SOCIALISM UTOPIAN AND SCIENTIFIC FREDERICK ENGELS Edited by EDWARD AVELING D.SE 자 ​0007 WII SCIENTIA ARTES LİBRARY VERITAS OF THE UNIVERSITY OF MICHIGAN E PLUR BUS URUH -- TODA SHQUAERIS PENINSULAM AMOENAME: CIRCUMSPICE DNU DISPOSITIVA ULJ ::: 1:1 23 1700DINUSITION1111111111111ifli 11111111110111111l|||||||||||IIII. SOCIALISM 41014 UTOPIAN AND SCIENTIFIC BY FREDERICK ENGELS TRANSLATED BY EDWARD AVELING D.Sc., Fellow of University College, London WITH A SPECIAL INTRODUCTION BY THE AUTHOR SO ARDVA QVÆ PVLCRA MUCHONV LONDON: SWAN SONNENSCHEIN & CO. NEW YORK: CHARLES SCRIBNER'S SONS 1892 НХ 2100 .E5613 1892 Я В VIVOVOM SOCIALISM UTOPIAN AND SCIENTIFIC INTRODUCTION. THE present little book is, originally, a part of a larger whole. About 1875, Dr. E. Dühring, privat- docent at Berlin University, suddenly and rather clamorously announced his conversion to Socialism, and presented the German public not only with an elaborate Socialist theory, but also with a complete practical plan for the reorganisation of society. As a matter of course, he fell foul of his predecessors ; above all, he honoured Marx by pouring out upon him the full vials of his wrath. This took place about the time when the two sections of the Socialist party in Germany-Eisen- achers and Lassallians—had just effected their fusion, and thus obtained not only an immense increase of strength, but, what was more, the faculty of employ- ing the whole of this strength against the common enemy. The Socialist party in Germany was fast becoming a power. But to make it a power, the first condition was that the newly-conquered unity should not be imperilled. And Dr. Dühring openly pro- ceeded to form around himself a sect, the nucleus of a future separate party. It thus became necessary to take up the gauntlet thrown down to us, and to fight out the struggle whether we liked it or not. 1 V 41014 vi Introduction. This, however, though it might not be an ovei difficult, was evidently a long-winded, business. As i well known, we Germans are of a terribly ponderou Gründlichkeit, radical profundity or profound radi- cality, whatever you may like to call it. Whenever anyone of us expounds what he considers a new doctrine, he has first to elaborate it into an all-com- prising system. He has to prove that both the first principles of logic and the fundamental laws of the universe had existed from all eternity for no other purpose than to ultimately lead to this newly-disy, covered, crowning theory. And Dr. Dühring, in this respect, was quite up to the national mark. Nothing less than a complete “System of Philosophy,” mental, moral, natural, and historical; a complete “System of Political Economy and Socialism ;” and, finally, a “Critical History of Political Economy”—three big volumes in octavo, heavy extrinsically and intrinsi- cally, three army - corps of arguments mobilised against all previous philosophers and economists in general, and against Marx in particular-in fact, an attempt at a complete "revolution in science "—these were what I should have to tackle. I had to treat of all and every possible subject, from the concepts of time and space to Bimetallism ; from the eternity of matter and motion to the perishable nature of moral ideas ; from Darwin's natural selection to the educa- tion of youth in a future society. Anyhow, the systematic comprehensiveness of my opponent gave me the opportunity of developing, in opposition to him, and in a more connected form than had pre- Introduction. vii viously been done, the views held by Marx and myself on this great variety of subjects. And that was the principal reason which made me undertake this other- wise ungrateful task. My reply was first published in a series of articles in the Leipzig “Vorwärts,” the chief organ of the Socialist party, and later on as a book: “Herrn Eugen Dühring's Umwälzung der Wissenschaft” (Mr. E. Dühring's “Revolution in Science "), a second edition of which appeared in Zürich, 1886. At the request of my friend, Paul Lafargue, now representative of Lille in the French Chamber of Deputies, I arranged three chapters of this book as a pamphlet, which he translated and published in 1880, under the title : “ Socialisme utopique et Socialisme scientifique.” From this French text a Polish and a Spanish edition were prepared. In 1883, our German friends brought out the pamphlet in the original language. Italian, Russian, Danish, Dutch, and Roumanian translations, based upon the German text, have since been published. Thus, with the present English edition, this little book circulates in ten languages. I am not aware that any other Socialist work, not even our “ Communist Manifesto.” of 1848 or Marx's “ Capital,” has been so often translated. In Germany it has had four editions of about 20,000 copies in all. The Appendix, “the Mark," was written with the intention of spreading among the German Socialist party some elementary knowledge of the history and development of landed property in Germany. This (6 viii Introduction. seemed all the more necessary at a time when the assimilation by that party of the working people of the towns was in a fair way of completion, and when the agricultural labourers and peasants had to be taken in hand. This appendix has been included in the translation, as the original forms of tenure of land common to all Teutonic tribes, and the history of their decay, are even less known in England than in Germany. I have left the text as it stands in the original, without alluding to the hypothesis recently started by Maxim Kovalevsky, according to which the partition of the arable and meadow lands among the members of the Mark was preceded by their being cultivated for joint-account by a large patri- archal family community embracing several genera- tions (as exemplified by the still existing South Slavonian Zadruga), and that the partition, later on, took place when the community had increased, so as to become too unwieldy for joint-account manage- ment. Kovalevsky is probably quite right, but the matter is still sub judice. The economic terms used in this work, as far as they are new, agree with those used in the English edition of Marx's “Capital.” We call “production of commodities” that economic phase where articles are produced not only for the use of the producers, but also for purposes of exchange; that is, as commodities, not as use-values. This phase extends from the first beginnings of production for exchange down to our present time; it attains its full development under - capitalist production only, that is, under conditions Introduction. ix where the capitalist, the owner of the means of pro- duction, employs, for wages, labourers, people deprived of all means of production except their own labour- power, and pockets the excess of the selling price of he products over his outlay We divide the history f industrial production since the Middle Ages into free periods: (1) handicraft, small master craftsmen with a few journeymen and apprentices, where each labourer produces the complete article ; (2) manufac- ture, where greater numbers of workmen, grouped in one large establishment, produce the complete article on the principle of division of labour, each workman performing only one partial operation, so that the product is complete only after having passed succes- sively through the hands of all ; (3) modern industry, where the product is produced by machinery driven by power, and where the work of the labourer is limited to superintending and correcting the per- formances of the mechanical agent. I am perfectly aware that the contents of this work will meet with objection from a considerable portion of the British public. But if we Continentals had taken the slightest notice of the prejudices of British respectability," we should be even worse off than we This book defends what we call “historical naterialism,” and the word materialism grates upon he ears of the immense majority of British readers. * Agnosticism ” might be tolerated, but materialism is itterly inadmissible. And yet the original home of all modern materialism, rom the seventeenth century onwards, is England. are. > X Introduction. “Materialism is the natural-born son of Great Britain. Already the British British schoolman, Duns Scotus, asked, 'whether it was impossible for matter to think? “In order to effect this miracle, he took refuge iv God's omnipotence, i.e., he made theology preac materialism. Moreover, he was a nominalist. Nom nalism, the first form of materialism, is chiefly founu among the English schoolmen. “The real progenitor of English materialism is Bacon. To him natural philosophy is the only true philosophy, and physics based upon the experience of the senses is the chiefest part of natural philosophy. Anaxagoras and his homoiomeriæ, Democritus and his atoms, he often quotes as his authorities. According to him the senses are infallible and the source of all knowledge. All science is based on experience, and consists in subjecting the data furnished by the senses to a rational method of investigation. Induction, analysis, comparison, ob- servation, experiment, are the principal forms of such a rational method. Among the qualities inherent in matter, motion is the first and foremost, not only in the form of mechanical and mathematical motion, but chiefly in the form of an impulse, a vital spirit, a tension — or a 'qual,' to use a term of Jacob Böhme's 1-of matter. - 1 “Qual” is a philosophical play upon words. Qual literally means torture, a pain which drives to action of some kind ; at the same time the mystic Böhme puts into the German word something of the meaning of the Latin qualitas; his “ qual” Introduction. xi “In Bacon, its first creator, materialism still occludes ithin itself the germs of a many-sided development. On the one hand, matter, surrounded by a sensuous, poetic glamour, seems to attract man's whole entity by winning smiles. On the other, the aphoristically formulated doctrine pullulates with inconsisten- cies imported from theology. “In its further evolution, materialism becomes one- sided. Hobbes is the man who systematises Baconian materialism. Knowledge based upon the senses loses its poetic blossom, it passes into the abstract expe- rience of the mathematician; geometry is proclaimed as the queen of sciences. Materialism takes to misanthropy. If it is to overcome its opponent, misanthropic, fleshless spiritualism, and that on the latter's own ground, materialism has to chastise its own flesh and turn ascetic. Thus, from a sensual, it basses into an intellectual, entity; but thus, too, it volves all the consistency, regardless of consequences, haracteristic of the intellect. Hobbes, as Bacon's continuator, argues thus : if all human knowledge is furnished by the senses, then our concepts and ideas are but the phantoms, divested of their sensual forms, of the real world. Philosophy can but give names to these phantoms. One name may be applied to more than one of them. There may even be names of names. It would imply a contradiction if, on the one hand, we maintained that I v f 66 was the activating principle arising from, and promoting in its turn, the spontaneous development of the thing, relation, or person subject to it, in contradistinction to a pain inflicted from without. xii Introduction. all ideas had their origin in the world of sensation and, on the other, that a word was more than a worc., that besides the beings known to us by our senses, beings which are one and all individuals, there existed also beings of a general, not individual, nature. An unbodily substance is the same absurdity as an unbodily body. Body, being, substance, are but different terms for the same reality. It is impossible to separate thought from matter that thinks. This matter is the substratum of all changes going on in the world. The word infinite is meaningless, unless it states that our mind is capable of performing an endless process of addition. Only material things being perceptible to us, we cannot know anything about the existence of God. My own existence alone is certain. Every human passion is a mechanical movement which has a beginning and an end. The objects of impulse are what we call good. Man is subject to the same laws as nature. Power and freedom are identical. “Hobbes had systematised Bacon, without, how ever, furnishing a proof for Bacon's fundamenta principle, the origin of all human knowledge from the world of sensation. It was Locke who, in his Essay on the Human Understanding, supplied this proof. “ Hobbes had shattered the theistic prejudices of Baconian materialism; Collins, Dodwall, Coward, Hartley, Priestley similarly shattered the last theological bars that still hemmed-in Locke's sen- sationalism. At all events, for practical material- Introduction. xiii 11 ts, Theism is but an easy-going way of getting rid religion." Thus Karl Marx wrote about the British origin of ..odern materialism. If Englishmen nowadays do not exactly relish the compliment he paid their ancestors, more's the pity. It is none the less un- deniable that Bacon, Hobbes, and Locke are the fathers of that brilliant school of French materialists which made the eighteenth century, in spite of all bat les on land and sea won over Frenchmen by Germans and Englishmen, a pre-eminently French century, even before that crowning French Revolu- tion, the results of which we outsiders, in England as well as in Germany, are still trying to acclimatise. There is no denying it. About the middle of this century, what struck every cultivated foreigner who set up his residence in England, was, what he was then bound to consider the religious bigotry and stupidity of the English respectable middle-class. We, at that time, were all materialists, or, at least, very advanced freethinkers, and to us it appeared inconceivable that almost all educated people in Eng- lani should believe in all sorts of impossible miracles, and that even geologists like Buckland and Mantell should contort the facts of their science so as not to clash too much with the myths of the book of Genesis; while, in order to find people who dared to use their own intellectual faculties with regard to religious matters, you had to go amongst the uneducated, the Marx and Engels, “Die Heilige Familie,” Frankfurt a. M. 1845, pp. 201-204. xiv Introduction. great unwashed,” as they were then called, the wor ing people, especially the Owenite Socialists. But England has been “civilised” since then. T exhibition of 1851 sounded the knell of Engli... insular exclusiveness. England became gradually internationalised, in diet, in manners, in ideas; so much so that I begin to wish that some English manners and customs had made as much headway on the Continent as other continental habits have made here. Anyhow, the introduction and spread of salád- oil (before 1851 known only to the aristocracy) has been accompanied by a fatal spread of continental scepticism in matters religious, and it has come to this, that agnosticism, though not yet considered " the thing ” quite as much as the Church of England, is yet very nearly on a par, as far as respectability goes, with Baptism, and decidedly ranks above the Salvation Army. And I cannot help believing that under these circumstances it will be consoling to many who sincerely regret and condemn this progress of infidelity, to learn that these "new-fangled notions" are not of foreign origin, are not "made in Germany like so many other articles of daily use, but are un- doubtedly Old English, and that their British origina- tors two hundred years ago went a good deal further than their descendants now dare to venture. What, indeed, is agnosticism, but, to use an ex- pressive Lancashire term,"shamefaced” materialism? The agnostic's conception of Nature is materialistic throughout. The entire natural world is governed by law, and absolutely excludes the intervention of Introduction. XV action from without. But, he adds, we have no means either of ascertaining or of disproving the ex- istence of some Supreme Being beyond the known universe. Now, this might hold good at the time when Laplace, to Napoleon's question, why in the great astronomer's Mécanique céleste the Creator was not even mentioned, proudly replied : Je n'avais pas besoin de cette hypothèse. But nowadays, in our evolutionary conception of the universe, there is absolutely no room for either a Creator or a Ruler ; and to talk of a Supreme Being shut out from the whole existing world, implies a contradiction in terms, and, as it seems to me, a gratuitous insult to the feel- ings of religious people. Again, our agnostic admits that all our knowledge is based upon the information imparted to us by our senses. But, he adds, how do we know that our senses give us correct representations of the objects we perceive through them? And he proceeds to inform us that, whenever he speaks of objects or their qualities, he does in reality not mean these objects and qualities, of which he cannot know anything for certain, but merely the impressions which they have produced on his senses. Now, this line of reasoning seems undoubtedly hard to beat by mere argumenta- tion. But before there was argumentation, there was action. Im Anfang war die That. And human action had solved the difficulty long before human ingenuity invented it. The proof of the pudding is in the eating. From the moment we turn to our own use these objects, according to the qualities we per- xvi Introduction. ness a ceive in them, we put to an infallible test the correct- or otherwise of our sense- perceptions. If these perceptions have been wrong, then our estimate of the use to which an object can be turned must also be wrong, and our attempt must fail. But if we succeed in accomplishing our aim, if we find that the object does agree with our idea of it, and does answer the purpose we intended it for, then that is positive proof that our perceptions of it and of its qualities, so far, agree with reality outside ourselves. And when- ever we find ourselves face to face with a failure, then we generally are not long in making out the cause that made us fail ; we find that the perception upon which we acted was either incomplete and superficial, or combined with the results of other perceptions in a way not warranted by them—what we call defective reasoning. So long as we take care to train and to use our senses properly, and to keep our action within the limits prescribed by perceptions properly made and properly used, so long we shall find that the result of our action proves the conformity of our per- ceptions with the objective nature of the things perceived. Not in one single instance, so far, have we been led to the conclusion that our sense-percep- tions, scientifically controlled, induce in our minds ideas respecting the outer world that are, by their very nature, at variance with reality, or that there is an inherent incompatibility between the outer world and our sense-perceptions of it. But then come the Neo-Kantian agnostics and say : We may correctly perceive the qualities of a thing, Introduction. xvii but we cannot by any sensible or mental process grasp the thing in itself. This “thing in itself” is beyond our ken. To this Hegel, long since, has replied : If you know all the qualities of a thing, you know the thing itself; nothing remains but the fact that the said thing exists without us ; and when your senses have taught you that fact, you have grasped the last remnant of the thing in itself, Kant's celebrated unknowable Ding an sich. To which it may be added, that in Kant's time our knowledge of natural objects was indeed so fragmentary that he might well suspect, behind the little we knew about each of them, a mysterious “thing in itself.” But one after another these ungraspable things have been grasped, analysed, and, what is more, reproduced by the giant progress of science; and what we can pro- duce, we certainly cannot consider as unknowable. To the chemistry of the first half of this century organic substances were such mysterious objects; now, we learn to build them up one after another from their chemical elements without the aid of organic processes. Modern chemists declare that as soon as the chemical constitution of no matter what body is known, it can be built up from its elements. We are still far from knowing the constitution of the highest organic sub- stances, the albuminous bodies ; but there is no reason why we should not, if only after centuries, arrive at that knowledgeand, armed with it, produce artificialalbumen. But if we arrive at that, we shall at the same time have produced organic life, for life, from its lowest to its highest forms, is but the normal mode of existence of albuminous bodies, 3 xviii Introduction. As soon, however, as our agnostic has made these formal mental reservations, he talks and acts as the rank materialist he at bottom is. He may say that, as far as we know, matter and motion, or as it is now called, energy, can neither be created nor destroyed, but that we have no proof of their not having been created at some time or other. But if you try to use this admission against him in any particular case, he will quickly put you out of court. If he admits the possibility of spiritualism in abstracto, he will have none of it in concreto. As far as we know and can know, he will tell you there is no Creator and no Ruler of the universe; as far as we are concerned, matter and energy can neither be created nor annihilated; for us, mind is a mode of energy, a , function of the brain ; all we know is that the material world is governed by immutable laws, and so forth. Thus, as far as he is a scientific man, as far as he knows anything, he is a materialist; outside his science, in spheres about which he knows nothing, he translates his ignorance into Greek and calls it agnosticism. At all events, one thing seems clear: even if I was an agnostic, it is evident that I could not describe the conception of history sketched out in this little book, as “historical agnosticism.” Religious people . would laugh at me, agnostics would indignantly ask, was I going to make fun of them ? And thus I hope even British respectability will not be overshocked if I use, in English as well as in so many other languages, the term, “historical materialism,” to designate that 9 Introduction. xix view of the course of history, which seeks the ultimate cause and the great moving power of all important historic events in the economic development of society, in the changes in the modes of production and ex- change, in the consequent division of society into dis- tinct classes, and in the struggles of these classes against one another. This indulgence will perhaps be accorded to me all the sooner if I show that historical materialism may be of advantage even to British respectability. I have mentioned the fact, that about forty or fifty years ago, any cultivated foreigner settling in England was struck by what he was then bound to consider the religious bigotry and stupidity of the English respect- able middle-class. I am now going to prove that the respectable English middle-class of that time was not quite as stupid as it looked to the intelligent foreigner. Its religious leanings can be explained. When Europe emerged from the Middle Ages, the rising middle-class of the towns constituted its revolu- tionary element. It had conquered a recognised position within mediæval feudal organisation, but this position, also, had become too narrow for its expansive power. The development of the middle-class, the bourgeoisie, became incompatible with the mainten- ance of the feudal system; the feudal system, there- fore, had to fall. But the great international centre of feudalism was the Roman Catholic Church. It united the whole of feudalised Western Europe, in spite of all internal wars, into one grand political system, opposed as much XX Introduction. to the schismatic Greeks as to the Mohammedan countries. It surrounded feudal institutions with the halo of divine consecration. It had organised its own hierarchy on the feudal model, and, lastly, it was itself by far the most powerful feudal lord, holding, as it did, fully one-third