III. Relations between absolute and concrete en- tities. {a.) In reference to number ':' addition, multipli- cation, subtraction, and division of numbers (not of concrete entities). These operations are active relations of agency, performed by the concrete en- tity man, on our ideas of the absolute entity number. (6.) In reference to space : mensuration of its parts by the concrete entity man ; and fitness or unfitness of any concrete entity to occupy any giv- en portion, or form of it. (c.) In relation to time: calculation of its parts by man ; and the relation of fitness or unfitness of a given portion of it to any specified purpose. The relations of entities may be divided into transitive and intransitive. The first, or transitive class of relations, embraces the relation of causation or agency in general, mechanical, instinctive, and moral. The second, or intransitive class, embraces the relations of similarity, diversity, contiguity, and, in short, all the other relations excepting those of causation and agency in general. These two classes may again be subdivided into absolute or indicative, and hypothetical or subjunc- tive. These relations are, in human language, most naturally expressed by verbs. Those words ex- pressing transitive relations are in their primitive nature active verbs ; those expressing intransitive relations are in their original form neuter verbs, verbs expressing a state of being. Passive verbs appear to be an improvement in language, and are not based on any separate distinction in the rela- 68 DIVISIONS OF RELATIONS. tions themselves, but refer simply to the entities between which they exist, and determine whether the speaker was the agent or recipient of the active influence, which they always express. This is beau- tifully illustrated by the Hebrew verbs in the Kal voice. The radical word throughout expresses the relation of action; the appendages prefixed and suffixed only designate the relations of the speak- ers and others, as the agents or recipients of the action. The same is also true, in a certain degree, of Latin and Greek verbs. The subdivision of both classes of relations into retrospective, present, and prospective, is obviously natural, and is expressed in language by the past, present, and future tenses of verbs. Each of these is again twofold ; the relation is either absolute or hypothetical. In the former case the verb express- ing this relation is in the indicative, and in the latter case it is in the subjunctive mood. The imperative mood is the annunciation to an individual, of his relation of obligation to perform a prescribed act ; whether this obligation results from his relation to the speaker as authorized to command him, or to some other human being, or to God. The other parts of speech express ideas, which may probably be reduced to appendages of the above-named three. Thus the prepositions " to," " in," &c, express relations of the verb, and are often incorporated with it ; as Produce, induct, ^os^pone, swZ>ject, &c, &c. Adverbs stand for ideas which qualify adjectives or composite enti- ties, that is, adjectives or verbs. MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. 69 CHAPTER II. OF OUR COGNITIVE IDEAS, OR MENTAL REPRESENTA- TIVES OF ENTITIES. SECTION I. What is the exact nature of those of our ideas which are knowledge ? In reply to this inquiry, we remark, that it is probably impossible to describe the intrinsic nature of our ideas in any other way than by stating that they belong to the class of entities termed mind ; and that every individual knows for himself what his ideas are, by the testimony of his own con- sciousness. One cardinal feature of the first class of ideas, by which they are clearly distinguished from all others, is, that they are representatives of either the properties or relations of things actually existing. It is, indeed, true of many of our cogni- tive ideas, that they do not represent actual realities with exactness. Thus those ideas formed by the active process of the mind, hereafter explained un- der the name of Modification, such as abstractions, generalizations, mathematical, moral, and metaphys- ical axioms, do not correspond exactly to realities, to real entities ; yet the elements of which they are composed are all derived from the contemplation 70 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. of individual realities, and whatever is affirmed in them, however generic it may be, is true of all the objects embraced in their terms : though it does not constitute a specific or distinguishing representative of any one of them. Thus the proposition, " things equal to the same thing are equal to each other," contains a cognitive idea, viz., the relation of sameness between three or more objects. It is true, this general proposition does not affirm this relation of any particular ob- iect. Nevertheless, it was originally learned by observing its truth in numberless individual ca- ses, even in our earliest years, and it is in reali- ty true of every object embraced in its terms, that is, it is a correct mental representative of ev- ery specific object embraced in its generic terms, so far as the particular relation affirmed is con- cerned. Thus, if two triangles or circles are equal in capacity to a third triangle or circle, they are equal to each other. The disputed question, whether our ideas are to be considered as some- thing distinct from the mind itself, we feel con- strained to answer in the affirmative ; while we, oi course, must reject the old Peripatetic notion, that these ideas are literal images, resembling the enti- ties, which are the subjects of them. SECTION II. What are the criteria by which the cognitive class of ideas is distinguished ? The following criteria may, we think, be clearly perceived, and should be regarded as characteristic : CRITERIA OF COGNITIVE IDEAS. 71 I. The. cognitive ideas have for their objects en- tities existing out of the mind, that is, things of any and of every description. As we regard the mind as distinct from its operations, it is evident that this language does not exclude from the list of cognitive ideas the knowledge of our own mental operations. In short, our knowledge of mental phenomena of ev- ery sort is embraced in this class, whether they be past, present, or prospective ; whether they be the operations of our own, or of other minds. II. The cognitive ideas derive their form and are dependant for their character on the entities them- selves which are the subjects of them, which have existence independently of us, and would be what they are if we had not this knowledge of them. We, of course, do not mean, that there exists any literal resemblance between our ideas of entities, and these entities themselves. Thus, our idea of a peach or a pear, does not resemble the object itself, in any one particular. But we mean, that there is a correspondence between the difference subsisting among different objects in nature, and the intellec- tual representatives of them, which, by the consti- tution of the mind, these objects produce, when brought within its observation. The same entities, when fairly viewed, always produce the same rep- resentatives in the mind of the same person ; but it also affords the same idea to all other persons, or rather an idea exactly similar. All men have the same uniform representatives of entities ; hence they can converse intelligibly about them. If the same entity afforded to different persons different 72 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. representatives of itself, men could no more con- verse intelligibly about it, than if they did not un- derstand the same language. Our idea of an en- tity, accordingly, is not what we please that it shall be, but is such, as, by the constitution of our minds, is naturally produced by the entity itself, when brought under the observation of the mind. Nor is our knowledge of the relations of entities, what we choose to make it ; but what God has made it by our mental structure. Thus, whether a land- scape, or any other object, shall appear to us beau- tiful, or otherwise, does not depend upon our wish- es. Beauty, and the reverse, are properties and re- lations inherent in the objects, to which they belong, and our apperception of them depends on their ex- istence in the object, which is the subject of our ob- servation. Our knowledge of the truth or falsity of a propo- sition no more depends upon our previous wishes, if the examination was impartial and faithful, than does the shape of a book, or the colour of an apple, when presented to our eyes. How often are not men called to attend the examination of a friend, who has been charged with some heinous crime, which, if established, would hurl him from the re- spectable eminence which he occupied in society, and prove him unworthy of the confidence which they had reposed in him, and of the affections of which he had been the subject. These friends pro- test his innocence, and gladly lend him every aid in obtaining able counsel, and the attendance of every desired witness, to wipe away the odious stain CRITERIA OF COGNITIVE IDEAS. 73 from his character. With intense feeling they en- ter the halls of justice, anxiously wishing that their friend may succeed in proving himself still worfhy of their affections and respect. But, alas ! one wit- ness after another is heard, one item of evidence after another is brought to light, until the guilt of their former friend no longer admits of any doubt. They hear the testimony in his favour, they listen to the arguments of his counsel, and find nothing but subterfuge and conjecture ; find, indeed, even in the nature of the efforts made to save his charac- ter, collateral evidence of his guilt, and are com- pelled, though with bleeding hearts, to believe that he who stands before them convicted as a criminal, is no longer the upright man, whom they loved and respected as a friend. Here the result of the in- vestigation was the knowledge, that the charge al- leged against their friend was true ; a knowledge of the relation of probation (proof or evidence), be- tween the facts adduced in the trial and the guilt of their friend. Surely no one would contend that the nature of the result depended on their wishes, or on anything else than the nature of the testi- mony itself, that is, on the facts, the entities and their relations, of which they acquired knowledge during the trial. III. The entities which are the subjects of our cognitive ideas, must have an existence previously to our knowledge of them. When we make a vo- lition, the subject of that volition is the intended future exertion of some physical or intellectual power, and the subject of the volition has no previ- G 74 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. ous existence. But when we have a knowledge of an apple, a stone, a mind, of space, or number, these cognitive ideas, or knowledge, are mental representatives of entities previously existing ; and, according to universal consent, they presuppose such previous existence. Thus, even in a fictitious narration, all the elements, so far as they are cog- nitive, are made up of ideas of entities which sepa- rately had a real existence. SECTION III. The nature and sources of error in our cognitive ideas. In order to obtain a correct view of this extreme- ly important subject, it is necessary first to advert to the exact nature and divisions of truth. All truths may be divided into three classes : I. Real or objective truths, that is, entities them- selves, existing in nature. II. Idealistic or subjective truths, that is, correct mental representatives of objective entities, that is, of objects in nature. III. Nominal or verbal truths, that is, proposi- tions or sentences, expressing in accurate language, correct ideas of things, correct mental representa- tives of objective entities. This division is evidently based on the nature of things, and affords us no small aid in understand- ing the sources, whence sprung the former philo- sophical sects of Realists and Nominalists, as well as the modern Idealists. The rancorous contentions of the former sects, REALISM AND IDEALISM. 75 about the metaphysical question, whether our ge- neric ideas are mere names (nomina rerum, seu fla- tus vocis) as the Nominalists contended, or realities existing in nature, generic archetypes according to which all individual entities are formed, as was maintained by the Realists from the days of Aristo- tle till the time of Roscellinus, in the eleventh cen- tury, were continued through subsequent ages, and rose to such a height, that the blood of several dis- tinguished leaders was shed in the contest. It was in no small degree the hatred of the Nominalist priests and bishops, who greatly preponderated in the Council of Constance, which induced them in 1415, to commit to the flames the innocent Huss, who was a learned and distinguished leader of the Realists ; and, for the same reason chiefly, the Re- alists in return obtained the condemnation of the Nominalist, John de Wesalia, doctor of theology in Erfurt, in 1479, who ended his life in prison. Philosophers of modern days, especially in Ger- many, have used the terms Realism and Idealism in a somewhat different sense, as characteristic of their several systems of philosophy. By Realism they designate that system of philos- ophy, which not only admits the existence of some- thing real or actual, something objective in nature; but also regards this real something as the original material, anterior to the ideal, and out of which the ideal (that is, consciousness, conception, knowledge) was deduced. The principle of this system is " re- ale prius, ideale posterius" the real existed first, the ideal is posterior to it. But to the various modifica- 76 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. tions of this system, it may justly be objected, that the derivation of the ideal, that is, of mental action, from the real, that is, from the organization of mat- ter, necessarily results in materialism. There is, moreover, no necessity whatever of deriving either mind from matter, or matter from mind, either the ideal from the real, or the real from the ideal. Both are realities created by God, and it is one of the idle conceits of philosophy, falsely so called, to suppose, that a system, to be complete, must have some one element to start from, out of which every- thing else can be evolved. By Idealism they designate that system of phi- losophy which regards " the real" (das Reale), that is, the actual or material world, as merely ideal or imaginary, and assumes that there exists nothing in nature corresponding to our ideas of the material world ; but that we ourselves confer objectivity on those ideas, that is, conceive the existence of some- thing real as corresponding to our ideas (to the ideal), because by a necessity of our nature we find ourselves possessed of those ideas. This system regards " the ideal" (das Ideale) as first, and the real as posterior to it, yea, admits the existence of the real or material universe, only because and as far as, the belief of it is the necessary result of our mental structure. The real (say they) is the mere product of the ideal. But this system is after all not what it boasts to be, a system of pure ideal- ism, for it begins by assuming the " reality" of the " ideal," that is, it assumes the existence of the mind which is the subject of the ideal, the mind in IDEALISM. 77 which the ideas of the universe are found. To es- cape from this difficulty, some idealists have sup- posed, these ideas of the material universe, to be produced in us immediately by God, the infinite mind. Fichte and others suppose the mind itself to be the originator of these ideas, acting by virtue of its original activity, according to certain laws or limitations of its nature, which are incomprehensi- ble to itself (to the ego). This system is termed by German philosophers Egoistic Idealism. The transcendental Idealism of Kant is, however, materially different from this. He admits or as- sumes the existence of " the real," that is, of the material world ; but maintains that it cannot be known to us as it is in itself objectively, apart from our views of it, but only as it appears to us through the medium of our senses. But our present design does not permit us to en- large on the opinions of these writers ; yet we think the view of this subject to which our system natu- rally leads us, will enable the reader to form a clear conception of the extent to which each system ad- heres to the truth. The exact truth in the dispute between the ancient Realists and Nominalists, will fully appear in the discussion of the third active pro- cess of the mind, modification, in the last part of this work ; where abstraction or generalization is discussed as a part of that process. The mind doubtless does possess the power of framing gen- eral ideas, which, though derived from real objects in nature, do not exactly correspond to any spe- cific one. Yet are these not merely names, as the G2 78 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. Nominalists held, but actual generic conceptions, as the later Conceptualists more correctly maintain. But we return to the discussion of the nature of truth. We have said, that all entities in the natural, in- tellectual, and moral world, and their relations, are realities or truths objectively considered. The word truth is indeed not often used precisely in this sense. Most generally it has a reference to our ideas of entities, and is therefore used subjectively ; but, if we wish to begin at the ultimate ground of our subject, we may be permitted to employ the word in this signification. The objective realities exist out of the mind, and would be what they are if we knew nothing about them. They are the subjects of our knowledge, and the ultimate basis of truth. Our cognitive idea of each objective reality, or entity, if it accord with the original, that is, if it be what by divine appointment and the constitution of our minds, that entity is designed to give, is an idealistic truth, or a truth subjectively considered, and evidently differs from objective truths. Sub- jective truth is more limited in its extent than the objective, and is of different extent in different minds. There is an immeasurable difference be- tween the extended and diversified knowledge of a Mosheim, a Leibnitz, or a Newton, and the lim- ited stock of ideas found in the mind of an igno- rant, unlettered savage ; but doubtless the knowl- edge of the most deservedly celebrated universal IDEAL AND NOMINAL TRUTH. 79 scholar, falls short of the entire range of real exist- ences in an inconceivably greater degree. The manner in which God determined the na- ture of our representatives of entities, is by the structure of the human mind itself ; so that if we have freely and impartially examined an entity with all the light attainable, the idea then formed of it in the mind, is that appointed by God as its repre- sentative. A nominal or verbal truth, is a sentence or prop- osition, spoken or written, in which a correct idea of a real entity is expressed by the precise words, which, according to the usage of language, are em- ployed to designate those very ideas. All error in statements, whether oral or written, must be situated in one of these two latter depart- ments. There may be an error in regard to the entire objective entity. Thus a timid individual, in a dark night, indistinctly beholding a stump before him, may believe it a robber, and so relate his story ; but he has made a premature and gratuitous infer- ence from the indistinct testimony of his senses, and thus obtained a false idea of an entity. The er- ror here is evidently in the idealistic department. Though the error in this case concerns the objec- tive entity, it specifically consists in the want of conformity of the subjective idea or mental repre- sentative, to the objective or real entity. In short, the error can never lie in the first department, namely, that of real or objective truth. Objective truths, or entities, are and must ever be, just what they are independently of our knowledge of them. 80 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. The fact that our mental representatives of them are correct or incorrect, cannot affect them in any degree. But, if an individual, who has a correct idea of an entity, either inadvertently, or through design, or through ignorance of language, describes his idea in terms which express either more than his precise idea, or something radically different from it, the error will be a nominal or verbal one ; it will con- sist in the incorrect selection of words to express the ideas. In addition to these two locations of error in statements, there is another in the hearer or reader. Error may be seated in the incorrect association in the mind of the reader or hearer, between the words which he reads or hears, and his own ideas. Thus, a sentence describing correct ideas in accurate language, might be mistaken by an ignorant person. With these preliminary views, we can find no difficulty in tracing the following sources of error : SOURCES OF ERROR IN HUMAN KNOWLEDGE. Involuntary Error embraces, I. Incorrect original mental representatives of en- tities. These may arise from the following sources : (a.) From a hasty, superficial inspection of entities. (J).) From forgetfulness of the exact mental repre- sentative originally obtained, and a consequent mis- statement of it. (c.) From listening to one part of a statement, and neglecting to listen to the whole. This remark applies not only to substantive and adjective entities, but also to composite. The re- INVOLUNTARY ERROR. 81 lations of sameness and contrariety may be easily observed by attentive inspection. But haste and inattention may also lead to error. The relation most difficult to be accurately discerned is that of causation, which is often prematurely admitted, where there was mere sequence. II. Involuntary error may arise from incorrect selection of sounds and written ivords, to express to others the true mental representative which we re- ally have. Thus we may select a word more or less specific than it ought to be ; as, for example, when we charge many with a crime which belongs only to few ; or, our expression may convey differ- ent circumstances from those which actually exist ; we may incautiously denominate that self-interest, which was really gratitude, and that pride, which, in fact, was vanity. III. Involuntary error may arise from the real imperfection of language, which does not furnish words to express our ideas with precision on all subjects. Thus, in translating a work, and giving an account of foreign countries, we find offices, coins, &c, different from any found in our own country, for which we have no exact name in our tongue. In the New Testament, denarius is trans- lated a penny, and daifiov, devil ; not because the English words were supposed by the translators exactly to correspond in meaning to the Greek, but because our language furnishes no words of precisely the same meaning. We have no coin exactly corresponding in value to the denarius, and, therefore, no word in popular use to designate it. 82 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. IV. Involuntary error may arise from mistakes in judging of the motives of others. We may sup- pose we perceive the relation of causation, between ambition and certain conduct of an individual, whereas that conduct results from a sense of duty in him. V. Involuntary errors may arise from uninten- tional, illogical reasoning, from fallacy either in the major or minor proposition, or in the conclusion. This embraces also premature generalization, in which the conclusion is more general than the ex- tent of our induction justifies. In short, it embra- ces every species of sophism, which can occur in any form of the syllogism. But it is unnecessary to specify these minutely at this time. VI. Another source from which involuntary error may arise, is the misapprehension of a correct sen- tence, through ignorance of language. SOURCES OF VOLUNTARY ERROR. I. Intentional misstatement of entities, simple or composite ; that is, of things or actions, from mal- ice or any other motive. In these cases, men in- tentionally use words which recall or suggest to others erroneous mental representatives, words which excite in them the idea of some evil proper- ty or relation, in connexion with an individual, to whom that property or relation does not belong. II. Voluntary error may arise from indulgence in the habit of mere high colouring, without directly stating a falsehood. III. Voluntary error may consist in voluntary ig- VOLUNTARY ERROR. 83 norance, resulting from the neglect of the means of information within our reach. It is obviously the duty of man to avail himself of all the opportunities appropriately within his reach, to extend the sphere of his knowledge, and to correct any errors which he may have adopted, either innocently or through neglect. Whoever, therefore, remains in error from this cause, may be justly charged with volun- tary error, and will doubtless be held responsible for it by the omniscient Judge. IV. Voluntary error may arise from the indul- gence of prejudice in regard to persons or things. So strong, indeed, is the influence of our personal feelings upon us, that every friend of the truth should incessantly be upon his guard, lest he be led captive by it. V. Voluntary error may result from the indul- gence of passion. Passion prompts to speedy and premature action, and thus prevents deliberate in- vestigation, and enlightened, conscientious choice. When error has been detected in our knowledge, or when we have reason even to suspect the accuracy of any of our opinions, it becomes us to institute inquiry and settle the point. The generic method of recti- fying any mistaken views, is to pass successively and carefully through the several steps by which, according to the laws of mind, we obtain our in- formation on the point in question. Truth may justly be regarded as that which the constitution of our minds compels us to believe, when its evidences are fairly presented, and impartially weighed. We may assume it as an undeniable position, that the 84 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. evidences of truth are stronger than those of error, and will, when carefully pondered, produce on a well-balanced mind a conviction precisely as strong as it was designed by the Creator to be, and as it is our duty to entertain. From the above considerations we see, at a glance, the fallacy of the favourite sentiment of free- thinkers, that man is not responsible for his opin- ions, that they are what they are by a constitution- al necessity of our minds, and lie beyond the sphere of human responsibility. SECTION IV. Division of our Cognitive Ideas. All our cognitive ideas may be divided into Indi- vidual and Relative : and again into Retrospective, Present, and Prospective. I. Of Individual knowledge. To this class be- longs our knowledge of every individual substan- tive entity in nature, and also of every individual property belonging to any entity. Our retrospect- ive knowledge of individual entities is also of the same individual class ; as is, in like manner, our prospective knowledge of them. II. Of Relative knowledge. To this class be- longs all our knowledge of composite entities, that is, of two or more adjective entities viewed in con- nexion, in respect to some particular relation be- tween them. Of this kind are our perceptions of all the different relations of sameness or difference in size, colour, shape, local contiguity, &c, of all perceivable objects. They are nothing else than a RELATIVE KNOWLEDGE. 85 knowledge of two or more of these adjective enti- ties viewed together, and viewed in reference to some one or more of their relations to each other. Thus, I see before me a father and his son ; my perception of each of them alone is individual knowledge ; but the father is twice as tall as the son. I view them in connexion, to ascertain their relative magnitude, and my knowledge of this rela- tion of difference is relative knowledge. It is a knowledge of something really existing, not in ei- ther of them alone, but in both taken together. To this class, also, belongs the greater part of our conceptions. Many individual, abstract terms, when rightly examined, are nothing else than signs of such composite entities. What do we mean by the terms virtue and vice, more than our knowledge of the relation of agreement or disagreement, be- tween human actions of a certain kind and the law of God, or the structure of the universe. Just as the mind, though it at one view acquires a knowl- edge of the size, form, and colour of an object, may make either of these items of its knowledge the exclusive subject of reflection, or of other men- tal operations ; so it may, by the process of abstrac- tion, make these items of its knowledge of the characteristics of human actions the subject of re- flection, without connecting with them the idea of individual persons. Of this kind, evidently, are our ideas of virtue and vice ; and language affords us words to designate these items of knowledge, as well as others. Geometrical axioms also belong to relative knowl- H 86 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. edge. Thus the axiom, " Things which are equal to the same thing, are equal to one another," ex- presses our knowledge of the relation of sameness in dimensions or number, between three given enti- ties. The axiom, " When equals are added to equals, the wholes are equal," more definitely sta- ted, would stand thus : If to quantities, dimensions, or numbers already equal to each other, equal addi- tions be made, the results will also be equal : and in this form what does the proposition express but our knowledge of the relation of agreement in quanti- ty, dimension, or number between several entities viewed together as one compound entity under the specified circumstances. Thus we might review all the twelve axioms of Euclid, and would find them all to confirm the statements we have made. To the same class of relative knowledge belong all the relations (not properties) of numbers in arith- metical calculations. Thus, " twice three are six," when fully stated, means, that the number three twice taken, or counted, bears the relation of equal- ity to the number six. Metaphysical axioms, when rightly examined, also belong to this class of relative knowledge. Thus, "Every effect must have a cause," or, more fully stated, every effect we ever knew had a cause, hence all other effects most probably have, seems to be nothing else than our knowledge of the rela- tion of analogy, between two or more given sub- stantive or adjective entites, viewed in relation to each other. Self-evident truths consist mainly of relations between entities. BELIEF, IMMEDIATE AND ACQUIRED. 87 Moral abstract propositions are also resolvable into expressions of our knowledge of some relation or other. Thus the maxim, " Vice is productive of misery," may be regarded as an abstract express- ion of the relation of causation, subsisting between sinful actions and misery ; or it may be changed into the knowledge of the relation of analogy by thus altering the terms : " Vicious actions have, so far as we have been able to observe, always sooner or later produced unhappiness, therefore they, in all probability, will do so also in future." Dictates of Conscience, or Moral Judgments, that is, judgments concerning the morality of ac- tions, concerning their conformity or non-conform- ity to the law of God, are also relative knowl- edge. The operations of conscience, when cor- rectly analyzed, consist of three distinct elements, the judicial, the sentient, and the impulsive. The judicial element is cognitive, and consists in a judg- ment of the mind concerning the relation of our ac- tions to our ideas of the law of God, as being con- formed to them, or in violation of them. If the views of men concerning the Divine law were al- ways correct, the decisions of conscience would in- variably be accurate as to the moral character of human actions. This judgment concerning the morality of the action always precedes as well the emotion of pleasure or pain, approbation or disap- probation, as the impulsive dictate of obligation, to perform or not to perform the act contemplated. Hence, as the views of the heathen concerning the law of God are very erroneous, they approve of 88 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. many actions, such as parricide, infanticide, sacri- fice of human beings, which are highly sinful, al- though their intention in all these cases may be to do right. And even Paul, so long as he consider- ed Christianity a violation of the law of his God, says, "I verily thought with myself that I ought to do many things contrary to the name of Jesus of Nazareth," although after his judgment of the char- acter of the act was changed, he deeply regretted his conduct.* Belief of a relation, is also relative knowledge. Belief may be divided into immediate and acquired ; the former embracing what are usually termed con- stitutional or intuitive judgments, and the latter, acquired or deduced judgments. There is no other difference between immediate and acquired judg- ments except that the relation subsisting between the two entities is so obvious in the one case, that the mind immediately perceives it to exist ; and in the other, that the relation is so indistinct, that other additional related entities, must be examined be- fore the mind perceives it to be true. Both intuitive and acquired truths may be divided into those, relating to our own minds, and those which refer to other entities. To the first class of truths, belong such as these : that the testimony of our senses fairly ascertained, is true — that we exist — that the several operations of our minds may gen- erally be relied on — that we are possessed of per- sonal identity. The second class embraces truths relating to the absolute and to the concrete entities. * See Part II., Moral Emotions, and Part III., First Constitutional In- clination. MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. 89 Among them are the truths, that every effect must have a cause — that the laws of nature, i. e.,the es- tablished modes of the Divine agency, are uniform — metaphysical axioms — moral truths, &c. All belief, therefore, of whatever degree, whether presumptive, or probable, or certain, differs in de- gree, but not in kind. And the all-wise Creator has so constituted the mind, that when the evidences of any truth are fully exhibited and impartially weigh- ed, the strength of our belief will be proportionate to the degree of evidence. Retrospective, Present, and Prospective Knowledge. Our cognitive ideas may again be divided into retrospective, present, and prospective. I. Retrospective knowledge is our knowledge of all our former cognitive, sentient, and active ideas, and is usually termed recollection or acts of memo- ry. It embraces all our past operations. This spe- cies of knowledge may be subdivided into sponta- neous and voluntary retrospective knowledge. By the former, or spontaneous retrospective knowl- edge, is meant that, which is not produced in the mind by a volition to recall it. By the latter is meant those recollections of former mental opera- tions, which are produced by a voluntary effort to recall them. This effort consists in an active review of related things, times, and places, and sometimes in a review of the letters of the alphabet, in expec- tation that the sight of the first letter of a word, will recall the whole word, and with it, our knowl- edge of the thing or entity. The extent of our H2 90 EXTENT OF RETROSPECTIVE KNOWLEDGE. spontaneous retrospective knowledge and the extent to which, and the facility with which we can volun- tarily recall it, depend on the following circum- stances. 1. On the natural aptitude of the mind for this exercise ; or, in other words, the natural retentive- ness of memory. This differs in different persons, but is, among all the powers of the mind, the most susceptible of improvement by practice. Some men appear to have at constant command an intui- tive retrospect of the great mass of the former inci- dents of their life, and of the sciences which they have studied. Doubtless this superior and abun- dant mass of materials, must necessarily give supe- rior scope and success to those active operations of the mind, which are based on them. It is thus, that men of genius, having the vast experience of former ages, and an extensive acquaintance with the laws, properties, and relations of entities at command, can produce much more accurate speci- mens of prospective knowledge, and make more able vindications of the positions they assume with regard to any subject. 2. The second ground of difference in the extent and facility of our retrospective knowledge, is found in the different degrees of logical accuracy, with which our knowledge is arranged, on paper or in the mind, according to the different relations them- selves which subsist between the entities. It is a well-established fact, that our knowledge of those entities, which are clearly connected by some ob- vious relation, such as sameness, contrariety, genus, MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. 91 species, &c, are most easily and most extensively recollected. Hence, one method of facilitating our voluntary recollections of former entities is, habitu- ally to classify our knowledge according to the most obvious relations of the entities themselves, which are the subjects of them, or with some principle or fact, confirmed or illustrated by them. This habit we strongly recommend to the young student. If early formed, and steadily persisted in, it will lead to the gradual and easy accumulation of an amount of useful knowledge, far greater, more various, and more readily at command, than would otherwise be retained. One important method of aiding us in committing a speech, or sermon, or any other composition to memory, is to write it in such a lo- gical manner, according to the objective relations of the subjects themselves. 3. The third ground of difference, is found in the different degrees of frequency, with which the knowledge to be retained was revised by the mind, and the feeling or interest which was felt in it. Our retrospective knowledge will be increased by the following methods : 1. By thinking fre- quently of the ideas intended to be recollected. 2. By reviewing those ideas together, which we wish to recollect together ; and in the very same order in which we desire to remember them. 3. By connecting them, in the act of memorizing, with some principle or fact, which we will be sure to re- member at the intended time. 4. By the habit of studying subjects rather than books. This is an ex- tremely important habit, which, as it is of constant 92 STUDY OF SUBJECTS RATHER THAN OF BOOKS. application, and may be continued through life, exerts a very perceptible influence on intellectual character and attainments. The man who reads through, even the more important works to which he has access, not only vainly expends his time in perusing much that he knew before, but also pur- sues an intellectual habit not the most profitable. It is not even every good book that deserves to be read through. Far better is it for the student, to keep up merely a general acquaintance with the publications which he deems worthy of his atten- tion, by an examination of their table of contents, and a tasting of them on some of the most impor- tant topics, so as to form an estimate of the char- acter and strength of the author, and then lay them by for future use ; while he devotes the greater part of his time to the systematic study of subjects, ex- amining, on each such subject, all the valuable au- thors to which he has access, and tracing the sub- ject through all its various ramifications and rela- tions. The selection of these subjects should be influenced by the professional duties of the individ- ual ; and, while collateral matters of taste and sci- ence should not be excluded, yet the more exten- sively the choice of subjects coincides with our daily duties, the greater will be the eminence at- tained. 5. Our retrospective knowledge will be increased by interesting our feelings in the subject, by viewing its relations to some of the constitution- al inclinations of the soul, hereafter to be explained. Scarcely any bounds can be affixed to the degree of improvement which the retentive powers have MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. 93 sometimes attained. Kepler, the celebrated Ger- man mathematician, could repeat the whole of Vir- gil's iEneid, and even specify the first and last lines on every page of the copy which he used. Henry de Mesmes could repeat the whole of Homer ; and of the celebrated Pascal it was said, that he very rarely forgot anything which he had ever known. Cyrus, we are told, knew the name of every soldier in his army ; and Themistocles could call by name the twenty thousand inhabitants of Athens. Even admitting that these accounts must be received, as we suppose they must, with some qualification, they are remarkable and most interesting examples of mnemonic power. These were instances of per- sons in health, who exhibited these extraordinary powers through life. But there are other facts, which shed a new light on the retrospective power of the soul, and seem to prove that persons of the most ordinary talents, yea, that the soul of every man naturally possesses equal and even greater mnemonic powers, which are now confined by the organs of the body, but will be fully developed in the eternal world. Different diseases have called forth temporary exhibitions of this superior power of mem- ory. " A case occurred at St. Thomas Hospital, of a man who was in a state of stupor in consequence of an injury of the head. On his partial recovery, he spoke a language which nobody in the hospital understood, but which was soon ascertained to be Welsh. It was then discovered that he had been thirty years absent from Wales, and, before the ac- cident, had entirely forgotten his native language. On his complete recovery, he entirely forgot his 94 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. Welsh again, and recovered the English language. A lady, mentioned by Dr. Pritchard, when in a state of delirium, spoke a language which nobody about her understood, but which also was discovered to be Welsh. None of her friends could form any concep- tion of the manner in which she had become ac- quainted with that language ; but, after much inquiry, it was discovered, that in her childhood she had a nurse, a native of a district on the coast of Brittany, the dialect of which is closely analogous to the Welsh. The lady had, at that time, learned a good deal of this dialect, but had entirely forgotten it for many years before this attack of fever."* But the most interesting case with which we have met, is that mentioned by Coleridge, of a young woman in Germany, some time before 1798. Though she could neither read nor write, yet, when labouring under a nervous fever, she uttered numerous senten- ces in Latin, Greek, and Hebrew. Her case excited great attention, and was, for a season, regarded as inexplicable. At length it was discovered that, in early life, she had lived in the family of a learned Protestant minister, who was in the habit of walk- ing up and down the passage of his house, into which the kitchen door opened, and reading aloud his fa- vourite authors in these languages. And it was also found, that the passages which she recited corre- sponded with these authors. In these cases it is evident that the impression made upon the memory, though the persons had not the power to recall them in health, were, nevertheless, not lost, but still re- mained engraven, as it were, on the tablets of the * Abercrombie on the Intellectual Powers, p. 123. MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. 95 soul, and disease wrought such a change in the bodily organs, or exerted such a stimulus upon the brain, that the soul had more free scope for action. Why, then, may we not indulge the amazing, the appalling, yet highly probable conjecture, that thought is indestructible in its nature, that every in- dividual idea we have ever had, though now for- gotten by us, is indelibly impressed upon the soul, is, as it were, locked up in its inner recesses, and at the great day of eternity will stand in full view be- fore us, will be recollected as vividly as the occur- rences of yesterday ? It seems, indeed, highly prob- able, that such an increased recollection will bring the whole agency of our present life into close con- nexion with the eternal world, and that, in the prov- idence of God, this whole accumulated mass of our thoughts will be the basis of our future retribution, will be the occasion, or will give some peculiarity to the circumstances of the happiness of the righ- teous and misery of the wicked. Various attempts have been made, both in ancient and modern times, to aid the energies of this im- portant power of the soul by artificial contrivances, not one of which has commanded the permanent approbation of the wise and judicious. Some em- pyrics recommended sundry medicinal prescrip- tions, which are, however, all eventually injurious to both body and mind. Others invented different artificial systems of mnemonics, some of which ap- pear in a few instances to afford an advantage ; but all of which are eventually of little or no benefit, and some of them positively injurious to the real improvement of the mind. The credit of having 96 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. invented the first system of this kind is attributed to Simonides, the poet and philosopher of Ceos, an island in the iEgean Sea, who lived B.C. about 557. On one occasion, as Cicero informs us,* while dining in company with some of his friends, he was called out of the house, but, on coming out, found no one. Just as he was about to return, the house or hall suddenly fell and crushed his friends to death. When the rubbish had been removed, they were found so much disfigured, that they could not be recognised ; but Simonides could distinguish them all, because he recollected the place in which each one had reclined around the table. By this incident he was led to reflect, that order, or a prop- er disposition of the objects to be recollected, af- fords the greatest aid to memory, and that those who desire to cultivate this talent should select cer- tain places, and picture upon their minds the things which they wish to recollect, and arrange them into these places. Thus the order of the places would enable them to recollect the order of the things, and the pictures or images of these things would point out the things themselves. The same prin- ciple of associating our ideas with certain symbols, or images, or hieroglyphics, and arranging these in various ways, seems also to be the basis of the principal systems of mnemonics of modern times. Different methods have likewise been invented to facilitate the recollection of dates and figures gen- erally. The most popular is, perhaps, that of Fein- agle, who framed the following table, which is first to be committed to memory with much accuracy. * Cicero, De Oratore, lib. ii., $ 86, p. 197. MENTAL 97 The number in question is then to be expressed by the letters of this key table, taken either from the consonants or vowels, as may seem most suitable, and annexed \o the end of the word to which the figures refer. a e i u au oi ei ou y 1 - 3 J 6 7 8 9 b d t f 1 s P k n z Thu , to recollect the date B.C. 46, when Julius Csesar obtained supreme command at Rome, take the letters o(=4) and s( = 6), and put them in place of the last letters of his name. We then have Julios, which is easily recollected, and cannot fail to indi- cate the date 46, unless the alphabet is forgotten. After all, the best general rule, in addition to those given above, is daily practice continued for years, and not entirely omitted even in after life. Quintili- an remarks, " Si qnis unam maximamque a me ar- tem memorise quaerat, exercitatio est et labor. Mul- ta ediscere, multa cogitare, et si fieri potest, quotid- ie, potentissimum est." We conclude our observations on memory by adding the excellent practical directions to teachers and younger pupils, compiled from Dr. Niemeyer.* 1 . We should begin at a very early age to teach our pupils to retain and to repeat what they have heard. Their internal organs thus acquire a certain degree of firmness, and their frequent exercise forms a hab- it. 2. They should be taught to retain signs, espe- * Grundsatze der Erziehung uud des Unterrichts, vol. i., p. 124. On this subject see also an excellent work by Professor Smith, Education : its His- tory and Practice, p. 214. 98 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. cially words, as well as things. That which is nat- urally most easy for them, requires less practice ; that which is more difficult, should receive the more attention. 3. If they retain words with facility, even without understanding their import, they should be exercised the more faithfully in recollect- ing ideas and things, both individually, and in their several relations. Otherwise the memory will be cultivated at the expense of the judgment. Thus the pupil should be called on to repeat the substance of a discourse which he has heard ; or, after he has read one page of a book, let him close the volume, and repeat to you the train of ideas contained on it ; or let him trace the thread of a discourse back- ward to its first idea. As a remarkable instance of the proficiency attainable by this kind of train- ing, we would mention the case of the late Rever- end Uhlhorn, pastor of the German Lutheran Church in Baltimore, and one of the most finished scholars that have crossed the Atlantic, who, after twice or thrice perusing any hymn of six or eight ver- ses, was able to repeat it backward, word for word, from end to beginning. 4. If, on the contrary, the pupil finds it easy to retain and repeat a multitude of ideas, concerning that which he has heard, or seen, or read, but cannot preserve their particular or- der or connexion, or repeat particular expressions ; this also requires special attention. For it is, on many accounts, advantageous to be able to retain names, numbers, and passages out of letters or books, and to repeat them verbatim. A number of words should, therefore, daily be assigned, but only such whose meaning the pupil understands, to PRESENT KNOWLEDGE. 99 be committed in a given time, and that number should be gradually increased. Subsequently, se- lect passages from different authors may be assign- ed, and the interest of the pupils kept up by the matter of the extracts committed, as well as by em- ulation among the scholars, and explanations of the importance of the exercise. 5. Let not a day pass without some exercise of memory for all the pupils. 