•L - º → : ... :-) ) * *rºiſae.: №gº §.” … * * * , ſ. • * x)|- §§ TEIE GIFT OF Mrs. George W. Barrus : - .G 3 + 7 Table of Coriterits, / X & © . Protection or Free Trade • The Land Question, tº Property in Land, The Condition of Labor. A Perplexed Philosopher, ſ. PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE AN EXAMINATION OF THE TARIFF QUESTION WITH ESPECIAL REGARD TO THE INTERESTs OF LABOR EY HENRY GEORGE “Prove all things; hoid fast that which is good.” NEW YORK HENRY GEORGE, 12 UNION SQUARE EAST 1888 WORKS BY HENRY GEORGE. PROGRESS AND POWERTY. 12mo, paper, 35 cents; cloth, $1.00; half calf or half morocco, $2.50. SOCIAL PROBLEMS. 12mo, paper, 35 cents; cloth, $1.00; half calf or half morocco, $2.50. - PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE 2 12mo, paper, 35 cents; cloth, $1.50; half Calf or half morocco, $3.00. | THE LAND QUESTION. Paper, 10 cents. PROPERTY IN LAND. A Controversy with the Duke of Argyll. Paper, 15 cents. For sale by all Booksellers, or sent post-paid on receipt of price. COPYRIGHT, 1886, BY HENRY GEORGE. ALL RIGHTS RESERVED. TO THE wevony OF TEIOSE ILLUSTRIOUS FRENCEIMEN OF A CENTURY AGO, QUESNAY, TURGOT, MIRA.BEAU, CONDORCET, DUPONT AND THEIR FELLOWS, WPIO IN THE NIGHT OF DESPOTISM FORESAW THIE GLORIES OF THE COMING DAY P. R. E. F. A. C. E. IN this book I have endeavored to determine whether protection or free trade better accords with the interests of labor, and to bring to a common conclusion on this subject those who really desire to raise wages. I have not only gone over the ground generally tra- versed, and examined the arguments commonly used, but, carrying the inquiry further than the controversial- ists on either side have yet ventured to go, I have sought to discover why protection retains such popular strength in spite of all exposures of its fallacies; to trace the con- nection between the tariff question and those still more important social questions, now rapidly becoming the “burning questions” of our times; and to show to what radical measures the principle of free trade logically leads. While pointing out the falsity of the belief that tariffs can protect labor, I have not failed to recognize the facts which give this belief vitality, and, by an exam- ination of these facts, have shown, not only how little the working classes can hope from that mere “revenue re- form " which is miscalled “free trade,” but how much they have to hope from real free trade. By thus har- monizing the truths which free traders perceive with the facts that to protectionists make their own theory plausible, I believe I have opened ground upon which those separated by seemingly irreconcilable differences of opinion may unite for that full application of the Wi PREFACE. free-trade principle which would secure both the largest production and the fairest distribution of wealth. By thus carrying the inquiry beyond the point where Adam Smith and the writers who have followed him have stopped; I believe I have stripped the vexed tariff question of its greatest difficulties, and have cleared the way for the settlement of a dispute which otherwise might go on interminably. The conclusions thus reached raise the doctrine of free trade from the emasculated form in which it has been taught by the English econo- mists to the fullness in which it was held by the prede- cessors of Adam Smith, those illustrious Frenchmen, with whom originated the motto Laissez faire, and who, whatever may have been the confusions of their termi- nology or the faults of their method, grasped a central truth which free traders since their time have ignored. My effort, in short, has been to make such a candid and thorough examination of the tariff question, in all its phases, as would aid men to whom the subject is now a perplexing maze to reach clear and firm conclusions. In this I trust I have done something to inspire a move- ment now faint-hearted with the earnestness and strength of radical conviction, to prevent the division into hostile camps of those whom a common purpose ought to unite, to give to efforts for the emancipation of labor greater definiteness of purpose, and to eradicate that belief in the opposition of national interests which leads peoples, even of the same blood and tongue, to regard each other as natural antagonists. To avoid any appearance of culling absurdities, I have, in referring to the protectionist position, quoted mainly from the latest writer who seems to be regarded by Amer- ican protectionists as an authoritative exponent of their views—Professor Thompson, of the University of Penn- sylvania. CHAPTER II. III. XIII, XIV, XV. XVI, XVII. XVIII. XIX, XX. XXI. C O N T E N T S. PAGE . INTRODUCTORY... . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1 CLEARING GROUND . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 12 OF METHOD. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 25 . PROTECTION As A UNIVERSAL NEED. . . . . . . . . . . . . 80 . THE PROTECTIVE UNIT. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 40 TRADE. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 49 PRODUCTION AND PRODUCERS. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 66 . TARIFFS FOR REVENUE. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 76 . TARIFFS FOR PROTECTION . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 88 . THE ENCOURAGEMENT OF INDUSTRY. . . . . . . . . . . . . . 103 . THE HOME MARKET AND HOME TRADE . . . . . . . . . 112 . EXPORTS AND IMPORTS. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 121 CONFUSIONS ARISING FROM THE USE OF MONEY. 132 DO HIGEI WAGES NECESSITATE PROTECTION ? . . . . 145 OF ADVANTAGES AND DISADVANTAGES AS REASONS FOR PROTECTION . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 154 THE DEVELOPMENT OF MANUFACTURES.. . . . . . . . . 163 PROTECTION AND PRODUCERS. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 177 EFFECT OF PROTECTION ON AMERICAN INDUSTRY. 193 PROTECTION AND WAGES. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 208 THE ABOLITION OF PROTECTION. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 231 INADEQUACY of THE FREE-TRADE ARGUMENT. . . . 288 viii CONTENTS. CHAPTER XXII. THE REAL WEAKNESs of FREE TRADE. . . . . . . XXIII. THE REAL STRENGTH OF PROTECTION. . . . . . . . . XXIV. THE PARADOX . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . ~ XXV. THE ROBBER THAT TAKES ALL THAT IS LEFT .... XXVI. TRUE FREE TRADE . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . XXVII. THE LION IN THE WAY. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . XXVIII. FREE TRADE AND SOCIALISM. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . XXIX. PRACTICAL POLITICS. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . XXX. CONCLUSION. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . PROTECTION OR H'REE TRADE P CEIAPTER T. I N T R O D U C T O R. Y. NEAR the window by which I write, a great bull is tethered by a ring in his nose. Grazing round and round he has swound his rope about the stake until now he stands a close prisoner, tantalized by rich grass he cannot reach, unable even to toss his head to rid him of the flies that cluster on his shoulders. Now and again he struggles vainly, and then, after pitiful bellowings, relapses into silent misery. This bull, a very type of massive strength, who, because he has not wit enough to see how he might be free, suffers want in sight of plenty, and is helplessly preyed upon by weaker creatures, seems to me no unfit emblem of the working masses. * In all lands, men whose toil creates abounding wealth are pinched with poverty, and, while advancing civilization opens wider vistas and awakens new de- sires, are held down to brutish levels by animal needs. Bitterly conscious of injustice, feeling in their inmost Souls that they were made for more than so narrow a life, they, too, spasmodically struggle and cry out. . But until they trace effect to cause, until they see how 2 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. they are fettered and how they may be freed, their struggles and outcries are as vain as those of the bull. Nay, they are vainer. I shall go out and drive the bull in the way that will untwist his rope. But who shall drive men into freedom? Till they use the reason with which they have been gifted, nothing can avail. For them there is no special providence. Under all forms of government the ultimate power lies with the masses. It is not kings nor aristocracies, nor land-owners nor capitalists, that anywhere really enslave the people. It is their own ignorance. Most clear is this where governments rest on universal suf- frage. The workingmen of the United States may mould to their will legislatures, courts and constitutions. Politicians strive for their favor and political parties bid against one another for their vote. But what avails this? The little finger of aggregated capital must be thicker than the loins of the working masses so long as they do not know how to use their power. And how far from any agreement as to practical reform are even those who most feel the injustice of existing condi- tions may be seen in the labor Organizations. Though beginning to realize the wastefulness of strikes and to feel the necessity of acting on general conditions through legislation, these organizations when they come to formulate political demands seem unable to unite upon any measures capable of large results. This political impotency must continue until the masses, or at least that sprinkling of more thoughtful men who are the file leaders of popular opinion, shall give such heed to larger questions as will enable them to agree on the path reform should take. It is with the hope of promoting such agreement INTRODUCTORY. J. 3 that I propose in these pages to examine a vexed ques- tion which must be settled before there can be any effi- cient union in political action for Social reform—the question whether protective tariffs are or are not helpful to those who get their living by their labor. This is a question important in itself, yet far more important in what it involves. Not only is it true that its examination cannot fail to throw light upon other social-economic questions, but it leads directly to that great “Labor Question” which every day as it passes brings more and more to the foreground in every country of the civilized world. For it is a ques- tion of direction—a question which of two divergent roads shall be taken. Whether labor is to be benefited by governmental restrictions or by the abolition of such restrictions is, in short, the question of how the bull shall go to untwist his rope. In one way or another, we must act upon the tariff question. Throughout the civilized world it everywhere lies within the range of practical politics. Even when protection is most thoroughly accepted there not only exists a more or less active minority who seek its overthrow, but the constant modifica- tions that are being made or proposed in existing tariffs are as constantly bringing the subject into the sphere of political action, while even in that country in which free trade has seemed to be most strongly rooted, the policy of protection is again raising its head. Here it is evident that the tariff question is the great political question of the immediate future. For more than a generation the slavery agitation, the war to which it led and the problems growing out of that war have absorbed political attention in the 4 - PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. United States. That era has passed, and a new one is beginning, in which economic questions must force themselves to the front. First among these questions, upon which party lines must soon be drawn and polit- ical discussion must rage, is the tariff question. It behooves not merely those who aspire to political leadership, but those who would conscientiously use their influence and their votes, to come to intelligent conclusions upon this question, and especially is this inčumbent upon the men whose aim is the emancipa- tion of labor. Some of these men are now supporters of protection; others are opposed to it. This division, which must place in political opposition to each other those who are at one in ultimate purpose, Ought not to exist. One thing or the other must be true—either protection does give better opportunities to labor and raises wages, or it does not. If it does, we who feel that labor has not its rightful opportunities and does not get its fair wages should know it, that we may unite, not merely in sustaining present protection, but in de- manding far more. If it does not, then, even if not positively harmful to the working classes, protection is a delusion and a snare, which distracts attention and divides strength, and the quicker it is seen that tariffs cannot raise wages the quicker are those who wish to raise wages likely to find out what can. The next thing to knowing how anything can be done, is to know how it cannot be done. If the bull I speak of had wit enough to see the uselessness of going one way, he would surely try the other. My aim in this inquiry is to ascertain beyond per- adventure whether protection or free-trade best accords with the interests of those who live by their labor - INTRODUCTORY. 5 I differ with those who say that with the rate of wages the state has no concern. I hold with those who deem the increase of wages a legitimate purpose of public policy. To raise and maintain wages is the great ob- ject that all who live by wages ought to seek, and workingmen are right in supporting any measure that will attain that object. Nor in this are they acting selfishly, for, while the question of wages is the most important of questions to laborers, it is also the most important of questions to society at large. Whatever improves the condition of the lowest and broadest social stratum must promote the true interests of all. Where the wages of common labor are high and remu- nerative employment is easy to obtain, prosperity will be general. Where wages are highest, there will be the largest production and the most equitable distribu- tion of wealth. There will invention be most active and the brain best guide the hand. There will be the greatest comfort, the widest diffusion of knowledge, the purest morals and the truest patriotism. If we would have a healthy, a happy, an enlightened and a virtuous people, if we would have a pure government, firmly based on the popular will and quickly responsive to it, we must strive to raise wages and keep them high. I accept as good and praiseworthy the ends avowed by the advocates of protective tariffs. What I propose to inquire is whether protective tariffs are in reality conducive to these ends. To do this thoroughly I wish to go over all the ground upon which pro- tective tariffs are advocated or defended, to consider what effect the opposite policy of free trade would have, and to stop not until conclusions are reached of which we may feel absolutely sure. 6 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. To some it may seem too much to think that this can be done. For a century no question of public policy has been so widely and persistently debated as that of Protection vs. Free Trade. Yet it seems to-day as far as ever from settlement—so far, indeed, that many have come to deem it a question as to which no certain con- clusions can be reached, and many more to regard it as too complex and abstruse to be understood by those who have not equipped themselves by long study. This is, indeed, a hopeless view. We may safely leave many branches of knowledge to such as can de- vote themselves to special pursuits. We may safely accept what chemists tell us of chemistry, or astron- omers of astronomy, or philologists of the development of language, or anatomists of our internal structure, for not only are there in such investigations no pecuni- ary temptations to warp the judgment, but the ordinary duties of men and of citizens do not call for such special knowledge, and the great body of a people may entertain the crudest notions as to such things and yet lead happy and useful lives. Far different, however, is it with matters which relate to the production and dis- tribution of wealth, and which thus directly affect the comfort and livelihood of men. The intelligence which can alone safely guide in these matters must be the in- telligence of the masses, for as to such things it is the common opinion, and not the opinion of the learned few, that finds expression in legislation. If the knowledge required for the proper ordering of public affairs be like the knowledge required for the prediction of an eclipse, the making of a chemical an- alysis, or the decipherment of a cuneiform inscription, or even like the knowledge required in any branch of art or INTRODUCTORY. 3. 7 handicraft, then the shortness of human life and the necessities of human existence must forever condemn the masses of men to ignorance of matters which direct- ly affect their means of subsistence. If this be so, then popular government is hopeless, and, confronted on One side by the fact, to which all experience testifies, that a people can never safely trust to any portion of their number the making of regulations which affect their earnings, and on the other by the fact that the masses can never see for themselves the effect of such regula- tions, the only prospect before mankind is that the many must always be ruled and robbed by the few. But this is not so. Political economy is only the economy of human aggregates, and its laws are laws which we may individually recognize. What is re- quired for their elucidation is not long arrays of statis- tics nor the collocation of laboriously ascertained facts, but that sort of clear thinking which, keeping in mind the distinction between the part and the whole, seeks the relations of familiar things, and which is as possible for the unlearned as for the learned. Whether protection does or does not increase na- tional wealth, whether it does or does not benefit the laborer, are questions that from their mature must admit of decisive answers. That the controversy be. tween protection and free trade, widely and ener- getically as it has been carried on, has as yet led to no accepted conclusion cannot therefore be due to diffi- culties inherent in the subject. It may in part be ac- counted for by the fact that powerful pecuniary interests are concerned in the issue, for it is true, as Macaulay said, that if large pecuniary interests were concerned in denying the attraction of gravitation, that most obvious 8 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. of physical facts would have disputers. But that so many fair-minded men who have no special interests to serve are still at variance on this subject can only, it seems to me, be fully explained on the assumption that the discussion has not been carried far enough to bring out that full truth which harmonizes all partial truths. The present condition of the controversy, indeed, shows this to be the fact. In the literature of the sub- ject, I know of no work in which the inquiry has yet been carried to its proper end. As to the effect of protection upon the production of wealth, all has prob- ably been said that can be said; but that part of the question which relates to wages and which is primarily concerned with the distribution of wealth has not been adequately treated. Yet this is the very heart of the controversy, the ground from which, until it is thor. ... oughly explored, fallacies and confusions must con- stantly arise, to envelop in obscurity even that which has of itself been sufficiently explained. e The reason of this failure is not far to seek. Politi- cal economy is the simplest of the sciences. It is but the intellectual recognition, as related to social life, of ... laws which in their moral aspect men instinctively rec- ognize, and which are embodied in the simple teachings of him whom the common people heard gladly. But, like Christianity, political economy has been warped by institutions which, denying the equality and brother- hood of man, have enlisted authority, silenced objec- tion, and ingrained themselves in custom and habit of thought. Its professors and teachers have almost in- variably belonged to or been dominated by that class which tolerates no questioning of social adjustments that give to those who do not labor the fruits of INTRODUCTORY. 9 labor's toil. They have been like physicians employed to make a diagnosis on condition that they shall dis- cover no unpleasant truth. Given social conditions such as those that throughout the civilized world to- day shock the moral sense, and political economy; fear. lessly pursued, must lead to conclusions that will be as a lion in the way to those who have any tenderness for “vested interests.” But in the colleges and universities of Our time, as in the Sanhedrim of old, it is idle to ex- pect any enunciation of truths unwelcome to the powers that be. Adam Smith demonstrated clearly enough that pro- tective tariffs hamper the production of wealth. But Adam Smith—the university professor, the tutor and pensioner of the Duke of Buccleugh, the prospective holder of a government place—either did not deem it prudent to go further, or, as is more probable, was pre- vented from seeing the necessity of doing so by the at- mosphere of his time and place. He at any rate failed to carry his great inquiry into the causes which from “that original state of things in which the production of labor constitutes the natural recompense or wages of labor” had developed a state of things in which nat- ural wages seemed to be only such part of the produce of labor as would enable the laborer to exist. And, following Smith, came Malthus, to formulate a doctrine which throws upon the Creator the responsibility for the want and vice that flow from man's injustice—a doctrine which has barred from the inquiry which Smith did not pursue even such high and generous minds as that of John Stuart Mill. Some of the pub- lications of the Anti-Corn-Law League contain indi- cations that if the struggle over the English corn laws 1% 10 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. had been longer continued, the discussion might have been pushed further than the question of revenue tariff or protective tariff; but, ending as it did, the capitalists of the Manchester school were satisfied, and in such discussion as has since ensued English free traders, with few exceptions, have made no further advance, while American advocates of free trade have merely followed the English free traders. On the other hand, the advocates of protection have evinced a like indisposition to venture on burning ground. They extol the virtues of protection as fur- nishing employment, without asking how it comes that any one should need to be furnished with employment; they assert that protection maintains the rate of wages, without explaining what determines the rate of wages. The ablest of them, under the lead of Carey, have re- jected the Malthusian doctrine, but only to set up an equally untenable optimistic theory which serves the same purpose of barring inquiry into the wrongs of labor, and which has been borrowed by Continental free traders as a weapon with which to fight the agi- tation for social reform. That, so far as it has yet gone, the controversy be. tween protection and free trade has not been carried to its logical conclusions is evident from the positions which both sides occupy. Protectionists and free traders alike seem to lack the courage of their convic- tions. If protection have the virtues claimed for it, why should it be confined to the restriction of imports from foreign countries? If it really “provides employ. ment" and raises wages, then a condition of things in which hundreds of thousands vainly seek employment, and wages touch the point of bare subsistence, demands INTRODUCTORY. 11 a far more vigorous application of this beneficent prin- ciple than any protectionist has yet proposed. On the other hand, if the principle of free trade be true, the substitution of a revenue tariff for a protective tariff is a ridiculously inefficient application of it. Like the two knights of allegory, who, halting one on each side of the shield, continued to dispute about it when the advance of either must have revealed a truth that would have ended their controversy, pro- tectionists and free traders stand to-day. Let it be ours to carry the inquiry wherever it may lead. The fact is, that fully to understand the tariff question we must go beyond the tariff question as ordinarily debated. And here, it may be, we shall find ground on which honest divergences of opinion may be reconciled, and facts which seem conflicting may fall into harmonious relations. CELAPTER II. CLEARING GROUND. THE protective theory has certainly the weight of most general acceptance. Forty years ago all civilized countries based their policy upon it; and though Great Britain has since discarded it, she remains the only considerable nation that has done so, while not only have her own colonies, as soon as they have obtained the power, shown a disposition to revert to it, but such a disposition has of late years been growing in Great Britain herself. It should be remembered, however, that the pre- sumption in favor of any belief generally entertained has existed in favor of many beliefs now known to be entirely erroneous, and is especially weak in the case of a theory which, like that of protection, enlists the Sup- port of powerful special interests. The history of man- kind everywhere shows the power that special inter- ests, capable of Organization and action, may exert in securing the acceptance of the most monstrous doc- trines. We have, indeed, only to look around us to see how easily a small special interest may exert greater influence in forming opinion and making laws than a large general interest. As what is everybody's busi- ness is nobody's business, so what is everybody's in- terest is nobody's interest. Two or three citizens of a seaside town see that the building of a custom-house or CLEARING GROUND. 13 the dredging of a creek will put money in their pock- ets; a few silver miners conclude that it will be a good thing for them to have the government stow away some millions of silver every month; a navy contractor wants the profit of repairing useless iron-clads or building needless cruisers, and again and again such petty inter- ests have their way against the larger interests of the whole people. What can be clearer than that a note directly issued by the government is at least as good as a note based on a government bond? Yet special interests have sufficed with us to institute and maintain a hybrid currency for which no other valid reason can be assigned than private profit. - Those who are specially interested in protective tariffs find it easy to believe that protection is of gen- eral benefit. The directness of their interest makes them active in spreading their views, and having con- trol of large means—for the protected industries are those in which large capitals are engaged—and being ready on occasion, as a matter of business, to spend money in propagating their doctrines, they exert great influence upon the organs of public opinion. Free trade, on the contrary, offers no special advantage to any particular interest, and in the present state of social morality benefits or injuries which men share in common with their fellows are not felt so intensely as those which affect them specially. I do not mean to say that the pecuniary interests which protection enlists suffice to explain the wide- spread acceptance of its theories and the tenacity with which they are held. But it is plain that these in- terests do constitute a power of the kind most potent in forming opinion and influencing legislation, and 14 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. that this fact weakens the presumption the wide accept. ance of protection might otherwise afford, and is a rea- son why those who believe in protection merely because they have constantly heard it praised should examine the question for themselves. Protection, moreover, has always found an effective ally in those national prejudices and hatreds which are in part the cause and in part the result of the wars that have made the annals of mankind a record of blood- shed and devastation—prejudices and hatreds which have everywhere been the means by which the masses have been induced to use their own power for their own enslavement. For the first half century of our national existence American protectionists pointed to the protective tariff of Great Britain as an example to be followed; but since that country, in 1846, discarded protection, its American advocates have endeavored to utilize national prejudice by constantly speaking of protection as an American system and of free trade as a British inven- tion. Just now they are endeavoring to utilize in the same way the enmity against everything British which long oppressions and insults have engendered in the Irish heart, and, in the words of a recent political plat- form, Irish-Americans are called upon “to resist the introduction into America of the English theory of free trade, which has been so successfully used as a means to destroy the industries and oppress the people of Ireland.” Even if free trade had originated in Great Britain we should be as foolish in rejecting it on that account as we should be in refusing to speak our mother tongue because it is of British origin, or in going back to hand CIEARING GROUND. 15 and water power because steam engines were first intro- duced in Great Britain. But, in truth, free trade no more originated in Great Britain than did the habit of walking on the feet. Free trade is the natural trade— the trade that goes on in the absence of artificial re- strictions. It is protection that had to be invented. But instead of being invented in the United States, it was in full force in Great Britain long before the Uni- ted States were thought of. It would be nearer the truth to say that protection originated in Great Britain, for, if the system did not originate there, it was fully developed there, and it is from that country that it has been derived by us. Nor yet did the reaction against it originate in Great Britain, but in France, among a school of eminent men headed by Quesnay, who were Adam Smith's predecessors and in many things his teachers. These French economists were what neither Smith nor any subsequent British economist or states- man has been—true free traders. They wished to sweep away not merely protective duties, but all taxes, direct and indirect, save a single tax upon land values. This logical conclusion of free-trade principles the so- called British free traders have shirked, and it meets to- day as bitter opposition from the Cobden Club as from American protectionists. The only sense in which we can properly speak of “British free trade” is the same sense in which we speak of a certain imitation metal as . “German silver.” “British free trade” is spurious free trade. Great Britain does not really enjoy free trade. To say nothing of internal taxes, inconsistent with true free trade, she still maintains a cordon of custom-house officers, coast guards and baggage searchers, and still collects over a hundred million dollars of her revenue 16 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. from import duties. To be sure, her tariff is “for rev. enue only,” but a tariff for revenue only is not free trade. The ruling classes of Great Britain have adopt- ed only so much free trade as suits their class inter- ests, and the battle for free trade in that country has yet to be fought. On the other hand, it is absurd to talk of protection as an American system. It had been fully developed in Europe before the American colonies were planted, and during our colonial period England maintained a more thorough system of protection than now anywhere exists—a system which aimed at building up English industries not merely by protective duties, but by the repression of like industries in Ireland and the colonies, and wherever else throughout the world English power could be exerted. What we got of protection was the wrong side of it, in regulations intended to prevent American industries from competing with those of the mother country and to give to her a monopoly of the American trade. - The irritation produced in the growing colonies by these restrictions was the main cause of the revolution which made of them an independent nation. Protec- tionist ideas were doubtless at that time latent among our people, for they permeated the mental atmosphere of the civilized world, but so little disposition was there to embody those ideas in a national policy, that the American representatives in negotiating the treaty of peace endeavored to secure complete freedom of trade between the United States and Great Britain. This was refused by England, then and for a long time afterward completely dominated by protective ideas. But during the period following the revolution CLEARING GROUND. 17 in which the American Union existed during the Articles of Confederation, no tariff hampered impor- tations into the American States. The adoption of the Constitution made a Federal tariff possible, and to give the Federal Government an independent revenue a tariff was soon imposed; but although protection had then begun to find advocates in the United States, this first American tariff was almost nominal as compared with what the British tariff was then or our tariff is now. And in the Federal Constitution state tariffs were prohibited— a step which has resulted in giving to the principle of free trade the greatest extension it has had in modern times. Nothing could more clearly show how far the American people then were from accepting the theories of protection since popularized among them, for the national idea had not then acquired the force it has since gained, and if protection had then been looked upon as necessary the different States would not without a struggle have given up the power of imposing tariffs of their own. Nor could protection have reached its present height in the United States but for the civil war. While at- tention was concentrated on the struggle and mothers were sending their sons to the battle-field, the interests that sought protection took advantage of the patriotism that was ready for any sacrifice to secure protective taxes such as had never before been dreamed of—taxes which they have ever since managed to keep in force, and even in many cases to increase. * The truth is that protection is no more American than is the distinction made in our regular army and navy between commissioned officers and enlisted men—a dis- 18 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. tinction not of degree but of kind, so that there is be: tween the highest non-commissioned officer and the lowest commissioned officer a deep gulf fixed, a gulf which can only be likened to that which exists between white and black where the color line is drawn sharpest. This distinction is historically a survival of that made in the armies of aristocratic Europe, when they were officered by nobles and recruited from peasants, and has been copied by us in the same spirit of imitation that has led us to copy other undemocratic customs and in- stitutions. Though we preserve this aristocratic dis- tinction after it has been abandoned in some European countries, it is in no sense American. It neither origin- ated with us nor does it consort with our distinctive ideas and institutions. So it is with protection. Whatever be its economic merits there can be no doubt that it conflicts with those ideas of natural right and personal freedom which received national expression in the es- tablishment of the American Republic, and which we have been accustomed to regard as distinctively Ameri- can. What more incongruous than the administering of custom-house oaths and the searching of trunks and hand-bags under the shadow of “Liberty Enlightening the World?” As for the assertion that “the English theory of free trade” has been used “to destroy the industries and oppress the people of Ireland,” the truth is that it was “the English theory of protection ” that was so used. The restrictions which British protection imposed upon the American colonies were trivial as compared with those imposed upon Ireland. The successful resistance of the colonies roused in Ireland the same spirit, and led to the great movement of “Irish Volunteers,” who, with CLEARING GROUND. 19 cannon bearing the inscription “Free Trade or —!” forced the repeal of those restrictions and won for a time Irish legislative independence. Whether Irish industries that were unquestionably hampered and throttled by British protection could now be benefited by Irish protection, like the question whether protection benefits the United States, is only to be settled by a determination of the effects of pro- tection upon the country that imposes it. But without going into that, it is evident that the free trade be- tween Great Britain and Ireland which has existed since the union in 1801, has not been the cause of the backwardness of Irish industry. There is one part of Ireland which has enjoyed comparative prosperity and in which important industries have grown up— Some of them, such as the building of iron ships, for which natural advantages cannot be claimed. How can this be explained on the theory that Irish industries cannot be re-established without protection? If the very men who are now trying to persuade Irish-American voters that Ireland has been impover- ished by “British free trade” were privately asked the cause of the greater prosperity of Ulster over other parts of Ireland, they would probably give the answer made familiar by religious bigotry—that Ulster is en- terprising and prosperous because it is Protestant, while the rest of Ireland is sluggish and poor because it is Catholic. But the true reason is plain. It is, that the land tenure in Ulster has been such that a larger por- tion of the wealth produced has been left there than in other parts of Ireland, and that the mass of the peo- ple have not been so remorsely hunted and oppressed. In Presbyterian Skye the same general poverty, the 20 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. same primitive conditions of industry exist as in Catho. lic Connemara, and its cause is to be seen in the same rapacious system of landlordism which has carried off the fruits of industry and prevented the accumulation of capital. To attribute the backwardness of industry among a people who are steadily stripped of all they can produce above a bare living, to the want of a pro- tective tariff or to religious opinions is like attributing the sinking of a scuttled ship to the loss of her figure- head or the color of her paint. What, however, in the United States at least, has tended more than any appeals to national feeling to dis- pose the masses in favor of protection, has been the difference of attitude toward the working classes as- sumed by the contending policies. In its beginnings in this country protection was strongest in those sec- tions where labor had the largest opportunities and was held in the highest esteem, while the strength of free trade has been the greatest in the section in which up to the civil war slavery prevailed. The political party which successfully challenged the aggressions of the slave power also declared for a protective tariff, while the men who tried to rend the Union in order to es- tablish a nation based upon the right of capital to own labor, prohibited protection in the constitution they formed. The explanation of these facts is, that in one section of the country there were many industries that could be protected, while in the other section there were few. While American cotton culture was in its earlier stages, Southern cotton planters were willing enough to avail themselves of a heavy duty on India Cottons, and Louisiana sugar growers have always been persist- ent sticklers for protection. But when cotton raised CLEARING GROUND. 21 for export became the great staple of the South, pro- tection, in the absence of manufactures, was not only clearly opposed to dominant Southern interests, but assumed the character of a sectional imposition by which the South was taxed for the benefit of the North. This sectional division on the tariff question had no reference whatever to the conditions of labor, but in many minds its effect has been to associate protection with respect for labor and free trade with its enslave- ment. - Irrespective of this there has been mugh in the pre- sentation of the two theories to dispose the working classes toward protection and against free trade. Workingmen generally feel that they do not get a fair reward for their labor. They know that what prevents them from successfully demanding higher wages is the competition of others anxious for work, and they are naturally disposed to favor the doctrine or party that proposes to shield them from competition. This, its advocates urge, is the aim of protection. And what- ever protection accomplishes, protectionists at least pro- fess regard for the working classes, and proclaim their desire to use the powers of government to raise and maintain wages. Protection, they declare, means the protection of labor. So constantly is this reiterated that many suppose that this is the real derivation of the term, and that “protection ” is short for “protection of labor.” On the other hand, the opponents of protection have, for the most part, not only professed no special interest in the well-being of the working classes and no desire to raise wages, but have denied the justice of attempt- ing to use the powers of government for this purpose. 22 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. The doctrines of free trade have been intertwined with teachings that throw upon the laws of nature respon- sibility for the poverty of the laboring class, and foster a callous indifference to their sufferings. On the same grounds on which they have condemned leg. islative interference with commerce, free-trade econ- omists have condemned interference with hours of labor, with the rate of wages, and even with the employ- ment of women and children, and have united protec- tionism and trades unionism in the same denuncia- tion, proclaiming supply and demand to be the only true and rightful regulator of the price of labor as of the price of pig iron. While protesting against re- strictions upon the production of wealth they have ignored the monstrous injustice of its distribution, and have treated as fair and normal that competition in which human beings, deprived of their natural oppor- tunities of employing themselves, are compelled by bit- ng want, to bid against one another. All this is true. But it is also true that the needs of labor require more than kind words, and are not to be satisfied by such soft phrases as we address to a horse when we want to catch him that we may put a bit in his mouth and a saddle on his back. Let me ask those who are disposed to regard protection as favorable to the aspirations of labor, to consider whether it can be true that what labor needs is to be protected? To admit that labor needs protection is to acknowl- edge its inferiority; it is to acquiesce in an assumption that degrades the workman to the position of a depend- ent, and leads logically to the claim that the employé is bound to vote in the interest of the employer who provides him with work. There is something in the CLEARING GROUND. 23 very word “protection " that ought to make work- ingmen cautious of accepting anything presented to them under it. The protection of the masses has in all times been the pretense of tyranny—the plea of monarchy, of aristocracy, of special privilege of every kind. The slave owners justified slavery as protect- ing the slaves. British misrule in Ireland is upheld on the ground that it is for the protection of the Irish. But, whether under a monarchy or under a re- public, is there an instance in the history of the world in which the “protection ” of the laboring masses has not meant their oppression ? The protection that those who have got the law-making power into their hands have given to labor, has at best always been the pro- tection that man gives to cattle—he protects them that he may use and eat them. There runs through protectionist professions of con- cern for labor a tone of condescending patronage more insulting to men who feel the true dignity of labor than frankly expressed contempt could be—an assumption that pauperism is the natural condition of labor, to which it must everywhere fall unless benevolently pro- tected. It is never intimated that the land-owner or the capitalist needs protection. They, it is always as- sumed, can take care of themselves. It is only the poor workingman who must be protected. What is labor that it should so need protection? Is not labor the creator of capital, the producer of all wealth 7 Is it not the men who labor that feed and clothe all others ? Is it not true, as has been said, that the three great orders of society are “workingmen, beggarmen and thieves?” How, then, does it come that workingmen alone need protection ? When the 24 FROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. first man came upon the earth who was there to pro- tect him or to provide him with employment? Yet whenever or however he came, he must have managed to get a living and raise a family When we consider that labor is the producer of all wealth, is it not evident that the impoverishment and dependence of labor are abnormal conditions re- Sulting from restrictions and usurpations, and that instead of accepting protection, what labor should de- mand is freedom 7 That those who advocate any ex- tension of freedom choose to go no further than suits their own special purpose is no reason why freedom it- self should be distrusted. For years it was held that the assertion of our Declaration of Independence that all men are created equal and endowed by their Creator with unalienable rights, applied only to white men. But this in nowise vitiated the principle. Nor does it vitiate the principle that it is still held to apply only to political rights. And so, that freedom of trade has been advocated by those who have no sympathy with labor should not prejudice us against it. Can the road to the industrial emancipation of the masses be any other than that of freedom 7 CEIAPTER III. OF METHOD. ON the deck of a ship men are pulling on a rope and on her mast a yard is rising. A man aloft is clinging to the tackle that raises the yard. Is his weight assist- ing its rise or retarding it? That, of course, depends on what part of the tackle his weight is thrown upon, and can only be told by noticing whether its tendency is with or against the efforts of those who pull on deck. If in things so simple we may easily err in assuming cause from effect, how much more liable to error are such assumptions in regard to the complicated phenom- ena of social life. Much that is urged in current discussions of the tariff question is of no validity whatever, and however it may serve the purpose of controversy, cannot aid in the discovery of truth. That a thing exists with or follows another thing is no proof that it is because of that other thing. This assumption is the fallacy post hoc, ergo propter hoc, which leads, if admitted, to the most preposterous conclusions. Wages in the United States are higher than in England, and we differ from England in having a protective tariff. But the assumption that the one fact is because of the other, is no more valid than would be the assumption that these higher wages are due to our decimal coinage or to our republican form of government. That Eng- 2 26 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. land has grown in wealth since the abolition of pro. tection proves no more for free trade than the growth of the United States under a protective tariff does for protection. It does not follow that an institu- tion is good because a country has prospered under it, nor bad because a country in which it exists is not prosperous. It does not even follow that institutions to be found in all prosperous countries and not to be found in backward countries are therefore beneficial. For this, at various times, might have been confidently asserted of slavery, of polygamy, of aristocracy, of es- tablished churches, and it may still be asserted of pub- lic debts, of private property in land, of pauperism, or of the existence of distinctively vicious or criminal classes. Nor even when it can be shown that certain changes in the prosperity of a country, of an industry, or of a class, have followed certain other changes in laws or institutions can it be inferred that the two are related to each other as effect and cause, unless it can also be shown that the assigned cause tends to produce the assigned effect, or unless, what is clearly impossible in most cases, it can be shown that there is no other cause to which the effect can be attributed. The almost endless multiplicity of causes constantly operating in human societies, and the almost endless interference of effect with effect, make that popular mode of reasoning which logicians call the method of simple enumeration worse than useless in social investigations. As for reliance upon statistics, that involves the ad- ditional difficulty of knowing whether we have the right statistics. Though “figures cannot lie,” there is in their collection and grouping such liability to over- sight and such temptation to bias that they are to be OF METHOD, - 27 distrusted in matters of controversy until they have been subjected to rigid examination. The value of most arguments turning upon statistics is well illus- trated in the story of the government clerk who, being told to get up the statistics of a certain question, wished first to know which side it was desired that they should support. Under their imposing appearance of exact- ness may lurk the gravest errors and Wildest assump- tions. To ascertain the effect of protective tariffs, we must inquire what they are and how they operate. When we thus discover their nature and tendencies, we shall be able to weigh what is said for or against them, and have a clew by which we may trace their results amid the complications of social phenomena. For the largest communities are but expansions of the smallest com- munities, and the rules of arithmetic by which we cal- culate gain or loss on transactions of dollars apply as well to transactions of hundreds of millions. Thus the facts we must use and the principles we must apply are common facts that are known to all and principles that are recognized in every-day life. Starting from premises as to which there can be no dispute, we have only to be careful as to our steps in order to reach conclusions of which we may feel sure. We cannot experiment with communities as the chem- ist can with material substances, or as the physiologist can with animals. Nor can we find nations so alike in all other respects that we can safely attribute any difference in their conditions to the presence or ab- sence of a single cause without first assuring our- selves of the tendency of that cause. But the imag- ination puts at our counmand a method of investi- 28 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. " gating economic problems which is within certain limits hardly less useful than actual experiment. We may test the working of known principles by. mentally separating, combining or eliminating con- ditions. Let me explain what I mean by an illus- tration I have once before used.* When I was a boy I went down to the wharf with another boy to see the first iron steamship that had ever crossed the ocean to Philadelphia. Now, hearing of an iron steamship seemed to us then a good deal like hearing of a leaden kite or a wooden cooking-stove. But we had not been long aboard of her, before my comrade said in a tone of contemptuous disgust: “Pooh! I see how it is. She's all lined with wood ; that's the reason she floats.” I could not controvert him for the moment, but I was not satisfied, and sitting down on the wharf when he left me, I set to work trying mental experiments. If it was the wood inside of her that made her float, then the more wood the higher she would float; and, mentally, I loaded her up with wood. But, as I was familiar with the process of making boats out of blocks of wood, I at once saw that, instead of floating higher, she would sink deeper. Then, I mentally took all the wood out of her, as we dug out our wooden boats, and saw that thus lightened she would float higher still. Then, in imagination, I jammed a hole in her, and saw that the water would run in and she would sink, as did our wooden boats when ballasted with leaden keels. And, thus I saw, as clearly as though I could have actually made these experiments with the steamer, that it was not the * Lecture before the students of the University of California, on the “Study of Political Economy,” April, 1877. OF METHOD, 29- wooden lining that made her float, but her hollowness, or, as I would now phrase it, her displacement of water. In such ways as this, with which we are all familiar, we can isolate, analyze or combine economic principles, and, by extending or diminishing the scale of propo- sitions, either subject them to inspection through a men- tal magnifying glass or bring a larger field into view. And this each one can do for himself. In the inquiry upon which we are about to enter, all I ask of the reader is that he shall in nothing trust to me. CHAPTER IV. PROTECTION AS A UNIVERSAL NEED. To understand a thing it is often well to begin by Jooking at it, as it were, from the outside and observing its relations, before examining it in detail. Let us do this with the protective theory. Protection, as the term has come to signify a certain national policy, means the levying of duties upon im- ported commodities for the purpose of protecting from competition the home producers of such commodities. Protectionists contend that to secure the highest pros- perity of each nation it should produce for itself every- thing it is capable of producing, and that to this end its home industries should be protected against the com- petition of foreign industries. They also contend (in the United States at least) that to enable workmen to obtain as high wages as possible they should be pro- tected by tariff duties against the competition of goods produced in countries where wages are lower. With- out disputing the correctness of this theory, let us con- sider its larger relations. The protective theory, it is to be observed, asserts a general law, as true in one country as in another. However protectionists in the United States may talk of “American protection” and “British free trade,” protection is, and of necessity, must be, advocated as of universal application. American protectionists use the PROTECTION AS A UNIVERSAL NEET). 31 arguments of foreign protectionists, and even where they complain that the protective policy of other coun- tries is injurious to us, commend it as an example which we should follow. They contend that (at least up to a certain point in national development) protec- tion is everywhere beneficial to a nation, and free trade everywhere injurious; that the prosperous nations have built up their prosperity by protection, and that all nations that would be prosperous must adopt that policy. And their arguments must be universal to have any plausibility, for it would be absurd to assert that a theory of national growth and prosperity applies, to some countries and not to others. Let me ask the reader who has hitherto accepted the protective theory to consider what its necessarily uni- versal character involves. It was the realization of this that first led me to question that theory. I was for a number of years after I had come of age a protec- tionist, or rather, I supposed I was, for, without real examination, I had accepted the belief, as in the first place we all accept our beliefs, on the authority of others. So far, however, as I thought at all on the subject, I was logical, and I well remember how when the Florida and Alabama were sinking American ships at sea, I thought their depredations, after all, a good thing for the state in which I lived—California—since the increased risk and cost of ocean carriage in Ameri- can ships (then the only way of bringing goods from the Eastern States to California) would give to her in- fant industries something of that needed protection against the lower wages and better established indus- tries of the Eastern States which the Federal Constitu- tion prevented her from securing by a State tariff. The 32 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. full bearing of such notions never occurred to me till I happened to hear the protective theory elaborately ex- pounded by an able man. As he urged that American industries must be protected from the competition of foreign countries, that we ought to work up our own raw materials and allow nothing to be imported that we could produce for ourselves, I began to realize that these propositions, if true, must be universally true, and that not only should every nation shut itself out from every other nation; not enly should the various sections of every large country institute tariffs of their own to shelter their industries from the competition of other sections, but that the reason given why no people should obtain from abroad anything they might make at home, must apply as well to the family. It was this that led me to weigh arguments I had before accepted without real examination. It seems to me impossible to consider the necessarily universal character of the protective theory without feeling it to be repugnant to moral perceptions and in- consistent with the simplicity and harmony which we everywhere discover in natural law. What should we think of human laws framed for the government of a country which should compel each family to keep con- stantly on their guard, against every other family, to expend a large part of their time and labor in prevent- ing exchanges with their neighbors, and to seek their own prosperity by opposing the natural efforts of other families to become prosperous 7 Yet the protective theory implies that laws such as these have been im- posed by the Creator upon the families of men who tenant this earth. It implies that by virtue of social laws, as immutable as the physical laws, each nation PROTECTION As A UNIVERSAL NEED. 33 must stand jealously on guard against every other ha- tion and erect artificial obstacles to national inter- course. It implies that a federation of mankind, such as that which prevents the establishment of tariffs be- tween the states of the American Union, would be a disaster to the race, and that in an ideal world each nation would be protected from every other nation by a cordon of tax collectors, with their attendant spies and informers. * Such a theory might consort with that form of poly- theism which assigned to each nation a separate and hostile God; but it is hard to reconcile it with the idea of the unity of the Creative Mind and the universality of law. Imagine a Christian missionary expounding to a newly discovered people the sublime truths of the gospel of peace and love—the fatherhood of God; the brotherhood of man; the duty of regarding the interests of our neighbors equally with our own, and of doing to others as we would have them do to us. Could he, in the same breath, go on to declare that, by virtue of the laws of this same God, each nation, to prosper, must defend itself against all other nations by a pro- tective tariff Ż Religion and experience alike teach us that the highest good of each is to be sought in the good of others; that the true interests of men are harmonious, not antagonistic; that prosperity is the daughter of good will and peace; and that want and destruction follow enmity and strife. The protective theory, on the other hand, implies the opposition of national interests; that the gain of one people is the loss of others; that each must seek its own good by constant efforts to get ad- vantage over others and to prevent others frcm getting 2* 34 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. ſ' advantage over it. It makes of nations rivals instead of co-operators; it inculcates a warfare of restrictions and prohibitions and searchings and seizures, which differs in weapons, but not in spirit, from that warfare which sinks ships and burns cities. Can we imagine the nations beating their swords into plowshares and their spears into pruning-hooks and yet maintaining hostile tariffs 7 No matter whether he call himself Christian or Deist, or Agnostic or Atheist, who can look about him with- out seeing that want and suffering flow inevitably from selfishness, and that in any community the golden rule which teaches us to regard the interests of others as carefully as our own would bring not only peace but plenty 2 Can it be that what is true of individuals ceases to be true of nations—that in One sphere the law of prosperity is the law of love; in the other that of strife? On the contrary, universal history testifies that poverty, degradation, and enslavement are the in- evitable results of that spirit which leads nations to regard each other as rivals and enemies. Every political truth must be a moral truth. Yet who can accept the protective theory as a moral truth 7 A few months ago I found myself one night, with four other passengers, in the smoking car of a Pennsyl- vania limited express train traveling west. The con- versation, beginning with fast trains, turned to fast steamers, and then to custom-house experiences. One told how, coming from Europe with a trunk filled with presents for his wife, he had significantly said to the custom-house inspector detailed to examine his trunks that he was in a hurry. “How much of a hurry?” said the officer. “Ten dollars' worth of a hurry,” was PROTECTION As A UNIVERSAL NEED. 35 the reply. The officer took a quick look through the trunk and remarked, “That's not much of a hurry for all this.” “I gave him ten more,” said the story-teller, “and he chalked the trunk.” Then another told how under similar circumstances he had placed a magnificent meerschaum pipºso that it would be the first thing seen on lifting the trunk lid, and, when the officer admired it, had replied that it was his. The third said he simply put a greenback con- spicuously in the first article of luggage; and the fourth told how his plan was to crumple up a note, and put it with his keys in the officer's hands. Here were four reputable business men, as I after- ward found them to be—one an iron worker, one a coal producer, and the other two manufacturers—men of at least average morality and patriotism, who not only thought it no harm to evade the tariff, but who made no scruple of the false oath necessary, and regarded the bribery of customs officers as a good joke. I had the curiosity to edge the conversation from this to the sub- ject of free trade, when I found that all four were staunch protectionists, and by edging it a little further I found that all four were thorough believers in the right of an employer to discharge any workman who voted for a free-trade candidate, holding, as they put it, that no one ought to eat the bread of an employer whose interests he opposed. I recall this conversation because it is typical. Who- ever has traveléd on trans-Atlantic steamers has listened to such conversations, and is aware that the great ma- jority of the American protectionists who visit Europe return with purchases which they smuggle through, even at the expense of a “custom-house oath’ and a 36 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. greenback to the examining officer. Many of our larg. est under-valuation smugglers have been men of the highest social and religious standing, who gave freely of their spoils to churches and benevolent societies. Not long ago a highly respected banker, an extremely religious gman, who had probably neglected the pre: cautions of my Smoking-car friends, was detected in the endeavor to smuggle through in his luggage (which he had of course taken a “custom-house oath. " did not contain anything dutiable) a lot of very valuable pres- ents to a church Conscientious men will (until they get used to them) shrink from false oaths, from bribery, or from other means necessary to evade a tariff, but even of be- lievers in protection are there any who really think such evasions wrong in themselves 7 What theoreti- cal protectionist is there, who, if no one was watch- ing him, would scruple to carry a box of cigars or a dress pattern, or anything else that could be carried, across a steamer wharf or across Niagara bridge? And why should he scruple to carry such things across a wharf, a river, or an imaginary line, since once inside the custom house frontier no one would object to his carrying them thousands of miles? That unscrupulous men, for their own private ad- vantage, break laws intended for the general good proves nothing; but that no one really feels smug- gling to be wrong proves a good deal. Whether we hold the basis of moral ideas to be intuitive or utili- tarian, is not the fact that protection thus lacks the support of the moral sentiment inconsistent with the idea that tariffs are necessary to the well-being and progress of mankind Ž If, as is held by some, moral PROTECTION As A UNIVERSAL NEED. 37 perceptions are implanted in our nature as a means whereby our conduct may be instinctively guided in such way as to conduce to the general well being, how is it, if the Creator has ordained that man should prosper by protective tariffs, that the moral sense takes no cognizance of such a law” If, as others hold, what we call moral perceptions be the result of general experience of what conduces to the common good, how is it that the beneficial effects of protection have not developed moral recognition? To make that a crime by statute which is no crime in morals, is inevitably to destroy respect for law; to resort to oaths to prevent men from doing what they feel injures no one, is to weaken the sanctity of oaths. Corruption, evasion and false swearing are inseparable from tariffs. Can that be good of which these are the fruits? A system which requires such spying and searching, such invoking of the Almighty to witness the contents of every box, bundle and package—a sys- tem which always has provoked, and in the nature of man always must provoke, corruption and fraud—can it be necessary to the prosperity and progress of mankind? Consider, moreover, how sharply this theory of pro- tection conflicts with common experience and habits of thought. Who would think of recommending a site for a proposed city or a new colony because it was very difficult to get at? Yet, if the protective theory be true, this would really be an advantage. Who would regard piracy as promotive of civilization 7 Yet a discriminating pirate, who would confine his seizures to goods which might be produced in the country to which they were being carried, would be as beneficial to that country as a tariff. 38 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. Whether protectionists or free traders, we all hear with interest and pleasure of improvements in trans. portation by water or land; we are all disposed to re- gard the opening of canals, the building of rail- ways, the deepening of harbors, the improvement of steamships, as beneficial. But if such things are beneficial, how can tariffs be beneficial 7 The effect of such things is to lessen the cost of transporting commodities; the effect of tariffs is to increase it. If the protective theory be true, every improvement that cheapens the carriage of goods between country and country is an injury to mankind unless tariffs be com- mensurately increased. The directness, the swiftness and the ease with which birds cleave the air, naturally excite man's desire. His fancy has always given angels wings, and he has ever dreamed of a time when the power of traversing those unobstructed fields might also be his. That this tri- umph is within the power of human ingenuity who in this age of marvels can doubt? And who would not hail with delight the news that invention had at last brought to realization the dream of ages, and made navigation of the atmosphere as practicable as naviga- tion of the ocean? Yet if the protective theory be true this mastery of another element would be a mis- fortune to man. For it would make protection impos- sible. Every inland town and village, every rood of ground on the whole earth's surface, would at once become a port of an all-embracing ocean, and the only way in which any people could continue to enjoy the blessings of protection would be to roof their coun- try in. It is not only improvements in transportation that PROTECTION AS A UNIVERSAL NEED. 39 are antagonistic to protection ; but all labor-saving invention and discovery. The utilization of natural gas bids fair to lessen the demand for native coal far more than could the free importation of foreign coal. Borings in Central New York have recently revealed vast beds of pure salt, the working of which will de- stroy the industry of salt making, to encourage which we impose a duty on foreign salt. We maintain a tariff for the avowed purpose of keeping out the pro- ducts of cheap foreign labor; yet machines are daily invented that produce goods cheaper than the cheapest foreign labor. . Clearly the only consistent protection- ism is that of China, which would not only prohibit foreign commerce, but forbid the introduction of labor- saving machinery. The aim of protection, in short, is to prevent the bringing into a country of things in themselves useful and valuable, in order to compel the making of such things. But what all mankind in the individual affairs. of every-day life, regard as to be desired is not the making of things, but the possession of things. CEIAPTER W. THE PROTECTIVE UNIT. THE more one considers the theory that every nation ought to “protect” itself against every other nation, the more inconsistent does it seem. Is there not, in the first place, an obvious absurdity in taking the nation or country as the protective unit and saying that each should have a protective tariff’” What is meant by nation or country in the protec- tionist theory is an independent political division. Thus Great Britain and Ireland are considered one nation, France another, Germany another, Switzerland another, the United States, Canada, Mexico, and each * That protectionist writers are themselves conscious of this ab- surdity is to be seen in their constant effort to suggest the idea, too preposterous to be broadly stated, that nations instead of being purely arbitrary political divisions of mankind, are natural, or divinely appointed, divisions. Thus, not to multiply instances, Professor Robert Ellis Thompson (Political Economy, p. 34) defines a nation as “a people speaking one language, living under one gov- ernment, and occupying a continuous area. This area is a district whose natural boundaries designate it as intended for the site of an independent people.” This definition is given in large type, while underneath is appended in small type : “No one point of this defi- nition is essential save the second.” Yet in spite of this admission that the “nation ” is a purely arbitrary political division, Professor Thompson endeavors throughout his book to suggest a different impression to the mind of the reader, by talking of “the existence of nations as parts of the world's providential order,” the “ proºf. dential boundaries of nations,” etc. THE PROTECTIVE UNIT. 41 - N. of the Central and South American republics are others. But these divisions are arbitrary. They do not co- incide with any differences in soil, climate, race or in- dustry—they have no maximum or minimum of area or population. They are, moreover, continually chang- ing. The maps of Europe and America used by school children to-day are very different from the maps their fathers used. The difference a hundred years ago was greater yet; and as we go further back still greater differences appear. According to this theory, when the three British kingdoms had separate governments it was necessary for the well-being of all that they should be protected from each other, and should Ire- land achieve independence that necessity would re- cur; but while the three countries are united under One government, it does not exist. The petty states of which a few years ago Germany and Italy consisted ought upon this theory to have had, as they once had, tariffs between them. Yet, now, upon the same theory, they no longer need these tariffs. Alsace and Lorraine when provinces of France needed to be protected against Germany. Now that they are German prov- ..inces they need protection against France. Texas, when part of Mexico, required a protective tariff against the |United States. Now, being a part of the United States, it requires a protective tariff against Mexico. We of the United States require a protective tariff against Canada, and the Canadians a tariff against us, but if Canada were to come into the Union the necessity for both of these tariffs would disappear. Do not these incongruities show that the protective theory is destitute of scientific basis; that instead of originating in any deduction from principles or induc- 42 PROTECTION oR FREE TRADE. tion from facts, it has been invented merely to serve the purposes of its inventors 7 Political changes in nowise alter soil, climate, or industrial needs. If the three British kingdoms do not now need tariffs against one another, they could not have needed them before the union. If it is not injurious to the various states of Italy or Germany to trade freely with each other now, it could not have been injurious before they were united. If Alsace and Lorraine are benefited by free trade with Germany now, they would have been bene- fited by it when French provinces. If the people of the opposite shores of the Great Lakes and St. Lawrence River would not be injured by the free exchange of their products should Canada enter the American Union, they could not be injured by freedom to ex- change their products now. Consider how inconsistent with the protective theory is the free trade that prevails between the states of the American Union. Our Union includes an area almost as large as Europe, yet the protectionists who hold that each European country ought to protect itself against all the rest make no objections to the free trade that ex- ists between the American states, though some of these states are larger than European kingdoms, and the dif' ferences between them, as to natural resources and in- dustrial development, are at least as great. If it is for the benefit of Germany and France that they should be separated by protective tariffs, does not New Jersey need the protection of a tariff from New York and Pennsylvania? and do not New York and Pennsyl- vania also need to be protected from New Jersey? And if New England needs protection against the Province of Quebec, and Ohio, Illinois and Michigan THE PROTECTIVE UNIT. 43 against the Province of Ontario, is it not clear that these states also need protection from the states which adjoin them on the south? What difference does it make that one set of states belong to the American Union and the other to the Canadian Confederation 7 Industry and commerce, when left to themselves, pay no more attention to political lines than do birds or fishes. Clearly, if there is any truth in the protective theory it must apply not only to the grand political divisions but to all their parts. If a country ought not to import from other countries anything which its own people can produce, the same principle must apply to every subdivision; and each state, each county and each town- ship, must need its own protective tariff. And further than this, the proper application of the protective theory requires the separation of mankind into the smallest possible political divisions, each defend- ed against the rest by its own tariff. For the larger the area of the protective unit, the more difficult does it become to apply the protective theory. With every extension of such countries as the United States the possibility of protection, if it can be applied only to the major political divisions, becomes less, and were the poet's dream realized, and mankind united in a “Fed- eration of the World,” the possibility of protection would vanish. On the other hand, the smaller the pro- tective unit the better can the theory of protection be applied. Protectionists do not go so far as to aver that all trade is injurious. They hold that each country may safely import what it cannot produce, but should restrict the importation of what it can produce. Thus dis. crimination is required, which becomes more possible the smaller the protective unit. 44 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. Upon protective principles the same tariff will no bet. ter suit all the states of Our Union than the same sized shoes will fit all our sixty million people. Massachu- setts, for instance, does not produce coal, iron or sugar. These, then, on protective principles, ought to come into Massachusetts free, while Pennsylvania enjoyed protection on iron and coal, and Louisiana on sugar. Oranges may be grown in Florida, but not in Minne- sota; therefore, while Florida needs a protective duty on Oranges, Minnesota does not. And so on through the whole list of states. To “protect” them all with the same tariff is to ignore as to each that part of the protective theory which permits the free importation of commodities that cannot be produced at home; and, by compelling them to pay higher prices for what they cannot produce, to neutralize the benefits arising from the protection of such commodities as they do produce. Furthermore, while Massachusetts, on the protective theory, does not need protection on coal, iron and sugar, which she cannot produce, she does need pro- tection against the beef, hogs and breadstuffs with which she is “deluged” from the West to the injury of her agricultural industries, and of which protection would enable her to raise enough for her home con- sumption. On the other hand, the West needs pro- tection against the boots and shoes and woolens of Massachusetts, so that Western leather and wool could be worked up at home, instead of being carried long distances in raw form, to be brought back in finished form. In the same way the iron workers of Ohio need protection against Pennsylvania more than they do against England, while it is only mockery to protect Rocky Mountain coal miners against the coal of Nova 'TEIE PROTECTIVE UNIT. 45 - Scotia, British Columbia and Australia, which cannot come into competition with them, while not protecting them against the coal of Iowa; or to protect the infant cotton mills of the South against Old England while giving them no protection against New England. Upon the protective theory protection is most needed against like industries. All protectionists agree that the United States has greater need of protection against Great Britain than against Brazil; and Canada against the United States than against India—all agree that if we must have free trade it should be with the countries most widely differing as to their productions from our own. Now there is far less difference between the pro- ductions and -productive capacities of New Hampshire and Vermont, of Indiana and Illinois, or of Kansas and Nebraska, than there is between the United States as a whole and any foreign country. Therefore, on the pro- tective theory, tariffs between these states are more needed than between the United States and foreign countries. And since adjoining townships differ less in industrial capacities than adjoining states, they re- quire protective tariffs all the more. The thirteen American colonies came together as thir- teen independent sovereignties, each retaining the full power of taxation, including that of levying duty on im- ports, which was not given up by them until 1787, eleven years after the Declaration of Independence, when the Federal Constitution was adopted. If the protective theory, then dominant in Great Britain, had at that time had the hold upon the American people which it afterward obtained, it is certain that the power of protecting themselves would never have been given up by the states. And had the Union continued as 46 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. at first formed, or had the framers of the Constitution lacked the foresight to prohibit state tariffs, there is no doubt that when we came to imitate the British system of protection we should have had as strong a demand in the various states for protection against other states as we have had for protection against foreign coun- tries, and the arguments now used against free trade with foreign countries would to-day be urged against free trade between the states. Nor can there be any doubt that if our political or. ganization made our townships independent of one another, we should have, in our townships and villages, the same clamor for protection against the industries of other townships and villages that we have now for the protection of the nation against other nations. I am writing on Long Island, near the town of Jamaica. I think I could make as good an argument to the people of that little town as is made by the pro- tectionists to the people of the United States. I could say to the shopkeepers of Jamaica, “Your townsmen now go to New York when they want to purchase a suit of clothes or a bill of dry goods, leaving to you only the fag ends of their custom, while the farmers' wagons that pass in a long line over the turnpike every night, carrying produce to New York and Brooklyn, bring back supplies the next day. A protective tariff will compel these purchases to be made here. Thus profits that now go to New York and Brooklyn will be retained in Jamaica; you will want larger stores and better houses, can pay your clerks and journeymen higher wages, will need more banking accommodations, will advertise more freely in Jamaican newspapers, and thus will the town grow and prosper.” • THE PROTECTIVE UNIT. 47 “Moreover,” I might say, “what a useless waste of labor there is in carrying milk and butter, chickens, eggs and vegetables to New York and Brooklyn and bringing back other things. How much better for our farmers if they had a home market. This we can secure for them by a tariff that will protect Jamaican industries against those of New York and Brooklyn. Clothing, cigars, boots and shoes, agricultural imple- ments and furniture may be manufactured here as well as in those cities. Why should we not have a cotton factory, a woolen mill, a foundry, and, in short, all the establishments necessary to supply the wants of our people? To get them we need only a protective tar- iff. Capital, when assured of protection, will be gladly forthcoming for such enterprises, and we shall soon be exporting what we now import, while our farmers will find a demand at their doors for all their produce. Even if at first they do have to pay somewhat higher prices for what they buy they will be much more than compensated by the higher prices they will get for what they sell, and will save an eight or ten mile haul to Brooklyn or New York. Thus, instead of Jamaica remaining a little village, the industries which a pro- tective tariff will build up here will make it a large town, while the increased demand for labor will make wages higher and employment steadier.” I submit that all this is at least as valid as the pro- tective arguments that are addressed to the people of the whole United States, and no one who has listened to the talk of village shopkeepers or noticed the comments of local newspapers can doubt that were our townships independent, village protectionists could get as ready a hearing as national protectionists do now. 48 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. But to follow the protective theory to its logical con- clusions we cannot stop with protection between state and state, township and township, village and village. If protection be needful between nations, it must be need- ful not only between political subdivisions, but between family and family. If nations should never buy of other nations what they might produce at home, the same principle must forbid each family to buy anything it might produce? Social laws, like physical laws, must apply to the molecule as well as to the aggregate. But a social condition in which the principle of protec- tion was thus fully carried out would be a condition of utter barbarism. CHAPTER VI. TRADE. PROTECTION implies prevention. To protect is to preserve or defend. What is it that protection by tariff prevents? It is trade. To speak more exactly, it is that part of trade which consists in bringing in from other countries com- modities that might be produced at home. But trade, from which “protection ” essays to pre- serve and defend us, is not, like flood, earthquake, or tornado, something that comes without human agency. Trade implies human action. There can be no need of preserving from or defending against trade, unless there are men who want to trade and try to trade. Who, then, are the men against whose efforts to trade “pro- tection” preserves and defends us? If I had been asked this question before I had come to think over the matter for myself, I should have said that the men against whom “protection ” defends us are foreign producers who wish to sell their goods in “our home markets. This is the assumption that runs through all protectionist arguments—the assumption that foreigners are constantly trying to force their pro- ducts upon us, and that a protective tariff is a means for defending ourselves against what they want to do. Yet a moment's thought will show that no effort of foreigners to sell us their products could of itself make 3 50 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. a tariff necessary. For the desire of one party, how- ever strong it may be, cannot of itself bring about trade. To every trade there must be two parties who mutually desire to trade, and whose actions are recipro- cal. No one can buy unless he can find some one will- ing to sell; and no one can sell unless there is some other one willing to buy. If Americans did not want to buy foreign goods, foreign goods could not be sold here even if there were no tariff. The efficient cause of the trade which our tariff aims to prevent is the de- sire of Americans to buy foreign goods, not the desire of foreign producers to sell them. Thus protection really prevents what the “protected" themselves want to do. It is not from foreigners that protection pre- serves and defends us; it is from ourselves. Trade is not invasion. It does not involve aggression on one side and resistance on the other, but mutual con- sent and gratification. There cannot be a trade unless the parties to it agree, any more than there can be a quarrel unless the parties to it differ. England, we say, forced trade with the outside world upon China, and the United States upon Japan. But, in both cases, what was done was not to force the people to trade, but to force their governments to let them. If the people had not wanted to trade, the opening of the ports would have been useless. Civilized nations, however, do not use their armies. and fleets to open one another's ports to trade. What they use their armies and fleets for, is, when they quar- rel, to close one another's ports. And their effort then is to prevent the carrying in of things even more than the bringing out of things—importing rather than ex- porting. For a people can be more quickly injured by TRADE. * 51 preventing them from getting things than by prevent- ing them from sending things away. Trade does not require force. Free trade consists simply in letting people buy and sell as they want to buy and sell. It is protection that requires force, for it consists in prevent- ing people from doing what they want to do. Protect- ive tariffs are as much applications of force as are blockading squadrons, and their object is the same— to prevent trade. The difference between the two is that blockading squadrons are a means whereby nations seek to prevent their enemies from trading; protective tariffs are a means whereby nations attempt to prevent their own people from trading. What protection teaches us, is to do to ourselves in time of peace what enemies seek to do to us in time of war. Can there be any greater misuse of language than to apply to commerce terms suggesting strife, and to talk of one nation invading, deluging, overwhelming or in- undating another with goods? Goods ! what are they but good things—things we are all glad to get? Is it not preposterous to talk of one nation forcing its good things upon another nation ? Who individually would wish to be preserved from such invasion? Who would object to being inundated with all the dress goods his wife and daughters could want; deluged with a horse and buggy; overywhelmed with clothing, with groceries, with good cigars, fine pictures, or anything else that has value? And who would take it kindly if any one should assume to protect him by driving off those who wanted to bring him such things? In point of fact, however, not only is it impossible for one nation to sell to another, unless that other wants to buy, but international trade does not consist in send. 52 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. ing out goods to be sold. The great mass of the im. ports of every civilized country consists of goods that have been ordered by the people of that country and are imported at their risk. This is true even in our own case, although one of the effects of our tariff is that many goods that otherwise would be imported by Americans are sent here by European manufacturers, because undervaluation is thus made easier. But it is not the importer who is the cause of impor- tation. Whether goods are brought here by American importers or sent here by foreign exporters, the cause of their coming here is that they are asked for by the American people. It is the demand of purchasers at retail that causes goods to be imported. Thus a pro- tective tariff is a prevention by a people not of what others want to do to them, but of what they them. selves want to do. When in the common use of the word we speak of individuals or communities protecting themselves, there is always implied the existence of some external enemy or danger, such as cold, heat or accident, Savage beasts or noxious vermin, fire or disease, robbers or invaders; something disposed to do what the protected object to. The only cases in which the common meaning of the word does not imply some external enemy or danger are those in which it implies some protector of superior intelligence, as when we speak of imbeciles, lunatics, drunkards or young children being protected against their own irrational acts. But the systems of restriction which their advo- cates have named “protective” lack both the one and the other of these essential qualities of real protection. What they defend a people against is not external TRADE. - 53 enemies or dangers, but what that people themselves want to do. Yet this “protection ” is not the protec- tion of a superior intelligence, for human wit has not yet been able to devise any scheme by which any intelligence can be secured in a Parliament or Con- gress superior to that of the people it represents. That where protective tariffs are imposed it is in accordance with the national will I do not deny. What I wish to point out is that even the people who thus impose protective tariffs upon themselves still want to do what by protective tariffs they strive to prevent themselves from doing. This is seen in the tendency of importation to continue in spite of tar- iffs, in the disposition of citizens to evade their tariff whenever they can, and in the fact that the very same individuals who demand the imposition of tariffs to prevent the importation of foreign commodities are among the individuals whose demand for those com- modities is the cause of their importation. Given a people of which every man, woman and child is a pro- tectionist, and a tariff unanimously agreed upon, and still that tariff will be a restriction upon what these people want to do and will still try to do. Protection- ists are only protectionists in theory and in politics. When it comes to buying what they want all protec- tionists are free traders. I say this to point out not the inconsistency of protectionists, but something more significant. “I write.” “I breathe.” Both propositions assert action on the part of the same individual, but action of different kinds. I write by conscious volition; I breathe instinctively. I am conscious that I breathe only when I think of it. Yet my breathing goes on 54 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. whether I think of it or not—when my consciousness is absorbed in thought, or is dormant in sleep. Though with all my will I try to stop breathing, I yet, in spite of myself, try to breathe, and will continue that en- deavor while life lasts. Other vital functions are even further beyond consciousness and will. We live by the continuous carrying on of multifarious and delicate processes apparent only in their results and utterly irresponsive to mental direction. Between the man and the community there is in these respects an analogy which becomes closer as civilization progresses and social relations grow more complex. That power of the whole which is lodged in governments is limited in its field of consciousness and action much as the conscious will of the indi- vidual is limited, and even that consensus of personal beliefs and wishes termed public opinion is but little wider in its range. There is, beyond national direction and below national consciousness, a life and relation of parts and a performance of functions which are to the social body what the vital processes are to the physical body. What would happen to the individual if all the functions of the body were placed under the control of the consciousness, and a man could forget to breathe, or miscalculate the amount of gastric juice needed by his stomach, or blunder as to what his kidneys should take from the blood, is what would happen to a nation in which all individual activities were directed by government. And though a people collectively may institute a tariff to prevent trade, their individual wants and de- sires will still force them to try to trade, just as TRADE. 55 when a man ties a ligature round his arm, his blood will still try to circulate. For the effort of each to sat. 1sfy his desires with the least exertion, which is the motive of trade, is as instinctive and persistent as are the instigations which the vital organs of the body obey. It is not the importer and the exporter who are the cause of trade, but the daily and hourly de- mands of those who never think of importing or ex- porting, and to whom trade carries that which they demand, just as the blood carries to each fibre of the body that for which it calls. It is as natural for men to trade as it is for blood to circulate. Man is by nature a trading animal, impelled to trade by persistent desires, placed in a world where everything shows that he was intended to trade, and finding in trade the possibility of social advance. Without trade man would be a savage. Where each family raises its own food, builds its own house, makes its own clothes and manufactures its own tools, no one can have more than the barest necessaries of life, and every local failure of crops must bring famine. A people living in this way will be independent, but their independence will resemble that of the beasts. They will be poor, ignorant, and all but powerless against the forces of nature and the vicissi- tudes of the seasons. This social condition, to which the protective theory would logically lead, is the lowest in which man is ever found—the condition from which he has toiled upward. He has progressed only as he has learned to satisfy his wants by exchanging with his fellows and has freed and extended trade. The difference between naked savages possessed only of the rudiments of the 56 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. arts, cowering in ignorance and weakness before the forces of nature, and the wealth, the knowledge and the power of our highest civilization, is due to the exchange of the independence which is the aim of the protective system, for that interdependence which comes with trade. Men cannot apply themselves to the pro- duction of but one of the many things human wants demand unless they can exchange their products for the products of others. And thus it is only as the growth of trade permits the division of labor that, beyond the merest rudiments, skill can be developed, knowledge acquired and invention made; and that productive power can so gain upon the requirements for maintaining life that leisure becomes possible and capital can be accumulated. - If to prevent trade were to stimulate industry and promote prosperity, then the localities where he was most isolated would show the first advances of man. The natural protection to home industry afforded by rugged mountain chains, by burning deserts, or by seas too wide and tempestuous for the frail bark of the early mariner, would have given us the first glimmerings of civilization and shown its most rapid growth. But, in fact, it is where trade could best be carried on that we find wealth first accumulating and civilization beginning. It is on accessible har- bors, by navigable rivers and much traveled high- ways that we find cities arising and the arts and sciences developing. And as trade becomes free and extensive—as roads are made and navigation improved; as pirates and robbers are extirpated and treaties of peace put an end to chronic warfare—so does wealth augment and civilization grow. All our TRADE. 57 great labor saving inventions, from that of money to that of the steam engine, spring from trade and pro- mote its extension. Trade has ever been the extin- guisher of war, the eradicator of prejudice, the diffuser of knowledge. It is by trade that useful seeds and animals, useful arts and inventions, have been carried over the world, and that men in one place have been enabled not only to obtain the products, but to profit by the observations, discoveries and inventions of men in other places. In a world created on protective principles, all habit- able parts would have the same soil and climate, and be fitted for the same productions, so that the inhabit- ants of each locality would be able to produce at home all they required. Its seas and rivers would not lend themselves to navigation, and every little section in- tended for the habitation of a separate community would be guarded by a protective mountain chain. If we found ourselves in such a world, we might infer it to be the intent of nature that each people should de- velop its own industries independently of all others. But the World in which we do find ourselves is not merely adapted to intercommunication, but what it yields to man is so distributed as to compel the people of different localities to trade with each other to fully satisfy their desires. The diversities of soil and climate, the distribution of water, wood and mineral deposits, the currents of sea and air, produce infinite differences in the adaptation of different parts to different produc- tions. It is not merely that one Zone yields sugar and coffee, the banana and the pineapple, and another wheat . and barley, the apple and the potato; that one supplies furs and another cotton; that here are hillsides adapted 3r 58 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. to pasture and there valleys fitted for the plow; here granite and there clay; in one place iron and coal and in another copper and lead ; but that there are differences so delicate that, though experience tells us they exist, we cannot say to what they are due. Wine of a cer- tain quality is produced in one place which cuttings from the same vines will not yield in another place, though soil and climate seem alike. Some localities, without assignable reason, become renowned for pro- ductions of one kind and some for productions of an- other kind; and experience often shows that plants thrive differently in different parts of the same field. These endless diversities, in the adaptation of different parts of the earth's surface to the production of the different things required by man, show that nature has not intended man to depend for the supply of his wants upon his own production, but to exchange with his fellows, just as the placing of the meat before one guest at table, the vegetables before another, and the bread before another, shows the intent of the host that they should help one another. Other natural facts have similar bearing. It has long been known that to obtain the best crops the farmer should not sow with seed grown in his own fields, but with seed brought from afar. The strain of domestic animals seems always improved by imported stock, even poultry-breeders finding it best to sell the male birds they raise and supply their places with cocks brought from a distance. Whether or not the same law holds true with regard to the physical part of man, it is certain that the admixture of peoples produces stimulating mental effects. Prejudices are worn down, wits are sharpened, language enriched, habits and cus. TRADE. 59 toms brought to the test of comparison and new ideas enkindled. The most progressive peoples, if not always of mixed blood, have always been the peoples who came most in contact with and learned most from others. “Home keeping youths have ever homely wits” is true of nations. And, further than this, it is characteristic of all the inventions and discoveries that are so rapidly increas- ing our power over nature that they require the greater division of labor, and extend trade. Thus every step in advance destroys the independence and increases the interdependence of men. The appointed condition of human progress is evidently that men shall come into closer relations and become more and more dependent upon each other. Thus the restrictions which protectionism urges us to impose upon ourselves are about as well calculated to promote national prosperity as ligatures, that would impede the circulation of the blood, would be to pro. mote bodily health and comfort 7 Protection calls upon us to pay officials, to encourage spies and in- formers, and to provoke fraud and perjury, for what? Why, to preserve ourselves from and protect ourselves against something which offends no moral law ; some- thing to which we are instinctively impelled; some- thing without which we could never have emerged from barbarism, and something which physical nature and social laws alike prove to be in conformity with the creative intent. It is true that protectionists do not condemn all trade, and though some of them have wished for an ocean of fire to bar out foreign products, others, more reasonable if less logical, would permit a country to import things 60 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. it cannot produce. The international trade which they concede to be harmless amounts not to a tenth and per- haps not to a twentieth of the international trade of the world, and, so far as our own country is concerned, the things we could not obtain at home amount to little more than a few productions of the torrid zone, and even these, if properly protected, might be grown at home by artificial heat, to the incidental encouragement of the glass and coal industries. But, so far as the cor- rectness of the theory goes, it does not matter whether the trade which “protection ” would permit, as com- pared with that it would prevent, be more or less. What “protection” calls on us to preserve ourselves from, and guardourselves against, is trade. And whether trade be between citizens of the same nation or citizens of dif- ferent nations, and whether we get by it things that we could produce for ourselves or things that we could not produce for ourselves, the object of trade is always the same. If I trade with a Canadian, a Mexican, or an Eng- lishman it is for the same reason that I trade with an American—that I would rather have the thing he gives me than the thing I give him. Why should I refuse to trade with a foreigner any more than with a fellow-citizen when my object in trading is my advantage, not his? And is it not in the one case, quite as much as in the other, an injury to me that my trade should be prevented? What difference does it make whether it would be pos- sible or impossible for me to make for myself the thing for which I trade. If I did not want the thing. I am to get more than the thing I am to give, I would not wish to make the trade. Here is a farmer who proposes to ex- change with his neighbor a horse he does not want for a couple of cows he does want. Would it benefit these TRADE. 61 farmers to prevent this trade on the ground that one might breed his own horses and the other raise his own cows? Yet if one farmer lived on the American and the other lived on the Canadian side of the line this is just what both the American and Canadian governments would do. And this is called “protection.” It is only one of the many benefits of trade that it enables people to obtain what the natural conditions of their own localities would not enable them to produce. This is, however, so obvious a benefit that protectionists cannot altogether ignore it, and a favorite doctrine with American protectionists is that trade ought to follow meridians of longitude instead of parallels of latitude, because the great differences of climate and conse- quently of natural productions are between north and south.* The most desirable reconstruction of the world on this theory would be its division into “countries” consisting of narrow strips running from the equator to: the poles, with high tariffs on either side and at the equatorial end, for the polar ice would serve the pur- pose at the other. But in the meantime, despite this notion that trade ought to be between north and south rather than between east and west, the fact is that the great commerce of the world is and always has been between east and west. And the reason is clear. It is that peoples most alike in habits and needs will call most largely for each other's productions, and that the * “This, then, is our position respecting commerce # * * that it should interchange the productions of diverse zones and climates, following in its trans-oceanic voyages lines of longitude oftener than lines of latitude.”—HoRACE GREELEY, Political Economy, p. 39. “Legitimate and natural commerce moves rather along the meridians than along the parallels of latitude.”—PROF. ROBERT ELLIS THOMPSON, Political Economy, p. 217. ty 62 FROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. course of migration and of assimilating influences has been rather between east and west than between north and South. Difference in latitude is but one element of difference in climate, and difference in climate is but one element of the endless diversity in natural productions and ca- pacities. In no one place will nature yield to labor all that man finds useful. Adaptation to one class of pro- ducts involves non-adaptation to others. Trade, by permitting us to obtain each of the things we need from the locality best fitted for its production, enables us to utilize the highest powers of nature in the produc- tion of them all, and thus to increase enormously the sum of various things which a given quantity of labor - expended in any locality can secure. But, what is even more important, trade also enables us to utilize the highest powers of the human factor in production. All men cannot do all things equally well. There are differences in physical and mental powers which give different degrees of aptitude for dif- ferent parts of the work of supplying human needs. And far more important still are the differences that arise from the development of special skill. By de- voting himself to one branch of production a man can acquire skill which enables him, with the same labor, to produce enormously more than one who has not made that branch his specialty. Twenty boys may have equal aptitude for any one of twenty trades, but if every boy tries to learn the twenty trades, none of them can become good workmen in any; whereas, if each devotes himself to one trade, all may become good workmen. There will not only be a saving of the time and effort required for learning, but each, more. TRADE. 63 over, can in a single vocation work to much better ad-. vantage, and may acquire and use tools which it would be impossible to obtain and employ did each attempt the whole twenty. And as there are differences between individuals which fit them for different branches of production, so, but to a much greater degree, are there such differences between communities. Not to speak again of the dif- ferences due to situation and natural facilities, some things can be produced with greater relative advantage where population is sparse, others where it is dense, and differences in industrial development, in habits, customs and related occupations, produce differences in relative adaptation. Such gains, moreover, as attend the division of labor between individuals, attend also the division of labor between communities, and lead to that localization of industry which causes different places to become noted for different industries. Wher- ever the production of some special thing becomes the leading industry, skill is more easily acquired, and is carried to a higher pitch, supplies are most readily. procured, auxiliary and correlative occupations grow up, and a larger scale of production leads to the employment of more efficient methods. Thus in the natural devel- opment of society trade brings about differentiations of industry between communities as between individuals, and with similar benefits. Men of different nations trade with each other for the same reason that men of the same nation do—because they find it profitable; because they thus obtain what they want with less labor than they otherwise could. Goods will not be imported into any country unless they can be obtained more easily by producing some- * 64 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. thing else and exchanging it for them, than by produc. ing them directly. And hence, to restrict importations must be to lessen productive power and reduce the fund from which all revenues are drawn. Any one can see what would be the result of for- bidding each individual to obtain from another any commodity or service which he himself was naturally fitted to produce or perform. Such a regulation, were any government mad enough to adopt it and powerful enough to maintain it, would paralyze the forces that make civilization possible and soon convert the most populous and wealthy country into a howling wilder- ness. The restrictions which protection would impose upon foreign trade differ only in degree, not in kind, from such restrictions as these. They would not re- duce a nation to barbarism, because they do not affect all trade, and rather hamper than prohibit the trade they do affect; but they must prevent the people that adopt them from obtaining the abundance they might otherwise enjoy. If the end of labor be, not the ex- penditure of effort, but the securing of results, then whether any particular thing ought to be obtained in a country by home production, or by importation, de- pends solely upon which mode of obtaining it will give the largest result to the least labor. This is a question involving such complex considerations that what any country ought to obtain in this way or in that cannot be settled by any Congress or Parliament. It can safely be left only to those sure instincts which are to society what the vital instincts are to the body, and which always impel men to take the easiest way open to them to reach their ends. When not caused by artificial obstacles, any tendency TRADE. 65 in trade to take a certain course is proof that it ought to take that course, and restrictions are harmful because they restrict, and in proportion as they restrict. To assert that the way for men to become healthy and strong is for them to force into their stomachs what nature tries to reject, to regulate the play of their lungs by bandages, or to control the circulation of their blood by ligatures, would be not a whit more absurd than to assert that the way for nations to become rich is for them to restrict the natural tendency to trade. CHAPTER VII. PRODUCTION AND PRODUCERS. REMOTE from neighbors, in a part of the country where population is only beginning to come, stands the rude house of a new settler. As the stars come out, a ruddy light glearns from the little window. The house- wife is preparing a meal. The wood that burns so cheerily was cut by the settler, the flour now turning into bread is from wheat of his raising; the fish hiss- ing in the pan were caught by one of the boys, and the water bubbling in the kettle, in readiness to be poured on the tea, was brought from the spring by the eldest girl before the sun had set. The settler cut the wood. But it took more than that to produce the wood. Had it been merely cut, it would still be lying where it fell. The labor of haul- ing it was as much a part of its production as the labor of cutting it. So the journey to and from the mill was as necessary to the production of the flour as the planting and reaping of the wheat. To produce the fish the boy had to walk to the lake and trudge back again. And the production of the water in the kettle required not merely the exertion of the girl who brought it from the spring, but also the sinking of the barrel in which it collected, and the making of the bucket in which it was carried. e As for the tea, it was grown in China, was carried on PRODUCTION AND PRODUCERS. 67 a bamboo pole upon the shoulders of a man to some river village, and sold to a Chinese merchant, who shipped it by boat to a treaty port. There, having been packed for ocean transportation, it was sold to the agency of Some American house, and sent by steamer to San Francisco. Thence it passed by railroad, with another transfer of ownership, into the hands of a Chi- cago jobber. The jobber, in turn, in pursuance of another sale, shipped it to the village store-keeper, who held it so that the settler might get it when and in such quantities as he pleased, just as the water from the spring is held in the sunken barrel so that it may be had when needed. The native dealer who first purchased this tea of the grower, the merchant who shipped it across the Pacific, the Chicago jobber who held it as in a reservoir until the store-keeper ordered it, the store-keeper who, bring- ing it from Chicago to the village, held it as in a smaller reservoir until the settler came for it, as well as those concerned in its transportation, from the coolie who carried it to the bank of the Chinese river to the brake- men of the train that brought it from Chicago—were they not all parties to the production of that tea to this family as truly as were the peasants who cultivated the plant and gathered its leaves 7 The settler got the tea by exchanging for it money obtained in exchange for things produced from nature by the labor of himself and his boys. Has not this tea, then, been produced to this family by their labor as truly as the wood, the flour or the water? Is it not true that the labor of this family devoted to producing things which were exchanged for tea has really pro- duced tea, even in the sense of causing it to be grown, 68 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. cured and transported Ž It is not the growing of the tea in China that causes it to be brought to the United States. It is the demand for tea in the United States —that is to say, the readiness to give other products of labor for it—that causes tea to be grown in China for shipment to the United States. To produce is to bring forth, or to bring to. There is no other word in our language which includes at Once all the operations, such as catching, gathering, extracting, growing, breeding or making, by which human labor brings forth from nature, or brings to conditions adapted to human uses, the material things desired by men and which constitute wealth. When, therefore, we wish to speak collectively of the oper- ations by which things are secured, or fitted for human use, as distinguished from operations which consist in moving them from place to place or passing them from hand to hand after they have been so secured or fitted, we are obliged to use the word production in distinc- tion to transportation or exchange. But we should always remember that this is but a narrow and special use of the word. While in conformity with the usages of our language we may properly speak of production as distinguished from transportation and exchange, just as we may prop- erly speak of men as distinguished from women and children, yet in its full meaning, production includes transportation and exchange, just as men includes women and children. In the narrow meaning of the word we speak of coal as having been produced when it has been moved from its place in the vein to the sur- face of the ground; but evidently the moving of the coal from the mouth of the mine to those who are to PRODUCTION AND PRODUCERS. 69 use it is as necessary a part of coal production, in the full sense, as is the bringing of it to the surface. . And while we may produce coal in the United States by digging it out of the ground, we may also just as truly produce it by exchanging other products of labor for it. Whether we get coal by digging it or by bringing it from Nova Scotia or Australia or England in exchange for other products of our labor, it is, in the one case as truly as in the other, produced here by our labor. Through all protectionist arguments runs the notion that transporters and traders are non-producers, whose support lessens the amount of wealth which other classes can enjoy.” This is a short-sighted view. In the full sense of the term transporters and traders are as truly producers as are miners, farmers or manufact- urers, since the transporting of things and the exchang- ing of things are as necessary to the enjoyment of things as is extracting, growing or making. There are some operations conducted under the forms of trade that are in reality gambling or blackmailing, but this does not alter the fact that real trade, which consists in exchang- ing and transporting commodities, is a part of produc- tion—a part so necessary and so important that without it the other operations of production could only be car. * “In my conception, the chief end of a true political economy is the conversion of idlers and useless exchangers and traſſickers into habitual, effective producers of wealth.”—HoRACE GREELEY, Politi- cal Economy, p. 29. The trader “adds nothing to the real wealth of society. He neither directs and manages a vital change in the form of matter as does the farmer, nor a chemical and mechanical change in form as does the manufacturer. He merely transfers things from the place of their production to the place of demand.”—PROF. R. E. THOMP- son, Political Economy, p. 198. 70 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. ried on in the most primitive manner and with the most niggard results. And not least important of the functions of the trader is that of holding things in stock, so that those who wish to use them may be able to get them at such times and places, and in such quantities, as are most convenient. This is a service analogous to that per- formed by the sunken barrel which holds the water of a spring so that it can be had by the bucketful when needed, or by the reservoirs and pipes which enable the inhabitant of a city to obtain water by the turning of a faucet. The profits of traders and “middlemen” may sometimes be excessive (and anything which hampers trade and increases the capital necessary to carry it on tends to make them excessive) but they are in reality based upon the performance of services in holding and distributing things as well as in transporting things. “When Charles Fourier was young,” says Professor Thompson (Political Economy, p. 199), “he was on a visit to Paris, and priced at a street stall some apples of a sort that grew abundantly in his native province. He was amazed to find that they sold for many times the sum they would bring at home, having passed through the hands of a host of middlemen on their way from the owner of the orchard to the eater of the fruit. The impression received at that instant never left him ; it gave the first impulse to his thinking out his socialistic scheme for the reconstruction of Society, in which among other sweeping changes the whole class of traders and their profits are to be abolished.” This story, quoted approvingly to convey an idea that the trader is a mere toll gatherer, simply shows what a superficial thinker Fourier was. If he had undertaken to bring with him to Paris a supply of apples and to carry them around with him so that he could have one when he felt like if he would have formed a much PRODUCTION AND PRODUCERS. 71 truer idea of what he was really paying for in the in. creased price. That price included not merely the cost of the apple at its place of growth, plus the cost of transporting it to Paris, the octrol at the Paris gates,” the loss of damaged apples, and remuneration for the service and capital of the wholesaler, who held the apples in stock until the vender chose to take them, but also payment to the vender, for standing all day in the streets of Paris, in order to supply a few apples to those who wanted an apple then and there. * So when I go to a druggist's and buy a small quan- tity of medicine or chemicals I pay many times the original cost of those articles, but what I thus pay is in much larger degree wages than profit. Out of such small sales the druggist must get not only the cost of what he sells me, with other costs incidental to the busi- ness, but also payment for his services. These services consist not only in the actual exertion of giving me what I want, but in waiting there in readiness to serve me when I choose to come. In the price of what he sells me he makes a charge for what printers call “waiting time.” And he must manifestly not merely charge “waiting time" for himself, but also for the stock of many different things only occasionally called for, which he must keep on hand. He has been wait- ing there, with his stock, in anticipation of the fact that * The octrol, or municipal tariff on produce brought into a town, is still levied in France, though abolished for a time by the Revo- lution. It is a survival of the local tariffs once common in Europe, which separated province from province and town from country. Colbert, the first Napoleon, and the German Zollverein did much in reducing and abolishing these restrictions to trade, producing in this way good results which are sometimes attributed by protections ists to external tariffs. tº 72 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. such persons as myself, in sudden need of some small quantities of drugs or chemicals, would find it cheaper to pay him many times their wholesale cost than to go further and buy larger quantities. What I pay him, even when it is not payment for the skilled labor of compounding, is largely a payment of the same nature as, were he not there, I might have had to make to a messenger. If each consumer had to go to the producer for the small quantities individually demanded, the producer would have to charge a higher price on account of the greater labor and expense of attending to such small transactions. A hundred cases of shoes may be sold at wholesale in less time than would be consumed in suiting a customer with a single pair. On the other hand, the going to the producer direct would involve an enormous increase of cost and trouble to the con- sumer, even when such a method of obtaining things would not be utterly impossible. What “middlemen" do is to save to both parties this trouble and expense, and the profits which compe- tition permits them to charge in return are infinitesimal as compared with the enormous savings effected—are like the charge made to each consumer for the cost of the aqueducts, mains and pumping engines of a great system of water supply as compared with the cost of providing a separate system for each house. And further than this, these middlemen between producer and consumer effect an enormous economy in the amount of commodities that it is necessary to keep in stock to provide for a given consumption, and con- sequently vastly lessen the loss from deterioration and decay. Let any one consider what amount of stores º PRODUCTION AND PRODUCERS. 73 would be needed to keep in their accustomed supply even for a month a family used to easy access to those handy magazines of commodities which retail dealers maintain. He will see at once that there are a number of things such as fresh meat, fish, fruits, etc., which it is impossible to keep on hand, so as to be sure of having them when needed. And of the things that would keep longer, such as flour, sugar, oil, etc., he will see that but for the retail dealer it would be necessary that much greater quantities should be kept in each house, with a much greater liability to loss from decay or accident. But it is when he comes to things not constantly needed, but which, when needed, though it may not be once a year or once a lifetime, may be needed very badly—that he will realize fully how the much-abused “middleman "economizes the capital of society and in- creases the opportunities of its members. A retail dealer is called by the English a “shop- keeper” and by the Americans a “store-keeper.” The American usage best expresses his real function. He is in reality a keeper of stores which otherwise his cus- tomers would have to keep on hand for themselves, or go without. The English speak of the shops of co- operative supply associations as “stores,” since it is in them that the various things required from time to time by the members of those associations are stored until called for. But this is precisely what, without any formal association, the retail dealer does for those who buy of him. And though co-operative purchasing associations have to a certain extent succeeded in Fngland (they have generally failed in the United States) there can be no question that the functions of keeping things in store and distributing them to consumers as needed are 7 74 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. on the whole performed more satisfactorily and more economically by self-appointed store or stock- keepers than they could be as yet by formal asso- ciations of consumers. And the tendencies of the time to economies in the distribution as well as in the production of commodities, are bringing about through the play of competition just such a saving of expense to the consumer as is aimed at by co-op- erative supply associations. That in civilized society to-day there seem to be too many store-keepers and other distributors is quite true. But so there seem to be too many pro- fessional men, too many mechanics, too many farm- ers, and too many laborers. What may be the cause of this most curious state of things it may hereafter lie in our way to inquire, but at present I am only concerned in pointing out that the trader is not a mere “useless exchanger,” who “adds nothing to the real wealth of society,” but that the transport- ing, storing, and exchanging of things are as neces- sary a part of the work of supplying human needs as is growing, extracting, or making, Nor should it be forgotten that the investigator, the philosopher, the teacher, the artist, the poet, the priest, though not engaged in the production of wealth, are not only engaged in the production of utilities and satisfactions to which the production of wealth is only a means, but by acquiring and diffus- ing knowledge, stimulating mental powers and ele- vating the moral sense, may greatly increase the ability to produce wealth. For man does not live by bread alone. He is not an engine, in which so much fuel gives so much power. On a capstan bar PRODUCTION AND PRODUCERS. 75 or a topsail halyard a good song tells like muscle, and a “Marseillaise ’’ or a “Battle Hymn of the Republic ’’ counts for bayonets. A hearty laugh, a noble thought, a perception of harmony, may add to the power of dealing even with material things. He who by any exertion of mind or body adds to the aggregate of enjoyable wealth, increases the sum of human knowledge or gives to human life higher elevation or greater fullness—he is in the large meaning of the words, a “producer,” a “working man,” a “laborer,” and is honestly earning honest wages. But he who without doing aught to make man- kind richer, wiser, better, happier, lives on the toil of others—he, no matter by what name of honor he may be called, or how lustily the priests of Mammon may swing their censers before him, is in the last analysis but a beggarman or a thief, CEIAPTER VIII. TARIFFS FOR REVENUE. TARIFFS may embrace duties on exports as well as on imports; but duties on exports are prohibited by the Constitution of the United States and are now levied only by a few countries, such as Brazil, and by them only on a few articles. The tariff, as we have to consider it, is a schedule of taxes upon imports. The word “tariff’ is said to be derived from the Spanish town of Tarifa, near Gibraltar, where the Moors in the days of their power collected duties, prob- ably much after the manner of those Chinese local cus- tom houses called “squeeze stations.” But the thing is older than the name. Augustus Caesar levied duties on imports into Italy, and there were tariffs long before the Caesars. - The purpose in which tariffs originate is that of rais- ing revenue. The idea of using them for protection is an afterthought. And before considering the protect- ive function of tariffs it will be well to consider them as a means for collecting revenue. It is usually assumed, even by the opponents of pro- tection, that tariffs should be maintained for revenue. Most of those who are commonly called free traders might more properly be called revenue tariff men. They object, not to the tariff, but only to its protective features, and propose, not to abolish it, but only to re- TARIFFS FOR REVENUE. 77 strict it to revenue purposes. Nearly all the opposi- tion to the protective system in the United States is of this kind, and in current discussion a tariff for revenue Only is usually assumed to be the sole alternative to a tariff for protection. But since there are other ways of raising revenue than by tariffs this manifestly is not so. And if not useful for protection, the only justification for any tariff is that it is a good means of raising rev- enue. Let us inquire as to this. - Duties on imports are indirect taxes. Therefore the question whether a tariff is a good means of raising revenue involves the question whether indirect taxa- tion is a good means of raising revenue. As to ease and cheapness of collection indirect taxa- tion is certainly not a good means of raising revenue. While there are direct taxes, such as taxes on real estate and taxes on legacies and successions, from which great revenues can easily and cheaply be col- lected, the only indirect taxes from which any consid- erable revenue can be obtained require large and expensive staffs of officials and the enforcement of vexatious and injurious regulations. To collect the in- direct tax on tobacco and cigars, France and some other countries make the trade and manufacture a strict government monopoly, while Great Britain prohibits the culture of tobacco under penalty of fine and im- prisonment—a prohibition particularly injurious to Ireland, where the soil and climate are in some parts admirably adapted to the growth of certain kinds of to- bacco. In the United States we maintain a costly in- quisitorial system which assumes to trace every pound of tobacco raised or imported, through all its stages of manufacture, and requires the most elaborate returns of 78 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. private business to be made to government officials. To more easily collect an indirect tax upon salt the government of British India cruelly prevents the mak- ing of Salt in many places where the natives suffer from the want of it. While indirect taxes upon spir- ituous liquors, wherever resorted to, require the most elaborate system of prohibition, inspection and espion- age. So with the collection of indirect taxes upon imports. Land frontiers must be guarded and sea-coasts watched; imports must be forbidden except at certain places and under regulations which are always vexatious and fre- quently entail wasteful delays and expenses; consuls must be maintained all over the world, and no end of oaths required; vessels must be watched from the time they enter harbor until the time they leave, and every- thing landed from them examined, down to the trunks and Satchels and sometimes the persons of passengers, while spies, informers and “bloodhounds” must be en- couraged. But in spite of prohibitions, restrictions, searchings, watchings, and swearings, indirect taxes on commodi- ties are largely evaded, sometimes by the bribery of officials and sometimes by the adoption of methods for eluding their vigilance, which though costly in them- selves, cost less than the taxes. All these costs, how- ever, whether borne by the government or by the first payers (or evaders) of the taxes, together with the increased charges due to increased prices, finally fall on consumers, and thus this method of taxation is extremely wasteful, taking from the people much more than the government obtains. A still more important objection to indirect taxation TARIFFS FOR REVENUE. 79 is that when imposed on articles of general use (and it is only from such articles that large revenues can be had) it bears with far greater weight on the poor than on the rich. Since such taxation falls on people not according to what they have, but according to what they consume, it is heaviest on those whose consump- tion is largest in proportion to their means. As much sugar is needed to sweeten a cup of tea for a working- girl as for the richest lady in the land, but the propor- tion of their means which a tax on sugar compels each to contribute to the government is in the case of the one much greater than in the case of the other. So it is with all taxes that increase the cost of articles of general consumption. They bear far more heavily on married men than on bachelors; on those who have children than on those who have none; on those barely able to support their families than on those whose incomes leave them a large surplus. If the million- aire chooses to live closely he need pay no more of these indirect taxes than the mechanic. I have known at least two millionaires—possessed not of one, but of from six to ten millions each—who paid little more of such taxes than ordinary day laborers. Even if cheaper articles were taxed at no higher rates than the more costly, such taxation would be grossly unjust; but in indirect taxation there is always a tendency to impose heavier taxes on the cheaper articles used by all than on the more costly articles used only by the rich. This arises from the necessities of the case. Not only do the larger amounts of articles of common consumption afford a wider basis for large revenues than the smaller amounts of more costly articles, but taxes imposed on them cannot be so easily 80. PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. evaded. For instance, while articles in use by the poor as well as the rich are under our tariff taxed fifty and a hundred, and even a hundred and fifty per cent., the tax on diamonds is only ten per cent., and this comparative light tax is most difficult to enforce, owing to the high value of diamonds as compared with their bulk. Even where discrimination of this kind is not made in the imposition of indirect taxation, it arises in its collection. Specific taxes fall more heavily upon the cheaper than the costlier grades of goods, while even, in the case of ad valorem taxes, under-valuation and evasion are easier in regard to the more valuable grades. That indirect taxes thus bear far more heavily on the poor than on the rich is undoubtedly one of the reasons why they have so readily been adopted. The rich are ever the powerful, and under all forms of government have most influence in forming public opinion and framing laws, while the poor are ever the voiceless. And while indirect taxation causes no loss to those who first pay it, it is collected in such insidious ways from those who finally pay it that they do not realize it. It thus affords the best means of getting the largest revenues from the body of the people with the least remonstrance against the amount collected or the uses to which it is put. This is the main reason that has induced governments to resort so largely to indirect taxation. A direct tax, where its justice and necessity are not clear, provokes outcry and oppo- sition which may at times rise to successful resistance; but not only do those indirectly taxed seldom realize it, but it is extremely difficult for them to refuse pay- ment. They are not called on at set times to pay TARIFFS FOR REVENUE. 