- . . . + . .. . . *. . - - - - A 581,644 1 . 1 • ' - * iriti 2:59 min me . . * . . . fisit * . . * . 1 G . 4 -' + USA ! * 11 + ! . . . . , - . . . 1. .. . + . . 1 1. . . 1 . * . i . + i . + . 0 . W.7890 mirisinden bi 7 IEVAL r i 3 UN . n . . . . Sir jirani bibli . .. . . . . .' .W = . . . Hud . . i .. N . . de A . 1 WPR ini, PAINETU. H .2 .. +1 . N O WYNIKI ta 1 WILL TYWNERS ISHT M . T . IS ::::: . . . . . P 106 181723 LLLLLLLLLLOLU BullSIMU . ng w ill .... TEST SCIENTIA .. M ... ... LIBRARY VERITAS OF THE .. OF MICHIGAN I URIHLIMAAndium - UNIVERSITY OF MIC NINSULUMIWINUINISHLIGHWIMMIG ........ - - - 1 .. - -- ..- he .-.- -. - - - --- - I TUNION . ME - - - S 5711HRM TRITIONELINNIHURTUM i !!! mitiitiliniintillittiin minnimhihinaIMAMARIANA - ------- - -.-. . V SI OUR!5 PLN (!5 PENINSULA AN AMO NAM CUMSPICL annuumHIMNHUMIHHunninumtulituliuunnMNOMNIH X. AL JI L.J.UU...NO.L'AJU. UV 37 IIIIIIIIIIIIIIII 2011MMUNION MINIMIN TOOOOOOOOOOOOO000000 I --. STILNlllllllllllllllllllll Ullen llllll - 2000 -200... .......OOOOOOOOOOOOOO ..... TANTI INVITHIN Dinwinnnnnuumminum munar . S . ON THE PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. Cambridge: PRINTED BY C. J. CLAY, M. A. AT THE UNIVERSITY PRESS. 5-104 ON THE PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY, CHAPTERS HISTORICAL AND CRITICAL ; BY WILLIAM WHEWELL, D.D. BLASTER OF TRINITY COLLEGE, CAMBRIDGE, AND CORRESPONDING MEMBER OF THE INSTITUTE OF FRANCE. INCLUDING THE COMPLETION OF. TAE THIRD EDITION OF THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE INDUCTIVE SCIENCES. el pedir U W SV X. lu ΛΑΜΠΑΔΙΑ ΕΧΟΝΤΕΣ ΔΙΑΔΩΣΟΥΣΙΝ ΑΛΛΗΔΟΙΣ. LONDON: JOHN W. PARKER AND SON, WEST STRAND. 1860. THE following are the latest editions of the series of works which has been published connected with the present subject: History of the Inductive Sciences, 3 Vols. 1857. History of Scientific Ideas, 2 Vols. 1858. Novum Organon Renovatum, I Vol. 1858. On the Philosophy of Discovery, 1 Vol. 1860. To the History of the Inductive Sciences are appended two Indexes (in Vol. I.), an Index of Proper Names, and an Index of Technical Terms. These Indexes, and the Tables of Contents of the other works, will enable the reader to refer to any person or event included in this series. ᏢᎡ E F A CE . MHE two works which I entitled The History of the Inductive Sciences, and The Philosophy of the Inductive Sciences, were intended to present to the reader a view of the steps by which those portions of human knowledge which are held to be most certain and stable have been acquired, and of the philosophical principles which are involved in those steps. Each of these steps was a scientific Discovery, in which a new conception was applied in order to bind together observed facts. And though the con- junction of the observed facts was in each case an example of logical Induction, it was not the induc- tive process merely, but the novelty of the result in each case which gave its peculiar character to the History; and the Philosophy at which I aimed was not the Philosophy of Induction, but the Philosophy of Discovery. In the present edition I have de- scribed this as my object in my Title. PREFACE. A great part of the present volume consists of chapters which composed the twelfth Book of the Philosophy in former editions, which Book was then described as a Review of Opinions on the nature of Knowledge and the Method of seeking it.' I have added to this part several new chapters, on Plato, Aristotle, the Arabian Philosophers, Francis Bacon, Mr. Mill, Mr. Mansel, the late Sir William Hamil- ton, and the German philosophers Kant, Fichte, Schelling and Hegel. I might, if time had allowed, have added a new chapter on Roger Bacon, founded on his Opus Minus and other works, recently published for the first time under the direction of the Master of the Rolls; a valuable contribution to the history of philosophy. But the review of this work would not materially alter the estimate of Roger Bacon which I had derived from the Opus Majus. But besides these historical and critical surveys of the philosophy of others, I have ventured to intro- duce some new views of my own; namely, views which bear upon the philosophy of religion. I have done so under the conviction that no philosophy of the universe can satisfy the minds of thoughtful men which does not deal with such questions as inevi- tably force themselves on our notice, respecting the Author and the Object of the universe ; and also PREFACE. vii universe which has any consistency must sug- gest answers, at least conjectural, to such ques- tions. No Cosmos is complete from which the ques- tion of Deity is excluded; and all Cosmology has a side turned towards Theology. Though I am aware therefore how easy it is, on this subject, to give offence and to incur obloquy, I have not thought it right to abstain from following out my philosophical principles to their results in this department of specu- lation. The results do not differ materially from those at which many pious and thoughtful speculators have arrived in previous ages of the world; though they have here, as seems to me, something of novelty in their connection with the philosophy of science. But this point I willingly leave to the calm de- cision of competent judges. I have added in an Appendix various Essays, previously published at different times, which may serve perhaps to illustrate some points of the history and philosophy of science, Se TRINITY LODGE, February 8, 1856. ON THE PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. CONTENTS The chapters marked thus * appear now for the first time. The chapters marked thus † have appeared in other works. CHAP. I. INTRODUOTION. CHAP. II. PLATO. CHAP. III. * ADDITIONAL REMARKS ON PLATO. 1. The Doctrine of Ideas. 2. The Doctrine of the One and Many. 3. The notion of the nature and aim of Science. 4. The Survey of existing Sciences, 5. The Constitution of the human Mind. CHAP. IV. ARISTOTLE. CHAP. V. * ADDITIONAL REMARKS ON ARISTOTLE. 1. Induction. 2. Invention. 3. The One in the Many. The “Five Words.” 5. Aristotle's contribution to the Physical Sciences. 6. Aristotle's Astronomy. 7. Aristotle on Classification. 8. F. Bacon on Aristotle. 9. Discovery of Causes. 10. Plato and Aristotle. 11. Aristotle against Plato's Ideas. CONTENTS. CHÁP. VI. THE LATER GREEKS. CHAP. VII. THE ROMANS. CHAP. VIII. *ARABIAN PHILOSOPHERS. CHAP. IX. THE SCHOOLMEN OF THE MIDDLE AGES. CHAP. X. THE INNOVATORS OF THE MIDDLE AGES. Raymond Lully. CHAP. XI. THE INNOVATORS OF THE MIDDLE AGES- continued. Roger Bacon. CHAP. XII. THE REVIVAL OF PLATONISM. 1. Causes of Delay in the Advance of Knowledge. 2. Causes of Progress. 3. Hermolaus Barbarus, &c. 4. Nicolaus Cusanus. 5. Manilius Ficinus. 6. Francis Patricius. 7. Picus, Agrippa, &c. 8. Paracelsus, Fludd, &c. CHAP. XIII. THE THEORETICAL REFORMERS OF SCIENCE. I. Bernardinus Telesius. 2. Thomas Campanella. 3. Andrew Cæsalpinus. 4. Giordano Bruno. 5. Peter Ramus. 6. The Reformers in General. 7. Melancthon. I. Charo CHAP. XIV. THE PRACTICAL REFORMERS OF SCIENCE. Character of the Practical Reformers, Leonardo da Vinci. 3. Copernicus. 4. Fabricius. 5. Maurolycus. 6. Benedetti. 7. Gilbert. CONTENTS, si 8. Galileo. 9. Kepler. 10. Tycho. CHAP. XV. FRANCIS BACON. 1. (I.) General Remarks. 2. Common estimate of bim. 3. We consider only Physical Science. 4. He is placed at the head of the change: 5. And justly. 6. (II.) He proclaims a New Era 7. (III.) By a Change of Method; 130 8. Including successive Steps; 9. Gradually ascending. (IV.) He contrasts the Old and the New Method. II. (V.) Has he neglected Ideas? 12. No. 13. Examples of Ideas treated by him. He has failed in applying his Method 15. (VI.) To the Cause of Heat. 16. He seeks Causes before Laws. 137 17. (VII.) His Technical Form worthless. 18. He is confused by words. 19. His “Instances." 20. Contain some good Suggestions. 21. (VIII.) His "Idols.” 22. (IX.) His view of Utility. 23. (X.) His Hopefulness. 24. (XI.) His Piety. 14. CHAP. XVI. * ADDITIONAL REMARKS ON FRANCIS BACON. 1. Mr. Ellis's views. 2. Mr. Spedding's views. CHAP. XVII. FROM BAQON TO NEWTON. I. Harvey. 2. Descartes. 3. Gassendi. 4. Actual Progress in Science. CONTENTS. 5. Otto Guericke, &c. 6. Hooke. 7. Royal Society. 8. Bacon's New Atalantis. 9. Cowley. 10. Barrow. CHAP. XVIII. NEWTON. 1. Animating effect of his Discoveries. 2. They confirm Bacon's views. 3. Newton shuns Hypotheses. 4. His views of Inductive Philosophy. 5. His “Rules of Philosophizing." 6. The First Rule. 7. What is a “True Cause”? 8. Such as are real? 9. Or those which are proved? 10. Use of the Rule. Rule otherwise expressed. The Second Rule. What are Events “of the same kind" ? The Third Rule: Not safe. 16. The Fourth Rule. 17. Occult Qualities. 18. Ridiculed. 19. Distinction of Laws and Causes. CHAP. XIX. LOOKE AND HIS FRENOH FOLLOWERS. 1. Cause of Locke's popularity. 2. Sensational School. 3. His inconsistencies. 4. Condillac, &c. Importance of Language. Ground of this. 7. The Encyclopedists. 8. Helvetius. 9. Value of Arts. 10. Tendency to Reaction. CONTENTS. xili CHAP. XX. THE REACTION AGAINST THE SENSATIONAL SCHOOL. “Nisi intellectus ipse.” 2. Price's “Review." 3. Stewart defends Price. 4. Archbishop Whately. 5. Laromiguière. 6. M. Cousin. 7. M. Ampère. 8. His Classification of Sciences. 9. Kant's Reform of Philosophy. 10. Its Effect in Germany. CHAP. XXI. FURTHER ADVANCE OF THE SENSATIONAL SCHOOL. M. Auguste Comte. M. Comte on three States of Science. 2. M. Comte rejects the Search of Causes. I 3. Causes in Physics. 4. Causes in other Sciences. 5. M. Comte's Practical Philosophy. 6. M. Comte on Hypotheses. * 7. M. Comte's Classification of Sciences. , CHAP. XXII. *MR. MILL'S LOGIO. (I.) What is Induction ? SS 1-14. (II.) Induction or Description, SS 15-23.. (III.) In Discovery a new Conception is introduced, SS 24–37. (IV.) Mr. Mill's Four Methods of Inquiry, $S 38 -40. (V.) His Examples, SS 414-48. (VI.) Mr. Mill against Hypotheses, SS 49, 50. (VII.) Against prediction of Facts, SS 51–53. (VIII.) Newton's Vera Causa, SS 54, 55. (IX.) Successive Generalizations, SS 56-62. (X.) Mr. Mill's Hope from Deductions, SS 63-67. (XI.) Fundamental opposition of our Doctrines, S8 68 71. (XII.) Absurdities in Mr. Mill's Logic, $$ 72-74. xiv CONTENTS. CHAP. XXIII. * POLITICAL ECONOMY AS AN INDUCTIVE SOIENCE. 1. Moral Sciences. 2. Political Economy. 3. Wages, Profits, and Rents. 4. Premature Generalizations. 5. Correction of these by Induction-Rent. , Wages. 7. „ Population. CHAP. XXIV. *MODERN GERMAN PAILOSOPHY. (I.) Science is the Idealization of Facts, SS 1~-8. (II.) Successive German Philosophies. Kant, Fichte, Schelling, Hegel, SS 9–16. CBAP. XXV. *THE FUNDAMENTAL ANTITHESIS AS IT EXISTS · IN THE MORAL WORLD. Moral Progress is the Realization of Ideas. CHAP. XXVI. *OF THE “PHILOSOPHY OF THE INFINITE." God is Eternal. CHAP. XXVII. SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON ON INERTIA AND WEIGHT. 1. Primary and Secondary Qualities. 2. Meaning of the Distinction. 3. Sir W. Hamilton adds “Secundo-Primary." 4. Inertia. 5. Sir W. Hamilton's arguments and reply. 6. Gravity. Sir W. Hamilton's arguments and reply. CHAP. XXVIII. + INFLUENCE OF GERMAN SYSTEMS OF PHI- LOSOPHY IN BRITAIN. 1. Stewart on Kant. 2. Mr. G. H. Lewes on Kant. 4-6. Mr. Mansel on Kant. His objection to our Fundamental Ideas, and Reply. 7-10. New Axioms are possible. II–13. Mr. Mansel's Kantianism. 14-16. Axioms are not from experience. CONTENTS. XV CHAP. XXIX. *NECESSARY TRUTH IS PROGRESSIVE. Objections considered. CHAP. XXX. *THE THEOLOGICAL BEARING OF THE PHILO- SOPHY OF DISCOVERY. 1-4. How can necessary truths be actual ? 5, 6. Small extent of necessary truth. 7. How did things come to be as they are ? 8. View of the Theist. 9-12. Is this Platonism? 13. Idea of Time. 15. Ideas of Force and Matter. 16. Creation of Matter. 17. Platonic Ideas. 18–21. Idea of Kind. Idea of Substance. 23. Idea of Final Cause. 24, 25. Human immeasurably inferior to Divine. 26. Science advances towards the Divine Ideas. 27. Recapitulation. CHAP. XXXI. *Man's KNOWLEDGE OF God. 1, 2. Opinions. 3. From Nature we learn something of God. 4-6. Though but little. 7, 8. From ourselves we learn something concerning God. 9-11. Objections answered. 12. Creation. 13. End of the World. 14. Moral and Theological views enter. CHAP. XXXII. *ANALOGIES OF PHYSICAL AND RELIGIOUS PHILOSOPHY. 1, 2. Idealization of Facts and Realization of Ideas; 3, 4. Both imperfect. 5, 6. Divine Ideas perfect. 7-9. Realization of Divine Love. 10-13. Realization of Divine Justice. 14. Analogy of Physical and Moral Philosophy. xvi CONTENTS 15, 16. Supernatural Beginning, Middle, and End indi- cated. 17. Suggestion of a Future State. 18–20. Confirmation from the Intellect of Man. 21. From the Moral Nature of Man. APPENDIX. PAGE APPEND. A. OF THE PLATONIC THEORY OF IDEAS . 403 B. ON PLATO'S SURVEY OF THE SCIENCES · 417 BB. ON Plato's NOTION OF DIALECTIO . . 429 C. OF THE INTELLECTUAL POWERS ACOORDING TO PLATO . . . . . . 440 D. CRITICISM OF ARISTOTLE'S ACCOUNT OF INDUCTION . . . . . . 449 E. ON THE FUNDAMENTAL ANTITHESIS OF PHILOSOPHY . . . . . . 462 F. REMARKS ON A REVIEW OF THE PHILO- SOPHY OF THE INDUCTIVE SOIENCES . 482 G. ON THE TRANSFORMATION OF HYPOTHESES IN THE HISTORY OF SCIENCE . . . 492 H. ON HEGEL'S CRITICISM OF NEWTON'S PRINCIPIA. . . . . . . 504 Appendix to the Memoir on Hegel's Criti- cism of Newton's Principia . . . 513 K. DEMONSTRATION THAT ALL MATTER 18 HEAVY . . . . . . . 522 TOIT VIII ON THE PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. Wär' nicht das Auge sonnenhaft Wie könnten wir das Licht erblicken ? Lebt nicht in uns des Gottes eigne Kraft Wie könnte uns das Göttliche entzücken? GOETAE. Were nothing sunlike in the Eye How could we Light itself descry? Were nothing godlike in the Mind How could we God in Nature find? CHAPTER 1. INTRODUCTION. DY the examination of the elements of human D thought in which I have been engaged, and by a consideration of the history of the most clear and certain parts of our knowledge, I have been led to doctrines respecting the progress of that exact and systematic knowledge which we call Science; and these doctrines I have endeavoured to lay before the reader in the History of the Sciences and of Scientific Ideas. The questions on which I have thus ventured to pronounce have had a strong interest for man from the earliest period of his intellectual progress, and have been the subjects of lively discussion and bold speculation in every age. I conceive that in the doc- trines to which these researches have conducted us, we have a far better hope that we possess a body of permanent truths than the earlier essays on the same subjects could furnish. For we have not taken our examples of knowledge at hazard, as earlier specula- tors did, and were almost compelled to do; but have drawn our materials from the vast store of unques- tioned truths which modern science offers to us : and we have formed our judgment concerning the nature and progress of knowledge by considering what such science is, and how it has reached its present condition. But though we have thus pursued our speculations concerning knowledge with advantages which earlier writers did not possess, it is still both interesting and instructive for us to regard the opinions upon this subject which have been delivered by the philosophers of past times. It is especially interesting to see some of the truths which we have endeavoured to expound, gradually dawning in men's minds, and assuming the B 2 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. clear and permanent form in which we can now con- template them. I shall therefore, in the ensuing chapters, pass in review many of the opinions of the writers of various ages concerning the mode by which man best acquires the truest knowledge; and I shall endeavour, as we proceed, to appreciate the real value of such judgments, and their place in the progress of sound philosophy. In this estimate of the opinions of others, I shall be guided by those general doctrines which I have, as I trust, established in the histories already published. And without attempting here to give any summary of these doctrines, I may remark that there are two main principles by which speculations on such sub- jects in all ages are connected and related to each 1 other; namely, the opposition of Ideas and Sensations, i and the distinction of practical and speculative know- ✓ ledge. The opposition of Ideas and Sensations is ex- -hibited to us in the antithesis of Theory and Fact, which are necessarily considered as distinct and of i opposite natures, and yet necessarily identical, and constituting Science by their identity. In like man- ner, although practical knowledge is in substance identical with speculative, (for all knowledge is specu- lation, there is a distinction between the two in their history, and in the subjects by which they are exem- plified, which distinction is quite essential in judging of the philosophical views of the ancients. The alternatives of identity and diversity, in these two antitheses,—the successive separation, opposition, and reunion of principles which thus arise, --have pro- duced, as they may easily be imagined capable of doing,) a long and varied series of systems concerning the nature of knowledge; among which we shall have to guide our course by the aid of the views already presented. I am far from undertaking, or wishing, to review the whole series of opinions which thus come under our notice; and I do not even attempt to examine all the principal authors who have written on such sub- jects. I merely wish to select some of the most con- INTRODUCTION. 5 siderable forms which such opinions have assumed, and to point out in some measure the progress of truth from age to age. In doing this, I can only endeavour to seize some of the most prominent features of each time and of each step, and I must pass rapidly from classical antiquity to those which we have called the dark ages, and from them to modern times. At each of these periods the modifications of opinion, and the speculations with which they were connected, formed a vast and tangled maze, the byways of which our plan does not allow us to enter. We shall esteem ourselves but too fortunate, if we can discover the single track by which ancient led to modern philo- sophy. I must also repeat that my survey of philosophical writers is here confined to this one point,--their opi- nions on the nature of knowledge and the method of science. I with some effort avoid entering upon other parts of the philosophy of those authors of whom I speak; I knowingly pass by those portions of their speculations which are in many cases the most inter- esting and celebrated ;—their opinions concerning the human soul, the Divine Governor of the world, the foundations or leading doctrines of politics, religion, and general philosophy. I am desirous that my reader should bear this in mind, since he must other- wise be offended with the scanty and partial view which I give in this place of the philosophers whom I enumerate. CHAPTER II. PLATO. THERE would be small advantage in beginning our I examination earlier than the period of the Socratic School at Athens; for although the spirit of inquiry on such subjects had awakened in Greece at an earlier period, and although the peculiar aptitude of the Grecian mind for such researches had shown itself repeatedly in subtle distinctions and acute reasonings, all the positive results of these early efforts were con- tained in a more definite form in the reasonings of the Platonic age. Before that time, the Greeks did not possess plain and familiar examples of exact know- ledge, such as the truths of Arithmetic, Geometry, Astronomy and Optics became in the school of Plato; nor were the antitheses of which we spoke above, so distinctly and fully unfolded as we find them in Plato's works. The question which hinges upon one of these anti- theses, occupies a prominent place in several of the Platonic dialogues ; namely, whether our knowledge be obtained by means of Sensation or of Ideas. One of the doctrines which Plato most earnestly inculcated upon his countrymen was, that we do not know con- cerning sensible objects, but concerning ideas. The first attempts of the Greeks at metaphysical analysis had given rise to a school which maintained that material objects are the only realities. In opposition to this, arose another school, which taught that ma- terial objects have no permanent reality, but are ever waxing and waning, constantly changing their sub- stance. “And hence," as Aristotle says", "arose the doctrine of ideas which the Platonists held. For they 1 Mctaph. xii. 4 PLATO. assented to the opinion of Heraclitus, that all sensible objects are in a constant state of flux. So that if there is to be any knowledge and science, it must be concerning some permanent natures, different from the sensible natures of objects; for there can be no permanent science respecting that which is perpetu- ally changing. It happened that. Socrates turned his speculations to the moral virtues, and was the first philosopher who endeavoured to give universal defi- nitions of such matters. He wished to reason sys- tematically, and therefore he tried to establish defi- nitions, for definitions are the basis of systematic reasoning. There are two things which may justly be looked upon as steps in philosophy due to Socrates; inductive reasonings, and universal definitions ;—both of them steps which belong to the foundations of science. Socrates, however, did not make universals, or definitions separable from the objects; but his fol- lowers separated them, and these essences they termed Ideas." And the same account is given by other writers”. “Some existences are sensible, some intel- ligible: and according to Plato, if we wish to under- stand the principles of things, we must first separate the ideas from the things, such as the ideas of Simi- larity, Unity, Number, Magnitude, Position, Motion : second, that we must assume an absolute Fair, Good, Just, and the like: third, that we must consider the ideas of relation, as Knowledge, Power: recollecting that the Things which we perceive have this or that appellation applied to them because they partake of this or that Idea; those things being just which par- ticipate in the idea of The Just, those being beautiful, which contain the idea of The Beautiful.” And many of the arguments by which this doctrine was main- tained are to be found in the Platonic dialogues. Thus the opinion that true knowledge consists in sensation, which had been asserted by Protagoras and others, is refuted in the Thecetetus: and, we may add, so vic- toriously refuted, that the arguments there put forth 2 Diog. Laert. Vit. Plat. 8 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. have ever since exercised a strong influence upon the speculative world. It may be remarked that in the minds of Plato and of those who have since pursued the same paths of speculation, the interest of such dis- cussions as those we are now referring to, was by no means limited to their bearing upon mere theory; but was closely connected with those great questions of morals which have always a practical import. Those who asserted that the only foundation of knowledge was sensation, asserted also that the only foundation of virtue was the desire of pleasure. And in Plato, the metaphysical part of the disquisitions concerning know- ledge in general, though independent in its principles, always seems to be subordinate in its purpose to the questions concerning the knowledge of our duty. Since Plato thus looked upon the Ideas which were involved in each department of knowledge as forming its only essential part, it was natural that he should look upon the study of Ideas as the true mode of pur- suing knowledge. This he himself describes in the Philebus. “The best way of arriving at truth is not very difficult to point out, but most hard to pursue. All the arts which have ever been discovered, were revealed in this manner. It is a gift of the gods to man, which, as I conceive, they sent down by some Prometheus, as by Prometheus they gave us the light of fire; and the ancients, more clear-sighted than we, and less removed from the gods, handed down this traditionary doctrine: that whatever is said to be, comes of One and of Many, and comprehends in it- itself the Finite and the Infinite in coalition (being One Kind, and consisting of Infinite Individuals). And this being the state of things, we must, in each case, endeavour to seize the One Idea (the idea of the Kind) as the chief point; for we shall find that it is there. And when we have seized this one thing, we may then consider how it comprehends in itself two, or three, or any other number; and, again, examine each of these ramifications separately; till at last we 3 T. ii. p. 16, c, d. ed. Bekker, t. V. p. 437. PLATO. perceive, not only that One is at the same time One and Many, but also how many. And when we have thus filled up the interval between the Infinite and the One, we may consider that we have done with each one. The gods then, as I have said, taught us by tradition thus to contemplate, and to learn, and to teach one another. But the philosophers of the pre- sent day seize upon the One, at hazard, too soon or too late, and then immediately snatch at the Infinite; but the intermediate steps escape them, in which resides the distinction between a truly logical and a mere disputatious discussion.” It would seem that what the author here describes as the most perfect form of exposition, is that which refers each object to its place in a classification con- taining a complete series of subordinations, and which gives a definition of each class. We have repeatedly remarked that, in sciences of classification, each new definition which gives a tenable and distinct separation of classes is an important advance in our knowledge; but that such definitions are rather the last than the first step in each advance. In the progress of real knowledge, these definitions are always the results of a laborious study of individual cases, and are never arrived at by a pure effort of thought, which is what Plato appears to have imagined as the true mode of philosophizing. And still less do the advances of other sciences consist in seizing at once upon the highest generality, and filling in afterwards all the interme- diate steps between that and the special instances. On the contrary, as we have seen, the ascents from par- ticular to general are all successive; and each step of this ascent requires time, and labour, and a patient examination of actual facts and objects. It would, of course, be absurd to blame Plato for having inadequate views of the nature of progressive knowledge, at the time when knowledge could hardly be said to have begun its progress. But we already find in his speculations, as appears in the passages just quoted from his writings, several points brought into view which will require our continued attention IO PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. as we proceed. In overlooking the necessity of a gradual and successive advance from the less general to the more general truths, Plato shared in a dimness of vision* which prevailed among philosophers to the time of Francis Bacon. In thinking too slightly of the study of actual nature, he manifested a bias from which the human intellect freed itself in the vigorous struggles which terminated the dark ages. In pointing out that all knowledge implies a unity of what we observe as manifold, which unity is given by the mind, Plato taught a lesson which has of late been too obscurely acknowledged, the recoil by which men repaired their long neglect of facts having car- ried them for a while so far as to think that facts were the whole of our knowledge. And in analysing this principle of Unity, by which we thus connect sensible things, into various Ideas, such as Number, Magnitude, Position, Motion, he made a highly im- portant step, which it has been the business of philo- sophers in succeeding times to complete and to follow out. But the efficacy of Plato's speculations in their bearing upon physical science, and upon theory in general, was much weakened by the confusion of practical with theoretical knowledge, which arose from the ethical propensities of the Socratic school. In the Platonic Dialogues, Art and Science are constantly spoken of indiscriminately. The skill possessed by the Painter, the Architect, the Shoemaker, is consi- dered as a just example of human science, no less than the knowledge which the geometer or the astro- nomer possesses of the theoretical truths with which he is conversant. Not only so; but traditionary and mythological tales, mystical imaginations and fantasti- cal etymologies, are mixed up, as no less choice in- gredients, with the most acute logical analyses, and the most exact conduct of metaphysical controversies. There is no distinction made between the knowledge possessed by the theoretical psychologist and the 4 See the remarks on this phrase in the next chapter. PLATO. II physician, the philosophical teacher of morals and the legislator or the administrator of law. This, indeed, is the less to be wondered at, since even in our own time the same confusion is very commonly made by persons not otherwise ignorant or uncultured. On the other hand, we may remark finally, that Plato's admiration of Ideas was not a barren imagina- tion, even so far as regarded physical science. For, as we have seen", he had a very important share in the introduction of the theory of epicycles, having been the first to propose to astronomers in a distinct form, the problem of which that theory was the solu- tion; namely, “to explain the celestial phenomena by the combination of equable circular motions.” This demand of an ideal hypothesis which should exactly express the phenomena (as well as they could then be observed), and from which, by the interposition of suitable steps, all special cases might be deduced, falls in well with those views respecting the proper mode of seeking knowledge which we have quoted from the Philebus. And the Idea which could thus represent and replace all the particular Facts, being not only sought but found, we may readily suppose that the philosopher was, by this event, strongly confirmed in his persuasion that such an Idea was indeed what the inquirer ought to seek. In this conviction all his genuine followers up to modern times have partici- pated; and thus, though they have avoided the error of those who hold that facts alone are valuable as the elements of our knowledge, they have frequently run into the opposite error of too much despising and neglecting facts, and of thinking that the business of the inquirer after truth was only a profound and con- stant contemplation of the conceptions of his own mind. But of this hereafter. 5 Hist. Ind. Sc. b. ii. c.ü. CHAPTER III. ADDITIONAL REMARKS ON Plato. THE leading points in Plato's writings which bear I upon the philosophy of discovery are these : I. The Doctrine of Ideas. 2. The Doctrine of the One and the Many. 3. The notion of the nature and aim of Science. 4. The survey of existing Sciences. 1. The Doctrine of Ideas is an attempt to solve a problem which in all ages forces itself upon the 'notice of thoughtful men; namely, How can certain and permanent knowledge be possible for man, since all his knowledge must be derived from transient and fluctuating sensations? And the answer given by this doctrine is, that certain and permanent knowledge is not derived from Sensations, but from Ideas. There are in the mind certain elements of knowledge which are not derived from sensation, and are only imper- fectly exemplified in sensible objects; and when we reason concerning sensible things so as to obtain real knowledge, we do so by considering such things as partaking of the qualities of the Ideas concerning which there can be truth. The sciences of Geometry and Arithmetic show that there are truths which man can know; and the Doctrine of Ideas explains how this is possible. So far the Doctrine of Ideas answers its primary purpose, and is a reply (by no means the least intel- ligible and satisfactory reply) to a question still agi- tated among philosophers: What is the ground of geometrical (and other necessary) truth? But Plato seems, in many of his writings, to extend this doctrine much further; and to assume, not only Ideas of Space and its properties, from which geome- ADDITIONAL REMARKS ON PLATO. 13 trical truths are derived; but of Relations, as the Relations of Like and Unlike, Greater and Less; and of mere material objects, as Tables and Chairs. Now to assume Ideas of such things as these solves no dif- ficulty and is supported by no argument. In this respect the Ideal theory is of no value in Science. It is curious that we have a very acute refutation of the Ideal theory in this sense, not only in Aristotle, the open opponent of Plato on this subject, but in the Platonic writings themselves : namely, in the Dialogue entitled Parmenides; which, on this and on other ac- counts, I consider to be the work not of Plato, but of an opponent of Plato? 2. I have spoken, in the preceding chapter, of Plato's doctrine that truth is to be obtained by dis- cerning the One in the Many. This expression is used, it would seem, in a somewhat large and fluctuat- ing way, to mean several things; as for instance, finding the one kind in many individuals (for in- stance, the one idea of dog in many dogs); or the one law in many phenomena (for instance, the eccen- trics and epicycles in many planets). In any inter- pretation, it is too loose and indefinite a rule to be of much value in the formation of sciences, though it has been recently again propounded as important in modern times. 3. I have said, in the preceding chapter, that Plato, though he saw that scientific truths of great generality might be obtained and were to be arrived at by philosophers, overlooked the necessity of a gra- dual and successive advance from the less general to the more general; and I have described this as a dimness of vision.' I must now acknowledge that this is not a very appropriate phrase; for not only no acuteness of vision could have enabled Plato to see that gradual generalization in science of which, as yet, no example had appeared; but it was very fortunate for the progress of truth, at that time, that Plato had imagined to himself the object of science to be general 1 This matter is further discussed in the Appendix, Essay A. 14 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. and sublime truths which prove themselves to be true by the light of their own generality and symmetry. It is worth while to illustrate this notice of Plato by some references to his writings. In the Sixth Book of the Republic, Plato treats of the then existing sciences as the instruments of a philosophical education. Among the most conspicu- ous of these is astronomy. He there ridicules the notion that astronomy is a sublime science because it makes men look upward. He asserts that the really sublime science is that which makes men look at the realities, which are suggested by the appearances seen in the heavens : namely, the spheres which revolve and carry the luminaries in their revolutions. Now it was no doubt the determined search for such “realities” as these which gave birth to the Greek Astronomy, that first and critical step in the progress of science. Plato, by his exhortations, if not by his suggestions, contributed effectually, as I conceive, to this step in science. In the same manner he requires a science of Harmonics which shall be free from the defects and inaccuracies which occur in actual instruments. This belief that the universe was full of mathematical rela- tions, and that these were the true objects of scientific research, gave a vigour, largeness of mind, and con- fidence to the Greek speculators which no more cau- tious view of the problem of scientific discovery could have supplied. It was well that this advanced guard in the army of discoverers was filled with indomitable courage, boundless hopes, and creative minds. But we must not forget that this disposition to what Bacon calls anticipation was full of danger as well as of hope. It led Plato into error, as it led Kepler afterwards, and many others in all ages of scientific activity. It led Plato into error, for in- stance, when it led him to assert (in the Timceus) that the four elements, Earth, Air, Fire and Water, have, for the forms of their particles respectively, the Cube, the Icosahedron, the Pyramid, and the Octabedron; and again, when it led him to despise the practical controversies of the musicians of his time; which con- ADDITIONAL REMARKS ON PLATO. 15 troversies were, in fact, the proof of the truth of the mathematical theory of Harmonics. And in like man- ner it led Kepler into error when it led him to believe that he had found the reason of the number, size and motion of the planetary orbits in the application of the five regular solids to the frame of the universe How far the caution in forming hypotheses which Bacon's writings urge upon us is more severe than suits the present prospects of science, we may hereafter consider; but it is plainly very conceivable that a boldness in the invention and application of hypo- theses which was propitious to science in its infancy, may be one of the greatest dangers of its more mature period: and further, that the happy effect of such a temper depended entirely upon the candour, skill and labour with which the hypotheses were compared with the observed phenomena. 4. Plato has given a survey of the sciences of his time as Francis Bacon has of his. Indeed Plato has given two such surveys: one, in the Republic, in reviewing, as I have said, the elements of a philoso- phical education; the other in the Timæus, as the portions of a theological view of the universe-such as has been called a Theodiccea, a justification of God. In the former passage of Plato, the sciences enume- rated are Arithmetic, Plane Geometry, Solid Geometry, Astronomy and Harmonics. In the Timaeus we have a further notice of many other subjects, in a way which is intended, I conceive, to include such know- ledge as Plato bad then arrived at on the various parts of the universe. The subjects there referred to are, as I have elsewhere stated", these: light and heat, water, ice, gold, gems, rust and other natural objects: --odours, taste, hearing, lights, colour, and the powers of sense in general :—the parts and organs of the body, as the bones, the marrow, the brain, flesh, muscles, tendons, ligaments and nerves; the skin, the hair, the 2 These matters are further discussed in the Appendix, Essay B. 3 Sce Appendix, Essay B. 4 Hist. Ind. Sc. b. ii. Additions to 3rd Ed. PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. nails; the veins and arteries; respiration; genera- tion; and in short, every obvious point of physiology. But the opinions thus delivered in the Timcus on the latter subject have little to do with the progress of real knowledge. The doctrines, on the other hand, which depend upon geometrical and arithmetical rela- tions are portions or preludes of the sciences which the fulness of time brought forth. 5. I may, as further bearing upon the Platonic notion of science, notice Plato's view of the constitu- tion of the human mind. According to him the Ideas which are the constituents of science form an Intel- ligible World, while the visible and tangible things which we perceive by our senses form the Visible World. In the visible world we have shadows and reflections of actual objects, and by these shadows and reflections we may judge of the objects, even when we cannot do so directly; as when men in a dark cavern judge of external objects by the shadows which they cast into the cavern. In like manner in the Intelli- gible World there are conceptions which are the usual objects of human thought, and about which we reason; but these are only shadows and reflections of the Ideas which are the real sources of truth. And the Reason- ing Faculty, the Discursive Reason, the Logos, which thus deals with conceptions, is subordinate to the In- tuitive Faculty, the Intuitive Reason, the Nous, which apprehends Ideas. This recognition of a Faculty in man which contemplates the foundations—the Funda- mental Ideas—of science, and by apprehending such Ideas, makes science possible, is consentaneous to the philosophy which I have all along presented, as the view taught us by a careful study of the history and nature of science. That new Fundamental Ideas are unfolded, and the Intuitive Faculty developed and enlarged by the progress of science and by an intimate acquaintance with its reasonings, Plato appears to have discerned in some measure, though dimly. And this is the less wonderful, inasmuch as this gradual and 5 See these views further discussed in the Appendix, Essay C. ADDITIONAL REMARKS ON PLATO. 17 successive extension of the field of Intuitive Truth, in proportion as we become familiar with a larger amount of derived truth, is even now accepted by few, though proved by the reasonings of the greatest scientific dis- coverers in every age. The leading defect in Plato's view of the nature of real science is his not seeing fully the extent to which experience and observation are the basis of all our knowledge of the universe. He considers the lumina- ries which appear in the heavens to be not the true objects of astronomy, but only some imperfect adum- bration of them;--mere diagrams which may assist us in the study of a higher truth, as beautiful diagrams might illustrate the truths of geometry, but would not prove them. This notion of an astronomy which is an astronomy of Theories and not of Facts, is not tenable, for Theories are Facts. Theories and Facts are equally real; true Theories are Facts, and Facts are familiar Theories. But when Plato says that astronomy is a series of problems suggested by visible things, he uses expressions quite conformable to the true philosophy of science; and the like is true of all other sciences. CHAPTER IV. ARISTOTLE. THE views of Aristotle with regard to the founda- I tions of human knowledge are very different from those of his tutor Plato, and are even by himself put in opposition to them. He dissents altogether from the Platonic doctrine that Ideas are the true materials of our knowledge; and after giving, respecting the origin of this doctrine, the account which we quoted in the last chapter, he goes on to reason against it. 6 Thus," he says, “they devised Ideas of all things which are spoken of as universals : much as if any one having to count a number of objects, should think that he could not do it while they were few, and should expect to count them by making them more numerous. For the kinds of things are almost more numerous than the special sensible objects, by seeking the causes of which they were led to their Ideas.” He then goes on to urge several other reasons against the assumption of Ideas and the use of them in philoso- phical researches. Aristotle himself establishes his doctrines by trains of reasoning. But reasoning must proceed from cer- tain First Principles; and the question then arises, Whence are these First Principles obtained? To this he replies, that they are the result of Experience, and he even employs the same technical expression by which we at this day describe the process of collecting these principles from observed facts ;—that they are obtained by Induction. I have already quoted pas- sages in which this statement is made. “The way of reasoning,” he says, “is the same in philosophy, 1 Metaph. xii. 4. 2 Hist. Ind. Sc. b. i. c. iii. sect. 2 3 Analyt. Prior. i. 30. ARISTOTLE. 19 and in any art or science: we must collect the facts (Tà unápxovta), and the things to which the facts hap- pen, and must have as large a supply of these as possible, and then we must examine them according to the terms of our syllogisms.”...“There are peculiar principles in each science; and in each case these principles must be obtained from experience. Thus astronomical observation supplies the principles of astronomical science. For the phenomena being rightly taken, the demonstrations of astronomy were discovered; and the same is the case with any other Art or Science. So that if the facts in each case be taken, it is our business to construct the demonstra- tions. For if in our natural history (kara try foto- plav) we have omitted none of the facts and properties which belong to the subject, we shall learu what we can demonstrate and what we cannot." And again', there must be some knowledge wanting, which we are thus prevented from having. For we acquire know- ledge either by Induction (étaywyên) or by Demonstra- tion : and Demonstration is from universals, but In- duction from particulars. It is impossible to have universal theoretical propositions except by Induction : and we cannot make inductions without having sen- sation; for sensation has to do with particulars.” It is easy to show that Aristotle uses the term Induction, as we use it, to express the process of collecting a general proposition from particular cases in which it is exemplified. Thus in a passage which we have already quoted', he says, “Induction, and Syllogism from Induction, is when we attribute one extreme term to the middle by means of the other.” The import of this technical phraseology will further appear by the example which he gives : “We find that several animals which are deficient in bile are . infer that all animals which are deficient in bile are long-lived.” 4 Analyt. Post. i. 18. 5 Analyt. Prior. ii. 23, trepi mis enaywyns. C2 20 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. We may observe, however, that both Aristotle's notion of induction, and many other parts of his philosophy, are obscure and imperfect, in consequence of his refusing to contemplate ideas as something distinct from sensation. It thus happens that he always assumes the ideas which enter into his proposi- tion as given ; and considers it as the philosopher's business to determine whether such propositions are true or not: whereas the most important feature in induction is, as we have said, the introduction of a new idea, and not its employment when once intro- duced. That the mind in this manner gives unity to that which is manifold,--that we are thus led to specu- lative principles which have an evidence higher than any others,—and that a peculiar sagacity in some men seizes upon the conceptions by which the facts may be bound into true propositions,—are doctrines which form no essential part of the philosophy of the Stagirite, although such views are sometimes recognized, more or less clearly, in his expressions. Thus he says, “ There can be no knowledge when the sensation does not continue in the mind. For this purpose, it is necessary both to perceive, and to have some unity in the mind (alodavouévous čxelv év te? ¿v Tŷ yuxôn); and many such perceptions having taken place, some difference is then perceived : and from the remem- brance of these arises Reason. Thus from Sensation comes Memory, and from Memory of the same thing often repeated comes Experience: for many acts of Memory make up one Experience. And from Expe- rience, or from any Universal Notion which takes a permanent place in the mind, from the unity in the manifold, the same some one thing being found in many facts,—springs the first principle of Art and of Science; of Art, if it be employed about production; of Science, if about existence.” 6 Analyt. Post. ii. 19. 7 But the best reading seems to be not ev ti butēri: and the clause must be rendered “both to perceive and to retain the perception in the mind.” This correction does not disturb the general sense of the passage, that the first principles of science are obtained by finding the one in the Many. ARISTOTLE. 21 I will add to this, Aristotle's notice of Sagacity; since, although little or no further reference is made to this quality in his philosophy, the passage fixes our attention upon an important step in the formation of knowledge. “Sagacity” (áyxívola), he says', “is a hitting by guess (evotoxía tis) upon the middle term (the conception common to two cases) in an inapprecia- ble time. As for example, if any one seeing that the bright side of the moon is always towards the sun, suddenly perceives why this is; namely, because the moon shines by the light of the sun :-or if he sees a person talking with a rich man, be guesses that he is borrowing money ;-or conjectures that two persons are friends, because they are enemies of the same person."--To consider only the first of these exam- ples;—the conception here introduced, that of a body shining by the light which another casts upon it, is not contained in the observed facts, but introduced by the mind. It is, in short, that conception which, in the act of induction, the mind superadds to the phe- nomena as they are presented by the senses : and to invent such appropriate conceptions, such "eustochies,” is, indeed, the precise office of inductive sagacity. At the end of this work (the Later Analytics) Aristotle ascribes our knowledge of principles to In- tellect (vous), or, as it appears necessary to translate the word, Intuition. “Since, of our intellectual habits by which we aim at truth, some are always true, but some admit of being false, as Opinion and Reasoning, but Science and Intuition are always true; and since there is nothing which is more certain than Science except Intuition; and since Principles are better known to us than the Deductions from them; and since all Science is connected by reasoning, we cannot have Science respecting Principles. Considering this then, and that the beginning of Demonstration cannot be Demonstration, nor the beginning of Science, Science; and since, as we have said, there is no other kind of truth, Intuition must be the beginning of Science." 8 Analyt. Post. i. 34 9 Ibid. ii, 19. 22 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. What is here said, is, no doubt, in accordance with the doctrines which we have endeavoured to establish respecting the nature of Science, if by this Intuition we understand that contemplation of certain Funda- mental Ideas, which is the basis of all rigorous know- ledge. But notwithstanding this apparent approxi- mation, Aristotle was far from having an habitual and practical possession of the principles which he thus touches upon. He did not, in reality, construct his philosophy by giving Unity to that which was manifold, or by seeking in Intuition principles which might be the basis of Demonstration; nor did he col- lect, in each subject, fundamental propositions by an induction of particulars. He rather endeavoured to divide than to unite; he employed himself, not in combining facts, but in analysing notions; and the criterion to which he referred his analysis was, not the facts of our experience, but our habits of lan- guage. Thus his opinions rested, not upon sound inductions, gathered in each case from the phenomena by means of appropriate Ideas; but upon the loose and vague generalizations which are implied in the common use of speech. Yet Aristotle was so far consistent with his own doctrine of the derivation of knowledge from expe- rience, that he made in almost every province of human knowledge, a vast collection of such special facts as the experience of his time supplied. These collections are almost unrivalled, even to the present day, espe- cially in Natural History; in other departments, when to the facts we must add the right Inductive Idea, in order to obtain truth, we find little of value in the Aristotelic works. But in those parts which refer to Natural History, we find not only an immense and varied collection of facts and observations, but a saga- city and acuteness in classification which it is impos- sible not to admire. This indeed appears to have been the most eminent faculty in Aristotle's mind. The influence of Aristotle in succeeding ages will come under our notice shortly. CHAPTER V. ADDITIONAL REMARKS ON ARISTOTLE. 1. ONE of the most conspicuous points in Aris- U totle's doctrines as bearing upon the philosophy of Science is his account of that mode of attaining truth which is called Induction; for we are accustomed to consider Induction as the process by which our Sciences have been formed; and we call them collect- ively the Inductive Sciences. Aristotle often speaks of Induction, as for instance, when he says that Socrates introduced the frequent use of it. But the cardinal passage on this subject is in his Analytics, in which he compares Syllogism and Induction as two modes of drawing conclusions?. . He there says that all belief arises either from Syllogism or from Induction: and adds that Induction is, when by means of one extreme term we infer the other extreme to be true of the middle term. The example which he gives is this : knowing that particular animals are long-lived, as elephant, horse, mule; and finding that these animals agree in having no gall-bladder; we infer, by In- duction, that all animals which have no gall-bladder are long-lived. This may be done, he says, if the middle and the second extreme are convertible : as the following formal statement may show. · Elephant, horse, mule, &c. are long-lived. Elephant, horse, mule, &c. are all gall-less. If we might convert this proposition, and say All gall-less animals are as elephant, horse, mule, &c. : 1 Analyt. Prior. ii. 25. 24 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. we might infer syllogistically that All gall-less animals are long-lived. And though we cannot infer this syllogistically, we infer it by Induction, when we have a sufficient amount of instances. I have already elsewhere given this account of In- duction, as a process employed in the formation of our knowledge. What I have now to remark concerning Aristotle is, that it does not appear to have occurred to him, that in establishing such a proposition as that which he gives as his instance, the main difficulty is the discovery of a middle term which will allow us to frame such a proposition as we need. The zoologist who wanted to know what kind of animals are long- lived, might guess long before he guessed that the absence of the gall-bladder supplied the requisite middle term; (if the proposition were true; which it is not.) And in like manner in other cases, it is diffi- cult to find a middle term, which enables us to collect a proposition by Induction. And herein consists the imperfection of his view of the subject; which con- siders the main point to be the proof of the proposition when the conceptions are given; whereas the main point really is, the discovery of conceptions which will make a true proposition possible. 2. Since the main characteristic of the steps which have occurred in the formation of the physical sciences, is not merely that they are propositions col- lected by Induction, but by the introduction of a new conception; it has been suggested that it is not a characteristic designation of these Sciences to call them Inductive Sciences. Almost every discovery involves in it the introduction of a new conception, as the ele- ment of a new proposition; and the novelty of the conception is more characteristic of the stages of disco- very than the inductive application of it. Hence as 2 See on this subject Appendix, Essay D. 3 See the chapter on Certain Characteristics of Scientific Induction in the Phil. Ind. Sc. or in the Nov. Org. Renov. ADDITIONAL REMARKS ON ARISTOTLE. 25 bearing upon the Philosophy of Discovery, the state- ments of Aristotle concerning Induction, though acute and valuable, are not so valuable as they might seem. Even Francis Bacon, it has been asserted, erred in the same way (and of course with less excuse) in asserting Induction, of a certain kind, to be the great instrument for the promotion of knowledge, and in overlooking the necessity of the Invention which gives Induction its value. 3. The invention or discovery of a conception by which many facts of observation are conjoined so as to make them the materials of a proposition, is called in Plato, as we have seen, finding the one in the Many. In the passage quoted from the Later Analytics, Aristotle uses the same expression, and speaks very justly respecting the formation of knowledge. Indeed the Titles of the chapters of this and many parts of Aristotle's works would lead us to expect just such a Philosophy of Discovery as is the object of our study at present. Thus we have, Anal. Post. B. II. chap. 13: “How we are to hunt (Onpeúelv) the predications of a Definition." Chap. 14: “Precepts for the invention of Problems and of a Middle Term :" and the like. But when we come to read these chapters, they con- tain little that is of value, and resolve themselves mostly into permutations of Aristotle's logical phraseo- logy. 4. The part of the Aristotelian philosophy which has most permanently retained its place in modern Sciences is a part of which a use has been made quite different from that which was originally contemplated. The “Five words” which are explained in the Intro- duction to Aristotle's Categories: namely, the words Genus, Species, Difference, Property, Accident, were in- troduced mainly that they might be used in the propo- sitions of which Syllogisms consist, and might thus be the elements of reasoning. But it has so happened that these words are rarely used in Sciences of Reasoning, but are abundantly and commonly used in 26 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. the Sciences of Classification, as I have explained in speaking of the Classificatory Sciences. 5. Of Aristotle's actual contributions to the Physi- cal Sciences I have spoken in the History of those Sciences". I have stated that he conceived the globu- lar form of the earth so clearly and gave so forcibly the arguments for that doctrine, that we may look upon him as the most effective teacher of it. Also in the Appendix to that History, published in the third edition, I bave given Aristotle's account of the Rain- bow, as a further example of his industrious accumula- tion of facts, and of his liability to error in his facts. 6. We do not find Aristotle so much impressed as we might have expected by that great monument of Grecian ingenuity, the theory of epicycles and ex- centrics which his predecessor Plato urged so strong- ly upon the attention of his contemporaries. Aris- totle proves, as I have said, the globular form of the earth by good and sufficient arguments. He also proves by arguments which seem to him quite con- clusive”, that the earth is in the center of the universe, and immoveable. As to the motions of the rest of the planets, he says little. The questions of their order, and their distances, and the like, belong, he says, to Astrology'. He remarks only that the revolution of the heaven itself, the outermost revolution, is simple and the quickest of all: that the revolutions of the others are slower, each moving in a direction opposite to the heaven in its own circle : and that it is reason- able that those which are nearest to the first revolu- tion should take the longest time in describing their own circle, and those that are furthest off, the least time, and the intermediate ones in the order of their distances, “as also the mathematicians show." In the Metaphysics" he enumerates the circular movements which had been introduced by the astro- 4 Phil. Ind. Sc. b. viii. c. i. art. 11, or Hist. Sc. Id. b. viii. 5 B. i. c. xi. sect. 2. O B. iii. c. i. sect. 2. 