of the soil of the Catholic world. Before profane feudalism could be successfully attacked in each country and in detail, this, its sacred central organisation, had to be destroyed. Moreover, parallel with the rise of the middle-class went on the great revival of science; astronomy, mechanics, physics, anatomy, physiology, were again cultivated. And the bourgeoisie, for the development of its industrial production, required a science which ascertained the physical properties of natural objects and the modes of action of the forces of Nature. Now up to then science had but been the humble handmaid of the Church, had not been allowed to overstep the limits set by faith, and for that reason had been no science at all. Science rebelled against the Church; the bourgeoisie could not do without science, and, therefore, had to join in the rebellion. The above, though touching but two of the points where the rising middle-class was bound to come into collision with the established religion, will be sufficient to show, first, that the class most directly interested in the struggle against the pretensions of the Roman Church was the bourgeoisie; and second, that every struggle against feudalism, at that time, had to take on a religious disguise, had to be directed against the Church in the first instance. But if the universities Introduction. xxi and the traders of the cities started the cry, it was sure to find, and did find, a strong echo in the masses of the country people, the peasants, who everywhere had to struggle for their very existence with their feudal lords, spiritual and temporal. The long fight of the bourgeoisie against feudalism culminated in three great, decisive battles. The first was what is called the Protestant Reforma- tion in Germany. The war-cry raised against the Church by Luther was responded to by two insurrec- tions of a political nature: first, that of the lower nobility under Franz von Sickingen (1523), then the great Peasants' War, 1525. Both were defeated, chiefly in consequence of the indecision of the parties most interested, the burghers of the towns-an indecision into the causes of which we cannot here enter. From that moment the struggle degenerated into a fight between the local princes and the central power, and ended by blotting out Germany, for two hundred years, from the politically active nations of Europe, The Lutheran reformation produced a new creed in- deed, a religion adapted to absolute monarchy. No sooner were the peasants of North-east Germany converted to Lutheranism than they were from free- men reduced to serfs. But where Luther failed, Calvin won the day. Calvin's creed was one fit for the boldest of the bourgeoisie of his time. His predestination doctrine was the religious expression of the fact that in the commercial world of competition success or failure does not depend upon a man's activity or cleverness, but xxii Introduction. upon circumstances uncontrollable by him. It is not of him that willeth or of him that runneth, but of the mercy of unknown superior economic powers; and this was especially true at a period of economic revolu- tion, when all old commercial routes and centres were replaced by new ones, when India and America were opened to the world, and when even the most sacred economic articles of faith—the value of gold and silver -began to totter and to break down. Calvin's church constitution was thoroughly democratic and republican; and where the kingdom of God was republicanised, could the kingdoms of this world remain subject to monarchs, bishops, and lords ? While German Luther- anism became a willing tool in the hands of princes, Calvinisın founded a republic in Holland, and active republican parties in England, and, above all, Scot- land. In Calvinism, the second great bourgeois upheaval found its doctrine ready cut and dried. This up- heaval took place in England. The middle-class of the towns brought it on, and the yeomanry of the country districts fought it out. Curiously enough, in all the three great bourgeois risings, the peasantry furnishes the army that has to do the fighting; and the peasantry is just the class that, the victory once gained, is most surely ruined by the economic con- sequences of that victory. A hundred years after Cromwell, the yeomanry of England had almost disappeared. Anyhow, had it not been for that yeomanry and for the plebeian element in the towns, the bourgeoisie alone would never have fought the Introduction. xxiii matter out to the bitter end, and would never have brought Charles I. to the scaffold. In order to secure even those conquests of the bourgeoisie that were ripe for gathering at the time, the revolution had to be carried considerably further-exactly as in 1793 in France and 1848 in Germany. This seems, in fact, to be one of the laws of evolution of bourgeois society. Well, upon this excess of revolutionary activity there necessarily followed the inevitable reaction which in its turn went beyond the point where it might have maintained itself. After a series of oscillations, the new centre of gravity was at last attained and became a new starting-point. The grand period of English history, known to respectability under the name of “the Great Rebellion,” and the struggles succeeding it, were brought to a close by the comparatively puny event entitled by Liberal historians, “the Glorious Revolution.” The new starting-point was a compromise between the rising middle-class and the ex-feudal landowners. The latter, though called, as now, the aristocracy, had been long since on the way which led them to be- come what Louis Philippe in France became at a much later period, “the first bourgeois of the king- dom.” Fortunately for England, the old feudal barons had killed one another during the Wars of the Roses. Their successors, though mostly scions of the old families, had been so much out of the direct line of descent that they constituted quite a new body, with habits and tendencies 'far more bourgeois 2 xxiv Introduction. than feudal. They fully understood the value of money, and at once began to increase their rents by turning hundreds of small farmers out and replacing them by sheep. Henry VIII., while squandering the Church lands, created fresh bourgeois landlords by wholesale; the innumerable confiscations of estates, re- granted to absolute or relative upstarts, and continued during the whole of the seventeenth century, had the same result. Consequently, ever since Henry VII., the English "aristocracy,” far from counteracting the development of industrial production, had, on the contrary, sought to indirectly profit thereby ; and there had always been a section of the great land- owners willing, from economical or political reasons, to co-operate with the leading men of the financial and industrial bourgeoisie. The compromise of 1689 was, therefore, easily accomplished. The political spoils of “pelf and place” were left to the great land- owning families, provided the economic interests of the financial, manufacturing, and commercial middle- class were sufficiently attended to. And these economic interests were at that time powerful enough to determine the general policy of the nation. There might be squabbles about matters of detail, but, on the whole, the aristocratic oligarchy knew too well that its own economic prosperity was irretrievably bound up with that of the industrial and commercial middle-class. From that time, the bourgeoisie was a humble, but still a recognised component of the ruling classes of England. With the rest of them, it had a common G ") Introduction. XXV interest in keeping in subjection the great working mass of the nation. The merchant or manufacturer himself stood in the position of master, or, as it was until lately called, of “natural superior” to his clerks, his workpeople, his domestic servants. His interest was to get as much and as good work out of them as he could ; for this end they had to be trained to proper submission. He was himself religious ; his religion had supplied the standard under which he had fought the king and the lords; he was not long in discovering the opportunities this same religion offered him for working upon the minds of his natural inferiors, and making them submissive to the behests of the masters it had pleased God to place over them. In short, the English bourgeoisie now had to take a part in keeping down the “lower orders,” the great producing mass of the nation, and one of the means employed for that purpose was the influence of religion. There was another fact that contributed to strengthen the religious leanings of the bourgeoisie. That was the rise of materialism in England. This new doctrine not only shocked the pious feelings of the middle-class; it announced itself as a philosophy only fit for scholars and cultivated men of the world, in contrast to religion which was good enough for the uneducated masses, including the bourgeoisie. With Hobbes it stepped on the stage as a defender of royal prerogative and omnipotence; it called upon absolute monarchy to keep down that puer robustus sed malitiosus, to wit, the people. Similarly, with the Xxvi Introduction. successors of Hobbes, with Bolingbroke, Shaftesbury, etc., the new deistic form of materialism remained an aristocratic, esoteric doctrine, and, therefore, hateful to the middle-class both for its religious heresy and for its anti-bourgeois political connexions. Accord- ingly, in opposition to the materialism and deism of the aristocracy, those Protestant sects which had fur- nished the flag and the fighting contingent against the Stuarts, continued to furnish the main strength of the progressive middle-class, and form even to-day the backbone of “the Great Liberal Party.” In the meantime materialism passed from England to France, where it met and coalesced with another materialistic school of philosophers, a branch of Cartesianism. In France, too, it remained at first an exclusively aristocratic doctrine. But soon its revo- lutionary character asserted itself. The French materialists did not limit their criticism to matters of religious belief; they extended it to whatever scientific tradition or political institution they met with ; and to prove the claim of their doctrine to universal appli- cation, they took the shortest cut, and boldly applied it to all subjects of knowledge in the giant work after which they were named—the Encyclopédie. Thus, in one or the other of its two forms—avowed materialism or deism-it became the creed of the whole cultured youth of France; so much so that, when the great Revolution broke out, the doctrine hatched by English Royalists gave a theoretical flag to French Republicans and Terrorists, and furnished the text for the Declaration of the Rights of Man. Introduction. xxvii The great French Revolution was the third uprising of the bourgeoisie, but the first that had entirely cast off the religious cloak, and was fought out on undis- guised political lines; it was the first, too, that was really fought out up to the destruction of one of the combatants, the aristocracy, and the complete triumph of the other, the bourgeoisie. In England the con- tinuity of pre-revolutionary and post-revolutionary institutions, and the compromise between landlords and capitalists, found its expression in the continuity of judicial precedents and in the religious preservation of the feudal forms of the law. In France the Revolu- tion constituted a complete breach with the traditions of the past ; it cleared out the very last vestiges of feudalism, and created in the Code Civil a masterly adaptation of the old Roman law—that almost perfect expression of the juridical relations corresponding to the economic stage called by Marx the production of commodities—to modern capitalistic conditions; so masterly that this French revolutionary code still serves as a model for reforms of the law of property in all other countries, not excepting England. Let us, however, not forget that if English law continues to express. the economic relations of capitalistic society in that barbarous feudal language which corresponds to the thing expressed, just as English spelling corresponds to English pronunciation—Vous écrivez Londres et vous prononcez Constantinople, said a Frenchman--that same English law is the only one which has preserved through ages, and transmitted to America and the Colonies the best part of that old xxviii Introduction. Germanic personal freedom, local self-government, and independence from all interference but that of the law courts, which on the Continent has been lost during the period of absolute monarchy, and has nowhere been as yet fully recovered. To return to our British bourgeois. The French Revolution gave him a splendid opportunity, with the help of the Continental monarchies, to destroy French maritime commerce, to annex French colonies, and to crush the last French pretensions to maritime rivalry. That was one reason why he fought it. Another was that the ways of this revolution went very much against his grain. Not only its "execrable " terror- ism, but the very attempt to carry bourgeois rule to extremes. What should the British bourgeois do without his aristocracy, that taught him manners, such as they were, and invented fashions for him- that furnished officers for the army, which kept order at home, and the navy, which conquered colonial possessions and new markets abroad ? There was indeed a progressive minority of the bourgeoisie, that minority whose interests were not so well attended to under the compromise ; this section, composed chiefly of the less wealthy middle-class, did sympathise with the Revolution, but it was powerless in Parliament. Thus, if materialism became the creed of the French Revolution, the God-fearing English bourgeois held all the faster to his religion. Had not the reign of terror in Paris proved what was the upshot, if the religious instincts of the masses were lost ? The more materialism spread from France to neighbour- Introduction. xxix ing countries, and was reinforced by similar doctrinal currents, notably by German philosophy, the more, in fact, materialism and freethought generally became, on the Continent, the necessary qualifications of a cultivated man, the more stubbornly the English middle-class stuck to its manifold religious creeds. These creeds might differ from one another, but they were, all of them, distinctly religious, Christian creeds. While the Revolution ensured the political triumph of the bourgeoisie in France, in England Watt, Ark- wright, Cartwright, and others, initiated an industrial revolution, which completely shifted the centre of gravity of economic power. . The wealth of the bourgeoisie increased considerably faster than that of the landed aristocracy. Within the bourgeoisie itself, the financial aristocracy, the bankers, etc., were more and more pushed into the background by the manu- facturers. The compromise of 1689, even after the gradual changes it had undergone in favour of the bourgeoisie, no longer corresponded to the relative position of the parties to it. The character of these parties, too, had changed ; the bourgeoisie of 1830 was very different from that of the preceding century. The political power still left to the aristocracy, and used by them to resist the pretensions of the new industrial bourgeoisie, became incompatible with the new economic interests. A fresh struggle with the aristocracy was necessary; it could end only in a victory of the new economic power. First, the Reform Act was pushed through, in spite of all re- sistance, under the impulse of the French Revolution XXX Introduction. of 1830. It gave to the bourgeoisie a recognised and powerful place in Parliament. Then the Repeal of the. Corn Laws, which settled, once for all, the supremacy of the bourgeoisie, and especially of its most active portion, the manufacturers, over the landed aristocracy. This was the greatest victory of the bourgeoisie ; it was, however, also the last it gained in its own exclusive interest. Whatever triumphs it obtained later on, it had to share with a new social power, first its ally, but soon its rival. The industrial revolution had created a class of large manufacturing capitalists, but also a class—and a far more numerous one-of manufacturing work- people. This class gradually increased in numbers, in proportion as the industrial revolution seized upon one branch of manufacture after another, and in the same proportion it increased in power. This power it proved as early as 1824, by forcing a reluctant Parliament to repeal the acts forbidding combinations of workmen. During the Reform agitation, the working-men constituted the Radical wing of the Reform party; the Act of 1832 having excluded them from the suffrage, they formulated their de- mands in the People's Charter, and constituted them- selves, in opposition to the great bourgeois Anti- Corn Law party, into an independent party, the Chartists, the first working-men's party of modern times. Then came the Continental revolutions of February and March, 1848, in which the working people played such a prominent part, and, at least in Paris, put for- * Introduction. xxxi ward demands which were certainly inadmissible from the point of view of capitalist society. And then came the general reaction. First the defeat of the Chartists on the roth April, 1848, then the crushing of the Paris working-men's insurrection in June of the same year, then the disasters of 1849 in Italy, Hun- gary, South Germany, and at last the victory of Louis Bonaparte over Paris, 2nd December, 1851. For a time, at least, the bugbear of working-class preten- sions was put down, but at what cost! If the British bourgeois had been convinced before of the necessity of maintaining the common people in a religious mood, how much more must he feel that necessity after all these experiences ? Regardless of the sneers of his Continental compeers, he continued to spend thousands and tens of thousands, year after year, upon the evangelisation of the lower orders ; not content with his own native religious machinery, he appealed to Brother Jonathan, the greatest organiser in exist- ence of religion as a trade, and imported from America revivalism, Moody and Sankey, and the like; and, finally, he accepted the dangerous aid of the Salvation Army, which revives the propaganda of early Christianity, appeals to the poor as the elect, fights capitalism in a religious way, and thus fosters an element of early Christian class antagonism, which one day may become troublesome to the well-to-do people who now find the ready money for it. It seems a law of historical development that the bourgeoisie can in no European country get hold of political power—at least for any length of time-in -- xxxii Introduction. the same exclusive way in which the feudal aristo- cracy kept hold of it during the Middle Ages. Even in France, where feudalism was completely extin- guished, the bourgeoisie, as a whole, has held full possession of the Government for very short periods only. During Louis Philippe's reign, 1830-48, a very . small portion of the bourgeoisie ruled the kingdom ; by far the larger part were excluded from the suffrage by the high qualification. Under the second Re- public, 1848-51, the whole bourgeoisie ruled, but for three years only; their incapacity brought on the second Empire. It is only now, in the third Republic, , that the bourgeoisie as a whole have kept possession of the helm for more than twenty years; and they are already showing lively signs of decadence. A A durable reign of the bourgeoisie has been possible only in countries like America, where feudalism was unknown, and society at the very beginning started from a bourgeois basis. And even in France and America, the successors of the bourgeoisie, the work- ing people, are already knocking at the door. In England, the bourgeoisie never held undivided sway. Even the victory of 1832 left the landed aris- tocracy in almost exclusive possession of all the leading Government offices. The meekness with which the wealthy middle-class submitted to this, remained inconceivable to me until the great Liberal manufacturer, Mr. W. A. Forster, in a public speech implored the young men of Bradford to learn French, as a means to get on in the world, and quoted from his own experience how sheepish he looked when, as Introduction. xxxiii a Cabinet Minister, he had to move in society where French was, at least, as necessary as English! The fact was, the English middle-class of that time were, as a rule, quite uneducated upstarts, and could not help leaving to the aristocracy those superior Govern- ment places where other qualifications were required than mere insular narrowness and insular conceit, seasoned by business sharpness. Even now the end- less newspaper debates about middle-class education show that the English middle-class does not yet con- 1 And even in business matters, the conceit of national Chauvinism is but a sorry adviser. Up to quite recently, the average English manufacturer considered it derogatory from an Englishman to speak any language but his own, and felt rather proud than otherwise of the fact that “poor devils” of foreigners settled in England and took off his hands the trouble of dispos- ing of his products abroad. He never noticed that these foreign- ers, mostly Germans, thus got command of a very large part of British foreign trade, imports and exports, and that the direct foreign trade of Englishmen became limited, almost entirely, to the colonies, China, the United States, and South America. Nor did he notice that these Germans traded with other Ger- mans abroad, who gradually organised a complete network of commercial colonies all over the world. But when Germany, about forty years ago, seriously began manufacturing for export, this network served her admirably in her transformation, in so short a time, from a corn-exporting into a first-rate manufactur- ing country. Then, about ten years ago, the British manufac- turer got frightened, and asked his ambassadors and consuls how it was that he could no longer keep his customers together. The unanimous answer was: (1) You don't learn your customer's language but expect him to speak your own; (2) You don't even try to suit your customer's wants, habits, and tastes, but expect him to conform to your English ones. xxxiv Introduction. sider itself good enough for the best education, and looks to something more modest. Thus, even after the Repeal of the Corn Laws, it appeared a matter of course, that the men who had carried the day, the Cobdens, Brights, Forsters, etc., should remain ex- cluded from a share in the official government of the country, until twenty years afterwards, a new Reform Act opened to them the door of the Cabinet. The English bourgeoisie are, up to the present day, so deeply penetrated by a sense of their social inferiority that they keep up, at their own expense and that of the nation, an ornamental caste of drones to repre- sent the nation worthily at all State functions; and they consider themselves highly honoured whenever one of themselves is found worthy of admission into this select and privileged body, manufactured, after all, by themselves. The industrial and commercial middle-class had, therefore, not yet succeeded in driving the landed aristocracy completely from political power when another competitor, the working-class, appeared on the stage. The reaction after the Chartist movement and the Continental revolutions, as well as the un- paralleled extension of English trade from 1848-1866, (ascribed vulgarly to Free Trade alone, but due far more to the colossal development of railways, ocean steamers, and means of intercourse generally), had again driven the working-class into the dependency of the Liberal party, of which they formed, as in pre-Chartist times, the Radical wing. Their claims to the franchise, however, gradually became irresistible; while the Introduction, XXXV а. Whig leaders of the Liberals "funked," Disraeli showed his superiority by making the Tories seize the favourable moment and introduce household suffrage in the boroughs, along with a redistribution