81 definite sums to government agents, but the tax becomes indistinguishably blended with the cost of the goods they buy. When it reaches those who must finally pay it, together with all costs and profits of collection, it is not a tax yet to be paid, but a tax which has already been paid, some time ago, and many removes back, and which cannot be separated from other elements which go to make up the cost of goods. There is no choice save to pay the tax or go without the goods. If a tax-gatherer stood at the door of every store, and levied a tax of twenty-five per cent. On every article bought, there would quickly be outcry; but the very people who would fight rather than pay a tax like this, will uncomplainingly pay higher taxes when they are collected by store-keepers in increased prices. And even if an indirect tax is consciously realized, it cannot easily be opposed. At the beginning of our Revolution the indirect tax on tea levied by the British government, without the consent of the American colo- nies, was successfully resisted by preventing the land- ing of the tea; but if the tea had once got into the hands of the dealers, with the taxes on it paid, the English government could have laughed at the oppo- sition of the patriots. When in Ireland, during the height of the Land League agitation, I was much struck with the ease and certainty with which an unpopular government can collect indirect taxes. At the begin- ning of the century the Irish people, without any assistance from America, proved in the famous Tithe war that the whole power of the English government could not collect direct taxes they had resolved not to pay; and the strike against rent, which so long as per 82 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. sisted in proved so effective, could readily have been made a strike against direct taxation. Had the gov- ernment which was enforcing the claim of the landlords depended on direct taxation, its resources could thus have been seriously diminished by the same blow which crippled the landlords; but during all the time of this strike the force used to put down the popular movement was being supported by indirect taxation on the people who were in passive rebellion. The people who struck against rent could not strike against taxes paid in buying the commodities they used. Even had rebellion been active and general, the British govern- ment could have collected the bulk of its revenues from indirect taxation, so long as it retained command of the principal towns. It is no wonder that princes and ministers anxious to make their revenues as large as possible should prefer a method that enables them to “pluck the goose with- out making it cry,” nor is it wonderful that this prefer. ence should be shared by those who get control of popular governments; but the reason which renders indirect taxes so agreeable to those who levy taxes is a sufficient reason why a people jealous of their liberties should insist that taxes levied for revenue only should be direct, not indirect. It is not merely the ease with which indirect taxes can be collected that urges to their adoption. Indirect taxes always enlist active private interests in their favor. The first rude device for making the collection of taxes easier to the governing power is to let them out to farm. Under this system, which existed in France up to the Revolution, and still exists in such countries as Turkey, persons called farmers of the TARIFES FOR REVENUE. 83 revenue buy the privilege of collecting certain taxes and make their profits, frequently very large, out of the greater amount which their vigilance and extortion enable them to collect. The system of indirect tax- ation is essentially of the same nature. The tendency of the restrictions and regulations necessary for the collection of indirect taxes is to con- centrate business and give large capital an advantage. For instance, with a board, a knife, a kettle of paste and a few dollars' worth of tobacco, a competent cigar maker could set up in business for himself, were it not for the revenue regulations. As it is, in the United States, the stock of tobacco which he must procure is not only increased in value some two or three times by a tax upon it; but before the cigar maker can go to work he must buy a manufacturer's license and find bonds in the sum of five hundred dollars. Before he can sell the cigars he has made, he must furthermore pay a tax on them, and even then if he would sell cigars in less quantities than by the box he must buy a second license. The effect of all this is to give capital a great advantage, and to concentrate in the hands of large manufacturers a business in which, if free, workmen could easily set up for themselves. , But even in the absence of such regulations indirect taxation tends to concentration. Indirect taxes add to the price of goods not only the tax itself but also the profit upon the tax. If on goods costing a dollar a manufacturer or merchant has paid fifty cents in tax- ation, he will now expect profit on a dollar and fifty cents instead of upon a dollar. As, in the course of trade, these taxed goods pass from hand to hand, the amount which each successive purchaser pays on account * 84 - PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. : : —of the tax is constantly augmenting. It is not merely inevitable that consumers have to pay considerably more than a dollar for every dollar the government receives, but larger capital is required by dealers. The need of larger capital for dealing in goods that have been enhanced in cost by taxation, the restrictions imposed on trade to secure the collection of the tax, and the better opportunities which those who do busi- ness on a large scale have of managing the payment or evading the tax, tend to concentrate business, and, by checking competition, to permit large profits, which must ultimately be paid by consumers. Thus the first pay- ers of indirect taxes are generally not merely indifferent to the tax, but regard it with favor. t That indirect taxation is of the nature of farming the revenue to private parties is shown by the fact that those who pay such taxes to the government seldom or never ask for their reduction or repeal, but on the con- trary generally oppose such propositions. The manu- facturers and dealers in tobacco and cigars have never striven to secure any reduction in the heavy taxes on those articles, and the importers who pay directly the immense sums collected by our custom houses have never grumbled at the duties, however they may grumble at the manner of their collection. When, at the time of the war, the national taxation was enormously in- creased there was no opposition to the imposition of indirect taxation from those who would thus be called upon to pay large sums to the government. On the contrary, the imposition of these taxes, by enhancing the value of stock in hand, made many fortunes. And since the war the main difficulty in reducing taxation has been the opposition of the very men who pay these TARIFFS FOR REVENUE, 85 taxes to the government. The reduction of the war tax on whisky was strongly opposed by the whisky ring, composed of great distillers. The match manufacturers fought bitterly the abolition of the tax on matches. Whenever it has been proposed to reduce or repeal any indirect tax Congress has been beset by a persistent lobby urging that, whatever other taxes might be dis- pensed with, that particular tax might be left in full force. In order to provide an excuse for keeping up indirect taxes all sorts of extravagant expenditures of the national money have been made, and hundreds of millions have been voted away to get them out of the Treasury.” Despite all this extravagance, we have a surplus; yet we go on collecting taxes we do not need because of the opposition of interested parties to their reduction. This opposition is of the same kind and springs from the same motives as that which the farmers of the revenue under the old French system would have made to the abolition of a tax which enabled them to extort two millions of francs from the French people for one million which they paid to the govern- Iment. Now, over and above the great loss to the people which indirect taxation thus imposes, the manner in which it gives individuals and corporations a direct and selfish interest in public affairs tends powerfully to the corruption of government. These moneyed inter- ests enter into our politics as a potent demoralizing force. What to the ordinary citizen is a question of public policy, affecting him only as one of some sixty * Just now (1886) the interests concerned in keeping up indirect taxation are urging a worse than useless Scheme for spending enor- mous sums on iron-clad coast defences. 8 86 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. millions of people, is to them a question of special pecuniary interest. To this is largely due the state of things in which politics has become the trade of pro- fessional politicians; in which it is seldom that one who has not money to spend can, with any prospect of suc- cess, present himself for the suffrages of his fellow-citi- zens; in which Congress is surrounded by lobbyists, clamorous for special interests, and questions of the utmost general importance are lost sight of in the struggle which goes on for the spoils of taxation. That under such a system of taxation our government is not far more corrupt than it is, is the strongest proof of the essential goodness of republican institutions. That indirect taxes may sometimes serve purposes other than the raising of revenue I do not deny. The license taxes exacted from the sellers of liquor may be defended on the ground that they diminish the number of saloons and lessen a traffic injurious to public morals. And so taxes on tobacco and spirits may be defended on the ground that the smoking of tobacco and the drinking of spirits are injurious vices, which may be lessened by making tobacco and spirits more expensive, so that (except the rich) those who smoke may be com- pelled to smoke poorer tobacco, and those who drink to drink viler liquor. But merely as a means of raising revenue, it is clear that indirect taxes are to be con- demned, since they cost far more than they yield, bear with the greatest weight upon those least able to pay, add to corruptive influences, and lessen the control of . the people over their government. tº - All the objections which apply to indirect taxes in general apply to import duties. Those protectionists are right who declare that protection is the only justi- TARIFF'S FOR REVENUE. 87. fication for a tariff,” and the advocates of “a tariff for revenue only ” have no case. If we do not need a tariff for protection we need no tariff at all, and for the purpose of raising revenue should resort to some system which will not tax the mechanic as heavily as the millionaire, and will not call on the man who rears a family to pay on that account more than the man who shirks his natural obligation, and leaves some woman whom in the scheme of nature it was intended that he should support, to take care of herself as best she cán. * “Tariffs for revenue should have no existence. Interferences with trade are to be tolerated only as measures of self-protection.”— H. C. CAREY, Past, Present and Future, p. 472. “Taxes for the sake of revenue should be imposed directly, be- cause such is the only mode in which the contribution of each in- dividual can be adjusted in proportion to his means.”—PROF. E. P. SMITH, Political Economy, pp. 265–8. “Duties for revenue * * * are highly unjust. They inflict all the hardship of indirect and unequal taxation without even the purpose of benefiting the consumer.”—PROF. R. E. THOMPSON, Political Economy, p. 232. CHAPTER IX. TARIFFS FOR PROTECTION. PROTECTIVE tariffs differ from revenue tariffs in their object, which is not so much that of obtaining revenue as that of protecting home producers from the compe- tition of imported commodities. The two objects, revenue and protection, are not merely distinct, but antagonistic. The same duty may raise some revenue and give some protection, but, past a certain point at least, in proportion as one object is secured the other is sacrificed, since revenue depends on the bringing in of commodities; protection on keep- ing them out. So the same tariff may embrace both protective and revenue duties, but while the protect- ive duties lessen its power of collecting revenue, the revenue duties by adding to the cost of home production lessen its power of encouraging home producers. The duties of a purely revenue tariff should fall only on commodities not produced in the country; or, if levied on commodities partly produced at home should be balanced by equivalent internal taxes to prevent inci- dental protection. In a purely protective tariff, on the other hand, commodities not produced in the country should be free and duties should be levied on com- modities that are or may be produced in the country. And, just in proportion as it accomplishes its object, TARIFFS FOR PROTECTION. 89 the less revenue will it yield. The tariff of Great Britain is an example of a purely revenue tariff, in- cidental protection being prevented by excise duties. There is no example of a purely protective tariff, the purpose of obtaining revenue seeming always to be the original stock upon which protective features are grafted. The tariff of the United States, like all actual protective tariffs, is partly revenue and partly protect- ive, its original purpose of yielding revenue having been subordinated to that of giving protection, until it may now be best described as a protective tariff yield- ing incidental revenue. & As we have already considered the revenue functions of tariffs, let us now consider their protective functions. Protection, as the word has come to be used to denote a scheme of national policy, signifies the levying of duties on the importation of commodities (as a means) in order (as an end) to encourage domestic industry. Now, when the means proposed in any such scheme . is the only means by which the proposed end can be reached, it is only needful to inquire as to the desir- ability of the end; but when the proposed means is only one of various means we must satisfy ourselves that it is the best. If it is not, the scheme is con- demned irrespective of the goodness of its end. Thus the advisability of protection does not, as is generally assumed, follow the admission of the advisability of encouraging domestic industry. That granted, the advisability of protection is still an open question, since it is clear that there are other ways of encourag- ing home industry than by import duties. Instead of levying import duties, we might, for in- stance, destroy a certain proportion of imported com- 90 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. modities, or require the ships bringing them to sail so many times round the world before landing at our ports. In either of these ways precisely the same pro- tective effect could be secured as by import duties, and in cases where duties secure full protection by prevent- ing importation, such methods would involve no more waste. Or, instead of indirectly encouraging domestic producers by levying duties on foreign goods, wenight directly encourage them by paying them bounties. As a means of encouraging domestic industry the bounty has over the protective system all the advan- tages that the system of paying public officers fixed salaries has over the system prevailing in some countries, and in some instances in our own, of letting them make what they can. As by paying fixed salaries we can get officials at such places and to perform such functions as we wish, while under the make-what-you- can system they can only be got at places and in ca- pacities that will enable them to pay themselves, so do bounties permit the encouragement of any industry, while protection permits only the encouragement of the comparatively few industries with which imported commodities compete. As salaries enable us to know what we are paying, to proportion the rewards of different offices to their respective dignity, responsibility and arduousness, while make-what-you-can may give to one official much more than is necessary, and to others not enough, so do bounties enable us to see and to fix the encouragement to each industry, while the protect- ive system leaves the public in the dark and makes the encouragement to each industry almost a matter of chance. And as salaries impose on the people much lighter and more fairly apportioned burdens than does TARIFFS FOR PROTECTION. 91 the make-what-you-can system, so is the difference be- tween bounties and protection. To illustrate the working of the two systems, let it be assumed desirable to encourage aerial navigation at public expense. Under the bounty system we should offer premiums for the building and successful operation of air ships. Under the protective system we should impose deterrent taxes on all existing methods of trans- portation. In the one case we should have nothing to pay till we got what we wanted, and would then pay a definite sum which would fall on individuals and locali- ties in general taxes. But in the other case we should have to suffer all the inconveniences of obstructed transportation before we got air ships, and whether we got them or not; and while these obstructions would, in some cases, more seriously affect individuals, busi- nesses and localities than in others, we should never be able to tell how much they distorted industry and cost the people, or how much they stimulated the invention and building of air ships. In the one case, moreover, after aerial navigation had proved successful, and the stipulated bounties had been paid, the air-ship men would hardly have the audacity to ask for more bounties, and would not be likely to get them if they did. In the other case, the public would have grown accustomed to the taxes on surface transportation, while the air-ship proprietors, if they had not convinced themselves that these taxes were necessary to the con- tinued prosperity of aerial navigation, could readily pretend so, and would have, in opposing their repeal, the advantage of that inertia which tends to the con- tinuance of anything that is. The superiority of the bounty system over the pro- 92 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. tective system for the encouragement of any single in. dustry is very great; but it becomes greater as the number of industries to be encouraged is increased. When we encourage an industry by a bounty we do not discourage any other industry, except as the neces. sary increase in general taxation may have a discour- aging effect. But when to encourage one industry we raise the price of its products by a protective duty, we at the same time produce a directly injurious effect upon other industries that use those products. So complicated has production become, so intimate are the relations between industries, and in so many forms do the products of one industry enter into the materials or processes of others, that what will be the effect of a single protective duty it is hard for an expert to say. But when it comes to encouraging not one nor a dozen, but a thousand different industries, it is impossible for human intelligence to trace the multifarious effects of raising the prices of so many products. The people cannot tell what such a system costs them, nor in most cases can even those who are supposed to be its bene- ficiaries really tell how their gains under it compare with their losses from it. The “drawback” system is an attempt to prevent, so far as exports are concerned, the discouragement to which the protection of one industry subjects others. Draw- backs are bounties paid on exports of domestic goods to an amount which it is calculated will compensate for the addition a duty on material has made to their cost. But drawbacks not only leave home prices undimin- ished, but while fruitful of fraud, can only in small part prevent the discouragement of exports, since it is only on goods into which dutiable commodities have TARIFFs FOR PROTECTION. 98 entered in large proportion and obvious ways that drawbacks are allowed, or that it is worth the while of the exporter to attempt to collect them. In 1884, for instance, the United States paid out a larger sum in drawbacks on copper than was received in duties on copper, yet it is certain that very many exports into which copper entered, and which were therefore en- hanced in cost by the duty, got no drawback what- ever. And so of drawbacks on refined sugar, for which we are paying a sum greatly in excess of the duties collected on the raw sugar, though many of our ex- ports, such as those of condensed milk, syrups and pre: served fruits, are much curtailed by these duties. The substitution of bounties for protection in en- couraging industry would do away with the necessity for such inefficient, fraud-provoking, and back-action devices. Under the bounty system prices would not be raised, except as affected by general taxation. Each encouraged producer would know in dollars and cents how much encouragement he got, and the people at large would know how much they paid. In short, all and even more than protection can do to encourage home industries can be done more cheaply and more certainly by bounties. It is sometimes asserted, as one of the advantages of tariff duties, that they fall on the producers of im- ported goods, and are thus paid by foreigners. This assertion contains a Scintilla of truth. An import duty on a commodity of which the production is a closely controlled foreign monopoly may in some cases fall in part or in whole upon the foreign producer. For instance, let us say that a foreign house or combi- nation has a monopoly in the production of a certain 94 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. article. Within the limits of cost on the one hand and the highest rate at which any can be sold on the other, the price of such article can be fixed by the producers, who will naturally fix it at the point they conclude will give the largest aggregate profits. If we impose an import duty on such an article they may prefer to reduce their profit on what they sell to this country rather than have the sale diminished by the addition of the duty to the price. In such case the duty will fall upon them. Or, again, let us suppose a Canadian farmer so situ- ated that the only market in which he can conveni- ently sell his wheat is on the American side. Wheat being a commodity of which our home production not merely supplies home demands, but leaves a surplus for export, the duty on wheat does not add to price, and the Canadian farmer so exceptionally situated that he must send wheat to this side although there is no general demand for Canadian wheat, cannot get back in enhanced price the duty he must pay. The two classes represented by these instances sug- gest all the cases in which import duties fall on for- eign producers.” Such cases, too unimportant to be * In certain cases where an import duty, levied in one country on the produce of another, has the effect of reducing price in the exporting country at the expense of rent, it may, in Some part, fall upon foreign land-owners. John Stuart Mill (Chap. III., Book V., Political Economy), further maintains that taxes on imports fall in part, not on the foreign producer of whom we buy, but on the foreign consumer to whom we sell—since they increase the cost of products we export. But this is only to say that the injury which we do ourselves by protection must in some part fall upon those with whom we trade. And even if import duties do, in such ways, Somewhat increase the cost to foreigners of what they get from us, TARIFFS FOR PROTECTION. 95 considered in any estimates of national revenue, are only the rare exceptions to the general rule that the ability to tax ends with the territorial limits of the taxing power. And it is well for mankind that this is so. If it were possible for the government of one country, by any system of taxation, to compel the peo- ple of other countries to pay its expenses, the world would soon be taxed into barbarism. But the possibility of exceptional cases in which im- port duties may in part or in whole fall on foreign producers, instead of domestic consumers, has in it, even for those who would gladly tax “foreigners,” no shadow of a recommendation for protection. For it will be noticed that the cases in which an import duty falls on foreign producers, are cases in which it can afford no encouragement to home producers. An . import duty can only fall on foreign producers when its payment does not add to price ; while the only and thus, in some degree, compel them to share our loss, yet they also handicap us when we come into competition with them. Thus, assuming that our tariff upon imports may at times, to some slight extent, have increased the price which English consumers have had to pay for our cotton, wheat or oil, the increased cost of production in the United States has certainly operated far more strongly to give English producers an advantage over American pro- ducers in markets in which they compete, and to enable England to take the lion's share of the Ocean-borne commerce of the world. The minute tracing of the actions and reactions of taxation upon international trade is, however, more a matter of theo- retical nicety than of practical interest, since the general conclu- sion will be that stated in the text, that while we cannot injure ourselves without injuring others, the taxing power of a Govern- ment is substantially restricted to its territorial limit. The clearest exception to this is in the case of export duties on articles of which the country levying the export duty has a monopoly, as Brazil has of India-rubber and Cuba of the Havana tobacco. 96 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. possible way in which an import duty can encourage home producers is by adding to price. It is sometimes said that protection does not in- crease prices. It is sufficient answer to ask, how then can it encourage? To say that a protective duty en- courages the home producer without raising prices, is to say that it encourages him without doing anything for him. Wherever beneath this assertion, as regard- less of fact as it is of theory, there is any glimmering of reason, it is either in the notion that protective duties do not permanently add to prices, because they bring about such a competition between home pro- ducers as finally carries prices down to the previous level; or else in a confused idea that it would be an advantage to home producers to be secured the whole ... home market, even if at no higher prices. But as to the first, the only way in which a pro- tective duty can increase home competition in the pro- duction of any commodity is by so increasing prices as to attract producers to the industry by the superior profits to be obtained. This competition, when free to operate, ultimately reduces profits to the general level.” But this is not to say that it reduces prices to what they would be without the duty. The profits of Louisiana sugar growing are now, doubtless, Lo larger than in other occupations involving equal risks, but the duty on sugar does make the price of sugar very much higher in the United States than it is in England, where there is no duty upon it. And even where there is no reason in natural or social conditions why a commodity should not be produced as cheaply as in any foreign * The effect of protection upon profits in the protected industries will be more fully examined in Chapter XVII, --" TARIFES FOR PROTECTION. ' *r 97 country, the effect of the net-work of duties, of which the particular duty is but a part, is to increase the cost of production, and thus, though profits may fall, to keep prices above the point of free importation. Did the price of a protected article fall to the point at which the foreign product could not be imported were there no duty, the duty would cease to protect, since the foreign product would not be imported if it were abolished, and the producers for whose protection it was imposed would cease to care for its retention. In what instance has this been the case? Are any of our protected in- dustries less clamorous for protection now than they were forty years ago? $ As to the second notion, it is to be observed that the only way in which a protective duty can give the home market to home producers is by increasing the price at which foreign products can be sold in it. Not merely does this increase in the price of foreign products compel an increase in the price of domestic products into which they enter, but the shutting out of foreign products must increase the price of similar domestic products. For it is only where prices are fixed by the will of the producer that increase or decrease in supply does not result in increase or decrease of price. Thus, while the newspaper business is not a monopoly, the publication of each individual paper is, and its price is fixed by the publisher. A publisher may, and in most cases will, prefer increased circulation to increased prices. And if competition were to be lessened, or even cut off, as, for instance, by imposing a stamp duty on, or pro- hibiting the publication of all the newspapers of New York save one, it would not necessarily follow that the price of that paper would be increased. But the 9 98 ºr PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. prices of the great mass of commodities, and especially the great mass of commodities which are exported and imported, are regulated by competition. They are not fixed by the will of producers, but by the relative intensity of supply and demand, which are brought to an equation in price by what Adam Smith called “the higgling of the market,” and hence any lessening of supply caused by the shutting out of importations will at once increase prices. In short, the protective system is simply a system of encouraging certain industries by enabling those carry- ing them on to obtain higher prices for the goods they produce. It is a clumsy and extravagant mode of giv- ing encouragement that could be given much better and at much less cost by bounties or subsidies. If it be wise to “encourage” American industries, and this we have yet to examine, the best way of doing so would be to abolish our tariff entirely and to pay bounties from funds obtained by direct taxation. In this way the cost could be distributed with some ap- proach to fairness, and the citizen who is worth a million times more than another could have the satis- faction of contributing a million times as much to the encouragement of American industry. I do not forget that, from the bounties given in the colonial days for the killing of noxious animals to the subsidies granted to the Pacific railroads, experience has shown that the bounty system inevitably leads to fraud and begets corruption, while but poorly accom- plishing the ends sought by it. But these evils are in- separable from any method of “encouragement,” and attach to the protective more than to the bounty sys- tem, because its operations are not so clear. If pro g TARIFFS FOR PROTECTION. 99 tection has been preferred to bounties it is not that it is a better means of encouragement, but for the same reason that indirect has been preferred to direct taxa- tion—because the people do not so readily realize what is being done. Where a grant of a hundred thousand dollars directly from the treasury would raise an out- cry, the imposition of a duty which will enable the appropriation of millions in higher prices excites no comment. Where bounties have been given by our States for the establishment of new industries they have been comparatively small sums, given in a single payment or in a subsidy for a definite term of years. Although the people have in some cases been willing thus to pay bounties to a small extent and for a short time, in no case have they consented to regard them as a settled thing, and to keep on paying them year after year. But protective duties once imposed, the pro- tected industry has always been as clamorous for the eontinuance of protection as it was in the beginning for the grant of it. And the people not being so con- scious of the payment have permitted it to go on. It is often said by protectionists that free trade is right in theory but wrong in practice. Whatever may be meant by such phrases they involve a contradiction in terms, since a theory that will not agree with facts must be false. But without inquiring into the validity of the protective theory it is clear that no such tariff as it proposes ever has been or ever can be made. The theory of free trade may be carried into practice to the point of ideal perfection. For to secure free trade we have only to abolish restrictions. But to carry the theory of protection into practice some articles must be taxed and others left untaxed, and, as to the 100 - PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. articles taxed, different rates of duty must be imposed. And as the protection given to any industry may be neutralized by protection that enhances the price of its materials, careful discrimination is required, for there are very few articles that can be deemed finished products in relation to all their uses. The finished products of some industries are the materials or tools of other industries. Thus, while the protection of any industry is useless unless sufficient to produce the desired effect, too much protection is likely, even from a protective standpoint, to do harm. s It is not merely that the ideal perfection with which the free trade theory may be reduced to practice is im- possible in the case of protection, but that even a rough approximation to the protective theory is impossible. There never has been a protective tariff that satisfied protectionists, and there never can be. Our present tariff, for instance, is admitted by protectionists to be full of the grossest blunders.” It was only adopted be. * For instance, to cite only one case, the last Tariff Act, which went into effect in July, 1883, raised the duty on the fabric used in the manufacture of ruching and rufflings from 35 to 125 per cent., while leaving the duty of the finished article at 35 per cent. Previous to this, say the manufacturers of these goods, in a memorial addressed to the Secretary of the Treasury, they not only supplied the American market, but sold hundreds of thou- sands of dollars’ worth every year to Canada, the West Indies and other countries, the labor-saving machinery which they had in use giving them an advantage which, in spite of the 35 per cent. tax on their material, enabled them to successfully compete with European factories. But the 125 per cent. duty has not only cut off this export trade completely, but has led to such an importation of British goods that, as the memorial declares, thousands of hands have lost their employment, and three-fourths of the manufacturers engaged in the business have been utterly ruined. This, of course, TARIFF's For PROTECTION. 101 cause, after a long wrangle, it was found impossible to agree upon a better one, and it is only maintained and defended because any attempt to amend it would begin a scramble out of which no one can tell what sort of a tariff would come. This has been the case with every former tariff, and must be the case with every future tariff. To make a protective tariff that would even roughly accord with the protective theory would require in the first place a minute knowledge of all trade and indus- try, and of the manner in which an effect produced on one industry would act and react on others. This no king, congress or parliament ever can have. But, fur- ther than this, absolute disinterestedness is required, for the fixing of protective duties is simply the distribution of pecuniary favors among a crowd of greedy appli- cants. And even were it possible to obtain for the making of a protective tariff a body of men themselves disinterested and incapable of yielding to bribery, to threats, to friendship or to flattery, they would have to be more than human not to be dazed by the clamor and misled by the representations of selfish interests, The making of a tariff, instead of being, as the pro- tective theory requires, a careful consideration of the circumstances and needs of each industry, is in prac- tice simply a great “grab" in which the retained ad- vocates of selfish interests bully and beg, bribe and log- roll, in the endeavor to get the largest possible pro- tection for themselves without regard for other interests or for the general good. The result is, and always was not intended by Congress. The ruffling industry is only one of the many minor industries that were thrown down and trampled upon in the last tariff scramble, I02 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. must be, the enactment of a tariff which resembles the theoretical protectionist's idea of what a protective tariff should be about as closely as a bucketful of paint thrown against a wall resembles the fresco of a Raphael. But this is not all. After a tariff has been enacted, come the interpretations and decisions of treasury offi- cials and courts to unmake and re-make it,” and duties are raised or lowered by a printer's placing of a comma or by arbitrary constructions, frequently open to grave suspicion, and which no one can foresee, so that, as Horace Greeley naively says (Political Economy, p. 183): “The longer a tariff continues the more weak spots are found, the more holes are picked in it, until at last, through the influence of successive evasions, constructions, decisions, its very father could not discern its original features in the transformed bantling that has quietly taken its place.” Under the bounty system, bad as it is, we can come much nearer to doing what we want to, and to know- ing what we have done. * The Secretary of the Treasury states that there are now (Feb- ruary, 1886) over 2,300 tariff cases pending in the Southern Dis- trict of New York alone. CELAPTER X. THE ENCOURAGEMENT OF INDUSTRY. WITHOUT questioning the end sought by them we have seen that protective tariffs are to be condemned as a means. Let us now consider their end—the en- couragement of home industry. There can be no difference of opinion as to what encouragement means. To encourage an industry in the protective sense is to secure to those carrying it on larger profits than they could of themselves obtain. Only so far and so long as it does this can any protec- tion encourage an industry. But when we ask what the industries are that pro- tection proposes to encourage we find a wide difference. Those whom American protectionists have regarded as their ablest advocates have asked protection for the encouragement of “infant industries"—describing the protective system as a means for establishing new in- dustries in countries to which they are adapted.* They * “Whoever will consult Alexander Hamilton's Report on Man- ufactures, the writings of Matthew Carey, Hezekiah Niles and their compeers, with the speeches of Henry Clay, Thomas Newton, James Tod, Walter Forward, Rollin C. Mallary, and other forensic champions of protection, with the messages of our earlier Presidents, of Governors Simon Snyder, George Clinton, Daniel D. Tompkins, De Witt Clinton, etc., cannot fail to note that they champion not the maintenance, but the creation of home manufactures.”—HoRACE GREELEY, Political Economy, p. 34. 104 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. have scouted the idea of attempting to encourage all industry, and declared the encouragement of industries not adapted to a country, or already established, or for a time longer than necessary for their establishment, to be waste and robbery. As it is now popularly ad- vocated and practically applied in the United States the aim of protection, however, is not the encourage- ment of “infant industries” but the encouragement of “home industry”—that is to say, of all home industries. And what has proved true in our case is generally true. Wherever protection is once begun, the imposition of duties never stops until every home industry of any political strength that can be protected by tariff gets Some encouragement. It is only in new countries and in the beginnings of the system that the encourage- ment of infant industries can be presented as the sole end of protection. European protectionists can hardly ask protection, on the ground of their infancy, for in- dustries that have been carried on since the time of the Romans. And in the United States to ask now the en- couragement of such giants as our iron, steel and textile industries as a means for their establishment would, after all these years of high tariffs, be manifestly absurd. We have thus two distinct propositions to examine— the proposition that new and desirable industries should be encouraged, which still figures in the apolo- getics of protection, and the proposition popularly urged and which our protectionist legislation attempts to carry into effect—that home industry should be encouraged. As an abstract proposition it is not, I think, to be denied that there may be industries to which temporary THE ENCOURAGEMENT OF INDUSTRY. 105 encouragement might profitably be extended. Indus- tries capable, in their development, of much public benefit have often to struggle under great disadvan- tages in their beginnings, and their development might sometimes be beneficially hastened by judicious en- couragement. But there are insuperable difficulties in the way of discovering what industries would repay encouragement. There are, doubtless, in every con- siderable community some men of exceptional powers who, if provided at public expense with an assured living and left free to investigate, to invent, or to think, would make to the public most valuable returns. But it is certain that, under any system yet devised, such livings, if instituted, would not be filled by men of this kind; but by the pushing and influential, by flatterers and dependents of those in power or by respectable nonentities. The very men who would give a good return in such places would, by virtue of their qualities, be the last to get them. º So it is with the encouragement of struggling in- dustries. All experience shows that the policy of en- couragement, once begun, leads to a scramble in which it is the strong, not the weak; the unscrupulous, not the deserving, that succeed. What are really infant industries have no more chance in the struggle for governmental encouragement than infant pigs have with full grown swine about a meal tub. Not merely is the encouragement likely to go to industries that do not need it, but it is likely to go to industries that can only be maintained in this way, and thus to cause absolute loss to the community by diverting labor and capital from remunerative industries. On the whole, the ability of any industry to establish and sustain 106 : PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. itself in a free field is the measure of its public utility, and that “struggle for existence” which drives out un- profitable industries is the best means of determining what industries are needed under existing conditions and what are not. Even promising industries are more apt to be demoralized and stunted than to be aided in healthy growth by encouragement that gives them what they do not earn, just as a young man is more likely to be injured than benefited by being left a fortune. The very difficulties with which new industries must con- tend not merely serve to determine which are really needed, but also serve to adapt them to surrounding conditions and to develop improvements and inventions that under more prosperous circumstances would never be sought for. Thus, while it may be abstractly true that there are industries that it would be wise to encourage, the only safe course is to give to all “a fair field and no favor.” Where there is a conscious need for the making of Some invention or for the establishment of some in- dustry which, though of public utility, would not be commercially profitable, the best way to encourage it is to offer a bounty conditional upon success. Nothing could better show the futility of attempting to make industries self-supporting by tariff than the confessed inability of the industries that we have so long encouraged to stand alone. In the early days of the American Republic, when the friends of pro- tection were trying to ingraft it upon the Federal revenue system, protection was asked, not for the main- tenance of American industry, but for the establish- ment of “infant industries,” which, it was asserted, would, if encouraged for a few years, be able to take THE ENCOURAGEMENT OF INDUSTRY. lū7 care of themselves. The infant boys and girls of that time have grown to maturity, become old men and women, and with rare exceptions have passed away. The nation then fringing the Atlantic seaboard has ex- tended across the continent, and instead of four million now numbers nearly sixty million people. But the “infant industries,” for which a little temporary pro- tection was then timidly asked, are still infants in their desire for encouragement. Though they have grown mightily they claim the benefits of the “Baby Act” all the more lustily, declaring that if they cannot have far higher protection than at the beginning they dreamed of asking they must perish outright. When United States Senator Broderick, shot by Chief-Justice Terry in a duel, died without making a will, a Dublin man wrote to the editor of a San Fran- cisco newspaper claiming to be next of kin. He gave the date of his birth, which showed him forty-seven years of age, and wound up by adjuring the editor to help a poor orphan, who had lost both father and mother. The “infant industry” argument nowadays always reminds me of that orphan. Protectionist writers have not yet given up the “in- fant industry” plea, for it is the only ground on which with any semblance of reason protection can be asked; but in the face of the facts they have extended the time in which it is averred that protection can establish an infant industry. The American people used to be told that moderate duties for a few years would enable the protected industries to stand alone and defy foreign competition. But in the latest edition of his Political Economy (p. 233), Professor Thompson, of the Univer- sity of Pennsylvania, tells us that “it will ordinarily 108 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. take the lifetime of two generations to acclimatize thoroughly a new manufacture, and to bring the native production up to the native demand.” When we are told that two generations should tax themselves to establish an industry for the third, well may we ask, “What has posterity ever done for us?” Yet even this promise is not borne out by facts. In- dustries that we have been, protecting for more than two generations, now need, according to protectionists, more protection than ever. The popular plea for protection in the United States to-day is not, however, the encouragement of infant industries, but the encouragement of home industry, that is, all home industry. Now it is manifestly impossible for a protective tariff to encourage all home industry. Duties upon com- modities entirely produced at home can, of course, have no effect in encouraging any home industry. It is only when imposed upon commodities partly im- ported and partly produced at home, or entirely im- ported, yet capable of being produced at home, that duties can in any way encourage an industry. No tariff which the United States imposed could, for in- stance, encourage the growth of grain or cotton, the raising of cattle, the production of coal oil or the mining of gold or silver; for instead of importing these things we not only supply ourselves, but have a surplus which we export. Nor could any import duty encourage any of the many industries which must be carried on where needed, such as building, horseshoeing, the printing of newspapers, and so on. Since these industries that cannot be protected constitute by far the larger part of the industries of every country, the utmost that by a THE ENCOURAGEMENT OF INDUSTRY. 109 protective tariff can be attempted is the encouragement of only a few of the total industries of a country. Yet in spite of this obvious fact, protection is never urged for the encouragement of the industries that alone can profit by a tariff. That would be to admit that to some it gave special advantages over others, and so in the popular pleas that are made for it pro- tection is urged for the encouragement of all industry. If we ask how this can be, we are told that the tariff encourages the protected industries, and then the pro- tected industries encourage the unprotected industries; that protection builds up the factory and iron furnace, and the factory and iron furnace create a demand for the farmer's productions. Imagine a village of say a hundred voters. Imagine two of these villagers to make such a proposition as this: “We are desirous, fellow-citizens, of seeing you more prosperous and to that end propose this plan: Give us the privilege of collecting a tax of five cents a day from every one in the village. No one will feel the tax much, for even to a man with a wife and eight children it will only come to the paltry sum of fifty cents a day. Yet this slight tax will give our village two rich citizens who can afford to spend money. We will at once begin to live in commensurate style. We . will enlarge our houses and improve our grounds, set up carriages, hire servants, give parties and buy much more freely at the stores. This will make trade brisk and cause a greater demand for labor. This, in turn, will create a greater demand for agricultural produc- tions, which will enable the neighboring farmers to make a greater demand for store goods and the labor of mechanics. Thus shall we all become prosperous.” IO L10 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. There is in no country under the sun a village in which the people would listen to such a proposition. Yet it is every whit as plausible as the doctrine that encouraging some industries encourages all industries. The only way in which we could even attempt to encourage all industry would be by the bounty or sub- sidy system. Were we to substitute bounties for duties as a means of encouraging industry it would not only become possible for us to encourage other industries than those now encouraged by tariff, but we should be forced to do so, for it is not in human nature that the farmers, the stock raisers, the builders, the newspaper publishers and so on, would consent to the payment of bounties to other industries without demanding them for their own. Nor could we consistently stop until every species of industry, to that of the bootblack or rag-picker, was subsidized. Yet evidently the result of such encouragement of each would be the discourage- ment of all. For as there could only be distributed what was raised by taxation, less the cost of collection, no one could get back in subsidies, were there any fairness in their distribution, as much as he would be called upon to pay in taxes. This practical reduction to absurdity is not possible under the protective system, because only a small part of the industries of a country can thus be “encour- aged,” while the cost of the encouragement is concealed in prices and is not realized by the masses. The tax- gatherer does not demand from each citizen a contribu- tion to the encouragement of the favored few. He sits down in a custom house and by taxing imports enables the favored producer to collect “encourage- ment” from his fellow-citizens in higher prices. Yet THE ENCOURAGEMENT OF INDUSTRY. 111 it is as true of encouragement by tariff as of encourage- ment by bounties that the gain to some involves loss to others, and since encouragement by tariff involves far more cost and waste than encouragement by bounty, the proportion which the loss bears to the gain must be greater. However protection may affect special forms of industry it must necessarily diminish the total return to industry—first, by the waste inseparable from encour- agement by tariff, and, second, by the loss due to the transfer of capital and labor from occupations which they would choose for themselves to less profitable occupa- tions which they must be bribed to engage in. If we do not see this without reflection, it is because our at- tention is engaged with but a part of the effects of pro- tection. We see the large smelting works and the mas- sive mill without realizing that the same taxes which we are told have built them up have made more costly every nail driven and every needleful of thread used throughout the whole country. Our imaginations are affected as were those of the first Europeans who vis- ited India, and who, impressed by the profusion and magnificence of the Rajahs, but not noticing the abject poverty of the masses, mistook for the richest country in the world what is really the poorest. But reflection will show that the claim popularly made for protection, that it encourages home industry (i. e., all home industry), can be true only in one sense —the sense in which Pharaoh encouraged Hebrew in- dustry when he compelled the making of bricks with- out straw. Protective tariffs make more work, in the sense in which the spilling of grease over her kitchen floor makes more work for the housewife, or as a rain that wets his hay makes more work for the farmer. -- CELAPTER XI. TEIE EIOME MARKET AND HOME TRADE. |WE should keep our own market for our own producers, seems by many to be regarded as the same kind of a proposition as, We should keep our own pasture for our own cows, whereas, in truth, it is such a proposition as, We should keep our own appetites for our own cookery, or TWe should keep our own transportation for our own legs. What is this home market from which protection- ists tell us we should so carefully exclude foreign produce? Is it not the home demand—the demand for the satisfaction of our own wants? Hence the proposition that we should keep our home market for home producers is simply the proposition that we should keep our own wants for our own powers of satisfying them. In short, to reduce it to the individual, it is that we ought not to eat a meal cooked by another, since that would deprive us of the pleasure of cooking a meal for ourselves, or make any use of horses or railways because that would deprive our legs of em- ployment. A short time ago English protectionists (for pro- tection is far from dead in England) were censuring the government for having given large orders for powder to German instead of to English producers. It turned out that the Germans were making a new powder called “cocoa,” which in heavy guns gives great THE HOME MARKET AND HOME TRADE. 113 velocity with low pressure, and with which all the continental powers had at once provided themselves. Had the English government refused to buy from foreign producers, English ships, in the event of war, which then seemed imminent, would have been placed at a serious disadvantage. Now, just as the policy of reserving home markets for home producers would in war put a country which should adhere to it at a great disadvantage—even to the extent, if fully carried out, of restricting the country that does not produce coal to the use of sailing ships, and compelling the country that yields no iron to fight with bows and arrows — so in all the vocations of peace does this policy involve like disadvantages. To strictly reserve our home market for home producers would be to exclude ourselves from participation in the advantages which natural conditions or the peculiar skill of their people give to other countries. If bananas will not grow at home we must not eat bananas. If india rubber is not a home production we must not avail ourselves of its thousand uses. If salt can only be obtained in our country by evaporating sea water we must continue so to obtain our salt, although in other countries nature has performed this work and provided already-crystallized salt in quantities sufficient not only for their people, but for us too. Because we cannot grow the cinchona tree we must shake with ague and die from malarial diseases, or must writhe in agony under the oculist's knife because the beneficent drug that gives local insensibility is not a home pro- duction. And so with all those products in which the peculiar development of industry has enabled the people of various countries to excel. To reserve our 114 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. home market to home production is to limit the world from which our wants may be supplied to the bounds of our own country, how little soever that may be. And to place any restrictions upon importations is, in so far as they operate, to deprive ourselves of oppor- tunities to satisfy our wants. It may be to the interest of a shopkeeper that the people of his neighborhood should be prohibited from buying from any one but him, so that they must take such goods as he chooses to keep, at such prices as he chooses to charge, but who would contend that this was to the general advantage 7 It might be to the interest of gas companies to restrict the number and size of windows, but hardly to the interest of a com- munity. Broken limbs bring fees to surgeons, but would it profit a municipality to prohibit the re- moval of ice from sidewalks in order to encourage surgery 7 Yet it is in such ways that protective tariffs act. Economically, what difference is there between restricting the importation of iron to benefit iron producers and restricting sanitary improvements to benefit undertakers. To attempt to make a nation prosperous by pre- venting it from buying from other nations is as ab- surd as it would be to attempt to make a man pros- perous by preventing him from buying from other men. How this operates in the case of the individual we can see from that practice which, since its applica- tion in the Irish land agitation, has come to be called “boycotting.” Captain Boycott, upon whom has been thrust the unenviable fame of having his name turned into a verb, was in fact “protected.” He had a pro- tective tariff of the most efficient kind built around him THE HOME MARKET AND HOME TRADE. 115 by a neighborhood decree more effective than act of Parliament. No one would sell him labor, no one would sell him milk or bread or meat or any service or commodity whatever. But instead of growing pros- perous, this much-protected man had to fly from a place where his own market was thus reserved for his own productions. What protectionists ask us to do to ourselves in reserving our home market for home producers, is in kind what the Land Leaguers did to Captain Boycott. They ask us to boycott ourselves. In order to convince us that this would be for our benefit, no little ingenuity has been expended. It is asserted (1) that restrictions on foreign trade are bene- ficial because home trade is more profitable than foreign trade; (2) that even if these restrictions do compel people to pay higher prices for the same commodities, the real cost is no greater, and (3) that even if the cost is greater they get it back again. Strangely enough, the first of these propositions is fortified by the authority of Adam Smith. In Book II., Chapter W., of The Wealth of Nations, occurs this pas- Sage: “The capital which is employed in purchasing in one part of the country in order to sell in another the produce of the industry of that country, generally replaces by every such operation two dis- tinct capitals that had both been employed in the agriculture or manufactures of that country, and thereby enables them to con- tinue that employment. * * * The capital which sends Scotch manufactures to London, and brings back English corn and man- ufactures to Edinburgh, necessarily replaces by every such opera- tion two British capitals which had both been employed in the agriculture or manufactures of Great Britain. “The capital employed in purchasing foreign goods for home con- sumption, when this purchase is made with the produce of domestic industry, replaces, too, by every such operation, two distinct capi- 116 . PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. tals : but one of them only is employed in supporting domestic industry. The capital which sends British goods to Portugal, and brings back Portuguese goods to Great Britain, replaces by every such operation only one British capital. The other is a Portuguese one. Though the returns, therefore, of the foreign trade of con- sumption should be as quick as those of the home trade, the capital employed in it will give but one-half the encouragement to the industry or productive labor of the country.” This astonishing proposition, of which Adam Smith never seemed to see the significance,” is one of the in- consistencies into which he was led by his abandon- ment of the solid ground from which labor is regarded as the prime factor in production for that from which capital is so regarded—a confusion of thought which has ever since befogged political economy. This pass- age is quoted approvingly by protectionist writers, and made by them the basis of assertions even more absurd, if that be possible. Yet the fallacy ought to be seen at a glance. It is of the same nature as the Irishman's division, “Two for you two, and two for me, too,” and de- pends upon the introduction of a term “British,” which includes in its meaning two of the terms previously used, “English " and “Scotch.” If we substitute for * In the next paragraph Adam Smith goes on to carry this propo- sition to an unconscious reductio ad absurdum. He says: “A capital therefore employed in the home trade will sometimes make twelve operations, or be sent out and returned twelve times, before a capital employed in the foreign trade of consumption has made one. If the capitals are equal, therefore, the one will give four-and-twenty times more encouragement and support to the in- dustry of the country than the other.” º This is just such a proposition as that an innkeeper who only permits his guests to stay with him one day can, with equal facili- ties, furnish twelve times as much entertainment to man and beast as can the innkeeper who permits each guest to stay with him twelve days. THE HOME MARKET AND HOME TRADE. 117 the terms used by Adam Smith other terms of the same relation we may obtain, with equal validity, such prop- ositions as this: If Episcopalians trade with Presby- terians, two profits are made by Protestants; whereas when Presbyterians trade with Catholics only one profit goes to Protestants. Therefore, trade between Protes- tants is twice as profitable as trade between Protestanti and Catholics. In Adam Smith's illustration there are two quantities of British goods, one in Edinburgh and one in London. In the domestic trade which he supposes, these two quantities of British goods are exchanged; but if the Scotch goods be sent to Portugal instead of to England and Portuguese goods brought back, only one quantity of British goods is exchanged. There will be only one-half the replacement in Great Britain, but there has been only one-half the displacement. The Edinburgh goods which have been sent away have been replaced with Portuguese goods; but the London goods have not been replaced with anything, because they are still there. In the one case twice the amount of British capital is employed as in the other, and consequently double returns show equal profitableness. The arguments by which it is attempted to prove that it is no hardship to a people to be forced to pay higher prices to home producers for goods they can more cheaply obtain by importation are of no better consistency. The real cost of commodities, it is de- clared, is not to be measured by their price but by the labor needed to produce them, and hence as it is put, though higher wages, interest, taxes, etc., may make it impossible to produce certain things for as low a price in One country as in another, their real cost is no 118 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. greater, if no greater amount of labor is needed for their production, and thus a nation loses nothing by shutting out the cheaper foreign products. The fallacy is in the assumption that equal amounts of labor always produce equal results. A first-class portrait painter may be able to do whitewashing with no more labor than a professional whitewasher, but it would nevertheless be a loss to him to take time in which he might earn the wages of a portrait painter in order to do whitewashing that he might get done for the wages of a whitewasher. Nor would his loss be the less real if he chose to average his income so as to credit himself with as much for whitewashing as for portrait painting. In the same way, it is not the amount of labor required to produce a thing here or there which determines whether it can be more profitably obtained by home production or by importation, but the relation between what the same labor could produce in that and in other employments. This is shown by price. Though as between different times and places the prices of things do not accurately indicate the relative quantity and quality of labor necessary to obtain them, they do in the same time and place. If at any given time, in any given place, a certain commodity cannot be pro- duced for as low a price as it can be imported for, this is not necessarily proof that it would take more labor to produce it in the given place, but it is proof that labor there and then can be more profitably employed. And when industry is diverted from more profitable to less profitable occupations, though the capital and labor so transferred may be compensated by duties or boun- ties, there must be a loss to the people as a whole. Thé argument that the higher prices which the tariff THE HOME MARKET AND HOME TRADE. 119 enables certain home producers to charge involves no loss to those who pay them is thus put by Horace Greeley (Political Economy, p. 150): “I never made any iron, nor had any other than a public, general interest in making any, while I have bought and used many thou- sands of dollars’ worth, in the shape of power presses, engines, boilers, building plates, etc. It is my interest, you say, to have cheap iron. Certainly; but I buy iron, not (ultimately and really) with money, but with the product of my labor—that is, with newspapers; and I can better afford to pay $70 per ton for iron made by men who can and do buy American newspapers than take it for $50 of those who rarely see and never buy one of my products. The money price of the American iron may be higher, but its real cost to me is less than that of the British iron. And my case is that of the great body of American farmers and other producers of exchangeable wealth.” The fallacy is in the assumption that the ability of certain persons to buy American newspapers depends upon their making of iron, whereas, it depends upon their making of something. Newspapers are not bought with iron, nor do newspaper publishers buy iron with newspapers. These transactions are effected with money, which represents no single form of wealth, but value in all forms. If, instead of making iron, the men to whom Mr. Greeley refers had made something else which was exchanged for British iron, Mr. Greeley's purchase of this foreign iron would have been just as truly an exchange of his products for theirs. The $20 per ton additional which the tariff compelled him to pay for iron represented a loss to him which was not a gain to any one else. For on Mr. Greeley's sup- position that the tariff was necessary to give American iron makers the same remuneration such labor could have obtained in other pursuits, its effect was simply to compel the expenditure of $70 worth of labor to obtain * 120 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. what otherwise could have been obtained by $50 worth of labor. To do this was necessarily to lessen the wealth of the country as a whole, and to reduce the fund available for the purchase of newspapers and other articles. This loss is as certain and is of the same kind as if Mr. Greeley had been compelled to employ portrait painters to do whitewashing. The more popular forms of this argument that pro- tection costs nothing, hardly need analysis. If, as is asserted, consumers lose nothing in the higher prices the tariff compels them to pay, because these prices are paid to our own people, then producers would lose nothing if compelled to sell to their fellow-citizens below cost. If workmen are necessarily compensated for high priced goods by the increased demand for their labor, then manufacturers would be compensated for high priced labor by the increased demand for their goods. In short, on this reasoning it makes no dif- ference to anybody whether the price of anything is high or low. When farmers complain of the high charges of railroads, they are making much ado about nothing; and workmen are taking needless trouble when they demand an increase of wages, while employers are quite as foolish when they try to cut wages down. CHAPTER XII. EXPORTS AND IMPORTS, THE aim of protection is to diminish imports, never to diminish exports. On the contrary, the protection- ist habit is to regard exports with favor, and to consider the country which exports most and imports least as doing the most profitable trade. When exports exceed imports there is said to be a favorable balance of trade. When imports exceed exports there is said to be an unfavorable balance of trade. In accordance with his idea all protectionist countries afford every facility for sending things away and fine men for bringing things in. If the things which we thus try to send away and prevent coming in were pests and vermin—things of which all men want as ſittle as possible—this policy would conform to reason. But the things of which ex- ports and imports consist are not things that nature forces on us against our will, and that we have to struggle to rid ourselves of; but things that nature gives only in return for labor, things for which men make exertions and undergo privations. Him who has or can command much of these things we call rich; him who has little we call poor; and when we say that a country increases in wealth we mean that the amount of these things which it contains increases 11 .122 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. faster than its population. What, then, is more repug. nant to reason than the notion that the way to increase the wealth of a country is to promote the sending of such things away and to prevent the bringing of them in? Could there be a queerer inversion of ideas? Should we not think even a dog had lost his senses that Snapped and snarled when given a bone, and wagged his tail when a bone was taken from him? Lawyers may profit by quarrels, doctors by diseases, rat-catchers by the prevalence of vermin, and so it may be to the interest of some of the individuals of a nation to have as much as possible of the good things which we call “goods” sent away, and as little as pos- sible brought in. But protectionists claim that it is for the benefit of a community, as a whole, of a nation considered as one man, to make it easy to send goods away and difficult to bring them in. Let us take a community which we must perforce consider as a whole—that country, with a population of one, which the genius of Defoe has made familiar not only to English readers but to the people of all European tongues. Robinson Crusoe, we will suppose, is still living alone on his island. Let us suppose an American pro- tectionist is the first to break his solitude with the long yearned-for music of human speech. Crusoe's delight we can well imagine. But now that he has been there so long he does not care to leave, the less since his visitor tells him that the island, having now been dis- covered, will often be visited by passing ships. Let us suppose that after having heard Crusoe's story, seen his island, enjoyed such hospitality as he could offer, told him in return of the wonderful changes in the great ExPORTS AND IMPORTS. 123 world, and left him books and papers, our protectionist prepares to depart, but before going seeks to offer some kindly warning of the danger Crusoe will be exposed to from the “deluge of cheap goods” that passing ships will seek to exchange for fruit and goats. Imagine him to tell Crusoe just what protectionists tell larger communities, and to warn him that, unless he takes measures to make it difficult to bring these goods ashore, his industry will be entirely ruined. “In fact,” we may imagine the protectionist to say, “so cheaply can all the things you require be produced abroad that un- less you make it hard to land them I do not see how you will be able to employ your own industry at all.” “Will they give me all these things?” Robinson Crusoe would naturally exclaim. “Do you mean that I shall get all these things for nothing and have no work at all to do? That will suit me completely. I shall rest and read and go fishing for the fun of it." I am not anxious to work if without work I can get the things I want.” “No, I don't quite mean that,” the protectionist would be forced to explain. “They will not give you such things for nothing. They will, of course, want some thing in return. But they will bring you so much and will take away so little that your imports will vastly exceed your exports, and it will soon be difficult for you to find employment for your labor.” “But I don't want to find employment for my labor,” Crusoe would naturally reply. “I did not spend months in digging out my canoe and weeks in tanning and Sewing these goat-skins because I wanted employment for my labor, but because I wanted the things. If I 124 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. can get what I want with less labor, so much the bet. ter, and the more I get and the less I give in the trade you tell me I am to carry on—or, as you phrase it, the more my imports exceed my exports—the easier I can live and the richer Ishall be. I am not afraid of being overwhelmed with goods. The more they bring the better it will suit me.” And so the two might part, for it is certain that no matter how long our protectionist talked the notion that his industry would be ruined by getting things with less labor than before would never frighten Crusoe. * Yet, are these arguments for protection a whit more absurd when addressed to one man living on an island than when addressed to sixty millions living on a con- tinent? What would be true in the case of Robinson Crusoe is true in the case of Brother Jonathan. If foreigners will bring us goods cheaper than we can make them ourselves, we shall be the gainers. The more we get in imports as compared with what we have to give in exports, the better the trade for us. And since foreigners are not liberal enough to give us their productions, but will only let us have them in return for our own productions, how can they ruin our industry? The only way they could ruin our industry would be by bringing us for nothing all we want, so as to save us the necessity for work. If this were possible, ought it seem very dreadful? Consider this matter in another way: To impose taxes on exports in order that home consumers might get the advantage of lower prices would be quite as just as to impose taxes on imports in Order that home producers may get the advantage of higher prices, and * EXPORTS AND IMPORTS. 125 it would be far more conformable to the principle of “the greatest good of the greatest number,” since all of us are consumers, while only a few of us are producers of the things that can be raised in price by taxes on imports. And since the wealthy country is the country that in proportion to its population contains the largest quantities of the things of which exports and imports consist, it would be a far more plausible method of ~ national enrichment to keep such things from going out than to keep them from coming in. Now, supposing it were seriously proposed, as a means for enriching the United States, to put restrictive duties on the carrying out of wealth instead of the bringing in of wealth. It is certain that this would be opposed by protectionists. But what objection could they make? The objection they would make would be in sub- stance this: “The sending away of things in trade from one country to another does not involve a loss to the country from which they are sent, but a gain, since other things of more value are brought back in return for them. Therefore, to place any restriction upon the sending away of things would be to lessen instead of to increase the wealth of a country.” This is true. But to say this, is to say that to restrict exports would be injurious because it would diminish imports? Yet, to diminish imports is the direct aim and effect of pro- tective tariffs. Exports and imports, so far as they are induced by trade, are correlative. Each is the cause and comple- ment of the other, and to impose any restrictions on the one is necessarily to lessen the other. And so far from its being the mark of a profitable commerce that 126 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. the value of a nation's exports exceeds her imports, the reverse of this is true. In a profitable international trade the value of im- ports will always exceed the value of the exports that pay for them, just as in a profitable trading voyage the return cargo must exceed in value the cargo carried out. This is possible to all the nations that are parties to commerce, for in a normal trade commodities are carried from places where they are relatively cheap to places where they are relatively dear, and their value is thus increased by the transportation, so that a cargo arrived at its destination has a higher value than on leaving the port of its exportation. But on the theory that a trade is profitable only when exports exceed im- ports, the only way for all countries to trade profitably with one another would be to carry commodities from places where they are relatively dear to places where they are relatively cheap. An international trade made up of such transactions as the exportation of manufactured ice from the West Indies to New England, and the exportation of hot-house fruits from New England to the West Indies, would enable all countries to export much larger values than they imported. On the same theory the more ships sunk at sea the better for the commercial world. To have all the ships that left each country sunk before they could reach any other country would, upon protectionist principles, be the quickest means of enriching the whole world, since ..all countries could then enjoy the maximum of exports with the minimum of imports. It must, however, be borne in mind that all export- ing and importing are not the exchanging of products. This, however, is a fact which puts in still stronger EXPORTS AND IMPORTS. 127 light, if that be possible, the absurdity of the notion that an excess of exports over imports shows increasing wealth. When Rome was mistress of the world, Sicily, Spain, Africa, Egypt, and Britain exported to Italy far more than they imported from Italy. But so far from this excess of their exports over their imports indicating their enrichment, it indicated their impoverishment. It meant that the wealth produced in the provinces was being drained to Rome in taxes and tribute and rent, for which no return was made. The tribute exacted by Germany from France in 1871 caused a large ex- cess of French exports over imports. So in India the “home charges” of an alien government and the remit- tances of alien officials secure a permanent excess of exports over imports. So the foreign debt which has been fastened upon Egypt requires large amounts of the produce of that country to be sent away for which there is no return in imports. And so for many years the exports from Ireland have largely exceeded the imports into Ireland, owing to the rent drain of ab- sentee landlords. The Irish landlords who live abroad do not directly draw produce for their rent, nor yet do they draw money. Irish cattle, hogs, sheep, butter, linen and other productions are exported as if in the regular course of trade, but their proceeds instead of coming back to Ireland as imports, are, through the medium of bank and mercantile exchanges, placed to the credit of the absent landlords, and used up by them. This drain of commodities in return for which no com- modities are imported, would be greater yet were it not for the fact that thousands of Irishmen cross the channel every summer to help get in the English harvests, and then return home, and that from those who have perma- 128 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. nently emigrated to other countries there is a constant stream of remittances to relatives left behind.* The last time I crossed to England I sat at the steamer table by two young Englishmen, who drank much champagne and in other ways showed they had plenty of money. As we became acquainted I learned that they were younger sons of English “county families,” graduates of a sort of school which has been established in Iowa for wealthy young English- men who wish to become “gentlemen farmers” or “estate owners” in the United States. Each had got him a considerable tract of new land, had cut it up into farms, erected on each farm a board house and barn, and then rented these farms to tenants for half the crops. They liked America, they said; it was a good country to have an estate in. The land laws were very good, and if a tenant did not pay promptly you could get rid of him without long formality. But they preferred to live in England, and were going back to enjoy their incomes there, having put their affairs in the hands of an agent, to whom the tenants were required to give notice when they wished to reap their * In Dublin in 1882 I several times met the secretary of one of the great banking institutions whose branches ramify through Ire- land. Each time he asked my opinion of the crop prospects in the United States, as though that were uppermost in his mind when- ever he met an American. Finally I said to him, “I suppose poor crops in the United States would be to your advantage, as it would increase the value of the agricultural products that Ireland ex- ports.” “Oh, no ; ” he replied, “we are greatly interested in hav- ing the American crops good. Good crops mean good times, and good times in the United States mean large remittances from the Irish in America to their families at home, and these remittances are more important to business here than the prices we get for our own products.” EXPORTS AND IMPORTS. 129 * * crops, and who saw that the landlord's half was prop- erly rendered. Thus in this case half the crop (less commissions) of certain Iowa farmers must annually be exported without any return in imports. And this tide of exposs for which no imports come back is only commencing to flow. Many Englishmen already own American land by the hundred thousand, and even by the million acres, and are only beginning to draw rent and royalties. Punch recently had a podderous joke, the point of which was that the British House of Lords had much greater landed interests in the United States than in Great Britain. . If not true already, it will not under present conditions be many years before the English aristocracy will draw far larger incomes from their American estates than from their home estates— incomes to supply which we must export without any return in imports.” * The Chicago Tribune of January 25, 1886, contains a long account of the American estates of an Irish landlord, William Scully. This Scully, who was one of the most notorious of the rack-renting and evictimg Irish landlords, owns from 75,000 to 90,000 acres of the richest land in Illinois, besides large tracts in other States. His estates are cut up into farms and rented to ten- ants who are obliged to pay all taxes and make all improvements, and who are not permitted to sell their crops until the rent is paid. A “spy system ’’ is maintained, and tenants are required to doff their hats when they enter the “estate office.” The Tribune de- scribes them as reduced to a condition of absolute serfdom. The houses in which they live are the poorest shanties, consisting gen- erally of a room and a half, and the whole district is described as blighted Scully got most of his land at nominal prices, ranging as low as seventy-five cents per acre. He lives in London, and is said to draw from his American estates a net income of $400,000 a. year, which means, of course, that American produce to that value is exported every year without any imports coming back. The Tribune closes its long account by saying : “Not content with acquiring land himself, Scully has induced a number of his rela- 130 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. In the commerce which goes on between the United States and Europe there are thus other elements than the exchange of productions. The sums borrowed of Europe by the sale of railway and other bonds, the sums paid by Europeans for land in the ºnited States or invested in industrial enterprises here, capital brought by emigrants, what is spent by Europeans traveling here, and some Small amounts of the nature of gifts, legacies, and successions tend to Swell our imports or reduce our exports. On the other hand, not only do we pay in exports to Europe for our imports from Brazil, India, and such countries, but interest on bonds and other obligations, profits on capital invested here, rent for American land owned abroad, remittances from immigrants to relatives at home, property passing by will or inheritance to people abroad, payments for Ocean transportation for- merly carried on by our own vessels but now carried on by foreign vessels, the sums spent by American tourists who every year visit Europe, and by the increas- ing number of rich Americans who live in Europe, all contribute to swell our exports and reduce our imports. The annual balance against us on these accounts is already very large and is steadily growing larger. Were we to prevent importations absolutely we should still have to export largely in order to pay our rents, to meet interest, and to provide for the increasing number of rich Americans who travel or reside abroad. But the fact that our exports must now thus exceed our imports instead of being what protectionists take it for, an evidence of increasing prosperity, is simply the evi- tives to become American landlords, and their system is patterned ~ on his own,” EXPORTS AND IMPORTS. º 131 dence of a drain upon national wealth like that which has so impoverished Ireland. - But this drain is not to be stopped by tariffs. It proceeds from a deeper cause than any tariff can touch, and is but part of a general drift. Our internal com- merce also involves the flow from country to city, and from West to East, of commodities for which there is no return. Our large mine owners, ranch owners, land speculators, and many of our large farmers, live in the great cities. Our small farmers have had in large part to buy their farms on mortgage of men who live in cities to the east of them; the bonds of the national, state, county, and municipal governments are largely so held, as are the stocks and bonds of railway and other com- panies—the result being that the country has to send to the cities, the West to the East, more than is re- turned. This flow is increasing, and, no matter what be our tariff legislation, must continue steadily to increase, for it springs from the most fundamental of Our Social adjustments, that which makes land private property. As the land in Illinois or Iowa, or Oregon, or New Mexico owned by a resident of New York or Boston increases in value, people who live in those States must send more and more of their produce to the New Yorker or Bostonian. They may work hard, but grow relatively poorer; he may not work at all, but grow relatively richer, so that when they need capital for building railroads or any other purpose, they must borrow and pay interest, while he can lend and get interest. The tendency of the time is thus to the ownership of the whole country by residents of cities, and it makes no difference to the people of the country districts whether those cities are in America or Europe. CEIAPTER XIII. CONFUSIONS ARISING FROM THE USE OF MONEY. THERE is no one who in exchanging his own pro- ductions for the productions of another would think that the more he gave and the less he got the better off he would be. Yet to many men nothing seems clearer than that the more of its own productions a nation sends away, and the less of the productions of other nations it receives in return, the more profitable its trade. So widespread is this belief that to-day nearly all civilized nations endeavor to discourage the bring- ing in of the productions of other nations while re- garding with satisfaction the sending away of their OWIO. What is the reason of this? Men are not apt to apply to the transactions of nations principles opposite to those they apply to individual transactions. On the contrary, the natural tendency is to personify nations, and to think and speak of them as actuated by the same motives and governed by the same laws as the human beings of whom they are made up. Nor have we to look far to see that the preposterous notion that a nation gains by exporting and loses by importing actually arises from the application to the commerce between nations of ideas to which individual transac- tions accustom civilized men. What men dispose of to others we term their sales; what they obtain from others we term their purchases. Hence we become CONFUSIONS ARISING FROM THE USE OF MONEY. 133 accustomed to think of exports as sales, and of imports as purchases. And as in daily life we habitually think that the greater the value of a man's sales and the less the value of his purchases the better his business; so, if we do not stop to fix the meaning of the words we use, it seems a matter of course that the more a na- tion exports and the less it imports the richer it will become. It is significant of its origin that such a notion is unknown among savages. Nor could it have arisen among civilized men if they were accustomed to trade as savages do. Not long ago a class of traders called “soap-fat men” used to go from house to house exchang- ing soap for the refuse fat accumulated by housewives. In this petty commerce, carried on in this primitive manner, the habit of thinking that in a profitable trade the value of sales must exceed the value of purchases could never have arisen, it being clearly to the interest of each party that the value of what he sold (or ex- ported) should be as little as possible, and the value of what he bought (or imported) as great as possible. But in civilized society this is only the exceptional form of trade. Buying and selling, as our daily life familiarizes us with them, are not the exchange of commodities for commodities, but the exchange of money for commod- ities, or of commodities for money. It is to confusions of thought growing out of this use of money that we may trace the belief that a nation profits by exporting and loses by importing—a belief to which countless lives and incalculable wealth have been sacrificed in bloody wars, and which to-day moulds the policy of nearly all civilized nations and interposes artificial barriers to the commerce of the World. 12 134 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. The primary form of trade is barter—the exchange of commodities for commodities. But just as when we begin to think and speak of length, weight or bulk, it is necessary to adopt measures or standards by which these qualities can be expressed, so when trade begins there arises a need for some common standard by which the value of different articles can be apprehended. The difficulties attending barter soon lead, also, to the adop- tion by common consent of some commodity as a med- ium of exchange, by means of which he who wishes to exchange a thing for one or more other things is no longer obliged to find some one with exactly reciprocal desires, but is enabled to divide the complete exchange into stages or steps, which can be made with different persons, to the enormous saving of time and trouble. In primitive society, cattle, skins, shells, and many other things have in a rude way fulfilled these func. tions. But the precious metals are so peculiarly adapt- ed to this use that wherever they have become known mankind has been led to adopt them as money. They are at first used by weight, but a great step in advance is taken when they are coined into pieces of definite weight and purity, so that no one who receives them needs to take the trouble of weighing and testing them. As civilization advances, as society becomes more settled and orderly, and exchanges more numerous and regular, gold and silver are gradually superseded as mediums of exchange by credit in various forms. By means of accounts current, one purchase is made to balance another purchase and one debt to cancel an other debt, Individuals or associations of recognized solvency issue bills of exchange, letters of credit, notes and drafts, which largely take the place of coin; banks CONFUSIONS ARISING FROM THE USE OF MONEY. 135 transfer credits between individuals, and clearing-houses . transfer credits between banks, so that immense trans- actions are carried on with a very small actual use of money; and finally, credits of convenient denominations, printed upon paper, and adapted to transference from hand to hand without indorsement or formality, being cheaper and more convenient, take in part or in whole the place of gold or silver in the country where they are issued. * This is, in brief, the history of that labor-saving in- strument which ranges in its forms from the cowries of the African or the warmpum of the red Indian to the bank-note or greenback, and which does so much to facilitate trade that without it civilization would be im- possible. The part which it plays in social life and intercourse is so necessary, its use is so common in thought and speech and actual transaction, that cer- tain confusions with regard to it are apt to grow up. It is not needful to speak of the delusion that interest grows out of the use of money, or that increase of money is increase of wealth, or that paper money can- not properly fulfill its functions unless an equivalent of coin is buried somewhere, but only of such confusions of thought as have a relation to international trade. I was present yesterday when one farmer gave an- other farmer a horse and four pigs for a mare. Both seemed pleased with the transaction, but neither said, “Thank you.” Yet when money is given for any- thing else it is usual for the person who receives the money to say, “Thank you,” or in some other way to indicate that he is more obliged in receiving the money than the other party is in receiving the thing _6. the money is given for. This custom is one of the 136 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. indications of a habit of thought which (although it is clear that a dollar cannot be more valuable than a dollar's worth) attaches the idea of benefit more to the giving of money for commodities than to the giving of commodities for money. The main reason of this I take to be that difficulties of exchange are most felt on the side of reduction to the medium of exchange. To exchange anything for money it is necessary to find some one who wants that par- ticular thing, but, this exchange effected, the exchange of money for other things is generally easier, since all who have anything to exchange are willing to take money for it. This, and the fact that the value of money is more certain and definite than the value of things measured by it, and the further fact that the sale or conversion of commodities into money completes those transactions upon which we usually estimate profit, easily lead us to look upon the getting of money as the object and end of trade, and upon selling as more profitable than buying. Further than this, money, being the medium of ex- change—the thing that can be most quickly and easily exchanged for other things—is, therefore, the most convenient in contingencies. In ruder times, before the organization of credit had reached such devel- opment as now, when the world was cut up into small states constantly warring with each other, when order was less well preserved, property far more insecure and the exhibition of riches often led to extortion; when pirates infested the sea and robbers the land; when fires were frequent and insurance had not been devised; when prisoners were held to ransom and captured cities given up to sack, the contingencies in which it is im. jº *- *- CONFUSIONS ARISING FROM THE USE OF MONEY. 137 portant to have wealth in the form in which it can be most conveniently carried, readily concealed, and speed- ily exchanged, were far more numerous than now, and every one strove to keep some part of his wealth in the precious metals. The peasant buried his savings, the merchant kept his money in his strong box, the miser gloated over his golden hoard and the prince sought to lay up a great treasure for time of sudden need. Thus gold and silver were even more striking symbols of wealth than now, and the habit of thinking of them as the only real wealth was formed. This habit of thought gave ready support to the pro- tective policy. When the growth of commerce made it possible to raise large revenues by indirect taxation, kings and their ministers soon discovered how easily the people could thus be made to pay an amount of taxes that they would have resisted if levied directly. Import taxes were first levied to obtain, revenue, but not only was it found to be exceedingly convenient to tax goods in the seaport towns from whence they were distributed through the country, but the taxation of im- ported goods met with the warm support of such home producers as were thus protected from competition. An interest was thus created in favor of “protection,” which availed itself of national prejudices and popular habits of thought, and a system was by degrees elabo- rated, which for centuries swayed the policy of Euro- pean nations. This system, which Adam Smith attacked under the name of the mercantile system of political economy, regarded nations as merchants competing with each other for the money of the world, and aimed at en- riching a country by bringing into it as much gold and 138 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. - silver as possible, and permitting as little as possible to flow out. To do this it was sought not only to pro- hibit the carrying of precious metals out of the country, but to encourage the domestic production of goods that could be sold abroad, and to throw every obstacle in the way of similar foreign or colonial industries. Not only were heavy import duties or absolute prohibitions placed on such products of foreign industry as might come into competition with home industry, but the ex- ports of such raw materials as foreign industries might require were burdened with export duties or entirely prohibited under savage penalties of death or mutila- tion. Skilled workmen were forbidden to leave the country lest they might teach foreigners their art; do. mestic industries were encouraged by bounties, by patents of monopoly and by the creation of artificial markets—sometimes by premiums paid on exports, and sometimes by laws which compelled the use of their products. One instance of this was the Act of Parliament which required every corpse to be buried in a woolen shroud, a piece of stupidity only paralleled by the laws under which the American people are taxed to bury in underground safes $2,000,000 of coined silver every month, and keep a hundred millions of goldlying idle in the treasury. But to attempt to increase the supply of gold and silver by such methods is both foolish and useless. Though the value of the precious metals is high their utility is low ; their principal use, next to that of money, being in Ostentation. And just as a farmer would become poorer, not richer, by selling his breed- ing stock and seed grain to obtain gold to hoard and silver to put on his table, or as a manufacturer would CONFUSIONS ARISING FROM THE USE OF MONEY. 139 lessen his income by selling a useful machine and keep- ing in his safe the money he got for it, so must a nation lessen its productive power by stimulating its exports or reducing its imports of things that could be pro- ductively used, in order to accumulate gold and silver for which it has no productive use. Such amounts of the precious metals as are needed for use as money will come to every nation that participates in the trade of the world, by virtue of a tendency that sets at naught all endeavors artificially to enhance supply, a tendency as constant as the tendency of water to seek a level. Wherever trade exists all commodities capable of trans- portation tend to flow from wherever their value is . relatively low to wherever their value is relatively high. This tendency is checked by the difficulties of transportation, which vary with different things as their bulk, weight, and liability to injury com- pare with their value. The precious metals do not suffer from transportation, and having (especially gold) little weight and bulk as compared with their value, are so portable that a very slight change in their rela- tive value is sufficient to cause their flow. So easily can they be carried and concealed that legal restrictions, backed by coast guards and custom-house officials, have never been able to prevent them from finding their way out of a country where their value was rela- tively low and into a country where their value was relatively high. The attempts of her despotic monarchs to keep in Spain the precious metals she drew from America were like trying to hold water in a sieve. The effect of artificially increasing the supply of precious metals in any country must be to lower their value as compared with that of other commodities. 140 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. The moment, therefore, that restrictions by which it is attempted to attract and retain the precious metals, begin so to operate as to increase the supply of those metals, a tendency to their outflowing is set up, in- creasing in force as the efforts to attract and retain them become more strenuous. Thus all efforts arti- ficially to increase the gold and silver of a country have had no result save to hamper industry and to make the country that engaged in them poorer instead of richer. This, experience has taught civilized nations, and few of them now make any direct efforts to attract or retain the precious metals, save by uselessly hoarding them in burglar-proof vaults as we do. But the notibn that gold and silver are the only true money, and that as such they have a peculiar value, still underlies protectionist arguments,” and the habit of as. sociating incomes with sales, and expenditure with pur- chases, which is formed in the thought and speech of every-day life, still disposes men to accept a policy which aims at restricting imports by protective tariffs. Being accustomed to measure the profits of business men by the excess of their sales over their purchases, the as- sumption that the exports of a nation are equivalent to the sales of a merchant, and its imports to his pur- * For instance, Professor Thompson writing where and when, save for subsidiary tokens, paper money was exclusively used, and so conscious of its ability to perform all the functions of money that he declares it to be as much superior to coin as the railway is to the stage-coach (Political Economy, p. 152), goes on subsequently (p. 223) to contend that protective duties are necessary to prevent the poorer country being drained of its money by the richer country, thus tacitly assuming that gold and silver alone are money—since neither he nor any one else would pretend that one country could drain another of its paper money. CONFUSIONS ARISING FROM THE USE OF MONEY. 141 chases, leads easily to the conclusion that the greater the amount of exports and the less the amount of im- ports, the more profit a nation gets by its trade.* Yet it only needs attention to see that this assump- tion involves a confusion of ideas. When we say that a merchant is doing a profitable business because his sales exceed his purchases, what we are really thinking of as sales is not the goods he sends out, but the money that we infer he takes in in exchange for them ; what we are really thinking of as purchases is not the goods he takes in, but the money we infer he pays out. We mean, in short, that he is growing richer because his in- come exceeds his out-go. We become so used in ordi- nary affairs to this transposition of terms by inference, that when we think of a nation's exports as its sales and of its imports as its purchases, habit leads us to at- tach to these words the same inferential meaning, and thus unconsciously to give to a word expressive of out- going, the significance of in-coming ; and to a word expressive of in-coming, the significance of out-going. But, manifestly, when we compare the trade of a mer- chant carried on in the usual way with the trade of a nation, it is not the goods that a merchant sells, but the money that he pays out, that is analogous to the ex- ports of a country; not the goods that he buys, but the money he takes in, that is analogous to imports. It is only where the trade of a merchant is carried on by the * A conclusion frequently carried by protectionists to the most ridiculous lengths, as, for instance, in the recent declaration of a Protectionist Senator (Wm. M. Evarts, of New York), that he would be ready for free trade “when protection had so far developed all our industries that the United States could sell in competition with all the world, and at the same time be free from the necessity of buying anything from all the world.” 142 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. exchange of commodities for commodities, that the com- modities he sells are analogous to the exports, and the commodities he buys are analogous to the imports of a nation. And the village dealer who exchanges grocer- ies and dry goods for eggs, poultry, and farm produce, or the Indian trader who exchanges manufactured goods for furs, is manifestly doing the more profitable business the more the value of the commodities he takes in (his imports) exceeds the value of the goods he gives out (his exports). The fact is, that all trade in the last analysis is sim- ply what it is in its primitive form of barter, the ex- change of commodities for commodities. The carrying on of trade by the use of money does not change its es- sential character, but merely permits the various ex- changes of which trade is made up to be divided into parts or steps, and thus more easily effected. When commodities are exchanged for money, but half a full exchange is completed. When a man sells a thing for money it is to use the money in buying some other thing—and it is only as money has this power that any- one wants or will take it. Our common use of the word “money” is largely metaphorical. We speak of a wealthy man as a moneyed man, and in talking of his wealth say that he has so much “money,” whereas the fact probably is, that though he may be worth mil- lions, he never has at any one time more than a few dol- lars, or at most a few hundred dollars, in his possession. His possessions really consist of houses, lands, goods, stocks, or of bonds or other obligations to pay money. The possession of these things we speak of as the pos- session of money because we habitually estimate their value in money. If we habitually estimated value in CONFUSIONS ARISING FROM THE USE OF MONEY. 143 shells, sugar or cattle, we would speak of rich men as having much of these, just as the use of postage stamps as currency at the beginning of our civil war led to speaking of rich men in the Slang of the day, as those who had plenty of “stamps.” And so, when a mer- chant is doing a profitable business, though we speak of him as making or accumulating money, the fact is, save in very rare cases, that he is putting out money as fast as he gets it in. The shrewd business man does not stow away money. On the contrary, with the money he obtains from his sales he hastens to make other pur- chases. If he does not buy commodities for use in his business, or commodities or services for personal gratifi- cation, he buys lands, houses, stocks, bonds, mort- gages, or other things from which he expects a profit- able return. The trade between nations, made up as it is of nu- merous individual transactions which separately are but parts or steps in a complete exchange, is in the aggregate, like the primitive form of trade, the ex- change of commodities for commodities. Money plays no part in international trade, and the world has yet to reach that stage of civilization which will give us in- ternational money. The paper currency which in all civilized nations now constitutes the larger part of their money, is never exported to settle balances, and when gold or silver coin is exported or imported it is as a commodity, and its value is estimated at that of the bullion contained. What each nation imports is paid for in the commodities which it exports, unless received as loans, or investments, or as interest, rent, or tribute. Before commerce had reached its present refinement of division and subdivision this was in many individual 144 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. cases clear enough. A vessel sailed from New York, Philadelphia, or Boston carrying, on account of owner or shipper, a cargo of flour, lumber and staves to the West Indies, where it was sold, and the proceeds in- vested in sugar, rum and molasses, which were brought back, or which, perhaps, were carried to Europe, there sold, and the proceeds invested in European goods, which were brought home. At present the exporter and importer are usually different persons, but the bills of exchange drawn by the one against goods exported are bought by the other, and used to pay for goods im- ported. So far as the country is concerned, the trans- action is the same as though importers and exporters were the same persons, and that imports exceed exports in value is no more proof of a losing trade than that in the old times a trading ship brought home a cargo worth more than that she carried out was proof of an unprofit- able voyage. CEIAPTER XIV. Do HIGH wages NECESSITATE PROTECTION? IN the United States, at present, protection derives strong support from the belief that the products of the lower paid labor of other countries could undersell the products of our higher paid labor if free competition were permitted. This belief not only leads working- men to imagine protection necessary to keep up wages —a matter of which I shall speak hereafter; but it also induces the belief that protection is necessary to the interests of the country at large—a matter which now falls in our way. And further than concerns the tariff this belief has important bearings. It enables employers to persuade themselves that they are serving general interests in re- ducing wages or resisting their increase, and greatly strengthens the opposition to the efforts of working- men to improve their condition, by setting against them a body of opinion that otherwise would be neutral, if not strongly in their favor. This is clearly seen in the case of the eight-hour system. Much of the opposition to this great reform arises from the be- lief that the increase of wages to which such a reduction of working hours would be equivalent, would place the United States at a great disadvantage in production as compared with other countries. It is evident that even those who most vociferously 18 º 146 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. assert that we need a protective tariff on account of our higher standard of wages do not really believe it them- Selves. For if protection be needed against countries of lower wages, it must be most needed against coun- tries of lowest wages and least needed against countries of highest wages. Now, against what country is it that American protectionists most demand protection? If we could have a protective tariff against only one country in the whole world, what country is it that American protectionists would select to be protected against? Unquestionably it is Great Britain. But Great Britain, instead of being the country of lowest wages, is, next to the United States and the British colonies, the country of highest wages. “It is a poor rule that will not work both ways.” If we require a protective tariff because of our high wages, then countries of low wages require free trade—or, at the very least, have nothing to fear from free trade. How is it, then, that we find the protectionists of France, Germany, and other low wage countries pro- testing that their industries will be ruined by the free competition of the higher wage industries of Great Britain and the United States just as vehemently as our protectionists protest that our industries would be ruined if exposed to free &ompetition with the products of the “pauper labor” of Europe? As popularly put, the argument that the country of high wages needs a protective tariff runs in this way: “Wages are higher here than elsewhere; therefore, if the produce of cheaper foreign labor were freely ad- mitted it would drive the produce of our dearer domestic labor out of the market.” But the conclusion does not follow from the premise. To make it valid two inter- DO HIGH WAGES NECESSITATE PROTECTION? 147 mediate propositions must be assumed: First that low wages mean low cost of production; and second, that production is determined solely by cost—or, to put it in another way, that trade being free, everything will be produced where it can be produced at least cost. Let us examine these two propositions separately. If the country of low wages can undersell the coun- try of high wages, how is it that though the American farm hand receives double the wages of the English agricultural laborer, yet American grain undersells English grain? How is it that while the general level of wages is higher here than anywhere else in the world we nevertheless do export the products of our high priced labor to countries of lower priced labor? The protectionist answer is that American grain un- dersells English grain, in spite of the difference of wages, because of our natural advantages for the pro- duction of grain; and that the bulk of our exports con- sists of those crude productions in which wages are not so important an element of cost, since they do not em- body so much labor as the more elaborate productions called manufactures. º: But the first part of this answer is an admission that the rate of wages is not the determining element in the cost of production, and that the country of low wages does not necessarily produce more cheaply than the country of high wages; while, as for the distinction drawn between the cruder and the more elaborate pro- ductions, it is evident that this is founded on the com- parison of such things by bulk or weight, whereas the only measure of embodied labor is value. A pound of cloth embodies more labor than a pound of cotton, but this is not true of a dollar's worth. That a small 148 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. weight of cloth will exchange for a large weight of cot- ton, or a small bulk of watches, for a large bulk of wheat, means simply that equal amounts of labor will produce larger weights or bulks of the one thing than of the other; and in the same way the exportation of a certain value of grain, Ore, stone or timber means the exportation of exactly as much of the produce of labor as would the exportation of the same value of lace or fancy goods. Looking further, we see in every direction that it is not the fact that low priced labor gives advantage in production. If this is the fact how was it that the development of industry in the slave States of the American Union was not more rapid than in the free States? How is it that Mexico, where peon labor can be had for from four to six dollars a month, does not undersell the products of our more highly paid labor? How is it that China and India and Japan are not “flooding the world” with the products of their cheap labor? How is it that England, where labor is better paid than on the Continent, leads the whole of Europe in commerce and manufactures” The truth is, that a low rate of wages does not mean a low cost of pro- duction, but the reverse. The universal and obvious truth is, that the country where wages are highest can produce with the greatest economy, because workmen have there the most intelligence, the most spirit and the most ability; because invention and discovery are there most quickly made and most readily utilized. The great inventions and discoveries which so enormously increase the power of human labor to produce wealth have all been made in countries where wages are com- paratively high. Do HIGH WAGES NECESSITATE PROTECTION? 149 That low wages mean inefficient labor may be seen wherever we look. Half a dozen Bengalese carpenters are needed to do a job that one American carpenter can do in less time. American residents in China get Ser- vants for almost nothing, but find that so many are required that servants cost more than in the United States; yet the Chinese who are largely employed in domestic service in California, and get wages that they would not have dreamed of in China, are efficient workers. Go to High Bridge, and you will see a great engine attended by a few men, exerting the power of thousands of horses in pumping up a small river for the supply of New York city, while on the Nile you may see Egyptian fellahs raising water by buckets and tread wheels. In Mexico, with labor at four or five dollars a month, silver ore has for centuries been carried to the surface on the backs of men who climbed rude ladders, but when silver mining began in Nevada, where labor could not be had for less than five or six dollars a day, steam power was employed. In Russia, where wages are very low, grain is still reaped by the sickle and threshed with the flail or by the hoofs of horses, while in our Western States, where labor is very high as compared with the Russian standard, grain is reaped, threshed and sacked by machinery. , If it were true that equal amounts of labor always produced equal results, then cheap labor might mean cheap production. But this is obviously untrue. The power of human muscle is, indeed, much the same everywhere, and if his wages be sufficient to keep him in good bodily health the poorly paid laborer can, per- haps, exert as much physical force as the highly paid laborer. But the power of human muscles, though 150 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. necessary to all production, is not the primary and ef. ficient force in production. That force is human intel- ligence, and human muscles are merely the agency by which that intelligence makes connection with and takes hold of external things, so as to utilize natural forces and mould matter to conformity with its desires. A race of intelligent pygmies with muscles no stronger than those of the grasshopper could produce far more wealth than a race of stupid giants with muscles as strong as those of the elephant. Now, intelligence varies with the standard of comfort, and the standard of comfort varies with wages. Wherever men are con- demned to a poor, hard and precarious living their mental qualities sink toward the level of the brute. Wherever easier conditions prevail the qualities that raise man above the brute and give him power to mas- ter and compel external nature develope and expand. And so it is that the efficiency of labor is greatest where laborers get the best living and have the most leisure—that is to say, where wages are highest. How then, in the face of these obvious facts, can we account for the prevalence of the belief that the low wage country has an advantage in production over the high wage country’ It cannot be charged to the teach- ing of protection. This is one of the fallacies which protectionism avails itself of, rather than one for which it is responsible. Men do not hold it because they are protectionists, but become protectionists, because they hold it. And it seems to be as firmly held, and On occasion as energetically preached by So-called free traders as by protectionists. Witness the predictions of free trade economists that trades unions, if successful in raising wages and shortening hours, would destroy Do HIGH wagºs NECESSITATE PROTECTION? 151 England's ability to sell her goods to other nations, and the similar objections by so-called free traders to similar movements on the part of workingmen in the United States. The truth is that the notion that low wages give a country an advantage in production is a careless infer- ence from the every-day fact that it is an advantage to an individual producer to obtain labor at low wages. It is true that an individual producer gains an ad- vantage when he can force down the wages of his em- ployees below the ordinary level, or can import laborers who will work for him for less, and that he may by this means be enabled to undersell his competitors, while the employer who continues to pay higher wages than other employers about him will, before long, be driven out of business. But it by no means follows that the country where wages are low can undersell the country where wages are high. For the efficiency of labor, though it may somewhat vary with the particular wages paid, is in greater degree determined by the general standard of comfort and intelligence, and the prevailing habits and methods which grow out of them. When a single employer manages to get labor for less than the rate of wages prevailing around him, the effi- ciency of the labor he gets is still largely fixed by that rate. But a country where the general rate of wages is low does not have a similar advantage over other coun- tries, because there the general efficiency of labor must also be low. The contention that industry can be more largely carried on where wages are low than where wages are high, another form of the same fallacy, may readily be seen to spring from a confusion of thought. For in- 152 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. stance, in the earlier days of California it was often said that the lowering of wages would be a great benefit to the State, as lower wages would enable capitalists to . work deposits of low grade quartz that it would not pay to work at the then existing rate of wages. But it is evident that a mere reduction of wages would not have resulted in the working of poorer mines, since it could not have increased the amount of labor or capital available for the working of mines, and what existed would still have been devoted to the working of the richer in preference to the poorer mines, no matter how much wages were reduced. It might, however, have been said that the effect would be to increase the profits of capital and thus bring in more capital. But, to say nothing of the deterrent effect upon the coming in of labor, a moment's reflection will show that such a re- duction of wages would not add to the profits of capital. It would add to the profits of mine owners, and mines would bring higher prices. Eliminating improvements in methods, or changes in the value of the product, lower wages and the working of poorer mines come, of course, together, but this is not because the lower wages cause the working of poorer mines, but the reverse. As the richer natural opportunities are taken up and pro- duction is forced to devote itself to natural opportuni- ties that will yield less to the same exertion, wages fall. There is, however, no gain to capital; and under such circumstances we do not see interest increase. The gain accrues to those who have possessed themselves of natural opportunities, and what we see is that the value of land increases. The immediate effect of a general reduction of wages in any country would be merely to alter the distribution of wealth. Of the amount produced less would go to the “-w , * * DO HIGH WAGES. NECESSITATE PROTECTION? 153 laborers and more to those who share in the results of production without contributing to it. Some changes in exports and imports would probably follow a general’ reduction of wages, owing to changes in relative de- mand. The working classes, getting less than before, would have to reduce their luxuries, and perhaps live on cheaper food. Other classes, finding their incomes increased, might use more costly food and demand more of the costlier luxuries, and larger numbers of them might go abroad and use up in foreign countries the produce of exports, by which, of course, imports would be diminished. But except as to such changes the foreign commerce of a country would be unaffected. The country as a whole would have no more to sell and could buy no more than before. And in a little while the inevitable effect of the degradation of labor involved in the reduction of wages would begin to tell in the re- duced power of production, and both exports and im- ports would fall off. So if in any country there were a general increase of wages, the immediate effect would only be so to alter the distribution of wealth that more of the aggregate product would go to the laboring classes and less to those who live on the labor of others. The result would be that more of the cheaper luxuries would be called for and less of the more costly luxuries. But pro- ductive power would in nowise be lessened; there would be no less to export than before and no less ability to pay for imports. On the contrary, some of the idle classes would find their incomes so reduced that they would have to go to work and thus increase production, while as soon as an increase in wages began to tell on the habits of the people and on industrial methods productive power would increase. CELAPTER XV. OF ADVANTAGES AND DISADVANTAGES AS REASONS FOR PROTECTION. WE have seen that low wages do not mean low cost of production, and that a high standard of wages, in- stead of putting a country at a disadvantage in produc- tion, is really an advantage. This disposes of the claim that protection is rendered necessary by high wages, by showing the invalidity of the first assumption upon which it is based. But it is worth while to examine the second assumption in this claim—that production is determined by cost, so that a country of less advan- tages cannot produce if the free competition of a coun. try of greater advantages be permitted. For while we are sometimes told that a country needs protection be- cause of great natural advantages that ought to be de- veloped, we are at other times told that protection is needed because of the sparseness of population, the want of capital or machinery or skill, or because of high taxes or a high rate of interest,” or other conditions which, it may be, involve real disadvantage. * The higher rate of interest in the United States than in Great Britain has until recently been one of the stock reasons of American protectionists for demanding a high tariff. We do not hear so much of this now that the rate in New York is as low as in London, if not lower, but we hear no less of the need for protection. It is hardly necessary in this discussion to treat of the nature and law of interest, a subject which I have gone over in Progress and Poverty. It may, ADVANTAGES AND DISADVANTAGES. 155 But without reference to the reality of the alleged ad- vantage or disadvantage, all these special pleas for pro- . tection are met when it is shown, as it can be shown, that whatever be its advantages or disadvantages for production a country can always increase its wealth by foreign trade. If we suppose two countries each of which is, for any reason, at a decided disadvantage in Some branch of production in which the other has a decided advantage, it is evident that the free exchange of commodities be- tween them will be mutually beneficial, by enabling each to make up for its own disadvantage by availing itself of the advantage of the other, just as the blind man and the lame man did in the familiar story. Trade between them will give to each country a greater amount of all things than it could otherwise obtain with the same quantity of labor. Such a case re- sembles that of two workmen, each having as to some things skill superior to the other, and who, by working together, each devoting himself to that part for which he is the better fitted, can accomplish more than twice as much as if each worked separately. But let us suppose two countries, one of which has advantages superior to the other for all the produc- tions of which both are capable. Trade between them being free, would one country do all the exporting and the other all the importing? That, of course, however, be worth while to say that a high rate of interest where it does not proceed from insecurity, is not to be regarded as a disad- vantage, but rather as evidence of the large returns to the active factors of production, labor and capital—returns which diminish as rent rises and the land owner gets a larger share of their produce for permitting labor and capital to work. 156 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. * would be preposterous. Would trade, then, be im- possible? Certainly not. Unless the people of the country of less advantages transferred themselves bod- ily to the country of greater advantages, trade would go on with mutual benefit. The people of the coun- try of greater advantages would import from the coun- try of less advantages those products as to which the difference of advantage between the two countries was least, and would export in return those products as to which the difference was greatest. By this exchange both peoples would gain. The people of the country of poorest advantages would gain by it some part of the advantages of the other country, and the people of the country of greatest advantages would also gain, since, by being saved the necessity of producing the things as to which their advantage was least, they could concentrate their energies upon the production of things in which their advantage was greatest. This case would resemble that of two workmen of different degrees of skill in all parts of their trade, or that of a skilled workman and an unskilled helper. Though the workman might be able to perform all parts of the work in less time than the helper, yet there would be some parts in which the advantage of his superior skill would be less than in others; and as by leaving these to the helper he could devote more time to those parts in which superior skill would be most effective, there would be, as in the former case, a mutual gain in their working together. Thus it is that neither advantages nor disadvantages afford any reason for restraining trade.” Trade is al- * In point of fact there is no country which as to all branches of production can be said to have superior advantages. The con- ADVANTAGES AND DISADVANTAGES. 157 ways to the benefit of both parties. If it were not there would be no disposition to carry it on. And thus we see again the fallacy of the protectionist contention that if it takes no more labor to produceathing in our country than elsewhere, we shall lose nothing by shutting out the foreign product, even though we have to pay a higher price for the home product. The interchange of the products of labor does not depend upon differences of absolute cost, but of comparative cost. Goods may profitably be sent from places where they cost more labor to places where they cost less labor, provided (and this is the only case in which they ever will be so sent) that a still greater difference in labor-cost exists as to other things which the first coun- try desires to obtain. Thus tea, which Horace Greeley was fond of referring to as a production that might advantageously be naturalized in the United States by a heavy duty, could undoubtedly be produced in the United States at less cost of labor than in China, for in transportation to the seaboard, packing, etc., we could save upon Chinese methods. But there are other things, ditions which make one part of the habitable globe better fitted for some productions, unfit it for others, and what is disadvantage for Some kinds of production, is generally advantage for other kinds. Even the lack of rain which makes some parts of the globe useless to man, may, if invention ever succeeds in directly utilizing the power of the Sun's rays, be found to be especially advantageous for certain parts of production. The advantages and disadvantages that come from the varying density of population, the special de- velopment of certain forms of industry, etc., are also largely rela- tive. The most positive of all advantages in production—that which most certainly gives superiority in all branches, is that which arises from that general intelligence which increases with the in- crease of the comfort and leisure of the masses of the people, that is to say, with the increase of wages. 14 158 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. such as the mining of silver, the refining of oil, the weaving of cloth, the making of clocks and watches, as to which our advantage over the Chinese is enormously greater than in the growing of tea. Hence, by pro- ducing these things and exchanging them directly or indirectly for Chinese tea, we obtain, in spite of the long carriage, more tea for the same labor than we could get by growing our own tea. Consider how this principle, that the interchange of commodities is governed by the comparative, not the absolute, cost of production, applies to the plea that protective duties are required on account of home tax- ation. It is of course true that a special tax placed upon any branch of production puts it at a disadvan- tage unless a like tax is placed upon the importation of similar productions. But this is not true of such general taxation as falls on all branches of industry alike. As such taxation does not alter the comparative profitableness of industries it does not diminish the relative inducement to carry any of them on, and to protect any particular industry from foreign competi- tion on account of such general taxation is simply to enable those engaged in it to throw off their share of a general burden. A favorite assumption of American protectionists is, or rather has been (for we once heard much more of it than now), that free trade is a good thing for rich coun- tries but a bad thing for poor countries—that it enables a country of better developed industries to prevent the development of industry in other countries, and to make such countries tributary to itself. But it follows from the principle which, as we have seen, causes and governs international exchanges, that for any country to ADVANTAGES AND DISADVANTAGES.” 