7 De Cælo, ü. 13. 8 Ivid. ii. 1o. 9 xii. 8. ADDITIONAL REMARKS ON ARISTOTLE. 27 nomers Eudoxus and Calippus for the explanation of the phenomena presented by the sun, moon and pla- nets. These, he says, amount to fifty-five; and this, he says, must be the number of essences and principles which exist in the universe. 7. In the Sciences of Classification, and especially in the classification of animals, higher claims have been made for Aristotle, which I have discussed in the History. I have there attempted to show that Aristotle's classification, inasmuch as it enumerates all the parts of animals, may be said to contain the mate- rials of every subsequent classification: but that it can- not be said to anticipate any modern system, because the different grades of classification are not made sub- ordinate to one another as a system of classification requires. I have the satisfaction of finding Mr. Owen agreeing with me in these views 8. Francis Bacon's criticism on Aristotle which I have quoted in the Appendix to the History 12, is severe, and I think evidently the result of prejudice. He disparages Aristotle in comparison with the other philosophers of Greece. Their systems,' he says, 'had some savour of experience, and nature, and bodily things; while the Physics of Aristotle, in general, sound only of Logical Terms. 'Nor let any one be moved by this: that in his books Of Animals, and in his Problems, and in others of his tracts, there is often a quoting of experiments. For he had made up his mind beforehand; and did not consult experience in order to make right propositions and axioms, but when be had settled his system to his will, he twisted experience round and made her bend to his system.' I do not think that this can be said with any truth. I know no instances in which Aristotle has twisted ex- perience round, and made her bend to his system. In 10 B. xvi. c. vi. 11 On the Classification of Mammalia, &c.: a Lecture delivered at Cam- bridge, May 10, 1859, p. 3. 12 B. i. c. xi. 28 PIIILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. his Problems, he is so far from giving dogmatical solu- tions of the questions proposed, that in most cases, he propounds two or three solutions as mere suggestions and conjectures. And both in his History of Animals, as I have said, and in others of his works, the want of system gives them an incoherent and tumultuary cha- racter, which even a false system would have advan- tageously removed; for, as I have said elsewhere, it is easier to translate a false system into a true one, than to introduce system into a mass of confusion. 9. It is curious that a fundamental error into which Aristotle fell in his view of the conditions which determine the formation of Science is very nearly the same as one of Francis Bacon's leading mistakes. Aristotle says, that Science consists in knowing the causes of things, as Bacon aims at ac- quiring a knowledge of the fornis or essences of things and their qualities. But the history of all the sciences teaches us that sciences do not begin with such know- ledge, and that in few cases only do they ever attain to it. Sciences begin by a knowledge of the laws of phe- nomena, and proceed by the discovery of the scientific ideas by which the phenomena are colligated, as I have shown in other works 13. The discovery of causes is not beyond the human powers, as some have taught. Those who thus speak disregard the lessons taught by the history of Physical Astronomy, of Geology, of Physical Optics, Thermotics and other sciences. But the discovery of causes, and of the essential forms of qualities, is a triumph reserved for the later stages of each Science, when the knowledge of the laws of phenomena has already made great progress. It was not to be expected that Aristotle would discern this truth, when, as yet, there was no Science extant in which it had been exemplified. Yet in Astronomy, the theory of epicycles and excentrics had immense value, and even has still, as representing the laws of phenomena; while the attempt to find in 13 History of Scientific Ideas, and Novrum Organum Renovatum, ADDITIONAL REMARKS ON ARISTOTLE. 29 it, as Aristotle wished to do, the ultimate causes of the motions of the universe, could only mislead. The Aristotelian maxim, which sounds so plausible, and has been so generally accepted, that “to know truly is to know the causes of things,” is a bad guide in scientific research. Instead of it we might substitute this : that “though we may aspire to know at last why things are, we must be content for a long time with knowing how they are." 10. Hence if we are asked whether Plato or Aristotle had the truer views of the nature and pro- perty of Science, we must give the preference to Plato; for though his notion of a real Intelligible World, of which the Visible world was a fleeting and changeable shadow, was extravagant, yet it led him to seek to determine the forms of the Intelligible Things, which are really the laws of visible phenomena; while Aris- totle was led to pass lightly over such laws, because they did not at once reveal the causes which produced the phenomena. 11. Aristotle, throughout his works, takes numerous occasions to argue against Plato's doctrine of Ideas. Yet these Ideas, so far as they were the Intelligible Forms of Visible Things, were really fit objects of philosophical research; and the search after them had à powerful influence in promoting the progress of Science. And we may see in the effect of this search the answer to many of Aristotle's strongest argu- ments. For instance, Aristotle says that Plato, by way of explaining things, adds to them as many Ideas, and that this is just as if a man having to reckon a large number, were to begin by adding to it another large number. It is plain that to this we may reply, that the adopting the Ideas of Cycles, along with the motions of the Planets, does really explain the motions; and that the Cycles are not simply added to the phenomena, but include and supersede the phe- nomena: a finite number of Cycles include and repre- sent an infinite number of separate phenomena. To Aristotle's argument that Ideas cannot be the Causes or Principles of Things, we should reply, that 30 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. though they cannot be this, they may nevertheless be, and must be, the Conditions and Principles of our Knowledge, which is what we want them to be. I have given an account of the main features of Aristotle's philosophy, so far as it concerns the Physi- cal Sciences, in the History of the Inductive Sciences, Book I. CHAPTER VI. THE LATER GREEKS. M HUS while Plato was disposed to seek the essence 1 of our knowledge in Ideas alone, Aristotle, slight- ing this source of truth, looked to Experience as the beginning of Science; and he attempted to obtain, by division and deduction, all that Experience did not immediately supply. And thus, with these two great names, began that struggle of opposite opinions which has ever since that time agitated the speculative world, as men have urged the claims of Ideas or of Expe- rience to our respect, and as alternately each of these elements of knowledge has been elevated above its due place, while the other has been unduly depressed. We shall see the successive turns of this balanced struggle in the remaining portions of this review. But we may observe that practically the influence of Plato predominated rather than that of Aristotle, in the remaining part of the history of ancient philo- sophy. It was, indeed, an habitual subject of dispute among men of letters, whether the sources of true knowledge are to be found in the Senses or in the Mind; the Epicureans taking one side of this alterna- tive, and the Academics another, while the Stoics in a certain manner included both elements in their view. But none of these sects showed their persuasion that the materials of knowledge were to be found in the domain of Sense, by seeking them there. No one appears to have thought of following the example of Aristotle, and gathering together a store of observed facts. We may except, perhaps, assertions belonging to some provinces of Natural History, which were collected by various writers : but in these, the mixed 32 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. character of the statements, the want of discrimination in the estimate of evidence, the credulity and love of the marvellous which the authors for the most part displayed, showed that instead of improving upon the example of Aristotle, they were wandering further and further from the path of real knowledge. And while they thus collected, with so little judgment, such statements as offered themselves, it hardly ap- pears to have occurred to any one to enlarge the stores of observation by the aid of experiment; and to learn what the laws of nature were, by trying what were their results in particular cases. They used no instru- ments for obtaining an insight into the constitution of the universe, except logical distinctions and discussions; and proceeded as if the phenomena familiar to their predecessors must contain all that was needed as a basis for natural philosophy. By thus contenting themselves with the facts which the earlier philoso- phers had contemplated, they were led also to confine themselves to the ideas which those philosophers had put forth. For all the most remarkable alternatives of hypothesis, so far as they could be constructed with a slight and common knowledge of phenomena, had been promulgated by the acute and profound thinkers who gave the first impulse to philosophy: and it was not given to man to add much to the original inven- tions of their minds till he had undergone anew a long discipline of observation, and of thought employed upon observation. Thus the later authors of the Greek Schools became little better than commentators on the earlier; and the common-places with which the different schools carried on their debates,—the con- stantly recurring argument, with its known attendant answer,--the distinctions drawn finer and finer and leading to nothivg-render the speculations of those times a scholastic philosophy, in the same sense in which we employ the term when we speak of the labours of the middle ages. It will be understood that I now refer to that which is here my subject, the opinions concerning our knowledge of nature, and the methods in use for the purpose of obtaining such THE LATER GREEKS. 33 knowledge. Whether the moral speculations of the ancient world were of the same stationary kind, going their round in a limited circle, like their metaphysics and physics, must be considered on some other occa- sion. Mr. Grote, in his very interesting discussion of Socrates's teaching, notices also the teaching of Hip- pocrates, which he conceives to have in one respect the same tendency as the philosophy of Socrates; namely, to turn away from the vague aggregate of doctrines and guesses which constituted the Physical Philosophy of that time, and to pursue instead a spe- cial and more practical course of inquiry: Hippocrates selecting Medicine and Socrates selecting Ethics. By this limitation of their subject, they avoided some of the errors of their predecessors. For, as Mr. Grote has also remarked, the earlier speculators, Anaxa- goras, Empedocles, Democritus, the Pythagoreans, all had still present to their minds the vast and undivided problems which have been transmitted down from the old poets; bending their minds to the invention of some system which would explain them all at once, or assist the imagination in conceiving both how the Kosmos first began and how it continued to move on." There could be no better remedy for this ambitious error of the human mind than to have a definite sub- ject of study, such as the diseases and the health of the human body. Accordingly, we see that the study of medicine did draw its cultivators away from this ancient but unprofitable field. Hippocrates condemns those who, as Empedocles, set themselves to make out what man was from the beginning, how he began first to exist, and in what manner he was constructed. This is, he says, no part of medicine. In like manner he blames and refutes those who make some simple element, Hot, or Cold, or Moist, or Dry, the cause of 1 The remainder of this chapter is new in the present edition. 2 Hist. of Greece, Part i chap. 68. 3 De Antiqua Medicina, C. 20. 34 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. diseases, and give medical precepts professing to be founded on this hypothesis. These passages are marked by the prudence which practical study suggests to a calm and clear-sighted man. They can hardly be said to have opened the way to a Science of Medicine; for in the sense in which we here use the word Science, namely, a collec- tion of general truths inferred from facts by successive discoverers, we have even yet no Science of Medicine. The question with regard to the number and nature of the Elements of which bodies are composed began to be agitated, as we have seen, at a very early period of Greek philosophy, and continued long to be regarded as a chief point of physiological doctrine. In Galen's work we have a treatise entitled, On the Elements according to Hippocrates, and the writer explains * that though Hippocrates has not written any work with the title on the Elements, yet that he has in his Treatise on the Nature of Man shown his opinion on that subject. That the doctrine of the Four Elements, Hot, Cold, Moist, Dry, subsisted long in the schools, we have evidence in Galen. He tells us that when he was a student of nineteen years old a teacher urged this lore upon him, and regarded him as very conten- tious and perverse, because he offered objections to it. His account of the Dialogue between him and the teacher is curious. But in Hippocrates the doctrine of these four elements is replaced, in a great measure, by the doctrine of the Four Humours of which the human body is constituted; namely, Blood, Phlegm, Yellow Bile and Black Bile. Galen dwells with em- phasis upon Hippocrates's proof that there must be more than one such elemente. " What,” he asks, “is the method of finding the Elements of bodies ? There can, in my opinion, be no other than that which was introduced by Hippo- crates; namely, we must inquire whether there be only one element, everywhere the same in kind, or whether 4 Lib. i. c. 9. 5 De Elem. i. 6. 6 In former editious I have not done justice to this passage. THE LATER GREEKS. 35 there are more than one, various and unlike each other. And if the Element be not one only, but several, various and dissimilar, we must inquire in the second place, how many elements there are, and what, and of what kind they are, and how related in their association. " Now that the First Element is not one only of which both our bodies and those of all other creatures were produced, Hippocrates shows from these consi- derations. And it is better first to put down his own expressions and then to expound them. 'I assert that if man consisted of one element only he could not fall sick; for there would be nothing which could derange his health, if he were all of one Element.'” The doctrine of One Element did not prevail much after the time of Hippocrates : the doctrine of Four Elements continued, as I have said, long to hold pos- session of the Schools, but does not appear as an important part of the doctrine of Hippocrates. The doctrine of the Four Humours (Blood, Phlegm, Yel- low Bile and Black Bile) is more peculiarly his, and long retained its place as a principle of physiological But we are here not so much concerned with his discoveries in medicine as with his views respecting the method of acquiring sound knowledge, and in this respect, as has been said, he recommends by his prac- tice a prudent limitation of the field of inquiry, a rejection of wide, ambitious, general assertions, and a practical study of his proper field. In ascribing these merits to Hippocrates's medical speculations as to the ethical speculations of his con- temporary Socrates, we assign considerable philosophi- cal value to Hippocrates, no less than to Socrates. These merits were at that time the great virtues of physieal as well as of ethical philosophy. But, as which then subsisted between the physical and ethical speculations prevailing at that time, ceased to ob- tain in later times. Indeed, it ceased to exist just at that time, in consequence of the establishment of D 2 36 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. scientific astronomy by the exertions of Plato and his contemporaries. From that time the Common Sense (as we call it) of a man like Socrates, though it might be a good guide in ethics, was not a good guide in phy- sics. I have shown elsewhere? how the Common Sense of Socrates was worthless in matters of astronomy. From that time one of the great intellectual lessons was, that in order to understand the external world, we must indeed observe carefully, but we must also guess boldly. Discovery here required an inventive mind like Plato's to deal with and arrange new and varied facts. But in ethics all the facts were old and fami- liar, and the generalizations of language by which they were grouped as Virtues and Vices, and the like, were common and well-known words. Here was no room for invention; and thus in the ethical specula- tions of Socrates or of any other moral teacher, we are not to look for any contributions to the Philosophy of Discovery. Nor do I find anything on this subject among later Greek writers, beyond the commendation of such in- tellectual virtues as Hippocrates and Galen, and other medical writers, schooled by the practice of their art, enjoined and praised. But before we quit the ancients I will point out some peculiarities which may be noticed in the Roman disciples of the Greek philosophy. ? Hist. Ind. Sc. Addition to Introduction in Third Edition. CHAPTER VII. THE ROMANS. THE Romans had no philosophy but that which I they borrowed from the Greeks; and what they thus received, they hardly made entirely their own. The vast and profound question of which we have been speaking, the relation between Existence and our Knowledge of what exists, they never appear to have fathomed, even so far as to discern how wide and deep it is. In the development of the ideas by which nature is to be understood, they went no fur- ther than their Greek masters had gone, nor indeed was more to be looked for. And in the practical habit of accumulating observed facts as materials for knowledge, they were much less discriminating and more credulous than their Greek predecessors. The descent from Aristotle to Pliny, in the judiciousness of the authors and the value of their collections of facts, is immense. Since the Romans were thus servile followers of their Greek teachers, and little acquainted with any example of new truths collected from the world around them, it was not to be expected that they could have any just conception of that long and magnificent ascent from one set of truths to others of higher order and wider compass, which the history of science began to exhibit when the human mind recovered its progres- sive habits. Yet some dim presentiment of the splendid career thus destined for the intellect of man appears from time to time to have arisen in their minds. Per- haps the circumstance which most powerfully contri- buted to suggest this vision, was the vast intellectual progress which they were themselves conscious of having made, through the introduction of the Greek 38 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. . philosophy; and to this may be added, perhaps, some other features of national character. Their temper was too stubborn to acquiesce in the absolute authority of the Greek philosophy, although their minds were not inventive enough to establish a rival by its side. And the wonderful progress of their political power had given them a hope in the progress of man which the Greeks never possessed. The Roman, as he be- lieved the fortune of his State to be destined for eternity, believed also in the immortal destiny and endless advance of that Intellectual Republic of which he had been admitted a denizen. It is easy to find examples of such feelings as I have endeavoured to describe. The enthusiasm with which Lucretius and Virgil speak of physical knowledge, manifestly arises in a great measure from the delight which they had felt in becoming acquainted with the Greek theories. Me vero primum dulces ante omnia Musa Quarum sacra fero ingenti perculsus amore Accipiant, cælique vias et sidera monstrent, Defectus Solis varios, Lunæque labores!.. Felix qui potuit rerum cognoscere causas ! Yė sacred Muses, with whose beauty fir'd, My soul is ravisht and my brain inspir'd: Whose Priest I am, whose holy fillets wear, Would you your Poet's first petition hear, Give me the ways of wand'ring stars to know, The depth of Heaven above and Earth below; Teach me the various labours of the Moon, And whence proceed th' eclipses of the Sun; Why flowing Tides prevail upon the main, And in what dark abyss they shrink again; What shakes the solid Earth; what cause delays The Summer Nights; and shortens Winter Days. . Happy the man who, studying Nature's Laws, Through known effects can trace the secret cause ! Ovid expresses a similar feeling. Felices animos quibus hæc cognoscere primis Inque domos superas scandere cura fuit!.. 1 Lib. i. Fast. THE ROMANS. 39 Admovere oculis distantia sidera nostris Ætheraque ingenio supposuere suo. Sic petitur colum: non ut ferat Ossam Olympus Summaque Peliacus sidera tanget apex. Thrice happy souls ! to whom 'twas given to rise To truths like these, and scale the spangled skies ! Far distant stars to clearest view they brought, And girdled ether with their chain of thought. So heaven is reached :—not as of old they tried By mountains piled on mountains in their pride. And from the whole tenour of these and similar passages, it is evident that the intellectual pleasure which arises from our first introduction to a beautiful physical theory had a main share in producing this enthusiasm at the contemplation of the victories of science; although undoubtedly the moral philosophy, which was never separated from the natural philosophy, and the triumph over superstitious fears, which a know- ledge of nature was supposed to furnish, added warmth to the feeling of exultation. We may trace a similar impression in the ardent expressions which Plinymakes use of in speaking of the early astronomers, and which we have quoted in the History. “Great men ! elevated above the com- mon standard of human nature, by discovering the laws which celestial occurrences obey, and by freeing the wretched mind of man from the fears which eclipses inspired.” This exulting contemplation of what science had done, naturally led the mind to an anticipation of further achievements still to be performed. Expres- sions of this feeling occur in Seneca, and are of the most remarkable kind, as the following example will show : “Why do we wonder that comets, so rare a pheno- menon, have not yet had their laws assigned !--that we should know so little of their beginning and their end, when their recurrence is at wide intervals? It is not yet fifteen hundred years since Greece, Stellis numeros et nomina fecit, 2 Hist. Nat. i. 75. 3 Quæst. Nat. vii. 25. 40 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. reckoned the stars, and gave them names.' There are still many nations which are acquainted with the heavens by sight only; which do not yet know why the moon disappears, why she is eclipsed. It is but lately that among us philosophy has reduced these matters to a certainty. The day shall come when the course of time and the labour of a maturer age shall bring to light what is yet concealed. One generation, even if it devoted itself to the skies, is not enough for re- searches so extensive. How then can it be so, when we divide this scanty allowance of years into no equal shares between our studies and our vices? These things then must be explained by a long succession of inquiries. We have but just begun to know how arise the morning and evening appearances, the sta- tions, the progressions, and the retrogradations of the fixed stars which put themselves in our way;-which appearing perpetually in another and another place compel us to be curious. Some one will hereafter demonstrate in what region the comets wander; why they move so far asunder from the rest; of what size and nature they are. Let us be content with what we have discovered : let posterity contribute its share to truth.” Again he adds4 in the same strain : “Let us not wonder that what lies so deep is brought out so slowly. How many animals have become known for the first time in this age! And the members of future generations shall know many of which we are ignorant. Many things are reserved for ages to come, when our memory shall have passed away. The world would be a small thing indeed, if it did not contain matter of inquiry for all the world. Eleusis reserves something for the second visit of the worshipper. So too Nature does not at once disclose all HER mysteries. We think ourselves initiated; we are but in the ves- tibule. The arcana are not thrown open without distinction and without reserve. This age will see some things; that which comes after us, others.” Quæst. Nat. vii. 30, 31, THE ROMANS. 41 While we admire the happy coincidence of these conjectures with the soundest views which the history of science teaches us, we must not forget that they are merely conjectures, suggested by very vague im- pressions, and associated with very scanty conceptions from which the above extract is taken, contains a series of dissertations on various subjects of Natural Philo- Rivers, Snow, Hail, Rain, Wind, Earthquakes and Comets. In the whole of these dissertations, the statements are loose, and the explanations of little or no value. Perhaps it may be worth our while to notice a case in which he refers to an observation of his own, although his conclusion from it be erroneous. He is arguings against the opinion that Springs arise from the water which falls in rain. “In the first place,” he says, “I, a very diligent digger in my vine- yard, affirm that no rain is so heavy as to moisten the earth to the depth of more than ten feet. All the moisture is consumed in this outer crust, and descends not to the lower part.” We have here something of the nature of an experiment; and indeed, as we may readily conceive, the instinct which impels man to seek truth by experiment can never be altogether ex- tinguished. Seneca's experiment was deprived of its value by the in distinctness of his ideas, which led him to rest in the crude conception of the water being “consumed ” in the superficial crust of the earth. It is unnecessary to pursue further the reasonings of the Romans on such subjects, and we now proceed to the ages which succeeded the fall of their empire. 5 Ibid. iii. 7. CHAPTER VIII. ARABIAN PHILOSOPHERS. T HAVE noticed certain additions to Physical Science I made by the Arabians ; namely, in Astronomy? The discovery of the motion of the Sun's Apogee by Albategnius, and the discovery of the Moon's Variation by Aboul-Wefa; and in Optics: the assertion of Alhazen. that the angle of refraction is not proportional to the angle of incidence, as Ptolemy had supposed : and cer- tain steps in the philosophy of vision. We must also suppose, as the Arabic word alkali reminds us, that the Arabians contributed to lay the foundations of che- mistry. The question which we have here to ask is, whether the Arabians made any steps beyond their predecessors in the philosophy of discovery. And to this question, I conceive the answer must be this: that among them as among the Greeks, those who practically observed nature, and especially those who made discoveries in Science, must have had a practical acquaintance with some of the maxims which are exemplified in the formation of Science. To discover that the Apogee of the Sun was 17 degrees distant from the point where Ptolemy had placed it, Alba- tegnius made careful observations, and referred them to the theory of the eccentric, so as to verify or correct that theory. And when, in the eleventh century, Arzachel found the Apogee to be less advanced than Albategnius had found it, he proceeded again to cor- rect the theory by introducing a new movement of the equinoctial points, which was called the Trepidation. 1 Fist. Ind. Sc. b. ii. c. iv. sect. 8. 2 Ibid. b. ix. c. ii. ARABIAN PHILOSOPHERS. 43 It appeared afterwards, however, that, in doing this, he had had too much confidence in the observations of his predecessors, and that no such movement as the Trepidation really existed. In like manner to correct Ptolemy's law of refraction, Alhazen had recourse to experiment: but he did not put his experiments in the form of a Table, as Ptolemy had done. If he had done this, he might possibly have discovered the law of sines, which Snell afterwards discovered. But though the Arabian philosophers thus, in some cases, observed facts, and referred those facts to general mathematical laws, it does not appear that they were led to put in any new or striking general form such maxims as this : That the progress of Sci- ence consists in the exact observation of facts and in colligating them by ideas. Those of them who were dissatisfied with the existing philosophy as barren and useless (for instance Algazel), were led to point at the faults and contradictions of that philosophy, but did not attempt, so far as I know, to substitute for it anything better. If they rejected Aristotle's Organon, they did not attempt to construct a new Organon for themselves. Indeed they do not appear even to have had suffi- cient confidence in the real truth of the astronomical theories which they had adopted from the Greeks, always to correct and extend those where their obser- vations showed that they required correction and ex- tension. Sometimes they did this, but not generally enough. When Arzachel found by observation the Apogee of the Sun to be situated too far back, he ven- tured to correct Ptolemy's statement of its motion. But when Aboul-Wefa had really discovered the Vari- ation of the Moon's motion, he did not express it by means of an epicycle. If he had done so, he would have made it unnecessary for Tycho Brahe at a later period to make the same discovery. 8 See Hist. Ind. Sc. b. iv. c. i. 44 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. The moral of this incident is the same moral which we have perpetually to note as taught us at every step by the history of Science :-namely, the necessity of con- stant, careful and exact observation of Facts; and the advantage of devising a Theory, (even if it have to be afterwards rejected, by which the Facts shall be bound together into a coherent whole. CHAPTER IX. THE SCHOOLMEN OF THE MIDDLE AGES. TN the History of the Sciences I have devoted a Book I to the state of Science in the middle ages, and have endeavoured to analyse the intellectual defects of that period. Among the characteristic features of the hu- man mind during those times, I have noticed Indis- tinctness of Ideas, a Commentatorial Spirit, Mysticism, and Dogmatism. The account there given of this portion of the history of man belongs, in reality, rather to the History of Ideas than to the History of Progressive Science. For, as we have there remarked, theoretical Science was, during the period of which we speak, almost entirely stationary; and the investiga- tion of the causes of such a state of things may be considered as a part of that review in which we are now engaged, of the vicissitudes of man's acquaintance with the methods of discovery. But when we offered to the world a history of science, to leave so large a chasm unexplained, would have made the series of events seem defective and broken; and the survey of the Middle Ages was therefore inserted. I would beg to refer to that portion of the former work the reader who wishes for information in addition to what is here given. The Indistinctness of Ideas and the Commenta- torial Disposition of those ages have already been here brought under our notice. Viewed with reference to the opposition between Experience and Ideas, on which point, as we have said, the succession of opinions in a great measure turns, it is clear that the commen- tatorial method belongs to the ideal side of the ques- tion: for the commentator seeks for such knowledge 40 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. as he values, by analysing and illustrating what his author has said; and, content with this material of speculation, does not desire to add to it new stores of experience and observation. And with regard to the two other features in the character which we gave to those ages, we may observe that Dogmatism demands for philosophical theories the submission of mind, due to those revealed religious doctrines which are to guide our conduct and direct our hopes : while Mysticism elevates ideas into realities, and offers them to us as the objects of our religious regard. Thus the Mysti- cism of the middle ages and their Dogmatism alike arose from not discriminating the offices of theoretical and practical philosophy. Mysticism claimed for ideas the dignity and reality of principles of moral action and religious hope: Dogmatism imposed theoretical opinions respecting speculative points with the impe- rative tone of rules of conduct and faith. If, however, the opposite claims of theory and prac- tice interfered with the progress of science by the con- fusion they thus occasioned, they did so far more by drawing men away altogether from mere physical speculations. The Christian religion, with its pre- cepts, its hopes, and its promises, became the leading subject of men's thoughts; and the great active truths thus revealed, and the duties thus enjoined, made all inquiries of mere curiosity appear frivolous and un- worthy of man. The Fathers of the Church some- times philosophized ill; but far more commonly they were too intent upon the great lessons which they had to teach, respecting man's situation in the eyes of his Heavenly Master, to philosophize at all respecting things remote from the business of life and of no im- portance in man's spiritual concerns. Yet man has his intellectual as well as his spiritual wants. He has faculties which demand systems and reasons, as well as precepts and promises. The Christ- ian doctor, who knew so much more than the heathen philosopher respecting the Creator and Governor of the universe, was not long content to know or to teach less, respecting the universe itself. While it was still main- SCHOOLMEN OF THE MIDDLE AGES. 47 tained that Theology was the only really important study, Theology was so extended and so fashioned as to include all other knowledge : and after no long time, the Fathers of the Church themselves became the authors of systems of universal knowledge. But when this happened, the commentatorial spirit was still in its full vigour. The learned Christians Romans, devise, by the mere force of their own inven- tion, new systems, full, comprehensive, and connected, like those of the heroic age of philosophy. The same mental tendencies which led men to look for specula- tive coherence and completeness in the view of the universe, led them also to admire and dwell upon the splendid and acute speculations of the Greeks. They were content to find, in those immortal works, the answers to the questions which their curiosity prompt- ed; and to seek what further satisfaction they might require, in analysing and unfolding the doctrines pro- mulgated by those great masters of knowledge. Thus the Christian doctors became, as to general philosophy, commentators upon the ancient Greek teachers. Among these, they selected Aristotle as their pecu- liar object of admiration and study. The vast store, both of opinions and facts, which his works contain, his acute distinctions, his cogent reasons in some por- tions of his speculations, his symmetrical systems in almost all, naturally commended him to the minds of subtle and curious men. We may add that Plato, who taught men to contemplate Ideas separate from Things, was not so well fitted for general acceptance as Aristotle, who rejected this separation. For al- though the due apprehension of this opposition of Ideas and Sensations is a necessary step in the progress of true philosophy, it requires a clearer view and a more possess; and Aristotle, who evaded the necessary per- plexities in which this antithesis involves us, appeared, to the temper of those times, the easier and the plainer guide of the two. The Doctors of the middle ages having thus adopted 48 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. Aristotle as their master in philosophy, we shall not be surprised to find them declaring, after him, that ex- perience is the source of our knowledge of the visible world. But though, like the Greeks, they thus talked of experiment, like the Greeks, they showed little disposition to discover the laws of nature by observa- tion of facts. This barren and formal recognition of experience or sensation as one source of knowledge, not being illustrated by a practical study of nature, and by real theoretical truths obtained by such a study, remained ever vague, wavering, and empty. Such a mere acknowledgment cannot, in any times, ancient or modern, be considered as indicating a just apprehension of the true basis and nature of science. In imperfectly perceiving how, and how far, expe- rience is the source of our knowledge of the external world, the teachers of the middle ages were in the dark; but so, on this subject, have been almost all the writers of all ages, with the exception of those who in recent times have had their minds enlightened by contemplating philosophically the modern progress of science. The opinions of the doctors of the middle ages on such subjects generally had those of Aristotle for their basis; but the subject was often still further analysed and systematized, with an acute and metho- dical skill hardly inferior to that of Aristotle himself. The Stagirite, in the beginning of his Physics, had made the following remarks. "In all bodies of doc- trine which involve principles, causes, or elements, Science and Knowledge arise from the knowledge of these; (for we then consider ourselves to know respecting any subject, when we know its first cause, its first principles, its ultimate elements.) It is evi- dent, therefore, that in seeking a knowledge of nature, we must first know what are its principles. But the course of our knowledge is, from the things which are better known and more manifest to us, to the things which are more certain and evident in nature. For those things which are most evident in truth, are not most evident to us. [And consequently we must advance from things obscure in nature, but SCHOOLMEN OF THE MIDDLE AGES. 49 manifest to us, towards the things which are really in nature more clear and certain. The things which are first obvious and apparent to us are complex; and from these we obtain, by analysis, principles and ele- ments. We must proceed from universals to particu- lars. For the whole is better known to our senses than the parts, and for the same reason, the universal better known than the particular. And thus words signify things in a large and indiscriminate way, which is afterwards analysed by definition; as we see that the children at first call all men father, and all women mother, but afterwards learn to distinguish.” There are various assertions contained in this ex- tract which came to be considered as standard maxims; and which occur constantly in the writers of the mid- dle ages. Such are, for instance, the maxim, “ Verè scire est per causas scire;" the remark, that com- pounds are known to us before their parts, and the illustration from the expressions used by children. Of the mode in which this subject was treated by the schoolmen, we may judge by looking at passages of Thomas Aquinas which treat of the subject of the human understanding. In the Sunma Theologice, the eighty-fifth Question is on the manner and order of understanding, which subject he considers in eight Articles; and these must, even now, be looked upon as exhibiting many of the most important and inter- esting points of the subject. They are, First, Whether our understanding understands by abstracting ideas (species) from appearances; Second, Whether intelli- gible species abstracted from appearances are related to our understanding as that which we understand, or that by which we understand; Third, Whether our understanding does naturally understand universals first; Fourth, Whether our understanding can under- stand many things at once; Fifth, Whether our un- derstanding understands by compounding and dividing; Sixth, Whether the understanding can err; Seventh, Whether one person can understand the same thing better than another; Eighth, Whether our under- standing understands the indivisible sooner than the E 50 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. divisible. And in the discussion of the last point, for example, reference is made to the passage of Aristotle which we have already quoted. “It may seem," he says, “that we understand the indivisible before the divisible; for the Philosopher says that we understand and know by knowing principles and elements; but indivisibles are the principles and elements of divisible things. But to this we may reply, that in our receiving of science, principles and elements are not always first; for sometimes from the sensible effects we go on to the knowledge of intelligible principles and causes.” We see that both the objection and the answer are drawn from Aristotle. We find the same close imitation of Aristotle in Albertus Magnus, who, like Aquinas, flourished in the thirteenth century. Albertus, indeed, wrote treatises corresponding to almost all those of the Stagirite, and was called the Ape of Aristotle. In the beginning of his Physics, he says, “Knowledge does not always begin from that which is first according to the nature of things, but from that of which the knowledge is easiest. For the human intellect, on account of its relation to the senses (propter reflexionem quam habet ad sensum), collects science from the senses; and thus it is easier for our knowledge to begin from that which we can apprehend by sense, imagination, and intellect, than from that which we apprehend by intellect alone.” We see that he has somewhat systematized what he has borrowed. This disposition to dwell upon and systematize the leading doctrines of metaphysics assumed a more defi- nite and permanent shape in the opposition of the Realists and Nominalists. The opposition involved in this controversy is, in fact, that fundamental antithesis of Sense and Ideas about which philosophy has always been engaged ; and of which we have marked the manifestation in Plato and Aristotle. The question, What is the object of our thoughts when we reason concerning the external world? must occur to all speculative minds : and the difficulties of the answer are manifest. We must reply, either that our own SCHOOLMEN OF THE MIDDLE AGES. 51 Ideas, or that Sensible Things, are the elements of our knowledge of nature. And then the scruples again occur,-how we have any general knowledge if our thoughts are fixed on particular objects; and, on the other hand,--how we can attain to any true know- ledge of nature by contemplating ideas which are not identical with objects in nature. The two opposite opinions maintained on this subject were, on the one side, that our general propositions refer to objects which are real, though divested of the peculiarities of individuals; and, on the other side,--that in such propositions, individuals are not represented by any reality, but bound together by a name. These two views were held by the Realists and Nominalists re- spectively : and thus the Realist manifested the adhe- rence to Ideas, and the Nominalist the adherence to the impressions of Sense, which have always existed as opposite yet correlative tendencies in man. The Realists were the prevailing sect in the Scho- lastic times : for example, both Thomas Aquinas and Duns Scotus, the Angelical and the Subtle Doctor, held this opinion, although opposed to each other in many of their leading doctrines on other subjects. And as the Nominalist, fixing his attention upon sen- sible objects, is obliged to consider what is the princi- ple of generalization, in order that the possibility of any general proposition may be conceivable; so on the other hand, the Realist, beginning with the contem- plation of universal ideas, is compelled to ask what is the principle of individuation, in order that he may comprehend the application of general propositions in each particular instance. This inquiry concerning the principle of individuation was accordingly a problem which occupied all the leading minds among the Schoolmen?. It will be apparent from what has been said, that it is only one of the many forms of the fundamental antithesis of the Ideas and the Senses, which we have constantly before us in this review. 1 See the opinion of Aquinas, in Degerando, Hist. Com. des Syst. iv. 499 ; of Duns Scotus, ibid. iv. 523. E 2 52 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. The recognition of the derivation of our knowledge, in part at least, from Experience, though always loose and incomplete, appears often to be independent of the Peripatetic traditions. Thus Richard of St. Victor, a writer of contemplative theology in the twelfth cen- tury, says”, that “there are three sources of know- ledge, experience, reason, faith. Some things we prove by experiment, others we collect by reasoning, the certainty of others we hold by believing. And with regard to temporal matters, we obtain our knowledge by actual experience; the other guides belong to divine knowledge.” Richard also propounds a division of human knowledge which is clearly not derived directly from the ancients, and which shows that con- siderable attention must have been paid to such specu- lations. He begins by laying down clearly and broadly the distinction, which, as we have seen, is of primary importance, between practice and theory. Practice, he says, includes seven mechanical arts; those of the clothier, the armourer, the navigator, the hunter, the physician, and the player. Theory is threefold, divine, natural, doctrinal; and is thus divided into Theology, Physics, and Mathematics. Mathematics, he adds, treats of the invisible forms of visible things. We have seen that by many profound thinkers this word forms has been selected as best fitted to describe those relations of things which are the subject of mathema- tics. Again, Physics discovers causes from their effects and effects from their causes. It would not be easy at the present day to give a better account of the ob- ject of physical science. But Richard of St. Victor makes this account still more remarkably judicious, by the examples to which he alludes ; which are earthquakes, the tides, the virtues of plants, the in- stincts of animals, the classification of minerals, plants and reptiles. Unde tremor terris, quâ vi maria alta tumescant, Herbarum vires, animos irasque ferarum, Omne genus fruticum, lapidum quoque, reptiliumque. ? Liber Excerptionum, Lib. i. c. i. SCHOOLMEN OF THE MIDDLE AGES. 53 He further adds, “Physical science ascends from effects to causes, and descends again from causes to effects.” This declaration Francis Bacon himself might have adopted. It is true, that Richard would probably have been little able to produce any clear ascent and descent were exemplified; but still the statement, even considered as a mere conjectural thought, contains a portion of that sagacity and com- prehensive power which we admire so much in Bacon. Richard of St. Victor, who lived in the twelfth century, thus exhibits more vigour and independence of speculative power than Thomas Aquinas, Albertus Magnus, and Duns Scotus, in the thirteenth. In the interval, about the end of the twelfth century, the writings of Aristotle had become generally known in the West; and had been elevated into the standard of philosophical doctrine, by the divines mentioned above, who felt a reverent sympathy with the systematizing and subtle spirit of the Stagirite as soon as it was made manifest to them. These doctors, following the example of their great forerunner, reduced every part of human knowledge to a systematic form; the sys- tems which they thus framed were presented to men's minds as the only true philosophy, and dissent from them was no longer considered to be blameless. It was an offence against religion as well as reason to reject the truth, and the truth could be but one. In this manner arose that claim which the Doctors of the Church put forth to control men's opinions upon all of Science as the Dogmatism of the Middle Ages. There is no difficulty in giving examples of this cha- racteristic. We may take for instance a Statute of the University of Paris, occasioned by a Bull of Pope John XXI., in which it is enacted, “that no Master or Bachelor of any faculty, shall presume to read lec- tures upon any author in a private room, on account of the many perils which may arise therefrom; but 3 Tr. Ex. Lib. i. c. vii. 54 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. shall read in public places, where all may resort, and may faithfully report what is there taught; excepting only books of Grammar and Logic, in which there can be no presumption.” And certain errors of Brescian are condemned in a Rescript* of the papal Legate Odo, with the following expressions: “Whereas, as we have been informed, certain Logical professors treating of Theology in their disputations, and Theo- logians treating of Logic, contrary to the command of the law are not afraid to mix and confound the lots of the Lord's heritage; we exhort and admonish your University, all and singular, that they be content with the landmarks of the Sciences and Faculties which our Fathers have fixed; and that having due fear of the curse pronounced in the law against him who removeth his neighbour's landmark, you hold such sober wisdom according to the Apostles, that ye may by no means incur the blame of innovation or pre- sumption.” The account which, in the History of Science, I gave of Dogmatism as a characteristic of the middle ages, has been indignantly rejected by a very pleasing modern writer, who has, with great feeling and great diligence, brought into view the merits and beauties of those times, termed by him Ages of Faith. He urges that religious authority was never claimed for physical science : and he quotes from Thomas Aquinas, à passage in which the author protests against the practice of confounding opinions of philosophy with doctrines of faith. We might quote in return the Re- script“ of Stephen, bishop of Paris, in which he declares that there can be but one truth, and rejects the dis- tinction of things being true according to philosophy and not according to the Catholic faith ; and it might be added, that among the errors condemned in this document are some of Thomas Aquinas himself. We might further observe, that if no physical doctrines 4 Tenneman, viii. 461. 5 Mores Catholici, or Ages of l'aith, viii. p. 247. 6 Tenneman, vii. 460. SCHOOLMEN OF THE MIDDLE AGES. 55 were condemned in the times of which we now speak, this was because, on such subjects, no new opinions were promulgated, and not because opinion was free. As soon as new opinions, even on physical subjects, attracted general notice, they were prohibited by authority, as we see in the case of Galileo?. But this disinclination to recognize philosophy as independent of religion, and this disposition to find in new theories, even in physical ones, something contrary to religion or scripture, are, it would seem, very na- tural tendencies of theologians; and it would be unjust to assert that these propensities were confined to the periods when the authority of papal Rome was highest; or that the spirit which has in a great degree con- trolled and removed such habits was introduced by the Reformation of religion in the sixteenth century. We must trace to other causes, the clear and general recognition of Philosophy, as distinct from Theology, and independent of her authority. In the earlier ages of the Church, indeed, this separation had been ac- knowledged. St. Augustin says, “ A Christian should beware how he speaks on questions of natural philo- sophy, as if they were doctrines of Holy Scripture; for 7 If there were any doubt on this (Tenneman, ix. 43.) We might urge subject, we might refer to the writers too, the evasions practised by philo- who afterwards questioned the su- sophical Reformers, through fear of premacy of Aristotle, and who with the dogmatism to which they had to one voice assert that an infallible submit; for example, the protesta- authority had been claimed for him. tion of Telesius at the end of the Thus Laurentius Valla: “Quo minus Proem to his work, De Rerum Na- ferendi sunt recentes Peripatetici, tura: “Nec tamen, si quid eorum qui nullius sectæ hominibus interdi- quæ nobis posita sunt, sacris literis, cunt libertate ab Aristotele dissenti- Catholicæve ecclesiæ decretis non endi, quasi sophos hic, non philoso- cohæreat, tenendum id, quin penitus phus." Pref. in Dial. (Tenneman, ix. rejiciendum asseveramus contendi- 29.) So Ludovicus Vives: “Sunt ex musque. Neque enim humana modo philosophis et ex theologis qui non ratio quævis, sed ipse etiam sensus solum quo Aristoteles pervenit ex- illis posthabendus, et si illis non con- tremum esse aiunt naturæ, sed quå gruat, abnegandus omnino et ipse pervenit eam rectissimam esse om etiam est sensus." nium et certissimani in natura viam." 56 U PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. an infidel who should hear him deliver absurdities could not avoid laughing. Thus the Christian would be confused, and the infidel but little edified; for the infidel would conclude that our authors really enter- tained these extravagant opinions, and therefore they would despise them, to their own eternal ruin. There- fore the opinions of philosophers should never be pro- posed as dogmas of faith, or rejected as contrary to faith, when it is not certain that they are so.” These words are quoted with approbation by Thomas Aqui- nas, and it is said, are cited in the same manner in every encyclopedical work of the middle ages. This warning of genuine wisdom was afterwards rejected, as we have seen; and it is only in modern times that its value has again been fully recognized. And this improvement we must ascribe, mainly, to the progress of physical science. For a great body of undeniable truths on physical subjects being accumulated, such as had no reference to nor connexion with the truths of religion, and yet such as possessed a strong interest for most men's minds, it was impossible longer to deny that there were wide provinces of knowledge which were not included in the dominions of Theology, and over which she had no authority. In the fifteenth and sixteenth centuries, the fundamental doctrines of mechanics, hydrostatics, optics, magnetics, chemistry, were established and promulgated; and along with them, a vast train of consequences, attractive to the mind by the ideal relations which they exhibited, and striking to the senses by the power which they gave man over nature. Here was a region in which philo- sophy felt herself entitled and impelled to assert her independence. From this region, there is a gradation of subjects in which philosophy advances more and more towards the peculiar domain of religion; and at some intermediate points there have been, and pro- bably will always be, conflicts respecting the boundary 8 Ages of Faith, viii. 247: to the author of which I am obliged for this quotation. SCHOOLMEN OF THE MIDDLE AGES. 57 line of the two fields of speculation. For the limit is vague and obscure, and appears to fluctuate and shift with the progress of time and knowledge. Our business at present is not with the whole ex- tent and limits of philosophy, but with the progress of physical science more particularly, and the methods by which it may be attained : and we are endeavouring to trace historically the views which have prevailed respecting such methods, at various periods of man's intellectual progress. Among the most conspicuous of the revolutions which opinions on this subject have undergone, is the transition from an implicit trust in the internal powers of man's mind to a professed de- pendence upon external observation; and from an un- bounded reverence for the wisdom of the past, to a fervid expectation of change and improvement. The origin and progress of this disposition of mind;-the introduction of a state of things in which men not only obtained a body of indestructible truths from experience, and increased it from generation to gene- ration, but professedly, and we may say, ostenta- tiously, declared such to be the source of their know- ledge, and such their hopes of its destined career; the rise, in short, of Experimental Philosophy, not only as a habit, but as a Philosophy of Experience, is what we must now endeavour to exhibit. CHAPTER X. THE INNOVATORS OF THE MIDDLE AGES. Raymond Lrilly. 1. General Remarks.—In the rise of Experimental Philosophy, understanding the term in the way just now stated, two features have already been alluded to: the disposition to cast off the prevalent reverence for the opinions and methods of preceding teachers with an eager expectation of some vast advantage to be de- rived from a change; and the belief that this improve- ment must be sought by drawing our knowledge from external observation rather than from mere intellectual efforts ;-the Insurrection against Authority, and the Appeal to Experience. These two movements were closely connected; but they may easily be distinguished, and in fact, persons were very prominent in the former part of the task, who had no comprehension of the lat- ter principle, from which alone the change derives its value. There were many Malcontents who had not the temper, talent or knowledge, which fitted them to be Reformers. The authority which was questioned, in the struggle of which we speak, was that of the Scholastic System, the combination of Philosophy with Theology; of which Aristotle, presented in the form and manner which the Doctors of the Church had imposed upon him, is to be considered the representative. When there was de- manded of men a submission of the mind, such as this system claimed, the natural love of freedom in man's bosom, and the speculative tendencies of his intellect, l'ose in rebellion, from time to time, against the ruling oppression. We find in all periods of the scholastic ages examples of this disposition of man to resist over- INNOVATORS OF THE MIDDLE AGES. 59 strained authority; the tendency being mostly, how- ever, combined with a want of solid thought, and showing itself in extravagant pretensions and fantasti- cal systems put forwards by the insurgents. We have pointed out one such opponent' of the established sys- tems, even among the Arabian schoolmen, a more servile race than ever the Europeans were. We may here notice more especially an extraordinary character who appeared in the thirteenth century, and who may be considered as belonging to the Prelude of the Re- form in Philosophy, although he had no share in the Reform itself. 