6. Let those of defective memory not be discoura- ged by harshness ; but let various methods be em- ployed for their encouragement, by calling to aid the principles of association. Associations of time and place will assist their recollection. Generic ideas will recall the specific one embraced in them, &c. II. Present knowledge embraces the testimony of consciousness, by which is meant that knowledge which we have of all our present mental operations of every class. Of course, if the lines of division be strictly adhered to, that portion of our knowledge which can correctly be called present, is compara- tively small ; for the moment after any act of present cognition is past, it belongs to the retrospective de- partment. Still, even when circumscribed by these narrow limits, consciousness embraces all the operations of our minds, at the precise time of their performance, such as our perceptions, our sensations, our emo- tions, our passions, our judgments in general, our acts of conscience, and, in short, all our mental operations. So soon, however, as any mental op- eration of which we are conscious is past, it be- comes, as it were, the property of memory, and falls into the retrospective department. Consciousness 100 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. is an important source oj" new ideas to us. By it we acquire all our knowledge of the inner man, of the powers, properties, and relations of our own minds, of that thinking, conscious subject myself. It is by consciousness that we obtain our knowledge of those mental operations expressed by the words thinking, believing, doubting, reflecting. &c. The term consciousness is strictly confined to the operations and processes which take place in the mind itself, and cannot with propriety be applied to any material object, or, indeed, to any other en- tity whatever except the phenomena of our own minds. We cannot be said to be conscious of the existence of the earth, or planets, or mountains, or trees, or even of our own bodies. We are con- scious of certain perceptions and sensations which these external objects produce in the mind, when they are at the time acting on us through our bodily organs, but not of these entities themselves. Ev- ery act of consciousness also, by a constitutional judgment of our mind, implies the existence of a conscious being, of myself, from whom it proceeds ; III. Prospective knowledge. By this we mean all our knowledge of the probable future existence of entities and their relations. That God has ac- tually bestowed on us some knowledge of futurity, is evident from an examination of our ideas them- selves, and even from the structure of human lan- guage. Every individual instance in which we use the future tense of a verb, is an exemplification of our remark. The vast sphere of human expecta- tions, of hopes and fears, is distinctly embraced PROSPECTIVE KNOWLEDGE. 101 within the limits of prospective knowledge. In- deed, calculations and expectations of a prospective nature enter into all human pursuits and occupa- tions. Without them, all business would be at a stand, the principal motive to human action would be destroyed, and the world itself would cease to be what it is. But here the question arises, Is our prospective knowledge also a knowledge of entities, and their relations really existing ? To this we re- ply, that in part it is ; and we suppose the follow- ing to be a correct view of this subject : The subject of our prospective knowledge, ob- jectively considered, seems always to be a com- posite entity, viz., a present entity and another sup- posed, future entity of some given character, as ex- isting at some future time more or less distant. The relation between these two, observed by the mind, is that of fitness, or analogy, or causation, &c. Thus our prospective knowledge or belief of the probable future existence of the material world, and of all existing classes of entities and their rela- tions, is nothing else than a knowledge of the rela- tion of fitness or causation, as existing between present entities and the same entities as existing at a future time. Thus, also, we behold a drunkard, fast hastening to the grave, and believe that he may yet live six months, but not six years. In both in- stances, the subject of our belief, is a composite en- tity. We observe, in one case, the relation of fit- ness between the entity, a drunkard, now existing with materially injured health, and his being still alive six months hence ; but we also perceive the I 2 102 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. relation of unfitness, between his present state, and his existence six years hence. Or we might say, we see between his present conduct and his death before six years, the relation of probable causation. "We see that intemperance will cause his death in less than the specified time. Our prospective knowledge of future human actions, under given circumstances, is nothing else than a prospective knowledge of the relation of suitableness, or causa- tion, between a given character of an individual, and a particular course of probable conduct. Of the many relations, perceivable between the different classes of entities, a few only seem to serve as bases of our prospective knowledge ; viz., fitness , by which we mean suitableness, reasonableness, or ac- cordance with the nature of the entity, analogy, causation, and revelation. Analogy, causation, and revelation may be regarded as the arches of the bridge, over which we pass from the present to a knowledge of the future. The relation of fitness is general in its nature, and seems to embrace analo- gy and causation ; yet there are cases in which the mind cannot clearly determine how far the antece- dent is really the cause of the consequent, or wheth- er it be merely the antecedent. The revelation, which God has given us, is another totally distinct basis of prospective knowledge. In many items of prospective knowledge derived from this source, we can now clearly perceive also the relation of fitness and causation, since that knowledge has been communicated to us ; although we were total- ly unable, a priori, to discover it. Our belief in a PROSPECTIVE KNOWLEDGE. 103 Divine revelation is a knowledge of a composite en- tity, viz., the Divine character, as known to us, and certain superhuman actions, termed miracles, of some kind or other. The relation perceived be- tween them, is that of suitableness or exclusive causation ; that is, causation which creatures could not exert. Our prospective knowledge of the future opera- tions and states of all inanimate entities, would be as certain as our present and retrospective knowl- edge of them, if we possessed a present, omniscient acquaintance with all their properties ; and if their circumstances and relations were not changed by the voluntary agency of animated beings, and if we knew that the Divine Being would not withdraw or change these properties. Or, in other words, in a world purely mechanical, in which no voluntary agency was mingled, an omniscient present knowl- edge, would necessarily imply an omniscient pro- spective knowledge to beings, endowed like our- selves, with the ability to perceive these relations. In such a world, the prospective knowledge of any creature constituted like man, however limited it might be, would probably be of equal extent with his present knowledge. Yet in our world, the oper- ations of inanimate nature are constantly influenced by the agency of animate beings, rational and irra- tional ; and therefore our prospective knowledge, even of the inanimate world, is, in many cases, very uncertain. Our prospective knowledge of the fu- ture conduct of animate beings, especially those of the higher class, must, for obvious reasons, be still 104 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. more indistinct and uncertain, on account of the voluntary agency possessed by man. Yet here also, whatever prospective knowledge we do possess, is strictly a knowledge of composite entities. Thus, the late sagacious politician Talleyrand had a pro- spective knowledge of the French Revolution, of 1830, some time at least before it occurred. What else was this knowledge, than a knowledge of the relation of causation between the arbitrary meas- ures of the French king and his cabinet, and a rev- olution, that is, resistance to these measures on the part of the discontented French people ? In short, every individual has a certain sphere of intellectual vision all around him, which, like the torch of the benighted traveller, enables him safely to steer his course through the circumstances and pursuits of life. This subject is one of great interest to every re- flecting mind. The principles above detailed, seem to present a definite and intelligible view of all our knowledge of futurity. It is nothing else than a knowledge of composite entities, one part of which is present, and the other future. In the present part we see the relation of fitness, of causation, of analogy to the supposed future part. On our knowledge of these relations in present entities, de- pends our power of prospection. All our knowl- edge of futurity, which is so important in human life, and is the basis of all our plans and enterpri- ses, may be reduced to the simple view, that it is a knowledge of the relations of causation, analogy, and revelation, seen by us in some existing entity, or learned from the inspired volume. On this pro- ORGANIC PROCESS. 105 spective knowledge, the politician bases his calcu- lations, the man of business and the Christian their arrangements for future operations. We know al- most with certainty, that the physical universe, the properties and tendencies of material things, will continue : and it is probable, that the other circum- stances of our situation will, in the main, remain unchanged. Thus, we have a highly probable fore- knowledge of the future continuance of nine tenths of the circumstances and prospects of our situation. We also know, that the changes which may occur will be limited by the powers of the different agents, and the laws of nature. Hence, the possi- ble changes cannot materially affect our prospects, or alter the propriety and wisdom of our course, and the principles of our action. Relying on all these circumstances, we pursue our course of busi- ness, secular or sacred, with confidence and de- light. CHAPTER III. ORGANIC PROCESS BY WHICH WE OBTAIN OUR IDEAS. The entire human body, considered as an organ for the influence of entities, may be viewed in a twofold light, as a general organ, and as a collec- tion of several organs. The effects produced in the mind through the bodily organs are a knowledge of the shape, colour, odour, flavour, and sound of entities, together with feelings more or less pleasant 106 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. or unpleasant, attending the operation of each or- gan. These organs, it need scarcely be observed, are not themselves the percipient agents ; but the mere unintelligent instrumentality, through which, by divine appointment, the soul acts. The invert- ed image of any object within the sphere of vision, is made on the retina of an ox's eye, after it has been taken from the head of the slaughtered ani- mal ; but, of course, the eye has no vision. The eyes of animals are mere instruments, like the tel- escope of the astronomer. Although it is indispen- sable to the perception of those celestial bodies, which are beyond the reach of the naked eye, yet no one could for a moment imagine that the tele- scope itself had a perception of these objects. Phil- osophically speaking, it is, therefore, not the eye which sees, but the soul. We might divide the results of the soul's action through bodily organs, into those produced through the medium of every part of the surface of the body, such as shape ; and, secondly, those for which only particular parts of the body, such as the eye, the ear, the nose, serve as organs, viz., colour, odour, sound, &c. I have knowledge of the sun by my eye, of music by my ear, of the flavour of an orange by my palate, of the odour of a flower by my olfactory organs, of the solidity of a ball by my hand, or some other part of my body which touches it. And, in each instance, this knowledge is more or less pleasant or unpleasant, or, in other words, is accompanied by some degree of feeling, which is in a greater or less degree either pleasing or the reverse. ORGANIC PROCESS. 107 In all cases, the influence of entities is exerted by the actual contact of the organ ; nor does auy u operatio in distans," so far as we know, take place. Thus, in taste, the palate and tongue are touched by the article tasted ; in hearing, the tym- panum of the ear is struck by the vibrations of the atmosphere ; in smelling, the olfactory nerves are touched by the particles emanating from the odorif- erous body ; as is proved by the fact, that the most fragrant rose or shrub, if placed under a glass cyl- inder, cannot be smelled. In vision, the eyes are touched by the rays of light, proceeding from the object which is seen, either by reflection, or refrac- tion, or repulsion, as the case may be. We are, therefore, under no necessity of having recourse to the exploded theory of animal spirits, or nervous fluid, or of intervening cerebral vibrations, in order to form a connexion between the mind and the ob- ject of its perception. And, in all these cases, the nerves of sensation and of motion, which are im- bodied in the organ of sense, or constitute a part of it, are connected with the brain, of which they are all branches, and which is the ultimate and principal physical organ, through which the mind acts and is acted upon, in its connexion with the material world. Whether the brain is one general organ, or, as phrenologists contend, consists of a collection of individual organs 2 each corresponding to a separate faculty of the mind, lias been much disputed. But from the harmony of universal sci- ence in all its ramifications, we may confidently predict, that the results of Phrenology, when brought 108 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. to a satisfactory degree of certainty, will not con- flict with the true system of Psychology. The mental results, both cognitive and sentient, of our sensorial action through these organs, are, in general, termed, in popular language, Sensations. Thus, we speak of the sensations of sight, of smell, of touch, of taste, &c, meaning principally those cognitions which we derive through these organs, and which are more specifically termed perceptions. This vague use of the term we derive from the Ro- mans, who employ in the same general manner both sentio and sensus, from which our word sensation is ultimately derived. Yet, as this term is, in com- mon language, more generally used as expressive of feeling's, and as the related terms, sensibility, sensitive, and sentient, are employed exclusively with a similar reference, a laudable desire of rigid precision, and consistency in metaphysical phraseol- ogy, would dictate the constant discrimination be- tween those results of our organic action which are cognitive and those that are sentient, and the em- ployment of the term perceptions, rather than sensa- tions, to designate the former. The eye, or organ of vision, is an instrument con- structed with the most perfect accuracy, in accord- ance with the ascertained principles of optics. The most perfect optical instruments fall far short of it in accuracy and excellence. Indeed, a more stri- king and intelligible exhibition of the knowledge and wisdom of the Creator, cannot be imagined. The ball of the eye itself is a species of camera obscura. Its exterior consists of two membraneous ORGANIC PROCESS. 109 coverings, the outer one called sclerotica {gkXtjpotl- it7]g, hard), on account of its superior firmness, and the inner, choroid {xopoeidTjg, like a skin), from its cuticular appearance. Within this inner coat, and expanded over its surface, is the optic nerve, which receives the rays of light, and on which they form an image of the external object, which reflects them to the eye. In the front part of the eye, which is exposed to view, is the cornea, so called because, when dried, it has nearly the consistence of very fine horn. It is transparent, and projects from the eyeball, like the segment of a smaller sphere. Back of the centre of the cornea, is a small opening in the choroid, termed the pupil, through which the rays of light enter. And in the rear of this, are the aqueous humour, then the crystalline lens of a dense texture, both nearly of the same size with the cornea, and, lastly, the vitreous or glassy humour, which fills the remaining cavity of the eye. These several pellucid humours collect the rays of light into a focus on the retina. The eye affords us the knowledge of colour, local direction, and expansion. When I open my eyes, I behold the different objects within the range of my vision, and instantly derive not only the idea of colour, but also of direction or location in space, of every one of them, as I successively direct my at- tention to each. And, by the improvement result- ing from practice, I also become able to judge of the shape and distance of objects through the in- strumentality of the eye. All objects of vision oc- cupy relative positions in space, and a perception K 110 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. of this position is one of the primary and original items of knowledge derived through the visual or- gan. By touch and locomotion, we may obtain similar knowledge, even if divested of sight. Yet the process is more tardy, and can be applied only to such objects as we can personally reach. Vision is performed through the medium of light, or, more properly speaking, light is the object of vision. It consists of rays of different colours and of different degrees of refrangibility. When we permit a portion of light to pass through a prism, its different colours are separated, in consequence of the shape of that instrument, by which the rays are refracted in different degrees out of a right line. We thus perceive the regular series of colours from red to violet. The superficial texture of all visible objects may be reduced to precisely as many varieties as are found in colour. Each of the textures reflects, or, according to a different theory, repels the light, in a manner somewhat different from every other, and reflects or repels a surface of rays equal to its own bulk. These rays light upon the lens of the eye, and are converged with the peculiarity of every dif- ferent texture to the retina ; and thus, by divine con- stitution, we have the knowledge of different colours. So that the rays of light, coming from the objects in different degrees of spissitude, and in the partic- ular state of reflection or repulsion corresponding to the particular texture of the objects, are as much, and in the same sense, the cause of our knowledge of colour, as the particles emitted by the rose and ORGANIC PROCESS. Ill touching our nostrils, are of smell, or the peach touching the palate and tongue, is of taste. In vision we see nothing, originally, but colour and location, or direction and extension. Distance is not the direct object of vision, because children will stretch out their little hands to catch the moon, until experience teaches them the futility of the at- tempt ; and a person cured of congenital blindness, by an operation for the cataract, will for some time hold out his hand and feel his way, lest he strike against the stove or table at the other end of the room. That we do form some original judgment of extension and peripheral shape by the eye, seems very clear. For, it can be demonstrated that the images formed on the retina, vary and correspond to the different outline and extension of the objects which they represent. Now, as the mind has a cor- respondent and different idea for every cognoscible diversity of objects, it must have one for this also. It is doubtless true, as Mr. Locke and others have maintained, that a blind man, who had learned by touch the difference of shape between a cube and a sphere, could not, on being restored to sight, dis- cover by his eye, which was cubical? and which was spherical. But this fact does not, we think, prove that we obtain no idea of extension and shape by the eye. It only establishes the position, that the man suddenly restored to sight/ could not at once decide which of the two different outlines of which he had an idea by sight, corresponds to the one, to his ideas of which, as obtained by touch, he had given the name either of cube or sphere. Both 112 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. sight and touch give us distinct and definite ideas of the peripheral shape of objects, but we cannot tell which one of the properties learned by one sense, corresponds to a given property learned by the other sense, until we have ascertained the fact by the conjoined action of both. It must also be remembered that the association between words and our ideas of objects is arbitrary, and is formed only by practice or usage. The blind man has long been accustomed to associate the ideas of touch, which he acquires from those objects, with the words cube and sphere ; but when his first vision also gives him the ideas of these objects appropriate to sight, there is no association existing between these ideas and the words cube and sphere. If, therefore, he be asked, which of the two is the figure which he had been accustomed to call either cube or sphere, he could not tell. He could only reply that they ap- pear evidently different ; but the association of these new ideas with sounds or names is yet to be formed. As yet, neither of these names will recall or desig- nate his newly-acquired ideas, and he can no more tell which is the cube, and which the sphere, than if you were to ask him in Greek, which is the avpog and which the ofyaipa. He has not yet learned the correspondence of the ideas themselves, much less of the terms which usage has employed to designate them. That the eye does not originally give us any knowledge of shape, excepting the mere outline, or extension, is evident; because a well-executed painting will deceive even an adult ; and all effort ORGANIC PROCESS. 113 to represent the shape of objects in portraits or other paintings, is based upon this fact, and demonstrative of it. Many of our readers may recollect, that on entering Peale's Museum in Philadelphia, at one end of the long hall, they saw at the other a flight of stairs, and an aged gentleman just in the act of as- cending, but, as if attracted by the noise of their entrance, looking back at them, full in the face. On nearer approach, however, the deception was dis- covered, and the whole proved to be a most suc- cessful effort of the artist's pencil, a lasting monu- ment of the high eminence attained by Mr. Peale, in his favourite pursuit. In short, the entity which is the object of our knowledge in vision, is not the external person or thing said to be seen, but is merely the rays of light. No man has ever literally seen his nearest friend, his father or mother-) his brother or sister. He has seen the light reflected from them on the retina of his eye, and nothing more. What we see is nothing else than those rays of light which actually enter into the pupil of the eye ; and it is experience which teaches us, that there are external objects corresponding to them, from which they proceed. It is the different tex- tures or affinities, corresponding to these different colours seen by us, of which we thus acquire a knowledge. For the idea of apparent and relative, but not of actual size, we are also indebted to the eye. The image formed on the retina is large or small ac- cording to the magnitude and distance of the ob- jects. Thus the apparent magnitude of objects va- K2 114 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. ries, but their real size is of course unchanged. When we first perceive a vessel at sea in the distant horizon, it appears very small ; but as it approaches us, its magnitude seems to increase, until it has at- tained its natural size in proximity ; yet the actual size of the vessel was of course unchanged. Of ob- jects equidistant from the eye, vision will give us a correct idea of the relative magnitude. Thus, as we know that the balloon and the basket attached to it are nearly equidistant from us, however far or near they may be, we can form an accurate judg- ment of the relative size of each, so long as both are visible to us. After we know the distance of any objects, practice enables us to judge of their actual size, by sight. Yet this is, originally, the combined result of touch and vision. Experience teaches us to judge of the diminution which distance makes, in the apparent magnitude of objects ; and optical science explains the causes on which these appear- ances depend. We are so accustomed to see ob- jects diminish in size as they recede from us, that daily observation confers considerable accuracy on our practical judgment ; and thus, by a rapid pro- cess, we learn to judge of the actual magnitude of all objects, whose distance we know. We form an estimate of the diminution, which the known dis- tance would make in the apparent size of an ob- ject, and thus judge of its actual magnitude. The idea, which the mind acquires of the images formed on the retina by different objects, does of course not resemble that image in any known property ; yet, for each image, the mind obtains a definite idea, ORGANIC PROCESS. 115 both as to colour, peripheral shape or outline, and size. It is on this principle, that in the science of perspective, we indicate on canvass the increased distance of a known object, by a diminution of its size. And, when we view an object through a spy- glass, and judge it to be brought nearer to us, this effect is produced in accordance with the same principles, the only change being that the lenses of the instrument make the rays of light fall on the retina in a more dilated or expanded form, thus ac- tually making on it a larger image. When objects are near at hand, or in the vicinity of others of whose distance we have some idea, we can form a judgment from the degree of incli- nation on the axis of vision and the angles formed with surrounding objects. For this purpose, the Creator has kindly given us two eyes, while for all other purposes one would suffice, as the action of each is separate and independent. The degree of distinctness with which objects are seen by us also leads us to form some judg- ment of their distance ; as we know that near ob- jects always appear more clearly visible than those afar off. For this cause, objects seen through a mist are judged to be more distant than they really are. The standard by which we judge is the degree of clearness in an ordinary atmosphere, and then our judgment is correct ; but when we apply the same standard to the appearance of objects seen through a mist, it is calculated to mislead us. When a strange object is in the vicinity of an- other of known size, we can judge of the size of 116 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. the former by its apparent relative size, even when the distance of both is unknown. On this princi- ple, painters show the size of a house by locating a man, or horse, or fence in its vicinity. As the size of these latter objects varies but little, it forms a standard by which to judge the magnitude of the others. It is an interesting fact, that objects appear to us in their natural position, while it can be proved that their image formed on the retina is inverted. Nor has any solution been given of this phenom- enon, other than that it is the appointed law of the mind. And of similar inexplicable nature is the fact, that though we see objects with two eyes, they appear to a person of sound organs as single ; while to persons who are affected with a disease in one eye, which prevents it from being acted on precisely like the other, objects are seen double, that is, images somewhat different are made on the retina of the two eyes, and ideas somewhat differ- ent are thus excited in the mind by the same object. In addition to the perceptions obtained through vision, the eye is also, at the same time, one of the media through which pleasing feelings are excited in the mind by external objects. It is through this or- gan that the pleasant feelings excited by the beauties of a landscape, that is, by the varieties and combi- nations of its colours, are produced in the mind. In short, this is the organ through which a benev- olent God designed to confer, and actually does bestow upon us, a large portion of the incidental happiness belonging to our pilgrimage on earth. Even the light of the returning day is calculated it- ORGANIC PROCESS. 117 self to inspire the mind with pleasure ; and whith- ersoever we direct our steps, objects meet the eye calculated to afford us delight. The vegetable kingdom presents to us the flowers of the field and garden, in their numberless varieties and shades of colour transcending the array of Solomon in all his glory : the grain fields, waving like the ocean be- fore the passing breeze ; and the trees of the- forest bending majestically before the still more powerful storm, are all calculated to excite feelings of the most interesting and pleasing nature. The mineral and animal kingdoms, in like manner, abound in objects calculated to delight the observer. Yea, so susceptible are we of pleasure from this source, that there is need of caution, lest we take so much delight in the creature as to overlook the Creator, by whom all these objects were made, and to whom they are all designed to conduct us. Who among my readers has not seen some naturalist to whom the words of nature's favourite, Pollok, would apply ? " One made acquaintanceship with plants and flowers, And happy grew in telling all their names ; One classed the quadrupeds ; a third the fowls ; Another found in minerals his joy : And I have seen a man, a worthy man, In happy mood conversing with a fly ; And as he, through his glass, made by himself, Beheld its wondrous eye and plumage fine, From leaping scarce he kept, for perfect joy." But in regard to vision, and to perception through any of the senses, the attention of the mind is ne- cessary to the perfection of the process. The rays of light may be reflected from an object to the eye, 118 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. and form an image on the retina ; but we have no recollection of a perception, unless our attention be directed to the object. The rays of light are at all times as fully reflected to the eye from all other ob- jects within the entire field of vision before us, as from that one to which our attention is at any given time directed ; and yet we recollect only the one which has attracted our attention. In short, there are hundreds of images formed on the retina at all times ; but it is a law of the soul that, although we have an indefinite simultaneous vision of several ob- jects before us, we take cognizance only of one at a time ; and of our perceptions of that one alone do we retain any recollection. As to the question which has so much puzzled philosophers of all ages and nations, how this per- ception is effected through the organs ; what, for example^ is the connexion between the image on the retina and the perception of the soul ; our re- ply is, that it is the constituted order of things, as appointed by God, and inexplicable to us. The image on the retina is as indispensable a link in the chain of instrumentality as the presence of light, and its passage through the lens of the eye ; but we can no more comprehend the connexion of the intelligent percipient action of the soul with the last link of instrumental organism, than with the first. In this, as in a thousand other instances, the facts are known and understood, but the mode of their occurrence, or the causal relation between them, is beyond our comprehension. The ear, or organ of hearing, is likewise a com- ORGANIC PROCESS. 119 plicated and very delicate member, whose structure is not as easily illustrated as that of the eye. Like the latter organ, it is placed in an elevated part of the body, so as to have a more extended sphere of sensorial action. The external ear is expanded, so as to receive a large surface of vibrations of the air, which it conveys to the point of entrance. Thence a tube, termed the auditory passage (meatus audi- torius), conducts the vibrations to the tympanum or drum, which is an expanded nerve analogous to the retina of the eye. From the tympanum, these vibrations are communicated, by the means of four little bones, to the water contained in the cavities of the labyrinth. By means of this water, they are conveyed to the auditory nerve, and finally to the brain. In order that the drum of the ear may act more freely, there is a communication, termed the Eustachian tube, extending from the drum to the back part of the mouth, freely admitting the air. Still, hearing may take place, though less perfectly, when the drum has been perforated, as is proved in the case of those persons who can, by taking smoke into their mouth, express it through one or both their ears, and yet are not deaf. In some cases, also, where suppuration had destroyed the continuity of the chain of little bones, the sense of hearing was not destroyed. The principal medium for the con- veyance of these vibrations is the air ; yet any other body possessing some elasticity, whether it be solid, liquid, or aeriform, which forms a connexion between the sounding body and the ear, may become the medium of sound. Thus our American Indians 120 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. apply their ears to the ground, to discover the ap- proach of their enemies, whom they could not yet hear through the air. Yet, in a vacuum, sound cannot be communicated, that is, these vibrations cannot be propagated to the ear except by some intervening body. The susceptibility of the audi- tory organs is different in different persons, but no one can hear the vibrations of a cord which vibrates less than about thirty-two times in a second. The whole range of distinguishable sounds forms upward of nine octaves. Sound is therefore an idea of the mind, caused by the vibrations of some stricken object, which vibrations are communicated through the air, or some other elastic medium, to the ear. When we hear the discharge of a distant cannon, the noise is not at the cannon, but in our minds. The discharge of the cannon causes a tremendous agitation in the atmosphere around it, which is extended, like the undulations of a pond when a stone is thrown into it, until they reach the ears of all animals within their circumference, and produce in every one of them the idea of sound. The number of sounds which we can distinguish is very great, both as to variety of tone and strength of utterance, amounting to many thousands. The mind also perceives a number of relations between sounds, and it is the discussion of these sounds and their relations, as well as the calculation of the caus- es, nature, and number of the vibrations, by which they are produced, which constitute the theoretical science of music. These vibrations are actions of ORGANIC PROCESS. 121 sounding bodies or entities, and our perceptions of them, and of the relations between them, are cogni- tive ideas. The relations of concord and discord are the coincidence or confusion of the vibrations of the sounding instrument. Thus, those different strings of a piano, which, owing to their length, thickness, weight, and tension, vibrate in the same time, are said to be in unison. If one string vibrates in exactly double the time of another, every alter- nate vibration of the one will coincide with the vibrations of the other, and form the concord of an octave. The ear is the medium not only of our knowl- edge of the vibrations of the atmosphere called sound, but also of the feeling of pleasure or pain, which the different combinations of these sounds, either harmonious or discordant, are intrinsically calculated to produce. When we listen to a piece of music, we find no difficulty in distinguishing be- tween the different notes, that is, the different vi- brations of the air, of which we obtain a knowledge through the ear, and the pleasant or unpleasant feelings excited by these vibrations or notes. Nor can we for a moment hesitate in believing, that the difference in the feelings excited by the harmonious or discordant combinations of sound, arises from a difference in the notes themselves, considered as simple entities, or from the relation of concord or discord subsisting between them. These notes, or rather the ideas of them, are the subjects of mathe- matical calculations in the science of music. But who ever heard of a writer on this subject, speak- L 122 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. ing of a chord or discord of feeling, that is, a chord of pleasure or a discord of pain ? Or who ever heard a musician speak of an octave of pleasure or pain ? Common sense, and the structure of the mind, have led men to distinguish between these things, and to acknowledge our perception of each note individually, and of the relations existing be- tween them, as entirely different from the feelings, pleasant or unpleasant, excited by them. Although the ear originally affords us only ideas of sound, yet, by practice, we learn to judge of many other things by this organ. There is but little doubt, that an impression somewhat different is made on the tympanum, not only by the different degrees of force with which the undulating atmosphere touches it, but also by the fact of its striking that organ in a direct or oblique manner. Of this difference we have a distinct idea by the ear alone ; yet, by that exclusively, we could never know that the difference in the loudness of the sound resulted either from the degree of force with which the atmosphere is agi- tated by the sonorous body, or from its proximity or distance from our ear : nor that the difference in our idea, produced by the directness or obliquity with which the undulations of air strike the ear, was indicative of the local direction of the sounding body whence they proceeded. It is by the com- bined use of sight, touch, and locomotion, that the distance and direction of the sonorous body are originally learned, and practice then enables us to judge of these circumstances by the ear alone. Yea, we even go farther, and apply these results to ORGAxNIC PROCESS. 123 objects which could not be reached by touch. It is thus that, having learned the velocity of sound, we judge of the distance of clouds, by the length of time intervening between the flash of lightning in them and our hearing the thunder. An interval of half a minute, we know, proves the cloud to be about six and a half miles distant. Children hear persons addressing them, and at the same time see whether they are in front, at their side, or in their rear ; and thus early learn to associate the peculiar sounds produced by persons speaking from different directions, with that direction itself. What this peculiarity about any sound is, it is not easy to de- scribe ; yet every person is familiar with it from experience. Nay, so obviously do we thus judge of direction by the ear, that if the vibrations pro- ceeding from a sounding body fall on some smooth and solid surface, and are reflected to our ear, thus causing what is termed an echo, we judge the cause of that echo to be in the direction not of the original sounding body, but of that smooth and solid sur- face which reflected them. In the same indirect manner, the loudness of a sound becomes an index of the distance of the object whence it proceeds. By the combined use of different organs, we become familiar with the ordinary loudness of any customary sound at a given distance, and also learn to distin- guish and recognise these different sounds, such as those produced by different musical instruments, by the voice of man, and other animals, &c. ; and these data being known by experience, we can form a judgment by the ear alone, of the distance of the 124 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. sounding body. By these results of experience, a kind of practical commutation of the senses takes place, and in the daily occurrences of life, though many objects are within the reach of only one or- gan, we at once acquire an amount of knowledge of them, which originally belongs to several. In the first volume of the Manchester Philosophical Memoirs is contained the following statement con- cerning a blind man in that city, quoted by Profes- sor Upham : "I had an opportunity of repeatedly observing the peculiar manner in which he arranged his ideas, and obtained his information. Whenever he was introduced into company, I remarked that he continued some time silent. The sound directed him to judge of the dimensions of the room, and the different voices, of the number of persons that were present. His distinction in these respects was very accurate, and his memory so retentive, that he was seldom mistaken. I have known him instantly to recognise a person on first hearing him, though more than two years had elapsed since the time of their last meeting. He determined pretty nearly the stature of those he was conversing with by the direction of their voices ; and he made tolerable conjectures respecting their tempers and dispositions by the manner in which they conducted their con- versation." The organ of touch is the whole body, wherever nerves extend, either over its surface, or through its interior. It has been a subject of dispute, wheth- er the nerves of the hand have naturally greater acuteness of sensibility than those of the other parts ORGANIC PROCESS. 125 of the body. As the acuteness or strength of all our local organs is confessedly much increased by practice, and, as in the case of this general organ, those parts of it which are found to be most acute, are also those which, from their position, are most used, it is highly probable that the difference be- tween the sensitiveness of the hand and the other parts of the body, as organs of touch, may also be attributed to that cause. From early life our hands are almost incessantly employed to pick up, to hold, or to move objects, and, in short, to per- form all the operations of physical agency, of which that important organ is capable. And as the atten- tion of the mind is ordinarily directed to these man- ual operations, we have the greater reason to ex- pect great improvement in the mental results ac- companying them. It is probably to this want of attention that other portions of the body which are often brought into contact with various objects do not improve proportionably in sensibility ; or, to speak more correctly, that the mind does not im- prove more in sensibility through them. Whether the organ of touch should be separated from that of muscular effort, has been disputed. Perhaps they may, with more propriety, be regard- ed as one organ exerted in different degrees. The slightest possible contact, although it could not af- ford us the same amount of knowledge which we derive from stronger contact, and from the muscular tension caused by firm resistance, yet does seem to include in it the elementary idea of resistance in a small degree, and, therefore, also of muscular action. L2 126 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. By the organ of touch we obtain a knowledge of the different degrees of solidity or fluidity of bodies, their shape, extension, smoothness or rough- ness, heat or cold. The ideas embraced in this knowledge may probably be reduced to modifica- tions of resistance and extension. We know that the ideas popularly expressed by these terms, as well as the feelings accompanying them, are deri- ved through the organ of touch; and we know, too, that in obtaining them our organ meets with re- sistance perfect or imperfect, continuous or irregu- lar. By the organ of touch combined with motion, we also acquire an idea of extension and shape ; but individual touch does not afford us a general idea of the object causing it. The terms heat and cold properly designate our perception or cognitive idea of a greater or less degree of caloric in the atmo- sphere, or any other body with which we come into contact. Cold is a negative term, implying the absence of heat. In winter we perceive but little caloric in the atmosphere, and term the weather cold. In summer, when the reverse is the case, we term it warm. What caloric is we do not ex- actly know ; but we employ the term to express the perception we have of it. Nor are we to sup- pose in this, more than in any other case, that ei- ther the perception of caloric, or the feeling at- tendant on it, has any resemblance to the caloric itself. This perception, however, does not teach us the nature of the radiating body, independently of the other organs of sense. It is a philosophic question, belonging to Pyronomics, rather than ORGANIC PROCESS. 127 Mental Philosophy, to determine the precise nature of caloric itself. But whether we suppose it to be an independent subtile fluid, or a mere modifica- tion of other bodies, all have the same perception of its influence on the human body, and of the feel- ings caused by it. The terms heat and cold, as expressing the sensation produced by this agent on our frame, are merely relative, the one being produced by our touching a body that has more caloric, and the other one that has less than our hand at the time possesses ; and if, after having immersed one hand in hot water and the other in cold, we put them both into water of a medium temperature, to the one hand this water will feel warm and to the other cold at the same time. In some cases of touch the contact may be so vi- olent that the organ becomes injured, and that the feeling of pain is so great as to make us lose sight of the perception connected with it. The feeling of exhaustion and fatigue, conse- quent on continued or violent exertion, seems not to belong to the sense of touch, but rather resembles the periodical appetites, and is a provision of the Creator to admonish us of the necessity of rest. It has been denied by some recent metaphysi- cians that the idea of externity is a result of touch, and, consequently, affirmed that our idea of the real existence of the external world is not derived from this or any other organ of sense. This view we consider erroneous. Yet those who maintain it, admit that the idea of externity and of an exter- nal world occurs on occasion of the use of these or- 128 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. gans, especially that of touch ; but affirm that it then occurs by a separate law of the soul. We see no reason for the admission of such a separate law in this case, any more than in that of the ideas ob- tained by the other senses, and prefer regarding it as the appropriate information obtained by this or- gan. Neither of the other senses could afford us the idea of externity. By the ear alone we could obtain only ideas of sound ; by the eye, only of col- our, expansion, and direction ; by the nostrils, only ideas of odours ; but by neither, nor all of these combined, could we have learned the idea of ex- ternity in general, or of the existence of the exter- nal world. It is to touch and locomotion that we are primarily indebted for our knowledge of the objective reality of these objects. The sense of touch has been improved to a most surprising degree by practice, and especially by the concentration of the powers of the mind upon it, in consequence of the loss of other senses. It ap- pears to be well ascertained, that some blind per- sons have been able to judge of their distance from solid bodies by the action or pulsation of the air upon their face, to distinguish spurious coins from such as are genuine, and to distinguish and separ- ate garments and other articles with which they were familiar, from a multitude of others of similar shape and texture. We are told that " Mr. San- derson, the blind mathematician," could distinguish by his hand, in a series of Roman medals, the true from the counterfeit, with a more unerring discrim- nation than the eye of a professed virtuoso ; and, ORGANIC PROCESS. 129 when he was present at the astronomical observa- tions in the garden of his college, he was accustomed to perceive every cloud which passed over the sun. This remarkable power, which has sometimes been referred to an increased intensity of particular sen- ses, in many cases evidently resolves itself into an increased habit of attention to the indications of all those senses which the individual retains. " Two in- stances have been related to me," proceeds Dr. Ab- ercrombie, " of blind men who were much esteemed as j udges of horses. One of these, in giving his opin- ion of a horse, declared him to be blind, though this had escaped the observation of several persons, who had the use of their eyes, and who were with some difficulty convinced of it. Being asked to give an account of the principle on which he had deci- ded, he said it was by the sound of the horse's step in walking, which implied a peculiar and unusual caution in his manner of putting down his feet." Thus, also, in the various institutions for the blind in this country and Europe, the sense of touch is employed as a substitute for sight, and by the use of uncial letters, elevated above the surface of the page, these unfortunate beings are enabled to dis- tinguish the letters by following them with their fingers, and by practice to spell and read with tol- erable facility. A communication has thus been opened for therrw-to the world of intellect, and the literature of the past and present ages may eventu- ally be brought within their view. The organ of taste consists of a number of papil- lae, distributed over the surface of the tongue, and 130 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. particularly over its sides and extreme point, as well as the roof of the mouth or palate. This organ is thus wisely located by a benevolent Providence at the very entrance, through which all articles of food must pass, the healthy or unhealthy character or condition of which may by this means, in most ca- ses, be tested. It serves as a guardian over the character of everything which finds access to the alimentary canal ; and it is probable, that in its natural state, unvitiated by luxury and the artificial habits of civilized life, this organ, together with that of smell, would be an almost infallible safe- guard against unhealthy food. It is. indeed, true, that these organs alone could merely teach us to distinguish the various odours and flavours of differ- ent objects, and to discriminate between the pleas- ant and the unpleasant feelings excited by them. But experience teaches us that articles of certain odours and flavours are healthy, while others are the reverse; and thus these flavours and odours be- come indices of the healthiness or noxiousness of edible objects. The pleasantness or unpleasant- ness of different flavours and odours is somewhat arbitrary and variable. What is pleasant to one man is often unpalatable to another ; and a flavour, which at first was unpleasant, may become agreea- ble by use. Yet, Providence has wisely ordered that the staple articles of food, bread and meal, and also the natural beverage which springs from the mountain rock, and is everywhere met with by digging into the earth, are pleasant to all mankind. It is, indeed, true, that if, with our eyes closed, we introduce a peach or apricot into the mouth, ORGANIC PROCESS. 