159 impose restrictions on its foreign commerce on account of its own disadvantages in production is to prevent such amelioration of those disadvantages as foreign trade would bring. Free trade is voluntary trade. It can- not go on unless to the advantage of both parties, and, as between the two, free trade is relatively more advan- tageous to the poor and undeveloped country than to the rich and prosperous country. The opening up of trade between a Robinson Crusoe and the rest of the world would be to the advantage of both parties. But relatively the advantage would be far greater to Robin- son Crusoe than to the rest of the world. There is a certain class of American protectionists who concede that free trade is good in itself, but who say that we cannot safely adopt it until all other nations have adopted it, or until all other nations have come up to our standard of civilization; or, as it is sometimes phrased, until the millennium has come and men have ceased to struggle for their own interests as opposed to the interests of others. And so British protectionists have now assumed the name of “Fair Traders.” They have ceased to deny the essential goodness of free trade, but contend that so long as other countries maintain protective tariffs Great Britain, in self-defence, should maintain a protective tariff too, at least against countries that refuse to admit British productions free. The fallacy underlying most of these American ex- cuses for protection is that considered in the previous chapter—the fallacy that the country of low wages can undersell the country of high wages; but there is also mixed with this the notion to which the British fair traders appeal—the notion that the abolition of duties by any country is to the advantage, not of the people 160 T PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. - * of that country, but of the people of the other coun- tries that are thus given free access to its markets. “Is not the fact that British manufacturers desire the abo- lition of our protective tariff a proof that we ought to continue it 7” ask American protectionists. “Is it not a suicidal policy to give foreigners free access to our markets while they refuse us access to theirs?” cry British fair traders. All these notions are forms of the delusion that to export is more profitable than to import, but so wide- spread and influential are they that it may be well to devote a few words to them. The direct effect of a tariff is to restrain the people of the country that im- poses it. It curtails the freedom of foreigners to trade only through its operation in curtailing the freedom of citizens to trade. So far as foreigners are concerned it only indirectly affects their freedom to trade with that particular country, while to citizens of that country it is a direct curtailment of the freedom to trade with all the world. Since trade involves mutual benefit, it is true that any restriction that prevents one party from trading must operate in some degree to the injury of another party. But the indirect injury which a pro- tective tariff inflicts upon other countries is diffused and slight, as compared with the injury it inflicts di- rectly upon the nation that imposes it. To illustrate: The tariff which we have so long maintained upon iron to prevent our people from ex- changing their products for British iron has unques- tionably lessened our trade with Great Britain. But the effect upon the United States has been very much more injurious than the effect upon Great Britain. While it has lessened our trade absolutely, it has ADVANTAGES AND DISADVANTAGES. rā1 lessened the trade of Great Britain only with us. What Great Britain has lost in this curtailment of her trade with us she has largely made up in the consequent ex- tension of her trade elsewhere. For the effect of duties on iron and iron ore, and of the system of which they are part, has been so to increase the cost of American productions as to give to Great Britain the greater part of the carrying trade of the world, for which we were her principal competitor, and to hand over to her the trade of South America and of other countries, of which, but for this, we should have had the largest share. And in the same way, for any nation to restrict the freedom of its own citizens to trade, because other nations so restrict the freedom of their citizens, is a policy of the “biting off one's nose to spite one's face” order. Other nations may injure us by the imposition of taxes which tend to impoverish their own citizens, for as denizens of the world it is to our real interest that all other denizens of the world should be prosper- ous. But no other nation can thus injure us so much as we shall injure ourselves if we impose similar taxes upon our own citizens by way of retaliation. Suppose that a farmer who has an improved variety of potatoes learns that a neighbor has wheat of such su- perior kind that it will yield many more bushels to the acre than that he has been sowing. He might naturally go to his neighbor and offer to exchange seed potatoes for seed wheat. But if the neighbor while willing to sell the wheat should refuse to buy the potatoes, would not our farmer be a fool to declare, “Since you will not buy my superior potatoes I will not buy your superior wheat l” Would it not be very stupid 162 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. *. retaliation for him to go on planting poorer seed and getting poorer crops? Or, suppose, isolated from the rest of mankind, half a dozen men so situated and so engaged that mutual convenience constantly prompts them to exchange pro- ductions with one another. Suppose five of these six to be under the dominion of some curious superstition which leads them when they receive anything in ex- change to burn one-half of it up before carrying home the other half. This would indirectly be to the injury of the sixth man, because by thus lessening their own wealth his five neighbors would lessen their ability to exchange with him. But, would he better himself if he were to say: “Since these fools will insist upon burning half of all they get in exchange Imust, in self- defense, follow their example and burn half of all I get?’” The constitution and scheme of things in this world in which we find ourselves for a few years is such that no one can do either good or evil for himself alone. No one can release himself from the influence of his sur- roundings, and say, “What others do is nothing to me;” nor yet can any one say, “What I do is nothing to others.” Nevertheless it is in the tendency of things that he who does good most profits by it, and he who does evil injures, most of all, himself. And those who say that a nation should adopt a policy essentially bad because other nations have embraced it are as unwise as those who say, Lie, because others are false; Be idle, because others are lazy; Refuse knowledge, because others are ignorant. CEIAPTER XVI. THE DEVELOPMENT OF MANUFACTURES. ENGLISH protectionists, during the present century at least, struggled for the protection of agriculture, and the repeal of the corn laws in 1846 was their Waterloo. On the continent, also, it is largely agriculture that is held to need protection, and special efforts have been made to protect the German hog, even to the extent of shutting out its American competitor. But in the United States the favorite plea for protection has been that it is necessary to the establishment of manufactures; and the prevalent American idea of protection is that it is a scheme for fostering manufactures. As a matter of fact, American protection has not been confined to manufactures, nor has there been any hesitation in imposing duties which by raising the cost of materials are the very reverse of encouraging to manufactures. In the scramble which the protective system has induced, every interest capable of being protected and powerful enough to compel consideration in congressional log-rolling has secured a greater Or less share of protection—a share not based upon any standard of needs or merits, but upon the number of votes it could command. Thus wool, the production of which is one of the most primitive of industries, pre- ceding even the tilling of the soil, has been protected by high duties, although certain grades of foreign wool 164 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. are necessary to American woolen manufacturers, who have by these duties been put at a disadvantage in competing with foreign manufacturers. Thus iron ore has been protected despite the fact that American steel makers need foreign ore to mix with American ore, and are obliged to import it even under the high duty. Thus copper ore has been protected, to the disadvan- tage of American Smelters, as well as of all, the many branches of manufacture into which copper enters. Thus salt has been protected, though it is an article of prime necessity, used in large quantities in such im- portant industries as the curing of meats and fish, and entering into many branches of manufacture. Thus lumber has been protected in spite of its importance in manufacturing as well as of the protests of all who have inquired into the consequences of the rapid clear- ing of our natural woodlands. Thus coal has been protected, though to many branches of manufacturing cheap fuel is of first importance. ...And so on, through the list. s Protection of this kind is direct discouragement of manufactures. Nor yet is it encouragement of any in- dustry, since its effect is, not to make production of any kind more profitable, but to raise the price of lands or mines from which these crude products are obtained. Yet in spite of all this discouragement of manu- factures, of which the instances I have given are but samples, protection is still advocated as necessary to manufactures, and the growth of American manufactures is claimed as its result. So long and so loudly has this claim been made that to-day many of our people believe, what protectionist writers and speakers constantly assume, that but for THE DEVELOPMENT OF MANUFACTURES. - 165 protection there would not now be a manufacture of any importance carried on in the United States, and that were protection abolished the sole industry that this great country could carry on would be the raising of agricultural products for exportation to Europe. That so many believe this is a striking instance of our readiness to accept anything that is persistently dinned into our ears. For that manufactures grow up without protection, and that the effect of our protective tariff is to stunt and injure them, can be conclusively shown from general principles and from common facts. But first, let me call attention to a confusion of thought which gives plausibility to the notion that manufactures should be “encouraged.” Manufactures grow up as population increases and capital accumu- lates, and, in the natural order of industry, are best de- veloped in countries of dense population and accumu- lated wealth. Seeing this connection, it is easy to mis- take for cause what is really effect, and to imagine that manufacturing brings population and wealth. Here, in substance, is the argument which has been addressed to the people of the United States from the time when we became a nation to the present day: Manufacturing countries are always rich countries. Countries that produce only raw materials are always poor. Therefore, if we would be rich we must have manufac- tures, and in order to get manufactures we must encourage them. To many this argument seems plausible, especially as the taxes for the “encouragement” of the protected in. dustries are levied in such a way that their payment is not realized. But I could make as good an argument to the people of the little town of Jamaica, near which 166 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. I am now living, in support of a subsidy to a theatre I could say to them: “All large cities have theatres, and the more theatres it has, the larger the city. Look at New York | New York has more theatres than any other city in Amer- ica, and is consequently the greatest city in America. Philadelphia ranks next to New York in the number and size of its theatres, and therefore comes next to New York in population and wealth. So, throughout the country, wherever you find large, well-appointed theatres, you will find large and prosperous towns, while where there are no theatres the towns are smali. Is it any wonder that Jamaica is so small and grows so slowly when it has no theatres at all? People do not like to settle in a place where they cannot occasionally go to the theatre. If you want Jamaica to thrive you must take steps to build a fine theatre, which will at- tract a large population. Look at Brooklyn ! Brook- lyn was only a small riverside village before its people had the enterprise to start a theatre, and see now, since they began to build theatres, how large a city Brooklyn has become.” Modeling my argument on that addressed to Amer- ican voters by the Presidential candidate of the Repub- lican party in 1884, I might then drop into “statistics” and point to the fact that when theatrical represen- tations first began in this country its population did not amount to a million; that it was totally destitute of railroads and without a single mile of telegraph wire. Such has been our progress since theatres were intro- duced that the census of 1880 showed that we had 50,- 155,783 people, 97,907 miles of railroad and 291,212 °, miles of telegraph wires. Or I might go into greater | THE DEVELOPMENT OF MANUFACTURES. 167 detail, as some protectionist “statisticians” are accus- tomed to do. I might take the date of the building of each of the New York theatres, give the population and wealth of the city at that time, and then, by present- ing the statistics of population and wealth a few years later, show that the building of each theatre had been followed by a marked increase in population and wealth. I might point out that San Francisco had not a theatre until the Americans came there, and was consequently but a-straggling village; that the new comers imme- diately set up theatres and maintained them more gen- erously than any other similar population in the world, and that the Consequence was the marvelous growth of San Francisco. I might show that Chicago and Denver and Kansas City, all remarkably good theatre towns, have also been remarkable for their rapid growth, and, as in the case of New York, prove statis- tically that the building of each theatre these cities contain has been followed by an increase of population and wealth. Then, stretching out after protectionist fashion into the historical argument, I might refer to the fact that Nineveh and Babylon had no theatres that we know of, and so went to utter ruin; dilate upon the fondness of the ancient Greeks for theatrical entertainments con- ducted at public expense, and their consequent great- ness in arts and arms; point out how the Romans went even further than the Greeks in their encouragement of the theatre, and built at public cost the largest theatre in the world, and how Rome became the mistress of the nations. And, to embellish and give point to the argument, I might perhaps drop into poetry, recalling Byron's lines: 168 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. “When falls the Coliseum, Rome shall fall; And when Rome falls—the world !” Recovering from this, I might cite the fact that in every province they conquered the Romans established theatres, as explaining the remarkable facility with which they extended their civilization and made the conquered provinces integral parts of their great em- pire; point out that the decline of these theatres and the decay of Roman power and civilization went on to- gether; and that the extinction of the theatre brought on the night of the Dark Ages. Dwelling then a mo- ment upon the rudeness and ignorance of that time when there were no theatres, I might triumphantly point to the beginning of modern civilization as con- temporaneous with the revival of theatrical entertain- ments in miracle plays and court masques. And show- ing how these plays and masques were always support- ed by monasteries, municipalities or princes, and how places where they began became sites of great cities, I could laud the wisdom of “encouraging infant theat- ricals.” Then, in the fact that English actors, until re- cently, styled themselves her Majesty's servants and that the Lord Chamberlain still has authority over the English boards and must license plays before they can be acted, I could trace to a national system of subsidiz- ing infant theatricals the foundation of England's great- ness. Coming back to our own times, I could call at tention to the fact that Paris, where theatres are still subsidized and actors still draw their salaries from the public treasury, is the world's metropolis of fashion and art, steadily growing in population and wealth, though other parts of the same country which do not enjoy subsidized theatres are either at a stand- THE DEVELOPMENT OF MANUFACTURES. 169 still or declining. And finally I could point to the astuteness of the Mormon leaders, who early in the settlement of Salt Lake built a spacious theatre, and whose little village in the sage brush, then hardly as large as Jamaica, has since the building of this theatre grown to be a populous and beautiful city, and indig- nantly ask whether the virtuous people of Jamaica should allow themselves to be outdone by wicked polygamists. If such an argument would not induce the Jamai- cans to tax themselves to “encourage” a theatre, would it not at least be as logical as arguments that have induced the American people to tax themselves to encourage manufactures? The truth is that manufactures, like theatres, are the result, not the cause, of the growth of population and wealth. If we take a watch, a book, a steam engine, a piece of dry goods, or the product of any of the industries which we class as manufactures, and trace the steps by which the material of which it is composed has been brought from the condition in which it is afford- ed by nature into finished form, we will see that to the carrying on of any manufacturing industry many other industries are necessary. That an industry of this kind shall be able to avail itself freely of the prod- ucts of other industries is a prime condition of its suc- cessful prosecution. Hardly less important is the ex. istence of related industries, which aid in economizing material and utilizing waste, or make easier the pro- curement of supplies or services, or the sale and dis- tribution of products. This is the reason why the more elaborate industries tend within certain limits to localization, so that we find a particular district, with- 170 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. out any assignable reason of soil, climate, material pro- ductions, or character of the people, become noted for a particular manufacture, while different places with- in that district become noted for different branches, Thus, in those parts of Massachusetts where the manu- facture of boots and shoes is largely carried on, distinc- tions such as those between pegged and sewed goods, men's and women's wear, coarse and fine, will be found to characterize the industry of different towns. And in any considerable city we may see the disposition of various industries, with their related industries, to cluster together. But with this tendency to localization there is also a tendency which causes industries to arise in their order wherever population increases. This tendency is due not only to the difficulty and cost of transportation, but to differences in taste and to the individuality of demands. For instance, it will be much more convenient and satis- factory to me, if I wish to have a boat built, to have it built where I can talk with the builder and watch its construction; or to have a coat made where I can try it on; or to have a book printed where I can readily read the proofs and consult with the printer. Further than this, that relation of industries which makes the exist- ence of certain industries conduce to the economy with which others can be carried on, not merely causes the growth of one industry to prepare the way for others, but to promote their establishment. Thus the development of industry is of the nature of an evolution, which goes on with the increase of popu- lation and the progress of society, the simpler industries coming first and forming a basis for the more elaborate OD6S. THE DEVELOPMENT OF MANUFACTURES. 171 The reason that newly settled countries do not man- ufacture is that they can get manufactured goods cheaper—that is to say, with less expenditure of labor —than by manufacturing them. Just as the farmer, though he may have ash and hickory growing on his place, finds it cheaper to buy a wagon than to make one, or to take his wagon to the wheelwright's when it wants repairing, rather than attempt the job himself, so in a new and sparsely settled country it may take less labor to obtain goods from long distances than to man- ufacture them, even when every natural condition for their manufacture exists. The conditions for profitably carrying on any manufacturing industry are not merely natural conditions. Even more important than climate, soil, and mineral deposits are the existence of subsidi- ary industries and of a large demand. Manufacturing involves the production of large quantities of the same thing. The development of skill, the use of machinery and of improved processes, only become possible as large quantities of the same product are required. If the small quantities of all the various things needed must be produced for itself by each small community, they can only be produced by rude and wasteful methods. But if trade permits these things to be produced in large quantities the same labor becomes much more effective, and all the various wants can be much better supplied. The rude methods of Savages are due less to igno- rance than to isolation. A gun and ammunition will enable a man to kill more game than a bow and arrows, but a man who had to make his own weapons from the materials furnished by nature, could hardly make him, self a gun in a lifetime, even if he understood gun making. Unless there is a large number of men to be 172 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. \ supplied with guns and ammunition, and the materials of which these are made can be produced with the . economy that comes with the production of large quan- tities, the most effective weapons, taking into account the labor of producing them, are bows and arrows, not fire-arms. With a steel axe a tree may be felled with much less labor than with a stone axe. But a man who must make his own axe would be able to fell many trees with a stone axe in the time he would spend trying to make a steel axe from the ore. We smile at the savages who for a sheath knife or copper kettle gladly give many rich furs. Such articles are with us of little value, because being made in large quantities the expenditure of labor required for each is very small, but if made in small quantities, as the savage would have to make them, the expenditure of labor would far exceed that needed to obtain the furs. Even if they had the fullest knowledge of the tools and methods of civilized industry, men isolated as savages are isolated, would be forced to resort to the rude tools and methods of savages. The great advantage which civilized men have over Savages in settling among them, is in the possession of tools and weapons made in that state of society in which alone it is possible to manufacture them, and that by keeping up communi- cation with the denser populations they have left behind them, the settlers are able by means of trade to avail themselves of the manufacturing advantages of a more fully developed society. If the first American colonists had been unable to import from Europe the goods they required, and thus to avail themselves of the fuller development of European industry, they must soon have been reduced to savage tools and weapons. And THE DEVELOPMENT OF MANUFACTURES. 173 this would have happened to all new settlements in the westward march of our people had they been cut off from trade with larger populations. In new countries the industries that yield the largest comparative returns are the primary or extractive in- dustries which obtain food and the raw materials of manufacture from nature. The reason of this is that in these primary industries there are not required such costly tools and appliances, nor the co-operation of so many other industries, nor yet is production in large quantities so important. The people of new countries can therefore get the largest return for their labor by applying it to the primary or extractive industries, and exchanging their products for those of the more elabo- rate industries that can best be carried on where popu- lation is denser. As population increases, the conditions under which the secondary or any more elaborate industries can be carried on gradually arise, and such industries will be established—those for which natural conditions are pe. culiarly favorable, and those whose products are in most general demand and will least bear transportation, coming first. Thus in a country having fine forests, manufactures of wood will arise before manufactures for which there is no special advantage. The making of bricks will precede the making of china, the manu- facture of plowshares that of cutlery, window glass will be made before telescope lenses, and the coarser grades of cloth before the finer. But while we may describe in a general way the con- ditions which determine the natural order of industry, yet so many are these conditions and so complex are their actions and reactions upon one another that no - 174 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. one can predict with any exactness what in any given community this natural order of development will be, or say when it becomes more profitable to manufacture a thing than to import it. Legislative interference, therefore, is sure to prove hurtful, and such questions should be left to the unfettered play of individual en- terprise, which is to the community what the uncon- Scious vital activities are to the man. If the time has come for the establishment of an industry for which proper natural conditions exist, restrictions upon impor- tation in order to promote its establishment are needless. If the time has not come, such restrictions can only di- vert labor and capital from industries in which the return is greater, to others in which it must be less, and thus reduce the aggregate production of wealth. Just as it is evident that to prevent the people of a new colony from importing from countries of fuller indus- trial development would deprive them of many things they could not possibly make for themselves, so it is evi- dent that to restrict importations must retard the sym- metrical development of domestic industries. It may be that protection applied to one or to a few industries may sometimes hasten their development at the expense of the general industrial growth; but when protection is indiscriminately given to every industry capable of pro- tection, as it is in the United States, and as is the inevitable tendency wherever protection is begun, the result must be to check not merely the general devel- opment of industry, but even the development of the very industries for whose benefit the system of protec- tion is most advocated, by making more costly the prod- ucts which they must use and repressing the correl- ative industries with which they interlace. THE DEVELOPMENT OF MANUFACTURES. 175 To assume, as protectionists do, that economy must necessarily result from bringing producer and consumer together in point of space,” is to assume that things can be produced as well in one place as in another, and that difficulties in exchange are to be measured solely by distance. The truth is, that commodities can often be produced in one place with so much greater facility than in another that it involves a less expenditure of labor to bring them long distances than to produce them On the spot, while two points a hundred miles apart may be commercially nearer each other than two points ten miles apart. To bring the producer to the consumer in point of distance, is, if it increases the cost of production, not economy but waste. But this is not to deny that trade as it is carried on to-day does involve much unnecessary transportation, and that producer and consumer are in many cases needlessly separated. Protectionists are right when they point to the wholesale exportation of the elements of fertility of our soil, in the great stream of breadstuffs and meats which pours across the Atlantic, as reckless profligacy, and fair traders are right when they deplore the waste involved in English importations of food while English fields are going out of cultivation. Both are right in saying that one country ought not to be made a “draw farm " for another, and that a true econ- omy of the powers of nature would bring factory and field closer together. But they are wrong in attributing these evils to the freedom of trade, or in supposing * Protectionist arguments frequently involve the additional assumption that the “home producer” and “home consumer” are necessarily close together in point of space, whereas, as in the United States, they may be thousands of miles apart. 176 fHOTECTION OR FREE TRADE. that the remedy lies in protection. That tariffs are powerless to remedy these evils may be seen in the fact that this exhausting exportation goes on in spite of our high protective tariff, and that internal trade exhibits the same features. Everywhere that modern civiliza- tion extends, and with greatest rapidity where its influ- ences are most strongly felt, population and wealth are concentrating in huge towns and an exhausting com- merce flows from country to city. But this ominous tendency is not natural, and does not arise from too much freedom; it is unnatural, and arises from restric- tions. It may be clearly traced to monopolies, of which the monopoly of material opportunities is the first and most important. In a word, the Roman system of land ownership, which in our modern civilization has dis- placed that of our Celtic and Teutonic ancestors, is pro- ducing the same effect that it did in the Roman world —the engorgement of the centres and the impoverish- ment of the extremities. While London and New York grow faster than Rome ever did, English fields are passing out of cultivation as did the fields of Latium, and in Iowa and Dakota goes on the exhausting culture that impoverished the provinces of Africa. The same disease which rotted the old civilization is exhibiting its symptoms in the new. That disease cannot be cured by protective tariffs. CEIAPTER XVII. PROTECTION AND PRODUCERS. THE primary purpose of protection is to encourage producers *—that is to say, to increase the profits of capital engaged in certain branches of industry. The protective theory is that the increase a protect- ive duty causes in the price at which an imported com- modity can be sold within the country, protects the home producer (i. e., the man on whose account com- modities are produced for sale) from foreign competi- tion, so as to encourage him by larger profits than he could otherwise get to engage in or increase production. All the beneficial effects claimed for protection depend upon its effect in thus encouraging the employing pro- ducer, just as all the effects produced by the motion of an engine upon the complicated machinery of a factory are dependent upon its effect in turning the main driv- ing wheel. The main driving wheel (so to speak) of the protective theory is that protection increases the profits of the protected producer. But when, assuming this, the opponents of protec- tion represent the whole class of protected producers * For want of a better term I have here used the word “pro- ducers ” in that limited sense in which it is applied to those who control capital and employ labor engaged in production. The industries protected by our tariff are (with perhaps some nominal exceptions) of the kind carried on in this way. 178 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. as growing rich at the expense of their fellow-citizens, they are contradicted by obvious facts. Business men well know that in our long-protected industries the margin of profit is as small and the chances of failure as great as in any others—if, in fact, those protected industries are not harder to win success in by reason of the more trying fluctuations to which they are subject. The reason why protection in most cases thus fails to encourage is not difficult to see. The cost of any protective duty to the people at large is (1), the tax collected upon imported goods, plus the profits upon the tax, plus the expense and profits of smuggling in all its forms; plus the expense of sometimes trying smugglers of the coarser sort, and occasionally sending a poor and friendless one to the penitentiary; plus bribes and moieties received by gov- ernment officers; and (2), the additional prices that must be paid for the products of the protected home industry. It is from this second part alone that the protected industry can get its encouragement. But only a part of this part of what the people at large pay is real en- couragement. In the first place, it is true of protective duties, as it is true of direct subsidies, that they cannot be had for nothing. Just as the Pacific Mail Steam- ship Company and the various land and bond grant railways had to expend large sums to secure representa- tion at Washington, and had to divide handsomely with the Washington lobby, so the cost of securing Congressional “recognition” for an infant industry, or fighting off threatened reductions in its “encourage. ment,” and looking after every new tariff bill, is a considerable item. But still more important is the PROTECTION AND PRODUCERs. . 179 absolute loss in carrying on industries so unprofitable in themselves that they can be maintained only by sub- sidies. And to this loss must be added the waste that seems inseparable from governmental fosterage, for just in proportion as industries are sheltered from competi- tion are they slow to avail themselves of improvements in machinery and methods.” Out of the encourage- ment which the tariff beneficiaries receive in higher prices, much must thus be consumed, so that the net encouragement is only a small fraction of what con- sumers pay. Taking encouraged producers and taxed consumers together there is an enormous loss. Hence in all cases in which duties are imposed for the benefit of any particular industry the discouragement to indus- try in general must be greater than the encouragement of the particular industry. So long, however, as the one is spread over a large surface and the other over a small surface, the encouragement is more marked than the discouragement, and the disadvantage imposed on all industry does not much affect the few subsidized industries. But to introduce a tariff bill into a congress or par- * This disposition is, of course, largely augmented by the greater cost of machinery under our protective tariff, which not only in- creases the capital required to begin, but makes the constant dis- carding of old machinery and purchase of new, required to keep up with the march of invention, a much more serious matter. Cases have occurred in which British manufacturers, compelled by com- petition to adopt the latest improvements, have actually sold their discarded machinery to be shipped to the United States and used by protected Americans. It was his coming across a case of this kind that led David A. Wells, when he visited Europe as Special Commissioner of Revenue, to begin to question the usefulness of our tariff in promoting American industry. 180 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. liament is like throwing a banana into a cage of mon- keys. No sooner is it proposed to protect one industry than all the industries that are capable of protection begin to screech and scramble for it. They are, in fact, forced to do so, for to be left out of the encour- aged ring is necessarily to be discouraged. The result is, as we see in the United States, that they all get protected, some more and some less, according to the money they can spend and the political influence they can exert. Now every tax that raises prices for the encouragement of one industry must operate to discour- age all other industries into which the products of that industry enter. Thus a duty that raises the price of lumber necessarily discourages the industries which make use of lumber, from those connected with the building of houses and ships to those engaged in the making of matches and wooden toothpicks; a duty that raises the price of iron discourages the innumerable industries into which iron enters; a duty that raises the price of salt discourages the dairyman and the fisher. man; a duty that raises the price of sugar discourages the fruit preserver, the maker of sirups and cordials, and so on. Thus it is evident that every additional in- dustry protected lessens the encouragement of those al- ready protected. And since the net encouragement that tariff beneficiaries can receive as a whole is very much less than the aggregate addition to prices required to secure it, it is evident that the point at which protec- tion will cease to give any advantage to the protected must be much short of that at which every one is protected. To illustrate: Say that the total number of industries is one hundred, of which one-half are capable of protection. Let us say that of what the protection PROTECTION AND PRODUCERs. 181 costs, one-fourth is realized by the protected industries. Then (presuming equality), as soon as twenty-five in- dustries obtain protection, the protection can be of no benefit even to them, while, of course, involving a heavy discouragement to all the rest. I use this illustration merely to show that there is a point at which protection must cease to benefit even the industries it strives to encourage, not that I think it possible to give numerical exactness to such matters. But that there is such a point is certain, and that in the United States it has been reached and passed is also certain. That is to say, not only is our protective tariff a dead weight upon industry generally, but it is a dead weight, upon the very industries it is intended to stimu- late. ( If there are producers who permanently profit by protective duties, it is only because they are in some other way protected from domestic competition, and hence the profit which comes to them by reason of the duties does not come to them as producers but as monopolists. That is to say, the only cases in which protection can more than temporarily benefit any class of producers are cases in which it cannot stimulate industry. For that neither duties nor subsidies can give any permanent advantage in any business open to home competition results from the tendency of profits to a common level. The risk to which protected industries are exposed from changes in the tariff may at times keep profits in them somewhat above the ordinary rate; but this represents not advantage, but the neces- sity for increased insurance, and though it may consti- tute a tax upon consumers does not operate to extend the industry. This element of insurance eliminated, 16 182 -- PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. profits in protected industries can only be kept above those of unprotected industries by some sort of mon- opoly which shields them from home competition as the tariff does from foreign competition. The first effect of a protective duty is to increase profits in the protected industry. But unless that industry be in some way protected from the influx of competitors which such in- creased profits must attract, this influx must soon bring these profits to the general level. A monopoly, more or less complete, which may thus enable certain pro- ducers to retain for themselves the increased profits which it is the first effect of a protective duty to give, may arise from the possession of advantages of different kinds. © It may arise, in the first place, from the possession of some peculiar natural advantage. For instance, the only chrome mines yet discovered in the United States, belonging to a single family, that family have been much encouraged by the higher prices which the pro- tective duty on chrome has enabled them to charge home consumers. In the same way, until the discovery of new and rich copper deposits in Arizona and Mon- tana the owners of the Lake Superior copper mines were enabled to make enormous dividends by the pro- tective duty on copper, which, so long as home compe- tition was impossible, shut out the only competition that could reduce their profits, and enabled them to get three or four cents more per pound for the copper they sold in the United States than for the copper they shipped to Europe. Or a similar monopoly may be obtained by the pos- session of exclusive privileges given by the patent laws. For instance, the combination based on patents PROTECTION AND PRODUCERs. 183 for making steel have, since home competition with them was thus shut out, been enabled, by the enormous duty on imported steel, to add most encouragingly to their dividends, and the owners of the patented process used in making paper from wood have been similarly encouraged by the duty on wood pulp. Or again, a similar monopoly may be secured by the concentration of a business requiring large capital and special knowledge, or by the combination of producers in a “ring” or “pool” so as to limit home production and crush home competition. For instance, the pro- tective duty on quinine, until its abolition in 1879, resulted to the sole benefit of thiree houses, while a combination of quarry owners—the Producers Marble Company—have succeeded in preventing any home competition in the production of marble, and are thus enabled to retain to themselves the higher profits which the protective duty on foreign marble makes possible, and to largely concentrate in their own hands the busi- ness of working up marble. But the higher profits thus obtained in no way en- courage the extension of such industries. On the con- trary, they result from the very conditions natural or artificial which prevent the extension of these indus- tries. They are, in fact, not the profits of capital en- gaged in industry, but the profits of ownership of natural opportunities, of patent rights, or of organiza- tion or combination, and they increase the value of ownership in these opportunities, rights, and monopo- listic combinations, not the returns of capital engaged in production. Though they may go to individuals or companies who are producers, they do not go to them as producers; though they may increase the Income of 184 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. persons who are capitalists, they do not go to them by virtue of their employment of capital, but by virtue of their ownership of special privileges. Of the monopolies which thus get the benefit of profits erroneously supposed to go to producers, the most important are those arising from the private ownership of land. That what goes to the land-owner in nowise benefits the producer we may readily see. The two primary factors of production, without which nothing whatever can be produced, are land and labor. To these essential factors is added, when production passes beyond primitive forms, a third factor, capital— which consists of the product of land and labor (wealth) used for the purpose of facilitating the production of more wealth. Thus to production as it goes on in civilized societies the three factors are land, labor, and capital, and since land is in modern civilization made a subject of private ownership, the proceeds of production are divided between the land-owner, the labor-owner, and the capital-owner. - But between these factors of production there exists an essential difference. Land is the purely passive factor; labor and capital are the active factors—the factors by whose application and according to whose application wealth is brought forth. Therefore, it is only that part of the produce which goes to labor and capital that constitutes the reward of producers and stimulates production. The land-owner is in no sense a producer—he adds nothing whatever to the sum of productive forces, and that portion of the proceeds of production which he receives for the use of natural op- portunities no more rewards and stimulates production than does that portion of their crops which superstitious PhotºCTION AND PRODUCERs. 185 savages might burn up before an idol in thank-offering for the sunlight that had ripened them. There can be no labor until there is a man; there can be no capital until man has worked and saved; but land was here before man came. To the production of commodities the laborer fu, dishes human exertion; the capitalist furnishes the results of human exertion embodied in forms that may be used to aid further exertion; but the land-owner furnishes—what? The superficies of the earth? the latent powers of the soil 7 the ores be- neath it? the rain? the sunshine? gravitation? the chemical affinities? What does the land-owner furnish that involves any contribution from him to the exertion required in production? The answer must be, nothing! And hence it is that what goes to the land-owner out of the results of production is not the reward of producers and does not stimulate production, but is merely a toll which producers are compelled to pay to one whom our laws permit to treat as his own what Nature furnishes. Now, keeping these principles in mind, let us turn to the effects of protection. Let us suppose that Eng- land were to do as the English agriculturist landlords are very anxious to have her do—go back to the pro- tective policy and impose a high duty on grain. This would much increase the price of grain in England, and its first effect would be, while seriously injuring other industries, to give much larger profits to English farm- ers. This increase of profits would cause a rush into the business of farming, and the increased competition for the use of agricultural land would raise agricultural rents, so that the result would be, when industry had readjusted itself, that though the people of England would have to pay more for grain, the profits of grain 186 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. producing would not be larger than profits in any other occupation. The only class that would derive any ben- efit from the increased price that the people of England would have to pay for their food would be the agricult. ural land-owners, who are not producers at all. Protection cannot add to the value of the land of a Country as a whole, any more than it can stimulate in- dustry as a whole; on the contrary, its tendency is to check the general increase of land values by checking the production of wealth; but by stimulating a par- ticular form of industry it may increase the value of a particular kind of land. And it is instructive to ob. serve this, for it largely explains the motive in urging protection, and where its benefits go. For instance, the duty on lumber has not been asked for and lobbied for by the producers of lumber—that is to say, the men engaged in cutting down and sawing up trees, and who derive their profits solely from that source—nor has it added to their profits. The parties who have really lobbied and log-rolled for the imposi- tion and maintenance of the lumber duty are the owners of timber lands, and its effect has been to increase the price of “stumpage,” the royalty which the producer of lumber must pay to the owner of timber land for the privilege of cutting down trees. A certain class of forestallers have made a business of getting possession of timber lands by all the various “land-grabbing” de- vices as soon as the progress of population promised to make them available. Constituting a compact and therefore powerful interest (three parties in Detroit, for instance, are said to own ºr of the timber lands in the great timber State of Michigan), they have been able to secure a duty on lumber, which, nominally imposed PROTECTION AND PRODUCERs. 187 for the encouragement of the lumber producer, has really encouraged only the timber land forestaller, who, instead of being a producer at all, is merely a black- mailer of production.* So it is with many other duties. The effect of the sugar duty, for instance, is to increase the value of sugar lands in Louisiana, and our treaty with the Hawaiian Islands, by which Hawaiian sugar is admit- ted free of this duty, being equivalent (since the pro- duction of Hawaiian sugar is not sufficient to supply the United States) to the payment of a heavy bounty to Hawaiian sugar growers, has enormously increased the value of sugar lands in the Hawaiian Islands. So with the duty on copper and copper ore, which for a long time enabled American copper companies to keep up the price of copper in the United States while they were shipping copper to Europe and selling it there at a considerably lower price. The benefits of these duties * When, after the great fire in Chicago a bill was introduced in Congress permitting the importation free of duty of materials in- tended for use in the rebuilding of that city, the Michigan timber land barons went to Washington in a special car and induced the committee to omit lumber from the bill. + A striking illustration of the way American industry has been encouraged by a duty which enabled the stockholders in a couple of copper mines to pay dividends of over a hundred per cent. is afforded by the following case : Some years ago a Dutch ship arrived at Boston having in her hold a quantity of copper with which her master proposed to have her resheathed in Boston. But learning that in this “land of liberty” he would not be permitted to take the copper from the inside of his ship and employ American mechanics to nail it on the outside, without paying a duty of forty- five per cent. On the new copper put on, as well as a duty of four cents per pound on the old copper taken off, he found it cheaper to sail in ballast to Halifax, get his ship re-coppered by Canadian workmen, and then come back to Boston for his return cargo. 188 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. went to companies engaged in producing copper, but it went to them not as producers of copper but as owners of copper mines. If, as is largely the case in coal and iron mining, the work had been carried on by operators who paid a royalty to the mine owners, the enormous dividends would have gone to the mine owners and not to the operators. º Horace Greeley used to think that he conclusively disproved the assertion that the duties on iron were enriching a few at the expense of the many, when he declared that our laws gave to no one any special privilege of making iron, and asked why, if the tariff gave such enormous profits to iron producers as the free traders said it did, these free traders did not go to work and make iron. So far as concerned those pro- ducers who derived no special advantage from patent rights or combinations, Mr. Greeley was right enough— the fact that there was no special rush to get into the business proving that iron producers as producers were making on the average no more than ordinary profits. And could iron be made from air, this fact would have shown what Mr. Greeley seems to have imagined it did, though it would not have shown that the nation was not losing greatly by the duty. But iron cannot be made from air; it can only be made from iron ore. And though Nature, especially in the United States, has provided abundant supplies of iron ore, she has not distributed them equally, but has stored them in large deposits in particular places. If inclined to take Hor- ace Greeley's advice to go and make iron, should I think its price too high, I must obtain access to one of these deposits, and that a deposit sufficiently near to other materials and to centres of population. I may PROTECTION AND PRODUCERS. 189 find plenty of such deposits which no one is using, but where can I find such a deposit that is free to be used by me? The laws of my country do not forbid me from mak- ing iron, but they do allow individuals to forbid me from making use of the natural material from which alone iron can be made—they do allow individuals to take possession of these deposits of ore which Nature has provided for the making of iron, and to treat and hold them as though they were their own private prop- erty, placed there by themselves and not by God. Con- sequently these deposits of iron ore are appropriated as soon as there is any prospect that any one will want to use them, and when I find one that will suit my pur- pose I find that it is in the possession of some owner who will not let me use it until I pay him down in a purchase price, or agree to pay him in a royalty of So much per ton, nearly, if not quite, all I can make above the ordinary return to capital in producing iron. Thus, while the duty which raises the price of iron may not benefit producers, it does benefit the dogs-in- the-manger whom our laws permit to claim as their own the stores which aeons before man appeared were accumulated by Nature for the use of the millions who would one day be called into being—enabling the mo- nopolists of our iron land to levy heavy taxes on their fellow-citizens long before they could otherwise have done so.” So with the duty on coal. It adds nothing * The royalty paid by iron miners for the privilege of taking the ore out of the earth in many cases equals and in some cases exceeds the cost of mining it. The royalties of the Pratt Iron and Coal Company of Alabama are said to run as high as $10,000 per acre. In the Chicago Inter-Ocean, a staunch protectionist paper, of Oc. Aºt 190 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. 3. to the profits of the coal operator who buys the right to take coal out of the earth, but it does enable a ring of coal-land and railway owners to levy in many places an additional black mail upon the use of Nature's bounty. The motive and effect of many of our duties are well tober 11, 1885, I find a description of the Colby Iron Mine at Besse- mer, Michigan. This mine, it is said, is owned by parties who got it for $1.25 per acre. They lease the privilege of taking out ore on a royalty of 40 cents per ton to the Colbys, who sub-lease it to Morse & Co. for 523 cents per ton royalty, who have a contract with Captain Sellwood to put the ore on the cars for 874 cents per ton. Sellwood sub-lets this contract for 124 cents per ton, and the sub- contractors are said to make a profit of 24 cents per ton, as the work is done by a steam shovel. Deducting transportation, etc., the ore brings $2.80 per ton, as mined, of which only 123 cents goes to the firm who do the actual work of production. The output is 1,200 tons per day, which, according to the Inter-Ocean correspondent, gives to the owners a net profit of $480 per day ; to the Colbys, $150 per day; Morse & Co., $1,680; Captain Sellwood, $90 per day; and the sub-contractors who do the work of mining $30 per day, “a total net profit from the mine, over and above what profit there may be in the labor, of $3,240 per day.” The account concludes by say- ing : “As the product will be at least doubled during the coming year, you see there will be some fortunes made out of the Colby mine.” To these fortunes our protective duty on foreign ore un- doubtedly contributes, but how much does it in this case encourage production? In Lebanon County, Pennsylvania, is a hill of magnetic iron ore nearly pure, which has merely to be quarried out. It is owned by the Coleman heirs, and has made them So enormously Wealthy that these are said by some to be the richest people in the United States. They are producers of iron, smelting their own ore, as well as rail- way owners and farmers, owning and cultivating by Superintendents great tracts of valuable land. They, doubtless, have been much encouraged by the duty on iron which we have maintained for “the protection of American labor,” but this encouragement comes to them as owners of this rich gift of Nature to—Mr. Coleman's heirs. The deposit of iron ore would be worked were there no duty, and was worked, I believe, before any duty on iron was imposed. * PROTECTION AND PRODUCERS. 191 illustrated by the import duty we levy on borax and boracic acid. We had no duties on borax and boracic acid (which have important uses in many branches of manufacture) until it was discovered that in the State of Nevada nature had provided a deposit of nearly pure borax for the use of the people of this continent. This free gift of the Almighty having been reduced to private ownership, in accordance with the laws of the United States for such cases made and provided, the enterpris- ing forestallers at once applied to Congress for (and of course secured) the imposition of a duty which would make borax artificially dear and increase the profits of this monopoly of a natural advantage. While our manufacturers and other producers have been caught readily enough with the delusive promise that protection would increase their profits, and have used their influence to institute and maintain protective duties, I am inclined to think that the most efficient interest on the side of protection in the United States has been that of those who have possessed themselves of lands or other natural advantages which they hoped protection would make more valuable. For it has been not merely the owners of coal, iron, timber, sugar, orange, or wine lands, of salt springs, borax lakes, or copper deposits, who have seen in the shutting out of foreign competition a quicker demand and higher value for their lands, but the same feeling has had its influ- ence upon the holders of city and village real estate, who, realizing that the establishment of factories or the working of mines in their vicinity would give value to their lots, have been disposed to support a policy which had for its avowed object the transfer of such industries from other countries to our own. 192 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. To repeat: It is only aſ first that a protective duty can stimulate an industry. When the forces of produc- tion have had time to readjust themselves, profits in the protected industry, unless kept up by obstacles which prevent further extension of the industry, must sink to the ordinary level, and the duty losing its power of further stimulation ceases to yield any advantage to producers unprotected against home competition. This is the situation of the greater part of “protected” American producers. They feel the general injury of the system without really participating in its special benefits. - JHow, then, it may be asked, is it that even these pro- ducers who are not sheltered by any home protection are in general so strongly in favor of a protective tariff? The true reason is to be found in the causes I will hereafter speak of, which predispose the common mind to an acceptance of protective ideas. And, while keen enough as to their individual interests, these producers are as blind to social interests as any other class. They have so long heard and been accustomed to repeat, that free trade would ruin American industry, that it never occurs to them to doubt it; and the effect of duties upon so many other products being to enhance the cost of their own productions, they see, without apprehend- ing the cause, that were it not for the particular duty that protects them they could be undersold by foreign products, and so they cling to the system. Protection ts necessary to them in many cases, because of the pro- tection of other industries. But were the whole system abolished there can be no doubt that American industry would spring forward with new vigor. CEIAPTER XVIII. Tº FFECTS OF PROTECTION ON AMERICAN INDUSTRY. IF there is one country in the world where the as: sumption that protection is necessary to the develop- ment of manufactures and the “diversification of in- dustry" is conclusively disproved by the most obvious facts, that country is the United States. The first set- tlers in America devoted themselves to trade with the Indians and to those extractive industries which a sparse population always finds most profitable, the produce of the forest, of the soil, and of the fisheries, constituting their staples, while even bricks and tiles were at first imported from the mother country. But without any protection and in spite of British regulations intended to prevent the growth of manufactures in the colonies, one industry after another took root, as population in- creased, until at the time of the first Tariff Act, in 1789, all the more important manufactures, including those of iron and textiles, had become firmly established. As up to this time they had grown without any tariff, so must they have continued to grow with the increase of population, even if we had never had a tariff. But the American who contends that protection is necessary to the diversification of industry must not merely ignore the history of his country during that long period before the first tariff of any kind was insti- 17 194 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. tuted, but he must ignore what has been going on ever since, and is still going on under his eyes. We need look no further back than the formation of the Union to see that if it were true that manufacturing could not grow up in new countries without the pro- tection of tariffs the manufacturing industries of the United States would to-day be confined to a narrow belt along the Atlantic sea-board. Philadelphia, New York, and Boston were considerable cities, and manu- factures had taken a firm root along the Atlantic, when Western New York and Western Pennsylvania were covered with forests, when Indiana and Illinois were buffalo ranges, when Detroit and St. Louis were trad- ing posts, Chicago undreamed of, and the continent beyond the Mississippi as little known as the interior of Africa is now. In the United States, the East has had over the West all the advantages which protection- ists say make it impossible for a new country to build up its manufacturing industries against the competition of an older country—larger capital, longer experience, and cheaper labor. Yet without any protective tariff between the West and the East, manufacturing has steadily moved westward with the movement of popu- lation, and is moving westward still. This is a fact that of itself conclusively disproves the protective theory. The protectionist assumption that manufactures have increased in the United States because of protective tariffs is even more unfounded than the assumption that the growth of New York after the building of each new theatre was because of the building of the theatre. It is as if one should tow a bucket behind a boat and insist that it helped the boat along because EFFECTS OF PROTECTION ON AMERICAN INDUSTRY. 195 & * she still moved forward. Manufacturing has increased in the United States because of the growth of popula- tion and the development of the country; not because of tariffs, but in spite of them. That protective tariffs have injured instead of helped American manufactures is shown by the fact that our manufactures are much less than they ought to be, considering our population and development—much less relatively than they were in the beginning of the century. Had we continued the policy of free trade our manufactures would have grown up in natural hardihood and vigor, and we should now not only be exporting manufactured goods to Mexico and the West Indies, South America and Australia, as Ohio is ex- porting manufactured goods to Kansas, Nebraska, Colo- rado and Dakota, but we should be exporting manu- factured goods to Great Britain, just as Ohio is to-day exporting manufactured goods to Pennsylvania and New York, where manufactures began before Ohio was settled. | But so heavily are our manufactures weighted by a tariff which increases the cost of all their mate- rials and appliances, that, in spite of our natural ad- vantages and the inventiveness of our people, our sales are confined to our protected market, and we can nowhere compete with the manufactures of other coun- tries. In spite of the increase of duties with which we have attempted to keep out foreign importations and build up our own manufacturing industries, the great bulk of our importations to-day are of manufactured goods, while all but a trivial percentage of our exports consist of raw materials. Even where we import largely from such countries as Brazil, which have almost no manufactures of their own, we cannot send 196 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. them in return the manufactured goods they want, but to pay for what we buy of them must send our raw materials to Europe. This is not a natural condition of trade. The United States have long passed the stage of growth in which raw materials constitute the only natural exports. We have now a population of nearly sixty millions, and con- sume more manufactured goods than any other nation. We possess unrivaled advantages for manufacturing. In extent and accessibility our coal deposits far surpass those of any other civilized country, while we have reservoirs of natural gas that supply fuel almost with- out labor. Moreover, we are the first of civilized nations in the invention and use of machinery, and in the economy of material and labor. But all these advantages are neutralized by the wall of protection we have built along our coasts. For as long as I can remember, the protectionist press has been from time to time chronicling the fact that considerable orders for this, that or the other American manufacture had been received from abroad, as proving that protection was at last beginning to bring about the results promised for it, and that American manu- facturing industry, so safely guarded during its infancy by a protective tariff, was now about to enter the mar- Rets of the world. The statements that have been made the basis of these congratulations have generally been true, but the predictions founded upon them have never been verified, and, while Óur population has doubled, our exports of manufactured articles have rel- atively declined. The explanation is this: The higher rates of wages that have prevailed in the United States, and the consequent higher standard of general intelli- EFFECTS OF PROTECTION ON AMERICAN INDUSTRY 197 _* gence, have stimulated American invention, and we are constantly making improvements upon the tools, meth- . ods, and patterns elsewhere in use. These improvements are constantly starting a foreign demand for American manufactures which seems to promise large increase. But before this increase takes place the improvements are adopted in countries where manufacturing is not so heavily burdened by taxes on material, and what should have been peculiarly an American manufacture is transferred to a foreign country. Every American who has visited London has doubt- less noticed, opposite the Parliament House at West- minster, a shop devoted to the sale of “American notions.” There are a number of such shops in Lon- don, and they are also to be found in every town of any size in the three kingdoms. These shops must sell in the aggregate quite an amount of American tools and contrivances, which in part accounts for the fact that we still export some manufactures. But the American will be deluded who from the number of these shops and the interest taken by the people who are constantly looking in the windows or examining the goods, im- agines that American manufactures are beginning to gain a foothold in the Old World. These shops are in fact curiosity shops, just as are the Chinese and Japan- ese shops that we find in the larger American cities, and people go to them to see the ingenious things the Americans are getting up. But no sooner do these shops so far popularize an “American notion” that a considerable demand for it arises, than some English manufacturer at once begins to make it, or the Ameri- can inventor, if he holds an English patent, finds more profit in manufacturing it abroad. Not having the dis. 198 BROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. couragements of American protection to contend with, he can make it in Great Britain cheaper than in the United States, and the consequence of the introduction of an American “notion” is that, instead of its importa- tion from America increasing, it comes to an end. This illustrates the history of American manufactures abroad. One article after another which has been in- vented or improved in the United States has seemed to get a foothold in foreign markets only to lose it when fairly introduced. We have sent locomotives to Russia, arms to Turkey and Germany, agricultural implements to England, river steamers to China, sewing machines to all parts of the world, but have never been able to hold the trade our inventiveness should have secured. But it is on the high seas and in an industry in which we once led the world that the effect of our protective policy can be most clearly seen. Thirty years ago ship-building had reached such a pitch of excellence in this country that we built not only for ourselves but for other nations. American ships were the fastest sailers, the largest carriers, and everywhere got the quickest dispatch and the highest freights. The registered tonnage of the United States almost equaled that of Great Britain, and a few years promised to give us the unquestionable supremacy of the ocean. The abolition of the more important British pro- tective duties in 1846 was followed in 1854 by the re- peal of the navigation laws, and from thenceforth not only were British subjects free to buy or build ships wherever they pleased, but the coasting trade of the British Isles was thrown open to foreigners. Dire were the predictions of British protectionists as to the EFFECTS OF PROTECTION ON AMERICAN INDUSTRY. 199 utter ruin that was thus prepared for British com- merce. The Yankees were to sweep the ocean, and “half-starved Swedes and Norwegians” were to drive the “ruddy, beef-eating English tar” from his own seas and channels. While one great commercial nation thus abandoned protection, the other redoubled it. The breaking out of our civil war was the golden opportunity of protec- tion, and the unselfish ardor of a people ready to make any sacrifice to prevent the dismemberment of their country was taken advantage of to pile protective taxes upon them. The ravages of Confederate cruisers and the consequent high rate of insurance on American ships would under any circumstances have diminished our deep-sea commerce; yet this effect was only tem- porary, and but for our protective policy we should at the end of the war have quickly resumed our place in the carrying trade of the world and moved forward to the lead with more vigor than ever. But crushed by a policy which prevents Americans from building, and forbids them to buy ships, our com- merce, ever since the war, has steadily shrunk, until American ships which, when we were a nation of twenty-five millions, ploughed every sea of the globe, are now, when we number nearly sixty millions, seldom seen on blue water. In Liverpool docks, where once it seemed as if every other vessel was American, you must search the forests of masts to find one. In San Fran- cisco Bay you may count English ship, and English ship, and English ship, before you come to an Ameri. can, while five-sixths of the foreign commerce of New York is carried on in foreign bottoms. Once no Amer- ican dreamed of crossing the Atlantic save on an 200 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. American ship; to-day no one thinks of taking one. It is the French and the Germans who compete with the British in carrying Americans to Europe and bring- ing them back. Once our ships were the finest or, the Ocean. To-day there is not a first-class ocean carrier under the American flag, and but for the fact that foreign vessels are absolutely prohibited from carrying between American ports, ship-building, in which we once led the world, would now be with us a lost art. As it is, we have utterly lost our place. . When I was a boy we confidently believed that American war ships could outsail, when they could not outfight, anything that floated, and in the event of war with a commercial nation we knew that every sea of the globe would swarm with swift American privateers. To-day, the ships on which we have wasted millions are, for pur- poses of modern warfare, as antiquated as Roman gal- leys. Compared with the vessels of other nations they can neither fight nor run ; while, as for privateers or chartered vessels, Great Britain could take from those greyhounds of the sea which American travel and trade support, enough fleet ships to Snap up any vessel that ventured out of an American port. I do not complain of the inefficiency of our navy. The maintenance of a navy in time of peace is un- worthy of the dignity of the Great Republic and of the place she should aspire to among the nations, and to my mind the hundreds of millions that during the last twenty years we have spent upon our navy would have been as truly wasted had they secured us good ships But I do complain of the decadence in our ability to build ships. Our misfortune is not that we have no navy, but that we lack the swift merchant fleet, the EFFECTs of PROTECTION ON AMERICAN INDUSTRY. 201 great founderies and shipyards, the skilled engineers and seamen and mechanics, in which, and not in navies, true power upon the seas consists. A people in whose veins runs the blood of Vikings have been driven off the ocean by-themselves. Of course the selfish interests that profit, or imagine they profit by the policy which has swept the Ameri- can flag from the ocean as no foreign enemy could have done, ascribe this effect to every cause but the right one. They say, for instance, that we cannot compete with other nations in ocean commerce, because they have an advantage in lower wages and cheaper capital, in willful disregard of the fact that when the difference in wages and interest between the two sides of the Atlantic was far greater than now we not only carried for ourselves but for other nations, and were rapidly rising to the position of the greatest of ocean carriers. The truth is, that if wages are higher with us this is really to our advantage, while not only can capital now be had as cheaply in New York as in London, but American capital is actually being used to run vessels under foreign flags, because of the taxes which make it unprofitable to build or run American vessels. De Tocqueville, fifty years ago, was struck with the fact that nine-tenths of the commerce between the United States and Europe and three-fourths of the com- merce of the New World with Europe was carried in American ships; that these ships filled the docks of Havre and Liverpool, while but few English and French vessels were to be seen at New York. This, he saw, could only be explained by the fact that “vessels of the United States can cross the seas at a cheaper rate than any other vessels in the world.” But, he continues: 202 ºw. PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. “It is difficult to say for what reason the American can trade at a lower rate than other nations; and one is at, first sight led to attribute this circumstance to the physical or natural advantages which are within their reach; but this supposition is erroneous. The American vessels cost almost as much as our own; they are not better built, and they generally last for a shorter time, while the pay of the American sailor is more considerable than the pay on board European ships. I am of opinion that the true cause of their superiority must not be sought for in physical advantages but that it is wholly attributable to their moral and intellectual qualities. “ * * * The European sailor navigates with prudence; he only sets sail when the weather is favorable; if an unforeseen acci- dent befalls him, he puts into port; at night he furls a portion of his canvas; and when the whitening billows intimate the vicinity of land, he checks his way and takes an observation of the sea. But the American neglects these precautions, and braves these dangers. He weighs anchor in the midst of tempestuous gales; by night and by day he spreads his sheets to the wind; he repairs as he goes along such damages as his vessel may have sustained from the storm; and when at last he approaches the term of his voyage he darts onward to the shore as if he already descried a port. The Americans are often shipwrecked, but no trader crosses the sea so rapidly, and, as they perform the same distance in a shorter time, they can perform it at a cheaper rate. “I cannot better explain my meaning than by saying that the American affects a sort of heroism in his manner of trading, in which he follows not only a caleulation of his gain, but an impulse of his nature.” What the observant Frenchman describes in some. what extravagant language was a real advantage—an advantage that attached not merely to the sailing of ships, but to their designing, their building, and every- thing connected with them. And what gave this ad- vantage was not anything in American nature that differed from other human nature, but the fact that higher wages and the resulting higher standard of com- fort and better opportunities developed a greater power of adapting means to ends. In short, the secret of our EFFECTS OF PROTECTION ON AMERICAN - INDUSTRY. 203 success upon the ocean (as of all our other successes) lay in the very things that according to the exponents of protectionism now shut us out from the ocean.* —e * By way of consolation for the manner in which protectionism has driven American ships from the ocean, Professor Thompson (Po- litical Economy, p. 216) says: “If there were no other reason for the policy that seeks to reduce foreign commerce to a minimum, a sufficient one would be found in its effect upon the human material it employs. Bentham thought the worst possible use that could be made of a man was to hang him ; a worse still is to make a common sailor of him. The life and the manly character of the sailor has been so admired in song and prose, and the real excellences of individuals of the profession have been made so prominent that we forget what the mass of this class of men are, and what representatives of our civilization and Christianity we send out to all lands in the tenants of the fore- Castle.’ There is some truth in this, but what there is is due to protection- ism in its broader sense. There is no reason in the nature of his vocation why the sailor should not be as well fed, well paid and well treated, as intelligent and self-respecting, as any mechanic. That he is not is at bottom due to the paternal interference of maritime law with the relations of employer and employed. The law does not specifically enforce contracts for services on shore, and for any breach of contract by an employee the employer has only a civil rem- edy. He cannot restrain the employed of his liberty, coerce him by violence or duress, or, should he quit work, call on the law to bring him back, and thus the personal relations of employer and cmployed are left to the frce play of mutual interest. For services requiring vigilance and sobriety, and where great loss or danger would result from a sudden refusal to go on with the work, the employer must look to the character of the men he employs, and must so pay and treat them that there will be no danger of their wishing to leave him. But what on shore is thus left to the self-regulative principle of freedom is, as to services to be performed on shipboard, attempted to be regulated on the paternal principle of protectionism. Here the law steps in to compel the specific performance of contracts, and not only gives the employer or his representative the right to restrain the employed of his personal liberty, and by violence or duress to compel his performance of Services he has contracted for, 204 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. Again, it is said that it is the substitution of steam for canvas and iron for wood that has led to the decay of American shipping. This is no more a reason for the decay of American shipping than is the substitution of the double top-sail yard for the single top-sail yard. River steamers were first developed here; it was an American steamship that first crossed from New York to Liverpool, and thirty years ago American steamers were making the “crack” passages. The same skill, the same energy, the same facility of adapting means to but if the employed leave the ship the law may be invoked to ar- rest, imprison, and force him back. The result has been on the one hand largely to destroy the incentive to proper treatment of their crews on the part of owners and masters of ships, and on the other to degrade the character of Seamen. Crews have been largely obtained by a system of virtual impressment or kidnapping called in 'long-shore vernacular “shanghaing,” by which men are put on board ship when drunk or even by force, for the sake of their ad- vance wages or a bonus called “blood-money,” which the power of keeping the men on board and compelling them to work enables the ship-owners safely to pay. The power that must be intrusted to the master of a ship, on whose skill and judgment depends the safety of all on board, is necessarily despotic, but while the abuse of this power has, under a system which enables a brutal captain to get crews with as much or almost as much facility as a humane one, been little checked by motives of self-interest, it has been stim. ulated by the degradation which such a system inevitably produces in the character of the crews. Various attempts have been made to remedy this state of things; but nothing can avail much that does not go to the root of the difficulty and leave the sailor, no matter what contract he may have signed or what advances have been paid to or for him, as free to quit a vessel as any mechanic on shore ls free to quit his employment. Theoretically the law may guard the rights of one party to a contract as well as those of the other; but practically the poor and uninfluential are always at a disadvant- age in appealing to the law. This is a vice which inheres in all forms of protectionism, from that of absolute monarchy to that of protective duties. EFFECTs of PROTECTION ON AMERICAN INDUSTRY. 205 ends which enabled our mechanics to build wooden ships would have enabled them to continue to build ships no matter what the change in material. With free trade we should not merely have kept abreast of the change from wood to iron, we should have led it. This we should have done even though not a pound of iron could have been produced on the whole continent. In the glorious days of American ship-building Donald McKay of Boston and William H. Webb of New York drew the materials for their white-winged racers from forests that were practically almost as far from those cities as they were from the Clyde, the Humber, or the Thames. Had our ship-builders been as free as their English rivals to get their materials wherever they could buy them best and cheapest, they could as easily have built ships with iron brought from England as they did build them with knees from Florida and planks from Maine and North Carolina, and spars from Oregon. Ireland produces neither iron nor coal, but Belfast has become noted for iron ship-building, and iron can be carried across the Atlantic almost as cheaply as across the Irish Sea. But so far from its being necessary to bring iron from Great Britain, our deposits of iron and coal are larger, better, and more easily worked than those of Great Britain, and before the Revolution we were actu- ally exporting iron to that country. Had we never embraced the policy of protection we should to-day have been the first of iron producers. The advantage that Great Britain has over us is simply that she has abandoned the repressive system of protection, while We have increased it. This difference in policy, while it has enabled the British producer to avail himself of * * ~~ 18 º 206 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. the advantages of all the world, has handicapped the American producer and restricted him to the market of his own country. The ores of Spain and Africa which, for some purposes, it is necessary to mix with our own ores, have been burdened with a heavy duty; a heavy duty has enabled a great steel combination to keep steel at a monopoly price; a heavy duty on copper has enabled another combination to get a high price for American copper at home, while exporting it to Great Britain for a low price; and to encourage a single bunting factory the very ensign of an American ship has been subjected to a duty of 150 per cent. From keelson to truck, from the wire in her stays to the brass in her taffrail log, everything that goes to the building, the fitting, or the storing of a ship is burdened with heavy taxes. Even should she be repaired abroad she must pay taxes for it on her return home. Thus has protection strangled an industry in which with free trade we might still have led the world. And the in- jury we have done ourselves has been, in Some degree at least, an injury to mankind. Who can doubt that ocean steamers would to-day have been swifter and better had American builders been free to compete with English builders? Though our Navigation Laws, which forbid the carrying of a pound of freight or a single passenger from American port to American port on any other than an American-built vessel, obscure the effects of protection in our coasting trade, they are just as truly felt as in our ocean trade. The increased cost of build, ing and running vessels has, especially as to steamers, operated to stunt the growth of our coasting trade, and to check by higher freights the development of other º *EFFECTs of PROTECTION ON AMERICAN in DUSTRY. 207 industries. And how restriction strengthens monopoly is seen in the manner in which the effect of protection upon our coastwise trade has been to make easier the extortions of railway syndicates. For instance, the Pacific Railway pool has for years paid the Pacific Mail Steamship Company $85,000 a month to keep up its rates of fare and freight between New York and San Francisco. It would have been impossible for the railway ring thus to prevent competition had the trade between the Atlantic and Pacific been open to foreign vessels. . s Z º - - --~~ y y/ ~~~ // ſº (A A --- // / A * / 2 *s ...' /. 2^*, *, *, *, *, * . / /, / 4 & 44%% , CHAPTER XIX. PROTECTION AND WAGES. WE have sufficiently seen the effect of protection on the production of wealth. Let us now inquire as to its effect on wages. This is a question of the distribution of wealth. Discussions of the tariff question seldom go further than the point we have now reached, for though much is said, in the United States at least, of the effect of protection on wages, it is as a deduction from what is asserted of its effect on the production of wealth. Its advocates claim that protection raises wages; but in so far as they attempt to prove this it is only by argu- ments, such as we have examined, that protection in- creases the prosperity of a country as a whole, from which it is assumed that it must increase wages. Or when the claim that protection raises wages is put in the negative form (a favorite method with Ameri- can protectionists) and it is asserted that protection prevents wages from falling to the lower level of other countries, this assertion is always based on the assump- tion that protéction is necessary to enable production to be carried on at the higher level of wages, and that if it were withdrawn production would so decline, by reason of the underselling of home, producers by for- eign producers, that wages must also decline.* *Here, for instance, taken from the Wew York Tribune during the last Presidential campaign (1884), is a sample of the arguments PROTECTION AND WAGES. 209 But although its whole basis has already been over- thrown, let us (since this is the most important part of the question) examine directly and independently the claim that protection raises (or maintains) wages. Though the question of wages is primarily a question of the distribution of wealth, no protectionist writer that I know of ventures to treat it as such, and free- traders generally stop where protectionists stop, arguing that protection must diminish the production of wealth, and (So far as they treat the matter of wages) from this inferring that protection must reduce wages. For pur- poses of controversy this is logically sufficient, since, free trade being natural trade, the onus of proof must lie upon those who would restrict it. But as my pur- pose is more than that of controversy, I cannot be con- tented with showing merely the unsoundness of the arguments for protection. A true proposition may be supported by a bad argument, and to satisfy ourselves thoroughly as to the effect of protection we must trace its influence on the distribution, as well as on the pro- duction of wealth. Error often arises from the assump- —tion that what benefits or injures the whole must in for protection which are manufactured about election times for the consumption of “the intelligent and highly paid American work- ing-man:” “All workers know that labor in other countries is not paid as well as it is here. But this difference could not exist if the products of 50-cent labor in England or Germany or Canada, could be sold freely in our market, instead of the production of $1 labor here. Hence, this country compels, the employers of the 50- cent labor abroad to pay a duty for the privilege of selling their goods in this market. That duty is called a tariff. If it is made high enough to fit the difference in rate of wages, so that labor in this country cannot be degraded toward the level of similar labor in other countries, it is called a protective tariff. Such a tariff is a defense of American industry against direct competition with the underpaid labor of other countries,” 210 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. like manner affect all its parts. Causes which increase or decrease aggregate wealth often produce the reverse effect on classes or individuals. The resort to salt in- stead of kelp for obtaining soda increased the produc- tion of wealth in Great Britain, but lessened the income of many Highland landlords. The introduction of railways, greatly as they have added to aggregate wealth, ruined the business of many small villages. Out of wars, destructive to national wealth though they be, great fortunes arise. Fires, floods, and famines, while disastrous to the community, may prove profit- able to individuals, and he who has a contract to fill, or who has speculated in stocks for a fall, may be en- riched by hard times. As, however, those who live by their labor constitute in all countries the large majority of the people, there is a strong presumption that no matter who else is benefited, anything that reduces the aggregate income of the community must be injurious to working-men. But that we may leave nothing to presumption, how- ever strong, let us examine directly the effect of pro- tective tariffs on wages. * Whatever affects the production of wealth may at the same time affect distribution. It is also possible that increase or decrease in the production of wealth may, under certain circumstances, alter the proportions of distribution. But it is only with the first of these questions that we have now to deal, since the second goes beyond the question of tariff, and if it shall be: come necessary to open it, that will not be until after we have satisfied ourselves as to the tendencies of pro- tection. Trade, as we have seen, is a mode of production, and PROTECTION AND wagºs. 211 the tendency of tariff restrictions on trade is to lessen the production of wealth. But protective tariffs also operate to alter the distribution of wealth, by imposing higher prices on some citizens and giving extra profits' to others. This alteration of distribution in their favor is the impelling motive with those most active in pro- curing the imposition of protective duties and in warn- ing workmen of the dire calamities that will come on them if such duties are repealed. But in what way can protective tariffs affect the distribution of wealth in favor of labor? The direct object and effect of pro- tective tariffs is to raise the price of commodities. But men who work for wages are not sellers of Com- modities; they are sellers of labor. They sell labor in order that they may buy commodities. How can in- crease in the price of commodities benefit them 7 I speak of price in conformity to the custom of comparing other values by that of money. But money is only a medium of exchange and a measure of the comparative values of other things. Money itself rises and falls in value as compared with other things, vary- ing between time and time, and place and place. In reality the only true and final standard of values is labor—the real value of anything being the amount of labor it will command in exchange. To speak ex- actly, therefore, the effect of a protective tariff is to in- Crease the amount of labor for which certain commodi- ties will exchange. Hence it reduces the value of labor just as it increases the value of commodities. Imagine a tariff that prevented the coming in of laborers, but placed no restriction on the coming in of commodities. Would those who have commodities to sell deem such a tariff for their benefit? Yet to say this 212 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. would be as reasonable as to say that a tariff upon com. modities is for the benefit of those who have labor to sell. It is not true that the products of lower priced labor will drive the products of higher priced labor out of any market in which they can be freely sold, since, as we have already seen, low priced labor does not mean cheap production, and it is the comparative, not the absolute, cost of production that determines exchanges. And we have but to look around to see that even in the same Occupation, wages paid for labor whose products sell freely together, are generally higher in large cities than in small towns, in some districts than in others. It is true that there is a constant tendency of all wages to a common level, and that this tendency arises from competition. But this competition is not the competition of the goods market; it is the competition of the labor market. The differences between the wages paid in the production of goods that sell freely in the same market cannot arise from checks on the competition of goods for sale; but manifestly arises from checks on the competition of labor for employ- ment. As the competition of labor varies between employment and employment, or between place and place, so do wages vary. "The cost of living being greater in large cities than in Small towns, the higher wages in the one are not more attractive than the lower wages in the other, while the differing rates of wages in different districts are manifestly maintained by the inertia and friction which retard the flow of population, or by causes, physical or social, which produce differ- ences in the intensity of competition in the labor market. PROTECTION AND WAGES. 213 - The tendency of wages to a common level is quickest in the same Occupation, because the transference of labor is easiest. There cannot be, in the same place, such differences in wages in the same industry as may exist between different industries, sincelabor in the same industry can transfer itself from employer to employer with far less difficulty than is involved in changing an occupation. There are times when we see one em- ployer reducing wages and others following his exam- ple, but this occurs too quickly to be caused by the com- petition of the goods market. It occurs at times when there is great competition in the labor market, and the same conditions which enable one employer to reduce wages enable others to do the same. If it were the com- petition of the goods market that brought wages to a level, they could not be raised in one establishment or in one locality unless at the same time raised in others that supplied the same market; whereas, at the times : when wages go up, we see workmen in one establish- ment or in One locality first demanding an increase, and then, if they are successful, workmen in other establish- ments or localities following their example. If we pass now to a comparison of occupation with occupation, we see that although there is a tendency to a common level, which maintains between wages in different occupations a certain relation, there are, in the same time and place, great differences of wages. These differences are notinconsistent with this tendency, but are due to it, just as the rising of a balloon and the falling of a stone exemplify the same physical law. While the competition of the labor market tends to bring wages in all occupations to a common level, there are differences between occupations (which may 214 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. be summed up as differences in attraction and differ- ences in the difficulty of access) that check in various de- grees the competition of labor and produce different rela- tive levels of wages. Though these differences exist, wages in different occupations are nevertheless held in a certain relation to each other by the tendency to a com- mon level, so that a reduction of wages in one trade tends to bring about a reduction in others, not through the competition of the goods market, but through that of the labor market. Thus cabinet makers, for instance, could not long get $2 where workmen in other trades as easily learned and practised were only getting $1, since the superior wages would so attract labor to cabinet making as to increase competition and bring wages down. But if the cabinet makers pos- sessed a union strong enough to strictly limit the num- ber of new workmen entering the trade, is it not clear that they could continue to get $2 while in other trades similar labor was only getting $17 As a matter of fact, trades-unions, by checking the competition of labor, have considerably raised wages in many occupations, and have even brought about differences between the wages of union and non-union men in the same occupation. And what limits the possibility of thus raising wages is clearly not the free sale of commodi- ties, but the difficulty of restricting the competition of labor. Do not these facts show that what American work- men have to fear is not the sale in our goods market of the products of “cheap foreign labor,” but the trans- ference to our labor market of that labor itself? Under the conditions existing over the greater part of the civilized world, the minimum of wages is fixed by what PROTECTION AND wages. 215 economists call the “standard of comfort”—that is to say, the poorer the mode of life to which laborers are accustomed the lower are their wages and the greater is their ability to compel a reduction in any labor market they enter. What, then, shall we say of that sort of “protection of American working-men” which, while imposing duties upon goods, under the pretense that they are made by “pauper labor,” freely admits the “pauper laborer" himself. The in-coming of the products of cheap labor is a very different thing from the in-coming of cheap labor. The effect of the one is upon the production of wealth, in- creasing the aggregate amount to be distributed; the effect of the other is upon the distribution of wealth, decreasing the proportion which goes to the working classes. We might permit the free importation of Chinese commodities without in the slightest degree affecting wages; but, under our present conditions, the free immigration of Chinese laborers would lessen wages. Let us imagine under the general conditions of modern civilization, one country of comparatively high wages, and another country of comparatively low wages. Let us, in imagination, bring these countries side by side, separating them only by a wall which permits the free transmission of commodities, but is impassable for human beings. Can we imagine, as pro- tectionist notions require, that the high wage country would do all the importing and the low wage country all the exporting, until the demand for labor so lessened in the one country that wages would fall to the level of the other? That would be to imagine that the former country would go on pushing its commodities through this wall and getting back nothing in return. Clearly 216 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. the one country would export no more than it got a return for, and the other could import no more than it gave a return for. What would go on between the two countries is the exchange of their respective productions, and, as previously pointed out, what commodities passed each way in this exchange would be determined, not by the difference in wages between the two countries, nor yet by differences between them in cost of production, but by differences in each country in the comparative cost of producing different things. This exchange of commodities would go on to the mutual advantage of both countries, increasing the amount which each ob- tained, but no matter to what dimensions it grew, how could it lessen the demand for labor or have any effect in reducing wages? Now let us change the supposition and imagine such a barrier between the two countries as would prevent the passage of commodities, while permitting the free passage of men. No goods produced by the lower paid labor of the one country could now be brought into the other; but would this prevent the reduction of wages? Manifestly not. Employers in the higher wage coun- try, being enabled to get in laborers willing to work for less, could quickly lower wages. What we may thus see by aid of the imagination accords with what we do see as a matter of fact. In spite of the high duties which shut out commodities on the pretense of protecting American labor, Ameri- can workmen in all trades are being forced into combi- nations to protect themselves by checking the compe- tition of the labor market. Our protective tariff on commodities raises the price of commodities, but what raising there is of wages has been accomplished by PROTECTION AND WAGES. 217 trades-unions and the Knights of Labor. Break up these organizations and what would the tariff do to pre- vent the forcing down of wages in all the now organized trades? A scheme really intended for the protection of work- ing-men from the competition of cheap labor would not merely prohibit the importation of cheap labor under contract, but would prohibit the landing of any laborer who had not sufficient means to raise him above the necessity of competing for wages, or who did not give bonds to join some trades-union and abide by its rules. And if, under such a scheme, any duties on commodi- ties were imposed, they would be imposed, in preference, on such commodities as could be produced with small capital, not on those which require large capital—that is to say, the effort would be to protect industries in which workmen can readily engage on their own ac- count, rather than those in which the mere workman can never hope to become his own employer. Our tariff, like all protective tariffs, aims at nothing of this kind. It shields the employing producer from competition, but in no way attempts to lessen competi- tion among those who must sell him their labor; and the industries it aims to protect are those in which the mere workman, or even the workman with a small capital, is helpless—those which cannot be carried on without large establishments, costly machinery, great amounts of capital, or the ownership of natural oppor- tunities which bear a high price. It is manifest that the aim of protection is to lessen competition in the selling of commodities, not in the selling of labor. In no case, save in the peculiar and exceptional cases I shall hereafter speak of, can a tariff 19 218 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. on commodities benefit those who have labor, not com, modities, to sell. Nor is there in our tariff any pro- vision that aims at compelling such employers as it benefits to share their benefits with their workmen. While it gives these employers protection in the goods market it leaves them free trade in the labor market, and for any protection they need workmen have to Or- ganize. I am not saying that any tariff could raise wages. I am merely pointing out that in our protective tariff there is no attempt, however inefficient, to do this—that the whole aim and spirit of protection is not the pro- tection of the sellers of labor but the protection of the buyers of labor, not the maintaining of wages but the maintaining of profits. The very class that profess anx- iety to protect American labor by raising the price of what they themselves have to sell, notoriously buy labor as cheap as they can and fiercely oppose any combina- tion of workmen to raisewages. The cry of “protection for American labor” comes most vociferously from news- papers that lie under the ban of the printers' unions; from coal and iron lords who, importing “pauper la- bor” by wholesale, have bitterly fought every effort of their men to claim anything like decent wages; and from factory owners who claim the right to dictate the votes of men. The whole spirit of protection is against the rights of labor. This is so obvious as hardly to need illustration, but there is a case in which it is so clearly to be seen as to tempt me to reference. There is one kind of labor in which capital has no advantage, and that a kind which has been held from remote antiquity to redound to the true greatness and PROTECTION AND WAGES. 219 glory of a country—the labor of the author, a species of labor hard in itself, requiring long preparation, and in the vast majority of cases extremely meagre in its pecu- niary returns. What protection have the protectionist majorities that have so long held sway in Congress given to this kind of labor 7 While the American manufac- turer of books—the employing capitalist who puts them on the market—has been carefully protected from the competition of foreign manufacturers, the American author has not only not been protected from the com- petition of foreign authors, but has been exposed to the competition of labor for which nothing whatever is paid, He has never asked for any protection save that of common justice, but this has been steadily refused, Foreign-made books have been saddled with a high pro- tective duty, a force of customs examiners is maintained in the post-Office, and an American is not even allowed to accept the present of a book from a friend abroad without paying a tax for it.” But this is not to protect the American author, who as an author is a mere la- borer, but to protect the American publisher, who is a capitalist. And this capitalist, so carefully protected * Although a great sum is raised in the United States every year to send the Bible to the heathen in foreign parts, we impose for the protection of the home “Bible manufacturer’’ a heavy tax upon the bringing of Bibles into our country. There have recently been complaints of the smuggling of Bibles across our northern frontier, which have doubtless inspired our custom-house officers to renewed vigilance, since, according to an official advertisement, the following property seized for violation of the United States revenue laws was sold at public auction in front of the Custom House, Detroit, on Saturday, February 6, 1886, at 12 o'clock noon: 1 set silver jew- elry, 3 bottles of brandy, 7 yards astrachan, 1 silk tidy, 7 books, 1 shawl, 1 sealskin cloak, 4 rosaries, 1 woolen shirt, 2 pairs of mit- tens, 1 pair of stockings, 1 bottle of gin, 1 Bible, 220 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. as to what he has to sell, has been permitted to compel the American author to compete with stolen labor. Congress, which year after year has been maintaining a heavy tariff, on the hypocritical plea of protecting American labor, has steadily refused the bare justice of acceding to an international copyright which would prevent American publishers from stealing the work of foreign authors, and enable American authors not only to meet foreign authors on fair terms at home, but to get payment for their books when reprinted in foreign countries. An international copyright, demand- ed as it is by honor, by morals and by every dictate of patriotic policy, has always been opposed by the pro- tective interest.* Could anything more clearly show that the real motive of protection is always the profit of the employing capitalist, never the benefit of labor? What would be thought of the Congressman who should propose, as a “working-man's measure,” to di- vide the surplus in the treasury between two or three railway kings, and who should gravely argue that to do this would be to raise wages in all occupations, since the railway kings, finding themselves so much richer, would at once raise the wages of their employees; which would lead to the raising of wages on all railways, and this again to the raising of wages in all occupations. Yet the contention that protective duties on goods raise wages involves just such assumptions. It is claimed that protection raises the wages of labor —that is to say, of labor generally. It is not merely contended that it raises wages in the special industries protected by the tariff. That would be to confess that *An exception is to be made in favor of Horace Greeley, who though a protectionist, did advocate an international copyright. pROTECTION AND WAGES. 221 the benefits of protection are distributed with partiality, a thing which its advocates are ever anxious to deny. It is always assumed by protectionists that the benefits of protection are felt in all industries, and even the wages of farm laborers (in an industry which in the United States is not and cannot be protected by the tariff) are pointed to as showing the results of protec- tion. The scheme of protection is, by checking importation to increase the price of protected commodities so as to enable the home producers of these commodities to make larger profits. It is only as it does this, and so long as it does this, that protection can have any en- couraging effect at all, and whatever effect it has upon wages must be derived from this. I have already shown that protection cannot, except temporarily, increase the profits of producers as pro- ducers, but without regard to this it is clear that the contention that protection raises wages involves two assumptions: (1) that increase in the profits of em- ployers means increase in the wages of their workmen; and (2) that increase of wages in the protected occu- pations involves increase of wages in all occupations. To state these assumptions is to show their absurdity. Is there anyone who really supposes that because an employer makes larger profits he therefore pays higher wages? I rode not long since on the platform of a Brooklyn horse-car and talked with the driver. He told me, bitterly and despairingly, of his long hours, hard work and poor pay—how he was chained to that car, a verier slave than the horses he drove; and how by turning himself into this kind of a horse-driving machine he 222 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. could barely keep wife and children, laying by nothing for a “rainy day.” I said to him, “Would it not be a good thing if the Legislature were to pass a law allowing the com- panies to raise the fare from five to six cents, so as to enable them to raise the wages of their drivers and conductors?” The driver measured me with a quick glance, and then exclaimed: “They give us more, because they made more 1 You might raise the fare to six cents or to sixty cents, and they would not pay us a penny more. No matter how much they made, we would get no more, so long as there are hundreds of men waiting and anxious to take our places. The company would pay higher dividends or water the stock; not raise our pay.” . Was not the driver right? Buyers of labor, like buyers of other things, pay, not according to what they can, but according to what they must. There are oc- casional exceptions, it is true; but these exceptions are referable to motives of benevolence, which the shrewd business man keeps out of his business, no matter how much he may otherwise indulge them. Whether you raise the profits of a horse-car company or of a manu- facturer, neither will on that account pay any higher wages. Employers never give the increase of their profits as a reason for raising the wages of their work- men, though they frequently assign decreased profits as a reason for reducing wages. But this is an excuse, not a reason. The true reason is that the dull times which diminish their profits increase the competition of work- men for employment. Such excuses are given only when employers feel that if they reduce wages their PROTECTION AND WAGES. 223 employees will be compelled to submit to the reduc- tion, since others will be glad to step into their places. And where trades-unions succeed in checking this com- petition they are enabled to raise wages. Since my talk with the driver, the horse-car employees of New York and Brooklyn, organized into assemblies of the Knights of Labor and supported by that association, have succeeded in somewhat raising their pay and shortening their hours, thus gaining what no increase in the profits of the companies would have had the slightest tendency to give them. No matter how much a protective duty may increase the profits of employers, it will have no effect in raising Wages unless it so acts upon competition as to give Workmen power to compel an increase of wages. There are cases in which a protective duty may have this effect, but only to a small extent and for a short time. When a duty, by increasing the demand for a certain domestic production, suddenly increases the de- mand for a certain kind of skilled labor, the wages of such labor may be temporarily increased, to an extent and for a time determined by the difficulties of obtaining skilled laborers from other countries or of the acquire- ment by new laborers of the needed skill. But in any industry it is only the few workmen of peculiar skill who can thus be affected, and even when by these few such an advantage is gained, it can only be maintained by trades-unions that limit entrance to the craft. The cases are, I think, few indeed in which any increase of wages has thus been gained by even that small class of workmen who in any protected industry require such exceptional skill that their ranks cannot easily be swelled; and the cases are fewer still, if they 224 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. exist at all, in which the difficulties of bringing work. men from abroad, or of teaching new workmen, have long sufficed to maintain such increase. As for the great mass of those engaged in the protected industries, their labor can hardly be called skilled. Much of it can be performed by ordinary unskilled laborers, and much of it does not even need the physical strength of the adult man, but consists of the mere tending of ma- chinery, or of manipulations which can be learned by boys and girls in a few weeks, a few days, or even a few hours. As to all this labor, which constitutes by far the greater part of the labor required in the industries we most carefully protect, any temporary effect which a tariff might have to increase wages in the way pointed out would be so quickly lost that it could hardly be said to come into operation. For an increase in the wages of such occupations would at once be counter- acted by the flow of labor from other occupations. And it must be remembered that the effect of “encour- aging” any industry by taxation is necessarily to dis- courage other industries, and thus to force labor into the protected industries by driving it out of others. Nor could wages be raised if the bounty which the tariff aims to give employing producers were given directly to their workmen. If, instead of laws intended to add to the profits of the employing producers in certain industries, we were to make laws by which so much should be added to the wages of the workmen, the increased competition which the bounty would cause would soon bring wages plus the bounty to the rate at which wages stood without the bounty. The result would be what it was in England when, during the early part of this century, it was attempted to im. PROTECTION AND WAGES. 225 prove the miserable condition of agricultural laborers by “grants in aid of wages” from parish rates. Just as these grants were made, so did the wages paid by the farmers sink. The car-driver was right. Nothing could raise his wages that did not lessen the competition of those who stood ready to take his place for the wages he was get- ting. If we were to enact that every car-driver should be paid a dollar a day additional from public funds, the result would simply be that the men who are anxious to get places as car-drivers for the wages now paid would be as anxious to get them at one dollar less. If we were to give every car-driver two dollars a day, the companies would be able to get men without pay- ing them anything, just as where restaurant waiters are customarily feed by the patrons, they get little or no wages, and in some cases even pay a bonus for their places. But if it be preposterous to imagine that any effect a tariff may have to raise profits in the protected in: dustries can raise wages in those industries, what shall we say of the notion that such raising of wages in the protected industries would raise wages in all industries 7 This is like saying that to dam the Hudson River would raise the level of New York Harbor and conse- quently that of the Atlantic Ocean. Wages, like water, tend to a level, and unless raised in the lowest and widest occupations can be raised in any particular oc- cupation only as it is walled in from competition. The general rate of wages in every country is mani- festly determined by the rate in the occupations which require least special skill, and to which the man who has nothing but his labor can most easily resort. As 226 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. they engage the greater body of labor these occupations constitute the base of the industrial organization, and are to other occupations what the ocean is to its bays. The rate of wages in the higher occupations can be raised above the rate prevailing in the lower, only as the higher occupations are shut off from the inflow of labor by their greater risk or uncertainty, by their requirement of superior skill, education or natural ability, or by re- strictions such as those imposed by trades-unions. And to secure anything like a general rise of wages, or even to secure a rise of wages in any occupation upon ingress to which restrictions are not at the same time placed, it is necessary to raise wages in the lower and wider oc- cupations. That is to say, to return to our former illus- tration, the level of the bays and harbors that open into it cannot be raised until the level of the ocean is raised. If it were evident in no other way, the recognition of this general principle would suffice to make it clear that duties on imports can never raise the general rate of wages. For import duties can only “protect” oc- cupations in which there is not sufficient labor employed to produce the supply we need. The labor thus en- gaged can never be more than a fraction of the labor en- gaged in producing commodities of which we not only provide the home supply but have a surplus for export, and the labor engaged in work that must be done on the spot. No matter what the shape or size of an iceberg, the mass above the water must be very much less than the mass below the water. So no matter what be the con- ditions of a country or what the peculiarities of its in- dustry, that part of its labor engaged in occupations PROTECTION AND WAG.E.S. 227 that can be “protected” by import duties must always be small as compared with that engaged in Occupations that cannot be protected. In the United States, where protection has been carried to the utmost, the census returns show that not more than one-twentieth of the labor of the country is engaged in protected industries. In the United States, as in the world at large, the low- est and widest occupations are those in which men apply their labor directly to nature, and of these agriculture is the most important. How quickly the rise of wages in these occupations will increase wages in all occu- pations was shown in the early days of California, as afterward in Australia. Had anything happened in California to increase the demand for cooks or car- penters or painters, the rise in such wages would have been quickly met by the inflow of labor from other occupations, and in this way retarded and finally neu- tralized. But the discovery of the placer mines, which greatly raised the wages of unskilled labor, raised wages in all occupations. The difference of wages between the United States and European countries is itself an illustration of this principle. During our colonial days, before we had any protective tariff, ordinary wages were higher here than in Europe. The reason is clear. Land being easy to obtain, the laborer could readily employ himself, and wages in agriculture being thus maintained at a higher level, the general rate of wages was higher. And since up to the present time it has been easier to obtain land here than in Europe, the higher rate of wages in agri- culture has kept up a higher general rate. - To raise the general rate of wages in the United States the wages of agricultural labor must be raised. But 228 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. our tariff does not and cannot raise even the price of agricultural produce, of which we are exporters, not im- porters. Yet, even had we as dense a population in proportion to our available land as Great Britain, and were we, like her, importers not exporters of agricult- ural productions, a protective tariff upon such produc- tions could not increase agricultural wages, still less could it increase wages in other occupations, which would then have become the widest. This we may see by the effect of the corn laws in Great Britain, which was to increase, not the wages of the agricultural laborer, nor even the profits of the farmer, but the rent of the agricultural landlord. And even if the differentiation between land-owner, farmer and laborer had, under the conditions I speak of, not become as clear here as in Great Britain, nothing which benefited the farmer would have the slightest tendency to raise wages, save as it benefited him, not as an owner of land or an owner of capital, but as a laborer. We thus see from theory that protection cannot raise wages. That it does not, facts show conclusively. This has been seen in Spain, in France, in Mexico, in England during protection times, and everywhere that protection has been tried. In countries where the working classes have little or no influence upon government it is never even pretended that protection raises wages. It is only in countries like the United States, where it is necessary to cajole the working class, that such a preposterous plea is made. And here the failure of protection to raise wages is shown by the most evident facts. Wages in the United States are higher than in other countries, not because of protection, but because we have had much vacant land to overrun. Before we had any PROTECTION AND WAGES. 229 tariff, wages were higher here than in Europe, and far higher, relatively to the productiveness of labor, than they are now after our years of protection. In spite of all our protection—and, for the last twenty-four years at least, protectionists have had it all their own way—the condition of the laboring classes of the United States has been slowly but steadily sinking to that of the “pauper labor” of Europe. It does not follow that this is because of protection, but it is certain that pro- tection has proved powerless to prevent it. To discover whether protection has or has not bene- fited the working classes of the United States it is not necessary to array tables of figures which only an ex- pert can verify and examine. The determining facts are notorious. It is a matter of common knowledge that those to whom we have given power to tax the Ameri- can people “for the protection of American industry,” pay their employees as little as they can, and make no scruple of importing the very foreign labor against whose products the tariff is maintained. It is notorious that wages in the protected industries are, if anything, lower than in the unprotected industries, and that, though the protected industries do not employ more than a twentieth of the working population of the United States, there occur in them more strikes, more lock outs, more attempts to reduce wages, than in all other industries. In the highly protected industries of Massachusetts, official reports declare that the operative cannot get a living without the work of wife and chil- dren. In the highly protected industries of New Jer- sey, many of the “protected" laborers are children whose parents are driven by their necessities to find employment for them by misrepresenting their age so 20 230 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. as to evade the State law. In the highly protected in- dustries of Pennsylvania, laborers, for whose sake we are told this high protection is imposed, are working for sixty-five cents a day, and half-clad women are feed- ing furnace fires. “Pluck-me stores,” company tene- ments and boarding-houses, Pinkerton detectives and mercenaries, and all the forms and evidences of the op- pression and degradation of labor are, throughout the country, characteristic of the protected industries. The greater degradation and unrest of labor in the protected than in the unprotected industries may in part be accounted for by the fact that the protected employers have been the largest importers of “foreign pauper labor.” But, in some part, at least, it is due to the greater fluctuations to which the protected in- dustries are exposed. Being shut off from foreign markets, Scarcity of their productions cannot be so quickly met by importation, nor surplus relieved by exportation, and so with them for much of the time it is either “a feast or a famine.” These violent fluctua- tions tend to bring workmen into a state of dependence, if not of actual peonage, and to depress wages below the general standard. But whatever be the reason, the fact is that so far is protection from raising wages in the protected industries, that the capitalists who carry them on would soon “enjoy "even lower priced labor than now, were it not that wages in them are kept up by the rate of wages in the unprotected industries. CELAPTER XX. THE ABOLITION OF PROTECTION. OUR inquiry has sufficiently shown the futility and absurdity of protection. It only remains to consider the plea that is always set up for protection when other ex- cuses fail—the plea that since capital has been invested and industry organized upon the basis of protection it would be unjust and injurious to abolish protective duties at once, and that their reduction must be gradual and slow. This plea for delay, though accepted and even urged by many of those who up to this time have been the most conspicuous opponents of protection, will not bear examination. If protection be unjust, if it be an infringement of equal rights that gives certain citizens the power to tax other citizens, then anything short of its complete and immediate abolition involves a continu- ance of injustice. No One can acquire a vested right in a wrong; no one can claim property in a privilege. To admit that privileges which have no other basis than a legislative Act cannot at any time be taken away by legislative Act, is to commit ourselves to the absurd doctrine that has been carried to such a length in Great Britain, where it is held that a sinecure cannot be abol- ished without buying out the incumbent, and that be- cause a man's ancestors have enjoyed the privilege of living on other people, he and his descendants, to the remotest time, have acquired a sacred right to live upon 232 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. other people. The true doctrine—of which we ought never, on any pretense, to yield one iota—is that enun- ciated in our Declaration of Independence, the self-evi- dent doctrine that men are endowed by their Creator with equal and unalienable rights, and that any law or institution that denies or impairs this natural equality may at any time be altered or abolished. And no more Salutary lesson could to-day be taught to capitalists throughout the world than that justice is an element in the safety of investments, and that the man who trades , upon the ignorance or the enslavement of a people does So at his own risk. A few such lessons, and every throne in Europe would topple, and every great standing army melt away. Moreover, abolition at once is the only way in which the industries now protected could be treated with any fairness. The gradual abolition of protection would give rise to the same scrambling and pipe-laying and log-rolling which every tariff change brings about, and the stronger would save themselves at the expense of the weaker. But further than this, the gradual abolition of pro- tection would not only continue for a long time, though in a diminishing degree, the waste, loss and injustice inseparable from the system, but during all this period the anticipation of coming changes and the uncertainty in regard to them would continue to inspire insecurity and depress business; whereas, were protection abol- ished at once, the shock, whatever it might be, would soon be over, and exchange and industry could at once reorganize upon a sure basis. Even on the theory that the abolition of protection involves temporary disaster, immediate abolition is as preferable to gradual abolition THE ABOLITION OF PROTECTION. 233 as amputation at one operation is to amputation by inches. * And to the working classes—the classes for whom those who deplore sudden change profess to have most concern—the difference would be greater still. It is always to the relative advantage of the poorer classes that any change involving disaster should be as sudden as possible, since the effect of delay is simply to give the richer classes opportunity to avoid it at the expense of the poorer. If there is to be a certain loss to any community, whether by flood, by fire, by invasion, by pestilence, or by commercial convulsion, that loss will fall more lightly on the poor and more heavily on the rich the shorter the time in which it is concentrated. If the cur- rency of a country slowly depreciates, the depreciating currency will be forced into the hands of those least able to protect themselves, the price of commodities will ad- vance in anticipation of the depreciation, while the price of labor will lag along after it; capitalists will have op- portunity to make secure their loans and to speculate in advancing prices, and the loss will thus fall with far greater relative severity upon the poor than upon the rich. In the same way, if a depreciated currency be slowly restored to par, the price of labor falls more quickly than the price of commodities; debtors struggle along in the endeavor to pay their obligations in an ap- preciating currency, and those who have the most means are best able to avoid the disadvantages and avail them- selves of the speculative opportunities brought about by the change. But the more suddenly any given change in the value of currency takes place the more equal will be its effects. 234 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. So it is with the imposition of public burdens. It is manifestly to the advantage of , the poorer class that any great public expense be met at once rather than spread over years by means of public debts. Thus, if the expenses of our Civil War had been met by taxation levied at the time, such taxation must have fallen heav- ily upon the rich. But by the device of a public debt —a twin invention to that of indirect taxation—the cost of the war was not, as was pretended, shifted from present time to future time (for that would only have been possible had the means to carry on the war been borrowed from abroad, which was not the case), but taxation, which otherwise must have fallen upon in- dividuals in proportion to their wealth, was changed into taxation spread over a long series of years and falling upon individuals in proportion, not to their means, but to their consumption, thus imposing upon the poor far greater relative burdens than upon the rich. Whether the rich would have had the patriotism to support a war which thus called upon them for sacrifices more com- mensurate with those of the poor, who in all wars furnish the far greater portion of “the food for powder,” is an- other matter; but it is certain that the spreading of the war taxation over years has not only made the cost of the war many times greater, but has been to the advan- tage of the rich and to the disadvantage of the working classes. If the abolition of protection is, as protectionists pre- dict, certain to disorganize trade and industry, then it is better for all, and especially is it better for the work- ing classes, that the change should be sharp and short, If the return to a natural condition of trade and pro. duction must temporarily throw men out of employ. THE ABOLITION OF PROTECTION. . 235 ment, then it is better that they should be thrown out at once and have done with it, than that the same loss of employment should be spread over a series of years with a constant depressing effect upon the labor market. In a sharp but short period of depression the public purse could, without serious consequences, be drawn upon to relieve distress, but any attempt to relieve in that way the less general but more protracted distress incident to a long period of depression, would tend to create an army of habitual paupers. But, in truth, the talk about the commercial convul- sions and industrial distress that would follow the ab- olition of protection is as baseless as the story with which Southern slave-holders during the war attempted to keep their chattels from running away—that the Northern armies would sell them to Cuba; as baseless as the predictions of Republican politicians that the election of a Democratic President would mean the as- sumption of the Confederate debt, if not the revival of the “Lost Cause.” The real fear that underlies all this talk of the dis- astrous effects of the sudden abolition of protection was well exemplified in a conversation a friend of mine had awhile ago with a large manufacturer, who belongs to a combination which prevents competition at home while the tariff prevents competition from abroad. The manufacturer was inveighing against any meddling with the tariff, and dilating upon the ruin that would be brought upon the country by free trade. “Yes,” said my friend, who had been listening with an air of sympathetic attention, “I suppose, if the tariff were abolished, you would have to shut up your works.” “Well, no; not quite that,” said the manufacturer. 236 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. “We could go ahead, even with free trade; but then— we couldn't get the same profit.” The notion that our manufactures would be suspend- ed and our iron works closed and our coal mines shut down by the abolition of protection is a notion akin to that of “the tail wagging the dog.” Where are the goods to come from which are thus to deluge our mar- kets, and how are they to be paid for 2 There is not productive power enough in Europe to supply them, nor are there ships to transport them, to say nothing of the effect upon European prices of the demands of sixty millions of people, who, head for head, consume more than any other people in the world. And since other countries are not going to deluge us with the products of their labor without demanding the products of our own labor in payment, any increase in our imports from the abolition of protection would involve a correspond- ing increase in exports. The truth is that, the change would not only be beneficial to our industries at large—four-fifths of which, at least, are not brought into competition with imported commodities, but it would be beneficial even to the “protected" industries. In those that are ‘sheltered by home monopolies, profits would be re- duced, in those in which the tariff permits the use of inferior machinery and slovenly methods, better ma- chinery would have to be provided and better methods introduced ; but in the great bulk of our manufacturing industries, the effect would only be beneficial, the re- duction in the cost of material far more than compen- sating for the reduction in prices. And with a lower cost of production foreign markets from which our manufacturers are now shut out would be opened. If THE ABOLITION OF PROTECTION. 237 any industry would be “crushed” it could only be some industry now carried on at national loss. The increased power which the removal of restric- tions upon trade would give in the production of wealth would be felt in all directions. Instead of a collapse there would be a revivification of industry. Rings would be broken up, and where profits are now exces- sive they would come down; but production would go on under healthier conditions and with greater energy. American manufacturers would begin to find markets the whole world over. American ships would again sail the high seas. The Delaware would ring like the Clyde with the clash of riveting hammers, and the United States would rapidly take that first place in the industrial and commercial world to which her popula- tion and her natural resources entitle her, but which is now occupied by England, while legislation and admin- istration would be relieved of a great cause of corrup- tion, and all governmental reforms would be made easier. CEIAPTER XXI. INADEQUACY OF THE FREE TRADE ARGUMENT. THE point we have now reached is that at which discussions of the tariff question usually end—the ex- treme limit to which the avowed champions of the op- posing policies carry their controversy. We have, in fact, reached the legitimate end of our inquiry so far as it relates to the respective merits of protection and free trade. The stream, whose course our examination has been following, here blends with other streams, and though it still flows on, it is as part of a wider and deeper river. As he who would trace the waters of the Ohio to their final union with the ocean cannot stop when the Ohio ends, but must still follow on that mighty Mississippi which unites streams from far different sources, so, as I said in the begin- ning, to really understand the tariff question we must go beyond the tariff question. This we may now see. So far as relates to questions usually debated between protectionists and free traders our inquiry is now com- plete and conclusive. We have seen the absurdity of protection as a general principle and the fallacy of the special pleas that are made for it. We have seen that protective duties cannot increase the aggregate wealth of the country that enforces them, and have no tendency to give a greater proportion of that wealth to the work- ing class. We have seen that their tendencies, on the INADEQUACY OF THE FREE TRADE ARGUMENT. 