of seats. Then followed the ballot; then in 1884 the extension of household suffrage to the counties and a fresh redistribution of seats, by which electoral districts were to some extent equalised. All these measures considerably increased the electoral power of the working-class, so much so that in at least 150 to 200 constituencies that class now furnishes the majority of voters. But parliamentary government is a capital school for teaching respect for tradition; if the middle-class look with awe and veneration upon what Lord John Manners playfully called “our old nobility,” the mass of the working-people then looked up with respect and deference to what used to be designated “their betters," the middle-class. Indeed, the British workman, some fifteen years ago, was the model workman, whose respectful regard for the position of his master, and whose self-restraining modesty in claiming rights for himself, consoled our German economists of the Katheder-Socialist school for the incurable communistic and revolutionary tendencies of their own working-men at home. But the English middle-class-good men of business as they are-saw farther than the German professors. They had shared their power but reluctantly with the working-class. They had learnt, during the Chartist years, what that puer robustus sed malitiosus, the people, is capable of. And since that time, they had > as xxxvi Introduction. been compelled to incorporate the better part of the People's Charter in the Statutes of the United King- dom. Now, if ever, the people must be kept in order by moral means, and the first and foremost of all moral means of action upon the masses is and remains-religion. Hence the parsons' majorities on the School Boards, hence the increasing self- taxation of the bourgeoisie for the support of all sorts of revivalism, from ritualism to the Salvation Army. And now came the triumph of British respectabil- ity over the freethought and religious laxity of the Continental bourgeois. The workmen of France and Germany had become rebellious. They were thoroughly infected with socialism, and, for very good reasons, were not at all particular as to the legality of the means by which to secure their own ascendency. The puer robustus, here, turned from day to day more malitiosus. Nothing remained to the French and Ger- man bourgeoisie as a last resource but to silently drop their freethought, as a youngster, when sea-sickness creeps upon him, quietly drops the burning cigar he brought swaggeringly on board ; one by one, the scoffers turned pious in outward behaviour, spoke with respect of the Church, its dogmas and rites, and even conformed with the latter as far as could not be helped. French bourgeoisie dined maigre on Fridays, and German ones sat out long Protestant sermons in their pews on Sundays. They had come to grief with materialism. “Die Religion muss dem Volk erhalten werden,”—religion must be kept alive for the people- that was the only and the last means to save society (6 Introduction. xxxvii from utter ruin. Unfortunately for thernselves, they did not find this out until they had done their level best to break up religion for ever. And now it was the turn of the British bourgeois to sneer and to say: “Why, you fools, I could have told you that two hundred years ago !” However, I am afraid neither the religious stolidity of the British, nor the post festum conversion of the Continental bourgeois will stem the rising Proletarian tide. Tradition is a great retarding force, is the vis inertiæ of history, but, being merely passive, is sure to be broken down ; and thus religion will be no lasting safeguard to capitalist society. If our juridical, philo- sophical, and religious ideas are the more or less remote offshoots of the economical relations prevailing in a given society, such ideas cannot, in the long run, withstand the effects of a complete change in these relations. And, unless we believe in supernatural revelation, we must admit that no religious tenets will ever suffice to prop up a tottering society. In fact, in England too, the working-people have begun to move again. They are, no doubt, shackled by traditions of various kinds. Bourgeois traditions, such as the widespread belief that there can be but two parties, Conservatives and Liberals, and that the working-class must work out its salvation by and through the great Liberal party. Working-men's traditions, inherited from their first tentative efforts at independent action, such as the exclusion, from ever so many old Trade Unions, of all applicants who have not gone through a regular apprenticeship; which xxxviii Introduction. means the breeding, by every such union, of its own blacklegs. But for all that the English working-class is moving, as even Professor Brentano has sorrowfully had to report to his brother Katheder-Socialists. It moves, like all things in England, with a slow and measured step, with hesitation here, with more or less unfruitful, tentative attempts there; it moves now and then with an over-cautious mistrust of the name of Socialism, while it gradually absorbs the substance ; and the movement spreads and seizes one layer of the workers after another. It has now shaken out of their torpor the unskilled labourers of the East End of London, and we all know what a splendid impulse these fresh forces have given it in return. And if the pace of the movement is not up to the impatience of some people, let them not forget that it is the working- class which keeps alive the finest qualities of the English character, and that, if a step in advance is once gained in England, it is, as a rule, never lost afterwards. If the sons of the old Chartists, for reasons explained above, were not quite up to the mark, the grandsons bid fair to be worthy of their forefathers. But the triumph of the European working-class does not depend upon England alone. It can only be secured by the co-operation of, at least, England, France, and Germany. In both the latter countries the working-class movement is well ahead of England. In Germany it is even within measurable distance of success. The progress it has there made during the last twenty-five years is unparalleled. It advances with ever-increasing velocity. If the German middle- Introduction. xxxix class have shown themselves lamentably deficient in political capacity, discipline, courage, energy, and perseverance, the German working-class have given ample proof of all these qualities. Four hundred years ago, Germany was the starting-point of the first upheaval of the European middle-class; as things are now, is it outside the limits of pos- sibility that Germany will be the scene, too, of the first great victory of the European proletariat ? F. ENGELS. April 20th, 1892. SOCIALISM: UTOPIAN AND SCIENTIFIC. I. 2. MODERN SOCIALISM is, in its essence, the direct product of the recognition, on the one hand, of the class antagonisms, existing in the society 1, of to-day, between proprietors and non-pro- prietors, between capitalists and wage-workers; on the other hand, of the anarchy existing in production. But, in its theoretical form, modern Socialism originally appears ostensibly as a more logical extension of the principles laid down by the great French philosophers of the eighteenth century. Like every new theory, modern Socialism had, at first, to connect itself with the intellectual stock-in- trade ready to its hand, /however_deeply its roots lay in material economic facts. The great men, who in France prepared А 2 Socialism : men's minds for the coming revolution, were themselves extreme revolutionists. They re- cognised no external authority of any kind whatever. Religion, natural science, society, political institutions, everything, was subjected to the most unsparing criticism : everything must justify its existence before the judgment- seat of reason, or give up existence. Reason became the sole measure of everything. It was the time when, as Hegel says, the world stood upon its head ; 1 first, in the sense that 1 This is the passage on the French Revolution : Thought, the concept of law, all at once made itself felt, and against this the old scaffolding of wrong could make no stand. In this conception of law, therefore, a constitu- tion has now been established, and henceforth everything must be based upon this. Since the sun had been in the firmament, and the planets circled round him, the sight had never been seen of man standing upon his head-i.e., on the Idea—and building reality after this image. Anaxagoras first said that the Nous, reason, rules the world; but now, for the first time, had man come to recognise that the Idea must rule the mental reality. And this was a magnificent sunrise. All thinking Beings have participated in celebrat- ing this holy day. A sublime emotion swayed men at that time, an enthusiasm of reason pervaded the world, as if now had come the reconciliation of the Divine Principle with the world.” [Hegel : “ Philosophy of History," 1840, : Utopian and Scientific. 3 the human head, and the principles arrived at by its thought, claimed to be the basis of all human action and association ; but by and by, also, in the wider sense that the reality which was in contradiction to these principles had, in fact, to be turned upside down. Every form of society and government then exist- ing, every old traditional notion was flung into the lumber-room as irrational ; the world had hitherto allowed itself to be led solely by prejudices; everything in the past deserved only pity and contempt. Now, for the first time, appeared the light of day, the kingdom of reason; henceforth superstition, injustice, privilege, oppression, were to be superseded by eternal truth, eternal Right, equality based on Nature and the inalienable rights of man. We know to-day that this kingdom of reason was nothing more than the idealised kingdom of the bourgeoisie; that this eternal Right found its realisation in bourgeois justice; that this equality reduced itself to bourgeois equality before the law; that bourgeois property was p. 535.] Is it not high time to set the anti-Socialist law in action against such teachings, subversive and to the common danger, by the late Professor Hegel ? 4 Socialism : proclaimed as one of the essential rights of man; and that the government of reason, the Contrat Social of Rousseau, came into being, and only could come into being, as a demo- cratic bourgeois republic. The great thinkers of the eighteenth century could, no more than their predecessors, go beyond the limits im- posed upon them by their epoch. But, side by side with the antagonism of the feudal nobility and the burghers, who claimed to represent all the rest of society, was the general antagonism of exploiters and exploited, of rich idlers and poor workers. It was this very circumstance that made it possible for the representatives of the bourgeoisie to put them- selves forward as representing, not one special class, but the whole of suffering humanity. Still further. From its origin, the bourgeoisie was saddled with its antithesis : capitalists cannot exist without wage-workers, and, in the same proportion as the mediæval burgher of the guild developed into the modern bour- geois, the guild journeyman and the day- labourer, outside the guilds, developed into the proletarian And although, upon the whole, the bourgeoisie, in their struggle with Utopian and Scientific. 5 the nobility, could claim to represent at the same time the interests of the different working-classes of that period, yet in every great bourgeois movement there were inde- pendent outbursts of that class which was the forerunner, more or less developed, of the modern proletariat. For example, at the time of the German reformation and the peasants' war, the Anabaptists and Thomas Münzer ; in the great English revolution, the Levellers ; in the great French revolution, Babeuf. There were theoretical enunciations cor- responding with these revolutionary upris- ings of a class not yet developed ; in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries, Utopian pictures of ideal social conditions ; in the eighteenth, actual communistic theories (Mor elly and Mably). The demand for equality no longer limited to political rights; it was extended also to the social conditions of individuals. It was not simply class privileges that were to be abolished, but class distinctions themselves. A Communism, as- cetic, denouncing all the pleasures of life, Spartan, was the first form of the new teaching, Then came the three great Utopians : Saint was 6 Socialism : Simon, to whom the middle-class movement, side by side with the proletarian, still had a cer- tain significance; Fourier; and Owen, who in the country where capitalist production was most de- veloped, and under the influence of the antagon- isms begotten of this, worked out his proposals for the removal of class distinction systemati- cally and in direct relation to French materialism. One thing is common to all three. Not one of them appears as a representative of the interests of that proletariat, which historical development had, in the meantime, produced. Like the French philosophers, they do not claim to emancipate a particular class to begin with, but all humanity at once. Like them, they wish to bring in the kingdom of reason and eternal justice, but this kingdom, as they see it, is as far as heaven from earth, from that of the French philosophers. For, to our three social reformers, the bourgeois world, based upon the principles of these philosophers, is quite as irrational and unjust, and, therefore, finds its way to the dust-hole quite as readily as feudalism and all the earlier stages of society. If pure ſeason and justice have not, hitherto, ruled Utopian and Scientific. 7 ✓ the world, this has been the case only because men have not rightly understood them. What was wanted was the individual man of genius, who has now arisen and who understands the truth. That he has now arisen, that the truth has now been clearly understood, is not an inevitable event, following of necessity in the chain of historical development, but a mere happy accident. He might just as well have been born 500 years earlier, and might then have spared humanity 500 years of error, , strife, and suffering. We saw how the French philosophers of the eighteenth century, the forerunners of the Re- volution, appealed to reason as the sole judge of all that is. A rational government, rational society, were to be founded ; everything that ran counter to eternal reason was to be re- morselessly done away with. We saw also that this eternal reason was in reality nothing but the idealised understanding of the eighteenth century citizen, just then evolving into the bourgeois. The French Revolution had real- ised this rational society and government. But the new order of things, rational enough as compared with earlier conditions, turned 8 Socialism : out to be by no means absolutely rational. The State based upon reason completely collapsed. Rousseau's. Contrat Social had found its realisation in the Reign of Terror, from which the bourgeoisie, who had lost con- fidence in their own political capacity, had taken refuge first in the corruption of the Directorate, and, finally, under the wing of the Napoleonic despotism. The promised eternal peace was turned into an endless war of con- quest. The society based upon reason had fared no better. The antagonism between rich and poor, instead of dissolving into general prosperity, had become intensified by the re- moval of the guild and other privileges, which had to some extent bridged it over, and by the removal of the charitable institutions of the Church. The freedom of property” from feudal fetters, now veritably accomplished, turned out to be, for the small capitalists and small proprietors, the freedom to sell their small property, crushed under the overmaster- ing competition of the large capitalists and landlords, to these great lords, and thus, as far as the small capitalists and peasant pro- prietors were concerned, became “freedom Utopian and Scientific. 9 from property.” The development of industry upon a capitalistic basis made poverty and misery of the working masses conditions of existence of society. Cash payment became more and more, in Carlyle's phrase, the sole nexus between man and man. The number of crimes increased from year to year. Formerly, the feudal vices had openly stalked about in broad daylight ; though not eradicated, they were now at any rate thrust into the background. In their stead, the bourgeois vices, hitherto practised in secret, began to blossom all the more luxuriantly. Trade became to a greater and greater extent cheating. The fraternity” of the revolutionary motto was realised in the chicanery and rivalries of the battle of competition. Oppression by force was replaced by corruption; the sword, as the first social lever, by gold. The right of the first night was transferred from the feudal lords to the bourgeois manufacturers. Prosti- tution increased to an extent never heard of. Marriage itself remained, as before, the legally recognised form, the official cloak of prostitu- tion, and, moreover, was supplemented by rich crops of adultery. 66 IO Socialism: reason In a word, compared with the splendid promises of the philosophers, the social and political institutions born of the "triumph of were bitterly disappointing carica- tures. All that was wanting was the men to formulate this disappointment, and they came with the turn of the century. In 1802 Saint Simon's Geneva letters appeared ; in 1808 appeared Fourier's first work, although the groundwork of his theory dated from 1799 ; on January 1, 1800, Robert Owen undertook the direction of New Lanark. At this time, however, the capitalist mode of production, and with it the antagonism be- tween the bourgeoisie and the proletariat, was still very incompletely developed. Modern Industry, which had just arisen in England, was still unknown in France. But Modern Industry develops, on the one hand, the conflicts which make absolutely necessary a'] revolution in the mode of production, and the doing away with its capitalistic character—-con- flicts not only between the classes begotten of it, but also between the very productive forces and the forms of exchange created by it. And, on the other hand, it develops, in these very Utopian and Scientific. 23 The answer was clear. It had been used to pay the proprietors of the establishment 5 per cent. on the capital they had laid out, in addi- tion to over £300,000 clear profit. And that which held for New Lanark held to a still greater extent for all the factories in England. “If this new wealth had not been created by machinery, imperfectly as it has been applied, the wars of Europe, in opposition to Napoleon, and to support the aristocratic principles of society, could not have been maintained. And yet this new power was the creation of the working-classes."1 To them, therefore, the fruits of this new power belonged. The newly - created gigantic productive forces, hitherto used only to enrich individuals and to enslave the masses, offered to Owen the foundations for a reconstruction of society ; they were destined, as the common property of all, to be worked for the common good of all. Owen's Communism was based upon this a memorial addressed to all the “red Republicans, Com- munists and Socialists of Europe," and sent to the provisional government of France, 1848, and also “to Queen Victoria and her responsible advisers.” 1 Note, l. c, p. 22. 24 Socialisin : purely business foundation, the outcome, so to say, of commercial calculation. Throughout, it maintained this practical character. Thus, in 1823, Owen proposed the relief of the distress in Ireland by Communist colonies, and drew up complete estimates of costs of founding them, yearly expenditure, and probable revenue. And in his definite plan for the future, the technical working out of details is managed with such practical knowledge-ground plan, front and side and bird's-eye views all included —that the Owen method of social reform once accepted, there is from the practical point of view little to be said against the actual arrange- ment of details. His advance in the direction of Communism was the turning-point in Owen's life. As long as he was simply a philanthropist, he was rewarded with nothing but wealth, applause, honour, and glory. He was the most popular man in Europe. Not only men of his own class, but statesmen and princes listened to him approvingly. But when he came with his Communist theories, that was quite another thing. Three great obstacles seemed to him especially to block the path to social out hotely rical Utopian and Scientific. 25 reform : private property, religion, the present form of marriage. He knew what confronted him if he attacked these-outlawry, excommuni- cation from official society, the loss of his whole social position. But nothing of this prevented him from attacking them without fear of con- sequences, and what he had foreseen happened. Banished from official society, with a conspiracy of silence against him in the press, ruined by his unsuccessful Communist experiments in America, in which he sacrificed all his fortune, he turned directly to the working-class and con- tinued working in their midst for thirty years. Every social movement, every real advance in England on behalf of the workers links itself on to the name of Robert Owen. He forced through in 1819, after five years' fighting, the first law limiting the hours of labour of women and children in factories. He was president of the first Congress at which all the Trade Unions of England united in a single great trade association. He introduced as transition measures to the complete communistic organi- sation of society, on the one hand, co-operative societies for retail trade and production. These have since that time, at least, given 26 Socialism : practical proof that the merchant and the manu- facturer are socially quite unnecessary. On the other hand, he introduced labour bazaars for the exchange of the products of labour through the medium of labour-notes, whose unit was a single hour of work; institutions necessarily doomed to failure, but completely anticipating Proudhon's bank of exchange of a much later period, and differing entirely from this in that it did not claim to be the panacea for all social ills, but only a first step towards a much more radical revolution of society. The Utopians' mode of thought has for a long time governed the socialist ideas of the nineteenth century, and still governs some of them. Until very recently all French and English Socialists did homage to it. The earlier German Communism, including that of Weitling, was of the same school. To all these Socialism is the expression of · ab- solute truth, reason, and justice, and has only to be discovered to conquer all the world by virtue of its own power, ( And as absolute truth is independent of time, space, and of the historical development of man, it is a mere accident when and where it is discovered. T P A N Utopian and Scientific. 27 With all this, absolute truth, reason, and justice are different with the founder of each different school. And as each one's special kind of absolute truth, reason, and justice is again conditioned by his subjective understand- ing, his conditions of existence, the measure of his knowledge and his intellectual training, there is no other ending possible in this con- flict of absolute truths than that they shall be mutually exclusive one of the other. Hence, from this nothing could come but a kind of eclectic, average Socialism, which, as a matter of fact, has up to the present time dominated the minds of most of the socialist workers in France and England. Hence, a mish-mash allowing of the most manifold shades of opinion ; a mish-mash of such critical state- ments, economic theories, pictures of future society by the founders of different sects, as excite a minimum of opposition ; a mish- mash which is the more easily brewed the more the definite sharp edges of the individual con- stituents are rubbed down in the stream of debate, like rounded pebbles in a brook. To make a science of Socialism, it had first to be placed upon a real basis. 