131 we obtain not only the idea of the flavour which those species of fruit are calculated to excite, but also some knowledge of their solidity and shape. By flavour is meant that adjective entity (property) in the fruit itself, which is the subject of our knowl- edge, and the excitant of feeling pleasant or un- pleasant. The word taste is used to designate our knowledge of the flavour, and the words pleasant and unpleasant express the feeling- excited by it. Thus also the word odour means the adjective en- tity (property) in objects, of which the term smell expresses our knowledge, and the words pleasant and unpleasant the feelings excited by the odour. But the knowledge of solidity and shape is, in the above-named instances also, obtained by touch, and the only thing of which the organ of taste is the medium is, 1. A knowledge of the flavour of the fruit ; and, 2. A feeling, pleasant or unpleasant, con- nected with it. Oftentimes several of the bodily or- gans are acted upon simultaneously. Thus in eat- ing a peach the several senses of smell, touch, and taste may be affected at the same moment, and each organ be the medium of the appropriate feeling and knowledge, which the entity peach is capable of producing. The flavours of different esculent enti- ties are almost as various as the entities themselves ; but it has not been found necessary in human lan- guage to distinguish many of them in any other way than by the name of the object itself. Thus, we speak of the taste of an orange, of a tomato, of an onion, of a peach, without having any other term to designate each. 132 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. Of Smell, The organ of this sense consists of numerous and minute ramifications of nerves, dis- tributed over the interior surface of the nostrils, and the sinuses connected with them. The bony bridge of the nose, and the cartilaginous projection beyond it, serve as a protection to these delicate organs, and their location in the immediate vicinity of the mouth, through which all that is eaten must pass, affords peculiar facility for the exercise of their power in the choice of our food. The odours of different objects are almost num- berless in kind and degree. Indeed, almost every entity, that has any perceptible odour, has one in some respect different from all others. But, except- ing a few general terms, such as fragrant, putrid, musty, &c, they are all designated by the name of the object by which they are emitted, and their precise nature learned by experience. Thus, we speak of the odour of a shrub, of a rose, &c. Some odours are perceptible both to taste and smell. Those who have visited regions abounding in bilious miasma, well know that, on entering the infected region, the miasma may sometimes be tasted on the tongue, as well as smelled by the ol- factories. The odour itself appears to consist of innumerable small particles, emitted in every direc- tion from the object to which it belongs, and borne upon the surrounding atmosphere. When this at- mosphere is inspired through the nostrils, the olfac- tories, wisely located by Providence, are touched by the odorous particles, and thus the smell is ob- tained. That such minute particles are emitted by SENSE OF SMELL. 133 the odorous body, is demonstrated by the fact, that if the most fragrant flower be placed under a glass receiver, no odour will be perceived by those around it, however near they may be to the glass, which is therefore impervious to these particles. Although these particles cannot penetrate glass, and are therefore not so small as light, they are in- conceivably minute ; for a grain of musk will fill, the surrounding atmosphere for years with a pungent odour, without itself experiencing the least sensible diminution of weight. This sense gives us no knowledge of the colour or shape of the entity to which the odour belongs, but only of the odour itself. In odours of a fa- miliar kind, Ave instantly recognise the entity by which it is excited. But this Ave do by a recollec- tion of the fact, that whenever Ave saw or felt a shrub or rose near us, Ave perceived the same odour ; and hence Ave discover the relation of anal- ogy between the cases, and believe that the same entity is again the exciting cause of the odour. It is thus, that Ave can, by taste and smell, infer the entities by which they are excited, because almost every entity Avhich can act on these two organs, excites a different idea or mental representative. That the organ of taste is the medium of knoAvl- edge, as Avell as feeling, is evident, 1. Because our ideas of the flavours of different objects, are almost as numerous as the objects themselves ; AA r hile the feelings excited by them are simply tAvo, pleasant or unpleasant. There are some odours concerning which, though totally dis- M 134 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. tinct from all others, and easily distinguished from them, as they have something very peculiar and striking in them, we may scarcely be able to deter- mine, whether they are pleasant or unpleasant. But this does not arise from the fact of their having but little flavour ; on the contrary, their flavour may be very strong. 2. While all men agree in the knowledge, con- veyed by the terms sweet or acid flavour, they very often differ entirely as to the question, whether a particular flavour, such as that of the tomato, is pleasant or unpleasant. Yea, the very same arti- cles of food will at one time be pleasant, and at another unpleasant to the same person ; and yet, to that same person the flavours of these and other en- tities, will appear as distinct from each other as they ever did. In short, we perceive, that all these sev- eral organs are the vehicles both of knowledge and feeling to the mind. The acuteness of our perceptions by any one or- gan, is. not only augmented in a surprising degree by continued practice and the force of habit thus formed ; but is also greatly enhanced by the loss of one or several other senses. Indeed, when one organ is destroyed, the improvement of the residue often amounts to a virtual compensation for its loss. So acute does the sense of touch become in the blind, that some of them have been able to distin- guish colours by it. And the sense of smell has been so wonderfully improved, that James Mitchell could distinguish by it the presence and location of a stranger in a room, and Dr. Moyse the black dress of his friends. ACQUIRED PERCEPTIONS. 135 The different professional pursuits of men, as they give direction to the action of the individual during a large portion of his life, naturally lead to a corre- spondent improvement of particular organs. Thus, says Dr. Reid, " Not only men, but children, idiots, and brutes, acquire by habit many perceptions which they had not originally. Almost every employ- ment in life hath perceptions of this kind, that are peculiar to it. The shepherd knows every sheep of his flock, as we do our acquaintance, and can pick them out of another flock one by one. The butcher knows by sight the weight and quality of his beeves and sheep before they are killed. The farmer perceives by his eye very nearly the quanti- ty of hay in a rick, or of corn in a heap. The sailor sees the burden, the build, and the distance of a ship at sea, while she is a great way off. Every man accustomed to writing distinguishes acquaintance by their handwriting, as he does by their faces. And the painter distinguishes in the works of his art, the style of all the great masters. In a word, acquired perception is very different in different persons, according to the diversity of objects about which they are employed, and the application they bestow in observing them."* In concluding this part of our subject we may yet remark, that although the body of man exerts so im- portant a part in his perception of external objects, that any material derangement of the bodily organ often impedes, and sometimes entirely precludes the specific action of mind, to the perfection of which * Vol. i., p. 286. 136 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. it is constitutionally necessary ; these two parts of our being are nevertheless separate and distinct. That a degree of mind, even remotely approxima- ting to that of man, is not necessary to the health or perfection of the mere animal economy, is dem- onstrated in the case of irrational beings. That mind can exist and prosper separate from body is also evident from the decided testimony of revela- tion concerning disimbodied spirits. Hence, it is by no means a necessary inference, that because body and mind co-operate in man, to qualify him for the purposes of his existence on earth, there- fore they are amalgamated into one substance, or have undergone a reciprocal transfusion of prop- erties ; or are of such a nature, that the dissolution of the one, implies the death of the other. This fact is fully confirmed by the phenomenal appear- ances of every day's experience. The properties of the mind and those of the body, remain as perfectly and evidently distinct and different, in the most in- tricate and involved operation of which man is capa- ble by their joint action, as they are in those of the simplest character. Often also we find the mind exhibiting its greatest vigour, after the body has been mutilated in every possible manner, yea, even after the greater part of the brain itself has been de- stroyed. On the other hand, the body is often found to vegetate best, after almost the last ray of intellect has been extinguished by misfortune or disease. Now a single case of this kind demonstrates, that mind and body cannot, as the materialist affirms, be one and the same substance : while all contrary CONNEXION OF MIND AND BODY. 137 cases only establish the fact of a strong sympathy between them in their present connexion. As to the questions, how the soul, which is a spir- it, can act upon the body, and also how the condi- tion of our bodily organs can affect (as we know it does) the operations of the mind, it is not probable that a satisfactory solution of them will be furnish- ed in this life. For, whatever progress we may make in ascertaining the minor ramifications of our bodily organism in the brain, there is just as great, as total a difference between the finest perceptible branch of nerve and the mind, as between the mind and the foot or hand. Nor has the finest nerve one single property in common with mind, any more than has the hand or foot. The most philosophic view of the subject, Ave think, is the following: As the fact of the reciprocal influence of mind and body on each other in this life is taught us by the testimony of our senses and of consciousness, we should admit it. As God is the author as well of our mind and body, as of their connexion with each other, we should refer their reciprocal influence on each other to his will. It is the Divine will that mind and body should, in this world at least, con- stitute one being, man. And He who formed them thus, established just such a connexion between them as was necessary to His purpose, as was ne- cessary to make them act in unison, to make the material organ obey the mental impulse, and to sub- ject that mental agent to sundry influences from the material organs. If, then, it be asked why, when I resolve to raise my hand, do the muscles of the M 2 138 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. arm obey the volition of my mind, the only philo- sophic, that is, reasonable and true, answer is, be- cause God has so appointed, has so formed me. The several theories of former days to account for the co-operation of soul and body, now find few advocates. Some writers of the seventeenth centu- ry contended that the soul and body have no im- mediate connexion, nor immediate control or in- fluence over each other, but that God, when he be- holds certain changes in the one, causes the corre- spondent changes to take place in the other by an immediate exertion of his power. But this hypoth- esis denies the reality of the reciprocal influence of soul and body on each other, instead of explaining it ; and, moreover, by making God the immediate author of all human actions, necessarily represents him as the author of sin. It was termed " Occa- sionalism," because it represents God as causing human actions from time to time, as occasion re- quired. Its author, as Dr. Krug informs us, was Arnold Geidinx, professor of Philosophy at Leyden, who died about 1664, or, according to another ac- count, 1669 ; and Des Cartes embraced a modifica- tion of it. Equally untenable, though for a season far more popular, was the theory of Leibnitz, termed the " pre-established harmony" (harmonia prasstabilita). According to this system, soul and body were from eternity designed by the Creator for a series of per- fectly harmonious changes, or actions, or phenom- ena. These changes or phenomena, both of the soul and body, are evolved separately in each, by THEORY OF LEIBNITZ. 139 virtue of an inherent necessity, without any con- nexion with the other ; and these phenomena of the soul and the body do coincide or harmonize with each other in this life, so as to lead to the opinion of there being a reciprocal influence be- tween them, not because they actually exert such a reciprocal influence on each other, but simply in consequence of the original purpose of God, that they should so coincide. To this hypothesis, Leib- nitz was led by his well-known system of monads, according to which every monad, or ultimate atom, in the universe was thus separately predetermined ; and he illustrated it by the supposition of two watches, both of which kept perfect time. They moved on together, they coincided in their indica- tions of time, yet each moved by a separate intrin- sic force, and there was no real connexion what- ever between them. It must be obvious that this theory also denies instead of explaining the recip- rocal influence of mind and body on each other, and by reducing everything to a state of predeter- mined fatality, destroys all moral agency and ac- countability in man. We may, therefore, with the greater propriety recur to our first position, and while we, on the best of evidence, admit the fact of the reciprocal influ- ence of the soul and body on each other, at the same time refer it wholly to the Divine constitution of our complex nature. Of similar and equally unsatisfactory character are the later theories, which were designed to ex- plain a part of the general connexion and influence 140 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. between soul and body, namely, those intended to explain the manner in which thought results from cerebral action, from impressions made on the bod- ily organs, and conducted by the nerves to the brain. Pes Cartes, adopting the ancient notion of ani- mal spirits circulating in the nervous fibres, con- jectured these fibres to be so many tubes pervading the body, and thought he could show how the pas- sage of these animal spirits through these tubes to and from the brain give rise to not only muscular motion, but also perception, memory, and imagin- ation. Yet, as anatomical investigations demon- strate that the nerves are not hollow, and as the very existence of these animal spirits is yet unes- tablished, this theory has naturally and justly found few advocates. Near the close of the seventeenth century, Sir Isaac Newton, who always carefully distinguished between the truths and facts which he considered as established by inductive evidence, and the mere con- jectures which he uttered as subjects of future in- vestigation for himself and others, proposed the in- quiry, " Whether there may not be an elastic medium, or ether, immensely more rare than air, which pervades all bodies, and which is the cause of gravitation ; of the refraction and reflection of the rays of light ; of the transmission of heat through spaces void of air ; and of many other phe- nomena." To these other phenomena he refers in " the 23d query subjoined to his optics, where he puts this question with regard to the impression made on THEORY OF DR. HARTLEY. 141 the nerves and brain in perception, Whether vision is effected chiefly by the vibrations of this medium, ex- cited in the bottom of the eye by the rays of light, and propagated along the solid, pellucid, and uni- form capillaments of the optic nerve ? And whether hearing is effected by the vibrations of this or some other medium, excited by the tremour of the air in the auditory nerves, and propagated along the solid, pellucid, and uniform capillaments of those nerves."* On this conjecture, Dr. Hartley, regarding the nerves as solid and elastic substances, built his fanci- ful system, by which he accounts for the transmis- sion to the brain of the impression made on the exter- nal organ, by the supposition that " such impression causes vibrations of the small, and, as one may say, infinitesimal medullary particles, first in the nerves, and then in the brain ;"f and farther, that " the vi- brations are excited, propagated, and kept up partly by the ether, that is, by a very subtile elastic fluid ; partly by the uniformity, continuity, softness, and active powers of the medullary substance of the brain, spinal marrow, and nerves." But, if it were even true that the nervous fibre, which is now known to be unelastic and incapable of tension, were susceptible of vibrations, and that there is such a substance as this ether, of which there is no evidence, and that these vibrations were continued to the brain, does all this afford us the least assist- ance in understanding how the perception or sensa- tion of the mind succeeds or is occasioned by the impression on the external organ ? Certainly not. * Dr. Reid's Works, vol. ii., p. 85, 86. t Idem, vol. ii., p. 86. 142 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. That there is some communication of influence be- tween the outward organ and the brain, through the medium of the nerves, seems to be certain, for the ligature to the nerve, or its total abscission, at once interrupts this communication, and destroys the sen- sibility of the nerve below the point of ligature or separation. But what the nature of this influence is, or how it is conveyed along the nerve, we know not. And if we did, this also would still leave us in the dark as to the mode of occurrence of the mental impression. For the brain itself, and the finest possible filament of it, is still matter, and ap- proximates no nearer the attributes of mind than does the external organ, the hand or foot. The last theory, which claims a passing notice, is that of ideas, as something intervening between the external object and the percipient mind. This view, with various modifications, has had numerous advocates both among the ancients and the moderns. The original term itself [idea, from Ideiv, to see) sig- nifies an image or form. In the Aristotelian phi- losophy, this term signified the original types or images of all created things in the Divine Mind, and also those higher conceptions of the human mind which correspond to these types. Subse- quently among the ancients, and also by some mod- erns, the word idea was used to designate certain images, or shadowy films, sometimes also termed species, forms, phantasms, and, by Mr. Hume, im- pressions, which all objects were supposed to be constantly sending forth in every direction. These images, it was believed, came in contact with the THE IDEAL SYSTEM. 143 brain through the organs of sense, and were the immediate object of perception to the mind. The particulars of this view are thus described by Male- branche :* " I suppose that every one will grant that we perceive not the objects that are without us, immediately or of themselves. We see the sun, the stars, and an infinity of objects without us ; and it is not at all likely that the soul sallies out of the body, and, as it were, takes a walk through the heavens to contemplate all those objects. She sees them not, therefore, by themselves ; and the imme- diate object of the mind, when it sees the sun, for example, is not the sun, but something which is in- timately united to the soul ; and it is that which I call an idea. So that by the word idea I under- stand nothing else here, but that which is the imme- diate object, or nearest to the mind, when we per- ceive any object. It ought to be carefully observed, that, in order to the mind's perceiving any object, it is absolutely necessary that the idea of that ob- ject be actually present to it. Of this it is not pos- sible to doubt. The things which the soul per- ceives are of two kinds. They are either in the soul or without the soul. Those that are in the soul are its own thoughts ; that is to say, all its dif- ferent modifications. The soul has no need of ideas for perceiving them. But with regard to things without the mind, we cannot perceive them but by means of ideas." How far this theory has pre- vailed in past ages is a matter of some uncertainty, in consequence of the confused and often figurative * Payne's Elements, p. 123. 144 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. manner in which writers on the subject often ex- pressed themselves. Dr. Reid supposed it to have been common till the days of Mr. Locke, and to have been received even by that illustrious writer himself. The language of Mr. Locke on this sub- ject is, doubtless, less perspicuous and discrimina- ting than it might be. Speaking of Jnis frequent use of the word idea, he says, "It serves best to stand for whatever is the object of the understand- ing when a man thinks. I have used it to express whatever is meant by phantasm, notion, species, or whatever it is, which the mind can be employed about in thinking. I presume that it will be grant- ed me that there are such ideas in men's minds; every man is conscious of them in himself, and men's words and actions will satisfy him that they are in others." The former part of this quotation, it must be confessed, looks much like the ideal system, while the latter appears to sustain Dr. Brown, Dr. Beasley,* and others, who deny it, and to imply that by idea Locke may have generally meant, not any images or phantasms extraneous to the mind, and emanating from the objects per- ceived, but the perceptions of the mind itself, which inhere in the mind, and subsequently become the subjects of reflection. This ideal system was so ful- ly exposed by Dr. Reid, that, at least since his time, it has found no advocates. Properly considered, it affords no real advantage in explaining the phenom- ena of sensation. As these images or phantasms * See an excellent article by the Rev. Dr. Beasley, late Provost of the University in Philadelphia, in the Methodist Magazine for October, 1842. THE IDEAL SYSTEM. 145 emanated from external objects, they must have been material ; and, however great their tenuity and refinement, they must have been matter still, and the transition from them to mind as difficult as that of any other matter. Nor is this theory at all ap- plicable to some of our perceptions, such as those of sound and smell ; for in what respect could these images resemble their original ? But the fallacy of this theory is most conclusively seen from the fact, that we have not the least shadow of evidence for the existence either of these phantasms, or of the impressions which they were supposed to make upon the brain. We must, therefore, revert to the view already given, that, in all our perceptions of external objects through any one of our bodily or- gans, it is the external object itself which is either directly or mediately the object of perception. And although we cannot explain the mode of communi- cation between the external object and the mind, yet the mystery attendant on this subject is not greater than that belonging to ten thousand other objects and processes around us, the truth of which is certain, while the mode of their existence or oc- currence is incomprehensible to us. N 146 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. PART II. SENTIENT IDEAS. Having completed the discussion of the first spe- cies of mental operations, to wit, the Cognitive class, we now proceed to call the reader's attention to what we have ranked as the second general class, namely, Sentient Ideas, or feelings. We stated on a former occasion, that entities bear a threefold relation to the human mind ; first, as subjects of our knowl- edge : secondly, as excitants of our feelings ; and, thirdly, as motives or materials for our action. As- suming, for the present, that entities are the ulti- mate excitants of feeling in us, we describe feeling as follows : By Feeling' is meant those sentient states of the mind mediately or immediately excited by. entities simple or composite. This influence is immediately excited, when the objective entities themselves, are at the time acting on us through the appropriate organs ; and it is excited mediate- ly, when our feelings are either retrospective or prospective. In the case of present entities, which are, at the time, the subjects of our attention, the entity itself is the excitant of our feeling. But when the entity is retrospective or prospective, our cognitive idea of it seems either to be itself the ex- citant, or, in some way, the medium or conductor CRITERIA OF THE FEELINGS. 147 through which the external entity acts. Very often feelings accompanying our knowledge of some en- tities, are so feeble and indifferent, that we can scarcely pronounce them either pleasing or pain- ful ; yet, whenever they are sufficiently increased in degree, they will be found to assume this char- acteristic. The criteria, by which feelings are distinguished, are such as these : I. They have no object beyond themselves. If we have knowledge, it is a knowledge of some- thing — of some entity. But, in feeling, we can distinguish nothing but the simple state of the mind itself, to which we attribute the name feeling. If we form a volition, that volition has for its subject some action, physical or intellectual, of which we judge ourselves capable. But in feeling, we can discover no such subjects. II. Our feelings are not so absolutely dependant for their character on entities without us, as our knowledge is. Thus acids, when tasted, afford to some persons a pleasant feeling, and to others a contrary one ; thus, also, the entity man, in the act of falling from his horse, excites a painful feeling in the breast of his friend, and, perhaps, a pleasant one in that of his inveterate and bitter enemy. III. Feelings are always preceded by a cogni- tion of the entity which mediately or immediately produces them. In the farther discussion of our sentient ideas, we invite your attention to the following three topics : I. To the classification of Feelings. 148 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. II. To entities as their ultimate excitants ; and, III. To the susceptibility of the mind for feeling ; that is, to the laws of feeling. CHAPTER I. THE CLASSIFICATION OF OUR FEELINGS. The ideas expressed by the term feelings, being simple and primitive ideas, cannot be logically de- fined, but are learned by every individual through consciousness. All feelings are in their intrinsic nature much alike, and hence great difficulty has presented itself in all attempts to classify them. They are, however, distinguished by a variety of circumstances attending them and their occurrence, and these may furnish a basis for their division. On this principle, all the feelings of which the human mind is susceptible may be divided into two classes — Individual and Relative Feeling. By individual feelings are meant those which have reference exclusively to ourselves ; such as joy, contentment, cheerfulness, hope, sorrow, grief, despair, &c. By the phrase relative feelings we would designate those which have a relation to some other sentient being, or other object ; such as love, hatred, friendship, compassion, gratitude, an- ger, envy, &c. We, therefore, present the follow- ing tabular analysis of human feelings. CO INDIVIDUAL FEELINGS. 149 !§ § .8 ° c - O 05 « Q 05 5 CD »£ .h O ■L9 "^ ^112 Oij W C ^3 v5,2 05 S o«8 i22 c "I |.| $a *f »a s| .g ! Si ■ I si ii Ii J s. J3-5* o -s^^fS 9 r rf^a-s:! U -fcJ fc£ CC '•& fl W O a> °. 1 A C3 1 73 -a S ad 03 I MT3 o ■S| c £j 8 fa <2 "3 o ;« a M ilillilii i-iii tot ift! * £ S J " e o'^^^^E- o-g g Bong's* c^-S S g-g-s«3 ^J ^1 .go) «; s -s <8 « S g o^^2 S s'SjiS'SM 5 s §1 .S-raT^©w N2 •soNnaai ivnaiAiaMi i ssy io 150 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. A division of relative feelings might also be made, into, 1. Those which refer to animate, and, 2. Those relating to inanimate objects. But this divis- ion would be based on the difference in the objects of the mental operations, rather than in the opera- tions themselves. Feelings may again be divided into the following three classes : I. Sensuous ; by which we mean those feelings obtained immediately through the bodily organs. II. Intellectual or Reflex, or those resulting from the reflex operations of the mind ; including the pleasures of taste, the feelings connected with our views of the beautiful, the sublime, the ludicrous, &c. III. Moral or Religious ; viz., those resulting from the consideration of the actions of moral agents in reference to the laws of man, and ulti- mately of God. Feeling has frequently been divided, in relation to time, into Present, Retrospective, and Prospective. This division is clear in its nature, and distinct in its lines of separation ; although we do not consid- er it so useful as the one first given, nor at all in- consistent with it. It labours, however, under the difficulty of requiring us to assign feelings of essen- tially the same kind to different classes. Thus, those feelings of approbation or disapprobation which attend the judicial act of conscience, as to the agreement or disagreement of our actions with the law of God, that is, with our duty, will belong to one class when they relate to present actions, but INDIVIDUAL FEELINGS. 151 to a different class if they refer to our past conduct. Upon the whole, we consider the first division as the most natural and the best, and therefore have adopted it. Remarks on the different branches of the above classification. CLASS I. OF INDIVIDUAL FEELINGS. I. Of Sensations. In a former part of this work, we remarked that the term sensation has been used by the major part of authors on this subject, with a degree of vague- ness which cannot fail to cause obscurity in meta- physical discussions, if not avoided. Sometimes it has been employed as synonymous with perceptions, and, at other times, to designate feelings of various kinds, but especially those which are consequent on the perceptions through our bodily organs. It must be evident to all who reflect on the criteria which distinguish cognitive ideas from such as are sentient, that two kinds of mental phenomena en- tirely distinct and different are here confounded. And as the cognates of the term sensation, namely, sensitive, sensibility, &c, are universally employed in our language to express feelings and not cogni- tions, it will, we think, be best, in mental philoso- phy, to restrict this term also in a similar way. We therefore use the word sensations to express, not cognitions, but feelings of various kinds, and espe- cially those produced through our bodily organs. When discussing the process by which we obtain ideas through the bodily senses, we proved that each 152 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. of the five senses is a source of cognitions as well as of feelings. We easily perceive the difference between the idea obtained by beholding a beautiful landscape, and the feeling of pleasure which fol- lows it. The former is cognitive, the latter is sen- tient, is feeling. But is not the idea derived from tasting an apple or orange equally distinct from the pleasant feeling attending the same process ? And are not our ideas of the successive notes in a piece of music, different from the feelings, either pleasant or painful, cheerful or melancholy, which those notes also produce ? There is, therefore, a neces- sity for both of these terms, for perceptions and sensations, in reference to the operations of each of our bodily organs ; and if the one be used to express the cognitive result of their action, and the other more generally be confined to that which is sentient, much confusion will be avoided. All these sensations are obviously individual feel- ings, because they terminate in ourselves, in the sentient subject. II. Of Emotions. The term emotion also is employed in several different significations by respectable writers. By some the words sensations, emotions, and passions are used to designate different degrees of intensity in one and the same species of mental operations. But there is certainly a fixed difference between these terms in the usage of our language. Thus, no good writer would employ the term emotion to express a higher degree of the sensation produced INDIVIDUAL FEELINGS. 153 by the organ of touch, any more than he would use the term passion to designate a still higher degree of it. Some authors by emotion designate a state of feeling intermediate between sensations and de- sires. Others define emotions to be those feelings which are consequent upon other mental operations than perceptions by the organs of sense. Yet this use of it is also not entirely correct ; because we speak of the emotions of the sublime or beautiful, and yet these emotions are immediately consequent on our perceptions, through the senses, of those objects which we regard as beautiful or sublime. And other writers employ the term emotion with almost as much latitude as feeling itself. A more correct description of emotions and appropriate use of the term, we think, would be the following. Emotions are those transient excitements of feeling which are consequent on mental operations direct or re- flective, other than perceptions through the organs of taste, smell, or touch. The very term emotion, in its primitive import, signifies a moving, a motion, an impulse ; thus indicating its transient nature. Nothing more is necessary to the intelligent inqui- rer than to reflect on the testimony of his own con- sciousness, to enable him to perceive that those feelings of the mind which he denominates emo- tions are of brief continuance, that they come and pass away again in a short time, and are then known to us only by memory. That they are different from cognitions and active operations, and that they are essentially sentient, 154 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. are a species of feelings, is also a matter which can- not be rendered intelligible by words, but must be referred to the consciousness of each individual. When I behold a messenger, whom I had despatch- ed on a journey of a hundred miles, in four or five hours again entering my room, I am filled with sur- prise at his unexpected return ; and certainly I find no difficulty in distinguishing my perception of his personal appearance, and my knowledge of the un- expected circumstances under which he appears, from the feeling or emotion which attends it. Emotions always succeed some cognition, or some active operation of the mind. Before I can expe- rience the emotion of the beautiful or sublime, I must have had a perception of the object by which the emotion is caused ; and if I feel emotions of regret or sorrow at my failure in any active process in which I was engaged, say in an attempt to finish a sermon or other piece of composition within a given time, the failure and the consciousness of it must certainly have preceded the emotion, the tem- porary regret. Emotions are sometimes motives to action, and then, of course, they precede the desires or volitions resulting from them. We do not recol- lect, however, that the word emotion is applied to the feelings, of any degree, which are consequent on our perceptions through the organs of taste, smell, and touch. Emotions may be divided into intellectual and moral. Intellectual emotions are those which ex- press and imply no reference to moral character or conduct. They are such as the emotions of sub- INDIVIDUAL FEELINGS. 155 lirnity, beauty, the ludicrous, emotions of surprise, wonder, astonishment, amazement, &c. The most important of these we will endeavour to explain in few words. It should, however, be distinctly re- membered that, in popular language, the terms em- ployed to designate these emotions, generally stand for a complex idea or state of mind, including a cognitive as well as a sentient element. Thus, when we speak of admiring the sublimity of a particular scene, we have reference as much, if not more, to our perceptions of its character and features, than to the emotions excited by it. And if we attempt to describe the ingredients of its sublimity, we de- scribe our perceptions as well as our consequent feelings. The terms beauty, sublimity, &c, are used both objectively and subjectively, and in men- tal philosophy we must discriminate between these different significations. Objective beauty inheres in the object itself which is styled beautiful. Sub- jective beauty is the effect produced on the mind by the contemplation of a beautiful object. This effect is complex, and includes both our perceptions of the object and the feelings accompanying them. Sublimity. The emotion of sublimity is that delightful, sol- emn, and expansive individual feeling of the mind, which, to use the language of a distinguished writer of our country,* is excited by the " contemplation of whatever is vast in nature, splendid in intellect, or lofty in morals." Or, in the language of Dr. Brown, * Dr. Wayland, in his Moral Dignity of the Missionary Enterprise. 156 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. " Whatever is vast in the material world — whatever is supremely comprehensive in intellect — whatever in morals implies virtuous affections, or passions, far removed beyond the ordinary level of humanity, or even guilt itself, that is ennobled, in some measure, by the fearlessness of its darings, or the magnitude of the ends to which it has the boldness to aspire — these and various other objects, in matter and mind, produce the vivid feelings of sublimity." It has sometimes been disputed whether there is such a thing as objective sublimity ; whether there is, in the objects which are regarded as sublime, any particu- lar property calculated to excite the emotions in question ; or whether they are not wholly the result of association of ideas. That is, when we hear the thunder rolling over our heads, and perceive the earth trembling under our feet, and the lightning flashing in the sky, is it these several appearances which call forth the emotions of sublimity that we feel, or is it solely the conception of resistless power associated with them ? Mr. Payne, erroneously, we think, affirms the latter. That our reflections asso- ciated with the perception of these phenomena are also concerned in the production of these emotions seems evident ; yet they are certainly not the sole cause of them. If the property of these phenomena, by which they cause the emotion of sublimity, be nothing more than their tendency to impress the mind with the conception of vast, resistless, and ter- rific power, still this would be a peculiar property of these objects, because others of a different kind do not possess it. Nor does the fact, that the rum- INDIVIDUAL FEELINGS. 157 bling of a cart may be mistaken for distant thunder, and excite emotions of sublimity, appear to disprove our position. It only shows, that the recollection of a scene of real sublimity may again excite emo- tions of the sublime ; and that any one feature of such a scene, or even anything nearly resembling it, may recall the essential circumstances of such scenes formerly witnessed by us. Thus the rum- bling of the cart recalls our former impressions of thunder, and with it, all those circumstances which are calculated to excite ideas of vast and resistless power, and thus it excites the emotions of sublimity. If thunder had no property peculiarly calculated to excite those ideas which produce emotions of sub- limity, then as the cart by association elicited our recollection of those same ideas, and thus produced these emotions, it would itself be regarded by us as a sublime object, even after it is known to be the cause of the sound. The sight of a fellow-mortal lying emaciated on a bed of sickness, scarce able to lift his hand, may, by the association of contrast, re- call to our minds the resistless power of Jehovah, and thus the emotion of sublimity be excited. But does any man transfer this emotion from God to the feeble mortal ? Certainly not. Therefore, what- ever is the process by which certain objects or ac- tions produce the emotion of sublimity, whether the effect be mediate or immediate, it is evident that entities or objects of this class do possess a peculiar tendency to produce these emotions, which objects of a different kind have not. If, then, it be inquired, is there any sublimity in external objects or actions O 158 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. themselves, we reply, there is that in them which calls forth emotions of the sublime ; and as univer- sal usage designates this something sublimity, we see no objection to the term. And this same train of remarks is equally applicable to objects exciting emotions of beauty. The ordinary ingredients of sublimity in objects, or those attributes of them which are found by ex- perience to excite in us the emotions of sublimity, are vastness in dimension, such as a boundless plain or the vast ocean ; but especially height and depth, as a high mountain, a deep precipice, or the expanse of heaven, which is both high and bound- less ; resistless force, as the rushing of mighty wa- ters, the devastating tornado, prostrating trees and houses in its course ; extremes of colour, as the dazzling brightness of the sun, or the contrary ex- treme, in the dark and lowering clouds of a gath- ering storm ; vast sounds, as the roaring of thun- der, the sound of many waters ; as well as vastness of power, physical, intellectual, and moral. Beauty. The emotion of beauty cannot be logically defi- ned, but is known by consciousness to every individ- ual. It may be described as that pleasant individ- ual feeling of the mind which is excited by the per- ception of certain objects, termed beautiful, in the physical, intellectual, and moral world. The term beauty, like sublimity, is used both objectively and subjectively ; to express a certain property in out- ward entities, and also to designate the perceptions INDIVIDUAL FEELINGS. 159 and feelings caused by them. In reference to this emotion, also, the very existence of objective beau- ty has been denied, and the entire effect of ob- jects of particular kinds in causing this emotion has been attributed to association. It is need- less to say, that these emotions do not resemble the properties in the object which produces them, as no mental operation, either cognitive, sentient, or active, does or can in any one particular resem- ble any material object. But that there are certain characteristics, belonging to those numberless ob- jects termed beautiful, which mediately or immedi- ately cause our emotions of beauty, and lead us to regard those objects as beautiful, is as evident in the case of beauty as of sublimity ; and the same arguments employed to prove it in that case are equally applicable to this. The emotions of beauty are augmented and multiplied by the influence of as- sociation ; but, certainly, there must be some ori- ginal basis for association to build upon, and even these associations must contain nothing inconsistent with the nature of beauty, or they impair instead of increasing the strength of the emotion. The influ- ence of association is exhibited in the figurative language often employed to express these feelings, or, rather, the objects exciting them. We charac- terize landscapes as cheerful or gloomy ; sounds as animated or mournful ; forms as delicate or modest ; colours as gay or grave, &c. It is difficult to describe the precise characteristics of beauty ; yet each individual possesses a natural susceptibility for objects of this kind, and can judge 160 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. for himself. The influence of association and edu- cation causes the diversity of taste observable among different persons on these subjects ; but there are some objects and characteristics pretty generally agreed on. Such are delicate rather than glaring colours, and also a particular variety of such colours. Some kinds of motion are beautiful, such as the gen- tle gliding of a bird through the air, the undulating motion of the surface of a lake when moved by a gentle breeze, or the waving of a field of wheat when a gentle current of air is passing over it. Some figures or forms are beautiful, either on ac- count of their regularity, as in the case of a circle, a triangle, or a square ; or on account of their graceful variety, as in plants, leaves, or trees. The waving line is termed the line of beauty, and the same character belongs to twisted pillars, or the vine or ivy gracefully entwined around the oak. Certain sounds are also found to excite the emotion of beauty, as well simply as in their combinations. All men who have a taste for music, characterize certain airs as beautiful. Some works of art also are beautiful, when they combine the natural ele- ments of beauty in their form or colour. The cre- ations of imagination, as seen in poems or other works of fiction, are beautiful when the writer has faithfully copied nature, that is, has employed the natural sources of beauty, and conformed to their principles. The human countenance is often among the most beautiful objects, not only on account of the beauties of form and colour, but also the ex- pression of amiable, and cheerful, and benevolent feelings in its lineaments. This is, in part, a spe- INDIVIDUAL FEELINGS, 161 cies of social, if not moral beauty. Intellectual and moral excellence is often exhibited in ways and under circumstances such as are felt to be beau- tiful by the corresponding emotions they excite. In some cases many of these sources of beauty are combined, and the general effect thus enhanced. " Perhaps," says Dr. Blair, " the most complete assemblage of beautiful objects that can anywhere be found, is presented by a rich, natural landscape, where there is a sufficient variety of objects : fields in verdure, scattered trees and flowers, running water, and animals grazing. If to these be joined some of the productions of art. which suit with such a scene, as a bridge with arches over a river, smoke rising from cottages in the midst of trees, and the distant view of a fine building seen by the rising- sun ; we then enjoy in the highest perfection that gay, cheerful, and placid sensation which charac- terizes beauty." Some operations purely intellect- ual possess a high degree of beauty, and excite corresponding pleasing emotions ; yet in some ca- ses, especially when they border on the sublime, they derive most of their influence from association. Thus, while there is manifest beauty in many of the demonstrations of geometry, we doubt not that the ecstatic emotion felt by the great mathematician Bernoulli, as he followed Sir Isaac Newton in some of his great steps — a feeling which he, on his death- bed, informed Professor Robinson, of Edinburgh, gave him the liveliest conception he had ever en- joyed of the happiness of heaven — arose, not sim- ply from the intellectual process of reasoning, but chiefly from the enlarged views thus obtained of the 02 162 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. grandeur and overwhelming extent of the universe itself. But even with this allowance, it is to be feared his idea of heaven was essentially defective, as it appears not to have embraced that " holiness'' of thought, feeling, and action which characterizes the inhabitants and occupations of heaven, and " without which no man can see God." The Ludicrous. The emotion of the ludicrous is that transient, pleasing individual feeling, excited in the mind by those entities or objects, physical or intellectual, which are calculated to cause laughter. The ob- jective ludicrous, or that property in entities which is directly or indirectly the cause of the emotion, has been variously defined. Mr. Payne and others regard it as a strange mixture of congruity and in- congruity, the unexpected perception of which oc- casions the mental emotion. This admixture of the congruous and incongruous is sometimes found in the language rather than the thing. Such is the case, for example, in puns and riddles ; as when a barrister, on hearing it remarked what a large quan- tity of ham he had eaten, replied that he had only been taking extracts from Bacon's Abridgment* But in the couplet of Hudibras, " For rhyme the rudder is of verses, s With which, like ships, they steer their courses," the incongruity is observed between the things com- pared, verses and a ship. To the class of ludicrous emotions belong those feelings excited by what is termed Wit. Wit seems to be the sudden and unexpected association of ideas, INDIVIDUAL FEELINGS. 163 natural, but novel, and often conveying an important fact or argument in few words, or by an allusion, the consequence of which flashes on the hearer's mind ; or by an accommodation or play on some word or thing said before. Thus, Plutarch informs us, when Metellus Nepos told Cicero that he had ruined more persons as a witness than he had saved as an advocate, Cicero replied, " I grant it, for I have more truth than eloquence." And when a young man, who lay under the charge of having given his father a poisoned cake, was talking in an insolent manner, and threatening that Cicero should feel the weight of his reproaches, Cicero replied, " I would much rather have them than your cake." Burlesque is a species of wit employed in ren- dering ludicrous that which is naturally grave or dig- nified, or which assumes to be so, by comparing it to things really mean and contemptible. Thus, Hudi- bras burlesques the adventures of his reputed hero : " Ah me ! what perils do environ The man that meddles with cold iron ; What plaguy mischiefs and mishaps Do dog him still with after-claps ! For though dame Fortune seem to smile, And leer upon him for a while, She'll after show him, in the nick Of all his glories, a dog-trick." The mock-heroic is another species of wit, which consists in making low or trifling persons or things appear ridiculous by speaking of them in lofty and grandiloquent language, or by representing them as speaking in such style. Thus, in the same poem, Ralpho is made to address the beaten and prostrate knight : 164 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. " You are, great sir, A self-denying conqueror, As high, victorious, and great, As ever fought for the churches yet, If you will give yourself but leave To make out what y'already have ; That's victory. The foe, for dread Of your nine-worthiness, is fled ; All save Crowdero, for whose sake You did the espous'd cause undertake ; And he lies pris'ner at your feet, To be disposed as you think meet ; Either for life, or death, or sale, The gallows, or perpetual jail ; For one wink of your powerful eye Must sentence him to live or die." Surprise, Wonder, Astonishment, Amazement. These are all different modifications of the same individual feeling, under different circumstances and degrees. Surprise is that feeling excited by the perception of something novel and unexpected This feeling is termed wonder, if the novel and un expected object is also strange or unaccountable Astonishment designates a higher degree of wonder And Amazement implies something intricate or in explicable in the object which caused, the feeling. These emotions may with propriety be termed monitory emotions, for they arrest for a season the action of the mind ; and, as Dr. Brown justly re- marks, " It is in new circumstances that it is most necessary for us to be upon our guard, because, from their novelty, we cannot be aware of the effects that attend them, and require, therefore, more than usual caution where foresight is impossible. But if new circumstances had not produced feelings pe- culiarly vivid, little regard might have been paid to INDIVIDUAL FEELINGS. 