289 contrary, are to lessen aggregate wealth, and to foster monopolies at the expense of the masses of the people. But although we have directly or inferentially dis- proved every argument that is made for protection, although we have seen conclusively that protection is in its nature inimical to general interests, and that free trade is in its nature promotive of general interests, yet if our inquiry were to stop here we should not have ac- complished the purpose with which we set out. For my part, did it end here, I would deem the labor I have sofar spent in writing this book little better than wasted. For all that we have seen has, with more or less coherence and clearness, been shown again and again. Yet protec- tion still retains its hold on the popular mind. And until something more is shown, protection will retain this hold. In exposing the fallacies of protection I have endeav- ored in each case to show what has made the fallacy plausible, but it still remains to explain why such ex- posures produce so little effect. The very conclusive- ness with which our examination has disproved the claims of protection will suggest that there must be something more to be said, and may well prompt the question, “If the protective theory is really so incon- gruous with the nature of things and so inconsistent with itself, how is it that after so many years of discus- sion it still obtains such wide and strong support?” Free traders usually attribute the persistence of the belief in protection to popular ignorance, played upon by special interests. But this explanation will hardly satisfy an unbiased mind. Vitality inheres in truth, not in error. Though accepted error has always the strength of habit and authority, and the battle against it 240 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. must always be hard at first, yet the tendency of discus- sion in which error is confronted with truth is to make the truth steadily clearer. That a theory which seems wholly false holds its ground in popular belief despite wide and long discussion, should prompt its opponents to inquire whether their arguments have really gone to the roots of popular belief, and whether this belief does not derive support from truths they have not con- sidered, or from errors not yet exposed, which still pass for truths—rather than to attribute its vitality to popu- lar incapacity to recognize truth. I shall hereafter show that the protective idea does indeed derive support from doctrines that have been ac. tively taught and zealously defended by the very econo- mists who have assailed it (who, so to speak, have been vigorously defending protection with the right hand while raining blows upon it with the left), and from habits of thought which the opponents no less than the advocates of protection have failed to call in question. But what I now wish to point out is the inadequacy of the arguments which free traders usually rely on to con- vince working-men that the abolition of protection is for their interest. In our examination we have gone as far, and in cer- tain respects somewhat further than free traders usually go. But what have we proved as to the main issue? Merely that it is the tendency of free trade to increase the production of wealth, and thus to permit of the increase of wages, and that it is the tendency of protection to decrease the production of wealth and foster certain monopolies. But from this it does not follow that the abolition of protection would be of any benefit to the working class. The tendency of a brick pushed off INADEQUACY OF THE FREE TRADE ARGUMENT. 241 a chimney top is to fall to the surface of the ground. But it will not fall to the surface of the ground if its fall be intercepted by the roof of a house. The tendency of anything that increases the productive power of labor is to augment wages. But it will not augment wages under conditions in which laborers are forced by compe- tition to offer their services for a mere living. In the United States, as in all countries where politi- cal power is in the hands of the masses, the vital point in the tariff controversy is as to its effect upon the earn- ings of “the poor people who have to work.”” But this point lies beyond the limit to which free traders are accustomed to confine their reasoning. They prove that the tendency of protection is to reduce the production of wealth and to increase the price of com- modities, and from this they assume that the effect of the abolition of protection would be to increase the earn- ings of labor. But not merely is such an assumption logically invalid until it is shown that there is nothing in existing conditions to prevent the working classes from getting the benefit of this tendency; but, although in itself a natural assumption, it is in the minds of “the poor people who have to work” contradicted by obvi- Ous facts. In this is the invalidity of the free trade argument, and here, and not in the ignorance of the masses, is the reason why all attempts to convert working-men to the free-tradeism which would substitute a revenue tariff for a protective tariff must, save under such conditions as existed in England forty years ago, utterly fail. * 1 find this suggestive phrase in a protectionist newspaper But it well expresses the attitude toward labor of many of the freq trade writers also. 21 242 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. While both sides have shown the same indisposition to go to the heart of the controversy, there can be no question that so far as issue is joined between protec- tionists and free traders, in current discussion, the free traders have the best of the argument. But that the belief in protection has survived long and wide discussion, that it seems to spring up again when beaten down and to arise with apparent spontane- ity in communities such as the United States, Canada and Australia, that have grown up without tariffs, and where the system lacks the advantage of inertia and of enlisted interests, proves that beyond the discussion there must be something which strongly commends pro- tection to the popular mind. This may also be inferred from what protectionists themselves say. Beaten in argument, the protectionist usually falls back upon some declaration which implies that the real grounds of his belief have been untouched, and which generally takes the form of an assertion that though free trade may be true in theory it fails in practice. In such form the assertion is untenable. A theory is but an explanation of the relation of facts,. and nothing can be true in theory that is not true in practice. But free traders really beg the question when they answer by merely pointing this out. The real question is, whether the reasoning on which free trad- ers rely takes into account all existing conditions? What the protectionist means, or at least the perception that he appeals to, when he talks in this way of the difference between theory and fact, is, that the free trade theory does not take into account all existing facts. And this is true. As the tariff question is presented, there are indeed, INADEQUACY OF THE FREE TRADE ARGUMENT. 243 under existing-social conditions, two sides to the shield, so that men who only look at one side, closing their eyes to the other, may continue, with equal confidence, to hold opposite opinions. And that the distinction between them may, with not entire inaptness, be described as that of exclusively regarding theory and that of exclu- sively regarding facts, we shall see when we have developed a theory which will embrace all the facts, and which will explain not only why it is that honest men have so diametrically differed upon the question of protection vs. free trade, but why the advocates of neither policy have been inclined to press on to that point where honest differences may be reconciled. For we have reached the place where the Ohio of the tariff question flows into the Mississippi of the great social Question. It need not surprise us that both parties to the controversy, as it has hitherto been conducted, should stop here, for it would be as rational to expect any thorough treatment of the social question from the well-to-do class represented in the English Cobden Club or the American Iron and Steel Association, or from their apologists in professorial chairs, as it would be to look for any thorough treatment of the subject of per- sonal liberty in the controversies of the slave-holding Whigs and slave-holding Democrats of forty years ago, or in the sermons of the preachers whose salaries were paid by them. CHAPTER XXII. THE REAL WEAKNESS OF FREE TRADE. HOW the abolition of protection would stimulate pro- duction, weaken monopolies and relieve government of a great cause of corruption, we have seen. “But what,” it will be asked, “would be the gain to working-men 7 Will wages increase?” For some time, and to some extent, yes. For the spring of industrial energy consequent upon the re- moval of the dead weight of the tariff would for a time make the demand for labor brisker and employment steadier, and in occupations where they can combine, workingmen would have better opportunity to reduce their hours and increase their wages, as, since the abo- lition of the protective tariff in England, many trades there have done. But even from the total abolition of protection, it is impossible to predict any general and permanent increase of wages or any general and perma- nent improvement in the condition of the working classes. The effect of the abolition of protection, great and beneficial though it must be, would in nature be similar to that of the inventions and discoveries which in our time have so greatly increased the production of wealth, yet have nowhere really raised wages or of themselves improved the condition of the working classes. THE REAL WEAKNESS OF FREE TRADE. 245 Here is the weakness of free trade as it is generally advocated and understood. The working-man asks the free trader: “How will the change you propose benefit me?” The free trader can only answer: “It will increase wealth and reduce the cost of commodities.” But in our own time the working-man has seen wealth enormously increased without feeling himself a sharer in the gain. He has seen the cost of commodities great- ly reduced without finding it any easier to live. He looks to England, where a revenue tariff has for some time taken the place of a protective tariff, and there he finds labor degraded and underpaid, a general standard of wages lower than that which prevails here, while such improvements as have been made in the condition of the working classes since the abolition of protection are clearly not traceable to that, but to trades-unions, to temperance and beneficial societies, to emigration, to education, and to such acts as those regulating the labor of women and children, and the sanitary conditions of factories and mines. And seeing this, the working-man, eventhough he may realize with more or less clearness the hypocrisy of the rings and combinations which demand tariff duties for “the protection of American labor,” accepts the fallacies of protection, or at least makes no effort to throw them off, not because of their strength so much as of the weakness of the appeal which free trade makes to him. A considerable proportion, at least, of the most intelli- gent and influential of American working-men are fully consgious that “protection ” does nothing for labor, but neither do they see what free trade could do. And so they regard the tariff question as one of no practical con- 246 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. cern to working-men—an attitude hardly less satisfac. tory to the protected interests than a thorough belief in protection. For when an interest is already intrenched in law and habit of thought, those who are not against it are for it. To prove that the abolition of protection would tend to increase the aggregate wealth is not of itself enough to evoke the strength necessary to overthrow protec- tion. To do that, it must be proved that the abolition of protection would mean improvement in the condition of the masses. It is, as I have said, natural to assume that increased production of wealth would be for the benefit of all, and to a child, a savage, or a civilized man who lived in his study and did not read the daily papers, this would doubtless seem a necessary assumption. Yet, to the majority of men in civilized society, so far is this as- Sumption from seeming necessary, that current explana- tions of the most important social phenomena involve the reverse. Without question the most important social phe- nomena of our time arise from that partial paralysis of industry which in all highly civilized countries is in some degree chronic, and which at recurring periods becomes intensified in widespread and long-continued industrial depressions. What is the current explanation of these phenomena? Is it not that which attributes them to over-production ? This explanation is positively or negatively support- ed even by men who attribute to popular ignorance the failure of the masses to appreciate the benefits of sub- stituting a revenue tariff for a protective tariff. But So long as conditions which bring racking anxiety and THE REAL WEAKNESS OF FREE TRADE. 247 bitter privation to millions are commonly attributed to the over-production of wealth, is it any wonder that a reform which is urged on the ground that it would still further increase the production of wealth should fail to arouse popular enthusiasm 7 If, indeed, it be popular ignorance that gives persist- ence to the belief in protection, it is an ignorance that extends to questions far more important and pressing than any question of tariff—an ignorance that the ad- vocates of free trade have done nothing to enlighten, and that they can do nothing to enlighten until they explain why it is that in spite of the enormous increase of productive power that has been going on with ac- celerating rapidity all this century it is yet so hard for the mere laborer to get a living. In this great fact, that increase in wealth and in the power of producing wealth does not bring any general benefit in which all classes share—does not for the great masses lessen the intensity of the struggle to live, lies the explanation of the popular weakness of free trade. It is owing to the increasing appreciation of this fact, and not to accidental causes, that all over the civilized world the free trade movement has for some time been losing energy. - American revenue reformers delude themselves if they imagine that protection can now be overthrown in the United States by a movement on the lines of the Cobden Club. The day for that has passed. It is true that the British tariff reformers of forty years ago were enabled on these lines to arouse the popular enthusiasm necessary to overthrow protection. But not only did the fact that the British tariff made food dear enable them to appeal to sympathy and 248 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. imagination with a directness and force impossible where the commodities affected by a tariff are not of such prime importance; but the feeling of that time in regard to such reforms was far more hopeful. The great social problems which to-day loom so dark on the horizon of the civilized world were then hardly per- ceived. In the destruction of political tyranny and the removal of trade restrictions ardent and generous spirits saw the emancipation of labor and the eradica- tion of chronic poverty, and there was a confident belief that the industrial inventions and discoveries of the new era which the world had entered would elevate society from its very foundations. The natural assump- tion that increase in the general wealth must mean a general improvement in the condition of the people was then confidently made. But disappointment after disappointment has chilled these hopes, and, just as faith in mere republicanism has weakened, so the power of the appeal that free traders make to the masses has weakened with the decline of the belief that mere increase in the power of production will increase the rewards of labor. In- stead of the abolition of protection in Great Britain being followed, as was expected, by the overthrow of protection everywhere, it is not only stronger through- out the civilized world than it was then, but is again raising its head in Great Britain. It is useless to tell working-men that increase in the general wealth means improvement in their condition. They know by experience that this is not true. The working classes of the United States have seen the general wealth enormously increased, and they have also seen that, as wealth has increased, the fortunes of THE REAL WEAKNESS OF FIREE TRADE. 249 the rich have grown larger, without its becoming a whit easier to get a living by labor. It is true that statistics may be arrayed in such way as to prove to the satisfaction of those who wish to believe it, that the condition of the working classes is steadily improving. But that this is not the fact working-men well know. It is true that the average consumption has increased, and that the cheapening of commodities has brought into common use things that were once considered luxuries. It is also true that in many trades wages have been somewhat raised and hours reduced by combinations among workmen. But although the prizes that are to be gained in the lottery of life—or, if any one prefers so to call them, the prizes that are to be gained by superior skill, energy and foresight—are constantly becoming greater and more glittering, the blanks grow more numerous. The man of superior powers and opportunities may hope to count his millions where a generation ago he could have hoped to count his tens of thousands; but to the ordinary man the chances of failure are greater, the fear of want more pressing. It is harder for the aver- age man to become his own employer, to provide for a family and to guard against contingencies. The anxi- eties attendant on the fear of losing employment are becoming greater and greater, and the fate of him who falls from his place more direful. To prove this it is not necessary to cite the statistics that show how pau- perism, crime, insanity and suicide are increasing faster than our increase in population. Who that reads our daily papers needs any proof that the increase in the aggregate of wealth does not mean increased ease of gaining a living by labor 7 |% 250 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. Here is an item which I take from the papers as I write. I do not take it because equally striking items are rare, but because I find a comment on it which I would also like to quote: “STARVED TO DEATH IN OHIO. “DAYTON, O., August 26.-One of the most horrible deaths that ever occurred in a civilized community was that of Frank Waltz- man, which happened in this city yesterday morning. He has seven children and a wife, and was once a prominent citizen of Xenia, O. He tried his hand at any kind of business where he could find opportunity, and finally was compelled to shovel gravel to get a crust for his children. He worked at this all last week, and on Saturday night was brought home in a wagon, unable to walk. This morning he was dead. An investigation of the affair established the fact that the man had starved to death. The family had been without food for nearly two weeks. His wife tells a horrible story of his death, saying that while he lay dying his children surrounded his couch and sobbed piteously for bread.” And here is the typical comment which the New York Tribune, shocked for a moment out of its attempt to convince working-men that the tariff has improved their condition, makes upon this item : “STARVED TO DEATH. “The Tribune, Tuesday, laid before its readers a very sad story of death by literal starvation, at Dayton, O. The details of this cast must have struck many thoughtful persons as more resembling thq. catastrophes we are accustomed to regard as appertaining to Euro- pean life than those indigenous here. The story is old enough in general outline. First, a merchant, prospering ; then decline of business, bankruptcy, and by degrees destitution, until pride and shame together brought on the culminating disaster. A few years ago it would have been said that such a fact was impossible in America, and certainly there was a time when no one with power and will to work need have starved in any part of this country. During that period, too, the strong elasticity and recuperative power of Americans were the world's wonder. No man thought much of failure in business. The demand for enterprise of all THE REAL WEAKNESS OF FIREE TRADE. 251 kinds was such that no man of ordinary pluck and energy could be kept down. Perhaps this ability to recover was not so much a national peculiarity as an effect of the existing state of Society. Certainly, as things settle more and more into regular grooves in the older States, the parallel between American and European civilization becomes closer, and the Social problems which perplex those Societies are beginning to overshadow this one also. Compe- tition in our centres of population narrows more and more the field of unmoneyed enterprise. It is no longer so easy for those who fall to rise again. And social conventions fetter men more and tend to hold them within narrower bounds. “The poor fellow who starved to death at Dayton the other day suffered an Old World fate. He was down and could not get up. He was deprived of his old resources and could not invent new ones. His large family increased his difficulties. He could not compete successfully with younger and less handicapped contemporaries, and so he sank, as thousands have done in the great capitals of Europe, but as hitherto very fow, it is to be hoped, have sunk in an American community. Yet this is the tendency of a rapid increase of popu- lation and wealth. The struggle becomes fiercer all the time ; and while the exactions of society enslave and hamper the ambitious increasingly, the average fertility of resource and Swift adapta- bility decline, just as the average skill of workmen declines with the perfection of mechanical appliances. Commerce and the arti- ficial requirements of social tyranny have already educated among us a class of people whose lives are a perpetual struggle and as perpetual an hypocrisy. They could live comfortably if they could give up display, but they cannot do it, and so they make themselves wretched and demoralize themselves at the same time. The Sound, healthy American characteristics are being eliminated in this way, and we are rearing up instead a generation of feeble folks who may in turn become the parents of such hewers of wood and drawers of water as the Old World city masses have long been. And here, as there, our remedy and regeneration must come from the more vigorous and better-trained products of the country life.” I will not ask how regeneration is to come from the more vigorous products of the country life, when every census shows a greater and greater proportion of our 252 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. population concentrating in cities, and when country roads to the remotest borders are filled with tramps. I merely reprint this article as a sample of the recogni- tion one meets everywhere, even on the part of those who formally deny it, of the obvious fact, that it is becoming harder and harder for the man who has noth- ing but his own exertions to depend on to get a living in the United States. This fact destroys the assump- tion that our protective tariff raises and maintains wages, but it also makes it impossible to assume that the abolition of protection would in any way alter the tendency which as wealth increases makes the struggle for existence harder and harder. This tendency shows itself throughout the civilized world, and arises from the more unequal distribution which everywhere ac- companies the increase of wealth. How could the abo- lition of protection affect it? The worst that can, in this respect, be said of protection is that it somewhat accelerates this tendency. The best that could be promised for the abolition of protection is that it might somewhat restrain it. In England the same tendency has continued to manifest itself since the abolition of protection, despite the fact that in other ways great agencies for the relief and elevation of the masses have been at work. Increased emigration, the greater diffu- sion of education, the growth of trades-unions, sanitary improvements, the better organization of charity, and governmental regulation of labor and its conditions have during all these years directly tended to improve the condition of the working class. Yet the depths of poverty are as dark as ever, and the contrast be. tween want and wealth more glaring. The Corn-Law Reformers thought to make hunger impossible, but THE REAL WEAKNESS OF FREE TRADE. 253 *, though the Corn laws have long since been abolished, starvation still figures in the mortuary statistics of a country overflowing with wealth. *. While “statisticians” marshal figures to show to Dives's satisfaction how much richer Lazarus is becom- ing, here is what the Congregational clergymen of the greatest and richest of the world's great cities declare in their “Bitter Cry of Outcast London". “While we have been building our churches and Solacing ourselves with our religion and dreaming that the millennium was coming, the poor have been growing poorer, the wretched more miserable and the immoral more corrupt. The gulf has been daily widening which separates the lowest classes of the community from our churches and chapels and from all decency and civilization. It is easy to bring an array of facts which seem to point to the opposite conclusion. But what does it all amount to? We are simply liv- ing in a fool's paradise if we imagine that all these agencies com- bined are doing a thousandth part of what needs to be done. We must face the facts, and these compel the conclusion that this terri- ble flood of sin and misery is gaining on us. It is rising every day.” This is everywhere the testimony of disinterested and sympathetic observers. Those who are raised above the fierce struggle may not realize what is going on beneath them. But whoever chooses to look may see. And when we take into account longer periods of time than are usually considered in discussions as to whether the condition of the working-man has or has not improved with improvement in productive agencies and increase in wealth, here is a great broad fact: Five centuries ago the wealth-producing power of England, man for man, was small indeed compared with what it is now. Not merely were all the great inventions and discoverics which since the introduc- tion of steam have revolutionized mechanical industry then undreamed of, but even agriculture was far ruder 254 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. and less productive. Artificial grasses had not been discovered. The potato, the carrot, the turnip, the beet, and many other plants and vegetables which the farmer now finds most prolific, had not been introduced. The advantages which ensue from rotation of crops were unknown. Agricultural implements consisted of the spade, the sickle, the flail, the rude plow and the har- row. Cattle had not been bred to more than one-half the size they average now, and sheep did not yield half the fleece. Roads, where there were roads, were extremely bad, wheel vehicles scarce and rude, and places a hun- dred miles from each other were, in difficulties of trans- portation, practically as far apart as London and Hong Kong, or San Francisco and New York, are now. Yet patient students of those times—such men as Professor Thorold Rogers, who has devoted himself to the history of prices, and has deciphered the records of colleges, manors and public offices—tell us that the con- dition of the English laborer was not only relatively, but absolutely better in those rude times than it is in England to-day, after five centuries of advance in the productive arts. They tell us that the working-man did not work so hard as he does now, and lived better; that he was exempt from the harassing dread of being forced by loss of employment to want and beggary, or of leaving a family that must apply to charity to avoid starvation. Pauperism as it prevails in the rich Eng- land of the nineteenth century was in the far poorer England of the fourteenth century, absolutely unknown. Medicine was empirical and superstitious, sanitary regulations and precautions were all but unknown. There was frequently plague and occasionally famine, for, owing to the difficulties of transportation, the THE REAL WEAKNESS OF FREE TRADE. 255 scarcity of one district could not be relieved by the plenty of another. But men did not, as they do now, starve in the midst of abundance; and what is perhaps the most significant fact of all is that not only were women and children not worked as they are to-day, but the eight-hour system, which even the working-classes of the United States, with all the profusion of labor-saving machinery and appliances have not yet attained, was then the common system If this be the result of five centuries of such increase in productive power as has never before been known in the world, what ground is there for hoping that the mere abolition of protective tariffs would permanently benefit working-men? And not merely do facts of this kind prevent us from assuming that the abolition of protection could more than temporarily benefit working-men, but they suggest the question, whether it could more than tem- porarily increase the production of wealth 7 : Inequality in the distribution of wealth tends to lessen the production of wealth—on the one side, by lessening intelligence and incentive among workers; and, on the other side, by augmenting the number of idlers and those who minister to them, and by increas- ing vice, crime and waste. Now, if increase in the production of wealth tends to increase inequality in distribution, not only shall we be mistaken in expecting its full effect from anything which tends to increase production, but there may be a point at which increased inequality of distribution will neutralize increased power of production, just as the carrying of too much sail may deaden a ship's way. 256 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. Trade is a labor-saving method of production, and the effect of tariff restrictions upon trade is unquestion- ably to diminish productive power. Yet, important as may be the effects of protection in diminishing the production of wealth, they are far less important than the waste of productive forces which is commonly attributed to the very excess of productive power. The existence of protective tariffs will not suffice to explain that paralysis of industrial forces which in all departments of industry seems to arise from an excess of productive power, over the demand for consumption, and which is everywhere leading to combinations to re- strain production. And considering this, can we feel quite sure that the effect of abolishing protection would be more than temporarily to increase the production of wealth? CEIAPTER XXIII. THE REAL STRENGTH OF PROTECTION. THE pleas for protection are contradictory and ab- surd ; the books in which it is attempted to give it the semblance of a coherent system are confused and illog- ical.” But we all know that the reasons men give for their conduct or opinions are not always the true reasons, and that beneath the reasons we advance to others or set forth to ourselves there often lurks a feeling or percep- tion which we may but vaguely apprehend or may even be unconscious of, but which is in reality the determin- ing factor. * The latest apology for protection, “Protection vs. Free Trade— the scientific validity and economic operation of defensive duties in the United States,” by ex-Governor Henry M. Hoyt, of Pennsyl- vania (New York, 1886), is hardly below the average in this respect, yet in the very preface the author discloses his equipment for eco- nomic investigation by talking of value as though it were a mea- sure of quantity, and supposing the case of a farmer who has $3,500 worth of produce which he cannot sell or barter. With this begin- ning it is hardly to be wondered at that the 420 pages of his work bring him to the conclusion, which he prints in italics, that “the nearer we come to organizing and conducting our competing indus- tries as if we were the only nation on the planet, the more we shall make and the more we shall have to divide among the makers.’ An asteroid of about the superficial area of Pennsylvania would doubt- less scem the most desirable of worlds to this protectionist statesman and philosopher. 258 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. I have been at pains to examine the arguments by which protection is advocated or defended, and this has been necessary to our inquiry, just as it is necessary that an advancing army should first take the outworks before it can move on the citadel. Yet though these arguments are not merely used controversially, but justify their faith in protection to protectionists them- selves, the real strength of protection must be sought elsewhere. One needs but to talk with the rank and file of the supporters of protection in such a way as to discover their thoughts rather than their arguments, to see that beneath all the reasons assigned for protection there is something which gives it vitality, no matter how clearly those reasons may be disproved. The truth is, that the fallacies of protection draw their real strength from a great fact, which is to them as the earth was to the fabled Antæus, so that they are beaten down only to spring up again. This fact is one which neither side in the controversy endeavors to ex- plain—which free traders quietly ignore and protec- tionists quietly utilize; but which is of all social facts most obvious and important to the working classes— the fact that as Soon, at least, as a certain stage of social development is reached, there are more laborers seek- ing employment than can find it—a surplus which at recurring periods of industrial depression becomes very large. Thus the opportunity of work comes to be regarded as a privilege, and work itself to be deemed in common thought a good.” * The getting of work, not the getting of the results of work, is assumed by protectionist writers to be the end at which a true na- tional policy should aim, though for obvious reasons they do not THE REAL STRENGTH OF PROTECTION. 259 Here, and not in the labored arguments which its advocates make, or in the power of the special interests which it enlists, lies the real strength of protection. Beneath all the mental habits I have spoken of as dis- posing men to accept the fallacies of protection lies one still more important—the habit ingrained in thought and speech of looking upon work as a boom. Protection, as we have seen, operates to reduce the power of a community to obtain wealth—to lessen the result which a given amount of exertion can secure. It “makes more work,” in the sense in which Pharaoh made more work for the Hebrew brick-makers when he refused them straw; in the sense in which the spilling of grease over her floor makes more work for the housewife, or the rain that wets his hay makes more work for the farmer. Yet, when we prove this, what have we proved to men whose greatest anxiety is to get work; whose idea of good times is that of times when work is plentiful? A rain that wets his hay is to the farmer clearly an injury; but is it an injury to the laborer who gets by reason of it a day's work and a day's pay that other- wise he would not have got? The spilling of grease upon her kitchen floor may be a bad thing for the housewife; but to the scrubbing dwell upon this notion. Thus, Professor Thompson says (p. 211, Political Economy): * “The [free trade] theory assumes that the chief end of national as of individual economy is to save labor, whereas the great problem is how to employ it productively. If buying in the cheapest market reduce the amount of employment, it will be for the nation that does it, the dearest of all buying.” Or, again (p. 235): “The national economy of labor consists, not in getting on with as little as possible, but in finding remunerative employment for as much of it as pos- sible.” 260 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. woman who is thereby enabled to earn a needed half. dollar it may be a godsend. * Or if the laborers on Pharaoh's public works had been like thé laborers on modern public works, anxious only that the job might last, and if outside of them had been a mass of less fortunate laborers, pressing, strug- gling, begging for employment in the brick-yards— would the edict that, by reducing the productiveness of labor, made more work have really been unpopular? Let us go back to Robinson Crusoe. In speaking of him I purposely left out Friday. Our protectionist might have talked until he was tired without convinc- ing Crusoe that the more he got and the less he gave in his exchange with passing ships the worse off he would be. But if he had taken Friday aside, recalled to his mind how Crusoe had sold Xury into slavery as soon as he had no further use for him, even though the poor boy had helped him escape from the Moors and had saved his life, and then had whispered into Friday's ear that the less work there was to do the less need would Crusoe have of him and the greater the danger that he might give him back to the cannibals, now that he was certain to have more congenial companions —would the idea that there might be danger in a deluge of cheap goods have seemed so ridiculous to Friday as it did to Crusoe? Those who imagine that they can overcome the popu- lar leaning to protection by pointing out that protec- tive tariffs make necessary more work to obtain the same result, ignore the fact that in all civilized coun- tries that have reached a certain stage of development the majority of the people are unable to employ them- selves, and, unless they find some one to give them THE REAL STRENGTH OF PROTECTION. 261 f work, are helpless, and, hence, are accustomed to re. gard work as a thing to be desired in itself, and any- thing which makes more work as a benefit, not an injury. Here is the rock against which “free traders” whose ideas of reform go no further than “a tariff for revenue only” waste their strength when they demonstrate that the effect of protection is to increase work without in- creasing wealth. And here is the reason why, as we have seen in the United States, in Canada, and in Aus- tralia, the disposition to resort to protective tariffs in- creases as that early stage in which there is no difficulty of finding employment is passed, and the social phenom- ena of older countries begin to appear.” O * The growth of the protective spirit as social development goes on, which has been very obvious in the United States, is generally attributed to the influence of the manufacturing interests which begin to arise. But observation has convinced me that this cause is inadequate, and that the true explanation lies in habits of thought engendered by the greater difficulties of finding employment. I am satisfied, for instance, that protection is far stronger in California than it was in the earlier days of that State. But the Californian in- dustries that can be protected by a national tariff are yet insignifi- cant as compared with industries that cannot be protected. But when tramps abound and charity is invoked for relief works, one needs not go far to find an explanation of the growth of a sentiment which favors the policy of “keeping work in the country.” Noth- ing can be clearer than that our protective tariff adds largely to the cost of nearly everything that the American farmer has to buy, while adding little, if anything, to the price of what he has to sell, and it has been a favorite theory with those who since the war have been endeavoring to arouse sentiment against protection that the attention of the agricultural classes only needed to be called to this to bring out an overwhelming opposition to protective duties. But with all the admirable work that has been done in this direction, it is hard to see any result. The truth is, as may be discovered by 262 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. There never yet lived a man who wanted work for its own sake. Even the employments, constructive or destructive, as may be, in which we engage to exercise our faculties or to dissipate ennui, must to please us show result. It is not the mere work of felling trees that tempts Mr. Gladstone to take up his axe as a relief from the cares of state and the strain of politics. He could get as much work—in the sense of exertion— from pounding a sand-bag with a wooden mallet. But he could no more derive pleasure from this than the man who enjoys a brisk walk could find like enjoy- ment in tramping a tread-mill. The pleasure is in the sense of accomplishment that accompanies the work— in seeing the chips fly and the great tree bend and fall. The natural inducement to the work by which hu- man wants are supplied is the produce of that work. But our industrial Organization is such that what large numbers of men expect to get by work is not the pro- duce or any proportional share of the produce of their work, but a fixed sum which is paid to them by those who take for their own uses the produce of their work. This sum takes to them the place of the natural induce. ment to work, and to obtain it becomes the object of their work. Now the very fact that without compulsion no one will work unless he can get Something for it, causes, in common thought, the idea of wages to become involved in the idea of work, and leads men to think and speak talking with farmers, that the average farmer feels that “there are already too many people in farming,” and hence is not ill-disposed toward a policy which, though it may increase the prices he has to pay, claims to “make work” in other branches of industry. THE REAL STRENGTH OF . PROTECTION. 263 of wanting work when what they really want are the wages that are to be got by work. But the fact that these wages are based upon the doing of work, not upon its productiveness, dissociates the idea of return to the laborer from the idea of the actual productive- ness of his labor, throwing this latter idea into the background or eliminating it altogether. In our modern civilization the masses of men pos- sess only the power to labor. It is true that labor is the producer of all wealth, in the sense of being the active factor of production ; but it is useless without the no less necessary passive factor. With nothing to exert itself upon, labor can produce nothing, and is ab- solutely helpless. And so, the men who have nothing but the power to labor must, to make that power of any use to them, either hire the material necessary to the exertion of labor, or, as is the prevailing method in our industrial organization, sell their labor to those who have the material. Thus it comes that the majority of men must find some one who will set them to work and pay them wages, he keeping as his own what their ex- penditure of labor produces. We have seen how in the exchange of commodities through the medium of money the idea arises, almost insensibly, that the buyer confers an obligation upon the seller. But this idea attaches to the buying and selling of labor with greater clearness and far greater force than to the buying and selling of commodities. There are several reasons for this. Labor will not keep. The man who does not sell a commodity to-day may sell it to-morrow. At any rate he retains the commodity. But the labor of the man who has stood idle to-day because no one would hire him cannot be 264. PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. sold to-morrow. The opportunity has gone from the man himself, and the labor that he might have exerted, had he found a buyer for it, is utterly lost. The men who have nothing but their labor are, moreover, the poorest class—the class who live from hand to mouth and who are least able to bear loss. Further than this, the sellers of labor are numerous as compared with buyers. All men in health have the power of labor, but under the conditions which prevail in modern civi- lization only a comparatively few have the means of employing labor, and there are always, even in the best of times, some men who find it difficult to sell their labor and who are thus exposed to privation and anx- iety, if not to physical suffering. Hence arises the feeling that the man who employs another to work is a benefactor to him—a feeling which even the economists who have made war upon some of the popular delusions growing out of it have done their best to foster, by teaching that capital employs and maintains labor. This feeling runs through all classes, and colors all our thought and speech. One cannot read our newspapers without seeing that the notice of a new building or projected enterprise of any kind usually concludes by stating that it will give employ- ment to so many men, as though the giving of employ- ment, the providing of work, were the measure of its public advantage, and something for which all should be grateful. This feeling, strong among employed, is stronger still among employers. The rich manufac. turer, or iron worker, or ship-builder, talks and thinks of the men to whom he has “given employment” as though he had actually given something which entitled him to their gratitude, and he is inclined to think, and THE REAL STRENGTH OF PROTECTION. 265 in most cases does think, that in combining to demand higher wages or less hours, or in any way endeavoring to put themselves in the position of freely contracting parties, they are snapping at the hand that has fed them, although the obvious fact is that such an em. ployer's men have given him a greater value than he has given them, else he could not have grown rich by employing them. This habit of looking on the giving of employment as a benefaction and on work as a boon, lends easy currency to teachings which assume that work is de- sirable in itself—something which each nation ought to try to get the most of and makes a system which professes to prevent other countries from doing for us work we might do for ourselves seem like a system for the enrichment of our own country and the benefit of its working-classes. It not only indisposes men to grasp the truth that protection can only operate to reduce the productiveness of labor; but it indis- poses them to care anything about that. It is the need for labor, not the productiveness of labor, that they are accustomed to look upon as the thing to be desired. So confirmed is this habit, that nothing is more com- mon than to hear it said of a useless construction or expenditure that “it has done no good, except to pro- vide employment,” while the most popular argument for the eight-hour system is that machinery has so reduced the amount of work to be done that there is not now enough to go around unless divided into smaller “takes.” When men are thus accustomed to think and speak of work as desirable in itself, is it any wonder that a 12 266 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. } system which proposes to “make work” should easily obtain popularity? Protectionism viewed in itself is absurd. But it is no more absurd than many other popular beliefs. Pro- fessor W. G. Sumner of Yale College, a fair representa- tive of the so-called free traders who have been vainly trying to weaken the hold of protectionism in the United States without disturbing its root, essayed, be- fore the United States Tariff Commission in 1882, to bring protectionism to a reductio ad absurdum by declar- ing that the protectionist theory involved such prop- ositions as these: that a big standing army would tend to raise wages by withdrawing men from competition in the labor market; that paupers in almshouses and convicts in prisons ought for the same reason to be maintained without labor; that it is better for the laboring class that rich people should live in idleness than that they should work; that trades unions should prevent their members from lessening the supply of work by doing too much; and that the destruction of property in riots must be a good thing for the laboring class, by increasing the work to be done. But whoever will listen to the ordinary talk of men and read the daily newspapers, will find that, so far from such notions seeming absurd to the common mind, they are accustomed ideas. Is it not true that the “good times during the war” are widely attributed to the “employment furnished by government" in calling so many men into the army, and to the brisk demand for commodities caused by their unproductive consump- tion and by actual destruction? Is it not true that all over the United States the working-classes are protest. ing against the employment of convicts in this, that, or THE REAL STRENGTH OF PROTECTION. 267 the other way, and would much rather have them kept in idleness than have them “take work from honest men.”? Is it not true that the rich man who “gives employment” to others by his lavish waste is univer- sally regarded as a better friend to the workers than the rich man who “takes work from those who need it.” by doing it himself? In themselves these notions may be what the Pro- fessor declares them, “miserable fallacies which sin against common sense,” but they arise from the recog- nition of actual facts. Take the most preposterous of them. The burning down of a city is indeed a lessen- ing of the aggregate wealth. But is the waste involved in the burning down of a city any more real than the waste involved in the standing idle of men who would gladly be at work in building up a city? Where every one who needed to work could find opportunity, there it would indeed be clear that the maintenance in idle- ness of convicts, paupers, or rich men must lessen the rewards of workers; but where hundreds of thousands must endure privation because of their inability to find work, the doing of work by those who can support themselves, or will be supported without it, seems like taking the opportunity to work from those who most need or most deserve it. Such “miserable fallacies” must continue to sway men's minds until some satisfac- tory explanation is afforded of the facts that make the “leave to toil” a boon. To attempt, as do “free- traders” of Professor Sumner's class, to eradicate pro- tectionist ideas while ignoring these facts, is utterly hopeless, What they take for a seedling that may be pulled up with a vigorous effort, is in reality the shoot of a tree whose spreading roots reach to the bed-rock 268 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. of Society. A political economy that will recognize no deeper social wrong than the framing of tariffs on a protective instead of on a revenue basis, and that, with • Such trivial exceptions, is but a justification of “things as they are,” is repellent to the instincts of the masses. To tell workingmen, as Professor Sumner does, that “trades-unionism and protectionism are falsehoods,” is simply to dispose them to protectionism, for whatever may be said of protection they well know that trades. unions have raised wages in many vocations, and that they are the only things that have yet given the work. ing-classes any power of resisting a strain of competi- tion that, unchecked, must force them to the maximum of toil for the minimum of pay. Such free-tradeism as Professor Sumner represents—and it is this that is taught in England, and that in the United States has essayed to do battle with protectionism—must, wherever the working-classes have political power, give to protec- tion positive strength. But it is not merely by indirection that what is known as the “orthodox political economy” strengthens pro- tection. While condemning protective tariffs it has justified revenue tariffs, and its most important teach- ings have not merely barred the way to such an ex- planation of social phenomena as would cut the ground from under protectionism, but have been directly cal- culated to strengthen the beliefs which render protec- tion plausible. The teaching that labor depends for employment upon capital, and that wages are drawn from capital and are determined by the ratio between the number of laborers and the amount of capital de- voted to their employment;-all the teachings, in short, which have degraded labor to the position of a second- THE REAL STRENGTH OF PROTECTION. 269 ary and dependent factor in production, have tended to sanction that view of things which disposes the labor- ing-class to look with favor upon anything which by preventing the coming into a country of the produce of other countries, seems, at least, to increase the require- ment for work at home. CELAPTER XXIV. THE PARADOX. IF our investigation has as yet led to no satisfactory conclusion it has at least explained why the controversy so long carried on between protectionists and free tra- ders has been so indeterminate. The paradox we have reached is one toward which all the social problems of our day converge, and had our examination been of any similar question it must have come to just such a point. Take, for instance, the question of the effects of ma- chinery. The opinion that finds most influential ex- pression is that labor-saving invention, although it may sometimes cause temporary inconvenience or even hard- ship to a few, is ultimately beneficial to all. On the other hand, there is among workingmen a widespread belief that labor-saving machinery is injurious to them, although, since the belief does not enlist those power- ful special interests that are concerned in the advo- cacy of protection, it has not been wrought into an elab- orate system and does not get anything like the same representation in the organs of public opinion. Now, should we subject this question to such an ex- amination as we have given to the tariff question we should reach similar results. We should find the motion that invention ought to be restrained as incon- gruous as the notion that trade ought to be restrained —as incapable of being carried to its logical conclusions THE PARADOX. 271 without resulting in absurdity. And while the use of machinery enormously increases the production of wealth, examination would show in it nothing to cause inequality in distribution. On the contrary, we should see that the increased power given by invention inures primarily to labor, and that this gain is so diffused by exchange that the effect of an improvement which in- creases the power of labor in one branch of industry must be shared by labor in all other branches. Thus the direct tendency of labor-saving improvement is to augment the earnings of labor. Nor is this tendency neutralized by the fact that labor-saving inventions generally require the use of capital, since competition, when free to act, must at length bring the profits of capital used in this way to the common level. Even the monopoly of a labor-saving invention, while it can seldom be maintained for any length of time, cannot prevent a large (and generally much the largest) part of the benefits from being diffused.* From this we might conclude with certainty, that the tendency of labor-saving improvements is to benefit all, and especially to benefit the working-class, and hence might naturally attribute any distrust of their beneficial effects partly to the temporary displacements which, in a highly organized Society, any change in the forms of industry must cause, and partly to the in- creased wants called forth by the increased ability to satisfy want. Yet, while as a matter of theory it is clear that labor- saving inventions ought to improve the condition of all; as a matter of fact it is equally clear that they do not. * For a fuller examination of the effects of machinery see my Social Problems. 272 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. In countries like Great Britain there is still a large class living on the verge of starvation, and constantly slipping over it—a class who have not derived the slightest benefit from the immense increase of produc- tive power, since their condition never could have been any worse than it is—a class whose habitual condition in times of peace and plenty is lower, harder, more precarious and more degraded than that of any sav- ageS. In countries like the United States, where such a class did not previously exist, its development has been contemporaneous with wondrous advances of labor- saving invention. The laws against tramps which have been placed upon the statute books of our states, the re- strictions upon child labor which have been found necessary, the walking advertisements of our cities, the growing bitterness of the strife which workingmen are forced to wage, indicate unmistakably that while dis- covery and invention have been steadily increasing the productive power of labor in every department of in- dustry, the condition of the mere laborer has been growing worse. It can be proved that labor-saving invention tends to benefit labor, but that this tendency is in some way aborted is even more clearly evident in the facts of to- day than it was when John Stuart Mill questioned if mechanical invention had lightened the day's toil of any human being. That in some places and in Some occupations there has been improvement in the condi- tion of labor is true. But not only is such improve. ment nowhere commensurate with the increase of pro- ductive power; it is clearly not due to it. It exists only where it has been won by combinations of work- THE PARADOX. 273 men or by legal interference. It is trade unions, not the increased power given by machinery, that have in many occupations in Great Britain reduced hours and increased pay; it is legislation, not any improvement in the general condition of labor, that has stopped the harnessing of women in mines and the working of little children in mills and brick-yards. Where such influ- ences have not been felt, it is not only certain that labor- saving inventions have not improved the condition of labor, but it seems as if they had exerted a depressing effect—operating to make labor a drug instead of to make it more valuable. Thus, in relation to the effects of machinery, as in relation to the effects of tariffs, there are two sides to the shield. Conclusions to which we are led by a con- sideration of principles are contradicted by conclusions we are compelled to draw from existing facts. But, while discussion may go on interminably between those who, looking only at one side of the shield, refuse to consider what their opponents see, yet to recognize the contradictory aspects of such a question is to realize the possibility of an explanation that will include both. The problem we must solve to explain why free trade or labor-saving invention or any similar cause fails to produce the general benefits we naturally ex- pect, is a problem of the distribution of wealth. When increased production of wealth does not proportionately benefit the working-classes, it must be that it is accom- panied by increased inequality of distribution. In themselves free trade and labor-saving inventions do not tend to inequality of distribution. Yet it is possible that they may promote such inequality, not by virtue of anything inherent in their tendencies, but 12% 274 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. through their effect in increasing production, for, as already pointed out, increase or decrease in the produc- tion of wealth may of itself, under certain circum- stances, alter the proportions of distribution. Let me illustrate: Smith, a plumber, and Jones, a gas-fitter, form a . partnership in the usual way, and go into the business of plumbing and gas-fitting. In this case whatever increases or decreases the profits of the firm will affect the partners equally, and whether these profits be much or little, the proportion which each takes will be the S3LO €. But let us suppose their agreement to be of a kind occasionally made, that the plumber shall have two- thirds of the profits on all plumbing done by the firm, and the gas-fitter two-thirds of the profits on all gas- fitting. In such case, every job they do will not only increase or decrease the profits of the firm, but, accord- ing as it is a job of plumbing or of gas-fitting, will directly affect the distribution of profits between the partners. Or, again, let us suppose that the partners differ in their ability to take risks. Smith has a family and must have a steady income, while Jones is a bachelor who could get along for some time without drawing from the firm. To better assure Smith of a living, it is agreed that he shall draw a fixed sum before any profits are distributed, and, in return for this guaranty, shall get only a quarter of the profits remaining. In such a case, increase or decrease of profits would of itself alter the proportions of distribution. Increase of profits would affect distribution in favor of Jones, and might go so far as to raise his share to nearly 75 THE PARADOX. #: 275 * per cent. and reduce the share of Smith to little over 25 per cent. Decrease of profits on the other hand would affect distribution in favor of Smith, and might go so far as to give him 100 per cent., while reducing Jones's share to nothing. In such a case as this, any circumstance which affected the amount of profits would affect the terms of distribution, but not by vir- tue of anything peculiar to the circumstance. Its real cause would be something external to, and unconnected with, such circumstance. The social phenomena we have to explain resemble those presented in this last case. The increased in- equality of distribution which accompanies material progress is evidently connected with the increased pro- duction of wealth, and does not arise from any direct effect of the causes which increase wealth. Our illustration, however, yet lacks something. In the case we have supposed, increase of their joint profits would benefit both partners, though in different degrees. Even when Smith's share diminished in pro- portion, it would increase in amount. But in the social phenomena we are considering, it is not merely that with increasing wealth the share that some classes ob- tain is not increased proportionately; it is that it is not increased absolutely, and that in some cases it is even absolutely, as well as proportionately, diminished. To get an illustration that will cover this point as well, let us therefore take another case. Let us go back to Robinson Crusoe's island, which may well serve us as an example of society in its simplest and therefore most intelligible form. The discovery of the island which we have heretofore supposed, involving calls by other ships, would greatly 276 - PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. increase the wealth which the labor of its population of two could obtain. But it would not follow that in the increased wealth both would gain. Friday was Crusoe's slave, and no matter how much the opening of trade with the rest of the world might increase wealth, he could only demand the wages of a slave—enough to maintain him in working ability. So long as Crusoe himself lived he would doubtless take good care of the companion of his solitude, but when in the course of time the island had fully come into the circle of civil- ized life, and had passed into the possession of some heir of Crusoe's, or of some purchaser, living probably in England, and was cultivated with a view to making it yield the largest income, the gulf between the pro- prietor who owned it and the slave who worked upon it would not merely have enormously widened as com- pared with the time when Crusoe and Friday shared with substantial equality the joint produce of their labor, but the share of the slave might have become absolutely less, and his condition lower and harder. It is not necessary to suppose positive cruelty or wanton harshness. The slaves who in the new order of things took Friday's place might have all their animal wants supplied—they might have as much to eat as Friday had, might wear better clothes, be lodged in better houses, be exempt from the fear of cannibals, and in illness have the attendance of a skilled physician. And seeing this, island “statisticians " might collate figures or devise diagrams to show how much better off these toilers were than their predecessor, who wore goatskins, slept in a cave and lived in constant dread of being eaten, and the conclusions of these gentlemen might be paraded in all the island newspapers, with a THE PARADOX. 277 chorus of: “Behold, in figures that cannot lie and dia- grams that can be measured, how industrial progress benefits everybody, even the slave l’ But in things of which the statistician takes no ac- count they would be worse off than Friday. Compelled to a round of dreary toil, unlightened by variety, un- dignified by responsibility, unstimulated by seeing re- sults and partaking of them, their life, as compared with that of Friday, would be less that of men and more that of machines. And the effect of such changes would be the same upon laborers such as we call free—free, that is to say, to use their own power to labor, but not free to that which is necessary to its use. If Friday, instead of setting Crusoe's foot upon his head, in token that he was thenceforward his slave, had simply acknowledged Crusoe's ownership of the island, what would have been the difference? As he could only live upon Cru- soe's property on Crusoe's terms, his freedom would simply have amounted to the freedom to emigrate, to drown himself in the sea, or to give himself up to the cannibals. Men enjoying only such freedom—that is to say, the freedom to starve or emigrate as the alter- native of getting some One else's permission to labor— cannot be enriched by improvements that increase the production of wealth. For they have no more power to claim any share of it than has the slave. Those who want them to work must give them what the master must give the slave if he wants him to work—enough to support life and strength; but when they can find no one who wants them to work they must starve, if they cannot beg. Grant to Crusoe ownership of the island, and Friday, the free man, would be as much subject to 278 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. his will as Friday, the slave; as incapable of claiming any share of an increased production of wealth, no matter how great it might be nor from what cause it might come. And what would be true in the case of one man would be true of any number. Suppose ten thousand Fridays, all free men, all absolute owners of themselves, and but one Crusoe, the absolute owner of the island. So long as his ownership was acknowledged and could be enforced, would not the one be the master of the ten thousand as fully as though he were the legal owner of their flesh and blood 7 Since no one could use his island without his consent, it would follow that no one could labor, or even live, without his permission. The order, “Leave my property” would be a sentence of death. This owner of the island would be to the other ten thousand “free men” who lived upon it, their land lord or land god, of whom they would stand in more real awe than of any deity that their religion taught them reigned above. For as a Scottish landlord told his tenants: “God Almighty may have made the land, but I own it. And if you don't do as I say, off you go ! }} No increase of wealth could enable such “free" laborers to claim more than a bare living. The open- ing up of foreign trade, the invention of labor-saving machines, the discovery of mineral deposits, the intro- duction of more prolific plants, the growth of skill, would simply increase the amount their land lord would charge for the privilege of living on his island, and could in no wise increase what those who had noth- ing but their labor could demand. Iſ Heaven itself rained down wealth upon the island that wealth would THE PARADOX. - 279 be his. And so, too, any economy that might enable these mere laborers to live more cheaply would simply increase the tribute that they could pay and that he could exact. Of course, no man could utilize a power like this to its full extent or for himself alone. A single landlord in the midst of ten thousand poor tenants, like a single master amid ten thousand slaves, would be as lonely as was Robinson Crusoe before Friday came. The human being is by nature a social animal, and no matter how selfish such a man might be, he would desire com- panions nearer his own condition. Natural impulse would prompt him to reward those who pleased him, prudence would urge him to interest the more influen- tial among his ten thousand Fridays in the maintenance of his ownership, while experience would show him if calculation did not, that a larger income could be ob- tained by leaving to superior energy, skill and thrift some part of what their efforts secured. But while the single owner of such an island would thus be in- duced to share his privileges by means of grants, leases, exemptions or stipends, with a class more or less nu- merous, who would thus partake with him in the advan- tages of any improvement that increased the power of producing wealth, there would yet remain a class, the mere laborers of only ordinary ability, to whom such improvement could bring no benefit. And it would only be necessary to be a little chary in granting per- mission to work upon the island, so as to keep a small percentage of the population constantly on the verge of starvation and begging to be permitted to use their power to labor, to create a competition in which, bidding against each other, men would of themselves offer all 280 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. that their labor could procure save a bare living, for the privilege of getting that. We can sometimes see principles all the clearer if we imagine them brought out under circumstances to which we are not habituated ; but, as a matter of fact, the Social adjustment which in modern civilization creates a class who can neither labor nor live save by permis- sion of others, never could have arisen in this way. The reader of The Further Adventures of Robinson Crusoe, as related by De Foe, will remember that during Crusoe's long absence, the three English rogues, led by Will Atkins, set up a claim to the ownership of the island, declaring that it had been given to them by Robinson Crusoe, and demanding that the rest of the inhabitants should work for them by way of rent. Though used in their own countries to the acknowledg- ment of just such claims, set up in the name of men gone, not to other lands, but to another world, the Spaniards, as well as the peaceable Englishmen, laughed at this demand, and, when it was insisted on, laid Will Atkins and his companions by the heels until they had got over the notion that other people should do their work for them. But if the three English rogues had got possession of all the fire-arms before asserting their claim to own the island, the rest of its population might have been compelled to acknowledge it. Thus a class of land-owners and a class of non-land-owners would have been established, to which arrangement the whole population might in a few generations have become so habituated as to think it the natural order, and when they had begun, in course of time, to colonize other islands, they would have established the same institu- tion there. Now, what might thus have happened on THE PARADOX 281 Crusoe's island, had the three English rogues got posses- sion of all the fire-arms, is precisely what on a larger scale, did happen in the development of European civilization, and what is happening in its extension to other parts of the world. Thus it is that we find in civilized countries a large class who, while they have power to labor, are denied any right to the use of the elements necessary to make that power available, and who, to obtain the use of those elements, must either give up in rent a part of the produce of their labor, or take in wages less than their labor yields. A class thus helpless can gain nothing from advance in productive power. Where such a class exists, increase in the general wealth can only mean increased inequality in distribution. And though this tendency may be a little checked as to some of them by trades-unions or similar combinations which artifically lessen competi- tion, it will operate to the full upon those outside of such combinations. And, let me repeat it, this increased inequality in distribution does not mean merely that the mass of those who have nothing but the power to labor do not proportionately share in the increase of wealth. It means that their condition must become absolutely, as well as relatively, worse. It is in the nature of industrial advance—it is of the very essence of those prodigious forces which modern invention and discovery are un- loosing, that they must injure where they do not benefit. These forces are not in themselves either good or evil. They bring good or evil according to the conditions under which they are exerted. In a state of society in which all men stood upon an equality with relation to the use of the material universe their effects could be * z 282 PROTECTION or FREE TRADE. only beneficent. But in a state of society in which some men are held to be the absolute owners of the material universe, while other men cannot use it without paying tribute, the blessing these forces might bring is changed into a curse—their tendency is to destroy independence, to dispense with skill and convert the artisan into a “hand,” to concentrate all business and make it harder for an employee to become his own em- ployer, and to compel women and children to injurious and stunting toil. The change industrial progress is now working in the conditions of the mere laborer, and which is only somewhat held in check by the opera, tions of trades-unions, is that change which would convert a slave who shared the varied occupations and rude comforts of his goatskin-clothed master into a slave held as a mere instrument of factory production. Compare the skilled craftsman of the Qld order with the operative of the new order, the mere feeder of a machine. Compare the American farm “help " of an earlier state, the social equal of his employer, with the cowboy, whose dreary life is enlivened only by a “round up" or “drunk,” or with the harvest hand of the “wheat fac- tory,” who sleeps in barracks or barns, and after a few months of employment goes on a tramp. Or compare the poverty of Connemara or Skye with the infinitely more degraded poverty of Belfast or Glasgow. Do this, and then say if to those who can only hope to sell their labor for a subsistence, our very industrial progress has not a dark side. And that this must be the tendency of labor-saving invention or reform in a society where the planet is held to be private property, and the children that come into life upon it are denied all right to its use except THE PARADOX. 283 as they buy or inherit the title of some dead man, we may see plainly if we imagine labor-saving inven- tion carried to its farthest imaginable extent. When we consider that the object of work is to satisfy want, the idea that labor-saving invention can ever cause want by making work more productive seems preposterous. Yet, could invention go so far as to make it possible to produce wealth without labor, what would be the effect upon a class who can call nothing their own, save the power to labor, and who, let wealth be never so abundant, can get no share of it except by selling this power? Would it not be to reduce to naught the value of what this class have to sell; to make them paupers in the midst of all possible wealth—to deprive them of the means of earning even a poor livelihood, and to compel them to beg or starve, if they could not steal? Such a point it may be impossible for invention ever to reach, but it is a point toward which modern invention drives. And is there not in this some explanation of the vast army of tramps and paupers, and of deaths by want and starvation in the very midst of plenty 2 . The abolition of protection would tend to increase the production of wealth—that is sure. But under conditions that exist, increase in the production of wealth may itself become a curse—first to the laboring- glass, and ultimately to Society at large. Is it not true, then, it may be asked, that protection, for the reason at least that it does check that freedom and extension of trade which are essential to the full play of modern industrial tendencies, is favorable to the working-classes? Much of the strength of protec- tion among workingmen comes, I think, from vague feelings of this kind. f 284 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. My reply would be negative. Not only has proteo tion—which is merely the protection of producing cap- italists against foreign competition in the home market —tendencies in itself toward monopoly and inequality, but it is impotent to check the concentrating tenden- cies of modern inventions and processes. To do this by “protection "we must not only forbid foreign commerce, but restrain internal commerce. We must not only prohibit any new applications of labor-saving inven- tion, but must prevent the use of the most important of those already adopted. We must tear up the rail- way and go back to the canal boat and freight wagon; cut down the telegraph wire and rely upon the post horse; substitute the scythe for the reaper, the needle for the sewing-machine, the hand loom for the factory; in short, discard all that a century of invention has given us, and return to the industrial processes of a hundred years ago. This is as impossible as for the chicken to go back to the egg. A man may become decrepit and childish, but once manhood is reached he cannot again become a child. No ; it is not in going backward, it is in going for- ward, that the hope of social improvement lies. CELAPTER XXV. THE ROBBER THAT TAKES ALL THAT IS LEFT. IN itself the abolition of protection is like the driving off of a robber. But it will not help a man to drive off one robber, if another, still stronger and more rapacious, be left to plunder him. Labor may be likened to a man who as he carries home his earnings is waylaid by a series of robbers. One demands this much, and another that much, but last of all stands one who demands all that is left, save just enough to enable the victim to maintain life and come forth next day to work. So long as this last- robber remains, what will it benefit such a man to drive off any or all of the other robbers? Such is the situation of labor to-day throughout the civilized world. And the robber that takes all that is left, is private property in land. Improvement, no matter how great, and reform, no matter now beneficial in itself, cannot help that class who deprived of all right to the use of the material elements, have only the power to labor—a power as useless in itself as a sail without wind, a pump without water, or a saddle without a horse. I have likened labor to a man beset by a series of robbers, because there are in every country other things than private property in land which tend to diminish 286 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. national prosperity and divert the wealth earned by labor into the hands of non-producers. This is the tendency of monopoly of the processes and machinery of production and exchange, the tendency of protect- ive tariffs, of bad systems of currency and finance, of Corrupt government, of public debts, of standing ar- mies, and of wars and preparations for war. But these things, some of which are conspicuous in one country and some in another, cannot account for that impover- ishment of labor which is to be seen everywhere. They are the lesser robbers, and to drive them off is only to leave more for the great robber to take. If the all-sufficient cause of the impoverishment of labor were abolished, then reform in any of these direc- tions would improve the condition of labor; but so long as that cause exists, no reform can effect any per- manent improvement. Public debts might be abolish- ed, standing armies disbanded, war and the thought *of war forgotten, protective tariffs everywhere dis- carded, government administered with the greatest purity and economy, and all monopolies, save the monopoly of land, destroyed, without any permanent improvement in the condition of the laboring-class. For the economic effect of all these reforms would simply be to diminish the waste or increase the production of wealth, and so long as competition for employment on the part of men who are powerless to employ them- selves tends steadily to force wages to the minimum that gives the laborer but a bare living, this is all the ordinary laborer can get. So long as this tendency exists—and it must continue to exist so long as private property in land exists—improvement (even if possible) in the personal qualities of the laboring masses, such THE ROBBER THAT TAKES ALL THAT IS LEFT. 287 as improvement in skill, in intelligence, in temperance or in thrift, cannot improve their material condition. Improvement of this kind can only benefit the individ- ual while it is confined to the individual, and thus gives him an advantage over the body of Ordinary labor- ers whose wages form the regulative basis of all other wages. If such personal improvements become general the effect can only be to enable competition to force wages to a lower level. Where few can read and write, the ability to do so confers a special advantage and raises the individual who possesses it above the level of Ordinary labor, enabling him to command the wages of Special skill. But where all can read and write, the mere possession of this ability cannot save ordinary laborers from being forced to as low a position as though they could not read and write. And so, where thriftlessness or intemperance pre- vails, the thrifty or temperate have a special advantage which may raise them above the conditions of ordinary labor; but should these virtues become general that advantage would cease. Let the great body of working- men so reform or so degrade their habits that it would become possible to live on one-half the lowest wages now paid, and that competition for employment which drives men to work for a bare living must proportion- ately reduce the level of wages. I do not say that reforms that increase the intelli- gence or improve the habits of the masses are even in this view useless. The diffusion of intelligence tends to make men discontented with a life of poverty in the midst of wealth, and the diminution of intem- perance better fits them to revolt against such a lot. Public schools and temperance societies are thus pre- 288 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. revolutionary agencies. But they can never abolish poverty so long as land continues to be treated as pri- vate property. The worthy people who imagine that compulsory education or the prohibition of the drink traffic can abolish poverty are making the same mis- take that the Anti-Corn Law reformers made when they imagined that the abolition of protection would make hunger impossible. Such reforms are in their own nature good and beneficial, but in a world like this, tenanted by beings like ourselves, and treated by them as the exclusive property of a part of their number, there must, under any conceivable conditions, be a class on the verge of starvation. • This necessity inheres in the nature of things; it arises from the relation between man and the external universe. Land is the superficies of the globe—that bottom of the ocean of air to which our physical structure confines us. It is our only possible standing place, our only possible workshop, the only reservoir from which we can draw material for the supply of our needs. Considering land in its narrow sense, as distinguished from water and air, it is still the element necessary to our use of the other elements. Without land man could not even avail himself of the light and heat of the sun or utilize the forces that pulse through matter. And whatever be his essence, man, in his physical constitution, is but a changing form of matter, a passing mode of motion, constantly drawn from na- ture's reservoirs and as constantly returning to them again. In physical structure and powers he is related to land as the fountain jet is related to the stream, or the flame of a gas burner to the gas that feeds it. Hence, let other conditions be what they may, the THE ROBBER THAT TAKES ALL THAT IS LEFT. 289 man who, if he lives and works at all, must live and work on land belonging to another, is necessarily a slave or a pauper. There are two forms of slavery—that which Friday accepted when he placed Crusoe's foot upon his head, and that which Will Atkins and his comrades attempted to establish when they set up a claim to.the ownership of the island and called on its other inhabitants to do all the work. The one, which consists in making prop- erty of man, is only resorted to when population is too sparse to make practicable the other, which consists in making property of land. For while population is sparse and unoccupied land is plenty, laborers are able to escape the necessity of buying the use of land, or can obtain it on nominal terms. Hence to obtain slaves—people who will work for you without your working for them in return—it is necessary to make property of their bodies or to resort to predial slavery or serfdom, which is an artificial anticipation of the power that comes to the land-owner with denser population, and which consists in confin- ing laborers to land on which it is desired to utilize their labor. But as population becomes denser and land more fully occupied, the competition of non-land- owners for the use of land obviates the necessity of making property of their bodies or of confining them to an estate in order to obtain their labor without return. They themselves will beg the privilege of giving their labor in return for being permitted what must be yield- ed to the slave—a spot to live on and enough of the produce of their own labor to maintain life. This, for the owner, is much the more convenient form of slavery. He does not have to worry about his 13 290 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. . slaves—is not at the trouble of whipping them to make them work, or chaining them to prevent their escape, or chasing them with blood-hounds when they run away. He is not concerned with seeing that they are properly fed in infancy, cared for in sickness or sup- ported in old age. He can let them live in hovels, let them work harder and fare worse, than could any half humane owner of the bodies of men, and this without a qualm of conscience or any reprobation from public opinion. In short, when society reaches the point of development where a brisk competition for the use of land springs up, the ownership of land gives more profit with less risk and trouble than does the ownership of men. If the two young Englishmen I have spoken of had come over here and bought so many American citizens, they could not have got from them so much of the produce of labor as they now get by having bought land which American citizens are glad to be allowed to till for half the crop. And so, even if our laws permitted, it would be foolish for an English duke or marquis to come over here and contract for ten thousand American babies, born or to be born, in the expectation that when able to work he could get out of them a large return. For by purchasing or fencing in a million acres of land that cannot run away and do not need to be fed, clothed or educated, he can, in twenty or thirty years, have ten thousand full grown Americans, ready to give him half of all that their labor can produce on his land for the privilege of sup- porting themselves and their families out of the other half. This gives him more of the produce of labor than he could exact from so many chattel slaves. And as time goes on and American citizens become moro THE ROBBER THAT TAKES ALL THAT IS LEFT. 291 plentiful, the ownership of this land will enable him to get more of them to work for him, and on lower terms. His speculation in land is as much a speculation in the growth of men as though he had bought children and contracted for infants yet to be born. For if infants ceased to be born and men to grow up in America, his land would be valueless. The profits on such investment do not arise from the growth of land or increase of its capabilities, but from growth of population. Land in itself has no value. Value arises only from human labor. It is not until the ownership of land be. comes equivalent to the ownership of laborers that any value attaches to it. And where land has a speculative value it is because of the expectation that the growth of society will in the future make its ownership equiva- lent to the ownership of laborers. It is true that all valuable things have the quality of enabling their owner to obtain labor or the produce of labor in return for them or for their use. But with things that are themselves the produce of labor such transactions involve an exchange—the giving of an equivalent of labor-produce in return for labor or its produce. Land, however, is not the produce of labor; it existed before man was, and, therefore, when the ownership of land can command labor or the products of labor, the transaction, though in form it may be an exchange, is in reality an appropriation. The power which the ownership of valuable land gives, is that of getting human service without giving human service, a power essentially the same as that power of appro- priation which resides in the ownership of slaves. It is not a power of exchange, but a power of blackmail, such as would be asserted were some men compelled to 292 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. pay other men for the use of the ocean, the air or the sunlight. The value of such things as grain, cattle, ships, houses, goods, or metals is a value of exchange, based upon the cost of production, and therefore tends to diminish as the progress of society lessens the amount of labor necessary to produce such things. But the value of land is a value of appropriation, based upon the amount that can be appropriated, and therefore tends to increase as the progress of society increases production. Thus it is, as we see, that while all sorts of products steadily fall in value, the value of land steadily rises. Inventions and discoveries that in- crease the productive power of labor lessen the value of the things that require labor for their production, but increase the value of land, since they increase the amount that labor can be compelled to give for its use. And so, where land is fully appropriated as private property no increase in the production of wealth, no economy in its use, can give the mere laborer more than the wages of the slave. If wealth rained down from heaven or welled up from the depths of the earth it could not enrich the laborer. It could merely increase the value of land. Nor do we have to appeal to the imagination to see this. In Western Pennsylvania it has recently been discovered that if borings are made into the earth com- bustible gas will force itself up—a sheer donation, as it were, by Nature, of a thing that heretofore could only be produced by labor. The direct and natural tend- ency of this new power of obtaining by boring and piping what has heretofore required the mining and retorting of coal is to make labor more valuable and to # * * -- THE-ROBBER THAT TAKES ALL THAT IS LEFT, 293 increase the earnings of the laborer. But land in Penn- sylvania being treated as private property, it can have no such effect. Its effect, in the first place, is to enrich the owners of the land through which the borings must be made, who, as legal owners of the whole material universe above and below their land, can levy a toll on the use of Nature's gift. In the next place, the cap- italists who have gone into the business of bringing the gas in pipes to Pittsburgh and other cities have formed a combination similar to that of the Standard Oil Company, by which they control the sale of the natural gas, and thus over and above the usual returns of cap- ital make a large profit. Still, however, a residue of advantage is left, for the new fuel is so much more easily handled, and produces so much more uniform a heat, that the glass and iron workers of Pittsburgh find it more economical than the old fuel, even at the same cost. But they cannot long retain this advantage. If it prove permanent, other glass and iron workers will soon be crowding to Pittsburgh to share in it, and the result will be that the value of city lots in Pittsburgh will so increase as finally to transfer this residual advan- tage to the owners of Pittsburgh land.” And if the monopoly of the piping company is abolished, or if by legislative regulation its profits are reduced to the ordinary earnings of capital, the ultimate result will, in the same way, be not an advantage to workers, but an advantage to land-owners. * The largest owners of Pittsburgh land are an English family named Schenley, who draw in ground rents a great revenue, thus (to the gratification of Pennsylvania protectionists) increasing our exports over our imports, just as though they owned so many Penn- sylvanians. 294 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. Thus it is that railways cheapen transportation only to increase the value of land, not the value of labor, and that when their rates are reduced it is land-owners not laborers who get the benefit. So it is with all im- provements of whatever nature. The Federal gov. ernment has acted the part of a munificent patron to Washington City. The consequence is that the value of lots has advanced. If the Federal government were to supply every Washington householder with free light, free fuel and free food, the value of lots would still further increase, and the owners of Washington “real estate” would ultimately pocket the donation. The primary factors of production are land and labor. Capital is their product, and the capitalist is but an intermediary between the landlord and the laborer. Hence workingmen who imagine that capital is the oppressor of labor are “barking up the wrong tree.” In the first place, much that seems on the sur- face like oppression by capital is in reality the result of the helplessness to which labor is reduced by being denied all right to the use of land. “The destruction of the poor is their poverty.” It is not in the power of capital to compel men who can obtain free access to nature to sell their labor for starvation wages. In the second place, whatever of the earnings of labor capital- istic monopolies may succeed in appropriating, they are merely lesser robbers, who take what, if they were abolished, land ownership would take. No matter whether the social organization be simple or complex, no matter whether the intermediaries be- tween the owners of land and the owners of, the mere power to labor be few or many, wherever the available land has been fully appropriated as the property of & THE ROBBER THAT TAKES ALL THAT IS LEFT, 295 'some of the people, there must exist a class, the labor- ers of ordinary ability and skill, who can never hope to get more than a bare living for the hardest toil, and who are constantly in danger of failure to get even that. We see that class existing in the simple industrial organization of Western Ireland or the Scottish High- lands, and we see it, still lower and more degraded, in the complex industrial organization of the great Brit- ish cities. In spite of the enormous increase of produc- "tive power, we have seen it developing in the United States, just as the appropriation of our land has gone on. This is as it must be, for the most fundamental of all human relations is that between man and the planet he inhabits. How the recognition of the consequences involved in the division of men into a class of world owners and a class who have no legal right to the use of the world explains many things otherwise inexplicable I cannot here point out, since I am dealing only with the tariff question. We have seen why what is miscalled “free trade”—the mere abolition of protection—can only temporarily benefit the working-classes, and we have now reached a position which will enable us to proceed with our inquiry and ascertain what the effects of true free trade would be. f CEIAPTER XXVI. TRUE FREE TRADE. “CoME with me,” said Richard Cobden, as John Bright turned heart-stricken from a new-made grave. “There are in England women and children dying with hunger—with hunger made by the laws. Come with me, and we will not rest until we repeal those laws.” In this spirit the free trade movement waxed and grew, arousing an enthusiasm that no mere fiscal re- form could have aroused. And intrenched though it was by restricted suffrage and rotten boroughs and aristocratic privilege, protection was overthrown in Great Britain. And there is hunger in Great Britain still, and women and children yet die of it. But this is not the failure of free trade. When pro- tection had been abolished and a revenue tariff substi- tuted for a protective tariff, free trade had only won an outpost. That women and children still die of hunger in Great Britain arises from the failure of the reformers to go on. Free trade has not yet been tried in Great Britain. Free trade in its fullness and entirety would indeed abolish hunger. This we may now see. Our inquiry has shown that the reason why the abolition of protection, greatly as it would increase the production of wealth, can accomplish no permanent benefit for the laboring-class, is, that so long as the TRUE FREE TRADE. 297 land on which all must live is made the property of some, increase of productive power can only increase the tribute which those who own the land can demand for its use. So long as land is held to be the individual property of but a portion of its inhabitants no possible increase of productive power, even if it went to the length of abolishing the necessity of labor, and no im- aginable increase of wealth, even though it poured down from heaven or gushed up from the bowels of the earth, could improve the condition of those who possess only the power to labor. The greatest imagin- able increase of wealth could only intensify in the greatest imaginable degree the phenomena which we are familiar with as “over-production”—could only reduce the laboring-class to universal pauperism. Thus it is, that to make either the abolition of pro- tection or any other reform beneficial to the working- class we must abolish the inequality of legal rights to land, and restore to all their natural and equal rights in the common heritage. How can this be done? Consider for a moment precisely what it is that needs to be done, for it is here that confusion some- times arises. To secure to each of the people of a country his cqual right to the land of that country does not mean to secure to each an equal piece of land. Save in an extremely primitive society, where popula- tion was sparse, the division of labor had made little progress, and family groups lived and worked in com- mon, a division of land into anything like equal pieces would indeed be impracticable. In a state of society such as exists in civilized countries to-day, it would be extremely difficult, if not altogether impossible, to 13% * 298 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE, make an equal division of land. Nor would one such division suffice. With the first division the difficulty would only begin. Where population is increasing and its centres are constantly changing; where differ- ent vocations make different uses of lands and require different qualities and amounts of it; where improve. ments and discoveries and inventions are constantly bringing out new uses, and changing relative values, a division that should be equal to-day would soon be- come very unequal, and to maintain equality a re- division every year would be necessary. But to make a re-division every year, or to treat land as a common, where no one could claim the ex- clusive use of any particular piece, would only be practicable where men lived in movable tents and made no permanent improvements, and would effectually prevent any advance beyond such a state. No one would sow a crop or build a house, or open a mine, or plant an Orchard, or cut a drain, so long as anyone else could come in and turn him out of the land in which or on which such improvements must be fixed. Thus it is absolutely necessary to the proper use and improve- ment of land that society should secure to the user and improver safe possession. This point is constantly raised by those who resent any questioning of our present treatment of land. They seek to befog the issue by persistently treating every proposition to secure equal rights to land as though it were a proposition to secure an equal division of land, and attempt to defend private property in land by setting forth the necessity of securing safe posses. sion to the improver. But the two things are essentially different. TRUE FREE TRADE. 299 In the first place equal rights to land could not be se. cured by the equal division of land, and in the second place it is not necessary to make land the private prop- erty of individuals in order to secure to improvers that safe possession of their improvements that is needed to induce men to make improvements. On the contrary, private property in land, as we may see in any country where it exists, enables mere dogs-in-the-manger to levy blackmail upon improvers. It enables the mere owner of land to compel the improver to pay him for the privilege of making improvements, and in many cases it enables him to confiscate the improvements. Here are two simple principles, both of which are self- evident : - T.—That all men have equal rights to the use and enjoyment of the elements provided by nature. II.-That each man has an exclusive right to the use and enjoyment of what is produced by his own labor. There is no conflict between these principles. On the contrary they are correlative. To fully secure the individual right of property in the produce of labor we must treat the elements of nature as common property. If any one could claim the sunlight as his property and could compel me to pay him for the agency of the sun in the growth of crops I had planted, it would neces. sarily lessen my right of property in the produce of my labor. And conversely, where every one is secured the full right of property in the produce of his labor, no one can have any right of property in what is not the produce of labor. No matter how complex the industrial organization, nor how highly developed the civilization, there is no real difficulty in carrying out these principles. All we 300 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. have to do is to treat the land as the joint property of the whole people, just as a railway is treated as the joint property of many shareholders, or as a ship is treated as the joint property of several owners. In other words, we can leave land now being used in the secure possession of those using it, and leave land now unused to be taken possession of by those who wish to make use of it, on condition that those who thus hold land shall pay to the community a fair rent for the ex- clusive privilege they enjoy—that is to say, a rent based on the value of the privilege the individual receives from the community in being accorded the exclusive use of this much of the common property, and which should have no reference to any improvement he had made in or on it, or to any profit due to the use of his labor and capital. In this way all would be placed upon an equality in regard to the use and enjoyment of those natural elements which are clearly the com- mon heritage, and that value which attaches to land, not because of what the individual user does, but be- cause of the growth of the community, would accrue to the community, and could be used for purposes of common benefit. As Herbert Spencer has said of it: “Such a doctrine is consistent with the highest state of civiliza- tion; may be carried out without involving a community of goods, and need cause no very serious revolution in existing arrangements. The change required would be simply a change of landlords. Sep- arate ownership would merge into the joint-stock ownership of the public. Instead of being in the possession of individuals, the coun- try would be held by the great corporate body—society. * * * A state of things so ordered would be in perfect harmony with the moral law. Under it all men would be equally landlords, all men would be alike free to become tenants. Clearly, therefore, on such a system the earth might be inclosed, occupied and cultivated, in entire subordination to the law of equal freedom.” TRUE FREE TRADE. * 301 That this simple change would, as Mr. Spencer says, involve no serious revolution in existing arrangements is in many cases not perceived by those who think of it for the first time. It is sometimes said that while this principle is manifestly just, and while it would be easy to apply it to a new country just being settled, it would be exceedingly difficult to apply it to an already settled country where land had already been divided as private property, since, in such a country, to take pos- session of the land as common property and let it out to individuals would involve a sudden revolution of the greatest magnitude. This objection, however, is founded upon the mistaken idea that it is necessary to do everything at once. But it often happens that a precipice we could not hope to climb, and that we might well despair of making a lad- der long enough and strong enough to scale, may be surmounted by a gentle road. And there is in this case a gentle road open to us, which will lead us so far that the rest will be but an easy step. To make land virtu- ally the common property of the whole people, and to appropriate ground rent for public use, there is a much simpler and easier way than that of formally as- suming the ownership of land and proceeding to rent it out in lots—a way that involves no shock, that will conform to present customs, and that, instead of requir. ing a great increase of governmental machinery, will permit of a great simplification of governmental ma- chinery. In every well-developed community large sums are needed for common purposes, and the sums thus needed increase with social growth, not merely in amount, but proportionately, since social progress tends steadily 302 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. to devolve on the community as a whole functions which in a ruder stage are discharged by individuals. Now, while people are not used to paying rent to gov. ernment, they are used to paying taxes to government. Some of these taxes are levied upon personal or mov- able property; some upon occupations or businesses or persons (as in the case of income taxes, which are in re- ality taxes on persons according to income); some upon the transportation or exchange of commodities, in which last category fall the taxes imposed by tariffs; and some, in the United States at least, on real estate—that is to say, on the value of land and of the improvements upon it, taken together. That part of the tax on real estate which is assessed on the value of land irrespective of improvements is, in its nature, not a tax, but a rent—a taking for the common use of the community of a part of the income that prop- erly belongs to the community by reason of the equal right of all to the use of land. Now it is evident that, in order to take for the use of the community the whole income arising from land, just as effectually as it could be taken by formally ap- propriating and letting out the land, it is only necessary to abolish, one after another, all other taxes now levied, and to increase the tax on land values till it reaches, as near as may be, the full annual value of the land. Whenever this point of theoretical perfection is reached, the selling value of land will entirely disap- pear, and the charge made to the individual by the com- munity for the use of the common property will become in form what it is in fact—a rent. But until that point is reached, this rent may be collected by the simple in: TRUE FREE TRADE. 303 crease of a tax already levied in all our states, assessed (as direct taxes are now assessed) upon the selling value of land irrespective of improvements—a value that can be ascertained more easily and more accurately than any other value. For a full exposition of the effects of this change in the method of raising public revenues, I must refer the reader to the works in which I have treated this branch of the subject at greater length than is here possible. Briefly, they would be threefold: In the first place, all taxes that now fall upon the exertion of labor or use of capital would be abolished. No one would be taxed for building a house orimprov- ing a farm or opening a mine, for bringing things in from foreign countries, or for adding in any way to the stock of things that satisfy human wants and con- stitute national wealth. Every one would be free to make and save wealth; to buy, sell, give or exchange, without let or hindrance, any article of human produc- tion the use of which did not involve any public in- jury. All those taxes which increase prices as things pass from hand to hand, falling finally upon the con- sumer, would disappear. Buildings or other fixed im- provements would be as secure as now, and could be bought and sold, as now, subject to the tax or ground rent due to the community for the ground on which they stood. Houses and the ground they stand on, or other improvements and the land they are made on, would also be rented as now. But the amount the tenant would have to pay would be less than now, since the taxes now levied on buildings or improve- ments fall ultimately (save in decaying communities) on the user, and the tenant would therefore get the 304 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. benefit of their abolition. And in this reduced rent the tenant would pay all those taxes that he now has to pay in addition to his rent—any remainder of what he paid on account of the ground going not to increase the wealth of a landlord, but to add to a fund in which the tenant himself would be an equal sharer. In the second place, a large and constantly increasing fund would be provided for common uses, without any tax on the earnings of labor or on the returns of capi- tal—a fund which in well settled countries would not only suffice for all of what are now considered necessary expenses of government, but would leave a large surplus to be devoted to purposes of general benefit. In the third place, and most important of all, the monopoly of land would be abolished, and land would be thrown open and kept open to the use of labor, since it would be unprofitable for any one to hold land without putting it to its full use, and both the tempt- ation and the power to speculate in natural opportuni- ties would be gone. The speculative value of land would be destroyed as soon as it was known that, no matter whether land was used or not, the tax would increase as fast as the value increased; and no one would want to hold land that he did not use. With the disappearance of the capitalized or selling value of land, the premium which must now be paid as pur- chase money by those who wish to use land would disappear, differences in the value of land being meas- ured by what would have to be paid for it to the community, nominally in taxes but really in rent. So long as any unused land remained, those who wished to use it could obtain it, not only without the TRUE FREE TRADE. 305 payment of any purchase price, but without the pay- ment of any tax or rent. Nothing would be required for the use of land till less advantageous land came into use, and possession thus gave an advantage over and above the return to the labor and capital expended upon it. And no matter how much the growth of population and the progress of society increased the value of land, this increase would go to the whole com- munity, swelling that general fund in which the poorest would be an equal sharer with the richest. Thus the great cause of the present unequal distri- bution of wealth would be destroyed, and that one- sided competition would cease which now deprives men who possess nothing but power to labor of the benefits of advancing civilization, and forces wages to a minimum no matter what the increase of wealth. Labor, free to the natural elements of production, would no longer be incapable of employing itself, and compe- tition, acting as fully and freely between employers as between employed, would carry wages up to what is truly their natural rate—the full value of the produce of labor—and keep them there. Let us turn again to the tariff question. The mere abolition of protection—the mere substi- tution of a revenue tariff for a protective tariff—is such a lame and timorous application of the free-trade principle that it is a misnomer to speak of it as free trade. A revenue tariff is only a somewhat milder re- striction on trade than a protective tariff. Free trade, in its true meaning, requires not merely the abolition of protection but the sweeping away of all tariffs—the abolition of all restrictions (save those 306 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. imposed in the interests of public health or morals) on the bringing of things into a country or the carry- ing of things Out of a country. But free trade cannot logically stop with the abo- lition of custom-houses. It applies as well to domestic as to foreign trade, and in its true sense requires the abolition of all internal taxes that fall on buying, sell- ing, transporting or exchanging, on the making of any transaction or the carrying on of any business, save of course where the motive of the tax is public safety, health or morals. -* Thus the adoption of true free trade involves the abolition of all indirect taxation of whatever kind, and the resort to direct taxation for all public revenues. But this is not all. Trade, as we have seen, is a mode of production, and the freeing of trade is bene- ficial because it is a freeing of production. For the same reason, therefore, that we ought not to tax any one for adding to the wealth of a country by bringing valuable things into it, we ought not to tax any one for adding to the wealth of a country by producing within that country valuable things. Thus the prin- ciple of free trade requires that we should not merely abolish all indirect taxes, but that we should abolish as well all direct taxes on things that are the produce of labor; that we should, in short, give full play to the natural stimulus to production—the possession and en- joyment of the things produced—by imposing no tax whatever upon the production, accumulation or pos. session of wealth (i. e., things produced by labor), leav- ing every one free to make, exchange, give, spend or bequeath. There are thus left as, the only taxes by which in TRUE FREE TRADE. 307 accordance with the free-trade principle revenue can be raised, these two classes: 1. Taxes on Ostentation. Since the motive of ostentation in the use of wealth is simply to show the ability to expend wealth, and since this can be shown as well in the ability to pay a tax, taxes on Ostentation pure and simple, while not checking the production of wealth, do not even restrain the enjoyment of wealth. But such taxes, while they have a place in the theory of taxation, are of no prac- tical importance. Some trivial amount is raised in England from taxes on footmen wearing powdered wigs, taxes on armorial bearings, etc., but such taxes are not resorted to in this country, and are incapable anywhere of yielding any considerable revenue. 2. Taxes on the value of land. Taxes on the value of land must not be confounded with taxes on land, from which they differ essentially. Taxes on land—that is to say, taxes levied on land by quantity or area—apply equally to all land, and hence fall ultimately on production, since they constitute a check to the use of land, a tax that must be paid as the condition of engaging in production. Taxes on land values, however, do not fall upon all land, but only upon valuable land, and on that in proportion to its value. Hence they do not in any degree check the ability of labor to avail itself of land, and are merely an appropriation, by the taxing power, of a portion of the premium which the owner of valuable land can charge labor for its use. In other words, a tax on land, according to quantity, could ultimately be transferred by owners of land to users of ‘land and become a tax upon production. But a tax on land vaſues, must, as 308 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. is recognized by all economists, fall on the owner of land and cannot be by him in any way transferred to the user. The land owner can no more compel those to whom he may sell or let his land to pay a tax levied on its value, than he could compel them to pay a mortgage. - A tax on land values is of all taxes that which best fulfills every requirement of a perfect tax. As land cannot be hidden or carried off, a tax on land values can be assessed with more certainty and can be col- 1ected with greater ease and less expense than any other tax, while it does not in the slightest degree check production or lessen its incentive. It is, in fact, a tax only in form, being in nature a rent—a taking for the use of the community of a value that arises not from Individual exertion but from the growth of the community. For it is not anything that the indi- vidual owner or user does that gives value to land. The value that he creates is a value that attaches to improvements. This, being the result of individual exertion, properly belongs to the individual, and can- not be taxed without lessening the incentive to produc- tion. But the value that attaches to land itself is a value arising from the growth of the community and increasing with Social growth. It, therefore, properly belongs to the community, and can be taken to the last penny without in the slightest degree lessening the incentive to production. Taxes on land values are thus the only taxes from which, in accordance with the principle of free trade, any considerable amount of revenue can be raised, and it is evident that to carry out the free-trade principle to the point of abolishing all taxes that hamper or les- TRUE FREE TRADE. 309 sen production would of itself involve very nearly the same measures which we have seen are required to assert the common right to land and place all citizens upon an equal footing. To make these measures identically the same, it is only necessary that the taxation of land values, to which true free trade compels us to resort for public revenues, should be carried far enough to take, as near as might practically be, the whole of the income arising from the value given to land by the growth of the community. But we have only to go one step further to see that free trade does, indeed, require this, and that the two reforms are thus absolutely identical. Free trade means free production. Now fully to free production it is necessary not only to remove all taxes on production, but also to remove all other restrictions on production. True free trade, in short, requires that the active factor of production, Labor, shall have free access to the passive factor of production, Land. To secure this all monopoly of land must be broken up, and the equal right of all to the use of the natural ele- ments must be secured by the treatment of the land as the common property in usufruct of the whole peo- ple. *. Thus it is that free trade brings us to the same sim- ple measure as that which we have seen is necessary to emancipate labor from its thralldom and to secure that justice in the distribution of wealth which will make every improvement or reform beneficial to all classes. The partial reform miscalled free trade, which con- sists in the mere abolition of protection—the mere sub- 310 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. stitution of a revenue tariff for a protective tariff– cannot help the laboring classes, because it does not touch the fundamental cause of that unjust and unequal distribution which, as we see to-day, makes “labor a drug and population a nuisance” in the midst of such a plethora of wealth that we talk of over production. True free trade, on the contrary, leads not only to the largest production of wealth, but to the fairest dis- tribution. It is the easy and obvious way of bringing about that change by which alone justice in distribution can be secured, and the great inventions and discover- ies which the human mind is now grasping can be con- verted into agencies for the elevation of society from its very foundations. This was seen with the utmost clearness by that knot of great Frenchmen who, in the last century, first raised the standard of free trade. What they proposed was not the mere substitution of a revenue tariff for a pro- tective tariff, but the total abolition of all taxes, direct and indirect, save a single tax upon the value of land— the impôt unique. They realized that this unification of taxation meant not merely the removal from com- merce and industry of the burdens placed upon them, but that it also meant the complete reconstruction of Society—the restoration to all men of their natural and equal rights to the use of the earth. It was because they realized this, that they spoke of it in terms that applied to any mere fiscal change, however benefi- cial, would seem wildly extravagant, likening it, in its importance to mankind, to those primary inventions which made the first advances in civilization possible— the use of money and the adoption of written char. aCterS. TRUE FREE TRADE. 311 And whoever will consider how far-reaching are the benefits that would result to mankind from a measure which, removing all restrictions from the production of wealth, would also secure equitable distribution, will • See that these great Frenchmen were not extravagant. True free trade would emancipate labor. CHAPTER XXVII. THE LION IN THE WAY. WE may now see why the advocacy of free trade has been so halting and half-hearted. It is because the free-trade principle carried to its logi- cal conclusion would destroy that monopoly of nature's bounty which enables those who do no work to live in luxury at the expense of “the poor people who have to work,” that so-called free traders have not ventured to ask even the abolition of tariffs, but have endeav- ored to confine the free-trade principle to the mere abolition of protective duties. To go further would be to meet the lion of “vested interests.” In Great Britain the ideas of Quesnay and Turgot found a soil in which, at the time, they could only grow in stunted form. The power of the landed aristocracy was only beginning to findsomething of a counterpoise in the growth of the power of capital, and in politics, as in liter- ature, Labor had no voice. Adam Smith belonged to that class of men of letters always disposed by strong motives to view things which the dominant class deem essential in the same light as they do, and who before the diffusion of education and the cheapening of books could have had no chance of being heard on any other terms. Under the shadow of an absolute despotism more liberty of thought and expression may sometimes be enjoyed than where power is more diffused, and THE LION IN THE WAY. 313 forty years ago it would doubtless have been safer to express in Russia opinions adverse to serfdom than in South Carolina to have questioned slavery. And so, while Quesnay, the favorite physician of the master of France, could in the palace of Versailles carry his free- trade propositions to the legitimate conclusion of the timpôt unique, Adam Smith, had he been so radical, could hardly have got the leisure to write the Wealth of Nations or the means to print it. I am not criticising Adam Smith, but pointing out conditions which have affected the development of an idea. The task which Adam Smith undertook—that of showing the absurdity and impolicy of protective tariffs—was in his time and place a sufficiently difficult one, and even if he saw how much further than this the principles he enunciated really led, the prudence of the man who wishes to do what may be done in his day and generation, confident that where he lays the foundation others will in due time rear the edifice, might have prompted him to avoid carrying them further. However this may be, it is evidently because free trade really goes so far, that British free traders, so- called, have been satisfied with the abolition of protec- tion, and, abbreviating the motto of Quesnay, “Clear the ways and let things alone,” into “Let things alone,” have shorn off its more important half. For one step further—the advocacy of the abolition of revenue tariffs, as well as of protective tariffs—would have brought them upon dangerous ground. It is not only, as English writers intimate to excuse the retaining of a revenue tariff, that direct taxation could not be resorted to with- out arousing the British people to ask themselves why 14 314 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. they should continue to support the descendants of royal favorites, and to pay interest on the vast sums spent dur- ing former generations in worse than useless wars; but it is that direct taxation could not be advocated with- out danger to even more important “vested interests.” One step beyond the abolition of protective duties, and the British free-trade movement must have come full against that fetich which for some generations the Brit- ish people have been taught to reverence as the very Ark of the Covenant—private property in land. For in the British kingdoms (save in Ireland and the Scottish Highlands) private property in land was not instituted in the short and easy way in which Will Atkins endeavored to institute it on Crusoe's island. It has been the gradual result of a long series of usurpa- tions and spoliations. In the view of British law there is to-day but one owner of British soil, the Crown—that is to say, the British people. The individual landholders are still in constitutional theory what they once were in actual fact—mere tenants. The process by which they have become virtual owners has been that of throwing upon indirect taxation the rents and taxes they were once held to pay in return for their lands, while they have added to their domains by fencing in the com- mons, in much the same manner as Some of the same class have recently fenced in large tracts of our own public domain. The entire abolition of the British tariff would in- volve as a necessary consequence the abolition of the greater part of the internal indirect taxation, and would thus compel heavy direct taxation, which would fall not upon consumption but upon possession. The mo- ment this became necessary, the question of what share THE LION IN THE WAY. 315 should be borne by the holders of land must inevitably arise in such a way as to open the whole question of the rightful ownership of British soil. For not only do all economic considerations point to a tax on land values as the proper source of public revenues; but so do all British traditions. A land tax of four shillings in the pound of rental value is still nominally enforced in Eng- land, but being levied on a valuation made in the reign or William III, it amounts in reality to not much over a penny in the pound. With the abolition of indirect taxation this is the tax to which men would naturally turn. The resistance of landholders would bring up the question of title, and thus any movement which went so far as to propose the substitution of direct for indirect taxation must inevitably end in a demand for the restoration to the British people of their birthright. This is the reason why in Great Britain the free trade principle was aborted into that spurious thing “British free trade,” which calls a sudden halt to its own princi- ples, and after demonstrating the injustice and impolicy of all tariffs, proceeds to treat tariffs for revenue as some- thing that must of necessity exist. In assigning these reasons for the failure to carry the free-trade movement further than the abolition of pro- tection, I do not, of course, mean to say that such rea- sons have consciously swayed free traders. I am defi- nitely pointing out what by them has been in many cases doubtless only vaguely felt. We imbibe the sympa- thies, prejudices and antipathies of the circle in which We move, rather than acquire them by any process of reasoning. And the prominent advocates of free trade, the men who have been in a position to lead and edu- cate public opinion, have belonged to the class in 316 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. which the feelings I speak of hold sway—for that is the class of education and leisure. In a society where unjust division of wealth gives the fruits of labor to those who do not labor, the classes who control the organs of public education and opinion —the classes to whom the many are accustomed to look for light and leading, must be loath to challenge the primary wrong, whatever it may be. This is inevitable, from the fact that the class of wealth and leisure, and consequently of culture and influence, must be, not the class which loses by the unjust distribution of wealth, but the class which (at least relatively) gains by it. Wealth means power and “respectability,” while poverty means weakness and disrepute. So in such a society the class that leads and is looked up to, while it may be willing to tolerate vague generalities and im- practicable proposals, must frown on any attempt to trace social evils to their real cause, since that is the cause that gives their class superiority. On the other hand, the class that suffers by these evils is, on that account, the ignorant and uninfluential class, the class that, from its own consciousness of inferiority, is prone to accept the teachings and imbibe the prejudices of the one above it; while the men of superior ability that arise within it and elbow their way to the front are constantly received into the ranks of the superior class and interested in its service, for this is the class that has rewards to give. Thus it is that social injus- tice so long endures and is so difficult to make head against. Thus it was that in our Southern States while slavery prevailed, the influence, not only of the slaveholders themselves, but of churches and colleges, the profes- THE LION IN THE WAY. 317 sions and the press, condemned so effectually any ques- tioning of slavery, that men who never owned and never expected to own a slave were ready to persecute and ostracize any one who breathed a word against property in flesh and blood—ready, even, when the time came, to go themselves and be shot in defence of the “peculiar institution.” Thus it was that even slaves believed abolitionists the worst of human kind, and were ready to join in the sport of tarring and feathering one. And so, an insti- tution in which only a comparatively small class were interested, and which was in reality so unprofitable, even to them, that now that slavery has been abolished, it would be hard to find an ex-slaveholder who would restore it if he could, not only dominated public opinion where it existed, but exerted such influence at the North, where it did not exist, that “abolitionist” was for a long time suggestive of “atheist,” “communist” and “incendiary.” The effect of the introduction of steam and labor-sav- ing machinery upon the industries of Great Britain was such a development of manufactures as to do away with all semblance of benefit to the manufacturing classes from import duties, to raise up a capitalistic power capable of challenging the dominance of the “landed interest,” and by concentrating workmen in towns to make of them a more important political factor. The abolition of protection in Great Britain was carried, against the opposition of the agricultural landholders, by a combination of two elements, capital and labor, neither of which would, of itself, have been capable of winning the victory. But, of the two, that which was represented by the Manchester manufacturers possessed, 318 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. much more effective and independent strength than that whose spirit breathed in the Anti-Corn Law rhymes. Capital furnished the leadership, the organizing ability, and the financial means for agitation, and when it was Satisfied, the further progress of the free-trade move- ment had to wait for the growth of a power which, as an independent factor, is only now beginning to make its entrance into British politics. Any advance toward the abolition of revenue duties would not only have added the strength of the holders of municipal and mining land to that of the holders of agricultural land, but would also have arrayed in opposition the very class most efficient in the free-trade movement. For, save where their apparent interests come into clear and strong opposition, as they did in Great Britain upon the question of protective duties, capitalists as a class share the feelings that animate landholders as a class. Even in England, where the division between the three eco- nomic orders—landholders, capitalists, and laborers—is clearer than anywhere else, the distinction between landholders and capitalists is more theoretical than real. That is to say, the landholder is generally a capitalist as well, and the capitalist is generally in actuality or ex- pectation to some extent a landholder, or by the agency of leases and mortgages is interested in the profits of landholding. Public debts and the investments based thereon constitute, moreover, a further powerful agency in disseminating through the whole “House of Have" a bitter antipathy to any thing that might bring the origin of property into discussion. In the United States the same principles have oper- ated, though owing to differences in industrial develop- ment the combinations have been different. Here the THE LION IN THE WAY. -- 819 interest that could not be “protected” has been the agricultural, and the active and powerful manufactur- ing interest has been on the side of protective duties. And though the “landed interest” here has not been so well intrenched politically as in Great Britain, yet not only has land ownership been more widely diffused, but our rapid growth has interested a larger proportion of the present population in anticipating, by speculation based on increasing land values, the power of levying tribute on those yet to come. Thus private property in land has been in reality even stronger here than in Great Britain, while it has been to those interested in it that the opponents of protection have principally appealed. Under such circumstances there has been here even less disposition than in Great Britain to carry the free-trade principle to its legitimate conclusions, and free trade has been presented to the American people in the emasculated shape of a “revenue reform" too timid to ask for even “British free trade.” CEIAPTER XXVIII. FREE TRAL) E AND SOCIALISM. THROUGHOUT the civilized world, and pre-eminently in Great Britain and the United States, a power is now arising which is capable of carrying the principles of free trade to their logical conclusion. But there are difficulties in the way of concentrating this power on such a purpose. It requires reflection to see that manifold effects result from a single cause, and that the remedy for a multitude of evils may lie in one simple reform. As in the infancy of medicine, men were disposed to think each distinct symptom called for a distinct remedy, so when thought begins to turn to social subjects there is a disposition to seek a special cure for every ill, or else (another form of the same shortsightedness) to imagine the only adequate remedy to be something which pre- supposes the absence of those ills; as, for instance, that all men should be good, as the cure for vice and crime; or that all men should be provided for by the State, as the cure for poverty. There is now sufficient social discontent and a sufficient desire for social reform to accomplish great things if concentrated on one line. But attention is dis- tracted and effort divided by schemes of reform which though they may be good in themselves are, with refer. FREE TRADE AND SOCIALISM. 