2. Raymond Lully.— Raymond Lully is perhaps traditionally best known as an Alchemist, of which art he appears to have been a cultivator. But this was only one of the many impulses of a spirit ardently thirsty of knowledge and novelty. He had”, in his youth, - been a man of pleasure, but was driven by a sudden shock of feeling to resolve on a complete change of life. He plunged into solitude, endeavoured to still the remorse of his conscience by prayer and penance, and soon had his soul possessed by visions which he conceived were vouchsafed to him. In the feeling of religious enthusiasm thus excited, he resolved to de- vote his life to the diffusion of Christian truth among Heathens and Mahomedans. For this purpose, at the age of thirty he betook himself to the study of Gram- mar, and of the Arabic language. He breathed earnest supplications for an illumination from above; and these were answered by his receiving from heaven, as his admirers declare, his Ars Magna by which he was able without labour or effort to learn and apply all know- ledge. The real state of the case is, that he put him- self in opposition to the established systems, and pro- pounded a New Art, from which he promised the most wonderful results; but that his Art really is merely a mode of combining ideal conceptions without any re- ference to real sources of knowledge, or any possibility 1 Algazel. See Hist. Ind. Sc. b. iv. C. I. ? Tenneman, viii. 830. 60 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. of real advantage. In a Treatise addressed, in A. D. 1310, to King Philip of France, entitled Liber La- mentationis Duodecim Principiorum Philosophice contra Averroistas, Lully introduced Philosophy, accompanied by her twelve Principles, (Matter, Form, Generation, &c.) uttering loud complaints against the prevailing system of doctrine; and represents her as presenting to the king a petition that she may be upheld and restored by her favourite, the Author. His Tabula Generalis ad omnes Scientias applicabilis was begun the 15th September, 1292, in the Harbour of Tunis, and finished in 1293, at Naples. In order to frame an Art of thus tabulating all existing sciences, and indeed all possible knowledge, he divides into various classes the conceptions with which he has to deal. The first Greatness, Duration, Power, Wisdom, Will, Virtue, Truth, Majesty. The second class has nine Relative Conceptions : Difference, Identity, Contrariety, Begin- ning, Middle, End, Majority, Equality, Minority. The third class contains nine Questions: Whether? What? Whence? Why? How great? How circumstanced ? the nine Most General Subjects: God, Angel, Heaven, Man, Imaginativum, Sensitivum, Vegetativum, Elemen- tativun, Instrumentativum. Then come nine Prædica- merts, nine Moral Qualities, and so on. These con- ceptions are arranged in the compartments of certain concentric moveable circles, and give various combina- tions by means of triangles and other figures, and thus propositions are constructed. It must be clear at once, that real knowledge, which is the union of facts and ideas, can never result from this machinery for shifting about, joining and disjoin- ing, empty conceptions. This, and all similar schemes, go upon the supposition that the logical combinations of notions do of themselves compose knowledge; and that really existing things may be arrived at by a successive system of derivation from our most general ideas. It is imagined that by distributing the nomenclature of abstract ideas according to the place which they can INNOVATORS OF THE MIDDLE AGES. 61 hold in our propositions, and by combining them ac- cording to certain conditions, we may obtain formula including all possible truths, and thus fabricate a science in which all sciences are contained. We thus obtain the means of talking and writing upon all sub- jects, without the trouble of thinking: the revolutions of the emblematical figures are substituted for the operations of the mind. Both exertion of thought, and knowledge of facts, become superfluous. And this reflection, adds an intelligent authors, explains the enormous number of books which Lully is said to have written; for he might have written those even during his sleep, by the aid of a moving power which should keep his machine in motion. Having once devised this invention for manufacturing science, Lully varied it in a thousand ways, and followed it into a variety of developments. Besides Synoptical Tables, he em- ploys Genealogical Trees, each of which he dignifies with the name of the Tree of Science. The only requi- site for the application of his System was a certain agreement in the numbers of the classes into which different subjects were distributed; and as this sym- metry does not really exist in the operations of our thoughts, some violence was done to the natural dis- tinction and subordination of conceptions, in order to fit them for the use of the system. Thus Lully, while he professed to teach an Art which was to shed new light upon every part of science, was in fact employed in a pedantic and trifling repetition of known truths or truisms; and while he complained of the errors of existing methods, he pro- posed in their place one which was far more empty, barren, and worthless, than the customary processes of human thought. Yet his method is spoken of4 with 3 Degerando, iv. 535. Arte Combinatoria, publié en 1666, et 4 Leibnitz's expressions are, (Op. t. qui a été reimprimé après malgré moi. vi. p. 16): “Quand j'étais jeune, je Mais comme je ne méprise rien facile- prenois quelque a l'Art de Lule, mais ment, excepté les arts divinatoires ju crus y entrevoir bien des défectuo- que ne sont que des tromperies toutes sités, dont j'ai dit quelque chose dans pures, j'ai trouvé quelque chose d'es- un petit Essai d'écolier intitulé De timable encore dans l'Art de Lulle.” 62 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. . some praise by Leibnitz, who indeed rather delighted in the region of ideas and words, than in the world of realities. But Francis Bacon speaks far otherwise and more justly on this subjects. “It is not to be omitted that some men, swollen with emptiness rather than knowledge, have laboured to produce a certain Method, not deserving the name of a legitimate Method, since it is rather a method of imposture: which yet is doubtless highly grateful to certain would-be philoso- phers. This method scatter's about certain little drops of science in such a manner that a smatterer may make a perverse and ostentatious use of them with a certain show of learning. Such was the art of Lully, which consisted of nothing but a mass and heap of the words of each science; with the intention that he who can readily produce the words of any science shall be supposed to know the science itself. Such collections are like a rag shop, where you find a patch of every- thing, but nothing which is of any value.” 5 IVorks, vii. 296. CHAPTER XI. THE INNOVATORS OF THE MIDDLE AGES—CONTINUED. Roger Bacon. W E now come to a philosopher of a very different VV character, who was impelled to declare his dissent from the reigning philosophy by the abundance of his knowledge, and by his clear apprehension of the mode in which real knowledge had been acquired and must be increased. Roger Bacon was born in 1214, near Ilchester, in Somersetshire, of an old family. In his youth he was a student at Oxford, and made extraordinary progress in all branches of learning. He then went to the University of Paris, as was at that time the custom of learned Englishmen, and there received the degree of Doctor of Theology. At the persuasion of Robert Grostête, bishop of Lincoln, he entered the brother- hood of Franciscans in Oxford, and gave himself up to study with extraordinary fervour. He was termed by his brother monks Doctor Mirabilis. We know from his own works, as well as from the traditions concern- ing him, that he possessed an intimate acquaintance with all the science of his time which could be ac- quired from books; and that he had made many re- markable advances by means of his own experimental labours. He was acquainted with Arabic, as well as with the other languages common in his time. In the title of his works, we find the whole range of science and philosophy, Mathematics and Mechanics Optics, Astronomy, Geography, Chronology, Chemistry, Magic, Music, Medicine, Grammar, Logic, Metaphysics, Ethics, and Theology; and judging from those which are published, these works are full of sound and exact 64 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. knowledge. He is with good reason, supposed to have discovered, or to have had some knowledge of, several of the most remarkable inventions which were made generally known soon afterwards; as gunpow- der, lenses, burning specula, telescopes, clocks, the correction of the calendar, and the explanation of the rainbow. Thus possessing, in the acquirements and habits of his own mind, abundant examples of the nature of knowledge and of the process of invention, Roger Bacon felt also a deep interest in the growth and pro- gress of science, a spirit of inquiry respecting the causes which produced or prevented its advance, and a fervent hope and trust in its future destinies; and these feelings impelled him to speculate worthily and wisely respecting a Reform of the Method of Philoso- phizing. The manuscripts of his works have existed for nearly six hundred years in many of the libraries of Europe, and especially in those of England; and for a long period the very imperfect portions of them which were generally known, left the character and attainments of the author shrouded in a kind of mys- terious obscurity. About a century ago, however, his Opus Majus was published" by Dr. S. Jebb, princi- pally from a manuscript in the Library of Trinity College, Dublin; and this contained most or all of the separate works which were previously known to the public, along with others still more peculiar and cha- racteristic. We are thus able to judge of Roger Bacon's knowledge and of his views, and they are in every way well worthy our attention. The Opus Majus is addressed to Pope Clement the Fourth, whom Bacon had known when he was legate in England as Cardinal-bishop of Sabina, and who admired the talents of the monk, and pitied him for the persecutions to which he was exposed. On his elevation to the papal chair, this account of Bacon's 1 Fratris Rogeri Bacon, Ordinis Mi- norum, Opus Majus, ad Clementem Quartum, Pontificem Romanum, e MS. Codice Dubliniensi cum aliis qui- busdam collato, nunc primum edidit S. Jebb, M.D. Londini, 1733. INNOVATORS OF THE MIDDLE AGES. 65 labours and views was sent, at the earnest request of the pontift. Besides the Opus Majus, he wrote two others, the Opus Minus and Opus Tertiun; which were also sent to the pope, as the author says, “on account of the danger of roads, and the possible loss of the work.” These works still exist unpublished, in the Cottonian and other libraries. The Opus Majus is a work equally wonderful with regard to its general scheme, and to the special trea- tises with which the outlines of the plan are filled up. The professed object of the work is to urge the neces- sity of a reform in the mode of philosophizing, to set forth the reasons why knowledge had not made a greater progress, to draw back attention to the sources of knowledge which had been unwisely neglected, to discover other sources which were yet almost un- touched, and to animate men in the undertaking, by a prospect of the vast advantages which it offered. In the development of this plan, all the leading portions of science are expounded in the most complete shape which they had at that time assumed; and improve- ments of a very wide and striking kind are proposed in some of the principal of these departments. Even if the work had had no leading purpose, it would have been highly valuable as a treasure of the most solid knowledge and soundest speculations of the time; even if it had contained no such details, it would have been a work most remarkable for its general views and scope. It may be considered as, at the same time, the Encyclopedia and the Novum Organon of the thir- teenth century. Since this work is thus so important in the history of Inductive Philosophy I shall give, in a note, a view 3 2 Opus Majus, Præf. 3 Contents of Roger Bacon's Opus Majus. Part I. On the four causes of human ignorance :~Authority, Custom, Popular Opinion, and the Pride of supposed Knowledge. Part II. On the source of perfect wisdom in the Sacred Scrip- ture. Part III. On the Usefulness of Grammar. Part IV. On the Usefulness of Ma- thematics. 66 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. of its divisions and contents. But I must now endea- vour to point out more especially the way in which the various principles, which the reform of scientific method involved, are here brought into view. One of the first points to be noticed for this pur- pose, is the resistance to authority; and at the stage of philosophical history with which we here have to do, this means resistance to the authority of Aristotle, as adopted and interpreted by the Doctors of the Schools. Bacon's workis divided into Six Parts; and of these Parts, the First is, Of the four universal Causes of all Human Ignorance. The causes thus enumerated” are :--the force of unworthy authority; — traditionary habit;—the imperfection of the undis- ciplined senses ;-and the disposition to conceal our ignorance and to make an ostentatious show of our knowledge. These influences involve every man, oc- cupy every condition. They prevent our obtaining the most useful and large and fair doctrines of wisdom, the secret of all sciences and arts. He then proceeds to argue, from the testimony of philosophers them- selves, that the authority of antiquity, and especially of Aristotle, is not infallible. “We find their books full of doubts, obscurities, and perplexities. They scarce agree with each other in one empty question or (1) The necessity of Mathematics in Human Things (published se- parately as the Specula Mathe- matica). (2) The necessity of Mathematics in Divine Things.—1°. This study has occupied holy men: 2°. Geography: 30. Chronology: 4º. Cycles; the Golden Number, &c. : 5º. Natural Phenomena, as the Rainbow: 6º. Arithme- tic: 7º. Music. (3) The necessity of Mathematics in Ecclesiastical Things. 1°. The Certification of Faith: 2°. The Correction of the Calendar. (4) The necessity of Mathematics in the State.-1°. Of Climates: 2°. Hydrography: 3º. Geography: 4º. Astrology. Part V. On Perspective (published separately as Perspectiva). (1) The organs of vision. (2) Vision in straight lines. (3) Vision reflected and refracted. (4) De multiplicatione specierum (on the propagation of the im- pressions of light, heat, &c.) . Part VI. On Experimental Scieuce. 4 Op. Maj. p. 1. 5 Ibid. p. 2. Ibid. p. 1o. INNOVATORS OF THE MIDDLE AGES. 67 one worthless sophism, or one operation of science, as one man agrees with another in the practical operations of medicine, surgery, and the like arts of Secular men. Indeed,” he adds, “not only the philosophers, but the saints have fallen into errors which they have afterwards retracted," and this he instances in Augus- tin, Jerome, and others. He gives an admirable sketch' of the progress of philosophy from the Ionic School to Aristotle; of whom he speaks with great applause. « Yet," he adds', “those who came after him corrected him in some things, and added many things to his works, and shall go on adding to the end of the world.” Aristotle, he adds, is now called pecu- liarly® the Philosopher, “yet there was a time when account of the rarity of copies of his works, or their dif- ficulty, or from envy; till after the time of Mahomet, 7 I will give a specimen. Opus Socrates and Greece could teach, made Majus, c. viii. p. 35: “These two kinds a laborious voyage to Egypt, to Ar- of philosophers, the Ionic and Italic, chytas of Tarentumn and Timæus, as ramified through many sects and says Jerome to Paulinus. And this various successors, till they came to Plato is, according to holy men, pre- the doctrine of Aristotle, who cor- ferred to all philosophers, because he rected and changed the propositions has written many excellent things con- of all his predecessors, and attempted cerning God, and morality, and a fu- to perfect philosophy. In the [Italic) ture life, which agree with the divine succession, Pythagoras, Archytas Ta wisdom of God. And Aristotle was rentinus and Timæus are most pro- born before the death of Socrates, minently mentioned. But the prin- since he was his hearer for three cipal philosophers, as Socrates, Plato, years, as we read in the life of and Aristotle, did not descend from Aristotle... This Aristotle, being this line, but were Iouics and true made the master of Alexander the Greeks, of whom the first was Thales Great, sent two thousand men into Milesius. . . Socrates, according to Au- all regions of the earth, to search out gustine in his 8th book, is related to the nature of things, as Pliny relates have been a disciple of Archelaus in the 8th book of his Naturalia, and This Socrates is called the father of composed a thousand books, as we the great philosophers, since he was read in his life.” the master of Plato andAristotle, from 8 Ibid. p. 36. whom all the sects of philosophers 9 Autonoinaticè. descended...Plato, first learning what 68 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. when Avicenna and Averroes, and others, recalled this philosophy into the full light of exposition. And although the Logic and some other works were trans- lated by Boethius from the Greek, yet the philoso- phy of Aristotle first received a quick increase among the Latins at the time of Michael Scot; who, in the year of our Lord 1230, appeared, bringing with him portions of the books of Aristotle on Natural Philo- sophy and Mathematics. And yet a small part only of the works of this author is translated, and a still smaller part is in the hands of common students." He adds further 10 (in the Third Part of the Opus Majus, which is a Dissertation on language), that the translations which are current of these writings, are very bad and imperfect. With these views, he is moved to express himself somewhat impatiently re- specting these works : “If I had," he says, “power over the works of Aristotle, I would have them all burnt; for it is only a loss of time to study in them, and a cause of error, and a multiplication of ignorance beyond expression." - The common herd of students," he says, "with their heads, have no principle by which they can be excited to any worthy employment; and hence they mope and make asses of themselves over their bad translations, and lose their time, and trouble, and money." The remedies which he recommends for these evils, are, in the first place, the study of that only perfect wisdom which is to be found in the sacred Scripture”, in the next place, the study of mathematics and the use of experimentsBy the aid of these methods, 0 0 10 Op. Maj. P. 46. ignorantiæ ultra id quod valeat ex- 11 See Pref. to Jebb's edition. The plicari.... Vulgus studentum cum passages, there quoted, however, are capitibus suis non habet unde exci- not extracts from the Opus Majus, but tetur ad aliquid dignum, et ideo lan- (apparently) from the Opus Minus guet et asininat circa male translata, (MS. Cott. Tib. c. 5.) “Si haberem et tempus et studiun amittit in om- potestatem supra libros Aristotelis, nibus et expensas.” ego facerem omnes cremari ; quia non 12 Part ii. . est nisi temporis amnissio studere in 13 Parts iv. v. and vi. llis, et causa erroris, et multiplicatio . INNOVATORS OF THE MIDDLE AGES. 69 Bacon anticipates the most splendid progress for human knowledge. He takes up the strain of hope and confidence which we have noticed as so peculiar in the Roman writers; and quotes some of the passages of Seneca which we adduced in illustration of this: that the attempts in science were at first rude and imperfect, and were afterwards improved ;-that the day will come, when what is still unknown shall be brought to light by the progress of time and the labours of a longer period;--that one age does not suffice for inquiries so wide and various ;-that the people of future times shall know many things un- known to us;—and that the time shall arrive when posterity will wonder that we overlooked what was so obvious. Bacon himself adds anticipations more pecu- liarly in the spirit of his own time. “We have seen," he says, at the end of the work, “how Aristotle, by the ways which wisdom teaches, could give to Alex- ander the empire of the world. And this the Church ought to take into consideration against the infidels and rebels, that there may be a sparing of Christian blood, and especially on account of the troubles that shall come to pass in the days of Antichrist; which by the grace of God, it would be easy to obviate, if prelates and princes would encourage study, and join in searching out the secrets of nature and art.” It may not be improper to observe here that this belief in the appointed progress of knowledge, is not combined with any overweening belief in the un- bounded and independent power of the human intellect. On the contrary, one of the lessons which Bacon draws from the state and prospects of knowledge, is the duty of faith and humility. “To him," he says 14, “who denies the truth of the faith because he is unable to understand it, I will propose in reply the course of nature, and as we have seen it in examples.” And after giving some instances, he adds, “These, and the like, ought to move men and to excite them to the reception of divine truths. For if, in the vilest objects 14 Op. Maj. P. 476. 70 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. of creation, truths are found, before which the inward pride of man must bow, and believe though it cannot understand, how much more should man humble his mind before the glorious truths of God!” He had before said 15: “Man is incapable of perfect wisdom in this life; it is hard for him to ascend towards perfec- tion, easy to glide downwards to falsehoods and vani- ties : let him then not boast of his wisdom, or extol his knowledge. What he knows is little and worth- less, in respect of that which he believes without know- ing; and still less, in respect of that which he is igno- rant of. He is mad who thinks highly of his wisdom; be most mad, who exhibits it as something to be won- dered at.” He adds, as another reason for humility, that he has proved by trial, he could teach in one year, to a poor boy, the marrow of all that the most diligent person could acquire in forty years' laborious and ex- pensive study. To proceed somewhat more in detail with regard to Roger Bacon's views of a Reform in Scientific Inquiry, we may observe that by making Mathematics and Ex- periment the two great points of his recommendation, be directed his improvement to the two essential parts of all knowledge, Ideas and Facts, and thus took the course which the most enlightened philosophy would have suggested. He did not urge the prosecution of experiment, to the comparative neglect of the existing mathematical sciences and conception; a fault which there is some ground for ascribing to his great name- sake and successor Francis Bacon: still less did he content himself with a mere protest against the au- thority of the schools, and a vague demand for change, which was almost all that was done by those who put themselves forward as reformers in the intermediate time. Roger Bacon holds his way steadily between the two poles of human knowledge; which, as we, have seen, it is far from easy to do. “There are two modes of knowing,” says he lº; "by argument, and by experi- 15 Or. Maj. P. 15. 10 Ibid. p. 445, see also p. 448. “Scientiæ aliæ sciunt sua principia invenire per experimenta, sed con- INNOVATORS OF THE MIDDLE AGES. 71 ment. Argument concludes a question; but it does not make us feel certain, or acquiesce in the contem- plation of truth, except the truth be also found to be so by experience.” It is not easy to express more decidedly the clearly seen union of exact conceptions with certain facts, which, as we have explained, consti- tutes real knowledge. One large division of the Opus Majus is “On the Usefulness of Mathematics,” which is shown by a copi- ous enumeration of existing branches of knowledge, as Chronology, Geography, the Calendar and in a sepa- rate Part) Optics. There is a chapter?), in which it is proved by reason, that all science requires mathe- matics. And the arguments which are used to es- tablish this doctrine, show a most just appreciation of the office of mathematics in science. They are such as follows:- That other sciences use examples taken from mathematics as the most evident:- That mathematical knowledge is, as it were, innate in us, on which point he refers to the well-known dialogue of Plato, as quoted by Cicero : That this science, being the easi- est, offers the best introduction to the more difficult: That in mathematics, things as known to us are identical with things as known to nature :—That we can here entirely avoid doubt and error, and obtain certainty and truth :--That mathematics is prior to other sciences in nature, because it takes cognizance of quantity, which is apprehended by intuition, (intuitu intellectus). “Moreover," he adds 18, “there have been found famous men, as Robert, bishop of Lincoln, and Brother Adam Marshman (de Marisco), and many others, who by the power of mathematics have been able to explain the causes of things; as may be seen in the writings of these men, for instance, concerning the Rainbow and Comets, and the generation of heat, and climates, and the celestial bodies.” clusiones per argumenta facta ex principiis inventis. Si vero debeant habere experientiam conclusionum suarum particularem et completam, tunc oportet quod habeant per adju- torium istius scientiæ nobilis (expe- rimentalis).” 17 Op. Maj. p. 60. 18 Ibid. p. 64.. 72 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. But undoubtedly the most remarkable portion of the Opus Majus is the Sixth and last Part, which is en- titled “De Scientia experimentali.” It is indeed an extraordinary circumstance to find a writer of the thirteenth century, not only recognizing experiment as one source of knowledge, but urging its claims as something far more important than men had yet been aware of, exemplifying its value by striking and just examples, and speaking of its authority with a dignity of diction which sounds like a foremurmur of the Ba- conian sentences uttered nearly four hundred years later. Yet this is the character of what we here find". “Experimental science, the sole mistress of speculative sciences, has three great. Prerogatives among other parts of knowledge: First she tests by experiment the noblest conclusions of all other sciences: Next she discovers respecting the notions which other sciences deal with, magnificent truths to which these sciences of themselves can by no means attain: her Third dig- nity is, that she by her own power and without respect of other sciences, investigates the secret of nature.” The examples which Bacon gives of these “Preroga- tives” are very curious, exhibiting, among some error and credulity, sound and clear views. His leading example of the First Prerogative, is the Rainbow, of which the cause, as given by Aristotle, is tested by reference to experiment with a skill which is, even to us now, truly admirable. The examples of the Second Prerogative are three :- first, the art of making an artificial sphere which shall move with the heavens by natural influences, which Bacon trusts may be done, though astronomy herself cannot do it—"et tunc,” he says, “thesaurum unius regis valeret hoc instrumen- tum;" — secondly, the art of prolonging life, which experiment may teach, though medicine has no means of securing it except by regimen “º ;-thirdly, the art of 19 “Veritates magnificas in termi- lativarum, potest dare.” Op. Maj. nis aliarum scientiarum in quas per p. 465. nullam viam possunt illae scientiæ, 20 One of the ingredients of a pre- bæc sola scientiarum domina specu- paration here mentioned, is the fleshi INNOVATORS OF THE MIDDLE AGES. 73 making gold finer than fine gold, which goes beyond the power of alchemy. The Third Prerogative of ex- perimental science, arts independent of the received sciences, is exemplified in many curious examples, many of them whimsical traditions. Thus it is said that the character of a people may be altered by altering the air. Alexander, it seems, applied to Aristotle to know whether he should exterminate certain nations which he had discovered, as being irreclaimably bar- barous; to which the philosopher replied, “ If you can alter their air, permit them to live, if not, put them to death.” In this part, we find the suggestion that the fire-works made by children, of saltpetre, might lead : to the invention of a formidable military weapon. It could not be expected that Roger Bacon, at a time when experimental science hardly existed, could give any precepts for the discovery of truth by experi- ment. But nothing can be a better example of the method of such investigation, than his inquiry con- cerning the cause of the Rainbow. Neither Aristotle, nor Avicenna, nor Seneca, he says, have given us any clear knowledge of this matter, but experimental science can do so. Let the experimenter (experimen- tator) consider the cases in which he finds the same colours, as the hexagonal crystals from Ireland and India; by looking into these he will see colours like those of the rainbow. Many think that this arises from some special virtue of these stones and their hex- agonal figure; let therefore the experimenter go on, and he will find the same in other transparent stones, in dark ones as well as in light-coloured. He will find the same effect also in other forms than the hexagon, of a dragon, which it appears is used them, and make them bound about as food by the Ethiopians. The mode in the air in a violent manner, that of preparing this food cannot fail to the hardness and toughness of the 'amuse the reader. “Where there are flesh may be reduced, as boars are good flying dragons, by the art which hunted and bulls are baited before they possess, they draw them out of they are killed for eating.” Op. Maj. their dens, and have bridles and sad. p. 470. dles in readiness, and they ride upon 21 Op. Maj. p. 473. 74 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. if they be furrowed in the surface, as the Irish crys- tals are. Let him consider too, that he sees the same colours in the drops which are dashed from oars in the sunshine;-and in the spray thrown by a mill- wheel ;- and in the dew-drops which lie on the grass in a meadow on a summer-morning;—and if a man takes water in his mouth and projects it on one side into a sunbeam ;-and if in an oil-lamp hanging in the air, the rays fall in certain positions upon the surface of the oil;—and in many other ways, are colours pro- duced. We have here a collection of instances, which are almost all examples of the same kind as the phe- nomenon under consideration; and by the help of a principle collected by induction from these facts, the colours of the rainbow were afterwards really explained. With regard to the form and other circumstances of the bow he is still more precise. He bids us measure the height of the bow and of the sun, to show that the center of the bow is exactly opposite to the sun. He explains the circular form of the bow,-its being inde- pendent of the form of the cloud, its moving when we move, its flying when we follow,—by its consisting of the reflections from a vast number of minute drops. He does not, indeed, trace the course of the rays through the drop, or account for the precise magni- tude which the bow assumes; but he approaches to the verge of this part of the explanation; and must be considered as having given a most happy example of experimental inquiry into nature, at a time when such examples were exceedingly scanty. In this respect, he was more fortunate than Francis Bacon, as we shall hereafter see. We know but little of the biography of Roger Bacon, but we have every reason to believe that his influence upon his age was not great. He was suspected of magic, and is said to have been put into close confine- ment in consequence of this charge. In his work he speaks of Astrology as a science well worth cultivat- ing. “But," says he, “Theologians and Decretists, not being learned in such matters and seeing that evil as well as good may be done, neglect and abhor such. INNOVATORS OF THE MIDDLE AGES. 75 things, and reckon them among Magic Arts." We have already seen, that at the very time when Bacon was thus raising his voice against the habit of blindly following authority, and seeking for all science in Aristotle, Thomas Aquinas was employed in fashion- ing Aristotle's tenets into that fixed form in which they became the great impediment to the progress of knowledge. It would seem, indeed, that something of a struggle between the progressive and stationary powers of the human mind was going on at this time. Bacon himself says”, “Never was there so great an appearance of wisdom, nor so much exercise of study in so many Faculties, in so many regions, as for this last forty years. Doctors are dispersed everywhere, in every castle, in every burgh, and especially by the stu- dents of two Orders, (he means the Franciscans and Dominicans, who were almost the only religious orders that distinguished themselves by an application to study 23.) which has not happened except for about forty years. And yet there was never so much igno- rance, so much error.” And in the part of his work which refers to Mathematics, he says of that study. 4, that it is the door and the key of the sciences; and that the neglect of it for thirty or forty years has en- tirely ruined the studies of the Latins. According to these statements, some change, disastrous to the for- tunes of science, must have taken place about 1230, soon after the foundation of the Dominican and Fran- ciscan Orders”. Nor can we doubt that the adoption of the Aristotelian philosophy by these two Orders, in the form in which the Angelical Doctor had sys- tematized it, was one of the events which most tended to defer, for three centuries, the reform which Roger Bacon urged as a matter of crying necessity in his own time. 22 Quoted by Jebb, Prof. to Op. Maj. w 24 Op. Maj. p. 57. 23 Mosheim, Hist. iii. 161. 25 Mosheim, iii. 161. CHAPTER XII. THE REVIVAL OF PLATONISM. 1. Causes of Delay in the Advance of Knowledge.- In the insight possessed by learned men into the method by which truth was to be discovered, the four- teenth and fifteenth centuries went backwards, rather than forwards, from the point which had been reached in the thirteenth. Roger Bacon had urged them to have recourse to experiment; but they returned with additional and exclusive zeal to the more favourite employment of reasoning upon their own conceptions. He had called upon them to look at the world without; but their eyes forthwith turned back upon the world within. In the constant oscillation of the human inind between Ideas and Facts, after having for a moment touched the latter, it seemed to swing back more impetuously to the former. Not only was the philosophy of Aristotle firmly established for a con- siderable period, but when men began to question its authority, they attempted to set up in its place a phi- losophy still more purely ideal, that of Plato. It was not till the actual progress of experimental knowledge for some centuries had given it a vast accumulation of force, that it was able to break its way fully into the circle of speculative science. The new Platonist school- men had to run their course, the practical discoverers had to prove their merit by their works, the Italian innovators had to utter their aspirations for a change, before the second Bacon could truly declare that the time for a fundamental reform was at length arrived. It cannot but seem strange, to any one who attempts to trace the general outline of the intellectual progress of man, and who considers him as under the guidance REVIVAL OF PLATONISM. 77 of a Providential sway, that he should thus be permit- ted to wander so long in a wilderness of intellectual darkness; and even to turn back, by a perverse ca- price as it might seem, when on the very border of the brighter and better land which was his destined in- heritance. We do not attempt to solve this difficulty: but such a course of things naturally suggests the thought, that a progress in physical science is not the main object of man's career, in the eyes of the Power who directs the fortunes of our race. We can easily conceive that it may have been necessary to man's general welfare that he should continue to turn his eyes inwards upon his own heart and faculties, till Law and Duty, Religion and Government, Faith and Hope, had been fully incorporated with all the past acquisitions of human intellect; rather than that he should have rushed on into a train of discoveries tend- ing to chain him to the objects and operations of the material world. The systematic Law and philoso- phical Theology which acquired their ascendancy in men's minds at the time of which we speak, kept them engaged in a region of speculations which per- haps prepared the way for a profounder and wider civilization, for a more elevated and spiritual charac- ter, than might have been possible without such a preparation. The great Italian poet of the fourteenth century speaks with strong admiration of the founders of the system which prevailed in his time. Thomas, Albert, Gratian, Peter Lombard, occupy distinguished places in the Paradise. The first, who is the poet's instructor, says,— Io fui degli agni della santa greggia Che Domenico mena per cammino U' ben s'impingua se non si vaneggia. Questo che m'è a destra piu vicino Frate e maestro fummi; ed esso Alberto E di Cologna, ed io Tomas d'Aquino. ... Quell'altro fiammeggiar esce del riso . i Gratian published the Decretals in the twelfth century; and the Canon and Civil Law became a regular study in the universities soon afterwards.. 78 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. De Grazian, che l'uno et l'altro foro Ajuto si che piace in Paradiso. I, then, was of the lambs that Dominic Leads, for his saintly flock, along the way Where well they thrive not swoln with vanity. He nearest on my right-hand brother was And master to me; Albert of Cologne Is this; and of Aquinum Thomas, I. .. That next resplendence issues from the smile Of Gratian, who to either forum lent Such help as favour wins in Paradise. It appears probable that neither poetry, nor painting, nor the other arts which require for their perfection a lofty and spiritualized imagination, would have ap- peared in the noble and beautiful forms which they assumed in the fourteenth and fifteenth century, if men of genius had, at the beginning of that period, made it their main business to discover the laws of nature, and to reduce them to a rigorous scientific form. Yet who can doubt that the absence of these touching and impressive works would have left one of the best and purest parts of man's nature without its due nutriment and development ? It may perhaps be a necessary condition in the progress of man, that the Arts which aim at beauty should reach their ex- cellence before the Sciences which seek speculative truth; and if this be so, we inherit, from the middle ages, treasures which may well reconcile us to the delay which took place in their cultivation of experi- mental science. However this may be, it is our business at present to trace the circumstances of this very lingering ad- vance. We have already noticed the contest of the Nominalists and Realists, which was one form, though, with regard to scientific methods, an unprofitable one, of the antithesis of Ideas and Things. Though, there- fore, this struggle continued, we need not dwell upon it. The Nominalists denied the real existence of Ideas, which doctrine was to a great extent implied in the prevailing systems; but the controversy in which they thus engaged, did not lead them to seek for knowledge in a new field and by new methods. The arguments · REVIVAL OF PLATONISM. 79 which Occam the Nominalist opposes to those of Duns Scotus the Realist, are marked with the stamp of the sane system, and consist only in permutations and combinations of the same elementary conceptions. It was not till the impulse of external circumstances was added to the discontent, which the more stirring in- tellects felt towards the barren dogmatism of their age, that the activity of the human mind was again called into full play, and a new career of progression entered upon, till then undreamt of, except by a few prophetie spirits. 2. Causes of Progress.-These circumstances were principally the revival of Greek and Roman literature, the invention of Printing, the Protestant Reformation, and a great number of curious discoveries and inven- tions in the arts, which were soon succeeded by im- portant steps in speculative physical science. Con- nected with the first of these events, was the rise of a party of learned men who expressed their dissatisfac- tion with the Aristotelian philosophy, as it was then taught, and manifested a strong preference for the views of Plato. It is by no means suitable to our plan to give a detailed account of this new Platonic school; but we may notice a few of the writers who belong to it, so far at least as to indicate its influence upon the Methods of pursuing science. In the fourteenth century, the frequent intercourse of the most cultivated persons of the Eastern and Western Empire, the increased study of the Greek lan- guage in Italy, the intellectual activity of the Italian States, the discovery of manuscripts of the classical authors, were circumstances which excited or nourished a new and zealous study of the works of Greek and Roman genius. The genuine writings of the ancients, when presented in their native life and beauty, instead of being seen only in those lifeless fragments and dull transformations which the scholastic system had ex- hibited, excited an intense enthusiasm. Europe, at that period, might be represented by Plato's beautiful 2 Tenneman, ix. 4. 80 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. allegory, of a man who, after being long kept in a dark cavern, in which his knowledge of the external world is gathered from the images which stream through the chinks of his prison, is at last led forth into the full blaze of day. It was inevitable that such a change should animate men's efforts and enlarge their facul- ties. Greek literature became more and more known, especially by the influence of learned men who came from Constantinople into Italy: these teachers, though they honoured Aristotle, reverenced Plato no less, and had never been accustomed to follow with servile sub- mission of thought either these or any other leaders. The effect of such influences soon reveals itself in the works of that period. Dante has woven into his Divina Conimedia some of the ideas of Platonism. Petrarch, who had formed his mind by the study of Cicero, and had thus been inspired with a profound admiration for the literature of Greece, learnt Greek from Barlaam, a monk who came as ambassador from the Emperor of the East to the Pope, in 1339. With this instructor, the poet read the works of Plato; struck by their beauty, he contributed, by his writings and his con- versation, to awake in others an admiration and love for that philosopher, which soon became strongly and extensively prevalent among the learned in Italy. 3. Hermolaus Barbarus, dc.-Along with the feel- ing there prevailed also, among those who had learnt to relish the genuine beauties of the Greek and Latin writers, a strong disgust for the barbarisms in which the scholastic philosophy was clothed. Hermolaus Bar- barus, who was born in 1454, at Venice, and had formed his taste by the study of classical literature, translated, among other learned works, Themistius's paraphrastic expositions of the Physics of Aristotle; with the view of trying whether the Aristotelian Natu- ral Philosophy could not be presented in good Latin, which the scholastic teachers denied. In his Preface he expresses great indignation against those philoso- phers who have written and disputed on philosophical 3 Teuneman, ix. 25. REVIVAL OF PLATONISM. 81 subjects in barbarous Latin, and in an uncultured style, so that all refined minds are repelled from these studies by weariness and disgust. They have, he says, by this barbarism, endeavoured to secure to themselves, in their own province, a supremacy without rivals or opponents. Hence they maintain that mathematics, philosophy, jurisprudence, cannot be expounded in cor- rect Latin ;-that between these sciences and the ge- nuine Latin language there is a great gulf, as between things that cannot be brought together; and on this ground they blame those who combine the study of phi- lology and eloquence with that of science. This opinion, adds Hermolaus, perverts and ruins our studies; and is highly prejudicial and unworthy in respect to the state. Hermolaus awoke in others, as for instance, in John Picus of Mirandula, the same dislike to the reigning school philosophy. As an opponent of the same kind, we may add Marius Nizobius of Bersallo, a scholar who carried his admiration of Cicero to an exaggerated ex- tent, and who was led, by a controversy with the de- fenders of the scholastic philosophy, to publish (1553) a work on the True Principles and True Method of Philosophizing. In the title of this work, he professes to give the true principles of almost all arts and sciences, refuting and rejecting almost all the false principles of the Logicians and Metaphysicians.” But although, in the work, he attacks the scholastic phi- losophy, he does little or nothing to justify the large pretensions of his title; and he excited, it is said, little notice. It is therefore curious that Leibnitz should have thought it worth his while to re-edit this work, which he did in 1670, adding remarks of his own. 4. Nicolaus Cusanus.— Without dwelling upon this opposition to the scholastic system on the ground of taste, I shall notice somewhat further those writers who put forwards Platonic views, as fitted to complete or to replace the doctrines of Aristotle. Among these, I may place Nicolaus Cusanus, (so called from Cus, a village on the Moselle, where he was born in 1401 ;) who was afterwards raised to the dignity of cardinal. We might, indeed, at first be, tempted to include 82 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. Cusanus among those persons who were led to reject the old philosophy by being themselves agents in the progressive movement of physical science. For he published, before Copernicus, and independently of him, the doctrine that the earth is in motion*. But it should be recollected that in order to see the possi- bility of this doctrine, and its claims to acceptance, no new reference to observation was requisite. The Heliocentric System was merely a new mode of repre- senting to the mind facts, with which all astronomers had long been familiar. The system might very easily have been embraced and inculcated by Plato himself; as indeed it is said to have been actually taught by Pythagoras. The mere adoption of the Heliocentric view, therefore, without attempting to realize the sys- tem in detail, as Copernicus did, cannot entitle a writer of the fifteenth century to be looked upon as one of the authors of the discoveries of that period; and we must consider Cusanus as a speculative anti- Aristotelian, rather than as a practical reformer. The title of Cusanus's book, De Doctå Ignorantia, shows how far he was from agreeing with those who conceived that, in the works of Aristotle, they had a full and complete system of all human knowledge. At the outset of this book”, he says, after pointing out some difficulties in the received philosophy, “If, there- fore, the case be so, (as even the very profound Aris- totle, in his First Philosophy, affirms,) that in things most manifest by nature, there is a difficulty, no less than for an owl to look at the sun; since the appetite of knowledge is not implanted in us in vain, we ought to desire to know that we are ignorant. If we can fully attain to this, we shall arrive at Instructed Ig- norance." How far he was from placing the source of knowledge in experience, as opposed to ideas, we may see in the following passage from another work of þis, On Conjectures. “Conjectures must proceed from 4 “Jam nobis manifestum est terram istam in veritate moveri,” &c.--De Doctů Ignorantii, lib. ii. c. xii. . 5 D: Doct. Ignor. lib. i. c. i, o De Conjecturis, lib. i. c. ii. iv. . · REVIVAL OF PLATONISM. our mind, as the real world proceeds from the infinite Divine Reason. For since the human mind, the lofty likeness of God, participates, as it may, in the fruitful- ness of the creative nature, it doth from itself, as the image of the Omnipotent Form, bring forth reasonable thoughts which have a similitude to real existences. Thus the Human Mind exists as a conjectural form of the world, as the Divine Mind is its real form.” We have here the Platonic or ideal side of knowledge put prominently and exclusively forwards. 5. Marsilius Ficinus, &c.—A person who had much more influence on the diffusion of Platonism was Mar- silius Ficinus, a physician of Florence. In that city there prevailed, at the time of which we speak, the greatest enthusiasm for Plato. George Gemistius Ple- tho, when in attendance upon the Council of Florence, had imparted to many persons the doctrines of the Greek philosopher; and, among others, had infused a lively interest on this subject into the elder Cosmo, the head of the family of the Medici. Cosmo formed the plan of founding a Platonic academy. Ficinus?, well instructed in the works of Plato, Plotinus, Pro- clus, and other Platonists, was selected to further this object, and was employed in translating the works of these authors into Latin. It is not to our present purpose to consider the doctrines of this school, except so far as they bear upon the nature and methods of knowledge; and therefore I must pass by, as I bave in other instances done, the greater part of their specu- lations, which related to the nature of God, the im- mortality of the soul, the principles of Goodness and Beauty, and other points of the same order. The object of these and other Platonists of this school, however, was not to expel the authority of Aristotle by that of Plato. Many of them had come to the con- viction that the highest ends of philosophy were to be reached only by bringing into accordance the doctrines of Plato and of Aristotle. Of this opinion was John Picus, Count of Mirandula and Concordia; and under 7 Born in 1433. G 2 84 PĦILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. this persuasion he employed the whole of his life in labouring upon a work, De Concordia Platonis et Aris- totelis, which was not completed at the time of his death, in 1494; and has never been published. But about a century later, another writer of the same school, Francis Patricius", pointing out the discrepancies be- tween the two Greek teachers, urged the propriety of deposing Aristotle from the supremacy he had so long enjoyed. “Now all these doctrines, and others not a few," he says, “since they are Platonic doctrines, philosophically most true, and consonant with the Catho- lic faith, whilst the Aristotelian tenets are contrary to the faith, and philosophically false, who will not, both as a Christian and a Philosopher, prefer Plato to Aristotle? And why should not hereafter, in all the colleges and monasteries of Europe, the reading and study of Plato be introduced ? Why should not the philosophy of Aristotle be forthwith exiled from such places? Why must men continue to drink the mortal poison of impiety from that source?” with much more in the same strain. The Platonic school, of which we have spoken, had, however, reached its highest point of prosperity before this time, and was already declining. About 1500, the Platouists appeared to triumph over the Peripa- tetics 10; but the death of their great patron, Cardinal Bessarion, about this time, and we may add, the hol- lowness of their system in many points, and its want of fitness for the wants and expectations of the age, turned men's thoughts partly back to the established Aristotelian doctrines, and partly forwards to schemes of bolder and fresher promise. 6. Francis Patricius.—Patricius, of whom we have just spoken, was one of those who had arrived at the conviction that the formation of a new philosophy, and not merely the restoration of an old one, was needed. In 1593, appeared his Nova de Universis 8 Born 1529, died 1597. 9 Aristotiles Exotericus, P. 50, 10 Tiraboschi, t. vii. pt. ii. P. 411. REVIVAL OF PLATONISM. 85 Philosophia; and the mode in which it begins can hardly fail to remind us of the expressions which Francis Bacon soon afterwards used in the opening of a work of the same nature. “Francis Patricius, being about to found anew the true philosophy of the uni- verse, dared to begin by announcing the following indisputable principles." Here, however, the resem- blance between Patricius and true inductive philoso- phers ends. His principles are barren à priori axioms; and his system has one main element, Light, (Lux, or Inimen,) to which all operations of nature are referred. In general cultivation, and practical knowledge of nature, he was distinguished among his contempora- ries. In various passages of his works he relates 12 ob- servations which he had made in the course of his travels, in Cyprus, Corfu, Spain, the mountains of the Modenese, and Dalmatia, which was his own country; his observations relate to light, the saltness of the sea, its flux and reflux, and other points of astronomy, meteorology, and natural history. He speaks of the sex of plants 13; rejects judicial astrology; and notices the astronomical systems of Copernicus, Tycho, Fra- castoro, and Torre. But the mode in which he speaks of experiments proves, what indeed is evident from the general scheme of his system, that he had no due appreciation of the place which observation must hold in real and natural philosophy. 7. Picus, Agrippa, &c.-It had been seen in the later philosophical history of Greece, how readily the ideas of the Platonic school lead on to a system of unfathomable and unbounded mysticism. John Picus, of Mirandula", added to the study of Plato and the 11 “Franciscus Patricius, novam ve- ram integram de universis couditurus philosophiam, sequentia uti verissima prænuntiare est ausus. Prænunciata ordine persecutus, divinis oraculis, geometricis rationibus, clarissimisque experimentis comprobavit. Ante primum nihil, Post primum omnia, A principio omnia,” &c. His other works are Panaugia, l'an- cosmia, Dissertationes Peripatetica'. 12 Tiraboschi, t. vii. pt. ii. p. 411. 13 Dissert. Perip. t. ii. lib. v. sub fin. 14 Tenneman, ix. 148. 86 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. Neoplatonists, a mass of allegorical interpretations of the Scriptures, and the dreams of the Cabbala, a Jew- ish system '5, which pretends to explain how all things are an emanation of the Deity. To this his nephew, Francis Picus, added a reference to inward illumina- tion 19, by which knowledge is obtained, independently of the progress of reasoning. John Reuchlin, or Cap- nio, born 1455; John Baptist Helmont, born 1577; Francis Mercurius Helmont, born 1618, and others, succeeded John Picus in his admiration of the Cab- bala: while others, as Jacob Boehmen, rested upon internal revelations like Francis Picus. And thus we have a series of mystical writers, continued into modern times, who may be considered as the successors of the Platonic school; and who all exhibit views alto- gether erroneous with regard to the nature and origin of knowledge. Among the various dreams of this school are certain wide and loose analogies of terres- trial and spiritual things. Thus in the writings of Cornelius Agrippa (who was born 1487, at Cologne) we have such systems as the following 17:—“Since there is a threefold world, elemental, celestial, and in- tellectual, and each lower one is governed by that above it, and receives the influence of its powers : so that the very Archetype and Supreme Author trans- fuses the virtues of his omnipotence into us through angels, heavens, stars, elements, animals, plants, stones, -into us, I say, for whose service he has framed and created all these things ;-the Magi do not think it irrational that we should be able to ascend by the same degrees, the same worlds, to this Archetype of the world, the Author and First Cause of all, of whom all things are, and from whom they proceed; and should not only avail ourselves of those powers which exist in the nobler works of creation, but also should be able to attract other powers, and add them to these." Agrippa's work, De Vanitate Scientiarum, may be 15 Tenneman, ix. 167. 16 Ibid. 158. 17 Agrippa, De Occult. Phil. lib. i. c. 1 -REVIVAL OF PLATONISM. 87. said rather to have a skeptical and cynical, than a Platonic, character. It is a declamation 13, in a melan- choly mood, against the condition of the sciences in his time. His indignation at the worldly success of men whom he considered inferior to himself, had, he says, metamorphosed him into a dog, as the poets relate of Hecuba of Troy, so that his impulse was to snarl and bark. His professed purpose, however, was to expose the dogmatism, the servility, the self-conceit, and the neglect of religious truth which prevailed in the reigning Schools of philosophy. His views of the nature of science, and the modes of improving its cul- tivation, are too imperfect and vague to allow us to rank him among the reformers of science. 8. Paracelsus, Fludd, &c.