28 Socialism: II. In the meantime, along with and after the French philosophy of the eighteenth century had arisen the new German philosophy, culminating in Hegel. ( Its greatest merit was the taking up again of dialectics as the highest form of reasoning.) The old Greek philosophers were all born natural dialecticians, and Aristotle, the most encyclopædic intellect of them, had al- ready analysed the most essential forms of dialectic thought. The newer philosophy, on the other hand, although in it also dialectics had brilliant exponents (e.g. Descartes and Spinoza), had, especially through English influence, be- come more and more rigidly fixed in the so- called metaphysical mode of reasoning, by which also the French of the eighteenth century were almost wholly dominated, at all events in their special philosophical work. Outside philosophy in the restricted sense, the French neverthe- less produced masterpieces of dialectic. We need only call to mind Diderot's “Le Neveu ason Utopian and Scientific. 29 our we see de Rameau," and Rousseau's “Discours sur l'origine et les fondements de l'inégalité parmi les hommes.” We give here, in brief, the essen- tial character of these two modes of thought. When we consider and reflect upon nature at large, or the history of mankind, or own intellectual activity, at first the picture of an endless entanglement of relations and reactions, permutations and combinations, in which nothing remains what, where, and as it was, but everything moves, changes, comes into being and passes away. We see, therefore, at first the picture as , a whole, with its individual parts still more or less kept in the background; we observe the movements, transitions, connections, rather than the things that move, combine, and are con- nected. This primitive, naïve, but intrinsi- cally correct conception of the world is that of ancient Greek philosophy, and was first clearly formulated by Heraclitus : everything is and is not, for everything is fluid, is con- stantly changing, constantly coming into being and passing away. But this conception, correctly as it expresses the general character of the picture of appear- 30 Socialism : ances as a whole, does not suffice to explain the details of which this picture is made up, and so , long as we do not understand these, we have not a clear idea of the whole picture. In order to understand these details we must detach them from their natural or historical connection and examine each one separately, its nature, special causes, effects, etc. This is, primarily, the task of natural science and historical re- search ; branches of science which the Greeks of classical times, on very good grounds, rel- egated to a subordinate position, because they had first of all to collect materials for these sciences to work upon. A certain amount of natural and historical material must be collected before there can be any critical analysis, com- parison, and arrangement in classes, orders, and species. The foundations of the exact natural sciences were, therefore, first worked out by the Greeks of the Alexandrian period, and later on, in the Middle Ages, by the Arabs. Real natural science dates from the second half of the fifteenth century, and thence onward it has advanced with constantly increasing rapidity. The analysis of Nature into its individual parts, the grouping of the different natural processes Utopian and Scientific. 31 and objects in definite classes, the study of the internal anatomy of organised bodies in their manifold forms—these were the fundamental conditions of the gigantic strides in our know- ledge of Nature that have been made during the last four hundred years. But this method of work has also left us as legacy the habit of observing natural objects and processes in isolation, apart from their connection with the vast whole; of observing them in repose, not in motion; as constants, not as esse as essentially variables ; in their death, not in their life. And when this way of looking at things was transferred by Bacon and Locke from natural emper science to philosophy, it begot the narrow, metaphysical mode of thought peculiar to the last century. To the metaphysician, things and their mental reflexes, ideas, are isolated, are to be considered one after the other and apart from each other, are objects of investigation fixed, rigid, given once for all. He thinks in abso- lutely irreconcilable antitheses. “His com- munication is ‘yea, yea; nay, nay;' for what- soever is more than these cometh of evil.” For him a thing either exists or does not exist ; 32 Socialism : a thing cannot at the same time be itself and something else. Positive and negative ab- solutely exclude one another; cause and effect stand in a rigid antithesis one to the other. At first sight this mode of thinking seems to us very luminous, because it is that of so-called sound commonsense. Only sound common- sense, respectable fellow that he is, in the homely realm of his own four walls, has very wonderful adventures directly he ventures out into the wide world of research. And the metaphysi- cal mode of thought, justifiable and necessary as it is in a number of domains whose extent varies according to the nature of the particular object of investigation, sooner or later reaches a limit, beyond which it becomes one-sided, re- stricted, abstract, lost in insoluble contradictions. In the contemplation of individual things, it forgets the connection between them ; in the contemplation of their existence, it forgets the beginning and end of that existence; of their repose, it forgets their motion. It cannot see the wood for the trees. For everyday purposes we know and can say, e.g., whether an animal is alive or not. But, upon closer inquiry, we find that this is, in Utopian and Scientific. 33 many cases, a very complex question, as the jurists know very well. They have cudgelled . their brains in vain to discover a rational limit beyond which the killing of the child in its mother's womb is murder. It is just as im- possible to determine absolutely the moment of death, for physiology proves that death is not an instantaneous, momentary phenomenon, but a very protracted process. In like manner, every organised being is every moment the same and not the same ; every moment it assimilates matter supplied from without, and gets rid of other matter; every moment some cells of its body die and others build themselves anew; in a longer or shorter time the matter of its body is completely renewed, and is replaced by other molecules of matter, so that every organised being is always itself, and yet something other than itself. Further, we find upon closer investigation that the two poles of an antithesis, positive and negative, e.g., are as inseparable as they are opposed, and that despite all their opposition, they mutually interpenetrate,* And we find, in like manner, that cause and effect are concep- tions which only hold good in their application с * unity of Opposites * 34 Socialism : to individual cases; but as soon as we consider the individual cases in their general connection with the universe as a whole, they run into each other, and they become confounded when we contemplate that universal action and reaction in which causes and effects are eternally changing places, so that what is effect here and now will be cause there and then, and vice versa. None of these processes and modes of thought enters into the framework of meta- physical reasoning. Dialectics, on the other hand, comprehends things and their represen- tations, ideas, in their essential connection, concatenation, motion, origin, and ending. Such processes as those mentioned above are, therefore, so many corroborations of its own method of procedure. Nature is the proof of dialectics, and it must be said for modern science that it has furnished this proof with very rich materials increasing daily, and thus has shown that, in the last resort, Nature works dialectically and metaphysically ; that she does not move in the eternal oneness of a perpetually recurring circle, but goes through a real historical evolution. In this connection Darwin must be named not ; Utopian and Scientific. 35 before all others. He dealt the metaphysical conception of Nature the heaviest blow by his proof that all organic beings, plants, animals, and man himself, are the products of a process of evolution going on through millions of years. But the naturalists who have learned to think dialectically are few and far between, and this conflict of the results of discovery with precon- ceived modes of thinking explains the end- less confusion now reigning in theoretical natural science, the despair of teachers as well as learners, of authors and readers alike. An exact representation of the universe, of its evolution, of the development of mankind, and of the reflection of this evolution in the minds of men, can therefore only be obtained by the methods of dialectics with its constant regard to the innumerable actions and reactions of life and death, of progressive or retrogressive changes. And in this spirit the new German philosophy has worked. Kant began his career by resolving the stable solar system of Newton and its eternal duration, after the famous initial impulse had once been given, into the result of a historic process, the formation of the sun and all the planets out of a rotating nebulous mass. From a 36 Socialism: this he at the same time drew the conclusion that, given this origin of the solar system, its future death followed of necessity. His theory half a century later was established mathe- matically by Laplace, and half a century after that the spectroscope proved the existence in space of such incandescent masses of gas in various stages of condensation. This new German philosophy culminated in the Hegelian system. In this system-and herein is its great merit-for the first time the whole world, natural, historical, intellectual, is represented as a process, i.e., as in constant motion, change, transformation, development; and the attempt is made to trace out the internal connection that makes a continuous whole of all this movement and development. From this point of view the history of man- kind no longer appeared as a wild whirl of senseless deeds of violence, all equally con- demnable at the judgment seat of mature philosophic reason, and which are best forgotten as quickly as possible ; but as the process of evolution of man himself. (It was now the task of the intellect to follow the gradual march of this process through all its devious ways, Utopian and Scientific. 37 and to trace out the inner law running through all its apparently accidental phenomena. ) That the Hegelian system did not solve the problem it propounded is here immaterial. Its epoch-making merit was that it propounded the problem. This problem is one that no single individual will ever be able to solve. Although Hegel was—with Saint Simon—the most en- - cyclopædic mind of his time, yet he was limited, first, by the necessarily limited extent of his own knowledge, and, second, by the limited extent and depth of the knowledge and con- ceptions of his age. To these limits a third must be added. Hegel was an idealist. To him the thoughts within his brain were not the more or less abstract pictures of actual things and processes, but, conversely, things and their evolution were only the realised pictures of the “Idea,” existing somewhere from eternity before the world was. This way of thinking X turned everything upside down, and completely reversed the actual connection of things in the world. Correctly and ingeniously as many individual groups of facts were grasped by Hegel, yet, for the reasons just given, there is much that is botched, artificial, laboured, in That's it Freddy. Just take what woh can use K 38 Socialism: a word, wrong in point of detail. The Hegelian system, in itself, was a colossal mis- carriage—but it was also the last of its kind. It was suffering, in fact, from an internal and incurable contradiction. Upon the one hand, its essential proposition was the con- ception that (human history is a process of evolution, which, by its very nature, \cannot find its intellectual final term in the discovery of any so-called absolute truth.) But, on the other hand, it laid claim to being the very essence of this absolute truth. A system of natural and historical knowledge, embracing everything, and final for all time, is a contra- diction to the fundamental law of dialectic reasoning. This law, indeed, by no excludes, but, on the contrary, includes the idea that the systematic knowledge of the external universe can make giant strides from age to age. The perception of the fundamental contra- diction in German idealism led necessarily back to materialism, but nota bene, not to the simply metaphysical, exclusively mechanical material- ism of the eighteenth century. Old materialism looked upon all previous history as a crude heap means Utopian and Scientific. E 39 of irrationality and violence; modern material- ism sees in it the process of evolution of humanity, and aims at discovering the laws thereof. With the French of the eighteenth century, and even with Hegel, the conception obtained of Nature as a whole, moving in narrow circles, and forever immutable, with its eternal celestial bodies, as Newton, and unalter- able organic species, as Linnæus, taught. Modern materialism embraces the more recent discoveries of natural science, according to which Nature also has its history in time, the celestial bodies, like the organic species that, under favourable conditions, people them, being born and perishing. And even if Nature, as a whole, must still be said to move in recurrent cycles, these cycles assume infinitely larger dimensions. In both aspects, modern material- ism is essentially dialectic, and no longer re- quires the assistance of that sort of philosophy which, queen-like, pretended to rule the remain- ing mob of sciences. As soon as each special science is bound to make clear its position in the great totality of things and of our knowledge of things, a special science dealing with this totality is superfluous or unnecessary. That 40 Socialism : which still survives of all earlier philosophy is the science of thought and its laws--formal logic and dialectics. Everything else is subsumed in the positive science of Nature and history. Whilst, however, the revolution in the con- ception of Nature could only be made in pro- portion to the corresponding positive materials furnished by research, already much earlier certain historical facts had occurred which led to a decisive change in the conception of his- tory. In 1831, the first working-class rising took place in Lyons ; between 1838 and 1842, the first national working-class movement, that of the English Chartists, reached its height. The class struggle between proletariat and bourgeoisie came to the front in the history of the most advanced countries in Europe, in proportion to the development, upon the one hand, of modern industry, upon the other, of the newly-acquired political supremacy of the bourgeoisie. Facts more and more strenu- ously gave the lie to the teachings of bourgeois economy as to the identity of the interests of capital and labour, as to the universal harmony and universal prosperity that would be the consequence of unbridled competition. All Utopian and Scientific. 41 these things could no longer be ignored, any more than the French and English Social- ism, which was their theoretical, though very imperfect, expression. But the old idealist conception of history, which was not yet dis- lodged, knew nothing of class struggles based upon economic interests, knew nothing of eco nomic interests ; production and all economic relations appeared in it only as incidental, sub- ordinate elements in the "history of civilisation.” The new facts made imperative a new ex- amination of all past history. Then it was seen that all past history, with the exception of its primitive stages, was the history of class struggles; that these warring classes of society are always the products of the modes of pro- duction and of exchange—in a word, of the economic conditions of their time; that the economic structure of society always furnishes the real basis, starting from which we can alone work out the ultimate explanation of the whole superstructure of juridical and political institutions as well as of the religious, philosophical, and other ideas of a given historical period. Hegel had freed his- tory from metaphysics-he had made it dia- 42 Socialism: N A gle is both protauti dialectic? lectic; but his conception of history was essen- tially idealistic. But now idealism was driven from its last refuge, the philosophy of history; now a materialistic treatment of history was propounded, and a method found of explaining man’s “knowing ” by his “ being," instead of, as heretofore, his “ being” by his “knowing.” From that time forward Socialism was no longer an accidental discovery of this or that ingenious brain, but the necessary outcome of the struggle between two historically developed classes—the proletariat and the bourgeoisie. #ts task was no longer to manufacture a system y of society as perfect as possible, but to ex- amine the historico-economic succession of events from which these classes and their an- tagonism had of necessity sprung, and to dis- cover in the economic conditions thus created the means of ending the conflict. But the Socialism of earlier days was as incompatible with this materialistic conception as the con- ception of Nature of the French materialists was with dialectics and modern natural science. The Socialism of earlier days certainly criticised the existing capitalistic mode of production and its consequences. But it could not Utopian and Scientific. 43 explain them, and, therefore, could not get the mastery of them. It could only simply reject them as bad. The more strongly this earlier Socialism denounced the exploitation of the working-class, inevitable under Capitalism, the less able was it clearly to show in what this exploitation consisted and how it arose. But for this it was necessary-(1) to present the capitalistic method of production in its historical connection and its inevitableness during a particular historical period, and therefore, also, to present its inevitable downfall; and (2) to lay bare its essential character, which was still This was done by the discovery of surplus-value. It was shown that the appro- priation of unpaid labour is the basis of the capitalist mode of production and of the ex- ploitation of the worker that occurs under it ; that even if the capitalist buys the labour-power of his labourer at its full value as a commodity on the market, he yet extracts more value from it than he paid for ; and that in the ultimate analysis this surplus-value forms those sums of value from which are heaped up the constantly increasing masses of capital in the hands of the possessing classes. The genesis of capitalist a secret. 44 Socialism: production and the production of capital were both explained. These two great discoveries, the materialistic conception of history and the revelation of the secret of capitalistic production through sur- plus-value, we owe to Marx. With these discoveries Socialism became a science. The next thing was to work out all its details and relations. Utopian and Scientific. 45 r III. The materialist conception of history starts from the proposition that the production of the means to support human life and, next to pro- duction, the exchange of things produced, is the basis of all social structure; that in every society that has appeared in history, the manner in which wealth is distributed and society divided into classes or orders, is dependent upon what is produced, how it is produced, and how the products are exchanged. From this point of view the final causes of all social changes and political revolutions are to be sought, not in men's brains, not in man's better insight into eternal truth and justice, but in changes in the modes of production and exchange. They are to be sought, not in the philo- sophy, but in the economics of each particular epoch. The growing perception that ex- isting social institutions unreasonable and unjust, that reason has become reason, and right wrong, is only proof that in the modes of production and exchange • are un- 46 Socialism : changes have silently taken place, with which the social order, adapted to earlier economic conditions, is no longer in keeping. From this it also follows that the means of getting rid of the incongruities that have been brought to light, must also be present, in a more or less developed condition, within the changed modes of production themselves. These means are not to be invented by deduction from fundamental principles, but are to be discovered in the stub- born facts of the existing system of production. What is, then, the position of modern Socialism in this connexion ? The present structure of society—this is now pretty generally conceded—is the creation of the ruling class of to-day, of the bourgeoisie. The mode of production peculiar to the bour- geoisie, known, since Marx, as the capitalist mode of production, was incompatible with the feudal system, with the privileges it conferred upon individuals, entire social ranks and local corporations, as well as with the hereditary ties of subordination which constituted the framework of its social organisation. The bourgeoisie broke up the feudal system and built upon its ruins the capitalist order of society, the kingdom of free Utopian and Scientific. 47 competition, of personal liberty, of the equality, before the law, of all commodity owners, of all the rest of the capitalist blessings. Thenceforward the capitalist mode of production could develop in freedom. Since steam, machinery, and the making of machines by machinery transformed the older manufacture into modern industry, the productive forces evolved under the guidance of the bourgeoisie developed with a rapidity and in a degree unheard of before. But just as the older manufacture, in its time, and handicraft, becom- ing more developed under its influence, had come into collision with the feudal trammels of the guilds, so now modern industry, in its more com- plete development, comes into collision with the bounds within which the capitalistic mode of production holds it confined. The new pro- ductive forces have already outgrown the capi- talistic mode of using them. ( And this conflict between productive forces and modes of pro- duction is not a conflict engendered in the mind of man, like that between original sin and divine justice. It exists, in fact, objectively, outside us, independently of the will and actions even of the men that have brought it on. Modern Social- ism is nothing but the reflex, in thought, of Socialism: this conflict in fact; its ideal reflection in the minds, first, of the class directly suffering under it, the working-class.) . Now, in what does this conflict consist ? Before capitalistic production, i.e., in the Middle Ages, the system of petty industry obtained generally, based upon the private property of the labourers in their means of pro- duction ; in the country, the agriculture of the small peasant, freeman or serf ; in the towns, the handicrafts organised in guilds. The instruments of labour—land, agricultural implements, the workshop, the tool-were the instruments of labour of single individuals, adapted for the use of one worker, and, therefore, of necessity, small, dwarfish, circumscribed. But, for this very reason they belonged, as a rule, to the producer himself. To concentrate these scattered, limited means of production, to enlarge them, to turn them into the powerful levers of production of the present day —this was precisely the historic rôle of capitalist production and of its upholder, the bourgeoisie. In the fourth section of “Capital” Marx has explained in detail, how since the fifteenth century this has been historically worked out through the three phases of simple co-operation, а. Utopian and Scientific. 