165 them, and the evil, therefore, might have been suf- fered before the alarm was felt. Against this dan- ger nature has most providentially guarded us. We cannot feel surprise without a more than ordinary- interest in the objects which may have excited this emotion, and a consequent tendency to pause till their properties have become in some degree known to us. Our astonishment may, therefore, be con- sidered as a voice from that Almighty goodness which constantly protects us, that, in circumstances in which inattention might be perilous, whispers, or almost cries to us, Beware." The Moral Emotions. Moral emotions may be described as those indi- vidual feelings of the mind which are consequent on our cognition of moral truth, as well as moral character or conduct. The contemplation of the beauty of holiness in the Divine law itself, causes a delightful emotion in the Christian. The morality or immorality of an action, properly consists in its agreement or disagreement with the law of God. And our ideas of its morality will depend on our idea of that law, be it more or less accurate or defective. This relation of agreement or disagreement with our views of the law of God is, therefore, the entity which causes the peculiar feelings of pleasure or pain in view of moral actions, either our own or those of others. The terms moral approbation or disapprobation seem to include both the cognitive and sentient element, both our judgment that the act is right or wrong, as well as the concomitant 166 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. feeling. Sense of moral obligation, more properly designates the impulsive part of conscience, and per- haps more or less feeling accompanying it. The operations of conscience, fully considered, consist of three ingredients, the judicial, the sentient, and the impulsive. The judicial ingredient is that judgment which we form of our actions, as being conformed or contrary to the law of God, and has found its place in the discussion of our cognitive ideas in the section on Relative Knowledge. The impulsive feature is active in its nature, and is discussed in the third division of our subject, when we treat of the first constitutional inclination. Our concern at present is wholly with the sentient part of these com- plex operations. The moral emotions, like all other feelings, are original feelings of the mind, which imply a suscep- tibility in the mind for such feelings, and thus at once decide the point, that conscience, or our moral faculty, is an original part of the constitution of the soul. But it does not hence follow that its opera- tions are not complex, embracing elements of differ- ent kinds. As they are original feelings, they must be learned from consciousness, and cannot be logi- cally defined. These feelings are neither numerous nor diversi- fied. They are either pleasant or painful, the for- mer consequent on a judgment of approval of a given action, and the latter resulting from a judg- ment of disapproval. From their intimate connex- ion with these judgments, some writers have con- founded the two, and even designated the pleasant feeling a feeling of approbation, and the unpleasant INDIVIDUAL FEELINGS. 167 one a feeling of disapproval, forgetful of the judg- ment included in the term. In popular language this may be allowed, but in philosophical discus- sions we should always distinguish the feeling ac- companying the approval from the approval itself, which is always a judgment of the mind, that the act is right, is conformed to the will of God. Keep- ing in view this distinction, it may not be improper to retain the popular designation, and speak of judgments of approval or disapproval, and also feel- ings of approbation and disapprobation, meaning by the latter the emotions, either pleasant or pain- ful, consequent on those judgments. Those feel- ings are also sometimes termed feelings of inno- cence or guilt, of self-approbation, or self-condem- nation, or remorse. As our moral emotions are consequent on the judgments of approval or disapproval to which they succeed, it follows, that if those judgments change, the feelings will 'change also. Thus, so long as Paul was conscious that his judgment approved of the persecution of Christians, he contemplated the act with pleasing emotions, and felt an inward im- pulse urging him to do it. But when his views on the subject of Jesus of Nazareth changed, and his judgment disapproved the act, he regarded with emotions of pain and regret the very conduct in which he had formerly delighted. Nor does this liability to change in our emotions imply that they are not to be depended on, any more than change of opinion in reference to any subject proves that our intellectual or cognitive powers cannot be re- lied on. It only proves that our moral nature, in 168 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. I ts cognitive, sentient, and active departments, is ' capable of improvement, and is a suitable subject of I education. The terms moral emotions may also be applied to transient impulses of some of our relative feelings, such as love and hatred, sympathy, &c, in as far as these feelings are matter of duty, and we have indirect control over them. III. The Affections. By the term affections we would designate those habits, or habitual states of feeling, which are more durable than sensations or emotions. Some of the affections refer only to ourselves, and some termi- nate on other objects. It is the former alone which belong to the individual feelings, now under dis- cussion. They may be divided into pleasant and unpleasant. The pleasant affections are such as joy, cheer- fulness, contentment, humility, patience. Joy is a highly pleasurable affection, excited in the mind by the contemplation of something past, present, or prospective, which we regard as highly favourabir to us or others. Cheerfulness is an habitual, moder- ate, pleasant affection of the mind, resulting from the view of our condition as on the whole favourable. It results from the habit of viewing the bright side of human affairs, and is of great importance in life, to ourselves and those around us. It often arises from constitutional temperament, but its purest source is true piety, which teaches us to dwell much on the numberless mercies surrounding us, and to believe that even the ills of life are designed for greater INDIVIDUAL FEELINGS. 169 good. Contentment is a moderate, tranquil, pleasant affection, resulting from the conviction, that the cir- cumstances of our situation are, on the whole, such as not to give us just cause of dissatisfaction. Hu- mility is a moderate, pleasing affection, arising from a view of our un worthiness. Patience is a moderate, pleasing affection, resulting from our determination to endure the ills of life without murmuring. The painful affections are by some writers termed passions, but this term is often applied to some rel- ative affections both pleasant and unpleasant, to designate their existence in a high degree. Thus we speak of the passion of love and of anger. The painful individual affections are such as penitence, discontent, sadness, grief, despair, pride, vanity, fretfulness, &c. Penitence is that painful guilty feeling of self-condemnation, resulting from a viola- tion of known duty. Discontent is a painful feeling arising from the conviction, that we have reason to complain of our condition or treatment. Sadness is a moderate, painful feeling of dejection, resulting from some loss or difficulty to ourselves or those we love. Grief is a more intense, painful affection than sadness, resulting from a higher degree of the same causes. Despair is an intense and settled painful affection, resulting from the belief that our condition is hopeless, or the object of our desire unattainable. Pride is that feeling of self-complacency which arises from an over-estimate of our own merits. Vanity is that affection of the mind which results from an over-estimate of our own merits, and a desire that they may be admired by others. Fretfulness is a P 170 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. painful feeling, resulting from losses or difficulties of minor importance. IV. The feelings connected with our Bodily Appe- tites. These appetites are such as hunger and thirst ; the operations of which are connected with feel- ings, pleasant or unpleasant, of the individual class, the nature of which will be more fully discussed in a subsequent section. We come now to the second general class of feelings. CLASS II. RELATIVE FEELINGS, OR THOSE WHICH TERMINATE ON SOME OTHER OBJECTS THAN OURSELVES. These we divide into benevolent, malevolent, sym- pathetic, and antipathetic. I. Benevolent Feelings or Affections. These are relative feelings, which are favourable to the being or thing, on which they terminate. These feelings constitute one of the noblest por- tions of our nature. When sanctified by Divine grace, they enter largely into the elements of true piety, and even in the natural man constitute one of the purest and principal sources of the happiness which he enjoys. The term affections is applied to this kind of feelings more generally than to any others, and in more specific accordance with the primitive import of the term. Benevolence, or Love, is a relative affection of a very broad character, and embraces various modi- fications, according to the different circumstances under which it is exercised. In its widest accepta- RELATIVE FEELINGS. 171 tion, benevolence is a pleasing feeling of good- will and desire for the happiness of all sentient beings, ir- respective of their character or conduct. With this affection a good man loves the whole human fami- ly, as well as irrational animals. This feeling ap- pears to be much weaker in depraved human na- ture than the other modifications of love, and a ca- reer of sin very soon habitually overpowers it. Love, in its other modifications, embraces in it a perception of something agreeable, praiseworthy, or desirable in the appearance, character, or con- duct of the object beloved. It also implies delight in this object, a desire for its possession or enjoy- ment, and a disposition to promote its happiness. It is always^ in its intrinsic nature, a pleasing affec- tion. To a certain extent it is voluntary in well- balanced minds, and can be mediately controlled, by either shunning the presence and contemplation of the object which excites it, or by frequenting that presence and indulging in reflections on it when absent. All this, however, clearly proves that there is something in the beloved object itself which excites our affection, while, of course, it presuppo- ses in the mind a constitutional susceptibility to be thus affected. The principal modifications of this affection are the following : Paternal love, that affection which a father feels for his offspring, and which induces him contentedly to toil all day long for the support of his children, and to promote their welfare in ev- ery possible way. Maternal love is that affection felt by a mother for her children, which makes her watch especially over their defenceless years with 172 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. ceaseless care, and willingly endure the loss of rest and convenience in protecting and rearing them. Conjugal love is the affection of husband and wife towards each other, which induces them to study- to promote each other's happiness, to overlook each other's infirmities, and to lighten by mutual sympa- thy the ordinary troubles and afflictions of life. Fil- ial affection is that love which children bear to their parents. These several species of affection form alike the basis of the domestic or family institution, and the cement by which its members are held to- gether. A beautiful instance of conjugal affection is related by Xenophon in his semi-historical Cyro- psedia. Cyrus had taken captive Tigranes, the young Prince of Armenia, together with his wife, whom he had recently married, and of whom he was pas- sionately fond. When both were brought before Cyrus, he asked the prince what he would pay to receive back his wife again, to which question Ti- granes replied, " I will, if necessary, give my life to redeem her from servitude." Cyrus nobly gave liberty to all the prisoners, who, on departing, could not find words to express their admiration of their noble conqueror ; some applauding his wisdom, oth- ers his bravery, others his clemency, and some his beauty and tallness. At length Tigranes thus ad- dressed his wife : " And do you, Armenia, tell me, did Cyrus appear to you to be handsome ?" " In- deed," said she, " I did not look at him." " At whom, then, were you looking ?" said Tigranes. " At him, truly, who said that he was willing to lay down his life to purchase my freedom." Of mater- nal affection the history of every age is replete with RELATIVE FEELINGS. 173 examples. An interesting case is quoted from an anonymous writer by Professor Upham. " When the Ajax, man-of-war, took fire in the straits of the Bosphorus, in 1807, an awful scene of distrac- tion ensued. The ship was of great size, full of people, and under the attack of an enemy at the time ; the mouths of destruction seemed to wage contention for their prey. Many of those on board could entertain no hopes of deliverance ; striving to shun one devouring element, they were the vic- tims of another. While the conflagration was ra- ging furiously, and shrieks of terror rent the air, an unfortunate mother, regardless of herself, seemed solicitous only for the safety of her infant child. She never attempted to escape ; but she committed it to the charge of an officer, who, at her earnest request, endeavoured to secure it in his coat ; and following the tender deposite with her eyes as he retired, she calmly awaited that catastrophe in which the rest were about to be involved. Amid the exertions of the officer in such an emergency, the infant dropped into the sea, which was no soon- er discovered by the unhappy parent, than, frantic, she plunged from the vessel's side as if to preserve it ; she sunk, and was seen no more." Gratitude, friendship, respect, confidence, patri- otism, and hope express pleasing relative feelings, the nature of which is so well understood as not to need farther elucidation. Love to God is that pleasant relative feeling which the good man cherishes towards God as a being of infinite perfections, and as deserving of P2 174 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. his supreme affection. This feeling, the Scriptures teach us, is supreme in the heart of the true Chris- tian ; and, as conversion does but restore the char- acter of fallen man in some degree to its primitive condition, it seems reasonable to believe that it was the supreme affection of the soul in the state of primitive innocence. Adoration includes, besides its cognitive and active elements, a kindred feeling of more solemn kind, which accompanies our acts of worship, that is, our repetition of the truths of Scripture concerning the glorious character and re- lations of God, in an oral or mental address to him. II. Malevolent, Repulsive, or Defensive Feelings. Malevolent, or defensive affections, are those painful relative feelings which involve hostility, and a disposition to injure the beings on which they ter- minate. The malevolent affections appear to be a perversion of an original susceptibility, which is per se good, and purely defensive in its nature. Even in our fallen state the command of God to us is, in certain circumstances, " Be ye angry and sin not ;" and, prior to the fall, the exercises of this power were all of that sinless kind. These feel- ings are consequent on the perception or contem- plation of any person or object, which we deem hostile to ourselves, or to those with whom we sym- pathize, or to that which is right. In our unfallen state, our interests and feelings were in invariable harmony with the will of God : consequently, no- thing could call forth these feelings but what was opposed to the will of God, or, in other words, was sin. Originally, therefore, our repulsive feelings RELATIVE FEELINGS. 175 were purely feelings of abhorrence or repugnance at sin. But, in the present state of man, it is un- deniable that the love of self preponderates over the love of God, and we often cherish interests and desires opposed to his will. Hence, when our re- pugnant feelings are excited against others for op- posing us, or our interests or desires, we are often wrong, and our opponents right, and these feelings are thus enlisted in opposition to right, in hostility to the will of God. Yet, in proportion as the im- age of God is restored in man, in proportion as he loves holiness and hates sin, his repugnant affec- tions will always be opposed only to sinners and to sin ; he will hate and feel anger only at that which God hates ; and thus, in exemplification of the Scripture precept, he " will be angry and not sin." The feelings belonging to this class are^such as the following : anger, hatred, resentment, revenge, malignity, cruelty, and malice. III. Sympathetic Feelings. Sympathetic feelings are relative affections of the mind, which imply similarity or congeniality to the feelings of the being on which they terminate. Sympathetic feelings do not differ in their gener- al nature from the other phenomena of our sentient nature. They are all feelings excited in the mind by the contemplation of certain entities. They are both pleasant and unpleasant, according as they are excited by the happiness or misery of our fellow- creatures. It is alike accordant with the principles of our nature, that we should rejoice with them that rejoice, and weep with those who weep. Yet ex- 176 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. perience proves that we sympathize most acutely with those whose feelings are similar to the pre- vailing state of our own minds at the time. We do not, indeed, even in this case, literally partici- pate in the feelings of others, because every man's feelings, like his other mental phenomena, are in- alienable and untransferable. But in the similar state of our own minds, our susceptibility for feel- ings of that kind is peculiarly acute, and, therefore, deeper and stronger feelings are excited by the con- templation of the same entities than would at other times be the case. The impulses of sympathy are often sudden and unpremeditated, and lead to in- stantaneous action for the relief of those in danger or in pain, as when we rush to the relief of an in- dividual who is sinking beneath the strokes of some ruffian. „These sympathetic feelings have a most happy influence in harmonizing the differences which often exist among associates and in families, and thus making happy the intercourse of those who would otherwise be ever at variance. Besides the general term sympathy, which is alike applicable to a fellow-feeling of a pleasing or pain- ful nature, the terms compassion, pity, commisera- tion, are often used as synonymous terms, and at other times to express some shades of diversity in these feelings. Condolence signifies a fellow-feel- ing with others in suffering. IV. Antipathetic Feelings. To this class we refer all those relative feelings which, though they have reference to some other being, imply only opposition of feeling, but not in- RELATIVE FEELINGS. 177 tention of action. They are such as envy, jealousy, disgust, grudging, fear, dread, horror, and indigna- tion. Envy is that painful relative feeling which is exci- ted in the selfish mind by the contemplation of some desirable property or possession of another. This feeling is excited more readily in some minds than in others, and the different susceptibility for it is proportioned to the relative preponderance of the second constitutional inclination over the first, that is, in proportion as the individual is in the habit of being influenced more by selfishness, the love of well-being, rather than by the moral fitness of things, his duty. It is the design and tendency of true religion to suppress and eradicate these feelings, and the truly pious man is rarely guilty of them. Jealousy, in its primary application, has reference to amatory affection, and signifies that painful feel- ing of temporary or qualified displeasure against an individual whom we love or have loved, because we suppose some other person to be preferred to ourselves. The term jealousy is, however, more generally applied to that painful feeling which is excited by apprehension that some other person has or will obtain some object which we had hoped to acquire ourselves. It is in this sense of it that we speak of professional jealousy, and jealousy be- tween competitors for any supposed good. This feeling has a particular tendency to warp the judg- ment, to make us place the most unfavourable con- struction on the actions of its object, and to magni- fy molehills into mountains ; so that it may with truth be said, 178 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. " Trifles, light as air, Are to the jealous confirmation strong As proofs of Holy Writ." Disgust is an unpleasant feeling of aversion to an individual on account of something low, mean, ob- scene, vulgar, or base in his person or conduct. Indignation is the same feeling, mingled with con- tempt and scorn for its object. Fear is a painful feeling, resulting from the con- viction of some impending or probable evil. Dread is a higher and more permanent degree of the same feeling. Horror is a still higher degree of fear, excited by the sudden and unexpected view of something very evil or dangerous in our condition or conduct. CHAPTER II. OF ENTITIES AS EXCITANTS OF FEELING. SECTION I. All feeling, like knowledge, may be traced me- diately or immediately to entities without the mind. The eye could never afford us feeling if the rays of light were not reflected from external entities to it, or did not reach it from the surrounding atmosphere. The pleasing or painful feelings, excited by entities through the eye, are produced immediately by the rays of light which reach the eyes, and ultimately, in a certain sense, by the particular object from EXTERNAL ENTITIES EXCITANTS OF FEELING. 179 which the rays pass, and which give them their pe- culiar texture or combination of colours. The ear could never be the medium through which either knowledge or feeling is excited, if the vibrations of the atmosphere were not permitted to reach the tympanum. The vibrating atmosphere is therefore the entity which immediately excites the feelings connected with sound, and the sounding body is the ultimate entity which gives the air its vibratory motion. The nose could never be the vehicle of knowl- edge or feeling to the mind, if the effluvia emana- ting from surrounding odorous bodies were not per- mitted to touch the olfactory nerves. Nor does religious feeling seem to be different in its nature. Thus, the Christian meditates on the glorious character of God, and the feelings of his heart are excited to the highest pitch. But what is this meditation else than an inspection of the entity God, and his relations to us ? By these it is that our feelings are excited. The case is similar, when our feelings are occasioned by reading the Divine word ; for the signs or letters read remind us of the sounds for which the letters stand, and the rec- ollection of these recalls the ideas of real, objective entities. The daily habit of meditating on heaven- ly or Divine things, by the same law of mind, keeps alive our interest, or, rather, our feelings, on this subject, and increases the frequency of our rein- spection of them ; thus, a kind of rapport is form- ed between the soul of the Christian and that heav- en which is his home, and that God who is his ev- erlasting friend. 180 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. SECTION II. Entities of every class possess some tendency, though very different in degree, to excite feeling in the mind. Our remark is not that this tendency is perceptible in every entity belonging to each class, but that it is perceptible in some of every class. With regard to solids and liquids, the truth of this remark is evident. It is self-evident, that all arti- cles of food or drink possess it in some degree. Other objects of these classes, which at first view might seem incapable of exciting feeling, change their aspect when more closely examined. Thus, who would attribute to the earth and minerals the power of exciting feeling in the mind ; and yet what else is the pleasure found by men in the pur- suit of Geology and Mineralogy, than the result of this very feeling excited by a contemplation of the laws and principles of these sciences, as delineated in nature ? The pleasures experienced in the study of optics, exemplify the feelings excited by the en- tity light, its laws, properties, and relations. Space and number, which would seem, from their nature, least capable of exciting feeling in the mind, are, in fact, found more operative than some others, and afford all the pleasures of geometrical and mathematical study. Our retrospective and prospective knowledge of en- tities also produces feelings similar in kind, though generally inferior in degree, to the objective entity itself, when it is the subject of present attention ; yet our retrospective ideas are also entities without DIFFERENT DEGREES OF THIS POWER IN ENTITIES. 181 the mind. I can reflect on a former interview with a long-absent and beloved friend, and derive the purest pleasure from the recollection. The va- rious relations of entities often exert this influence. Thus, the pleasure experienced by the mind when contemplating the beauty of holiness, is excited by the composite entity, a perfect law, and the con- duct of a moral agent ; and the relation which ex- cites this feeling, is that of agreement between them. SECTION III. The degrees in ivhich different entities possess this exciting power are very different, and can be ac- curately learned only from experience. Nor can any organ originally afford us this information, except the one through which the feeling is produced. We should be unable, from the mere appearance of an orange or a peach, to know, a priori, that their red- ness or yellowness is indicative of superior aptitude to gratify the palate. Yet after we have by expe- rience learned the fact of this tendency, and learned that the degrees of it are usually attended by these external appearances, they serve as indexes to the mind. But not only is the feeling, produced by en- tities of different classes, different in degree ; the same diversity belongs to one and the same entity, when acting in different ways, and under different circumstances. So far as this arises from a differ- ent susceptibility in different minds, or in the same mind at different times, its discussion falls under a subsequent division of our subject ; other circum- stances only claim our present attention. Q 182 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. The influence of different entities in exciting our feelings. (a.) Their strongest influence entities certainly exert when brought into contact with the particular organs of our body, through which, according to the divine constitution, they act upon the mind. Thus, a peach affords most pleasure, when brought into contact with the palate ; a beautiful landscape, when actually viewed by the eye ; an escape from the hands of a murderer, when really experienced by us ; and the pains of disease, hunger, disappoint- ed hope or ambition, when we are actually the sub- jects of them. (b.) When we have a prospective knowledge, that we shall, at some future time, probably be the subjects of their influence, they exert their next greatest power ; that is, when they are the sub- jects of hope or fear. In many instances our prospective view is ac- companied by stronger feeling than when we are the direct subjects of the influence of the entity. But this arises from erroneous ideas of the pleasures or pains which will be occasioned by actual experience. The law of nature seems to be that present feeling is stronger than retrospective or prospective. (c.) When these entities excite retrospective feel- ing, they are again productive of a different degree of pleasure or pain. [d.) Sympathetic feeling is, as a general rule, weaker than its corresponding direct class of feel- ings. (e.) The least degree of feeling is excited by en- EXTERNAL ENTITIES AS EXCITANTS OF FEELING. 183 tities, when we view only their abstract tendency to produce pleasure or pain, without supposing ourselves or others to be actually the subjects of them. This might be termed their original degree of influence, and is, perhaps, the exact degree of strength which the Author of our being designed they should exert upon us as motives. It might also be termed their simple influence, because in all other cases additional principles, such as self- love, &c, are called into action. SECTION IV. Entities of the classes of solids and liquids excite more feeling, and exert more motive power, when near us than when far off. This circumstance may be demonstrated by a variety of cases, al- though it is not so easy to assign the philosophical reason of the fact. This appears to be the case particularly with those solids and liquids, which gratify our periodical susceptibilities of feeling, such as hunger and thirst. SECTION V. The manner in which entities act in exciting' feeling, seems to be very similar to that observed in the pro- duction of knowledge. Each adjective or composite entity can originally excite feeling in the mind, only through that organ by which it becomes the subject of our knowledge. The flavour of fruit can excite pleasure in us originally only through the palate. Again ; each individual property or rela- tion of an entity acts independently and individual- 184 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. ly, in exciting feeling ; so that the same substantive entity may produce different feelings in us, when we inspect different properties or relations of it. Hence, if I now love him whom I once hated, it is because I now contemplate different properties, or relations to me, or to others, from those which were formerly prominent in the same individual. This principle is extremely important to enable us to un- derstand how it is, that the penitent and converted sinner finds very different feelings excited by the contemplation of the Divine Being, from those which he formerly experienced. SECTION VI. In feeling, as in knowledge, two things are neces- sary ; first, the action of the entity on its appropriate organ ; and, secondly, the attention of the mind to that entity. Thus, if a peach or pear be placed be- fore my face, and my attention is firmly fixed on some other object of thought, the rays of light are indeed reflected from the peach to the retina of my eye, but the soul derives neither knowledge nor feeling from the peach, because my attention is oth- erwise directed. Hence attention, and the power of directing the mind to one or other object, are highly important active powers of the soul. LAWS OF FEELING. 185 CHAPTER III. THE SUSCEPTIBILITY OF THE MIND FOR FEELING, AND LAWS OF FEELING. Having discussed the nature and classification of feelings themselves, and also the cause from which they spring, that is, entities as excitants of feeling, we now proceed to examine the suscepti- bilities of the mind for feeling, and the laws by which they seem to be regulated. First law. Sensation, no less than cognition, is an attribute of the mind, and not of the body. That is, all sensation is in the mind. As sensations are obviously ideas, it must be admitted by all except materialists, that they are phenomena appertaining to the entity to which ideas belong, that is, to mind. As to the materialist, since he supposes cognitions also to be attributes of matter, or the re- sult of bodily organization, he can without great- er absurdity extend the same supposition to sensa- tions. But, so long as all the known properties of matter are totally different from all the known properties of mind, we may well leave the absurd supposition of their being the same substance, to those who delight in philosophical nonsense and par- adoxes. The popular impression, that sensations have some kind of local habitation in the organs, through the instrumentality of which they are pro- duced, results from a confusion of the organ through Q2 186 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. which we perceive, and the thinking being itself. But obviously, there is little more propriety in re- garding the eye as the being that sees, than the tel- escope through which we see ; nor ear as the being that hears, than the acoustic tube by which the hearing of the partially deaf is improved. In like manner, the feeling produced by touch is wholly in the mind ; although the antecedent perception, which is different for some different parts of the body, en- ables us, by practice, generally to tell what part of the body has experienced the contact. Second law. The original susceptibility of different minds for feeling is evidently very different in degree. In this there is a striking similarity between the susceptibility for knowledge and feeling. Whether the ground of this diversity is seated partly in the mind itself, or wholly in the different texture or per- fection of the bodily organs by which the operations of the soul are limited, it is difficult to decide. That there is a striking diversity in the texture or organization of different individuals, cannot admit of a moment's doubt ; it is a subject of ocular and anatomical demonstration. The fact, moreover, is one of universal ocular observation, and its ex- pression provided for in popular language. What else is meant by the phrases, a person of ardent feelings, and, a cold-hearted man, than persons char- acterized by a diversity in the degree of their ha- bitual feelings ; i. e., by a natural diversity in their original susceptibility for feeling. The diversity in the texture of the organs themselves is designated by the term temperament. It is a point doubted LAWS OP FEELING. 187 by no man of observation, that mankind are distin- guished by those diversities, and that they may be reduced to several classes, such as the phlegmatic, sanguine, choleric, &c. The various commixtures of these temperaments are almost infinite ; nor is the difference in the texture of the body which is designated by the word temperament, confined to any particular organ of sense; the characteristic pervades the whole organization of the body, the skin, the lymphatics, flesh, blood, bones, nerves, &c. Nothing, however, is more certain, than that the temperaments of men are hereditarily transmitted according to certain laws, which are fixed by the Author of our nature ; but which are not, and prob- ably never will be, fully understood by us. Third law. Excepting this diversity, which results from the different temperaments, the relative degrees of susceptibility for the influence of different entities is, in all minds, naturally the same. Although A is twice as sensitive as B, yet, the difference of tem- perament excepted, an entity which produces twice as much feeling in A as another given entity would, also naturally produces in B twice as much as the other would. A will be operated upon twice as forcibly as B by all motives to good, and it might be supposed that he was favoured by Providence more highly than B, whose natural susceptibility is only half as strong. But it must be remembered that A is also operated upon twice as forcibly as B by all motives to evil, and therefore the relative degree of his susceptibility for feeling is, in effect, equal to that of B. The relative equality of the influence 188 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. of different entities has an important bearing on the subject of the moral government of God; be- cause feelings are motives to action, and, other things being equal, they naturally exert a power proportionate to this degree. That the above pe- culiarity of the natural susceptibility for feeling also occurs in feelings of a religious character, seems to be certain. This fact must be taken into consider- ation by every pastor, who wishes to form a correct view of the religious progress of his spiritual chil- dren, and also by every individual, who would judge with accuracy of the religious state of his own soul. Fourth law. Feeling is, in a great measure, invol- untary at the time. We cannot, when acted upon by an entity, and when our attention is directed to it, determine whether feeling shall or shall not, in the first instance, be excited in us. Fifth law. We can, however, at the time, add to the intensity and duration of the feeling, or subtract from both, by either confining our attention to the exciting entity, or directing it to another object. Thus, the more wholly we fix our attention upon a piece of music performed within our hearing, the greater will be the feeling excited in us ; and the more wholly and intensely we direct our attention to the truths pronounced from the sacred desk, the more fully will they exert their proper influence of feeling and motive power upon us. Sixth law. When any particular feeling, or pas- sion, or purpose becomes dominant in the soul, and absorbs in a great measure its other energies, all LAWS OF FEELING. 189 feelings at variance with this are impaired. Thus the sensualist, the miser, and the votary of ambi- tion, are in most cases found comparatively insen- sible to objects unconnected with their favourite pursuits. In like manner, when men find it neces- sary to success in any of their habitual pursuits, to suppress those feelings which would endanger that success, they can, by a settled purpose and contin- ued effort, succeed in steeling their hearts against those feelings, and can acquire an insensibility, which at first is artificial, but if persevered in, be- comes habitual and natural. It is on this principle that the most benevolent physician from the best of motives, the desire of benefiting his patient, stud- ies to acquire that control over his feelings amid scenes of the most distressing character, which is requisite to enable him to judge wisely of his pa- tient's condition, and to select the most appropriate remedies for his case. And it is upon the same principle, though from far less honourable motives, that military chieftains and professional soldiers ac- quire the unenviable ability to wade in the blood of their nominal foes, and even to climb unmoved over the mangled bodies of their slaughtered com- rades. Seventh law. The tendency of entities to excite pleasant or unpleasant feelings when they are the subjects of prospective or retrospective knowledge, depends, in a great measure, on their accordance, or discordance, with what will hereafter be described as the constitutional inclinations of the soid, espe- cially the love of well-being or happiness. 190 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. Eighth law. The influence of an entity, in exci- ting' feeling, is, to a mind of given susceptibility, stronger when it for the first time acts upon us, on account of its novelty. We may here refer to an analogous ease in medical science. A medicine, administered for the first time, produces a greater effect than the same dose does after having been re- peatedly taken. How far this analogy is occasioned by similarity of cause, would be an interesting sub- ject of inquiry, in which, however, we have not time to engage. This principle accounts for the fact, that the feelings of the newly-converted are so peculiarly vivid when the entities exciting them, that is, their new relations to God and his law, and to the Saviour, are first presented to their minds. Yet, as continued attention increases the constitu- tional susceptibility of feeling, the same mind may, by such attention, subsequently have feelings as vivid as those first experienced. Ninth law. Feelings produced by the same sub- stantive entity, in the same person, at different times, are in some cases different. This fact is explained by the principle adverted to on a former occasion, that every property or relation of an entity acts separately in the production of feeling. Every property, indeed, and every relation of an entity, produces a feeling peculiar to itself, and produces this feeling invariably ; but, as entities have various properties and relations, the different properties and relations of the same entity, in many cases, produce contrary feelings. Hence it will always be found, that when an entity produces feelings diverse from LAWS OF FEELING. 191 those which it formerly excited, the reason is, either that the entity has changed its properties or rela- tions, or that a different property or relation is now the subject of our attention, and the excitant of our feeling. At one time we habitually dwell on one property or relation of an entity, and our feelings are correspondent ; but when our feelings change, it is because we dwell upon another relation of the same entity. Thus, reflecting on the death of my friend, viewing its relation to me as a social loss, I am grieved, that is, this relation produces painful feeling ; but when I reflect on it as a means of his translation from a bed of long-protracted, painful, and hopeless sickness to a world of bliss, I rejoice ; this relation of the same event excites pleasant feel- ings. When our feelings change towards any of our fellow-men, it is always because either their character has changed, or we have acquired addi- tional knowledge concerning it, or, from a change m our own character, we now dwell on different relations of it. The character of men being so very mutable, changes in the relative feelings existing among them, are constantly occurring. Tenth law. The susceptibility of the mind for feelings of every kind is increased by attentive practice. Here the question arises, whether the cause of increased susceptibility from practice is oc- casioned by an improvement in the bodily organs or in the mental power. Probably it may be found jointly in both. This principle is exemplified in the pleasures of the glutton, the drunkard, the mu- sician. In other words, the feelings of men are 192 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. augmented by habit, just as all their cognitive and active operations are. The law of habit pervades the entire man physical and intellectual, and adds facility and strength to all his operations. Feelings of benevolence or of malevolence may be and are confirmed and increased by repetition ; and it is owing to this principle that we are enabled, as moral agents, by repeated voluntary exercise of our affec- tions on proper objects, to cherish and cultivate those habits of feeling and traits of character which we know to be good. Eleventh law. Intense and long- continued feel- ing produces a temporary exhaustion, and fatigues the system in a manner similar to intense cognitive mental action. Yet it is difficult, as knowledge and feeling always go together, to distinguish what por- tion of the fatigue is to be attributed to each. The question might arise whether the sleepiness of the glutton after dinner be owing to the debility occa- sioned by this feeling during eating, or by the fact that nature has been compelled to concentrate her energies upon the stomach to digest the newly-re- ceived load. Twelfth law. The susceptibility for feeling nat- urally declines with age and with the decline of the constitution, even if that be premature. Thirteenth law. A negligent review of entities diminishes their tendency to produce feeling. Upon this principle it is that religious formality tends to produce insensibility of mind. Fourteenth law. Time wears off retrospective feeling. There are cases of exception to this law, LAWS OF FEELING. 193 such as in those persons who have become melan- choly in consequence of severe afflictions, and of always pondering over their loss. But here there is a morbid state of the mind, which, therefore, does not disprove the general law. The ordinary fact is, that the retrospect of our sufferings is at- tended by feelings less acute than our original suf- ferings, and that each successive retrospect by the same individual is productive of emotions of di- minished acuteness. This law must be regarded as a most benevolent arrangement of Providence. Life is a scene of not unfrequent trials and afflic- tions. Some of these, at the time of their occur- rence, fill us with grief almost as great as we can bear. Now, if the suffering caused by these suc- cessive calamities were all accumulated, with undi- minished vigour, as we advance in our earthly pil- grimage, life itself would in most cases become an intolerable burden, and man be disqualified for its ordinary duties. On the other hand, the death of friends or relatives could not affect us less at the time, without such a change in our mental struc- ture as would make us place a far lower estimate on their value, and thus greatly diminish our social enjoyments. The result of such a change would necessarily be to weaken the strongest and most endearing ties by which society is held together. We are, therefore, wisely and benevolently so con- structed that our suffering at the loss of friends and relatives is poignant, in order that we may take the better care of them when living ; and time diminish- R 194 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. es the eight of these sorrows, so that their accu- mulated pressure might not disqualify us for the du- ties of life. Fifteenth law. Feeling is, in general, not instant- ly excited, as is knowledge, when an entity becomes the subject of our attention. Oftentimes feeling is elicited by continued application of the mind. Sixteenth law. The feelings connected with the gratification of our periodical appetites, such as hun- ger and thirst, have the following peculiarities. (1.) They are stronger in proportion to the length of previous abstinence, unless that has been ex- treme, and has impaired the organs. (2.) They are increased by the frequent attention of the soul to the. entities capable of gratifying these appetites. (3.) This feeling is diminished and eventually sus- pended by gratification. (4.) It is interrupted by the debility and increased by the vigour of the body. From the preceding laws and considerations it is evident that the state of our feelings is, to a cer- tain extent, under our own control. It is indeed true, that no man can instantly change his feel- ings by a mere volition to do so. But the end can be accomplished eventually, by his habitually di- recting his attention to those entities and truths calculated to produce the desired feelings. We are, therefore, justly held responsible by our moral Governor for the character of our feelings, so far as they are under our control. Nor is the case different with what is often termed the habitual MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. 195 stale of our feeliyigs or affections. As every feel- ing is individual and transient, as it continues only so long as our minds dwell on the entity or idea which excited it, and as it must, in every instance, be excited anew by the appropriate entity, or our knowledge of it, it follows that by the state of our feelings or affections must be meant our suscepti- bility for feelings from any particular entities. This susceptibility is permanent, being a part of our ori- ginal mental constitution, and is either increased or diminished according as it is more or less frequent- ly and designedly exercised towards any given ob- ject. To this increased susceptibility must be added, the increased tendency to the spontaneous recur- rence of the ideas of the objects, on which our sus- ceptibility is most frequently employed. These two things, the increased spontaneous recurrence of the ideas of the entities which excite feelings of any given character, and the increased susceptibility of the mind to their influence when presented, consti- tute those different habitual states of feeling, or of the affections, by which different persons are char- acterized. In this, so far as known to us, consists the difference between the virtuous and the vicious, the pure and the impure, in regard to the state of their affections. The licentious, for example, by continued voluntary indulgence of criminal thoughts, if not actions, have formed the habit of frequent spontaneous recurrence of licentious thoughts. By the same course they have increased the suscepti- bility of their minds to be excited by thoughts of 196 SUSCEPTIBILITY FOR FEELINGS. that kind ; and thus they have corrupted the state of their affections, and made them far worse than they naturally were. For this corrupted state of their affections, they will justly be held liable by the Judge of all the earth. Thus a person of malevolent disposition, is one who has formed the habit of indulging in such views of human character as are calculated to ex- cite the malevolent feelings, and who has thus aug- mented the susceptibility of his mind for feelings of that description. Persons of a benevolent disposition are those of a directly contrary habit. As our feelings are al- ways preceded by a cognitive idea of the entity by which they are produced, we cannot determine whether there is any immediate connexion, any nexus rerum, between the several feelings them- selves, by which their tendency to recurrence is in- creased, or whether that tendency is based only on the association between the cognitive ideas, while the recurrence of these superinduces the repetition of the feelings. If, however, the individual feel- ings themselves have this tendency, it is exerted only through the medium of our cognitive ideas. The feelings connected with what are termed our periodical appetites, such as hunger and thiust, might at first view seem to form an exception to the remark, that all our feelings are transient and individual, and must be excited anew in every in- stance by their appropriate entity, or the recurrence of our idea of it; because they seem often to be permanent, at least for a season, and to continue MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. 