—The celebrated Para- celsus 19 put himself forwards as a reformer in philo- sophy, and obtained no small number of adherents. He was, in most respects, a shallow and impudent pretender; and had small knowledge of the literature or science of his time: but by the tone of his speaking and writing he manifestly belongs to the mystical school of which we are now speaking. Perhaps by the boldness with which he proposed new systems, and by connecting these with the practical doctrines of medicine, he contributed something to the intro- duction of a new philosophy. We have seen in the History of Chemistry that he was the author of the system of Three Principles, (salt, sulphur, and mèr- cury,) which replaced the ancient doctrine of Four Elements, and prepared the way for a true science of chemistry. But the salt, sulphur, and mercury of Paracelsus were not, he tells his disciples, the visible bodies which we call by those names, but certain in- visible, astral, or sidereal elements. The astral salt is the basis of the solidity and incombustible parts in bodies; the astral sulphur is the source of combustion 18 Written in 1526. 19 Philip Aurelius Theophrastus Bombastus von Holienheim, also called Paracelsus Eremita, born at Einsiedlen in Switzerland, in 1493. 88. PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. and vegetation; the astral mercury is the origin of fluidity and volatility. And again, these three ele- ments are analogous to the three elements of man,- Body, Spirit, and Soul. A writer of our own country, belonging to this mystical school, is Robert Fludd, or De Fluctibus, who was born in 1571, in Kent, and after pursuing his studies at Oxford, travelled for several years. Of all the Theosophists and Mystics, he is by much the most learned; and was engaged in various controver- sies with Mersenne, Gassendi, Kepler, and others. He thus brings us in contact with the next class of philosophers whom we have to consider, the practical reformers of philosophy;—those who furthered the cause of science by making, promulgating, or defeud- ing the great discoveries which now began to occupy men. He adopted the principle, which we have no- ticed elsewhere?, of the analogy of the Macrocosm and Microcosm, the world of nature and the world of man. His system contains such a mixture and confusion of physical and metaphysical doctrines as might be ex- pected from his ground-plan, and from his school. Indeed his object, the general object of mystical specu- lators, is to identify physical with spiritual truths. Yet the influence of the practical experimental philo- sophy which was now gaining ground in the world may be traced in him. Thus he refers to experiments on distillation to prove the existence and relation of the regions of water, air, and fire, and of the spirits which correspond to them; and is conceived, by some persons“, to have anticipated Torricelli in the inven- tion of the Barometer. We need no further follow the speculations of this school. We see already abundant reason why the re- form of the methods of pursuing science could not proceed from the Platonists. Instead of seeking know- ledge by experiment, they immersed themselves deeper than even the Aristotelians had done in traditionary ET 20 Hist. Sc. Id. b. ix. C. 2. sect. 1. The Mystical School of Biology. 21 Tenneman, ix. 221. REVIVAL OF PLATONISM. 89 lore, or turned their eyes inwards in search of an in- ternal illumination. Some attempts were made to remedy the defects of philosophy by a recourse to the doctrines of other sects of antiquity, when men began to feel more distinctly the need of a more connected and solid knowledge of nature than the established system gave them. Among these attempts were those of Berigardº, Magernus, and especially Gassendi, to bring into repute the philosophy of the Ionian school, of Democritus and of Epicurus. But these endeavours were posterior in time to the new impulse given to knowledge by Copernicus, Kepler, and Galileo, and were influenced by views arising out of the success of these discoveries, and they must, therefore, be con- sidered hereafter. In the mean time, some indepen- dent efforts (arising from speculative rather than prac- tical reformers) were made to cast off the yoke of the Aristotelian dogmatism, and to apprehend the true form of that new philosophy which the most active and hopeful minds saw to be needed; and we must give some account of these attempts, before we can commit ourselves to the full stream of progressive philosophy. . 22 Tenneman, ix, 265. CHAPTER XIII. THE THEORETICAL REFORMERS OF SCIENCE. W E have already seen that Patricius, about the V middle of the sixteenth century, announced his purpose of founding anew the whole fabric of philoso- phy; but that, in executing this plan, he ran into wide and baseless hypotheses, suggested by a priori concep- tions rather than by external observation; and that he was further misled by fanciful analogies resembling those which the Platonic mystics loved to contemplate. The same time, and the period which followed it, pro- duced several other essays which were of the same nature, with the exception of their being free from the peculiar tendencies of the Platonic school: and these insurrections against the authority of the established dogmas, although they did not directly substitute a better positive system in the place of that which they assailed, shook the authority of the Aristotelian sys- tem, and led to its overthrow; which took place as soon as these theoretical reformers were aided by practical reformers. 1. Bernardinus Telesius.—Italy, always, in modern times, fertile in the beginnings of new systems, was the soil on which these innovators arose. The earli- est and most conspicuous of them is Bernardinus Telesius, who was born in 1508, at Cosenza, in the kingdom of Naples. His studies, carried on with great zeal and ability, first at Milan and then at Rome, made him well acquainted with the knowledge of his times; but his own reflections convinced him that the basis of science, as then received, was alto- gether erroneous; and led him to attempt a reform, with which view, in 1565, he published, at Rome, his THEORETICAL REFORMERS OF SCIENCE. 91 work”, “Bernardinus Telesius, of Cosenza, on the Na- ture of Things, according to principles of his own.” In the preface of this work he gives a short accounta of the train of reflection by which he was led to put himself in opposition to the Aristotelian philosophy. This kind of autobiography occurs not unfrequently in the writings of theoretical reformers; and shows how livelily they felt the novelty of their undertaking. After the storm and sack of Rome in 1527, Telesius retired to Padua, as a peaceful seat of the muses; and there studied philosophy and mathematics, with great zeal, under the direction of Jerome Amalthæus and Frederic Delphinus. In these studies he made great progress; and the knowledge which he thus acquired threw a new light upon his view of the Aristotelian philosophy. He undertook a closer ex- amination of the Physical Doctrines of Aristotle; and as the result of this, he was astonished how it could have been possible that so many excellent men, so many nations, and even almost the whole human race, should, for so long a time, have allowed themselves to be carried away by a blind reverence for a teacher, who had committed errors so numerous and grave as he perceived to exist in “the philosopher.” Along with this view of the insufficiency of the Aris- totelian philosophy, arose, at an early period, the thought of erecting a better system in its place. With this purpose he left Padua, when he had received the degree of Doctor, and went to Rome, where he was encouraged in his design by the approval and friendly exhortations of distinguished men of letters, amongst whom were Ubaldino Bandinelli and Giovanni della Casa. From Rome he went to his native place, when the incidents and occupations of a married life for a while interrupted his philosophical project. But after his i Bernardini Telesii Consentini De man: this Proem was omitted in sub- Rerum Natura juxta propria Prin- sequent editions of Telesius, and is cipia. not in the one which I have consult- 2 I take this account from Tenne- ed. Tenneman, Gesch. a Phil. ix. 280. 92 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. wife was dead, and his eldest son grown to manhood, he resumed with ardour the scheme of his youth ; again studied the works of Aristotle and other phi- losophers, and composed and published the first two books of his treatise. The opening to this work suffi- ciently exhibits the spirit in which it was conceived. Its object is stated in the title to be to show, that “the construction of the world, the magnitude and nature of the bodies contained in it, are not to be investigated by reasoning, which was done by the ancients, but are to be apprehended by the senses, and collected from the things themselves.” And the Proem is in the same strain. “They who before us have in- quired concerning the construction of this world and of the things which it contains, seem indeed to have prosecuted their examination with protracted vigils and great labour, but never to have looked at it." And thus, he observes, they found nothing but error. This be ascribes to their presumption. “For, as it were, attempting to rival God in wisdom, and ven- turing to seek for the principles and causes of the world by the light of their own reason, and thinking they had found what they had only invented, they made an arbitrary world of their own.” “We then," he adds, “not relying on ourselves, and of a duller intellect than they, propose to ourselves to turn our regards to the world itself and its parts.” The execution of the work, however, by no means corresponds to the announcement. The doctrines of Aristotle are indeed attacked; and the objections to these, and to other received opinions, form a large part of the work. But these objections are supported by à priori reasoning, and not by experiments. And thus, rejecting the Aristotelian physics, he proposes a system at least equally baseless; although, no doubt, grateful to the author from its sweeping and apparently simple character. He assumes three principles, Heat, Cold, and Matter : Heat is the principle of motion, Cold of immobility, and Matter is the corporeal substratum, in which these incorporeal and active principles produce their effects. It is easy to imagine that, by combining THEORETICAL REFORMERS OF SCIENCE. 93 . and separating these abstractions in various ways, a sort of account of many natural phenomena may be given; but it is impossible to ascribe any real value to such a system. The merit of Telesius must be con- sidered to consist in his rejection of the Aristotelian errors, in his perception of the necessity of a reform in the method of philosophizing, and in his persuasion that this reform must be founded on experiments rather than on reasoning. When he said, “We propose to ourselves to turn our eyes to the world itself, and its parts, their passions, actions, operations, and species," his view of the course to be followed was right; but bis purpose remained but ill fulfilled, by the arbitrary edifice of abstract conceptions which his system ex- hibits. Francis Bacon, who, about half a century later, treated the subject of a reform of philosophy in a far more penetrating and masterly manner, has given us his judgment of Telesius. In his view, he takes Telesius as the restorer of the Atomic philosophy, which Democritus and Parmenides taught among the ancients; and according to his custom, he presents an image of this philosophy in an adaptation of a portion of ancient mythology? The Celestial Cupid, who with Caelus, was the parent of the Gods and of the Uni- verse, is exhibited as a representation of matter and its properties, according to the Democritean philoso- phy. “Concerning Telesius,” says Bacon, “we think well, and acknowledge him as a lover of truth, a use- ful contributor to science, an amender of some tenets, the first of recent men. But we have to do with him as the restorer of the philosophy of Parmenides, to whom much reverence is due.” With regard to this philosophy, he pronounces a judgment which very truly expresses the cause of its rashness and empti- ness. “It is,” he says, “such a system as naturally 3 Proem. .4 "De Principiis atque Originibus sccundum fabulas Cupidinis et Coli: sive Parmenidis et Telesii et præcipuè Democriti Philosophia tractata in Fabula de Cupidine." 5“Talia sunt qualia possunt esse ea quæ ab intellectu sibi permisso, 94 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY, proceeds from the intellect, abandoned to its own im-.. pulse, and not rising from experience to theory con- tinuously and successively.” Accordingly, he says that, “Telesius, although learned in the Peripatetic philoso- phy (if that were anything), which indeed, he has turned against the teachers of it, is hindered by his affirmations, and is more successful in destroying than in building." The work of Telesius excited no small notice, and was placed in the Index Expurgatorius. It made many disciples, a consequence probably due to its spirit of system-making, no less than to its promise of reform, or its acuteness of argument; for till trial and reflec- tion have taught man modesty and moderation, he can never be content to receive knowledge in the small successive instalments in which nature gives it forth to him. It is the makers of large systems, arranged with an appearance of completeness and symmetry, who, principally, give rise to Schools of philosophy. 2. (Thomas Campanella).- Accordingly, Telesius may be looked upon as the founder of a School. His most distinguished successor was Thomas Campanella, who was born in 1568, at Stilo, in Calabria. He showed great talents at an early age, prosecuting his studies at Cosenza, the birth-place of the great opponent of Aristotle and reformer of philosophy. He, too, has given us an accounto of the course of thought by which he was led to become an innovator. “Being afraid that not genuine truth, but falsehood in the place of truth, was the tenant of the Peripatetic School, I ex- amined all the Greek, Latin, and Arabic commen- tators of Aristotle, and hesitated more and more, as I sought to learn whether what they have said were also to be read in the world itself, which I had been taught by learned men was the living book of God. And as my doctors could not satisfy my scruples, I resolved to read all the books of Plato, Pliny, Galen, the Stoics, nec ab experimentis continenter et gradatim sublevato, profecta viden- tur.” Thom. Campanella de Libris pro- priis, as quoted in Tenueman, ix, 291. THEORETICAL REFORMERS OF SCIENCE. 95 and the Democriteans, and especially those of Telesius; and to compare them with that first and original writing, the world; that thus from the primary auto- graph, I might learn if the copies contained anything false.” Campanella probably refers here to an ex- pression of Plato, who says, “the world is God's epistle to mankind.” And this image, of the natural world as an original manuscript, while human systems of philosophy are but copies, and may be false ones, became a favourite thought of the reformers, and ap- pears repeatedly in their writings from this time. T. When I held my public disputation at Cosenza," Campanella proceeds, “and still more, when I con- versed privately with the brethren of the monastery, I found little satisfaction in their answers; but Telesius delighted me, on account of his freedom in philoso- phizing, and because he rested upon the nature of things, and not upon the assertions of men." With these views and feelings, it is not wonderful that Campanella, at the early age of twenty-two (1590,) published a work remarkable for the bold promise of its title: “ Thomas Campanella's Philosophy demon- strated to the senses, against those who have philosophized in an arbitrary and dogmatical manner, not taking nature for their guide; in which the errors of Aristotle and his followers are refuted from their own assertions and the laws of nature; and all the imaginations feigned in the place of nature by the Peripatetics are altogether rejected ; with a true defence of Bernardin Telesius of Cosenza, the greatest of philosophers; con- firmed by the opinions of the ancients, here elucidated and defended, especially those of the Platonists." This work was written in answer to a book pub- lished against Telesius by a Neapolitan professor named Marta ; and it was the boast of the young author that he had only employed eleven months in the composi- tion of his defence, while his adversary had been engaged eleven years in preparing his attack. Campa- nella found a favourable reception in the house of the Marchese Lavelli, and there employed himself in the composition of an additional work, entitled On the 90 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. Sense of Things and Magic, and in other literary labours. These, however, are full of the indications of an enthusiastic temper, inclined to mystical devotion, and of opinions bearing the cast of pantheism. For instance, the title of the book last quoted sets forth as demonstrated in the course of the work, that “the world is the living and intelligent statue of God; and that all its parts, and particles of parts, are endowed some with a clearer, some with a more obscure sense, such as suffices for the preservation of each and of the whole." Besides these opinions, which could not fail to make him obnoxious to the religious authorities, Campa- nella? engaged in schemes of political revolution, which involved him in danger and calamity. He took part in a conspiracy, of which the object was to cast off the tyranny of Spain, and to make Calabria a republic. This design was discovered; and Campanella, along with others, was thrown into prison and subjected to torture. He was kept in confinement twenty-seven years; and at last obtained his liberation by the inter- position of Pope Urban VIII. He was, however, still in danger from the Neapolitan Inquisition; and escaped in disguise to Paris, where he received a pension from the king, and lived in intercourse with the most emi- nent men of letters. He died there in 1639. Campanella was a contemporary of Francis Bacon, whom we must consider as belonging to an epoch to which the Calabrian school of innovators was only a prelude. I shall not therefore further follow the con- nexion of writers of this order. Tobias Adami, a Saxon writer, an admirer of Campanella's works, employed himself, about 1620, in adapting them to the German public, and in recommending them strongly to German philosophers. ' Descartes, and even Bacon, may be con- sidered as successors of Campanella; for they too were theoretical reformers; but they enjoyed the advantage of the light which had, in the mean time, been thrown upon the philosophy of science, by the great practical advances of Kepler, Galileo, and others. To these ? Economisti Italiani, t. i. p. xxxii. THEORETICAL REFORMERS OF SCIENCE. 97 practical reformers we must soon turn our attention : but we may first notice one or two additional circum- stances belonging to our present subject. Campanella remarks that both the Peripatetics and long and circuitous path, which he wished to shorten by setting out from the sense. Without speaking of the methods which he proposed, we may notice one maxim' of considerable value which he propounds, and to which we have already been led. “We begin to reason from sensible objects, and definition is the end and epilogue of science. It is not the beginning of our knowing, but only of our teaching." 3. (Andrew Caesalpinus.)—The same maxim had al- ready been announced by Cæsalpinus, a contemporary of Telesius; (he was born at Arezzo in 1520, and died at Rome in 1603). Cæsalpinus is a great name in science, though professedly an Aristotelian. It has been seen in the History of Science”, that he formed the first great epoch of the science of botany by his systematic arrangement of plants, and that in this task he had no successor for nearly a century. He also approached near to the great discovery of the circulation of the blood. He takes a view of science which includes the remark that we have just quoted from Campanella: “We reach perfect knowledge by three steps: Induction, Division, Definition. By In- duction, we collect likeness and agreement from ob- servation; by Division, we collect unlikeness and dis- agreement; by Definition, we learn the proper sub- stance of each object. Induction makes universals from particulars, and offers to the mind all intelligible matter; Division discovers the difference of univer- sals, and leads to species; Definition resolves species into their principles and elements.” Without assert- ing this to be rigorously correct, it is incomparably more true and philosophical than the opposite view, 8 Tenneman, ix. 305. 10 Toid. b. xvii. c. ii. sect. 1. 9 Hist. Ind. Sc. b. xvi. c. ü. sect. 2. 11 Quæst. Peripat. i. 1. IL 98 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. which represents definition as the beginning of our knowledge; and the establishment of such a doctrine is a material step in inductive philosophy 12 4. (Giordano Bruno.)-Among the Italian innova- tors of this time we must notice the unfortunate Gior- dano Bruno, who was born at Nola about 1550, and burnt at Rome in 1600. He is, however, a reformer of a different school from Campanella; for he derives his philosophy from Ideas and not from Observation. He represents himself as the author of a new doctrine, which he terms the Nolan Philosophy. He was a zealous promulgator and defender of the Copernican system of the universe, as we have noticed in the History of Science18 Campanella also wrote in de- fence of that system. It is worthy of remark that a thought which is often quoted from Francis Bacon, occurs in Bruno's Cena di Cenere, published in 1584; I mean, the notion that the later times are more aged than the earlier. In the course of the dialogue, the Pedant, who is one of the interlocutors, says, “In antiquity is wisdom;" to which the Philosophical Character replies, “If you knew what you were talking about, you would see that your principle leads to the opposite result of that which you wish to infer;—I mean, that we are older, and have lived longer, than our predecessors." He then proceeds to apply this, by tracing the course of astronomy through the earlier astronomers up to Co- pernicus. 5. (Peter Ramus.)-I will notice one other reformer of this period, who attacked the Aristotelian system on another side, on which it was considered to be most impregnable. This was Peter Ramus, (born in Picardy in 1515,) who ventured to denounce the Logic of Aris- totle as unphilosophical and useless. After showing an extraordinary aptitude for the acquirement of know- ledge in his youth, when he proceeded to the degree of Master of Arts, he astonished his examiners by 12 Tenneman, ix. 108. 13 Hist. Ind. Sc. b. V. C. iii. sect. 2. THEORETICAL REFORMERS OF SCIENCE. 99 choosing for the subject of the requisite disputation the thesis 4, “that what Aristotle has said is all wrong.” This position, so startling in 1535, he de- fended for the whole day, without being defeated. This was, however, only a formal academical exercise, which did not necessarily imply any permanent con- viction of the opinion thus expressed. But his mind was really labouring to detect and remedy the errors which he thus proclaimed. From him, as from the other reformers of this time, we have an account of this mental struggle 15. He says, in a work on this subject, “I will candidly and simply explain how I was delivered from the darkness of Aristotle. When, according to the laws of our university, I had spent three years and a half in the Aristotelian philosophy, and was now invested with the philosophical laurel as a Master of Arts, I took an account of the time which I had consumed in this study, and considered on what subjects I should employ this logical art of Aristotle, which I had learnt with so much labour and noise, I found it made me not more versed in history or an- tiquities, more eloquent in discourse, more ready in verse, more wise in any subject. Alas for me! hov was I overpowered, how deeply did I groan, how did I deplore my lot and my nature, how did I deem myself to be by some unhappy and dismal fate and frame of mind abhorrent from the Muses, when I found that I was one who, after all my pains, could reap no benefit from that wisdom of which I heard so much, as being contained in the Logic of Aristotle.” He then relates that he was led to the study of the Dialogues of Plato, and was delighted with the kind of analysis of the subjects discussed which Socrates is there represented as executing. "Well," he adds, “I began thus to reflect within myself—(I should have thought it impious to say it to another) - What, I 1 14 Tenneman, ix. 420. “Quæcunque ab Aristotele dicta essent commenticia esse.” Freigius. Vita Petri Rami, p. 10. 15 Rami, Animadv. Aristot. i. iv. H 2 100 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. pray you, prevents me from socratizing; and from ask- ing, without regard to Aristotle's authority, whether Aristotle's Logic be true and correct? It may be that that philosopher leads us wrong; and if so, no wonder that I cannot find in his books the treasure which is not there. What if his dogmas be mere figments? Do I not tease and torment myself in vain, trying to get a harvest from a barren soil?" He convinced himself that the Aristotelian logic was worthless: and con- structed a new system of Logic, founded mainly on the Platonic process of exhausting a subject by analytical classification of its parts. Both works, his Animad- versions on Aristotle, and his Logic, appeared in 1543. The learned world was startled and shocked to find a young man, on his first entrance into life, condemning as faulty, fallacious, and useless, that part of Aris- totle's works which had always hitherto been held as a masterpiece of philosophical acuteness, and as the Organon of scientific reasoning. And in truth, it must be granted that Ramus does not appear to have understood the real nature and object of Aristotle's Logic; while his own system could not supply the place of the old one, and was not of much real value. This dissent from the established doctrines was, how- ever, not only condemned but punished. The printing and selling of his books was forbidden through France; and Ramus was stigmatized by a sentence 16 which declared him rash, arrogant, impudent, and ignorant, and prohibited from teaching logic and philosophy. He was, however, afterwards restored to the office of professor: and though much attacked, persisted in his plan of reforniing, not only Logic but Physics and Metaphysics. He made his position still more dan- gerous by adopting the reformed religion; and during the unhappy civil wars of France, he was deprived of his professorship, driven from Paris, and had his library plundered. He endeavoured, but in vain, to engage a German professor, Schegk, to undertake the 16 See Hist. Ind. Sc. b. iv. c. iv. sect. 4 THEORETICAL REFORMERS OF SCIENCE. IOI reform of the Aristotelian Physics; a portion of know- ledge in which he felt himself not to be strong. Un- happily for himself, he afterwards returned to Paris, where he perished in the massacre of St. Bartholomew in 1572. Ramus's main objection to the Aristotelian Logic is, that it is not the image of the natural process of thought; an objectiou which shows little philosophical insight; for the course by which we obtain knowledge inay well differ from the order in which our know- ledge, wlien obtained, is exhibited. We have already seen that Ramus's contemporaries, Cæsalpinus and Campanella, had a wiser view; placing definition as the last step in knowing, but the first in teaching. But the effect which Ramus produced was by uo means slight. He aided powerfully in turning the minds of men to question the authority of Aristotle on all points; and had many followers, especially among the Protestants. Among the rest, Milton, our great poet, published “Artis Logicæ plenior Institu- tio ad Petri Rami methodum concinnata;" but this work, appearing in 1672, belongs to a succeeding period. 6. (The Reformers in general). It is impossible not to be struck with the series of misfortunes which assailed the reformers of philosophy of the period we have had to review. Roger Bacon was repeatedly condemned and imprisoned; and, not to speak of others who suf- fered under the imputation of magical arts, Telesius is said ? to have been driven from Naples to his native city by calumny and envy; Cæsalpinus was accused of atheism 1º; Campanella was imprisoned for twenty- seven years and tortured; Giordano Bruno was burnt at Rome as a heretic; Ramus was persecuted during his life, and finally murdered by his personal enemy Jacques Charpentier, in a massacre of which the plea was religion. It is true, that for the most part these inisfortunes were not principally due to the attempts 17 Tenneman, ix. 230. 18 Ibid. 108, 102 • PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. at philosophical reform, but were connected rather with politics or religion. But we cannot doubt that the spirit which led men to assail the received philo- sophy, might readily incline them to reject some tenets of the established religion; since the boundary line of these subjects is difficult to draw. And as we have seen, there was in most of the persons of whom we have spoken, not only a well-founded persuasion of the defects of existing systems, but an eager spirit of change, and a sanguine anticipation of some wide and lofty philosophy, which was soon to elevate the minds and conditions of men. The most unfortunate were, for the most part, the least temperate and judicious reformers. Patricius, who, as we have seen, declared himself against the Aristotelian philosophy, lived and died at Rome in peace and honour19. . 7. (Melancthon.)—It is not easy to point out with precision the connexion between the efforts at a Reform in Philosophy, and the great Reformation of Religion in the sixteenth century. The disposition to assert (practically at least) a freedom of thinking, and to reject the corruptions which tradition had introduced and authority maintained, naturally extended its in- fluence from one subject to another; and especially in subjects so nearly connected as theology and philoso- phy. The Protestants, however, did not reject the Aristotelian system; they only reformed it, by going back to the original works of the author, and by re- ducing it to a conformity with Scripture. In this reform, Melancthon was the chief author, and wrote works on Logic, Physics, Morals, and Metaphysics, which were used among Protestants. On the subject of the origin of our knowledge, his views contained a very philosophical improvement of the Aristotelian doctrines. He recognized the importance of Ideas, as well as of Experieuce. “We could not,” he says, “proceed to reason at all, except there were by nature 19 Tenneman, ix, 246 20 Melancthon, De Anima, p. 207, quoted in Tenneman, ix. 12r. THEORETICAL REFORMERS OF SCIENCE. 103 innate in man certain fixed points, that is, principles of science;--as Number, the recognition of Order and Proportion, logical, geometrical, physical and moral Principles. Physical principles are such as these, everything which exists proceeds from a cause, -a body cannot be in two places at once,--time is a con- tinued series of things or of motions, and the like." It is not difficult to see that such Principles partake of the nature of the Fundamental Ideas which we have attempted to arrange and enumerate in a pre- vious part of this work. Before we proceed to the next chapter, which treats of the Practical Reformers of Scientific Method, let us for an instant look at the strong persuasion implied in the titles of the works of this period, that the time of a philosophical revolution was at hand. Tele- sius published De Rerum Natura juxta propria prin- cipia; Francis Helmont, Philosophia vulgaris refre- tata; Patricius, Nova de Universis Philosophic; Cam- panella, Philosophia sensibus demonstrata, adversus errores Aristotelis; Bruno professed himself the author of a Nolan Philosophy; and Ramus of a New Logic. The age announced itself pregnant; and the eyes of all who took an interest in the intellectual fortunes of the race, were looking eagerly for the expected off- spring. CHAPTER XIV. THE PRACTICAL REFORMERS OF SCIENCE. 1. Character of the Practical Reformers. We now come to a class of speculators who had perhaps a greater share in bringing about the change from sta- tionary to progressive knowledge, than those writers who so loudly announced the revolution. The mode in which the philosophers of whom we now speak produced their impressions on men's minds, was very different from the procedure of the theoretical re- .formers. What these talked of, they did; what these promised, they performed. While the theorists con- cerning knowledge proclaimed that great advances were to be made, the practical discoverers went stead- ily forwards. While one class spoke of a complete Reform of scientific Methods, the other, boasting little, and often thinking little of Method, proved the novelty of their instrument by obtaining new results. While the metaphysicians were exhorting men to consult ex- perience and the senses, the physicists were examining nature by such means with unparalleled success. And while the former, even when they did for a moment refer to facts, soon rushed back into their own region of ideas, and tried at once to seize the widest generali- zations, the latter, fastening their attention upon the phenomena, and trying to reduce them to laws, were carried forwards by steps measured and gradual, such as no conjectural view of scientific method had sug- gested; but leading to truths as profound and com- prehensive as any which conjecture had dared to anticipate. The theoretical reformers were bold, self- confident, hasty, contemptuous of antiquity, ambitious of ruling all future speculations, as they whom they PRACTICAL REFORMERS OF SCIENCE. 105 sought to depose had ruled the past. The practical reformers were cautious, modest, slow, despising no knowledge, whether borrowed from tradition or obser- vation, confident in the ultimate triumph of science, but impressed with the conviction that each single person could contribute a little only to its progress. Yet though thus working rather than speculating, - dealing with particulars more than with generals,- employed mainly in adding to knowledge, and not in defining what knowledge is, or how additions are to be made to it,—these men, thoughtful, curious, and of comprehensive minds, were constantly led to important views on the nature and methods of science. And these views, thus suggested by reflections on their own mental activity, were gradually incorporated with the more abstract doctrines of the metaphysicians, and had a most important influence in establishing an im- proved philosophy of science. The indications of such views we must now endeavour to collect from the writings of the discoverers of the times preceding the seventeenth century. Some of the earliest of these indications are to be found in those who dealt with Art rather than with Science. I have already endeavoured to show that the advance of the arts which give us a command over the powers of nature, is generally prior to the formation of exact and speculative knowledge concerning those powers. But Art, which is thus the predecessor of Science, is, among nations of acute and active intellects, usually its parent. There operates, in such a case, a speculative spirit, leading men to seek for the reasons of that which they find themselves able to do. How slowly, and with what repeated deviations men follow this leading, when under the influence of a partial and dogmatical philosophy, the late birth and slow growth of sound physical theory shows. But at the period of which we now speak, we find men, at length, proceed- ing in obedience to the impulse which thus drives them from practice to theory ;-from an acquaintance with phenomena to a free and intelligent inquiry concerning their causes. 106 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. 2. Leonardo da Vinci.--I have already noted, in the History of Science, that the Indistinctness of Ideas, which was long one main impediment to the progress of science in the middle ages, was first remedied among architects and engineers. These men, so far at least as mechanical ideas were concerned, were compelled by their employments to judge rightly of the relations and properties of the materials with which they had to deal; and would have been chastised by the failure of their works, if they had violated the laws of mechanical truth. It was not wonderful, therefore, that these laws became known to them first. We have seen, in the History, that Leonardo da Vinci, the celebrated painter, who. was also an engineer, is the first writer in whom we find the true view of the laws of equilibrium of the Jever in the most general case. This artist, a man of a lively and discursive mind, is led to make some re- marks' on the formation of our knowledge, which may show the opinions on that subject that already offered themselves at the beginning of the sixteenth century. He expresses himself as follows:-“Theory is the gene- įral, Experiments are the soldiers. The interpreter of the artifices of nature is Experience: she is never de- ceived. Our judgment sometimes is deceived, because it expects effects which Experience refuses to allow." And again, “We must consult Experience, and vary ' the circumstances till we have drawn from them gene- · lal rules; for it is she who furnishes true rules. But of what use, you ask, are these rules ; I reply, that they direct us in the researches of nature and the operations of art. They prevent our imposing upon ourselves and others by promising ourselves results which we cannot obtain. "In the study of the sciences which depend on mathe- matics, those who do not consult nature but authors, are not the children of nature, they are only her grand- 1 His works have never been pub- Essai sur les Ouvrages de Leonard do 'lished, and exist in manuscript in the Vinci. Paris, 1797. library of the Institute at Paris. Some 2 Leonardo died in 1520, at the age extracts were published by Venturi, of 78. PRACTICAL REFORMERS OF SCIENCE. 107 children. She is the true teacher of men of genius. · But see the absurdity of men ! They turn up their noses at a man who prefers to learn from nature her- self rather than from authors who are only her clerks." In another place, in reference to a particular case, he says, “Nature begins from the Reason and ends in Experience; but for all that, we must take the opposite course; begin from the Experiment and try to discover the Reason." Leonardo was born forty-six years before Telesius; yet we have here an estimate of the value of experience far more just and substantial than the Calabrian school ever reached. The expressions contained in the above extracts, are well worthy our notice;-that experience is never deceived ; that we must vary our experi- ments, and draw from them general rules ;—that na- ture is the original source of knowledge, and books only a derivative substitute; with a lively image of the sons and grandsons of nature. Some of these assertions have been deemed, and not without reason, very similar to those made by Bacon a century later. Yet it is probable that the import of such expressions, in Leonardo's mind, was less clear and definite than that which they acquired by the progress of sound phi- losophy. When he says that theory is the general and experiments the soldiers, he probably meant that theory directs men what experiments to make; and had not in his mind the notion of a theoretical Idea ordering and brigading the Facts. When he says that Experience is the interpreter of Nature, we may recol- lect, that in a more correct use of this image, Expe- rience and Nature are the writing, and the Intellect of man the interpreter. We may add, that the clear apprehension of the importance of Experience led, in this as in other cases, to an unjust depreciation of the value of what science owed to books. Leonardo would have made little progress, if he had attempted to master a complex science, astronomy for instance, by means of observation alone, without the aid of books. But in spite of such criticism, Leonardo's maxims show extraordinary, sagacity and insight; and they 108 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. appear to us the more remarkable, when we see how rare such views are for a century after his time. 3. Copernicus.—For we by no means find, even in those practical discoverers to whom, in reality, the re- volution in science, and consequently in the philosophy of science, was due, this prompt and vigorous recognition of the supreme authority of observation as a ground of belief; this bold estimate of the probable worthlessness of traditional knowledge; and this plain assertion of the reality of theory founded upon experience. Among such discoverers, Copernicus must ever hold a most distinguished place. The heliocentric theory of the universe, established by him with vast labour and deep knowledge, was, for the succeeding century, the field of discipline and exertion of all the most active speculative minds. Men, during that time, proved their freedom of thought, their hopeful spirit, and their comprehensive view, by adopting, inculcating, and following out the philosophy which this theory suggested. But in the first promulgation of the theory, in the works of Copernicus himself, we find a far more cautious and reserved temper. He does not, indeed, give up the reality of his theory, but he ex- presses himself so as to avoid shocking those who might (as some afterwards did) think it safe to speak of it as an hypothesis rather than a truth. In his preface ad- dressed to the Pope”, after speaking of the difficulties in the old and received doctrines, by which he was led to his own theory, he says, “Hence I began to think of the mobility of the earth; and although the opinion seemed absurd, yet because I knew that to others be- fore me this liberty had been conceded, of imagining any kinds of circles in order to explain the phenomena of the stars, I thought it would also be readily granted me, that I might try whether, by supposing the earth to be in motion, I might not arrive at a better expla- nation than theirs, of the revolutions of the celestial orbs.” Nor does he anywhere assert that the seeming 3 Paul III. in 1543. PRACTICAL REFORMERS OF SCIENCE. 109 absurdity had become a certain truth, or betray any feeling of triumph over the mistaken belief of his predecessors. And, as I have elsewhere shown, his disciples* indignantly and justly defended him from the charge of disrespect towards Ptolemy and other ancient astronomers. Yet Copernicus is far from com- promising the value or evidence of the great truths which he introduced to general acceptance; and from sinking in his exposition of his discoveries below the temper which had led to them. His quotation from Ptolemy, that “He who is to follow philosophy must be a freeman in mind,” is a grand and noble maxim, which it well became him to utter. 4. Fabricius.-In another of the great discoverers of this period, though employed on a very different sub- ject; we discern much of the same temper. Fabricius of Acquapendente", the tutor and forerunner of our Harvey, and one of that illustrious series of Paduan professors who were the fathers of anatomy", exhibits something of the same respect for antiquity, in the midst of his original speculations. Thus in a disser- tation? On the Action of the Joints, he quotes Aris- totle's Mechanical Problems to prove that in all ani- mal motion there must be some quiescent fulcrum; and finds merit even in Aristotle's ignorance. "Aris- totle,” he says, “did not know that motion was produced by the muscle; and after staggering about from one supposition to auother, at last is compelled by the facts themselves to recur to an innate spirit, which, he conceives, is contrasted, and which pulls and pushes. And here we cannot help admiring the genius of Aristotle, who, though ignorant of the mus- cle, invents something which produces nearly the same effect as the muscle, namely, contraction and pulling.” He then, with great acuteness, points out the dis- tinction between Aristotle's opinions, thus favourably interpreted, and those of Galen. In all this, we see 4 Hist. Ind. Sc. b. V. c. ii. 5 Born 1537, died 1619 6 Hist. Ind. Sc. B. xvii. c. ii. sect. I. ? Fabricius, De Motu Locali, p. 182. 8 p. 199. IIO PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. something of the wish to find all truths in the writings of the ancients, but nothing which materially inter- feres with freedom of inquiry. The anatomists have in all ages and countries been practically employed in seeking knowledge from observation. Facts have ever been to them a subject of careful and profitable study; while the ideas which enter into the wider truths of the science, are, as .we have seen, even still involved in obscurity, doubt, and contest. 5. Maurolycus.-Francis Maurolycus of Messana, whose mathematical works were published in 1575, was one of the great improvers of the science of optics in his time. In his Preface to his Treatise on the Spheres, he speaks of previous writers on the same subject; and observes that as they have not superseded one another, they have not rendered it unfit for any one to treat the subject afresh. “Yet," he says, “it is impossible to amend the errors of all who have preceded us. This would be a task too hard for Atlas, although he supports the heavens. Even Copernicus is tolerated, who makes the sun to be fixed, and the earth to move round it in a circle, and who is more worthy of a whip or a scourge than of a refutation.” The mathe- maticians and astronomers of that time were not the persons most sensible of the progress of physical know- ledge; for the basis of their science, and a great part of its substance, were contained in the writings of the ancients; and till the time of Kepler, Ptolemy's work was, very justly, looked upon as including all that was essential in the science. 6. Benedetti.—But the writers on Mechanics were naturally led to present themselves as innovators and experimenters; for all that the ancients had taught concerning the doctrine of motion was erroneous; while those who sought their knowledge from experi- ment, were constantly led to new truths. John Bap- tist Benedetti, a Venetian nobleman, in 1599, pub- lished his Speculationum Liber, containing, among other matter, a treatise on Mechanics, in which several of the Aristotelian errors were refuted. In the Preface to this Treatise, he says, “Many authors have written PRACTICAL REFORMERS OF SCIENCE. III much, and with great ability, on Mechanics; but since nature is constantly bringing to light something either new, or before unnoticed, I too wished to put forth a few things hitherto unattempted, or not sufficiently explained.” In the doctrine of motion he distinctly and at some length condemns and argues against all the Aristotelian doctrines concerning motion, weight, and many other fundamental principles of physics. Benedetti is also an adherent of the Copernican doc- trine. He states 9 the enormous velocity which the heavenly bodies must have, if the earth be the centre of their motions; and adds, " which difficulty does not occur according to the beautiful theory of the Samian Aristarchus, expounded in a divine manner by Nicolas Copernicus; against which the reasons alleged by Aris- totle are of no weight.” Benedetti throughout shows no want of the courage or ability which were needed in order to rise in opposition against the dogmas of the Peripatetics. He does not, however, refer to ex- periment in a very direct manner; indeed most of the facts on which the elementary truths of mechanics rest, were known and admitted by the Aristotelians; and therefore could not be adduced as novelties. On the contrary, he begins with à priori maxims, which experience would not have confirmed. “Since,” he says , "we have undertaken the task of proving that Aristotle is wrong in his opinions concerning motion, there are certain absolute truths, the objects of the intellect known of themselves, which we must lay down in the first place.” And then, as an example of these truths, he states this: “Any two bodies of equal size and figure, but of different materials, will have their natural velocities in the same proportion as their weights;" where by their natural velocities, he means the velocities with which they naturally fall down- wards. 7. Gilbert. The greatest of these practical reform- ers of science is our countryman, William Gilbert; if, 9 Speculationun Liber, p. 195. 10 Ibid. p. 169. II2 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. indeed, in virtue of the clear views of the prospects which were then opening to science, and of the methods by which her future progress was to be se- cured, while he exemplified those views by physical discoveries, he does not rather deserve the still higher praise of being at the same time a theoretical and a practical reformer. Gilbert's physical researches and speculations were employed principally upon subjects on which the ancients had known little or nothing; and on which therefore it could not be doubtful whe- ther tradition or observation was the source of know- ledge. Such was magnetism; for the ancients were barely acquainted with the attractive property of the magnet. Its polarity, including repulsion as well as attraction, its direction towards the north, its limited variation from this direction, its declination from the horizontal position, were all modern discoveries. Gil- bert's work on the magnet and on the magnetism of the earth, appeared in 1600; and in this, he repeatedly inaintains the superiority of experimental knowledge over the physical philosophy of the ancients. His preface opens thus: “Since in making discoveries and searching out the hidden causes of things, stronger reasons are obtained from trustworthy experiments and demonstrable arguments, than from probable con- jectures and the dogmas of those who philosophize in the usual manner," he has, he says, “endeavoured to proceed from common magnetical experiments to the inward constitution of the earth.” As I have stated in the History of Magnetism", Gilbert's work con tains all the fundamental facts of that science, so fully stated, that we have, at this day, little to add to them. He is not, however, by the advance which he thus made, led to depreciate the ancients, but only to claim for himself the same liberty of philosophizing which 11 Gulielmi Gilberti, Colcestricnsis, Medici Londinensis, De Magnete, Mag- neticisque Corporibus, et de Magno Magnete Tellure, Physiologia Nova, pluri- mis et Argumentis et Experimentis demonstrata. 12 Hist. Ind. Sc. b. xii. c. i. PRACTICAL REFORMERS OF SCIENCE. 113 - - - they had enjoyed 13. “To those ancient and first parents of philosophy, Aristotle, Theophrastus, Ptolemy, Hip- pocrates, Galen, be all due honour; from them it was that the stream of wisdom has been derived down to posterity. But our age has discovered and brought to light many things which they, if they were yet alive, would gladly embrace. Wherefore we also shall not hesitate to expound, by probable hypotheses, those things which by long experience we have ascertained." In this work the author not only adopts the Coper- nican doctrine of the earth's motion, but speaks of the contrary supposition as utterly absurd, founding his argument mainly on the vast velocities which such a supposition requires us to ascribe to the celestial bodies. Dr. Gilbert was physician to Queen Elizabeth and to James the First, and died in 1603. Some time after his death the executors of his brother published another work of his, De Mundo nostro Sublunari Phi- losophia Nova, in which similar views are still more comprehensively presented. In this he says, “The two lords of philosophy, Aristotle and Galen, are held in worship like gods, and rule the schools;—the for- mer by some destiny obtained a sway and influence among philosophers, like that of his pupil Alexander among the kings of the earth ;-Galen, with like suc- cess, holds his triumph among the physicians of Eu- rope.” This comparison of Aristotle to Alexander was also taken hold of by Bacon. Nor is Gilbert an unworthy precursor of Bacon in the view he gives of the History of Science, which occupies the first three chapters of his Philosophy. He traces this history from “the simplicity and ignorance of the ancients," through “the fabrication of the fable of the four ele- ments," to Aristotle and Galen. He mentions with due disapproval the host of commentators which suc- ceeded, the alchemists, the “shipwreck of science in the deluge of the Goths," and the revival of letters and genius in the time of “our grandfathers.” “This 13 Pref. 14 De Magnete, lib. vi. C. 3, 4 114 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. later age," he says, “has exploded the Barbarians, and restored the Greeks and Latins to their pristine grace and honour. It remains, that if they have written aught in error, this should be remedied by better and more productive processes (frugiferis institutis), not to be contemned for their novelty; (for nothing which is true is really new, but is perfect from eternity, though to weak man it may be unknown;) and that thus Philosophy may bear her fruit." The reader of Bacon will not fail to recognize, in these references to “fruit-bearing” knowledge, a similarity of expression with the Novun Organon. Bacon does not appear to me to have done justice to his contemporary. He nowhere recognizes in the la- bours of Gilbert a community of purpose and spirit with his own. On the other hand, he casts upon him a reflection which he by no means deserves. In the Advancement of Learning 15, he says, “ Another error is, that men have used to infect their meditations, opinions, and doctrines, with some conceits which they have most admired, or some sciences to which they have most applied; and given all things else a tinc- ture according to them, utterly untrue and improper... So have the alchemists made a philosophy out of a few experiments of the furnace; and Gilbertus, our countryman, hath made a philosophy out of the ob- servations of a loadstone,” (in the Latin, philosophiam etiam e magnete elicuit). And in the same manner he mentions him in the Novum Organon 16, as afford- ing an example of an empirical kind of philosophy, which appears to those daily conversant with the ex- periments, probable, but to other persons incredible and empty. · But instead of blaming Gilbert for dis- turbing and narrowing science by a too constant re- ference to magnetical rules, we might rather censure Bacon, for not seeing how important in all natural philosophy are those laws of attraction and repulsion of which magnetical phenomena are the most obvious 15 Nov. Org. b. i. 16 B. i. Aph. 64. PRACTICAL REFORMERS OF SCIENCE. 115 illustration. We may find ground for such a judg- ment in another passage in which Bacon speaks of Gilbert. In the Second Book of the Novum Orga- non, having classified motions, he gives, as one kind, what he calls, in his figurative language, motion for gain, or motion of need, by which a body shuns hete- rogeneous, and seeks cognate bodies. And he adds, "The Electrical operation, concerning which Gilbert and others since him have made up such a wonderful story, is nothing less than the appetite of a body, which, excited by friction, does not well tolerate the air, and prefers another tangible body if it be found near." Bacon's notion of an appetite in the body is certainly much less philosophical than Gilbert's, who speaks of light bodies as drawn towards amber by certain material radii 1'; and we might perhaps ven- ture to say that Bacon here manifests a want of clear mechanical ideas. Bacon, too, showed his inferior aptitude for physical research in rejecting the Coper- nican doctrine which Gilbert adopted. In the Ad- vancement of Learning", suggesting a history of the opinions of philosophers, he says that he would have inserted in it even recent theories, as those of Para- celsus; of Telesius, who restored the philosophy of Parmenides; or Patricius, who resublimed the fumes of Platonism; or Gilbert, who brought back the dog- mas of Philolaus. But Bacon quotes 20 with pleasure Gilbert's ridicule of the Peripatetics' definition of heat. They had said, that heat is that which sepa- rates heterogeneous and unites homogeneous matter; which, said Gilbert, is as if any one were to define man as that which sows wheat and plants vines. Galileo, another of Gilbert's distinguished contem- poraries, had a higher opinion of him. He says”, “I extremely admire and envy this author. I think him worthy of the greatest praise for the many new and true observations which he has made, to the disgrace 17 Vol. ix. 185. 18 De Magnete, p. 6o. 19 B. iii. C. 4. 20 Nov. Org. b. ii. Aph. 48. 21 Drinkwater's Life of Galileo, p. 18. I 2 116 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. of so many vain and fabling authors; who write, not from their own knowledge only, but repeat everything they hear from the foolish and vulgar, without at- tempting to satisfy themselves of the same by experi- ence; perhaps that they may not diminish the size of their books." 8. Galileo.--Galileo was content with the active and not demand that such researches should be made ex- pressly subservient to that wider and more ambitious philosophy, on which the author of the Novum Organon employed his powers. But still it now becomes our business to trace those portions of Galileo's views which have reference to the theory, as well as the practice, of scientific investigation. On this subject, Galileo did not think more profoundly, perhaps, than several of his contemporaries; but in the liveliness of expression and illustration with which he recommended his opinions on such topics, he was unrivalled. Writing in the lan- guage of the people, in the attractive form of dialogue, with clearness, grace, and wit, he did far more than any of his predecessors had done to render the new methods, results, and prospects of science familiar to a wide circle of readers, first in Italy, and soon, all over Europe. The principal points inculcated by him were already becoming familiar to men of active and inquir- ing minds; such as, that knowledge was to be sought from observation, and not from books; that it was absurd to adhere to, and debate about, the physical tenets of Aristotle and the rest of the ancients. On persons who followed this latter course, Galileo fixed the epithet of Paper Philosophers”?; because, as he wrote in a letter to Kepler, this sort of men fancied that philosophy was to be studied like the Æneid or Odyssee, and that the true reading of nature was to be detected by the collation of texts. Nothing so much shook the authority of the received system of Physics as the experimental discoveries, directly contradicting 22 Life of Galileo, p. 9. PRACTICAL REFORMERS OF SCIENCE. 