49 manufacture, and modern industry. But the bourgeoisie, as is also shown there, could not transform these puny means of production into mighty productive forces, without transforming them, at the same time, from means of production of the individual into social means of production only workable by a collectivity of men. The spinning-wheel, the handloom, the blacksmith's hammer, were replaced by the spinning- machine, the power-loom, the steam-hammer; the individual workshop, by the factory implying the co-operation of hundreds and thousands of workmen. In like manner, production itself changed from a series of a individual into a series of social acts, and the products from individual to social products. The yarn, the cloth, the metal articles that now came out of the factory were the joint product of many workers, through whose hands they had successively to pass before they were ready No one person could say of them : · I made that ; this is my product.” But where, in a given society, the funda- mental form of production is that spontaneous division of labour which creeps in gradually and not upon any preconceived plan, there the pro- ) D 50 Socialism: wants. ducts take on the form of commodities, whose mutual exchange, buying and selling, enable the individual producers to satisfy their manifold And this was the case in the Middle Ages. The peasant, e.g., sold to the artisan agricultural products and bought from him the products of handicraft. Into this society of in- dividual producers, of commodity-producers, the new mode of production thrust itself. In the midst of the old division of labour, grown up spontaneously and upon no definite plan, which had governed the whole of society, now arose division of labour upon a definite plan, as organ- ised in the factory ; side by side with individual production appeared social production. The products of both were sold in the same market, and, therefore, at prices at least approximately equal. But organisation upon a definite plan was stronger than spontaneous division of labour. The factories working with the com- bined social forces of a collectivity of individuals produced their commodities far more cheaply than the individual small producers. Individual production succumbed in one department after another. Socialised production revolutionised all the old methods of production. But its ; a Utopian and Scientific. 51 revolutionary character was, at the same time, so little recognised, that it was, on the contrary, introduced as a means of increasing and de- veloping the production of commodities. When it arose, it found ready-made, and made liberal use of, certain machinery for the production and exchange of commodities; merchants' capital, handicraft, wage-labour. Socialised production thus introducing itself as a new form of the pro- duction of commodities, it was a matter of course that under it the old forms of appropria- tion remained in full swing, and were applied to its products as well. In the mediæval stage of evolution of the production of commodities, the question as to the owner of the product of labour could not arise. The individual producer, as a rule, had, from raw material belonging to himself, and generally his own handiwork, produced it with his own tools, by the labour of his own hands or of his family. There was no need for him to appropriate the new product. It belonged wholly to him, as a matter of course. perty in the product was, therefore, based upon his own labour. Even where external help was used, this was, as a rule, of little importance, and His pro- 52 Socialisin : very generally was compensated by something other than wages. The apprentices and journey- men of the guilds worked less for board and wages than for education, in order that they might become master craftsmen themselves. Then came the concentration of the means of production and of the producers in large work- shops and manufactories, their transformation into actual socialised means of production and socialised producers. But the socialised pro- ducers and means of production and their pro- ducts were still treated, after this change, just as they had been before, i.e., as the means of production and the products of individuals. //hitherto, the owner of the instruments of labour had himself appropriated the product, because, as a rule, it was his own product and the assistance of others was the exception. Now the owner of the instruments of labour always appropriated to himself the product, although it was no longer his product but exclusively the product of the labour of others/ Thus, the products now produced socially were not appropriated by those who had actually set in motion the means of production and actually produced the commodities, but by the capitalists. Utopian and Scientific. 53 The means of production, and production itself, had become in essence socialised. But they were subjected to a form of appropriation which presupposes the private production of indi- viduals, under which, therefore, every one owns his own product and brings it to market. The mode of production is subjected to this form of appropriation, although it abolishes the con- ditions upon which the latter rests./ This contradiction, which gives to the new mode of production its capitalistic character, contains the germ of the whole of the social anta- gonisms of to-day. The greater the mastery ob- tained by the new mode of production over all important fields of production and in all manu- facturing countries, the more it reduced individual production to an insignificant residuum, the more 1 It is hardly necessary in this connexion to point out, that, even if the form of appropriation remains the same, the character of the appropriation is just as much revolu- tionised as production is by the changes described above. It is, of course, a very different matter whether I appropriate to myself my own product or that of another. Note in passing that wage-labour, which contains the whole capitalistic mode of production in embryo, is very ancient ; in a sporadic, scattered form it existed for centuries alongside of slave-labour. But the embryo could duly de- velop into the capitalistic mode of production only when the necessary historical pre-conditions had been furnished. ?? so? 22.50 alcoletion of fend, mod, e onde concentrate of 54 Socialism : clearly was brought out the incompatibility of so- cialised production with capitalistic appropriation. The first capitalists found, as we have said, alongside of other forms of labour, wage-labour ready-made for them on the market. But it was exceptional, complementary, accessory, transi- tory wage-labour. The agricultural labourer, , though, upon occasion, he hired himself out by the day, had a few acres of his own land on which he could at all events live at a pinch. The guilds were so organised that the journey- man of to-day became the master of to-morrow. But all this changed, as soon as the means of production became socialised and concentrated in the hands of capitalists. The means of pro- duction, as well as the product, of the individual producer became more and more worthless ; there was nothing left for him but to turn wage- worker under the capitalist. Wage-labour, aforetime the exception and accessory, now be- came the rule and basis of all production; afore- time complementary, it now became the sole remaining function of the worker. The wage- worker for a time became a wage-worker for life. The number of these permanent wage- workers was further enormously increased by Utopian and Scientific. 55 the breaking-up of the feudal system that oc- curred at the same time, by the disbanding of the retainers of the feudal lords, the eviction of the peasants from their homesteads, etc. The separation was made complete between the means of production concentrated in the hands of the capitalists on the one side, and the producers, possessing nothing but their labour- power, on the other. The contradiction between socialised production and capitalistic appro- priation manifested itself as the antagonism of proletariat and bourgeoisie. We have seen that the capitalistic mode of production thrust its way into a society of commodity-producers, of individual producers, whose social bond was the exchange of their products. But every society, based upon the production of commodities, has this peculiarity: that the producers have lost control over their own social inter-relations. Each man produces for himself with such means of production as he may happen to have, and for such exchange as he may require to satisfy his remaining wants. No one knows how much of his particular article is coming on the market, nor how much of it will ( be wanted. (No one knows whether his indi- 56 Socialism : vidual product will meet an actual demand, whether he will be able to make good his cost of production or even to sell his commodity at all. Anarchy reigns in socialised production. But the production of commodities, like every other form of production, has its peculiar, inherent laws inseparable from it; and these laws work, despite anarchy, in and through anarchy. They reveal themselves in the only persistent form of social inter-relations, i.e., in exchange, and here they affect the individual producers as compulsory laws of competition. They are, at first, unknown to these producers themselves, and have to be discovered by them gradually and as the result of experience. They work themselves out, therefore, inde- pendently of the producers, and in antagonism to them, as inexorable natural laws of their particular form of production. The product governs the producers.- Prolitarist) In mediæval society, especially in the earlier centuries, production was essentially directed towards satisfying the wants of the individual. It satisfied, in the main, only the wants of the producer and his family. Where relations of personal dependence existed, as in the country, Bilit do that? If so, we that enough? Utopian and Scientific. 57 it also helped to satisfy the wants of the feudal lord. In all this there was, therefore, no ex- change; the products, consequently, did not as- sume the character of commodities. The family of the peasant produced almost everything they wanted : clothes and furniture, as well as means of subsistence. Only when it began to produce more than was sufficient to supply its own wants and the payments in kind to the feudal lord, only then did it also produce commodities. This surplus, thrown into socialised exchange and offered for sale, became commodities. The artisans of the towns, it is true, had from the first to produce for exchange. But they, also, themselves supplied the greatest part of their own individual wants. They had gardens and plots of land. They turned their cattle out into the communal forest, which, also, yielded them timber and firing. The women spun flax, wool, and so forth. Production for the purpose of exchange, production of com- modities, was only in its infancy. Hence, ex- change was restricted, the market narrow, the methods of production stable ; there was local exclusiveness without, local unity within ; the mark 1 in the country, in the town, the guild, 1 See Appendix, 1 58 Socialism : But with the extension of the production of commodities, and especially with the introduc- tion of the capitalist mode of production, the laws of commodity-production, hitherto latent, came into action more openly and with greater force. The old bonds were loosened, the old exclusive limits broken through, the producers were more and more turned into independent, isolated producers of commodities. It became apparent that the production of society at large was ruled by absence of plan, by accident, by anarchy ; and this anarchy grew to greater and greater height. But the chief means by aid of which the capitalist mode of production intensi- fied this anarchy of socialised production, was the exact opposite of anarchy. It was the in- creasing organisation of production, upon a social basis, in every individual productive establish- ment. By this, the old, peaceful, stable condition of things was ended. Wherever this organisa- tion of production was introduced into a branch of industry, it brooked no other method of pro- duction by its side. The field of labour became a battle-ground. The great geographical dis- coveries, and the colonisation following upon them, multiplied markets and quickened the Utopian and Scientific. 59 transformation of handicraft into manufacture. The war did not simply break out between the individual producers of particular localities. The local struggles begat in their turn national conflicts, the commercial wars of the seven- teenth and the eighteenth centuries. Finally, modern industry and the opening of the world-market made the struggle universal, and at the same time gave it an unheard-of viru- lence. Advantages in natural or artificial condi- tions of production now decide the existence or non-existence of individual capitalists, as well as of whole industries and countries. He that falls is remorselessly cast aside. It is the Darwinian struggle of the individual for existence transferred from Nature to society with intensified violence. The conditions of existence natural to the animal appear as the final term of human development. The contradiction between socialised produc- tion and capitalistic appropriation now pre- sents itself as an antagonism between the organisation of production in the individual workshop and the anarchy of production in society generally The capitalistic mode of production moves in these two forms of the antagonism immanent 60 Socialism: б Cractly what is production ? anarchyun in soesel social to it from its very origin. It is never able to get out of that “vicious circle," which Fourier had already discovered. "What Fourier could not, indeed, see in his time is, that this circle is gradually narrowing; that the movement be- comes more and more a spiral, and must come to an end, like the movement of the planets, by collision with the centre, It is the com- pelling force of anarchy in the production of society at large that more and more completely turns the great majority of men into proletarians ; and it is the masses of the proletariat again who will finally put an end to anarchy in production. It is the compelling force of anarchy in social production that turns the limitless perfectibility of machinery under modern industry into a com- pulsory law by which every individual industrial capitalist must perfect his machinery more and more, under penalty of ruin. , But the perfecting of machinery is the mak- ing human labour superfluous. If the intro- duction and increase of machinery means the displacement of millions of manual, by a few machine, workers, improvement in machinery means the displacement of more and more of the machine-workers themselves. It means, in , a Hosthisbeendeoproien? ? Utopian and Scientific. 61 a the last instance, the production of a number of available wage-workers in excess of the average needs of capital, the formation of a complete industrial reserve army, as I called it in 1845,1 available at the times when industry is working at high pressure, to be cast out upon the street when the inevitable crash comes, a constant dead weight upon the limbs of the working- class in its struggle for existence with capital, a regulator for the keeping of wages down to the low level that suits the interests of capital. Thus it comes about, to quote Marx, that machinery becomes the most powerful weapon in the war of capital against the working-class ; that the instruments of labour constantly tear the means of subsistence out of the hands of the labourer; that the very product of the worker is turned into an instrument for his subjugation. Thus it comes about that the economising of the instruments of labour be- comes at the same time, from the outset, the most reckless waste of labour-power, and robbery based upon the normal conditions under which labour functions ; that machinery, 1 “ The Condition of the Working-Class in England” (Sonnenschein & Co.), p. 84. 62 Socialism : * “the most powerful instrument for shortening labour-time, becomes the most unfailing means for placing every moment of the labourer's time and that of his family at the disposal of the capi- talist for the purpose of expanding the value of his capital" ("Capital," English edition, p. 406). Thus it comes about that over-work of some be- comes the preliminary condition for the idleness of others, and that modern industry, which hunts after new consume mers over the whole world, forces the consumption of the masses at home down to a starvation minimum, and in doing thus destroys its own home market. “ The law that always equilibrates the rela- tive surplus population, or industrial reserve army, to the extent and energy of accumulation, this law rivets the labourer to capital more firmly than the wedges of Vulcan did Prome- theus to the rock. It establishes an accumula- tion of misery, corresponding with accumulation of capital. Accumulation of wealth at one pole is, therefore, at the same time, accumulation of misery, agony of toil, slavery, ignorance, brutality, mental degradation, at the opposite pole, i.e., on the side of the class that produces its own product in the form of capital.” (Marx' Utopian and Scientific. 63 Capital ” [Sonnenschein & Co.), p. 661.) And to expect any other division of the products from the capitalistic mode of pro- duction is the same as expecting the electrodes of a battery not to decompose acidulated water, not to liberate oxygen at the positive, hydrogen at the negative pole, so long as they are con- nected with the battery. We have seen that the ever-increasing perfectibility of modern machinery is, by the anarchy of social production, turned into a compulsory law that forces the individual industrial capitalist always to improve his machinery, always to increase its produc- tive force. The bare possibility of extend- ing the field of production is transformed for him into a similar compulsory law. The enormous expansive force of modern in- dustry, compared with which that of gases is mere child's play, appears to us now as necessity for expansion, both qualitative and quantitative, that laughs at all resistance. Such resistance is offered by consumption, by sales, by the markets for the products of modern industry. But the capacity for extension, ex- . tensive and intensive, of the markets is prim- 64 Socialisın : arily governed by quite different laws, that work much less energetically. The extension of the markets cannot keep pace with the extension of production. The collision be- comes inevitable, and as this cannot produce any real solution so long as it does not break in pieces the capitalist mode of production, the collisions become periodic. Capitalist production has begotten another vicious circle.” As a matter of fact, since 1825, when the first general crisis broke out, the whole in- dustrial and commercial world, production and exchange among all civilised peoples and their more or less barbaric hangers-on, are thrown out of joint about once every ten years. ( Com- ( merce is at a standstill, the markets are glutted, products accumulate, as multitudinous as they are unsaleable, hard cash disappears, credit vanishes, factories are closed, the mass of the workers are in want of the means of subsist- ence, because they have produced too much of the means of subsistence; bankruptcy follows upon bankruptcy, execution upon execution. The stagnation lasts for years ; productive forces and products are wasted and destroyed D E vonoz Utopian and Scientific. 65 a wholesale, until the accumulated mass of com- modities finally filter off, more or less depreciated in value, until production and exchange gradually begin to move again. Little by little the pace quickens. It becomes a trot. The industrial trot breaks into a canter, the canter in turn grows into the headlong gallop of a perfect steeplechase of industry, commercial credit, and speculation, which finally, after breakneck leaps, ends where it began in the ditch of a crisis.) And so over and over again. We have now, since the year 1825, gone through this five times, and at the present moment (1877) we are going through it for the sixth time. And the character of these crises is so clearly defined that Fourier hit all of them off, when he described the first as “ crise pléthorique," a crisis from plethora. In these crises, the contradiction between socialised production and capitalist appropriation ends in a violent explosion. The circulation of commodities is, for the time being, stopped. Money, the means of circulation, becomes a hindrance to circulation. All the laws of pro- duction and circulation of commodities are turned upside down. The economic collision has reached its apogee. The mode of pro- . E 66 Socialism : t duction is in rebellion against the mode of exchange. The fact that the socialised organisation of production within the factory has developed so far that it has become incompatible with the anarchy of production in society, which exists side by side with and dominates it, is brought home to the capitalists themselves by the violent concentration of capital that occurs during crises, through the ruin of many large, and a still greater number of small, capitalists. The whole mechanism of the capitalist mode of production breaks down under the pressure of the pro- ductive forces, its own creations. It is no longer able to turn all this mass of means of production into capital. They lie fallow, and for that very reason the industrial reserve army must also lie fallow. Means of production, means of subsistence, available labourers, all the elements of production and of general wealth, are present in abundance. But "abundance becomes the source bf distress and want (Fourier), because it is the very thing that pre- vents the transformation of the means of pro- duction and subsistence into capital. (For in capitalistic society the means of production can ) Utopian and Scientific. 67 only function when they have undergone a preliminary transformation into capital, into the means of exploiting human labour-power. The necessity of this transformation into capital of the means of production and subsistence stands like a ghost between these and the workers. It alone prevents the coming together of the material and personal levers of production ; it alone forbids the means of production to function, the workers to work and live. On the one hand, therefore, the capitalistic mode of production stands convicted of its own in- capacity to further direct these productive forces. On the other, these productive forces them- selves, with increasing energy, press forward to the removal of the existing contradiction, to the abolition of their quality as capital, to the practical recognition of their character as social productive forces. This rebellion of the productive forces, as they grow more and more powerful, against their quality as capital, this stronger and stronger command that their social character shall be re- cognised, forces the capitalist class itself to treat them more and more as social productive forces, so far as this is possible under capitalist 68 Socialism : conditions. The period of industrial high pres- sure, with its unbounded inflation of credit, not less than the crash itself, by the collapse of great capitalist establishments, tends to bring about that form of the socialisation of great masses of means of production, which we meet with in the different kinds of joint-stock companies. Many of these means of production and of distribution are, from the outset, so colossal, that, like the railroads, they exclude all other forms of capitalistic exploitation. At a further stage of evolution this form also becomes insufficient. The producers on a large scale in a particular branch of industry in a particular country unite in a “Trust,” a union for the purpose of regu- lating production. They determine the total amount to be produced, parcel it out among themselves, and thus enforce the selling price fixed beforehand. But trusts of this kind, as soon as business becomes bad, are generally liable to break up, and, on this very account, compel a yet greater concentration of association. The whole of the particular industry is turned into one gigantic joint-stock company; internal competition gives place to the internal monopoly of this one company. This has happened in (6 a Utopian and Scientific. 