197 even without the presence of the external entity or the thought of it, by which they are gratified. But, upon closer examination it will be evident, that du- ring the whole time of their continuance, there is an objective entity acting on the organ and exci- ting the feeling. Thus, for example, in hunger, the exciting entity has been supposed to be the gastric fluid irritating the coats of the stomach, which in this case are the organ of sensation. This irrita- tion is continued so long as there is not a sufficiency of food thrown into the stomach to absorb or occu- py the gastric fluid, and divert it from the coats of the stomach. And just so long, and no longer, do we experience the feeling we term hunger, and the desire of food resulting from it, without its being excited by any external article of food or the thought of any. Still, even while this desire and feeling are excited by continued action of the gas- tric fluid within us, the idea of food of some kind or other is almost constantly present to the mind, and adds its excitement to the feeling and desire excited from within. The feeling of hunger thus seems simply to be that pain produced by the gas- tric fluid. The desire connected with it is the re- sult of the motive influence of some article of food, or the idea of it, acting on the mind, and tending to a volition to procure it. The feeling- of hunger can exist independently of any idea of food ; the desire of any kind of food whatever cannot exist without either its presence, or the thought of it. R2 198 ACTIVE OPERATIONS OF THE SOUL. PART III. ACTIVE OPERATIONS OF THE SOUL. Having taken a brief survey of the various classes of entities around us, and having discussed the two kinds of mental representatives, which are obtained by the soul, when these entities are the subjects of our attention, viz., the cognitive and sentient, that is, those ideas which constitute our knowledge and feeling, we must next advance to the examination of those active operations of which the soul is ca- pable, and which certainly constitute the most im- portant feature of our character, as beings respon- sible to God. Our knowledge and feeling may be regarded mainly as our acquaintance with the uni- verse which God created. They are what our Creator has made them, and, with the exceptions detailed in former portions of this work, we have in general little or no influence over them, so far as their mere original nature is concerned ; but these entities, simple and composite, are the mate- rials with which, and the motives in view of which, all the active operations of the soul are performed. As these active operations are either directly or indirectly, mediately or immediately, under our in- dividual control ; as it is by these actions that we exert our influence on the other rational and senti- ent beings associated with us in this probationary world, an influence always operating for evil or for ACTIVE OPERATIONS OF THE SOUL. 199 good ; and as it is only through these active opera- tions that the character of our cognitive and senti- ent states of mind, be they good or evil, can make their influence felt on others, it must be evident that these active operations constitute the principal and most important part of our mental phenomena, that part more immediately contemplated in the precepts and sanctions of the moral government of Jehovah. A man may harbour sentiments of the rankest infidelity, and so long as he keeps them se- cret, so long as he does not perform the active op- eration of communicating them to others, either orally or in writing, they will exert no direct ten- dency to contaminate those around him. Perhaps, if he could prevent his sentiments from influencing his own conduct in the neglect of duty and in giv- ing direction to his agency through life, his opin- ions and feelings would injure no one but himself. But so soon as they are manifest in his active oper- ations, which in most instances is very soon the case, their baneful tendency is seen and felt by his associates, and by all within the circle of his influ- ence, either personal or literary. In accordance with this is the common sentiment of mankind, that propriety of conduct is more important than the ex- tent of our knowledge or the acuteness of our sen- sibility ; that to do right is more valuable and meri- torious than to know accurately or to reason clearly. Before we proceed in the attempt to enumerate the several species of active operations, we shall first call your attention to the criteria hy which men- tal operations of the third class are distinguished. The more we compare the active, operations of the 200 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. soul with its knowledge and feeling, the more dis- tinctly do we perceive that they are radically dif- ferent in their nature. The marks of distinction are such as the follow- ing : (1.) One grand feature of this diversity is, that, while knowledge and feeling are effects, ultimately produced upon the mind by external entities, our active operations are mainly causes originating in the mind, or rather they are the mind itself, exert- ing its influence on the entities which are the sub- jects of its action. Knowledge and feeling are in- ward effects produced from without ; the active op- erations are outward effects caused from within. In short, in the two former mental operations we are, to a certain extent, passive recipients of exter- nal influence ; but in the third we are the active agents, ourselves originating the action. (2.) The entities by which our cognitive and sen- tient ideas are excited, must have an existence be- fore we can have either knowledge or feeling by them ; but the action, which is the subject of our volition, is yet future, and cannot have an existence at the time when we resolve to perform it. I can have no knowledge of an orange or a peach which has no existence, nor can either affect my palate by feeling unless it exist ; but when I will or re- solve to perform any action, the act which I deter- mine to perform has no existence at the time when I resolve upon doing it. (3.) Our feeling is, in some measure, and our knowledge still more, dependant for its character MATERIALS FOR HUMAN ACTION. 201 on the entities which produce it. But when we re- solve to perform an action, that action does not ne- cessarily depend for its character on anything with- out us ; it is what, within the limits of the laws of nature, we determine that it shall be. Of Entities as the Materials on which our Active Operations are performed. As the soul, in both cognitive and sentient oper- ations, is the subject of the influence of entities without us ; so the active operations of the soul have also their subjects on which the exerted ac- tion is performed. This subject is, in every in- stance, entities without the mind, which is the case even when some operation is performed upon ideas. Entities of every class and of every species are the materials which, in a greater or less degree, are within the range of our active influence ; and on these all our active operations are performed. The soul, like a mechanist, goes to work on these ma- terials, and is capable of producing various combi- nations, modifications, and alterations in them, lim- ited indeed by the laws of its own nature, and the na- ture of these materials ; but nevertheless important in themselves, and sufficient to enable us to accom- plish the customary purposes of daily life, and the grand ultimate end of our existence upon earth. In order that you may be prepared for under- standing the active operations of the soul, it will be advantageous to fix in your minds a specific view of the various materials for human action. These are the following : 202 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. (a.) The external objective entities of the differ- ent classes. {b.) Past mental operations of any class ; that is, mental representatives of entities, and sentient ideas, and active operations either of our own or other minds. (c.) The natural signs by which these represent- atives or ideas are expressed ; such as, (1.) The sounds which constitute oral language, and (2.) The signs employed ; such as the expression of the coun- tenance, gesture, and pantomime in general. The artificial marks or letters by which these sounds are designated in written or printed language, might at first view appear to be an additional class of ma- terials, but they are merely the results of physical action on paper or other materials, which are em- braced in the class of external entities already des- ignated. CHAPTER I. DIVISION AND DISCUSSION OF THE ACTIVE OPERATIONS OF THE SOUL. All the active processes of the soul are essen- tially alike, so far as mere activity is concerned ; but they differ in the end contemplated by each, in the operation performed, in the different results of the action, and in the different objects on which they terminate. The first place among these ac- INSPECTION. 203 tive processes seems, for various reasons, to be due to what may be termed the process of inspection, by which we mean the survey or investigation of entities. SECTION I. Of Inspection. By Inspection we would designate that active operation in which the attention of the soul is direct- ed to some entity, simple or composite; prospective, present, or retrospective ; with a view to acquire some knowledge concerning it. Or, in other w r ords, inspection is that active process of the mind by which w r e contemplate, either some external entity through the bodily organs, or some idea or operation of the mind, without employing the bodily organs, at least at the time. Some of the ideas thus inspected, are often ideas originally obtained through the bod- ily organs ; although this is not always the case. Thus, we inspect the objects in nature around us, and the result of this act of inspection is a knowl- edge of the properties perceptible to us. Thus, also, we inspect a train of argument, which we late- ly heard, on the importance of phrenology ; and the result is the belief, or knowledge, that the mer- its of that science are much overrated, and that it affords few instructions that can safely be relied on, beyond those general indications w T hich have long since been established as a branch of physiognomy. Or, I inspect the abstract proposition, " That things equal to the same thing are equal to one another," and perceive, acquire a knowledge of its truth ; or 204 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. the metaphysical proposition, " It is impossible for the same thing to be and not to be at the same time," and I judge, perceive, know its truth. The sphere in which this operation is conducted, embra- ces all the entities within our knowledge, including our own mind and its operations, as well as our ideas concerning all these entities. If the entities inspected were always present, external entities, and never retrospective or prospective, the defini- tion might be altered thus : Inspection is that active operation in which, by a voluntary effort, the atten- tion of the soul is directed to some one or more of the bodily organs, and that organ directed to a par- ticular entity. Thus, when a man wiio is partially deaf, and does not hear the carriage that is rush- ing on at some little distance behind him, is called to by a person standing near him to look at the car- riage approaching, the information conveyed to him through the ear induces him to look at, that is, in- spect the entity by which his safety is endangered. By what action is this accomplished ? First, by volition or resolution to inspect ; secondly, by a di- rection of the bodily organ towards the entity to be inspected ; and, thirdly, by directing the atten- tion of the soul to the organ, or, rather, to the rays of light reflected from the carriage to the retina of the eye. But when we contemplate the mind it- self or its operations, or when we take a retrospect of an external entity, that is, inspect our knowledge of a past entity, or when we view an entity, either past, present, or prospective, in its relation to some abstract truth, or proposition, or law, the bodily or- FIRST ACTIVE OPERATION, INSPECTION. 205 gan is not used at all ; and to embrace such cases, the definition must be more general. The specific objects of the soul in this inspection may be various. In present entities its object may be, and its results are, the following : (1.) To obtain more correct mental representa- tives of the properties of entities. For instance, suppose the Capitol of the United States were the subject of our inspection. We direct our attention to it, and, in so doing, also our eyes, and the first glance gives us an idea of its general structure. "We, however, wish to acquire a more minute ac- quaintance with its structure, and for this specific purpose continue to direct our eyes and our atten- tion successively to every part of it. We may ex- amine it with a specific design of ascertaining its general plan, or the execution of any particular part of the work, such as that performed by the mason, or the plasterer, or the carpenter ; and thus, by re- peated and continued inspection, we acquire more correct and minute mental representatives of the external entity. (2.) The second object in inspecting present en- tities may be to give more vividness to our mental representatives of them. This vividness may per- haps consist in the additional feeling, excited by a reiterated and attentive inspection. After having examined all the features of a painting, we have a correct mental representative of it ; but we may resolve to fix our attention successively on its dif- ferent features, and exert the intensity of that atten- tion on them ; and thus, perhaps, it is in part, that S 206 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. our ideas of it become more vivid, because our feel- ings are more interested. (3.) We may inspect entities with the express view of ascertaining their relations. Thus, we in- spect different entities for the purpose of ascertain- ing their relation of sameness, or diversity, or con- tiguity, or causation. In all these examinations, the accuracy of our results will greatly depend on the deliberateness and degree of attention with which the process is conducted. Particular caution is re- quisite, when the design of our inspection is to as- certain the relation of causation between entities, or to decide, whether the relation be one of mere an- tecedence and sequence. In inspecting the moral character of any action, that is, its relation of congruity or incongruity with some law of God, inferred by reason from the works of nature, or learned from Revelation, the relation may be so obvious as to be instantaneously per- ceived, and thus our judgment is intuitive. In otner cases, the moral character of the action may not be so clear, and then continued attention and investigation are requisite, either to ascertain, by an induction of facts, the real tendency of the actions in question, or by continued exegetical investiga- tions, conducted according to the laws of impartial hermeneutics, to ascertain the true sense of Scrips ture, to determine whether the disputed action is or is not interdicted in the Sacred Volume. For the same general purposes, namely, to ascer- tain the relations of entities, the mechanist exam- ines, inspects the materials which he designs to em- FIRST ACTIVE OPERATION, INSPECTION. 207 ploy. Thus the carpenter inspects a piece of wood in order to discover its relation of fitness or unfit- ness for the specific purpose for which he intends it, or with a view to perform some voluntary action on it, such as sawing, planing, or cutting it. In the case of retrospective entities, simple or composite. (1.) These we inspect, or rather our mental representatives of them, in order to revive those representatives, that is, as it is popularly ex- pressed, to refresh our memory. Experience proves, that both knowledge and feeling have a tendency to vanish from the mind. Both become weakened by time, and, unless revived by retrospection, will be lost to us, at least in the present world. When we reflect on the instances of extraordinary memory on record, and combine with them the fact, that some persons of very ordinary powers of retention have, under the influence of disease, recollected facts which they had long forgotten, and rehearsed extended passages of authors in a language un- known to them, which they had heard repeated many years before, but which in health they were utterly unable to repeat, we may well be inclined to regard thought as indestructible, and think it probable that all the mental operations of our whole life will be recollected by us in eternity, and per- haps these reminiscences will be one of the princi- pal bases of our future happiness or misery. But in the present life, there is a constant tendency in the mind to forget what is long past, if it be not re- vived by reinspection. ^2.) The second object of inspecting retrospect- 208 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. ive entities is to view their relations to each other ; that is, to compare them with each other, or a present entity with a prospective one. Thus, we may in- spect the relation of causation between the British Stamp Act and our Revolutionary War, both being retrospective entities ; or we may examine the re- lation of causation between our Revolutionary War and our present enjoyment of free institutions; in which case we compare a retrospective and a pres- ent entity or idea. Finally, we may consider the relation of probable causation between our Revolu- tionary War and a future regeneration and remodel- ling of all the governments in Europe ; here we compare a past with a future entity. In this last example we have an instance of the inspection of the prospective knowledge of entities. All the subjects of our prospective knowledge may be sub- jects of inspection. Indeed, this department of our knowledge, more than any other, seems to be the fruit of voluntary inspection. Every hypothetical case that can be imagined is, at least in part, an in- spection of prospective entities. The process of inspection embraces all the vol- untary operations which, in former systems, have been attributed to the faculties of perception, con- sciousness, conception, judgment in moral as well as intellectual and physical cases, voluntary recol- lection, analytic reasoning, and conscience. That the operations of the mind termed perceptions, when voluntary, are embraced in the process of inspec- tion, is evident from what was said on the subject of the inspection of present entities. That the op- FIRST ACTIVE OPERATION, INSPECTION. 209 erations usually ascribed to conception are nothing else than inspection, is evident from the remarks made on the inquiry, how many of our supposed faculties furnish us with knowledge, or how many of the operations of the supposed faculties are cog- nitive in their character. The only cases which, might seem to militate against the classification of the operations of conception under the process of inspection are abstract ideas, such as virtue, vice, &c. But we have already exhibited to you the proof, that these terms designate our ideas of cer- tain relations of real entities which are observed by inspection. The conception of the meaning of a proposition, is nothing more than the inspection of retrospective knowledge, aided by the signs called words, either written or oral. In the inspection of present entities, the entity itself is the subject of inspection. In the inspection of retrospective entities, however, it is not the entity itself, but onr knowledge of it, which is the subject of our inspection. This seems evident from the fact, lhat, if our original knowledge of an entity was incorrect, a review of it, however frequent, will not rectify it ; unless we compare our knowledge with the original entity itself, or with a description of it by another, whose knowledge was more accurate, and in whose testimony we confide ; whereas, every attentive review of a present entity tends to correct any error in our first idea of it. These facts also prove the fallacy of Dr. Brown's opinion, that all mental operations are merely the mind itself in certain states. When we review our knowledge, S2 210 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. are not the passive, inert items of this knowledge manifestly different from the active being, or mind, which is at work on them ? As well might we say- that the wood, out of which the cabinet-maker is framing a desk or table, is nothing else than the workman himself, in a certain state. The act of memorizing is an active operation em- braced under the process of inspection. It may- be defined thus : The act of memorizing is a vol- untary, repeated, attentive review of some entities, or of our ideas of them, or of some signs of such ideas, in order that we may have a retrospective knowledge of either the ideas of the entities, or the ideas of the associated signs. Thus, if we commit to memory a piece of composition with a view to speak it verbatim, we make the recollection of our ideas of the sounds, which are associated with the ideas of the entities, the subjects of our chief at- tention. But if we wish to recollect only the ideas of the entities themselves, we pay little attention to the ideas of the sounds, and leave them to be re- called at the time of delivery by the ideas of the entities. Thus, it is evident, we are able to make different things the subjects of our aim in the act of committing to memory, and different persons have different habits on this subject. The man who, as it is usually expressed, recollects only ideas, is one who by habit, or possibly by a con- stitutional predisposition, recollects principally the ideas of the entities themselves about which he is speaking, and trusts to the association formed in his mind between the ideas of the entities and those SECOND ACTIVE OPERATION, ARRANGEMENT. 211 of the sounds designating them, for the suggestion of words at the time of speaking. The man dis- tinguished for verbal memory, on the contrary, is one who is in the habit of inspecting the ideas of the sounds as well as of the entities signified by them ; and to his mind, in the moment of delivery, the very words recur in which he had committed the speech. Perhaps, in the one case, the train of the ideas of the signs is the leading train, on which the retrospective energy of his mind is expended ; and this train of the ideas of sounds does, in the moment of delivery, recall the parallel train of the ideas of entities. In the other case, the train of the ideas of entities is the prominent one which re- curs, and, by association, brings with it the train of the ideas of the connected sounds. Yet, as there is no relation at all between the ideas of sounds except that of contiguity, whereas the ideas of the entities are related by the additional connexion sub- sisting between them in a well-digested composi- tion, it is not improbable that the ideas of the en- tities discussed are in most cases the prominent train in the recollection ; and the different degrees in which sounds are recollected form the difference between ideal and verbal memories. That analytic reasoning is also chiefly a process of inspection, is evident from its nature, as it consists of the successive investigation of a series of particulars, from which eventually a general conclusion is inferred to be applicable to all other particulars of the same kind. Thus we learn from observation (inspection), that a number of material objects, such as trees, stones, portions of lead, water, earth, &c, gravitate 212 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. towards the centre of the earth. Hence, as we find this property to belong to all material objects, with- out excepiton, which we have examined, we infer, with the greatest probability, that it belongs also to all other material substances. Our syllogism will then stand thus : Trees, stones, lead, water, earth, &c, gravitate towards the centre of the earth : Trees, stones, lead, water, earth, &c, are all the material bodies which are within the reach of our examination : Therefore all the material bodies which are with- in the reach of our observation, gravitate towards the centre of the earth. Should we invert this reasoning, and form our syllogism in the synthetic mode, it would run thus: All material bodies, within the reach of our ob- servation, gravitate towards the centre of the earth : Stone is a material body within the reach of our observation : Therefore stone gravitates towards the centre of the earth. The analytic method is best adapted to the in- vestigation of subjects, and the synthetic to the communication of knowledge already attained. In all its reasonings, however, the mind is gov- erned by certain principles of its own structure, or haws of Belief) the most important of which it may not be unimportant to enumerate. These truths are, however, not abstract or general in their intrin- sic nature or form, in which they operate on. the mind. They are, indeed, often formed into general truths, and by some writers these general truths LAWS OF HUMAN BELIEF. 213 were supposed to possess greater strength of evi- dence than the individual cases from which they are derived. But this is incorrect. The general truth is merely an abstract statement, derived from the individual cases, and embracing them all, and, consequently, cannot possibly possess stronger pro- bative influence than the individuals of which it is composed. With this explanation, we proceed to state the Fundamental Laws of Human Belief. All men make the following constitutional judg- ments, in each individual case as it occurs : 1. That the testimony of their senses, when clear- ly ascertained, is true. This truth has never been sincerely doubted by any man in his senses, not even by those skeptics who, in theory, professed to do so. 2. That the testimony of consciousness is entitled to our confidence in every case. This is, indeed, the fundamental source of our knowledge of all our mental operations, of our cognitions, of our feelings, and of our active processes of mind. If this chan- nel, so to speak, through which all our knowledge passes, were unworthy of confidence, of course no other item of our knowledge, of any kind whatever, could claim a higher degree of certainty. 3. That the testimony of memory, when distinct, and so far as distinct, may be relied on as true. I am just as certain that I lately re-examined the prophecies of Daniel, and the Revelation of St. John, on the second coming of our Saviour, a sub- ject now arresting so much attention in some parts 214 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. of our country, as that I see the pen with which I am now writing. Our confidence in our reminis- cences is strong in proportion to the degree of dis- tinctness which they appear to us to possess. Yet our recollection of a general fact may often be perfectly distinct, while we recollect but imperfect- ly some of its attendant circumstances. In this case our confidence in the former is unwavering, and our belief in the latter doubtful. I remember with great certainty my having read Dr. Channing's sermon at the ordination of Mr. Sparks upward of twenty years ago, and also Professor Stuart's letters in reply to it ; yet of some of the arguments and explanations contained in these works, my recollec- tion is indistinct. But I can, on this account, no more doubt that I perused these productions, than if it had occurred yesterday. 4. That all the other operations of our mind, such as reasonings and judgment, may be relied on with a degree of certainty proportioned to their nature, and to the circumstances under which they are per- formed. 5. That all men naturally speak the truth, when they have no motive to practise deception. 6. That every act of consciousness presupposes or implies a conscious being, the soul. On occasion of every such act we constitutionally judge the exist- ence of a conscious subject, to whom these acts be- long. The only case we have met with of an in- dividual who disbelieved the existence of his soul, is that of Rev. Simon Browne, of England, a dis- senting minister, of excellent character, who died about 1732. " He imagined, that in consequence LAWS OF HUMAN BELIEF. 215 of an extraordinary interposition of Divine power, his rational soul was gradually annihilated, and that nothing was now left of him but a principle of ani- mal life, which he held in common with the brutes." But no man can be at a loss for the proper solution of this melancholy phenomenon. All will just as readily regard it as the result of mental derange- ment, as if he had denied the axioms of mathemat- ics, or disbelieved the existence of his body. The circumstance which so preyed upon his mind as to deprive him of reason, was the death of his wife and only son, in 1723.* 7. That every act of memory, or succession of acts of consciousness, implies our personal identity, and is the occasion which elicits the constitutional judgment of such identity. Nor is this judgment of our identity destroyed, even if consciousness and memory, yea, all conscious mental action, is for a season interrupted. A very singular case, illustra- tive of this fact, was reported to the Royal Acade- my of Sciences in France. " A nobleman of Lau- sanne, as he was giving orders to a servant, sudden- ly lost his speech and all his senses. Different rem- edies were tried without effect for six months, du- ring all which time he appeared to be in a deep sleep, or deliquium, with various symptoms at differ- ent periods. At last, after some chirurgical opera- tions, at the end of six months his speech and senses were suddenly restored. When he recovered, the servant to whom he had been giving orders when he was first seized with the distemper, happening to * See the Narrative of his case in the Adventurer, No. 88. 216 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. be in the room, he asked whether he had executed his commission : not being sensible, it seems, that any interval of time, except, perhaps, a very short one, had elapsed during his illness. He lived ten years after, and died of another disease."* Dr. Beattie also cites his own experience in support of the same view. " That consciousness may be in- terrupted by a total deliquium, without any change in our notions of our own identity, I know by my own experience. I am, therefore, fully persuaded that the identity of this substance, which I call my soul, may continue even when I am unconscious of it ; and if for a shorter space, why not for a longer ?"f 8. In addition to the above constitutional truths, there are some other judgments, not intuitive, indeed, but early acquired and universally entertained, which also lie at the basis of much of our reasoning. Thus all men judge that the laws of nature and the known properties of all entities or objects in the ivorld will, ivith almost entire certainty, continue, because they have found them to continue with absolute invaria- bleness during the whole time of their observation and recollection. 9. Different kinds of truth are found to be pos- sessed of different kinds and degrees of evidence. And we have reason to believe that the Author of ■ our nature has invested every truth, which he has placed within our sphere of observation, with a de- gree of evidence sufficient, when fully and impar- tially weighed, to produce just as strong a convic- tion as he designs us to feel. * Dr. Beattie, on Truth, p. 36. t Essay on Truth, p. 36. REASONING. 217 These principles are presupposed in all kinds of reasoning. The different species of reasoning are influenced by the nature of the subject or entity under investigation. Analytic reasoning may relate to physical, intellectual, or moral subjects or entities. In the investigation of physical objects, the ma- terials for reasoning must be acquired through our bodily senses, on the testimony of which we confi- dently rely. In the investigation of intellectual objects, the phenomena of mind are the materials for reasoning, and these we acquire by the testimony of conscious- ness, which we judge to be true. In the investigation of moral truth, in its most limited sense, the moral relations of rational beings to each other and to God, as well as the relation of their actions to the Divine law, are the materials for reasoning ; and in the acquisition of our knowledge of these, we rely on the accuracy of consciousness and other powers of the soul, as well as on the tes- timony of our senses when the actions of men are concerned. But, as it is not our design to embrace Logic in this treatise, Ave shall not enter into the discussion of these different processes of ratiocina- tion. SECTION II. Of Arrangement. Arrangement is hat active operation of the soul by ivhich we select sl me from among the mass, either of external entities themselves, or of our mental rep- resentatives of them, and place them, as wholes or T 218 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. units, in a particular order, with a view to a specific purpose. In present entities, the entities themselves are the subjects of the arrangement. Thus, having a number of ivory balls of different colours before us, after having inspected them, the result of this inspection is a knowledge of their shape, colour, &c, and nothing more than knowledge. But when we select those of the same colour from the mass and place them together, we perform an additional and distinct operation, viz., that of arrangement. In addition to the present entities themselves, this operation is also performed on our mental repre- sentatives of retrospective and prospective entities. "When, e. g., we resolve to arrange into classes all the various animals which we have ever seen, and of which we have a recollection, we can accom- plish the work, though not one of those animals be present. But then it is not the animals themselves (present entities) which we arrange into different classes of quadrupeds, bipeds, carnivorous, grami- nivorous, oviparous, viviparous, &c, but only our mental representatives or cognitive ideas of them. The purposes of this arrangement, and the princi- ples on which it is made, may be various. (1.) We may arrange them according to any one of the various relations of entities to each other ; such as sameness, diversity, contiguity, cau- sation, majority, minority, progression, proportion, &c. Thus the mental act of comparison in lan- guage is nothing else than the arrangement of two entities according to the relation of similarity, to- gether with an expression of their relation in words. SECOND ACTIVE OPERATION, ARRANGEMENT. 219 E. g., " Virtue is the pillar of a republic." This sentence means, that virtue in a republic resembles the pillar of an edifice, which supports the fabric. Comparison may be performed on present entities, or on our ideas of them. The arithmetical processes of addition, subtrac- tion, division, multiplication, are so many species of this second active operation, arrangement, per- formed by man on different numbers. Addibility, subtractibility, &c, i. e., the capacity of being thus operated on, are properties of the absolute entity number ; but the operation of addition, &c, is an active process of the mind of man on these prop- erties. Addition is the arrangement of several numbers into one class or sum; division is the ar- rangement of a certain number into a given num- ber of parts ; subtraction is the arrangement of some of the integral parts of a given number into a separate class or number ; and multiplication is the addition of a sum a given number of times. (2.) The second principle according to which the process of arrangement may be conducted, is that of genus, species, class, &c. The difference between this and the first mode of arrangement is, that in the former only one classification is em- braced, whereas, in the latter, there are several grades of similarity. The arrangement of entities differs from the mere reinspection of them, in the fact, that the latter always embraces merely the view of entities, without including any change effected in their relations to other entities or ideas. In- spection can only view the universe of entities as it 220 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. exists at the time of inspection, but arrangement changes their order, or connexion, or relation, by bringing those into contiguity which were separate before, and by separating such as were before con- tiguous. By this process, we form all the varieties of mental associations which are based on any nat- ural principle or affinity ; while unnatural and ar- bitrary associations are the product of what we term the third active process, modification. The musician, who composes a piece of music, performs this process of arrangement. He takes the several individual notes or sounds, and places them into such relation as, by the constitutional in- fluence which they exert on our minds, will produce the effects at which he aims. The act of recording such composition by writing is a process of physi- cal agency. (3.) This arrangement may be made according to the probative relation of entities to a given prop- osition or to the human mind. The order in which i evidence, that is, related entities are arranged, gives | them more or less force or influence upon the mind. | This is well understood by the advocate, the logi- } cian, and the intelligent and faithful preacher. The | successful arrangement of our knowledge or argu- j ments according to their probative relations to the i human mind, constitutes the all-important operation of synthetic reasoning, so far as its object is to pro- duce in others, conviction of truths already known | to the speaker or writer. The capacity of reason- ! ing clearly, in a public speaker or writer, is nothing else than the ability to arrange his ideas or. argu- ; SECOND ACTIVE OPERATION, ARRANGEMENT. 221 ments in their best probative order, and in that order in which they produce their greatest convin- cing effect, to enunciate them in words, or record them in written signs, which will recall those words to all who read (i. e., inspect) them. Thus we see that analytic reasoning, or, more properly, investi- gation, is an operation of inspection, while synthetic reasoning, that is, the logical arrangement of the result and evidences of our investigation, is chiefly an instance of the second active operation, viz., Arrangement. The formation of generic proposi- tions, in which the results of our investigations are synthetically proposed, is a process of abstraction or generalization, and thus belongs to the active process, modification. The presentation of the whole to others in oral or written language belongs to the last active operation, namely, the communi- cation of our ideas to others, or intellectual inter- course with other minds. Evidence, objectively considered, is the tendency or fitness of any one entity in the physical, intel- lectual, or moral universe, or of its relations, to make the reality of another supposed entity credi- ble, that is, apparent to the mind. Evidence, sub- jectively considered, is the tendency of our knowl- edge of some entity, or its relations, to make our knowledge of other entities, or their relations, ap- pear true. Here is presented to our view one of the grandest features of intellectual science — truth based upon the rock of the universe, which God founded, while our knowledge is but the shadow or reflection of it, merely its mental representative. T 2 222 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. The probative order or relation of entities to a certain proposition, seems to consist in their being detached from all irrelevant appendages, and placed in such connexion of contiguity or succession, in relation to the proposition, as is best calculated for the inspection of the hearer, so as to present the greatest facility for the operation of inspection by the auditors or readers. The more completely ar- guments are separated from everything irrelevant, the more easily can they be inspected by the mind. Every species of syllogism is nothing- else than a particular arrangement of certain entities, or rather of propositions expressing our ideas of them, such as is best calculated to facilitate their inspection ; and the art of reasoning well is nothing else than the habit of arranging the related ideas in this way for easy inspection. Before we exemplify these observations by the examination of the process of reasoning itself, we would remind the student of the classification of composite entities, that is, of relations as the bases of verbs in human language : for, as all syllogisms embrace verbs, an accurate idea of the nature of verbs is essential to the com- prehension of the subject. We have, on a former occasion, remarked that the words in human lan- guage originally and most naturally expressing sub- stantive entities are in grammar substantives, and those standing for adjective entities are originally adjectives. But it is the verbs which alone most naturally express the relations subsisting between different entities. In pursuing our examination of syllogisms, we begin with the several parts, and SYLLOGISMS. 223 first inquire, What are they ? They consist of hu- man language, of propositions. These describe some of our mental representatives or ideas ; and the question is, Of what entities are they represent- atives, of substantive, or adjective, or composite entities, or of all combined ? An example will best illustrate these observations in their application to the structure of the syllogism. Major proposition: If there is a God, he ought to be worshipped. Minor proposition : But there is a God. Conclusion : Therefore he ought to be worship- ped. Here the term God, or letters G, o, d, express the sound, which, in our language, is the sign of a certain idea, which idea is our mental representa- tive of a real entity, viz., the great Author of the universe. This is a substantive entity. The phrase " ought to be worshipped'' is a verb, and expresses our idea of a certain composite entity, viz., the rela- tion of moral fitness or obligation between the two parts of a composite entity, viz., God (a Being of a certain character), and his rational creatures wor- shipping him. The major proposition, therefore, expressed in the language of our system, would run thus: "If there be an entity corresponding to the idea designated by the sound which is spelled by the letters G-o-d, he ought to be worshipped ;" i. e., we see the relation of suitableness between him and those actions of his rational creatures called the worship of him. The major proposition, when closely examined, seems evidently to be nothing 224 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. else than a sentence expressing in words our ideas of a composite entity, i. e., of the relation of two simple entities to each other. The simple entities are, (1.) A Being corresponding to the idea desig- nated by the sound and word God ; and, (2.) Those actions of his rational creatures, which they per- form with a view of worshipping him ; and the relation between them is that of suitableness. The process by which this relation is known is none other than that of inspection. The result of inspection is, in all cases, knowledge ; and in this case likewise we can trace no other operation than the act of inspecting the two parts of a composite entity, God and the worship of him by rational creatures, and the result of this inspection is, con- viction of the relation. This knowledge or convic- tion is not optional, but necessary. The minor proposition, philosophically stated, runs thus : " But there is an entity corresponding to the mental rep- resentative designated by the sound, which we de- scribe by the letters G-o-d ;" " hence he ought to be worshipped" is the conclusion or relation per- ceived by the mind. It is evident that the only point to be proved in this syllogism is the minor, viz., that there exists an entity which we designate by the term God, and this must be done, and can be done, only by the successive inspection of the entities which constitute the proof. MODIFICATION. 22o SECTION III. Of Modification. The third active operation or process is termed modification, and embraces a class of operations distinct in their nature from those which have pre- ceded. Modification is that active operation of the soul, by which we take some from among our mental representatives of real entities (rarely the objective entities themselves), and bring them into such forms or combinations as do not correspond to realities; that is, make arbitrary substantive and composite en- tities out of them. The materials on which these op- erations are performed are seldom objective enti- ties themselves, but generally^ are our mental rep- resentatives of them. This operation is distinguish- ed from the two preceding by the following dis- tinct peculiarities : (1.) The operations of inspec- tion and arrangement act as generally on objective entities themselves, as on our mental representa- tives of them ; whereas, that of modification is con- versant chiefly about our ideas. (2.) The former two operations take our mental representatives of substantive entities as wholes or units, and leave them such throughout all the process of their influ- ence ; take our ideas of the combination of prop- erties found coexisting, and leave these combina- tions unaltered ; but modification changes them from their natural state, and brings their constituent parts or elements into forms and combinations which do not exactly correspond to real entities. This operation embraces, among others, the follow- ing processes : 226 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. 1. The process of abstraction and generalization ; that is, the process of framing ideas and combina- tions of ideas, which do not fully represent any one entity, but are used to express a whole class of in- dividual entities which have, in common, the prop- erties expressed by the generic idea and term. Thus the idea quadruped is formed by the process of abstraction. We take the combinations of our mental representatives of the properties found co- existing in each of the several animals, horse, cow, sheep, dog, &c. We compare with each other our ideas of these several combinations of properties, each one of which combinations is found coexisting in one or other of these animals. Thus comparing these several combinations of ideas, we omit from each every individual idea which is peculiar to itself, until at last we have nothing remaining but the idea of four legs, as the property or peculiarity which they have in common, and by which they are distinguished from animals of a different class. In considering this process, let it be recollected that our mental representative of each one of the differ- ent coexisting objective properties is separate and independent. We can therefore, with the greatest ease, abstract from our ideas of the combination, any one or more of its elements at option, and use the residue as a substantive entity in our ratiocina- tions. It is in this way that all generic terms are formed. If we examine the ideas conveyed to the mind by the term quadruped and the phrase four legs, we instantly perceive a great distinction between PROCESS OF MODIFICATION. 227 them : the latter designates our idea of a part of an animal, while the former signifies not only a whole animal, but a whole class of animals each of which has four legs. But it is evident that the idea ex- pressed by the term quadruped does not correspond with any individual entity intended by it, any far- ther than the circumstance of its having four legs. The term quadruped, therefore, expresses one of those general ideas which we refer to the process of abstraction. Thus also the idea expressed by the term all, when definitely used, does not corre- spond fully to any real entity, but is a generic idea embracing a great number of entities. Of the same character, generically, are negations, and the ideas expressed by particles of speech which have no objective entity in nature corre- sponding to them. They are, though of differ- ent kinds, the product of this power of modifica- tion. Thus the word " nothing" expresses a nega- tive generic idea, and is equivalent to not a solid, not a liquid, not a gas, not light, not caloric, &c, &c. The idea is acquired by the perception of the absence of one entity after another, and ultimately the supposed absence of all entities. Generally, however, when we use the term nothing, we em- ploy it in a qualified sense. About absolute no- thing we seldom speak, and can say but little in- telligently. Generic propositions are formed by striking out from a specific proposition, the name of the in- dividual objective entity of which the predicate of the proposition may be affirmed, and soibstitu- 228 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. ting in its stead some generic name, which com- prehends all the individual objective entities to which the predicate is believed to be applicable. One of the most important rules of correct reason- ing is, that the utmost caution be always observed not to introduce into our general proposition a term more generic than our actual examinations warrant, not so general as to include any entity, of which we are not certain that the predicate really belongs to it, or in regard to which our experience is not sufficiently extensive, and also uniform so far as it goes. This process of generalization or abstrac- tion is one of the most important among all our mental operations. Among its results are embraced, (1.) Geometrical axioms ; (2.) Metaphysical axioms ; (3.) Mathemat- ical truths ; (4.) Moral general truths or principles ; such as, virtue is productive of happiness and vice of misery. Hence the opinion of Kant and many other German philosophers, that knowledge of this kind is a priori, that is, inherent in the mind, is erroneous. There are, indeed, many truths which may be characterized as universal and unchangeable, which are the prop- erties assigned by him to the truths of pure reason (Reine Vernunft). And there can be no objection to calling them transcendental. But they do not differ in their nature from other ideas. Viewed subjectively, these general ideas are phenomena of our minds, are mental representatives of actual re- lations in nature, abstracted from the entities in which they are found. Viewed objectively, gen- kant's view of a priori knowledge. 229 eral truths are relations actually existing in na- ture, not in an abstract, but in a concrete state, be- tween different individual entities. Thus the axiom, " Things which are equal to the same thing are equal to one another," is nothing else than a prop- osition expressing the relation of agreement be- tween different entities, and especially the truth taught by experience, that any two of them which are equal to a third, will also be found equal to each other. But if it be inquired whether these truths are a priori knowledge, we reply in the nega- tive. The individual relation of equality between the different objects existed before we perceived it ; but the general, abstract, subjective idea of this relation, having been formed from the ideas of the individual relations perceived, must necessarily be subsequent to our (empyric) perceptions of the in- dividual relations. The general truth has nothing in nature corresponding to it ; because all actual relations and entities are individual. It therefore exists only as an idea in the mind of man. There are, indeed, some laws of the mind itself, which reg- ulate and limit its operations, our knowledge of which is not derived from the observation of exter- nal nature. These laws, it is admitted, exist prior to our knowledge of them. But so do the laws of the material universe. And just as we derive our knowledge of the laws of the physical universe by observation of external nature, so we acquire our knowledge of the laws of mind by observing the phenomena of mind. Yet, there is as much differ- ence between the laws of mind and our knowledge U 230 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. of those laws, as there is between the laws of mat- ter and our knowledge of them. Nor can we per- ceive any reason why the one should be regarded as a priori knowledge, rather than the other ; for in reality neither possesses any claim to that character. 2. Fictitious combinations of ideas : (a.) Fictitious simple entities, either substantive or adjective, i. e., fictitious persons, things, and properties, (b.) Fic- titious composite entities, or relations, or actions performed by one on the other, or existing between several. This process brings different entire sub- stantive entities into imaginary combinations, and attributes to them imaginary actions. To this spe- cies of modification belong all the operations of imagination and fancy, the active element of many specimens of wit and burlesque ; all specimens of painting, and all works of fiction, either in poetry or prose ; and also, what is of the same character, though of different design, every species of misrep- resentation, falsehood, or lying. The operations of what is termed imagination are clearly specimens of modification. The defini- tions of imagination, adopted by the best writers, sufficiently prove this. " It is the province of ima- gination," says Mr. Stewart, " to make a selection of qualities and of circumstances from a variety of dif- ferent objects, and by combining and disposing these, to form a new creation of its own." What is this else than modification, which, according to our definition, " is that active operation of the soul, by which we take some from among our mental representatives of real entities (rarely the objective entities themselves), and bring them into such forms RELATIONS OF ENTITIES. 