117 it, which Galileo made. By experiment, as I have elsewhere stated 23, he disproved the Aristotelian doc- trine that bodies fall quickly or slowly in proportion to their weight. And when he had invented the tele- scope, a number of new discoveries of the most striking kind (the inequalities of the moon's surface, the spots in the sun, the moon-like phases of Venus, the satel- lites of Jupiter, the ring of Saturn,) showed, by the evidence of the eyes, how inadequate were the concep- tions, and how erroneous the doctrines of the ancients, respecting the constitution of the universe. How severe the blow was to the disciples of the ancient schools, we may judge by the extraordinary forms of defence in which they tried to intrench themselves. They would not look through Galileo's glasses ; they maintained that what was seen was an illusion of witchcraft; and they tried, as Galileo says”, with logical arguments, as if with magical incantations, to charm the new planets out of the sky. No one could be better fitted than Galileo for such a warfare. His great knowledge, clear intellect, gaiety, and light irony, (with the advantage of being in the right,) enabled him to play with his adversaries as he pleased. Thus when an Aristotelian 25 rejected the discovery of the irregularities in the moon's surface, because, according to the ancient doctrine, her form was a perfect sphere, and held that the apparent cavities were filled with an invisible crystal substance, Galileo replied, that he had no objection to assent to this, but that then he should require his adversary in return to believe that there were on the same sur- face invisible crystal mountains ten times as high as those visible ones which he had actually observed and measured. since become established maxims of modern philoso- phy. “Philosophy," he says, “is written in that great book, I mean the Universe, which is constantly open before our eyes; but it cannot be understood; 23 Hist. Ind. Sc. b. vi. c. i. sect. 5. 25 Ibid. p. 33. 24 Life of Galileo, p. 29. 26 Il Sagyiatore, ii. 247. 118 . PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. unless we first know the language and learn the characters in which it is written." With this thought he combines some other lively images. One of his interlocutors says concerning another, “Sarsi perhaps thinks that philosophy is a book made up of the fan- cies of men, like the Iliad or Orlando Furioso, in which the matter of least importance is, that what is written be true." And again, with regard to the system of authority, he says, “I think I'discover in him a firm belief that, in philosophizing, it is necessary to lean upon the opinion of some celebrated author; as if our mind must necessarily remain unfruitful and barren till it be married to another man's reason.”— “No," he says, “the case is not so.—When we have the decrees of Nature, authority goes for nothing; reason is absolute 27.” In the course of Galileo's controversies, questions of the logic of science came under discussion. Vincenzio di Grazia objected to a proof from induction which Galileo adduced, because all the particulars were not enumerated; to which the latter justly replies 28, that if induction were required to pass through all the cases, it would be either useless or impossible;—impossible when the cases are innumerable; useless when they have each already been verified, since then the general proposition adds nothing to our knowledge. One of the most novel of the characters which Science assumes in Galileo's hands is, that she becomes cautious. She not only proceeds leaning upon Experi- ence, but she is content to proceed a little way at a time. She already begins to perceive that she must rise to the heights of knowledge by many small and separate steps. The philosopher is desirous to know much, but resigned to be ignorant for a time of that which cannot yet be known. Thus when Galileo dis- covered the true law of the motion of a falling body 29, that the velocity increases proportionally to the time from the beginning of the fall, he did not insist upon 37 I Saggiatore, ü. 200. 28 Ibid. i. 501. 9 Hist. Inc, Sc. b. vi. c. ii. sect. 2.. . PRACTICAL REFORMERS OF SCIENCE. 119 immediately assigning the cause of this law. “The cause of the acceleration of the motions of falling bodies is not,” he says, “a necessary part of the in- vestigation." Yet the conception of this acceleration, as the result of the continued action of the force of gravity upon the falling body, could hardly fail to suggest itself to one who had formed the idea of force. In like manner, the truth that the velocities, acquired by bodies falling down planes of equal heights, are all equal, was known to Galileo and his disciples, long before he accounted for ita, by the principle, ap- parently so obvious, that the momentum generated is as the moving force which generates it. He was not tempted to rush at once, from an experimental truth to a universal system. Science had learnt that she must move step by step; and the gravity of her pace already indicated her approaching maturity and her consciousness of the long path which lay before her. But besides the genuine philosophical prudence which thus withheld Galileo from leaping hastily from one inference to another, he had perhaps a preponderating inclination towards facts; and did not feel, so much as some other persons of his time, the need of reducing them to ideas. He could bear to contemplate laws of motion without being urged by an uncontrollable desire to refer them to conceptions of force. 9. Kepler. In this respect his friend Kepler differed from him; for Kepler was restless and unsatisfied till he had reduced facts to laws, and laws to causes; and never acquiesced in ignorance, though he tested with the most rigorous scrutiny that which presented itself in the shape of knowledge to fill the void. It may be seen in the History of Astronomy 81 with what per- severance, energy, and fertility of invention, Kepler pursued his labours, (enlivened and relieved by the most curious freaks of fancy,) with a view of discover- ing the rules which regulate the motions of the planet 30 Hist. Ind. Sc. b. vi. c. ii. sect. 4. 31 I vid. b. V. c. iv. sect. I. I20 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. Mars. He represents this employment under the image of a warfare; and describes 89 his object to be “to triumph over Mars, and to prepare for him, as for one altogether vanquished, tabular prisons and equated eccentric fetters;”. and when, “the enemy, left at home a despised captive, had burst all the chains of the equations, and broken forth of the prisons of the tables;"_when "it was buzzed here and there that the victory is vain, and that the war is raging anew as violently as before;"_that is, when the rules which he had proposed did not coincide with the facts ;-he by no means desisted from his attempts, but "suddenly sent into the field a reserve of new physical reasonings on the rout and dispersion of the veterans,” that is, tried new suppositions suggested by such views as he then entertained of the celestial motions. His efforts to obtain the formal laws of the planetary motions resulted in some of the most important discoveries ever made in astronomy; and if his physical reason- ings were for the time fruitless, this arose only from the want of that discipline in mechanical ideas which the minds of mathematicians had still to undergo; for the great discoveries of Newton in the next generation showed that, in reality, the next step of the advance was in this direction. Among all Kepler's fantastical expressions, the fundamental thoughts were sound and true; namely, that it was his business, as a physical investigator, to discover a mathematical rule which governed and included all the special facts; and that the rules of the motions of the planets must conform to some conception of causation. The same characteristics,—the conviction of rule and cause, perseverance in seeking these, inventiveness in devising hypotheses, love of truth in trying and re- jecting them, and a lively Fancy playing with the Reason without interrupting her,—appear also in his work on Optics; in which he tried to discover the exact law of optical refraction 83. In this undertaking 32 De Stell. Mart. p. iv. C. 51 (1609); Drinkwater's Kepler, p. 33. 33 Published 1604. Hist. Ind. Sc. b. ix. c. ii. PRACTICAL REFORMERS OF SCIENCE. I2I he did not succeed entirely; nor does he profess to have done so. He ends his numerous attempts by saying, “Now, reader, you and I have been detained sufficiently long while I have been attempting to collect into one fagot the measures of different refractions." In this and in other expressions, we see how clearly he apprehended that colligation of fucts which is the main business of the practical discoverer. And by his peculiar endowments and habits, Kepler exhibits an essential portion of this process, which hardly appears at all in Galileo. In order to bind together facts, theory is requisite as well as observation, the cord as well as the fagots. And the true theory is often, if not always, obtained by trying several and selecting the right. Now of this portion of the discoverer's exertions, Kepler is a most conspicuous example. His fertility in devising suppositions, his undaunted indus- try in calculating the results of them, his entire honesty and. candour in resigning them if these results dis- agreed with the facts, are a very instructive spectacle; and are fortunately exhibited to us in the most lively manner in his own garrulous narratives. Galileo urged men by precept as well as example to begin their phi- losophy from observation; Kepler taught them by his practice that they must proceed from observation by means of hypotheses. The one insisted upon facts; the other dealt no less copiously with ideas. In the practical, as in the speculative portion of our history, this antithesis shows itself; although in the practical part we cannot have the two elements separated, as in the speculative we sometimes have. In the History of Science 34, I have devoted several pages to the intellectual character of Kepler, inasmuch as his habit of devising so great a multitude of hypo- theses, so fancifully expressed, had led some writers to look upon him as an inquirer who transgressed the most fixed rules of philosophical inquiry. This opi- nion has arisen, I conceive, among those who have 34 Hist. Ind. Sc. b. v. c. iv. sect. I. I22. PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. forgotten the necessity of Ideas as well as Facts for all theory; or who have overlooked the impossibility of selecting and explicating our ideas without a good deal of spontaneous play of the mind. It must, how- ever, always be recollected that Kepler's genius and fancy derived all their scientific value from his genuine and unmingled love of truth. These qualities appeared, not only in the judgment he passed upon hypotheses, but also in matters which more immediately concerned his reputation. Thus when Galileo's discovery of the telescope disproved several opinions which Kepler had published and strenuously maintained, he did not hesi- tate a moment to retract his assertions and range him- self by the side of Galileo, whom he vigorously sup- ported in his warfare against those who were incapable of thus cheerfully acknowledging the triumph of new facts over their old theories. 10. Tycho.-There remains one eminent astronomer, the friend and fellow-labourer of Kepler, whom we must not separate from him as one of the practical reformers of science. I speak of Tycho Brahe, who is, I think, not justly appreciated by the literary world in general, in consequence of his having made a retrograde step in that portion of astronomical theory which is most familiar to the popular mind. Though he adopted the Copernican view of the motion of the planets about the sun, he refused to acknowledge the annual and diurnal motion of the earth. But notwithstanding this mistake, into which he was led by his interpreta- tion of Scripture rather than of nature, Tycho must ever be one of the greatest names in astronomy. In the philosophy of science also, the influence of what he did is far from inconsiderable; and especially its value in bringing into notice these two points :—that not only are observations the beginning of science, but that the progress of science may often depend upon the observer's pursuing his task regularly and carefully for a long time, and with well devised instruments; and again, that observed facts offer a succession of laws which we discover as our observations become better, and as our theories are better adapted to the PRACTICAL REFORMERS OF SCIENCE. 123 observations. With regard to the former point, Tycho's observatory was far superior to all that had preceded it's not only in the optical, but in the mechanical arrangements; a matter of almost equal consequence. And hence it was that his observations inspired in. Kepler that confidence which led him to all his la- bours and all his discoveries. “Since," he says 36, “the divine goodness has given us in Tycho Brahe an exact. observer, from whose observations this error of eight minutes in the calculations of the Ptolemaic hypothesis is detected, let us acknowledge and make use of this gift of God: and since this error cannot be neglected, these eight minutes alone have prepared the way for an entire reform of Astronomy, and are to be the main subject of this work." With regard to Tycho's discoveries respecting the moon, it is to be recollected that besides the first in- equality of the moon's motion, (the equation of the centre, arising from the elliptical form of her orbit,) . Ptolemy had discovered a second inequality, the evec- tion, which, as we have observed in the History of this subject 87, might have naturally suggested the sus- picion that there were still other inequalities. In the middle ages, however, such suggestions, implying a constant progress in science, were little attended to; and, we have seen, that when an Arabian astrono- mer3had really discovered another inequality of the moon, it was soon forgotten, because it had no place in the established systems. Tycho not only rediscovered the lunar inequality, (the variation,) thus once before won and lost, but also two other inequalities; namely89, the change of inclination of the moon's orbit as the line of nodes moves round, and an inequality in the motion of the line of nodes. Thus, as I have else- where said, it appeared that the discovery of a rule is a step to the discovery of deviations from that rule, which require to be expressed in other rules. It 35 Hist. Inc. Sc. b. vii. c. vi. sect. I. 36 De Stell. Mart. P. II, C. 19. 37 Hist. Ind. Sc. b. ii. c. iv. sect. 6. 38 Ivid. sect. 8. 39 Montucla, i. 566. 124 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. became manifest to astronomers, and through them to all philosophers, that in the application of theory to observation, we find, not only the stated phenomena, for which the theory does account, but also residual phenomend, which are unaccounted for, and remain over and above the calculation. And it was seen fur- ther, that these residual phenomena might be, alto- gether or in part, exhausted by new theories. These were valuable lessons; and the more valuable inasmuch as men were now trying to lay down maxims and methods for the conduct of science. A revolution was not only at hand, but had really taken place, in the great body of real cultivators of science. The occasion now required that this revolution should be formally recognized ;--that the new intellectual power should be clothed with the forms of government;, that the new philosophical republic should be acknow- ledged as a sister state by the ancient dynasties of Aristotle and Plato. There was needed some great Theoretical Reformer, to speak in the name of the Experimental Philosophy; to lay before the world a declaration of its rights and a scheme of its laws. And thus our eyes are turned to Francis Bacon, and others who like him attempted this great office. We quit those august and venerable names of discoverers, whose appearance was the prelude and announcement of the new state of things then opening; and in doing so, we may apply to them the language which Bacon applies to himself 40:- Χαίρετε Κήρυκες Διός άγγελοι ήδε και ανδρών. Hail, Heralds, Messengers of Gods and Men ! 40 De Augm. lib. iv. c. 1. CHAPTER XV. FRANCIS BACON. (I.) 1. General Remarks. It is a matter of some difficulty to speak of the character and merits of this illustrious man, as regards his place in that philosophical history with which we are here engaged. If we were to content ourselves with estimating him according to the office which, as we have just seen, he claims for himself', as merely the harbinger and announcer of a sounder method of scientific inquiry than that which was re- cognized before him, the task would be comparatively easy. For we might select from his writings those passages in which he has delivered opinions and point- ed out processes, then novel and strange, but since confirmed by the experience of actual discoverers, and by the judgments of the wisest of succeeding philoso- phers; and we might pass by, without disrespect, but without notice, maxims and proposals which have not been found available for use;views so indistinct and vague, that we are even yet unable to pronounce upon their justice;—and boundless anticipations, dictated by the sanguine hopes of a noble and comprehensive in- tellect. But if we thus reduce the philosophy of Bacon to that portion which the subsequent progress of science has rigorously verified, we shall have to pass over many of those declarations which have excited most notice in his writings, and shall lose sight of many of those striking thoughts which his admirers most love to dwell upon. For he is usually spoken ; ? And in other passages : thus, “Ego enim buccinator tantum pugnam non ineo." Nov. Orj. lib. iv. C. I. 126 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. م . sof, at least in this country, as a teacher who not only commenced, but in a great measure completed, the « Philosophy of Induction. He is considered, not only as having asserted some general principles, but laid down the special rules of scientific investigation; as not only one of the Founders, but the supreme Legis- ^ lator of the modern Republic of Science; not only the Hercules who slew the monsters that obstructed the earlier traveller, but the Solon who established a con- stitution fitted for all future time. 2. Nor is it our purpose to deny that of such praise he deserves a share which, considering the pe- riod at which he lived, is truly astonishing. But it is necessary for us in this place to discriminate and select that portion of his system which, bearing upon physical science, has since been confirmed by the actual history/ of science. Many of Bacon's most impressive and cap: tivating passages contemplate the extension of the new methods of discovering truth to intellectual, to moral, to political, as well as to physical science. And how far, and how, the advantages of the inductive method may be secured for those important branches of specu- lation, it will at some future time be a highly inter- esting task to examine. But our plan requires us at present to omit the consideration of these ; for our purpose is to learn what the genuine course of the for- mation of science is, by tracing it in those portions of human knowledge, which, by the confession of all, are most exact, most certain, most complete. Hence we must here deny ourselves the dignity and interest which float about all speculations in which the great moral and political concerns of men are involved. It cannot be doubted that the cominanding position which Bacon occupies in men's estimation arises from his proclaiming a reform in philosophy of so comprehen- sive a nature;-a reform which was to infuse a new spirit into every part of knowledge. Physical Science has tranquilly and noiselessly adopted many of his suggestions; which were, indeed, her own natural im- pulses, not borrowed from him; and she is too deeply and satisfactorily absorbed in contemplating her re- FRANCIS BACON. 127 sults, to talk much about the methods of obtaining them which she has thus instinctively pursued. But the philosophy which deals with mind, with manners, with morals, with polity, is conscious still of much ob- scurity and perplexity; and would gladly borrow aid from a system in which aid is so confidently promised. The aphorisms and phrases of the Novum Organon are far more frequently quoted by metaphysical, ethical, and even theological writers, than they are by the au- thors of works on physics. 3. Again, even as regards physics, Bacon's fame rests upon something besides the novelty of the max- ims which he promulgated. That a revolution in the method of scientific research was going on, all the greatest physical investigators of the sixteenth century were fully aware, as we have shown in the last chap- ter. But their writings conveyed this conviction to the public at large somewhat slowly. Men of letters, men of the world, men of rank, did not become fa- miliar with the abstruse works in which these views were published; and above all, they did not, by such occasional glimpses as they took of the state of physi- cal science, become aware of the magnitude and conse- quences of this change. But Bacon's lofty eloquence, wide learning, comprehensive views, bold pictures of the coming state of things, were fitted to make men turn a far more general and earnest gaze upon the passing change. When a man of his acquirements, of his talents, of his rank and position, of his gravity and caution, poured forth the strongest and loftiest expres- sions and images which his mind could supply, in order to depict the “Great Instauration" which he announced;-in order to contrast the weakness, the blindness, the iguorance, the wretchedness, under which men had laboured while they followed the long beaten track, with the light, the power, the privileges, which they were to find in the paths to which he pointed;—it was impossible that readers of all classes should not have their attention arrested, their minds stirred, their hopes warmed; and should not listen with wonder and with pleasure to the strains of 128 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. prophetic eloquence in which so great a subject was presented. And when it was found that the pro- phecy was verified ; when it appeared that an immense change in the methods of scientific research really had occurred;—that vast additions to man's knowledge and power had been acquired, in modes like those which had been spoken of;--that further advances might be constantly looked for;—and that a progress, seemingly boundless, was going on in the direction in which the seer had thus pointed ;-it was natural that men should bail him as the leader of the revolution; that they should identify him with the event which he was the first to announce; that they should look upon him as the author of that which he had, as they per- ceived, so soon and so thoroughly comprehended. 4. For we must remark, that although (as we have seen) he was not the only, nor the earliest writer, who declared that the time was come for such a change, he not only proclaimed it more emphatically, but understood it, in its general character, much more exactly, than any of his contemporaries. Among the maxims, suggestions and anticipations which he threw out, there were many of which the wisdom and the novelty were alike striking to his immediate succes- sors;—there are many which even now, from time to time, we find fresh reason to admire, for their acute- ness and justice. Bacon stands far above the herd of loose and visionary speculators who, before and about his time, spoke of the establishment of new philoso- · phies. If we must select some one philosopher as the Hero of the revolution in scientific method, beyond all doubt Francis Bacon must occupy the place of honour. We shall, however, no longer dwell upon these general considerations, but shall proceed to notice some of the more peculiar and characteristic features of Bacon's philosophy; and especially those views, which, occurring for the first time in his writings, have been fully illustrated and confirmed by the subsequent pro- gress of science, and have become a portion of the per- manent philosophy of our times. (II.) 5. A New Era announced. The first great FRANCIS BACON. ' I 29 feature which strikes us in Bacon's philosophical views is that which we have already notioed ;-his confident and emphatic announcement of a New Era in the pro- gress of science, compared with which the advances of former times were poor and trifling. This was with Bacon no loose and shallow opinion, taken up on light grounds and involving only vague, general notions. He had satisfied himself of the justice of such a view by a laborious course of research and reflection. In 1605, at the age of forty-four, he published his Trea- tise of the Advancement of Learning, in which he takes a comprehensive and spirited survey of the con- dition of all branches of knowledge which had been cultivated up to that time. This work was composed with a view to that reform of the existing philosophy which Bacon always had before his eyes; and in the Latin edition of his works, forms the First Part of the Instauratio Magna. In the Second Part of the In- stauratio, the Novun Organon, published in 1620, he more explicitly and confidently states his expectations on this subject. He points out how slightly and feebly. the examination of nature had been pursued up to his , time, and with what scanty fruit. He notes the indi-1 cations of this in the very limited knowledge of the Greeks who had till then been the teachers of Europe, in the complaints of authors concerning the subtilty + and obscurity of the secrets of nature, in the dissen-1 sions of sects, in the absence of useful inventions re- ; sulting from theory, in the fixed form which the sci- . ences had retained for two thousand years. Nor, he , adds”, is this wonderful; for how little of his thought and labour has man bestowed upon science! Out of twenty-five centuries scarce six have been favourable to the progress of knowledge. And even in those favoured times, natural philosophy received the small- est share of man's attention; while the portion so given was marred by controversy and dogmatism; and even those who have bestowed a little thought upon 2 Lib. 1. Ajhor. 78 et seq. 130 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. this philosophy, have never made it their main study, but have used it as a passage or drawbridge to serve other objects. And thus, he says, the great Mother of the Sciences is thrust down with indignity to the of- fices of a handmaid; is made to minister to the labours of medicine or mathematics, or to give the first prepa- ratory tinge to the immature minds of youth. For these and similar considerations of the errors of past time, he draws hope for the future, employing the same argument which Demosthenes uses to the Athe- nians: “That which is worst in the events of the past, is the best as a ground of trust in the future. For if you had done all that became you, and still had been in this condition, your case might be desperate; but since your failure is the result of your own mis- takes, there is good hope that, correcting the error of your course, you may reach a prosperity yet unknown to you.” (III.) 6. A change of existing Method.-All Bacon's hope of improvement indeed was placed in an entire change of the Method by which science was pursued; and the boldness, and at the same time (the then existing state of science being considered), the definite- ness of his views of the change that was requisite, are truly remarkable. That all knowledge must begin with observation, is one great principle of Bacon's philosophy; but I hardly think it necessary to notice the inculcation of this maxim as one of his main services to the cause of sound knowledge, since it had, as we have seen, been fully insisted upon by others before him, and was growing rapidly into general acceptance without his aid. But if he was not the first to tell men that they must col- lect their knowledge from observation, he had no rival in his peculiar office of teaching them how science must thus be gathered from experience. It appears to me that by far the most extraordinary parts of Bacon's works are those in which, with extreme earnestness and clearness, he insists upon a graduated and successive induction, as opposed to a hasty transit froin special facts to the highest generalizations. The FRANCIS BACON. 131 nineteenth Axiom of the First Book of the Novum Organon contains a view of the nature of true science most exact and profound, and, so far as I am aware, at the time perfectly new. “There are two ways, and can only be two, of seeking and finding truth. The one, from sense and particulars, takes a flight to the most general axioms, and from those principles and their truth, settled once for all, invents and judges of inter- mediate axioms. The other method collects axioms from sense and particulars, ascending continuously and by degrees, so that in the end it arrives at the most general axioms; this latter way is the true one, but bitherto untried.” It is to be remarked, that in this passage Bacon employs the term wcioms to express any propositions collected from facts by induction, and thus fitted to become the starting-point of deductive reasonings. How far propositions so obtained may approach to the character of axioms in the more rigorous sense of the term, we have already in some measure examined; but that question does not here immediately concern us. The truly remarkable circumstance is to find this recommendation of a continuous advance from observa- tion, by limited steps, through successive gradations of generality, given at a time when speculative men in general had only just begun to perceive that they must begin their course from experience in some way or other. How exactly this description represents the general structure of the soundest and most compre- hensive physical theories, all persons who have studied the progress of science up to modern times can bear testimony; but perhaps this structure of science can- not in any other way be made so apparent as by those Tables of successive generalizations in which we have exhibited the history and constitution of some of the principal physical sciences, in the Chapter of a pre- ceding work which treats of the Logic of Induction, Aud the view which Bacon thus took of the true pro- gress of science was not only new, but, so far as I am aware, has never been adequately illustrated up to the present day. * 2 132 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. 7. It is true, as I observed in the last chapter, that Galileo had been led to see the necessity, not only of . proceeding from experience in the pursuit of know- wledge, but of proceeding cautiously and gradually; and he had exemplified this rule more than once, when, having made one step in discovery, he held back his foot, for a time, from the next step, however tempting. But Galileo had not reached this wide and command- ing view.of the successive subordination of many steps, all leading up at last to some wide and simple general truth. In catching sight of this principle, and in ascribing to it its due importance, Bacon's sagacity, so far as I am aware, wrought unassisted and unrivalled. 8. Nor is there any wavering or vagueness in Bacon's assertion of this important truth. He repeats it over and over again ; illustrates it by a great number of the most lively metaphors and emphatic expressions. Thus he speaks of the successive foors (tabulata) of -induction; and speaks of each science as a pyramid [which has observation and experience for its basis. No images can better exhibit the relation of general and particular truths, as our own Inductive Tables may serve to show. (IV.) 9. Comparison of the New and Old Method. Again; not less remarkable is his contrasting this true Method of Science (while it was almost, as he says, yet untried) with the ancient and vicious Method, 1. which began, indeed, with facts of observation, but rushed at once and with no gradations, to the most general principles. For this was the course which had been actually followed by all those speculative re- formers who had talked so loudly of the necessity of beginning our philosophy from experience. All these men, if they attempted to frame physical doctrines at | all, had caught up a few facts of observation, and had 3 Aug. Sc. Lib. iii. C. 4. P. 194. So non intermissos aut hiulcos a parti- in other places, as Nov. Org. i. Aph. culari us ascendetur ad axiomata 104. “De scientiis tum demum bene minora, et deinde ad media, alia sperandum est quando per scalam aliis superiora, et postremo demuni veram et per gradus continuos, et ad generalissima." FRANCIS BACON. 133 erected a universal theory upon the suggestions which these offered. This process of illicit generalization, or, as Bacon terms it, Anticipation of Nature (anticipatio - naturo), in opposition to the Interpretation of Nature, - he depicts with singular acuteness, in its character and causes. “These two ways," he says “both begin from sense and particulars; but their discrepancy is immense. The one merely skims over experience and particulars in a cursory transit; the other deals with them in a due and orderly manner. The one, at its very outset, frames certain general abstract principles, but useless; the other gradually rises to those principles-which have a real existence in nature." "The former path,” he adds, “that of illicit and hasty generalization, is one which the intellect follows when abandoned to its own impulse; and this it does from the requisitions of logic. For the mind has a yearning which makes it dart forth to generalities, _ that it may have something to rest in; and after a little dallying with experience, becomes weary of it; and all these evils are augmented by logic, which re- quires these generalities to make a show with in its disputations." "In a sober, patient, grave intellect," he further adds, “the mind, by its own impulse, (and more especially if it be not impelled by the sway of established opinions) attempts in some measure that other and"true way, of gradual generalization; but this it does with small profit; for the intellect, except it be regulated and aided, is a faculty of unequal operation, and altogether unapt to master the obscurity of things.” The profound and searching wisdom of these remarks appears more and more, as we apply them to the vari- ous attempts which men have made to obtain know- ledge; when they begin with the contemplation of a few facts, and pursue their speculations, as upon most subjects they have hitherto generally done; for almost all such attempts have led immediately to some process 4 Nov. Ory. I. Aph. 22. 6 Ib. Aph. 20. 134 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. of illicit generalization, which introduces an intermin- able course of controversy. In the physical sciences, however, we have the further inestimable advantage of seeing the other side of the contrast exemplified : for many of them, as our inductive Tables show us, have gone on according to the most rigorous conditions of gradual and successive generalization, and in con- sequence of this circumstance in their constitution, possess, in each part of their structure, a solid truth, which is always ready to stand the severest tests of reasoning and experiment. We see how justly and clearly Bacon judged con- cerning the mode in which facts are to be employed in the construction of science. This, indeed, has ever been deemed his great merit: insomuch that many persons appear to apprehend the main substance of his doctrine to reside in the maxim that facts of obser- vation, and such facts alone, are the essential elements of all true science. - (V.) 10. Ideas are necessary.— Yet we have en- deavoured to establish the doctrine that facts are but one of two ingredients of knowledge both equally necessary;-that Ideas are no less indispensable than facts themselves; and that except these be duly un- -folded and applied, facts are collected in vain. Has Bacon then neglected this great portion of his subject? Has he been led by some partiality of view, or some peculiarity of circumstances, to leave this curious and essential element of science in its pristine obscurity? Was he, unaware of its interest and importance? We may reply that Bacon's philosophy, in its effect upon his readers in general, does not give due weight or due attention to the ideal element of our know- pledge. He is considered as peculiarly and eminently the asserter of the value of experiment and observa- tion. He is always understood to belong to the ex- periential, as opposed to the ideal school. He is held up in contrast to Plato and others who love to dwell upon that part of knowledge which has its origin in the intellect of man. II. Nor can it be denied that Bacon has, in the -. .- FRANCIS BACON. 135 finished part of his Novum Organon, put prominently forwards the necessary dependence of all our know- ledge upon Experience, and said little of its depend- ence, equally necessary, upon the Conceptions which the intellect itself supplies. It will appear, however, on a close examination, that he was by no means in- sensible or careless of this internal element of all con- nected speculation. He held the balance, with no partial or feeble hand, between phenomena and ideas. He urged the Colligation of Facts, but he was not the less aware of the value of the Explication of Con- ceptions. 12. This appears plainly from some remarkable Aphorisms in the Novum Organon. Thus, in noticing the causes of the little progress then made by science, he states this:-“In the current Notions, all is un- sound, whether they be logical or physical. Substance, quality, action, passion, even being, are not good Con- ceptions; still less are heavy, light, dense, rare, moist, dry, generation, corruption, attraction, repulsion, ele- ment, matter, form, and others of that kind; all are fantastical and ill-defined.” And in his attempt to exemplify his own system, he hesitates’ in accepting or rejecting the notions of elementary, celestial, rare, as belonging to fire, since, as he says, they are vague and ill-defined notions (notiones vagce nec bene termi- natce). In that part of his work which appears to be completed, there is not, so far as I have noticed, any attempt to fix and define any notions thus complained of as loose and obscure. But yet such an undertaking appears to have formed part of his plan; and in the Abecedarium Naturce", which consists of the heads of various portions of his great scheme, marked by letters of the alphabet, we find the titles of a series of dis- sertations “On the Conditions of Being," which must have had for their object the elucidation of divers Notions essential to science, and which would have * 6 I AX, 15. 7 Nov. Org. lib. ii. Aph. 19. 8 Inst. Mag. par. ii. (vol. viii. p. 244). 136 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. been contributions to the Explication of Conceptions, such as we have attempted in a former part of this -- work. Thus some of the subjects of these disserta- tions are ;-Of Much and Little ;—Of Durable and Transitory ;-Of Natural and Monstrous ;-Of Natu- ral and Artificial. When the philosopher of induction came to discuss these, considered as conditions of ex- istence, he could not do otherwise than develope, limit, methodize, and define the Ideas involved in these Notions, so as to make them consistent with them- selves, and a fit basis of demonstrative reasoning. His task would have been of the same nature as ours has been, in that part of this work which treats of the Fundamental Ideas of the various classes of sciences. M 13. Thus Bacon, in his speculative philosophy, Etook firmly hold of both the handles of science; and | if he had completed his scheme, would probably have given due attention to Ideas, no less than to Facts, as Lan element of our knowledge; while in his view of the general method of ascending from facts to princi- in ples, he displayed a sagacity truly wonderful. But we cannot be surprised, that in attempting to ex- emplify the method which he recommended, he should have failed. For the method could be exemplified only by some important discovery in physical science; and great discoveries, even with the most perfect methods, do not come at command. Moreover, al- though the general structure of his scheme was cor- rect, the precise import of some of its details could hardly be understood, till the actual progress of science had made men somewhat familiar with the kind of steps which it included. - (VI.) 14. Bacon's Example.—Accordingly, Bacon's Inquisition into the Nature of Heat, which is given in the Second Book of the Novum Organon as an ex- ample of the mode of interrogating Nature, cannot be W looked upon otherwise than as a complete failure. This will be evident if we consider that, although the exact nature of heat is still an obscure and contro- verted matter, the science of Heat now consists of many important truths; and that to none of these FRANCIS BACON. 137 truths is there any approximation in Bacon's essay. From his process he arrives at this, as the “ forma or true definition” of heat ;-" that it is an expansive, restrained motion, modified in certain ways, and ex- erted in the smaller particles of the body.” But the steps by which the science of Heat really advanced were (as may be seen in the history of the subject) these ;—The discovery of a measure of heat or tem- perature (the thermometer); the establishment of the laws of conduction and radiation; of the laws of spe- cific heat, latent heat, and the like. Such steps have led to Ampère's hypothesis”, that heat consists in the vibrations of an imponderable fluid; and to Laplace's hypothesis, that temperature. consists in the internal l'adiation of such a fluid. These hypotheses cannot yet be said to be even probable; but at least they are >> so modified as to include some of the preceding laws which are firmly established; whereas Bacon's hypo- thetical motion includes no laws of phenomena, ex- plains no process, and is indeed itself an example of illicit generalization. 15. One main ground of Bacon's ill fortune in this undertaking appears to be, that he was not aware of an important maxim of inductive science, that we must first obtain the measure and ascertain the laws of phenomena, before we endeavour to discover their causes. The whole history of thermotics up to the present time has been occupied with the former step, and the task is not yet completed : it is no wonder, therefore, that Bacon failed entirely, when he so pre- maturely attempted the second. His sagacity had taught him that the progress of science must be gra- dual; but it had not led him to judge adequately how gradual it must be, nor of what different kinds of inquiries, taken in due order, it must needs consist, in order to obtain success. A.nother mistake, which could not fail to render it unlikely that Bacon should really exemplify his 9 Hist. Ind. Sa. b. X. c. 1: in Ib. Co.iv, 138 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. -.* -- - ---- precepts by any actual advance in science, was, that he did not justly appreciate the sagacity, the inventive genius, which all discovery requires. He conceived that be could supersede the necessity of such peculiar reudowments. “Our method of discovery in science," he says", "is of such a nature, that there is not much left to acuteness and strength of genius, but all de- grees of genius and iutellect are brought nearly to the -same level.” And he illustrates this by comparing his method to a pair of compasses, by means of which a person with no manual skill may draw a perfect -circle. In the same spirit he speaks of proceeding by due rejections; and appears to imagine that when we have obtained a collection of facts, if we go on suc- cessively rejecting what is false, we shall at last find that we have, left in our hands, that scientific truth · which we seek. I need not observe how far this view is removed from the real state of the case. The ne- ị cessity of a conception which must be furnished by the mind in order to bind together the facts, could hardly have escaped the eye of Bacon, if he had cultivated, more carefully the ideal side of his own philosophy. And any attempts which he could have made to con- struct such conceptions by mere rule and method, must have ended in convincing him that nothing but à peculiar inventive talent could supply that which was thus not contained in the facts, and yet was needed for the discovery. (VII.) 16. His Failure.—Since Bacon, with all his acuteness, had not divined circumstances so important in the formation of science, it is not wonderful that his attempt to reduce this process to a Technical Formu is of little value. In the first place, he says", we must prepare a natural and experimental history, good - - collected are to be arranged in Tables in some orderly way; and then we must apply a legitimate and true induction. And in his example, he first collects a 11 Nov. Org. lib. i. Aph. 6z. 12 Nov. Org. lib. ii. Aph. Io. 13 Aph. II. : FRANCIS BACON. 139 great number of cases in which heat appears under various circumstances, which he calls “a Muster of Instances before the intellect,” (comparentia instan- tiarum ad intellectum,) or a Table of the Presence of the thing sought. He then adds a Table of its Ab- sence in proximate cases, containing instances where heat does not appear; then a Table of Degrees, in which it appears with greater or less intensity. He then adds?4, that we must try to cxclude several ob- vious suppositions, which he does by reference to some of the instances he has collected; and this step he calls the Exclusive, or the Rejection of Natures. He then observes, (and justly,) that whereas truth emerges more easily from error than from confusion, we may, after this preparation, give play to the intellect, (fiat permis- sio intellectus,) and make an attempt at induction, liable afterwards to be corrected; and by this step, which he terms his First Vindemiction, or Inchoate Induction, he is led to the proposition concerning heat, which we have stated above. 17. In all the details of his example he is unfortu- nate. By proposing to himself to examine at once into the nature of heat, instead of the laws of special classes of phenomena, he makes, as we have said, a fundamental mistake; which is the less surprising since he had before him so few examples of the right course in the previous history of science. But fur- ther, his collection of instances is very loosely brought together; for he includes in his list the hot taste of aromatic plants, the caustic effects of acids, and many other facts which cannot be ascribed to heat without a studious laxity in the use of the word. And when he comes to that point where he permits his intellect its range, the conception of motion upon which it at once fastens, appears to be selected with little choice or skill, the suggestion being taken from flame 15, boiling liquids, a blown fire, and some other cases. If from such examples we could imagine heat to be motion, we 14 Aph. 15, P. 105. 15 Page 110. 140 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. ought at least to have some gradation to cases of heat where no motion is visible, as in a red-hot iron. It would seem that, after a large collection of instances had been looked at, the intellect, even in its first at- tempts, ought not to have dwelt upon such an hypo- thesis as this. 18. After these steps, Bacon speaks of several classes of instances which, singling them out of the general and indiscriminate collection of facts, he terms Instances with Prerogative: and these he points out as peculiar aids and guides to the intellect in its task. These Instances with Prerogative hare generally been much dwelt upon by those who have commented on the Novum Organon. Yet, in reality, such a classifi- cation, as has been observed by one of the ablest writers of the present day, is of little service in the task of induction. For the instances are, for the most part, classed, not according to the ideas which they in- volve, or to any obvious circumstance in the facts of which they consist, but according to the extent or manner of their influence upon the inquiry in which they are employed. Thus we have Solitary Instances, Migrating Instances, Ostensive Instances, Clandestine Instances, so termed according to the degree in which they exhibit, or seem to exhibit, the property whose nature we would examine. We have Guide-Post In- stances, (Instantice Crucis,) Instances of the Parted Road, of the Doorway, of the Lamp, according to the guidance they supply to our advance. Such a classi- fication is much of the same nature as if, having to teach the art of building, we were to describe tools with reference to the amount and place of the work which they inust do, instead of pointing out their con- struction and use :--as if we were to inform the pupil that we must have tools for lifting a stone up, tools for moving it sideways, tools for laying it square, tools for cementing it firmly. Such an enumeration of ends would convey little instruction as to the means. 16 Herschel, On the Study of Nat. Phil. Art. 192. FRANCIS BACON. 141 Moreover, many of Bacon's classes of instances are vitiated by the assumption that the “form,” that is, the general law and cause of the property which is the subject of investigation, is to be looked for directly in the instances; which, as we have seen in his inquiry concerning heat, is a fundamental error. 19. Yet his phraseology in some cases, as in the instantia crucis, serves well to mark the place which certain experiments hold in our reasonings: and many of the special examples wbich he gives are full of acuteness and sagacity. Thus he suggests swinging a pendulum in a mine, in order to determine whether the attraction of the earth arises from the attraction of its parts; and observing the tide at the same moment in different parts of the world, in order to ascertain whether the motion of the water is expansive or pro- gressive; with other ingenious proposals. These marks of genius may serve to counterbalance the unfavour- able judgment of Bacon's aptitude for physical science which we are sometimes tempted to form, in conse- quence of his false views on other points; as his rejec- tion of the Copernican system, and his undervaluing Gilbert's magnetical speculations. Most of these errors arose from a too ambitious habit of intellect, which would not be contented with any except very wide and general truths; and from an indistinctness of mechanical, and perhaps, in general, of mathematical ideas :—defects which Bacon's own philosophy was di- rected to remedy, and which, in the progress of time, it has remedied in others. (VIII.) 20. His Idols.-Having thus freely given our judgment concerning the most exact and definite portion of Bacon's precepts, it cannot be necessary for us to discuss at any length the value of those more vague and general Warnings against prejudice and par- tiality, against intellectual indolence and presumption, with which his works abound. His advice and exhor- tations of this kind are always expressed with energy and point, often clothed in the happiest forms of ima- gery; and hence it has come to pass, that such pas- sages are perhaps more familiar to the general reader 142 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. than any other part of his writings. Nor are Bacon's counsels without their importance, when we have to do with those subjects in which prejudice and par- tiality exercise their peculiar sway. Questions of poli- tics and morals, of manners, taste, or history, cannot be subjected to a scheme of rigorous induction; and though on such matters we venture to assert general principles, these are commonly obtained with some de- gree of insecurity, and depend upon special habits of thought, not upon mere logical connexion. Here, therefore, the intellect may be perverted, by mixing, with the pure reason, our gregarious affections, or our individual propensities; the false suggestions involved in language, or the imposing delusions of received theories. In these dim and complex labyrinths of human thought, the Idol of the Tribe, or of the Den, of the Forum, or of the Theatre, may occupy men's minds with delusive shapes, and may obscure or pervert their vision of truth. But in that Natural Philosophy with which we are here concerned, there is little oppor- tunity for such influences. As far as a physical theory is completed through all the steps of a just induction, there is a clear daylight diffused over it which leaves no lurking-place for prejudice. Each part can be ex- amined separately and repeatedly; and the theory is not to be deemed perfect till it will bear the scrutiny of all sound minds alike. Although, therefore, Bacon, by warning men against the idols of fallacious images above spoken of, may have guarded them from danger- ous error, his precepts have little to do with Natural Philosophy: and we cannot agree with him when he says"?, that the doctrine concerning these idols bears the same relation to the interpretation of nature as the doctrine concerning sophistical paralogisms bears to common logic. (IX.) 21. His Aim, Utility. There is one very prominent feature in Bacon's speculations which we must not omit to notice; it is a leading and constant 17 Nov. Or. lib. i. Aph. 40. FRANCIS BACON. 143 object with him to apply his knowledge to Use. The insight which he obtains into nature, he would employ in commanding nature for the service of man. He wishes to have not only principles but works. The phrase which best describes the aim of his philosophy is his own", “ Ascendendo ad axiomata, descendendo ad opera." This disposition appears in the first apho- rism of the Novuni Organon, and runs through the work. “Man, the minister and interpreter of nature, does and understands, so far as he has, in fact or in thought, observed the course of nature; and he cannot know or do more than this.” It is not necessary for us to dwell much upon this turn of mind; for the whole of our present inquiry goes upon the suppo- sition that an acquaintance with the laws of nature is worth our having for its own sake. It may be uni- versally true, that Knowledge is Power; but we have to do with it not as Power, but as Knowledge. It is the formation of Science, not of Art, with which we are here concerned. It may give a peculiar interest to the history of science, to show how it constantly tends to provide better and better for the wants and comforts of the body; but that is not the interest which engages us in our present inquiry into the na- ture and course of philosophy. The consideration of the means which promote man's material well-being often appears to be invested with a kind of dignity, by the discovery of general laws which it involves; and the satisfaction which rises in our minds at the con- templation of such cases, men sometimes ascribe, with a false ingenuity, to the love of mere bodily enjoy- ment. But it is never difficult to see that this baser and coarser element is not the real source of our ad- miration. Those who hold that it is the main business of science to construct instruments for the uses of life, appear sometimes to be willing to accept the conse- quence which follows from such a doctrine, that the first shoemaker was a philosopher worthy of the highest 18 Nov. Org. lib. i. Ax. 103. 144 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. admiration19. But those who maintain such para- doxes, often, by a happy inconsistency, make it their own aim, not to devise some improved covering for the feet, but to delight the mind with acute speculations, exhibited in all the graces of wit and fancy. It has been said žo that the key of the Baconian dotrine consists in two words, Utility and Progress. With regard to the latter point, we have already seen that the hope and prospect of a boundless progress in human knowledge had sprung up in men's minds, even in the early times of imperial Rome; and were most emphatically expressed by that very Seneca who dis- dained to reckon the worth of knowledge by its value in food and clothing. And when we say that Utility was the great business of Bacon's philosophy, we forget one-half of his characteristic phrase: "Ascendendo ad aximomata,” no less than "descendendo ad opera," was, he repeatedly declared, the scheme of his path. He constantly spoke, we are told by his secretary, of two kinds of experiments, experimenta fructifera, and ex- perimenta lucifera. Again; when we are told by modern writers that Bacon merely recommended such induction as all men instinctively practise, we ought to recollect his own earnest and incessant declarations to the contrary. The induction hitherto practised is, he says, of no use for obtaining solid science. There are two ways, “hæc via in usu est,” “altera vera, sed intentata." Men have constantly been employed in anticipation; in illicit induction. The intellect left to itself rushes on in this roadº; the conclusions so obtained are persuasive 24; far more persuasive than inductions made with due caution 25. But still this method must be rejected if we would obtain true knowledge. We shall then at length have ground of good hope for science when we 20 19 Edinb. Rev. No. cxxxii. p. 65. TO. 21 Pref. to the Nat. Hist. i. 243. 22 Nov. Org. lib. i. Aph. 19. 23 Ibid. lib. i. Aph. 20. 24 Aph. 27. 25 Ib. 28. FRANCIS BACON. 145 Je H proceed in another manner 26. We must rise, not by a leap, but by small steps, by successive advances, by a gradation of ascents, trying our facts, and clearing our notions at every interval. The scheme of true philoso- phy, according to Bacon, is not obvious and simple, but long and technical, requiring constant care and self- denial to follow it. And we have seen that, in this opinion, his judgment is confirmed by the past history and present condition of science. Again; it is by no means a just view of Bacon's character to place him in contrast to Plato. Plato's philosophy was the philosophy of Ideas; but it was not left for Bacon to set up the philosophy of Facts in opposition to that of Ideas. That had been done fully by the speculative reformers of the sixteenth century. Bacon had the merit of showing that Facts and Ideas ? must be combined; and not only so, but of divining many of the special rules and forms of this combina- tion, when as yet there were no examples of them, with a sagacity hitherto quite unparalleled. (X.) 22. His Perseverance.