69 1890 with the English alkali production, which is now, after the fusion of 48 large works, in , the hands of one company, conducted upon a single plan, and with a capital of £6,000,000. In the trusts, freedom of competition changes into its very opposite—into mono- poly; and the production without any de- finite plan of capitalistic society capitulates to the production upon a definite plan of the invading socialistic society. Certainly this is so far still to the benefit and advantage of the capitalists. But in this case the exploitation is so palpable that it must break down. No nation will put up with production conducted by trusts, with so barefaced an exploitation of the com- munity by a small band of dividend-mongers. In any case, with trusts or without, the official representative of capitalist society—the State- will ultimately have to undertake the direction of production. This necessity for conversion into 1 I say “have to.” For only when the means of produc- tion and distribution have actually outgrown the form of management by joint-stock companies, and when, there- fore, the taking them over by the State has become economically inevitable, only then — even if it is the State of to-day that effects this — is there an economic advance, the attainment of another step preliminary to the taking over of all productive forces by society itself. - - 70 Socialism: But there are other reasons here too. ( State-property is felt first in the great institutions for intercourse and communication—the post- office, the telegraphs, the railways. If the crises demonstrate the incapacity of the bourgeoisie for managing any longer modern productive forces, the transformation of the great establishments for production and distribution into joint-stock companies, trusts, and State property, show how unnecessary the But of late, since Bismarck went in for State-ownership of industrial establishments, a kind of spurious Socialism has arisen, degenerating, now and again, into something of flunkeyism, that without more ado declares all State-owner- ship, even of the Bismarckian sort, to be socialistic. Cer- tainly, if the taking over by the State of the tobacco industry is socialistic, then Napoleon and Metternich must be num- bered among the founders of Socialism. If the Belgian State, for quite ordinary political and financial reasons, itself constructed its chief railway lines; if Bismarck, not under any economic compulsion, took over for the State the chief Prussian lines, simply to be the better able to have them in hand in case of war, to bring up the railway employees as voting cattle for the Government, and especially to create for himself a new source of income independent of parlia- mentary votes—this was, in no sense, a socialistic meas- ure, directly or indirectly, consciously or unconsciously. Otherwise, the Royal Maritime Company, the Royal porce- lain manufacture, and even the regimental tailor of the army would also be socialistic institutions, or even, as was seri- ously proposed by a sly dog in Frederick William III.'s reign, the taking over by the State of the brothels. Utopian and Scientific. 71 bourgeoisie are for that purpose. All the social functions of the capitalist are now per- formed by salaried employees. The capitalist has no further social function than that of pocketing dividends, tearing off coupons, and gambling on the Stock Exchange, where the different capitalists despoil one another of their capital. At first the capitalistic mode of pro- duction forces out the workers. Now it forces out the capitalists, and reduces them, just as it reduced the workers, to the ranks of the sur- plus population, although not immediately into those of the industrial reserve army. But the transformation, either into joint- stock companies and trusts, or into State- ownership, does not do away with the capital- istic nature of the productive forces. In the joint-stock companies and trusts this is obvious. And the modern State, again, is only the organisation that bourgeois society takes on in order to support the external conditions of the capitalist mode of production against the en- croachments, as well of the workers as of individ- ual capitalists. The modern State, no matter what its form, is essentially a capitalist machine, the state of the capitalists, the ideal personifica- 72 Socialism : 0 tion of the total national capital. The more it proceeds to the taking over of productive forces, the more does it actually become the national capitalist, the more citizens does it exploit. The workers remain wage-workers-proletarians. The capitalist relation is not done away with. It is rather brought to a head. But, brought to a head, it topples over. State-ownership of the productive forces is not the solution of the con- flict, but concealed within it are the technical conditions that form the elements of that solution. This solution can only consist in the practical recognition of the social nature of the modern forces of production, and therefore in the harmonising the modes of production, ap- propriation, and exchange with the socialised character of the means of production. And this can only come about by society openly and directly taking possession of the produc- tive forces which have outgrown all control except that of society as a whole. The social character of the means of production and of the products to-day reacts against the producers, periodically disrupts all produc- tion and exchange, acts only like a law of Nature working blindly, forcibly, destructively. Utopian and Scientific. 73 But with the taking over by society of the productive forces, the social character of the means of production and of the products will be utilised by the producers with a perfect understanding of its nature, and instead of being a source of disturbance and periodical collapse, will become the most powerful lever of production itself . Active social forces work exactly like natural forces : blindly, forcibly, destructively, so long as we do not understand, and reckon with, them. But when once we understand them, when once we grasp their action, their direction, their effects, it depends only upon ourselves to subject them more and more to our own will, and by means of them to reach our own ends. And this holds quite especially of the mighty productive forces of to-day. As long as we obstinately refuse to understand the nature and the character of these social means of action—and this understanding goes against the grain of the capitalist mode of pro- duction and its defenders—so long these forces are at work in spite of us, in opposition to us, so long they master us, as we have shown above in detail. 74 Socialisin : When do we know this for sure ? 하 ​But when once their nature is understood, they can, in the hands of the producers work- ing together, be transformed from master demons into willing servants. The difference is as that between the destructive force of electricity in the lightning of the storm, and electricity under command in the telegraph and the voltaic arc; the difference between a conflagration, and fire working in the service of man. With this recognition at last of the real nature of the productive forces of to-day, the social anarchy of production gives place to a social regulation of production upon a definite plan, according to the needs of the community and of each individual. Then the capitalist mode of appropriation, in which the pro- duct enslaves first the producer and then the appropriator, is replaced by the mode of appropriation of the products that is based upon the nature of the modern means of production ; upon the one hand, direct social appropriation, as means to the maintenance and extension of production on the other, direct individual appropriation, as means of subsistence and of enjoyment. Whilst the capitalist mode of production Utopian and Scientific. 75 The pro- more and more completely transforms the great majority of the population into prole- tarians, it creates the power which, under penalty of its own destruction, is forced to accomplish this revolution. Whilst it forces on, more and more, the transformation of the vast means of production, already socialised, into State property, it shows itself the way to accomplishing this revolution. letariat seizes political power and turns the means of production into State property. But, in doing this, it abolishes itself as proletariat, abolishes all class distinctions and class antagonisms, abolishes also the State as State. Society thus far, based upon class antagonisms, had need of the State. That is, of an organisation of the particular class which was pro tempore the exploiting class, an organisa- tion for the purpose of preventing any interfer- ence from without with the existing conditions of production, and therefore, especially, for the purpose of forcibly keeping the exploited classes in the condition of oppression corresponding with the given mode of production (slavery, serfdom, wage-labour). The State was the official representative of society as a whole ; 76 Socialism : our the gathering of it together into a visible embodiment. But it was this only in so far as it was the State of that class which itself represented, for the time being, society as a whole; in ancient times, the State of slave- owning citizens; in the middle ages, the feudal lords ; in own time, the bourgeoisie. When at last it becomes the real representative of the whole of society, it renders itself un- necessary As soon as there is no longer any social class to be held in subjection ; as soon as class rule, and the individual struggle for existence based upon our present anarchy in production, with the collisions and excesses arising from these, are removed, nothing more remains to be repressed, and a special repres- sive force, a State, is no longer necessary. The first act by virtue of which the State really constitutes itself the representative of the whole of society-the taking possession of the means of production in the name of society—this is, at the same time, its last independent act as a State. State interference in social relations becomes, in one domain after another, superfluous, and then dies out of itself; the government of persons is replaced The // Hurry upadie, Russia Utopian and Scientific. 77 2 or less by the administration of things, and by the conduct of processes of production. The State is not “abolished.” It dies out. This gives the measure of the value of the phrase "a free State,” both as to its justifiable use at times by agitators, and as to its ultimate scientific insufficiency; and also of the demands of the so-called anarchists for the abolition of the State out of hand. Since the historical appearance of the capitalist mode of production, the appropria- tion by society of all the means of production has often been dreamed of, more vaguely, by individuals, as well as by sects, as the ideal of the future. But it could be- come possible, could become historical necessity, only when the actual conditions for its realisation were there. Like every other social advance, it becomes practicable, not by men understanding that the existence of classes is in contradiction to justice, equality, etc., not by the mere willingness to abolish these classes, but by virtue of certain new economic conditions. The separation of society into an exploiting and an exploited class, a ruling and an oppressed class, was the necessary consequence a 78 Socialism: of the deficient and restricted development of production in former times. So long as the total social labour only yields a produce which but slightly exceeds that barely necessary for the existence of all; so long, therefore, as labour engages all or almost all the time of the great majority of the members of society--so long, of necessity, this society is divided into classes. Side by side with the great majority, exclu- sively bond slaves to labour, arises a class freed from directly productive labour, which looks after the general affairs of society; the direc- tion of labour, State business, law, science, art, It is, therefore, the law of division of labour that lies at the basis of the division into classes. But this does not prevent this division into classes from being carried out by means of violence and robbery, trickery and fraud. It does not prevent the ruling class, once having the upper hand, from consolidating its power at the expense of the working-class, from turning their social leadership into an intensified exploitation of the masses. (But if, upon this showing, division into classes has a certain historical justification, it has this only for a given period, only under etc. Utopian and Scientific. 79 given social conditions. It was based upon the insufficiency of production. It will be swept away by the complete development of modern productive forces. And, in fact, , , the abolition of classes in society presupposes a degree of historical evolution, at which the existence, not simply of this or that particular ruling class, but of any ruling class at all, and, therefore, the existence of class distinction itself has become an obsolete anachronism. It pre- supposes, therefore, the development of pro- duction carried out to a degree at which appropriation of the means of production and of the products, and, with this, of political domination, of the monopoly of culture, and of intellectual leadership by a particular class of society, has become not only superfluous, but economically, politically, intellectually a hin- drance to development. This point is now reached. Their political and intellectual bankruptcy is scarcely any longer a secret to the bourgeoisie themselves. Their economic bankruptcy recurs regularly every ten years. In every crisis, society is suffocated beneath the weight of its own productive forces and products, which it cannot use, and stands 80 Socialism : + consume, helpless, face to face with the absurd contra- diction that the producers have nothing to because consumers are wanting. The expansive force of the means of produc- tion bursts the bonds that the capitalist mode of production had imposed upon them. Their deliverance from these bonds is the one pre- condition for an unbroken, constantly-acceler- ated development of the productive forces, and therewith for a practically unlimited increase of production itself. Nor is this all. The social- ised appropriation of the means of production does away, not only with the present artificial restrictions upon production, but also with the positive waste and devastation of productive forces and products that are at the present time the inevitable concomitants of production, and that reach their height in the crises. Further, it sets free for the community at large a mass of means of production and of products, by doing away with the senseless extravagance of the ruling classes of to-day, and their politi- cal representatives. The possibility of securing for every member of society, by means of socialised production, an existence not only fully sufficient materially, and becoming day Utopian and Scientific 81 . by day more full, but an existence guarantee- ing to all the free development and exercise of their physical and mental faculties—this possibility is now for the first time here, but it is here.1 With the seizing of the means of production by society, production of commodities is done away with, and, simultaneously, the mastery of the product over the producer. Anarchy in social production is replaced by systematic, definite organisation. The struggle for indi- vidual existence disappears. Then for the first time, man, in a certain sense, is finally marked off from the rest of the animal kingdom, and emerges from mere animal conditions of exist- 1 A few figures inay serve to give an approximate idea of the enormous expansive force of the modern means of pro- duction, even under capitalist pressure. According to Mr. Giffen, the total wealth of Great Britain and Ireland amounted, in round numbers, in 1814 to £2,200,000,000. 1865 to £6,100,000,000. 1875 to £8,500,000,000. As an instance of the squandering of means of production and of products during a crisis, the total loss in the German iron industry alone, in the crisis 1873-78, was given at the second German Industrial Congress (Berlin, February 21, 1878) as £22,750,000, F 82 Socialisin : own ence into really human ones. The whole sphere of the conditions of life which environ man, and which have hitherto ruled man, now comes under the dominion and control of man, who for the first time becomes the real, conscious lord of Nature, because he has now become master of his own social organisation. The laws of his own social action, hitherto stand- ing face to face with man as laws of Nature foreign to, and dominating, him, will then be used with full understanding, and so mastered by him. Man's social organisation, hitherto confronting him as a necessity im- posed by Nature and history, now becomes the result of his own free action.) The ex- traneous objective forces that have hitherto governed history, pass under the control of man himself. Only from that time will man himself, more and more consciously, make his own history-only from that time will the social causes set in movement by him have, in the main and in a constantly growing measure, the results intended by him. It is the ascent of man from the kingdom of necessity to the king- dom of freedom. Utopian and Scientific. 83 Let us briefly sum up our sketch of historical evolution. I. Mediaval Society.—Individual production on a small scale. Means of production adapted for individual use ; hence primitive, ungainly, petty, dwarfed in action. Production for imme- diate consumption, either of the producer him- self or of his feudal lord. Only where an excess of production over this consumption occurs is such excess offered for sale, enters into exchange. Production of commodities, there- fore, only in its infancy. But already it con- tains within itself, in embryo, anarchy in the production of society at large. II. Capitalist Revolution. Transformation of industry, at first by means of simple co- operation and manufacture. Concentration of the means of production, hitherto scattered, into great workshops. As a consequence, their transformation from individual to social means of production--a transformation which does not, on the whole, affect the form of exchange. The old forms of appropriation remain in force. The capitalist appears. In his capacity as owner 84 Socialism: of the means of production, he also appro- priates the products -and turns them into com- modities. Production has become a social act. Exchange and appropriation continue to be individual acts, the acts of individuals. The social product is appropriated by the individual capitalist. Fundamental contradiction, whence arise all the contradictions in which our present day society moves, and which modern industry brings to light. A. Severance of the producer from the means of production. Condemnation of the worker to wage-labour for life. Antagonism between the proletariat and the bourgeoisie. B. Growing predominance and increasing effectiveness of the laws governing the produc- tion of commodities. Unbridled competition. Contradiction between socialised organisation in the individual factory and social anarchy in production as a whole. C. On the one hand, perfecting of machinery, made by competition compulsory for each in- dividual manufacturer, and complemented by a Utopian and Scientific. 85 constantly growing displacement of labourers. Industrial reserve-army. On the other hand, unlimited extension of production, also compul- sory under competition, for every manufacturer. On both sides, unheard of development of pro- ductive forces, excess of supply over demand, over-production, glutting of the markets, crises every ten years, the vicious circle : excess here, of means of production and products-excess there, of labourers, without employment and without means of existence. But these two levers of production and of social well-being are unable to work together, because the capi- talist form of production prevents the productive forces from working and the products from circulating, unless they are first turned into capital—which their very superabundance pre- vents. The contradiction has grown into an absurdity. The mode of production rises in rebellion against the form of exchange. The bourgeoisie are convicted of incapacity further to manage their own social productive forces. D. Partial recognition of the social character of the productive forces forced upon the capi- talists themselves. Taking over of the great 86 Socialism : institutions for production and communication, first by joint-stock companies, later on by trusts, then by the State. The bourgeoisie demon- strated to be a superfluous class. All its social functions are now performed by salaried em- ployees. III. Proletarian Revolution.-Solution of the contradictions. The proletariat seizes the public power, and by means of this transforms the socialised means of production, slipping from the hands of the bourgeoisie, into public pro- perty. By this act, the proletariat frees the means of production from the character of capital they have thus far borne, and gives their socialised character complete freedom to work itself out. Socialised production upon a pre- determined plan becomes henceforth possible. The development of production makes the exist- ence of different classes of society thenceforth an anachronism. In proportion as anarchy in social production vanishes, the political autho- rity of the State dies out. Man, at last the master of his own form of social organisation, becomes at the same time the lord over Nature, his own master-free. To accomplish this act of universal emanci- Utopian and Scientific. 87 pation is the historịcal mission of the modern proletariat. To thoroughly comprehend the historical conditions and thus the very nature of this act, to impart to the now oppressed proletarian class a full knowledge of the condi- tions and of the meaning of the momentous act it is called upon to accomplish, this is the task of the theoretical expression of the prole- tarian movement, scientific Socialism. APPENDI X. THE MARK. See p. 57 In a country like Germany, in which quite half the population live by agriculture, it is necessary that the socialist working-men, and through them the peasants, should learn how the present system of landed pro- perty, large as well as small, has arisen. It is neces- sary to contrast the misery of the agricultural labourers of the present time and the mortgage-servitude of the small peasants, with the old common property of all free men in what was then in truth their “fatherland," the free common possession of all by inheritance. I shall give, therefore, a short historical sketch of the primitive agrarian conditions of the German tribes. A few traces of these have survived until our own time, but all through the Middle Ages they served as the basis and as the type of all public in- stitutions, and permeated the whole of public life, not only in Germany, but also in the north of France, England, and Scandinavia. And yet they have been 89 90 Appendix. so completely forgotten, that recently G. L. Maurer has had to re-discover their real significance. Two fundamental facts, that arose spontaneously, govern the primitive history of all, or of almost all, nations; the grouping of the people according to kindred, and common property in the soil. And this was the case with the Germans. As they had brought with them from Asia the method of grouping by tribes and gentes, as they even in the time of the Romans so drew up their battle array, that those related to each other always stood shoulder to shoulder, this grouping also governed the partitioning of their new territory east of the Rhine and north of the Danube. Each tribe settled down upon the new possession, not according to whim or accident, but, as Cæsar ex- pressly states, according to the gens-relationship between the members of the tribe. A particular area was apportioned to each of the nearly related larger groups, and on this again the individual gentes, each including a certain number of families, settled down by villages. A number of allied villages formed a hundred (old high German, huntari; old Norse, heradh). A number of hundreds formed a gau or shire. The sum total of the shires was the people itself. The land which was not taken possession of by the village remained at the disposal of the hundred. What was not assigned to the latter remained for the Appendix. 