231 or combinations as do not correspond to realities." Still more accordant with our definition of modifi- cation is that given of imagination by Dr. Aber- crombie, who says, " In the process of imagination, we take the component elements of real scenes, events, or characters, and combine them anew by a process of the mind itself, so as to form compounds which have no existence in nature." But the pro- cess of abstraction, or generalization, also consists in an operation of the same general kind, but for different purposes. Some of the processes termed wit, burlesque, and the ludicrous, partake of the same nature. Hence, as these several processes differ only in minor circumstances, while they are generically the same, it is more philosophic not to regard them as entirely different operations, but to adopt one general process of modification, and re- gard these as its different species. Thus, when the painter designs to paint an imaginary landscape of perfect beauty, how does he proceed ? He re- calls to his reminiscences all the most beautiful scenes which he has witnessed in nature, and se- lecting from them his ideas of those traits which strike him as most beautiful, he forms these into one imaginary landscape in his own mind. After this, he tries successively to imitate these several features with his pencil, that is, he records this new creation of his imagination on the canvass. The poet passes through the same process, more or less formally, only he makes his record in words instead of colours, with the pen instead of the painter's pen- cil. " Milton," says Mr. Stuart, " has, in his gar- den of Eden, created a landscape more perfect, 232 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. probably, in all its parts, than has ever been reali- zed in nature, and certainly very different from any- thing that this country (England) exhibited at the time when he wrote. It is a curious remark of Mr. Walpole, that Milton's Eden is free from the defects of the old English garden, and is imagined on the same principles, which it was reserved for the present age to carry into execution." But it was no peculiarity of Milton, that he depicted his garden as more beautiful than any which nature presents to us. This is characteristic of poets and novelists generally. They exhibit their heroes and heroines either as elevated above the bounds of hu- man perfection, or sunk below the dregs of our race. For this very reason, a fondness for works of this description is no promising trait of charac- ter, especially in the young ; and the habitual in- dulgence of it almost invariably disqualifies, in a greater or less degree, for the sober realities and the active scenes of real life. But another and still more serious objection to the great mass of popular novels, romances, tragedies, and comedies, is, that they familiarize the mind with scenes of pol- lution, and thus destroy the moral sensibilities of the soul ; and they often present vice arrayed in so many circumstances of interest, as to make the reader insensibly forget its deformity. Nor does the unfortunate end which is sometimes made to close the career of wickedness, and which is the reputed moral of the tale, at all compensate for the corrupting influence exerted on the reader's mind by long familiarity with scenes of impurity through- out the book. Even when scenes of affliction or CONNEXION BETWEEN MIND AND MATTER. 233 misfortune are presented, and the sympathy of the reader becomes deeply interested, as the whole is confessedly fictitious, and no opportunity is afford- ed to him to exercise his sympathy in efforts to re- lieve the unfortunate, the practical benevolent ten- dencies of his nature are impaired, and even his sensibility to real misfortune blunted. The sudden and arbitrary combinations of thought, which constitute the intellectual part of wit and burlesque, are in many cases different species of the process of modification, while the sentient part of these complex efforts of mind constitute the feel- ing or emotion of the ludicrous. The architect and the sculptor, likewise, first make a creation of fancy, and then endeavour to realize it by erecting some splendid and tasteful ed- ifice, or an animated, almost living statue. SECTION IV. The fourth active process is that mental agency which immediately regards and regulates the action of our bodily organs. It may be termed the men- tal direction of our physical action. It embraces all voluntary control over the entire muscular sys- tem, by which alone motion is produced in any part of the body. The intrinsic connexion between mind and matter, and the manner in which the lat- ter is made to obey the former, is a mystery to us. The fact of the obedience of the body to the mind is of daily and hourly, yea, of incessant occurrence ; but is as incomprehensible to the greatest philoso- U2 234 CONNEXION BETWEEN MIND AND MATTER. pher, as any other mystery in nature or religion. I will to hold the pen in my right hand, and so to move it as to form letters and words ; but why my right hand takes the pen rather than the left, why my fingers move the pen so as to form alphabetic letters rather than mathematical figures, I know not. I can assign no other reason than my antece- dent volition, that they should do so. And a man who has suffered a paralysis is surprised when, for the first time, he finds that the muscles of his arm or leg refuse to obey the volitions of his mind. This connexion between the mind and body, this obedience of the muscles to the will, in healthy persons, being assumed as one of the best- estab- lished facts in nature, our next inquiry is, how far is so-called physical action really physical, and how far is it mental ? It seems evident that every- thing about it, except the simple tension and relax- ation of the muscles, and consequent locomotion of the body, or some of its parts, is mental. Mechan- ical skill is an improvement of the mind in direct- ing bodily motion. Intelligence, memory, wisdom in the selection of appropriate materials, and ap- propriate bodily motions, to effect an end, are in- volved, as are also other mental processes. This agency might be divided into different kinds, according to the different organs to which it more immediately relates ; or it might be divided into the different processes effected by the hands, by the feet, the eyes, the whole body, &c. Under the operations effected by the hands would be em- braced, (1.) The different species of mechanical and MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. 235 agricultural labour ; (2.) The manipulations requi- site to performances on musical instruments, in which there is, combined with much physical ac- tivity, remarkable intellectual skill. Of the opera- tions of the feet, walking is the most remarkable. It properly results from the combined muscular ef- fort of the whole body, and consists in balancing the body by leaning forward so far that the centre of gravity is brought beyond the base, and sustain- ing the body from falling by the continued position of one foot after another in advance of the whole. In all cases of voluntary physical action, we can distinguish the following mental processes : (1.) Se- lection of the end to be accomplished ; (2.) Knowl- edge of the ways and means for its attainment ; (3.) The volition to exert the bodily organ ; (4.) The attention of the soul to the organ ; (5.) The inspec- tion of the material on which the agency is to be performed ; and, (6.) The active process of the mind conducting and regulating the physical action. SECTION V. The fifth process is that of holding intellectual intercourse with other minds ; or, as it is com- monly, though incorrectly termed, the process of communicating our ideas to others. Philosophically speaking, this process consists in exciting in others the ideas which they themselves have already obtained from those entities on which we wish them to think, and exciting them in such order, and in such combinations, and with such ad- jective properties annexed, as we wish them to en- 236 INTELLECTUAL INTERCOURSE. tertain. When we utter articulate sounds, these sounds, by their exact similitude to those which the person whom we address has heard in connexion with certain ideas, first recall his idea of the simi- lar sound formerly heard by himself, and this re- calls the idea of an entity then connected in his mind with that idea of the sound. Thus, by speak- ing to others, that is, by successively pronouncing the sounds corresponding to the train of thought in our own minds, we not only excite in others the similar ideas which they have received from enti- ties, but we bring them into new connexions, and add epithets to suit our purpose. This process of intellectual intercourse is carried on in different ways : I. By speaking-, or expressing- our ideas by ar- ticulate sounds. We are born with organs of ar- ticulation, by the voluntary action of which we can so modify the expiring breath as to produce specific articulate sounds. The air on which the action of these organs is exerted is only the ex- piring breath, the breath as it is in the act of pass- ing out from the lungs. The constant inhalation and expiration of breath is, within certain limits, involuntary, and goes on during sleep ; but wheth- er we will or will not modify this breath by the or- gans of speech, and emit it with such force as to produce sound, is voluntary. The scope of vol- untary control which we have over respiration, seems to be just as much as is necessary for speak- ing, and yet not sufficient to destroy life by a total interruption of breathing. If it were possible to MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. 237 withhold respiration entirely, a man might at any moment easily put an end to his existence. If, on the other hand, we had no control over our respi- ration, but were compelled to inspire and expire at regular intervals, our sentences would all have to be of a certain length, or our enunciation could have no reference to their punctuation, and the op- eration of speaking would be subject to such monot- onous interruptions, as would be unpleasantly me- chanical. Hence, it is evident, this voluntary con- trol was given, and this voluntary respiration with- held, for these very purposes. Children find the same pleasure in exercising their organs of articulation on the expiring breath, that they do in using their arms and legs. God has so constituted animals, that the use of their or- gans is, in itself and for its own sake, pleasant. The fishes skipping about in their watery element, the birds in the atmosphere filling it with warbling notes, exhibit such signs of enjoyment as to leave no doubt, that if the vocabulary of their language were intelligible to man, the feelings would be joy- ous which they express. For the same reason, chil- dren, when they find themselves able to talk, are prone to talk incessantly. Even before they can articulate correctly, they find, by crying, that they can in some measure control their organs of speech, and thus they learn the rudiments of oral action. By continued practice they increase this ability, and in due time they learn to articulate, that is, to speak, with tolerable accuracy. The following appears to be the manner in which 238 CONNEXION OF WORDS WITH THINGS. words become connected with things, or, rather, in which the ideas of oral words, that is, sounds, be come connected in our minds with the ideas of ex- ternal entities. Children see an entity, and hear a certain sound pronounced in connexion with it. The idea of an entity, for example, an apple, ob^ tained by sight, and the idea of the sound obtained by the ear, are received almost simultaneously, and thus, having the relation of contiguity of time, the one, by virtue of this relation, recalls the other. Thus a father approaches his child with an apple ; he stretches out the fruit that the child may take it, and, in so doing, pronounces the word apple. The child's mind thus receives, almost simultane- ously, two ideas, viz., that of the colour of the ap- ple, obtained by the eye, and that of the sound in- dicated by the written word apple, acquired by the ear. Originally the child perceives no connexion between these ideas, the one of sound and the other of colour ; but finding the two generally connected by other persons, that is, hearing the same sound pronounced by all who seem to be speaking of the same entity, the child soon learns that the one, viz., the sound apple, is used as a sign or name to des- ignate the other, the thing apple. Thus both these ideas, or items of knowledge, having been obtained together, have the relation of (temporal) contiguity, and become so closely related, that if the attention of the mind is by any means directed to the one, it spontaneously pursues this relation, and is con- ducted to the other. The idea of the colour of the apple may also at any time be recalled by the pres- MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. 239 ence of another apple, which will afford a similar idea, and thus, by the relation of similarity, recall the first. The visual idea may likewise be medi- ately recalled by seeing the letters which spell the sound which stands for that idea. These remarks show us that, parallel to our train of thoughts, the subjects of which are objective en- tities, runs another coequal train of thoughts, the subjects of which are sounds, viz., those sounds which, by experience, have become associated with those entities. But speaking is an active operation of the articulating organs consequent on a volition to communicate our wishes, commands, or other ideas, to those whom we address ; experience hav- ing taught us that others associate with certain sounds the same ideas that we do, and, therefore, that the utterance of sounds by us, similar to those which we have heard uttered by others, will excite in others the same ideas which we attach to these sounds. Properly speaking, however, we neither do nor can excite in others the same identical ideas which we connect with our words. The ideas which all men connect with words are the mental representa- tives of entities which they originally derive from entities themselves, and which they can derive from no other source. "When they hear others pronounce the same, or, rather, exactly similar sounds, they, by the relation of similarity, recall the recollection of the sounds which they formerly heard ; and the recollection of these former sounds recalls the ideas formerly associated with them. Thus, when a 240 PARALLEL AND COEQUAL TRAINS OF THOUGHTS. speaker addresses an audience, there is a truly re- markable train of collateral and parallel operations running on with the train of the speaker's ideas. Every idea of the speaker is succeeded by the fol- lowing operations before it accomplishes its design. (1.) The idea of the speaker himself. (2.) The speaker's recollection of the idea of the sound for- merly associated with that idea by himself. (3.) His volition to articulate a similar sound. (4.) The articulating action of his organs on the expiring breath to produce a similar sound. (5.) The hear- er's idea of the sound produced by the speaker's voice. (6.) The hearer's recollection of the simi- lar sound which he himself had often made. (7.) The recurrence of the idea which he formerly con- nected with the similar sound made by himself. All these parallel trains of operations attend every thought conveyed by the speaker. The security that men by this process will substantially under- stand each other, rests on the fact, that all men de- rive from an inspection of the same entity substan- tially the same representative ; otherwise there could not be any common language or communica- tion of thought among men. Our ability to make just such sounds as corre- spond to our recollection of sounds made by oth- ers, results from our being able to make at option coarser or finer, dental or labial, lingual or guttural sounds, and from our ability to discern whether the sounds which we make, and of which we have an idea so soon as we hear them, exactly resemble those which we heard from others. MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. 241 The structure of the human articulating organs is such, that all men naturally make certain element- ary sounds. These sounds are expressed by the letters of the alphabet, and are substantially the same in all languages. Even the difference ob- served in the number of letters in different langua- ges is often the result of the imperfect state of the art of designating these elementary or alphabetic sounds, and two languages whose alphabets differ most, may, when spoken, bear much greater simi- larity to each other in their elementary sounds. So far then, at least, as the elementary sounds are concerned, we must answer the long-disputed ques- tion in the affirmative, and maintain that language is of Divine origin ; because the nature of these ele- mentary sounds results from the structure of the organs which God gave us. We learn, by early habit, to articulate nearly all the elementary sounds with great promptness and certainty ; and it is thus that we learn new langua- ges ; because we can form relations of contiguity between our ideas and the words of a new tongue. Nay, although it is a rare attainment, we may, by frequent repetition and long-continued habit, form so close a connexion between old ideas which we were wont to express in our vernacular tongue, and the words of a new language, that we spontaneous- ly think in it ; that is, as we reinspect the old ideas, the corresponding words of the newly-acquired lan- guage will spontaneously recur to our memory as we advance, instead of those of our vernacular tongue. In the exercise of articulation the breath X 242 COMMUNICATION OF THOUGHTS BY WRITTEN SIG. is voluntarily modulated into those sounds : one lungs' full after another, leaving only short intervals for inspiration, just as long as we wish to convey our ideas to others ; and when this volition is ac- complished, the articulating organs become motion- less, and the breath is inhaled and exhaled without any sound, except what is termed audible breathing. II. The second means of communicating our ideas to others is by gestures and muscular action of the countenance correspondent to the thought. How far this kind of communication may be car- ried, is forcibly exhibited in pantomimic exhibitions, in which a regular succession of scenes is intelligi- bly represented by gestures and muscular expres- sion of the countenance, without the utterance of a single word. This process it is not necessary for our purpose to examine in greater detail. III. The third mode of communicating our thoughts is by written signs. These signs are of different kinds. (1.) The regular alphabetical let- ters. These designate the elementary sounds which belong to languages in general, and are virtually the same in them all. These signs, or letters, con- stitute the most perfect form of the alphabet, and in point of time were probably later than the hiero- glyphic and syllabic signs. In the Chinese lan- guage the written signs do not designate elementa- ry sounds ; but at least many of them stand for whole words, and designate those elementary ob- jects which men find it necessary to express in the infancy of knowledge ; additional words being form- ed by a combination of these. You will easily per- MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. 243 ceive, that the accumulation of signs in this lan- guage must be unusually great, and very inconve- nient. So much is this the case, that it is said very few of the most learned men in China itself are fully acquainted with all the marks of their own language, and the exact import of their numerous combinations. Of the syllabic alphabet, intermediate between the Chinese and European languages, we have a modern instance in the invention of See-qua-yah (George Guess), a North American Indian of the Cherokee tribe, which deserves notice. It consists of an alphabet of eighty-six letters, each of them designating neither an elementary sound, as in Eu- ropean languages, nor an entire word, as in the Chinese, but a syllable or part of a word. (2.) Arithmetical figures and signs, which stand for sounds designating our ideas of the entity num- ber. (3.) Musical notes, which designate our ideas of such sounds as are used in musical composition. IV. The fourth mode of expressing our thoughts is by singing. This is a voluntary effort to make certain sounds in accordance with different princi- ples, with a view to excite in ourselves or others certain feelings, and sometimes to give interest to certain truths. This mode might, indeed, be re- garded as a subdivision of the first or oral sounds. The exercise of Composition is a complex opera- tion, consisting of an act of voluntary inspection and arrangement of ideas of entities, simple or com- i 244 THE EXERCISE OF COMPOSITION. posite, together with the act of expressing the ideas thus arranged, by signs on paper ; that is, writing the ideas as arranged by us. Thus, e. g., we re- solve to compose an essay on the evils of intemper- ance. We reflect on the entity a drunkard, or our idea of him, that is, inspect it in all its various mel- ancholy and disgusting relations, and arrange our ideas with reference to the object in view, and then write them as arranged. We do not write every idea which the mind lights on in its voluntary in- spection, but only those which are particularly suit- ed to our purpose. Here the question arises, What are the new ideas, not retrospective, which we nev- er had before, but which thus oftentimes occur to the mind ? Are they not merely cognitive repre- sentatives of relations ; of new combinations of sim- ple entities, which were known before, but never precisely thus combined by the mind ? Now from these new combinations result new relations, which, when viewed by the mind, are called original or new ideas. This feature of suggestion presented some difficulty to Dr. Brown ; but, according to this view of it, its nature would be sufficiently plain. It is incorrect to say that the new idea recurred to the mind. The true statement is this : the simple en- tities thus viewed together by the mind are inactive, as are also our ideas of them ; but the mind itself is the active agent, which, in voluntarily contempla- ting, that is, inspecting the entity and its relations, perceives this, to it, new relation, which, however, existed before it was viewed, and was perhaps per- ceived by many others before, and which would MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. 245 exist in nature if it had never been viewed by any- one. The preceding five operations, viz., Inspection, Arrangement, Modification, Physical action or agen- cy, and Intellectual intercourse with other minds, appear to constitute all the specific active opera- tions of the soul. To one or other of these every operation of the mind may be referred which is in its nature active, excepting only what remains to be discussed under the mode of their occurrence. SECTION VI. Of Attention. We shall first make a few remarks on the sub- ject of attention before we inquire whether it is entitled to the rank of a distinct active process. Whatever be the active operation in which we are engaged, the clearness, success, and mnemonic te- nacity attending it, will generally be in proportion to the degree of attention exerted in the operation. Every one must have observed, that an inattentive perusal of a book leaves an indistinct impression, figuratively speaking, of its contents on the mind ; while an attentive perusal produces a directly con- trary effect. In conducting an inquiry, if the pro- cess be negligently conducted, the result may be a total failure to obtain a clear conviction ; but an attentive review, that is, reinspection, of the very same evidence, will often produce clear conviction, and dispel every doubt. The influence of attention on the degree of feel- ing excited in the mind is equally striking. In- X2 246 ATTENTION. deed, in most cases, there can be very little feeling, that is, little pleasure or pain, without attention. The t same remark is equally true of knowledge. Thus, the rays of light may be reflected from an object to the retina of the eye, and form the image there, but ! it will fail to convey knowledge to the mind, if the \ attention be not directed to it. So also the same | entity can produce no feeling unless the attention j be directed to it ; or, in other words, unless it be j observed. There are, indeed, cases of disease in which painful feeling is irresistibly produced, and ! we are not able entirely to divert our attention from it ; but in so far and so long as we can divert it, the pain is greatly diminished. Attention also greatly improves every active op- eration to which it is directed. The success and accuracy of inspection are obviously improved by it in the highest degree. Arrangement can also be performed with an accuracy and facility propor- tioned to the attention bestowed on the operation. The abstractions and generalizations of the active process of modification are in like manner greatly improved by attention. Who can doubt, that the excellence of mechanical operations, or of the exe- cution of instrumental music, requires the attention of the performer ? Or who would be guilty of the absurdity of denying, that the communication of thought on any subject, whether performed orally or in writing, can be executed with greater accu- racy, and system, and effect, when the energy, the attention of the soul, is expended on the effort ? In complex operations, also, the influence of con- MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. 247 tinued attention, that is, of attention combined with habit, is strongly displayed. Some talented indi- viduals have thus acquired the ability to conduct a simultaneous train of several operations, each of which ordinarily engrosses the attention of men separately. Thus, of Julius Caesar it is said, that he could at the same time dictate seven letters to as many secretaries, and that even when engaged in writing himself, he could dictate to four others. Attention, too intensely exerted, and too long continued upon any one subject, sometimes induces monomania. But it is a benevolent law of our na- ture, that the lassitude arising from continued atten- tion unlooses, as it were, the grasp of attention, and enables the mind to resume the natural and salutary self-control and equipoise of its powers. That attention, however, is not a distinct and separate operation, will appear evident from the fol- lowing facts : (1.) We cannot conceive of it as acting by itself, but only in connexion with some other operation of the mind. (2.) It does not give us any results of its action, distinct from those of the active operation with which it is combined. (3.) It is common to all the active operations. (4.) It seems only to be a property of the active opera- tions conducted at the time. We therefore define attention to be the energy of the soul exerted in some active operation. The causes which excite attention appear, in gen- eral, to be these. (1.) A volition to bestow atten- tion on the performance of some active operation. (2.) The present interest or pleasure felt in the op- 248 MODE OF OCCURRENCE OF ACTIVE OPERATIONS. eration itself. Thus, we commence the perusal of a book incidentally met with, not knowing what its contents may be, but soon become so interested, that the most, intense attention is excited in our breast. (3.) Some impression from without made through" the bodily organs. Thus, we may be en- gaged listening to some interesting narrative ; but, a band of musicians passing by, their music makes an impression on the organs of hearing, and it at- tracts and diverts the attention. This we suppose to be a correct view of the character of attention, which we, therefore, cannot regard as a separate or distinct active operation. CHAPTER IT. THE MODE OF OCCURRENCE OF THE TIVE ACTIVE OPERATIONS. If it be asked, tohy does the soul engage in active operations at all rather than not, we reply, the rea- son is, because the nature of the soul is active. By this we mean, that the Divine Author of our nature has so constituted the mind of man, that, du- ring his waking hours, it is unavoidably and inces- santly engaged in some one of these five active processes. Of this we can be convinced by an ex- amination of our own mental operations. On such an investigation we find, that it is not optional with us whether our minds shall be engaged in thinking MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. 249 or not ; we are constitutionally thus engaged, and can at best, by the most determined voluntary ef- fort, interrupt the succession of thought for a few seconds only. As to the manner in which this continued action is mediately sustained, several theories might be suggested ; but the fact, which is beyond dispute, is all that is requisite to the accuracy of our sys- tem ; and as we have endeavoured to avoid mere theory heretofore, we shall not at present call your attention to either of these. If it be inquired, in the second place, why does the soul, at any given time, engage in one of these active operations rather than another, the experi- ence of every individual will unhesitatingly reply, that these operations are engaged in in one of two ways : either from deliberate choice or from habit. The testimony of every man's own consciousness, if Ave mistake not, is decided and conclusive on this subject, and teaches that in one of these two ways, and in no other, do active operations at any time take place. The mode of occurrence in the active operations of the mind is twofold : I. Voluntary. II. Spontaneous. SECTION I. Of the Voluntary Occurrence of the Active Opera- tions. The active processes of the soul are voluntary, when we engage in them in consequence of a voli- tion so to do, or, to express the same in popular 250 VOLUNTARY OCCURRENCE OF ACTIVE OPERATION*. language, when they are undertaken from deliber- ate choice. That we do perform such acts of choice every hour of the day, must be evident to every impartial inquirer, from the testimony of his own consciousness. (1.) The certainty of our performing such acts of uncontrolled choice is just as evident and indu- bitable to every individual, as is the certainty of his performing any other mental act. All men agree as to the existence of our other mental oper- ations, such as knowledge and feeling ; nor do any doubt in practice the existence of our acts of choice, because it rests on the same basis. (2.) As to the nature of this act of choice, our ideas must be derived from the same source by which we become acquainted with the nature of knowledge and feeling. It is probable, too, that all men agree in fact and practice, though not in the- ory, in their views of these acts of choice, as much as in their ideas of knowledge and feeling. The differences of opinion which exist do not relate to the existence of the power of willing, nor to the idea which consciousness furnishes of our volitions as mental acts, but to the supposed relations be- tween volitions and precedent operations, and to other powers and principles of the mind, (a.) All men agree that these acts of choice differ from acts of necessity, and are in their nature opposite to them. When the fiendlike assassin has deliberately sent the fatal ball through the heart of his victim, we do not censure the bullet that penetrated his heart, nor the rifle which contained the powder, nor the MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. 251 spark which ignited it, nor the cock which elicited the spark, nor the trigger which moved the cock, nor even the finger which moved the trigger : but instantly perceiving that all these are not voluntary- agents, we attribute the blame to the malicious mind, which originated the whole train of second causes. Nor does the common sense of mankind discriminate merely between the voluntary actions of man and the actions of mechanical and irration- al agents ; the distinction between the voluntary and involuntary actions of man himself is equally clear, and universally acknowledged. What different feelings from those produced by the voluntary act of the cold-blooded assassin, are excited in every bosom when, as two intimate companions are run- ning through a thicket in pursuit of game, their guns cocked and hands applied to the trigger, the foot of the hindermost is caught in a brush ; he stumbles, and in his effort to regain himself presses unconsciously the fatal trigger, and prostrates his friend, a corpse, before him. (b.) It is only for such actions as are voluntary that we accuse or excuse ourselves, and for these alone can we feel true penitence, if they are contrary to known duty. When we have yielded to the force of temptation, we are conscious of our guilt, because we know that the force of these temptations was not irresisti- ble ; we know that we could and ought to have re- sisted it. (c.) All men agree, that for their own acts of choice alone, and the consequences of them, can they really and justly be held responsible either by God or man. (d.) Every reflecting man who 252 CONSTITUTIONAL INCLINATIONS OF THE SOUL. has attained mature development of mind, is con- scious of the fact that he can and ought to regulate the voluntary actions of his life according to certain fixed rules and principles. The question now arises, Is the soul, in choosing and refusing from among the acts possible to it, en- tirely free from any and every bias, and left to make its choice uninfluenced by anything whatever, or do we perceive in the voluntary actions of the soul any evidence to the contrary ? If we find, that the great majority of the acts of deliberate choice in all men of every character, under all circumstances, and of every age, are of a particular kind, are calculated to promote a particular general end, and made with a view to accomplish the same general purpose, we are irresistibly led to the belief, that there is in the soul itself a constitutional impulse, or bias, or in- clination to that end. This inclination must be prior to the actions themselves, and is among the causes which produce them. It must belong to the struc- ture of the soul itself, and may therefore with pro- priety be termed a constitutional inclination. If we are not grossly mistaken, the conduct of all men does present evidence of such inclinations in every situation of life, from the cradle to the tomb. Though these inclinations at first view appear numerous and complicated, on closer examination they resolve themselves into the following two con- stitutional inclinations : I. The inclination to action in accordance with the fitness of things, moral, intellectual, andphysU cal. MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. 253 II. The inclination to well-being, or the en- joyment of pleasure, present and ultimate ; and the avoiding of pain. These inclinations are not faculties, because they are not sources of distinct species of mental opera- tions. Nor are they themselves mental operations, in the ordinary sense of the term, because they ex- ist constantly, and prior to action. Nor are they habits of the soul, for habits are merely a facility for the performance of actions of particular kinds, and a tendency to their spontaneous performance, which facility is acquired by practice, and may be changed; while the constitutional inclinations are permanent and immutable. They are therefore natural characteristics of the soul, and belong to its constitutional structure. This bias seems to have been impressed upon our minds by the great Crea- tor, to determine, in some degree, the general ten- our of our voluntary actions ; and experience teach- es us that the great mass of all human actions is in accordance with one or the other, or both of these inclinations. I. The first constitutional inclination, viz., the in- clination to action in accordance with the physical, intellectual, and moral fitness of things, is an attri- bute of the soul, the existence of which is clearly established by a multitude of facts. All mankind do habitually evince the existence of this disposi- tion, in a greater or less degree, in their unpremed- itated actions. It is this inclination which leads all men, even from their earliest years, naturally to speak the truth rather than falsehood, unless they Y 254 FIRST INCLINATION OF THE SOUL. have acquired the habit of misrepresentation from deliberate and self-interested calculations. The truth of this fact is not only admitted by men on ordinary occasions, but is incorporated into their criminal codes and judicial proceedings. It is an admitted rule of testimony in all our courts. Ac- cordingly, if the testimony of a stranger be offered in a trial, we inquire whether he has any interest in the issue, which his testimony may tend to produce. And if it be fully ascertained that no interest of his, even of the most remote kind, can possibly be affected by the decision, we naturally expect, in the absence of contrary evidence, that he will not de- signedly swerve from the truth. All mankind have a constitutional sense of obli- gation, a constitutional inclination to obey the moral fitness of things. Whatever men naturally judge to be right, they also feel some impulse to do. This impulse is, alas ! too often, and in many persons habitually resisted ; yet its existence is clearly taught in the occasional unpremeditated actions, and in the deathbed confessions of the most aban- doned. And all who pay the least attention to the moral dictates of their nature, will not only freely admit its existence, but also acknowledge that its empire is justly unlimited ; that wherever, through- out the whole range of creation, they perceive a trace of moral fitness, there they also find this im- pulse accompanying it, and feel a constitutional monition to obey its dictates. This obligation, too, though so often resisted, is seen by all men to be paramount in importance, and in the strength of its MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. 255 claims, to everything else. It is this inclination which leads men, when travelling in a strange land, to keep the road rather than pass through an ad- joining grain-field, where they would destroy the provision which God has made for his creatures. This inclination also urges us to obey the intellec- tual fitness of things in general ; such as, to yield submission to those who have a right to direct, and to receive instruction from those who are older and wiser than Ave ; to arise in the morning when we awake ; to take care of things belonging to un- known persons, rather than to destroy them. In short, when we examine the whole sphere of human agency, we find that the crimes of men alone are exceptions to the observance of this constitutional inclination, while the precepts of the law on all subjects exhibit its appropriate dictates. The ten- dency to observe the physical fitness of things is witnessed throughout the whole sphere of physical action, in every department of life. Thus, apart from every self-interested motive, who can doubt that there is a natural disposition in persons enga- ged in mechanical or commercial pursuits, to make things right rather than wrong ? to make them ac- cording to the principles of physical fitness rather than the reverse ? From the above considerations, it is evident that the first constitutional inclination is one of the most important features of our moral nature, and em- braces all that is monitory or impulsive, in what is termed the moral sense, in the widest import of the term, and also in conscience, in its stricter accepta- 256 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. tion. As the operations of conscience are complex in their nature, their several constituent parts belong to different branches of our subject. There is in conscience something that is judicial, something that is sentient, and something that is impulsive. The first was discussed in the observations made on rel- ative knowledge ; the second, when treating of moral emotions ; and the third, or impulsive part, belongs to this place. The monitions or impulses of conscience are original and constitutional. If we attend to the testimony of our own consciousness on this subject, we think all will admit that these impulses arise spontaneously in the soul, whenever we contemplate our relations to the beings around us in the universe, in their bearings on our own conduct. Whatever we thus perceive to be dictated by these relations, to be our duty, to be right, to be conformed to the moral fitness of things, we also feel an imperative monition to perform. It follows, therefore, that conscience, in its principal, its impulsive feature, is an original faculty or power of the soul, although the operations generally designated by the term are complex, and several of their elements referable to cognition (judgment) and sensibility. The very structure of all different languages, proves alike the existence and the universality of this principle. Whenever we use the term " ought," or any others equivalent to it, we express an impulse of this con- stitutional inclination of conscience ; and where is the language on earth that is destitute of terms equivalent to these ; or where is the individual, in CONSTITUTIONAL INCLINATIONS. 257 any nation under the sun, which never employs them ? All men also judge the impulses of this monitor, ■whom God has implanted into our breasts, to be su- preme in the authority of its dictates. If at any time we yield to the solicitations of passion, and violate the prescriptions of conscience, we feel guilty and degraded ; we feel that we have done that which is unworthy of our nature, and have violated the relations we sustain to the great Author of our being. This principle of our nature is one of the funda- mental bases of our moral responsibility. Without it, man could not be a moral agent ; for, however lucid might be his views of the relations of the dif- ferent beings in the universe to God and to each other, and of the influence of his conduct on their happiness or misery, he certainly could not be re- sponsible for the conduct he pursued, if he felt no sense of obligation, no impulse to select the one and shun the other. The impulses of this principle of our moral nature, though strong enough in all to make us justly re- sponsible for our conduct, are not, in any case, irre- sistible. They never destroy our liberty, although they are strong enough to justify conscience in " ex- cusing, or else accusing, us" for our conduct. Like every other power of the soul, the consti- tutional inclination can be strengthened by faithful exercise, and it may be weakened by the neglect or violation of its dictates. The first entrance into the paths of known sin is generally made with a Y2 258 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. tremulous step. The first oath, or the first act of theft or violence, is perpetrated with uncomfortable feelings, and followed with a sense of guilt and self- condemnation. Happy would it be, if erring, guilty- man would then listen to this kind, monitory voice, and return to virtue's paths, for they are paths of pleasantness and peace ! But the repetition of crime soon impairs the strength of these monitory impulses, and every subsequent transgression makes farther violations easier. On the other hand, sincere and faithful obedience to the dictates of conscience, both in ascertaining what our duty is, and in labour- ing to perform it, will increase the strength of its impulses, and make subsequent obedience the more easy. II. The second constitutional inclination, viz., the love of well-being-, acquires different names in pop- ular language, according as it is habitually indulged in reference to any particular class of entities. This inclination embraces the following, among other modifications : (1.) Love of life. This is one of the fundamental principles of the soul, and is implied in all the subsequent modifications of this constitu- tional inclination. Independently of its superad- ded pleasures, life itself is regarded by man as a great good. " Skin for skin, and all that a man hath, will he give for his life," is a sentiment which, notwithstanding the source whence it proceeded, is undeniably true. The afflictions of life have some- times made men willing to leave this world ; but it was always in the expectation, true or false, that a hereafter would restore them to life and pleasure. CONSTITUTIONAL INCLINATIONS. 259 So much is man attached to his existence, and so deeply ingrafted on our nature is the love of life, that we can scarcely find, even among the most miserable of the sons and daughters of affliction, one who would be willing to purchase release from his sufferings at the expense of his being, one who would be willing to be blotted out from existence. In the beautiful language of Grey, we may confi- dently inquire, " For who, to dumb forgetfulness a prey, This pleasing, anxious being e'er resigned ; Left the warm precincts of the cheerful day, Nor cast one longing, ling'ring look behind]" This love of life leads us to a proper care of our health, and to all necessary acts of self-defence in time of danger. As this principle is an inherent part of our mental nature, it seems to be right that man, when assailed by violence, should defend himself to the utmost extremity, unless by the laws of God he has forfeited his right to live. And if in this defence his own life cannot be preserved except at the risk of that of his assailant, this constitutional principle seems to dictate a preference of his own existence to that of others. The propriety of this position is not doubted if the assailant be a serpent or some ravenous beast, nor can we perceive why it should not be equally proper in reference to rob- bers and murderers. We have no right to submit to be murdered, and by doing so Ave would often cause two deaths instead of one, as the murderer will gen- erally also, and justly, be executed. But " if he has done anything worthy of death," then, like Paul, 260 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. he ought '"not to refuse to die." (2.) Love of es- teem or power , which is the inclination to gratify our love of well-being by the pursuit of such enti- ties and the performance of such active operations as acquire for us the applause and admiration of men. A desire for the approbation and esteem of others is in itself, when regulated by a proper regard to the first constitutional inclination, an important and useful principle of our nature. It tends to make us observe the decencies of life, and to pur- sue such a course of conduct as will commend us to others. It is only when it becomes inordinate, and is indulged in violation of the fitness of things, that it becomes sinful and pernicious in its conse- quences. So, also, the desire of possessing influence or pow- er is in itself commendable, if that influence be desi- red not to promote any selfish ends, but chiefly as a means to advance the welfare of the community and the glory of God. When this principle be- comes inordinate, it is termed ambition, in the un- favourable sense of that term. (3.) Love of prop- erty or possession, which is the inclination to gratify our love of well-being in the pursuit and posses- sion of wealth. So long as the love of property is controlled by the first constitutional inclination, the fitness of things ; so long as it is not pursued con- trary to right, contrary to the relations we sustain to others, it is a useful principle, and leads men to industry and exertion to provide comfortably for themselves, and those of their own household ; but when it degenerates into avarice, it becomes not CONSTITUTIONAL INCLINATIONS. 261 only morally wrong, but also detrimental to the in- terests of society. (4.) Love of novelty, or curios- ity, which is the inclination to gratify our love of well-being by the pursuit of frequent change in the objects of our attention, having learned from our experience that any entity excites the greater feel- ing for being novel to the mind. (5.) Sensuality, which is the inclination to gratify the second consti- tutional inclination by the pursuit of objects adapt- ed to the indulgence of the sensual propensities. (6.) Love of science, which is the inclination to gratify our second constitutional inclination by the pursuit of the different objects of human knowl- edge. (7.) Social inclination, which is the inclina- tion to gratify our love of well-being by seeking the society of others. These, and various other modi- fications of the second constitutional inclination, are exhibited in the actions of mankind generally. This second constitutional inclination, the love of self, or of well-being, was, in its original condition, morally good, and of salutary tendency. The Scrip- tures often address our love of happiness, and the Saviour expressly commends it : " Thou shalt love thy neighbour as thyself." These two constitutional inclinations of the soul exert more or less influence on the character of our acts of choice, but never destroy the ability to choose ; that is, they never act irresistibly. When an individual act of choice is in harmony with both these inclinations of the soul, both as to motive and outward form, it is right in the sight of God. But it is evident that the great mass of human actions 262 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. is an indulgence of the second inclination at the expense of the first, that is, consists in actions which are an indulgence of our love of pleasure or well- being in violation of the dictates of the physical, in- tellectual, or moral fitness of things. All such ac- tions are sinful. Among this class must be reckon- ed, also, some actions which, in themselves consid- ered, that is, so far as the outward acts are con- cerned, are right, but which originate from a mo- tive of pure selfishness. Thus, that modification of the second constitutional inclination termed am- bition, induces many men of the world to observe outward morality of deportment, and even to per- form acts of beneficence, and to support the institu- tions of religion, in order that they may secure the public approbation, and be successful in their aspi- rations after fame or power. Such morality is, in- deed, less unfavourable in its influence on the com- munity at large than open vice ; yea, it may even tend to support the order and promote the well-be- ing of society ; but it evidently cannot secure the Divine approbation, because a regard to the moral fitness of things, a regard to what is morally right, and duty, did not enter into the motive with which it was performed. It is greatly to be feared that a large portion of the morality of the world is of this kind, is the re- sult of selfishness in some one or other of its modi- fications. This may even be the case without the person himself being fully aware of it, because he has not carefully and faithfully examined his heart, CONSTITUTIONAL INCLINATIONS. 