-— With Bacon's un- happy political life we have here nothing to do. But we cannot but notice with pleasure how faithfully, how perseveringly, how energetically he discharged his great philosophical office of a Reformer of Methods. He had conceived the purpose of making this his ob- ject at an early period. When meditating the con- tinuation of his ſovum Organon, and speaking of his reasons for trusting that his work will reach some completeness of effect, he says, “I am by two argu- ments thus persuaded. First, I think thus from the zeal and constancy of my mind, which has not waxed old in this design, nor, after so many years, grown cold and indifferent; I remember that about forty years ago. I composed a juvenile work about these things, which with great contrivance and a pompous title I called temporis partum maximum, or the most considerable 26 Aph. 104. So Aph. 105. “In constituendo axiomate forma inductionis alia quam adhuc in usu fuit excogitanda est," &c. 27 Ep. ad P. Fulgentium. Op. X. 330. 146 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. birth of time; Next, that on account of its usefulness, it may hope the Divine blessing.” In stating the grounds of hope for future progress in the sciences, he says 28 : “Some hope may, we conceive, be ministered to men by our own example: and this we say, not for the sake of boasting, but because it is useful to be said. If any despond, let them look at me, a man among all others of my age most occupied with civil affairs, nor of very sound health, (which brings a great loss of time;) also in this attempt the first explorer, following the footsteps of no man, nor communicating on these subjects with any mortal; yet, having steadily entered upon the true road and made my mind submit to things themselves, one who has, in this undertaking, made, (as we think,) some progress.” He then pro- ceeds to speak of what may be done by the combined and more prosperous labours of others, in that strain of noble hope and confidence, which rises again and again, like a chorus, at iutervals in every part of his writings. In the Advancement of Learning he had said, “I could not be true and constant to the argu- ment I handle, if I were not willing to go beyond others, but yet not more willing than to have others go beyond me again.” In the Preface to the Instau- ratio Magna, he had placed among his postulates those expressions which have more than once warmed the breast of a philosophical reformera. “Concerning our- selves we speak not; but as touching the matter which we have in hand, this we ask;—that men be of good hope, neither feign and imagine to themselves this our Reform as something of infinite dimension and beyond the grasp of mortal man, when in truth it is the end and true limit of infinite error; and is by no means unmindful of the condition of mortality and humanity, not confiding that such a thing can be carried to its perfect close in the space of a single age, but assigning it as a task to a succession of genera- tions." In a later portion of the Instauratio lie 28 Nov. Org i. Aph. 113. 29 See the motto to Kant's Kritik der Ruincu Veriunt. FRANCIS BACON. 147 says: “We bear the strongest love to the human re- public our common country; and we by no means abandon the hope that there will arise and come forth some man among posterity, who will be able to receive and digest all that is best in what we deliver; and whose care it will be to cultivate and perfect such things. Therefore, by the blessing of the Deity, to tend to this object, to open up the fountains, to dis- cover the useful, to gather guidance for the way, shall be our task; and from this we shall never, while we remain in life, desist.” (XI.) 23. His Piety.-We may add, that the spirit of piety as well as of hope which is seen in this passage, appears to have been habitual to Bacon at all periods of his life. We find in his works several drafts of por- tions of his great scheme, and several of them begin with a prayer. One of these entitled, in the edition of his works, “The Student's Prayer," appears to me to belong probably to his early youth. Another, en- titled “The Writer's Prayer," is inserted at the end of the Preface of the Instauratio, as it was finally pub- lished. I will conclude my notice of this wonderful man by inserting here these two prayers. “To God the Father, God the Word, God the Spirit, we pour forth most humble and hearty supplications ; that he, remembering the calamities of mankind, and the pilgrimage of this our life, in which we wear out days few and evil, would please to open to us new refreshments out of the fountains of his goodness for the alleviating of our miseries. This also we humbly and earnestly beg, that human things may not preju- dice such as are divine; neither that, from the unlock- ing of the gates of sense, and the kindling of a greater natural light, anything of incredulity, or intellectual night, may arise in our minds towards divine mysteries. But rather, that by our mind thoroughly cleansed and purged from fancy and vanities, and yet subject and perfectly given up to the Divine oracles, there may be given unto faith the things that are faith's." “Thou, O Father, who gavest the visible light as the first-born of thy creatures, and didst pour into L 2 148 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. man the intellectual light as the top and consumma- tion of thy workmanship, be pleased to protect and govern this work, which coming from thy goodness, returneth to thy glory. Thou, after thou hadst re- viewed the works which thy hands had made, be- heldest that everything was very good, and thou didst rest with complacency in them. But man, reflecting on the works which he had made, saw that all was vanity and vexation of spirit, and could by no means acquiesce in them. Wherefore, if we labour in thy works with the sweat of our brows, thou wilt make us partakers of thy vision and thy Sabbath. We humbly beg that this mind may be steadfastly in us; and that thou, by our hands, and also by the hands of others on whom thou shalt bestow the same spirit, wilt please to convey a largess of new alms to thy family of mankind. These things we commend to thy everlasting love, by our Jesus, thy Christ, God with us. Amen." CHAPTER XVI. ADDITIONAL REMARKS ON FRANCIS BACON. TRANCIS BACON and his works have recently T been discussed and examined by various writers in France and Germany as well as England". Not to mention smaller essays, M. Bouillet has published a valuable edition of his philosophical works; Count Joseph de Maistre wrote a severe critique of his philo- sophy, which has been published since the death of the author; M. Charles Remusat has written a lucid and discriminating Essay on the subject; and in Eng- land we have had a new edition of the works pub- lished, with a careful and thoughtful examination of the philosophy which they contain, written by one of the editors: a person especially fitted for such an ex- amination by an acute intellect, great acquaintance with philosophical literature, and a wide knowledge of modern science. Robert Leslie Ellis, the editor of whom I speak, died during the publication of the edition, and before he had done full justice to his powers; but he had already written various disserta- tions on Bacon's philosophy, which accompany the different Treatises in the new edition. Mr. Ellis has given a more precise view than any of his predecessors had done of the nature of Bacon's 1 Euvres Philosophiques de Bacon, de François Bacon, par J. B. de Vau- &c. par M. N. Bouillet, 3 Tomes. gelles. Examen de la Philosophie de Bacon Franz Baco von Verulam, von (Euvres Posthumes du Comte J. de Kuno Fischer. Maistre). The Works of Francis Bacon, col- Bacon, sa Vie, son Temps, sa Philo- lected and edited by James Spedding, suppie, par Charles de Remusat. Robert Leslie Ellis, and Douglas Histoire de la Vic et des Ouvrages Denon Heath. 150 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. induction and of his philosophy of discovery. Bacon's object was to discover the natures' or essences of things, in order that he might reproduce these natures or essences at will; he conceived that these natures were limited in number, and manifested in various combinations in the bodies which exist in the uni- verse; so that by accumulating observations of them in a multitude of cases, we may learn by induction in what they do and in what they do not consist; the In- duction which is to be used for this purpose consists in a great measure of excluding the cases which do not exhibit the nature in question; and by such exclusion, duly repeated, we have at last left in our hands the elements of which the proposed nature con- sists. And the knowledge which is thus obtained may be applied to reproduce the things so analysed. As exhibiting this view clearly we may take a passage in the Sylva Sylvarum : “Gold has these natures : great- ness of weight, closeness of parts, fixation, pliantness or softness, immunity from rust, colour or tincture of yellow. Therefore the sure way, though most about, to make gold, is to know the causes of the several na- tures before rehearsed, and the axioms concerning the same. For if a man can make a metal, that hath all these properties, let men dispute whether it be gold or no." He means that however they dispute, it is gold for all practical purposes. For such an Induction as this, Bacon claims the merit both of being certain, and of being nearly inde- pendent of the ingenuity of the inquirer. It is a method which enables all men to make exact dis- coveries, as a pair of compasses enables all men to draw an exact circle. : Now it is necessary for us, who are exploring the progress of the true philosophy of discovery, to say plainly, that this part of Bacon's speculation is erro- neous and valueless. No scientific discovery ever has been made in this way. Men have not obtained truths concerning the natural world by seeking for the na- tures of things, and by extracting them from pheno- mena by rejecting the cases in which they were not. ADDITIONAL REMARKS ON FRANCIS BACON. 151 On the contrary, they have begun by ascertaining the laws of the phenomena; and have then gone on, not by a mechanical method which levels all intellect, but by special efforts of the brightest intellects to catch hold of the ideas by which these laws of phenomena might be interpreted and expressed in more general terms. These two steps, the finding the laws of phe- nomena, and finding the conceptions by which those laws can be expressed, are really the course of dis- covery, as the history of science exhibits it to us. - Bacon, therefore, according to the view now pre- sented, was wrong both as to his object and as to his method. He was wrong in taking for his object the essences of things,—the causes of abstract properties : for these man cannot, or can very rarely discover; and all Bacon's ingenuity in enumerating and classify- ing these essences and abstract properties has led, and could lead, to no result. The vast results of modern science have been obtained, not by seeking and finding the essences of things, but by exploring the laws of phenomena and the causes of those laws. And Bacon's method, as well as his object, is vitiated? by a pervading error:—the error of supposing that to be done by method which must be done by mind;- that to be done by rule which must be done by a flight beyond rule;—that to be mainly negative which is eminently positive;—that to depend on other meni which must depend on the discoverer himself;—that to be mere prose which must have a dash of poetry ;- that to be a work of mere labour which must be also i a work of genius. · Mr. Ellis has seen very clearly and explained very candidly that this method thus recommended by Bacon has not led to discovery. “It is," he says, “ neither to the technical part of his method nor to the details of his view of the nature and progress of science, that his great fame is justly owing. His merits are of another kind. They belong to the spirit rather than to the positive precepts of his philosophy." As the reader of the last chapter will see, this amounts to much the same as the account which I 152 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. had given of the positive results of Bacon's method, and the real value of that portion of his philosophy which Tė himself valued most. But still there remain, as I have also noted, portions of Bacon's speculations which have a great and enduring value, namely, his doctrine that Science is the Interpretation of Nature, his dis- tinction of this Interpretation of Nature from the vicious and premature Anticipation of Nature which had generally prevailed till then; and the recom- mendation of a graduated and successive induction by which alone the highest and most general truths were to be reached. These are points which he urges with great clearness and with great earnestness; and these are important points in the true philosophy of dis- covery. I may add that Mr. Ellis agrees with me in noting the invention of the conception by which the laws of phenomena are interpreted as something additional to Induction, both in the common and in the Baconian sense of the word. He says (General Preface, Art. 9), p"In all cases this process scientific discovery] in- volves an element to which nothing corresponds in the Tables of Comparence and Exclusion; namely the application to the facts of a principle of arrangement, au idea, existing in the mind of the discoverer an- tecedently to the act of induction.” It may be said that this principle or idea is aimed at in the Baconian analysis. “And this is in one sense true: but it must be added, that this analysis, if it be thought right to call it so, is of the essence of the discovery which results from it. To take for granted that it has been already effected is simply a petitio principii. In most cases the mere act of induction follows as a matter of course as soon as the appropriate idea has been introduced.” And as an example he takes Kep- ler's invention of the ellipse, as the idea by which Mars's motions could be reduced to law; making the same use of this example which we have repeatedly made of it. Mr. Ellis may at first sight appear to express him- self more favourably than I have done, with regard to ADDITIONAL REMARKS ON FRANCIS BACON. 153 the value of Bacon's Inquisitio in Naturam Calidi in the Second Book of the Novum Organon. He says of one part of it : “ Bacon here anticipates not merely the essential character of the most recent theory of heat, but also the kind of evidence by which it has been established.... The merit of having perceived the true significance of the production of heat by friction belongs of right to Bacon." But notwithstanding this, Mr. Ellis's general judg- ment on this specimen of Bacon's application of his own method does not differ essentially from mine. He examines the Inquisitio at some length, and finally says: “If it were affirmed that Bacon, after having had a glimpse of the truth suggested by some obvious phenomena, had then recourse, as he himself expresses it, to certain differentiæ inanes' in order to save the phenomena, I think it would be hard to dispute the truth of the censure." Another of the Editors of this edition (Mr. Sped- ding) fixes his attention upon another of the features of the method of discovery proposed by Bacon, and is disposed to think that the proposed method has never yet had justice done it, because it has not been tried in the way and on the scale that Bacon proposes *. Bacon recommended that a great collection of facts should be at once made and accumulated, regarding every branch of human knowledge; and conceived that, when this had been done by common observers, philosophers might extract scientific truths from this mass of facts by the application of a right method. This separation of the offices of the observer and dis- coverer, Mr. Spedding thinks is shown to be possible by such practical examples as meteorological observa- tions, made by ordinary observers, and reduced to tables and laws by a central calculator; by hydrogra- phical observations made by ships provided with pro- per instructions, and reduced to general laws by the Note to Aph. xviif.. 3 Prof.. to the Parascouc, Vol. i. p. 382. 154 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. man of science in his study; by magnetical observa- tions made by many persons in every part of the world, and reduced into subservience to theory by mathema- ticians at home. And to this our reply will be, in the terms which the history of all the Sciences has taught us, that such methods of procedure as this do not belong to the Epoch of Discovery, but to the Period of verification and application of the discovery which follows. When a theory has been established in its general form, our knowledge of the distribution of its phenomena in time and space can be much promoted by ordinary ob- servers scattered over the earth, and succeeding each other in time, provided they are furnished with instru- ments and methods of observation, duly constructed on the principles of science; but such observers can- not in any degree supersede the discoverer who is first to establish the theory, and to introduce into the facts a new principle of order. When the laws of nature have been caught sight of, much may be done, even by ordinary observers, in verifying and exactly deter- mining them; but when a real discovery is to be made, Į this separation of the observer and the theorist is not I possible. In those cases, the questioning temper, the busy suggestive mind, is needed at every step, to di- rect the operating hand or the open gaze. No possible accumulation of facts about mixture and heat, collected in the way of blind trial, could have led to the doc- trines of chemistry, or crystallography, or the atomic theory, or voltaic and chemical and magnetic polarity, or physiology, or any other science. Indeed not only is an existing theory requisite to supply the observer with instruments and methods, but without theory he cannot even describe his observations. He says that he mixes an acid and an alkali; but what is an acid ? What is an alkali? How does he know them? He classifies crystals according to their forms: but till he has learnt what is distinctive in the form of a crystal, he cannot distinguish a cube from a square prism, even if he had a goniometer and could use it. And the like impossibility hangs over all the other subjects. To + ADDITIONAL REMARKS ON FRANCIS BACON. 155 report facts for scientific purposes without some aid : from theory, is not only useless, but impossibe. When Mr. Spedding says, “I could wish that men of science would apply themselves earnestly to the solution of this practical problem: What measures are to be taken in order that the greatest variety of may be carried on in concert upon a common plan and brought to a common centre:"/he is urging upon men of science to do what they have always done, so far as they have had any power, and in proportion as the state of science rendered such a procedure possible and profitable to science. In Astronomy, it has been done from the times of the Greeks and even of the Chal- deans, having been begun as soon as the heavens were reduced to law at all. In meteorology, it has been done extensively, though to little purpose, because the weather has not yet been reduced to rule. Men of sci- ence have shown how barometers, thermometers, hy- grometers, and the like, may be constructed; and these may be now read by any one as easily as a clock; but of ten thousand meteorological registers thus kept by ordinary observers, what good has come to science Again : The laws of the tides have been in a great measure determined by observations in all parts of the globe, because theory pointed out what was to be ob- served. In like manner the facts of terrestrial mag- netism were ascertained with tolerable completeness by extended observations, then, and then only, when a most recondite and profound branch of mathematics had pointed out what was to be observed, and most ingenious instruments had been devised by men of science for observing. And even with these, it re- quires an education to use the instruments. But in e many cases no education in the use of instruments de- : retical and suggestive spirit in the inquirer himself. , He must devise his own instruments and his own me- thods, if he is to make any discorery. What chemist, or inquirer about polarities, or about optical laws yet undiscovered, can make any progress by using another 156 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. man's experiments and observations? He must invent A at every step of his observation; and the observer and theorist can no more be dissevered, than the body and soul of the inquirer. That persons of moderate philosophical powers may, when duly educated, make observations which may be used by greater discoverers than themselves, is true. We have examples of such a subordination of scientific offices in astronomy, in geology, and in many other departments. But still, as I have said, a very con- siderable degree of scientific education is needed even for the subordinate labourers in science; and the more considerable in proportion as science advances further and further; since every advance implies a knowledge of what has already been done, and requires a new precision or generality in the new points of inquiry. CHAPTER XVII. FROM BACON TO NEWTON. 1. Harvey.--We have already seen that Bacon was by no means the first mover or principal author of the revolution in the method of philosophizing which took place in his time; but only the writer who pro- claimed in the most impressive and comprehensive manner, the scheme, the profit, the dignity, and the prospects of the new philosophy. Those, therefore, who after him, took up the same views are not to be considered as his successors, but as his fellow-labourers; and the line of historical succession of opinions must be pursued without special reference to any one lead- ing character, as the principal figure of the epoch. I resume this line, by noticing a contemporary and fellow-countryman of Bacon, Harvey, the discoverer of the circulation of the blood. This discovery was not published and generally accepted till near the end of Bacon's life; but the anatomist's reflections on the method of pursuing science, though strongly marked with the character of the revolution that was taking place, belong to a very different school from the Chan- cellor's. Harvey was a pupil of Fabricius of Acqua- pendente, whom we noticed among the practical re- formers of the sixteenth century. He entertained, like his master, a strong reverence for the great names which had ruled in philosophy up to that time, Aris- totle and Galen; and was disposed rather to recom- mend his own method by exhibiting it as the true . interpretation of ancient wisdom, than to boast of its novelty. It is true, that he assigns, as his reason for 158 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. publishing some of his researches ", " that by revealing the method I use in searching into things, I might propose to studious men, a new and (if I mistake not) à surer path to the attainment of knowledge;" but he soon proceeds to fortify himself with the authority of Aristotle. In doing this, however, he has the very great merit of giving a living and practical character to truths which exist in the Aristotelian works, but which had hitherto been barren and empty professions. We have seen that Aristotle had asserted the im- portance of experience as one root of knowledge ; and in this had been followed by the schoolmen of the middle ages: but this assertion came with very dif- ferent force and effect from a man, the whole of whose life had been spent in obtaining, by means of expe- rience, knowledge which no man had possessed before. In Harvey's general reflections, the necessity of both the elements of knowledge, sensations and ideas, ex- perience and reason, is fully brought into view, and rightly connected with the metaphysics of Aristotle. He puts the antithesis of these two elements with i Anatomical Exercitations con- knowledge of those less considerable cerning the Generation of Living Crea- secrets of Nature, but even a certain tures, 1653. Preface. admiration of that Supreme Essence, 2 He used similar expressions in the Creator. And though I have conversation. George Ent, who edit- ever been ready to acknowledge, that ed his Generation of Animals, visited many things have been discovered him, “at that time residing not far by learned men of former times; yet from the city; and found him very do I still believe that the number of intent upon the perscrutation of those which remain yet concealed in nature's works, and with a counte- the darkness of impervestigable Na- nance as cheerful, as mind imper- ture is much greater. Nay, I cannot turbed; Democritus - like, chiefly forbear to wonder, and sometimes searching into the cause of natural smile at those, who persuade them- things.” In the course of conversa- selves, that all things were so con- tion the writer said, "It hath always summately and absolutely delivered been your choice about the secrets of by Aristotle, Galen, or some other Nature, to consult Nature herself.” great name, as that nothing was left “ 'Tis true," replied he; "and I have to the superaddition of any that suc- constantly been of opinion that from ceeded.” thence we might acquire not only the FROM BACON TO NEWTON. 159 great clearness. “Universals are chiefly known to us, for science is begot by reasoning from universals to particulars; yet that very comprehension of universals in the understanding springs from the perception of singulars in our sense.” Again, he quotes Aristotle's . apparently opposite assertions:—that made in his Phy- sics, “that we must advance from things which are first known to us, though confusedly, to things more distinctly intelligible in themselves; from the whole to the part; from the universal to the particular;" and that made in the Analytics*; that “ Singulars are more known to us and do first exist according to sense: for nothing is in the understanding which was not before in the sense." Both, he says, are true, though at first they seem to clash: for “though in knowledge we begin with sense, sensation itself is a universal thing." This he further illustrates; and quotes Seneca, who says, that “Art itself is nothing but the reason of the work, implanted in the Artist's mind:” and adds, “the same way by which we gain an Art, by the very same way we attain any kind of science or knowledge whatever; for as Art is a habit whose object is something to be done, so Science is a habit whose object is something to be known; and as the former proceedeth from the imitation of examples, so this latter, from the knowledge of things natural. The source of both is from sense and experience; since [but?) it is impossible that Art should be rightly pur- chased by the one or Science by the other without a direction from ideas." Without here dwelling on the relation of Art and Science, (very justly stated by Harvey, except that ideas exist in a very different form in the mind of the Artist and the Scientist) it will be seen that this doctrine, of science springing from experience with a direction from ideas, is exactly that the subject. From this view, Harvey proceeds to inferv the importance of a reference to sense in his own 3 Lib. i. c. 2, 3. 4 Ancil. Post. ii. 160 PHILOSOFHY OF DISCOVERY. subject, not only for first discovering, but for receiving knowledge: “Without experience, not other men's but our own, no man is a proper disciple of any part of natural knowledge; without experimental skill in ana- tomy, he will no better apprehend what I shall deliver concerning generation, than a man born blind can judge of the nature and difference of colours, or one born deaf, of sounds.” “If we do otherwise, we may get a humid and floating opinion, but never a solid and infallible knowledge: as is happenable to those who see foreign countries only in maps, and the bowels of men falsely described in anatomical tables. And hence it comes about, that in this rank age, we have many sophisters and bookwrights, but few wise men and philosophers.” He had before declared "how unsafe and degenerate a thing it is, to be tutored by other men's commentaries, without making trial of the things themselves; especially since Nature's book is so open and legible.” We are here reminded of Gali- leo's condemnation of the "paper philosophers.” The train of thought thus expressed by the practical dis- coverers, spread rapidly with the spread of the new knowledge that had suggested it, and soon became general and unquestioned." 2. Descartes.--Such opinions are now among the most familiar and popular of those which are current among writers and speakers; but we should err much if we were to imagine that after they were once pro- pounded they were never resisted or contradicted. In- deed, even in our own time, not only are such maxims very often practically neglected or forgotten, but the opposite opinions, and views of science quite in- consistent with those we have been explaining, are often promulgated and widely accepted. The philoso- phy of pure ideas has its commonplaces, as well as the philosophy of experience. And at the time of which we speak, the former philosophy, no less than the latter, had its great asserter and expounder; a man in his own time more admired than Bacon, regarded with more deference by a large body of disciples all Lover Europe, and more powerful in stirring up men's FROM BACON TO NEWTON. 161 minds to a new activity of inquiry. I speak of Des- cartes, whose labours, considered as a philosophical system, were an endeavour to revive the method of obtaining knowledge by reasoning from our own ideas only, and to erect it in opposition to the method of observation and experiment. The Cartesian philoso- phy contained an attempt at a counter-revolution. Thus in this author's Principia Philosophice", he says that “he will give a short account of the principal phenomena of the world, not that he may use them as reasons to prove anything; for," adds he, “we desire to deduce effects from causes, not causes from effects; but only in order that out of the innumerable effects which we learn to be capable of resulting from the same causes, we may determine our mind to consider some rather than others.” He had before said, “The principles which we have obtained [by pure à priori reasoning] are so vast and so fruitful, that many more consequences follow from them than we see contained in this visible world, and even many more than our mind can ever take a full survey of.” And he pro- fesses to apply this method in detail. Thus in at- tempting to state the three fundamental laws of mo- tion; he employs only à priori reasonings, and is in fact led into error in the third law which he thus ob- tains. And in his Dioptrics? he pretends to deduce the laws of reflection and refraction of light from cer- tain comparisons (which are, in truth, arbitrary,) in which the radiation of light is represented by the mo- tion of a ball impinging upon the reflecting or refract- ing body. It might be represented as a curious in- stance of the caprice of fortune, which appears in sci- entific as in other history, that Kepler, professing to derive all his knowledge from experience, and exert- ing himself with the greatest energy and perseverance, failed in detecting the law of refraction; while Des- cartes, who professed to be able to despise experiment, obtained the true law of sines. But as we have stated 5 Pars iii. p. 45. See Hist. Ind. Sc. b. vi. c. ii. ? Cap. i. ii. 162. PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. in the History, Descartes appears to have learnt this law from Snell's papers. And whether this be so or not, it is certain that notwithstanding the profession of independence which his philosophy made, it was in reality constantly guided and instructed by experience. Thus in explaining the Rainbow (in which his portion of the discovery merits great praise) he speaks' of taking a globe of glass, allowing the sun to shine on one side of it, and noting the colours produced by rays after two refractions and one reflection. And in many other instances, indeed in all that relates to physics, the reasonings and explanations of Descartes and his followers were, consciously or unconsciously, directed by the known facts, which they had observed them- selves or learnt from others. But since Descartes thus, speculatively at least, set himself in opposition to the great reform of scientific method which was going on in his time, how, it may be asked, did he acquire so strong an influence over the most active minds of his time? How is it that he became the founder of a large and distinguished school of philosophers? How is it that he not only was mainly instrumental in deposing Aristotle from his in- tellectual throne, but for a time appeared to have esta- blished himself with almost equal powers, and to have rendered the Cartesian school as firm a body as the Peripatetic had been? The causes to be assigned for this remarkable result are, I conceive, the following. In the first place, the physicists of the Cartesian school did, as I have just stated, found their philosophy upon experiment, and did not practically, or indeed, most of them, theo- retically, assent to their master's boast of showing what the phenomena must be, instead of looking to see what they are. And as Descartes had really incorpo- rated in his philosophy all the chief physical disco- veries of his own and preceding times, and had de- livered, in a more general and systematic shape than 8 Hist. Ind. Sc. b. ix. c. ü. 9 Meteorum, c. viil. p. 187. FROM BACON TO NEWTON. 163 any one before him, the principles which he thus esta- blished, the physical philosophy of his school was in reality far the best then current; and was an immense improvement upon the Aristotelian doctrines, which had not yet been displaced as a system. Another cir- cumstance which gained him much favour, was the bold and ostentatious manner in which he professed to begin his philosophy by liberating himself from all preconceived prejudice. The first sentence of his phi- losophy contains this celebrated declaration : “Since," he says, “we begin life as infants, and have contracted various judgments concerning sensible things before we possess the entire use of our reason, we are turned aside from the knowledge of truth by many prejudices : from which it does not appear that we can be any otherwise delivered, than if once in our life we make it our business to doubt of everything in which we discern the smallest suspicion of uncertainty.” In the face of this sweeping rejection or unhesitating scrutiny of all preconceived opinions, the power of the ancient authorities and masters in philosophy must obviously shrink away; and thus Descartes came to be con- sidered as the great hero of the overthrow of the Aris- totelian dogmatism. But in addition to these causes, and perhaps more powerful than all in procuring the assent of men to his doctrines, came the deductive and systematic character of his philosophy. For although all knowledge of the external world is in reality only to be obtained from observation, by inductive steps, minute, perhaps, and slow, and many, as Galileo and Bacon had already taught; the human mind conforms to these conditions reluctantly and unsteadily, and is ever ready to rush to general principles, and then to employ itself in deducing conclusions from these by synthetical reasonings; a task grateful, from the dis- tinctness and certainty of the result, and the accom- : panying feeling of our own sufficiency. Hence men readily overlooked the precarious character of Des- cartes' fundamental assumptions, in their admiration of the skill with which a varied and complex Universe was evolved out of them. And the complete and M 2 164 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. systematic character of this philosophy attracted men no less than its logical connexion. I may quote here what a philosopher10 of our own time has said of another writer: “He owed his influence to various causes; at the head of which may be placed that genius for sys- tem which, though it cramps the growth of know- ledge, perhaps finally atones for that mischief by the zeal and activity which it rouses among followers and opponents, who discover truth by accident when in pursuit of weapons for their warfare. A system which attempts a task so hard as that of subjecting vast pro- vinces of human knowledge to one or two principles, if it presents some striking instances of conformity to superficial appearances, is sure to delight the framer ; and for a time to subdue and captivate the student too entirely for sober reflection and rigorous examination. In the first instance consistency passes for truth. When principles in some instances have proved sufficient to give an unexpected explanation of facts, the delighted reader is content to accept as true all other deductions from the principles. Specious premises being assumed to be true, nothing more can be required than logical inference. Mathematical forms pass current as the equivalent of mathematical certainty. The unwary admirer is satisfied with the completeness and sym- metry of the plan of his house, unmindful of the need of examining the firmness of the foundation and the soundness of the materials. The system-maker, like the conqueror, long dazzles and overawes the world; but when their sway is past, the vulgar herd, unable to measure their astonishing faculties, take revenge by trampling on fallen greatness." Bacon showed his wisdom in his reflections on this subject, when he said that “Method, carrying a show of total and perfect knowledge, bath a tendency to generate ac- quiescence.” The main value of Descartes' physical doctrines consisted in their being arrived at in a way incon- 10 Mackintosh, Dissertation on Ethical Science. FROM BACON TO NEWTON. 165 sistent with his own professed method, namely, by a reference to observation. But though he did in reality begin from facts, his system was nevertheless a glaring example of that error which Bacon had called Anti- cipation; that illicit generalization which leaps at once from special facts to principles of the widest and remotest kind; such, for instance, as the Cartesian doctrine, that the world is an absolute plenum, every part being full of matter of some kind, and that all natural effects depend on the laws of motion. Against this fault, to which the human mind is so prone, Bacon had lifted his warning voice in vain, so far as the Cartesians were concerned; as indeed, to this day, one theorist after another pursues his course, and turns a deaf ear to the Verulamian injunctions; perhaps even complacently boasts that he founds his theory upon observation; and forgets that there are, as the aphorism of the Novuni Organon declares, two ways by which this may be done ;-the one hitherto in use and suggested by our common tendencies, but barren and worthless; the other almost untried, to be pursued only with effort and self-denial, but alone capable of producing true knowledge. 3. Gassendi. --Thus the lessons which Bacon taught were far from being generally accepted and applied at first. The amount of the influence of these two men, Bacon and Descartes, upon their age, has often been a subject of discussion. The fortunes of the. Cartesian school have been in some measure traced in the History of Science. But I may mention the notice taken of these two philosophers by Gassendi, a contemporary and countryman of Descartes. Gas- sendi, as I have elsewhere stated”, was associated with Descartes in public opinion, as an opponent of the Aristotelian dogmatism; but was not in fact a follower or profound admirer of that writer. In a Treatise on Logic, Gassendi gives an account of the Logic of various sects and authors; treating, in order, of the 11 Hist. Ind. Sc. b. vii. c. i. 166 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. Logic of Zeno (the Eleatic), of Euclid (the Megarean), of Plato, of Aristotle, of the Stoics, of Epicurus, of Lullius, of Ramus; and to these he adds the Logic of Verulam, and the Logic of Cartesius. “We must not," he says, “on account of the celebrity it has obtained, pass over the Organon or Logic of Francis Bacon Lord Verulam, High Chancellor of England, whose noble purpose in our time it has been, to make an Instauration of the Sciences.” He then gives a brief account of the Novun Organon, noticing the prin- cipal features in its rules, and especially the distinction between the vulgar induction which leaps at once from particular experiments to the more general axioms, and the chastised and gradual induction, which the author of the Organon recommends. In his account of the Cartesian Logic, he justly observes, that “He too imitated Verulam in this, that being about to build up a new philosophy from the foundation, he wished in the first place to lay aside all prejudice : and having then found some solid principle, to make that the ground-work of his whole structure. But he pro- ceeds by a very different path from that which Veru- lam follows; for while Verulam seeks aid from things, to perfect the cogitation of the intellect, Cartesius con- ceives, that when we have laid aside all knowledge of things, there is, in our thoughts alone, such a resource, that the intellect may by its own power arrive at a per- fect knowledge of all, even the most abstruse things.” The writings of Descartes have been most admired, and his method most commended, by those authors who have employed themselves upon metaphysical ra- ther than physical subjects of inquiry. Perhaps we might say that, in reference to such subjects, this method is not so vicious as at first, when contrasted with the Baconian induction, it seems to be: for it might be urged that the thoughts from which Descartes begins his reasonings are, in reality, experiments of the kind which the subject requires us to consider : each such thought is a fact in the intellectual world; and of such facts, the metaphysician seeks to discover the laws. I shall not here examine the validity of this * FROM BACON TO NEWTON. 167 plea; but shall turn to the consideration of the actual progress of physical science, and its effect on men's minds. 4. Actual progress in Science.—The practical dis- coverers were indeed very active and very successful during the seventeenth century, which opened with Bacon's survey and exhortations. The laws of nature, of which men had begun to obtain a glimpse in the preceding century, were investigated with zeal and sagacity, and the consequence was that the foundations of most of the modern physical sciences were laid. That mode of research by experiment and observation, which had, a little time ago, been a strange, and to many, an unwelcome innovation, was now become the habitual course of philosophers. The revolution from the philosophy of tradition to the philosophy of ex- perience was completed. The great discoveries of Kep- ler belonged to the preceding century. They are not, I believe, noticed, either by Bacon or by Descartes; but they gave a strong impulse to astronomical and mechanical speculators, by showing the necessity of a sound science of motion. Such a science Galileo had already begun to construct. At the time of which I speak, his disciples 12 were still labouring at this task, and at other problems which rapidly suggested them- selves. They had already convinced themselves that air had weight; in 1643 Torricelli proved this practi- cally by the invention of the Barometer; in 1647 Pas- cal proved it still further by sending the Barometer to the top of a mountain. Pascal and Boyle brought into clear view the fundamental laws of fluid equilibrium; Boyle and Mariotte determined the law of the com- pression of air as regulated by its elasticity. Otto Guericke invented the air-pump, and by his “Madge- burg Experiments” on a vacuum, illustrated still fur- ther the effects of the air. Guericke pursued what Gilbert had begun, the observation of electrical pheno- 12 Castelli, Torricelli, Viviani, Baliani, Gassendi, Mersenne, Borelli, Ca- valleri. 168 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. mena; and these two physicists made an important step, by detecting repulsion as well as attraction in these phenomena. Gilbert had already laid the founda- tions of the science of Magnetism. The law of refrac- tion, at which Kepler had laboured in vain, was, as we have seen, discovered by Snell (about 1621), and some of the more important parts of the theory of Harmonics. In sciences of a different kind, the same movement was visible. Chemical doctrines tended to assume a proper degree of generality, when Sylvius in 1679 taught the opposition of acid and alkali, and Stahl, soon after, the phlogistic theory of combustion. Steno had remarked the most important law of crystal- lography in 1669, that the angles of the same kind of crystals are always equal. In the sciences of classifi- cation, about 1680, Ray and Morison in England resumed the attempt to form a systematic botany, which had been interrupted for a hundred years, from the time of the memorable essay of Cæsalpinus. The Harvey about 1619, was followed in 1651 by Pecquet's discovery of the course of the chyle. There could now no longer be any question whether science was pro- gressive, or whether observation could lead to new truths. - Among these cultivators of science, such sentiments as have been already quoted became very familiar; that knowledge is to be sought from nature herself by observation and experiment;—that in such matters and that mere reasonings without facts cannot lead to solid knowledge. But I do not know that we find in these writers any more special rules of induction and scientific research which have since been confirmed. and universally adopted. Perhaps too, as was natural in so great a revolution, the writers of this time, espe- cially the second-rate ones, were somewhat too prone to disparage the labours and talents of Aristotle and the ancients in general, and to overlook the ideal element of our knowledge, in their zealous study of FROM BACON TO NEWTON. 169 phenomena. They urged, sometimes in an exagge- rated manner, the superiority of modern times in all that regards science, and the supreme and sole im- portance of facts in scientific investigations. There prevailed among them also a lofty and dignified tone of speaking of the condition and prospects of science, such as we are accustomed to admire in the Verula- mian writings; for this, in a less degree, is epidemic among those who a little after his time speak of the new philosophy. 5. Otto Guericke, &c.—I need not illustrate these characteristics at any great length. I may as an ex- ample notice Otto Guericke's Preface to his Experi- menta Magdeburgica (1670). He quotes a passage from Kircher's Treatise on the Magnetic Art, in which the author says, “Hence it appears how all philosophy, except it be supported by experiments, is empty, fal- lacious, and useless; what monstrosities philosophers, in other respects of the highest and subtlest genius, may produce in philosophy by neglecting experiment. Thus Experience alone is the Dissolver of Doubts, the Reconciler of Difficulties, the sole Mistress of Truth, who holds a torch before us in obscurity, unties our knots, teaches us the true causes of things." Guericke himself reiterates the same remark, adding that "phi- losophers, insisting upon their own thoughts and argu- ments merely, cannot come to any sound conclusion respecting the natural constitution of the world.” Nor were the Cartesians slow in taking up the same train of reflection. Thus Gilbert Clark who, in 1660, pub- lished 13 a defence of Descartes' doctrine of a plenum in the universe, speaks in a tone which reminds us of Bacon, and indeed was very probably caught from him: “Natural philosophy formerly consisted entirely of loose and most doubtful controversies, carried on in high-sounding words, fit rather to delude than to in- struct men. But at last (by the favour of the Deity) 18 De Plenitudine Mundi, in qua defenditur Cartesiana Philosophia contra sententias Francisci Baconi, Th. Hobbii et Sethi Wardı. 170 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. there shone forth some more divine intellects, who taking as their counsellors reason and experience to- gether, exhibited a new method of philosophizing. Hence has been conceived a strong hope that philoso- phers may embrace, not a shadow or empty image of Truth, but Truth herself: and that Physiology (Physics) scattering these controversies to the winds, will con- tract an alliance with Mathematics. Yet this is hardly the work of one age; still less of one man. Yet let not the mind despond, or doubt not that, one party of investigators after another following the same method of philosophizing, at last, under good auguries, the .mysteries of nature being daily unlocked as far as human feebleness will allow, Truth may at last appear in full, and these nuptial torches may be lighted.”. As another instance of the same kind, I may quote the preface to the First volume of the Transactions of the Academy of Sciences at Paris: “It is only since the present century,” says the writer, “that we can reckon the revival of Mathematics and Physics. M. Descartes and other great men have laboured at this work with so much success, that in this depart- ment of literature, the whole face of things has been changed. Men have quitted a sterile system of physics, which for several generations had been always at the same point; the reign of words and terms is passed; men will have things; they establish principles which they understand, they follow those principles; and thus they make progress. Authority has ceased to have more weight than Reason: that which was re- ceived without contradiction because it had been long received, is now examined, and often rejected: and philosophers have made it their business to consult, respecting natural things, Nature herself rather than the Ancients." These had now become the common- places of those who spoke concerning the course and method of the Sciences. 6. Hooke.--In England, as might be expected, the influence of Francis Bacon was more directly visible. We find many writers, about this time, repeating the truths which Bacon had proclaimed, and in almost · FROM BACON TO NEWTON. 171 every case showing the same imperfections in their views which we have noticed in him. We may take as an example of this Hooke's Essay, entitled “A General Scheme or Idea of the present state of Natural Philosophy, and how its defects may be remedied by a Methodical proceeding in the making Experiments and collecting Observations; whereby to compile a Natural History as a solid basis for the superstructure of true Philosophy.” This Essay may be looked upon as an attempt to adapt the Novum Organon to the age which succeeded its publication. We have in this imitation, as in the original, an enumeration of vari- ous mistakes and impediments which had in preceding times prevented the progress of knowledge; exhorta- tions to experiment and observation as the only solid basis of Science; very ingenious suggestions of trains of inquiry, and modes of pursuing them; and a promise of obtaining scientific truths when facts have been duly accumulated. This last part of his scheme the author calls a Philosophical Algebra, and he appears to have imagined that it might answer the purpose of finding unknown causes from known facts, by means of certain regular processes, in the same manner as Common Algebra finds unknown from known quanti- ties. But this part of the plan appears to have re- mained unexecuted. The suggestion of such a method was a result of the Baconian notion that invention in a discoverer might be dispensed with. We find Hooke adopting the phrases in which this notion is implied: thus he speaks of the understanding as "being very prone to run into the affirmative way of judging, and wanting patience to follow and prosecute the nega- tive way of inquiry, by rejection of disagreeing natures." And he follows Bacon also in the error of attempting at once to obtain from the facts the discovery of a “nature," instead of investigating first the measures and the laws of phenomena. I return to more general notices of the course of men's thoughts on this subject. 7. Royal Society. Those who associated them- selves together for the prosecution of science quoted Bacon as their leader, and exulted in the progress 172 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. made by the philosophy which proceeded upon his principles. Thus in Oldenburg's Dedication of the Transactions of the Royal Society of London for 1670, to Robert Boyle, he says; “I am informed by such as well remember the best and worst days of the famous Lord Bacon, that though he wrote his Ad- vancement of Learning and his Instauratio Magna in the time of his greatest power, yet his greatest re- putation rebounded first from the most intelligent foreigners in many parts of Christendom :” and after speaking of his practical talents and his public em- ployments, he adds, “much more justly still may we wonder how, without any great skill in Chemistry, without much pretence to the Mathematics or Me- chanics, without optic aids or other engines of late invention, he should so much transcend the philoso- phers then living, in judicious and clear instructions, in so many useful observations and discoveries, I think I may say beyond the records of many ages.” And in the end of the Preface to the same volume, he speaks with great exultation of the advance of science all over Europe, referring undoubtedly to facts then familiar. “And now let envy snarl, it cannot stop the wheels of active philosophy, in no part of the known world;—not in France, either in Paris or in Caen :—not in Italy, either in Rome, Naples, Milan, Florence, Venice, Bononia or Padua;—in none of the Universities either on this or on that side of the seas, Madrid and Lisbon, all the best spirits in Spain and Portugal, and the spacious and remote dominions to them belonging ;—the Imperial Court and the Princes of Germany; the Northern Kings and their best lumi- naries; and even the frozen Muscovite and Russian have all taken the operative ferment: and it works high and prevails every way, to the encouragement of all sincere lovers of knowledge and virtue." Again, in the Preface for 1672, he pursues the same thought into detail : “We must grant that in the last age, when operative philosophy began to re- cover ground, and to tread on the heels of triumphant Philology; emergent adventures and great successes FROM BACON TO NEWTON211 173 . were encountered by dangerous oppositions and strong obstructions. Galilæus and others in Italy suffered extremities for their celestial discoveries; and here in England Sir Walter Raleigh, when he was in his greatest lustre, was notoriously slandered to have erected a school of atheism, because he gave counte- nance to chemistry, to practical arts, and to curious mechanical operations, and designed to form the best of them into a college. And Queen Elizabeth's Gilbert was a long time esteemed extravagant for his magnet- isms; and Harvey for his diligent researches in pur- suance of the circulation of the blood. But when our renowned Lord Bacon had demonstrated the methods for a perfect restoration of all parts of real knowledge; and the generous and philosophical Peireskius had, soon after, agitated in all parts to redeem the most instructive antiquities, and to excite experimental essays and fresh discoveries; the success became on a sudden stupendous; and effective philosophy began to sparkle, and even to flow into beams of shining light all over the world.” The formation of the Royal Society of London and of the Academy of Sciences of Paris, from which pro- ceeded the declamations just quoted, were among many indications, belonging to this period, of the importance which states as well as individuals had by this time begun to attach to the cultivation of science. The English Society was established almost immediately when the restoration of the monarchy appeared to give a promise of tranquillity to the nation (in 1660), and the French Academy very soon afterwards in 1666). These measures were very soon followed by the establishment of the Observatories of Paris and Greenwich (in 1667 and 1675); which may be con- sidered to be a kind of public recognition of the astro- nomy of observation, as an object on which it was the advantage and the duty of nations to bestow their wealth. 8. Bacon's New Atalantis. — When philosophers had their attention turned to the boundless prospect of increase to the knowledge and powers and pleasures of 174 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. man which the cultivation of experimental philosophy seemed to promise, it was natural that they should think of devising institutions and associations by which such benefits might be secured. Bacon had drawn a picture of a society organized with a view to such pur- pose, in his fiction of the “New Atalantis.” The imaginary teacher who explains this institution to the inquiring traveller, describes it by the name of Solo- mon's House; and says 14, “The end of our founda- tion is the knowledge of causes and secret motions of things; and the enlarging the bounds of the human empire to effecting of things possible.” And, as parts of this House, he describes caves and wells, chambers and towers, baths and gardens, parks and pools, dis- pensatories and furnaces, and many other contrivances, provided for the purpose of making experiments of many kinds. He describes also the various employ- ments of the Fellows of this College, who take a share in its researches. There are merchants of light, who bring books and inventions from foreign countries ; depredators, who gather the experiments which exist in books; mystery-men, who collect the experiments of the mechanical arts; pioneers or miners, who invent new experiments; and compilers, “who draw the ex- periments of the former into titles and tables, to give the better light for the drawing of observations and axioms out of them.” There are also dowry-men or benefactors, that cast about how to draw out of the experiments of their fellows things of use and prac- tice for man's life; lamps, that direct new experiments of a more penetrating light than the former; in- oculators, that execute the experiments so directed. Finally, there are the interpreters of nature, that raise the former discoveries by experiments into greater ob- servations (that is, more general truths), axioms and aphorisms. Upon this scheme we may remark, that fictitious as it undisguisedly is, it still serves to exhibit very clearly some of the main features of the author's 14 Bacon's Works, vol. ii. 111. FROM BACON TO NEWTON. 