91 shire. Whatever after that was still to be disposed of -generally a very large tract of land—was the im- mediate possession of the whole people. Thus in Sweden we find all these different stages of common holding side by side. Each village had its village common land (bys almänningar), and beyond this was the hundred common land (härads), the shire common land (lands), and finally the people's common land. This last, claimed by the king as representative of the whole nation, was known therefore as Konungs almänningar. But all of these, even the royal lands, were named, without distinction, almänningar, com- mon land. This old Swedish arrangement of the common land, in its minute subdivision, evidently belongs to a later stage of development. If it ever did exist in Germany, it soon vanished. The rapid increase in the population led to the establishment of a number of daughter-villages on the Mark, i.e., on the large tract of land attributed to each individual mother village. These daughter-villages formed a single mark-association with the mother village, on the basis of equal or of restricted rights. Thus we find every- where in Germany, so far as research goes back, a larger or smaller number of villages united in one mark-association. But these associations were, at least, at first, still subject to the great federations of 92 Appendix. the marks of the hundred, or of the shire. And, finally, the people, as a whole, originally formed one single great mark-association, not only for the admin- istration of the land that remained the immediate possession of the people, but also as a supreme court over the subordinate local marks. Until the time when the Frankish kingdom sub- dued Germany east of the Rhine, the centre of gravity of the mark-association seems to have been in the gau or shire—the shire seems to have formed the unit mark-association. For, upon this assumption alone is it explicable that, upon the official division of the kingdom, so many old and large marks reappear as shires. Soon after this time began the decay of the old large marks. Yet even in the code known as the Kaiserrecht, the “Emperor's Law” of the thirteenth or fourteenth century, it is a general rule that a mark includes from six to twelve villages. In Cæsar's time a great part at least of the Ger- mans, the Suevi, to wit, who had not yet got any fixed settlement, cultivated their fields in common From analogy with other peoples we may take it that this was carried on in such a way that the individual gentes, each including a number of nearly related families, cultivated in common the land apportioned to them, which was changed from year to year, and divided the products among the families. But after 6 Appendix. 93 era, had the Suevi, about the beginning of our era, settled down in their new domains, this soon ceased. At all events, Tacitus (150 years after Cæsar) only mentions the tilling of the soil by individual families. But the land to be tilled only belonged to these for a year. Every year it was divided up anew and re- distributed. How this was done, is still to be seen at the present time on the Moselle and in the Hochwald, on the so-called "Gehöferschaften.” There the whole of the land under cultivation, arable and meadows, not annually it is true, but every three, six, nine, or twelve years, is thrown together and parcelled out into a number of “Gewanne,” or areas, according to situation and the quality of the soil. Each Gewann is again divided into as many equal parts, long, narrow strips, as there are claimants in the associa- tion. These are shared by lot among the members, so that every member receives an equal portion in each Gewann. At the present time the shares have become unequal by divisions among heirs, sales, etc. ; but the old full share still furnishes the unit that deter- mines the half, or quarter, or one-eighth shares. The uncultivated land, forest and pasture land, is still a common possession for common use. The same primitive arrangement obtained until the beginning of this century in the so-called assignments by lot (Loosgüter) of the Rhein palatinate in Bavaria, 94 Appendix. whose arable land has since been turned into the private property of individuals. The Gehöferschaften also find it more and more to their interest to let the periodical re-division become obsolete and to turn the changing ownership into settled private property. Thus most of them, if not all, have died out in the last forty years and given place to villages with peasant proprietors using the forests and pasture land in common. The first piece of ground that passed into the private property of individuals was that on which the house stood. The inviolability of the dwelling, that basis of all personal freedom, was transferred from the caravan of the nomadic train to the log house of the stationary peasant, and gradually was transformed into a complete right of property in the homestead. This had already come about in the time of Tacitus. The free German's homestead must, even in that time, have been excluded from the mark, and thereby in- accessible to its officials, a safe place of refuge for fugitives, as we find it described in the regulations of the marks of later times, and to some extent, even in the “ leges Barbarorum,” the codifications of German tribal customary law, written down from the fifth to the eighth century. For the sacredness of the dwelling was not the effect but the cause of its transformation into private property. Appendix. 95 Four or five hundred years after Tacitus, according to the same law-books, the cultivated land also was the hereditary, although not the absolute freehold property of individual peasants, who had the right to dispose of it by sale or any other means of transfer. The causes of this transformation, as far as we can trace them, are twofold. First, from the beginning there were in Germany itself, besides the close villages already described, with their complete ownership in common of the land, other villages where, besides homesteads, the fields also were excluded from the mark, the property of the community, and were parcelled out among the in- dividual peasants as their hereditary property. But this was only the case where the nature of the place, so to say, compelled it: in narrow valleys, and on narrow, flat ridges between marshes, as in Westphalia; later on, in the Odenwald, and in almost all the Alpine valleys. In these places the village consisted, as it does now, of scattered individual dwellings, each surrounded by the fields belonging to it. A periodical re-division of the arable land was in these cases hardly possible, and so what remained within the mark was only the circumjacent untilled land. When, later, the right to dispose of the homestead by transfer to a third person became an important consideration, those who were free owners of their fields found them- 96 Appendix, selves in an advantageous position. The wish to attain these advantages may have led in many of the villages with common ownership of the land to the letting the customary method of partition die out and to the transformation of theindividual shares of the mem- bers into hereditary and transferable freehold property. But, second, conquest led the Germans on to Roman territory, where, for centuries, the soil had been private property (the unlimited property of Roman law), and where the small number of conquerors could not possibly altogether do away with a form of holding so deeply rooted. The connexion of hereditary private property in fields and meadows with Roman law, at all events on territory that had been Roman, is supported by the fact that such remains of common property in arable land as have come down to our time are found on the left bank of the Rhine-i.e., on conquered terri- tory, but territory thoroughly Germanised. When the Franks settled here in the fifth century, common ownership in the fields must still have existed among them, otherwise we should not find there Gehöfer- schaften and Loosgüter. But here also private owner- ship soon got the mastery, for this form of holding only do we find mentioned, in so far as arable land is concerned, in the Riparian law of the sixth century, And in the interior of Germany, as I have said, the cultivated land also soon became private property. Appendix. 97 But if the German conquerors adopted private ownership in fields and meadows—i.e., gave up at the first division of the land, or soon after, any re-par- tition (for it was nothing more than this), they intro- duced, on the other hand, everywhere their German mark system, with common holding of woods and pastures, together with the over-lordship of the mark in respect to the partitioned land. This hap- pened not only with the Franks in the north of France and the Anglo-Saxons in England, but also with the Burgundians in Eastern France, the Visigoths in the south of France and Spain, and the Ostro- goths and Langobardians in Italy. In these last- named countries, however, as far as is known, traces of the mark government have lasted until the present time almost exclusively in the higher mountain regions. The form that the mark government has assumed after the periodical partition of the cultivated land had fallen into disuse, is that which now meets us, not only in the old popular laws of the fifth, sixth, seventh, and eighth centuries, but also in the English and Scandin- avian law-books of the Middle Ages, in the many German mark regulations (the so-called Weisthümer) from the fifteenth to the seventeenth century, and in the customary laws (coûtumes) of Northern France. Whilst the association of the mark gave up the G 98 Appendix. right of, from time to time, partitioning fields and meadows anew among its individual members, it did not give up a single one of its other rights over these lands. And these rights were very important. The association had only transferred their fields to in- dividuals with a view to their being used as arable and meadow land, and with that view alone. Beyond that the individual owner had no right. Treasures found in the earth, if they lay deeper than the ploughshare goes, did not, therefore, originally belong to him, but to the community. It was the , . same thing with digging for ores, and the like. All these rights were, later on, stolen by the princes and landlords for their own use. But, further, the use of arable and meadow lands was under the supervision and direction of the com- munity and that in the following form. Wherever three-field farming obtained—and that was almost everywhere—the whole cultivated area of the village was divided into three equal parts, each of which was alternately sown one year with winter seed, the second with summer seed, and the third lay fallow. Thus the village had each year its winter field, its summer field, its fallow field. In the partition of the land care was taken that each member's share was made up of equal portions from each of the three fields, so that everyone could, without difficulty, Appendix. 99 accommodate himself to the regulations of the com- munity, in accordance with which he would have to sow autumn seed only in his winter field, and so on. The field whose turn it was to lie fallow returned, for the time being, into the common possession, and served the community in general for pasture. And as soon as the two other fields were reaped, they likewise became again common property until seed-time, and were used as common pasturage. The same thing occurred with the meadows after the aftermath. The owners had to remove the fences upon all fields given over to pasturage. This compulsory pasturage, of course, made it necessary that the time of sowing and of reaping should not be left to the individual, but be fixed for all by the community or by custom. All other land, i.e., all that was not house and farm- yard, or so much of the mark as had been distributed among individuals, remained, as in early times, common property for common use; forests, pasture lands, heaths, moors, rivers, ponds, lakes, roads and , bridges, hunting and fishing grounds. Just as the share of each member in so much of the mark as was distributed was of equal size, so was his share also in the use of the “common mark.” The nature of this use was determined by the members of the community as a whole. So, too, was the mode of partition, if the soil that had been cultivated no 100 Appendix. longer sufficed, and a portion of the common mark was taken under cultivation. The chief use of the common mark was in pasturage for the cattle and feeding of pigs on acorns. Besides that, the forest yielded timber and firewood, litter for the animals, berries and mushrooms, whilst the moor, where it ex- isted, yielded turf. The regulations as to pasture, the use of wood, etc., make up the most part of the many mark records written down at various epochs between the thirteenth and the eighteenth centuries, at the time when the old unwritten law of custom began to be contested. The common woodlands that are still met with here and there, are the remnants of these ancient unpartitioned marks. Another relic, at all all events in West and South Germany, is the idea, deeply rooted in the popular consciousness, that the forest should be common property, wherein every one may gather flowers, berries, mushrooms, beechnuts and the like, and generally so long as he does no mischief, act and do as he will. But this also Bismarck remedies, and with his famous berry-legislation brings down the Western Provinces to the level of the old Prussian squirearchy. Just as the members of the community originally had equal shares in the soil and equal rights of us- age, so they had also an equal share in the legislation, Appendix. IOI administration, and jurisdiction within the mark. At fixed times and, if necessary, more frequently, they met in the open air to discuss the affairs of the mark and to sit in judgment upon breaches of regulations and disputes concerning the mark. It was, only in miniature, the primitive assembly of the German people, which was, originally, nothing other than a great assembly of the mark. Laws were made, but only in rare cases of necessity. Officials were chosen, their conduct in office examined, but chiefly judicial functions were exercised. The president had only to formulate the questions. The judgment was given by the aggregate of the members present. The unwritten law of the mark was, in primitive times, pretty much the only public law of those German tribes, which had no kings; the old tribal nobility, which disappeared during the conquest of the Roman empire, or soon after, easily fitted itself into this primitive constitution, as easily as all other spontaneous growths of the time, just as the Celtic clan-nobility, even as late as the seventeenth century, found its place in the Irish holding of the soil in com- mon. And this unwritten law has struck such deep roots into the whole life of the Germans, that we find traces of it at every step and turn in the historical development of our people. In primitive times, the whole public authority in time of peace was exclu- IO2 Appendix. sively judicial, and rested in the popular assembly of the hundred, the shire, or of the whole tribe. But this popular tribunal was only the popular tribunal of the mark adapted to cases that did not purely concern the mark, but came within the scope of the public authority. Even when the Frankish kings began to transform the self-governing shires into pro- vinces governed by royal delegates, and thus separated the royal shire-courts from the common mark tribun- als, in both the judicial function remained vested in the people. It was only when the old democratic freedom had been long undermined, when attendance at the public assemblies and tribunals had become a severe burden upon the impoverished freemen, that Charlemagne, in his shire-courts, could introduce judgment by Schöffen, lay assessors, appointed by the king's judge, in the place of judgment by the whole popular assembly. But this did not seriously touch the tribunals of the mark. These, on the contrary, still remained the model even for the feudal tribunals in the Middle Ages. In these, too, the feudal lord only formulated the issues, whilst 1 Not to be confused with the Schöffen courts after the manner of Bismarck and Leonhardt, in which lawyers and lay assessors combined find verdict and judgment. In the old judicial courts there were no lawyers at all, the presiding judge had no vote at all, and the Schöffen or lay assessors gave the verdict inde- pendently. Appendix. 103 the vassals themselves found the verdict. The institu- tions governing a village during the Middle Ages are but those of an independent village mark, and passed into those of a town as soon as the village was trans- formed into a town, i.e., was fortified with walls and trenches. All later constitutions of cities have grown out of these original town mark regulations. And, finally, from the assembly of the mark were copied the arrangements of the numberless free associations of mediæval times not based upon common holding of the land, and especially those of the free guilds. The rights conferred upon the guild for the exclusive carrying on of a particular trade were dealt with just as if they were rights in a common mark. With the same jealousy, often with precisely the same means in the guilds as in the mark, care was taken that the share of each member in the common benefits and advantages should be equal, or as nearly equal as possible. All this shows the mark organisation to have possessed an almost wonderful capacity for adapta- tion to the most different departments of public life and to the most various ends. The same qualities it manifested during the progressive development of agriculture and in the struggle of the peasants with the advance of large landed property. It had arisen with the settlement of the Germans in Germania Magna, 104 Appendix. that is, at a time when the breeding of cattle was the chief means of livelihood, and when the rudimentary, half-forgotten agriculture which they had brought with them from Asia was only just put into practice again. It held its own all through the Middle Ages in fierce, incessant conflicts with the land-holding nobility. But it was still such a necessity that wherever the nobles had appropriated the peasants' land, the villages inhabited by these peasants, now turned into serfs, or at best into coloni or dependent tenants, were still organised on the lines of the old mark, in spite of the constantly increasing encroachments of the lords of the manor. Farther on we will give an example of this. It adapted itself to the most different forms of holding the cultivated land, so long as only an uncultivated common was still left, and in like man- ner to the most different rights of property in the common mark, as soon as this ceased to be the free property of the community. It died out when almost the whole of the peasants' lands, both private and common, were stolen by the nobles and the clergy, with the willing help of the princes. But economi- cally obsolete and incapable of continuing as the pre- valent social organisation of agriculture it became only, when the great advances in farming of the last hundred years made agriculture a science and led to altogether new systems of carrying it on. Appendix. 105 As re- The undermining of the mark organisation began soon after the conquest of the Roman empire. presentatives of the nation, the Frankish kings took possession of the immense territories belonging to the people as a whole, especially the forests, in order to squander them away as presents to their courtiers, to their generals, to bishops and abbots. Thus they laid the foundation of the great landed estates, later on, of the nobles and the Church. Long before the time of Charlemagne, the Church had a full third of all the land in France, and it is certain that, during the Middle Ages, this proportion held generally for the whole of Catholic Western Europe. The constant wars, internal and external, whose regular consequences were confiscations of land, ruined a great number of peasants, so that even during the Merovingian dynasty, there were very many free men owning no land. The incessant wars of Charlemagne broke down the mainstay of the free peasantry. Origin- ally every freeholder owed service, and not only had to equip himself, but also to maintain himself under arms for six months. No wonder that even in Charle- magne's time scarcely one man in five could be actually got to serve. Under the chaotic rule of his successors, the freedom of the peasants went still more rapidly to the dogs. On the one hand, the ravages of 106 Appendix. the Northmen's invasions, the eternal wars between kings, and feuds between nobles, compelled one free peasant after another to seek the protection of some lord. Upon the other hand, the covetousness of these same lords and of the Church hastened this process; by fraud, by promises, threats, violence, they forced more and more peasants and peasants' land under their yoke. In both cases, the peasants' land was added to the lord's manor, and was, at best, only given back for the use of the peasant in return for tribute and ser- vice. Thus the peasant, from a free owner of the land, was turned into a tribute-paying, service-rendering ap- panage of it, into a serf. This was the case in the western Frankish kingdom, especially west of the Rhine. East of the Rhine, on the other hand, a large number of free peasants still held their own, for the most part scattered, occasionally united in villages entirely composed of freemen. Even here, however, in the tenth, eleventh, and twelfth centuries, the over- whelming power of the nobles and the Church was constantly forcing more and more peasants into serf- dom. When a large landowner-clerical or lay-got hold of a peasant's holding, he acquired with it, at the same time, the rights in the mark that appertained to the holding. The new landlords were thus members of the mark and, within the mark, they were, originally, Appendix. 