321 ence to the great end to be attained, either inadequate or super-adequate. Here is a traveler who, beset by robbers, has been left bound, blindfolded, and gagged. Shall we stand in a knot about him and discuss whether to put a piece of court-plaster on his cheek or a new patch on his coat, or shall we dispute with each other as to what road he ought to take and whether a bicycle, a tricycle, a horse and wagon, or a railway, would best help him on? Should we not rather postpone such discussion until we have cut the man's bonds? Then he can see for him- self, speak for himself, and help himself. Though with a scratched cheek and a torn coat, he may get on his feet, and if he cannot find a conveyance to suit him, he will at least be free to walk. Very much like such a discussion is a good deal of that now going on over “the social problem "- a dis- cussion in which all sorts of inadequate and impossible schemes are advocated to the neglect of the simple plan of removing restrictions and giving Labor the use of its own powers. This is the first thing to do. And, if not of itself sufficient to cure all social ills and bring about the highest social state, it will at least remove the primary cause of widespread poverty, give to all the opportu- nity to use their labor and secure the earnings that are its due, stimulate all improvement and make all other reſorms easier. It must be remembered that reforms and improve- ments in themselves good may be utterly inefficient to work any general improvement until some more funda- mental reform is carried out. It must be remembered that there is in every work a certain order which must 14% 322 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. be observed to accomplish anything. To a habitable house a roof is as important as walls; and we express in a word the end to which a house is built when we speak of putting a roof over our heads. But we can- not build a house from roof down; we must build from foundation up. . To recur to our simile of the laborer habitually preyed upon by a series of robbers. It is surely wiser in him to fight them one by one, than all together. And the robber that takes all he has left is the one against whom his efforts should first be directed. For no matter how he may drive off the other robbers, that will not avail him except as it may make it easier to get rid of the robber that takes all that is left. But by withstanding this robber he will secure immediate re- lief, and being able to get home more of his earnings than before, will be able so to nourish and strengthen himself that he can better contend with robbers—can, perhaps, buy a gun or hire a lawyer, according to the method of fighting in fashion in his country. It is in just such a way as this that Labor must seek to rid itself of the robbers that now levy upon its earn- ings. Brute strength will avail little unless guided by intelligence. The first attempts of workingmen to improve their condition are by combining to demand higher wages of their direct employers. Something can be done in this way for those within such organizations; but it is after all very little. For a trades-union can only artificially lessen competition within the trade; it cannot affect the general conditions which force men into bitter competition with each other for the opportunity to gain a living. And such organizations as the Knights of Labor, which are FREE TRADE AND SOCIALISM. 323 to trades-unions what the trades-union is to its individ- ual members, while they give greater power, must en- counter the same difficulties in their efforts to raise wages directly. All such efforts have the inherent dis- advantage of struggling against general tendencies. They are like the attempts of a man in a crowd to gain room by forcing back those who press upon him—like attempts to stop a great engine by the sheer force of human muscle, without cutting off steam. This, those who are at first inclined to put faith in the power of trades-unionism are beginning to see, and the logic of events must more and more lead them to see. But the perception that to accomplish large re- sults general tendencies must be controlled, inclines those who do not analyze these tendencies into their causes to transfer faith from some form of the volun- tary organization of labor to some form of governmental organization and direction. All varieties of what is vaguely called socialism rec- ognize with more or less clearness the solidarity of the interests of the masses of all countries. Whatever may be objected to socialism in its extremest forms, it has at least the merit of lessening national prejudices and aiming at the disbandment of armies and the suppres- sion of war. It is thus opposed to the cardinal tenet of protectionism that the interests of the people of different “nations” are diverse and antagonistic. But, on the other hand, those who call themselves socialists, so far from being disposed to look with disfavor upon govern- mental interference and regulation, are disposed to sym- pathize with protection as in this respect in harmony with Socialism, and to regard free trade, at least as it has been popularly presented, as involving a reliance 324. PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. on that principle of free competition which to their thinking means the crushing of the weak. Let us endeavor, as well as can in brief be done, to trace the relations between the conclusions to which we have come and what, with various shades of meaning, is termed “socialism.” ” In socialism as distinguished from individualism there is an unquestionable truth—and that a truth to which (especially by those most identified with free- trade principles) too little attention has been paid. Man is primarily an individual—a separate entity, dif- fering from his fellows in desires and powers, and re- quiring for the exercise of those powers and the gratifi- cation of those desires individual play and freedom. But he is also a social being, having desires that har- monize with those of his fellows, and powers that can only be brought out in concerted action. There is thus a domain of individual action and a domain of social action—some things which can best be done when each acts for himself, and some things which can best be done when society acts for all its members. And * The term “socialism’ is used so loosely that it is hard to attach to it a definite meaning. I myself am classed as a socialist by those who denounce socialism, while those who profess themselves social- ists declare me not to be one. For my own part I neither claim nor repudiate the name, and realizing as I do the correlative truth of bath principles can no more call myself an individualist or a social- ist than one who considers the forces by which the planets are held to their orbits could call himself a centrifugalist or a centripetalist. The German socialism of the school of Marx (of which the leading representative in England is Mr. H. M. Hyndman, and the best exposition in America has been given by Mr. Laurence Gronlund), seems to me a high-purposed but incoherent mixture of truth and fallacy, the defects of which may be summed up in its want of radi. calism—that is to Say, of going to the root. FREE TRADE AND SOCIALISM. 325 the natural tendency of advancing civilizationistomake social conditions relatively more important, and more and more to enlarge the domain of social action. This has not been sufficiently regarded, and at the present time, evil unquestionably results from leaving to in- dividual action functions that by reason of the growth of society and the development of the arts have passed into the domain of social action; just as on the other hand, evil unquestionably results from social inter- ference with what properly belongs to the individual. Society ought not to leave the telegraph and the rail- wāy to the management and control of individuals; nor yet ought society to step in and collect individual debts or attempt to direct individual industry. But while there is a truth in socialism which in- dividualists forget, there is a school of socialists who in like manner ignore the truth there is in individualism, and whose propositions for the improvement of social conditions belong to the class I have called “super-ade- Quate.” Socialism in its narrow sense—the socialism that would have the State absorb capital and abolish competition—is the scheme of men who, looking upon Society in its most complex organization, have failed to see that principles obvious in a simpler stage still hold true in the more intimate relations that result from the division of labor and the use of complex tools and methods, and have thus fallen into fallacies elaborated by the economists of a totally different school, who have taught that capital is the employer and sustainer of labor, and have striven to confuse the distinction between property in land and property in labor-products. Their scheme is that of men who, while revolting from the heartlessness and hopelessness *\, 326 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. of the “orthodox political economy,” are yet entangled in its fallacies and blinded by its confusions. Con- founding “capital” with “means of production,” and ac- cepting the dictum that “natural wages” are the least on which competition can force the laborer to live, they essay to cut a knot they do not see how to unravel, by making the State the sole capitalist and employer, and abolishing competition. The carrying on by government of all production and exchange, as a remedy for the difficulty of finding em- ployment on the one side, and for overgrown fortunes on the other, belongs to the same category as the prescrip- tion that all men should be good. That if all men were assigned proper employment and all wealth fairly dis- tributed, then none would need employment and there would be no injustice in distribution, is as indisputable a proposition as that if all were good none would be bad. But it will not help a man perplexed as to his path to tell him that the way to get to his journey's end is to get there. That all men should be good is the greatest desidera- tum, but it can only be secured by the abolition of con- ditions which tempt some and drive others into evil doing. That each should render according to his abilities and receive according to his needs, is indeed the very highest social state of which we can conceive, but how shall we hope to attain such perfection until we can first find some way of securing to every man the opportunity to labor and the fair earnings of his labor. Shall we try to be generous before we have learned how to be just? All schemes for securing equality in the conditions of men by placing the distribution of wealth in the * • ‘FREE TRADE AND SOCIALISM. 327 hands of government have the fatal defect of beginning at the wrong end. They pre-suppose pure government; but it is not government that makes society; it is so- ciety that makes government; and until there is some- thing like substantial equality in the distribution of wealth, we cannot expect pure government. But to put all men on a footing of substantial equal- ity, so that there could be no dearth of employment, no “over-production,” no tendency of wages to the min- imum of subsistence, no monstrous fortunes on the one side and no army of proletarians on the other, it is not necessary that the state should assume the ownership of all the means of production and become the general employer and universal exchanger; it is necessary only that the equal rights of all to that primary means of production which is the source all other means of pro- duction are derived from, should be asserted. And this, so far from involving an extension of govern- mental functions and machinery, involves, as we have seen, their great reduction. It would thus tend to purify government in two ways—first by the better- ment of the social conditions on which purity in gov- ernment depends, and second, by the simplification of administration. This step taken, and we could safely begin to add to the functions of the state in its proper or co-operative sphere. There is in reality no conflict between labor and capi- tal; * the true conflict is between labor and monopoly. * The great source of confusion in regard to such matters arises from the failure to attach any definite meaning to terms. It must always be remembered that nothing that can be classed either as labor or as land can be accounted capital in any definite use of the term, and that much that we commonly speak of as capital— such as solvent debts, government bonds, etc.—is in reality not even 328 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. That a rich employer “squeezes” needy workmen may be true. But does this squeezing power result from his riches or from their need 7 No matter how rich an employer might be, how would it be possible for him to squeeze workmen who could make a good living for themselves without going into his employment 7. The competition of workmen with workmen for employment, which is the real cause that enables, and even in most cases forces, the employer to Squeeze his workmen, arises from the fact that men, debarred of the natural opportunities to employ themselves, are compelled to bid against one another for the wages of an employer. Abolish the monopoly that forbids men to employ themselves, and capital could not possibly oppress labor. In no case could the capitalist obtain labor for less than the laborer could get by employing himself. Once remove the cause of that injustice which deprives the laborer of the capital his toil creates, and the sharp dis- tinction between capitalist and laborer would, in fact, cease to exist. They who, seeing how men are forced by competi- tion to the extreme of human wretchedness, jump to the conclusion that competition should be abolished, are like those who, seeing a house burn down, would prohibit the use of fire. The air we breathe exerts upon every square inch of our bodies a pressure of fifteen pounds. Were this pressure exerted only on one side, it would pin us to the ground and crush us to a jelly. But being exerted on all sides, we move under it with perfect freedom. It wealth—which all true capital must be. For a fuller elucidation of this, as of similar points, I must refer the reader to my Progress and Poverty. FREE TRADE AND SOCIALISM. 329 not only does not inconvenience us, but it serves such indispensable purposes that, relieved of its pressure, we should die. *- So it is with competition. Where there exists a class denied all right to the element necessary to life and labor, competition is one-sided, and as population increases must press the lowest class into virtual slavery, and even starvation. But where the natural rights of all are secured, then competition, acting on every hand—be- tween employers as between employed; between buyers as between sellers—can injure no one. On the contrary it becomes the most simple, most extensive, most elastic, and most refined system of co-operation, that, in the present stage of social development, and in the domain where it will freely act, we can rely on for the co-ordi- nation of industry and the economizing of Social forces. In short, competition plays just such a part in the social organism as those vital impulses which are be- neath consciousness do in the bodily organism. With it, as with them, it is only necessary that it should be free. The line at which the state should come in is that where free competition becomes impossible—a line analogous to that which in the individual organism separates the conscious from the unconscious functions. There is such a line, though extreme Socialists and ex- treme individualists both ignore it. The extreme in- dividualist is like the man who would have his hunger provide him food; the extreme socialist is like the man who would have his conscious will direct his stomach how to digest it. Individualism and socialism are in truth not antag- onistic but correlative. Where the domain of the one principle ends that of the other begins. And although 330 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. the motto Laissez faire has been taken as the watch. word of an individualism that tends to anarchism, and so-called free traders have made “the law of supply and demand” a stench in the nostrils of men alive to social injustice, there is in free trade nothing that conflicts with a rational socialism. On the contrary, we have but to carry out the free trade principle to its logical con- clusions to see that it brings us to such socialism. The free-trade principle is, as we have seen, the prin- ciple of free production—it requires not merely the abolition of protective tariffs, but the removal of all re- strictions upon production. Within recent years a class of restrictions on produc- tion, imposed by concentrations and combinations which have for their purpose the limiting of production and the increase of prices, have begun to make themselves felt and to assume greater and greater importance. This power of combinations to restrict production arises in some cases from temporary monopolies granted by our patent laws, which (being the premium that society holds out to invention), have a compensatory principle, however faulty they may be in method. Such cases aside, this power of restricting produc- tion is derived, in part, from tariff restrictions. Thus the American steel makers who have recently limited their production, and put up the price of rails 40 per cent. at one stroke, are enabled to do this only by the heavy duty on imported rails. They are able, by com- bination, to put up the price of steel rails to the point at which they could be imported plus the duty, but no further. Hence, with the abolition of the duty this power would be gone. To prevent the play of compe- tition, a combination of the steel workers of the whole FREE TRADE AND SOCIALISM. 331 world would then be necessary, and this is practically impossible. In other part, this restrictive power arises from abil- ity to monopolize natural advantages. This would be destroyed if the taxation of land values made it un- profitable to hold land without using it. In still other part, it arises from the control of businesses which in their nature do not admit of competition, such as those of railway, telegraph, gas, and other similar companies. I read in the daily papers that half a dozen repre- sentatives of the “anthracite coal interest” met last even- ing (March 24, 1886), in an office in New York. Their conference, interrupted only by a collation, lasted till three o'clock in the morning. When they separated they had come to “an understanding among gentle- men” to restrict the production of anthracite coal and advance its price. Now how comes it that half a dozen men, sitting around some bottles of champagne and a box of cigars in a New York office, can by an “understanding among gentlemen” compel Pennsylvania miners to stand idle, and advance the price of coal along the whole eastern seaboard? The power thus exercised is derived in various parts from three sources. 1. From the protective duty on coal. Free trade would abolish that. 2. From the power to monopolize land, which enables them to prevent others from using coal deposits which they will not use themselves. True free trade, as we have seen, would abolish that. 3. From the control of railways, and the consequent power of fixing rates and making discriminations in * transportation. 332 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. The power of fixing rates of transportation, and in this way of discriminating against persons and places, is a power essentially of the same nature as that ex- ercised by governments in levying import duties. And the principle of free trade as clearly requires the removal of such restrictions as it requires the removal of import duties. But here we reach a point where positive action on the part of government is needed. Except as between terminal or “competitive” points where two or more roads meet (and as to these the ten- dency is, by combination or “pooling,” to do away with competition), the carrying of goods and passengers by rail, like the business of telegraph, telephone, gas, water, or similar companies, is in its nature a monopoly. To prevent restrictions and discriminations, governmental control is therefore required. Such control is not only not inconsistent with the free-trade principle; it follows from it, just as the interference of government to prevent and punish assaults upon persons and prop- erty follows from the principle of individual liberty. Thus, if we carry free trade to its logical conclusions we are inevitably led to what monopolists, who wish to be “let alone” to plunder the public, denounce as “so- cialism,” and which is, indeed, socialism, in the sense that it recognizes the true domain of social functions. Whether businesses in their nature monopolies should be regulated by law or should be carried on by the com- munity, is a question of method. It seems to me, how- ever, that experiences goes to show that better results can be secured, with less risk of governmental corrup- tion, by state management than by state regulation. But the great simplification of government which would result from the abolition of the present complex and demoralizing modes of taxation would vastly increase FREE TRADE AND SOCIALISM, 333 the ease and safety with which either of these methods could be applied. The assumption by the state of all . those social functions in which competition will not op- erate would involve nothing like the strain upon gov- ernmental powers, and would be nothing like as pro- vocative of corruption and dishonesty, as our present method of collecting taxes. The more equal distribu- tion of wealth that would ensue from the reform which thus simplified government, would, moreover, increase public intelligence and purify public morals, and enable us to bring a higher standard of honesty and ability to the management of public affairs. We have no right to assume that men would be as grasping and dishonest in a social state where the poorest could get an abun- dant living as they are in the present social state, where - the fear of poverty begets insane greed. Thére is another way, moreover, in which true free trade tends strongly to socialism, in the highest and best sense of the term. The taking for the use of the community of that value of privilege which attaches to the possession of land, would, wherever social develop- ment has advanced beyond a certain stage, yield rev- enues even larger than those now raised by taxation, while there would be an enormous reduction in public oxpenses consequent, directly and indirectly, upon the abolition of present modes of taxation. Thus would be provided a fund, increasing steadily with social growth, that could be applied to social purposes now neglected. And among the purposes which will Sug- gest themselves to the reader by which the surplus in- come of the community could be used to increase the sum of human knowledge, the diffusion of elevating tastes, and the gratification of healthy desires, there is none more worthy thaf, that of making honorable pro- 334 PROTEC ſIC/N OR FREE TRADE. vision for those deprived of their natural protectors, or through no fault of their own incapacitated for the struggle of life. We should think it sin and shame if a great steamer, dashing across the ocean, were not brought to a stop by a signal of distress from the meanest smack; at the sight of an infant lashed to a spar, the mighty ship would round to, and men would spring to launch a boat in angry seas. Thus strongly does the bond of our common humanity appeal to us when we get beyond the hum of civilized life. And yet—a miner is entombed alive, a painter falls from a scaffold, a brakeman is crushed in coupling cars, a merchant fails, falls ill and dies, and organized society leaves widow and children to bitter want or degrading alms. This ought not to be. Citizenship in a civilized community ought of itself to be insurance against such a fate. And having in mind that the income which the community ought to obtain from the land to which the growth of the com- munity gives value is in reality not a tax but the pro- ceeds of a just rent, an English Democrat (William Saunders, M. P.) puts in this phrase the aim of true free trade: “No taxes at all, and a pension to everybody.” This is denounced as “the rankest socialism " by those whose notion of the fitness of things is, that the descendants of royal favorites and blue-blooded thieves should be kept in luxurious idleness all their lives long, by pensions wrung from struggling industry, while the laborcr and his wife, worn out by hard work, for which they have received scarce living wages, are degraded by a parish dole, or separated from each other in a “work-house.” If this is socialism, then, indeed, is it true that free trade leads to Socialism. CEIAPTER XXIX. PRACTICAL POLITICS. ON a railway train I once fell in with a Pittsburg brass band that was returning from a celebration. The leader and I shared the same seat, and between the tunes with which they beguiled the night, we got into a talk which, from politics, touched the tariff. I nei- ther expressed my own opinions nor disputed his, but asked him some questions as to how protection bene- fited labor. His answers seemed hardly to satisfy him- self, and suddenly he said: “Look here, stranger, may I ask you a question 7 I mean no offense, but I'd like to ask you a straight- forward question. Are you a free trader?” “I am.” “A real free trader—one that wants to abolish the tariff 7" “Yes, a real free trader. I would have trade be- tween the United States and the rest of the world as free as it is between Pennsylvania and Ohio.” “Give me your hand, stranger,” said the band leader, jumping up. “I like a man who's out and out.” “Boys,” he exclaimed, turning to some of his bands- men, “here's a sort of man you never saw; here's a real free trader, and he ain't ashamed to own it.” And when the “boys” had shaken hands with me, very much as they might have shaken hands with the “Liv. 336 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. ing Skeleton” or the “Chinese Giant,” “Do you know, stranger,” the bandmaster continued, “I’ve been hear. ing of free traders all my life, but you're the first I ever met. T've seen men that other people called free traders, but when it came their turn they always de- nied it. The most they would admit was that they wanted to trim the tariff down a little, or fix it up bet- ter. But they always insisted we must have a tariff, and I’d got to believe that there were no real free traders; that they were only a sort of bugaboo.” My Pittsburg friend was in this respect, I think, no unfair sample of the great body of the American peo- ple of this generation. The only free traders most of them have seen and heard have been anxious to deny the appellation—or at least to insist that we always must have a tariff, and to deprecate sudden reductions. Is it any wonder that the fallacies of protection run rampant when such is the only opposition they meet? Dwarfed into mere revenue reform the harmony and beauty of free trade are hidden; its moral force is lost; its power to remedy social evils cannot be shown, and the injustice and meanness of protection cannot be ar- raigned. The “international law of God” becomes a mere fiscal question which appeals only to the intellect and not to the heart, to the pocket and not to the con- science, and on which it is impossible to arouse the en- thusiasm that is alone capable of contending with pow- erful interests. When it is conceded that custom-houses must be maintained and import duties levied, the aver- age man will conclude that these duties might as well be protective, or at least will trouble himself little about them. When told that they must beware of moving too quickly, people are not likely to move at all. PRACTICAL POLITICS. 337 Such advocacy is not of the sort that can compel dis- cussion, awaken thought, and press forward a great cause against powerful opposition. Half a truth is not half so strong as a whole truth, and to minimize such a principle as that of free trade in the hope of disarming opposition, is to lessen its power of securing support in far greater degree than to lessen the antagonism it must encounter. A principle that in its purity will be grasped by the popular mind loses its power when befogged by concessions and enervated by compromises. But the mistake which such advocates of free trade make has a deeper root than any misapprehension as to policy. They are, for the most part, men who derive their ideas from the emasculated and incoherent political economy taught in our colleges, or from political tradi- tions of “states rights" and “strict construction ” now broken and weak. They do not present free trade in its beauty and strength because they do not so see it. They have not the courage of conviction, because they have not the conviction. They have opinions, but these opinions lack that burning, that compelling force that springs from a vital conviction. They see the absurd. ity and waste of protection, and the illogical character of the pleas made for it, and these things offend their sense of fitness and truth; but they do not see that free trade really means the emancipation of labor, the aboli- tion of poverty, the restoring to the disinherited of their birthright. Such free traders are well represented by journals which mildly oppose protection when no elec- tion is on, but which at election times are as quiet as mice. They are in favor of what they call free trade, as a certain class of good people are in favor of the con- version of the Jews. When entirely convenient they 338 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. will speak, write, attend a meeting, eat a dinner or give - a little money for the cause, but they will hardly break with their party or “throw away” a vote. Even the most energetic and public-spirited of these men are at a fatal disadvantage when it comes to a popu- lar propaganda. They can well enough point out the abuses of protection and expose its more transparent Sophistries, but they cannot explain the social phenom- ena in which protection finds its real strength. All they can promise the laborer is that production shall be increased and many commodities cheapened. But how can this appeal to men who are accustomed to look upon “over-production” as the cause of widespread distress, and who are constantly told that the cheapness of commodities is the reason why thousands have to suffer for the want of them? And when confronted by the failure of revenue reform to eradicate pauperism and abolish starvation—when asked why in spite of the adoption in Great Britain of the measures he proposes, wages there are so low and poverty so dire, the free trader of this type can make no answer that will satisfy the questioner, even if he can give one satisfactory to himself. The only answer his philosophy can give— the only answer he can obtain from the political econ- omy taught by the “free-trade” text-books—is that the bitter struggle for existence which crushes men into pauperism and starvation is of the nature of things. And whether he attributes this nature of things to the conscious volition of an intelligent Creator or to the working of blind forces, the man who either defi- nitely or vaguely accepts this answer is incapable of feeling himself or of calling forth in others the spirit of Cobden's appeal to Bright. f PRACTICAL FOLITICS. 339 Thus it is that free trade, narrowed to a mere fiscal reform, can only appeal to the lower and weaker mo- tives—to motives that are inadequate to move men in masses. Take the current free-trade literature. Its aim is to show the impolicy of protection, rather than its injustice; its appeal is to the pocket, not to the sympathies. Yet to begin and maintain great popular movements it is the moral sense rather than the intellect that must be appealed to, sympathy rather than self- interest. For however it may be with any individual, the sense of justice is with the masses of men keener and truer than intellectual perception, and unless a question can assume the form of right and wrong it can- not provoke general discussion and excite the many to action. And while material gain or loss impresses us less vividly the greater the number of those we share it with, the power of sympathy increases as it spreads from man to man—becomes cumulative and conta- gious. But he who follows the principle of free trade to its logical conclusion can strike at the very root of protec- tion; can answer every question and meet every objec- tion, and appeal to the surest of instincts and the strongest of motives. He will see in free trade not a mere fiscal reform, but a movement which has for its aim and end nothing less than the abolition of poverty, and of the vice and crime and degradation that flow from it, by the restoration to the disinherited of their natural rights and the establishment of society upon the basis of justice. He will catch the inspiration of a cause great enough to live for and to die for, and be moved by an enthusiasm that he can evoke in others. It is true that to advocate free trade in its fullness 840 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. would excite the opposition of interests far stronger than those concerned in maintaining protective tariffs. But on the other hand it would bring to the standard of free trade, forces without which it cannot succeed. And what those who would arouse thought have to fear is not so much opposition as indifference. With- out opposition that attention cannot be excited, that energy evoked, that are necessary to overcome the in- ertia that is the strongest bulwark of existing abuses. A party can mo more be rallied on a question that no one disputes than steam can be raised to working pres- sure in an open vessel. The working class of the United States, who have constituted the voting strength of protection, are now ready for a movement that will appeal to them on be. half of real free trade. For some years past educative agencies have been at work among them that have sapped their faith in protection. If they have not learned that protection cannot help them, they have at least become widely conscious that protection does not help them. They have been awakening to the fact that there is some deep wrong in the constitution of society, although they may not see clearly what that wrong is; they have been gradually coming to feel that to emanci- pate labor radical measures are needed, although they may not know what those measures are. And scattered through the great body thus beginning to stir and grope are a rapidly increasing number of men who do know what this primary wrong is—men who see that in the recognition of the equal right of all to the element necessary to life and labor is the hope, and the only hope, of curing social injustice. * It is to men of this kind that I would particularly PRACTICAL POLITICS." 341 \ speak. They are the leaven which has in it power to leaven the whole lump. To abolish private property in land is an undertak- ing so great that it may at first seem impracticable. But this seeming impracticability consists merely in the fact that the public mind is not yet sufficiently awakened to the justice and necessity of this great change. To bring it about is simply a work of arous- ing thought. How men vote is something we need not much concern ourselves with. The important thing is how they think. Now the chief agency in promoting thought is dis- cussion. And to secure the most general and most effective discussion of a principle it must be embodied in concrete form and presented in practical politics, so that men, being called to vote on it, shall be forced to think and talk about it. The advocates of a great principle should know no thought of compromise. They should proclaim it in its fullness, and point to its complete attainment as their goal. But the zeal of the propagandist needs to be supplemented by the skill of the politician. While the one need not fear to arouse opposition, the other should seek to minimize resistance. The political art, like the military art, consists in massing the greatest force against the point of least resistance; and, to bring a principle most quickly and effectively into prac- tical politics, the measure which presents it should be so moderate as (while involving the principle) to secure the largest support and excite the least resistance. For whether the first step be long or short is of little consequence. When a start is once made in a right direction, progress is a mere matter of keeping on, 342 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. It is in this way that great questions always enter the phase of political action. Important political bat- tles begin with affairs of outposts, in themselves of little moment, and are generally decided upon issue joined not on the main question, but on some minor or collateral question. Thus the slavery question in the United States came into practical politics upon the issue of the extension of slavery to new territory, and was decisively settled upon the issue of secession. Re- garded as an end, the abolitionist might well have looked with contempt on the proposals of the Republi- cans, but these proposals were the means of bringing to realization what the abolitionists would in vain have sought to accomplish directly. So with the tariff question. Whether we have a protective tariff or a revenue tariff is in itself of small importance, for, though the abolition of protection would increase production, the tendency to unequal distribution would be unaffected and would soon neu- tralize the gain. Yet, what is thus unimportant as an end, is all-important as a means. Protection is a little robber, it is true; but it is the sentinel and outpost of the great robber—the little robber who cannot be routed without carrying the struggle into the very stronghold of the great robber. The great robber is so well in- trenched, and people have so long been used to his ex- actions, that it is hard to arouse them to assail him directly. But to help those engaged in a conflict with this little robber will be to open the easiest way to at- tack his master, and to arouse a spirit that must push on. To secure to all the free use of the power to labor and the full enjoyment of its products, equal rights to land must be secured. * PRACTICAL POLITICS. 343 To secure equal rights to land there is in this stage of civilization but one way. Such measures as peasant proprietary, or “land limitation,” or the reservation to actual settlers of what is left of the public domain, do not tend toward it; they lead away from it. They can affect only a comparatively unimportant class, and that temporarily, while their outcome is not to weaken land-ownership but rather to strengthen it, by interest. ing a larger number in its maintenance. The only way to abolish private property in land is by the way of taxation. That way is clear and straightforward. It consists simply in abolishing, one after another, all im- posts that are in their nature really taxes, and resorting for public revenues to economic rent, or ground value. To the full freeing of land, and the complete emancipa- tion of labor, it is, of course, necessary that the whole of this value should be taken for the common benefit; but that will inevitably follow the decision to collect from this source the revenues now needed, or even any con- siderable part of them, just as the entrance of a victori- ous army into a city follows the rout of the army that defended it. In the United States the most direct way of moving on property in land is through local taxation, since that is already to some extent levied upon land values. And that is doubtless the way in which the final and decisive advance will be made. But national politics dominate state politics, and a question can be brought into discussion much more quickly and thoroughly as a national than as a local question. Now to bring an issue into politics it is not necessary to form a party. Parties are not to be manufactured; they grow out of existing parties by the bringing for 344 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. ward of issues upon which men will divide. We have ready to our hand, in the tariff question, a means of bringing the whole subject of taxation, and, through it, the whole social question, into the fullest discus- SIOT). As we have seen in the inquiry through which we have passed, the tariff question necessarily opens the whole social question. Any discussion of it to-day must go further and deeper than the Anti-Corn Law agitation in Great Britain, or than the tariff controver- sies of Whigs and Democrats, for the progress of thought and the march of invention have made the distribution of wealth the burning question of our times. The making of the tariff question a national political issue must now mean the discussion in every newspaper, on every stump, and at every cross-roads where two men meet, of questions of work and wages, of capital and labor, of the incidence of taxation, of the nature and rights of property, and of the question to which all these questions lead—the question of the relation of men to the planet on which they live. In this way more can be accomplished for popular economic education in a year than could otherwise be accomplished in decades. Therefore it is that I would urge earnest men who aim at the emancipation of labor and the establishment of social justice, to throw themselves into the free-trade movement with might and main, and to force the tariff question to the front. It is not merely that the free- trade side of the tariff controversy best consorts with the interests of labor; it is not merely that until work- ingmen get over thinking of labor as a poor thing that needs to be “protected,” and of work as a dole from gracious capitalists or paternal governments, they cannot PRACTICAL POLITICS. 345 rise to a sense of their rights; but it is that the move. ment for free trade is in reality the van of the struggle for the emancipation of labor. This is the way the bull must go to untwist his rope. It makes no difference how timorously the issue against protection is now pre- sented ; it is still the thin end of the wedge. It makes no difference how little we can hope at once to do; social progress is by steps, and the step to which we should address ourselves is always the next step.” --- l * There is no reason why at least the bulk of the revenues needed nor the national government under our system should not be col- lected from a percentage on land values, leaving the rest for the local governments, just as state, county and municipal taxes are collected on one assessment and by one set of officials. On the contrary there is, over and above the economy that would thus be secured, a strong reason for the Collection of national revenues from land values in the fact that the ground values of great cities and mineral deposits are due to the general growth of population. But the total abolition of the tariff need not await any such ad- justment. The issuance of paper money, a function belonging properly to the General Government, would, properly used, yield a considerable income; while independent sources of any needed amount of revenue could be found in various taxes, which though not economically perfect, as is the tax on land values, are yet much less objectionable than taxes on imports. The excise tax on spiritu- ous liquors ought to be abolished, as it fosters corruption, injuri- ously affects many branches of manufacture and puts a premium on adulteration ; but either by a government monopoly, or by license taxes on retail sales, a large revenue might be derived from the liquor traffic with much greater advantage to public health and morals than by the present system. There are also some stamp taxes which are comparatively uninjurious and can be collectected easily and cheaply. But of all methods of raising an independent Federal revenue, that which would yield the largest return with the greatest ease and least injury is a tax upon legacies and successions. In a large population the proportion of deaths is as regular as that of births, and with proper exemptions in favor of widows, minor children and 346 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. Nor does it matter that those now active in the free. trade movement have no sympathy with our aims; nor that they denounce and misrepresent us. It is our policy to support them, and strengthen them and urgo them on. No matter how soon they may propose to stop, the direction they wish to take is the direction in which we must go if we would reach our goal. In joining our forces to theirs, we shall not be putting- ourselves to their use, we shall be making use of them. But these men themselves, when fairly started and borne on by the impulse of controversy, will go further than they now dream. It is the law of all such move- ments that they must become more and more radical. And while we are especially fortunate in the United States in a class of protectionist leaders who will not yield an inch until forced to, our political conditions differ from those of Great Britain in 1846, when, the laboring class being debarred from political power, a timely surrender on the part of the defenders of pro- tection checked for awhile the natural course of the movement, and thus prevented the demand for the abo- lition of protection from becoming at once a demand for the abolition of landlordism. The class that in dependent relatives, such a tax would bear harshly on no one, and from the publicity which must attach to the transfer of property by death or in view of death it is easily collected and little liable to evasion. The appropriation of land values would of itself strike at the heart of overgrown fortunes, but until that is aſ cºmplished, a . tax of this kind would have the incidental advantage of interfering with their transmission. g Of all excuses for the continuance of any tariff at all, the most groundless is that it is necessary to secure Federal revenues. Ever the income tax, bad as it is, is in all respects better than a tariff. PRACTICAL POLITICS. 347 Great Britain is only coming into political power has, with us, political power already. Yet even in Great Britain the inevitable tendencies of the free-trade movement may clearly be seen. Not only has the abolition of protection cleared the ground for the far greater questions now beginning to enter British politics; not only has the impulse of the free- trade agitation led to reforms which are placing political power in the hands of the many; but the work done by men who, having begun by opposing protection, were not content to stop with its abolition, has been one of the most telling factors in hastening the revolu- tion now in its incipient stages—a revolution that can- not stop short of the restoration to the British people of their natural rights to their native land. Richard Cobden saw that the agitation of the tariff question must ultimately pass into the agitation of the land question, and from what I have heard of him I am inclined to think that were he in life and vigor to-day, he would be leading in the movement for the restora- tion to the British people of their natural rights in their native land. But, however this may be, the British free-trade movement left a “remnant” who, like Thomas Briggs,” have constantly advocated the carrying of free trade to its final conclusions. And one of the most ef- fective of the revolutionary agencies now at work in Great Britain is the Liverpool Financial Reform Asso- * Author of Property and Taa’ation, etc., and a warm supporter of the movement for the restoration of their land to the British people. Mr. Briggs was one of the Manchester manufacturers active in the Anti-Corn Law movement, and, regarding that victory as a mere beginning, has always insisted that Great Britain was yet under the blight of protectionism, and that the struggle for trº free trade was yet to come. 348 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. ciation, whose Financial Reform Almanac and other publications are doing so much to make the British people acquainted with the process of usurpation and spoliation by which the land of Great Britain has been made the private property of a class, and British labor saddled with the support of a horde of aristocratic pau- pers. Yet the Liverpool Financial Reform Association is composed of men who, for the most part, would shrink from any deliberate attack upon property in land. They are simply free traders of the Manchester school, logical enough to see that free trade means the abolition of rev- enue tariffs as well as of protective tariffs. But in striking at indirect taxation they are of necessity deal- ing tremendous blows at private property in land, and Sapping the very foundations of aristocracy, since, in showing the history of indirect taxation, they are show- ing how the tenants of the nation's land made them- selves virtual owners; and in proposing the restoration of the direct tax upon land values they are making an issue which will involve the complete restoration of British land to the British people. Thus it is that when men take up the principle of freedom they are led on and on, and that the hearty advocacy of freedom to trade becomes at length the ad- vocacy of freedom to labor. And so must it be in the United States. Once the tariff question becomes a na- tional issue, and in the struggle against protection, free traders will be forced to attack indirect taxation. Pro- tection is so well intrenched that before a revenue tar- iff can be secured the active spirits of the free-trade party will have far passed the point when that would satisfy them; while before the abolition of indirect tax- ation is reached, the incidence of taxation and the na’ PRACTICAL POLITICS. . 349 ture and effect of private property in land will have been so well discussed that the rest will be but a matter of time. Property in land is as indefensible as property in man. It is so absurdly impolitic, so outrageously unjust, so flagrantly subversive of the true right of property, that it can only be instituted by force and maintained by confounding in the popular mind the distinction be. tween property in land and property in things that are the result of labor. Once that distinction is made clear —and a thorough discussion of the tariff question must How make it clear—and private property in land is doomed. CEIAPTER XXX. CONCLUSION. A WEALTHY citizen whom I once supported, and called on others to support, for the Presidential chair, under the impression that he was a Democrat of the school of Jefferson, has recently published a letter ad- vising us to steel-plate our coasts, lest foreign navies come over and bombard us. This counsel of timidity has for its hardly disguised object the inducing of such an enormous expenditure of public money as will pre- vent any demand for the reduction of taxation, and thus secure to the tariff rings a longer lease of plunder. It well illustrates the essential meanness of the protection- ist spirit—a spirit that no more comprehends the true dignity of the American Republic and the grandeur of her possibilities than it cares for the material interests of the great masses of her citizens—“the poor people who have to work.” That which is good harmonizes with all things good; and that which is evil tends to other evil things. Prop- erly does Buckle, in his History of Civilization, apply the term “protective " not merely to the system of robbery by tariffs, but to the spirit that teaches that the many are born to serve and the few to rule; that props thrones with bayonets, substitutes small vanities and petty jealousies for high-minded patriotism, and converts the CONCLUSION. 351 { * *. flower of European youth into uniformed slaves, trained to kill each other at the word of command. It is not accidental that Mr. Tilden, anxious to get rid of the surplus revenue in order to prevent a demand for the repeal of protective duties, should propose wasting it on steel-clad forts, rather than applying it to any pur- pose of general utility. Fortifications and navies and standing armies not merely suit the protectionist pur- pose in requiring a constant expenditure, and develop. ing a class who look on warlike expenditures as con- ducive to their own profit and importance, but they are of a piece with a theory that teaches us that our interests are antagonistic to those of other nations. . Unembarrassed by hostile neighbors; unentangled in European quarrels; already, in her sixty millions of people the most powerful nation on earth, and rapidly rising to a position that will dwarf the greatest empires, the American Republic can afford to laugh to scorn any suggestion that she should ape the armaments of Old World monarchies, as she should laugh to scorn the parallel suggestion that her industries could be ruined by throwing open her ports to the commerce of the world. The giant of the nations does not depend for her safety upon steel-clad fortresses and armor-plated ships which the march of invention must within a few years make, even in war-time, mere useless rubbish ; but in her population, in her wealth, in the intelligence and inventiveness and spirit of her people, she has all that would be really useful in time of need. No nation on earth would venture wantonly to attack her, and none could do so with impunity. If we ever again have a foreign war it will be of our own making. And 352 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. too strong to fear aggression, we ought to be too just to commit it. In throwing open our ports to the commerce of the world we shall far better secure their safety than by fortifying them with all the “protected” plates that our steel ring could make. For not merely would free trade give us again that mastery of the ocean which protection has deprived us of, and stimulate the productive power in which real fighting strength lies; but while steel-clad forts could afford no defense against the dynamite-dropping balloons and death-deal- ing air ships which will be the next product of destruc- tive invention, free trade would prevent their ever be. ing sent against us. The spirit of protectionism, which is the real thing that it is sought to defend by steel- plating, is that of national enmity and strife. The spirit of free trade is that of fraternity and peace. A nobler career is open to the American Republic than the servile imitation of European follies and vices. Instead of following in what is mean and low, she may lead toward what is grand and high. This league of sovereign states, settling their differences by a common tribunal and opposing no impediments to trade and travel, has in it possibilities of giving to the world a more than Roman peace. What are the real, substantial advantages of this Union of ours ? Are they not summed up in the abso- lute freedom of trade which it secures, and the commu- nity of interests that grows out of this freedom. If our states were fighting each other with hostile tariſts, and a citizen could not cross a state boundary line with. out having his baggage searched, or a book printed in New York could not be sent across the river to CONCLUSION. 353 Jersey City without being held in the post-office until duty was paid, how long would our Union last, or what would it be worth 2 The true benefits of our Union, the true basis of the inter-state peace it secures, is that it has prevented the establishment of state tariffs and given us free trade over the better part of a conti- ment. We may “extend the area of freedom" whenever we choose to—whenever we apply to our intercourse with other nations the same principle that we apply to inter- course between our states. We may annex Canada to all intents and purposes whenever we throw down the tariff wall we have built around Ourselves, We need not ask for any reciprocity; if we abolish our custom houses and call off our baggage searchers and Bible confiscators, Canada would not and could not maintain hers. This would make the two countries practically one. Whether the Canadians chose to maintain a sepa- rate Parliament and pay a British lordling for keep- ing up a mock court at Rideau Hall, need not in the slightest concern us. The intimate relations that would come of unrestricted commerce would soon ob- literate the boundary line; and mutual interest and mutual convenience would speedily induce the exten- sion over both countries of the same general laws and institutions. And so would it be with our kindred over the sea. With the abolition of our custom houses and the open- ing of our ports to the free entry of all good things, the trade between the British Islands and the United States would become so immense, the intercourse so intimate, that we should become one people, and would inevita- bly so conform currency, and postal system and general 29 354 PROTECTION OR FREE TRADE. laws that Englishman and Amerigan would feel them. selves as much citizens of a common country as do New Yorker and Californian. Three thousand miles of water are no more of an impediment to this than are three thousand miles of land. And with relations so close, ties of blood and language would assert their power, and mutual interest, general convenience and fraternal feeling might soon lead to a pact, which, in the words of our own, would unite all the English speaking peoples in a league “to establish justice, in- sure domestic tranquillity, provide for the common defense, promote the general welfare, and secure the blessings of liberty.” Thus would free trade unite what a century ago pro- tectionism severed, and in a federation of the nations of English speech—the world-tongue of the future— take the first step to a federation of mankind. And upon our relations with all other nations our repudiation of protection would have a similar tend- ency. The sending of delegations to ask the trade of our sister republics of Spanish America avails nothing so long as we maintain a tariff which repels their trade. We have but to open our ports to draw their trade to us and avail ourselves of all their natural advantages. And more potent than anything clºe would be the moral influence of our action. The spectacle of a con- tinental republic such as ours, really putting her faith in the principle of freedom, would revolutionize the civilized world. For, as I have shown, that violation of natural rights which imposes tariff duties is inseparably linked with that violation of natural rights which compels the masses to pay tribute for the privilege of living. The one CONCLUSION. 355 cannot be abolished without the other. And a republic wherein the free-trade principle was thus carried to its conclusion, wherein the equal and unalienable rights of men were thus acknowledged, would indeed be as a city set on a hill. The dangers to the Republic come not from without but from within. What menaces her safety is no armada launched from European shores, but the gather- ing cloud of tramps in her own highways. That Krupp is casting monstrous cannon, and that in Cherbourg and Woolwich projectiles of unheard-of destructiveness are being stored, need not alarm her, but there is black omen in the fact that Pennsylvania miners are working for 65 cents a day. No triumphant invader can tread our soil till the blight of “great estates’ has brought “failure of the crop of men;” if there be danger that our cities blaze, it is from torches lit in faction fight, not from foreign shells. Against such dangers forts will not guard us, iron- clads protect us, or standing armies prove of any avail. They are not to be avoided by any aping of European protectionism; they come from our failure to be true to that spirit of liberty which was invoked at the forma- tion of the Republic. They are only to be avoided by conforming our institutions to the principle of free- dom. For it is true, as was declared by the first National Assembly of France, that “ignorance, neglect, or contempt of human rights are the sole causes of public misfortunes and corruptions of government.” Here is the conclusion of the whole matter : That we should do unto others as we would have them do 356. PROTECTION or FREE TRADE. to us—that we should respect the rights of others as scrupulously as we would have our own rights re- spected, is not a mere counsel of perfection to individ- uals, but it is the law to which we must conform social institutions and national policy if we would secure the blessings of abundance and peace. IN D F X. American Republic, possibilities of, 351. Balance of trade, 121. origin of the idea, 132. Bounties, 90, 98, 106, 110. Briggs, Thomas, 347. Bright, John, 296. Buckle, 351. Capital, not the oppressor of labor, 294; no conflict between capital and labor, 327; con- fusions in regard to, 327. Carey, H. C., 10, 86. Coal and iron monopolies, 189, 331. Cobden Club, opposed to true free trade, 15. Cobden, Richard, 296, 347. Competition, functions and ef- ſects, 328. Concentration, causes of tend- ency to, 176. Co-operative stores, 73. Copyright, international, 219. De Tocqueville, 201. Distribution, effects of increased production on, 274. Drawbacks, 92. Duties, export and import, com- pared, 124. Bºh estates in America, 128, 293. Evarts, Wm. M., 141. Exchange, international, gov- erned by comparative cost of production, 157. Export duties, objections to, 125. Exports, due to other things than exchange, 126. “Fair-traders,” 159. Fortification of our coasts, 351. Fourier, Charles, 70. Free trade, a general interest, 13; not a British invention, 14; natural trade, 15; British, 15; in the United States, 16; in Ireland, 19; in the U. S., causes which have prejudiced workingmen against, 20, 238, 244; and socialism, 321; inade- quacy of the usual argument for, 238, 244; movement in Eng- land, 247, 312, 346; true, 296; why its advocacy has been so halting, 312; means peace, 351. Greeley, Horace, 61, 69, 102, 108, 119, 157, 188, 220. Gronlund, Laurence, 324. Hoyt, Henry M., 257. Hyndman, H. M., 324. Imports, in a profitable trade jä exceed exports, 125; do not always imply exports, 126. Import duties, fall on consumers, 78; claim that they are paid by foreigners, 93. Interest, rate of, as reason for rotection, 154. Individualism, 324. Invention, effects of labor-saving, 281. Ireland, tariffs and industry of, 18; American remittances to, 127. 358 INDEX. Iron, effect of the duty on, 160, 189. Labor, efficiency varies with wages, 149; value the measure of embodied, 118, 147; relative not absolute cost of, determines exchanges, 157; the true stand- ard of value, 211; not pro- tected by tariffs, 218; condi- tions becoming harder, 249, 275; of itself helpless, 263; cause of its impoverishment, 285. Laborer, full meaning of the term, 75. Land, value of, increases as wages fall, 152; effects of private ownership of, 176, 184, 285; the passive factor in produc- tion, 184; monopoly of timber and mineral lands, 183; influ- ence of price of, on wages, 227; monopoly of, gives control of labor, 277, 295; value of, 290; how equal rights to, may be asserted, 297; necessity of se- cure possession, 298. Land-owner, not a producer, 185. Machinery, effects of, 270. Malthus, 9. Manufactures, natural develop- ment of, 163; localization of, 1 º ; large demand necessary to, 171. Marx, Karl, 324. Mill, John Stuart, 9, 94. Middlemen, 70. Mining royalties, 188. Money, confusions arising from use of, 132; fluctuations in the value of, 211. Navigation laws, effects of, 206. Over-production, 246. Octroi, 71. Physiocrats, 15, 310, 312. Political economy, simplicity of, 8; method of, 27; mercantile system of, 187. Production, , what it embraces, 66; cost of, not determined by wages, 147; advantages for, 15; factors of, 184; increase of, does not benefit all, 246. Protection reasserting itself in Great Britain, 3, 112, 159; ends praiseworthy, 5; general ac- ceptance, 12; influences it en- lists, 13; not American, 14, 45; in the case of Ireland, 18; causes that dispose Working- men in its favor, 20, 257; its Spirit that of enmity, 14, 34, 350; its corrupting tendencies, 35, 84, 100; what it prevents, 49; a world suited to, 57; its genesis, 76, 82, 137; is boy- cotting of ourselves, 114, 160; its real beneficiaries, 177; ef- fect on prices, 96; effect on profits, 96, 177; effect upon other countries, 160; effect on land values, 186; first asked for the establishment of new industries, 103; difference be- tween protectionist writers and popular pleas, 107; derives strength from confusions of thought arising from the use of money, 137; effects on American industry, 193; in- jurious to the development of manufactures, 163, 177, 193; tends to unjust distribution, 252; home market argument, 1.12; balance-of-trade argu- ment, 121; high-wages' argu- ment, 145; arguments drawn from advantages or disadvan- tages, 154; abolition of, would stimulate industry, 192, 231; plea for gradual abolition, 231; effect on wages, 244; cannot be abolished in the United States on the same lines as in Great Britain, 247; and wages, 208; cannot protect labor, 215; real strength of, 257; how it makes INDEX. 359 work, 258; cannot check con- centrating tendencies, 283; strengthened by opponents, 268; its relation to monopoly of land, 343. Protective theory, if true, then universally true, 30; opposed to natural perceptions and im- pulses, 38, 64; arbitrary and shifting character of the pro- tective unit, 40; inconsistencies of, 40, 101; applies to smaller even more than to larger di- visions, 43; cannot be put in practice, 99. Property in 1and, 176, 184, 285, 349; how instituted in Great Britain, 314. Public debts, 234. Quesnay, 15, 312. Revenue, Federal, possible sources of, 345. Rogers, Prof. Thorold, 254. Sailors, character of, 202, Savages, their rude methods due to isolation, 171. Scully, Wm., American estates of, 129. Shipping, American, 198. Slavery, two forms of, 289; in- fluence of American on public opinion, 316. Smith, Adam, 9, Smith, E. P., 87. Socialism, relations of frce trade to, 322. Spencer, Herbert, 300. Sumner, Prof. W. G., 266. 15, 98,115,812. Tariffs, origin of, 76; first Amer- ican, 17; are restrictions, not on foreigners, but on the peo- ple that impose them, 49, 160; for revenue, 76; for protection, 88; frequoni, modifications of, 181; Act of 1883, typical blum- der in, 100. Tariff question, its importance, 3; not safely to be left to spe- cialists, 6; not recondite, 7; not yet thoroughly discussed, 7; cannot be understood without going further, 10, 238; para- dox to which it leads, 270. Taxation, indirect, a farming of revenue, 84. Taxes, direct and indirect, con- sidered, 77; on ostentation, 307; on land values, 307 ; Federal, 345. Thompson, Prof. R. E., 40, 61, 69, 86, 107, 140, 203, 259. Tobacco and cigars, taxes on, 77. Trade, nature and function of, 49; a mode of production, 210. Trades-unions, influence on com- petition, 214, 223; can do lit- tle, 323. Value, the measure of embodied labor, 118, 147. Wages, a high standard of, a proper concernment of the State, 5; assumption that they are higher in U. S. because of tariff, 25; not the determining factor in cost of production, 147; rate of, as related to land values, 152, 227; effect of pro- tection on, 208; tendency to a common level, 212; governed by competition in labor mar- ket, not in goods market, 212; do not increase with employers' profits, 22%; in widest occupa- tions, determine general rate of, 225; effects of abolition of protection on, 244. Wealth, increase of, does not benefit all classes, 245. Wells, D. A., 179. Work, treated by protectionists as an end, 258; how this feeling arises, &62. 2 . THE LAND QUESTION WHAT VT /AVVOZVES, AAWD HOW AZOAVE A 7" CAAW AAE SAE 7'7"ZAZZO BY HENRY GEORGE AUTHOR OF “PROGRESS AND POVERTY,” “social PROBLEMs,” ETC. “We hold these truths to be self-evident: That all men are created equal ; that they are endowed by their Creator with certain unalienable rights; that among these are life, liberty, and the pursuit of happiness. That to secure these rights, governments are instituted among men, deriving their just powers from the consent of the governed; that whenever any form of government becomes destructive of these ends, it is the right of the people to alter or abolish it.”—DECLARATION of INDEPENDENCE. NEW YORK CHARLES L. WEBSTER & COMPANY y 1893 CopyRIGHT, 1881, BY HENRY GEORGE PR E F A C E. THIS book was first published in the early part of 1881, under the title of “The Irish Land Ques- tion.” In order to better indicate the general char- acter of this subject, and to conform to the title under which it had been republished in other coun- tries, the title was subsequently changed to “The Land Question.” C O N T E N T S. Chapter I.-Unpalatable Truth, . © º e tº II.-Distress and Famine, tº & o tº III.-A Universal Question, . & Qe IV.-Proposed Remedies, º V.—Whose Land is it 2 VI.-Landlords' Right is Labor's Wrong, VII.-The Great-Great-Grandson of Captain Kidd, . VIII.-The Only Way, the Easy Way, IX. —Principle the Best Policy, X.—Appeals to Animosity, XI.—How to Win, XII.-In the United States, XIII.—A Little Island or a Little World, XIV.-The Civilization that is Possible, XV.-The Civilization that is, . XVI.-True Conservatism, XVII.-“In Hoc Signo Vinces,” º e e PAGE I3 I8 24 29 3I 35 42 45 48 5.I 58 6O , 63 69 77 84 THE LAND QUESTION. CHAPTER I. |UNPALATABLE TRUTH. In charging the Dublin jury in the Land League cases, Mr. Justice Fitzgerald told them that the land laws of Ireland were more favorable to the tenant than those of Great Britain, Belgium, or the United States. As a matter of fact, Justice Fitzgerald is right. For in Ireland certain local customs and the provisions of the Bright Land Act mitigate somewhat the power of the landlord in his dealings with the tenant. In Great Britain, save by custom in a few localities, there are no such mitigations. In Belgium I believe there are none. There are certainly none in the United States. This fact which Justice Fitzgerald cites will be re- echoed by the enemies of the Irish movement. And it it a fact well worth the consideration of its friends. For the Irish movement has passed its first stage, and it is time for a more definite understanding of what is needed and how it is to be got. It is the fashion of Land League orators and sympa- thizing newspapers in this country to talk as if the dis- tress and disquiet in Ireland were wholly due to politi- cal oppression, and our national House of Representa- tives recently passed, by unanimous vote, a resolution which censured England for her treatment of Ireland. But, while it is indeed true that Ireland has been deeply wronged and bitterly oppressed by England, it is not true that there is any economic oppression of Ireland 8 . THE LAND QUESTION. by England now. To whatever cause Irish distress may be due, it is certainly not due to the existence of laws which press on industry more heavily in Ireland than in any other part of the United Kingdom. And, further than this, the Irish land system, which is so much talked of as though it were some peculiarly atrocious system, is essentially the same land system which prevails in all civilized countries, which we of the United States have accepted unquestioningly, and have extended over the whole temperate zone of a new continent—the same system which all over the civilized world men are accustomed to consider natural and just. Justice Fitzgerald is unquestionably right. As to England, it is well known that the English land- lords exercise freely all the powers complained of in the Irish landlords, without even the slight restrictions imposed in Ireland. - As to Belgium, let me quote the high authority of th distinguished Belgian publicist, M. Emile de Laveleye, of the University of Liege. He says that the Belgian tenant farmers—for tenancy largely prevails even where the land is most minutely divided—are rack-rented with a mercilessness unknown in England or even in Ireland, and are compelled to vote as their landlords dictate And as to the United States, let me ask the men who to applauding audiences are nightly Comparing the freedom of America with the oppression of Ireland—let me ask the Representatives who voted for the resolution of sympathy with Ireland, this simple question : What would the Irish landlords lose, what would the Irish tenants gain, if, to-morrow, Ireland were made a State in the American Union and American law substituted for English law Ż I think it will puzzle them to reply. The truth is that the gain would be to the landlords, the loss to the tenants. The simple truth is, that, under our laws, the Irish landlords could rack-rent, distrain, evict, or absent themselves, as they pleased, and without any restriction from Ulster tenant-right or legal requirement of com- pensation for improvements. Under our laws they could, just as freely as they can now, impose whatever terms they pleased upon their tenants—whether as to cultivation, as to improvements, as to game, as to mar- UNPAZAZABZE 7 rvzºº. 9 riages, as to voting, or as to anything else. For these powers do not spring from special laws. They are merely incident to the right of property; they result simply from the acknowledgment of the right of the owner of land to do as he pleases with his own—to let it, or not let it. So far as law can give them to him, every American landlord has these powers as fully as any Irish landlord. Can not the American owner of land make, in letting it, any stipulation he pleases as to how it shall be used, or improved, or cultivated 2 Can he not reserve any of his own rights upon it, such as the right of entry, or of cutting wood, or shooting game, or catching fish 2 And, in the absence of special agree- ment, does not American law give him, what the law of Ireland does not now give him, the ownership at the expiration of the lease of all the improvements made by the tenant 2 What single power has the Irish landowner that the American landowner has not as fully 2 Is not the Amer- ican landlord just as free as is the Irish landlord to re- fuse to rent his lands or his houses to any one who does not attend a certain church or vote a certain ticket 2 Is he not quite as free to do this as he is free to refuse his contributions to all but one particular benevolent so- ciety or political committee Or, if, not liking a cer- tain newspaper, he chooses to give notice to quit to any tenant whom he finds taking that newspaper, what law can be invoked to prevent him 2 There is none. The property is his, and he can let it, or not let it, as he wills. And, having this power to let or not let, he has power to demand any terms he pleases. That Ireland is a conquered country ; that centuries ago her soil was taken from its native possessors and parcelled out among aliens, and that it has been confis- cated again and again, has nothing to do with the real question of to-day—no more to do with it than have the confiscations of Marius and Sylla. England, too, is a Conquered country ; her soil has been confiscated again and again ; and, spite of all talk about Saxon and Celt, it is not probable that, after the admixture of genera- tions, the division of landholder and non-landholder any more coincides with distinction of race in the one coun- try than in the other. That Irish land titles rest on. IO THE ZAND QUESTION: force and fraud is true ; but so do land titles in every country—even to a large extent in our own peacefully settled country. Even in our most recently settled States, how much land is there to which title has been got by fraud and perjury and bribery—by the arts of the lobbyist or the cunning tricks of hired lawyers, by double-barrelled shotguns and repeating rifles The truth is that the Irish land system is simply the general system of modern civilization. In no essential feature does it differ from the system that obtains here —in what we are accustomed to consider the freest country under the sun. Entails and primogeniture and family settlements may be in themselves bad things, and may sometimes interfere with putting the land to its best use, but their effects upon the relations of land- lord and tenant are not worth talking about. As for rack-rent, which is simply a rent fixed at short intervals by competition, that is in the United States even a more common way of letting land than in Ireland. In our cities the majority of our people live in houses rented from month to month or year to year for the highest price the landlord thinks he can get. The usual term, in the newer States, at least, for the letting of agricul- tural land is from season to season. And that the rent of land in the United States comes, on the whole, more closely to the standard of rack, or full competition rent, there can be, I think, little doubt. That the land of Ireland is, as the apologists for landlordism say, largely under-rented (that is, not rented for the full amount the landlord might get with free competition) is probably true. Miss C. G. O'Brien, in a recent article in the “Nine- teenth Century,” states that the tenant-farmers gener- ally get for such patches as they sublet to their laborers twice the rent they pay the landlords. And we hear in- cidentally of many “good landlords,” i.e., landlords not in the habit of pushing their tenants for as much as they might get by rigorously demanding all that any one would give. These things, as well as the peculiar bitterness of complaints against middle-men and the speculators who have purchased encumbered estates and manage them solely with a view to profit, go to show the truth of the statement that the land of Ireland has been, by its pres: OWAVAEAZA 7TA BAEAE 7"R U 7A. If ent owners, largely underlet, when considered from what we would deem a business point of view. And this is but what might be expected. Human nature is about the same the world over, and the Irish landlords as a class are no better nor worse than would be other men under like conditions. An aristocracy such as that of Ireland has its virtues as well as its vices, and is in- fluenced by sentiments which do not enter into mere business transactions—sentiments which must often modify and soften the calculations of cold self-interest. But with us the letting of land is as much a business matter as the buying or selling of wheat or of stocks. An American would not think he was showing his good- ness by renting his land for low rates, any more than he would think he was showing, his goodness by selling wheat for less than the market price, or stocks for less than the quotations. So in those districts of France and Belgium where the land is most subdivided, the peasant proprietors, says M. de Laveleye, boast to one another of the high rents they get, just as they boast of the high prices they get for pigs or for poultry. The best measure of rent is, of course, its proportion to the produce. The only estimate of Irish rent as a pro- portion of which I know is that of Buckle, who puts it at one-fourth of the produce. In this country I am in- clined to think one-fourth would generally be considered a moderate rent. Even in California there is considerable land rented for one-third the crop, and some that rents. for one-half the crop ; while, according to a writer in the “Atlantic Monthly,” the common rent in that great wheat-growing section of the new Northwest now being opened up is one-half the crop ! It does not seem to me that Justice Fitzgerald's state- ment can be disputed, though of course its developments are not yet as strikingly bad, for this is yet a new coun- try, and tenants are comparatively few, and land com- paratively easy to get. The American land system is really worse for the tenant than the Irish system. For with us there is neither sentiment nor custom to check the force of competition or mitigate the natural desire of the landlord to get all he can. Nor is there anything in our system to prevent or check absenteeism, so much complained of in regard to I2 THE LAND QUESTION. Ireland. Before the modern era, which has so facilitated travel and communication, and made the great cities so attractive to those having money to spend, the preva- lence of Irish absenteeism may have been due to special causes, but at the present day there is certainly nothing peculiar in it. Most of the large English and Scotch landholders are absentees for the greater part of the year, and many of them live permanently or for long intervals upon the Continent. So are our large American landowners generally absentees. In New York, in San Francisco, in Washington, Boston, Chicago, and St. Louis, live men who own large tracts of land which they seldom or never see. A resident of Rochester is said to own no less than four hundred farms in different States, one of which (I believe in Kentucky) comprises thirty-five thousand acres. Under the plantation sys- tem of farming and that of stock-raising on a grand scale, which are developing so rapidly in our new States, very much of the profits go to professional men and capitalists who live in distant cities. Corporations whose stock is held in the East or in Europe own much greater bodies of land, at much greater distances, than do the London corporations possessing landed estates in Ireland. To say nothing of the great land-grant rail- road companies, the Standard Oil Company probably owns more acres of Western land than all the London companies put together own of Irish land. And, al- though landlordism in its grosser forms is only begin- ning in the United States, there is probably no Ameri- can, wherever he may live, who cannot in his immediate vicinity see some instance of absentee landlordism. The tendency to concentration born of the new era ushered in by the application of steam shows itself in this way as in many others. To those who can live where they please, the great cities are becoming more and more at- tractive. And it is further to be remarked that too much stress is laid upon absenteeism, and that it might be prevented without much of the evil often attributed to it being cured. That is to say, that to his tenantry and neighborhood the owner of land in Galway or Kilkenny would be as much an absentee if he lived in Dublin as if he lived in London, and that, if Irish A)/SZTAEAESS AAWD AEAM/AVE. 13 landlords were compelled to live in Ireland, all that the Irish people would gain would be, metaphorically speak- 1ng, the crumbs that fell from the landlords’ tables. For if the butter and eggs, the pigs and the poultry, of the Irish peasant must be taken from him and exported to pay for his landlord's wine and cigars, what difference does it make to him where the wine is drunk or the cigars are smoked 2 CHAPTER II. T)ISTRESS AND FAMINE. But it will be asked: If the land system which pre- vails in Ireland is essentially the same as that which prevails elsewhere, how is it that it does not produce the same results elsewhere I answer that it does everywhere produce the same Áind of results. As there is nothing essentially peculiar in the Irish land system, so is there nothing essentially peculiar in Irish distress. Between the distress in Ire- land and the distress in other countries there may be differences in degree and differences in manifestation ; but that is all. The truth is, that as there is nothing peculiar in the Irish land system, so is there nothing peculiar in the distress which that land system causes. We hear a great deal of Irish emigration, of the millions of sons and daughters of Erin who have been compelled to leave their native soil. But have not the Scottish High- lands been all but depopulated 2 Do not the English emigrate in the same way, and for the same reasons P Do not the Germans and Italians and Scandinavians also emigrate 2 Is there not a constant emigration from the Eastern States of the Union to the Western—an emigration impelled by the same motives as that which sets across the Atlantic 2 Nor am I sure that this is not in some respects a more demoralizing emigration than the Irish, for I do not think there is any such monstrous disproportion of the sexes in Ireland as in Massachusetts 2 If French and Belgian peasants do 14 7 HE ZAND OUAES7 row. not emigrate as do the Irish, is it not simply because they do not have such “long families” ” There has recently been deep and wide-spread dis- tress in Ireland, and but for the contributions of charity many would have perished for want of food. But, to say nothing of such countries as India, China, Persia, and Syria, is it not true that within the last few years there have been similar spasms of distress in the most highly civilized countries—not merely in Russia and in Poland, but in Germany and England 2 Yes, even in the United States. Have there not been, are there not constantly occur- ring, in all these countries, times when the poorest classes are reduced to the direst straits, and large num- bers are only saved from starvation by charity? - When there is famine among savages it is because food enough is not to be had. But this was not the case in Ireland. In any part of Ireland, during the height of what was called the famine, there was food enough for whoever had means to pay for it. The trouble was not in the scarcity of food. There was, as a matter of fact, no real scarcity of food, and the proof of it is that food did not command scarcity prices. During all the so-called famine, food was constantly exported from Ireland to England, which would not have been the case had there been any more true famine in one coun- try than in the other. During all the so-called famine a practically unlimited supply of American meat and grain could have been poured into Ireland, through the existing mechanism of exchange, so quickly that the re- lief would have been felt instantaneously. Our send- ing of supplies in a national war-ship was a piece of vulgar ostentation, fitly paralleled by their ostentatious distribution in British gunboats under the nominal su- perintendence of a royal prince. Had we been bent on relief, not display, we might have saved our Govern- ment the expense of fitting up its antiquated war-ship, the British gunboats their coal, the Lord Mayor his dinner, and the Royal Prince his valuable time. A cable draft, turned in Dublin into postal orders, would have afforded the relief, not merely much more easily and cheaply, but in less time than it took our war-ship to get ready to receive her cargo ; for the reason that P/S7RAESS AAWD FAM/MWAE. 15 so many of the Irish people were starving was, not that the food was not to be had, but that they had not the means to buy it. Had the Irish people had money or its equivalent, the bad seasons might have come and gone without stinting any one of a full meal. Their effect would merely have been to determine toward Ire- land the flow of more abundant harvests. I wish clearly to bring to view this point. The Irish famine was not a true famine arising from scarcity of food. It was what an English writer styled the Indian famine—a “financial famine,” arising not from scarcity of food but from the poverty of the people. The ef- fect of the short crops in producing distress was not so much in raising the price of food as in cutting off the accustomed incomes of the people. The masses of the Irish people get so little in ordinary times that they are barely able to live, and when anything occurs to inter- rupt their accustomed incomes they have nothing to fall back on. Yet is this not true of large classes in all countries 2 And are not all countries subject to just such famines as this Irish famine P Good seasons and bad seasons are in the order of nature, just as the day of Sunshine and the day of rain, the summer's warmth and the winter's snow. But agriculture is, on the whole, as certain as any other pursuit, for even those industries which may be carried on regardless of weather are subject to alter- nations as marked as those to which agriculture is liable. There are good seasons and bad seasons even in fishing and hunting, while the alternations are very marked in mining and in manufacturing. In fact, the more highly differentiated branches of industry which advancing civilization tends to develop, though less directly de- pendent upon rain and sunshine, heat and cold, seem increasingly subject to alternations more frequent and intense. Though in a country of more diversified in- dustry the failure of a crop or two could not have such widespread effects as in Ireland, yet the countries of more complex industries are liable to a greater variety of disasters. A war on another continent produces famine in Lancashire ; Parisian milliners decree a change of fashion, and Coventry operatives are only saved from starvation by public alms ; a railroad com- 16 7"HE LAND QUESTION. bination decides to raise the price of coal, and Pennsyl vania miners find their earnings diminished by half or totally cut off; a bank breaks in New York, and in all the large American cities soup-houses must be opened ! In this Irish famine which provoked the land agita- tion, there is nothing that is peculiar. Such famines on a smaller or a larger Scale are constantly occurring. Nay, more the fact is, that famine, just such famine as this Irish famine, constantly exists in the richest and most highly civilized lands. It persists even in “good times” when trade is “booming ”; it spreads and rages whenever from any cause industrial depression comes. It is kept under, or at least kept from showing its worst phases, by poor-rates and almshouses, by private be- nevolence and by vast organized charities, but it still exists, gnawing in secret when it does not openly rage. In the very centres of civilization, where the machinery. of production and exchange is at the highest point of efficiency, where bank-vaults hold millions, and show- windows flash with more than a prince's ransom, where elevators and warehouses are gorged with grain, and markets are piled with all things succulent and tooth- some, where the dinners of Lucullus are eaten every day, and, if it be but cool, the very greyhounds wear dainty blankets—in these centres of wealth and power and refinement, there are always hungry men and women and little children. Never the sun goes down but on human beings prowling like wolves for food, or huddling together like vermin for shelter and warmth. “Always with You" is the significant heading under which a New York paper, in these most prosperous times, publishes daily the tales of chronic famine ; and in the greatest and richest city in the world—in that very London, where the plenty of meat in the butchers' shops seemed to some Savages the most wondrous of ail its wonderful sights—in that very London, the mortuary reports have a standing column for deaths by starva- tion. But no more in its chronic than in its spasmodic forms is famine to be measured by the deaths from starvation. Perfect, indeed, in all its parts must be the human machine if it can run till the last bit of availa- ble tissue be drawn on to feed its fires. It is under AX/S7RAESS AAWD AWAM/AVE. 17 the guise of disease to which physicians can give less shocking names, that famine, especially the chronic famine of civilization, kills. And the statistics of mor- tality, especially of infant mortality, show that in the richest communities famine is constantly at its work. Insufficient nourishment, inadequate warmth and cloth- ing, and unwholesome surroundings, constantly, in the very centres of plenty, swell the death rates. What is this but famine—just such famine as the Irish famine 2 It is not that the needed things are really scarce ; but that those whose need is direst have not the means to get them, and, when not relieved by charity, want kills them in its various ways. When, in the hot midsummer, little children die like flies in the New York tenement wards, what is that but famine 2 And those barges crowded with such children that a noble and tender charity sends down New York Harbor to catch the fresh salt breath of the Atlantic—are they not fighting famine as truly as was our food-laden war-ship and the Royal Prince's gunboats 2 Alas ! to find famine one has not to cross the Sea. There was bitter satire in the cartoon that one of our illustrated papers published when subscriptions to the Irish famine fund were being made—a cartoon that represented James Gordon Bennett sailing away for Ireland in a boat loaded down with provisions, while a sad-eyed, hungry-looking, tattered group gazed wist- fully on them from the pier. The bite and the bitterness of it, the humiliating sting and satire of it, were in its truth. This is “the home of freedom,” and “the asylum of the oppressed "; our population is yet sparse, our public domain yet wide ; we are the greatest of food producers, yet even here there are beggars, tramps, paupers, men torn by anxiety for the support of their families, women who know not which way to turn, little children growing up in such poverty and squalor that only a miracle can keep them pure. “Always with you,” even here. What is the week or the day of the week that our papers do not tell of man or woman who, * to escape the tortures of want, has stepped out of life unbidden 2 What is this but famine 7 -- 2 *- gº 18 ZAZ ZAMD Q0A2SZZOM. CHAPTER III. A UNIVERSAL QUESTION. Let me be understood. I am not endeavoring to ex cuse or belittle Irish distress. I am merely pointing out that distress of the same kind exists elsewhere. This is a fact I want to make clear, for it has hitherto, in most of the discussions of the Irish Land Question, been ignored. And without an appreciation of this fact the real nature of the Irish Land Question is not understood, nor the real importance of the agitation SCCI). What I contend for is this : That it is a mistake to consider the Irish Land Question as a mere local ques- tion, arising out of conditions peculiar to Ireland, and which can be settled by remedies that can have but local application. On the contrary, I contend that what has been brought into prominence by Irish distress, and forced into discussion by Irish agitation, is some- thing infinitely more important than any mere local question could be ; it is nothing less than that question of transcendent importance which is everywhere begin- ning to agitate, and, if not settled, must soon convulse the civilized world—the question whether, their politi- cal equality conceded (for, where this has not already been, it soon will be), the masses of mankind are to re- main mere hewers of wood and drawers of water for the benefit of a fortunate few 2 whether, having escaped from feudalism, modern Society is to pass into an in- dustrial Organization more grinding and oppressive, more heartless and hopeless, than feudalism 2 whether, amid the abundance their labor creates, the producers of wealth are to be content in good times with the barest of livings and in bad times to suffer and to starve 7 What is involved in this Irish Land Question is not a mere local matter between Irish landlords and Irish tenants, but the great social problem of modern civili- zation. What is arraigned in the arraignment of the claims of Irish landlords is nothing less than the wide- Aſ -UAVYMERSAZ QUEST/OM. 19 spread institution of private property in land. In the assertion of the natural rights of the Irish people is the assertion of the natural rights that, by virtue of his ex- istence, pertain everywhere to man. It is probable that the Irish agitators did not at first perceive the real bearing and importance of the ques- tion they took in hand. But they—the more intelli- gent and earnest of them, at least—must now begin to realize it.* Yet, save, perhaps, on the part of the ultra Tories, who would resist any concession as the open- ing of a door that cannot again be shut, there is on all sides a disposition to ignore the real nature of the ques- tion, and to treat it as springing from conditions pecu- liar to Ireland. On the one hand, there is a large class in England and elsewhere, who, while willing to concede or even actually desire that something should be done for Ireland, fear any extension of the agitation into a questioning of the rights of landowners else- where. And, on the other hand, the Irish leaders seem anxious to confine attention in the same way, evi- dently fearing that, should the question assume a broader aspect, strong forces now with them might fall away and, perhaps to a large extent, become directly and strongly antagonistic. . But it is not possible to so confine the discussion; no more possible than it was possible to confine to France the questions involved in the French Revolution ; no more possible than it was possible to keep the discus- sion which arose over slavery in the Territories confined to the subject of slavery in the Territories. And it is best that the truth be fully stated and clearly recognized. He who sees the truth, let him proclaim it, without asking who is for it or who is against it. This is not radicalism in the bad sense which so many attach to the word. This is conservatism in the true sense. What gives to the Irish land question its supreme sig- nificance is that it brings into attention and discussion —nay, that it forces into attention and discussion, not a * The “Irish World,” which, though published in New York, has ex- erted a large influence upon the agitation on both sides of the Atlantic, does realize, and has from the first frankly declared, that the fight must be against landlordism in toto and everywhere. 2O 7//E ZAND QUEST/ow. mere Irish question, but a question of world-wide im portance. - What has brought the land question to the front in Ireland, what permits the relation between land and labor to be seen there with such distinctness—to be seen even by those who cannot in other places perceive them—is certain special conditions. Ireland is a coun- try of dense population, so that competition for the use of land is so sharp and high as to produce marked ef- fects upon the distribution of wealth. It is mainly an agricultural country, so that production is concerned directly and unmistakably with the soil. Its industrial Organization is largely that simple one in which an em- ploying capitalist does not stand between laborer and landowner, so that the connection between rent and wages is not obscured. Ireland, moreover, was never con- quered by the Romans, nor, until comparatively recently, by any people who had felt in their legal system the ef- fect of Roman domination. It is the European coun- try in which primitive ideas as to land tenures have longest held their sway, and the circumstances of its conquest, its cruel misgovernment, and the differences of race and religion between the masses of the people and those among whom the land was parcelled, have tended to preserve old traditions and to direct the strength of Irish feeling and the fervor of Irish imagi- nation against a system which forces the descendant of the ancient possessors of the soil to pay tribute for it to the representative of a hated stranger. It is for these reasons that the connection between Irish distress and Irish landlordism is so easily seen and readily real- ized. But does not the same relation exist between Eng- lish pauperism and English landlordism—between American tramps and the American land system 2 Es- sentially the same land system as that of Ireland exists elsewhere, and, wherever it exists, distress of essentially the same kind is to be seen. And elsewhere, just as certainly as in Ireland, is the connection between the two that of cause and effect. When the agent of the Irish landlord takes from the Irish cottier for rent his pigs, his poultry, or his potatoes, or the money that he gains by the Sale of these things, it A UNIVERSAL QUESTION. 21 is clear enough that this rent comes from the earnings of labor, and diminishes what the laborer gets. But is not this in reality just as clear when a dozen middle- men stand between laborer and landlord 2 Is it not just as clear when, instead of being paid monthly or quarterly or yearly, rent is paid in a lumped sum called purchase money 2 Whence comes the incomes which the owners of land in mining districts, in manufacturing districts, or in commercial districts, receive for the use of their land 2 Manifestly, they must come from the earnings of labor—there is no other source from which they can come. From what are the revenues of Trinity Church corporation drawn, if not from the earnings of labor 2 What is the source of the income of the Astors, if it is not the labor of laboring men, women, and children 2 When a man makes a fortune by the rise of real estate, as in New York and elsewhere many men have done within the past few months, what does it mean It means that he may have fine clothes, costly food, a grand house luxuriously furnished, etc. Now, these things are not the spontaneous fruits of the soil ; neither do they fall from heaven, nor are they cast up by the sea. They are products of labor—can only be produced by labor. And hence, if men who do no labor get them, it must necessarily be at the expense of those who do labor. It may seem as if I were needlessly dwelling upon a truth apparent by mere statement. Yet, simple as this truth is, it is persistently ignored. This is the reason that the true relation and true importance of the ques- tion which has come to the front in Ireland are so little realized. To give an illustration : In his article in the “North American Review" last year, Mr. Parnell speaks as though the building up of manufactures in Ireland would lessen the competition for land. What justifica- tion for such a view is there either in theory or in fact Can manufacturing be carried on without land any more than agriculture can be carried on without land 2 Is not competition for land measured by price, and, if Ireland were a manufacturing country, would not the value of her land be greater than now Had English clamor for “protection to home industry” not been suf- fered to secure the strangling of Irish industries in their 22 THE ZAND QUESTION. infancy, Ireland might now be more of a manufacturing country with larger population and a greater aggregate production of wealth. But the tribute which the land- owners could have taken would likewise have been greater. Put a Glasgow, a Manchester, or a London in one of the Irish agricultural counties, and, where the landlords now take pounds in rent, they would be en- abled to demand hundreds and thousands of pounds. And it would necessarily come from the same source— the ultimate source of all incomes—the earnings of la- bor. That so large a proportion of the laboring class would not have to compete with each other for agricul- tural land is true. But they would have to do what is precisely the same thing. They would have to compete with each other for employment—for the opportunity to make a living. And there is no reason to think that this competition would be less intense than now. On the contrary, in the manufacturing districts of England and Scotland, just as in the agricultural districts of Ireland, the competition for the privilege of earning a living forces wages to such a minimum as, even in good times, will only give a living. What is the difference 2 The Irish peasant cultivator hires his little farm from a landlord, and pays rent di- rectly. The English agricultural laborer hires himself to an employing farmer who hires the land, and who out of the produce pays to the one his wages and to the other his rent. In both cases competition forces the la- borer down to a bare living as a net return for his work, and only stops at that point because, when men do not get enough to live on, they die and cease to compete. And, in the same way, competition forces the employ- ing farmer to give up to the landlord all that he has left after paying wages, save the ordinary returns of capital —for the profits of the English farmer do not, on the average, I understand, exceed five or six per cent. And in other businesses, such as manufacturing, competition in the same way forces down wages to the minimum of a bare living, while rent goes up and up. Thus is it clear that no change in methods or improvements in the processes of industry lessens the landlord's power of claiming the lion's share. I am utterly unable to see in what essential thing the A UNIVERSAL QUESTION. 23 condition of the Irish peasant would be a whit improved were Ireland as rich as England, and her industries as diversified. For the Irish peasant is not to be compared with the English tenant-farmer, who is really a capital- ist, but with the English agricultural laborer and the lowest class of factory operatives. Surely their condi- tion is not so much better than that of the Irish peasant as to make a difference worth talking about. On the contrary, miserable as is the condition of the Irish peas- antry, sickening as are the stories of their suffering, I am inclined to think that for the worst instances of human degradation one must go to the reports that describe the condition of the laboring poor of England, rather than to the literature of Irish misery. For there are three things for which, in spite of their poverty and wretchedness and occasional famine, the very poorest of Irish peasants are by all accounts remarkable—the physical vigor of their men, the purity of their women, and the strength of the family affections. This, to put it mildly, cannot be said of large classes of the labor- ing populations of England and Scotland. In those rich manufacturing districts are classes stunted and de- teriorated physically by want and unwholesome employ- ments; classes in which the idea of female virtue is all but lost, and the family affections all but trodden out. But it is needless to compare sufferings and measure miseries. I merely wish to correct that impression which leads so many people to talk and write as though rent and land tenures related solely to agriculture and to agricultural communities. Nothing could be more er- roneous. Land is necessary to all production, no mat- ter what be its kind or form ; land is the standing-place, the workshop, the storehouse of labor; it is to the hu- man being the only means by which he can obtain ac- cess to the material universe or utilize its powers. With- out land man cannot exist. To whom the ownership of land is given, to him is given the virtual ownership of the men who must live upon it. When this neces- sity is absolute, then does he necessarily become their absolute master. And just as this point is neared—that is to say, just as competition increases the demand for land—just in that degree does the power of taking a larger and larger share of the earnings of labor increase. 24 THE LAND QUESTION. It is this power that gives land its value ; this is the power that enables the owner of valuable land to reap where he has not sown—to appropriate to himself wealth which he has had no share in producing. Rent is al- ways the devourer of wages. The owner of city land takes, in the rents he receives for his land, the earnings of labor just as clearly as does the owner of farming land. And whether he be working in a garret, ten stories above the street, or in a mining drift thousands of feet below the earth's surface, it is the competition for the use of land that ultimately determines what pro- portion of the produce of his labor the laborer will get for himself. This is the reason why modern progress does not tend to extirpate poverty; this is the reason why, with all the inventions and improvements and economies which so enormously increase productive power, wages everywhere tend to the minimum of a bare living. The cause that in Ireland produces pov- erty and distress—the ownership by some of the people of the land on which and from which the whole people must live—everywhere else produces the same results. It is this that produces the hideous squalor of London and Glasgow slums; it is this that makes want jostle luxury in the street of rich New York, that forces little chil- dren to monotonous and stunting toil in Massachusetts mills, and that fills the highways of our newest States with tramps. CHAPTER IV. IPROPOSED REMEDIES. The facts we have been considering give to the Irish agitation a significance and dignity that no effort for the redress of merely local grievances, no struggle for mere national independence could have. As the cause which produces Irish distress exists everywhere throughout modern civilization, and everywhere produces the same results, the question as to what measures will fully meet the case of Ireland has for us not merely a speculative and sentimental interest, but a direct and personal in- terest. AA’OA O.S.AE/O RAEMAZZO/ES. 25 For a year and more the English journals and maga- zines have been teeming with articles on the Irish Land Question ; but, among all the remedies proposed, even by men whose reputation is that of clear thinkers and advanced Liberals, I have seen nothing which shows any adequate grasp of the subject. And this is true also of the measures proposed by the agitators, so far as they have proposed any. They are illogical and insufficient to the last degree. They neither disclose any clear principle nor do they aim at any result worth the strug- le. g From the most timid to the most radical, these schemes are restricted to one or more of the following proposi- tions : 1st. To abolish entails and primogenitures and other legal difficulties in the way of sales. 2d. To legalize and extend tenant-right. 3d. To establish tribunals of arbitrament which shall decide upon appeal the rent to be paid. 4th. To have the State buy out the landlords and sell again on time to the tenants. The first of these propositions is good in itself. To make the transfer of land easy would be to remove ob- stacles which prevent its passing into the hands of those who would make the most out of it. But, so far as this will have any effect at all, it will not be toward giving the Irish tenants more merciful landlords; nor yet will it be to the diffusion of landed property. Those who think so shut their eyes to the fact that the tendency of the time is to concentration. As for the propositions which look in various forms to the establishment of tenant-right, it is to be observed that, in so far as they go beyond giving the tenant Surety for his improvements, they merely carve out of the es- tate of the landlord an estate for the tenant. Even if the proposal to empower the courts, in cases of dispute, to decide what is a fair rent were to amount to anything (and the Land Leaguers say it would not), the fixing of a lower rent as the share of the landlord would merely enable the tenant to charge a higher price to his suc- cessor. Whatever might thus be done for present agri- cultural tenants would be of no use to future tenants, and nothing whatever would be done for the masses of 26 7 HE ZAND QUESTION. the people. In fact, that the effect would be to increase rent in the aggregate there can be no doubt. What- ever modification might be made in the landlord's de- mands, the sum which the Outgoing tenant would ask would be very certain to be all he could possibly get so that rent in the aggregate, instead of being dimin- ished, would be screwed up to the full competition or rack-rent standard. What seem to be considered the most radical propo- sitions yet made are those for the creation of a “peas- ant proprietary "-the State to buy out the landlords and resell to the tenants, for annual payments extend- ing over a term of years, and covering principal and in- terest. Waiving all practical difficulties, and they are very great, what could thus be accomplished 2 Nothing real and permanent. For not merely is this, too, but a partial measure, which could not improve the condition of the masses of the people or help those most needing help, but no sooner were the lands thus divided than a process of concentration would infallibly set in which would be all the more rapid from the fact that the new landholders would be heavily mortgaged. The ten- dency to concentration which has so steadily operated in Great Britain, and is so plainly showing itself in our new States, must operate in Ireland, and would imme- diately begin to weld together again the little patches of the newly created peasant proprietors. The tendency of the time is against peasant proprietorships ; it is in everything to concentration, not to separation. The tendency which has wiped out the small landowners, the boasted yeomanry, of England—which in our new States is uniting the quarter-sections of prečmption and homestead settlers into great farms of thousands of acres —is already too strong to be resisted, and is constantly becoming stronger and more penetrating. For it springs from the inventions and improvements and economies which are transforming modern industry—the same in- fluences which are concentrating population in large cities, business into the hands of great houses, and for the blacksmith making his own nails or the weaver work- ing his own loom substitutes the factory of the great cor- poration. That a great deal that the English advocates of peas- Proposeo REMEDIES. 27 ant proprietorship have to say about the results of their favorite system in continential Europe is not borne out by the facts, any one who chooses to look over the tes- timony may see. But it is useless to discuss that. Peasant proprietorship in continental Europe is a sur- vival. It exists only among populations which have not felt fully the breath of the new era. It continues to exist only by virtue of conditions which do not obtain in Ireland. The Irish peasant is not the French or Belgian peasant. He is in the habit of having very “long families,” they very short ones. He has become familiar with the idea of emigrating; they have not. He can hardly be expected to have acquired those habits of close economy and careful forethought for which they are so remarkable ; and there are various agencies, among which are to be counted the national schools and the reaction from America, that have roused in him aspirations and ambitions which would prevent him from continuing to water his little patch with his sweat, as do the French and Belgian peasant proprie- tors, when he could sell it for enough to emigrate. Peasant proprietorship, like that of France and Belgium, might possibly have been instituted in Ireland some time ago, before the railroad and the telegraph and the national schools and the establishment of the steam bridge across the Atlantic. But to do it now to any extent, and with any permanency, seems to me about as practicable as to go back to handloom weaving in Manchester. Much more in accordance with modern tendencies is the notice I have recently seen of the formation of a company to buy up land in Southern Ireland, and cultivate it on a large scale ; for to pro- duction on a large scale modern processes more and more strongly tend. It is not merely the steam-plow and harvesting machinery that make the cultivation of the large field more profitable than that of the small one ; it is the railroad, the telegraph, the manifold inventions of all sorts. Even butter and cheese are now made and chickens hatched and fattened in fac- tories. But the fatal defect of all these schemes as remedial measures is, that they do not go to the cause of the dis- ease. What they propose to do, they propose to do 28 THE LAWD O UES77ON. merely for one class of the Irish people—the agricultu. ral tenants. Now, the agricultural tenants are not sq large nor so poor a class (among them are in fact many large capitalist farmers of the English type) as the ag- ricultural laborers, while besides these there are the laborers of other kinds—the artisans, operatives, and poorer classes of the cities. What extension of tenant- right or conversion of tenant-farmers into partial or absolute proprietors is to benefit them 2 Even if the number of owners of Irish soil could thus be in- creased, the soil of Ireland would still be in the hands of a class, though of a Somewhat larger class. And the spring of Irish misery would be untouched. Those who had merely their labor would be as badly off as now, if not in some respects worse off. Rent would soon de- vour wages, and the injustice involved in the present system would be intrenched by the increase in the num- ber who seemingly profit by it. It is that peasant proprietors would strengthen the existing system that makes schemes for creating them so popular among certain sections of the propertied classes of Great Britain. This is the ground on which these schemes are largely urged. These small land- owners are desired that they may be used as a buffer and bulwark against any questioning of the claims of the larger owners. They would be put forward to resist the shock of “agrarianism,” just as the women are put forward in resistance to the process-servers. “What! do you propose to rob these poor peasants of their little homesteads 2" would be the answer to any one who pro- posed to attack the system under which the larger land- holders draw millions annually from the produce of labor. And here is the danger in the adoption of measures not based upon correct principles. They not only fail to do any real and permanent good, but they make proper measures more difficult. Even if a majority of the people of Ireland were made the owners of the soil, the injustice to the minority would be as great as now, and wages would still tend to the minimum, which in good times means a bare living, and in bad times means starvation. Even were it possible to cut up the soil of Ireland into those little patches into which the soil of tp/roSE LAWD /S 17's 29 France and Belgium is cut in the districts where the morceſ/ement prevails, this would not be the attainment of a just and healthy social state. But it would make the attainment of a just and healthy Social state much more difficult. CHAPTER V. whose LAND IS IT? What, then, is the true solution of the Irish problem The answer is as important to other countries as to Ire- land, for the Irish problem is but a local phase of the great problem which is everywhere pressing upon the civilized world. With the leaders of the Irish movement, the question is, of course, not merely what ought to be done, but what can be done. But, to a clear understanding of the whole subject, the question of principle must necessari- ly precede that of method. We must decide where we want to go before we can decide what is the best roa to take. º The first question that naturally arises is that of right. Among whatever kind of people such a matter as this is discussed, the question of right is sure to be raised. This, to me, seems a very significant thing; for I believe it to spring from nothing less than a univer- sal perception of the human mind—a perception often dim and vague, yet still a universal perception, that jus- tice is the Supreme law of the universe, so that, as a short road to what is best, we instinctively ask what is right 2 Now, what are the rights of this case ? To whom rightfully does the soil of Ireland belong 2 Who are justly entitled to its use and to all the benefits that flow from its use 2 Let us settle this question clearly and decisively, before we attempt anything else. Let me go to the heart of this question by asking an- Other question : Has or has not the child born in Ire- land a right to live 2 There can be but one answer, for no one would contend that it was right to drown Irish 30 7 H.A. ZAND OUAESTrow. babies, or that any human law could make it right Well, then, if every human being born in Ireland has a right to live in Ireland, these rights must be equal. If each one has a right to live, then no one can have any better right to live than any other one. There can be no dispute about this. No one will contend that it would be any less a crime to drown a baby of an Irish peasant woman than it would be to drown the baby of the proud- est duchess, or that a law commanding the one would be any more justifiable than a law commanding the other. Since, then, all the Irish people have the same equal right to life, it follows that they must all have the same equal right to the land of Ireland. If they are all in II eland by the same equal permission of Nature, so that no one of them can justly set up a superior claim to life than any other one of them ; so that all the rest of them could not justly say to any one of them, “You have not the same right to live as we have ; therefore we will pitch you out of Ireland into the sea ſ” then they must all have the same equal rights to the elements which Nature has provided for the sustaining of life—to air, to water, and to land. For to deny the equal right to the elements necessary to the maintaining of life is to deny the equal right to life. Any law that said, “Cer- tain babies have no right to the soil of Ireland ; there- fore they shall be thrown off the soil of Ireland;” would be precisely equivalent to a law that said, “Certain babies have no right to live ; therefore they shall be thrown into the sea.” And as no law or custom or agreement can justify the denial of the equal right to life, so no law or custom or agreement can justify the denial of the equal right to land. It therefore follows, from the very fact of their exist- ence, that the right of each one of the people of Ireland to an equal share in the land of Ireland is equal and in- alienable : that is to say, that the use and benefit of the land of Ireland belong rightfully to the whole people of Ireland, to each one as much as to every other ; to no one more than to any other—not to some individuals, to the exclusion of other individuals; not to one class, to the exclusion of other classes; not to landlords, not to tenants, not to cultivators, but to the whole people. AAAVZ) / OR/),S” A*/GAZ7" ZS ZABOA”,S WAEOAVG. 31 “This right is irrefutable and indefeasible. It per- tains to and springs from the fact of existence, the right to live. No law, no covenant, no agreement, can bar it. One generation cannot stipulate away the rights of another generation. If the whole people of Ireland were to unite in bargaining away their rights in the land, how could they justly bargain away the right of the child who the next moment is born ? No one can bargain away what is not his ; no one can stipulate away the rights of another. And if the new-born infant has an equal right to life, then has it an equal right to land. Its warrant, which comes direct from Nature, and which sets aside all human laws or title-deeds, is the fact that it is born. Here we have a firm, self-apparent principle from which we may safely proceed. The land of Ireland does not belong to one individual more than to another individual, to one class more than to another class ; to one generation more than to the generations that come after. It belongs to the whole people who at the time exist upon it. CHAPTER VI. LANDLORDS' RIGHT IS LABOR's WRONG. I do not dwell upon this principle because it has not yet been asserted. I dwell upon it because, although it has been asserted, no proposal to carry it out has yet been made. The cry has indeed gone up that the land of Ireland belongs to the people of Ireland, but there the recognition of the principle has stopped. To say that the land of Ireland belongs to the people of Ire. land, and then merely to ask that rents shall be reduced, or that tenant-right be extended, or that the State shall buy the land from one class and sell it to another class, is utterly illogical and absurd. Either the land of Ireland rightfully belongs to the Irish landlords, or it rightfully belongs to the Irish people ; there can be no middle ground. If it right, fully belongs to the landlords, then is the whole agita- 32 7 HE ZAND QUEST/OAV. tion wrong, and every scheme for interfering in any way with the landlords is condemned. If the land rightfully belongs to the landlords, then it is nobody else's business what they do with it, or what rent they charge for it, or where or how they spend the money they draw from it, and whoever does not want to live upon it on the landlords' terms is at perfect liberty to starve or emigrate. But if, on the contrary, the land of Ireland rightfully belongs to the Irish people, then the only logical demand is, not that the tenants shall be made joint owners with the landlords, not that it be bought from a smaller class and sold to a larger class, but that it be resumed by the whole people. To pro- pose to pay the landlords for it is to deny the right of the people to it. The real fight for Irish rights must be made outside of Ireland; and, above all things, the Irish agitators ought to take a logical position, based upon a broad, clear principle which can be everywhere understood and appreciated. To ask for tenant-right or peasant proprietorship is not to take such a position ; to concede that the landlords ought to be paid is to utterly abandon the principle that the land belongs rightfully to the people. . To admit, as even the most radical of the Irish agita- tors seem to admit, that the landlords should be paid the value of their lands, is to deny the rights of the people. It is an admission that the agitation is an in- terference with the just rights of property. It is to ig- nore the only principle on which the agitation can be justified, and on which it can gather strength for the accomplishment of anything real and permanent. To admit this is to admit that the Irish people have no more right to the soil of Ireland than any outsider. For, any outsider can go to Ireland and buy land, if he will give its market value. To propose to buy out the landlords is to propose to continue the present injustice in another form. They would get in interest on the debt created what they now get in rent. They would still have a lien upon Irish labor. And why should the landlords be paid 2 If the land of Ireland belongs of natural right to the Irish people, what valid claim for payment can be set up by the land- lords 2 No one will contend that the land is theirs of AAAV/D/ OK’A).S.’ Ae/GA/7” ZS ZAAPOA”,S WA’OAVG. 33 natural right, for the day has gone by when men could be told that the Creator of the universe intended his bounty for the exclusive use and benefit of a privileged class of his creatures—that he intended a few to roll in luxury while their fellows toiled and starved for them. The claim of the landlords to the land rests not on nat- ural right, but merely on municipal law—on municipal law which contravenes natural right. And, whenever the sovereign power changes municipal law so as to con- form to natural right, what claim can they assert to com- pensation ? Some of them bought their lands, it is true; but they got no better title than the seller had to give. And what are these titles 2 Titles based on murder and robbery, on blood and rapine—titles which rest on the most atrocious and wholesale crimes. Created by force and maintained by force, they have not behind them the first shadow of right. That Henry II. and James I. and Cromwell and the Long Parliament had the power to give and grant Irish lands is true ; but will any one con- tend they had the right 2 Will any one contend that in all the past generations there has existed on the British Isles or anywhere else any human being, or any num- ber of human beings, who had the right to say that in the year 1881 the great mass of Irishmen should be compelled to pay—in many cases to residents of England, France, or the United States—for the privilege of living in their native country and making a living from their native soil Even if it be said that might makes right; even if it be contended that in the twelfth, or seventeenth, or eighteenth century lived men who, having the power, had therefore the right, to give away the soil of Ireland, it cannot be contended that their right went further than their power, or that their gifts and grants are binding on the men of the present generation. No one can urge such a preposterous doctrine. And, if might makes right, then the moment the people get power to take the land the rights of the present landholders utter- ly cease, and any proposal to compensate them is a pro- posal to do a fresh wrong. Should it be urged that, no matter on what they orig- inally rest, the lapse of time has given to the legal owners of Irish land a title of which they cannot now be justly deprived without compensation, it is sufficient 3 34 THE LAND QUEST/OM. to ask, with Herbert Spencer, at what rate per annum wrong becomes right 2 Even the shallow pretence that the acquiescence of society can vest in a few the exclu- sive right to that element on which and from which Nature has ordained that all must live, cannot be urged in the case of Ireland. For the Irish people have never ac- quiesced in their spoliation, unless the bound and gagged victim may be said to acquiesce in the robbery and mal- treatment which he cannot prevent. Though the memory of their ancient rights in the land of their country may have been utterly stamped out among the people of Eng- land, and have been utterly forgotten among their kin on this side of the sea, it has long survived among the Irish. If the Irish people have gone hungry and cold and ignor- ant, if they have been evicted from lands on which their ancestors had lived from time immemorial, if they have been forced to emigrate or to starve, it has not been for the want of protest. They have protested all they could ; they have struggled all they could. It has been but su- perior force that has stifled their protests and made their struggles vain. In a blind, dumb way, they are pro- testing now and struggling now, though even if their hands were free they might not at first know how to untie the knots in the cords that bind them. But acqui- esce they never have. Yet, even supposing they had acquiesced, as in their ignorance the working classes of such countries as Eng- land and the United States now acquiesce, in the iniq- uitous system which makes the common birthright of all the exclusive property of some. What then 2 Does such acquiescence turn wrong into right 2 If the sleeping traveller wake to find a robber with his hand in his pocket, is he bound to buy the robber off—bound not merely to let him keep what he has previously taken, but pay him the full value of all he expected the sleep of his victim to permit him to get 2 If the stock- holders of a bank find that for a long term of years their cashier has been appropriating the lion's share of the profits, are they to be told that they cannot discharge him without paying him for what he might have got had his peculations not been discovered 2 7 HE GREA?'