263 and tested the motives of his conduct by the light of truth, either natural or revealed. Thus multi- tudes deceive themselves as to their real charac- ter. The first constitutional inclination is mani- festly the more noble ; but it is evident to all im- partial observers, that in the natural state of man the second greatly preponderates : and in this, so far as the mind is concerned, may at least in part consist the natural or constitutional depravity or disorder of man. Self preponderates over God, pleasure over what is right. This constitutional bias of the soul itself, let. it be remembered, deter- mines only the general end ; but not the specific means by which, in any case, we accomplish that end. Thus, the second constitutional inclination, in the form of self-interest, inclines our fellow-citi- zens to seek the melioration of their temporal con- dition by the construction of internal improve- ments ; but it does not decide whether they shall do it by making railroads or canals. This latter point the soul itself decides, after an inspection of the relative properties and advantages of both these means of gratifying our constitutional inclination. The several volitions of the mind, resulting from these different sources, are different in regard to comprehensiveness. Some of them are of the most generic kind, as they relate indefinitely to the gen- eral end ; others, which contemplate some particu- lar method of accomplishing the generic one, are specific in their character. Resolutions in regard to our general conduct are generic volitions, and exert an important influence on the specific voli- 264 MOTIVE POWER OF EXTERNAL ENTITIES. tions, and other operations of the mind, concerned in executing therm Besides these constitutional inclinations within the soul itself, by which the Author of our nature has given a general direction to the agency of man, there is also in entities themselves without the mind, a certain degree of motive influence, that is, a cer- tain degree of adaptation to influence the mind to action, in view of which the soul exercises its pow- ers of choice. All entities without the mind may be divided, in reference to this subject, into two classes: 1. Our own bodies. 2. All other entities in the universe. In our own bodies we find certain phenomena, termed bodily appetites, which possess a strong motive power. By bodily appetites we here strictly mean the corporeal part, the material part of those appe- tites. Thus by the bodily appetite, hunger, we mean the periodical action of the gastric fluid on the coats of the stomach (or, as this theory has of late been impugned, whatever other physical change that may be the true cause of the feeling), which results from the structure of our bodily organisms, and was de- signed by the Creator as a periodical motive to urge us to take the necessary food. The same remarks are applicable to thirst, which is nothing else than that peculiar condition of the throat and fauces, oc- casioned by the want of a liquid, and causing a de- sire to obtain it, or some other substance, in order to relieve the pain felt ; and also sometimes in or- der to enjoy the pleasure occasioned by the reception MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. 265 of the liquid. The fluid thus taken into the stom- ach is consumed by the progress of the bodily func- tions, and its want occasions a painful feeling term- ed thirst. Both these appetites are the work of God. They are the necessary results of the bodily organization of man, and may justly be considered by him as clear indications of the Divine will, that they should lead to the course of action by which they are relieved, though under the limitations of reason. The second general class of motives embraces all other entities except the above. The pleasure we expect to derive from eating any fruit, or from pe- rusing the work of a well-known author, acts as a motive to procure the object of our desire. Enti- ties of every class seem to possess some motive in- fluence on the will, e. g., all kinds of food, a land- scape, a beautiful passage in any author, literary or scientific. To the mathematician, the pleasures found in the discussion of the relations of space and number are a strong inducement to the repeti- tion of the exercise. The question here arises, Have these entities any certain motive power which they exert on all minds, and how is their relative strength determined ? It is certain that every entity does possess a definite, invariable, intrinsic desirableness, or the contrary ; and one entity is more or less desirable than anoth- er. Again, when we view these relatively, they all have certain fixed relations to each other, and to human actions and interests, as means to an end. After having weighed the merits of a case or a plan, Z 266 MOTIVE POWER OF ENTITIES. we can practically decide which is most suitable, and which presents the strongest inducements to its adoption ; and we are seldom in doubt as to what we ought to do, that is, on which side the strongest inducements lie. But these inducements or entities do certainly not act with irresistible force or mechanical power on the will ; otherwise men would always act in obedience to the strongest consideration, that is, to truth, and thus they would act virtuously. It is ev- idently the duty of all men thus to do ; God has made the inducements to virtue stronger than those to vice, the evidences of truth stronger than those of falsehood ; hence it is the duty of all men volun- tarily to obey the truth by pursuing virtue. But have they no power to act otherwise ? The fact that they do, must forever set this point at rest. And it is certain even with regard to our bodily ap- petites, that we can resist their cravings. A sensi- ble man can refuse to satisfy the most ravenous ap- petite, when he knows that abstinence is necessary to the recovery of health. In this case, regarding health as a greater motive than present gratification, he wills to obey the stronger motive, and declines eating ; while another, under the same circumstan- ces, wills to prefer present gratification to ultimate health. It seems evident, therefore, that, though men gen- erally do, in matters relating to temporal interests, will in accordance with the strongest motive, yet they certainly can will contrary to conviction and to a sense of duty. Hence it is evident that, though MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. 267 the determinations of the will are made in view of motives, that is, of a knowledge of entities, they are nevertheless made freely. The spontaneous recurrence of retrospective knowledge of certain entities exerts an important motive influence upon the soul. When this recur- rence is habitual, it will constitute a particular trait in the character of its subject. A certain sphere of this knowledge and feeling, retrospective, present, and prospective, is constantly at our command, and some item or other of it is constantly recurring to us spontaneously, when the attention of the mind is not occupied in some active, voluntary operation. When we are not engaged in any voluntary active process, the tenour of this spontaneous recurrence is regulated by the impressions made on the organs of sense, or by other principles to be enumerated in the discussion of spontaneous inspection. Some such impression is made almost every moment, and each object, seen, or heard, or felt, educes a train of related spontaneous knowledge. Thus each item of present knowledge or feeling gives rise to a train of related ideas, which runs on according to certain laws, until interrupted by some other impression on the organs of sense, or by some process of voluntary action. Peculiar pursuits in life, also, form habits of peculiarly frequent spontaneous recurrence of our knowledge of the particular entities connected with them, which also exert an important influence on the will, by bringing the entities referred to more frequently to bear on it by their retrospective influ- ence. Hence the incalculable advantage of a good, 268 INFLUENCE OF DESIRE. a religious education. And as knowledge can in- fluence our active operations only so long as it is recollected, the advantage of early good instruction is manifest ; because what is learned in early life is longest recollected. And, finally, as a daily, or, at least, frequent attentive review of such truths, tends to rivet them on the mind, and make them the subjects of frequent spontaneous retrospection, we cannot fail to perceive the salutary tendency of the habit of daily perusing a portion of the Sacred Vol- ume, or reading it in our family circle. Desire is that state of the soul in which an entity, that is the subject of inspection, is exerting its mo- tive power, but the will has not yet made a decis- ion. Hence desire may be regarded as incipient, but suspended volition. Nor is the decision of the will always, or at any time necessarily, in accord- ance with the desire. Oftentimes we decide against the solicitations of the present desire, in consequence of our recollection of other and more influential considerations to the contrary. And if we direct our attention to these preponderant considerations or objects, and dwell upon them, they will gradually excite desire in us. Desire is therefore a state of soul, tending to a volition to choose the object by which it is excited, but not necessarily producing it. Various objects possess different degrees of desira- bleness in our view ; and each one, when it is made the subject of our deliberate attention, will excite its appropriate degree of desire in us. Desires differ from feelings in this particular, by which they may easily be distinguished. The im~ mediate object of desire is always some action ; DESIRES. 269 while the immediate object of relative feelings, with which alone it may be confounded, is always some person or thing. If I desire, I always desire to do, to be, or to possess some person or thing ; but if I have love, it is towards some person or thing ; and if I hate, I hate something or some person. Or, in the language of our system, relative feeling imme- diately contemplates substantive or adjective enti- ties, while the immediate object of desire is a com- posite entity. The strength of our desires for particular objects is not the same in all men, nor in the same person at all times of life. It is very much influenced by the preponderance of the one or the other constitu- tional inclination in reference to the objects in question, and the strength of the constitutional in- clination is influenced by the habitual voluntary conduct. To the miser a purse of gold will appear more desirable than to another man; because the second constitutional inclination has become strong- er in consequence of his long-continued voluntary pursuit of money, and seeking his enjoyment in its possession. Desires always presuppose a cognition of the object desired, and generally, also, a pleasant emo- tion or feeling in reference to it. Yet this pleasant feeling does not appear to be always present ; for we may desire a dose of medicine that is nauseous to us and makes us shudder ; but here the end which we hope to accomplish by it appears desirable to us. Desire is a state of mind, which is sometimes of long continuance. Z2 270 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. With regard to our power of choice, usually term- ed power of volition, we may yet remark, that it is confined, in the intended objects on which it deter- mines to act, to some future time. However vari- ous the actions which we resolve to do or not to do, they must be done or avoided hereafter. Yet this future time admits of various modifications in rela- tion to the will ; we can resolve to do an act imme- diately, or at some future time more or less distant ; we can resolve absolutely or conditionally. The object of every act of volition or choice is the per- formance or non-performance of some one or more of the five active operations ; and one trait of dif- ference between them is, that, while some one or other of the five active operations is always going forward in the mind, the act of choice occurs more rarely and at intervals, either to give a new direc- tion or continued energy to the current active pro- cess. Our entire view of the will therefore resolves itself into the following features. I. The soul of man does possess the power of free, uncontrolled choice. II. In the exercise of this power, the soul is in- fluenced (but not certainly or irresistibly deter- mined) by the following things : 1. By its two constitutional inclinations, which relate only to the general end to be aimed at. 2. By the motive power of entities without the mind. These relate to the specific means for the THE SOUL'S CHOICE, BY WHAT INFLUENCED. 271 attainment of the ends pointed out by our constitu- tional inclinations. These entities are the follow- ing : (a.) Our bodily appetites, (b.) All other ex- ternal entities. 3. By our knowledge of these entities, either ret- rospective or prospective. This knowledge em- braces truth of every kind, which, by generating conviction and exciting feeling, exerts a definite motive influence. 4. By the habitual state of our feelings on similar or related subjects, or, to speak more accurately, by the state of our susceptibility of feeling from the ob- ject in question ; that is, from the degree in which our feelings are susceptible of being excited by said object. Every feeling is individual, and more or less transient in its nature. Every individual feeling must be excited anew in each individual case, either by its appropriate objective entity, or by our knowl- edge of it, retrospective or prospective. But our sus* ceptibility for feeling is permanent, and is increased or diminished, in each individual, by his mental hab- its. Thus the ambitious man habitually seeks the gratification of his second constitutional inclination, the love of well-being, by the pursuit of human ap- plause. By this habit, the susceptibility of his mind to pleasure from demonstrations of popular appro- bation, and pain from the reverse, is augmented. Thus also the sensualist habitually seeks the grat- ification of his second constitutional inclination, the love of well-being or pleasure, in the pursuit of ob- jects of licentious indulgence. His mental associations cluster around such 272 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. scenes, and his spontaneous mental operations re- cur to them. By this habit the susceptibility of his mind to be influenced by such objects is greatly increased. Thus, every circumstance, however re- motely connected with such scenes, becomes a temptation to him, and every exposure to direct temptation acquires a double influence on his mind. And thus it is that his volitions, in view of such circumstances of temptation, will obviously be in- fluenced by the state of his susceptibility for feeling in reference to them. The native activity of the soul prompts us to ac- tion. The constitutional inclinations of the soul deter- mine the general character of the ends, or results, at which we aim. Our knowledge presents to us the various entities, with their difTerent and relative properties, by ac- tive operations upon which the proposed end may be attained in various ways and in different degrees. The different entities exert a motive power pro- portional to their relative adaptation to accomplish the end proposed, and influenced by the habitual state of our feelings on related subjects ; and, final- ly, in view of all these circumstances, the soul freely determines in its choice of the different possible means of attaining the desired end. We therefore define the will as follows : The will is that power of the soul by which it freely determines, in view of motives, either now or hereafter, absolutely or conditionally, to perform or not to perform some one or more of the five active operations. SPONTANEOUS OCCURRENCE OF ACTIVE OPERATIONS. 273 SECTION II. Of the Spontaneous Occurrence of the Active Oper- ations. When the attention of the soul is withdrawn, the greater part, if not all the five active operations, are carried on spontaneously, viz., inspectiou, arrange- ment, modification, the intellectual agency concern- ed in physical action, and intellectual intercourse with other minds. The difference between the voluntary and spon- taneous active operations seems to consist chiefly in the following circumstances : 1. The former are the results of volition in their commencement, that is, are always begun in conse- quence of volition ; while the latter are not com- menced in consequence of volition, but result from an inherent constitutional disposition of the mind to be always, during waking hours, engaged in some active operation. The reason why one active op- eration is spontaneously engaged in rather than an- other, or why one entity is the subject of its action rather than another, seems to be a previous habit formed by frequent or late voluntary action of the same kind, on the same entities, or on our mental representatives of them. Habit is an increased facility in the performance of any active operation, resulting from repeated acts of the same kind. Habit not only renders the performance of any op- eration more easy, but also enables us to perform it with greater perfection and success. It is truly surprising with what facility and perfection we are 274 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. able to perform many active operations when long- continued practice has rendered them habitual ; which at first we could perform at all only with the greatest difficulty. After years of continued prac- tice, a student will commit to memory a given piece of composition, in one fifth of the time at first re- quisite for the task. An expert performer on the pianoforte will with ease execute some of the most intricate and difficult pieces of music, which he could not perform at all, in proper time, before long practice had established the habit from which his ability results. The same is true of all intellectual operations : habit makes them easy, and, in most cases, pleasant. This principle of habit seems to be nothing more than the progressive development of the powers of the soul by continued practice, and is applicable more or less to every part of our mental and bodily organism, not excepting even the constitutional inclinations of the soul. It is wit- nessed in the rapid reasonings, the almost intuitive conclusions of the experienced logician, in the dec- lamation of the orator, and in the skill and expert- ness of every species of mechanical operation. It must, however, not be supposed, that these pro- cesses, which have become habitual to us, and in which continued practice has enabled us to make great improvements, are always performed sponta- neously. The contrary is obviously the case. Even the celebrated Paganini, when performing a diffi- cult piece of music, which he has never before seen, must certainly exert a volition to strike every individual note ; although the execution may be so rapid that he will have no recollection in refer- SPONTANEOUS ACTION. 275 ence to any single note, and will merely remember his generic volition to play the piece, that is, to fol- low the series of notes, as he sees them before him. The same is also the case when a familiar piece of music is designedly performed by the most skilful artist. He has, indeed, no recollection of a volition in reference to a score of things, a knowledge of which is implied by every note that he strikes, and each of which he had at first to perform by deliberate volition. But then he has learned to produce mu- sical sounds on an instrument with as much facility as he utters oral sounds when reading the printed page. And who, in reading, can recollect the sep- arate volitions to articulate each individual letter, and to combine these sounds into syllables, and these syllables into words, as he is rapidly reading? These operations are spontaneous only when atten- tion is withdrawn, and they are performed negli- gently, without deliberate purpose to do so. And even when thus negligently commenced, there is probably some effort of will occasionally exerted in the progress of such spontaneous exercises. The improveableness of the different bodily and mental powers by practice is a subject of great ex- tent and peculiar interest ; but we shall not pursue it farther in this place. The formation of these habits is voluntary, but their subsequent action is spontaneous. When we say, the formation of these habits is voluntary, Ave do not mean that there are not, in the constitutional structure of our minds and bodies, more opportuni- ties, yea, constant temptations, to the formation of 276 SPONTANEOUS OPERATIONS OF THE MIND. some particular habits rather than others. The contrary is evidently the fact. There seems to be, even in the mind itself, a greater aptitude for the formation of sinful habits than of such as arc holy. Fewer voluntary acts will create or form a sinful habit, and the habit resulting from any given num- ber of voluntary sinful acts is stronger than would result from the same number of acts of a different character. The perverted state of our bodily pro- pensities, since the fall, also leads men into frequent temptations to sin. The bodily propensity is invol- untary, but the indulgence of the inspection of ob- jects to which it prompts is voluntary and sinful, and is one cause of the formation of sinful habits. 2. Voluntary active operations are carried on with much more attention and energy than those which are spontaneous. The spontaneous operations of the mind in many persons constitute far the greater part of all their mental action ; and in all persons, even in those most constantly engaged in duties or labours, men- tal or bodily, they occupy much of their time. In- deed, it is the spontaneous action of an individual that exhibits his real character. Hence, as the spontaneous action results from that which is vol- untary, and is correspondent w T it.h it. either holy or unholy, it is evident that we are responsible to God, not only for our voluntary action, but also for that which is spontaneous, i. e., for the mental habits by which we are characterized. It might, at first glance, appear as if our view of the spontaneous op- erations tended to remove them from the sphere of responsibility ; but, on a more careful examination, SPONTANEOUS ACTION. 277 we think this difficulty will vanish. The grounds of our responsibility for spontaneous action, and the rea- sons which will make it evident, are the following: {a.) The fact, that any particular active opera- tion is spontaneously engaged in rather than anoth- er, is owing to the circumstances of our having, by previous voluntary action, formed a habit, or facil- ity, and inclination for such action. As it is thus ultimately caused by our voluntary acts, responsi- bility justly attaches to it. (b.) We can, moreover, prevent much of our spontaneous mental action, by keeping the mind constantly employed in voluntary engagements. (c.) Although spontaneous operations are com- menced without deliberate volition to do so, there is often some slight degree of volition exercised in their progress. (d.) Spontaneous operations are at all times un- der the control of the will as to their continuance. We can at any moment put a stop to any sponta- neous operations of the mind, by a volition to do so, and to engage in some other mental process. Spontaneous operations are, therefore, continued by consent of the will. Since, therefore, the com- mencement, continuance, and termination of these processes are at all times under our voluntary con- trol, it seems evident that we are justly held re- sponsible for their character by our great moral Governor. Spontaneous action has for its materials, like our voluntary action, entities, simple or composite, past, present, or future. Aa 278 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. An important fact of a physiological nature touching this subject is, that spontaneous active operations are much less debilitating to the mind than voluntary. The more entirely we can with- hold the mind from voluntary action, and even from intense attention to a process of spontaneous thought, the more complete is this state of rest. Hence, riding on horseback or walking in company with others, by presenting a series of changing ob- jects to the mind, and preventing us from entering on a very attentive inspection of any of them, is excellent relaxation. A solitary walk of a student, in which he becomes absorbed in the customary subjects of his pursuit, is but an ambulatory study, and affords very slight relaxation to the mind. On this principle, the different debilitating tendency of various species of mental exercise can be regularly graduated. Each mental process will debilitate in proportion to its difficulty to the student, and to the degree of attention requisite to its performance. When the mind is fatigued, or, for any reason whatever, does not engage by volition in any of the five active processes, some of them will invariably occur in a spontaneous, indifferent, and careless manner ; so that we have little, and sometimes no, recollection of the operation so long as it proceeds in this spontaneous way. The operations which oc- cur spontaneously with the greatest frequency belong chiefly to the process of inspection, and they are gen- erally such as are most frequently, or have been most recently, engaged in in a voluntary manner. I. Spontaneous Inspection. — In the spontaneous SPONTANEOUS INSPECTION. 279 inspection of entities, or their mental representa- tives, the mind is found generally to proceed in several uniform ways, or laws of association. (1.) It seems to follow the relations of the enti- ties, which are the subjects of its inspection. The relations which are most frequently followed are sameness, contrariety, contiguity — temporal, local, or numerical — and causation. But all the other relations are also occasionally pursued in our spon- taneous inspections. Perhaps the relative frequen- cy with which each of the relations is pursued in spontaneous inspection, is not materially different from the order in which those relations have been enumerated. But the course of the mental train of action is often changed by one or more of the principles yet to be enumerated. (2.) There is a tendency in spontaneous inspec- tion to pursue, in preference, the train of those en- tities which have most frequently been the subjects of its voluntary attention. Thus, the mind of the mathematician pursues its spontaneous rambles in the regions of mathematical science ; the mind of the sensualist recurs to the objects of his sinful grat- ification ; and the mind of the faithful Christian de- lights to dwell upon the topics connected with his high and holy calling. And if several persons, of different pursuits, were requested to give us some account of their reminiscences of a recent tour which they had made, the memory of the farmer would spontaneously recur to the agricultural productions of the country through which he had passed ; the painter would think first of the landscapes, the 280 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. statesman of some political intelligence which he had obtained, and the Christian, of an interesting conversation which he had heard on the subject of the Redeemer's kingdom. (3.) The mind more readily recurs to those ob- jects which have lately been the subjects of its at- tention. (4.) It pursues more frequently those entities which excite the most pleasant feelings and gratify the second constitutional inclination. This incli- nation, or love of well-being, is not, in itself, sin- ful ; on the contrary, the joys and pleasures of re- ligion itself are sought in accordance with its dic- tates. But it becomes sinful when it is so inordi- nate as to outweigh the sense of obligation to obey the fitness of things, to obey the strongest evidence, that is, to obey truth. This preponderating influ- ence is found in all unconverted persons by nature, and thus all by nature are sinners. (5.) The mind is diverted from the pursuit of the above-mentioned relations in its spontaneous op- erations, by the immediate action of some entities, at the time, through the bodily organs. (6.) It is interrupted by volition. While en- gaged in spontaneous action we may, for some rea- son or other, resolve to do something, i. e., to en- gage in some active process, and thus the sponta- neous character of our mental action is instantly interrupted and succeeded by a process of a volun- tary nature. These spontaneous retrospections have, by some recent metaphysicians, been termed suggestions. ARRANGEMENT SOMETIMES SPONTANEOUS. 281 This word, though it conveys something of the char- acter of these operations, seems not to be well select- ed as their generic and characteristic appellation. It seems to represent one item in a train of consec- utive reminiscences or associations, as the agent that causes the occurrence of the other, while the mind is regarded rather as the passive recipient of these influences. In reality, however, the mind is the active subject ; its spontaneous rambles result from the constitutional activity of its nature, while in these rambles it, by a law of its nature, pursues in preference the channel of those natural relations between the different entities or objects which real- ly subsist between them, or those artificial rela- tions constituted in the course of events, or those habits of mind which proceed from individual vol- untary action. The principles regulating these as- sociations are therefore intelligible, and it is also evident that, to a certain extent, they are the re- sult of our most frequent voluntary actions. Their character is therefore, though not immediately, yet ultimately, in a great measure under our control. And just so far as this is the case, we are evidently responsible for the moral character of our sponta- neous reminiscences and other spontaneous mental operations. II. The operations of Arrangement are also some- times carried on spontaneously. If, in passing along the road, we see any animal, and especially one of rare occurrence, how often do we not spontaneously arrange it with the class of quadrupeds, or bipeds, &c, as the case may be ; how often do we not Aa2 282 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. compare it to other similar animals, and thus spon- taneously arrange the two by the relation of same- ness. Every figure of comparison used by extem- poraneous speakers, consists of spontaneous arrange- ments according to the relation of similarity, ex- pressed in words. And when a person of well-dis- ciplined mind hears a fact which has an important probative bearing, he instantly and previous to voli- tion, even in the act of rapidly reading a book, ar- ranges it with other facts bearing on the same sub- ject. III. The process of modification very seldom oc- curs spontaneously, especially in persons of veracity and conscientious character ; yet, doubtless, the mind of the novelist, who has habituated himself by voluntary effort to the very frequent fabrication of fiction, will, when left unoccupied, sometimes form such combinations spontaneously. IV. The mental process regulating our physical action is very often exercised spontaneously. How many motions of the hands, or feet, or entire body do we not daily perform from mere habit, without volition. How often does the musician find him- self engaged in the spontaneous act of singing, and the ambitious orator, in practising emphatic and pe- culiar pronunciation. How often do some men spontaneously fumble their watch-key, or play with their penknife, without being aware of the fact. In short, all those actions of the body, which are said to be performed from mere habit, are spontaneous operations. Men sometimes, and with truth, as- sign it as an excuse for particular actions, that they SPONTANEOUS INTELLECTUAL INTERCOURSE. 283 did them without thinking, did them unintentional- ly ; doubtless some of these acts are spontaneous. Sometimes, however, physical action is performed in a manner which does not properly fail within the division either of spontaneous or voluntary action, but is properly attributed to instinct. V. The process of intellectual intercourse is some- times carried on spontaneously, in a revery ; as is evident from our making articulate sounds in the same spontaneous manner to express our ideas. How often do those who are in the habit of talking much, such as children and some talkative superan- nuated persons, talk not only without a volition, but even contrary to a resolution not to do so. A PRAGMATIC VIEW OPERATIONS OF THE WAKING MINL FOR THE PURPOSE OF EXEMPLIFYING THE PRECEDING j PRINCIPLES. I. When a superabundance of animal and men- tal vigour has been accumulated during sleep, we make a transition from the sleeping to the active, conscious, waking state. This transition is, in gen- eral, independent of our wishes, and seems to be the result of the stimulating or exciting influence of the principle of animal vigour, accumulated du- ring sleep. In some cases the act of awaking is produced by the uneasiness resulting from the accumulation of some of the products of the ani- mal economy, such as a painful stricture on the bladder in persons advanced in years, and some other cases which might be cited ; but these we should regard as mere exceptions to the general rule. Persons labouring under such difficulties, awake before the time in which the system w^ould spontaneously return to the condition of cerebral preponderance or waking action. And if the ac- cumulated vigour is not yet sufficient to produce this effect by itself, the auxiliary stimulus of the light of returning day will aid in exciting us to a OPERATIONS OF THE WAKING MIND. 285 waking state. This is demonstrated by the fact, that all persons can sleep longer and more soundly in a dark, than in a light room. Thus the adorable Author of our being admonishes us, that night is the proper time for sleep, and that the artificial perversions of day and night, which are met with in some of the more fashionable ranks of society, are not only contrary to the constitution of our na- ture, but also detrimental to our health. II. The moment we make the transition from the sleeping to the waking state, the mind begins to act, and the body, particularly the muscles and or- gans of sense, become subservient to the mind. The first action of the waking mind seems gener- ally to be spontaneous ; in most cases it consists in the spontaneous inspection of the objects surround- ing our bed. Sometimes this spontaneous inspec- tion gives rise to voluntary action, such as the re- flection, i. e., the voluntary retrospection, of some entities related to those spontaneously seen by us and recalled by them. Thus, from the light per- ceived in the room, the mind of pious habits will revert to the great Father of lights from whom it comes, and to the value of that spiritual light, which constitutes the Christian's greatest and most con- stant source of happiness on earth and expected bliss in heaven. The worldly-minded, from the inspection of the same light, will be led to reflect on some profitable business or pursuit which this light enables them to prosecute. In this manner more or less time is spent until the next prominent active operation is engaged in, viz., 286 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. III. The voluntary actions of physical agency^ such as rising, dressing, washing, &c. If we in- quire in what manner these voluntary actions take place, we trace them to the constitutional inclina- tion to obey the fitness of things actively prompt- ing us to perform what is right, fit, suitable, profit- able, or agreeable to the Divine will. We have a knowledge that it is right or fit to rise in the morn- ing, and, invited by the joint influence of these several considerations, we voluntarily determine to perform the active operation. Here, then, we dis- tinguish the following several things : 1. Our constitutional vigour compels us to act either spontaneously or voluntarily, i. e., it keeps the mind always engaged in some active process during waking hours. 2. The constitutional inclinations of the soul in- cline us to the end, viz., obedience to the fitness, or propriety, or constitution of things, or pursuit of pleasure. 3. Our knowledge of the manner in which that end will be accomplished, determines the means or individual acts to be performed. Inasmuch as duty, fitness, profit, love of pleasure, often all dictate the performance of the same action, persons of differ- ent character will frequently do the same act from different motives. This is a very important fact, and shows that the moral worth of actions must be judged by the view or motive from which they were performed. Those who are in the habit of being influenced by the love of gain, i. e., of self, and personal advantage, will rise early, because OPERATIONS OF THE WAKING MIND. 287 they know early rising to be a means of enabling them to transact more business, and accumulate wealth. 4. The same view seems to be exemplified in the daily duties of men. The Christian is prompted, by an habitual regard to the first constitutional incli- nation, to obey the moral fitness or obligation, i. e., to obey the Divine will. He knows that the act of offering up his morning and evening sacrifice to the Author and Preserver of his life, is a means or instance of obedience to his will, and thus performs it with benefit and delight. With the same motive he pursues his daily business, because he regards it as a means of supporting his family and of glorify- ing his God. The man of the world engages in the same various occupations of the day from dif- ferent motives, some more and others less honour- able in their nature. Thus, throughout the day, various active opera- tions are voluntarily engaged in and pursued. The intervals between these voluntary operations are filled up with spontaneous active processes, the na- ture of which, as has been already explained, will be influenced by the prevailing habits of voluntary engagement of each individual. Thus, between the voluntary and spontaneous processes, between labours and intermissions of labour, the day is pass- ed. To the several customary meals the individual is invited, partly by the recurrence of stated times, partly by the solicitations of his periodical appetites, and partly by other circumstances. The close of the engagements of the day and 288 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. evening, ordinarily finds every individual somewhat languid, and finally a feeling of exhaustion or drow- siness ensues, and sooner or later the cerebral gives way to the preponderance of the ganglionic action, and he relapses into the state of sleep in which the vigour of his system, if he be in health, is again re- cruited, and he prepared to pass through the same routine of another day. OF DREAMS. Before closing the discussions of this volume, it may not be improper to add a few words on the subject of another species of spontaneous mental operations, which, though properly belonging to the diseased action of the soul, is of such frequent oc- currence, and oftentimes attended by so slight a derangement of the bodily functions, that it is pop- ularly, though erroneously, regarded as a healthy state of mental action. The existence of mankind in this life, is divided by a clear and definite line into two very different states ; that of dormancy, and the waking state. Between these two conditions, the life of man and of every other animate being is spent. It is our waking action that properly belongs to us as moral beings, and constitutes the appropriate agency of man in life. Indeed, it seems to be the design of the Author of our nature, that sleep should be, as in healthy subjects it actually is, an entire cessation from all conscious mental action. Habitual, deep sleep is a characteristic of sound general health ; and those who enjoy the highest degree of it are not conscious of dreaming at all. It, however, not unfrequently happens, that disease affects our bodily functions, and disturbs the exact relation which or- dinarily subsists between them and the soul, thus Bb 290 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. rendering less distinct the line of separation be- tween our sleeping and our waking hours. Sleep being properly a physical phenomenon, belonging in common to man, to irrational animals, and, in a subordinate sense also, to the vegetable kingdom, its particular discussion does not fall with- in the design of our work. In animals it is a most important and salutary restorative process of nature. It is a fact of daily observation, that the perform- ance of the various mental and bodily operations, during our waking hours, exhausts the animal vig- our of the system, and that this exhaustion in a healthy subject naturally predisposes to sleep, and results in it. Equally well established is the posi- tion, that the healthy subject awakes with the re- turning light of the morning, refreshed by sleep, and conscious of the feelings of renovated life and vigour, but without any recollection of having been disturbed by dreams. Yet it may, perhaps, be pos- sible to excite dreams in a healthy subject, by de- signedly acting on his bodily senses during his sleep, and the same effect may with equal probability be produced, when such impression is made accident- ally. But we suppose that no healthy person will have any recollection of dreams, unless thus acted on from without. As we recollect some dreams ourselves, and as others have discovered from our talking, and walk- ing, and other actions in sleep, that we did dream when we had no recollection of it ourselves, the probability is, that the soul is essentially active, that active operations are always going on spontaneous- NATURE OF DREAMS. 291 ]y when we are asleep. This is rendered the more probable, because many of the dreams recollected by us, occurred, while others who observed us saw that our bodies were perfectly motionless, and sup- posed us to be enveloped in profound sleep. The most perfect repose of the body, therefore, affords no argument against the supposition of constant, spontaneous, mental processes. Dreams may be regarded as those spontaneous trains of mental operation, which occur, when sleep has, in a great measure, suspended that self-control, through reason and volition, which we possess, and ordinarily exercise when awake. The term dream has often been confined to those trains of thought, of which we retain some recollection in our waking state. But it is also applied to the cases observed by others, though not recollected by ourselves, and is in its nature equally applicable to all other in- stances of mental action in sleep. The correctness of this view of dreams is strong- ly corroborated by the fact, that we often have no recollection of them until some time after, when they are recalled to our memory by some related thought or occurrence, which would, on the principles of association, have recalled the same train, if it had first occurred when we were awake. In dreams the exercise of reason and volition is not entirely suspended ; although it is probably more in a defect of the exercise of these powers than in anything else, that dreams differ from our waking reveries or unrestricted spontaneous mental trains. We can and do sustain conversations ei- 292 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. ther mentally or orally ; we enact scenes, and per- form various achievements ; in short, all the differ- ent powers of the mind appear sometimes to be exerted in dreams, though with various degrees of imperfection. The farmer has sometimes engaged in threshing his grain, the lawyer has prepared his argument, and the preacher has imagined himself in the great assembly, and proclaimed to listless walls the truths of his holy religion. Such cases of somniloquism and somnambulism are within the knowledge of all. Other instances of still more singular and extraordinary morbid action of the mind are on record ; but, as they do not properly fall within the limits of our science, we pass them in silence. From the map of the mind in its healthy state, which we have endeavoured to present, we perceive evidence enough that we are " wonder- fully and fearfully," and, at the same time, benev- olently " made ;" and that we " should praise the Lord for his goodness and his wonderful works to the children of men." It is an interesting peculiarity of dreams, that they often disregard the exact relations of time and space. Though the scenes are passed through with the utmost rapidity of waking thought, we some- times suppose them all to have been real, and ima- gine that months, and sometimes years, have trans- pired in their occurrence. This singular circum- stance may be owing, among other things, to two causes ; to the fact, that in sleep we hold no com- munion with the visible world through the senses, by which, especially through the succession of night CONNEXION OF DREAMS WITH WAKING THOUGHTS. 293 and day, and the aid of memory, we have learned to measure time, even in its minor fractions, and also the fact, that the exercise of judgment is chiefly suspended, by which, in our waking state, we can distinguish between fact and fiction. From this view of the nature of dreams, it fol- lows, that however fantastic and unnatural they may sometimes be, yet there will, on the whole, be some analogy between the dreams of any individ- ual, and the habitual traits and peculiarities of his mind when awake. The poet, the mathematician^ the lawyer, the politician, the agriculturist, the me- chanic, and the minister of religion, will all find in their habitual dreams some special relation to their waking pursuits. Even the peculiarities of genius may often be traced in dreams. The moral char- acter, which is frequently concealed during waking hours, will sometimes be betrayed in dreams ; and the Rev. Mr. Young, in his " Record of Provi- dence," relates an instance of a murderer in Eng- land, whose dreams led to his arrest and convic- tion, seven years after he had committed the crime, for which he was eventually executed. It is also evident from the nature of dreams, that there can be nothing ominous or prophetic in them. We do not affirm that no dream was ever of this character. The Almighty doubtless can, and, as the Volume of Inspiration teaches, has communi- cated his will to some individuals in the form of dreams. But this was as certainly miraculous, as if the same communication had been made in open day by a voice from Heaven. What we maintain Bb2 294 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. is, that dreams have nothing ominous or prophetic in their own nature. As they are spontaneous pro- cesses of the mind, they depend for their character, in some measure, on the voluntary waking habits, from which they result. As the peculiarities of these spontaneous processes arise from the suspen- sion of the exercise of judgment and reason in sleep, they must evidently be entitled to less confi- dence than our waking thoughts. And the adven- titious influences on the senses, which tend still far- ther to modify them, cannot fail to divest them of all claim to confidence. Such are our natural dreams. The fact, that one dream in a million has some resemblance to an event that succeeds, only proves that in these cases men may form somewhat correct anticipations of coming events when awake, and that the same conjecture may recur to them in their sleep, and constitute the burden of their pro- phetic dreams ! RECAPITULATION. 295 CHAPTER III. RECAPITULATION, FOR THE PURPOSE OF REVIEWS. Introduction. Methodology of Mental Philoso- phy. Difference between Mathematical and Men- tal Science, p. 13-20. Mental Philosophy is that science which discusses the properties and operations of the human soul, p. 21. Various names have been attached to this sci- ence, such as Metaphysics, Anthropology, Psychol- ogy, p. 21, 22. The proper materials of this science doubtless are, not the supposed faculties, of which we know nothing directly, but the known phenomena of the mind, and all those other entities, or existences, which exert an influence upon these phenomena, or are concerned in their production, p. 22, 23. In the classification of mental operations, various systems have been adopted. The 'first, and most generally received in the English philosophical world, is that into Nine Faculties of the Mind : viz., Perception, Consciousness, Conception, Judgment, Memory, Reasoning, Conscience, Feeling, and Vo- lition, p. 23, 24. Dr. Reid, adopting in the main this classifica- tion, separates these faculties or powers into two general classes, viz., Intellectual Powers and Active Powers. 296 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. Mr. Stewart adds to these a third general class, viz., Social Powers. Dr. Brown's celebrated division is into two class- es : External and Internal Affections or States of the Mind, p. 25, 26. The German division into three faculties, Sensi- bilities, Understanding', and Will. Professor Up- ham's view, p. 26. Unable, after mature deliberation, to adopt either of these divisions, we propose another, founded, not upon the unknown and supposed faculties or es- sence of the mind, but upon those mental phenom- ena which are known to us. It is a threefold di- vision, into Cognitive Ideas, Sentient Ideas, and Ac- tive Operations, p. 27. Difference between this and the German system. (a.) In its principle, (b.) In its lines of division, (c.) In the contents of the different parts, p. 29. On the extent of the several parts of this divis- ion, p. 30. I. The Cognitive class embraces Perceptions, Acts of Consciousness, Conceptions, Judgments, Recollections, Results of Reasoning, and the Dic- tates or Decisions of Conscience, p. 31. II. The Sentient class embraces Sensations, Emo- tions, Affections, and Passions, p. 34. III. The Active class embraces Volitions, Pro- cesses of Reasoning, the Act of Memorizing, the In- tellectual Act of communicating our thoughts to others, and some other processes, p. 36. RECAPITULATION. 297 PART I. COGNITIVE IDEAS. Cognitive Ideas are acquired by the mind through the medium of certain parts of the body called or- gans of sense, when these organs are brought into a particular relation to external objects, and from the operations and powers of the mind of which we are conscious. In this acquisition we distinguish three things, p. 38, 39. First. The external entity, or object of knowl- edge ; Secondly. The knowledge itself; and, Thirdly. The process by which the knowledge is obtained. CHAPTER I. OF OBJECTIVE ENTITIES AS SUBJECTS OF OUR KNOWL- EDGE, p. 39. SECTION I. Of the different classes of Entities, p. 40. We constitutionally judge external entities to be possessed of real objectivity, i. e., to have an ac- tual existence out of our minds. An entity is any- thing whatever, of which we can have an idea, p. 39. The reality of the material universe, in general, is proved by the testimony of our senses, which we constitutionally judge to be true. No reasoning is necessary on this point ; nor could it make the testimony of our senses more certain. 