175 philosophy :--namely, his steady view of the necessity of ascending from facts to the most general truths by several stages ;—an exaggerated opinion of the aid that could be derived in such a task from technical sepa- ration of the phenomena and a distribution of them into tables ;-a belief, probably incorrect, that the offices of experimenter and interpreter may be entirely separated, and pursued by different persons with a certainty of obtaining success !—and a strong determi- nation to make knowledge constantly subservient to the uses of life. 9. Cowley.--Another project of the same kind, less ambitious but apparently more directed to prac- tice, was published a little later (1657) by another eminent man of letters in this country. I speak of Cowley's “Proposition for the Advancement of Experi- mental Philosophy.” He suggests that a College should be established at a short distance from London, en- dowed with a revenue of four thousand pounds, and consisting of twenty professors with other members. The objects of the labours of these professors he de- scribes to be, first, to examine all knowledge of nature delivered to us from former ages and to pronounce it sound or worthless; second, to recover the lost inven- tions of the ancients; third, to improve all arts that We now have; lastly, to discover others that we get have not. In this proposal we cannot help marking the visible declension from Bacon's more philosophical view. For we have here only a very vague indication of improving old arts and discovering new, instead of the two clear Verulamian antitheses, Experiments and Axioms deduced from them, on the one hand, and on the other an ascent to general Laws, and a derivation, from these, of Arts for daily use. Moreover the pro- minent place which Cowley has assigned to the verify- ing the knowledge of former ages and recovering “ the lost inventions and drowned lands of the ancients," implies a disposition to think too highly of traditionary knowledge; a weakness which Bacon's scheme shows him to have fully overcome. And thus it has been up to the present day, that with all Bacon's mistakes, in 176 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. the philosophy of scientific method few have come up to him, and perhaps none have gone beyond him. Cowley exerted himself to do justice to the new philosophy in verse as well as prose, and his Poem to the Royal Society expresses in a very noble manner those views of the history and prospects of philosophy which prevailed among the men by whom the Royal Society was founded. The fertility and ingenuity of comparison which characterize Cowley's poetry are well known; and these qualities are in this instance largely employed for the embellishment of his subject. Many of the comparisons which he exhibits are apt and striking. Philosophy is a ward whose estate (hu- man knowledge) is, in his nonage, kept from him by his guardians and tutors; (a case which the ancient rhetoricians were fond of taking as a subject of decla- mation;) and these wrong-doers retain him in unjust tutelage and constraint for their own purposes; until Bacon at last, a mighty man, arose, (Whom a wise King, and Nature, chose Lord Chancellor of both their laws) And boldly undertook the injured pupil's cause. Again, Bacon is one who breaks a scarecrow Priapus which stands in the garden of knowledge. Again, Bacon is one who, instead of a picture of painted grapes, gives us real grapes from which we press "the thirsty soul's refreshing wine." Again, Bacon is like Moses, who led the Hebrews forth from the barren wilderness, and ascended Pisgah ;- Did on the very border stand Of the blest promised land, And from the mountain's top of his exalted wit Saw it himself and showed us it. The poet however adds, that Bacon discovered, but did not conquer this new world; and that the men whom he addresses must subdue these regions. These “chanıpions” are then ingeniously compared to Gi- deon's band : Their old and empty pitchers first they brake, And with their hands then lifted up the light, 177 There were still at this time some who sneered at or condemned the new philosophy; but the tide of popular opinion was soon strongly in its favour. I have else- where 15 noticed a pasquinade of the poet Boileau in 1682, directed against the Aristotelians. At this time, and indeed for long afterwards, the philosophers of France were Cartesians. · The English men of science, although partially and for a time they accepted some of Descartes' opinions, for the most part carried on the reform independently, and in pursuance of their own views. And they very soon found a much greater leader than Descartes to place at their head, and to take as their authority, so far as they acknowledged authority, in their speculations. I speak of Newton, whose influence upon the philosophy of science I must now consider. . Barrow. I will, however, first mention one other writer who may, in more than one way, be regarded as the predecessor of Newton. I speak of Isaac Bar- row, whom Newton succeeded as Professor of Mathe- matics in the University of Cambridge, and who in his mathematical speculations approached very near to Newton's method of Fluxions. He afterwards (in 1673) became Master of Trinity College, which office he held till his death in 1677. But the passages which I shall quote belong to an earlier period, (when Barrow was about 22 years old,) and may be regarded as ex- pressions of the opinions which were then current among active-minded and studious young men. They manifest a complete familiarity with the writings both of Bacon and of Descartes, and a very just appreciation of both. The discourse of which I speak is an aca- demical exercise delivered in 1652, on the thesis Car- tesiana hypothesis haud satisfacit prcecipuis naturae phænomenis. By the “Cartesian hypothesis,” he does not mean the hypothesis that the planets are moved by vortices of etherial matter : I believe that this Car- tesian tenet never had any disciples in England; it 16 Hist. Ind. Sc. b. vii. c. i 178 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. certainly never took any hold of Cainbridge. By the Cartesian hypothesis, Barrow means the doctrine that all the phenomena of nature can be accounted for by matter and motion; and allowing that the motions of the planets are to be so accounted for, (which is New- tonian as well as Cartesian doctrine,) he denies that the Cartesian hypothesis accounts for the generations, properties, and specific operations of animals, plants, minerals, stones, and other natural bodies,” in doing which he shows a sound philosophical judgment. But among the parts of this discourse most bearing on our present purpose are those where he mentions Bacon. Against Cartesius," he says, “I pit the chymists and others, but especially as the foremost champion of this battle, our Verulam, a man of great name and of great judgment, who condemned this philosophy before it was born.” “He,” adds Barrow, "several times in his Organon, warned men against all hypotheses of this kind, and noticed beforehand that there was not much to be expected from those principles which are brought into being by violent efforts of argumentation from the brains of particular men: for that, as upon the pheno- mena of the stars, various constructions of the heavens may be devised, so also upon the phenomena of the Universe, still more dogmas may be founded and con- structed; and yet all such are mere inventions, and as many philosophies of this kind as are or shall be ex- tant, so many fictitious and theatrical worlds are made." The reference is doubtless to Aphorism LXII. of the first Book of the Novum Organon, in which Bacon is speaking of his “Idols of the Theatre.” After making the remark which Barrow has adopted, Bacon adds, “Such theatrical fables have also this in common with those of dramatic poets, that the dramatic story is more regular and elegant than true histories are, and is made so as to be agreeable.” Barrow, having this in his mind, goes on to say: “And though Cartesius has dressed up the stage of his theatre more prettily than any other person, and made his drama more like history, still he is not exempt from the like censure.” And he then refers to Cartesius's own declaration, that FROM BACON TO NEWTON. 179 he did not learn his system from things themselves, but tried to impose his own laws upon things; thus in- verting the order of true philosophy, Other parts of Bacon's work to which Barrow refers are those where he speaks of the Form, or Formal Cause of a body, and says that in comparison with that, the Efficient Cause and the Material Cause are things unimportant and superficial, and contribute little to true and active science 10. And again, his classification of the various kinds of motions"?,—the motus libertatis, motus nexus, motus continuitatis, motus ad lucrum, fugæ, unionis, congregationis; and the explanation of electrical attraction (about which Gilbert and others had written) as motus ad lucrum. These passages show that Barrow had read the Novum Organon in a careful and intelligent manner, and presumed his Cambridge hearers to be acquainted with the work. Nor is his judgment of Descartes less wise and philosophical. He rejects, as we have seen, his system as a true scheme of the universe, and condemns altogether his à priori mode of philosophiz- ing; but this does not prevent his accepting Descartes' real discoveries, and admiring the boldness and vigour of his attempts to reform philosophy. There is, in Barrow's works, academic verse, as well as prose, on the subject of the Cartesian hypothesis. In this, Des- cartes himself is highly praised, though his doctrines are very partially accepted. The writer says: “Par- don us, great Cartesius, if the Muse resists you. Par- don! We follow you, Inquiring Spirit that you are, while we reject your system. As you have taught us free thought, and broken down the rule of tyranny, we undauntedly speculate, even in opposition to you." Descartes is even yet spoken of, especially by French writers, as the person who first asserted and estab- lished the freedom of inquiry which is the boast of modern philosophy; but this is said with reference to metaphysics, not to physics. In physical philosophy, 16 Nov. Org. lib. ii. Aph. 2. 17 IV. lib. ii. Aph. 45. N 2 180 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. though he caught hold of some of the discoveries which were then coming into view, the method in which he reasoned or professed to reason was alto- gether vicious; and was, as I have already said, an attempt to undo what the reformers, both theoretical and practical, had been doing :-to discredit the philo- sophy of experience, and to restore the reign of à priori. systems. It was, however, now, too late to make any such attempt; and nothing came of it to interrupt the pro- gress of a better philosophy of discovery. CHAPTER XVIII. NEWTON. I. DOLD and extensive as had been the antici- D pations of those whose minds were excited by the promise of the new philosophy, the discoveries of Newton respecting the mechanics of the universe, brought into view truths more general and profound than those earlier philosophers had hoped or imagined. With these vast accessions to human knowledge, men's thoughts were again set in action; and philosophers made earnest and various attempts to draw, from these extraordinary advances in science, the true moral with regard to the conduct and limits of the human under- standing. They not only endeavoured to verify and illustrate, by these new portions of science, what had recently been taught concerning the methods of ob- taining sound knowledge; but they were also led to speculate concerning many new and more interesting questions relating to this subject. They saw, for the first time, or at least far more clearly than before, the distinction between the inquiry into the laws, and into the causes of phenomena. They were tempted to ask, how far the discovery of causes could be carried; and whether it would soon reach, or clearly point to, the ultimate cause. They were driven to consider whether the properties which they discovered were essential properties of all matter, necessarily and primarily in- volved in its essence, though revealed to us at a late period by their derivative effects. These questions even now agitate the thoughts of speculative men. Some of them have already, in this work, been dis- cussed, or arranged in the places which our view of the philosophy of these subjects assigns to them. But we 182 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. must here notice them as they occurred to Newton himself and his immediate followers. 2. The general Baconian notion of the method of philosophizing,--that it consists in ascending from phe- nomena, through various stages of generalization, to truths of the highest order, received, in Newton's dis- covery of the universal mutual gravitation of every particle of matter, that pointed actual exemplification, for want of which it had hitherto been almost over- looked, or at least very vaguely understood. That great truth, and the steps by which it was established, afford, even now, by far the best example of the suc- cessive ascent, from one scientific truth to another, of the repeated transition from less to more general pro- positions, which we can get produce; as may be seen in the Table which exhibits the relation of these steps in Book II. of the Novum Organon Renovatum. Newton himself did not fail to recognize this feature in the truths which he exhibited. Thus he says, “By the way of Analysis we proceed from compounds to ingre- dients, as from motions to the forces producing them; and in general, from effects to their causes, and from particular causes to more general ones, till the argument ends in the most general.” And in like manner in ano- ther Query: “The main business of natural philoso- phy is to argue from phenomena without feigning hypo- theses, and to deduce causes from effects, till we come to the First Cause, which is certainly not mechanical.” 3. Newton appears to have had a horror of the term hypothesis, which probably arose from his ac- quaintance with the rash and illicit general assump- tions of Descartes. Thus in the passage just quoted, after declaring that gravity must have some other cause than matter, he says, “Later philosophers banish the consideration of such a cause out of Natural Phi- losophy, feigning hypotheses for explaining all things mechanically, and referring other causes to meta- physics.” In the celebrated Scholium at the end of . 1 Optics, qu. 31, near the end. 2. Qu. 28. NEWTON. 183 the Principia he says, “Whatever is not deduced from the phenomena, is to be termed hypothesis ; and hypotheses, whether metaphysical or physical, or oc- for cult causes, or mechanical, have no place in experi- mental philosophy. In this philosophy, propositions are deduced from phenomena, and rendered general by.. induction.” And in another place, he arrests the course of his own suggestions, saying, “Verum hypo- theses non fingo.” I have already attempted to show that this is, in reality, a superstitious and self-destruc- tive spirit of speculation. Some hypotheses are neces-> sary, in order to connect the facts which are observed; some new principle of unity must be applied to the phenomena, before induction can be attempted. What is requisite is, that the hypothesis should be close to the facts, and not connected with them by the interme- diation of other arbitrary and untried facts; and that the philosopher should be ready to resign it as soon as the facts refuse to confirm it. We have seen in the Historys, that it was by such a use of hypotheses, that both Newton himself, and Kepler, on whose discoveries those of Newton were based, made their discoveries. The suppositions of a force tending to the sun and vary- ing inversely as the square of the distance; of a mutual force between all the bodies of the solar system ; of the force of each body arising from the attraction of all its parts; not to mention others, also propounded by Newton,-were all hypotheses before they were veri-, fied as theories. It is related that when Newton was i asked how it was that he saw into the laws of nature so much further than other men, he replied, that if it were so, it resulted from his keeping his thoughts steadily occupied upon the subject which was to be thus penetrated. But what is this occupation of the thoughts, if it be not the process of keeping the phe- nomena clearly in view, and trying, one after another, all the plausible hypotheses which seem likely to con- nect them, till at last the true law is discovered? Hy- potheses so used are a necessary element of discovery, 8 Hist. Ind. Sc. b. v. and b. vii. 184 . Q PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY4. With regard to the details of the process of discovery, Newton has given us some of his views, which are well worthy of notice, on account of their coming from him ; and which are real additions to the philosophy of this subject. He speaks repeatedly of the analysis and synthesis of observed facts; and thus marks certain steps in scientific research, very import- ant, and not, I think, clearly pointed out by his prede- cessors. Thus he says", “As in Mathematics, so in Natural Philosophy, the investigation of difficult things by the method of analysis ought ever to precede the method of composition. This analysis consists in mak- ing experiments and observations, and in drawing general conclusions from them by induction, and ad- mitting of no objections against the conclusions, but such as are taken from experiments or other certain truths. And although the arguing from experiments and observations by induction be no demonstration of general conclusions; yet it is the best way of arguing which the nature of things admits of, and may be look- ed upon as so much the stronger, by how much the induction is more general.” And he then observes, as we have quoted above, that by this way of analysis we proceed from compounds to ingredients, from motions to forces, from effects to causes, and from less to more general causes. The analysis here spoken of includes the steps which in our Novum Organon we call the decomposition of facts, the exact observation and mea- surenent of the phenomena, and the colligation of facts; the necessary intermediate step, the selection and expli- cation of the appropriate conception, being passed over by Newton, in the fear of seeming to encourage the fabrication of hypotheses. The synthesis of which New- ton here speaks consists of those steps of deductive reco- soning, proceeding from the conception once assumed, which are requisite for the comparison of its conse- quences with the observed facts. This, his statement of the process of research, is, as far as it goes, perfectly exact. 4 Optics, qu. 31. NEWTON. 185 5. In speaking of Newton's precepts on the subject, we are naturally led to the celebrated “Rules of Phi- losophizing," inserted in the second edition of the Prin- cipia. These rules have generally been quoted and commented on with an almost unquestioning reverence. Such Rules, coming from such an authority, cannot fail to be highly interesting to us; but at the same time, we cannot here evade the necessity of scrutiniz- ing their truth and value, according to the principles which our survey of this subject has brought into view. The Rules stand at the beginning of that part of the Principia (the Third Book) in which he infers the mu- tual gravitation of the sun, moon, planets, and all parts of each. They are as follows : “Rule I. We are not to admit other causes of na- tural things than such as both are true, and suffice for explaining their phenomena. 56 Rule II. Natural effects of the same kind are to be referred to the same causes, as far as can be done. “Rule III. The qualities of bodies which cannot be increased or diminished in intensity, and which be- long to all bodies in which we can institute experi- ments, are to be held for qualities of all bodies what- ever. “Rule IV. In experimental philosophy, proposi- tions collected from phenomena by induction, are to be held as true either accurately or approximately, not- withstanding contrary hypotheses; till other pheno- mena occur by which they may be rendered either more accurate or liable to exception." In considering these Rules, we cannot help remark- ing, in the first place, that they are constructed with an intentional adaptation to the case with which New- ton has to deal,-the induction of Universal Gravita- tion; and are intended to protect the reasonings before which they stand. Thus the first Rule is designed to strengthen the inference of gravitation from the celes- tial phenomena, by describing it as a verc causa, a true cause; the second Rule countenances the doctrine that the planetary motions are governed by mechanical i 186 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. forces, as terrestrial motions are; the third rule ap- pears intended to justify the assertion of gravitation, as a universal quality of bodies; and the fourth con- tains, along with a general declaration of the authority of induction, the author's usual protest against hypo- theses, levelled at the Cartesian hypotheses especially. 6. Of the First Rule.—We, however, must consi- der these Rules in their general application, in which point of view they have often been referred to, and have had very great authority allowed them. One of the points which has been most discussed, is that maxim which requires that the causes of phenomena which we assign should be true causes, verce causa. Of course this does not mean that they should be the true or right cause; for although it is the philosopher's aim to discover such causes, he would be little aided in his search of truth, by being told that it is truth which he is to seek. The rule has generally been un- derstood to prescribe that in attempting to account for any class of phenomena, we must assume such causes only, as from other considerations, we know to exist. Thus gravity, which was employed in explaining the motions of the moon and planets, was already known to exist and operate at the earth's surface. Now the Rule thus interpreted is, I conceive, an injurious limitation of the field of induction. For it forbids us to look for a cause, except among the causes with which we are already familiar. But if we follow this rule, how shall we ever become acquainted with any new cause? Or how do we know that the pheno- mena which we contemplate do really arise from some cause which we already truly know? If they do not, must we still insist upon making them depend upon some of our known causes; or must we abandon the study of them altogether? Must we, for example, resolve to refer the action of radiant heat to the air, rather than to any peculiar fluid or ether, because the former is known to exist, the latter is merely assumed for the purpose of explanation ? But why should we do this? Why should we not endeavour to learn the cause from the effects, even if it be not already known NEWTON. 187 to us? We can infer causes, which are new when we · first become acquainted with them. Chemical Forces, Optical Forces, Vital Forces, are known to us only by chemical and optical and vital phenomena; must we, therefore, reject their existence or abandon their study? They do not conform to the double condition, that they far as they explain the facts, but are they, therefore, unintelligible or useless? Are they not highly im- portant and instructive subjects of speculation ? And if the gravitation which rules the motions of the pla- nets bad not existed at the earth's surface;- if it had been there masked and concealed by the superior effect of magnetism, or some other extraneous force,-might not Newton still have inferred, from Kepler's laws, the tendency of the planets to the sun; and from their perturbations, their tendency to each other? His dis- coveries would still have been immense, if the cause which he assigned had not been a vera causa in the sense now contemplated.. 7. But what do we mean by calling gravity a "true cause”? How do we learn its reality? Of course, by its effects, with which we are familiar;-by the weight and fall of bodies about us. These strike even the most careless observer. No one can fail to see that all bodies which we come in contact with are heavy; that gravity acts in our neighbourhood here upon earth. Hence, it may be said, this cause is at any rate a true cause, whether it explains the celestial phenomena or not. But if this be what is meant by a vera causa, it appears strange to require that in all cases we should find such a one to account for all classes of pheno- mena. Is it reasonable or prudent to demand that we shall reduce every set of phenomena, however minute, or abstruse, or complicated, to causes so obviously ex- isting as to strike the most incurious, and to be fami- liar among men? How can we expect to find such verce cause for the delicate and recondite phenomena which an exact and skilful observer detects in chemi- cal, or optical, or electrical experiments? The facts 188 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. themselves are too fine for vulgar apprehension; their relations, their symmetries, their measures require a previous discipline to understand them. How then can their causes be found among those agencies with which the common unscientific herd of mankind are familiar? What likelihood is there that causes held for real by such persons, shall explain facts which such persons cannot see or cannot understand? Again: if we give authority to such a rule, and require that the causes by which science explains the facts which she notes and measures and analyses, shall be causes which men, without any special study, have already come to believe in, from the effects which they casually see around them, what is this, except to make our first rude and unscientific persuasions the criterion and test of our most laborious and thoughtful infer- ences? What is it, but to give to ignorance and thoughtlessness the right of pronouncing upon the con- victions of intense study and long-disciplined thought? “ Electrical atmospheres” surrounding electrized bo- dies, were at one time held to be a “true cause" of the effects which such bodies produce. These atmo- spheres, it was said, are obvious to the senses; we feel them like a spider's web on the hands and face. Æpinus had to answer such persons, by proving that there are no atmospheres, no effluvia, but only repul- sion. He thus, for a true cause in the vulgar sense of the term, substituted an hypothesis; yet who doubts that what he did was an advance in the science of electricity? 8. Perhaps some persons may be disposed to say, that Newton's Rule does not enjoin us to take those causes only which we clearly know, or suppose we know, to be really existing and operating, but only causes of such kinds as we have already satisfied our- selves do exist in nature. It may be urged that we are entitled to infer that the planets are governed in their motions by an attractive force, because we find, in the bodies immediately subject to observation and experiment, that such motions are produced by attrac- tive forces, for example, by that of the earth. It may NEWTON. 189 be said that we might on similar grounds infer forces which unite particles of chemical compounds, or deflect particles of light, because we see adhesion and deflec- tion produced by forces. But it is easy to show that the Rule, thus laxly un- derstood, loses all significance. It prohibits no hypo- thesis; for all hypotheses suppose causes such as, in some case or other, we have seen in action. No one would think of explaining phenomena by referring them to forces and agencies altogether different from any which are known; for on this supposition, how could he pretend to reason about the effects of the assumed causes, or undertake to prove that they would explain the facts? Some close similarity with some known kind of cause is requisite, in order that the hypothesis may have the appearance of an explana- tion. No forces, or virtues, or sympathies, or fluids, or ethers, would be excluded by this interpretation of verce cause. Least of all, would such an interpreta- tion reject the Cartesian hypothesis of vortices; which undoubtedly, as I conceive, Newton intended to con- demn by his Rule. For that such a case as a whirling fluid, carrying bodies round a centre in orbits, does occur, is too obvious to require proof. Every eddying stream, or blast that twirls the dust in the road, ex- hibits examples of such action, and would justify the assumption of the vortices which carry the planets in their courses; as indeed, without doubt, such facts suggested the Cartesian explanation of the solar sys- tem. The vortices, in this mode of considering the subject, are at the least as real a cause of motion as gravity itself. 9. Thus the Rule which enjoins “true causes," is nugatory, if we take verce cause in the extended sense of any causes of a real kind, and unphilosophical, if we understand the term of those very causes which we familiarly suppose to exist. But it may be said that we are to designate as “true causes,” not those which are collected in a loose, confused and precarious man- ner, by undisciplined minds, from obvious phenomena, but those which are justly and rigorously inferred. 190 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. Such a cause, it may be added, gravity is; for the facts of the downward pressures and downward mo- tions of bodies at the earth's surface lead us, by the plainest and strictest induction, to the assertion of such a force. Now to this interpretation of the Rule there is no objection; but then, it must be observed, that on this view, terrestrial gravity is inferred by the same process as celestial gravitation; and the cause is no more entitled to be called “true," because it is obtained from the former, than because it is obtained from the latter class of facts. We thus obtain an in- telligible and tenable explanation of a vera causa; but then, by this explanation, its verity ceases to be distinguishable from its other condition, that it "suf- fices for the explanation of the phenomena." The assumption of universal gravitation accounts for the fall of a stone; it also accounts for the revolutions of the Moon or of Saturn; but since both these explana- tions are of the same kind, we cannot with justice make the one a criterion or condition of the admis- sibility of the other. Io. But still, the Rule, so understood, is so far from being unmeaning or frivolous, that it expresses one of the most important tests which can be given of a sound physical theory. It is true, the explanation of one set of facts may be of the same nature as the explanation of the other class : but then, that the cause explains both classes, gives it a very different claim upon our attention and assent from that which it would have if it explained one class only. The very circumstance that the two explanations coincide, is a most weighty presumption in their favour. It is the testimony of two witnesses in behalf of the hypo- thesis; and in proportion as these two witnesses are separate and independent, the conviction produced by their agreement is more and more complete. When the explanation of two kinds of phenomena, distinct, - and not apparently connected, leads us to the same cause, such a coincidence does give a reality to the cause, which it has not while it merely accounts for those appearances which suggested the supposition. NEWTON. 191 This coincidence of propositions inferred from sepa- rate classes of facts, is exactly what we noticed in the Novum Organon Renovatum (b. ii. C. 5, sect. 3), as one of the most decisive characteristics of a true theory, under the name of Consilience of Inductions. That Newton's First Rule of Philosophizing, so un- derstood, authorizes the inferences which he himself believed by philosophers. Thus when the doctrine of a gravity varying inversely as the square of the dis- tance from the body, accounted at the same time for the relations of times and distances in the planetary orbits and for the amount of the moon's deflection from the tangent of her orbit, such a doctrine became most convincing: or again, when the doctrine of the universal gravitation of all parts of matter, which explained so admirably the inequalities of the moon's motions, also gave a satisfactory account of a pheno- menon utterly different, the precession of the equi- noxes. And of the same kind is the evidence in favour of the undulatory theory of light, when the assumption of the length of an undulation, to which we are led by the colours of thin plates, is found to be identical with that length which explains the pheno- mena of diffraction; or when the hypothesis of trans- verse vibrations, suggested by the facts of polarization, explains also the laws of double refraction. When such a convergence of two trains of induction points to the same spot, we can no longer suspect that we are wrong. Such an accumulation of proof really persuades us that we have to do with a vera causa. And if this kind of proof be multiplied ;-if we again find other facts of a sort uncontemplated in framing our hypothesis, but yet clearly accounted for when we have adopted the supposition ;-we are still further confirmed in our belief; and by such accumulation of proof we may be so far satisfied, as to believe without conceiving it possible to doubt. In this case, when the validity of the opinion adopted by us has been repeatedly confirmed by its sufficiency in unforeseen cases, so that all doubt is removed and forgotten, the 192 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. theoretical cause takes its place among the realities of the world, and becomes a true cause. II. Newton's Rule then, to avoid mistakes, might 'be thus expressed : That “we may, provisorily, assume such hypothetical cause as will account for any given class of natural phenomena; but that when two dif- ferent classes of facts lead us to the same hypothesis, we may hold it to be a true cause.” And this Rule will rarely or never mislead us. There are no in- stances, in which a doctrine recommended in this manner bas afterwards been discovered to be false. There have been hypotheses which have explained many phenomena, and kept their ground long, and have afterwards been rejected. But these have been hypotheses which explained only one class of pheno- mena; and their fall took place when another kind of facts was examined and brought into conflict with the former. Thus the system of eccentrics and epicycles accounted for all the observed motions of the planets, and was the means of expressing and transmitting all astronomical knowledge for two thousand years. But then, how was it overthrown? By considering the distances as well as motions of the heavenly bodies. Here was a second class of facts; and when the sys- tem was adjusted so as to agree with the one class, it was at variance with the other. These cycles and epicycles could not be true, because they could not be made a just representation of the facts. But if the measures of distance as well as of position had con- spired in pointing out the cycles and epicycles, as the paths of the planets, the paths so determined could not have been otherwise than their real paths; and the epicyclical theory would have been, at least geo- metrically, true. 12. Of the Second Rule.—Newton's Second Rule directs that “natural events of the same kind are to be referred to the same causes, so far as can be done." Such a precept at first appears to help us but little; for all systems, however little solid, profess to conform to such a rule. When any theorist undertakes to ex- plain a class of facts, he assigns causes which, according NEWTON. · 193 to him, will by their natural action, as seen in other cases, produce the effects in question. The events which he accounts for by his hypothetical cause, are, he holds, of the same kind as those which such a cause is known to produce. Kepler, in ascribing the pla- netary motions to magnetism, Descartes, in explaining them by means of vortices, held that they were re- ferring celestial motions to the causes which give rise to terrestrial motions of the same kind. The question is, Are the effects of the same kind? This once settled, there will be no question about the propriety of assign- ing them to the same cause. But the difficulty is, to determine when events are of the same kind. Are the motions of the planets of the same kind with the motion of a body moving freely in a curvilinear path, or do they not rather resemble the motion of a floating body swept round by a whirling current? The Newtonian and the Cartesian answered this question differently. How then can we apply this Rule with any advantage? 13. To this we reply, that there is no way of escap- ing this uncertainty and ambiguity, but by obtaining a clear possession of the ideas which our hypothesis involves, and by reasoning rigorously from them. Newton asserts that the planets move in free paths, acted on by certain forces. The most exact calcula- tion gives the closest agreement of the results of this hypothesis with the facts. Descartes asserts that the planets are carried round by a fluid. The more rigor- ously the conceptions of force and the laws of motion are applied to this hypothesis, the more signal is its failure in reconciling the facts to one another. Without such calculation, we can come to no decision between the two hypotheses. If the Newtonian hold that the motions of the planets are evidently of the same kind as those of a body describing a curve in free space, and therefore, like that, to be explained by a force acting upon the body; the Cartesian denies that the planets do move in free space. They are, he main- tains, immersed in a plenum. It is only when it appears that comets pass through this plenum in all 194 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. directions with no impediment, and that no possible form and motion of its whirlpools can explain the forces and motions which are observed in the solar system, that he is compelled to allow the Newtonian's classifi- cation of events of the same kind. Thus it does not appear that this Rule of Newton can be interpreted in any distinct and positive manner, otherwise than as enjoining that, in the task of induc- tion, we employ clear ideas, rigorous reasoning, and close and fair comparison of the results of the hypo- thesis with the facts. These are, no doubt, important and fundamental conditions of a just induction; but in this injunction we find no peculiar or technical criterion by which we may satisfy ourselves that we are right, or detect our errors. Still, of such general prudential rules, none can be more wise than one which thus, in the task of connecting facts by means of ideas, recommends that the ideas be clear, the facts, correct, and the chain of reasoning which connects them, without a flaw. 14. Of the Third Rule.- The Third Rule, that "qualities which are observed without exception be held to be universal," as I have already said, seems to be intended to authorize the assertion of gravitation as a universal attribute of matter. We formerly stated, in treating of Mechanical Ideas', that this application of such a Rule appears to be a mode of reasoning far from conclusive. The assertion of the universality of any property of bodies must be grounded upon the reason of the case, and not upon any arbitrary maxim. Is it intended by this Rule to prohibit any further ex- amination how far gravity is an original property of matter, and how far it may be resolved into the result of other agencies? We know perfectly well that this was not Newton's intention; since the cause of gravity was a point which he proposed to himself as a subject of inquiry. It would certainly be very unphilosophical to pretend, by this Rule of Philosophizing, to prejudge the question of such hypotheses as that of Mosotti, 5 History of Ideas, b. ii. C. X. NEWTON. 195 That gravity is the excess of the electrical attraction over electrical repulsion, and yet to adopt this hy- pothesis, would be to suppose electrical forces more truly universal than gravity; for according to the hypothesis, gravity, being the inequality of the attrac- tion and repulsion, is only an accidental and partial relation of these forces. Nor would it be allowable to urge this Rule as a reason of assuming that double stars are attracted to each other by a force varying according to the inverse square of the distance; with- out examining, as Herschel and others have done, the is not available in such cases, what is its real value and authority? and in what cases are they exemplified? fundamental laws of motion, and the properties of matter which these involve, are, after a full considera- tion of the subject, unavoidably assumed as universally true. It was further shown, that although our know- ledge of these laws and properties be gathered from ex- perience, we are strongly impelled, (some philosophers think, authorized,) to look upon these as not only uni- versally, but necessarily true. It was also stated, that the law of gravitation, though its universality may be deemed probable, does not apparently involve the same necessity as the fundamental laws of motion. But it was pointed out that these are some of the most abstruse and difficult questions of the whole of phi- losophy; involving the profound, perhaps insoluble, problem of the identity or diversity of Ideas and Things. It cannot, therefore, be deemed philosophical to cut these Gordian knots by peremptory maxims, which encourage us to decide withont rendering a reason. Moreover, it appears clear that the reason which is rendered for this Rule by the Newtonians is quite untenable; namely, that we know extension, hardness, and inertia, to be universal qualities of bo- dies by experience alone, and that we have the same o Ibid. b. iii. c. ix. x. xi. O 2 196. PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. evidence of experience for the universality of gravita- tion. We have already observed that we cannot, with any propriety, say that we find by experience all bodies are extended. This could not be a just assertion, unless we conceive the possibility of our finding the contrary. But who can conceive our finding by ex- perience some bodies which are not extended ? It appears, then, that the reason given for the Third Rule of Newton involves a mistake respecting the nature and authority of experience. And the Rule itself cannot be applied without attempting to decide, by the casual limits of observation, questions which recessarily depend upon the relations of ideas. 16. Of the Fourth Rule.—Newton's Fourth Rule is, that “Propositions collected from phenomena by induction, shall be held to be true, notwithstanding contrary hypotheses; but shall be liable to be rendered more accurate, or to have their exceptions pointed out, by additional study of phenomena.” This Rule con- tains little more than a general assertion of the autho- rity of induction, accompanied by Newton's usual protest against hypotheses. The really valuable part of the Fourth Rule is that which implies that a constant verification, and, if neces- sary, rectification, of truths discovered by induction, should go on in the scientific world. Even when the law is, or appears to be, most certainly exact and uni- versal, it should be constantly exhibited to us afresh in the form of experience and observation. This is neces- sary, in order to discover exceptions and modifications if such exist: and if the law be rigorously true, the contemplation of it, as exemplified in the world of phenomena, will best give us that clear apprehension of its bearings which may lead us to see the ground of its truth. The concluding clause of this Fourth Rule appears, at first, to imply that all inductive propositions are to be considered as merely provisional and limited, and never secure from exception. But to judge thus would be to underrate the stability and generality of scientific truths; for what man of science can suppose that we NEWTON 197 shall hereafter discover exceptions to the universal gravitation of all parts of the solar system? And it is plain that the author did not intend the restric- tion to be applied so rigorously; for in the Third Rule, as we have just seen, he authorizes us to infer uni- versal properties of matter from observation, and car- ries the liberty of inductive inference to its full extent. The Third Rule appears to encourage us to assert a law to be universal, even in cases in which it has not been tried; the Fourth Rule seems to warn us that the law may be inaccurate, even in cases in which it has been tried. Nor is either of these sug- gestions erroneous; but both the universality and the rigorous accuracy of our laws are proved by reference to Ideas rather than to Experience; a truth, which, perhaps, the philosophers of Newton's time were some- what disposed to overlook. 17. The disposition to ascribe all our knowledge to Experience, appears in Newton and the Newtonians by other indications; for instance, it is seen in their extreme dislike to the ancient expressions by which the principles and causes of phenomena were described, as the occult causes of the Schoolmen, and the forms of the Aristotelians, which had been adopted by Bacon. Newton says”, that the particles of matter not only possess inertia, but also active principles, as gravity, fermentation, cohesion; he adds, “ These principles I consider not as Occult Qualities, supposed to result from the Specific Forms of things, but as General Laws of Nature, by which the things themselves are formed: their truth appearing to us by phenomena, though their causes be not yet discovered. For these are manifest qualities, and their causes only are occult. And the Aristotelians gave the name of occult qualities, not to manifest qualities, but to such qualities only as they supposed to lie hid in bodies, and to the unknown causes of manifest effects : such as would be the causes of gravity, and of magnetick and electrick attractions, 7 Opticks, qu. 31. 198 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. and of fermentations, if we should suppose that these forces or actions arose from qualities unknown to us, and incapable of being discovered and made manifest. Such occult qualities put a stop to the improvement of Natural Philosophy, and therefore of late years have been rejected. To tell us that every species of things acts and produces manifest effects, is to tell us no- thing: but to derive two or three general principles of motion from phenomena, and afterwards to tell us how the properties and actions of all corporeal things fol- low from these manifest principles, would be a great step in philosophy, though the causes of those prin- ciples were not yet discovered: and therefore I scruple not to propose the principles of motion above main- tained, they being of very general extent, and leave their causes to be found out." 18. All that is here said is highly philosophical and valuable; but we may observe that the investigation of specific forms in the sense in which some writers had used the phrase, was by no means a frivolous or un- meaning object of inquiry. Bacon and others had used form as equivalent to law. If we could ascertain that arrangement of the particles of a crystal from which its external crystalline form and other proper- ties arise, this arrangement would be the internal form of the crystal. If the undulatory theory be true, the form of light is transverse vibrations: if the emission theory be maintained, the form of light is particles moving in straight lines, and deflected by various forces. Both the terms, form and law, imply an ideal connexion of sensible phenomena; form supposes mat- 8 Nov. Org. 1. ii. Aph. 2. “Licet enim in natura nihil existet præter corpora individua, edentia actus pu- ros individuos ex lege; in doctrinis tamen illa ipsa lex, ejusque inquisi. tio, et inventio, et explicatio, pro fundamento est tam ad scienduin quam ad operandum. Eam autem legem, ejusque paragraphos, forma- rum nomine intelligimus; præsertim cum hoc vocabulum invaluerit, et familiariter occurrat.” Aph. 17. “Eadem res est forma calidi vel forma luminis, et lex calidi aut lex luminis." NEWTON. 199 ter which is moulded to the form; law supposes objects which are governed by the law. The former term lefers more precisely to existences, the latter to occur- rences. The latter term is now the more familiar, and is, perhaps, the better metaphor: but the former also contains the essential antithesis which belongs to the subject, and might be used in expressing the same con- clusions. But occult causes, employed in the way in which Newton describes, had certainly been very prejudicial to the progress of knowledge, by stopping inquiry with a mere word. The absurdity of such pretended expla- nations had not escaped ridicule. The pretended phy- sician in the comedy gives an example of an occult cause or virtue. Mibi demandatur A doctissimo Doctore Quare Opium facit dormire: Et ego respondeo, Quia est in eo Virtus dormitiva, Cujus natura est sensus assoupire. 19. But the most valuable part of the view present- ed to us in the quotation just given from Newton is the distinct separation, already noticed as peculiarly brought into prominence by him, of the determination of the laws of phenomena, and the investigation of their causes. The maxim, that the former inquiry must precede the latter, and that if the general laws of facts be discovered, the result is highly valuable, although the causes remain unknown, is extremely important; and had not, I think, ever been so strongly and clearly stated, till Newton both repeatedly pro- mulgated the precept, and added to it the weight of the most striking examples. We have seen that Newton, along with views the i most just and important concerning the nature and methods of science, had something of the tendency, prevalent in his time, to suspect or reject, at least speculatively, all elements of knowledge except ob- servation. This tendency was, however, in him so 200 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. corrected and restrained by his own wonderful sagacity and mathematical habits, that it scarcely led to any opinion which we might not safely adopt. But we must now consider the cases in which this tendency operated in a more unbalanced manner, and led to the assertion of doctrines which, if consistently followed, would destroy the very foundations of all general and certain knowledge, CHAPTER XIX. LOCKE AND HIS FRENCH FOLLOWERS. I. TN the constant opposition and struggle of the I schools of philosophy, which consider our Senses and our Ideas respectively, as the principal sources of our knowledge, we have seen that at the period of which we now treat, the tendency was to exalt the external and disparage the internal element. The dis- position to ascribe our knowledge to observation alone, had already, in Bacon's time, led him to dwell to a disproportionate degree upon that half of his subject; and had tinged Newton's expressions, though it had not biassed his practice. But this partiality soon as- sumed a more prominent shape, becoming extreme in Locke, and extravagant in those who professed to follow him. Indeed Locke appears to owe his popularity and influence as a popular writer mainly to his being one of the first to express, in a plain and unhesitating manner, opinions which had for some time been ripen- ing in the minds of a large portion of the cultivated public. Hobbes had already promulgated the main doctrines which Locke afterwards urged, on the sub- ject of the origin and nature of our knowledge : but in him these doctrines were combined with offensive opinions on points of morals, government, and religion, so that their access to general favour was impeded : and it was to Locke that they were indebted for the extensive influence which they soon after obtained. Locke owed this authority mainly to the intellectual circumstances of the time. Although a writer of great merit, he by no means possesses such metaphysi- cal acuteness or such philosophical largeness of view, 202 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. or such a charm of writing, as must necessarily give him the high place he has held in the literature of Europe. But he came at a period when the reign of Ideas was tottering to its fall. All the most active and ambitious spirits had gone over to the new opinions, and were prepared to follow the fortunes of the Philo- sophy of Experiment, then in the most prosperous and brilliant condition, and full of still brighter pro- mise. There were, indeed, a few learned and thought- ful men who still remained faithful to the empire of Ideas; partly, it may be, from a too fond attachment to ancient systems; but partly, also, because they knew that there were subjects of vast importance, in which experience did not form the whole foundation of our knowledge. They knew, too, that many of the plau- sible tenets of the new philosophy were revivals of fallacies which had been discussed and refuted in an- cient times. But the advocates of mere experience came on with a vast store of weighty truth among their artillery, and with the energy which the advance usually bestows. The ideal system of philosophy could, for the present, make no effectual resistance; Locke, by putting himself at the head of the assault, became the watchword of those who adhere to the philosophy of the senses up to our owu times. 2. Locke himself did not assert the exclusive au- thority of the senses in the extreme unmitigated manner in which some who call themselves his disci- ples have done. But this is the common lot of the leaders of revolutions, for they are usually bound by some ties of affection and habit to the previous state of things, and would not destroy all traces of that condition : while their followers attend, not to their inconsistent wishes, but to the meaning of the revolu- tion itself; and carry out, to their genuine and com- plete results, the principles which won the victory, and which have been brought out more sharp from the conflict. Thus Locke himself does not assert that all our ideas are derived from Sensation, but from Sensation and Reflection. But it was easily seen that, LOCKE AND HIS FRENCH FOLLOWERS. 203 in this assertion, two very heterogeneous elements were conjoined : that while to pronounce Sensation the origin of ideas, is a clear decided tenet, the ac- ceptance or rejection of which determines the general character of our philosophy; to make the same decla- ration concerning Reflection, is in the highest degree vague and ambiguous; since, reflection may either be resolved into a mere modification of sensation, as was done by one school, or may mean all that the opposite school opposes to sensation, under the name of Ideas. Hence the clear and strong impression which fastened upon men's minds, and which does in fact represent all the systematic and consistent part of Locke's phi- losophy, was, that in it all our ideas are represented as derived from Sensation. 3. We need not spend much time in pointing out the inconsistencies into which Locke fell, as all must fall into inconsistencies who recognize no source of knowledge except the senses. Thus he maintains that our Idea of Space is derived from the senses of sight and touch; our Idea of Solidity from the touch alone. Our Notion of Substance is an unknown support of unknown qualities, and is illustrated by the Indian fable of the tortoise which supports the elephant, which supports the world. Our Notion of Power or Cause is in like manner got from the senses. And yet, though these ideas are thus mere fragments of our experience, Locke does not hesitate to ascribe to them necessity and universality when they occur in pro- positions. Thus he maintains the necessary truth of geometrical properties : he asserts that the resistance arising from solidity is absolutely insurmountable?; he conceives that nothing short of Omnipotence can. annihilate a particle of matter?; and he has no mis- givings in arguing upon the axiom that Every thing must have a cause. He does not perceive that, upon his own account of the origin of our knowledge, we can have no right to make any of these assertions. If 1 Essay, b. xi. c. iv. sect. 3. 2 Ibid. c. xiii. sect. 22. 204 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. our knowledge of the truths which concern the exter- nal world were wholly derived from experience, all that we could venture to say would be,—that geome- trical properties of figures are true as far as we have tried them ;—that we have seen no example of a solid body being reduced to occupy less space by pressure, or of a material substance annihilated by natural means;-and that wherever we have examined, we have found that every change has had a cause. Experience can never entitle us to declare that what she has not seen is impossible; still less, that things which she can not see are certain. Locke himself intended to throw no doubt upon the certainty of either human or divine knowledge; but his principles, when men discarded the temper in which he applied them, and the checks to their misapplication which he conceived that he had provided, easily led to a very comprehensive skep- ticism. His doctrines tended to dislodge from their true bases the most indisputable parts of knowledge; as, for example, pure and mixed mathematics. It may well be supposed, therefore, that they shook the foun- dations of many other parts of knowledge in the minds of common thinkers. It was not long before these consequences of the overthrow of ideas showed themselves in the specula- tive world. I have already in a previous work mentioned Hume's skeptical inferences from Locke's maxim, that we have no ideas except those which we acquire by experience; and the doctrines set up in opposition to this by the metaphysicians of Ger- many. I might trace the progress of the sensational opinions in Britain till the reaction took place here also : but they were so much more clearly and deci- dedly followed out in France, that I shall pursue their history in that country. 4. The French Followers of Locke, Condillac, &c.- Most of the French writers who adopted Locke's lead- ing doctrines, rejected the “ Reflection," which formed 3 History of Ideas, b. ü. c. iii. Modern Opinions respecting the Idea of Cause. LOCKE AND. HIS FRENCH FOLLOWERS. 