. GREAT-GRAMDSOM OF CAP7. KIDD 35 CHAPTER VII. THE GREAT-GREAT-GRANDSON OF CAPTAIN KIDD. I apologize to the Irish landlords and to all other landlords for likening them to thieves and robbers. I trust they will understand that I do not consider them as personally worse than other men, but that I am obliged to use such illustrations because no others will fit the case. I am concerned not with individuals, but with the system. What I want to do is, to point out a distinction that in the plea for the vested rights of land- owners is ignored—a distinction which arises from the essential difference between land and things that are the produce of human labor, and which is obscured by our habit of classing them all together as property. The galleys that carried Caesar to Britain, the accou- trements of his legionaries, the baggage that they car- ried, the arms that they bore, the buildings that they erected ; the scythed chariots of the ancient Britons, the horses that drew them, their wicker boats and wat- tled houses—where are they now 2 But the land for which Roman and Briton fought, there it is still. That British soil is yet as fresh and as new as it was in the days of the Romans. Generation after generation has lived on it since, and generation after generation will live on it yet. Now, here is a very great difference. The right to possess and to pass on the ownership of things that in their nature decay and soon cease to be is a very different thing from the right to possess and to pass on the ownership of that which does not decay, but from which each successive generation must live. To show how this difference between land and such other species of property as are properly styled wealth bears upon the argument for the vested rights of land. holders, let me illustrate again. Captain Kidd was a pirate. He made a business of sailing the seas, capturing merchantmen, making their crews walk the plank, and appropriating their cargoes. In this way he accumulated much wealth, which he is 36 7A/E LAND QUEST/OA. thought to have buried. But let us suppose, for the sake of the illustration, that he did not bury his wealth, but left it to his legal heirs, and they to their heirs and so on, until at the present day this wealth or a part of it has come to a great-great-grandson of Captain Kidd. Now, let us suppose that some one—say a great-great- grandson of one of the ship-masters whom Captain Kidd plundered, makes complaint, and says: “This man's great-great-grandfather plundered my great-great- father of certain things or certain sums, which have been transmitted to him, whereas but for this wrongful act they would have been transmitted to me; therefore, I demand that he be made to restore them.” What would society answer Society, speaking by its proper tribunals, and in ac- cordance with principles recognized among all civilized nations, would say: “We cannot entertain such a de- mand. It may be true that Mr. Kidd's great-great- grandfather robbed your great-great-grandfather, and that as the result of this wrong he has got things that otherwise might have come to you. But we cannot in- quire into occurrences that happened so long ago. Each generation has enough to do to attend to its own affairs. If we go to righting the wrongs and reopening the controversies of our great-great-grandfathers, there will be endless disputes and pretexts for dispute. What you say may be true, but somewhere we must draw the line, and have an end to strife. Though this man’s great-great-grandfather may have robbed your great- great-grandfather, he has not robbed you. He came into possession of these things peacefully, and has held them peacefully, and we must take this peaceful possession, when it has been continued for a certain time, as abso- lute evidence of just title ; for, were we not to do that, there would be no end to dispute and no secure posses- sion of anything. Now, it is this common-sense principle that is ex- pressed in the statute of limitations—in the doctrine of vested rights. This is the reason why it is held—and as to most things held justly—that peaceable possession for a certain time cures all defects of title. But let us pursue the illustration a little further : Let us suppose that Captain Kidd, having established Z"HE GREAT GREAT-GRANDSON OF CAPT. KIDD. 37 a large and profitable piratical business, left it to his son, and he to his son, and so on, until the great-great- grandson, who now pursues it, has come to consider it the most natural thing in the world that his ships should roam the Sea, Capturing peaceful merchantmen, making their crews walk the plank, and bringing home to him much plunder, whereby he is enabled, though he does no work at all, to live in very great luxury, and look down with contempt upon people who have to work. But at last, let us suppose, the merchants get tired of having their ships sunk and their goods taken, and sail- ors get tired of trembling for their lives every time a sail lifts above the horizon, and they demand of society that piracy be stopped. Now, what should society say if Mr. Kidd got indig- nant, appealed to the doctrine of vested rights, and as- serted that society was bound to prevent any interfer- ence with the business that he had inherited, and that, if it wanted him to stop, it must buy him out, paying him all that his business was worth—that is to say, at least as much as he could make in twenty years' success- ful pirating, so that if he stopped pirating he could still continue to live in luxury off of the profits of the mer- chants and the earnings of the sailors 2 What ought Society to say to such a claim as this. There will be but one answer. We will all say that so- ciety should tell Mr. Kidd that his was a business to which the statute of limitations and the doctrine of vested rights did not apply ; that because his father, and his grandfather, and his great- and great-great-grand- father pursued the business of capturing ships and making their crews walk the plank, was no reason why he should be permitted to pursue it. Society, we will all agree, ought to say he would have to stop piracy and stop it at once, and that without getting a cent for stopping. Or supposing it had happened that Mr. Kidd had sold out his piratical business to Smith, Jones, or Rob- inson, we will all agree that society ought to say that their purchase of the business gave them no greater right than Mr. Kidd had. We will all agree that that is what society ought to say. Observe, I do not ask what society would say. 38 THE LAAWD QUESTION. For, ridiculous and preposterous as it may appear, I am satisfied that, under the circumstances I have sup- posed, Society would not for a long time say what we have agreed it ought to say. Not only would all the Kidds loudly claim that to make them give up their business without full recompense would be a wicked interference with vested rights, but the justice of this claim would at first be assumed as a matter of course by all or nearly all the influential classes—the great lawyers, the able journalists, the writers for the maga- zines, the eloquent clergymen, and the principal pro- fessors in the principal universities. Nay, even the merchants and sailors, when they first began to com- plain, would be so tyrannized and browbeaten by this public opinion that they would hardly think of more than of buying out the Kidds, and, wherever here and there any one dared to raise his voice in favor of stop- ping piracy at Once and without compensation, he would only do so under penalty of being stigmatized as a reckless disturber and wicked foe of social order. If any one denies this, if any one says mankind are not such fools, then I appeal to universal history to bear me witness. I appeal to the facts of to-day. Show me a wrong, no matter how monstrous, that ever yet, among any people, became ingrafted in the social system, and I will prove to you the truth of what I say. The majority of men do not think ; the majority of men have to expend so much energy in the struggle to make a living that they do not have time to think. The majority of men accept, as a matter of course, whatever is. This is what makes the task of the social reformer so difficult, his path so hard. This is what brings upon those who first raise their voices in behalf of a great truth the sneers of the powerful and the curses of the rabble, ostracism and martyrdom, the robe of derision and the crown of thorns. Am I not right 2 Have there not been states of so- ciety in which piracy has been considered the most re- spectable and honorable of pursuits P Did the Roman populace see anything more reprehensible in a gladia- torial show than we do in a horse-race 2 Does public opinion in Dahomey see anything reprehensible in the 7 HE GREAT-GREAT-GRANDSOAV OF CAPT. KIDD. 39 custom of sacrificing a thousand or two human beings by way of signalizing grand occasions 2 Are there not states of Society in which, in spite of the natural pro- portions of the sexes, polygamy is considered a matter of course 2 Are there not states of society in which it would be considered the most ridiculous thing in the world to say that a man's son was more closely related to him than his nephew 2 Are there not states of so- ciety in which it would be considered disreputable for a man to carry a burden while a woman who could stag- ger under it was around 2–states of society in which the husband who did not occasionally beat his wife would be deemed by both sexes a weak-minded, low- spirited fellow 2 What would Chinese fashionable so- ciety consider more outrageous than to be told that mothers should not be permitted to squeeze their daugh- ters' feet, or Flathead women than being restrained from tying a board on their infants' skulls 2 How long has it been since the monstrous doctrine of the divine right of kings was taught through all Christendom P What is the slave trade but piracy of the worst kind 2 Yet it is not long since the slave trade was looked upon as a perfectly respectable business, afford- ing as legitimate an opening for the investment of cap- ital and the display of enterprise as any other. The proposition to prohibit it was first looked upon as ridic- ulous, then as fanatical, then as wicked. It was only slowly and by hard fighting that the truth in regard to it gained ground. Does not our very Constitution bear witness to what I say ? Does not the fundamental law of the nation, adopted twelve years after the enunciation of the Declaration of Independence, declare that for twenty years the slave trade shall not be prohibited nor restricted P Such dominion had the idea of vested in- terests over the minds of those who had already pro- claimed the inalienable right of man to life, liberty, and the pursuit of happiness Is it not but yesterday that in the freest and greatest republic on earth, among the people who boast that they lead the very van of civilization, this doctrine of vested rights was deemed a sufficient justification for all the cruel wrongs of human slavery 2 Is it not but yes- terday, when whoever dared to say that the rights oi 4O THE LAND QUESTION. property did not justly attach to human beings; when whoever dared to deny that human beings could not be rightfully bought and sold like cattle—the husband torn from the wife and the child from the mother ; when whoever denied the right of whoever had paid his money for him to work or whip his own nigger was looked upon as a wicked assailant of the rights of prop- erty 2 Is it not but yesterday when in the South who- ever whispered such a thought took his life in his hands; when in the North the abolitionist was held by the churches as worse than an infidel, was denounced by the politicians and rotten-egged by the mob P I was born in a Northern State, I have never lived in the South, I am not yet gray; but I well remember, as every American of middle age must remember, how over and over again I have heard all questionings of slavery silenced by the declaration that the negroes were the property of their masters, and that to take away a man's slave without payment was as much a crime as to take away his horse without payment. And whoever does not remember that far back, let him look over American literature previous to the war, and say whether, if the business of piracy had been a flourish- ing business, it would have lacked defenders ? Let him say whether any proposal to stop the business of piracy without compensating the pirates would not have been denounced at first as a proposal to set aside vested rights 2 But I am appealing to other states of society and to times that are past merely to get my readers, if I can, out of their accustomed ruts of thought. The proof of what I assert about the Kidds and their business is in the thought and speech of to-day. Here is a system which robs the producers of wealth as remorselessly and far more regularly and systemati- cally than the pirate robs the merchantman. Here is a system that steadily condemns thousands to far more lingering and horrible deaths than that of walking the plank—to death of the mind and death of the soul, as well as death of the body. These things are undis- puted. No one denies that Irish pauperism and famine are the direct results of this land system, and no one who will examine the subject will deny that the chronic THE GREA 7. GREAT-GRAAWDSOAV OF CAPT. KIDD 41 pauperism and chronic famine which everywhere mark our civilization are the results of this system. Yet we are told—nay, it seems to be taken for granted—that this system can not be abolished without buying off those who profit by it. Was there ever more degrading abasement of the human mind before a fetish 2 Can we wonder, as we see it, at any perversion of ideas 2 Consider: is not the parallel I have drawn a true one? Is it not just as much a perversion of ideas to apply the doctrine of vested rights to property in land, when these are its admitted fruits, as it was to apply it to property in human flesh and blood ; as it would be to apply it to the business of piracy 2 In what does the claim of the Irish landholders differ from that of the hereditary pirate or the man who has bought out a piratical bus- iness 2 “Because I have inherited or purchased the business of robbing merchantmen,” says the pirate, “therefore respect for the rights of property must com- pel you to let me go on robbing ships and making sailors walk the plank until you buy me out.” “Be- cause we have inherited or purchased the privilege of appropriating to ourselves the lion's share of the pro- duce of labor,” says the landlord, “therefore you must continue to let us do it, even though poor wretches shiver with cold and faint with hunger, even though, in their poverty and misery, they are reduced to wallow with the pigs.” What is the difference 2 This is the point I want to make clearly and distinctly, for it shows a distinction that in current thought is over- looked. Property in land, like property in slaves, is es- sentially different from property in things that are the result of labor. Rob a man or a people of money, or goods, or cattle, and the robbery is finished there and then. The lapse of time does not, indeed, change wrong into right, but it obliterates the effects of the deed. That is done ; it is over ; and, unless it be very soon righted, it glides away into the past, with the men who were parties to it, so swiftly that nothing save om- niscience can trace its effects; and in attempting to right it we would be in danger of doing fresh wrong. The past is for ever beyond us. We can neither punish nor recompense the dead. But rob a people of the land on which they must live, and the robbery is con- 42 - 7 HE LAND QUESTION. tinuous. It is a fresh robbery of every succeeding gen, eration—a new robbery every year and every day; it is like the robbery which condemns to slavery the children of the slave. To apply to it the statute of limitations, to acknowledge for it the title of prescription, is not to condone the past ; it is to legalize robbery in the pres- ent, to justify it in the future. The indictment which really lies against the Irish landlords is not that their ancestors, or the ancestors of their grantors, robbed the ancestors of the Irish people. That makes no difference. “Let the dead bury their dead.” The indictment that truly lies is that here, now, in the year 1881, they rob the Irish people. And shall we be told that there can be a vested right to continue such robbery CHAPTER VIII. THE ONLY WAY, THE EASY way. I have dwelt so long upon this question of compen- sating landowners, not merely because it is of great practical importance, but because its discussion brings clearly into view the principles upon which the land question, in any country, can alone be justly and finally settled. In the light of these principles we see that landowners have no rightful claim either to the land or to compensation for its resumption by the people, and, further than that, we see that no such rightful claim can ever be created. It would be wrong to pay the present landowners for “their " land at the expense of the people ; it would likewise be wrong to sell it again to smaller holders. It would be wrong to abolish the pay- ment of rent, and to give the land to its present culti- vators. In the very nature of things, land can not right- fully be made individual property. This principle is absolute. The title of a peasant proprietor deserves no more respect than the title of a great territorial noble. No sovereign political power, no compact or agreement, €Ven though consented to by the whole population of THE ONLY WAY. THE EASY WAY. 43 the globe, can give to an individual a valid title to the ex- clusive ownership of a square inch of soil. The earth is an entailed estate—entailed upon all the generations of the children of men, by a deed written in the constitution of Nature, a deed that no human proceedings can bar, and no prescription determine. Each succeeding gen- eration has but a tenancy for life. Admitting that any set of men may barter away their own natural rights (and this logically involves an admission of the right of suicide), they can no more barter away the rights of their successors than they can barter away the rights of the inhabitants of other worlds. What should be aimed at in the settlement of the Irish land question is thus very clear. The “three F’s ” are, what they have already been called, three frauds; and the proposition to create peasant proprietorship is no better. It will not do merely to carve out of the es- tates of the landlords minor estates for the tenants ; it will not do merely to substitute a larger for a smaller class of proprietors ; it will not do to confine the settle- ment to agricultural land, leaving to its present possess- ors the land of the towns and villages. None of these lame and impotent conclusions will satisfy the demands of justice or cure the bitter evils now so apparent. The only true and just solution of the problem, the only end worth aiming at, is to make all the land the common property of all the people. This principle conceded, the question of method arises. How shall this be done 2 Nothing is easier. It is merely necessary to divert the rent which now flows into the pockets of the landlords into the common treasury of the whole people. It is not possible to so divide up the land of Ireland so as to give each family, still less each individual, an equal share. And, even if that were possible, it would not be possible to maintain equality, for old people are constantly dying and new people constantly being born, while the relative value of land is constantly changing. But it is possible to equally divide the rent, or, what amounts to the same thing, to apply it to purposes of common benefit. This is the way, and this is the only way, in which absolute justice can be done. This is the way, and this is the only way, in which the equal right of every man, woman, 44 THE LAND QUESTION. and child can be acknowledged and secured. As Her. bert Spencer says of it: * Such a doctrine is consistent with the highest state of civilization ; may be carried out without involving a community of goods, and need cause no very serious revolution in existing arrangements. The change required would simply be a change of landlords. Separate ownership would merge into the joint-stock ownership of the public. Instead of being in the possession of individuals, the country would be held by the great corporate body—society. Instead of leasing his acres from an isolated proprietor, the farmer would lease them from the nation. Instead of paying his rent to the agent of Sir John or his Grace, he would pay it to an agent or deputy agent of the community. Stewards would be public officials instead of private ones, and tenancy the only land tenure. A state of things so ordered would be in perfect harmony with the moral law. Under it, all men would be equally landlords; all men would be alike free to become tenants. . . . Clearly, therefore, on such a system, the earth might be enclosed, occupied, and cultivated, in entire subordination to the law of equal freedom. • Now, it is a very easy thing to thus sweep away all private ownership of land, and convert all occupiers into tenants of the State, by appropriating rent. No complicated laws or cumbersome machinery is neces. sary. It is only necessary to tax land up to its full value. Do that, and without any talk about disposses- sing landlords, without any use of the ugly word “con- fiscation,” without any infringement of the just rights of property, the land would become virtually the peo- ple's, while the landlords would be left the absolute and unqualified possessors of—their deeds of title and con- veyance | They could continue to call themselves land- lords, if they wished to, just as that poor old Bourbon, the Comte de Chambord, continues to call himself King of France ; but, as what, under this system, was paid by the tenant would be taken by the State, it is pretty clear that middle-men, would not long survive, and that very soon the occupiers of land would come to be nominally the owners, though, in reality, they would be the tenants of the whole people. How beautifully this simple method would satisfy every economic requirement ; how, freeing labor and capital from the fetters that now oppress them (for all other taxes could be easily remitted), it would enor- wºg- * “Social Statics,” Chap. ix., sec. 8, AbA*/AVC/AP/A 7'AºA2 A3/ES7" POZAC V. 45 mously increase the production of wealth ; how it would make distribution conform to the law of justice, dry up the springs of want and misery, elevate Society from its lowest stratum, and give all their fair share in the bless- ings of advancing civilization, can perhaps only be fully shown by such a detailed examination of the whole social problem as I have made in a book” which I hope will be read by all the readers of this, since in it I go Over much ground and treat many subjects which can not be even touched upon here. Nevertheless, any one can see that to tax land up to its full rental value would amount to precisely the same thing as to formally take possession of it, and then let it out to the highest bid- ders. CHAPTER IX. PRINCIPLE THE BEST POLICY. We have now seen the point that should be aimed at, and the method by which it is to be reached. There is another branch of the subject which practical men must consider: the political forces that may be marshalled; the political resistance that must be overcome. It is One thing to work out such a problem in the closet—to demonstrate its proper solution to the satisfaction of a few intelligent readers. It is another thing to solve it in the field of action, where ignorance, prejudice, and pow- erful interests must be met. It can not be that the really earnest men in the Irish movement are satisfied with any programme yet put forth. But they are doubtless influenced by the fear that the avowal of radical views and aims would not merely intensify present opposition, but frighten away from their cause large numbers and important influences now with it. To say nothing of English conservatism, there is in Ireland a large class now supporting the movement who are morbidly afraid of anything which * “Progress and Poverty.” 46 THE ZAAWD ovEszrow. savors of “communism" or “socialism,” while in the United States, whence much moral support and pecun- iary aid have been derived, it is certain that many of those who are now loudest in their expressions of sympathy would slink away from a movement which avowed the intention of abolishing private property in land. A resolution, expressive of sympathy with the Irish people in their “struggle for the repeal of oppres- sive land laws" was, by a unanimous vote of the Na- tional House of Representatives, flung füll in the face of the British lion. How many votes would that reso- lution have got had it involved a declaration of hostil- ity to the institution of individual property in land 2 I understand all this. Nevertheless, I am convinced that the Irish land movement would gain, not lose, were its earnest leaders, disdaining timid counsels, to boldly avow the principle that the land of Ireland belongs of right to the whole people of Ireland, and, without both- ering about compensation to the landholders, to pro- pose its resumption by the people in the simple way I have suggested. That, in doing this, they would lose strength and increase antagonism in some directions is true, but they would in other directions gain strength and allay antagonisms. And, while the loss would con- stantly tend to diminish, the gain would constantly tend to increase. They would, to use the phrase of Emerson, have “hitched their wagon to a star.” I admit, as will be urged by those who would hold back from such an avowal as I propose, that political progress must be by short steps rather than by great leaps; that those who would have the people follow them readily, and especially those who would enjoy a present popularity and preferment, must not go too far in ad- vance ; and that to demand a little at first is often the surest way to obtain much at last. So far as personal consideration is concerned, it is only to earnest men capable of feeling the inspiration of a great principle that I care to talk, or that I can hope to convince. To them I wish to point out that caution is not wisdom when it involves the ignoring of a great principle ; that it is not every step that involves progression, but only such steps as are in the right line and make easier the next ; that there are strong forces AAE/AVC/P/A 7//E BEST POZ/CY. 47 that wait but the raising of the true standard to rally on its side. - Let the time-servers, the demagogues, the compro- misers, to whom nothing is right and nothing is wrong, but who are always seeking to find some half-way house between right and wrong—let them all go their ways. Any cause which can lay hold of a great truth is the stronger without them. If the earnest men among the Irish leaders abandon their present half-hearted illogical position, and take their stand frankly and firmly upon the principle that the youngest child of the poorest peasant has as good a right to tread the soil and breathe the air of Ireland as the eldest son of the proudest duke, they will have put their fight on the right line. Present de- feat will but pave the way for future victory, and each step won makes easier the next. Their position will not only be logically defensible, but will prove the stronger the more it is discussed ; for private property in land, which never arises from the natural perceptions of men, but springs historically from usurpation and robbery, is something so utterly absurd, SO Outrageously unjust, so clearly a waste of productive forces and a barrier to the most profitable use of natural opportunities, so thoroughly opposed to all sound maxims of public pol- icy, so glaringly in the way of further progress, that it is only tolerated because the majority of men never think about it or hear it questioned. Once fairly ar- raign it, and it must be condemned ; once call upon its advocates to exhibit its claims, and their cause is lost in advance. There is to-day no political economist of standing who dare hazard his reputation by defending it on economic grounds; there is to-day no thinker of eminence who either does not, like Herbert Spencer, openly declare the injustice of private property in land, or tacitly make the same admission. Once force the discussion on this line, and the Irish reformers will com- pel to their side the most active and powerful of the men who mould thought. And they will not merely close up their own ranks, now in danger of being broken ; they will “carry the war into Africa,” and make possible the most powerful of political combinations. It is already beginning to be perceived that the Irish 48 7 H.A. ZAA/D OUAES77OAZ movement, so far as it has yet gone, is merely in the in- terest of a class ; that, so far as it has yet voiced any demand, it promises nothing to the laboring and artisan classes. Its opponents already see this opportunity for division, which, even without their efforts, must soon show itself, and which, now that the first impulse of the movement is over, will the more readily develop. To close up its ranks, and hold them firm, so that, even though they be forced to bend, they will not break and scatter, it must cease to be a movement looking merely to the benefit of the tenant-farmer, and become a move- ment for the benefit of the whole laboring class. And the moment this is done the Irish land agitation assumes a new and a grander phase. It ceases to be an Irish movement ; it becomes but the van of a world- wide struggle. Count the loss and the gain. CHAPTER X. APPEALS TO ANIMOSITY. The Land League movement, as an Irish movement, has in its favor the strength of Irish national feeling. In assuming the radical ground I urge, it would lose some of this ; for there are doubtless a considerable number of Irishmen on both sides of the Atlantic who would shrink at first from the proposal to abolish pri- vate property in land. But all that is worth having would soon come back to it. And its strength would be more compact and intense—animated by a more definite purpose and a more profound conviction. But in ceasing to be a movement having relation sim- ply to Ireland—in proclaiming a truth and proposing a remedy which apply as well to every other country—it would allay opposition, which, as a mere local move- ment, it arouses, and brings to its support powerful forces. The powerful landed interest of England is against the movement anyhow. The natural allies of the Irish agitators are the English working classes—not merely the Irishmen and sons of Irishmen who, in the larger AAEAEAEA ZS 7"O AAV/M OS/Z"Y. 49 English cities, are numerous enough to make some show and exert some voting power, without being nu- merous enough to effect any important result—but the great laboring masses of Great Britain. So long as merely Irish measures are proposed, they can not gain the hearty support even of the English radicals; so long as race prejudices and hatreds are appealed to, counter prejudices and hatreds must be aroused. It is the very madness of folly, it is one of those po- litical blunders worse than crimes, to permit in this land agitation that indiscriminating denunciation of England and everything English which is so common at Land League meetings and in the newspapers which voice Irish sentiment. The men who do this may be giving way to a natural sentiment; but they are most effectually doing the work of the real oppressors of Ire- land. Were they secret emissaries of the London po- lice, were they bribed with the gold which the British oligarchy grinds out of the toil of its white slaves in mill and mine and field, they could not better be doing its work. “Divide and conquer” is the golden maxim of the oppressors of mankind. It is by arousing race antipathies and exciting national animosities, by ap- pealing to local prejudices and setting people against people, that aristocracies and despotisms have been founded and maintained. They who would free men must rise above such feelings if they would be success- ful. The greatest enemy of the people's cause is he who appeals to national passion and excites old hatreds. He is its best friend who does his utmost to bury them out of sight. For that action and reaction are equal and uniform is the law of the moral as of the physical world. Herein lies the far-reaching sweep of those sublime teachings that, after centuries of nominal acceptance, the so-called Christian world yet ignores, and which call on us to answer not revilings with revilings, but to meet hatred with love. “For,” as say the Scriptures of the Buddhists, “hatred never ceases by hatred at any time ; hatred ceases by love ; that is an old rule.” To undiscriminately denounce Englishmen is simply to arouse prejudices and excite animosities—to separate forces that ought to be united. To make this the fight of the Irish people against the English people is to 4. } 5o THE LAND QUESTYOXV, doom it to failure. To make it the common cause of the people everywhere against a system which every- where oppresses and robs them is to make its success assured. Had this been made to appear, the Irish mem- bers would not have stood alone when it came to the final resistance to coercion. Had this been made to ap- pear, Great Britain would be in a ferment at the pro- posal to give the Government despotic powers. If the Irish leaders are wise, they may yet avail themselves of the rising tide of British democracy. Let the Land Leaguers adopt the noble maxim of the German So- cial Democrats. Let them be Land Leaguers first, and Irishmen afterward. Let them account him an enemy of their cause who seeks to pander to prejudice and arouse hate. Let them arouse to a higher love than the mere love of country; to a wider patriotism than that which exhausts itself on one little subdivision of the hu- man race, one little spot on the great earth's surface ; and in this name, and by this sign, call upon their brothers, not so much to aid them, as to strike for themselves. The Irish people have the same inalienable right to govern themselves as have every other people ; but the full recognition of this right need not necessarily in- volve separation, and to talk of separation first is to arouse passions that will be utilized by the worst ene- mies of Ireland. The demand for the full political rights of the Irish people will be the stronger if it be made to line with and include the demand for the full political rights of the unenfranchised British people. And it must be remembered that all the tendencies of the time are not to separation, but to integration ; not to independence, but to interdependence. This is observa- ble wherever modern influences reach, and in all things. To attempt to resist it is to attempt to turn back the tide of progress. It is not with the English people that the Irish peo- ple have cause of quarrel. It is with the system that oppresses both. That is the thing to denounce ; that is the thing to fight. And it is to be fought most effectu- ally by uniting the masses against it. Monarchy, aris- tocracy, landiordism, would get but a new lease of life by the arousing of sectional passions. The greatest A/O W 7"O WZAV. 51 blow that could be struck against them would be, scru- pulously avoiding everything that could excite antago- nistic popular feeling, to carry this land agitation into Great Britain, not as a mere Irish question, but as a home question as well. To proclaim the universal truth that land is of natural right common property ; to aban- don all timid and half-way schemes which attempt to compromise between justice and injustice, and to de- mand nothing more nor less than a full recognition of this natural right would be to do this. It would inevi- tably be to put the British masses upon inquiry ; to put British landholders upon the defensive, and give them more than enough to do at home. Both England and Scotland are ripe for such an agitation, and, once fairly begun, it can have but one result—the victory of the popular cause. CHAPTER XI. HOW TO WIN. Nor is it merely the laboring classes of Great Britain who may thus be brought into the fight, if the true standard be raised. To demand the nationalization of land by the simple means I have proposed makes possi- ble—nay, as the discussion goes on, makes inevitable— an irresistible combination, the combination of labor and capital against landlordism. This combination proved its power by winning the battle of free trade in 1846 against the most determined resistance of the landed interest. It would be much more powerful now, and, if it can again be made on the land question, it can again force the intrenchments of the landed aristocracy. This combination can not be made on any of the timid, illogical schemes as yet proposed ; but it can be made on the broad principle that land is rightfully com- mon property. Paradoxical as it may seem, it is yet true that, while the present position of the Irish agita- tors does involve a menace to capital, the absolute denial of the right of private property in land would not. in admitting that the landlords ought to get any rent 52 7 HE ZAAWD OUAES7:/OM. at all, in admitting that, if the land is taken from them, they must be paid for it, the Irish agitators give away their whole case. For in this they admit that the land really belongs to the landlords, and put property in land in the same category with other property. Thus they place themselves in an indefensible position ; thus they give to the agitation a “communistic” + character, and excite against it that natural and proper feeling which strongly resents any attack upon the rights of property as an attack upon the very foundations of society. It was doubtless this mistake of the agitators in admitting the right of private property in land to which Archbishop McCabe recently alluded in saying that some of the ut- terances of the agitators excited the solicitude of the Holy See. For this mistake gives to the agitation the character of an attack upon the rights of. property. If the land is really the property of the landlords (and this is admitted when it is admitted that they are entitled to any rent or to any compensation), then to limit the rent which they shall get, or to interfere with their free- dom to make what terms they please with tenants, is an attack upon property rights. If the land is rightfully the landlords', then is any compulsion as to how they shall let it, or on what terms they shall part with it, a bad and dangerous precedent, which naturally alarms capital and excites the solicitude of those who are con- cerned for good morals and social order. For, if a man may be made to part with one species of property by Boycotting or agitation, why not with another ? If a man's title to land is as . rightful as his title to his watch, what is the difference between agitation by Land League meetings and Parliamentary filibustering to make him give up the one and agitation with a cocked pistol to make him give up the other ? But, if it be denied that land justly is, or can be, pri- vate property, if the equal rights of the whole people to the use of the elements gratuitously furnished by Na- ture be asserted without drawback or compromise, then the essential difference between property in land and * I use the word in the usual sense in which it is used by the vulgar, and in which a communist is understood as one who wants to divide up other people's property. AyOW 7'O W/AW. 53 property in things of human production is at once brought out. Then will it clearly appear not only that the denial of the right of individual property in land does not involve any menace to legitimate property rights, but that the maintenance of private property in land necessarily involves a denial of the right to all other property, and that the recognition of the claims of the landlords means a continuous robbery of capital as well as of labor. All this will appear more and more clearly as the prac- tical measures necessary to make land common property are proposed and discussed. These simple measures involve no harsh proceedings, no forcible dispossession, no shock to public confidence, no retrogression to a lower industrial organization, no loaning of public money, or establishment of cumbrous commissions. Instead of doing violence to the rightful sense of prop- erty, they assert and vindicate it. The way to make land common property is simply to take rent for the common benefit. And to do this, the easy way is to abolish one tax after another, until the whole weight of taxation falls upon the value of land. When that point is reached, the battle is won. The hare is caught, killed, and skinned, and to cook him will be a very easy mat- ter. The real fight will come on the proposition to con- solidate existing taxation upon land values. When that is once won, the landholders will not merely have been decisively defeated, they will have been routed; and the nature of land values will be so generally un- derstood that to raise taxation so as to take the whole rent for common purposes will be a mere matter of COUI rSé. - The political art is like the military art. It consists in combining the greatest strength against the point of least resistance. I have pointed out the way in which, 1n the case we are considering, this can be done. And, the more the matter is considered, the clearer and clearer will it appear that there is every practical rea- son, as there is every theoretical reason, why the Irish reformers should take this vantage-ground of principle. To propose to put the public burdens upon the land- holders is not a novel and unheard of thing against which English prejudice would run as something “new 54 THE LA WD QUESTION: fangled,” some new invention of modern socialism. On the contrary, it is the ancient English practice. It would be but a return, in a form adapted to modern times, to the system under which English land was orig- inally parcelled out to the predecessors of the present holders—the just system, recognized for centuries, that those who enjoy the common property should bear the common burdens. The putting of property in land in the same category as property in things produced by labor is comparatively modern. In England, as in Ireland and Scotland, as in fact among every people of whom we know anything, the land was originally treated as common property, and this recognition ran all through the feudal system. The essence of the feudal system was in treating the landholders not as an owner, but as a lessee. William the Conqueror did not give away the land of England as the Church lands were given away by Henry VIII., when he divided among his syco- phants the property of the people, which, after the man- ner of the times, had been set apart for the support of religious, educational, and charitable institutions. To every grant of land made by the Conqueror was an- nexed a condition which amounted to a heavy perpet. ual tax or rent. One of his first acts was to divide the soil of England into sixty thousand knights' fees ; and thus, besides many other dues and obligations, was thrown upon the landholders the cost of providing and maintaining the army. All the long, costly wars that England fought during feudal times involved no public debt. Public debt, pauperism, and the grinding pov- erty of the poorer classes came in as the landholders gradually shook off the obligations on which they had received their land, an operation culminating in the ab- olition after the Restoration of the feudal tenures, for which were substituted indirect taxes that still weigh upon the whole people. To now reverse this process, to abolish the taxes which are born by labor and capi- tal, and to substitute for them a tax on rent, would not be the adoption of anything new, but a simple going back to the old plan. In England, as in Ireland, the movement would appeal to the popular imagination as a demand for the reassertion of ancient rights. There are other most important respects in Which this AyO W 7"O WZAV. 55 measure will commend itself to the English mind. The tax upon land values or rent is in all economic respects the most perfect of taxes. No political economist will deny that it combines the maximum of certainty with the minimum of loss and cost ; that, unlike taxes upon capital or exchange or improvement, it does not check production or enhance prices or fall ultimately upon the consumer. And, in proposing to abolish all other taxes in favor of this theoretically perfect tax, the Land Reformers will have on their side the advantage of ideas already current, while they can bring the argu- mentum ad hominem to bear on those who might never comprehend an abstract principle. Englishmen of all classes have happily been educated up to a belief in free trade, though a very large amount of revenue is still collected from customs. Let the Land Reformers take advantage of this by proposing to carry out the doctrine of free trade to its fullest extent. If a revenue tariff is better than a protective tariff, then no tariff at all is better than a revenue tariff. Let them propose to abolish the customs duties entirely, and to abolish as well harbor dues and lighthouse dues and dock charges, and in their place to add to the tax on rent, or the value of land exclusive of improvements. Let them in the same way propose to get rid of the excise, the various license taxes, the tax upon buildings, the Onerous and unpopu- lar income tax, etc., and to saddle all public expenses on the landlords. This would bring home the land question to thou- sands and thousands who have never thought of it be- fore ; to thousands and thousands who have heretofore looked upon the land question as something peculiarly Irish, or something that related exclusively to agricul- ture and to farmers, and have never seen how, in various direct and indirect ways, they have to contribute to the immense sums received by the landlords as rent. It would be putting the argument in a shape in which even the most stupid could understand it. It would be directing the appeal to a spot where even the unimagi- native are sensitive—the pocket. How long would a merchant or banker or manufacturer or annuitant re gard as dangerous and wicked an agitation which pro- posed to take taxation off of him Even the most prej 56 7A/E LA WD QUESTION. udiced can be relied on to listen with patience to an argument in favor of making some one else pay what they now are paying. Let me illustrate by a little story what I feel confident would be the effect of the policy I propose : Once upon a time I was the Pacific-coast agent of an Eastern news association, which took advantage of an opposition telegraph Company to run against the Asso- ciated Press monopoly. The association in California consisted of one strong San Francisco paper, to which telegraphic news was of much importance, and a num- ber of interior papers, to which it was of minor impor- tance, if of any importance at all. It became necessary to raise more money for the expenses of collecting and transmitting these dispatches, and, thinking it only fair, I assessed the increased cost to the strong metropolitan paper. The proprietor of this paper was very indignant. He appealed to the proprietors of all the other papers, and they all joined in his protest. I replied by calling a meeting. At this meeting the proprietor of the San Francisco paper led off with an indignant speech. He was seconded by several others, and evidently had the sympathy of the whole crowd. Then came my turn. I said, in effect: “Gentlemen, you can do what you please about this matter. Whatever satisfies you satisfies me. The only thing fixed is, that more money has to be raised. As this San Francisco paper pays now a much lower relative rate than you do, I thought it only fair that it should pay the increased cost. But, if you think otherwise, there is no reason in the world why you should not pay it yourselves.” The debate immediately took another turn, and in a few minutes my action was endorsed by a unanimous vote, for the San Francisco man was so disgusted by the way his supporters left him that he would not vote at all. Now, that is just about what will happen to the British landlords if the question be put in the way I propose. The British landowners are in numbers but an insignifi- cant minority. And, the more they protested against the injustice of having to pay all the taxes, the quicker would the public mind realize the essential injustice of private property in land, the quicker would the majority of the people come to see that the landowners ought not AyO W 7"O WZAV. 57 only to pay all the taxes, but a good deal more besides. Once put the question in such a way that the British workingman will realize that he pays two prices for his ale and half a dozen prices for his tobacco, because a landowners' Parliament in the time of Charles II. shook off their ancient dues to the State, and imposed them in indirect taxation on him ; once bring to the attention of the well-to-do Englishman, who grunts as he pays his in- come tax, the question as to whether the landowner who draws his income from property that of natural right be- longs to the whole people ought not to pay it instead of him, and it will not be long before the absurd injustice of allowing rent to be appropriated by individuals will be thoroughly understood. This is a very different thing from asking the British taxpayer to buy out the Irish landlord for the sake of the Irish peasant. I have been speaking as though all landholders would resist the change which would sacrifice their special inter- ests to the larger interests of society. But I am satisfied that to think this is to do landholders a great injustice. For landholders as a class are not more stupid nor more selfish than any other class. And as they saw, as they must see, as the discussion progresses, that they also would be the gainers in the great social change which would abolish poverty and elevate the very lowest classes —the “mudsills” of society, as a Southern Senator ex- pressively called them during the Slavery discussion— above the want, the misery, the vice, and degradation in which they are now plunged, there are many landowners who would join heartily and unreservedly in the effort to bring this change about. This I believe, not merely because my reading and observation both teach me that low, narrow views of self-interest are not the strongest of human motives, but because I know that to-day among those who see the truth I have here tried to set forth, and who would carry out the reform I have proposed, are many landholders.” And, if they be earnest men, I appeal to * Among the warm friends my book “Progress and Poverty” has found are many landholders—some of them large landholders. As types I may mention the names of D. A. Learnard, of San Joaquin, a considerable farmer, who had no sooner read it than he sent for a dozen copies to circulate among his neighbors; Hiram Tubbs, of San Francisco, the owner of much valuable real estate in and near that city; and Sir George 58 THE LA WD OUEST/OM. landholders as confidently as to any other class. There is that in a great truth that can raise a human soul above the mists of selfishness. The course which I suggest is the only course which can be logically based on principle. It has everything to commend it. It will concentrate the greatest strength against the least resistance. And it will be on the right line. Every step gained will be an advance toward the ultimate goal; every step gained will make easier the Ilext. CHAPTER XII. IN THE UNITED STATES. In speaking with special reference to the case of Ire- land, I have, so far as general principles are concerned, been using it as a stalking-horse. In discussing the Irish land question, we really discuss the most vital of Amer- ican questions. And if we of the United States can not see the beam in our own eye, save by looking at the mote in our brother's, then let us look at the mote ; and let us take counsel together how he may get it out. For, at least, we shall in this way learn how we may deal with our own case when we wake up to the conscious- ness of it. And never had the parable of the mote and the beam a better illustration than in the attitude of so many Americans toward this Irish land question. We de- nounce the Irish land system We express our sympa- thy with Ireland We tender our advice by congres- sional and legislative resolution to our British brethren across the Sea Truly our indignation is cheap and our sympathy is cheap, and our advice is very, very cheap For what are we doing 2 Extending over new soil the very institution that to them descended from a ruder and a darker time. With what conscience can we lec- ture them With all power in the hands of the people, Grey, of New Zealand, the owner of a good deal of land in that colony. of which he was formerly governor, as Well, as I understand, of valuable estates in England, * * & AV 7"Ay AE UAV/7′EZD STA 7"E.S. 59 with institutions yet plastic, with millions of virgin acres yet to settle, it should be ours to do more than vent denunciation, and express sympathy, and give ad- vice. It should be ours to show the way. This we have not done ; this we do not do. Out in our new States may be seen the growth of a system of cultivation worse in its social effects than that which prevails in Ireland. In Ireland the laborer has some sort of a home, and enjoys some of the family affections. In these great “wheat-manufacturing ” districts the laborer is a nomad, his home is in his blankets, which he carries around with him. The soil bears wheat, crop after crop, till its fertility is gone. It does not bear children. These ma- chine-worked “grain factories " of the great Republic of the New World are doing just what was done by the slave-worked latifundia of the Roman world. Here they prevent, where there they destroyed, “the crop of men.” And in our large cities may we not see misery of the same kind as exists in Ireland 2 If it is less in amount, is it not merely because our country is yet newer; because we have yet a wide territory and a sparse population—conditions past which our progress is rap- idly carrying us? As for evictions, is it an unheard-of thing, even in New York, for families to be turned out of their homes because they can not pay the rent 2 Are there not many acres in this country from which those who made homes have been driven by sheriffs' posses, and even by troops ? Do not a number of the Mussell Slough settlers lie in Santa Clara jail to-day because a great railroad corporation set its envious eyes on soil which they had turned from desert into garden, and they in their madness tried to resist ejectment 2 And the men on the other side of the Atlantic who vainly imagine that they may settle the great question now pressing upon them by free trade in land, or tenant- right, or some mild device for establishing a peasant proprietary—they may learn something about their own case if they will turn their eyes to us. We have had free trade in land ; we have had in our American farmer, owning his own acres, using his own capital, and working with his own hands, Something far better than peasant proprietorship. We have had, what no legislation can give the people of Great Britain, vast 60 THE LAND QUESTION. areas of virgin soil. We have had all of these under democratic institutions. Yet we have here social disease of precisely the same kind as that which exists in Ire- land and England. And the reason is that we have had here precisely the same cause—that we have made land private property. So long as this exists, our democratic institutions are vain, our pretence of equality but cruel irony, Our public Schools can but sow the seeds of dis- content. So long as this exists, material progress can but force the masses of our people into a harder and more hopeless slavery. Until we in some way make the land, what Nature intended it to be, common property, until we in some way secure to every child born among us his natural birthright, we have not established the Republic in any sense worthy of the name, and we can not establish the Republic. Its foundations are quick- Sand. CHAPTER XIII. A LITTLE ISLAND OR A LITTLE WORLD. Imagine an island girt with ocean ; imagine a little world Swimming in space. Put on it, in imagination, human beings. Let them divide the land, share and share alike, as individual property. At first, while pop- ulation is sparse and industrial processes rude and prim- itive, this will work well enough. Turn away the eyes of the mind for a moment, let time pass, and look again. Some families will have died out, some have greatly multiplied ; on the whole, oopu- lation will have largely increased, and even supposing there have been no important inventions or improve- ments in the productive arts, the increase in population, by causing the division of labor, will have made indus- try more complex. During this time some of these peo- ple will have been careless, generous, improvident; some will have been thrifty and grasping. Some of them will have devoted much of their powers to think- ing of how they themselves and the things they see around them came to be, to inquiries and speculations A Z/7'7"ZAZ ZSZAAWD OR A Z/7'7"ZAF WORAE/O. 61 as to what there is in the universe beyond their little is- land or their little world, to making poems, painting pic- tures, or writing books; to noting the differences in rocks and trees and shrubs and grasses; to classifying beasts and birds and fishes and insects—to the doing, in short, of all the many things which add so largely to the sum of human knowledge and human happiness, without much or any gain of wealth to the doer. Others again will have devoted all their energies to the extending of their possessions. What, then, shall we see, land hav- ing been all this time treated as private property Clearly, we shall see that the primitive equality has given way to inequality. Some will have very much more than one of the original shares into which the land was divided ; very many will have no land at all. Sup- pose that, in all things save this, our little island or Our little world is Utopia—that there are no wars or rob- beries; that the government is absolutely pure and taxes nominal ; suppose, if you want to, any sort of a cur- rency ; imagine, if you can imagine such a world or island, that interest is utterly abolished ; yet inequality in the ownership of land will have produced poverty and virtual slavery. For the people we have supposed are human beings —that is to say, in their physical natures at least, they are animals who can only live on land and by the aid of the products of land. They may make machines which will enable them to float on the sea, or perhaps to fly in the air, but to build and equip these machines they must have land and the products of land, and must constantly come back to land. Therefore those who own the land must be the masters of the rest. Thus, if one man has come to own all the land, he is their absolute master even to life or death. If they can only live on the land on his terms, then they can only live on his terms, for without land they cannot live. They are his absolute slaves, and so long as his ownership is acknowledged, if they want to live, they must do in everything as he wills. If, however, the concentration of landownership has not gone so far as to make one or a very few men the owners of all the land—if there are still so many land- owners that there is competition between them as well 62 7A/F ZAND QUEST/OM. as between those who have only their labor—then the terms on which these non-landholders can live will seem more like free contract. But it will not be free con- tract. Land can yield no wealth without the applica- tion of labor ; labor can produce no wealth without land. These are the two equally necessary factors of production. Yet, to say that they are equally necessary factors of production is not to say that, in the making of contracts as to how the results of production are di- vided, the possessors of these two meet on equal terms. For the nature of these two factors is very different. Land is a natural element ; the human being must have his stomach filled every few hours. Land can exist without labor, but labor can not exist without land. If I own a piece of land, I can let it lay idle for a year or for years, and it will eat nothing. But the laborer must eat every day, and his family must eat. And so, in the making of terms between them, the landowner has an immense advantage over the laborer. It is on the side of the laborer that the intense pressure of com- petition comes, for in his case it is competition urged by hunger. And, further than this : As population in- creases, as the competition for the use of land becomes more and more intense, so are the owners of land en- abled to get for the use of their land a larger and larger part of the wealth which labor exerted upon it pro- duces. That is to say, the value of land steadily rises. Now, this steady rise in the value of land brings about a confident expectation of future increase of value, which produces among landowners all the effects of a combination to hold for higher prices. Thus there is a constant tendency to force mere laborers to take less and less or to give more and more (put it which way you please, it amounts to the same thing) of the pro- ducts of their work for the opportunity to work. And thus, in the very nature of things, we should see on our little island or our little world that, after a time had passed, some of the people would be able to take and enjoy a superabundance of all the fruits of labor with- out doing any labor at all, while others would be forced to work the livelong day for a pitiful living. But let us introduce another element into the sup- position. Let us suppose great discoveries and inven- TAA C/D//ZZZA 7/OM 7 AMA 7" /S POSS/BZÄ. 63 tions—such as the steam engine, the power loom, the Bessemer process, the reaping machine, and the thou- sand-and-C me labor-saving devices that are such a marked feature of our era. What would be the result 2 Manifestly, the effect of all such discoveries and in- ventions is to increase the power of labor in producing wealth—to enable the same amount of wealth to be produced by less labor, or a greater amount with the same labor. But none of them lessen, or can lessen the necessity for land. Until we can discover some way of making Something out of nothing—and that is so far beyond our powers as to be absolutely unthinkable— there is no possible discovery or invention which can lessen the dependence of labor upon land. And, this being the case, the effect of these labor-saving devices, land being the private property of some, would simply be to increase the proportion of the wealth produced that landowners could demand for the use of their land. The ultimate effect of these discoveries and inventions would be not to benefit the laborer, but to make him more dependent. And, since we are imagining conditions, imagine la- bor-saving inventions to go to the farthest imaginable point, that is to say, to perfection. What then 2 Why then, the necessity for labor being done away with, all the wealth that the land could produce would go entire to the landowners. None of it whatever could be claimed by any one else. For the laborers there would be no use at all. If they continued to exist, it would be merely as paupers on the bounty of the landowners' CHAPTER XIV. THE CIVILIZATION THAT IS POSSIBLE. In the effects upon the distribution of wealth, of mak- ing land private property, we may thus see an explana- tion of that paradox presented by modern progress. The perplexing phenomena of deepening want with in- creasing wealth, of labor rendered more dependent and helpless by the very introduction of labor-saving ma- 64 g THE LAND QUEST/OM. chinery, are the inevitable result of natural laws as fixed and certain as the law of gravitation. Private property . in land is the primary cause of the monstrous inequali- ties which are developing in modern society. It is this, and not any miscalculation of Nature in bringing into the world more mouths than she can feed, that gives rise to that tendency of wages to a minimum—that “iron law of wages,” as the Germans call it—that, in spite of all advances in productive power, compels the laboring classes to the least return on which they will consent to live. It is this that produces all those phenomena that are so often attributed to the conflict of labor and capi- tal. It is this that condemns Irish peasants to rags and hunger, that produces the pauperism of England and the tramps of America. It is this that makes the alms- house and the penitentiary the marks of what we call high civilization; that in the midst of schools and churches degrades and brutalizes men, crushes the sweet- ness out of womanhood and the joy out of childhood. It is this that makes lives that might be a blessing a pain and a curse, and every year drives more and more to seek unbidden refuge in the gates of death. For, a per- manent tendency to inequality once set up, all the forces of progress tend to greater and greater inequality. All this is contrary to Nature. The poverty and mis- ery, the vice and degradation, that spring from the un- equal distribution of wealth, are not the results of natural law; they spring from our defiance of natural law. They are the fruits of our refusal to obey the supreme law of justice. It is because we rob the child of his birthright; because we make the bounty which the Creator intended for all the exclusive property of some, that these things come upon us, and, though advancing and advancing, we chase but the mirage. When, lit by lightning-flash or friction amid dry grasses, the consuming flames of fire first flung their lurid glow into the face of man, how must he have started back in affright ! When he first stood by the shores of the sea, how must its waves have said to him, “Thus far shalt thou go, but no farther ”! Yet, as he learned to use them, fire became his most useful servant, the Sea his easiest highway. The most destructive element of which we know—that which for ages and ages seemed 7A/A2 CAE PAZAZA 7/OAV 7"HA 7" ZS AEOSS/BZE. 65 the very thunderbolt of the angry gods—is, as we are now beginning to learn, fraught for us with untold powers of usefulness. Already it enables us to annihi- late space in our messages, to illuminate the night with new suns; and its uses are only beginning. And throughout all Nature, as far as we can see, whatever is potent for evil is potent for good. “Dirt,” said Lord Brougham, “is matter in the wrong place.” And so the squalor and vice and misery that abound in the very heart of our civilization are but results of the misappli- cation of forces in their nature most elevating. I doubt not that whichever way a man may turn to in- quire of Nature, he will come upon adjustments which will arouse not merely his wonder, but his gratitude. Yet what has most impressed me with the feeling that the laws of Nature are the laws of beneficent intelli- gence is what I see of the social possibilities involved in the law of rent. Rent * springs from natural causes. It arises, as society develops, from the differences in natural opportunities and the differences in the distribu- tion of population. It increases with the division of labor, with the advance of the arts, with the progress of invention. And thus, by virtue of a law impressed upon the very nature of things, has the Creator provided that the natural advance of mankind shall be an advance toward equality, an advance toward Co-operation, an ad- vance toward a social state in which not even the weak- est need be crowded to the wall, in which even for the unfortunate and the Cripple there may be ample pro- vision. For this revenue, which arises from the common property, which represents not the creation of value by the individual, but the creation by the community as a whole, which increases just as Society develops, affords a common fund, which, properly used, tends constantly to equalize conditions, to open the largest opportunities for all, and to utterly banish want or the fear of want. The squalid poverty that festers in the heart of our civilization, the vice and crime and degradation and rav- ening greed that flow from it, are the results of a treat- ment of land that ignores the simple law of justice, a law * I, of course, use the word “rent” in its economic, not in its com- mon sense, meaning by it what is commonly called ground rent. 5 66 7 H.A. ZAND QUEST/OM. so clear and plain that it is universally recognized by the veriest savages. What is by nature the common birthright of all, we have made the exclusive property of individuals ; what is by natural law the common fund, from which common wants should be met, we give to a few that they may lord it over their fellows. And so Some are gorged while some go hungry, and more is wasted than would suffice to keep all in luxury. In this nineteenth century, among any people who have begun to utilize the forces and methods of modern production, there is no necessity for want. There is no good reason why even the poorest should not have all the Comforts, all the luxuries, all the opportunities for culture, all the gratifications of refined taste that only the richest now enjoy. There is no reason why any one should be compelled to long and monotonous labor. Did invention and discovery stop to-day, the forces of production are ample for this. What hampers produc- tion is the unnatural inequality in distribution. And, with just distribution, invention and discovery would only have begun. Appropriate rent in the way I propose, and speculative rent would be at once destroyed. The dogs in the man- ger who are now holding so much land they have no use for, in order to extract a high price from those who do want to use it, would be at once choked off, and land from which labor and capital are now debarred under penalty of a heavy fine would be thrown open to im- provement and use. The incentive to land monopoly would be gone. Population would spread where it is now too dense, and become denser where it is now too sparse. Appropriate rent in this way, and not only would nat- ural opportunities be thus opened to labor and capital, but all the taxes which now weigh upon production and rest upon the consumer could be abolished. The demand for labor would increase, wages would rise, every wheel of production would be set in motion. Appropriate rent in this way, and the present expenses of government would be at once very much reduced— reduced directly by the saving in the present cumbrous and expensive schemes of taxation, reduced indirectly by the diminution in pauperism and in crime. This 7"Ay AE CAP//ZZA 7/OAV 7"HA 7" ZS POSS/B/CAE. 67 simplification in governmental machinery, this elevation of moral tone which would result, would make it possi- ble for government to assume the running of railroads, telegraphs, and other businesses which, being in their nature monopolies, can not, as experience is showing, be safely left in the hands of private individuals and corporations. In short, losing its character as a re- pressive agency, government could thus gradually pass into an administrative agency of the great co-operative association—Society. For, appropriate rent in this way, and there would be at once a large surplus over and above what are now considered the legitimate expenses of government. We could divide this, if we wanted to, among the whole community, share and share alike. Or we could give every boy a small capital for a start when he came of age, every girl a dower, every widow an annuity, every aged person a pension, out of this common estate. Or we could do with our great common fund many, many things that would be for the common benefit, many, many things that would give to the poorest what even the richest can not now enjoy. We could establish free libraries, lectures, museums, art-galleries, observatories, gymnasiums, baths, parks, theatres ; we could line our roads with fruit-trees, and make our cities clean and wholesome and beautiful ; we could conduct experi- ments, and offer rewards for inventions, and throw them open to public use.* Think of the enormous wastes that now go on : The waste of false revenue systems, which hamper produc- tion and bar exchange, which fine a man for erecting a building where none stood before, or for making two blades of grass grow where there was but one. The waste of unemployed labor, of idle machinery, of those periodical depressions of industry almost as destructive as war. The waste entailed by poverty, and the vice and crime and thriftlessness and drunkenness that spring from it ; the waste entailed by that greed of gain that is its shadow, and which makes business in large part but a masked war; the waste entailed by the fret and worry * A million dollars spent in premiums and experiments would, in all probability, make aërial navigation an accomplished fact, 68 THE LAND QUEST/OM. about the mere physical necessities of existence, to which so many of us are condemned; the waste entailed by ignorance, by cramped and undeveloped faculties, by the turning of human beings into mere machinesſ Think of these enormous wastes, and of the others which, like these, are due to the fundamental wrong which produces an unjust distribution of wealth and distorts the natural development of society, and you will begin to see what a higher, purer, richer civilization would be made possible by the simple measure that will assert natural rights. You will begin to see how, even if no one but the present landholders were to be considered, this would be the greatest boon that could be vouch- safed thern by society, and that, for them to fight it, would be as if the dog with a tin kettle tied to his tail should snap at the hand that offered to free him. Even the greatest landholder As for such landholders as our working farmers and homestead owners, the slightest discussion would show them that they had everything to gain by the change. But even such landholders as the Duke of Westminster and the Astors would be gainers. * For it is of the very nature of injustice that it really profits no one. When and where was slavery good for slaveholders ? Did her cruelties in America, her expul- sions of Moors and Jews, her burnings of heretics, profit Spain f Has England gained by her injustice toward Ireland? Did not the curse of an unjust social system rest on Louis XIV. and Louis XV. as well as on the poor- est peasant whom it condemned to rags and Starvation —as well as on that Louis whom it sent to the block 2 Is the Czar of Russia to be envied ? This we may know certainly, this we may hold to con- fidently : that which is unjust can really profit no one ; that which is just can really harm no one. Though all other lights move and circle, this is the pole-Star by which we may safely steer. 7A/E CZWZZZZA ZZOAV ZALA 7" ZS. 60 CHAPTER xv. THE CIVILIZATION THAT IS. When we think of the civilization that might be, how poor and pitiful, how little better than utter barbarism, seems this civilization of which we boast ! Even here, where it has had the freest field and fullest development 1 Even here ! This is a broad land and a rich land. How wide it is, how rich it is, how the fifty millions of us already here are but beginning to Scratch it, a man can not begin to realize, till he does some thousands of miles of travel- ling over it. There are a School and a church and a news- paper in every hamlet; we have no privileged orders, no legacies of antiquated institutions, no strong and covertly hostile neighbors, who in fancy or reality oblige us to keep up great standing armies. We have had the experience of all other nations to guide us in selecting what is good and rejecting what is bad. In politics, in religion, in Science, in mechanism, everything shows the latest improvements. We think we stand, and in fact we do stand, in the very van of civilization, Food here is cheaper, wages higher, than anywhere else. There is here a higher average of education, of intel- ligence, of material comfort, and of individual opportu- nity, than among any other of the great civilized na- tions. Here modern civilization is at its very best. Yet even here ! Last winter I was in San Francisco. There are in San Francisco citizens who can build themselves houses that cost a million and a half; citizens who can give each of their children two millions of registered United States bonds for a Christmas present ; citizens who can send their wives to Paris to keep house there, or rather to “keep palace" in a style that outdoes the lavishness of Russian grand dukes; citizens whose daughters are golden prizes to the bluest-blooded of English aristo- crats; citizens who can buy seats in the United States Senate and leave them empty, just to show their gran 7o THE LAND QUESTION: deur. There are, also, in San Francisco other citizens Last winter I could hardly walk a block without meet. ing a citizen begging for ten cents. And, when a charity fund was raised to give work, with pick and shovel to such as would rather work than beg, the applications were so numerous that, to make the charity fund go as far as possible, one set of men was discharged after having been given a few days' work, in order to make room for another set. This and much else of the same sort I saw in San Francisco last winter. Likewise in Sacramento, and in other towns. Last summer, on the plains, I took from its tired mother, and held in my arms, a little sun-browned baby, the youngest of a family of the sturdy and keen Western New England stock, who alone in their two wagons had travelled near three thousand miles looking for some place to locate and finding none, and who were now re- turning to where the father and his biggest boy could go to work on a railroad, what they had got by the sale of their Nebraska farm all gone. And I walked awhile by the side of long, lank Southwestern men who, after similar fruitless journeyings way up into Washington Territory, were going back to the Choctaw Nation. This winter I have been in New York. New York is the greatest and richest of American cities—the third city of the modern world, and moving steadily toward the first place. This is a time of great prosperity. Never before were so many goods sold, so much business done. Real estate is advancing with big jumps, and within the last few months many fortunes have been made in buy- ing and selling vacant lots. Landlords nearly everywhere3 are demanding increased rents; asking in some of the business quarters an increase of three hundred per cent. Money is so plenty that Government four per cents sell for I 14, and a bill is passing Congress for refunding the maturing national debt at three per cent. per annum, a rate that awhile ago in California was not thought ex- orbitant per month. All sorts of shares and bonds have been going up and up. You can sell almost anything if you give it a high-Sounding Corporate name and issue well-printed shares of stock. Seats in the Board of Brokers are worth thirty thousand dollars, and are cheap at that. There are citizens here who rake in millions at THE crºzzzza Trow THAT IS. 71 a single operation with as much ease as a faro-dealer rakes in a handful of chips. Nor is this the mere seeming prosperity of feverish speculation. The country is really prosperous. The crops have been enormous, the demand insatiable. We have at last a sound currency ; gold has been pouring in. The railroads have been choked with produce, steel rails are being laid faster than ever before ; all sorts of fac- tories are running full time or over time. So prosper- ous is the country, so good are the times, that, at the Presidential election a few months since, the determin- ing argument was that we could not afford to take the chance of disturbing so much material prosperity by a political change. Nevertheless, prosperous as are these times, citizens of the United States beg you on the streets for ten cents and five cents, and although you know that there are in this city two hundred charitable societies, although you realize that on general principles to give money in this way is to do evil rather than good, you are afraid to re- fuse them when you read of men in this great city freez- ing to death and starving to death. Prosperous as are these times, women are making overalls for sixty cents a dozen, and you can hire citizens for trivial sums to parade up and down the streets all day with advertising placards on their backs. I get on a horse-car and ride with the driver. He is evidently a sober, steady man, as intelligent as a man can be who drives a horse-car all the time he is not asleep or eating his meals. He tells me has a wife and four children. He gets home (if a couple of rooms can be called a home) at two o'clock in the morning ; he has to be back on his car at nine. Sun- day he has a couple of hours more, which he has to put in in sleep, else, as he says, he would utterly break down. His children he never sees, save when one of them comes at noon or Supper-time to the horse-car route with some- thing for him to eat in a tin pail. He gets for his day's work one dollar and seventy-five cents—a sum that will buy at Delmonico's a beefsteak and cup of coffee. I say to him that it must be pretty hard to pay rent and keep six persons on one dollar and seventy-five cents a day. He says it is ; that he has been trying for a month to get enough ahead to buy a new pair of shoes, but he hasn't 72 7 HE LAND QUESTION: yet succeeded. I ask why he does not leave such a job. He says, “What can I do 2 There are a thousand men ready to step into my place l’ And so, in this time of prosperity, he is chained to his car. The horses that he drives, they are changed six times during his working- day. They have lots of time to stretch themselves and rest themselves and eat in peace their plentiful meals, for they are worth from one to two hundred dollars each, and it would be a loss to the company for them to fall ill. But this driver, this citizen of the United States, he may fall ill or drop dead, and the company would not lose a cent. As between him and the beasts he drives, I am inclined to think that this most prosperous era is more prosperous for horses than for men. Our Napoleon of Wall Street, our rising Charlemagne of railroads, who came to this city with nothing but a new kind of mouse-trap in a mahogany box, but who now, though yet in the vigor of his prime, counts his wealth by hundreds of millions, if it can be counted at all, is interviewed by a reporter just as he is about to step aboard his palace-car for a grand combination ex- pedition into the Southwest. He descants upon the services he is rendering in welding into one big ma- chine a lot of smaller machines, in uniting into one vast railroad empire the separated railroad kingdoms. He likewise descants upon the great prosperity of the whole country. Everybody is prosperous and con- tented, he says: there is, of course, a good deal of mis- ery in the big cities, but, then, there always is Yet not alone in the great cities. I ride on the Hud- son River Railroad on a bitter cold day, and from one of the pretty towns with Dutch names gets in a consta- ble with a prisoner, whom he is to take to the Albany penitentiary. In this case justice has been swift enough, for the crime, the taking of a shovel, has only been committed a few hours before. Such coat as the man has he keeps buttoned up, even in the hot car, for, the constable says, he has no underclothes at all. He stole the shovel to get to the penitentiary, where it is warm. The constable Says they have lots of such cases, and that even in these good times these pretty country towns are infested with such tramps. With all our vast organ- izing, our developing of productive powers and cheap. 7"HE CZWZZZZA 7TWOAW 7A/A 7" ZS. 73 ening of transportation, we are yet creating a class of utter pariahs. And they are to be found not merely in the great cities, but wherever the locomotive runs. Is it real advance in civilization which, on the one hand, produces these great Captains of industry, and, on the other, these social outcasts 2 It is the year of grace 1881, and of the Republic the Iosth. The girl who has brought in coal for my fire is twenty years old. She was born in New York, and can neither read nor write. To me, when I heard it, this seemed sin and shame, and I got her a spelling book. She is trying what she can, but it is up-hill work. She has really no time. Last night when I came in, at eleven, she was not through scrubbing the halls. She gets four dollars a month. Her shoes cost two dollars a pair. She says she can sew ; but I guess it is about as I can. In the natural course of things, this girl will be a mother of citizens of the Republic. Underneath are girls who can sew ; they run sewing- machines with their feet all day. I have seen girls in Asia carrying water-jugs on their heads and young women in South America bearing burdens. They were lithe and strong and symmetrical ; but to turn a young women into motive power for a sewing-machine is to weaken and injure her physically. And these girls are to rear, or ought to rear, citizens of the Republic. But there is worse and worse than this. Go out into the streets at night, and you will find them filled with girls who will never be mothers. To the man who has known the love of mother, of sister, of sweetheart, wife, and daughter, this is the saddest sight of all. The ladies of the Brooklyn churches—they are get- ting up petitions for the suppression of Mormon polyg- amy ; they would have it rooted out with pains and penalties, trampled out, if need be, with fire and sword ; and their reverend Congressman-elect is going, when he takes his seat, to introduce a most stringent bill to that end ; for that a man should have more wives than One is a burning Scandal in a Christian country. So it is ; but there are also other burning scandals. As for Scandals that excite talk, I will spare Brooklyn a com parison with Salt Lake. But as to ordinary things : I have walked through the streets of Salt Lake City, by 74 THE LAND QUESZZON. day and by night, without seeing what in the streets of New York or Brooklyn excites no comment. Polygamy is unnatural and wrong, no doubt of that, for Nature brings into the world something over twenty-two boys for every twenty girls. But is not a state of society unnatural and wrong in which there are thousands and thousands of girls for whom no husband ever offers ? Can we brag of a state of Society in which one citizen can load his wife with more diamonds than an Indian chief can put beads on his squaw, while many other citizens are afraid to marry lest they can not support a wife—a state of Society in which prostitution flourishes 2 Polygamy is bad, but is it not better than that P Civilization is advancing day by day; never was such progress as we are making ! Yet divorces are increasing and insanity is increasing. What is the goal of a civilization that tends toward free love and the madhouse 2 This is a most highly civilized community. There is not a bear nor wolf on Manhattan Island, save in a menagerie. Yet it is easier, where they are worst, to guard against bears and wolves than it is to guard against the human beasts of prey that roam this island. In this highly civilized city every lower window has to be barred, every door locked and bolted ; even door- mats, not worth twenty-five cents, you will see chained to the steps. Stop for a moment in a crowd and your watch is gone as if by magic ; shirt-studs are taken from their owners' bosoms, and ear-rings cut from la- dies' ears. Even a standing army of policemen do not prevent highway robbery; there are populous districts that to walk through after nightfall is a risk, and where you have far more need to go armed and to be wary than in the backwoods. There are dens into which men are lured only to be drugged and robbed, sometimes to be murdered. All the resources of science and inven- tive genius are exhausted in making burglar proof strong-rooms and safes, yet, as the steel plate becomes thicker and harder, so does the burglar's tool become keener. If the combination lock can not be picked, it is blown open. If not a crack large enough for the in- troduction of powder is left, then the air-pump is ap- plied and a vacuum is created. So that those who in the heart of civilization would guard their treasures 7A/E CATVZZZZA 7"ZOAV 7"HA 7" ZS. 75 safely must come back to the most barbarous device, and either themselves, or by proxy, sleeplessly stand guard. What sort of a civilization is this In what does civilization essentially consist if not in civility— that is to say, in respect for the rights of person and of property 2 Yet this is not all, nor the worst. These are but the grosser forms of that spirit that in the midst of our civ- ilization compels every one to stand on guard. What is the maxim of business intercourse among the most highly respectable classes P. That if you are Swindled it will be your own fault ; that you must treat every man you have dealings with as though he but wanted the chance to cheat and rob you. Caveat emptor. “Let the buyer beware.” If a man steal a few dollars he may stand a chance of going to the penitentiary—I read the other day of a man who was sent to the penitentiary for stealing four cents from a horse-car company. But, if he steal a million by business methods, he is courted and flattered, even though he steal the poor little savings which washerwomen and sewing-girls have brought to him in trust, even though he rob widows and orphans of the security which dead men have struggled and stinted to provide. This is a most Christian city. There are churches and churches. All sorts of churches, where are preached all sorts of religions, save that which once in Galilee taught the arrant socialistic doctrine that it is easier for a camel to pass through the eye of a needle than for a rich man to enter the kingdom of God ; all save that which once in Jerusalem drove the money-changers from the temple. Churches of brown and gray and yellow stone, lifting toward heaven in such noble sym- metry that architecture seems invocation and benison ; where, on stained-glass windows, glow angel and apos- tle, and the entering light is dimmed to a soft glory ; where such music throbs and supplicates and bursts in joy as once in St. Sophia ravished the souls of heathen Northmen; churches where richly cushioned pews let for the very highest prices, and the auctioneer deter- mines who shall sit in the foremost seats ; churches out- side of which on Sunday stand long lines of carriages, on each carriage a coachman, And there are white. 76 7 HE LA WD QUESTION: marble churches, so pure and shapely that the stone seems to have bloomed and flowered—the concrete ex- pression of a grand, Sweet thought. Churches restful to the very eye, and into which the weary and heavy- laden can enter and join in the worship of their Creator for no larger an admission fee than it costs on the Bowery to see the bearded lady or the Zulu giant eight feet high. And then there are mission churches, run expressly for poor people, where it does not cost a cent. There is no lack of churches. There are, in fact, more churches than there are people who care to attend them. And there are likewise Sunday-schools, and big relig- ious “book concerns,” and tract societies, and societies for spreading the light of the Gospel among the heathen in foreign parts. Yet, land a heathen on the Battery with money in his pocket, and he will be robbed of the last cent of it be- fore he is a day older. “By their fruits shall ye know them.” I wonder whether they who send missionaries to the heathen ever read the daily papers. I think I could take a file of these newspapers, and from their daily chroniclings match anything that could be told in the same period of any heathen community—at least, of any heathen community in a like state of peace and prosperity. I think I could take a file of these papers, and match, horror for horror, all that returning mis- sionaries have to tell—even to the car of Juggernaut or infants tossed from mothers' arms into the sacred river; even to Ashantee “customs” or cannibalistic feasts. I do not say that such things are because of civiliza- tion, or because of Christianity. On the contrary, I point to them as inconsistent with civilization, as in- compatible with Christianity. They show that our civ- ilization is one-sided and can not last as at present based ; they show that our so-called Christian com- munities are not Christian at all. I believe a civiliza- tion is possible in which all could be civilized—in which such things would be impossible. But it must be a civilization based on justice and acknowledging the equal rights of all to natural opportunities. I believe that there is in true Christianity a power to regenerate the world. But it must be a Christianity that attacks * ~ * ~ * 7"RöA COAVSAEA? MA 7'/S//. *7 them. The religion which allies itself with injustice to preach down the natural aspirations of the masses is worse than atheism. • CHAPTER XVI. TRUE CONSERVATISM. There are those who may look on this little book as very radical, in the bad sense they attach to the word. They mistake. This is, in the true sense of the word, a most conservative little book. I do not appeal to prej- udice and passion. I appeal to intelligence. I do not incite to strife ; I seek to prevent strife. That the civilized world is on the verge of the most tremendous struggle, which, according to the frankness and sagacity with which it is met, will be a struggle of ideas or a struggle of actual physical force, calling upon all the potent agencies of destruction which modern invention has discovered, every sign of the times portends. The voices that proclaim the eve of revolution are in the air. Steam and electricity are not merely transporting goods and carrying messages. They are everywhere changing social and industrial or- ganization ; they are everywhere stimulating thought, and arousing new hopes and fears and desires and pas- sions; they are everywhere breaking down the barriers that have separated men, and integrating nations into one vast organism, through which the same pulses throb and the same nerves tingle. The present situation in Great Britain is full of dan- gers, of dangers graver and nearer than those who there are making history are likely to see. Who in France, a century ago, foresaw the drama of blood so soon to open 2 Who in the United States dreamed of what was coming till the cannon-shot rang and the flag fell on Sumter 2 How confidently we said, “The American people are too intelligent, too practical, to go to cut- ting each other's throats” . How confidently we relied upon the strong common-sense of the great masses, upon the great business interests, upon the univer- 78 7A/A. f. AMD OUEST/OM. sai desire to make money! “War does not pay,” we said, “therefore war is impossible.” A shot rang over Charleston harbor; a bit of bunting dropped, and, riven into two hostile camps, a nation sprang to its feet to close in the death lock. And to just such a point are events hurrying in Great Britain to day. History repeats itself, and what hap- pened a century ago on one side of the English Chan- nel is beginning again on the other. Already has the States General met, and the Third Estate put on their hats. Already Necker is in despair. Already has the /it de justice been held, and the Tennis Court been locked, and ball-cartridge been served to the Swiss Guard | For the moment the forces of reaction tri- umph. Davitt is snatched to prison; a “Liberal ” gov- ernment carries coercion by a tremendous majority, and the most despotic powers are invoked to make possible the eviction of Irish peasants. The order of Warsaw is to reign in Ireland, and the upholders of ancient wrong deem it secure again, as the wave that was mounting seems sweeping back. Let them wait a little and they will see. For again the wave will mount, and higher and higher, and soon the white foam will seethe and hiss on its toppling crest. It is not true conservatism which cries “Peace peace ” when there is no peace ; which, like the ostrich, sticks its head in the sand and fancies itself secure ; which would compromise matters by putting more coal in the furnace, and hanging heavier weights on the safety-valve That alone is true conservatism which would look facts in the face, which would reconcile opposing forces on the only basis on which reconciliation is possible—that of jus- tice. I speak again of Great Britain, but I speak with ref- erence to the whole modern world. The true nature of the inevitable conflict with which modern civilization is everywhere beginning to throb, can, it seems to me, best be seen in the United States, and in the newer States even more clearly than in the older States. That intelligent Englishmen imagine that in the de- mocratization of political institutions, in free trade in land, or in peasant proprietorship, can be found any solution of the difficulties which are confronting them, 7% UAE COAWSAZA WA 7/SM. 79 is because they do not see what may be seen in the United States by whoever will look. That intelligent Americans imagine that by these questions which are so menacingly presenting themselves in Europe their peace is to be unvexed, is because they shut their eyes to what is going on around them, because they attribute to themselves and their institutions what is really due to conditions now rapidly passing away—to the sparse- ness of population and the cheapness of land. Yet it is here, in this American Republic, that the true nature of that inevitable conflict now rapidly approaching which must determine the fate of modern civilization may be most clearly seen. We have here abolished all hereditary privileges and legal distinctions of class. Monarchy, aristocracy, prel- acy, we have swept them all away. We have carried mere political democracy to its ultimate. Every child born in the United States may aspire to be President. Every man, even though he be a tramp or a pauper, has a vote, and one man's vote counts for as much as any other man's vote. Before the law all citizens are abso- lutely equal. In the name of the people all laws run. They are the source of all power, the fountain of all honor. In their name and by their will all government is carried on ; the highest officials are but their servants. Primogeniture and entail we have abolished wherever they existed. We have and have had free trade in land. We started with something infinitely better than any scheme of peasant proprietorship which it is possible to carry into effect in Great Britain. We have had for our public domain the best part of an immense conti- nent. We have had the pre-emption law and the home- stead law. It has been our boast that here every one who wished it could have a farm. We have had full liberty of speech and of the press. We have not merely com- mon Schools, but high Schools and universities, open to all who may choose to attend. Yet here the same social difficulties apparent on the other side of the Atlantic are beginning to appear. It is already clear that our democracy is a vain pretence, our make-believe of equality a sham and a fraud. Already are the sovereign people becoming but a roi fainéant, like the Merovingian kings of France, like the 86 7 H.A. LA WD QUEST/OM. Mikados of Japan. The shadow of power is theirs; but the substance of power is being grasped and wielded by the bandit chiefs of the stock exchange, the robber leaders who organize politics into machines. In any matter in which they are interested, the little finger of the great corporations is thicker than the loins of the people. Is it sovereign States or is it railroad cor- porations that are really represented in the elective Senate which we have substituted for an hereditary House of Lords 2 Where is the count or marquis or duke in Europe who wields such power as is wielded by such simple citizens as Our Stanfords, Goulds, and Vanderbilts 2 What does legal equality amount to, when the fortunes of some citizens can only be esti- mated in hundreds of millions, and other citizens have nothing 2 What does the suffrage amount to when, un- der threat of discharge from employment, citizens can be forced to vote as their employers dictate 2 when votes can be bought on election day for a few dollars apiece 2 If there are citizens so dependent that they must vote as their employers wish, so poor that a few dollars on election day seem to them more than any higher consideration, then giving them votes simply adds to the political power of wealth, and universal suffrage becomes the surest basis for the establishment of tyranny. “Tyranny " There is a lesson in the very word. What are our American bosses but the ex- act antitypes of the Greek tyrants, from whom the word comes 2 They who gave the word tyrant its mean- ing did not claim to rule by right divine. They were simply the Grand Sachems of Greek Tammanys, the organizers of Hellenic “stalwart machines.” Even if universal history did not teach the lesson, it is in the United States already becoming very evident that political equality can only continue to exist upon a basis of social equality ; that where the disparity in the distribution of wealth increases, political democracy only makes easier the concentration of power, and must inevitably lead to tyranny and anarchy. And it is al- ready evident that there is nothing in political de- mocracy, nothing in popular education, nothing in any of our American institutions, to prevent the most enor- mous disparity in the distribution of wealth. Nowhere 7"R UE COMSEAE VA 7T/SM. 81 in the world are such great fortunes growing up as in the United States. Considering that the average income of the working masses of our people is only a few hun- dred dollars a year, a fortune of a million dollars is a monstrous thing—a more monstrous and dangerous thing under a democratic government than anywhere else. Yet fortunes of ten and twelve million dollars are with us ceasing to be noticeable. We already have citizens whose wealth can only be estimated in hun- dreds of millions, and before the end of the century, if present tendencies continue, we are likely to have for- tunes estimated in thousands of millions—such mon- strous fortunes as the world has never seen since the growth of similar fortunes ate out the heart of Rome. And the necessary correlative of the growth of such for- tunes is the impoverishment and loss of independence on the part of the masses. These great aggregations of wealth are like great trees, which strike deep roots and spread wide branches, and which, by sucking up the moisture from the soil and intercepting the sunshine, stunt and kill the vegetation around them. When a capi- tal of a million dollars comes into competition with capi- tals of thousands of dollars, the smaller capitalists must be driven out of the business or destroyed. With great capital nothing can compete Save great capital. Hence, every aggregation of wealth increases the tendency to the aggregation of wealth, and decreases the possibility of the employee ever becoming more than an employee, compelling him to compete with his fellows as to who will work cheapest for the great capitalist—a competi- tion that can have but one result, that of forcing wages to the minimum at which the supply of labor can be kept up. Where we are is not so important as in what direction we are going, and in the United States all ten- dencies are clearly in this direction. A while ago, and any journeyman shoemaker could set up in business for him- self with the savings of a few months. But now the operative shoemaker could not in a lifetime save enough from his wages to go into business for himself. And, now that great capital has entered agriculture, it must be with the same results. The large farmer, who can buy the latest machinery at the lowest cash prices and use it to the best advantage, who can run a straight furrow for miles. 6 82 7"HE LA WD QUEST/OM. who can make special rates with railroad companies, take advantage of the market, and sell in large lots for the least Commission, must drive out the Small farmer of the early American type just as the shoe factory has driven out the journeyman shoemaker. And this is going on to-day. There is nothing unnatural in this. On the contrary, it is in the highest degree natural. Social development is in accordance with certain immutable laws. And the law of development, whether it be the development of a solar system, of the tiniest organism, or of a human SO- ciety, is the law of integration. It is in obedience to this law—a law evidently as all-compelling as the law of gravitation—that these new agencies, which so powerfully stimulate social growth, tend to the specialization and interdependence of industry. It is in obedience to this law that the factory is superseding the independent me- chanic, the large farm is swallowing up the little one, the big store shutting up the small one, that corpora- tions are arising that dwarf the State, and that popula- tion tends more and more to concentrate in cities. Men must work together in larger and in more closely re- lated groups. Production must be on a greater Scale. The only question is, whether the relation in which men are thus drawn together and compelled to act together shall be the natural relation of interdependence in equality. or in the unnatural relation of dependence upon a mas- ter. If the one, then may civilization advance in what is evidently the natural order, each step leading to a higher step. If the other, then what Nature has in- tended as a blessing becomes a curse, and a condition of inequality is produced which will inevitably destroy civilization. Every new invention but hastens the catastrophe. - Now, all this we may deduce from natural laws as fixed and certain as the law of gravitation. And all this we may see going on to-day. This is the reason why modern progress, great as it has been, fails to relieve poverty; this is the secret of the increasing discontent which pervades every civilized country. Under present conditions, with land treated as private property, mate- riai progress is developing two diverse tendencies, two opposing currents. On the one side, the tendency of 7 'A' UAE COAVSAEAE PA 7/SM. 83 increasing population and of all improvement in the arts of production is to build up enormous fortunes, to wipe out the intermediate classes, and to crowd down the masses to a level of lower wages and greater de- pendence. On the other hand, by bringing men closer together, by stimulating thought, by creating new wants, by arousing new ambitions, the tendency of modern progress is to make the masses discontented with their condition, to feel bitterly its injustice. The result can be predicted just as certainly as the result can be pre- dicted when two trains are rushing toward each other On the same track. This thing is absolutely certain : Private property in land blocks the way of advancing civilization. The two can not long coexist. Either private property in land must be abolished, or, as has happened again and again in the history of mankind, civilization must again turn back in anarchy and bloodshed. Let the remaining years of the nineteenth century bear me witness. Even now, I believe, the inevitable struggle has begun. It is not conservatism which would ignore such a tremendous fact. It is the blindness that invites destruction. He that is truly conservative let him look the facts in the face ; let him speak frankly and dispassionately. This is the duty of the hour. For, when a great social ques- tion presses for settlement, it is only for a little while that the voice of Reason can be heard. The masses of men hardly think at any time. It is difficult even in sober moments to get them to calmly reason. But when passion is roused, then they are like a herd of stampeded bulls. I do not fear that present social adjustments can continue. That is impossible. What I fear is that the dams may hold till the flood rises to fury. What I fear is that dogged resistance on the one side may kindle a passionate sense of wrong on the other. What I fear are the demagogues and the accidents. The present condition of all civilized countries is that of increasing unstable equilibrium. In steam and elec- tricity, and all the countless inventions which they typify, mighty forces have entered the world. If rightly used, they are our servants, more potent to do our bidding than the genii of Arabian story. If wrongly used, they, too, must turn to monsters of destruction. They re- 84 THE LAWD QUEST/6M. quire and will compel great social changes. That we may already see. Operating under social institutions which are based on natural justice, which acknowledge the equal rights of all to the material and opportunities of nature, their elevating power will be equally exerted, and industrial organization will pass naturally into that of a vast co-operative society. Operating under social institutions which deny natural justice by treating land as private property, their power is unequally exerted, and tends, by producing inequality, to engender forces that will tear and rend and shatter. The old bottles can not hold the new wine. This is the ferment which throughout the civilized world is everywhere beginning. CHAPTER XVII. IN HOC SIGNO VINCES. Let me recapitulate. What I want to impress upon those who may read this paper is this: - The land question is nowhere a mere local question ; it is a universal question. It involves the great problem of the distribution of wealth, which is everywhere forc- ing itself upon attention. It can not be settled by measures which in their na- ture can have but local application. It can only be settled by measures which in their nature will apply everywhere. It can not be settled by half-way measures. It can only be settled by the acknowledgment of equal rights to land. Upon this basis it can be settled easily and permanently. If the Irish reformers take this ground, they will make their fight the common fight of all the peoples, they will concentrate strength and divide opposition. They will turn the flank of the system that oppresses them, and awake the struggle in its very intrenchments They will rouse against it a force that is like the force of rising tides. - What I urge the men of Ireland to do is to proclaim, A Hoc S/GAſo v/WCAES. 85 without limitation or evasion, that the land, of natural right, is the common property of the whole people, aud to propose practical measures which will recognize thys right in all countries as well as in Ireland. What I urge the Land Leagues of the United States to do is to announce this great principle as of universal application ; to give their movement a reference to America as well as to Ireland ; to broaden and deepen and strengthen it by making it a movement for the re- generation of the world—a movement which shall con- centrate and give shape to aspirations that are stirring among all nations. Ask not for Ireland mere charity or sympathy. Let her call be the call of fraternity : “For yourselves, O brothers, as well as for us !” Let her rallying cry awake all who slumber, and rouse to a common struggle all who are oppressed. Let it breathe not old hates; let it ring and echo with the new hope In many lands her sons are true to her; under many skies her daughters burn with the love of her. Lo! the ages bring their opportunity. Let those who would honor her bear her banner to the front The harp and the shamrock, the golden sunburst on the field of living green ſ emblems of a country without nationality; standard of a people down-trodden and op- pressed The hour has come when they may lead the van of the great world-struggle. Types of harmony and of ever-springing hope, of light and of lifel The hour has come when they may stand for something higher than local patriotism ; something grander than national independence. The hour has come when they may stand forth to speak the world's hope, to lead the world's ad- vance Torn away by pirates, tending in a strange land a hea- then master's swine, the slave boy, with the spirit of Christ in his heart, praying in the snow for those who had enslaved him, and returning to bring to his op- pressors the message of the Gospel, returning with good to give where evil had been received, to kindle in the darkness a great light—this is Ireland's patron saint. In his spirit let Ireland's struggle be. Not merely through Irish vales and hamlets, but into England, into Scotland, into Wales, wherever our common tongue is 86 7//E ZAND OUAES77OAV. spoken, let the torch be carried and the word be preached. And beyond The brotherhood of man stops not with differences of speech any more than with seas or mountain chains. A century ago it was ours to speak the ringing word. Then it was France's. Now it may be Ireland's, if her sons be true. But wherever, or by whom, the word must be spoken, the standard will be raised. No matter what the Irish leaders do or do not do, it is too late to permanently set- tle the question on any basis short of the recognition of equal natural right. And, whether the Land Leagues move forward or slink back, the agitation must spread to this side of the Atlantic. The Republic, the true Republic, is not yet here. But her birth struggle must soon begin. Already, with the hope of her, men's thoughts are stirring. Not a republic of landlords and peasants; not a re- public of millionaires and tramps; not a republic in which some are masters and some serve. But a repub- lic of equal citizens, where competition becomes co- operation, and the interdependence of all gives true independence to each ; where moral progress goes hand-in-hand with intellectual progress, and material progress elevates and enfranchises even the poorest and weakest and lowliest. - And the gospel of deliverance, let us not forget it : it is the gospel, of love, not of hate. He whom it eman- cipates will know neither Jew nor Gentile, nor Irishman nor Englishman, nor German nor Frenchman, nor European nor American, nor difference of color nor of race, nor animosities of class nor condition. Let us set our feet on old prejudices, let us bury the old hates. There have been “Holy Alliances” of kings. Let us strive for the Holy Alliance of the people. Liberty, equality, fraternity Write them on the banners. Let them be for sign and countersign. With- out equality, liberty can not be ; without fraternity, neither equality nor liberty can be achieved. Liberty—the full freedom of each bounded only by the equal freedom of every other. Equality—the equal right of each to the use and en- joyment of all natural opportunities, to all the essentials of happy, healthful, human life AV AIOC S/GAVO IV/AWCES. 87 Fraternity—that sympathy which links together those who struggle in a noble cause; that would live and let live; that would help as well as be helped; that, in seek- ing the good of all, finds the highest good of each “By this sign shall ye conquer l’” “ We hold these truths to be self-evident: 7%af al/ men are created equal; that they are endozwed by their Creator with certain unalienable rights; that among these are life, /iberty, and the pursuit of happiness /’’ It is over a century since these words rang out. It is time to give them their full, true meaning. Let the stand- ard be lifted that all may see it; let the advance be sounded that all may hear it. Let those who would fall back, fall back. Let those who would oppose, oppose. Everywhere are those who will rally. The stars in their courses fight against Sisera ! HENRY GEORGE. NEw York, February 28, 1881. PROPERTY IN LAND PROPERTY IN LAND A PASSAGE-AT-ARMS BETWEEN THE DUKE OF ARGYLL AND HENRY GEORGE NEW YORK CHARLES L. WEBSTER & COMPANY 1893 C O N TENTS. I.—“THE PROPHET of SAN FRANCIsco,” by the Duke of Argyll, in the Nineteenth Century for April, 1884. II.—“THE REDUCTION TO INIQUITY,” by Henry George, in the Nineteenth Century for July, 1884, from advance sheets. PEROPERTY IN LAND. I. THE PROPELET OF SAN FRANCISCO. BY THE DURE OF ARGYLL. THERE are some advantages in being a citizen—-even a very humble citizen—in the Republic of Letters. If any man has ever written anything on matters of serious concern, which others have read with interest, he will very soon find himself in contact with curious diversities of mind. Subtle sources of sympathy will open up be- fore him in contrast with sources, not less subtle, of an- tipathy, and both of them are often interesting and in- structive in the highest degree. A good many years ago a friend of mine, whose opinion I greatly value, was kind enough to tell me of his approval of a little book which I had then lately published. As he was a man of pure taste, and naturally much more inclined to criticism than assent, his approval gave me pleasure. But being a man also very honest and outspoken, he took care to explain that his approval was not unqualified. He liked the whole book except one chapter, “in which,” he added, “it seems to me there is a good deal of nonsense.” There was no need to ask him what that chapter was. I knew it very well. It could be none other than a 8 PROPERTY IN LAND. chapter called “Law in Politics,” which was devoted to the question how far, in human conduct and affairs, we can trace the Reign of Law in the same sense, or in a sense very closely analogous to that in which we can trace it in the physical sciences. There were several things in that chapter which my friend was not predis- posed to like. In the first place he was an active politician, and such men are sure to feel the reasoning to be unnatural and unjust which tends to represent all the activities of their life as more or less the results of cir- cumstance. In the second place, he was above all other things a Free Trader, and the governing idea of that school is that every attempt to interfere by law with anything connected with trade or manufacture is a folly if not a crime. Now, one main object of my “non- sense” chapter was to show that this doctrine is not true as an absolute proposition. It drew a line between two provinces of legislation, in one of which such inter- ference had indeed been proved to be mischievous, but in the other of which interference had been equally proved to be absolutely required. Protection, it was shown, had been found to be wrong in all attempts to regulate the value or the price of anything. But Pro- tection, it was also shown, had been found to be right and necessary in defending the interests of life, health, and morals. As a matter of historical fact, it was pointed out that during the present century there had been two steady movements on the part of Parliament— one a movement of retreat, the other a movement of advance. Step by step legislation had been abandoned in all endeavors to regulate interests purely economic ; while, step by step, not less steadily, legislation had been adopted more and more extensively for the regulation of ilatters in which those higher interests were concerned. THE PROPHIET OF SAN FRANCISCO. 9 Moreover, I had ventured to represent both these move- ments as equally important—the movement in favor of Protection in one direction being quite as valuable as the movement against Protection in another direction. It was not in the nature of things that my friend should admit this equality, or even any approach to a compari- son between the two movements. In promoting one of them he had spent his life, and the truths it represented were to him the subject of passionate conviction. Of the other movement he had been at best only a passive spectator, or had followed its steps with cold and critical toleration. To place them on anything like the same level as steps of advance in the science of government, could not but appear to him as a proposition involving “a good deal of nonsense.” But critics may them- selves be criticised ; and sometimes authors are in the happy position of seeing behind both the praise and the blame they get. In this case I am unrepentant. I am firmly convinced that the social and political value of the principle which has led to the repeal of all laws for the regulation of price is not greater than the value of the principle which has led to the enactment of many laws for the regulation of labor. If the Factory Acts and many others of the like kind had not been passed we should for many years have been hearing a hundred “bitter cries’’ for every one which assails us now, and the social problems which still confront us would have been much more difficult and dangerous than they are. Certain it is that if the train of thought which led up to this conclusion was distasteful to some minds, it turned out to be eminently attractive to many others. And of this, some years later, I had a curious proof. From the other side of the world, and from a perfect stranger, there came a courteous letter accompanied by 10 PROPERTY IN LAND. the present of a book. The author had read mine, and he sent his own. In spite of prepossessions, he had con- fidence in a candid hearing. The letter was from Mr. Henry George, and the book was “Progress and Poverty.” Both were then unknown to fame ; nor was it possible for me fully to appreciate the compliment conveyed until I found that the book was directed to prove that almost all the evils of humanity are to be traced to the very existence of landowners, and that by divine right land could only belong to everybody in general and to nobody in particular. The credit of being open to conviction is a great credit, and even the heaviest drafts upon it cannot well be made the subject of complaint. And so I could not be otherwise than flattered when this appeal in the sphere of politics was followed by another in the sphere of Science. Another author was good enough to present me with his book ; and I found that it was directed to prove that all the errors of modern physical philosophy arise from the prevalent belief that our planet is a globe. In reality it is flat. Elaborate chapters, and equally elaborate diagrams are devoted to the proof. At first I thought that the argument was a joke, like Archbishop Whately’s “Historic Doubts.” But I soon saw that the author was quite as earnest as Mr. Henry George. Lately I have seen that both these authors have been addressing public meetings with great success; and con- sidering that all obvious appearances and the language of common life are against the accepted doctrine of Copernicus, it is perhaps not surprising that the popular audiences which have listened to the two reformers have evidently been almost as incompetent to detect the blunders of the one as to see through the logical fallacies of the other, But the Californian philosopher has one THE PROPEIET OF SAN FRANCISCO, 11 immense advantage. Nobody has any personal interest in believing that the world is flat. But many persons may have an interest, very personal indeed, in believing that they have a right to appropriate a share in their neighbor’s vineyard. There are, at least, a few axioms in life on which we are entitled to decline discussion. Even the most scep- tical minds have done so. The mind of Voltaire was certainly not disposed to accept without question any of the beliefs that underlay the rotten political system which he saw and hated. He was one of those who assailed it with every weapon, and who ultimately over- threw it. Among his fellows in that work there was a perfect revelry of rebellion and of unbelief. In the grotesque procession of new opinions which had begun to pass across the stage while he was still upon it, this particular opinion against property in land had been advocated by the famous “Jean Jacques.” Voltaire turned his powerful glance upon it, and this is how he treated it : * IB. Avez-vous oublié que Jean-Jacques, un des pères de l'Eglise Moderne, a dit, que le premier qui osa clore et cultiver un terrain fut l'ennemi du genre humain, qu'il fallait l'exterminer, et que les fruits sont à tous, et que la terre n'est à personne N'avons-nous pas déjà examiné ensemble cette belle proposition si utile à la Société? A. Quel est ce Jean-Jacques 2 Il faut que ce soit quelque Hun, bel esprit, qui ait &crit cette impertinence abominable, ou quelque mau- vais plaisant, buffo magro, qui ait woulu rire de ce que le monde en- tier a de plus sérieux. . . For my own part, however, I confess that the mock- ing spirit of Voltaire is not the spirit in which I am ever tempted to look at the fallacies of Communism. Apart altogether from the appeal which was made to me * Dictionnaire Philosophique, 1764, art, “Loi Naturelle,” 12 - PROPERTY IN LAND. by this author, I have always felt the high interest which belongs to those fallacies, because of the protean forms in which they tend to revive and reappear, and because of the call they make upon us from time to time to ex- amine and identify the fundamental facts which do really govern the condition of mankind. Never, perhaps, have communistic theories assumed a form more curious, or lent themselves to more fruitful processes of analysis, than in the writings of Mr. Henry George. These writ- ings now include a volume on “Social Problems,” pub- lished recently. It represents the same ideas as those which inspire the work on “Progress and Poverty.” They are often expressed in almost the same words, but they exhibit some development and applications which are of high interest and importance. In this paper I shall refer to both, but for the present I can do no more than group together some of the more prominent feat- ures of this new political philosophy. In the first place, it is not a little remarkable to find one of the most extreme doctrines of Communism advo- cated by a man who is a citizen of the United States. We have been accustomed to associate that country with boundless resources, and an almost inexhaustible future. It has been for two centuries, and it still is, the land of refuge and the land of promise to millions of the human race. And among all the States which are there “united,” those which occupy the Far West are credited with the largest share in this abundant present, and this still more abundant future. Yet it is out of these United States, and out of the one State which, perhaps, above all others, has this fame of opulence, that we have a soli- tary voice, prophesying a future of intolerable woes. Be declares that all the miseries of the Old World are already firmly established in the New. He declares that THE PROPEIET OF SAN FRANCISCO. 13 they are increasing in an ever-accelerating ratio, growing with the growth of the people, and strengthening with its apparent strength. He tells us of crowded cities, of pestilential rooms, of men and women struggling for employments however mean, of the breathlessness of competition, of the extremes of poverty and of wealth— in short, of all the inequalities of condition, of all the pressures and Suffocations which accompany the struggle for existence in the oldest and most crowded societies in the world. I do not pretend to accept this picture as an accurate representation of the truth. At the best it is a picture only of the darkest shadows with a complete omission of the lights. The author is above all things a Pessimist, and he is under obvious temptations to adopt this kind of coloring. He has a theory of his own as to the only remedy for all the evils of humanity ; and this remedy he knows to be regarded with aversion both by the intel- lect and by the conscience of his countrymen. He can only hope for success by trying to convince Society that it is in the grasp of some deadly malady. Large allow- ance must be made for this temptation. Still, after making every allowance, it remains a most remarkable fact that such a picture can be drawn by a citizen of the United States. There can be no doubt whatever that at least as regards many of the great cities of the Union, it is quite as true a picture of them as it would be of the great cities of Europe. And even as regards the popula- tion of the States as a whole, other observers have re- ported on the feverish atmosphere which accompanies its eager pursuit of wealth, and on the strain which is everywhere manifest for the attainment of standards of living and of enjoyment which are never reached except by a very few. So far, at least, we may accept Mr. 14 DROPERTY IN LANI). George's representations as borne out by independent evidence. But here we encounter another most remarkable cir- cumstance in Mr. George's books. The man who gives this dark—this almost black—picture of the tendencies of American progress, is the same man who rejects with indignation the doctrine that population does everywhere tend to press in the same way upon the limits of subsist- ence. This, as is well known, is the general proposition which is historically connected with the name of Malthus, although other writers before him had unconsciously felt and assumed its truth. Since his time it has been almost universally admitted not as a theory but as a fact, and one of the most clearly ascertained of all the facts of economic science. But, like all Communists, Mr. George hates the very name of Malthus. He admits and even exaggerates the fact of pressure as applicable to the people of America. He admits it as applicable to the people of Europe, and of India, and of China. He admits it as a fact as applicable more or less obviously to every existing population of the globe. But he will not allow the fact to be generalized into a law. He will not allow this—because the generalization suggests a cause which he denies, and shuts out another cause which he asserts. But this is not a legitimate reason for refusing to express phenomena in terms as wide and general as their actual occurrence. Never mind causes until we have clearly ascertained facts; but when these are clearly ascertained let us record them fearlessly in terms as wide as the truth demands. If there is not a single popula- tion on the globe which does not exhibit the fact of pressure more or less severe on the limits of their actual subsistence, let us at least recognize this fact in all its breadth and sweep. The diversities of laws and institu. THE PROPHET of SAN FRANCISCo. 15 tions, of habits and of manners, are almost infinite. Yet amid all these diversities this one fact is universal. Mr. George himself is the latest witness. He sees it to be a fact—a terrible and alarming fact, in his opinion— as applicable to the young and hopeful society of the New World. In a country where there is no monarch, no aristocracy, no ancient families, no entails of land, no standing armies worthy of the name, no pensions, no courtiers, where all are absolutely equal before the law, there, even there—in this paradise of Democracy, Mr. George tells us that the pressure of the masses upon the means of living and enjoyment which are open to them is becoming more and more severe, and that the inequal- ities of men are becoming as wide and glaring as in the oldest societies of Asia and of Europe. The contrast between this wonderful confirmation of Malthusian facts, and the vehement denunciation of Malthusian “law,” is surely one of the curiosities of literature. But the explanation is clear enough. Mr. George sees that facts common to so many nations must be due to some cause as common as the result. But, on the other hand, it would not suit his theory to admit that this cause can possibly be anything inherent in the con- stitution of Man, or in the natural System under which he lives. From this region, therefore, he steadily averts his face. There are a good many other facts in human nature and in human conditions that have this common and universal character. There are a number of such facts connected with the mind, another number con- nected with the body, and still another number connected with the opportunities of men. But all of these Mr. George passes over—in order that he may fix attention upon one solitary fact—namely, that in all nations in- dividual men, and individual communities of men, have 16 PROPERTY IN LAND. hitherto been allowed to acquire bits of land and to deal with them as their own. The distinction between Natural Law and Positive In- stitution is indeed a distinction not to be neglected. But it is one of the very deepest subjects in all philoso- phy, and there are many indications that Mr. George has dipped into its abysmal waters with the very shortest of Sounding lines. Human laws are evolved out of human instincts, and these are among the gifts of nature. Reason may pervert them, and Reason is all the more apt to do so when it begins to spin logical webs out of its own bowels. But it may be safely said that in direct proportion as human laws, and the accepted ideas on which they rest, are really universal, in that same pro- portion they have a claim to be regarded as really natural, and as the legitimate expression of fundamental truths. Sometimes the very men who set up as re- formers against such laws, and denounce as “ stupid '’” even the greatest nations which have abided by them, are themselves unconsciously subject to the same ideas, and are only working out of them some perverted appli- cation. For here, again, we come upon another wonderful circumstance affecting Mr. George's writings. I have spoken of Mr. George as a citizen of the United States, and also as a citizen of the particular State of California. In this latter capacity, as the citizen of a democratic government, he is a member of that government, which is the government of the whole people. Now, what is the most striking feature about the power claimed by that government, and actually exercised by it every day ? * This is the epithet applied by Mr. George to the English people, because they will persist in allowing what all other nations have equally allowed. THE PROPEIET OF SAN FRANCISCO. 17 It is the power of excluding the whole human race abso- lutely, except on its own conditions, from a large portion of the earth’s surface—a portion so large that it embraces no less than ninety-nine millions of acres, or 156,000 square miles of plain and valley, of mountain and of hill, of lake and river, and of estuaries of the sea. Yet the community which claims and exercises this exclusive ownership over this enormous territory is, as compared with its extent, a mere handful of men. The whole population of the State of California represents only the fractional number of 5.5 to the square mile. It is less than one quarter of the population of London. If the whole of it could be collected into one place they would hardly make a black spot in the enormous landscape if it were swept by a telescope. Such is the little company of men which claims to own absolutely and exclusively this enormous territory. Yet it is a member of this community who goes about the world preaching the doctrine, as a doctrine of Divine right, that land is to be as free as the atmosphere, which is the common property of all, and in which no exclusive ownership can be claimed by any. It is true that Mr. George does denounce the conduct of his own Government in the matter of its disposal of land. But strange to say, he does not denounce it because it claims this exclusive ownership. On the contrary, he denounces it because it ever consents to part with it. Not the land only, but the very atmosphere of California—to use his own phraseology—is to be held so absolutely and so ex- clusively as the property of this community, that it is never to be parted with except on lease and for such annual rent as the government may determine. Who gave this exclusive ownership over this immense terri- tory to this particular community ? Was it conquest ? 18 pIRO PERTY IN LANI). And if so, may it not be as rightfully acquired by any who are strong enough to seize it ! And if exclusive ownership is conferred by conquest, then has it not been open to every conquering army, and to every occupying host in all ages and in all countries of the world, to establish a similar ownership, and to deal with it as they please ? It is at this point that we catch sight of one aspect of Mr. George's theory in which it is capable of at least a rational explanation. The question how a comparatively small community of men like the first gold-diggers of California and their descendants can with best advantage use or employ its exclusive claims of ownership over so vast an area, is clearly quite an open question. It is one thing for any given political society to refuse to divide its vacant territory among individual owners. It is quite another thing for a political society, which for ages has recognized such ownership and encouraged it, to break faith with those who have acquired such ownership and have lived and labored, and bought and sold, and willed upon the faith of it. If Mr. George can persuade the State of which he is a citizen, and the Government of which he is in this sense a member, that it would be best never any more to sell any bit of its unoccupied territory to any individual, by all means let him try to do so, and some plausible arguments might be used in favor of such a course. But there is a strong presump- tion against it and him. The question of the best method of disposing of such territory has been before every one of our great colonies, and before the United States for several generations; and the universal instinct of them all has been that the individual ownership of iand is the one great attraction which they can hold out to the settlers whom it is their highest interest to invite THE PROPHET OF SAN FRANCISCO. 19 and to establish. They know that the land of a country is never so well “nationalized '' as when it is committed to the ownership of men whose interest it is to make the most of it. They know that under no other inducement could men be found to clear the soil from stifling forests, or to water it from arid wastes, or to drain it from pestilen- tial swamps, or to enclose it from the access of wild animals, or to defend it from the assaults of Savage tribes. Accordingly their verdict has been unanimous ; and it has been given under conditions in which they were free from all traditions except those which they carried with them as parts of their own nature, in har- mony and correspondence with the nature of things around them. I do not stop to argue this question here ; but I do stop to point out that both solutions of it—the One quite as much as the other—involve the exclusive occupation of land by individuals, and the doctrine of absolute ownership vested in particular communities, as against all the rest of mankind. Both are equally in- compatible with the fustian which compares the exclusive occupation of land to exclusive occupation of the atmos- phere. Supposing that settlers could be found willing to devote the years of labor and of skill which are neces- sary to make wild soils productive, under no other tenure than that of a long “improvement lease,” pay- ing of course for some long period either no rent at all, or else a rent which must be purely nominal ; supposing this to be true, still equally the whole area of any given region would soon be in the exclusive possession for long periods of time of a certain number of individual farmers, and would not be open to the occupation by the poor of all the world. Thus the absolute ownership which Mr. George declares to be blasphemous against God and Nature, is still asserted on behalf of some mere 20 FROPERTY IN LAND. fraction of the human race, and this absolute ownership is again doled out to the members of this small com- munity, and to them alone, in such shares as it considers to be most remunerative to itself. And here again, for the third time, we come upon a most remarkable testimony to facts in Mr. George's book, the import and bearing of which he does not ap- parently perceive. Of course the question whether it is most advantageous to any given society of men to own and cultivate its own lands in severalty or in common, is a question largely depending on the conduct and the motives and the character of governments, as compared with the conduct and the character and the motives of individual men. In the disposal and application of wealth, as well as in the acquisition of it, are men more pure and honest when they act in public capacities as members of a Government or of a Legislature, than when they act in private capacities toward their fellow- men 2 Is it not notoriously the reverse ? Is it not obvious that men will do, and are constantly seen doing, as politicians, what they would be ashamed to do in private life 2 And has not this been proved under all the forms which government has taken in the history of political societies 2 Lastly, I will ask one other question —Is it not true that, to say the very least, this inherent tendency to corruption has received no check from the democratic constitutions of those many “new worlds” in which kings were left behind, and aristocracies have not had time to be established ? These are the very questions which Mr. George answers with no faltering voice ; and it is impossible to disregard his evidence. He declares over and over again, in language of virtuous indignation, that govern- ment in the United States is everywhere becoming more THE PROPEIET OF SAN FRANCISCO. 21 and more corrupt. Not only are the Legislatures cor- rupt, but that last refuge of virtue even in the worst societies—the Judiciary—is corrupt also. In none of the old countries of the world has the very name of politician fallen so low as in the democratic communities of America. Nor would it be true to say that it is the wealthy classes who have corrupted the constituencies. These—at least to a very large extent—are themselves corrupt. Probably there is no sample of the Demos more infected with corruption than the Demos of New York. Its management of the municipal rates is alleged to be a system of scandalous jobbery. Now, the won- derful thing is that of all this Mr. George is thoroughly aware. He sees it, he repeats it in every variety of form. Let us hear a single passage : * It behooves us to look facts in the face. The experiment of popu- lar government in the United States is clearly a failure. Not that it is a failure everywhere and in everything. An experiment of this kind does not have to be fully worked out to be proved a failure. But, speaking generally of the whole country, from the Atlantic to the Pacific, and from the Lakes to the Gulf, our government by the people has in large degree become, is in larger degree becoming, government by the strong and unscrupulous. Again, I say that it is fair to remember that Mr. George is a Pessimist. But while remembering this, and making every possible allowance for it, we must not less remem- ber that his evidence does not stand alone. In the United States, from citizens still proud of their country, and out of the United States, from representative Americans, I have been told of transactions from per- sonal knowledge which conclusively indicated a condition of things closely corresponding to the indictment of Mr. George. At all events we cannot be wrong in our con- * “Social Problems,” p. 22. 22 PROPERTY IN LAND. clusion that it is not among the public bodies and Governments of the States of America that we are to look in that country for the best exhibitions of purity or of virtue. Yet it is to these bodies—legislative, administrative, and judicial, of which he gives us such an account—that Mr. George would confine the rights of absolute owner- ship in the soil. It is these bodies that he would consti- tute the sole and universal landlord, and it is to them he would confide the duty of assessing and of spending the rents of everybody all over the area of every State. He tells us that a great revenue, fit for the support of some such great rulers as have been common in the Old World, could be afforded out of one half the “waste and stealages” of such Municipalities as his own at San Fran- cisco. What would be the “waste and stealages” of a governing body having at its disposal the whole agricult- ural and mining wealth of such States as California and Texas, of Illinois and Colorado & But this is not all. The testimony which is borne by Mr. George as to what the governing bodies of America now are is as nothing to the testimony of his own writ- ings as to what they would be —if they were ever to adopt his system, and if they were ever to listen to his teaching. Like all Communists, he regards Society not as consisting of individuals whose separate welfare is to be the basis of the welfare of the whole, but as a great abstract Personality, in which all power is to be centred, and to which all separate rights and interests are to be subordinate. If this is to be the doctrine, we might at least have hoped that with such powers committed to Governments, as against the individual, corresponding duties and responsibilities, toward the individual, would have been recognized as an indispensable accompani- THE PROPHET OF SAN FRANCISCO. 23 ment. If, for example, every political society as a whole is an abiding Personality, with a continuity of rights over all its members, we might at least have ex- pected that the continuous obligation of honor and good faith would have been recognized as equally binding on this Personality in all its relations with those who are subject to its rule. But this is not at all Mr. George's view. On the contrary, he preaches systematically not only the high privilege, but the positive duty of re- pudiation. He is not content with urging that no more bits of unoccupied land should be ever sold, but he in- sists upon it that the ownership of every bit already sold shall be resumed without compensation to the settler who has bought it, who has spent upon it years of labor, and who from first to last has relied on the security of the State and on the honor of its Government. There is no mere practice of corruption which has ever been alleged against the worst administrative body in any country that can be compared in corruption with the desolating dishonor of this teaching. In olden times, under violent and rapacious rulers, the Prophets of Israel and of Judah used to raise their voices against all forms of wrong and robbery, and they pronounced a special benediction upon him who sweareth to his own hurt and changeth not. But the new Prophet of San Francisco is of a different opinion. Ahab would have been saved all his trouble, and Jezebel would have been saved all her tortuous in- trigues if only they could have had beside them the voice of Mr. Henry George. Elijah was a fool. What right could Naboth have to talk about the “inheritance of his fathers” . * His fathers could have no more right to acquire the ownership of those acres on the Hill of * 1 Kings 21 ; 3. 