298 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. The universe, as known to us, consists of nothing else than various combinations of properties. Each of these combinations, as found in nature, is individual, and in some respects different from all others. There are, nevertheless, gradations of similarity in these properties, which form a just basis for classification. On such classification human language is framed, having words not for each individual substantive object, but {a) for the different properties, (b) for the relations subsisting between them, and (c) for the different classes of substantive objects, more or less generic, as stone, tree, quadrupeds, &c. All objects known to us in the universe are either substantive objects, that is, objects to which several coexisting properties appertain, or they are individual properties, or relations between them. All substantive objects maybe referred to the fol- lowing classes : Solids, Liquids, Gases, the Ethereal or Incoerci- ble Fluids, such as Light, Caloric, Electric Fluid, and the Magnetic Principle ; Mind, Spirit, Glori- fied Bodies, Deity ; together with Time, Space, and Number. The relation of the properties of mind to mind itself is not different from that of the properties of other objects to their substratum, the objects them- selves. Supposed plastic power rejected. Our knowledge of the Divine Being, how acquired, its nature. The peculiarities of Time, Space, and Number : MENTAL PHILOSOPHY, 299 as three universal, fundamental entities created by- God, of entirely peculiar properties, in which, or in the forms of which, all other created entities exist, p. 55. No one denies that we have ideas relating to all these classes of entities. Not all are agreed as to the question whether they are ideas of reality, many supposing them to be mere ideas of the mind, without anything in na- ture corresponding to them, or causing them. SECTION II. Division of these Classes, p. 56. All these classes of entities may be referred to two generic kinds, viz., Absolute and Concrete En- tities. Absolute are those of which we can conceive without reference to the concrete class. They are Space, Time, and Number. Concrete are those of which we cannot conceive except as existing in the absolute class, or being re- lated to it. They are all the others except Space, Time, and Number. SECTION III. Subdivision of Individual Entities, p. 57. Entities may be subdivided into Substantive, Ad' jective, and Composite. A Substantive Entity is that to which any num- ber of coexisting properties appertains. An Adjective Entity is any one property of a sub- stantive entity. 300 RECAPITULATION. A Composite Entity consists of two or more ad- jective entities, viewed in regard to some relation existing between them. SECTION IV. Relations of Entities, 1. Of Absolute Entities, p. 61. (a.) Equality, diversity, antecedence, subse- quence, &c, of Time. (b.) Equality, difference, progression or ratio, plurality, minority, &c, of Number. (c.) Equality, diversity, contiguity, remoteness, superiority, and inferiority of Space. 2. Of Concrete Entities to each other, (a.) Similarity and diversity. (&.) Contiguity or remoteness, as to space, time, and number. (c.) Fitness, physical, intellectual, and moral. (d.) Analogy. (e.) Causation or agency, (a.) Mechanical, ei- ther uniform or contingent; (b.) Instinctive; and (c.) Moral. 3. Between Absolute and Concrete Entities. These, (a.) in regard to number, are Addition, Multiplication, Subtraction, and Division ; which are active relations of agency performed by the con- crete entity man on our ideas of the absolute entity number, (b.) Space, (c.) Time. These Relations are, (a.) Transitive or Intransi- tive. (6.) Absolute or Hypothetical. (c.) Retrospective, Present, or Prospective. MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. 301 CHAPTER II. OF OUR COGNITIVE IDEAS, OR MENTAL REPRESENTA- TIVES OF ENTITIES. SECTION I., p. 69. Of the exact Mature of those of our Ideas which are Knowledge. They belong to the class of entities termed Mind, but are distinct from the mind, and are, with cer- tain qualifications, representatives of things actual- ly existing. SECTION II. Of the Criteria by which the Cognitive Class of Ideas is distinguished, p. 70. I. The Cognitive Ideas have for their objects en- tities existing out of the mind, or some mental op- eration of our own or other minds. II. The Cognitive Ideas are dependant for their character on the entities themselves. III. The Cognitive Ideas presuppose the previ- ous existence of the entities, from which they are derived. SECTION III. On the Nature and Sources of Error in our Cognitive Ideas, p. 74. In order to obtain a correct view of this extremely important subject, it is necessary first to make some remarks upon the nature and divisions of truth. All truths may be divided into three classes ; viz., I. Real or Objective Truths; that is, objective entities existing in nature. C c 302 RECAPITULATION. II. Idealistic or Subjective Truths ; i. e., correct mental representatives of objective Entities. View of the ancient Realists and Nominalists, and of modern German Realism and Idealism ; Trans- cendental Idealism of Kant. III. Nominal Truths; i. e., correct mental repre-? sentatives expressed by proper words. 1. Sources of Involuntary Error, p. 80. 1. Incorrect original mental representatives of en- tities. These may arise, (a.) From a hasty, superficial inspection of en- tities. (b.) From forgetfulness of the exact mental rep- resentative originally obtained, and a consequent misstatement of it. (c.) From listening to one part of a statement, and neglecting to listen to the whole. II. Incorrect selection of sounds and written words, to express to others the true mental representative which we really have. III. The real imperfection of language, which does not furnish words to express our ideas exactly on all subjects. IV. Mistakes in judging of the motives of others. V. Unintentional illogical reasoning. VI. Misapprehension of a correct sentence, through ignorance of language. 2. Sources of Voluntary Error, p. 82. I. Intentional misstatement of entities, simple or composite. II. Indulgence in the habit of mere high colouring , without directly stating a falsehood. MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. 303 III. Errors resulting from voluntary ignorance, IV. The indulgence of prejudice in regard to per- sons or things. V. The indulgence of passion. SECTION IV. Division of our Cognitive Ideas, p. 84. They may be divided in two ways : First, into Individual and Relative ; and, Secondly, into Retrospective, Present, and Pro- spective. I. Individual Knowledge. To this class belongs our knowledge of every individual substance in na- ture, and also of every individual property belong- ing to any entity. II. Relative Knowledge. To this class belongs our knowledge of composite entities ; the greater part of our conceptions ; geometrical axioms ; the relations of numbers ; metaphysical axioms ; moral abstract propositions ; and belief, immediate and acquired. I. Retrospective Knowledge, p. 89. This is our knowledge of all our former cognitive, sentient, and active ideas, and is usually termed memory. It may be divided into spontaneous and voluntary. The extent of our spontaneous retrospective knowledge depends on, (a.) The natural aptitude of the mind for this ex- ercise ; i. e., the natural retentiveness of memory. (b.) The different degrees of logical accuracy with which our knowledge is arranged on paper, or in the mind, according to the different relations them- selves which subsist between the entities. 304 RECAPITULATION. (c.) The frequency with which the knowledge to be retained was reviewed by the mind, and the in- terest which was felt in it. Our retrospective knowledge will be increased by the following methods : (a.) By thinking frequently of the ideas intended to be recollected. (£.) By reviewing those ideas together which we wish to recollect together, and in the very same or- der in which we wish to remember them. (c.) By connecting them, in the act of memori- zing, with some idea which we will be sure to rec- ollect at the intended time. (d.) By the habit of studying subjects rather than books. (e.) By interesting our feelings in the subject. Cases of extraordinary memory in persons in health, Kepler, Des Mesmes, Pascal, Cyrus, The- mistocles. There is reason to believe that the soul of every man naturally possesses a degree of mnemonic pow- er, equal or greater than was exhibited by these distinguished men ; but this power is restrained by our bodily organs. Yet in eternity it will be re- leased from the shackles of these organs, and will develop its expanded powers. Remarkable cases in proof. A man in St. Thomas hospital. Case cited by Dr. Pritchard ; another remarkable case cited by Coleridge : Probable inference, that thought is indestructible, RECAPITULATION. 305 and will be a prominent ingredient in the future retribution of the righteous and wicked. Mnemonics ; different systems. The inventor of the earliest system, Simoni- des. Cicero's account of him. Account of the system. The greater part of modern systems are based on the same principle. Numerical mnemonics, Feinagle's system and table. Dr. Niemeyer's directions to teachers and pupils for the improvement of memory. Case of Rev. Mr. Uhlhorn, as an example of a well-trained memory. II. Present Knowledge, p. 99. III. Prospective Knowledge, p. 100. This is all our knowledge of the probable future existence of entities and their relations. (a.) The Subject of our prospective knowledge is always a composite entity ; viz., the relation between a present entity and a supposed future entity, (6.) The Bases of prospective knowledge are Analogy, Causation, and Revelation. CHAPTER III. OF THE ORGANIC PROCESS BY WHICH WE OBTAIN OUR IDEAS, p. 105. The influence of entities upon the mind is exert- ed either through the medium of every part of the Cc2 306 RECAPITULATION. body, such as shape, &c. ; or through particular parts of the body, called organs of sense. In alV cases, actual contact of some kind is necessary. Nervous connexion between the different organs and the brain. Phrenology, its results, when once fully settled, will not conflict with a correct system of mental philosophy. The Eye : description of its constituent parts, the sclerotica, choroid, cornea, optic nerve, pupil, &c. The eye affords us knowledge of colour, local di- rection, and expansion. Light is the medium, or, rather, the object of vision. The different colours. Distance not an original object of vision, but ac- quired. Proof that extension is an original object of vision. Solid shape is not originally perceived by sight, though peripheral shape is. Apparent and relative, but not actual size, is taught by the eye. The distinctness of objects af- fords some indirect criterion of their distance. The image formed on the retina of the eye, inverted. The objects of our perceptions are also excitants of feeling. Variety and different degrees of feelings excited by the works of nature. Attention necessary to the recollection of our perceptions. The connexion between the image on the retina and the perception of the mind unknown. The Ear : description of its parts, the external ear, the auditory passage, the tympanum, the audi- tory nerve, &c. MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. 307 The atmosphere is the principal medium of sound ; other elastic bodies. Sound is an idea of the mind, caused by the vibrations or pulsations of the agita- ted air upon the tympanum of the ear. The various feelings attending our perceptions of sounds. Sound the exclusive original result of our audi- tory organs ; yet by practice we learn also to judge of local direction and distance. Of echoes. Im- provement of the sense of hearing in the blind. Organ of touch is the whole body, especially the hands. By this organ we acquire a knowledge of the solidity or fluidity of bodies, their shape, exten- sion, smoothness or roughness, heat or cold ; together with the feelings accompanying these perceptions. Feeling of exhaustion from violent effort does not belong to the sense of touch. The idea of exter- nity is the result of touch. Improvement of this sense, especially in the blind. Examples, Sander- son, &c. Method of printing for the blind. The organ of Taste : description of its parts. Benevolent location of this organ. Different fla- vours ; cognitive and sentient results of this sense. Organ of Smell : description of it. Different odours — emitted by all objects that can be smelled. Knowledge of odour alone is the original cognitive result of smell ; but by experience we learn to rec- ognise different objects by their odour. Improve- ment of this sense. Quotation from Dr. Reid. The different theories on the mode of the recipro- cal influence of the body and the soul upon each other in general. 308 RECAPITULATION. The theory of Occasionalism. Theory of pre- established harmony by Leibnitz. Theories to account for a part of this influence, viz., in sensation through the bodily organs. Des Cartes's theory ; Newton's view ; Dr. Hartley's theory of nervous vibrations. The last-named the- ory is that of ideas, as something material, as films, or images, or phantasms, emanating from outward objects and passing through the medium of the or- gan of sense to the brain, and there perceived by the mind. Malebranche's account of this theory. This view charged on Mr. Locke by some writers, and denied by others. Result : no theory can ex- plain this subject. The facts we know, and must admit — the mode we must refer to the great Au- thor of our being. PART II. SENTIENT IDEAS, p. 146. Feelings are those sentient states of the mind me- diately or immediately excited by entities, simple or composite. Feelings are known by the following criteria : I. They have no object beyond themselves. II. Our feelings are not so absolutely dependant for their character on entities without us, as our knowledge is. III. Feelings are always preceded by a cogni- tion of the entity which mediately or immediately produces them, p. 147. RECAPITULATION. 309 CHAPTER I. CLASSIFICATION OF OUR FEELINGS, p. 148. All Feelings are either, I. Individual ; viz., those which have reference exclusively to ourselves ; or, II. Relative; viz., those which have a relation to some other sentient being, or other object. 1. Sensations; feelings accompanying the perceptions of sight, touch, smell, &c. 2. Some Emotions : (a.) Intellectual emo- tions, of the sublime, beautiful. (6.) Moral emotions, connected with conscience. 3. Some of the Affections : (a.) Pleasant. (b.) Unpleasant. 4. Feeling attending the bodily Appetites. Benevolent feelings : love, friendship, grati- tude, veneration, &c. "■§ ;3 . Malevolent feelings : hatred, malice, anger. Sympathetic feelings : condolence, pity, &c. Antipathetic feelings : envy, grudging, and what the Germans term Schadenfreude. $ B ^5 bo a fife Remarks on the Analysis of Feeling's. CLASS I. INDIVIDUAL FEELINGS. 1. Of Sensations. Twofold use of the term, both cognitive and sentient. The latter use preferred, and perception for the cognitive result. 2. Emotions are those transient excitements of feeling which are consequent on mental operations, 310 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. direct or reflective, other than perceptions through the organs of taste, smell, or touch. Emotions suc- ceed cognitions or active operations ; and some- times are succeeded by desires or volition. (a.) Intellectual emotions — of the sublime, its na- ture, objective and subjective ; beautiful; ludicrous; wit ; burlesque ; mock-heroic — -surprise, wonder, as- tonishment, amazement. (b.) Moral emotions are those individual feelings of the mind which are consequent on the cognition of moral truth, conduct, or character. Moral emo- tions are the sentient part of acts of conscience. It is consequent on the cognitive or judicial ingre- dient of conscience, and precedes the impulsive. They are either pleasant or painful, and, in pop- ular language, termed feelings of approval or dis- approval, though, strictly speaking, the approval or disapproval is judicial and cognitive. Our moral emotions, in reference to particular acts, change if our judgment concerning them does. 3. The Affections. By affections we mean those habits, or habitual states of feeling, which are more durable than sensations or emotions. They are either pleasant, as joy, cheerfulness, contentment ; or painful, as penitence, discontent, sadness, despair. 4. Feelings connected with our bodily appetites, such as hunger and thirst. CLASS II. RELATIVE FEELINGS. 1. Benevolent feelings : those feelings which are favourable to the object on which they terminate. RELATIVE FELLINGS. 311 Importance of these feelings to piety and social hap- piness. Benevolence ; love, parental, filial, conju- gal ; gratitude, friendship, respect, confidence, &c. Love to God, adoration. 2. Malevolent, or defensive feelings, are those painful relative feelings which involve hostility, and a disposition to injure the beings on which they ter- minate. These affections were, before the fall, pure- ly defensive and good : in our fallen state, often of- fensive and sinful. 3. Sympathetic feelings are those relative affec- tions of the mind, which imply similarity or conge- niality to the feelings of the being on which they terminate. They are either pleasant or painful. We sympathize most freely with those whose feelings are similar to the prevailing state of our own minds at the time. They are such as compassion, pity, commiseration. 4. Antipathetic feelings are those relative feelings which, though they have reference to some other being, imply only opposition of feeling, but not in- tention of action, such as envy, jealousy, disgust, grudging, fear, dread, horror, &c. Feelings may also be divided into Sensuous, In- tellectual, and Moral ; and into Present, Retro- spective, and Prospective. CHAPTER II. OF ENTITIES AS EXCITANTS OF FEELING, p. 178. SECTION I. All feeling, like knowledge, may be traced, me- diately or immediately, to entities without the mind, p. 178. 312 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. SECTION II. Entities of every class possess some tendency, though very different in degree, to excite feeling in the mind, p. 180. SECTION III. The degrees in which different entities possess this exciting power are very different, and can be accurately learned only from experience ; nor can any organ originally afford us this information, ex- cept the one through which the feeling is produced, p. 181. I. The strongest influence is exerted by entities when they are brought into contact with their ap- propriate organ. II. The next strongest, when we have a prospect- ive knowledge that we shall, at some future time, probably be the subjects of their influence. III. The next strongest, when they excite retro- spective feeling. IV. Sympathetic feeling is weaker than its cor- responding direct feeling. V. The least influence is exerted by them, when we view merely their abstract tendency to produce feeling. SECTION IV. Entities of the classes of solids and liquids ex- cite more feeling, and exert more motive power when near, than when far off, p. 183. SECTION V. The manner in which entities act in exciting feel- RECAPITULATION. 313 ing, seems to be very similar to that observed in the production of knowledge, p. 183. SECTION VI. In feeling, as in knowledge, two things are ne- cessary ; viz., I. The action of the entity on its appropriate or- gan ; and, II. The attention of the mind to that organ, p. 184. CHAPTER III. SUSCEPTIBILITY OF THE MIND FOR FEELING, AND LAWS OF FEELING. First law. Sensation, no less than cognition, is an attribute of the mind and not of the body, p. 185. Second law. The original susceptibility of differ- ent minds for feeling is very different in degree. Influence of temperament : phlegmatic, choleric &c, temperament, p. 186. Third law. Excepting this diversity, which re- sults from the different temperaments, the relative degree of susceptibility for the influence of different entities is in all minds naturally the same, p. 187. Fourth law. Feeling is, in a great measure, in- voluntary at the time, p. 188. Fifth law. But we can add to or subtract from the duration or intensity of the feeling, by confining our attention to the exciting object, or directing it to another, p. 188. Sixth law. When any one feeling or purpose be- comes dominant and habitual in the soul, all others inconsistent with it are impaired, p. 188. Dd 314 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. Seventh law. The two constitutional inclinations of the soul exert an influence upon the tendency of entities to excite feeling in the mind, p. 189. Eighth law. Entities always exert a greater in- fluence when first presented, on account of their novelty, p. 190. Ninth law. Feelings produced in the same per- son, by the same entity, at different times, may be different, p. 190. Tenth law. The susceptibility for feeling is in- creased by attentive practice, p. 191. Eleventh law. Intense and long-continued feel- ing exhausts and fatigues the system, p. 192. Twelfth law. Susceptibility for feeling declines with age and with the decline of the constitution, though that be premature, p. 192. Thirteenth law. A negligent review of entities diminishes their tendency to produce feeling, p. 192. Fourteenth law. Time wears off retrospective feeling, p. 192. Fifteenth law. Feeling is, in general, not in- stantly excited, as knowledge is, p. 194. Sixteenth law. The feelings connected with the gratification of our periodical appetites are pecu- liar, p. 194. I. They are stronger in proportion to the length of previous abstinence, unless that be extreme. II. They are increased by the frequent attention of the soul to the entities capable of gratifying those appetites. III. This feeling is diminished, and eventually suspended, by gratification. RECAPITULATION. 315 IV. It is interrupted by the debility and increas- ed by the vigour of the body. (a.) From the preceding considerations, it fol- lows that we are responsible in a great degree for our individual feelings, as also for the habitual state of our feelings or affections, p. 194. (b.) That feelings are individual, and transient, and continue no longer than the attention of the mind is directed to the entity or to the cognitive idea with which they are connected, p. 195. (c.) By the state of our affections or feelings, is meant the increased or diminished degree of habit- ual susceptibility for feelings of any particular kind, produced by continued voluntary practice, and also the increased or. diminished tendency to the spon- taneous recurrence of the ideas of the entities, which produce the feelings in question, p. 195. PART III. ACTIVE OPERATIONS. Active Operations constitute the most important feature of our character as beings responsible to God, p. 198. The criteria by which they are known : I. Knowledge and feeling are inward effects pro- duced from without. Active operations are out- ward effects, or operations tending ad extra, pro- duced from within. II. Knowledge and feeling require the entities exciting them to have a previous existence ; but the active operations contemplated by our volitions, are future. 316 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. III. The character of our active operations de- pends but little upon the entities upon which they are exerted. The materials on which our active operations are performed, p. 201. I. The external objective entities of the different classes. II. Past mental operations of every class. III. The natural signs by which these represent- atives are expressed. CHAPTER I. DIVISION AND DISCUSSION OF THE ACTIVE OPERATIONS OF THE SOUL. All active operations are alike as it respects mere activity, but differ in regard to the end contempla- ted ; in the operation performed ; in the results of the action ; and in the objects on which they ter- minate, p. 202. SECTION I. Of Inspection. Inspection is that active operation in which the attention of the soul is directed to some entity, sim- ple or composite ; prospective, present, or retro- spective, with a view to acquire some knowledge concerning it, p. 203. The specific object of inspection, in present enti- ties, may be, I. To obtain more correct mental representatives of the properties of entities, p. 205. II. To give more vividness to our mental repre- sentatives of them. RECAPITULATION. 317 III. To ascertain their relations. In retrospective entities, it may be, I. To revive their representatives, p. 206. II. To view their relations to each other. Inspection embraces the voluntary operations of Perception, Consciousness, Conception, Judgment, Recollection, Analytic Reasoning, and Conscience. The Act of Memorizing explained. Analytic reasoning explained. In all our reasonings we proceed on the implica- tion of certain laws of human belief, which are ad- mitted and acted on by all men. Fundamental Laws of Human Belief. 1 . That the testimony of our senses, clearly as- certained, is true. 2. That the testimony of conscience can be re- lied on. 3. That memory, as far as it is distinct, may be relied on. 4. The other operations of the mind, such as reasoning and judgment, may be relied on, with a certainty proportioned to the circumstances of the case. 5. That all men will naturally speak the truth, when they have no motive to practise deception. 6. That every act of consciousness presupposes a conscious being, the soul. — Case of Rev. Dr. Brown. 7. That every act of memory, or succession of aets of consciousness, implies our personal identity. Other truths universally implied in reasoning. Dd2 318 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. 8. That the laws of nature and known properties of entities will continue unchanged. On the uniformity of these laws the enterprise of man and the business of life in general de- pend. 9. That different kinds of truth possess different kinds and degrees of evidence, producing different degrees of belief. SECTION II. Arrangement, p. 217. Arrangement is that active operation of the soul by which we select some from among the mass, ei- ther of external entities themselves, or of our mental representatives of them, and place them, as wholes or units, in a particular order, with a view to a spe- cific purpose. The purposes of this arrangement, and the prin- ciples upon which it may be made, are various : I. We may arrange them according to any one of the various relations of entities to each other ; sameness, diversity, &c. II. We may arrange them according to any prin- ciple of genus, species, &c. III. We may arrange them according to the pro- bative relation of entities to a given proposition, or to the human mind. Here is included all syllogistic reasoning. SECTION III. Modification. Modification is that active operation of the sou] MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. 319 by which we take some from among our mental representatives of real entities (rarely the objective entities themselves), and bring them into such forms or combinations as do not correspond to realities, p. 225. This operation differs from the preceding ; be- cause, I. The operations of Inspection and Arrange- ment are performed as frequently on objective en- tities themselves as on our mental representatives of them ; whereas, that of Modification is conver- sant chiefly about our mental representatives. II. The former two operations take our mental representatives of substantive entities as wholes or units, and leave them such throughout all the pro- cess of their influence ; but Modification changes them from their natural state, and brings them into forms and combinations which do not actually cor- respond to real entities. Modification embraces, I. The process of Abstraction or Generalization, Among the results of this are, {a.) Geometrical axioms ; {b.) Metaphysical axioms ; (c.) Mathemat- ical truths; {d.) Moral general principles. Objection to Kant's view of these truths, as knowledge a priori. II. Fictitious combinations of ideas. (a.) Fictitious simple entities : (b.) Fictitious composite entities or relations, imagination, fancy, wit, burlesque, painting, sculpture. 320 RECAPITULATION. SECTION IV. Mental Agency concerned in the production of Physical Action. This embraces all voluntary control over the en- tire muscular system, by which alone motion is pro- duced in any part of the body, p. 233. The mode of this influence, of the action of mind on muscle, is inexplicable. In all cases of voluntary physical action, we can distinguish the following mental processes : I. The volition to exert the bodily organ. II. The attention of the soul to that organ. III. The inspection of the material on which the operation is to be performed. IV. The active process of the mind conducting and regulating the physical action. SECTION V. Intellectual Intercourse. This process consists in exciting in others the ideas which they themselves have already obtained from those entities on which we wish them to think, and exciting them in such order, and in such com- binations, and with such adjective properties an- nexed, as we wish them to entertain, p. 235. This process is carried on in different ways : I. By speaking, or expressing our ideas by ar- ticulate sounds. We do not, however, by speaking, excite in oth- ers identically the same ideas which we connect with our words, but such ideas as they formerly at- MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. 321 tached to the words which we utter. Every idea of a speaker is succeeded by the following operations before it accomplishes its design, p. 240 : (a.) The idea of the speaker himself. (6.) The recollection of the idea of the sound for- merly associated with that idea by the speaker. (c.) His volition to articulate a similar sound. (d.) The articulating action of his organs on the expiring breath, to produce a similar sound. (e.) The hearer's idea of the sound produced by the speaker's voice. (/.) The hearer's recollection of the similar sound which he himself had often made. (g.) The recurrence of the idea which he for- merly connected with the similar sound made by himself. The structure of the human articulating organs is such, that all men naturally make certain ele- mentary sounds; alphabetic sounds are, therefore, substantially the same in all languages, p. 241. II. By gestures and muscular action of the coun- tenance, p. 242. Pantomime. III. By written signs. {a.) Alphabetical letters ; (b.) Arithmetical fig- ures and signs; (c.) Musical notes. SECTION VI. Composition. Composition is not a distinct active operation, but is complex, consisting of voluntary inspection and arrangement of ideas of entities, simple or compos- 322 RECAPITULATION. ite, together with the act of expressing the ideas thus arranged, by signs, on paper, p. 243. What are called new or original ideas are mere- ly old relations, for the first time viewed by the mind. SECTION VII. Attention, p. 245. Attention is likewise not a distinct operation ; be- cause, I. We cannot conceive of it as acting by itself, but only in connexion with some other operation of the mind. II. It does not give us any results of its action, distinct from those of the active operation with which it is combined. III. It is common to all the active operations. IV. It seems only to be a property of the active operation, conducted at the time. Attention is the energy of the soul exerted on some active operation. The causes which excite attention appear, in general, to be these : I. A volition to bestow attention on the perform- ance of some active operation. II. The present interest or pleasure felt in the op- eration itself. III. Some impression from without made through the bodily organs. MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. 32 3 CHAPTER II. THE MODE OF OCCURRENCE OF THE FIVE ACTIVE OP- ERATIONS. Active Operations are either Voluntary or Spon- taneous, p. 248. SECTION I. Of the Voluntary Occurrence of the Active Operation. The active processes of the soul are voluntary, when undertaken from deliberate choice, p. 249. Do we perform acts of choice ? Yes ; the certainty of our performing such acts rests upon the same basis with the certainty of our other mental operations, such as knowledge and feeling. What is the nature of acts of choice ? I. All men agree that acts of choice differ from acts of necessity. II. It is only for such actions that we accuse or excuse ourselves. III. All men agree that only for their own acts of choice, and the consequences of them, can they really and justly be held responsible, either by God or man. IV. Every reflecting man, who has attained ma- ture development of mind, is conscious of the fact that he can and ought to regulate the voluntary ac- tions of his life according to certain fixed rules and principles, p. 250. But the soul is not left entirely free from bias in the performance of these acts of choice. There 324 RECAPITULATION. are two constitutional inclinations by which it is materially influenced. I. The inclination to Action in accordance with the fitness of things, moral, intellectual, and physical. This inclines us naturally to speak the truth, and to do whatever is right. Crimes are the only excep- tion to the observance of this constitutional inclina- tion. This sense of obligation is universal. It em- braces in it the impulsive part of The Operations of Conscience. The operations of conscience are complex, in- cluding a judicial, a sentient, and an impulsive in- gredient. Conscience, in its impulsive feature, is an original faculty. Each of its features is treated of in its ap- propriate part of this work. The structure of all languages implies the ex- istence and operations of conscience. All men judge the authority of conscience to be supreme. Conscience essential to our character as moral agents. The influence of this constitutional inclination, like that of every other power of the soul, can be increased by obedience to its dictates and dimin- ished by disobedience. II. The inclination to Well-being, or the enjoy- ment of pleasure, present and ultimate, and the avoiding of pain. This embraces, 1. Love of Life : this is universal, and of great utility in its effects. On this principle is based the right of RECAPITULATION. 325 self-defence when unjustly assailed by personal vi- olence. The case the same in principle, whether the as- sailant be a serpent or ravenous beast, or a robber or murderer. 2. Love of esteem or power. Proper use of this principle. Its abuse. 3. Love of property or possession. Its use and abuse — avarice. 4. Love of novelty — curiosity. 5. Sensuality. 6. Love of Science. 7. Social Inclination, &c. These inclinations are not faculties, nor mental operations, nor habits, but natural characteristics of the soul. The first of these inclinations is evidently the more noble ; but in the natural state of man the second preponderates. These inclinations do not act irresistibly. The soul is secondly influenced by ( 1. Our own bodies, acting upon us External j through the bodily appetites. Entities, j 2. All other entities in the universe, p. [ 264. But these entities act not with irresistible force, else men would be compelled always to act vir- tuously, since God has made the inducements to virtue stronger than those to vice. Men can and do resist these motives. Desires — their nature. The native activity of the soul prompts us to ac- tion. E E 326 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. The constitutional inclinations of the soul deter- mine the general character of the ends, or results, at which we aim. Our knowledge presents to us the various entities with their different and relative properties, by ac- tive operations upon which the proposed end may be attained in various ways and in different degrees. The different entities exert a motive power pro- portional to their relative adaptation to accomplish the end proposed ; and, finally, in view of all these circumstances, the soul freely determines in its choice of the different means of attaining the de- sired end. Our definition therefore is, The Will is that power of the soul by which it freely determines, in view of motives, either now or hereafter, absolutely or conditionally ', to perform or not to perform some one or more of the five active operations, p. 270. SECTION II. Of the Spontaneous Occurrence of the Active Opera- tions, p. 273. There are two marks of difference between Vol- untary and Spontaneous active operations. I. The former are the result of volition in their commencement : the latter, not. II. The former are carried on with much more attention and energy than the latter. We are responsible to God for all our spontane- ous actions. I. Spontaneous Inspection, p. 278. In the spontaneous inspection of entities or their RECAPITULATION. 327 mental representatives, the mind is found to pro- ceed in several uniform ways : 1. It seems to follow the relations of the entities which are the subjects of its inspection ; especially sameness, contrariety, contiguity, and causation. 2. It has a tendency to pursue the train of those entities, which have most frequently been the sub- jects of its voluntary attention. 3. It more readily recurs to those objects which have lately been the subjects of its attention. 4. It pursues more frequently those entities which excite the most pleasant feelings, and gratify the second constitutional inclination. 5. It is diverted from its spontaneous operations by the immediate action of some entities through the bodily organs. 6. It is interrupted by volition. II. Spontaneous Arrangement, p. 281. This operation is sometimes carried on spontane- ously. Every figure of comparison consists of spontaneous arrangements according to the relation of similarity expressed in words. III. Spontaneous Modification, p. 282. This occurs very seldom, especially in persons of veracity. IV. Mental Process regulating our Physical Ac- tion, p. 282. This is very often exercised spontaneously. All habits of bodily action are spontaneous operations of this kind. But some actions apparently sponta- neous are instinctive. V. The Process of Intellectual Intercourse, p. 328 MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. 283, is sometimes carried on spontaneously in a revery ; as is evident from our making articulate sounds, in the same spontaneous manner, to express our ideas. PRAGMATIC VIEW, &c. I. When a superabundance of animal and men- tal vigour has been accumulated during sleep, we make a transition from the sleeping to the active, conscious, waking state. II. The moment we make the transition from the sleeping to the waking state, the mind begins to act, and the body, particularly the muscles and or- gans of sense, becomes subservient to the mind. Its first action is generally spontaneous, but this soon gives way to, III. The voluntary actions of physical agency ; which are performed in accordance with the prin- ciples laid down in part iii., chap, ii., sect. i. IV Other voluntary operations of various kinds are undertaken ; and the interval between them filled up by such as are spontaneous. DREAMS. Dreams are those spontaneous trains of mental operation which occur when sleep has in a great SCHMUCKER'S MENTAL PHILOSOPHY, DESIGNED FOR ACADEMIES AND COLLEGES. PUBLISHED BY HARPER & BROTHERS. From the American Biblical Repository, in a review of the work by Rev. Dr. Kratjth, President of Pennsylvania College. The Psychology of Dr. Schmucker comes before us with peculiar preten- sions, and raises, in consequence of them, peculiar expectations. It propo- ses to be the product, not of the study of the patriarchs of the science, but of original examination of the mind ; or, to express it in the wonted phra- seology of the craft, the exercise of consciousness in regard to the author's mental operations. The propriety and the value of this method all the initi- ated will concede. Its difficulty has deterred many from undertaking it, and but few comparatively have push- ed it to any great extent. But, not- withstanding the magnitude of the undertaking, our author has, during years of patient study, ventured inde- pendently to analyze his own mental processes. The history of his pro- cedure, and the classification of our mental actions, are here given us. Such a contribution from such a mind ought to be regarded as a present of no inconsiderable value. . . . The au- thor of this book, in the true spirit of the Baconian philosophy, discards for the time the labours of others, and engages in proper efforts of induction, to obtain a firmer footing. In pursu- ing this course he has not failed. Those who read his book — and we venture to predict that it will be exten- sively read — will not fail to perceive that he has planted his standard in ad- vance of his predecessors. He takes his place among the original and in- dependent thinkers, and deserves to be enrolled — an honour which we would not allow to the mere compi- ler or teacher of mental philosophy — among metaphysicians, with such men as Kant, Heinroth, Schubert, in Germany; Locke, Reid, Stuart, and Brown, in Great Britain. Our author divides all mental phenomena into three classes : 1. Cognitive ideas ; 2. Sentient ideas ; and, 3. Active opera- tions. The remarks on the cognitive class of ideas are admirable. The details of their extent is very accu- rately given. In connexion with cog- nitive ideal, we have a statement of the sources of error, the careful study of which cannot but be of great use to every one who would have clear mental representatives of external things or an accurate acquaintance with truth. We think the subject of feeling has been placed in a clear and comprehensive light. The pages on this subject cannot be read without the conviction that the author was not moving in the beaten track; that he has studied carefully the evolution of feeling, and has exhibited it in such a manner as to render his labours worthy of high praise. A slight com- parison of the systems of metaphy- sicians will render it evident that a reforming hand was needed in this part of mental science. We see it, and we seek it here; and, without claiming for this part of the work per- fection, we give it our decided appro- bation. The third and last part of the work we take up with the feel- ing that it would require much space to do it justice. Had the author done nothing else, his account of the ac- tive operations would entitle him to the praise which we have accorded, and give to his contributions to meta- physics the claims of originality and depth. We challenge for this part of the work no ordinary interest. It is interesting to the man of letters, to the metaphysician, to the orator, to the theologian, and to the expounder, in the sacred desk, of the Gospel of the Son of God. The whole subject of the freedom of the will is discussed in a very satisfactory manner, and the account of the constitutional incli- nations by which we are influenced presents the whole matter in a novel light, and renders this part of the work peculiarly instructive. It en- ables us to solve the manifestations of man's moral structure, and shows clearly the source of the light and shade of human character. We leave this work with sincere respect for the abilities of the author, gratitude for his labours, which have been brought to so successful an issue, and with the determination to make use of his labours in our future efforts to teach ingenuous youth the philosophy of the noblest part of God's creation, the im- mortal mind of immortal man. SCHMUCKER S MENTAL PHILOSOPHY. Commendatory Letters — continued. From Rev. D. M'Conaughy, D.D., President of Washington College, Pa. I have read with much interest Dr. Schmucker's late work on mental sci- ence. It seems to me to exhibit an accurate and intelligible development of the phenomena of mind. They are all included in his divisions, and all are assigned to their proper classes. Those classes are entirely distinguish- able and distinct. The-cbjects which give rise to the various mental phe- nomena are well defined ; and the re- sulting knowledge, feeling and action, are explained in a manner which is verified by the consciousness of every man who attentively reads the histo- ry of his own mind. Accustomed to terms and phrases which seem almost consecrated by their long association with psychological subjects, the new nomenclature strikes the reader as singular, but in import it is precise and significant. I congratulate the author upon having presented to the literary world a volume embracing so much useful information upon the constitution, laws, and operations of the mind, and I hope that its benefi- cial influence will be widely felt, and its merit be duly appreciated. From Rev. S. Boyer, A.M., Principal of the Academy in York, Pa. I concur in the opinion of Dr. M'Conaughy, believing the work of Dr. Schmucker to be a production of much merit, and well adapted not only for intelligent popular readers, but also for use as a text-book in col- leges and academies. Extract of a letter from Rev. M. Cald- well, Professor of Metaphysics and Political Economy in Dickinson Col- lege, Carlisle, Pa. I have examined and re-examined the work of Dr. Schmucker on Men- tal Philosophy, and, I must say, with increased satisfaction. I am pleased with the spirit in which the author has conducted his investigations, and doubt not but many of his original views will be adopted by future wri- ters on the human mind. Notwith- standing the forbidding terminology adopted in the work, its truly philo- ophical character will cause "it to be read with interest by every lover of mental science. From the Rev. Dr. Morris, of Balti- more. . .It has long been known that the learned author contemplated the pub- lication of his system of Psycholo- gy ; and from the representations of its character by his pupils, to whom it has been taught for some years, it has been looked for with impatience. We are aware of his fondness for such investigations and his metaphysical acumen, and we had a right to expect a work of uncommon character and of an original cast — hence we have a new and original system. This work presents an admirable specimen of rigid analytical induction. It is all close, solid, massive argumentation. The lines of division are distinctly drawn — the whole subject is nicely dissected — each part is separately laid before you, and then, again, its con- nexion with the whole plainly demon- strated. From the Methodist Quarterly Review. . . .Designing the work, as the title intimates, for a text-book in colleges and academies, Dr. Schmucker has judiciously confined himself to a rigid outline of his system, leaving detailed illustration chiefly to the viva voce in- structions of the teacher. This is a feature of the work which pleases us much. We are presented, as it were, with an anatomical skeleton, which shows us clearly the connexion and ramification of the operations of the mind ; with a chart of our road, which may guide us safely as Ariadne's clew through the labyrinthine windings of the darksome way. Perhaps the most interesting and valuable portion of the volume is the third part : that treats of the active operations of the mind under five heads, inspection, arrange- ment, modification, mental direction of physical action, and the process of intellectual intercourse between dif- ferent minds. We are convinced that those who have most deeply studied the constitution of the human mind will here find much matter for profit- able reflection. We cannot conclude this review without a hearty recom- mendation of the work to the atten- tion of instructers. From the American Biblical Repository, in an editorial notice. Dr. Schmucker, if we mistake not, has accomplished a valuable work by the clearness and simplicity of his di- vision of the elements of this science. There is no affectation of novelty ; but the author, having thoroughly studied the works of others, has carefully sub- jected every principle to the test of his schmucker's mental philosophy. Commendatory Letters — continued. own experience. The result is the suggestion of what he regards some important modifications and improve- ments in the arrangement and classi- fication of the materials of the sci- ence ; and which, as a system, may perhaps with some propriety be de- nominated new. This system has been constructed with great care and thor- oughness. It is sufficiently conden- sed in the volume before us, and is stated and illustrated with unusual precision and clearness. It is in these respects well adapted for use as a text-book in academies and colleges. The difference between the principles of this system and those of others is only occasionally referred to, and the work is wholly free from that polem- ical aspect which has too mch af- fected most philosophical discussions. On the whole, we anticipate a favour- able reception of this new system, as a concise, intelligible, and convenient class-book of mental science. From a review of the work in the New World. . . . Casting away the trammels of authority, Dr. Schmucker has dared to be an original and independent thinker. Those who read the book will not fail to perceive that it is not the sole product of the study of the patriarchs of the science, but that its original features give the author a place alongside those patriarchs, Locke, Reid, Stewart, and Brown. Dr. Schmucker has given us a new analysis of the mental operations, by which their synthesis is illustrated and rendered more intelligible. The antagonism of his system to transcen- dentalism is decided. The friends of the German or transcendental school may naturally be expected to resist Dr. Schmucker's publication, which, be- longing to the school of Locke and Reid, was professedly and fairly con- structed by inductive investigations. From the Lutheran Observer. Dr. Schmucker's work bears the same relation to the present stage of mental science which was sustained by the immortal essay of Locke to the systems by which it was surrounded. . . The great incantation by which Locke wrought such wonders was not that he produced anything positively new, nor that his system advanced facts before unheard of; but that he re- modelled, simplified, and stated with more correctness, and a reduction to truer principles, what had long been ac- knowledged as truth. ... It is in these important particulars that we trace the resemblance between Locke's Es- say on the Human Understanding and Dr. Schmucker's Psychology. The great (might I be allowed the expres- sion), the transcendent merit of this Psychology, is its new division and its accurate definition. Completeness and order are the characteristics alike of the mind and writing of its author. ... To the Psychology, the cherished product of years of careful investiga- tion, those qualities belong in an em- inent degree, and moral evidence be- neath his pen has assumed almost the simplicity of element, and clearness of mathematical demonstration. ... In our opinion this work presents the clearest, most intelligible, and satis- factory view which has yet been fur- nished of the workings of the inner man. From the Southern Literary Messenger of May, 1842. . . . For purposes of education, we know of no book more available than a concise and well-arranged treatise on Psychology, or a system of Mental Philosophy founded on consciousness and common sense, by one of the able theological professors at the Gettys- burg Institution. It is expressly de- signed for the use of academies and colleges, and we commend it to the attention of teachers and all interested in education. From the Philadelphia Observer. ... It gives us pleasure to commend this work to the attention of the pub- he. It contains the results of long- continued thought and inquiries of a distinguished scholar and able writer on a science which is intimately con- nected with the progress of truth in almost every department of knowl- edge We consider the work emi- nently worthy of the attention and study of ministers, students, and intel- ligent popular readers. K7 In addition to the above, nu- merous notices, equally favourable, of Schmucker's Psychology, have been received from the most respect- able sources, from some of which the publishers may hereafter present brief extracts. RECAPITULATION. 329 measure suspended that self-control through reason and volition, which we possess, and ordinarily ex- ercise, when awake. Dreams can have nothing ominous or prophetic in them, unless they are miraculous. THE END. i g '% %< % X o. ~x X ^ » X X X - ,= ^ ^ x X v v ^ --> vOo oc / / . v* ^ X $ ^x - Deacidlfied using the Bookkeeper proce v Neutralizing agent: Magnesium Oxide •$.' Treatment Date: Oct. 2004 PreservationTechnoiogle A WORLD LEADER IN PAPER PRESER\?ATI! 1 1 1 Thomson Park Drive Cranberry Township, PA 16066 (724)779-2111 *+. \ '■ - tt y x v HSSBBSBl Bra ^n -<"'• ■ - i,l.^ ». , J- lv»lVH«, l «V , »i(»,*i. ''44 -T, LIBRARY OF CONGRESS to-'E^ntf ■ § ■ ■ ■ I ■ f* 1 I *■■*>■> 'Sjjii ■ b^'rr^jT^.irrHv.ti **v» »»<