107 only regarded as on an equality with the other mem- bers of it, whether free or serfs, even if these happened to be their own bondsmen. But soon, in spite of the dogged resistance of the peasants, the lords acquired in many places special privileges in the mark, and were often able to make the whole of it subject to their own rule as lords of the manor. Nevertheless the old or- ganisation of the mark continued, though now it was presided over and encroached upon by the lord of the manor. How absolutely necessary at that time the constitu- tion of the mark was for agriculture, even on large estates, is shown in the most striking way by the col- onisation of Brandenburg and Silesia by Frisian and Saxon settlers, and by settlers from the Netherlands and the Frankish banks of the Rhine. From the twelfth century, the people were settled in villages on the lands of the lords according to German law, i.e., according to the old mark law, so far as it still held on the manors owned by lords. Every man had house and homestead; a share in the village fields, determined after the old method by lot, and of the same size for and the right of using the woods and pastures, generally in the woods of the lord of the manor, less frequently in a special mark. These rights were hereditary. The fee simple of the land continued in the lord, to whom the colonists owed certain hereditary all ; 108 Appendix. tributes and services. But these dues were so moder- ate, that the condition of the peasants was better here than anywhere else in Germany. Hence, they kept quiet when the peasants' war broke out. For this apostasy from their own cause they were sorely chas- tised. About the middle of the thirteenth century there was everywhere a decisive change in favour of the peasants. The crusades had prepared the way for it. . Many of the lords, when they set out to the East, explicitly set their peasant serfs free. Others were killed or never returned. Hundreds of noble families vanished, whose peasant serfs frequently gained their freedom. Moreover, as the needs of the landlords in- creased, the command over the payments in kind and services of the peasants became much more important than that over their persons. The serfdom of the earlier Middle Ages, which still had in it much of ancient slavery, gave to the lords rights which lost more and more their value ; it gradually vanished, the position of the serfs narrowed itself down to that of simple hereditary tenants. As the method of cultivating the land reinained exactly as of old, an increase in the revenues of the lord of the manor was only to be ob- tained by the breaking up of new ground, the estab- lishing new villages. But this was only possible by a friendly agreement with the colonists, whether they be- Appendix. 109 longed to the estate or were strangers. Hence, in the documents of this time, we meet with a clear deter- a mination and a moderate scale of the peasants' dues, and good treatment of the peasants, especially by the spiritual landlords. And, lastly, the favourable posi- tion of the new colonists reacted again on the condition of their neighbours, the bondmen, so that in all the North of Germany these also, whilst they continued their services to the lords of the manor, received their personal freedom. The Slav and Lithuanian peasants alone were not freed. But this was not to last. In the fourteenth and fifteenth centuries the towns rose rapidly, and became rapidly rich. Their artistic handicraft, their luxurious life, throve and flourished, especially in South Germany and on the Rhine. The profusion of the town patricians aroused the envy of the coarsely-fed, coarsely-clothed, roughly-furnished, coun- try lords. But whence to obtain all these fine things? Lying in wait for travelling merchants became more and more dangerous and unprofitable. But to buy them, money was requisite. And that the peasants alone could furnish. Hence, renewed oppression of the peasants, higher tributes, and more corvée; hence renewed and always increasing eagerness to force the free peasants to become bondmen, the bondmen to become serfs, and to turn the common mark-land into land belonging to the lord. In this the princes and ΙΙΟ Appendix. nobles were helped by the Roman jurists, who, with their application of Roman jurisprudence to German conditions, for the most part not understood by them, knew how to produce endless confusion, but yet that sort of confusion by which the lord always won and the peasant always lost. The spiritual lords helped themselves in a more simple way. They forged documents, by which the rights of the peasants were curtailed and their duties increased. Against these robberies by the landlords, the peasants, from the end of the fifteenth century, frequently rose in isolated insurrections, until, in 1525, the great Peasants' War overflowed Suabia, Bavaria, Franconia, extending into Alsace, the Palatinate, the Rheingau, and Thuringen. The peasants succumbed after hard fighting. From that time dates the renewed predom- inance of serfdom amongst the German peasants generally. In those places where the fight had raged, all remaining rights of the peasants were now shame- lessly trodden under foot, their common land turned into the property of the lord, they themselves into serfs. The North German peasants, being placed in more favourable conditions, had remained quiet ; their only reward was that they fell under the same sub- jection, only more slowly. Serfdom is introduced among the German peasantry from the middle of the sixteenth century in Eastern Prussia, Pomerania, Appendix. III Brandenburg, Silesia, and from the end of that century in Schleswig-Holstein, and henceforth becomes more and more their general condition. This new act of violence had, however, an economic cause. From the wars consequent upon the Pro- testant Reformation, only the German princes had gained greater power. It was now all up with the nobles' favourite trade of highway robbery. If the nobles were not to go to ruin, greater revenues had to be got out of their landed property. But the only way to effect this was to work at least a part of their own estates on their own account, upon the model of the large estates of the princes, and especially of the monasteries. That which had hitherto been the exception now became a necessity. But this new agricultural plan was stopped by the fact that almost everywhere the soil had been given to tribute-paying peasants. As soon as the tributary peasants, whether free men or coloni, had been turned into serfs, the noble lords had a free hand. Part of the peasants were, as it is now called in Ireland, evicted, i.e., either hunted away or degraded to the level of cottars, with mere huts and a bit of garden land, whilst the ground belonging to their homestead was made part and parcel of the demesne of the lord, and was cultivated by the new cottars and such peasants as were still left, in corvée labour. Not only were many II2 Appendix. peasants thus actually driven away, but the corvée service of those still left was enhanced considerably, and at an ever increasing rate. The capitalistic period announced itself in the country districts as the period of agricultural industry on a large scale, based upon the corvée labour of serfs. This transformation took place at first rather slowly. But then came the Thirty Years' War. For a whole generation Germany was overrun in all directions by the most licentious soldiery known to history. Every- where was burning, plundering, rape, and murder. The peasant suffered most where, apart from the great armies, the smaller independent bands, or rather the freebooters, operated uncontrolled, and upon their own account. The devastation and de- population were beyond all bounds. When peace came, Germany lay on the ground helpless, down-trodden, cut to pieces, bleeding; but, once again, the most pitiable, miserable of all was the peasant. The land-owning noble was now the only lord in the country districts. The princes, who just at that time were reducing to nothing his political rights in the assemblies of Estates by way of compensa- tion, left him a free hand against the peasants. The last power of resistance on the part of the peasants had been broken by the war. Thus the Appendix. II3 noble was able to arrange all agrarian conditions in the manner most conducive to the restoration of his ruined finances. Not only were the deserted home- steads of the peasants, without further ado, united with the lord's demesne; the eviction of the peasants was carried on wholesale and systematically. The greater the lord of the manor's demesne, the greater, of course, the corvée required from the peasants. The system of “unlimited corvée " was introduced anew; the noble lord was able to command the peasant, his family, his cattle, to labour for him, as often and as long as he pleased. Serfdom was now general; a free peasant was now as rare as a white And in order that the noble lord might be in a position to nip in the bud the very smallest resistance on the part of the peasants, he received from the princes of the land the right of patrimonial jurisdiction, i.e., he was nominated sole judge in all cases of offence and dispute among the peasants, even if the peasant's dispute was with him, the lord himself, so that the lord was judge in his own case! From that time, the stick and the whip ruled the agri- cultural districts. The German peasant, like the whole of Germany, had reached his lowest point of degradation. The peasant, like the whole of Ger- many, had become so powerless that all self-help failed him, and deliverance could only come from without. crow. H 114 Appendix. And it came. With the French Revolution came for Germany also and for the German peasant the dawn of a better day. No sooner had the armies of the Revolution conquered the left bank of the Rhine, than all the old rubbish vanished, as at the stroke of an enchanter's wand—corvée service, rent dues of every kind to the lord, together with the noble lord himself. The peasant of the left bank of the Rhine was now lord of his own holding; moreover, in the Code Civil, drawn up at the time of the Revolution and only baffled and botched by Napoleon, he received a code of laws 'adapted to his new conditions, that he could not only understand, but also carry comfort- ably in his pocket. But the peasant on the right bank of the Rhine had still to wait a long time. It is true that in Prussia, after the well-deserved defeat at Jena, some of the most shameful privileges of the nobles were abolished, and the so-called redemption of such peasants' burdens as were still left was made legally possible. But to a great extent and for a long time this was only on paper. In the other German States, still less was done. A second French Revolution, that of 1830, was needed to bring about the "redemption” in Baden and certain other small States bordering upon France. And at the moment when the third French Revolution, in 1848, at last carried Germany along ) Appendix. 115 with it, the redemption was far from being completed in Prussia, and in Bavaria had not even begun. After that, it went along more rapidly and unimpeded; the corvée labour of the peasants, who had this time become rebellious on their own account, had lost all value. And in what did this redemption consist ? In this, that the noble lord, on receipt of a certain sum of money or of a piece of land from the peasant, should henceforth recognise the peasant's land, as much or as little as was left to him, as the peasant's property, free of all burdens; though all the land that had at any time belonged to the noble lord was nothing but land stolen from the peasants. Nor was this all. In these arrangements, the Government officials charged with carrying them out almost always took the side, natur- ally, of the lords, with whom they lived and caroused, so that the peasants, even against the letter of the law, were again defrauded right and left. And thus, thanks to three French revolutions, and to the German one, that has grown out of them, we have once again a free peasantry. But how very in- ferior is the position of our free peasant of to-day compared with the free member of the mark of the olden time! His homestead is generally much smaller, and the unpartitioned mark is reduced to a few very small and poor bits of communal forest. But, without , 116 Appendix. the use of the mark, there can be no cattle for the small peasant; without cattle, no manure; without manure, no agriculture. The tax-collector and the officer of the law threatening in the rear of him, whom the peasant of to-day knows only too well, were people unknown to the old members of the mark. And so was the mortgagee, into whose clutches nowadays one peasant's holding after another falls. And the best of it is that these modern free peasants, whose property is so restricted, and whose wings are so clipped, were created in Germany, where everything happens too late, at a time when scientific agriculture and the newly-invented agricultural machinery make cultivation on a small scale a method of production more and more antiquated, less and less capable of yielding a liveli- hood. As spinning and weaving by machinery re- placed the spinning-wheel and the hand-loom, so these new methods of agricultural production must inevit- ably replace the cultivation of land in small plots by landed property on a iarge scale, provided that the time necessary for this be granted. For already the whole of European agriculture, as carried on at the present time, is threatened by an overpowering rival, viz., the production of corn on a gigantic scale by America. Against this soil, fertile, manured by nature for a long range of years, and to be had for a bagatelle, neither our small peasants, up Appendix. 117 to their eyes in debt, nor our large landowners, equally deep in debt, can fight. The whole of the European agricultural system is being beaten by American com- petition. 'Agriculture, as far as Europe is concerned, will only be possible if carried on upon socialised lines, and for the advantage of society as a whole. This is the outlook for our peasants. And the restoration of a free peasant class, starved and stunted as it is, has this value,—that it has put the peasant in a position, with the aid of his natural comrade, the worker, to help himself, as soon as he once under- stands how. a THE END. Printed by Cowan & Co., Limited, Perth. OPINIONS OF THE PRESS ON THE SOCIAL SCIENCE SERIES. YOS ". The Principles of State Interference' is another of Messrs. Swan Sonnen- schein's Series of Handbooks on Scientific Social Subjects. It would be fitting to close our remarks on this little work with a word of com- mendation of the publishers of so many useful volumes by eminent writers on questions of pressing interest to a large number of the com- munity. We have now received and read a good number of the handbooks which Messrs. Swan Sonnenschein have published in this series, and can speak in the highest terms of them. They are written by men of con- siderable knowledge of the subjects they have undertaken to discuss; they are concise; they give a fair estimate of the progress which recent dis- cussion has added towards the solution of the pressing social questions of to-day, are well up to date, and are published at a price within the resources of the public to which they are likely to be of the most use.” Westminster Review, July, 1891. “ The excellent Social Science Series,' which is published at as low a price as to place it within everybody's reach.”-Review of Reviews. "A most useful series. ... This impartial series welcomes both just writers and unjust.”—Manchester Guardian. “The Social Science Series' is doubtless doing useful service in calling atten- tion to certain special needs and defects of the body politic, and pointing out the way to improvement and reform."-Bookseller. "Convenient, well-printed, and moderately-priced volumes."--Reynold's News- paper. "There is a certain impartiality about the attractive and well-printed volumes which form the series to which the works noticed in this article belong. There is no editor and no common design beyond a desire to redress those errors and irregularities of society which all the writers, though they may agree in little else, concur in acknowledging and deploring. The system adopted appears to be to select men known to have a claim to speak with more or less authority upon the shortcomings of civilisation, and to allow each to propound the views which commend themselves most strongly to his mind, without reference to the possible flat contradiction which may be forthcoming at the hands of the next contributor."-Literary World. ". The Social Science Series' aims at the illustration of all sides of social and economic truth and error."-Scotsman. SWAN SONNENSCHEIN & CO., LONDON. SOCIAL SCIENCE SERIES. SCARLET CLOTH, EACH 28. 6d. 1. Work and Wages. Prof. J. E. THOROLD ROGERS. “Nothing that Professor Rogers writes can fail to be of interest to thoughtful people."-- Athenæum. 2. Civilisation : its Cause and Cure. EDWARD CARPENTER. “No passing piece of polemics, but a permanent possession."-Scottish Review. 3. Quintessence of Socialism. Dr. SCHÄFFLE. “Precisely the manual needed. Brief, lucid, fair and wise."— British Weekly. 4. Darwinism and Politics. D. G. RITCHIE, M.A. (Oxon.). New Edition, with two additional Essays on HUMAN EVOLUTION. “One of the most suggestive books we have met with.”- Literary World. 5. Religion of Socialism. E. BELFORT Bax. 6. Ethics of Socialism. E. BELFORT BAX. “Mr. Bax is by far the ablest of the English exponents of Socialism.”-Westminster Review. 7. The Drink Question. Dr. KATE MITCHELL. “Plenty of interesting matter for reflection.'-Graphic. 8. Promotion of General Happiness. Prof. M. MACMILLAN. “A reasoned account of the most advanced and most enlightened utilitarian doc- trine in a clear and readable form.”-Scotsman. 9. England's Ideal, &c. EDWARD CARPENTER. "The literary power is unmistakable, their freshness of style, their humour, and their enthusiasm."-Pall Mall Gazette. 10. Socialism in England. SIDNEY WEBB, LL.B. “The best general view of the subject from the modern Socialist side." —Athenæum. 11. Prince Bismarck and State Socialism. W. H. DAWSON. "A succinct, well-digested review of German social and economic legislation since 1870."-Saturday Review. 12. Godwin's Political Justice (On Property). Edited by H. S. SALT. "Shows Godwin at his best ; with an interesting and informing introduction." - Glasgow Herald 13. The Story of the French Revolution. E. BELFORT BAX. “A trustworthy outline."-Scotsman. 14. The Co-Operative Commonwealth. LAURENCE GRONLUND. “An independent exposition of the Socialism of the Marx school.” —Contemporary Review. 15. Essays and Addresses. BERNARD BOSANQUET, M.A. (Oxon.). “Ought to be in the hands of every student of the Nineteenth Century spirit."- Echo. “No one can complain of not being able to understand what Mr. Bosanquet means."-Pall Mall Gazette. 16. Charity Organisation. C. S. Loch, Secretary to Charity Organisation Society. “A perfect little manual."— Athenæum. “Deserves a wide circulation.”---Scotsman. 17. Thoreau's Anti-Slavery and Reform Papers. Edited by H. S. SALT. “An interesting collection of essays.” -- Literary World. 18. Self-Help a Hundred Years Ago. G. J. HOLYOAKE. “Will be studied with much benefit by all who are interested in the amelioration of the condition of the poor."- Morning Post. 19. The New York State Reformatory at Elmira. ALEXANDER WINTER. With Preface by HAVELOCK ELLIS. "A valuable contribution to the literature of penology."-Black and White. SOCIAL SCIENCE SERIES-(Continued). 20. Common Sense about Women. T. W. HIGGINSON. “An admirable collection of papers, advocating in the most liberal spirit the emancipation of women.”-Woman's Herald. 21. The Unearned Increment. W. H. Dawson. “A concise but comprehensive volume.”—Echo. 22. Our Destiny. LAURENCE GRONLUND. "A very vigorous little book, dealing with the influence of Socialism on morals and religion.”—Daily Chronicle. 23. The Working-Class Movement in America. Dr. EDWARD and E. MARX AVELING. “Will give a good idea of the condition of the working classes in America, and of the various organisations which they have formed." --Scots Leader. 24. Luxury Prof. EMILE DE LAVELEYE. "An eloquent plea on moral and economical grounds for simplicity of life.”- Academy. 25. The Land and the Labourers. Rev. C. W. STUBBS, M.A. “This admirable book should be circulated in every village in the country.”- Manchester Guardian. 26. The Evolution of Property. PAUL LAFARGUE. “Will prove interesting and profitable to all students of economic history."- Scotsman, 27. Crime and its Causes. W. DOUGLAS MORRISON. “Can hardly fail to suggest to all readers several new and pregnant reflections on the subject.”- Anti-Jacobin. 28. Principles of State Interference. D. G. RITCHIE, M.A. “An interesting contribution to the controversy on the functions of the State.”- Glasgow Herald 29. German Socialism and F. Lassalle. W. H. Dawson. “As a biographical history of German Socialistic movements during this century it may be accepted as complete.”British Weekly. 30. The Purse and the Conscience. H. M. THOMPSON, B.A. (Cantab.). “Shows common sense and fairness in his arguments.”-Scotsman. 31. Origin of Property in Land. FUSTEL DE COULANGES. Edited, with an Introductory Chapter on the English Manor, by Prof. W. J. ASHLEY, M.A. “His views are clearly stated, and are worth reading."-Saturday Review. 32. The English Republic. W. J. LINTON. Edited by KINETON PARKES. “Characterised by that vigorous intellectuality which has marked his long life of literary and artistic activity.”—Glasgow Herald. 33. The Co-Operative Movement. BEATRICE POTTER. “Without doubt the ablest and most philosophical analysis of the Co-Operative Movement which has yet been produced."-Speaker. 34. Neighbourhood Guilds. Dr. STANTON COIT. "A most suggestive little book to anyone interested in the social question.”— Pall Mall Gazette. 35. Modern Humanists. J. M. ROBERTSON. “Mr. Robertson's style is excellent-nay, even brilliant--and his purely literary criticisms bear the mark of much acumen."— Times. 36. Outlooks from the New Standpoint. E. BELFORT BAX. “Mr. Bax is a very acute and accomplished student of history and economics." - Daily Chronicle. Edited by 37. Distributing Co-Operative Societies. Dr. LUIGI PIZZAMIGLIO. F. J. SNELL. "Dr. Pizzamiglio has gathered together and grouped a wide array of facts and statistics, and they speak for themselves."-Speaker. 38. Collectivism and Socialism. By A. NACQUET. Edited by W. HEAFORD. “ An admirable criticism by a well-known French politician of the New Socialism of Marx and Lassalle."--Daily Chronicle. 6 SOCIAL SCIENC, NERIES--(Continued). 39. The London Programme. SIDNEY WEBB, LL.B. "Brimful of excellent ideas.”- Anti-Jacobin. 40. The Modern State. PAUL LEROY BEAULIEU. “A most interesting book; well worth a place in the library of every social inquirer."--N.B. Economist. 41. The Condition of Labour. HENRY GEORGE. "Written with striking ability and sure to attract attention.”- Newcastle Chronicle. 42. The Revolutionary Spirit preceding the French Revolution. FELIX ROCQUAIN. With a Preface by Professor HUXLEY. “The student of the French Revolution will find in it an excellent introduction to the study of that catastrophe.”- Scotsman. 43. The Student's Marx. EDWARD AVELING, D.Sc. “One of the most practically useful of any in the Series.”—Glasgow Heralt. 44. A Short History of Parliament. B. C. SKOTTOWE, M.A. (Oxon.). “Deals very carefully and completely with this side of constitutional history."- Spectator. 45. Poverty : Its Genesis and Exodus. J. G. GODARD. “He states the problems with great force and clearness.”—N. British Economist. 46. The Trade Policy of Imperial Federation. MAURICE H. HERVEY. “An interesting contribution to the discussion.”- Publishers' Circular. 47. The Dawn of Radicalism. J. BOWLES DALY, LL.D. “Forms an admirable picture of an epoch more pregnant, perhaps, with political instruction than any other in the world's history." —Daily Telegraph. 48. The Destitute Alien in Great Britain. ARNOLD WHITE; MONTAGUE CRACKAN- THORPE, Q.C.; W. A. M'ARTHUR, M.P.; W. H. WILKINS, &c. 49. Illegitimacy and the Influence of Seasons on Conduct. ALBERT LEFFINGWELL, M.D. 50. Commercial Panics of the Nineteenth Century. H. M. HYNDMAN. DOUBLE VOLUMES, Each 3s. 6d. 1. Life of Robert Owen. LLOYD JONES. “A worthy record of a life of noble activities." - Manchester Examiner. 2. The Impossibility of Social Democracy: a Second Part of “The Quintessence of Socialism". Dr. A. SCHÄFFLE. 3. The Condition of the Working Class in England in 1844. FREDERICK ENGELS. 4. The Elements of Social Economy. YVES GUYOT. IN PREPARATION- Progress and Prospects of Political Economy. Prof. J. K. INGRAM. Socialism : Scientific and Utopian. FRED, ENGELS. The State and Pensions in Old Age. J. A. SPENDER and ARTHUR ACLAND, M.P. University Extension. Dr. M. E. SADLER. The Elements of Socialism. Prof. R. T. ELY. Communism and Anarchism. R. W. BURNIE. Catholic Socialism. Dr. NITTI. The Effects of Machinery on Wages. Prof. J. S. NICHOLSON. The Fallacy of Saving. JOHN M. ROBERTSON. SWAN SONNENSCHEIN & CO.: LONDON. CHARLES SCRIBNER'S SONS: NEW YORK. 9737098€ 66&MAR UNIVERSITY OF MICHIGAN 3 9015 01215 5654