24 PROPERTY IN LAND. Jezreel than he could have to continue in the usurpation of it. No matter what might be his pretended title, no man and no body of men could give it :—not Joshua nor the Judges; not Saul nor David ; not Solomon in all his glory—could “make sure” to Naboth’s fathers that portion of God’s earth against the undying claims of the head of the State, and of the representative of the whole people of Israel. - But now another vista of consequence opens up before us. If the doctrine be established that no faith is to be kept with the owners of land, will the same principle not apply to tenancy as well as ownership ! If one genera- tion cannot bind the next to recognize a purchase, can one generation bind another to recognize a lease ? If the one promise can be broken and ought to be broken, why should the other be admitted to be binding 2 If the accumulated value arising out of many years, or even generations, of labor, can be and ought to be appro- priated, is there any just impediment against seizing that value every year as it comes to be 2 If this new gospel be indeed gospel, why should not this Californian form of “faith unfaithful ?” keep us perennially, and forever “falsely true” 2 Nay, more, is there any reason why the doctrine of repudiation should be confined to pledges respecting either the tenancy or the ownership of land Ž This question maturally arose in the minds of all who read with any intelligence “Progress and Poverty” when it first appeared. But the extent to which its immoral doctrines might be applied was then a matter of infer- ence only, however clear that inference might be. If all owners of land, great and small, might be robbed, and ought to be robbed of that which Society had from time immemorial allowed them and encouraged them to ac- THE PROPEIET OF SAN FRANCISCO. 25 quire and to call their own ; if the thousands of men, women, and children who directly and indirectly live on rent, whether in the form of returns to the improver, or of mortgage to the capitalist, or jointure to the widow, or portion to the children, are all equally to be ruined by the confiscation of the fund on which they depend—are there not other funds which would be all swept into the same net of envy and of violence 2 In particular, what is to become of that great fund on which also thousands and thousands depend—men, women, and children, the aged, the widow, and the orphan—the fund which the State has borrowed and which constitutes the Debt of Nations ? Even in “Progress and Poverty” there were dark hints and individual passages which indicated the goal of all its reasoning in this direction. But men’s intellects just now are so flabby on these subjects, and they are so fond of shaking their heads when property in land is compared with property in other things, that such suspicions and forebodings as to the issue of Mr. George's arguments would to many have seemed over- strained. Fortunately, in his later book he has had the courage of his opinions, and the logic of false premises has steeled his moral sense against the iniquity of even the most dishonorable conclusions. All National Debts are as unjust as property in land ; all such Debts are to be treated with the sponge. As no faith is due to land- owners, or to any who depend on their sources of in- come, so neither is any faith to be kept with bond- holders, or with any who depend on the revenues which have been pledged to them. The Jew who may have lent a million, and the small tradesman who may have lent his little savings to the State—the trust-funds of children and of widows which have been similarly lent— are all equally to be the victims of repudiation. When 26 PROPERTY IN LAND. we remember the enormous amount of the national debts of Europe and of the American States, and the vast number of persons of all kinds and degrees of wealth whose property is invested in these “promises to pay,” we can perhaps faintly imagine the ruin which would be caused by the gigantic fraud recommended by Mr. George. Take England alone. About seven hundred and fifty millions is the amount of her Public Debt. This great sum is held by about 181,721 persons, of whom the immense majority—about 111,000—receive dividends amounting to 400l. a year and under. Of these, again, by far the greater part enjoy incomes of less than 100l. a year. And then the same principle is of course applicable to the debt of all public bodies; those of the Municipalities alone which are rapidly in- creasing, would now amount to something like 150 millions more. Everything in America is on a gigantic scale, even its forms of villainy, and the villainy advocated by Mr. George is an illustration of this as striking as the Mam- moth Caves of Kentucky, or the frauds of the celebrated “Tammany Ring” in New York. The world has never seen such a Preacher of Unrighteousness as Mr. Henry George. For he goes to the roots of things, and shows us how unfounded are the rules of probity, and what mere senseless superstitions are the obligations which have been only too long acknowledged. Let us hear him on National Debts, for it is an excellent speci- men of his childish logic, and of his profligate con- clusions: The institution of public debts, like the institution of private prop- erty in land, rests upon the preposterous assumption that one gen- eration may bind another generation. If a man were to come to me and say, “Here is a promissory note which your great-grandfather THE PROPHET OF SAN FRANCISCO. 27 gave to my great-grandfather, and which you will oblige me by pay- ing,” I would laugh at him and tell him that if he wanted to collect his note he had better hunt up the man who made it : that I had nothing to do with my great-grandfather's promises. And if he were to insist upon payment, and to call my attention to the terms of the bond in which my great-grandfather expressly stip- ulated with his great-grandfather that I should pay him, I would only laugh the more, and be more certain that he was a lunatic. To such a demand any one of us would reply in effect, “My great-grandfather was evidently a knave or a joker, and your great-grandfather was cer- tainly a fool, which quality you surely have inherited if you expect me to pay you money because my great-grandfather promised that I should do so. He might as well have given your great-grandfather a draft upon Adam, or a check upon the First National Bank of the Moon.” - Yet upon this assumption that ascendants may bind descendants, that one generation may legislate for another generation, rests the assumed validity of our land titles and public debts.” Yet even in this wonderful passage we have not touched the bottom of Mr. George's lessons in the phil- Osophy of spoliation. If we may take the property of those who have trusted to our honor, surely it must be still more legitimate to take the property of those who have placed in us no such confidence. If we may fleece the public creditor, it must be at least equally open to us to fleece all those who have invested otherwise their private fortunes. All the other accumulations of in- dustry must be as rightfully liable to confiscation. Whenever “the people” see any large handful in the hands of any one, they have a right to have it—in order to save themselves from any necessity of submitting to taxation. Accordingly we find, as usual, that Mr. George has a wonderful honesty in avowing what hitherto the unin- structed world has been agreed upon considering as dis- * “Social Problems,” pp. 213-14, 28 PROPERTY IN LAND. honesty. But this time the avowal comes out under circumstances which are deserving of special notice. We all know that not many years ago the United States was engaged in a civil war of long duration, at one time apparently of doubtful issue, and on which the national existence hung. I was one of those—not too many in this country—who held from the beginning of that terrible contest that “ the North’’ were right in fighting it. Lord Russell, on a celebrated occasion, said that they were fighting for “dominion.” Yes’; and for what else have nations ever fought, and by what else than dominion, in one sense or another—have great nations ever come to be 3 The Demos has no greater right to fight for dominion than Kings; but it has the same. But behind and above the existence of the Union as a nation there was the further question involved whether, in this nineteenth century of the Christian era, there was to be established a great dominion of civilized men which was to have negro slavery as its fundamental doctrine and as the cherished basis of its constitution. On both of these great questions the people of the Northern States—in whatever proportions the one or the other issue might affect individual minds—had before them as noble a cause as any which has ever called men to arms. It is a cause which will be forever associated in the memory of mankind with one great figure—the figure of Abraham Lincoln, the best and highest repre- sentative of the American people in that tremendous crisis. In nothing has the bearing of that people been more admirable than in the patient and willing submis- sion of the masses, as of one man, not only to the deso- lating sacrifice of life which it entailed, but to the heavy and lasting burden of taxation which was inseparable from it. It is indeed deplorable—nothing I have ever THE PROPHET OF SAN FRANCISCO. 29 read in all literature has struck me as so deplorable—than that at this time of day, when by patient continuance in well-doing the burden has become comparatively light, and there is a near prospect of its final disappearance, one single American citizen should be found who appre- ciates so little the glory of his country as to express his regret that they did not begin this great contest by an act of stealing. Yet this is the case with Mr. Henry George. In strict pursuance of his dishonest doctrines of repudiation respecting public debts, and knowing that the war could not have been prosecuted without funds, he speaks with absolute bitterness of the folly which led the Government to “shrink” from at once seizing the whole, or all but a mere fraction, of the property of the few individual citizens who had the reputation of being exceptionally rich. If, for example, it were known that any man had made a fortune of 200,000l., the Washing- ton Government ought not to have “shrunk” from tak- ing the whole—except some 200l., which remainder might, perhaps, by a great favor, be left for such sup- port as it might afford to the former owner. And so by a number of seizures of this kind, all over the States, the war might possibly have been conducted for the benefit of all at the cost of a very few.” It may be worth while to illustrate how this would have worked in a single instance. When I was in New York, a few years ago, one of the sights which was pointed out to me was a house of great size and of great beauty both in respect to material and to workmanship. In these respects at least, if not in its architecture, it * Mr. George's words are these : “If, when we called on men to die for their country, we had not shrunk from taking, if necessary, nine hundred and ninety-nine thousand dollars from every millionaire, We need not have created any debt.”—“Social Problems,” p. 216. 30 PROPERTY IN LAND. was equal to any of the palaces which are owned by private citizens in any of the richest capitals of the Old World. It was built wholly of pure white marble, and the owner, not having been satisfied with any of the marbles of America, had gone to the expense of import- ing Italian marble for the building. This beautiful and costly house was, I was further told, the property of a Scotchman who had emigrated to America with no other fortune and no other capital than his own good brains. He had begun by selling ribbons. By selling cheap, and for ready money, but always also goods of the best quality, he had soon acquired a reputation for dealings which were eminently advantageous to those who bought. But those who bought were the public, and so a larger and a larger portion of the public became eager to secure the advantages of this exceptionally moderate and honest dealer. With the industry of his race he had also its thrift, and the constant turning of his capital on an ever-increasing scale, coupled with his own limited expenditure, had soon led to larger and larger savings. These, again, had been judiciously invested in promoting every public undertaking which promised advantage to his adopted country, and which, by fulfilling that promise, could alone become remunerative. And so by a process which, in every step of it, was an eminent Ser- vice to the community of which he was a member, he became what is called a millionaire. Nor in the spending of his wealth had he done otherwise than con- tribute to the taste and splendor of his country, as well as to the lucrative employment of its people. All Nature is full of the love of ornament, and the habita- tions of creatures, even the lowest in the scale of being, are rich in coloring and in carving of the most exquisite and elaborate decoration. It is only an ignorant and THE PROPHET OF SAN FRANCISCO. 31 uncultured spirit which denounces the same love of ornament in Man, and it is a stupid doctrine which sees in it nothing but a waste of means. The great mer. chant of New York had indeed built his house at great cost ; but this is only another form of saying that he had spent among the artificers of that city a great sum of money, and had in the same proportion contributed to the only employment by which they live. In every way, therefore, both as regards the getting and the spending of his wealth, this millionaire was an honor and a benefactor to his country. This is the man on whom that same country would have been incited by Mr. Henry George to turn the big eyes of brutal envy, and to rob of all his earnings. It is not so much the dishonesty or the violence of such teaching that strikes us most, but its unutterable meanness. That a great nation, having a great cause at stake, and representing in the history of the world a life-and-death struggle against barbarous institutions, ought to have begun its memorable war by plundering a few of its own citizens —this is surely the very lowest depth which has ever been reached by any political philosophy. And not less instructive than the results of this phil- osophy are the methods of its reasoning, its methods of illustration, and its way of representing facts. Of these we cannot have a better example than the passage before quoted, in which Mr. Henry George explains the right of nations and the right of individuals to repudiate an hereditary debt. It is well to see that the man who defends the most dishonorable conduct on the part of Governments defends it equally on the part of private persons. The passage is a typical specimen of the kind of stuff of which Mr. George's works are full. The element of plausibility in it is the idea that a man should 32 PROPERTY IN LAND. not be held responsible for promises to which he was not himself a consenting party. This idea is presented by itself, with a careful suppression of the conditions which make it inapplicable to the case in hand. Hereditary debts do not attach to persons except in respect to hereditary possessions. Are these possessions to be kept while the corresponding obligations are to be denied ? Mr. George is loud on the absurdity of calling upon him to honor any promise which his great-grandfather may have made, but he is silent about giving up any re- Sources which his great-grandfather may have left. Possibly he might get out of this difficulty by avowing that he would allow no property to pass from one generation to another—not even from father to son— that upon every death all the savings of every individual should be confiscated by the State. Such a proposal would not be one whit more violent, or more destructive to society, than other proposals which he does avow. But so far as I have observed, this particular conse- quence of his reasoning is either not seen, or is kept in the dark. With all his apparent and occasional honesty in confronting results however anarchical, there is a good deal of evidence that he knows how to conceal his hand. The prominence given in his agitation to an attack on the particular class of capitalists who are owners of land, and the total or comparative silence which he maintains on his desire to rob fundholders of all kinds, and espe- cially the public creditor, is a clear indication of astrategy which is more dexterous than honest. And so it may really be true that he repudiates all hereditary debt be- cause he will also destroy all hereditary succession in Sav- ings of any kind. But it must be observed that even thus he cannot escape from the inconsistency I have pointed out, as it affects all public debts. These have THE PROPHIET OF SAN FRANCISCO. 33 all been contracted for the purpose of effecting great national objects, such as the preservation of national in- dependence, or the acquisition of national territory, or the preparations needed for national defence. The State cannot be disinherited of the benefits and possessions thus secured, as individuals may be disinherited of their fathers' gains. In the case of national debts, therefore, it is quite clear that the immorality of Mr. George's argument is as conspicuous as the childishness of its reasoning. But there are other examples, quite as striking, of the incredible absurdity of his reasoning, which are im- mediately connected with his dominant idea about prop- erty in land. Thus the notion that because all the natural and elementary substances which constitute the raw materials of human wealth are substances derived from the ground, therefore all forms of that wealth must ultimately tend to concentration in the hands of those who own the land ; this notion must strike a landowner as one worthy only of Bedlam. He may not be able at a moment’s notice to unravel all the fallacies on which it rests, and he may even be able to see in it the mad mimicry of logic which deceives the ignorant. But it does not need to be a landowner to see immediately that the conclusion is an absurdity. We have only to apply this notion in detail in order to see more and more clearly its discrepancy with fact. Thus, for example, we may put one application of it thus: All houses are built of materials derived from the soil, of stone, of lime, of brick, or of wood, or of all three combined. But of these materials three are not only products of the soil, but parts of its very substance and material. Clearly it must follow that the whole value of house property must end in passing into the hands of those 34 PROPERTY IN LAN i). who own these materials, quarries of building stone, beds of brick-earth, beds of lime, and forests. Unfortunately for landowners, this wonderful demonstration does not, Somehow, take effect. But Mr. Henry George's processes in matters of reasoning are not more absurd than his assumptions in matters of fact. The whole tone is based on the assumption that owners of land are not producers, and that rent does not represent, or represents only in a very minor degree the interest of capital. Even an American ought to know better than this ; because, although there are in some parts of the United States immense areas of prairie land which are ready for the plough with almost no preliminary labor, yet even in the New World the areas are still more immense in which the soil can only be made capable of producing human food by the hardest labor, and the most prolonged. But in the old countries of Europe, and especially in our own, every landowner knows well, and others ought to know a little, that the present condition of the soil is the result of generations of costly improvements, and of renewed and reiterated outlays to keep these improvements in effective order. Yet on this subject I fear that many persons are almost as ignorant as Mr. Henry George. My own experience now extends over a period of the best part of forty years. During that time I have built more than fifty home- steads complete for man and beast ; I have drained and reclaimed many hundreds, and enclosed some thousands, of acres. In this sense I have “added house to house and field to field,” not—as pulpit orators have assumed in similar cases—that I might “ dwell alone in the land,” but that the cultivating class might live more comfort- ably, and with better appliances for increasing the prod- Yuce of the soil. I know no more animating scene than THE PROPHET OF SAN FRANCISCO. 35 that presented to us in the essays and journals which give an account of the agricultural improvements effected in Scotland since the close of the Civil Wars in 1745. Thousands and thousands of acres have been re- claimed from bog and waste. Ignorance has given place to science, and barbarous customs of immemorial strength have been replaced by habits of intelligence and of business. In every county the great landowners, and very often the smaller, were the great pioneers in a proc- ess which has transformed the whole face of the coun- try. And this process is still in full career. If I men- tion again my own case, it is because I know it to be only a specimen, and that others have been working on a still larger scale. During the four years since Mr. George did me the honor of sending to me a book assuming that landowners are not producers, I find that I have spent on one property alone the sum of 40,000l. entirely on the improvement of the soil. Moreover, I know that this outlay on my own part, and similar out- lay on the part of my neighbors, so far from having power to absorb and concentrate in our hands all other forms of wealth, is unable to secure anything like the return which the same capital would have won—and won easily—in many other kinds of enterprise. I am in possession of authentic information that on one great estate in England the outlay on improvements purely agricultural, has, for twenty-one years past, been at the rate of 35,000l. a year, while including outlay on churches and schools, it has amounted in the last forty years to nearly 2,000,000l. sterling. To such outlays landowners are incited very often, and to a great extent, by the mere love of seeing a happier landscape and a more prosperous people. From much of the capital so invested they often seek no return at all, and from very 36 1PROPERTY IN LAND. little of it indeed do they ever get a high rate of interest. And yet the whole—every farthing of it—goes directly to the public advantage. Production is increased in full proportion, although the profit on that production is small to the owner. There has been grown more corn, more potatoes, more turnips; there has been produced more milk, more butter, more cheese, more beef, more mutton, more pork, more fowls, and eggs, and all these articles in direct proportion to their abundance have been sold at lower prices to the people. When a man tells me, and argues on steps of logic which he boasts as ir- refutable, that in all this, I and others have been serv- ing no interests but our own—nay, more, that we have been but making “ the poor poorer” than they were-I know very well that, whether I can unravel his fallacies or not, he is talking the most arrant nonsense, and must have in his composition, howeveringenious and however eloquent, a rich combination, and a very large percent- age of the fanatic and of the goose. And here, again, we have a new indication of these elements in one great assumption of fact, and that is the assumption that wealth has been becoming less and less diffused—“ the rich richer, the poor poorer.” It did not require the recent elaborate and able statistical examination of Mr. Giffen to convince me that this assumption is altogether false. It is impossible for any man to have been a considerable employer of labor dur- ing a period embracing one full generation, without his seeing and feeling abundant evidence that all classes have partaken in the progress of the country, and no class more extensively than that which lives by labor. He must know that wages have more than doubled—some- times a great deal more—while the continuous remission -ºf taxes has tended to make, and has actually made almost THE PROPHET OF SAN FRANCISCO. 37 every article of subsistence a great deal cheaper than it was thirty years ago. And outside the province of mere muscular labor, among all the classes who are concerned in the work of distribution or of manufacture, I have seen around me, and on my own property, the enormous increase of those whose incomes must be comfortable without being large. The houses that are built for their weeks of rest and leisure, the furniture with which these houses are provided, the gardens and shrubberies which are planted for the ornament of them ; all of these in- dications, and a thousand more, tell of increasing com- fort far more widely if not universally diffused. And if personal experience enables me to contradict absolutely one of Mr. George's assumptions, official ex- perience enables me not less certainly to contradict another. Personally I know what private ownership has done for one country. Officially I have had only too good cause to know what State ownership has not done for another country. India is a country in which, theoretically at least, the State is the only and the uni- versal landowner, and over a large part of it the State does actually take to itself a share of the gross produce which fully represents ordinary rent. Yet this is the very country in which the poverty of the masses is so abject that millions live only from hand to mouth, and when there is any—even a partial—failure of the crops, thousands and hundreds of thousands are in danger of actual starvation. The Indian Government is not cor- rupt—whatever other failings it may have—and the rents of a vast territory can be far more safe if left to its dis- posal than they could be left at the disposal of such popular governments as those which Mr. George has denounced on the American Continent. Yet somehow the functions and duties which in more civilized coun- 38 PROPERTY IN LAND. tries are discharged by the institution of private owner. ship in land are not as adequately discharged by the Ind- ian Administration. Moreover, I could not fail to observe, when I was connected with the Government of India, that the portion of that country which has most grown in wealth is precisely that part of it in which the Government has parted with its power of absorbing rent by having agreed to a Permanent Settlement. Many Anglo-Indian statesmen have looked with envious eyes at the wealth which has been developed in Lower Ben- gal, and have mourned over the policy by which the State has been withheld from taking it into the hands of Government. There are two questions, however, which have always occurred to me when this mourning has been expressed—the first is whether we are quite sure that the wealth of Lower Bengal would ever have arisen if its sources had not been thus protected ; and the second is whether even now it is quite certain that any Govern- ments, even the best, spend wealth better for the public interests than those to whom it belongs by the natural processes of acquisition. These questions have never, I think, been adequately considered. But whatever may be the true answer to either of them, there is at least one question on which all English statesmen have been unanimous—and that is, that promises once given by the Government, however long ago, must be absolutely kept. When landed property has been bought and sold and in- herited in Bengal for some three generations—since 1793 —under the guarantee of the Government that the Rent Tax upon it is to remain at a fixed amount, no public man, so far as I know, has ever suggested that the pub- lic faith should be violated. And not only so, but there has been a disposition even to put upon the engagement of the Government an overstrained interpretation, and to TH E PROPHET OF SAIN FRANCISCO. 39 claim for the landowners who are protected under it an immunity from all other taxes affecting the same sources of income. As Secretary of State for India. I had to deal with this question along with my colleagues in the Indian Council, and the result we arrived at was embodied in a despatch which laid down the principles applicable to the case so clearly that in India it appears to have been accepted as conclusive. The Land Tax was a special impost upon rent. The promise was that this special impost should never be increased ; or, in its own words, that there should be no “augmentation of the public assessment in consequence of the improve- ment of their estates.” It was not a promise that no other taxes should ever be raised affecting the same sources of income, provided such taxes were not special, but affected all other sources of income equally. On this interpretation the growing wealth of Bengal accruing under the Permanent Settlement would remain accessible to taxation along with the growing wealth derived from all other kinds of property, but not otherwise. There was to be no confiscation by the State of the increased value of land, any more than of the increased value of other kinds of property, on the pretext that this increase was unearned. On the other hand, the State did not exempt that increased value from any taxation which might be levied also and equally from all the rest of the community. In this way we reconciled and established two great principles which to shortsighted theorists may seem antagonistic. One of these principles is that it is the interest of every community to give equal and abso- lute security to every one of its members in his pursuit of wealth ; the other is that when the public interests demand a public revenue all forms of wealth should be equally accessible to taxation. 40 PROPERTY IN LAND. It would have saved us all, both in London and in Calcutta, much anxious and careful reasoning if we could only have persuaded ourselves that the Government of 1793 could not possibly bind the Government of 1870. It would have given us a still wider Inargin if we had been able to believe that no faith can be pledged to land- owners, and that we had a divine right to seize not only all the wealth of the Zemindars of Bengal, but also all the property derived from the same source which had grown up since i793, and has now become distributed and absorbed among a great number of intermediate sharers, standing between the actual cultivator and the represen- tatives of those to whom the promise was originally given. But one doctrine has been tenaciously held by the “stupid English people” in the government of their Eastern Empire, and that is, that our honor is the greatest of our possessions, and that absolute trust in that honor is one of the strongest foundations of our power. In this paper it has not been my aim to argue. A simple record and exposure of a few of the results arrived at by Mr. Henry George, has been all that I in- tended to accomplish. To see what are the practical consequences of any train of reasoning is so much gained. And there are cases in which this gain is every- thing. In mathematical reasoning the “reduction to absurdity” is one of the most familiar methods of dis- proof. In political reasoning the “reduction to iniquity” ought to be of equal value. And if it is not found to be so with all minds, this is because of a peculiarity in human character which is the secret of all its corruption, and of the most dreadful forms in which that corruption has been exhibited. In pursuing another investigation I have lately had occasion to THE PROPEIET OF SAN FRANCISCO. 41 observe upon the contrast which, in this respect, exists between our moral and our purely intellectual faculties.* Our Reason is so constituted in respect to certain funda- mental truths that those truths are intuitively perceived, and any rejection of them is at once seen to be absurd. But in the far higher sphere of Morals and Religion, it would seem that we have no equally secure moorings to duty and to truth. There is no consequence, however hideous or cruel its application may be, that men have been prevented from accepting because of such hideous- ness or of such cruelty. Nothing, however shocking, is quite sure to shock them. If it follows from some false belief, or from some fallacious verbal proposition, they will entertain it, and sometimes will even rejoice in it with a savage fanaticism. It is a fact that none of us should ever forget that the moral faculties of Man do not as certainly revolt against iniquity as his reasoning faculties do revolt against absurdity. All history is crowded with illustrations of this distinction, and it is the only explanation of a thousand horrors. There has seldom been such a curious example as the immoral teachings of Mr. Henry George. Here we have a man who probably sincerely thinks he is a Christian, and who sets up as a philosopher, but who is not the least shocked by consequences which abolish the Decalogue, and deny the primary obligations both of public and of private honor. This is a very curious phenomenon, and well deserving of some closer investigation. What are the erroneous data—what are the abstract propositions— which so overpower the Moral Sense, and coming from the sphere of Speculation dictate such flagitious recom- mendations in the sphere of Conduct ' To this question * “Unity of Nature,” chap. x. pp. 440–5. 42 - PROPERTY IN LAND. I may perhaps return, not with exclusive reference to the writings of one man, but with reference to the writ- ings of many others who have tried to reduce to scien- tific form the laws which govern the social developments of our race, and who in doing so have forgotten— strangely forgotten—some of the most fundamental facts of Nature. II. THE “REDUCTION TO INIQUITY.” BY HENRY GEORGE. “IN this paper it has not been my aim to argue,” says the Duke of Argyll, in concluding his article entitled “The Prophet of San Francisco.” It is gener- ally waste of time to reply to those who do not argue. Yet, partly because of my respect for other writings of his, and partly because of the ground to which he invites me, I take the first opportunity I have had to reply to the Duke. In doing so, let me explain the personal incident to which he refers, and which he has seemingly misunder- stood. In sending the Duke of Argyll a copy of “Prog- ress and Poverty,’” I intended no impertinence, and was unconscious of any impropriety. Instead, I paid him a high compliment. For, as I stated in an accom- panying note, I sent him my book not only to mark my esteem for the author of “The Reign of Law,” but be- cause I thought him a man superior to his accidents. I am still conscious of the profit I derived from “The Reign of Law,” and can still recall the pleasure it gave me. What attracted me, however, was not, as the Duke seems to think, what he styles his “nonsense chapter.” On the contrary, the notion that it is necessary to impose restrictions upon labor seems to me strangely incon- 44 PROPERTY IN LAND. gruous, not only with free trade, but with the idea of the dominance and harmony of natural laws, which in preceding chapters he so well develops. Where such restrictions as Factory Acts seem needed in the interests of labor, the seeming need, to my mind, arises from pre- vious restrictions, in the removal of which, and not in further restrictions, the true remedy is to be sought. What attracted me in “The Reign of Law” was the manner in which the Duke points out the existence of physical laws and adaptations which compel the mind that thinks upon them to the recognition of creative pur- pose. In this way the Duke's book was to me useful and grateful, as I doubt not it has been to many others. My book, I thought, might, in return, be useful and grateful to the Duke—might give him something of that “immense and instinctive pleasure” of which he had spoken as arising from the recognition of the grand sim- plicity and unspeakable harmony of universal law. And in the domain in which I had, as I believed, done some- thing to point out the reign of law this pleasure is per- haps even more intense than in that of which he had written. For in physical laws we recognize only intelli- gence, and can but trust that infinite wisdom implies in- finite goodness. But in social laws he who looks may recognize beneficence as well as intelligence ; may see that the moral perceptions of men are perceptions of realities; and find ground for an abiding faith that this short life does not bound the destiny of the human soul. I knew the Duke of Argyll then only by his book. I had never been in Scotland, or learned the character as a landlord he bears there. I intended to pay a tribute and give a pleasure to a citizen of the republic of letters, not to irritate a landowner. I did not think a trumpery title and a patch of ground could fetter a mind that had THE ‘‘ REDUCTION TO INIQUITY.” 45 communed with Nature and busied itself with causes and beginnings. My mistake was that of ignorance. Since the Duke of Argyll has publicly called attention to it, I thus publicly apologize. - The Duke declares it has not been his aim to argue. This is clear. I wish it were as clear it had not been his aim to misrepresent. He seems to have written for those who have never read the books he criticises. But as those who have done so constitute a very respectable part of the reading world, I can leave his misrepresenta- tions to take care of themselves, confident that the in- credible absurdity he attributes to my reasonings will be seen, by whoever reads my books, to belong really to the Duke's distortions. In what I have here to say I prefer to meet him upon his own ground and to hold to the main question.* I accept the reduction to iniquity. Strangely enough, the Duke expresses distrust of the very tribunal to which he appeals. “It is a fact,” he tells us, “that none of us should ever forget, that the moral faculties do not as certainly revolt against iniquity as the reasoning faculties do against absurdity.” If that be the case, why, then, may I ask, is the Duke’s whole article addressed to the moral faculties 2 Why does he talk about right and wrong, about justice and injustice, about honor and dishonor ; about my “immoral doc- trines” and “profligate conclusions,” “the unutterable meanness of the gigantic villainy” I advocate 2 why style me “such a Preacher of Unrighteousness as the world has never seen,” and so on ? If the Duke will permit * It is unnecessary for me to say anything of India further than to remark that the essence of nationalization of land is not in the col- lection of rent by government, but in its utilization for the benefit of the people. Nor on the subject of public debts is it worth while here to add anything to what I have said ir “Social Problems.” 46 12ROPERTY IN LAND. me I will tell him, for in all probability he does not know —he himself, to paraphrase his own words, being a good example of how men who sometimes set up as philoso- phers and deny laws of the human mind are themselves unconsciously subject to those very laws. The Duke appeals to moral perceptions for the same reason that impels all men, good or bad, learned or simple, to appeal to moral perceptions whenever they become warm in argument ; and this reason is, the instinctive feeling that the moral sense is higher and truer than the intellectual sense ; that the moral faculties do more certainly revolt against iniquity than the intellectual faculties against absurdity. The Duke appeals to the moral sense, be- cause he instinctively feels that with all men its decisions have the highest sanction ; and if he afterward seeks to weaken its authority, it is because this very moral sense whispers to him that his case is not a good one. My opinion as to the relative superiority of the moral and intellectual perceptions is the reverse of that stated by the Duke. It seems to me certain that the moral faculties constitute a truer guide than the intellectual faculties, and that what, in reality, we should never for- get, is not that the moral faculties are untrustworthy, but that those faculties may be dulled by refusal to heed them, and distorted by the promptings of selfishness. So true, so ineradicable is the moral sense, that where selfishness or passion would outrage it, the intellectual faculties are always called upon to supply excuse. No unjust war was ever begun without some pretence of asserting right or redressing wrong, or, despite them- selves, of doing some good to the conquered. No petty thief but makes for himself some justification. It is doubtful if any deliberate wrong is ever committed, it is certain no wrongful course of action is ever continued, THE “ REDUCTION TO INIQUITY.” 4? without the framing of some theory which may dull or placate the moral sense. And while as to things apprehended solely by the in- tellectual faculties the greatest diversities of perception have obtained and still obtain among men, and those perceptions constantly change with the growth of knowl- edge, there is a striking consensus of moral perceptions. In all stages of social development, and under all forms of religion, no matter how distorted by selfish motives and intellectual perversions, truth, justice, and benevo- lence have ever been esteemed, and all our intellectual progress has given us no higher moral ideals than have obtained among primitive peoples. The very distortions of the moral sense, the apparent differences in the moral standards of different times and peoples, do but show essential unity. Wherever moral perceptions have differed or do differ the disturbance may be traced to causes which, originating in selfishness and perpetuated by intellectual perversions, have distorted or dulled the moral faculty. It seems to me that the Creator, whom both the Duke of Argyll and myself recognize behind physical and mental laws, has not left us to grope our way in darkness, but has, indeed, given us a light by which our steps may be safely guided—a compass by which, in all degrees of intellectual development, the way to the highest good may be surely traced. But just as the compass by which the mariner steers his course over the trackless sea in the blackest night, may be dis- turbed by other attractions, may be misread or clogged, so is it with the moral sense. This evidently is not a world in which men must be either wise or good, but a world in which they may bring about good or evil as they use the faculties given them. I speak of this because the recognition of the suprem. 48 PROPERTY IN LAND. acy and certainty of the moral faculties seems to me to throw light upon problems otherwise dark, rather than because it is necessary here, since I admit even more unreservedly than the Duke the competence of the tribunal before which he cites me. I am willing to sub- mit every question of political economy to the test of ethics. So far as I can see there is no social law which does not conform to moral law, and no social question which cannot be determined more quickly and certainly by appeal to moral perceptions than by appeal to intel- lectual perceptions. Nor can there be any dispute be- tween us as to the issue to be joined. He charges me with advocating violation of the moral law in proposing robbery. I agree that robbery is a violation of the moral law, and is therefore, without further inquiry, to be condemned. As to what constitutes robbery, it is, we will both agree, the taking or withholding from another of that which rightfully belongs to him. That which rightfully belongs to him, be it observed, not that which legally belongs to him. As to what extent human law may create rights is beside this discussion, for what I propose is to change, not to violate human law. Such change the Duke declares would be unrighteous. He thus ap- peals to that moral law which is before and above all human laws, and by which all human laws are to be judged. Let me insist upon this point. Landholders must elect to try their case either by human law or by moral law. If they say that land is rightfully property because made so by human law, they cannot charge those who would change that law with advocating rob- bery. But if they charge that such change in human law would be robbery, then they must show that land is rightfully property irrespective of human law. THE “ REDUCTION TO INIQUITY.” 49 For land is not of that species of things to which the presumption of rightful property attaches. This does attach to things that are properly termed wealth, and that are the produce of labor. Such things, in their be- ginning must have an owner, as they originate in human exertion, and the right of property which attaches to them springs from the manifest natural right of every individual to himself and to the benefit of his own ex- ertions. This is the moral basis of property, which makes certain things rightfully property totally irre- spective of human law. The Eighth Commandment does not derive its validity from human enactment. It is written upon the facts of nature and self-evident to the perceptions of men. If there were but two men in the world, the fish which either of them took from the sea, the beast which he captured in the chase, the fruit which he gathered, or the hut which he erected, would be his rightful property, which the other could not take from him without violation of the moral law. But how could either of them claim the world as his rightful property ? Or if they agreed to divide the world be- tween them, what moral right could their compact give as against the next man who came into the world ! It is needless, however, to insist that property in land rests only on human enactment, which may, at any time be changed without violation of moral law. No one Seriously asserts any other derivation. It is sometimes said that property in land is derived from appropriation. But those who say this do not really mean it. Appro- priation can give no right. The man who raises a cup- ful of water from a river, acquires a right to that cupful, and no one may rightfully snatch it from his hand ; but this right is derived from labor, not from appropriation. How could he acquire a right to the river, by merely 50 12.ROPERTY IN TAND. appropriating it ! Columbus did not dream of appro- priating the New World to himself and his heirs, and would have been deemed a lunatic had he done so. Nations and princes divided America between them, but by “right of strength.” This, and this alone, it is that gives any validity to appropriation. And this, evidently, is what they really mean who talk of the right given by appropriation. This “right of conquest,” this power of the strong, is the only basis of property in land to which the Duke ventures to refer. He does so in asking whether the exclusive right of ownership to the territory of Cali- fornia, which, according to him, I attribute to the exist- ing people of California, does not rest upon conquest, and “if so, may it not be as rightfully acquired by any who are strong enough to seize it 7” To this I reply in the affirmative. If exclusive ownership is conferred by conquest, then, not merely, as the Duke says, has it “been open to every conquering army and every oc- cupying host in all ages and in all countries of the world to establish a similar ownership ;” but it is now open, and whenever the masses of Scotland, who have the power, choose to take from the Duke the estates he now holds, he cannot, if this be the basis of his claim, con- sistently complain. But I have never admitted that conquest or any other exertion of force can give right. Nor have I ever asserted, but on the contrary have expressly denied, that the present population of California, or any other coun- try, have any exclusive right of ownership in the soil, or can in any way acquire such a right. I hold that the present, the past, or the future population of California, or of any other country, have not, have not had, and cannot have, any right save to the use of the soil, and THE “REDUCTION TO INIQUITY.” 51 that as to this their rights are equal. I hold with Thomas Jefferson, that “the earth belongs in usufruct to the living, and that the dead have no power or right over it.” I hold that the land was not created for One generation to dispose of, but as a dwelling-place for all generations; that the men of the present are not bound by any grants of land the men of the past may have made, and cannot grant away the rights of the men of the future. I hold that if all the people of California, or any other country, were to unite in any disposition of the land which ignored the equal right of one of their number, they would be doing a wrong ; and that even if they could grant away their own rights, they are powerless to impair the natural rights of their children. And it is for this reason that I hold that the titles to the ownership of land which the Government of the United States is now granting are of no greater moral validity than the land-titles of the British Isles, which rest his- torically upon the forcible spoliation of the masses. How ownership of land was acquired in the past can have no bearing upon the question of how we should treat land now ; yet the inquiry is interesting, as show- ing the nature of the institution. The Duke of Argyll has written a great deal about the rights of landowners, but has never, I think, told us anything of the historical derivation of these rights. He has spoken of his own estates, but has nowhere told us how they came to be his estates. This, I know, is a delicate question, and on that account I will not press it. But while a man ought not to be taunted with the sins of his ancestors, neither ought he to profit by them. And the general fact is, that the exclusive ownership of land has everywhere had its beginnings in force and fraud, in selfish greed and unscrupulous cunning. It Originated, as all evil institu. 52 TROPERTY IN LAND. tions originate, in the bad passions of man, not in their perceptions of what is right or their experience of what is wise. “ Human laws,” the Duke tells us, “are evolved out of human instincts, and in direct proportion as the accepted ideas on which they rest are really universal, in that same proportion have they a claim to be regarded as really natural, and as the legitimate ex- pression of fundamental truths.” If he would thus found on the widespread existence of exclusive property in land an argument for its righteousness, what, may I ask him, will he say to the much stronger argument that might thus be made for the righteousness of polygamy or chattel slavery But it is a fact, of which I need hardly more than remind him, though less well-informed people may be ignorant of it, that the treatment of land as individual property is comparatively recent, and by at least nine hundred and ninety-nine out of every thousand of those who have lived on this world, has never been dreamed of. It is only within the last two centuries that it has, by the abolition of feudal tenures, and the suppression of tribal customs, fully obtained among our own people. In fact, even among us it has hardly yet reached full development. For not only are we still spreading over land yet unreduced to individual owner- ship, but in the fragments of common rights which yet remain in Great Britain, as well as in laws and customs, are there survivals of the older system. The first and universal perception of mankind is that declared by the American Indian Chief, Black Hawk: “The Great Spirit has told me that land is not to be made property like other property. The earth is our mother l’’ And this primitive perception of the right of all men to the use of the soil from which all must live, has never been obscured save by a long course of usurpation and oppression. THE “ REDUCTION TO INIQUITY.” 53 But it is needless for me to discuss such questions with the Duke. There is higher ground on which we may meet. He believes in an intelligent Creator ; he sees in Nature contrivance and intent ; he realizes that it is only by conforming his actions to universal law that man can master his conditions and fulfil his destiny. Let me, then, ask the Duke to look around him in the richest country of the world, where art, science, and the power that comes from the utilization of physical laws have been carried to the highest point yet attained, and note how few of this population can avail themselves fully of the advantages of civilization. Among the masses the struggle for existence is so intense that the Duke himself declares it necessary by law to restrain parents from working their children to disease and death ! Let him consider the conditions of life involved in such facts as this—conditions, alas, obvious on every side, and then ask himself whether this is in accordance with the intent of Nature ? The Duke of Argyll has explained to me in his “Reign of Law” with what nice adaptations the feathers on a bird’s wing are designed to give it the power of flight : he has told me that the claw on the wing of a bat is intended for it to climb by. Will he let me ask him to look in the same way at the human beings around him 8 Consider, O Duke the little children growing up in city slums, toiling in mines, working in noisome rooms; the young girls chained to machinery all day or walking the streets by night ; the women bending over forges in the Black Country or turned into beasts of burden in the Scottish Highlands; the men who all life long must spend life's energies in the effort to maintain life Consider them as you have considered the bat and 54 PROPERTY IN LAND. the bird. If the hook of the bat be intended to climb by and the wing of the bird be intended to fly by, with what intent have human creatures been given capabilities of body and mind which under conditions that exist in such countries as Great Britain only a few of them can use and enjoy 7 They who see in Nature no evidences of conscious, planning intelligence may think that all this is as it must be ; but who that recognizes in His works an infinitely wise Creator can for a moment hesitate to infer that the wide difference between obvious intent and actual ac- complishment is due, not to the clash of natural laws, but to our ignoring them 2 Nor need we go far to con- firm this inference. The moment we consider in the largest way what kind of an animal man is, we see in the most important of social adjustments a violation of Nature’s intent sufficient to account for want and misery and aborted development. Given a ship sent to sea with abundant provisions for all her company. What must happen if some of that company take possession of the provisions and deny to the rest any share ? Given a world so made and ordered that intelligent beings placed upon it may draw from its substance an abundant supply for all physical needs. Must there not be want and misery in such a world if some of those beings make its surface and substance their exclusive property and deny the right of the others to its use ? Here, as on any other world we can conceive of, two and two make four, and when all is taken from anything nothing remains. What we see clearly would happen on any other world, does happen on this. The Duke sees intent in Nature. So do I. That which conforms to this intent is natural, wise, and THE “REDUCTION TO INIQUITY.” 55 righteous. That which contravenes it is unnatural, foolish, and iniquitous. In this we agree. Let us then bring to this test the institution which I arraign and he defends. Place, stripped of clothes, a landowner's baby among a dozen workhouse babies, and who that you call in can tell the one from the others ? Is the human law which declares the one born to the possession of a hundred thousand acres of land, while the others have no right to a single square inch, conformable to the intent of Nature or not ? Is it, judged by this appeal, natural or un- natural, wise or foolish, righteous or iniquitous ! Put the bodies of a duke and a peasant on a dissecting table, and bring, if you can, the surgeon who, by laying bare the brain or examining the viscera, can tell which is duke and which is peasant 4 Are not both land animals of the same kind, with like organs and like needs Is it not evidently the intent of Nature that both shall live on land and use land in the same way and to the same degree ? Is there not, therefore, a violation of the in- tent of Nature in human laws which give to one more land than he can possibly use, and deny any land to the other ? Let me ask the Duke to consider, from the point of view of an observer of Nature, a landless man—a being fitted in all his parts and powers for the use of land, compelled by all his needs to the use of land, and yet denied all right to land. Is he not as unnatural as a bird without air, a fish without water And can anything more clearly violate the intent of Nature than the human laws which produce such anomalies : I call upon the Duke to observe that what Nature teaches us is not merely that men were equally intended to live on land, and to use land, and therefore had §6 PROPERTY IN LAND. originally equal rights to land, but that they are now equally intended to live on and use land, and, therefore, that present rights to land are equal. It is said that fish deprived of light will, in the course of generations, lose their eyes, and, within certain narrow limits, it is certain that Nature does conform some of her living creatures to conditions imposed by man. In such cases the intent of Nature may be said to have conformed to that of man, or rather to embrace that of man. But there is no such conforming in this case. The intent of Nature, that all human beings should use land, is as clearly seen in the children born to-day as it could have been seen in any past generation. How foolish, then, are those who say that although the right to land was originally equal, this equality of right has been lost by the action or sufferance of intermediate generations. How illogical those who declare that, while it would be just to assert this equality of right in the laws of a new country where people are now coming to live, it would be unjust to conform to it the laws of a country where people long have lived ? Has Nature anywhere or in anything shown any disposition to conform to what we call vested interests 2 Does the child born in an old country differ from the child born in a new country' Moral right and wrong, the Duke must agree with me, are not matters of precedent. The repetition of a wrong may dull the moral sense, but will not make it right. A robbery is no less a robbery the thousand millionth time it is committed than it was the first time. This they forgot who declaring the slave trade piracy still legalized the enslavement of those already enslaved. This they forget who admitting the equality of natural rights to the soil declare that it would be unjust now to a sºrt them. For, as the keeping of a man in slavery is THE “ REDUCTION TO INIQUITY.” 5? as much a violation of natural right as the seizure of his remote ancestor, so is the robbery involved in the present denial of natural rights to the soil as much a robbery as was the first act of fraud or force which violated those rights. Those who say it would be unjust for the people to resume their natural rights in the land without compensating present holders, confound right and wrong as flagrantly as did they who held it a crime in the slave to run away without first paying his owner his market value. They have never formed a clear idea of what property in land means. It means not merely a continuous exclusion of some people from the element which it is plainly the intent of Nature that all should enjoy, but it involves a continuous confiscation of labor and the results of labor. The Duke of Argyll has, we say, a large income drawn from land. But is this income really drawn from land 2 Were there no men on his land what income could the Duke get from it, save such as his own hands produced 3 Precisely as if drawn from slaves, this income represents an appro- priation of the earnings of labor. The effect of permit- ting the Duke to treat this land as his property, is to make so many other Scotsmen, in whole or in part, his serfs—to compel them to labor for him without pay, or to enable him to take from them their earnings without return. Surely, if the Duke will look at the matter in this way, he must see that the iniquity is not in abolish- ing an institution which permits one man to plunder others, but in continuing it. He must see that any claim of iandowners to compensation is not a claim to payment for what they have previously taken, but to payment for what they might yet take, precisely as would be the claim of the slaveholder—the true character of which appears in the fact that he would demand more compensation for 58 - PROPERTY IN LAND. a strong slave, out of whom he might yet get much work, than for a decrepit one, out of whom he had already forced nearly all the labor he could yield. In assuming that denial of the justice of property in land is the prelude to an attack upon all rights of prop- erty, the Duke ignores the essential distinction between land and things rightfully property. The things which constitute wealth, or capital (which is wealth used in production), and to which the right of property justly attaches, are produced by human exertion. Their substance is matter, which existed before man, and which man can neither create nor destroy ; but their essence— that which gives them the character of wealth—is labor impressed upon or modifying the conditions of matter. Their existence is due to the physical exertion of man, and, like his physical frame, they tend constantly to re- turn again to Nature’s reservoirs of matter and force. Land, on the contrary, is that part of the external uni- verse on which and from which alone man can live ; that reservoir of matter and force on which he must draw for all his needs. Its existence is not due to man, but is referable only to that Power from which man himself proceeds. It continues while he comes and goes, and will continue, so far as we can see, after he and his works shall disappear. Both species of things have value, but the value of the one species depends upon the amount of labor required for their production ; the value of the other upon the power which its reduction to ownership gives of commanding labor or the results of labor without paying any equivalent. The recognition of the right of property in wealth, or things produced by labor, is thus but a recognition of the right of each human being to himself and to the results of his own ex- ertions; but the recognition of a similar right of prop. THE “REDUCTION TO INIQUITY.” 59 erty in land is necessarily the impairment and denial of this true right of property. Turn from principles to facts. Whether as to national strength or national character, whether as to the number of people or as to their physical and moral health, whether as to the production of wealth or as to its equi- table distribution, the fruits of the primary injustice in- volved in making the land, on which and from which a whole people must live, the property of but a portion of their number, are everywhere evil and nothing but evil. If this seems to any too strong a statement, it is only because they associate individual ownership of land with permanence of possession and security of improvements. These are necessary to the proper use of land, but so far from being dependent upon individual ownership of land, they can be secured without it in greater degree than with it. This will be evident upon reflection. That the existing system does not secure permanence of possession and security of improvements in anything like the degree necessary to the best use of land, is obvious everywhere, but especially obvious in Great Britain, where the owners of land and the users of land are for the most part distinct persons. In many cases the users of land have no security from year to year, a logical development of individual ownership in land so fla- grantly unjust to the user and so manifestly detrimental to the community, that in Ireland, where this system most largely prevailed, it has been deemed necessary for the State to interfere in the most arbitrary manner. In other cases, where land is let for years, the user is often hampered with restrictions that prevent improvement and interfere with use, and at the expiration of the lease he is not merely deprived of his improvements, but is frequently subjected to a blackmail calculated upon the 60 PROPERTY IN LAND. inconvenience and loss which removal would cost him. Wherever I have been in Great Britain, from Land’s End to John O'Groat’s, and from Liverpool to Hull, I have heard of improvements prevented and production curtailed from this cause—in instances which run from the prevention of the building of an outhouse, the paint- ing of a dwelling, the enlargement of a chapel, the widening of a street, or the excavation of a dock, to the shutting up of a mine, the demolition of a village, the tearing up of a railway track, or the turning of land from the support of men to the breeding of wild beasts. I could cite case after case, each typical of a class, but it is unnecessary. How largely use and improvement are restricted and prevented by private ownership of land may be appreciated only by a few, but specific cases are known to all. How insecurity of improvement and possession prevents the proper maintenance of dwellings in the cities, how it hampers the farmer, how it fills the shopkeeper with dread as the expiration of his lease draws nigh, have been, to some extent at least, brought out by recent discussions, and in all these directions propositions are being made for State interference more or less violent, arbitrary, and destructive of the sound principle that men should be left free to manage their own property as they deem best. Does not all this interference and demand for inter- ference show that private property in land does not pro- duce good results, that it does not give the necessary permanence of possession and security of improvements : Is not an institution that needs such tinkering funda- mentally wrong ' That property in land must have different treatment from other property, all, or nearly all, are now agreed. Does not this prove that land ought not to be made individual property at all ; that to THE “REDUCTION TO INIQUITY.” 61 treat it as individual property is to weaken and endanger the true rights of property 2 The Duke of Argyll asserts that in the United States we have made land private property because we have found it necessary to secure settlement and improve- ment. Nothing could be further from the truth. The Duke might as well urge that our protective tariff is a proof of the necessity of “protection.” We have made land private property because we are but transplanted Europeans, wedded to custom, and have followed it in this matter more readily, because in a new country the evils that at length spring from private property in land are less obvious, while a much larger portion of the peo- ple seemingly profit by it—those on the ground gaining at the expense of those who come afterward. But so far from this treatment of land in the United States hav- ing promoted settlement and reclamation, the very re- verse is true. What it has promoted is the scattering of population in the country and its undue concentration in cities, to the disadvantage of production and the lessen- ing of comfort. It has forced into the wilderness families for whom there was plenty of room in well- Settled neighborhoods, and raised tenement houses amid vacant lots, led to waste of labor and capital in roads and railways not really needed, locked up natural opportuni. ties that otherwise would have been improved, made tramps and idlers of men who, had they found it in time, would gladly have been at work, and given to our agriculture a character that is rapidly and steadily decreasing the productiveness of the soil. As to political corruption in the United States, of which I have spoken in “Social Problems,” and to which the Duke refers, it springs, as I have shown in that book, not from excess but from deficiency of democracy, 62 PROPERTY IN LAN D. and mainly from our failure to recognize the equality of natural rights as well as of political rights. In compar- ing the two countries, it may be well to note that the exposure of abuses is quicker and sharper in the United States than in England, and that to some extent abuses which in the one country appear in naked deformity, are in the other hidden by the ivy of custom and respecta- bility. But be this as it may, the reforms I propose, in- stead of adding to corruptive forces, would destroy pro- lific sources of corruption. Our “protective” tariff, our excise taxes, and demoralizing system of local taxation, would, in their direct and indirect effects, corrupt any government, even if not aided by the corrupting effects of the grabbing for public lands. But the first step I propose would sweep away these corruptive influences, and it is to governments thus reformed, in a state of society in which the reckless struggle for wealth would be lessened by the elimination of the fear of want, that I would give, not the management of land or the direc- tion of enterprise, but the administration of the funds arising from the appropriation of economic rent. The Duke styles me a Pessimist. But, however pessimistic I may be as to present social tendencies, I have a firm faith in human nature. I am convinced that the attainment of pure government is merely a matter of conforming social institutions to moral law. If we do this, there is, to my mind, no reason why in the proper sphere of public administration we should not find men as honest and as faithful as when acting in private capacities. But to return to the reduction to iniquity. Test the institution of private property in land by its fruits in any country where it exists. Take Scotland. What, there, are its results & That wild beasts have supplanted human THE “ REDUCTION To INIQUITY.” 63 beings: that glens which once sent forth their thousand fighting men are now tenanted by a couple of game- keepers; that there is destitution and degradation that would shame savages; that little children are stunted and starved for want of proper nourishment ; that women are compelled to do the work of animals; that young girls who ought to be fitting themselves for wifehood and motherhood are held to the monotonous toil of factories, while others, whose fate is sadder still, prowl the streets ; that while a few Scotsmen have castles and palaces, Inore than a third of Scottish families live in one room each, and more than two thirds in not more than two rooms each ; that thousands of acres are kept as playgrounds for strangers, while the masses have not enough of their native soil to grow a flower, are shut out even from moor and mountain ; dare not take a trout from a loch or a salmon from the sea If the Duke thinks all classes have gained by the advance in civilization, let him go into the huts of the Highlands. There he may find countrymen of his, men and women the equals in natural ability and in moral character of any peer or peeress in the land, to whom the advance of our wondrous age has brought no gain. He may find them tilling the ground with the crockit spade, cutting grain with the sickle, threshing it with the flail, winnowing it by tossing it in the air, grinding it as their forefathers did a thousand years ago. He may see spinning-wheel and distaff yet in use, and the smoke from the fire in the centre of the hut ascending as it can through the thatch, that the precious heat, which costs so much labor to procure, may be economized to the utmost. These human beings are in natural parts and powers just such human beings as may be met at a royal levee, at a gathering of scientists, or inventors, or cap- 64. PROPERTY IN LAND. tains of industry. That they so live and so work, is not because of their stupidity, but because of their poverty— the direct and indisputable result of the denial of their natural rights. They have not merely been prevented from participating in the “general advance,” but are positively worse off than were their ancestors before commerce had penetrated the Highlands or the modern era of labor-saving inventions had begun. They have been driven from the good land to the poor land. While their rents have been increased, their holdings have been diminished, and their pasturage cut off. Where they once had beasts, they cannot now eat a chicken or keep a donkey, and their women must do work once done by animals. With the same thoughtful attention he has given to “the way of an eagle in the air,” let the Duke consider a sight he must have seen many times—a Scot- tish woman toiling uphill with a load of manure on her back. Then let him apply “the reduction to iniquity.” Let the Duke not be content with feasting his eyes upon those comfortable houses of the large farmers which so excite his admiration. Let him visit the bothies in which farm servants are herded together like cattle, and learn, as he may learn, that the lot of the Scottish farm servant—a lot from which no industry or thrift can release him—is to die in the workhouse or in the receipt of a parish dole if he be so unfortunate as to outlive his ability to work. Or let him visit those poor broken-down creatures who, enduring everything rather than accept the humiliation of the workhouse, are eking out their last days upon a few shillings from the parish, supplemented by the charity of people nearly as poor as themselves. Let him consider them, and if he has imagination enough, put himself in their place. Then let him try “the reduction to iniquity.” THE ‘‘ REDUCTION TO INIQUITY.” 65 Let the Duke go to Glasgow, the metropolis of Scot- iand, where, in underground cellars and miserable rooms, he will find crowded together families who (some of them, lest they might offend the deer) have been driven from their native soil into the great city to compete with each other for employment at any price, to have their children debauched by daily contact with all that is vile. Let him some Saturday evening leave the dis- tricts where the richer classes live, wander for awhile through the streets tenanted by working people, and note the stunted forms, the pinched features. Vice, drunkenness, the recklessness that comes when hope goes, he will see too. How should not such conditions produce such effects & But he will also see, if he chooses to look, hard, brave, stubborn struggling—the work- man, who, do his best, cannot find steady employment ; the bread-winner stricken with illness ; the widow straining to keep her children from the workhouse. Let the Duke observe and reflect upon these things, and then apply the reduction to iniquity. Or, let him go to Edinburgh, the “modern Athens,” of which Scotsmen speak with pride, and in buildings from whose roofs a bowman might strike the spires of twenty churches, he will find human beings living as he would not keep his meanest dog. Let him toil up the stairs of one of those monstrous buildings, let him enter one of those “dark houses,” let him close the door, and in the blackness think what life must be in such a place. Then let him try the reduction to iniquity. And if he go to that good charity (but, alas, how futile is Charity without Justice () where little children are kept while their mothers are at work, and children are fed who would otherwise go hungry, he may see infants whose limbs are shrunken from want of nourishment. Per- 66 PROPERTY IN LANT). haps they may tell him, as they told me, of that little girl, barefooted, ragged, and hungry, who, when they gave her bread, raised her eyes and clasped her hands, and thanked our Father in Heaven for His bounty to her. They who told me that never dreamed, I think, of its terrible meaning. But I ask the Duke of Argyll, did that little child, thankful for that poor dole, get what our Father provided for her ? Is He so niggard ; If not, what is it, who is it, that stands between such children and our Father’s bounty ? If it be an institu- tion, is it not our duty to God and to our neighbor to rest not till we destroy it ! If it be a man, were it not better for him that a millstone were hanged about his neck and he were cast into the depths of the sea 7 There can be no question of over-population—no pre- tence that Nature has brought more men into being than she has made provision for. Scotland Surely is not over-populated. Much land is unusued ; much land is devoted to lower uses, such as the breeding of game and the raising of cattle, that might be devoted to higher uses ; there are mineral resources untouched ; the wealth drawn from the sea is but a small part of what might be drawn. But it is idle to argue this point. Neither in Scotland, nor in any other country, can any excess of population over the power of nature to provide for then, be shown. The poverty so painful in Scotland is mani- festly no more due to over-population than the crowding of two thirds of the families into houses of one or two rooms is due to want of space to build houses upon. And just as the crowding of people into insufficient lodg- ings is directly due to institutions which permit men to hold vacant land needed for buildings until they can force a monopoly price from those wishing to build, so is the poverty of the masses due to the fact that they are THE ‘‘REDUCTION TO INIQUITY.” 6? in like manner shut out from the opportunities Nature has provided for the employment of their labor in the satisfaction of their wants. Take the Island of Skye as illustrating on a small scale the cause of poverty throughout Scotland. The people of Skye are poor—very poor. Is it because there are too many of them An explanation lies nearer—an ex- planation which would account for poverty no matter how small the population. If there were but one man in Skye, and if all that he produced, save enough to give him a bare living, were periodically taken from him and carried off, he would necessarily be poor. That is the condition of the people of Skye. With a population of some seventeen thousand there are, if my memory serves me, twenty-four landowners. The few proprietors who live upon the island, though they do nothing to produce wealth, have fine houses, and live luxuriously, while the greater portion of the rents are carried off to be spent abroad. It is not merely that there is thus a constant drain upon the wealth produced ; but that the power of producing wealth is enormously lessened. As the people are deprived of the power to accumulate capital, produc- tion is carried on in the most primitive style, and at the greatest disadvantage. If there are really too many people in Scotland, why not have the landlords emigrate & They are not merely best fitted to emigrate, but would give the greatest relief. They consume most, waste most, carry off most, while they produce least. As landlords, in fact, they produce nothing. They merely consume and destroy. Economically considered, they have the same effect upon production as bands of robbers or pirate fleets. To national wealth they are as weavils in the grain, as rats in the storehouse, as ferrets in the poultry yard. 58 f’RODERTY IN 1...ANI). The Duke of Argyll complains of what he calls my “assumption that owners of land are not producers, and that rent does not represent, or represents in a very minor degree, the interest of capital.” The Duke will justify his complaint if he will show how the owning of land can produce anything. Failing in this, he must admit that though the same person may be a laborer, capitalist, and landowner, the owner of land, as an owner of land, is not a producer. And surely he knows that the term “rent’’ as used in political economy, and as I use it in the books he criticises, never represents the interest on capital, but refers alone to the sum paid for the use of the inherent capabilities of the soil. As illustrating the usefulness of landlords, the Duke Says : “My own experience now extends over the best part offorty years. During that time I have built over fifty homesteads, complete for man and beast. I have drained and reclaimed many hundreds, and enclosed some thousands of acres. In this sense I have added house to house, and field to field, not—as pulpit orators have assumed in similar cases—that I might dwell alone in the land, but that the cultivating class may live more comfortably and with better appli- ances for increasing the produce of the soil.’’ And again he says that during the last four years he has spent on one property £40,000 in the improvement of the soil. I fear that in Scotland the Duke of Argyll has been “hiding his light under a bushel,” for his version of the way in which he has “added house to house, and field to field'’ differs much from that which common Scots- men give. But this is a matter into which I do not wish to enter. What I would like to ask the Duke is, how he built the fifty homesteads and reclaimed the thou- sands of acres 2 Not with his own hands, of course ; THE “REDUCTION TO INIQUITY.” 69 but with his money. Where, then, did he get that money : Was is not taken as rent from the cultivators of the soil ' And might not they, had it been left to them, have devoted it to the building of homesteads and the improvement of the soil as well as he Z Suppose the Duke spends on such improvements all he draws in rent, minus what it costs him to live, is not the cost of his living so much waste so far as the improvement of the land is concerned ? Would there not be a considerably greater fund to devote to this purpose if the Duke got no rent, and had to work for a living 2 But all Scottish landholders are not even such im- provers as the Duke. There are landlords who spend their incomes in racing, in profligacy, in doing things which when not injurious are quite as useless to man or beast, as the works of that English Duke, recently dead, who spent millions in burrowing underground like a mole. What the Scottish landlords call their “improve- ments” have, for the most part, consisted in building castles, laying out pleasure grounds, raising rents, and evicting their kinsmen. But the encouragement given to agriculture, by even such improving owners as the Duke of Argyll, is very much like the encouragement given to traffic by the Duke of Bedford, who keeps two or three old men and women to open and shut gates he has erected across the streets of London. That much the greater part of the incomes drawn by landlords is as completely lost for all productive purposes as though it were thrown into the sea, there can be no doubt. But that even the small part which is devoted to reproduc- tive improvement is largely wasted, the Duke of Argyll himself clearly shows in stating, what I have learned from other sources, that the large outlays of the great landholders yield little interest, and in many cases no in, 70 PROPERTY IN LAND. terest at all. Clearly, the stock of wealth would have been much greater had this capital been left in the hands of the cultivators, who, in most cases, suffer from lack of capital, and in many cases have to pay the most usurious interest. In fact, the plea of the landlords that they, as land- lords, assist in production, is very much like the plea of the slaveholders that they gave a living to the slaves. And I am convinced that if the Duke of Argyll will consider the matter as a philosopher rather than as a landlord, he will see the gross inconsistency between the views he expresses as to negro slavery and the position he assumes as to property in land. In principle the two systems of appropriating the labor of other men are essentially the same. Since it is from land and on land that man must live, if he is to live at all, a human being is as completely enslaved when the land on which he must live is made the property of another as when his own flesh and blood are made the property of that other. And at least, after a certain point in social development is reached, the slavery that results from depriving men of all legal right to land is, for the very reason that the relation between master and slave is not so direct and obvious, more cruel and more demoralizing than that which makes property of their bodies. And turning to facts, the Duke must see, if he will look, that the effects of the two systems are substantially the same. He is, for instance, an hereditary legislator, with power in making laws which other Scotsmen, who have little or no voice in making laws, must obey under penalty of being fined, imprisoned, or hanged. He has this power, which is essentially that of the master to compel the slave, not because any one thinks that Nature THE “ REDUCTION TO INIQUITY.” 71 gives wisdom and patriotism to eldest sons more than to younger sons, or to some families more than to other families, but because as the legal owner of a considerable part of Scotland, he is deemed to have greater rights in making laws than other Scotsmen, who can live in their native land only by paying some of the legal owners of Scotland for the privilege. That power over men arises from ownership of land as well as from ownership of their bodies the Duke may see in varied manifestations if he will look. The power of the Scottish landlords over even the large farmers, and, in the smaller towns, over even the well-to-do shop- keepers and professional men, is enormous. Even where it is the custom to let on lease, and large capital is re- quired, competition, aided in many cases by the law of hypotheca, enable the landlord to exert a direct power over even the large farmer. That many substantial farmers have been driven from their homes and ruined because they voted or were supposed to have voted against the wishes of their landlords is well known. A man whose reputation was that of the best farmer in Scotland was driven from his home in this way a few years since for having politically offended his landlord. In Leeds (England) I was told of a Scottish physician who died there lately. He had been in comfortable practice in a village on the estate of a Scottish duke. Because he voted for a Liberal candidate, word was given by the landlord's agent that he was no longer to be employed, and as the people feared to disobey the hint, he was obliged to leave. He came to Leeds, and not succeeding in establishing himself, pined away, and would have died in utter destitution but that some friends he had made in Leeds wrote to the candidate for supporting whom he had been boycotted, who came to 72 PROPERTY IN LAN ID. Leeds, provided for his few days of life, and assumed the care of his children. I mention to his honor the name of that gentleman as it was given to me. It was Sir Sydney Waterlew. * During a recent visit to the Highlands I was over and over again told by well-to-do men that they did not dare to let their opinions be known or to take any action the landlords or their agents might dislike. In one town such men came to me by night and asked me to speak, but telling me frankly that they did not dare to apply for a hall, requested me to do that for myself, as I was be- yond the tyranny they feared. If this be the condition of the well-to-do, the condition of the crofters can be imagined. One of them said to me, “We have feared the landlord more than we have feared God Almighty ; we have feared the factor more than the landlord, and the ground officer more than the factor.” But there is a class lower still even than the crofters—the cotters— who, on forty-eight hours’ notice, can be turned out of what by courtesy are called their homes, and who are at the mercy of the large farmers or tacksmen, who in turn fear the landlord or agent. Take this class, or the class of farm servants who are kept in bothies. Can the Duke tell me of any American slaves who were lodged and fed as these white slaves are lodged and fed, or who had less of all the comforts and enjoyments of life 2 The slaveholders of the South never, in any case that I have heard of, interfered with the religion of the slaves, and the Duke of Argyll will doubtless admit that this is a power which one man ought not to have over another. Yet he must know that at the disruption of the Scottish Church, some forty years ago, Scottish pro- prietors not merely evicted tenants who joined the Free Church (and in many cases eviction meant ruin and THE “ REDUCTION TO INIQUITY.” 73 death), but absolutely refused sites for churches and even permission for the people to stand upon the land and worship God according to the dictates of their con- science. Hugh Miller has told, in “The Cruise of the Betsy,” how one minister, denied permission to live on the land, had to make his home on the sea in a small boat. Large congregations had to worship on mountain roadsides without shelter from storm and sleet, and even on the seashore, where the tide flowed around their knees as they took the communion. But perhaps the slavish- ness which has been engendered in Scotland by land monopoly is not better illustrated than in the case where, after keeping them off his land for more than six years, a Scottish Duke allowed a congregation the use of a gravel-pit for purposes of worship, whereupon they sent him a resolution of thanks In the large cities tyranny of this kind cannot, of course, be exercised, but it is in the large cities that the slavery resulting from the reduction of land to private ownership assumes the darkest shades. Negro slavery had its horrors, but they were not so many or so black as those constantly occurring in such cities. Their own selfish interests, if not their human sympathies or the restraint of public opinion, would have prevented the owners of negro slaves from lodging and feeding and working them as many of the so-called free people in the centres of civilization are lodged and fed and worked. With all allowance for the prepossessions of a great landlord, it is difficult to understand how the Duke of Argyll can regard as an animating scene the history of agricultural improvement in Scotland since 1745. From the date mentioned, and the fact that he is a High- lander, I presume that he refers mainly to the High- 74 PROPERTY IN LAND. lands. But as a parallel to calling this history “animat- ing,” I can think of nothing so close as the observation of an economist of the Duke’s school, who, in an ac- count of a visit to Scotland, a generation or so ago, spoke of the pleasure with which, in a workhouse, he had seen “both sexes and all ages, even to infants of two and three years, earning their living by picking oakum,” or as the expression of pride with which a Polish noble, in the last century, pointed out to an English visitor some miserable-looking creatures who, he said, were samples of the serfs, any one of whom he could kick as he pleased “Thousands and thousands of acres,” says the Duke, “have been reclaimed from barren wastes; ignorance has given place to science, and barbarous customs of immemorial strength have been replaced by habits of in- telligence and business.” This is one side of the picture, but unfortunately there is another side—chief- tains taking advantage of the reverential affection of their clansmen, and their ignorance of a foreign language and a foreign law, to reduce those clansmen to a con- dition of virtual slavery ; to rob them of the land which by immemorial custom they had enjoyed ; to substitute for the mutual tie that bound chief to vassal and vassal to chief, the cold maxims of money-making greed ; to drive them from their homes that sheep might have place, or to hand them over to the tender mercies of a great farmer. “There has been grown,” says the Duke, “more corn, more potatoes, more turnips ; there has been pro- duced more milk, more butter, more cheese, more beef, more mutton, more pork, more fowls and eggs.” But what becomes of them : The Duke must know that the ordinary food of the common people is meal and THE “ REDUCTION TO INIQUITY.” 75 potatoes; that of these many do not get enough ; that many would starve outright if they were not kept alive by charity. Even the wild meat which their fathers took freely, the common people cannot now touch. A Highland poor-law physician, whose district is on the estate of a prominent member of the Liberal party, was telling me recently of the miserable poverty of the peo- ple among whom his official duties lie, and how in- sufficient and monotonous food was beginning to produce among them diseases like the pellegria in Italy, when I asked him if they could not, despite the gamekeepers, take for themselves enough fish and game to vary their diet. “They never think of it,” he replied ; “they are too cowed. Why, the moment any one of them was even suspected of cultivating a taste for trout or grouse, he would be driven off the estate like a mad dog.” Besides the essays and journals referred to by the Duke of Argyll, there is another publication, which any one wishing to be informed on the subject may read with advantage, though not with pleasure. It is entitled “Highland Clearances,” and is published in Inverness by A. McKenzie. There is nothing in savage life more cold-bloodedly atrocious than the warfare here recorded as carried on against the clansmen by those who were their hereditary protectors. The burning of houses : the ejection of old and young ; the tearing down of shelters put up to shield women with child and tender infants from the bitter night blast ; the threats of similar treatment against all who should give them hospitality ; the forcing of poor helpless creatures into emigrant ships which carried them to strange lands and among a people of whose tongue they were utterly ignorant, to die in many cases like rotten sheep or to be reduced to utter degradation. An animating scene truly Great dis- 76 PROPERTY IN LAND. tricts once peopled with a race, rude it may be and slavish to their chiefs, but still a race of manly virtues, brave, kind, and hospitable—now tenanted only by sheep or cattle, by grouse or deer | No one can read of the atrocities perpetrated upon the Scottish people, during what is called “the improvement of the Highlands,” without feeling something like utter contempt for men who, lions abroad, were such sheep at home that they suffered these outrages without striking a blow, even if an ineffectual one. But the explanation of this reveals a lower depth in the “reduction to iniquity.” The rea- son of the tame submission of the Highland people to outrages which should have nerved the most timid is to be found in the prostitution of their religion. The Highland people are a deeply religious people, and dur- ing these evictions their preachers preached to them that their trials were the visitations of the Almighty and must be submitted to under the penalty of eternal damna- tion | I met accidentally in Scotland, recently, a lady of the small landlord class, and the conversation turned upon the poverty of the Highland people. “Yes, they are poor,” she said, “but they deserve to be poor ; they are so dirty. I have no sympathy with women who won’t keep their houses neat and their children tidy.” I suggested that neatness could hardly be expected from women who every day had to trudge for miles with creels of peat and seaweed on their backs. “Yes,” she said, “they do have to work hard. But that is not so sad as the hard lives of the horses. Did you ever think of the horses They have to work all their lives—till they can’t work any longer. It makes me sad to think of it. There ought to be big farms where horses should be turned out after they had worked THE “ REDUCTION TO INIQUITY.” ** Some years, so that they might have time to enjoy them- selves before they died.” “But the people º’’ I interposed. “They, too, have to work till they can’t work longer.” “Oh, yes!” she replied, “but the people have souls, and even if they do have a hard time of it here, they will, if they are good, go to heaven when they die, and be happy hereafter. But the poor beasts have no souls, and if they don’t enjoy themselves here, they have no chance of enjoying themselves at all. It is too had l’” . The woman was in sober earnest. And I question if she did not fairly represent much that has been taught in Scotland as Christianity. But at last, thank God the day is breaking, and the blasphemy that has been preached as religion will not be heard much longer. The manifesto of the Scottish Land Restoration League, calling upon the Scottish people to bind themselves together in solemn league and covenant for the extirpa- tion of the sin and shame of landlordism is a lark’s note in the dawn. : As in Scotland so elsewhere. I have spoken par- ticularly of Scotland only because the Duke does so. But everywhere that our civilization extends the same primary injustice is bearing the same evil fruits. And everywhere the same spirit is rising, the same truth is beginning to force its way. 4 . . THE CONDITION OF LABOR. AN OPEN LETTER TO POPE LEO XIII. BY EIENERY GEORGE WITH ENCYCLICAL LETTER OF POPE LEO XIII. ON THE CONDITION OF LABOR NEW YORK CHARLES L. WEBSTER & COMPANY 1893 CopyRIGHT, 1881, BY HENRY GEORGE THE CONDITION OF LABOR An Open Letter to Pope Leo XIII. To POPE LEO XIII. Your Holiness: I have read with care your Encyclical letter on the condition of labor, addressed, through the Patriarchs, Primates, Archbishops and Bishops of your faith, to the Christian World. Since its most strikingly pronounced condemnations are directed against a theory that we who hold it know to be deserving of your support, I ask permission to lay before your Holiness the grounds of our belief, and to set forth some considerations that you have unfortunately overlooked. The momentous serious- ness of the facts you refer to, the poverty, suffering and Seething discontent that pervade the Christian world, the danger that passion may lead ignorance in a blind struggle against social conditions rapidly be- coming intolerable, are my justification. I. Our postulates are all stated or implied in your Encyclical. They are the primary perceptions of 4. THE CONDITION OF LABOR. human reason, the fundamental teachings of the Christian faith : We hold : That— This world is the creation of God. The men brought into it for the brief period of their earthly lives are the equal creatures of His bounty, the equal subjects of His provident care. By his constitution man is beset by physical wants, on the satisfaction of which depend not only the maintenance of his physical life but also the develop- ment of his intellectual and spiritual life. - God has made the satisfaction of these wants dependent on man’s own exertions, giving him the power and laying on him the injunction to labor—a power that of itself raises him far above the brute, since we may reverently say that it enables him to become as it were a helper in the creative work. God has not put on man the task of making bricks without straw. With the need for labor and the power to labor He has also given to man the material for labor. This material is land—man physically being a land animal, who can live only on and from land, and can use other elements, such as air, Sunshine and water, only by the use of land. Being the equal creatures of the Creator, equally entitled under His providence to live their lives and satisfy their needs, men are equally entitled to the use of land, and any adjustment that denies this equal use of land is morally wrong. As to the right of ownership, we hold: That— Being created individuals, with individual wants and powers, men are individually entitled (subject of OPEN LETTER TO POPE LEO XIIIs 5 course to the moral obligations that arise from such re- lations as that of the family) to the use of their own powers and the enjoyment of the results. There thus arises, anterior to human law, and deriving its validity from the law of God, a right of private ownership in things produced by labor—a right that the possessor may transfer, but of which to de- prive him without his will is theft. This right of property, originating in the right of the individual to himself, is the only full and complete right of property. It attaches to things produced by labor, but cannot attach to things created by God. Thus, if a man take a fish from the ocean he acquires a right of property in that fish, which exclusive right he may transfer by sale or gift. But he cannot obtain a similar right of property in the ocean, so that he may sell it or give it or forbid others to use it. Or, if he set up a windmill he acquires a right of property in the things such use of wind enables him to produce. But he cannot claim a right of property in the wind itself, so that he may sell it or forbid others to use it. Or, if he cultivate grain he acquires a right of prop- erty in the grain his labor brings forth. But he cannot obtain a similar right of property in the sun which ripened it or the soil on which it grew. For these things are of the continuing gifts of God to all genera- tions of men, which all may use, but none may claim as his alone. To attach to things created by God the same right of private ownership that justly attaches to things pro- duced by labor is to impair and deny the true rights of property. For a man who out of the proceeds of 6 THE CONDITION OF LABOR. his labor is obliged to pay another man for the use of Ocean or air or sunshine or soil, all of which are to men involved in the single term land, is in this de. prived of his rightful property and thus robbed. As to the use of land, we hold : That— While the right of ownership that justly attaches to things produced by labor cannot attach to land, there may attach to land a right of possession. As your Holiness says, “God has not granted the earth to man- kind in general in the sense that all without distinction can deal with it as they please,” and regulations necessary for its best use may be fixed by human laws. But such regulations must conform to the moral law —must secure to all equal participation in the advan- tages of God’s general bounty. The principle is the same as where a human father leaves property equally to a number of children. Some of the things thus left may be incapable of common use or of specific division. Such things may properly be assigned to some of the children, but only under condition that the equality of benefit among them all be preserved. In the rudest social state, while industry consists in hunting, fishing, and gathering the spontaneous fruits of the earth, private possession of land is not necessary. But as men begin to cultivate the ground and expend their labor in permanent works, private possession of the land on which labor is thus expended is needed to secure the right of property in the products of labor. For who would sow if not assured of the exclusive possession needed to enable him to reap f who would attach costly works to the soil without such exclusive OPEN LETTER TO POPE LEO XIII. 7 possession of the soil as would enable him to secure the benefit 2 This right of private possession in things created by God is however very different from the right of private ownership in things produced by labor. The one is limited, the other unlimited, save in cases when the dictate of self-preservation terminates all other rights. The purpose of the one, the exclusive possession of land, is merely to secure the other, the exclusive ownership of the products of labor; and it can never rightfully be carried so far as to impair or deny this. While anyone may hold exclusive possession of land so far as it does not interfere with the equal rights of others, he can rightfully hold it no further. Thus Cain and Abel, were there only two men on earth, might by agreement divide the earth between them. Under this compact each might claim exclusive right to his share as against the other. But neither could rightfully continue such claim against the next man born. For since no one comes into the world without God’s permission, his presence attests his equal right to the use of God's bounty. For them to refuse him any use of the earth which they had divided between them would therefore be for them to commit murder. And for them to refuse him any use of the earth, unless by laboring for them or by giving them part of the products of his labor he bought it of them, would be for them to commit theft. God’s laws do not change. Though their applica- tions may alter with altering conditions, the same principles of right and wrong that hold when men are few and industry is rude also hold amid teeming 8 THE CONDITION OF LABOR. populations and complex industries. In our cities of millions and our states of scores of millions, in a civilization where the division of labor has gone so far that large numbers are hardly conscious that they are land users, it still remains true that we are all land animals and can live only on land, and that land is God’s bounty to all, of which no one can be deprived without being murdered, and for which no one can be compelled to pay another without being robbed. But even in a state of society where the elaboration of industry and the increase of permanent improvements have made the need for private posses- sion of land widespread, there is no difficulty in conforming individual possession with the equal right to land. For as soon as any piece of land will yield to the possessor a larger return than is had by similar labor on other land a value attaches to it which is shown when it is sold or rented. Thus, the value of the land itself, irrespective of the value of any improvements in or on it, always indicates the precise value of the benefit to which all are entitled in its use, as distinguished from the value which as producer or successor of a producer belongs to the possessor in individual right. To combine the advantages of private possession with the justice of common ownership it is only necessary therefore to take for common uses what value attaches to land irrespective of any exertion of labor on it. The principle is the same as in the case referred to, where a human father leaves equally to his children things not susceptible of specific division or common use. In that case such things would be Sold or rented and the value equally applied. OPEN LETTER TO POPE LEO XIII. 9 It is on this common sense principle that we, who term ourselves single tax men, would have the com- munity act. We do not propose to assert equal rights to land by keeping land common, letting any one use any part of it at any time. We do not propose the task, impossible in the present state of society, of dividing land in equal shares; still less the yet more impossible task of keeping it so divided. We propose, leaving land in the private possession of individuals, with full liberty on their part to give, sell or bequeath it, simply to levy on it for public uses a tax that shall equal the annual value of the land itself, irrespective of the use made of it or the improvements on it. And since this would provide amply for the need of public revenues, we would accompany this tax on land values with the repeal of all taxes now levied on the products and processes of industry—which taxes, since they take from the earnings of labor, we hold to be infringements of the right of property. This we propose, not as a cunning device of human ingenuity, but as a conforming of human regulations to the will of God. God cannot contradict himself nor impose on his creatures laws that clash. If it be God’s command to men that they should not steal—that is to say, that they should respect the right of property which each one has in the fruits of his labor ; And if He be also the Father of all men, who in His common bounty has intended all to have equal opportunities for sharing; 10 THE CONDITION OF LABOR. Then, in any possible stage of civilization, how- ever elaborate, there must be some way in which the exclusive right to the products of industry may be reconciled with the equal right to land. If the Almighty be consistent with Himself, it cannot be, as say those socialists referred to by you, that in order to secure the equal participation of men in the opportunities of life and labor we must ignore the right of private property. Nor yet can it be, as you yourself in the Encyclical seem to argue, that to secure the right of private property we must ignore the equality of right in the opportunities of life and labor. To say the one thing or the other is equally to deny the harmony of God’s laws. But, the private possession of land, subject to the payment to the community of the value of any special advantage thus given to the individual, satisfies both laws, securing to all equal participation in the bounty of the Creator and to each the full ownership of the products of his labor. Nor do we hesitate to say that this way of securing the equal right to the bounty of the Creator and the exclusive right to the products of labor is the way intended by God for raising public revenues. For we are not atheists, who deny God; nor semi-atheists, who deny that He has any concern in politics and legislation. It is true as you say—a salutary truth too often forgotten—that “man is older than the state, and he holds the right of providing for the life of his body prior to the formation of any state.” Yet, as you too perceive, it is also true that the state is in the divinely OPEN LETTER TO POPE LEO XIII. 11 appointed order. For He who foresaw all things and provided for all things, foresaw and provided that with the increase of population and the development of industry the organization of human society into states or governments would become both expedient and necessary. No sooner does the state arise than, as we all know, it needs revenues. This need for revenues is small at first, while population is sparse, industry rude and the functions of the state few and simple. But with growth of population and advance of civilization the functions of the state increase and larger and larger revenues are needed. Now, He that made the world and placed man in it, He that preordained civilization as the means whereby man might rise to higher powers and become more and more conscious of the works of his Creator, must have foreseen this increasing need for state revenues and have made provision for it. That is to say: The increasing need for public revenues with social advance, being a natural, God-ordained need, there must be a right way of raising them—some way that we can truly say is the way intended by God. It is clear that this right way of raising public revenues must accord with the moral law. Hence: It must not take from individuals what rightfully belongs to individuals. It must not give some an advantage over others, as by increasing the prices of what some have to sell and others must buy. It must not lead men into temptation, by requiring 12 THE CONDITION OF LABOR. trivial oaths, by making it profitable to lie, to swear falsely, to bribe or to take bribes. It must not confuse the distinctions of right and wrong, and weaken the sanctions of religion and the state by creating crimes that are not sins, and punish. ing men for doing what in itself they have an un- doubted right to do. It must not repress industry. It must not check commerce. It must not punish thrift. It must offer no impediment to the largest production and the fairest division of wealth. Let me ask your Holiness to consider the taxes on the processes and products of industry by which through the civilized world public revenues are collected—the Octroi duties that surround Italian cities with barriers; the monstrous customs duties that hamper intercourse between so-called Christian states; the taxes on Occupations, on earnings, on investments, on the building of houses, on the culti- vation of fields, on industry and thrift in all forms. Can these be the ways God has intended that govern- ments should raise the means they need & Have any of them the characteristics indispensable in any plan we can deem a right one All these taxes violate the moral law. They take by force what belongs to the individual alone; they give to the unscrupulous an advantage over the scrupulous; they have the effect, may are largely in- tended, to increase the price of what some have to sell and others must buy; they corrupt government; they make oaths a mockery; they shackle commerce; they fine industry and thrift; they lessen the wealth OPEN LETTER TO POPE LEO XIII. 13 that men might enjoy, and enrich some by impoverish- ing others. Yet what most strikingly shows how opposed to Christianity is this system of raising public revenues is its influence on thought. Christianity teaches us that all men are brethren ; that their true interests are harmonious, not an- tagonistic. It gives us, as the golden rule of life, that we should do to others as we would have others do to us. But out of the system of taxing the products and processes of labor, and out of its effects in increas- ing the price of what some have to sell and others must buy, has grown the theory of “protection,” which denies this gospel, which holds Christ ignorant of political economy and proclaims laws of national well-being utterly at variance with His teaching. This theory sanctifies national hatreds; it inculcates a universal war of hostile tariffs; it teaches peoples that their prosperity lies in imposing on the pro- ductions of other peoples restrictions they do not wish imposed on their own; and instead of the Christian doctrine of man’s brotherhood it makes injury of foreigners a civic virtue. “By their fruits you shall know them.” Can any- thing more clearly show that to tax the products and processes of industry is not the way God intended public revenues to be raised ? But to consider what we propose—the raising of public revenues by a single tax on the value of land irrespective of improvements—is to see that in all respects this does conform to the moral law. Let me ask your Holiness to keep in mind that the value we propose to tax, the value of land irrespective 14 "THE CONDITION OF LABOR. of improvements, does not come from any exertion of labor or investment of capital on or in it—the values produced in this way being values of improve- ment which we would exempt. The value of land irrespective of improvement is the value that attaches to land by reason of increasing population and social progress. This is a value that always goes to the owner as owner, and never does and never can go to the user; for if the user be a different person from the owner he must always pay the owner for it in rent or in purchase money; while if the user be also the owner, it is as owner, not as user, that he receives it, and by selling or renting the land he can, as owner, continue to receive it after he ceases to be a user. Thus, taxes on land irrespective of improvement can- not lessen the rewards of industry, nor add to prices,” *As to this point it may be well to add that all economists are agreed that taxes on land values irrespective of improvement or use—or what in the terminology of Political Economy is styled rent, a term distinguished from the ordinary use of the word rent by being applied solely to payments for the use of land itself— must be paid by the owner and cannot be shifted by him on the user. To explain in another way the reason given in the text Price is not determined by the will of the seller or the will of the buyer, but by the equation of demand and supply, and therefore as to things constantly demanded and constantly produced rests at a point determined by the cost of production—whatever tends to increase the cost of bringing fresh quantities of such articles to the consumer increasing price by checking supply, and what ever tends to reduce such cost decreasing price by increasing supply. Thus taxes on wheat or tobacco or cloth add to the price that the consumer must pay, and thus the cheapening in the cost of producing steel which improved processes have made in recent years has greatly reduced the price of steel. But land has no cost of production, since it is created by God, not pro- duced by man. Its price therefore is fixed—1 (monopoly rent), where land is held in close monopoly, by what the owners can extract from the users under penalty of deprivation and con- sequently of starvation, and amounts to all that common labor can earn on it beyond what is necesstry to life ; 2 (economic rent proper), where there is no special monopoly, by what the OPEN LETTER TO POPE LEO XIII. - 15 nor in any way take from the individual what belongs to the individual. They can only take the value that attaches to land by the growth of the community, and which therefore belongs to the community as a whole. To take land values for the state, abolishing all taxes on the products of labor, would therefore leave to the laborer the full produce of labor; to the individual all that rightfully belongs to the individual. It would impose no burden on industry, no check on commerce, no punishment on thrift; it would secure the largest production and the fairest distribution of wealth, by leaving men free to produce and to exchange as they please, without any artificial enhancement of prices; and by taking for public purposes a value that cannot be carried off, that cannot be hidden, that of all values is most easily ascertained and most certainly and particular land will yield to common labor over and above what may be had by like expenditure and exertion on land having no special advantage and for which no rent is paid ; and, 3 (specu- lative rent, which is a species of monopoly rent, telling particu- larly in selling price), by the expectation of future increase of value from social growth and improvement, which expectation causing land owners to withhold land at present prices has the same effect as combination. Taxes on land values or economic rent can therefore never be shifted by the land owner to the land user, since they in no wise increase the demand for land or enable land owners to check supply by withholding land from use. Where rent depends on mere monopolization, a case I mention because rent may in this way be demanded for the use of land even before economic or natural rent arises, the taking by taxation of what the land- Owners were able to extort from labor could not enable them to extort any more, since laborers, if not left enough to live on, will die. So, in the case of economic rent proper, to take from the land owners the premiums they receive, would in no way increase the superiority of their land and the demand for it. While so far as price is affected by speculative rent, to compel the land owners to pay taxes on the value of land whether they were getting any income from it or not, would make it more difficult for them to withhold land from use ; and to tax the ...' value would not merely destroy the power but the desire to do S0, 16 THE CONDITION OF LABOR. cheaply collected, it would enormously lessen the number of officials, dispense with oaths, do away with temptations to bribery and evasion, and abolish man- made crimes in themselves innocent. But, further : That God has intended the state to obtain the revenues it needs by the taxation of land values is shown by the same order and degree of evidence that shows that God has intended the milk of the mother for the nourishment of the babe. See how close is the analogy. In that primitive condition ere the need for the state arises there are no land values. The products of labor have value, but in the sparsity of population no value as yet attaches to land itself. But as increasing density of population and increasing elaboration of industry necessitate the organization of the state, with its need for revenues, value begins to attach to land. As population still increases and industry grows more elaborate, so the needs for public revenues increase. And at the same time and from the same causes land values increase. The connection is invariable. The value of things produced by labor tends to decline with social develop- ment, since the larger scale of production and the improvement of processes tend steadily to reduce their cost. But the value of land on which popu- lation centers goes up and up. Take Rome or Paris or London or New York or Melbourne. Consider the enormous value of land in such cities as compared with the value of land in sparsely settled parts of the same countries. To what is this due : Is it not due to the density and activity of the populations of those cities—to the very causes that require great OPEN LETTER, TO POPE LEO XIII. 17 public expenditure for streets, drains, public buildings, and all the many things needed for the health, con- venience and safety of such great cities? See how with the growth of such cities the one thing that steadily increases in value is land; how the opening of roads, the building of railways, the making of any public improvement, adds to the value of land. Is it not clear that here is a natural law—that is to say a tendency willed by the Creator? Can it mean anything else than that He who ordained the state with its needs has in the values which attach to land provided the means to meet those needs? That it does mean this and nothing else is confirmed if we look deeper still, and inquire not merely as to the intent, but as to the purpose of the intent. If we do so we may see in this natural law by which land val- ues increase with the growth of society not only such a perfectly adapted, provision for the needs of society as gratifies our intellectual perceptions by showing us the wisdom of the Creator, but a purpose with regard to the individual that gratifies our moral perceptions by opening to us a glimpse of His beneficence. Consider: Here is a natural law by which as society advances the one thing that increases in value island— a natural law by virtue of which all growth of popula- tion, all advance of the arts, all general improvements of whatever kind, add to a fund that both the commands of justice and the dictates of expediency prompt us to take for the common uses of society. Now, since increase in the fund available for the common uses of society is increase in the gain that goes equally to each member of society, is it not clear 18 THE CONDITION OF i.ABOR. that the law by which land values increase with social advance while the value of the products of labor do not increase, tends with the advance of civilization to make the share that goes equally to each member of society more and more important as compared with what goes to him from his individual earnings, and thus to make the advance of civilization lessen rel- atively the differences that in a ruder social state must exist between the strong and the weak, the fortunate and the unfortunate? Does it not show the purpose of the Creator to be that the advance of man in civilization should be an advance not merely to larger powers but to a greater and greater equality, instead of what we, by our ignoring of His intent, are making it, an advance towards a more and more monstrous inequality ? That the value attaching to land with social growth is intended for social needs is shown by the final proof. God is indeed a jealous God in the sense that nothing but injury and disaster can attend the effort of men to do things other than in the way He has intended; in the sense that where the blessings He proffers to men are refused or misused they turn to evils that scourge us. And just as for the mother to withhold the provision that fills her breast with the birth of the child is to endanger physical health, so for society to refuse to take for social uses the pro- vision intended for them is to breed social disease. For refusal to take for public purposes the increasing values that attach to land with social growth is to necessitate the getting of public revenues by taxes that lessen production, distort distribution and corrupt OfEN LETTER TO POP15. LEO XIII. 19 Society. It is to leave some to take what justly belongs to all; it is to forego the only means by which it is possible in an advanced civilization to combine the security of possession that is necessary to improve- ment with the equality of natural opportunity that is the most important of all natural rights. It is thus at the basis of all social life to set up an unjust inequality between man and man, compelling some to pay others for the privilege of living, for the chance of working, for the advantages of civilization, for the gifts of their God. But it is even more than this. The very robbery that the masses of men thus suffer gives rise in advancing communities to a new robbery. For the value that with the increase of population and social advance attaches to land being suffered to go to individuals who have secured ownership of the land, it prompts to a forestalling of and speculation in land wherever there is any prospect of advancing population or of coming improvement, thus produc- ing an artificial scarcity of the natural elements of life and labor, and a strangulation of production that shows itself in recurring spasms of industrial depression as disastrous to the world as destructive wars. It is this that is driving men from the old countries to the new countries, only to bring there the same curses. It is this that causes our material advance not merely to fail to improve the condition of the mere worker, but to make the condition of large classes positively worse. It is this that in our richest Christian countries is giving us a large population whose lives are harder, more hopeless, more degraded than those of the veriest Savages. It is this that leads so many men to think that God is a bungler and is constantly 20 THE CONDITION OF LABOR. bringing more people into His world than He has made provision for; or that there is no God, and that belief in Him is a superstition which the facts of life and the advance of science are dispelling. The darkness in light, the weakness in strength, the poverty amid wealth, the seething discontent foreboding civil strife, that characterize our civilization of to-day, are the natural, the inevitable results of our rejection of God’s beneficence, of our ignoring of His intent. Were we on the other hand to follow His clear, simple rule of right, leaving scrupulously to the individual all that individual labor produces, and taking for the community the value that attaches to land by the growth of the community itself, not merely could evil modes of raising public revenues be dispensed with, but all men would be placed on an equal level of opportunity with regard to the bounty of their Creator, on an equal level of opportunity to exert their labor and to enjoy its fruits. And then, without drastic or restrictive measures the forestalling of land would cease. For then the possession of land would mean only security for the permanence of its use, and there would be no object for any one to get land or to keep land except for use; nor would his possession of better land than others had confer any unjust advantage on him, or unjust deprivation on them, since the equivalent of the advantage would be taken by the state for the benefit of all. The Right Reverend Dr. Thomas Nulty, Bishop of Meath, who sees all this as clearly as we do, in pointing out to the clergy and laity of his diocese * * Letter addressed to the Clergy and Laity of the Diocese of Meath, Ireland, April 2, 1881: OPEN LETTER TO POPE LEO XIII. 21 the design of Divine Providence that the rent of land should be taken for the community, says: “I think, therefore, that I may fairly infer, on the strength of authority as well as of reason, that the people are and always must be the real owners of the land of their country. This great social fact appears to me to be of incalculable importance, and it is fortunate, indeed, that on the strictest principles of justice it is not clouded even by a shadow of uncertainty or doubt. There is, moreover, a charm and a peculiar beauty in the clearness with which it reveals the wisdom and the benevolence of the designs of Providence in the admirable provision He has made for the wants and the necessities of that state of social existence of which He is author, and in which the very instincts of nature tell us we are to spend our lives. A vast public property, a great national fund, has been placed under the dominion and at the disposal of the nation to supply itself abundantly with resources necessary to liquidate the expenses of its government, the administration of its laws and the education of its youth, and to enable it to provide for the suitable sustentation and support of its criminal and pauper population. One of the most interesting peculiarities of this property is that its value is never stationary; it is constantly progressive and increasing in a direct ratio to the growth of the population, and the very causes that increase and multiply the demands made on it increase proportion- ately its ability to meet them.” There is, indeed, as Bishop Nulty says, a peculiar beauty in the clearness with which the wisdom and benevolence of Providence are revealed in this great social fact, the provision made for the common needs of society in what economists call the law of rent. Of all the evidence that natural religion gives, it is this that most clearly shows the existence of a 22 THE CONDITION OF LABOR. beneficent God, and most conclusively silences the doubts that in our days lead so many to materialism. For in this beautiful provision made by natural law for the social needs of civilization we see that God has intended civilization; that all our discoveries and inventions do not and cannot outrun. His forethought, and that steam, electricity and labor saving appliances only make the great moral laws clearer and more important. In the growth of this great fund, increasing with Social advance—a fund that accrues from the growth of the community and belongs therefore to the community—we see not only that there is no need for the taxes that lessen wealth, that engender corrup- tion, that promote inequality and teach men to deny the gospel; but that to take this fund for the purpose for which it was evidently intended would in the highest civilization secure to all the equal enjoyment of God’s bounty, the abundant opportunity to satisfy their wants, and would provide amply for every legitimate need of the state. We see that God in His dealings with men has not been a bungler or a niggard; that He has not brought too many men into the world; that He has not neglected abundantly to supply them; that He has not intended that bitter competition of the masses for a mere animal existence and that monstrous aggregation of wealth which characterize our civilization; but that these evils which lead so many to say there is no God, or yet more impiously to say that they are of God's ordering, are due to our denial of His moral law. We see that the law of justice, the law of the Golden Rule, is not a mere counsel of perfection, but indeed the law of social life. We see that if we were only to observe it OPEN LETTER, TO POPE LEO XIII. 23 there would be work for all, leisure for all, abundance for all; and that civilization would tend to give to the poorest not only necessaries, but all comforts and reasonable luxuries as well. We see that Christ was not a mere dreamer when He told men that if they would seek the kingdom of God and its right doing they might no more worry about material things than do the lilies of the field about their raiment; but that He was only declaring what political economy in the light of modern discovery shows to be a sober truth. Your Holiness, even to see this is deep and lasting joy. For it is to see for one’s self that there is a God who lives and reigns, and that He is a God of justice and love—Our Father who art in Heaven. It is to open a rift of sunlight through the clouds of our darker questionings, and to make the faith that trusts where it cannot see a living thing. II. Your Holiness will see from the explanation I have given that the reform we propose, like all true re- forms, has both an ethical and an economic side. By ignoring the ethical side, and pushing our proposal merely as a reform of taxation, we could avoid the objections that arise from confounding ownership with possession and attributing to private property in land that security of use and improvement that can be had even better without it. All that we seek practi- cally is the legal abolition, as fast as possible, of taxes on the products and processes of labor, and the con. sequent concentration of taxation on land values irrespective of improvements. To put our proposals 24 THE CONDITION OF LABOR. in this way would be to urge them merely as a matter of wise public expediency. There are indeed many single tax men who do put our proposals in this way; who seeing the beauty of our plan from a fiscal standpoint do not concern them- selves farther. But to those who think as I do, the ethical is the more important side. Not only do we not wish to evade the question of private property in land, but to us it seems that the beneficent and far- reaching revolution we aim at is too great a thing to be accomplished by “intelligent self-interest,” and can be carried by nothing less than the religious con- Science. Hence we earnestly seek the judgment of religion. This is the tribunal of which your Holiness as the head of the largest body of Christians is the most august representative. It therefore behooves us to examine the reasons you urge in support of private property inland—if they. be sound to accept them, and if they be not sound respectfully to point out to you wherein is their error. To your proposition that “Our first and most fun- damental principle when we undertake to alleviate the condition of the masses must be the inviolability of private property” we would joyfully agree if we could only understand you to have in mind the moral element, and to mean rightful private property, as when you speak of marriage as ordained by God’s authority we may understand an implied exclusion of improper marriages. Unfortunately, however, other expressions show that you mean private property in general and have expressly in mind private property in land. This confusion of thought, this non-distri- OPEN LETTER TO POPE LEO XIII. 25 bution of terms, runs through your whole argument, leading you to conclusions so unwarranted by your premises as to be utterly repugnant to them, as when from the moral sanction of private property in the things produced by labor you infer something entirely different and utterly opposed, a similar right of pro- perty in the land created by God. Private property is not of one species, and moral sanction can no more be asserted universally of it than of marriage. That proper marriage conforms to the law of God does not justify the polygamic, or poly- andric or incestuous marriages that are in some countries permitted by the civil law. And as there may be immoral marriage so may there be im- moral private property. Private property is that which may be held in ownership by an individual, or that which may be held in ownership by an individual with the sanction of the state. The mere lawyer, the mere servant of the state, may rest here, refusing to distinguish between what the state holds equally law- ful. Your Holiness, however, is not a servant of the state, but a servant of God, a guardian of morals. You know, as said by St. Thomas of Aquin, that “Human law is law only in virtue of its accordance with right reason and it is thus manifest that it flows from the eternal law. And in so far as it deviates from right reason it is called an unjust law. In such case it is not law at all, but rather a species of violence.” Thus, that any species of property is permitted by he state does not of itself give it moral sanction. The state has often made things property that are not justly property, but involve violence and robbery. 26 THE CONDITION OF LABOR. For instance, the things of religion, the dignity and authority of offices of the church, the power of ad- ministering her Sacraments and controlling her tempo- ralities have often by profligate princes been given as Salable property to courtiers and concubines. At this very day in England an atheist or a heathen may buy in open market, and hold as legal property, to be Sold, given or bequeathed as he pleases, the power of appointing to the cure of Souls, and the value of these legal rights of presentation is said to be no less than 4217,000,000. . Or again: Slaves were universally treated as property by the customs and laws of the classical nations, and were so acknowledged in Europe long after the ac- ceptance of Christianity. At the beginning of this century there was no Christian nation that did not, in her colonies at least, recognize property in slaves, and slave ships crossed the seas under Christian flags. In the United States, little more than thirty years ago, to buy a man gave the same legal ownership as to buy a horse, and in Mohammedan countries law and custom yet make the slave the property of his captor or purchaser. - Yet your Holiness, one of the glories of whose pontificate is the attempt to break up slavery in its last strongholds, will not contend that the moral sanction that attaches to property in things produced by labor can, or ever could, apply to property in slaves. Your use, in so many passages of your Encyclical, of the inclusive term “property” or “private” property, of which in morals nothing can be either affirmed or denied, makes your meaning, if we take isolated sentences, in many places ambiguous. But reading OPEN LETTER TO POPE LEO XIII. 27 it as a whole, there can be no doubt of your intention that private property in land shall be understood when you speak merely of private property. With this interpretation, I find that the reasons you urge for private property in land are eight. Let us consider them in order of presentation. You urge: 1. That what is bought with rightful property is nightful property. (5.)