205 an anomalous part of his philosophy, and declared that Sensation alone was the source of ideas. Among these writers, Condillac was the most distinguished. He expressed the leading tenet of their school in a clear and pointed manner by saying that “All ideas are transformed sensations." We have already considered this phrase, and need not here dwell upon it. Opinions such as these tend to annihilate, as we have seen, one of the two co-ordinate elements of our knowledge. Yet they were far from being so preju- dicial to the progress of science, or even of the philo- sophy of science, as might have been anticipated. One reason of this was, that they were practically corrected, especially among the cultivators of Natural Philosophy, by the study of mathematics; for that study did really supply all that was requisite on the ideal side of sci- ence, so far as the ideas of space, time, and number, were concerned, and partly also with regard to the idea of cause and some others. And the methods of disco- very, though the philosophy of them made no material advance, were practically employed with so much ac- tivity, and in so many various subjects, that a certain kind of prudence and skill in this employment was very widely diffused. 5. Importance of Language.--In one respect this school of metaphysicians rendered a very valuable ser- vice to the philosophy of science. They brought into prominent notice the great importance of words and terms in the formation and progress of knowledge, and pointed out that the office of language is not only to convey and preserve our thoughts, but to perform the analysis in which reasoning consists. They were led to this train of speculation, in a great measure, by taking pure mathematical science as their standard example of substantial knowledge. Condillac, reject- ing, as we have said, almost all those ideas on which universal and demonstrable truths must be based, was still not at all disposed to question the reality of 4 Ibid. b. i. c. iv. 206 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. human knowledge ; but was, on the contrary, a zealous admirer of the evidence and connexion which appear in those sciences which have the ideas of space and number for their foundation, especially the latter. He looked for the grounds of the certainty and reality of the knowledge which these sciences contain; and found them, as he conceived, in the nature of the language which they employ. The Signs which are used in arithmetic and algebra enable us to keep steadily in view the identity of the same quantity under all the forms which, by composition and decomposition, it may be made to assume; and these Signs also not only express the operations which are performed, but suggest the extension of the operations according to analogy Algebra, according to him, is only a very perfect language ; and language answers its purpose of leading us to truth, by possessing the characteristics of algebra. Words are the symbols of certain groups of impressions or facts; they are so selected and applied as to exhibit the analogies which prevail among these facts; and these analogies are the truths of which our knowledge consists. “Every language is an analytical method; every analytical method is a languages ;" these were the truths “alike new and simple," as he held, which he conceived that he had demonstrated. “The art of speaking, the art of writing, the art of reasoning, the art of thinking, are only, at bottom, one and the same art 6." Each of these operations consists in a succession of analytical operations; and words are the marks by which we are able to fix our minds upon the steps of this analysis. 6. The analysis of our impressions and notions does in reality lead to truth, not only in virtue of the identity of the whole with its parts, as Condillac held, but also in virtue of certain Ideas which govern the synthesis of our sensations, and which contain the elements of universal truths, as we have all along en- deavoured to show. But although Condillac overlooked or rejected this doctrine, the importance of words, as s Langue des Calculs, p. 1. 6 Grammaire, p. xxxvi. LOCKE AND HIS FRENCH FOLLOWERS. 207 marking the successive steps of this synthesis and. analysis, is not less than he represented it to be. Every truth, once established by induction from facts, when it is become familiar under a brief and precise form of expression, becomes itself a fact; and is capable of being employed, along with other facts of a like kind, as the materials of fresh inductions. In this successive process, the term, like the cord of a fagot, both binds together the facts which it includes, and makes it pos- sible to manage the assemblage as a single thing. On occasion of most discoveries in science, the selection of a technical term is an essential part of the proceeding. In the History of Science, we have had numerous op- portunities of remarking this; and the List of technical terms given as an Index to that work, refers us, by almost every word, to one such occasion. And these terms, which thus have had so large a share in the formation of science, and which constitute its language, do also offer the means of analyzing its truths, each into its constituent truths; and these into facts more special, till the original foundations of our most gene- ral propositions are clearly exhibited. The relations of general and particular truths are most evidently represented by the Inductive Tables given in Book II. of the Novum Organon Renovatum. But each step in each of these Tables has its proper form of ex- pression, familiar among the cultivators of science; and the analysis which our Tables display, is com- monly performed in men's minds, when it becomes necessary, by fixing the attention successively upon a series of words, not upon the lines of a Table. Lan- guage offers to the mind such a scale or ladder as the Table offers to the eye; and since such Tables present to us, as we have said, the Logic of Induction, that is, the formal conditions of the soundness of our reasoning from facts, we may with propriety say that a just ana- lysis of the meaning of words is an essential portion of Inductive Logic. In saying this, we must not forget that a decom- position of general truths into ideas, as well as into facts, belongs to our philosophy; but the point we 208 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. have here to remark, is the essential importance of words to the latter of these processes. And this point had not ever had its due weight assigned to it till the time of Condillac and other followers of Locke, who pursued their speculations in the spirit I have just described. The doctrine of the importance of terms is the most considerable addition to the philosophy of science which has been made since the time of Bacon?. 7. The French Encyclopedists.—The French Ency- clopédie, published in 1751, of which Diderot and Da- lembert were the editors, may be considered as repre- senting the leading characters of European philosophy during the greater part of the eighteenth century. The writers in this work belong for the most part to the school of Locke and Condillac; and we may make a few remarks upon them, in order to bring into view one or two points in addition to what we have already said of that school. The Discours Préliminaire, written by Dalembert, is celebrated as containing a view of the origin of our knowledge, and the connexion and classification of the sciences. A tendency of the speculations of the Encyclope- dists, as of the School of Locke in general, is to reject all ideal principles of connexion among facts, as some- thing which experience, the only source of true know- ledge, does not give. Hence all certain knowledge consists only in the recognition of the same thing un- der different aspects, or different forms of expression. Axioms are not the result of an original relation of ideas, but of the use, or it may be the abuse”, of words. In like manner, the propositions of Geometry are a series of modifications, of distortions, so to speak,— of one original truth; much as if the proposition were stated in the successive forms of expression presented by a language which was constantly growing more and 7 Since the selection and construc- tion of terms is thus a matter of so much consequence in the formation of science, it is proper that systema- tic rules, founded upon sound prin- ciples, should be laid down for the performance of this operation. Some such rules are accordingly suggested in b. iv. of the Nov. Org. Ron. 8 Disc. Prélim. p. viii. LOCKE AND HIS FRENCH FOLLOWERS. 209 more artificial. Several of the sciences which rest upon physical principles, that is, (says the writer,) truths of experience or simple hypotheses, have only an experimental or hypothetical certainty. Impene- trability added to the idea of extent is a mystery in addition: the nature of motion is a riddle for philoso- phers: the metaphysical principle of the laws of per- .cussion is equally concealed from them. The more profoundly they study the idea of matter and of the properties which represent it, the more obscure this idea becomes; the more completely does it escape them. 8. This is a very common style of reflection, even down to our own times. I have endeavoured to show that concerning the Fundamental Ideas of space, of force and resistance, of substance, external quality, and the like, we know enough to make these Ideas the grounds of certain and universal truths ;-enough to supply us with axioms from which we can demonstra- tively reason. If men wish for any other knowledge of the nature of matter than that which ideas, and facts conformable to ideas, give them, undoubtedly their desire will be frustrated, and they will be left in a mysterious vacancy; for it does not appear how such knowledge as they ask for could be knowledge at all. But in reality, this complaint of our ignorance of the real nature of things proceeds from the rejection of ideas, and the assumption of the senses alone as the ground of knowledge. “Observation and calculation are the only sources of truth;" this is the motto of the school of which we now speak. And its import amounts to this:—that they reject all ideas except the idea of number, and recognize the modifications which parts undergo by addition and subtraction as the only modes in which true propositions are generated. The laws of nature are assemblages of facts: the truths of science are assertions of the identity of things which are the same. “By the avowal of almost all philoso- phers,” says a writer of this school”, “the most sublime 9 Helvctius Sur l'Homme, c. xxiii.. 210 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. truths, when once simplified and reduced to their low- est terms, are converted into facts, and thenceforth present to the mind only this proposition; the white is white, the black is black.” These statements are true in what they positively assert, but they involve error in the denial which by implication they convey. It is true that observation and demonstration are the only sources of scientific truth; but then, demonstration may be founded on other grounds besides the elementary properties of number. It is true that the theory of gravitation is but the assertion of a general fact; but this is so, not because a sound theory does not involve ideas, but be- cause our apprehension of a fact does. 9. Another characteristic indication of the temper of the Encyclopedists and of the age to which they belong, is the importance by them assigned to those practical Arts which minister to man's comfort and convenience. Not only, in the body of the Encyclo- pedia, are the Mechanical Arts placed side by side with the Sciences, and treated at great length; but in the Preliminary Discourse, the preference assigned to the liberal over the mechanical Arts is treated as a prejudice, and the value of science is spoken of as measured by its utility. “The discovery of the Mari- ner's Compass is not less advantageous to the human race than the explanation of its properties would be to physics.—- Why should we not esteem those to whom we owe the fusee and the escapement of watches as much as the inventors of Algebra?" And in the clas- sification of sciences which accompanies the Discourse, the labours of artisans of all kinds have a place. This classification of the various branches of science contained in the Dissertation is often spoken of. It has for its basis the classification proposed by Bacon, in which the parts of human knowledge are arranged according to the faculties of the mind in which they originate; and these faculties are taken, both by Bacon and by Dalembert, as Memory, Reason, and Imagi- 10 P. xiii. LOCKE AND HIS FRENCH FOLLOWERS. 211 nation. The insufficiency of Bacon's arrangement as a scientific classification is so glaring, that the adoption of it, with only superficial modifications, at the period of the Encyclopedia, is a remarkable proof of the want of original thought and real philosophy at the time of which we speak. 10. We need not trace further the opinion which derives all our knowledge from the senses in its appli- cation to the philosophy of Science. Its declared aim is to reduce all knowledge to the knowledge of Facts; and it rejects all inquiries which involve the Idea of Cause, and similar Ideas, describing them as “meta- physical,” or in some other damnatory way. It pro- fesses, indeed, to discard all Ideas; but, as we have long ago seen, some Ideas or other are inevitably in- cluded even in the simplest Facts. Accordingly the speculations of this school are compelled to retain the relations of Position, Succession, Number and Resem- blance, which are rigorously ideal relations. The phi- losophy of Sensation, in order to be consistent, ought to reject these Ideas along with the rest, and to deny altogether the possibility of general knowledge. . When the opinions of the Sensational School had gone to an extreme length, a Reaction naturally began to take place in men's minds. Such have been the alternations of opinion, from the earliest ages of human speculation. Man may perhaps have existed in an original condition in which he was only aware of the impressions of Sense; but his first attempts to analyse his perceptions brought under his notice Ideas as a separate element, essential to the existence of know- ledge. Ideas were thenceforth almost the sole subject of the study of philosophers; of Plato and his disci- ples, professedly; of Aristotle, and still more of the followers and commentators of Aristotle, practically. And this continued till the time of Galileo, when the authority of the Senses again began to be asserted; for it was shown by the great discoveries which were then made, that the Senses had at least some share in the promotion of knowledge. As discoveries more numerous and more striking were supplied by Obser- P 2 212 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. vation, the world gradually passed over to the opinion: that the share which had been ascribed to Ideas in the formation of real knowledge was altogether a delusion, and that Sensation alone was true. But when this was asserted as a general doctrine, both its manifest falsity and its alarming consequences roused men's ininds, and made them recoil from the extreme point to which they were approaching. Philosophy again oscillated back towards Ideas; and over a great part of Europe, in the clearest and most comprehensive minds, this regression from the dogmas of the Sensational School is at present the prevailing movement. We shall conclude our review by noticing a few indications of this state of things. CHAPTER XX. THE REACTION AGAINST THE SENSATIONAL SCHOOL. 1. THEN Locke's Essay appeared, it was easily V seen that its tendency was to urge, in a much more rigorous sense than had previously been usual, the ancient maxim of Aristotle, adopted by the school- men of the middle ages, that "nothing exists in the intellect but what has entered by the senses.” Leib- nitz expressed in a pointed manner the limitation with which this doctrine had always been understood. “Ni- hil est in intellectu quod non prius fuerit in sensu ;- nempe," he added, "nisi intellectus ipse.” To this it has been objected', that we cannot say that the in- tellect is in the intellect. But this remark is obvi- ously frivolous; for the faculties of the understanding (which are what the argument against the Sensational School requires us to reserve) may be said to be in the understanding, with as much justice as we may assert there are in it the impressions derived from sense. And when we take account of these faculties, and of the Ideas to which, by their operation, we neces- sarily subordinate our apprehension of phenomena, we are led to a refutation of the philosophy which makes phenomena, unconnected by Ideas, the source of all knowledge. The succeeding opponents of the Lockian school insisted upon and developed in various ways this remark of Leibnitz, or some equivalent view. 2. It was by inquiries into the foundations of Morals that English philosophers were led to question the truth of Locke's theory. Dr. Price, in his Review ? See Mr Sharpe's Essays. 214 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. of the Principal Questions in Morals, first published in 1757, maintained that we cannot with propriety assert all our ideas to be derived from sensation and reflection. He pointed out, very steadily, the other source. "The power, I assert, that understands, or the faculty within us that discerns truth, and that compares all the objects of thought and judges of them, is a spring of new ideas?” And he exhibits the anti- thesis in various forms. “Were not sense and knowledge entirely different, we should rest satisfied with sensible impressions, such as light, colours and sounds, and in- quire no further about them, at least when the im- pressions are strong and vigorous: whereas, on the contrary, we necessarily desire some further acquaint- ance with them, and can never be satisfied till we have subjected them to the survey of reason. Sense presents particular forms to the mind, but cannot rise to any general ideas. It is the intellect that examines and compares the presented forms, that rises above indi- viduals to universal and abstract ideas; and thus looks downward upon objects, takes in at one view an in- finity of particulars, and is capable of discovering general truths. Sense sees only the outside of things, reason acquaints itself with their natures. Sensation is only a mode of feeling in the mind; but knowledge implies an active and vital energy in the mind 3." 3. The necessity of refuting Hume's inferences from the mere-sensation system led other writers to limit, in various ways, their assent to Locke. Especially was this the case with a number of intelligent metaphysi- cians in Scotland, as Reid, Beattie, Dugald Stewart, and Thomas Brown. Thus Reid asserts", "that the account which Mr. Locke himself gives of the Idea of Power cannot be reconciled to his favourite doctrine, that all our simple ideas have their origin from sensa- tion or reflection.” Reid remarks, that our memory and our reasoning power come in for a share in the 3 P. 18. 2 Price's Essays, p. 16. 4 Reid, Essays on the Powers of the Human Mind, üi. 31. REACTION AGAINST SENSATIONISTS. 215 origin of this idea : and in speaking of reasoning, he obviously assumes the axiom that every event must have a cause. By succeeding writers of this school, the assumption of the fundamental principles, to which our nature in such cases irresistibly directs us, is more clearly pointed out. Thus Stewart defends the form of expression used by Price5: “A variety of intuitive judgments might be mentioned, involving simple ideas, which it is impossible to trace to any origin but to the power which enables us to form these judgments. Thus it is surely an intuitive truth that the sensations of which I am conscious, and all those I remember, be- long to one and the same being, which I call myself. Here is an intuitive judgment involving the simple idea of Identity. In like manner, the changes which I perceive in the universe impress me with a convic- tion that some cause must have operated to produce them. Here is an intuitive judgment involving the simple Idea of Causation. When we consider the adjacent angles made by a straight line standing upon another, and perceive that their sum is equal to two right angles, the judgment we form involves a simple idea of Equality. To say, therefore, that the Reason or the Understanding is a source of new ideas, is not so exceptionable a mode of speaking as has been some- times supposed. According to Locke, Sense furnishes our ideas, and Reason perceives their agreements and disagreements. But the truth is, that these agree- ments and disagreements are in many instances, sim- ple ideas, of which no analysis can be given; and of which the origin must therefore be referred to Reason, according to Locke's own doctrine.” This view, ac- cording to which the Reason or Understanding is the source of certain simple ideas, such as Identity, Causa- tion, Equality, which ideas are necessarily involved in the intuitive judgments which we form, when we recognize fundamental truths of science, approaches very near in effect to the doctrine which in several works I have presented, of Fundamental Ideas belonging to 5 Stewart, Outlines of Moral Phil. p. 138. 216 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. each science, and manifesting themselves in the axioms of the science. It may be observed, however, that by attempting to enumerate these ideas and axioms, so as to lay the foundations of the whole body of physical science, and by endeavouring, as far as possible, to simplify and connect each group of such Ideas, I have at least given a more systematic form to this consequences to which it necessarily leads, but which do not appear to have been contemplated by the meta- physicians of the Scotch school. But I gladly acknow- ledge my obligations to the writers of that school; and I trust that in the near agreement of my views on such points with theirs, there is ground for believ- to be that to which the minds of thoughtful men, who have meditated on such subjects, are generally tending. 4. As a further instance that such a tendency is at work, I may make a quotation from an eminent English philosophical writer of another school. “If you will be at the pains," says Archbishop Whately, “carefully to analyze the simplest description you hear of any transaction or state of things, you will find that the process which almost invariably takes place is, in logical language, this: that each individual has in his mind certain major premises or principles relative to the subject in question ;—that observation of what actually presents itself to the senses, supplies minor premises; and that the statement given (and which is reported as a thing experienced) consists, in fact, of the conclusions drawn from the combinations of these premises.” The major premises here spoken of are the Fundamental Ideas, and the Axioms and Proposi- tions to which they lead; and whatever is regarded as a fact of observation is necessarily a conclusion in which these propositions are assumed; for these con- tain, as we have said, the conditions of our experience. 6 Whately, Polit. Econ. P. 76. REACTION AGAINST SENSATIONISTS. 217 Our experience conforms to these axioms and their consequences, whether or not the connexion be stated in a logical manner, by means of premises and a con- clusion. 5. The same persuasion is also suggested by the course which the study of metaphysics has taken of late years in France. In that country, as we have seen, the Sensational System, which was considered as the necessary consequence of the revolution beguu by Locke, obtained a more complete ascendancy than it did in England; and in that country too, the reaction, among metaphysical and moral writers, when its time came, was more decided and rapid than it was among Locke's own countrymen. It would appear that M. Laromiguière was one of the first to give expression to this feeling, of the necessity of a modification of the sensational philosophy. He began by professing him- self the disciple of Condillac, even while he was almost unconsciously subverting the fundamental principles of that writer. And thus, as M. Cousin justly ob- serves?, his opinions had the more powerful effect from being presented, not as thwarting and contradicting, but as sharing and following out the spirit of his age. M. Laromiguière's work, entitled Essai sur les Facul- tés de l'Ame, consists of lectures given to the Faculty of Letters of the Academy of Paris, in the years 1811, 1812 and 1813. In the views which these lectures present, there is much which the author has in com- mon with Condillac. But he is led by his investiga- tion to assert, that it is not true that sensation is the sole fundamental element of our thoughts and our un- derstanding. Attention also is requisite: and here we have an element of quite another kind. For sensation is passive; attention is active. Attention does not spring out of sensation; the passive principle is not the reason of the active principle. Activity and pas- sivity are two facts entirely different. Nor can this activity be defined or derived; being, as the author 7 Cousin, Fragmens Philosophiques, i. 53. 8 Ibid. i. 67. 218 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. says, a fundamental idea. The distinction is manifest by its own nature; and we may find evidence of it in the very forms of language. To look is more than to see; to hearken is more than to hear. The French language marks this distinction with respect to other senses also. “On voit, et l'on regarde; on entend, et l'on écoute; on sent, et l'on faire; on goûte, et l'on savoure." And thus the mere sensation, or capacity of feeling, is only the occasion on which the attention is exercised; while the attention is the foundation of all the operations of the understanding. The reader of my works will have seen how much I have insisted upon the activity of the mind, as the necessary basis of all knowledge. In all ob- servation and experience, the mind is active, and by its activity apprehends all sensations in subor- dination to its own ideas; and thus it becomes capa- ble of collecting knowledge from phenomena, since ideas involve general relations and connexions, which sensations of themselves cannot involve. And thus we see that, in this respect also, our philosophy stands at that point to which the speculations of the most reflecting men have of late constantly been verging 6. M. Cousin himself, from whom we have quoted the above account of Laromiguière, shares in this tend- ency, and has argued very energetically and success- fully against the doctrines of the Sensational School. He has made it his office once more to bring into notice among his countrymen, the doctrine of ideas as the sources of knowledge; and has revived the study of Plato, who may still be considered as one of the great leaders of the ideal school. But the larger portion of M. Cousin's works refers to questions out of the reach of our present review, and it would be unsuitable to dwell longer upon them in this place. 7. We turn to speculations more closely connected with our present subject. M. Ampère, a French man of science, well entitled by his extensive knowledge, and large and profound views, to deal with the philo- REACTION AGAINST SENSATIONISTS. 219 "sophy of the sciences, published in 1834, his Essai sur la Philosophie des Sciences, ou Exposition analytique d'une Classification Naturelle de toutes les connaissances Humaines. In this remarkable work we see strong evidence of the progress of the reaction against the system which derives our knowledge from sensation only. The author starts from a maxim, that in class- ing the sciences, we must not only regard the nature of the objects about which each science is concerned, but also the point of view under which it considers them: that is, the ideas which each science involves. M. Ampère also gives briefly his views of the intel- lectual constitution of man; a subject on which he had long and sedulously employed his thoughts; and these views are far from belonging to the Sensational School. Human thought, he says, is composed of phe- nomena and of conceptions. Phenomena are external, or sensitive; and internal, or active. Conceptions are of four kinds; primitive, as space and motion, duration and cause; objective, as our idea of matter and sub- stance; onomatic, or those which we associate with the general terms which language presents to us; and explicative, by which we ascend to causes after a com- parative study of phenomena. He teaches further, that in deriving ideas from sensation, the mind is not passive; but exerts an action which, when voluntary, is called attention, but when it is, as it often is, inyo- luntary, may be termed reaction. I shall not dwell upon the examination of these opinions'; but I may remark, that both in the recog- nition of conceptions as an original and essential ele- ment of the mind, and in giving a prominent place to the active function of the mind, in the origin of our knowledge, this view approaches to that which I have presented in preceding works; although undoubtedly with considerable differences. 8. The classification of the sciences which M. See also the vigorous critique of Locke's Essay, by Lemaistre, Soirées de St Petersbourg, 220 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. Ampère proposes, is founded upon a consideration of the sciences themselves; and is, the author conceives, in accordance with the conditions of natural classifi- cations, as exhibited in Botany and other sciences. It is of a more symmetrical kind, and exhibits more steps of subordination, than that to which I have been led; it includes also practical Art as well as theoretical Sci- ence; and it is extended to moral and political as well as physical Sciences. It will not be necessary for me here to examine it in detail: but I may remark, that it is throughout a dichotonous division, each higher member being subdivided into two lower ones, and so on. In this way, M. Ampère obtains sciences of the First Order, each of which is divided into two sciences of the Second, and four of the Third Order. Thus Mechanics is divided into Cinematics, Statics, Dyna- mics, and Molecular Mechanics; Physics is divided into Experimental Physics, Chemistry, Stereometry, and Atomology; Geology is divided into Physical Geogra- phy, Mineralogy, Geonomy, and Theory of the Earth. Without here criticizing these divisions or their prin- ciple, I may observe that Cinematics, the doctrine of motion without reference to the force which produces it, is a portion of knowledge which our investigation has led us also to see the necessity of erecting into a separate science; and which we have termed Pure Mechanism. Of the divisions of Geology, Physical Geography, especially as explained by M. Ampère, is certainly a part of the subject, both important and tolerably distinct from the rest. Geonomy contains what we have termed in the History, Descriptive Geo- logy ;-the exhibition of the facts separate from the inquiry into their causes; while our Physical Geology agrees with M. Ampère's Theory of the Earth. Mine- realogy appears to be placed by him in a different place from that which it occupies in our scheme: but in fact, he uses the term for a different science; he applies it to the classification not of simple minerals, but of rocks, which is a science auxiliary to geology, and which has sometimes been called Petralogy. What we have termed Mineralogy, M. Ampère unites with REACTION AGAINST SENSATIONISTS. 221 Chemistry. “It belongs," he says, “to Chemistry, and not to Mineralogy, to inquire how many atoms of silicium and of oxygen compose silica; to tell us that its primitive form is a rhombohedron of certain angles, that it is called quartz, &c.; leaving, on one hand, to Molecular Geometry the task of explaining the differ- ent secondary forms which may result from the pri- mitive form ; and on the other hand, leaving to Mine- ralogy the office of describing the different varieties of quartz, and the rocks in which they occur, according as the quartz is crystallized, transparent, coloured, amorphous, solid, or in sand.” But we may remark, that by adopting this arrangement, we separate from Mineralogy almost all the knowledge, and absolutely all the general knowledge, which books professing to treat of that science have. usually contained. The consideration of Mineralogical Classifications, which, as may be seen in the History of Science, is so curious and instructive, is forced into the domain of Chemistry, although many of the persons who figure in it were not at all properly chemists. And we lose, in this way, the advantage of that peculiar office which, in our arrangement, Mineralogy fills; of forming a rigor- ous transition from the sciences of classification to those which consider the mathematical properties of bodies; and connecting the external characters and the internal constitution of bodies by means of a system of important general truths. I conceive, therefore, that our disposition of this science, and our mode of applying the name, are far more convenient than those of M. Ampère. 9. We have seen the reaction against the pure sen- sational doctrines operating very powerfully in England and in France. But it was in Germany that these doctrines were most decidedly rejected; and systems in extreme opposition to these put forth with confi- dence, and received with applause. Of the authors who gave this impulse to opinions in that country, Kant 10 Ampère, Essai, p. 210. U 222 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. was the first, and by far the most important. I have in the History of Ideas (b. iii. c. 3), endeavoured to ex- plain how he was aroused, by the skepticism of Hume, to examine wherein the fallacy lay which appeared to invalidate all reasonings from effect to cause; and how this inquiry terminated in a conviction that the foun- dations of our reasonings on this and similar points were to be sought in the mind, and not in the phenomena ;- in the subject, and not in the object. The revolution in the customary mode of contemplating human know- ledge which Kant's opinions involved, was most com- plete. He himself, with no small justice, compares 11 it with the change produced by Copernicus's theory of the solar system. " Hitherto,” he says, “men have assumed that all our knowledge must be regulated by the objects of it; yet all attempts to make out anything concerning objects à priori by means of our conceptions,” (as for instance their geometrical proper- ties) “must, on this foundation, be unavailing. Let us then try whether we cannot make out something more in the problems of metaphysics, by assuming that objects must be regulated by our knowledge, since this agrees better with that supposition, which we are prompted to make, that we can know some- thing of them d priori. This thought is like that of Copernicus, who, when he found that nothing was to be made of the phenomena of the heavens so long as everything was supposed to turn about the spec- tator, tried whether the matter might not be better explained if he made the spectator turn, and left the stars at rest. We may make the same essay in meta- physics, as to what concerns our intuitive knowledge respecting objects. If our apprehension of objects must be regulated by the properties of the objects, I cannot comprehend how we can possibly know any- thing about them d priori. But if the object, as ap- prehended by us, be regulated by the constitution of our faculties of apprehension, I can readily conceive 11 Kritik der Reinen Vernunft, Pref. p. xv. REACTION AGAINST SENSATIONISTS. 223 this possibility." From this he infers that our expe- rience must be regulated by our conceptions. Io. This view of the nature of knowledge soon superseded entirely the doctrines of the Sensational School among the metaphysicians of Germany. These philosophers did not gradually modify and reject the dogmas of Locke and Condillac, as was done in England and France ; nor did they endeavour to ascertain the extent of the empire of Ideas by a careful survey of its several provinces, as we have been doing in this series of works. The German metaphysicians saw at once that Ideas and Things, the Subjective and the Objective elements of our knowledge, were, by Kant's system, brought into opposition and cor- relation, as equally real and equally indispensable. Seeing this, they rushed at once to the highest and most difficult problem of philosophy,—to deter- mine what this correlation is ;-to discover how Ideas and Things are at the same time opposite and iden- tical ;-how the world; while it is distinct from and independent of us, is yet, as an object of our know- ledge, governed by the conditions of our thoughts. The attempts to solve this problem, taken in the widest sense, including the forms which it assumes in Morals, Politics, the Arts, and Religion, as well as in the Material Sciences, have, since that time, occupied the most profound speculators of Germany; and have given rise to a number of systems, which, rapidly succeeding each other, have, each in its day, been looked upon as a complete solution of the problem. To trace the characters of these various systems, does not belong to the business of the present chapter: my task is ended when I have shown, as I have now done, how the progress of thought in the philosophical world, followed from the earliest up to the present time, has 12 The sensational system never acquired in Germany the ascendancy which it obtained in England and France; but I am compelled here to pass over the history of philosophy in Germany, except so far as it af- fects ourselves. 224 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. led to that recognition of the co-existence and joint necessity of the two opposite elements of our know- ledge; and when I have pointed out processes adapted to the extension of our knowledge, which a true view of its nature has suggested or may suggest. The latter portion of this task occupies the third book of the Novum Organon Renovatum. With regard sophy, I shall add something in a subsequent chapter: and I shall also venture to trace further than I have yet done, the bearing of the philosophy of science upon the theological view of the universe and the moral and religious condition of man. CHAPTER XXI. FURTHER ADVANCE OF THE SENSATIONAL SCHOOL. M. AUGUSTE COMTE. T SHALL now take the liberty of noticing the views 1 published by a contemporary writer; not that it forms part of my design to offer any criticism upon the writings of all those who have treated of those subjects on which we are now employed; but because we can more distinctly in this manner point out the contrasts and ultimate tendencies of the several sys- tens of opinion which have come under our survey: and since from among these systems we have endea- voured to extract and secure the portion of truth which remains in each, and to reject the rest, we are led to point out the errors on which our attention is thus fixed, in recent as well as older writers. M. Auguste Comte published in 1830 the first, and in 1835 the second volume of his Cours de Philosophie Positive; of which the aim is not much different from that of the present work, since as he states (p. viii.) such a title as the Philosophy of the Sciences would describe a part of his object, and would be inappro- priate only by excluding that portion (not yet pub- lished) which refers to speculations concerning social relations. 1. M. Comte on Three States of Science.--By em- ploying the term Philosophie Positive, he wishes to distinguish the philosophy involved in the present state of our sciences from the previous forms of human knowledge. For according to him, each branch of knowledge passes, in the course of man's history, through three different states; it is first theological, then metaphysical, then positive. By the latter term 226 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. he implies a state which includes nothing but general representations of facts;—phenomena arranged accord- ing to relations of succession and resemblance. This “positive philosophy” rejects all inquiry after causes, which inquiry he holds to be void of sense' and inac- cessible. All such conceptions belong to the “meta- physical” state of science which deals with abstract forces, real entities, and the like. Still more completely does he reject, as altogether antiquated and absurd, the “theological” view of phenomena. Indeed he conceives” that any one's own consciousness of what passes within himself is sufficient to convince him of the truth of the law of the three phases through which knowledge must pass. “Does not each of us,” he says, “in contemplating his own history, recollect that he has been successively a theologian in his in- fancy, a metaphysician in his youth, and a physicist in his ripe age? This may easily be verified for all men who are up to the level of their time.” It is plain from such statements, and from the whole course of his work, that M. Comte holds, in their most rigorous form, the doctrines to which the speculations of Locke and his successors led; and which tended, as we have seen, to the exclusion of all ideas except those of number and resemblance. As M. Comte refuses to admit into his philosophy the fundamental idea of Cause, he of course excludes most of the other ideas, which are, as we endeavoured to show, the foundations of science; such as the ideas of Media by which secondary qualities are made knowu to us; the ideas of Chemical Attraction, of Polar Forces, and the like. He would reduce all science to the mere expression of laws of phenomena, expressed in formula of space, time, and number; and would condemn as unmeaning, and as belonging to an obsolete state of science, all endeavours to determine the causes of phenomena, or even to refer them to any of the other ideas just mentioned. ii. p. 14. 2 i. p. 7. i M. AUGUSTE COMTE. 227 2. ·M. Comte rejects the Search of Causes. — In a previous workI have shown, I trust. decisively, that it is the genuine office of science to inquire into the causes as well as the laws of phenomena; - that such an inquiry cannot be avoided; and that it has been the source of almost all the science we possess. I need not here repeat the arguments there urged; but I may make a remark or two upon M. Comte's hypothesis, that all science is first “meta- physical” and then “positive;” since it is in virtue of this hypothesis that he rejects the investigation of causes, as worthy only of the infancy of science. All discussions concerning ideas, M. Comte would condemn as “metaphysical,” and would consider as mere pre- ludes to positive philosophy. Now I venture to assert, on the contrary, that discussions concerning ideas, and real discoveries, have in every science gone hand in hand. There is no science in which the pretended order of things can be pointed out. There is no science in which the discoveries of the laws of phenomena, when once begun, have been carried on independently of discussions concerning ideas. There is no science in which the expression of the laws of phenomena can at this time dispense with ideas which have acquired their place in science in virtue of metaphysical con- siderations. There is no science in which the most active disquisitions concerning ideas did not come after, not before, the first discovery of laws of pheno- mena. In Astronomy, the discovery of the pheno- menal laws of the epicyclical motions of the heavens led to assumptions of the metaphysical principle of equable circular motions: Kepler's discoveries would never have been made but for his metaphysical notions. These discoveries of the laws of phenomena did not lead immediately to Newton's theory, becarise a century of metaphysical discussions was requisite as a prepa- ration. Newton then discovered, not merely a law of phenomena, but a cause; and therefore he was the 3 list. Ind. Sc. b. xi. C. vii, Q2 228 PIIILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. greatest of discoverers. The same is the case in Op- tics; the ancients possessed some share of our know- ledge of facts; but meddled little with the metaphy- sical reasonings of the subject. In modern times when men began to inquire into the nature of light, they soon extended their knowledge of its laws. When this series of discoveries had come to a pause, a new series of brilliant discoveries of laws of phenomena went on, inseparably connected with a new series of views of the nature and cause of light. In like man- ner, the most modern discoveries in chemistry involve indispensably the idea of polar forces. The metaphy-. sics (in M. Comte's sense) of each subject advances in a parallel line with the knowledge of physical laws. The Explication of Conceptions inust go on, as we have already shown, at the same rate as the Colligation of Facts. M. Comte will say that Newton's discovery of gravitation only consists in exhibiting the astronomical phenomena of the universe as one single fact under different points of view. But this fact involves the idea of force, that is, of cause. And that this idea is not a mere modification of the ideas of time and space, we have shown : if it were so, how could it lead to the axiom that attraction is mutual, an indis- pensable part of the Newtonian theory? M. Comte says that we do not know what attraction is, since we can only define it by identical phrases : but this is just as true of space, or time, or motion; and is in fact exactly the characteristic of a fundamental idea. We do not obtain such ideas from definitions, but we possess them not the less truly because we cannot define them. That M. Comte's hypothesis is historically false, is obvious by such examples as I have mentioned. Meta- physical discussions have been essential steps in the progress of each science. If we arbitrarily reject all these portions of scientific history as useless trifling, 4 P. 15. 5 P. 16. M. AUGUSTE COMTE. 229 belonging to the first rude attempts at knowledge, we shall not only distort the progress of things, but per- vert the plainest facts. Of this we have an example in M. Comte's account of Kepler's mechanical specu- lations. We have seen, in the History of Physical Astronomy, that Kepler's second law, (that the planets describe areas about the sun proportional to the times.) was proved by him, by means of calculations founded on the observations of Tycho; but that the mechani- cal reason of it was not assigned till a later period, when it appeared as the first proposition of Newton's Principia. It is plain from the writings of Kepler, that it was impossible for him to show how this law resulted from the forces which were in action; since the forces which he considered were not those tending to the centre, which really determine the property in question, but forces exerted by the sun in the direction of the planet's motion, without which forces Kepler conceived that the motion could not go on. In short, the state of mechanical science in Kepler's time was such that no demonstration of the law could be given. The terms in which such a demonstration must be expressed had not at that time acquired a precise significance; and it was in virtue of many subsequent metaphysical discussions (as M. Comte would teim them) that these terms became capable of expressing sound mechanical reasoning. Kepler did indeed pre- tend to assign what he called a "physical proof” of his law, depending upon this, that the sun's force is less at greater distances; a condition which does not at all influence the result. Thus Kepler's reason for his law proves nothing but the confusion of thought in which he was involved on such subjects. Yet M. Comte assigns to Kepler the credit of having proved this law by sound mechanical reasoning, as well as established it as a matter of factº. “This discovery by Kepler," 6 M. Comte's statement is so en tirely at variance with the fact that I must quote it here. (Phil. Pos. vol. i. p. 705.) “Le second théorème général de dynamique consiste dans le celébre et important principe des aires, dont le première idée est due à Kepler, 230 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERI. he adds, “is the inore remarkable, inasmuch as it oc- eurred before the science of dynamics had really been created by Galileo.” We may remark that inasmuch as M. Comte perceived this incongruity in the facts as he stated them, it is the more remarkable that he did not examine them more carefully. 3. Causes in Physics. The condemnation of the inquiry into causes which is conveyed in M. Comte's notion of the three stages of Science, he again ex- presses more in detail, in stating? what he calls his Fundamental theory of hypotheses. This “theory” is, that we may employ hypotheses in our natural philosophy, but these hypotheses must always be such as admit of a positive verification. We must have no suppositions concerning the agents by which effects are produced. All such suppositions have an anti-scientific charac- ter, and can only impede the real progress of physics. There can be no use in the ethers and imaginary fluids to which some persons refer the phenomena of heat, light, electricity and magnetism. And in agreement with this doctrine, M. Comte in his account of the qui découvrit et démontra forte sim- sante de l'action sur le corps d'un force plement cette propriété pour le cas dirigée sans cesse vers ce point.” du mouvement d'une molecule u. There is not a trace of the above nique, ou en d'autres terms, d'un propositions in the work De Stella corps dont tous les points se meu- Martis, which contains Kepler's dis- vent identiquement. Kepler établit, covery of his law, nor, I am con- par les considérations les plus élé- vinced, in any other of Kepler's mentaires, qui si la force accélératrice works. He is everywhere constant totale dont une molecule est animée to his conceptions of the magnetic tend constamment vers un point fixé, virtue residing in the sun, by means le rayon vecteur du mobile décrit of which the sun, revolving on his autour de ce point des aires égales en axis, carries the planets round with temps egaux, de telle sorte que l'aire him. M. Comte's statement so exactly décrite au bout d'un temps quel- expresses Newton's propositions, that conque croît proportionellement à ce one is led to suspect some extraordi- temps. Il fit voir en outre que reci- nary mistake, by which what should proquement, si une semblable réla- have been said of the one was trans- tion a été verifiée dans le mouve- ferred to the other. ment d'un corps par rapport à un 7 Vol ü. p. 433. certain point, c'est une preuve suffi- 8 Vol. ii, 640. M. AUGUSTE COMTE. 231. Science of Optics, condemns, as utterly unphiloso- phical and absurd, both the theory of emission and that of undulation. To this we reply, that theory of one kind or other is indispensable to the expression of the phenomena; and that when the laws are expressed, and apparently explained, by means of a theory, to forbid us to in- quire whether it be really true or false, is a pedantic and capricious limitation of our knowledge, to which the intellect of man neither can nor should submit. If any one holds the adoption of one or other of these theories to be indifferent, let him express the laws of phenomena of diffraction in terms of the theory of emissionº. If any one rejects the doctrine of undula- tion, let him point out some other way of connecting double refraction with polarization. And surely no man of science will contend that the beautiful branch of science which refers to that connexion is not a portion of our positive knowledge. M. Comte's contempt for the speculations of the undulationists seems to have prevented his acquainting himself with their reasonings, and even with the laws of phenomena on which they have reasoned, although these form by far the most striking and beautiful addition which Science has received in modern times. He adduces, as an insuperable objection to the undu- latory theory, a difficulty which is fully removed by calculation in every work on the subject:—the ex- istence of shadow 10. He barely mentions the subject of diffraction, and Young's law of interferences ;-speaks of Fresnel as having applied this principle to the phenomena of coloured rings, “on which the ingenious labours of Newton left much to desire;" as if Fresnel's labours on this subject had been the supplement of those of Newton: and after regretting that “this principle of interferences has not yet been distinctly 9 I venture to offer this problem ;- to express the laws of the phenomena of diffraction without the hypothesis of undulations;—as a challenge to any one who holds such hypothesis to be unphilosophical. 10 ü. p. 641. 232 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. disentangled from chemical conceptions on the nature of light,” concludes his chapter. He does not even mention the phenomena of dipolarization, of circular and elliptical polarization, or of the optical properties of crystals; discoveries of laws of phenomena quite as remarkable as any which can be mentioned. M. Comte's favourite example of physical research is Thermotics, and especially Fourier's researches with regard to heat. It is shown in the History of Ther- motics, that the general phenomena of radiation re- quired the assumption of a fluid to express them; as appears in the theory of exchanges 12. And the ex- planation of the principal laws of radiation, which Fourier gives, depends upon the conception of material molecular radiation. The flux of caloric, of which Fourier speaks, cannot be conceived otherwise than as implying a material flow. M. Comte apologizes 13 for this expression, as too figurative, and says that it merely indicates a fact. But what is the flow of a current of fluid except a fact? And is it not evident that without such expressions, and the ideas corre- sponding to them, Fourier could neither have conveyed nor conceived his theory? In concluding this discussion it must be recollected, that though it is a most narrow and untenable rule to say that we will admit no agency of ethers and fluids into philosophy; yet the reality of such agents is only to be held in the way, and to the extent, which the laws of phenomena indicate. It is not only allowable, but inevitable to assume, as the vehicle of heat and light, a medium possessing some of the properties of more familiar kinds of matter. But the idea of such a medium, which we possess, and on which we cannot but reason, can be fully developed only by an assi- duous study of the cases in which it is applicable. It may be, that as science advances, all our knowledge may converge to one general and single aspect of the 11 ii. p. 673. 12 Hist. Ind. Sc. ii. 489, b. X. c. i. 18 ii. p. 561. M. AUGUSTE COMTE. 233 universe. We abandon and reject this hope, if we refuse to admit those ideas which must be our step- ping-stones in advancing to such a point: and we no less frustrate such an expectation, if we allow ourselves to imagine that from our present position we can stride at once to the summit. 4. Causes in other Sciences.-—But if it is, in the sciences just mentioned, impracticable to reduce our knowledge to laws of phenomena alone, without refer- ring to causes, media, and other agencies; how much more plainly is it impossible to confine our thoughts to phenomena, and to laws of succession and resem- blance, in other sciences, as chemistry, physiology, and geology? Who shall forbid us, or why should we be forbidden, to inquire whether chemical and galvanic forces are identical; whether irritability is a peculiar vital power; whether geological causes have been uni- form or paroxysmal? To exclude such inquiries, would be to secure ourselves from the poison of error by abstaining from the banquet of truth :-it would be to attempt to feed our minds with the meagre diet of space and number, because we may find too delightful a relish in such matters as cause and end, symmetry and affinity, organization and development. Thus M. Comte's arrangement of the progress of science as successively metaphysical and positive, is contrary to history in fact, and contrary to sound phi- losophy in principle. Nor is there any better founda- tion for his statement that theological views are to be found only in the rude infantine condition of human knowledge, and vanish as science advances. Even in material sciences this is not the case. We have shown in the chapter on Final Causes, that physiologists have been directed in their remarks by the conviction of a purpose in every part of the structure of animals; and that this idea, which had its rise after the first obser- vations, has gone on constantly gaining strength and clearness, so that it is now the basis of a large portion of the science. We have seen, too, in the Book on the palæetiological sciences, that the researches of that class do by no means lead us to reject an origin of the series 234 PHILOSOPHY OF DISCOVERY. of events, nor to suppose this origin to be included in the series of natural laws. Science has not at all shown any reason for denying either the creation or the purpose of the universe. This is true of those aspects of the universe which have become the subjects of rigorous science: but how small a portion of the whole do they form! Especially how minute a proportion does our knowledge bear to our ignorance, if we admit into science, as M. Comte advises, only the laws of phenomena! Even in the best explored fields of science, how few such laws do we know! Meteorology, climate, terrestrial magnetism, the colours and other properties of bodies, the con- ditions of musical and articulate sound, and a thou- sand other facts of physics, are not defined by any known laws. In physiology we may readily convince ourselves how little we know of laws, since we can hardly study one species without discovering some un- guessed property, or apply the microscope without seeing some new structure in the best known organs. And when we go on to social and moral and political matters, we may well doubt whether any one single rigorous rule of phenomena has ever been stated, al- though op such subjects man's ideas have been busily and eagerly working ever since his origin. What a wanton and baseless assumption it would be, then, to reject those suggestions of a Governor of the universe which we derive from man's moral and spiritual na- ture, and from the institutions of society, because we fancy we see in the small field of our existing “positive knowledge” a tendency to exclude “theological views!” Because we can explain the motion of the stars by a general Law which seems to imply no hyperphysical agency, and can trace a few more limited laws in other properties of matter, we are exhorted to reject convictions irresistibly suggested to us by our bodies and our souls, by history and antiquities, by conscience and human law. 5. M. Comte's practical philosophy. — It is not merely as a speculative doctrine that M. Comte urges the necessity of our thus following the guidance of M. AUGUSTE COMTE. 235