* Clearly, purchase and sale cannot give, but can only transfer ownership. Property that in itself has no moral sanction does not obtain moral sanction by passing from seller to buyer. - If right reason does not make the slave the property of the slave hunter it does not make him the property of the slave buyer. Yet your reasoning as to private property in land would as well justify property in slaves. To show this it is only needful to change in your argument the word land to the word slave. It would then read : “It is surely undeniable that when a man engages in remunerative labor the very reason and motive of his work is to obtain property, and to hold it in his own private possession. “If one man hire out to another his strength or his industry he does this for the purpose of receiving in return what is necessary for food and living; he thereby expressly proposes to acquire a full and legal right, not only to the remuneration, but also to the disposal of that remuneration as he pleases. “Thus, if he lives sparingly, saves money and invests his savings for greater security in a slave, the slave in * To facilitate references the paragraphs of the Encyclical are indicated by number. ! 28 THE CONDITION OF LABOR. such a case is only his wages in another form; and con- sequently a workingman’s slave thus purchased should be as completely at his own disposal as the wages he receives for his labor.” Nor in turning your argument for private property in land into an argument for private property in men am I doing a new thing. In my own country, in my own time, this very argument, that purchase gave ownership, was the common defense of slavery. It was made by statesmen, by jurists, by clergymen, by bishops; it was accepted over the whole country by the great mass of the people. By it was justified the separation of wives from husbands, of children from parents, the compelling of labor, the appropriation of its fruits, the buying and selling of Christians by Christians. In language almost identical with yours it was asked, “Here is a poor man who has worked hard, lived sparingly, and invested his savings in a few slaves. Would you rob him of his earnings by liberating those slaves?” Or it was said: “Here is a poor widow; all her husband has been able to leave her is a few negroes, the earnings of his hard toil. Would you rob the widow and the orphan by freeing these negroes?” And because of this perversion of reason, this confounding of unjust property rights with just property rights, this acceptance of man's law as though it were God’s law, there came on our nation a judgment of fire and blood. The error of our people in thinking that what in itself was not rightfully property could become rightful property by purchase and sale is the same error into which your Holiness falls. It is not merely formally the same; it is essentially the same. Private property OPEN LETTER TO POPIE 1,EO XIII. 29 in land, no less than private property in slaves, is a violation of the true rights of property. They are different forms of the same robbery; twin devices by which the perverted ingenuity of man has sought to enable the strong and the cunning to escape God's requirement of labor by forcing it on others. What difference does it make whether I merely own the land on which another man must live or own the man himself? Am I not in the one case as much his master as in the other ? Can I not compel him to work for me? Can I not take to myself as much of the fruits of his labor; as fully dictate his actions? Have I not over him the power of life and death? For to deprive a man of land is as certainly to kill him as to deprive him of blood by opening his veins, or of air by tightening a halter around his neck. The essence of slavery is in empowering one man to obtain the labor of another without recompense. Private property in land does this as fully as chattel slavery. The slave owner must leave to the slave enough of his earnings to enable him to live. Are there not in so called free countries great bodies of workingmen who get no more ? How much more of the fruits of their toil do the agricultural laborers of Italy and England get than did the slaves of our Southern States? Did not private property in land permit the land owner of Europe in ruder times to demand the jus prima noctis & Does not the same last outrage exist to-day in diffused form in the immorality born of monstrous wealth on the one hand and ghastly poverty on the other ? In what did the slavery of Russia consist but in giv- 30 THE CONIDITION OF f, ABOR. ing to the master land on which the serf was forced to live 2 When an Ivan or a Catherine enriched their favorites with the labor of others they did not give men, they gave land. And when the appropriation of land has gone so far that no free land remains to which the landless man may turn, then without further violence the more insidious form of labor robbery involved in priv- ate property in land takes the place of chattel slavery, because more economical and convenient. For under it the slave does not have to be caught or held, or to be fed when not needed. He comes of himself, begging the privilege of serving, and when no longer wanted can be discharged. The lash is unnecessary; hunger is as efficacious. This is why the Norman con. querors of England and the English conquerors of Ireland did not divide up the people, but divided the land. This is why European slave ships took their cargoes to the New World, not to Europe. Slavery is not yet abolished. Though in all Christian countries its ruder form has now gone, it still exists in the heart of our civilization in more insidious form, and is increasing. There is work to be done for the glory of God and the liberty of man by other soldiers of the cross than those warrior monks whom, with the blessing of your Holiness, Cardinal Lavigerie is send- ing into the Sahara. Yet, your Encyclical employs in defense of one form of slavery the same fallacies that the apologists for chattel slavery used in defense of the other The Arabs are not wanting in acumen. Your Encyclical reaches far. What shall your warrior monks say, if when at the muzzle of their rifles they demand of some Arab slave merchant his miserable OPEN LETTER TO POPE LBO XIII. 31 caravan, he shall declare that he bought them with his savings, and producing a copy of your Encyclical, shall prove by your reasoning that his slaves are conse- quently “only his wages in another form,” and ask if they who bear your blessing and own your authority propose to “deprive him of the liberty of disposing of his wages and thus of all hope and possibility of increasing his stock and bettering his condition in life 2 ” 2. That private property in land proceeds from man's gift of reason. (6–7.) In the second place your Holiness argues that man possessing reason and forethought may not only ac- Quire ownership of the fruits of the earth, but also of the earth itself, so that out of its products he may make provision for the future. Reason, with its attendant forethought, is indeed the distinguishing attribute of man ; that which raises him above the brute, and shows, as the Scriptures de clare, that he is created in the likeness of God. And this gift of reason does, as your IIoliness points out, involve the need and right of private property in whatever is produced by the exertion of reason and its attendant forethought, as well as in what is pro- duced by physical labor. In truth, these elements of man's production are inseparable, and labor involves the use of reason. It is by his reason that man differs from the animals in being a producer, and in this sense a maker. Of themselves his physical powers are slight, forming as it were but the connection by which the mind takes hold of material things, so as to utilize to its will the mott ºr and forces of nature. It 32 THE CONDITION OF LABOR. is mind, the intelligent reason, that is the prime mover in labor, the essential agent in production. The right of private ownership does therefore in- disputably attach to things provided by man’s reason and forethought. But it cannot attach to things pro- vided by the reason and forethought of God! To illustrate: Let us suppose a company travelling through the desert as the Israelites travel ed from Egypt. Such of them as had the forethought to provide themselves with vessels of water would ac- quire a just right of property in the water so carried, and in the thirst of the waterless desert those who had neglected to provide themselves, though they might ask water from the provident in charity, could not de- mand it in right. For while water itself is of the providence of God, the presence of this water in such vessels, at such place, results from the providence of the men who carried it. Thus they have to it an ex- clusive right. But suppose others use their forethought in push- ing ahead and appropriating the springs, refusing when their fellows come up to let them drink of the water save as they buy it of them. Would such forethought give any right 2 Your Holiness, it is not the forethought of carrying water where it is needed, but the forethought of seiz- ing springs, that you seek to defend in defending the private ownership of land Let me show this more fully, since it may be worth while to meet those who say that if private property in land be not just, then private property in the products of labor is not just, as the material of these products is taken from land. It will be seen on con- O1215 N LETTER TO POPE LEO XIII. 33 sideration that all of man's production is analogous to such transportation of water as we have supposed. In growing grain, or smelting metals, or building houses, or weaving cloth, or doing any of the things that con- stitute producing, all that man does is to change in place or form pre-existing matter. As a producer man is merely a changer, not a creator; God alone creates. And since the changes in which man's pro- duction consists inhere in matter so long as they per- sist, the right of private ownership attaches the accident to the essence, and gives the right of owner- ship in that natural material in which the labor of production is embodied. Thus water, which in its original form and place is the common gift of God to all men, when drawn from its natural reservoir and brought into the desert, passes rightfully into the ownership of the individual who by changing its place has produced it there. But such right of ownership is in reality a mere right of temporary possession. For though man may take material from the storehouse of nature and change it in place or form to suit his desires, yet from the moment he takes it, it tends back to that storehouse again. Wood decays, iron rusts, stone disintegrates and is displaced, while of more perishable products, some will last for only a few months, others for only a few days, and some disappear immediately on use. Though, so far as we can see, matter is eternal and force forever persists; though we can neither annihi- late nor create the tiniest mote that floats in a sun- beam or the faintest impulse that stirs a leaf, yet in the ceaseless flux of nature, man's work of moving and com- bining constantly passes away. Thus the recognition 34 THE CONDITION OF LABOR. of the ownership of what natural material is embodied in the products of man never constitutes more than temporary possession—never interferes with the reservoir provided for all. As taking water from one place and carrying it to another place by no means lessens the store of water, since whether it is drunk or spilled or left to evaporate, it must return again to the natural reservoirs—so is it with all things on which man in production can lay the impress of his labor. Hence, when you say that man’s reason puts it within his right to have in stable and permanent pos- session not only things that perish in the using, but also those that remain for use in the future, you are right in so far as you may include such things as buildings, which with repair will last for generations, with such things as food or firewood, which are de- stroyed in the use. But when you infer that man can have private ownership in those permanent things of nature that are the reservoirs from which all must draw, you are clearly wrong. Man may indeed hold In private ownership the fruits of the earth produced by his labor, since they lose in time the impress of that labor, and pass again into the natural reservoirs from which they were taken, and thus the ownership of them by one works no injury to others. But he cannot so own the earth itself, for that is the reservoir from which must constantly be drawn not only the material with which alone men can produce, but even their very bodies. The conclusive reason why man cannot claim owner- ship in the earth itself as he can in the fruits that he by labor brings forth from it, is in the facts stated OPEN LETTER TO POP15. DEO XIII. 35 by you in the very next paragraph (7), when you truly say: “Man’s needs do not die out, but recur; satisfied to-day they demand new supplies to-morrow. Mature therefore owes to man a storehouse that shall never fail, the daily supply of his daily wants. And this he finds only in the inexhaustible fertility of the earth.” By man you mean all men. Can what nature owes to all men be made the private property of some men, from which they may debar all other men? Let me dwell on the words of your Holiness, “Wature, therefore, owes to man a storehouse that shall never fail.” By Nature you mean God. Thus your thought, that in creating us, God himself has incurred an obligation to provide us with a storehouse that shall never fail, is the same as is thus expressed and carried to its irresistible conclusion by the Bishop of Meath : “God was perfectly free in the act by which He created us; but having created us He bound himself by that act to provide us with the means necessary for our subsistence. The land is the only source of this kind now known to us. The land, therefore, of every country is the common property of the people of that country, because its real owner, the Creator who made it, has transferred it as a voluntary gift to them. ‘Terram autem dedit filiis hominum.” Now, as every individual in that country is a creature and child of God, and as all His creatures are equal in His sight, any settlement of the land of a country that would exclude the humblest man in that country from his share of the common inheritance would be not only an injustice and a wrong to that man, but, moreover, be AN IMPIOUS RESISTANCE TO THE BENEvol.INT INTEN- TIONS OF HIS CREATOR.” 36 THE CONDITION OF LAROR. 3. That private property in land deprives no one of the use of land. (8.) Your own statement that land is the inexhaustible storehouse that God owes to man must have aroused in your Holiness's mind an uneasy questioning of its appropriation as private property, for, as though to reassure yourself, you proceed to argue that its ownership by some will not injure others. You say in substance, that even though divided among private owners the earth does not cease to minister to the needs of all, since those who do not possess the soil can by selling their labor obtain in payment the produce of the land. g Suppose that to your Holiness as a judge of morals one should put this case of conscience: “I am one of several children to whom Our father left a field abundant for our support. As he assigned no part of it to any one of us in particular, leaving the limits of our separate possession to be fixed by ourselves, I being the eldest took the whole field in exclusive ownership. But in doing so I have not de- prived my brothers of their support from it, for I have let them work for me on it, paying them from the produce as much wages as I would have had to pay strangers. Is there any reason why my con- science should not be clear?” What would be your answer? Would you not tell him that he was in mortal sin, and that his excuse added to his guilt? Would you not call on him to make restitution and to do penance % Or, suppose that as a temporal prince your Holi. ness were ruler of a rainless land, such as Egypt, where there were no springs or brooks, their want being supplied by a bountiful river like the Nile, OPEN LETTER TO POPE LEO XIII. 37 Supposing that having sent a number of your subjects to make fruitful this land, bidding them do justly and prosper, you were told that some of them had set up a claim of ownership in the river, refusing the others a drop of water, except as they bought it of them ; and that thus they had become rich without work, while the others, though working hard, were so im- poverished by paying for water as to be hardly able to exist? Would not your indignation wax hot when this was told 3 Suppose that then the river owners should send to you and thus excuse their action: “The river, though divided among private owners ceases not thereby to minister to the needs of all, for there is no one who drinks who does not drink of the water of the river. Those who do not possess the water of the river contribute their labor to get it; so that it may be truly said that all water is supplied either from one’s own river, or from some laborious industry which is paid for either in the water, or in that which is exchanged for the water.” Would the indignation of your Holiness be abated . Would it not wax fiercer yet for the insult to your intelligence of this excuse? I do not need more formally to show your Holiness that between utterly depriving a man of God’s gifts and depriving him of God's gifts unless he will buy them, is merely the difference between the robber who leaves his victim to die and the robber who puts him to ransom. But I would like to point out how your statement that “the earth though divided among private owners ceases not thereby to minister to the needs of all” overlooks the largest facts, 38 . THE CONDITION OF LABOR. From your palace of the Vatican the eye may rest on the expanse of the Campagna, where the pious toil of religious congregations and the efforts of the state are only now beginning to make it possible for men to live. Once that expanse was tilled by thriving husbandmen and dotted with smiling hamlets. What for centuries has condemned it to desertion ? History tells us. It was private property in land; the growth of the great estates of which Pliny saw that ancient Italy was perishing; the cause that, by bringing failure to the crop of men, let in the Goths and Van- dals, gave Roman Britain to the worship of Odin and Thor, and in what were once the rich and populous provinces of the East shivered the thinned ranks and palsied arms of the legions on the cimiters of Moham- medan hordes, and in the sepulchre of our Lord and in the Church of St. Sophia trampled the cross to rear the crescent If you will go to Scotland, you may see great tracts that under the Gaelic tenure, which recognized the right of each to a foothold in the soil, bred sturdy men, but that now, under the recognition of private property in land, are given up to wild animals. If you go to Ireland, your Bishops will show you, on lands where now only beasts graze, the traces of hamlets that when they were young priests, were filled with honest, kindly, religious people.* * Let any one who wishes visit this diocese and see with his own eyes the vast and boundless extent of the fairest land in Europe that has been ruthlessly depopulated since the commencement of the present century, and which is now abandoned to a loneliness and solitude more depressing than that of the prairie or the wilderness. Thus has this land system actually exercised the power of life and death on a vast scale, for which there is no parallel even in the dark records of slavery.—Bishop Wully's letter to the Clergy and Laity of the Diocese of Meath, OPEN LETTER TO POPE LEO XIII. 39 If you will come to the United States, you will find in a land wide enough and rich enough to support in comfort the whole population of Europe, the growth of a sentiment that looks with evil eye on immigration, because the artificial scarcity that results from pri- vate property in land makes it seem as if there is not room enough and work enough for those already here. Or go to the Antipodes, and in Australia as in Eng- land, you may see that private property in land is operating to leave the land barren and to crowd the bulk of the population into great cities. Go wherever you please where the forces loosed by modern invention are beginning to be felt and you may see that private property in land is the curse, denounced by the prophet, that prompts men to lay field to field till they “alone dwell in the midst of the earth.” To the mere materialist this is sin and shame. Shall we to whom this world is God’s world—we who hold that man is called to this life only as a prelude to a higher life—shall we defend it 4. That Industry expended on land gives owner- ship in the land itself. (9–10) Your Holiness next contends that industry expended on land gives a right to ownership of the land, and that the improvement of land creates benefits indis- tinguishable and inseparable from the land itself. This contention, if valid, could only justify the ownership of land by those who expend industry on it. It would not justify private property in land as it exists. On the contrary, it would justify a gigantic no-rent declaration that would take land 40 THE CONDITION OF LABOR. from those who now legally own it, the landlords, and turn it over to the tenants and laborers. And if it also be that improvements cannot be distinguished and separated from the land itself, how could the landlords claim consideration even for improvements they had made 2 But your Holiness cannot mean what your words imply. What you really mean, I take it, is that the original justification and title of land ownership is in the expenditure of labor on it. But neither can this justify private property in land as it exists. For is it not all but universally true that existing land titles do not come from use, but from force or fraud? Take Italy | Is it not true that the greater part of the land of Italy is held by those who so far from ever having expended industry on it have been mere appropriators of the industry of those who have 7 Is this not also true of Great Britain and of other countries? Even in the United States, where the forces of concentration have not yet had time to fully operate and there has been some attempt to give land to users, it is probably true to-day that the greater part of the land is held by those who neither use it nor propose to use it themselves, but merely hold it to compel others to pay them for permission to use it. And if industry give ownership to land what are the limits of this ownership ! If a man may acquire the ownership of several square miles of land by grazing sheep on it, does this give to him and his heirs the ownership of the same land when it is found to con- tain rich mines, or when by the growth of population and the progress of society it is needed for farming, for gardening, for the close occupation of a great OPEN LETTER TO POPE LEO XIII. 41 city ? Is it on the rights given by the industry of those who first used it for grazing cows or growing potatoes that you would found the title to the land now covered by the city of New York and having a value of thousands of millions of dollars ? But your contention is not valid. Industry expended On land gives ownership in the fruits of that in- dustry, but not in the land itself, just as industry ex- pended on the ocean would give a right of ownership to the fish taken by it, but not a right of ownership in the ocean. Nor yet is it true that private owner- ship of land is necessary to secure the fruits of labor on land; nor does the improvement of land create benefits indistinguishable and inseparable from the land itself. That secure possession is necessary to the use and improvement of land I have already explained, but that ownership is not necessary is shown by the fact that in all civilized countries land owned by one person is cultivated and improved by other persons. Most of the cultivated land in the British Islands, as in Italy and other countries, is cultivated not by owners but by tenants. And so the costliest buildings are erected by those who are not owners of the land, but who have from the owner a mere right of possession for a time on condition of certain payments. Nearly the whole of London has been built in this way, and in New York, Chicago, Denver, San Francisco, Sydney and Melbourne, as well as in continental cities, the owners of many of the largest edifices will be found to be different persons from the owners of the ground. So far from the value of improvements being inseparable from the value of land, it is in individual transactions constantly separated. For instance, one-half of the 42 THE CONDITION OF LABOR. land on which the immense Grand Pacific Hotel in Chicago stands was recently separately sold, and in Ceylon it is a not infrequent occurrence for one person to own a fruit tree and another to own the ground in which it is implanted. There is, indeed, no improvement of land, whether it be clearing, plowing, manuring, cultivating, the digging of cellars, the opening of wells or the building of houses, that so long as its usefulness continues does not have a value clearly distinguishable from the value of the land. Forland having such improvements will always sell or rent for more than similar land without them. If, therefore, the state levy a tax equal to what the land irrespective of improvement would bring, it will take the benefits of mere ownership, but will leave the full benefits of use and improvement, which the prevailing system does not do. And since the holder, who would still in form continue to be the owner, could at any time give or sell both possession and improvements, subject to future assessment by the state on the value of the land alone, he will be perfectly free to retain or dispose of the full amount of property that the exertion of his labor or the investment of his capital has attached to or stored up in the land. Thus, what we propose would secure, as it is im- possible in any other way to secure, what you properly say is just and right—“that the results of labor should belong to him who has labored.” But private property in land—to allow the holder without adequate payment to the state to take for himself the benefit of the value that attaches to land with social growth and improve- ment—does take the results of labor from him who OPEN LETTER TO POPE LEO XIII. 43 has labored, does turn over the fruits of one man’s labor to be enjoyed by another. For labor, as the active factor, is the producer of all wealth. Mere ownership produces nothing. A man might own a world, but so sure is the decree that “by the sweat of thy brow shalt thou eat bread,” that without labor he could not get a meal or provide himself a garment. Hence, when the owners of land, by virtue of their ownership and without laboring themselves, get the products of labor in abundance, these things must come from the labor of others, must be the fruits of others’ sweat, taken from those who have a right to them and enjoyed by those who have no right to them. The only utility of private ownership of land as dis- tinguished from possession is the evil utility of giving to the owner products of labor he does not earn. For until land will yield to its owner some return beyond that of the labor and capital he expends on it—that is to say, until by sale or rental he can without expendi- ture of labor obtain from it products of labor, owner- ship amounts to no more than security of possession, and has no value. Its importance and value begin only when, either in the present or prospectively, it will yield a revenue—that is to say, will enable the owner as owner to obtain products of labor without exertion on his part, and thus to enjoy the results of others’ labor. What largely keeps men from realizing the robbery involved in private property in land is that in the most striking cases the robbery is not of individuals, but of the community. For, as I have before explained, it is impossible for rent in the economic sense—that value which attaches to land by reason of social growth and improvement—to go to the user. It can go only to the 44 THE CONDITION OF LABOR. owner or to the community. Thus those who pay enormous rents for the use of land in such centres as London or New York are not individually injured. Individually they get a return for what they pay, and must feel that they have no better right to the use of such peculiarly advantageous localities without paying for it than have thousands of others. And so, not thinking or not caring for the interests of the com- munity, they make no objection to the system. It recently came to light in New York that a man having no title whatever had been for years collecting rents on a piece of land that the growth of the city had made very valuable. Those who paid these rents had never stopped to ask whether he had any right to them. They felt that they had no right to land that so many others would like to have, without paying for it, and did not think of, or did not care for, the rights of all. 5. That private property in land has the support of the common opinion of mankind, and has conduced to peace and tranquility, and that it is sanctioned by Divine Law. (11.) Even were it true that the common opinion of man- kind has sanctioned private property in land, this would no more prove its justice than the once universal prac- tice of the known world would have proved the justice of slavery. But it is not true. Examination will show that wherever we can trace them the first perceptions of mankind have always recognized the equality of right to land, and that when individual possession became necessary to secure the right of ownership in things produced by labor some method of securing equality, OP15)N LETTER TO POPE LEO XIII. 45 sufficient in the existing state of social development, was adopted. Thus, among some peoples, land used for cultivation was periodically divided, land used for pasturage and wood being held in common. Among others, every family was permitted to hold what land it needed for a dwelling and for cultivation, but the moment that such use and cultivation stopped any one else could step in and take it on like tenure. Of the same nature were the land laws of the Mosaic code. The land, first fairly divided among the people, was made inalienable by the provision of the jubilee, under which, if sold, it reverted every fiftieth year to the children of its original possessors. Private property in land as we know it, the attach- ing to land of the same right of ownership that justly attaches to the products of labor, has never grown up anywhere save by usurpation or force. Like slavery, it is the result of war. It comes to us of the modern world from your ancestors, the Romans, whose civili- zation it corrupted and whose empire it destroyed. It made with the freer spirit of the northern peoples the combination of the feudal system, in which, though subordination was substituted for equal- ity, there was still a rough recognition of the principle of common rights in land. A fief was a trust, and to enjoyment was annexed some obligation. The sover- eign, the representative of the whole people, was the only owner of land. Of him, immediately or medi- ately, held tenants, whose possession involved duties or payments, which, though rudely and imperfectly, embodied the idea that we would carry out in the single tax, of taking land values for public uses. The crown lands maintained the sovereign and the civil 46 THE CONDITION OF LABOR. list; the church lands defrayed the cost of public wor- ship and instruction, of the relief of the sick, the destitute and the wayworn ; while the military tenures provided for public defense and bore the costs of war. A fourth and very large portion of the land remained in common, the people of the neighborhood being free to pasture it, cut wood on it, or put it to other common UlSeS. In this partial yet substantial recognition of common rights to land is to be found the reason why, in a time when the industrial arts were rude, wars frequent, and the great discoveries and inventions of our time unthought of, the condition of the laborer was devoid of that grinding poverty which despite our marvellous advances now exists. Speaking of England, the highest authority on such subjects, the late Professor Thorold Rogers, declares that in the thirteenth century there was no class so poor, so helpless, so pressed and degraded as are millions of Englishmen in our boasted nineteenth century; and that, save in times of actual famine, there was no laborer so poor as to fear that his wife and children might come to want even were he taken from them. Dark and rude in many respects as they were, these were the times when the cathedrals and churches and religious houses whose ruins yet excite our admiration were built; the times when England had no national debt, no poor law, no standing army, no hereditary paupers, no thousands and thousands of human beings rising in the morning without knowing where they might lay their heads at night. With the decay of the feudal system, the system of private property in land that had destroyed Rome was OPEN LETTER TO POPſ, f, EO XIII. 47 extended. As to England, it may briefly be said that the crown lands were for the most part given away to favorites; that the church lands were parcelled among his courtiers by Henry VIII., and in Scotland grasped by the nobles; that the military dues were finally re- mitted in the seventeenth century, and taxation on consumption substituted; and that by a process be- ginning with the Tudors and extending to our own time all but a mere fraction of the commons were en- closed by the greater land owners; while the same private ownership of land was extended over Ireland and the Scottish Highlands, partly by the sword and partly by bribery of the chiefs. Even the military dues, had they been commuted, not remitted, would to-day have more than sufficed to pay all public ex- penses without one penny of other taxation. Of the New World, whose institutions but continue those of Europe, it is only necessary to say that to the parcelling out of land in great tracts is due the back- wardness and turbulence of Spanish America; that to the large plantations of the Southern States of the Union was due the persistence of slavery there, and that the more northern settlements showed the earlier English feeling, land being fairly well divided and the attempts to establish manorial estates coming to little or nothing. In this lies the secret of the more vigorous growth of the northern states. But the idea that land was to be treated as private property had been thoroughly established in English thought before the colonial period ended, and it has been so treated by the United States and by the several States. And though land was at first sold cheaply, and then given to actual settlers, it was also sold in large 48 THE CON101TION OF DABOR. quantities to speculators, given away in great tracts for railroads and other purposes, until now the public domain of the United States, which a genera- tion ago seemed illimitable, has practically gone. And this, as the experience of other countries shows, is the natural result in a growing community of making land private property. When the possession of land means the gain of unearned wealth, the strong and unscrupulous will secure it. But when, as we propose, economic rent, the “unearned increment of wealth,” is taken by the state for the use of the com- munity, then land will pass into the hands of users and remain there, since no matter how great its value, its possession will only be profitable to users. S. As to private property in land having conduced to the peace and tranquility of human life, it is not neces- sary more than to allude to the notorious fact that the struggle for land has been the prolific source of wars and of law suits, while it is the poverty en- gendered by private property in land that make the prison and the workhouse the unfailing attributes of what we call Christian civilization. Your Holiness intimates that the Divine Law gives its sanction to the private ownership of land, quoting from Deuteronomy, “Thou shalt not covet thy neigh- bor’s wife, nor his house, nor his field, nor his man- servant, nor his maid-servant, nor his ox, nor his ass, nor anything which is his.” If, as your IIoliness conveys, this inclusion of the words, “nor his field,” is to be taken as sanctioning private property in land as it exists to-day, then, but with far greater force, must the words, “his man- servant, nor his maid-servant,” be taken to Sanction OPTEN LETTER TO POPE LEO XIII. 49 chattel slavery; for it is evident from other provisions of the same code that these terms referred both to bondsmen for a term of years and to perpetual slaves. But the word “field” involves the idea of use and improvement, to which the right of possession and ownership does attach without recognition of prop- erty in the land itself. And that this reference to the “field” is not a sanction of private property in land as it exists to-day is proved by the fact that the Mosaic code expressly denied such unqualified owner- ship in land, and with the declaration, “the land also shall not be sold forever, because it is mine, and you are strangers and sojourners with me,” provided for its reversion every fiftieth year; thus, in a way adapted to the primitive industrial conditions of the time, securing to all of the chosen people a foothold in the soil. Nowhere in fact throughout the Scriptures can the slightest justification be found for the attaching to land of the same right of property that justly attaches to the things produced by labor. Everywhere is it treated as the free bounty of God, “the land which the Lord thy God giveth thee.” 6. That fathers should provide for their children and that private property in land is necessary to enable them to do so. (14–17.) With all that your Holiness has to say of the Sacredness of the family relation we are in full accord. But how the obligation of the father to the child can justify private property in land we cannot see. You reason that private property in land is necessary to the y 50 THE CONDITION OF LABOR. discharge of the duty of the father, and is therefore requisite and just, because— “It is a most sacred law of nature that a father must provide food and all necessities for those whom he has begotten ; and similarly nature dictates that a man’s children, who carry on as it were and continue his own personality, should be provided by him with all that is needful to enable them honorably to keep themselves from want and misery in the uncertain- ties of this mortal life. Now in no other way can a father effect this except by the ownership of profitable property, which he can transmit to his children by inheritance.” (14.) Thanks to Him who has bound the generations of men together by a provision that brings the tenderest love to greet our entrance into the world and soothes our exit with filial piety, it is both the duty and the joy of the father to care for the child till its powers mature, and afterwards in the natural order it becomes the duty and privilege of the child to be the stay of the parent. This is the natural reason for that rela- tion of marriage, the ground work of the sweetest, tenderest and purest of human joys, which the Catho- lic Church has guarded with such unremitting vigilance. We do, for a few years, need the providence of our fathers after the flesh. But how small, how transient, how narrow is this need, as compared with our constant need for the providence of Him in whom we live, move and have our being—Our Father who art in Heaven It is to Him, “the giver of every good and perfect gift,” and not to our fathers after the flesh, that Christ taught us to pray, “Give us this day our daily bread.” And how true it is that it is through OPEN LETTER TO POPE LEO XIII. 51 Him that the generations of men exist. Let the mean temperature of the earth rise or fall a few degrees, an amount as nothing compared with differences produced in our laboratories, and mankind would disappear as ice disappears under a tropical sun, would fall as the leaves fall at the touch of frost. Or, let for two or three seasons the earth refuse her increase, and how many of our millions would remain alive The duty of fathers to transmit to their children profitable property that will enable them to keep themselves from want and misery in the uncertainties of this mortal lifel What is not possible cannot be a duty. And how is it possible for fathers to do that ? Your Holiness has not considered how mankind really lives from hand to mouth, getting each day its daily bread; how little one generation does or can leave another. It is doubtful if the wealth of the civilized world all told amounts to anything like as much as one year's labor, while it is certain that if labor were to stop and men had to rely on existing accumulation, it would be only a few days ere in the richest countries pestilence and famine would stalk. The profitable property your Holiness refers to, is private property in land. Now profitable land, as all economists will agree, is land superior to the land that the ordinary man can get. It is land that will yield an income to the owner as owner, and therefore that will permit the owner to appropriate the products of labor without doing labor, its profitableness to the individual involving the robbery of other individuals. It is there- fore possible only for some fathers to leave their chil- dren profitable land. What therefore your Holiness practically declares is, that it is the duty of all fathers 52 THE CONDITION OF LABOR. to struggle to leave their children what only the few peculiarly strong, lucky or unscrupulous can leave ; and that, a something that involves the robbery of others—their deprivation of the material gifts of God. This anti-Christian doctrine has been long in practice throughout the Christian world. What are its results 2 Are they not the very evils set forth in your Encycli- cal ? Are they not, so far from enabling men to keep themselves from want and misery in the uncertainties of this mortal life, to condemn the great masses of men to want and misery that the natural conditions of our mortal life do not entail; to want and misery deeper and more widespread than exist among heathen Savages? Under the regime of private property in land and in the richest countries not five per cent. of fathers are able at their death to leave anything substantial to their children, and probably a large majority do not leave enough to bury them Some few children are left by their fathers richer than it is good for them to be, but the vast majority not only are left nothing by their fathers, but by the system that makes land private property are deprived of the bounty of their Heavenly Father; are compelled to sue others for permission to live and to work, and to toil all their .ives for a pittance that often does not enable them to escape starvation and pauperism. What your Holiness is actually, though of course inadvertently, urging, is that earthly fathers should assume the functions of the IIeavenly Father. It is not the business of one generation to provide the succeeding generation with “all that is needful to enable them honorably to keep themselves from want and misery.” That is God’s business. We no more OPEN LETTER TO POPE LEO XIII. 53 create our children than we create our fathers. It is God who is the Creator of each succeeding generation as fully as of the one that preceded it. And, to recall your own words (7), “Nature [God] therefore owes to man a storehouse that shall never fail, the daily supply of his daily wants. And this he finds only in the inexhaustible fertility of the earth.” What you are now assuming is, that it is the duty of men to provide for the wants of their children by appropri- ating this storehouse and depriving other men's chil- dren of the unfailing supply that God has provided for all. The duty of the father to the child—the duty pos- sible to all fathers | Is it not so to conduct him- self, so to nurture and teach it, that it shall come to manhood with a sound body, well developed mind, habits of virtue, piety and industry, and in a state of society that shall give it and all others free access to the bounty of God, the providence of the All-Father ? In doing this the father would be doing more to secure his children from want and misery than is possible now to the richest of fathers—as much more as the providence of God surpasses that of man. For the justice of God laughs at the efforts of men to circumvent it, and the subtle law that binds humanity together poisons the rich in the sufferings of the poor. Even the few who are able in the general struggle to leave their children wealth that they fondly think will keep them from want and misery in the uncer- tainties of this mortal life—do they succeed ? Does experience show that it is a benefit to a child to place him above his fellows and enable him to think God’s law of labor is not for him : Is not such wealth 54 THE CONDITION OF LABOR. oftener a curse than a blessing, and does not its expecta- tion often destroy filial love and bring dissensions and heart burnings into families? And how far and how long are even the richest and strongest able to exempt their children from the common lot? Nothing is more certain than that the blood of the masters of the world flows to-day in lazzaroni and that the descendants of kings and princes tenant slums and workhouses. But in the state of society we strive for, where the monopoly and waste of God’s bounty would be done away with and the fruits of labor would go to the laborer, it would be within the ability of all to make more than a comfortable living with reasonable labor. And for those who might be crippled or incapacitated, or deprived of their natural protectors and bread winners, the most ample provision could be made out of that great and increasing fund with which God in his law of rent has provided society—not as a matter of niggardly and degrading alms, but as a matter of right, as the assurance which in a Christian state society owes to all its members. Thus it is that the duty of the father, the obligation to the child, instead of giving any support to private property in land, utterly condemnsit, urging us by the . most powerful considerations to abolish it in the simple and efficacious way of the single tax. This duty of the father, this obligation to chil- dren, is not confined to those who have actually chil- dren of their own, but rests on all of us who have come to the powers and responsibilities of manhood. For did not Christ set a little child in the midst of the disciples, saying to them that the angels of such little ones always behold the face of His father; saying OPEN LETTER, TO POPE LEO XIII. 55 to them that it were better for a man to hang a millstone about his neck and plunge into the utter- most depths of the sea than to injure such a little one & And what to-day is the result of private property in land in the richest of so called Christian countries 2 Is it not that young people fear to marry; that married people fear to have children; that children are driven out of life from sheer want of proper nourishment and care, or compelled to toil when they ought to be at school or at play; that great numbers of those who attain maturity enter it with under-nourished bodies, overstrained nerves, undeveloped minds— under conditions that foredoom them, not merely to suffering, but to crime; that fit them in advance for the prison and the brothel ? If your Holiness will consider these things we are confident that instead of defending private property in land you will condemn it with anathema 7. That the private ownership of land stimulates *ndustry, increases wealth, and attaches men to the soil and to their country. (51.) The idea, as expressed by Arthur Young, that “the magic of property turns barren sands to gold’ springs from the confusion of ownership with possession, of which I have before spoken, that attributes to private property in land what is due to security of the products of labor. It is needless for me again to point out that the change we propose, the taxation for public uses of land values, or economic rent, and the aboli- tion of other taxes, would give to the user of land far greater security for the fruits of his labor than the 56 THE CONDITION OF LABOR. present system and far greater permanence of posses- sion. Nor is it necessary further to show how it would give homes to those who are now homeless and bind men to their country. For under it every one who wanted a piece of land for a home or for produc- tive use could get it without purchase price and hold it even without tax, since the tax we propose would not fall on all land, nor even on all land in use, but only on land better than the poorest land in use, and is in reality not a tax at all, but merely a return to the state for the use of a valuable privilege. And even those who from circumstances or occupation did not wish to make permanent use of land would still have an equal interest with all others in the land of their country and in the general prosperity. But I should like your Holiness to consider how utterly unnatural is the condition of the masses in the richest and most progressive of Christian countries; how large bodies of them live in habitations in which a rich man would not ask his dog to dwell; how the great majority have no homes from which they are not liable on the slightest misfortune to be evicted ; how numbers have no homes at all, but must seek what shelter chance or charity offers. I should like to ask your Holiness to consider how the great majority of men in such countries have no interest whatever in what they are taught to call their native land, for which they are told that on occasions it is their duty to fight or to die. What right, for instance, have the majority of your countrymen in the land of their birth? Can they live in Italy outside of a prison or a poor- house except as they buy the privilege from some of the exclusive owners of Italy: Cannot an English. OPEN LETTER TO POPE LEO XIII. ã7 man, an American, an Arab or a Japanese do as much 3 May not what was said centuries ago by Tiberius Gracchus be said to-day : “Men of Rome / you are called the lords of the world, yet have no right to a square foot of its soil / The wild beasts have their dens, but the soldiers of Italy have only water and air /?' What is true of Italy is true of the civilized world— is becoming increasingly true. It is the inevitable effect as civilization progresses of private property in land. 8. That the right to possess private property in land is from Nature, not from man; that the state has no night to abolish it, and that to take the value of land ownership in taxation would be unjust and cruel to the private owner. (51). This, like much else that your Holiness says, is masked in the use of the indefinite terms private property and private owner—a want of precision in the use of words that has doubtless aided in the con- fusion of your own thought. But the context leaves no doubt that by private property you mean private property in land, and by private owner, the private owner of land. The contention, thus made, that private property in land is from nature, not from man, has no other basis than the confounding of ownership with possession and the ascription to property in land of what belongs to its contradictory, property in the proceeds of labor. You do not attempt to show for it any other basis, nor has any one else ever attempted to do so. That private property in the products of labor is from nature is clear, for nature gives such 58 THE CONDITION OF LABOR. things to labor and to labor alone. Of every article of this kind, we know that it came into being as nature's response to the exertion of an individual man or of individual men—given by nature directly and ex- clusively to him or to them. Thus there inheres in such things a right of private property, which originates from and goes back to the source of ownership, the maker of the thing. This right is anterior to the state and superior to its enactments, so that, as we hold, it is a violation of natural right and an injustice to the private owner for the state to tax the processes and products of labor. They do not belong to Caesar. They are things that God, of whom nature is but an expression, gives to those who apply for them in the way. He has appointed—by labor. But who will dare trace the individual ownership of land to any grant from the Maker of land ' What does nature give to such ownership? how does she in any way recognize it? Will any one show from difference of form or feature, of stature or complexion, from dissection of their bodies or analysis of their powers and needs, that one man was intended by nature to own land and another to live on it as his tenant? That which derives its existence from man and passes away like him, which is indeed but the evanescent expression of his labor, man may hold and transfer as the exclusive property of the individual; but how can such individual ownership attach to land, which existed before man was, and which continues to exist while the generations of men come and go—the unfailing storehouse that the Creator gives to man for “the daily supply of his daily wants?” Clearly, the private ownership of land is from the OPEN LETTER TO POPE I,EO XIII. 59 state, not from nature. Thus, not merely can no objection be made on the score of morals when it is proposed that the state shall abolish it altogether, but insomuch as it is a violation of natural right, its exist- ence involving a gross injustice on the part of the state, an “impious violation of the benevolent inten- tion of the Creator,” it is a moral duty that the state so abolish it. So far from there being anything unjust in taking the full value of land ownership for the use of the community, the real injustice is in leaving it in private hands—an injustice that amounts to robbery and murder. And when your Holiness shall see this I have no fear that you will listen for one moment to the impudent plea that before the community can take what God intended it to take, before men who have been disin- herited of their natural rights can be restored to them, the present owners of land shall first be compensated. For not only will you see that the single tax will directly and largely benefit small land owners, whose interests as laborers and capitalists are much greater than their interests as land owners, and that though the great landowners—or rather the propertied class in general among whom the profits of land ownership are really divided through mortgages, rent charges, etc.—would relatively lose, they too would be absolute gainers in the increased prosperity and improved morals; but more quickly, more strongly, more per- emptorily than from any calculation of gains or losses would your duty as a man, your faith as a Christian, forbid you to listen for one moment to any such palter- ing with right and wrong. 60 THE & JNDITION OF LABOR. Where the state takes some land for public uses it is only just that those whose land is taken should be com- pensated, otherwise some land owners would be treated more harshly than others. But where, by a measure affecting all alike, rent is appropriated for the benefit of all, there can be no claim to compensation. Com- pensation in such case would be a continuance of the same injustice in another form—the giving to land owners in the shape of interest of what they before got as rent. Your Holiness knows that justice and in- justice are not thus to be juggled with, and when you fully realize that land is really the storehouse that God owes to all His children, you will no more listen to any demand for compensation for restoring it to them than Moses would have listened to a demand that Pharaoh should be compensated before letting the children of Israel go. Compensated for what? For giving up what has been unjustly taken & The demand of land owners for compensation is not that. We do not seek to spoil the Egyptians. We do not ask that what has been unjustly taken from laborers shall be restored. We are willing that bygones should be bygones and to leave dead wrongs to bury their dead. We propose to let those who by the past appropriation of land value have taken the fruits of labor to retain what they have thus got. We merely propose that for the future such robbery of labor shall cease—that for the fu- ture, not for the past, landholders shall pay to the community the rent that to the community is justly due. OPEN LETTER TO POPE LEO XIII. 61 III. I have said enough to show your Holiness the injus- tice into which you fall in classing us, who in seeking virtually to abolish private property in land seek more fully to secure the true rights of property, with those whom you speak of as socialists, who wish to make all property common. But you also do injustice to the socialists. There are many, it is true, who feeling bitterly the monstrous wrongs of the present distribution of wealth are animated only by a blind hatred of the rich and a fierce desire to destroy existing social adjustments. This class is indeed only less dangerous than those who proclaim that no social improvement is needed or is possible. But it is not fair to confound with them those who, however mistakenly, propose definite schemes of remedy. The socialists, as I understand them, and as the term has come to apply to anything like a definite theory and not to be vaguely and improperly used to include all who desire Social improvement, do not, as you imply, seek the abolition of all private property. Those who do this are properly called communists. What the socialists seek is the state assumption of capital (in which they vaguely and erroneously include land), or more properly speaking, of large capitals, and state management and direction of at least the larger operations of industry. In this way they hope to abolish interest, which they regard as a wrong and an evil; to do away with the gains of ex- changers, speculators, contractors and middlemen, which they regard as waste; to do away with the wage system and Secure general co-operation; and 62 THE CONDIT ION OF LABOR. to prevent competition, which they deem the fundamental cause of the impoverishment of labor. The more moderate of them, without going so far, go in the same direction, and seek some remedy or palliation of the worst forms of poverty by govern- ment regulation. The essential character of socialism is that it looks to the extension of the functions of the state for the remedy of social evils; that it would substitute regulation and direction for competition; and intelligent control by organized society for the free play of individual desire and effort. Though not usually classed as Socialists, both the trades unionists and the protectionists have the same essential character. The trades unionists seek the increase of wages, the reduction of working hours and the general improvement in the condition of wage- workers, by organizing them into guilds or associa- tions which shall fix the rates at which they will sell their labor; shall deal as one body with employers in case of dispute; shall use on Occasion their necessary weapon, the strike; and shall accumulate funds for such purposes and for the purpose of assisting mem- bers when on a strike, or (sometimes) when out of em- ployment. The protectionists seek by governmental prohibitions or taxes on imports to regulate the in dustry and control the exchanges of each country, so, as they imagine, to diversify home industries and pre- vent the competition of people of other countries. At the opposite extreme are the anarchists, a term which, though frequently applied to mere vio- lent destructionists, refers also to those who, seeing the many evils of too much government, regard govern- ment in itself as evil, and believe that in the absence OPEN LETTER TO POPE LEO XIII. 63 of coercive power the mutual interests of men would secure voluntarily what co-operation is needed. Differing from all these are those for whom I would speak. Believing that the rights of true property are sacred, we would regard forcible communism as robbery that would bring destruction. But we would not be disposed to deny that voluntary communism might be the highest possible state of which men can conceive. Nor do we say that it cannot be possible" for mankind to attain it, since among the early Christians and among the religious orders of the Catholic church we have examples of communistic societies on a small scale. St. Peter and St. Paul, St. Thomas of Aquin and Fra Angelico, the illus. trious orders of the Carmelites and Franciscans, the Jesuits, whose heroism carried the cross among the most savage tribes of American forests, the societies that wherever your communion is known have deemed no work of mercy too dangerous or too re- pellent—were or are communists. Knowing these things we cannot take it on ourselves to say that a social condition may not be possible in which an all- embracing love shall have taken the place of all other motives. But we see that communism is only possible where there exists a general and intense re- ligious faith, and we see that such a state can be reached only through a state of justice. For before a man can be a saint he must first be an honest man. With both anarchists and socialists, we, who for want of a better term have come to call ourselves single tax men, fundamentally differ. We regard them as err- ing in opposite directions—the one in ignoring the social nature of man, the other in ignoring his individual 64 THE CONDITION OF LABOR. nature. While we see that man is primarily an individual, and that nothing but evil has come or can come from the interference by the state with things that belong to individual action, we also see that he is a social being, or, as Aristotle called him, a political animal, and that the state is requisite to social advance, having an indispensable place in the natural order. Looking ou the bodily organism as the analogue of the Social organism, and on the proper functions of the state as akin to those that in the human organism are discharged by the conscious intelligence, while the play of individual impulse and interest performs functions akin to those discharged in the bodily organism by the unconscious instincts and involuntary motions, the anarchists seem to us like men who would try to get along without heads and the socialists like men who would try to rule the wonderfully complex and delicate internal relations of their frames by conscious wili. The philosophical anarchists of whom I speak are few in number, and of little practical importance. It is with socialism in its various phases that we have to do battle. With the socialists we have some points of agree- ment, for we recognize fully the social nature of man and believe that all monopolies should be held and gov- erned by the state. In these, and in directions where the general health, knowledge, comfort and con- venience might be improved, we, too, would extend the functions of the state. But it seems to us the vice of socialism in all its de- grees is its want of radicalism, of going to the root. It takes its theories from those who have sought to justify OP1.N. f. ETTER TO POff f, EO XIII. 65 the impoverishment of the masses, and its advocates generally teach the preposterous and degrading doc- trine that slavery was the first condition of labor. It assumes that the tendency of wages to a minimum is the natural law, and seeks to abolish wages; it assumes that the natural result of competition is to grind down workers, and seeks to abolish competition by restrictions, prohibitions and extensions of governing power. Thus mistaking effects for causes, and childishly blaming the stone for hitting it, it wastes strength in striving for remedies that when not worse are futile. Associat- ed though it is in many places with democratic aspira- tion, yet its essence is the same delusion to which the Children of Israel yielded when against the protest of their prophet they insisted on a king; the delusion that has everywhere corrupted democracies and en- throned tyrants—that power over the people can be used for the benefit of the people; that there may be devised machinery that through human agencies will secure for the management of individual affairs more wisdom and more virtue than the people themselves possess. This superficiality and this tendency may be seen in all the phases of socialism. Take, for instance, protectionism. What support it has, beyond the mere selfish desire of sellers to compel buyers to pay them more than their goods are worth, springs from such superficial ideas as that pro- duction, not consumption, is the end of effort; that money is more valuable than money’s worth, and to sell more profitable than to buy; and above all from a desire to limit competition, springing from an unan- alyzing recognition of the phenomena that necessarily } €6 THE CONDITION OF i,A13OR. follow when men who have the need to labor are deprived by monopoly of access to the natural and indispensable element of all labor. Its methods involve the idea that governments can more wisely direct the expenditure of labor and the investment of capital than can laborers and capitalists, and that the men who control governments will use this power for the general good and not in their own interests. They tend to multiply officials, restrict liberty, invent crimes. They promote perjury, fraud and corruption. And they would, were the theory carried to its logical conclusion, destroy civilization and reduce mankind to savagery. Take trades unionism. While within narrow lines trades unionism promotes the idea of the mutuality of interests, and often helps to raise courage and further political education, and while it has enabled limited bodies of workingmen to improve somewhat their condition, and gain, as it were, breathing space, yet it takes no note of the general causes that deter- mine the conditions of labor, and strives for the eleva- tion of only a small part of the great body by means that cannot help the rest. Aiming at the restriction of competition—the limitation of the right to labor, its methods are like those of an army, which even in a righteous cause are subversive of liberty and liable to abuse, while its weapon, the strike, is destructive in its nature, both to combatants and non- combatants, being a form of passive war. To apply the principle of trades unions to all industry, as some dream of doing, would be to enthrall men in a caste System. Or take even such moderate measures as the limita- OPEN LETTER TO POPE LEO XIII. 67 tion of working hours and of the labor of women and children. They are superficial in looking no further than to the eagerness of men and women and little children to work unduly, and in proposing forcibly to restrain overwork while utterly ignoring its cause, the sting of poverty that forces human beings to it. And the methods by which these restraints must be enforced, multiply officials, interfere with personal liberty, tend to corruption, and are liable to abuse. As for thorough going socialism, which is the more to be honored as having the courage of its convictions, it would carry these vices to full expression. Jump- ing to conclusions without effort to discover causes, it fails to see that oppression does not come from the nature of capital, but from the wrong that robs labor of capital by divorcing it from land, and that cre- ates a fictitious capital that is really capitalized monop- oly. It fails to see that it would be impossible for capital to oppress labor were labor free to the natural material of production ; that the wage system in itself springs from mutual convenience, being a form of co-operation in which one of the parties prefers a certain to a contingent result; and that what it calls the “iron law of wages” is not the natural law of wages, but only the law of wages in that unnatural condition in which men are made helpless by being deprived of the materials for life and work. It fails to see that what it mistakes for the evils of competi- tion are really the evils of restricted competition— are due to a one sided competition to which men are forced when deprived of land. While its meth- ods, the organization of men into industrial armies, the direction and control of all production and ex- 68 THE CONDITION OF TABOR. change by governmental or semi-governmental bu- reaus, would, if carried to full expression, mean Egyptian despotism. We differ from the socialists in our diagnosis of the evil and we differ from them as to remedies. We have no fear of capital, regarding it as the natural hand- maiden of labor; we look on Interest in itself as natural and just ; we would set no limit to accumula- tion, nor impose on the rich any burden that is not equally placed on the poor; we see no evil in com- petition, but deem unrestricted competition to be as necessary to the health of the industrial and social organism as the free circulation of the blood is to the health of the bodily organism—to be the agency where- by the fullest co-operation is to be secured. We would simply take for the community what belongs to the community, the value that attaches to land by the growth of the community; leave sacredly to the indi- vidual all that belongs to the individual; and, treat- ing necessary monopolies as functions of the state, abolish all restrictions and prohibitions save those required for public health, safety, morals and con- venience. w But the fundamental difference—the difference I ask your Holiness specially to note, is in this: socialism in all its phases looks on the evils of our civilization as springing from the inadequacy or inharmony of natural relations, which must be artificially organized or improved. In its idea there devolves on the state the necessity of intelligently organizing the industrial relations of men; the construction, as it were, of a great machine whose complicated parts shall properly work together under the direction of human intelligence. OPEN LETTER TO POPE LEO XIII. 69 This is the reason why socialism tends towards atheism. Failing to see the order and symmetry of natural law, it fails to recognize God. On the other hand, we who call ourselves single tax men (a name which expresses merely our practical propositions) see in the social and industrial relations of men not a machine which requires construction, but an organism which needs only to be suffered to grow. We see in the natural social and industrial laws such harmony as we see in the adjustments of the human body, and that as far transcends the power of man’s intelligence to order and direct as it is beyond man's intelligence to order and direct the vital move- ments of his frame. We see in these social and indus- trial laws so close a relation to the moral law as must spring from the same Authorship, and that proves the moral law to be the sure guide of man where his intelli- gence would wander and go astray. Thus, to us, all that is needed to remedy the evils of our time is to do justice and give freedom. This is the reason why our beliefs tend towards, may are indeed the only beliefs consistent with a firm and reverent faith in God, and with the recognition of His law as the Supreme law which men must follow if they would secure prosperity and avoid destruction. This is the reason why to us political economy only serves to show the depth of wisdom in the simple truths which common people heard gladly from the lips of Him of whom it was said with wonder, “Is not this the Carpenter of Nazareth ''” And it is because that in what we propose—the securing to all men of equal natural opportunities for the exercise of their powers and the removal of all legal restriction on the legitimate exercise of those 70 THE CONDITION OF LABOR. powers—we see the conformation of human law to the moral law, that we hold with confidence not merely that this is the sufficient remedy for all the evils you so strikingly portray, but that it is the only possible remedy. Nor is there any other. The organization of man is such, his relations to the world in which he is placed are such—that is to say, the immutable laws of God are such, that it is beyond the power of human in- genuity to devise any way by which the evils born of the injustice that robs men of their birthright can be removed otherwise than by doing justice, by opening to all the bounty that God has provided for all. Since man can live only on land and from land, since land is the reservoir of matter and force from which man's body itself is taken, and on which he must draw for all that he can produce, does it not irresistibly follow that to give the land in ownership to some men and to deny to others all right to it is to divide man- kind into the rich and the poor, the privileged and the helpless? Does it not follow that those who have no rights to the use of land can live only by selling their power to labor to those who own the land 2 Does it not follow that what the socialists call “the iron law of wages,” what the political economists term “the tendency of wages to a minimum,” must take from the landless masses—the mere laborers, who of themselves have no power to use their labor—all the benefits of any possible advance or improvement that does not alter this unjust division of land. For having no power to employ themselves, they must, either as labor Sellers or land renters, compete with one another for permission to labor. This competition with one OPEN LETTER TO POPE LEO XIII. 71 another of men shut out from God’s inexhaustible store- house has no limit but starvation, and must ultimately force wages to their lowest point, the point at which life can just be maintained and reproduction carried OIl. This is not to say that all wages must fall to this point, but that the wages of that necessarily largest stratum of laborers who have only ordinary knowledge, skill and aptitude must so fall. The wages of special classes, who are fenced off from the pressure of competition by peculiar knowledge, skill or other causes, may remain above that ordinary level. Thus, where the ability to read and write is rare its posses- sion enables a man to obtain higher wages than the ordinary laborer. But as the diffusion of education makes the ability to read and write general this advantage is lost. So when a vocation requires special training or skill, or is made difficult of access by artificial restrictions, the checking of competition tends to keep wages in it at a higher level. But as the prog- ress of invention dispenses with peculiar skill, or artificial restrictions are broken down, these higher wages sink to the ordinary level. And so, it is only so long as they are special that such qualities as indus- try, prudence and thrift can enable the ordinary laborer to maintain a condition above that which gives a mere living. Where they become general, the law of competition must reduce the earnings or savings of such qualities to the general level—which, land being monopolized and labor helpless, can be only that at which the next lowest point is the cessation of life. Or, to state the same thing in another way: Land being necessary to life and labor, its owners will be 72 THE CONDITION OF LABOR. able, in return for permission to use it, to obtain from mere laborers all that labor can produce, save enough to enable such of them to maintain life as are wanted by the land owners and their dependents. Thus, where private property in land has divided society into a land owning class and a landless class, there is no possible invention or improvement, whether it be industrial, social or moral, which, so long as it does not affect the ownership of land, can prevent poverty or relieve the general conditions of mere laborers. For whether the effect of any inven- tion or improvement be to increase what labor can produce or to decrease what is required to support the laborer, it can, so soon as it becomes general, result only in increasing the income of the owners of land, without at all benefiting the mere laborers. In no event can those possessed of the mere ordinary power to labor, a power utterly useless without the means necessary to labor, keep more of their earnings than enough to enable them to live. How true this is we may see in the facts of to-day. In our own time invention and discovery have enor- mously increased the productive power of labor, and at the same time greatly reduced the cost of many things ecessary to the support of the laborer. Have these improvements anywhere raised the earnings of the mere laborer ? Have not their benefits mainly gone to the owners of land—enormously increased land values? I say mainly, for some part of the benefit has gone to the cost of monstrous standing armies and warlike preparations; to the payment of interest on great public debts; and, largely disguised as interest on fictitious OPEN LETTER TO POPE LEO XIII. 73 capital, to the owners of monopolies other than that of land. But improvements that would do away with these wastes would not benefit labor; they would sim- ply increase the profits of land owners. Were stand- ing armies and all their incidents abolished, were all monopolies other than that of land done away with, were governments to become models of economy, were the profits of speculators, of middlemen, of all sorts of exchangers saved, were every one to become so strictly honest that no policemen, no courts, no prisons, no precautions against dishonesty would be needed—the result would not differ from that which has followed the increase of productive power. Nay, would not these very blessings bring starva- tion to many of those who now manage to live? Is it not true that if there were proposed to-day, what all Christian men ought to pray for, the complete dis- bandment of all the armies of Europe, the greatest fears would be aroused for the consequences of throw- ing on the labor market so many unemployed laborers? The explanation of this and of similar paradoxes that in our time perplex on every side may be easily seen. The effect of all inventions and improvements that increase productive power, that save waste and economize effort, is to lessen the labor required for a given result, and thus to save labor, so that we speak of them as labor Saving inventions or improvements. Now, in a natural state of society where the rights of all to the use of the earth are acknowledged, labor Saving improvements might go to the very utmost that can be imagined without lessening the demand for men, since in such natural conditions the demand 74. THE • CONDITION OF LABOR. for men lies in their own enjoyment of life and the strong instincts that the Creator has implanted in the human breast. But in that unnatural state of society where the masses of men are disinherited of all but the power to labor when opportunity to labor is given them by others, there the demand for them becomes simply the demand for their services by those who hold this opportunity, and man himself becomes a commodity. Hence, although the natural effect of labor saving improvement is to increase wages, yet in the unnatural condition which private ownership of the land begets, the effect, even of such moral im- provements as the disbandment of armies and the Sav- ing of the labor that vice entails, is by lessening the commercial demand, to lower wages and reduce mere laborers to starvation or pauperism. If labor Saving inventions and improvements could be carried to the very abolition of the necessity for labor, what would be the result 2 Would it not be that land owners could then get all the wealth that the land was capable of producing, and would have no need at all for laborers, who must then either starve or live as pensioners on the bounty of the land owners? w Thus, so long as private property in land continues —so long as some men are treated as owners of the earth and other meu can live on it only by their suffer- ance—human wisdom can devise no means by which the evils of our present condition may be avoided. Nor yet could the wisdom of God. By the light of that right reason of which St. Thomas speaks we may see that even He, the Al- mighty, so long as His laws remain what they are, OPEN LETTER TO POPE LEO XIII. 75 could do nothing to prevent poverty and starvation while property in land continues. How could He? Should he infuse new vigor into the sunlight, new virtue into the air, new fertility into the soil, would not all this new bounty go to the owners of the land, and work not benefit, but rather injury, to mere laborers? Should He open the minds of men to the possibilities of new substances, new ad- justments, new powers, could this do any more to relieve poverty than steam, electricity and all the num- berless discoveries and inventions of our time have done? Or, if He were to send down from the heavens above or cause to gush up from the subterranean depths, food, clothing, all the things that satisfy man’s material desires, to whom under our laws would all these belong? So far from benefiting man, would not this increase and extension of His bounty prove but a curse, enabling the privileged class more riotously to roll in wealth, and bringing the disinherited class to more widespread starvation or pauperism 2 IV. Believing that the social question is at bottom a religious question, we deem it of happy augury to the world that in your Encyclical the most influential of all religious teachers has directed attention to the condi- tion of labor. - But while we appreciate the many wholesome truths you utter, while we feel, as all must feel, that you are animated by a desire to help the suffering and oppressed, and to put an end to any idea that the Church is divorced from the aspiration for liberty and 76 THE CONDITION OF LABOR. progress, yet it is painfully obvious to us that one fatal assumption hides from you the cause of the evils you see, and makes it impossible for you to propose any adequate remedy. This assumption is, that pri- vate property in land is of the same nature and has the same sanctions as private property in things pro- duced by labor. In spite of its undeniable truths and its benevolent spirit, your Encyclical shows you to be involved in such difficulties as a physician called to examine one suffering from disease of the stomach would meet should he begin with a refusal to consider the stomach. Prevented by this assumption from seeing the true cause, the only causes you find it possible to assign for the growth of misery and wretchedness are the destrue- tion of workingmen's guilds in the last century, the repudiation in public institutions and laws of the ancient religion, rapacious usury, the custom of work- ing by contract, and the concentration of trade. Such diagnosis is manifestly inadequate to account for evils that are alike felt in Catholic countries, in Protestant countries, in countries that adhere to the Greek communion and in countries where no religion is professed by the state; that are alike felt in old countries and in new countries; where industry is simple and where it is most elaborate; and amid all varieties of industrial customs and relations. iłut the real cause will be clear if you will consider that since labor must find its workshop and reservoir in land, the labor question is but another name for the land question, and will re-examine your assumption that private property in land is necessary and right. See how fully adequate is the cause I have pointed OPEN LETTER TO POPE DEO XIII. 77 out. The most important of all the material relations of man is his relation to the planet he inhabits, and hence, the “impious resistance to the benevolent inten- tions of his Creator,” which, as Bishop Nulty says, is involved in private property in land, must produce evils wherever it exists. But by virtue of the law, “unto whom much is given, from him much is required,” the very progress of civilization makes the evils pro- duced by private property in land more widespread and intense. What is producing throughout the civilized world that condition of things you rightly describe as intoler- able is not this and that local error or minor mistake. It is nothing less than the progress of civilization itself; nothing less than the intellectual advance and the ma- terial growth in which our century has been so pre-eminent, acting in a state of society based on private property in land; nothing less than the new gifts that in our time God has been showering on man, but which are being turned into scourges by man’s “im- pious resistance to the benevolent intention of his Creator.” The discoveries of science, the gains of invention, have given to us in this wonderful century more than has been given to men in any time before ; and, in a degree so rapidly accelerating as to suggest geometrical progression, are placing in our hands new material powers. But with the benefit comes the obligation. In a civilization beginning to pulse with steam and electricity, where the sun paints pictures and the phono- graph stores speech, it will not do to be merely as just as were our fathers. Intellectual advance and material advance require corresponding moral advance. ISnowl- 78 THE CON }) iTION OF i,ABOR. edge and power are neither good nor evil. They are not ends but means—evolving forces that if not con- trolled in orderly relations must take disorderly and destructive forms. The deepening pain, the increasing perplexity, the growing discontent for which, as you truly say, some remedy must be found and quickly found, mean nothing less than that forces of destruction swifter and more terrible than those that have shattered every preceding civilization are already menacing ours —that if it does not quickly rise to a higher moral level; if it does not become in deed as in word a Christian civilization, on the wall of its splendor must flame the doom of Babylon : “Thou art weighed in the balance and found wanting !” One false assumption prevents you from seeing the real cause and true significance of the facts that have prompted your Encyclical. And it fatally fetters you when you seek a remedy. You state that you approach the subject with confi- dence, yet in all that greater part of the Encyclical (19–67) devoted to the remedy, while there is an abundance of moral reflections and injunctions, excellent in themselves but dead and meaningless as you apply them, the only definite practical proposals for the improvement of the condition of labor are: 1. That the State should step in to prevent over- work, to restrict the employment of women and children, to secure in workshops conditions not un- favorable to health and morals, and, at least where there is danger of insufficient wages provoking strikes, to regulate wages (39–40). Of EN LETTER TO fºop E. f.EO XIII. 79 2. That it should encourage the acquisition of property (in land) by workingmen (50–51). 3. That workingmen's associations should be formed (52–67). These remedies so far as they go are socialistic, and though the Encyclical is not without recognition of the individual character of man and of the priority of the individual and the family to the state, yet the whole tendency and spirit of its remedial suggestions lean unmistakably to socialism—extremely moderate socialism it is true : Socialism hampered and emas- culated by a supreme respect for private possessions; yet socialism still. But, although you frequently use the ambiguous term “private property” when the con- text shows that you have in mind private property in land, the one thing clear on the surface and becom- ing clearer still with examination is that you insist that whatever else may be done, the private owner- ship of land shall be left untouched. I have already referred generally to the defects that attach to all socialistic remedies for the evil con- dition of labor, but respect for your Holiness dictates that I should speak specifically, even though briefly, of the remedies proposed or suggested by you. Of these, the widest and strongest are that the state should restrict the hours of labor, the employ- ment of women and children, the unsanitary condi- tions of workshops, etc. Yet how little may in this way be accomplished. A strong, absolute ruler might hope by such regula- tions to alleviate the conditions of chattel slaves. But the tendency of our times is towards democracy, and 8() THE CONDITION OF LABOR. democratic states are necessarily weaker in paternal. ism, while in the industrial slavery, growing out of private ownership of land, that prevails in Christen- dom to-day, it is not the master who forces the slave to labor, but the slave who urges the master to let him labor. Thus the greatest difficulty in enforcing such regulations comes from those whom they are in- tended to benefit. It is not, for instance, the masters who make it difficult to enforce restrictions on child labor in factories, but the mothers, who, prompted by poverty, misrepresent the ages of their children even to the masters, and teach the children to misrepresent. But while in large factories and mines regulations as to hours, ages, etc., though subject to evasion and offering opportunities for extortion and corruption, may be to some extent enforced, how can they have any effect in those far wider branches of industry where the laborer works for himself or for small employers ? All such remedies are of the nature of the remedy for overcrowding that is generally prescribed with them—the restriction under penalty of the number who may occupy a room and the demolition of unsani- tary buildings. Since these measures have no ten- dency to increase house accommodation or to augment ability to pay for it, the overcrowding that is forced back in some places goes on in other places and to a worse degree. All such remedies begin at the wrong end. They are like putting on brake and bit to hold in quietness horses that are being lashed into frenzy; they are like trying to stop a locomotive by holding its wheels instead of shutting off steam ; like attempt. ing to cure smallpox by driving back its pustules, OPEN LETTER TO POPE DEO XIII. 81 Men do not overwork themselves because they like it; it is not in the nature of the mother's heart to send children to work when they ought to be at play; it is not of choice that laborers will work in dangerous and unsanitary conditions. These things, like over- crowding, come from the sting of poverty. And so long as the poverty of which they are the ex- pression is left untouched, restrictions such as you endorse can have only partial and evanescent results. The cause remaining, repression in one place can only bring out its effects in other places, and the task you assign to the state is as hopeless as to ask it to lower the level of the ocean by bailing out the sea. Nor can the state cure poverty by regulating wages. It is as much beyond the power of the state to regulate wages as it is to regulate the rates of interest. Usury laws have been tried again and again, but the only effect they have ever had has been to increase what the poorer borrowers must pay, and for the same reasons that all attempts to lower by regulation the price of goods have always resulted merely in increasing them. The general rate of wages is fixed by the ease or difficulty with which labor can obtain access to land, ranging from the full earnings of labor, where land is free, to the least on which laborers can live and reproduce, where land is fully monopolized. Thus, where it has been com- paratively easy for laborers to get land, as in the United States and in Australasia, wages have been higher than in Europe and it has been impossible to get European laborers to work there for wages that they would gladly accept at home; while as monopoli. zation goes on under the influence of private property 82 THE CONDITION OF LABOR. in land, wages tend to fall, and the social conditions of Europe to appear. Thus, under the partial yet sub- stantial recognition of common rights to land, of which I have spoken, the many attempts of the British parliaments to reduce wages by regulation failed utterly. And so, when the institution of private property in land had done its work in England, all attempts of Parliament to raise wages proved unavail- ing. In the beginning of this century it was even attempted to increase the earnings of laborers by grants in aid of wages. But the only result was to lower commensurately what wages employers paid. The state could only maintain wages above the ten- dency of the market (for as I have shown labor de- prived of land becomes a commodity), by offering employment to all who wish it; or by lending its sanction to strikes and supporting them with its funds. Thus it is, that the thorough going social- ists who want the state to take all industry into its hands are much more logical than those timid social- ists who propose that the state should regulate private industry—but only a little. \ The same hopelessness attends your suggestion that working people should be encouraged by the state in obtaining a share of the land. It is evident that by this you mean that, as is now being attempted in Ireland, the state shall buy out large land owners in favor of small ones, establishing what is known as peasant proprietors. Supposing that this can be done even to a considerable extent, what will be ac- complished save to substitute a larger privileged class for a smaller privileged class? What will be done for OPEN if TTER TO POPE II: O XIII. 83 the still larger class that must remain, the laborers of the agricultural districts, the workmen of the towns, the proletarians of the cities? Is it not true, as Pro- fessor De Laveleye says, that in such countries as Belgium, where peasant proprietary exists, the tenants, for there still exist tenants, are rackrented with a mercilessness unknown in Ireland Ž Is it not true that in such countries as Belgium the condition of the mere laborer is even worse than it is in Great Britain, where large ownerships obtain' And if the state attempts to buy up land for peasant proprietors will not the effect be, what is seen to-day in Ireland, to in- crease the market value of land and thus make it more difficult for those not so favored, and for those who will come after, to get land 8 How, moreover, on the principle which you declare (36), that “to the state the interests of all are equal, whether high or low,” will you justify state aid to one man to buy a bit of land without also insisting on state aid to another man to buy a donkey, to another to buy a shop, to another to buy the tools and materials of a trade— state aid in short to everybody who may be able to make good use of it or thinks that he could And are you not thus landed in communism—not the com- munism of the early Christians and of the religious orders, but communism that uses the coercive power of the state to take rightful property by force from those who have, to give to those who have not ? For the state has no purse of Fortunatus; the state cannot repeat the miracle of the loaves and fishes; all that the state can give, it must get by some form or other of the taxing power. And whether it gives or lends money, or gives or lends credit, it cannot give 84 THE CONDITION OF LABOR. to those who have not, without taking from those who have. But aside from all this, any scheme of dividing up land while maintaining private property in land is futile. Small holdings cannot co-exist with the treat- ment of land as private property where civilization is materially advancing and wealth augments. We may see this in the economic tendencies that in ancient times were the main cause that transformed world- conquering Italy from a land of small farms to a land of great estates. We may see it in the fact that while two centuries ago the majority of English farmers were owners of the land they tilled, tenancy has been for a long time the all but universal condition of the English farmer. And now the mighty forces of steam and electricity have come to urge concentration. It is in the United States that we may see on the largest scale how their power is operating to turn a nation of land owners into a nation of tenants. The principle is clear and irresistible. Material progress makes land more valuable, and when this increasing value is left to private owners land must pass from the ownership of the poor into the ownership of the rich, just as dia- monds so pass when poor men find them. What the British government is attempting in Ireland is to build snow houses in the Arabian desert to plant bananas in Labrador There is one way, and only one way, in which working people in our civilization may be secured a share in the land of their country, and that is the way that we propose—the taking of the profits of land ownership for the community. OPEN LETTER TO POPE LEO XIII. 85 As to workingmen's associations, what your Holi- ness seems to contemplate is the formation and encour- agement of societies akin to the Catholic sodalities, and to the friendly and beneficial societies, like the Odd Fellows, which have had a large extension in English speaking countries. Such associations may promote fraternity, extend social intercourse and pro- vide assurance in case of sickness or death, but if they go no further they are powerless to affect wages even among their members. As to trades unions proper, it is hard to define your position, which is, perhaps, best stated as one of warm approbation provided that they do not go too far. For while you object to strikes; while you reprehend societies that “do their best to get into their hands the whole field of labor and to force workingmen either to join them or to starve;” while you discountenance the coercing of employers and seem to think that arbitration might take the place of strikes; yet you use expressions and assert principles that are all that the trade unionist would ask, not merely to justify the strike and the boycott, but even the use of violence where only violence would suffice. For you speak of the insufficient wages of workmen as due to the greed of rich employers; you assume the moral right of the workman to obtain employment from others at wages greater than those others are will- ing freely to give ; and you deny the right of any one to work for such wages as he pleases, in such a way as to lead Mr. Stead, in so widely read a journal as the Review of Reviews, to approvingly declare that you regard “blacklegging,” i. e., the working for less than union wages, as a crime. To men conscious of bitter injustice, to men steeped 86 THE CONDITION OF LABOR. in poverty yet mocked by flaunting wealth, such words mean more than I can think you realize. When fire shall be cool and ice be warm, when armies shall throw away lead and iron, to try con- clusions by the pelting of rose leaves, such labor associations as you are thinking of may be possible. But not till then. For labor associations can do nothing to raise wages but by force. It may be force applied passively, or force applied actively, or force held in reserve, but it must be force. They must coerce or hold the power to coerce employers; they must coerce those among their own members dis- posed to straggle; they must do their best to get into their hands the whole field of labor they seek to occupy and to force other workingmen either to join them or to starve. Those who tell you of trades unions bent on raising wages by moral suasion alone are like those who would tell you of tigers that live On Oranges. The condition of the masses to-day is that of men pressed together in a hall where ingress is open and more are constantly coming, but where the doors for egress are closed. If forbidden to relieve the gen- eral pressure by throwing open those doors, whose bars and bolts are private property in land, they can only mitigate the pressure on themselves by forcing back others, and the weakest must be driven to the wall. This is the way of labor unions and trade guilds. Even those amiable societies that you rec- ommend would in their efforts to find employment for their own members necessarily displace others. For even the philanthropy which, recognizing the evil of trying to help labor by alms, seeks to help OPEN LETTER TO POPE LEO XIII. 87 men to help themselves by finding them work, becomes aggressive in the blind and bitter struggle that private property in land entails, and in helping one set of men injures others. Thus, to minimize the bitter complaints of taking work from others and lessening the wages of others in providing their own beneficiaries with work and wages, benevolent so- cieties are forced to devices akin to the digging of holes and filling them up again. Our American So- cieties feel this difficulty, General Booth encounters it in England, and the Catholic societies which your Holiness recommends must find it, when they are formed. Your Holiness knows of, and I am sure honors, the princely generosity of Baron Hirsch towards his suffering co-religionists. But, as I write, the New York newspapers contain accounts of an immense meeting held in Cooper Union, in this city, on the evening of Friday, September 4, in which a number of Hebrew trades unions protested in the strong- est manner against the loss of work and reduction of wages that is being effected by Baron Hirsch's generosity in bringing their own countrymen here and teaching them to work. The resolution unani- mously adopted at this great meeting thus concludes: “We now demand of Baron Hirsch himself that he release us from his ‘charity’ and take back the millions, which, instead of a blessing, have proved a curse and a source of misery.” Nor does this show that the members of these Hebrew labor unions—who are themselves immi- grants of the same class as those Baron IIirsch is striving to help, for in the next generation they lose 88 THE CONDITION OH LABOR. with us their distinctiveness—are a whit less gen- erous than other men. Labor associations of the nature of trade guilds or unions are necessarily selfish; by the law of their being they must fight for their own hand, regardless of who is hurt; they ignore and must ignore the teaching of Christ that we should do to others as we would have them do to us, which a true political economy shows is the only way to the full emancipation of the masses. They must do their best to starve workmen who do not join them, they must by all means in their power force back the “blackleg"—as the soldier in battle must shoot down his mother's son if in the opposing ranks. And who is the blackleg : A fellow creature seeking work—a fellow creature in all probability more pressed and starved than those who so bitterly denounce him, and often with the hungry pleading faces of wife and child behind him. And, in So far as they succeed, what is it that trades guilds and unions do but to impose more restrictions on natural rights; to create “trusts” in labor; to add to privileged classes other somewhat privileged classes; and to press the weaker closer to the wall? I speak without prejudice against trades unions, of which for years I was an active member. And in pointing out to your Holiness that their principle is selfish and incapable of large and permanent benefits, and that their methods violate natural rights and work hardship and injustice, I am only saying to you what, both in my books and by word of mouth, I have said over and over again to them. Nor is what I say capable of dispute. Intelligent trades unionists know it, and the less intelligent OPEN LETTER TO POPE LEO XIII. 89 vaguely feel it. And even those of the classes of wealth and leisure who, as if to head off the demand for natural rights, are preaching trades unionism to working men, must needs admit it. Your Holiness will remember the great London dock strike of two years ago, which, with that of other influential men, received the moral support of that Prince of the Church whom we of the English speech hold higher and dearer than any prelate has been held by us since the blood of Thomas A'Becket stained the Canterbury altar. In a volume called “The Story of the Dockers' Strike,” written by Messrs. H. Lewellyn Smith and Vaughan Nash, with an introduction by Sydney Buxton, M. P., which advocates trades unionism as the solution of the labor question, and of which a large number were sent to Australia as a sort of official recognition of the generous aid received from there by the strikers, I find in the summing up, on pages 164–5, the following: º “If the settlement lasts, work at the docks will be more regular, better paid, and carried on under better conditions than ever before. All this will be an unqualified gain to those who get the benefit from it. But another result will undoubtedly be to contract the field of employment and lessen the number of those for whom work can be found. The lower class casual will, in the end, find his position more precarious than ever before, in proportion to the increased regu- larity of work which the “fitter” of the laborers will secure. The effect of the organization of dock labor, as of all classes of labor, will be to squeeze out tºe pesiduum. The loafer, the cadger, the failure in the industrial race—the members of ‘Class 13° of Mr. Charles Booth's hierarchy of social classes—will be no 90 THE CONDITION OF LABOR. gainers by the change, but will rather find another door closed against them, and this in many cases the last door to employment.” I am far from wishing that your Holiness should join in that pharisaical denunciation of trades unions common among those who, while quick to point out the injustice of trades unions in denying to others the equal right to work, are themselves supporters of that more primary injustice that denies the equal right to the standing place and natural material necessary to work. What I wish to point out is that trades unionism, while it may be a partial paliative, is not a remedy; that it has not that moral character which could alone justify one in the position of your Holiness in urging it as good in itself. Yet, So long as you insist on private property in land what better can you do? W. In the beginning of the Encyclical you declare that the responsibility of the apostolical office urges your IIoliness to treat the question of the condition of labor “expressly and at length in order that there may be no mistake as to the principles which truth and justice dictate for its settlement.” But, blinded by one false assumption, you do not see even fundamentals. You assume that the labor question is a question between wage-workers and their employers. But working for wages is not the primary or exclusive occu- pation of labor. Primarily men work for themselves without the intervention of an employer. And the primary source of wages is in the earnings of labor, OPEN LETTER TO POPE LEO XIII. 91 the man who works for himself and consumes his own products receiving his wages in the fruits of his labor. Are not fishermen, boatmen, cab drivers, peddlers, working farmers—all, in short, of the many workers who get their wages directly by the sale of their services or products without the medium of an employer, as much laborers as those who work for the specific wages of an employer ? In your consideration of remedies you do not seem even to have thought of them. Yet in reality the laborers who work for themselves are the first to be considered, since what men will be willing to accept from employers depends manifestly on what they can get by working for them- selves. You assume that all employers are rich men, who might raise wages much higher were they not so grasping. But is it not the fact that the great majority of employers are in reality as much pressed by competition as their workmen, many of them constantly on the verge of failure? Such employers could not possibly raise the wages they pay, however they might wish to, unless all others were compelled to do so. You assume that there are in the natural order two classes, the rich and the poor, and that laborers naturally belong to the poor. It is true as you say that there are differences in capacity, in diligence, in health and in strength, that may produce differences in fortune. These, however, are not the differences that divide men into rich and poor. The natural differences in powers and aptitudes are certainly not greater than are natural differences in stature. But while it is only by selecting giants 92 THE CONDITION OF LABOR. and dwarfs that we can find men twice as tall as others, yet in the difference between rich and poor that exists to-day we find some men richer than other men by the thousand fold and the million fold. Nowhere do these differences between wealth and poverty coincide with differences in individual powers and aptitudes. The real difference between rich and poor is the difference between those who hold the toll gates and those who pay toll ; between tribute re- ceivers and tribute yielders. In what way does nature justify such a difference? In the numberless varieties of animated Lature we find some species that are evidently intended to live on other species. But their relations are always marked by unmistakable differences in size, shape or organs. To man has been given dominion over all the other living things that tenant the earth. But is not this mastery indicated even in externals, so that no one can fail on sight to distinguish between a man and one of the inferior animals. Our American apologists for slavery used to contend that the black skin and wooly hair of the negro indicated the intent of nature that the black should serve the white; but the difference that you assume to be natural is between men of the same race. What difference does nature show between such men as would indicate her intent that one should live idly yet be rich, and the other should work hard yet be poor? If I could bring you from the United States a man who has $200,000,000, and one who is glad to work for a few dollars a week, and place them side by side in your ante-chamber, would you be able to tell which was which, even were you to call in the most skilled anatomist' Is it not clear that OPEN LETTER TO POPE LEO XIII. 93 God in no way countenances or condones the di- vision of rich and poor that exists to-day, or in any way permits it, except as having given them free will he permits men to choose either good or evil, and to avoid heaven if they prefer hell. For is it not clear that the division of men into the classes rich and poor has invariably its origin in force and fraud; invariably involves violation of the moral law ; and is really a division into those who get the profits of robbery and those who are robbed; those who hold in exclusive possession what God made for all, and those who are deprived of His bounty . Did not Christ in all His utterances and parables show that the gross difference between rich and poor is opposed to God's law Ż Would he have condemned the rich so strongly as he did, if the class distinction between rich and poor did not involve injustice—was not opposed to God’s intent 7 It seems to us that your Holiness misses its real signi- ficance in intimating that Christ, in becoming the son of a carpenter and Himself working as a carpenter, showed merely that “there is nothing to be ashamed of in seeking one's bread by labor.” To say that is almost like saying that by not robbing people He showed that there is nothing to be ashamed of in honesty . If you will consider how true in any large view is the classifi- cation of all men into workingmen, beggarmen and thieves, you will see that it was morally impossible that Christ during His stay on earth should have been anything else than a workingman, since He who came to fulfil the law must by deed as well as word obey God’s law of labor. See how fully and how beautifully Christ's life 94. THE CONDITION OF LABOR. on earth illustrated this law. Entering our earthly life in the weakness of infancy, as it is appointed that all should enter it, He lovingly took what in the natural order is lovingly rendered, the sustenance, secured by labor, that one generation owes to its immediate successors. Arrived at maturity, He earned His own subsistence by that common labor in which the majority of men must and do earn it. Then passing to a higher—to the very highest–sphere of labor, Ile earned His subsistence by the teaching of moral and spiritual truths, receiving its material wages in the love offerings of grateful hearers, and not refusing the costly spikenard with which Mary anointed His feet. So, when He chose His dis- ciples, He did not go to land owners or other mo- nopolists who live on the labor of others, but to common laboring men. And when He called them to a higher sphere of labor and sent them out to teach moral and spiritual truths, He told them to take, with- out condescension on the one hand or sense of degradation on the other, the loving return for such labor, saying to them that the “laborer is worthy of his hire,” thus showing, what we hold, that all labor does not consist in what is called manual labor, but that whoever helps to add to the material, intellectual, moral or spiritual fullness of life is also a laborer.” * Nor should it be forgotten that the investigator, the philoso- pher, the teacher, the artist, the poet, the priest, though not engaged in the production of wealth, are not only engaged in the production of utilities and satisfactions to which the production of wealth is only a means, but by acquiring and diffusing knowl- edge, stimulating mental powers and elevating the moral Sense, may greatly increase the ability to produce wealth. For man does not live by bread alone. * * * He who by any exertion of mind or body adds to the aggregate of enjoyable wealth, increases the sum of human knowledge, or gives to human life higher eleva- OPEN f,ETTER TO POPE LEO XIII. 95 In assuming that laborers, even ordinary manual laborers, are naturally poor, you ignore the fact that labor is the producer of wealth, and attribute to the natural law of the Creator an injustice that comes from man’s impious violation of His benevolent intention. In the rudest stage of the arts it is possible, where justice prevails, for all well men to earn a living. With the labor-saving appliances of our time, it should be possible for all to earn much more. And so, in saying that poverty is no disgrace, you convey an unreasonable implication. For poverty ought to be a disgrace, since in a condition of social justice, it would, where unsought from religious motives or un- imposed by unavoidable misfortune, imply recklessness or laziness. The sympathy of your Holiness seems exclusively directed to the poor, the workers. Ought this to be so 2 Are not the rich, the idlers, to be pitied also : By the word of the Gospel it is the rich rather than the poor who call for pity, for the presumption is that they will share the fate of Dives. And to any one who believes in a future life the condition of him who wakes to find his cherished millions left behind must seem pitiful. But even in this life, how really pitiable are the rich. The evil is not in wealth in itself—in its command over material things; it is in the possession tion or greater fullness—he is, in the large meaning of the words, a “producer,” a “working man,” a “ laborer,” and is honestly earning honest wages. But he who without doing aught to make mankind richer, wiser, better, happier, lives on the toil of others— he, no matter by what name of honor he may be called, or how lustily the priests of Mammon may swing their censers before him, is in the last analysis but a beggarman or a thief.-Protec- tion or Free Trade, pp. 74-75. 96 THE CONDITION OF LABOR. of wealth while others are steeped in poverty; in being raised above touch with the life of humanity, from its work and its struggles, its hopes and its fears, and above all, from the love that sweetens life, and the kindly sympathies and generous acts that strengthen faith in man and trust in God. Consider how the rich see the meaner side of human nature; how they are surrounded by flatterers and sycophants; how they find ready instruments not only to gratify vicious impulses, but to prompt and stimulate them; how they must constantly be on guard lest they be swindled; how often they must suspect an ulterior motive behind kindly deed or friendly word; how if they try to be generous they are beset by shameless beggars and scheming impostors; how often the family affections are chilled for them, and their deaths anticipated with the ill-concealed joy of expectant possession. The worst evil of poverty is not in the want of material things, but in the stunting and distortion of the higher qualities. So, though in another way, the possession of unearned wealth likewise stunts and distorts what is noblest in man. - God’s commands cannot be evaded with impunity. If it be God's command that men shall earn their bread by labor, the idle rich must suffer. And they do. See the utter vacancy of the lives of those who live for pleasure; see the loathsome vices bred in a class who surrounded by poverty are sated with wealth. See that terrible punishment of ennui, of which the poor know so little that they cannot understand it; see the pessimism that grows among the wealthy classes— that shuts out God, that despises men, that deems OPEN LETTER TO POPE LEO XIII. 97 existence in itself an evil, and fearing death yet longs for annihilation. When Christ told the rich young man who sought Him to sell all he had and to give it to the poor, He was not thinking of the poor, but of the young man. And I doubt not that among the rich, and especially among the self-made rich, there are many who at times at least feel keenly the folly of their riches and fear for the dangers and temptations to which these expose their children. But the strength of long habit, the promptings of pride, the excitement of making and holding what has become for them the counters in a game of cards, the family expectations that have assumed the character of rights, and the real difficulty they find in making any good use of their wealth, bind them to their burden, like a weary donkey to his pack, till they stumble on the precipice that bounds this life. Men who are sure of getting food when they shall need it eat only what appetite dictates. But with the sparse tribes who exist on the verge of the habitable globe life is either a famine or a feast. Enduring hunger for days, the fear of it prompts them to gorge like anacondas when successful in their quest of game. And so, what gives wealth its curse is what drives men to seek it, what makes it so envied and admired—the fear of want. As the unduly rich are the corollary of the unduly poor, so is the soul-destroying quality of riches but the reflex of the want that embrutes and degrades. The real evil lies in the injustice from which unnatural possession and unnatural deprivation both spring. But this injustice can hardly be charged on individ- 98 THE CONI)ITION OF LABOR. uals or classes. The existence of private property in land is a great social wrong from which society at large suffers, and of which the very rich and the very poor are alike victims, though at the opposite extremes. Seeing this, it seems to us like a violation of Christian charity to speak of the rich as though they individually were responsible for the sufferings of the poor. Yet, while you do this, you insist that the cause of monstrous wealth and degrading poverty shall not be touched. Here is a man with a disfiguring and dangerous excrescence. One physician would kindly, gently, but firmly remove it. Another insists that it shall not be removed, but at the same time holds up the poor victim to hatred and ridicule. Which is right? - In seeking to restore all men to their equal and natural rights we do not seek the benefit of any class, but of all. For we both know by faith and see by fact that injustice can profit no one and that justice must benefit all. Nor do we seek any “futile and ridiculous equality.” We recognize, with you, that there must always be differences and inequalities. In so far as these are in conformity with the moral law, in so far as they do not violate the command, “Thou shalt not steal,” we are content. We do not seek to better God’s work; we seek only to do His will. The equality we would bring about is not the equality of fortune, but the equality of natural opportunity; the equality that reason and religion alike proclaim—the equality in usufruct of all His children to the bounty of Our Father who art in Heaven. And in taking for the uses of Society what we OPEN LETTER TO POPE LEO XIII. 99 clearly see is the great fund intended for society in the divine order, we would not levy the slightest tax on the possessors of wealth, no matter how rich they might be. Not only do we deem such taxes a violation of the right of property, but we see that by virtue of beautiful adaptations in the economic laws of the Creator, it is impossible for any one honestly to ac- quire wealth, without at the same time adding to the wealth of the world. To persist in a wrong, to refuse to undo it, is always to become involved in other wrongs. Those who defend private property in land, and thereby deny the first and most important of all human rights, the equal right to the material substratum of life, are compelled to one of two courses. Either they must, as do those whose gospel is “Devil take the hindermost,” deny the equal right to life, and by some theory like that to which the English clergyman Malthus has given his name, assert that nature (they do not venture to say God) brings into the world more men than there is provision for ; or, they must, as do the socialists, assert as rights what in themselves are wrongs. - Your Holiness in the Encyclical gives an example of this. Denying the equality of right to the material basis of life, and yet conscious that there is a right to live, you assert the right of laborers to em- ployment and their right to receive from their employers a certain indefinite wage. No such rights exist. No one has a right to demand employment of another, or to demand higher wages than the other is willing to give, or in any way to put pressure on 100 THE CONI) [TION OF LABOR. another to make him raise such wages against his will. There can be no better moral justification for such demands on employers by workingmen than there would be for employers demanding that workingmen shall be compelled to work for them when they do not want to and to accept wages lower than they are willing to take. Any seeming justification springs from a prior wrong, the denial to workingmen of their natural rights, and can in the last analysis only rest on that supreme dictate of self-preservation that under extraordinary circumstances makes pardonable what in itself is theft, or sacrilege or even murder. A fugitive slave with the bloodhounds of his pur- suers baying at his heels would in true Christian morals be held blameless if he seized the first horse he came across, even though to take it he had to knock down the rider. But this is not to justify horse-stealing as an ordinary means of traveling. When his disciples were hungry Christ permitted them to pluck corn on the Sabbath day. But He never denied the sanctity of the Sabbath by asserting that it was under ordinary circumstances a proper time to gather corn. He justified David, who when pressed by hunger committed what ordinarily would be sacrilege, by taking from the temple the loaves of proposition. But in this He was far from saying that the robbing of temples was a proper way of getting a living. In the Encyclical however you commend the appli- cation to the ordinary relations of life, under normal conditions, of principles that in ethics are only to be tolerated under extraordinary conditions. You are driven to this assertion of false rights by your OPEN LETTER TO POPE LEO XIII. 101 denial of true rights. The natural right which each man has is not that of demanding employment or wages from another man; but that of employing himself—that of applying by his own labor to the inexhaustible storehouse which the Creator has in the land provided for all men. Were that storehouse open, as by the single tax we would open it, the natural de- mand for labor would keep pace with the supply, the man who sold labor and the man who bought it would become free exchangers for mutual advantage, and all cause for dispute between workman and em- ployer would be gone. For then, all being free to em- ploy themselves, the mere opportunity to labor would cease to seem a boon; and since no one would work for another for less, all things considered, than he could earn by working for himself, wages would necessarily rise to their full value, and the relations of workman and employer be regulated by mutual interest and convenience. This is the only way in which they can be satisfac- torily regulated. Your Holiness seems to assume that there is some just rate of wages that employers ought to be willing to pay and that laborers should be content to receive, and to imagine that if this were secured there would be an end of strife. This rate you evidently think of as that which will give workingmen a frugal living, and perhaps enable them by hard work and strict economy to lay by a little something. • But how can a just rate of wages be fixed without the “higgling of the market” any more than the just price of corn or pigs or ships or paintings can be so fixed ? And would not arbitrary regulation in the 102 THE CONDITION OF LABOR. one case as in the other check that interplay that most effectively promotes the economical adjustment of productive forces? Why should buyers of labor, any more than buyers of commodities, be called on to pay higher prices than in a free market they are com- pelled to pay ? Why should the sellers of labor be content with anything less than in a free market they can obtain' Why should workingmen be content with frugal fare when the world is so rich & Why should they be satisfied with a life time of toil and stinting, when the world is so beautiful? Why should not they also desire to gratify the higher instincts, the finer tastes? Why should they be forever content to travel in the steerage when others find the cabin more enjoyable? Nor will they. The ferment of our time does not arise merely from the fact that workingmen find it harder to live on the same scale of comfort. It is also and perhaps still more largely due to the increase of their desires with an improved scale of comfort. This increase of desire must continue. For working- men are men. And man is the unsatisfied animal. He is not an ox, of whom it may be said, so much grass, so much grain, so much water, and a little salt, and he will be content. On the contrary, the more he gets the more he craves. When he has enough food then he wants better food. When he gets a shelter then he wants a more commodious and tasty one. When his animal needs are satisfied then men- tal and spiritual desires arise. “SOCIAL STATICS ’’—THE RIGHT OF PROPERTY. 33 satisfactory answers. Let us take a sample of these arguments, and examine its defects. “Though the earth and all inferior creatures,” says Locke, “be common to all men, yet every man has a property in his own person : this nobody has a right to but himself. The labor of his body, and the work of his hands, we may say are properly his. Whatever then he removes out of the state that nature hath provided and left it in, he hath mixed his labor with, and joined to it something that is his own, and thereby makes it his property. It being by him removed from the common state nature hath placed it in, it hath by this labor some- thing annexed to it that excludes the common right of other men. For this labor being the unquestionable property of the laborer, no man but he can have a right to what that is once joined to, at least when there is enough and as good left in common for others.” If inclined to cavil, one might in reply to this observe, that as, according to the premises, “the earth and all inferior creatures " — all things, in fact, that the earth produces — are “common to all men,” the consent of all men must be obtained before any article can be equi- tably “removed from the common state nature hath placed it in.” It might be argued that the real question is overlooked, when it is said, that, by gathering any natural product, a man “hath mixed his labor with it, and joined to it something that is his own, and thereby made it his property;” for that the point to be debated is, whether he had any right to gather, or mix his labor with that, which, by the hypothesis, previously belonged to mankind at large. The reasoning used in the last chapter to prove that no amount of labor, bestowed by an individual upon a part of the earth's surface, can nul- lify the title of Society to that part, might be similarly employed to show that no one can, by the mere act of appropriating to himself any wild unclaimed animal or fruit, supersede the joint claims of other men to it. It may be quite true that the labor a man expends in catching or gathering, gives him a better right to the thing caught or gathered, than any one other man; but the question at issue is, whether by labor so expended, he has made his right to the thing caught or gathered, greater than the pre-existing rights of all other men put 34 DECLARATION. together. And unless he can prove that he has done this, his title to possession cannot be admitted as a matter of right, but can be conceded only on the ground of com- We]]I6]] Cé. Further difficulties are suggested by the qualification, that the claim to any article of property thus obtained, is valid only “when there is enough and as good left in common for others.” A condition like this gives birth to such a host of queries, doubts, and limitations, as practically to neutralize the general proposition entirely. It may be asked, for example — How is it to be known that enough is “left in common for others” 7 Who can determine whether what remains is “as good" as what is taken 2 How if the remnant is less accessible 2 If there is not enough “left in common for others,” how must the right of appropriation be exercised ? Why, in such case, does the mixing of labor with the acquired object, cease to “exclude the common right of other men " ? Supposing enough to be attainable, but not all equally good, by what rule must each man choose ? Out of which inquisition it seems impossible to liberate the alleged right, without such mutilations as to render it, in an ethical point of view, entirely valueless. Thus, as already hinted, we find, that the circum- stances of savage life, render the principles of abstract morality inapplicable; for it is impossible, under ante- social conditions, to determine the rightness or wrong- ness of certain actions by an exact measurement of the amount of freedom assumed by the parties concerned. We must not expect, therefore, that the right of prop- erty can be satisfactorily based upon the premises afforded by such a state of existence. § 2. But, under the system of land-tenure pointed out in the last chapter, as the only one that is consistent with the equal claims of all men to the use of the earth, these difficulties disappear; and the right of property obtains a legitimate foundation. We have seen that, without any infraction of the law of equal freedom, an individual may lease from society a given surface of soil, by agreeing to pay in return a stated amount of the pro- duce he obtains from that soil. We found that, in doing this, he does no more than what every other man is “SOCIAL STATICs” — THE RIGHT OF PROPERTY. 35 equally free with himself to do — that each has the same power with himself to become the tenant — and that the rent he pays accrues alike to all. Having thus hired a tract of land from his fellow-men, for a given period, for understood purposes, and on specified terms — hav- ing thus obtained, for a time, the exclusive use of that land by a definite agreement with its owners, it is mani- fest that an individual may, without any infringement of the rights of others, appropriate to himself that por- tion of produce which remains after he has paid to man- kind the promised rent. He has now, to use Locke's expression, “mixed his labor with ” certain products of the earth; and his claim to them is in this case valid, because he obtained the consent of society before so ex- pending his labor; and having fulfilled the condition which society imposed in giving that consent — the pay- ment of rent — society, to fulfil its part of the agree- ment, must acknowledge his title to that surplus which remains after the rent has been paid. “Provided you deliver to us a stated share of the produce which by culti- vation you can obtain from this piece of land, we give you the exclusive use of the remainder of that produce : ” these are the words of the contract; and in virtue of this contract, the tenant may equitably claim the sup- plementary share as his private property: may so claim it without any disobedience to the law of equal free- dom; and has therefore a right so to claim it. Any doubt that may be felt as to the fact that this is a logical deduction from our first principle, that every man has freedom to do all that he wills provided he in- fringes not the equal freedom of any other man, may be readily cleared up by comparing the respective degrees of freedom assumed in such a case by the occupier and the members of society with whom he bargains. As was shown in the preceding chapter, if the public alto- gether deprive any individual of the use of the earth, they allow him less liberty than they themselves claim ; and by so breaking the law of equal freedom, commit a wrong. If, conversely, an individual usurps a given portion of the earth, to which, as we have seen, all other men have as good a title as himself, he breaks the law by assuming more liberty than the rest. But when an in- dividual holds land as a tenant of society, a balance is 36 DECLARATION. maintained between these extremes, and the claims of both parties are respected. A price is paid by the one, for a certain privilege granted by the other. By the fact of the agreement being made, it is shown that such price and privilege are considered to be equivalents. The lessor and the lessee have both, within the pre- scribed limits, done that which they willed : the one in letting a certain holding for a specified sum ; the other in agreeing to give that sum. And so long as this con- tract remains intact, the law of equal freedom is duly observed. If, however, any of the prescribed conditions be not fulfilled, the law is necessarily broken, and the parties are involved in one of the predicaments above named. If the tenant refuses to pay the rent, then he tacitly lays claim to the exclusive use and benefit of the land he occupies — practically asserts that he is the sole owner of its produce; and consequently violates the law, by assuming a greater share of freedom than the rest of mankind. If, on the other hand, society take from the tenant that portion of the fruits obtained by the culture of his farm which remains with him after the payment of rent, they virtually deny him the use of the earth entirely (for by the use of the earth we mean the use of its products), and in so doing, claim for them- selves a greater share of liberty than they allow him. Clearly, therefore, this surplus produce equitably re- mains with the tenant : society cannot take it without trespassing upon his freedom ; he can take it without trespassing on the freedom of Society. And as, accord- ing to the law, he is free to do all that he wills, provided he infringes not the equal freedom of any other, he is free to take possession of such surplus as his property. § 3. The doctrine that all men have equal rights to the use of the earth, does indeed, at first sight, seem to countenance a species of social organization at variance with that from which the right of property has just been deduced; an organization, namely, in which the public, instead of letting out the land to individual members of their body, shall retain it in their own hands; cultivate it by joint-stock agency; and share the produce : in fact, what is usually termed Socialism or Communism. “SOCIAL STATICS”—THE RIGHT OF PROPERTY. 37 Plausible though it may be, such a scheme is not capa- ble of realization in strict conformity with the moral law. Of the two forms under which it may be pre- sented, the one is ethically imperfect; and the other, although correct in theory, is impracticable. Thus, if an equal portion of the earth's produce is awarded to every man, irrespective of the amount or quality of the labor he has contributed toward the obtainment of that produce, a breach of equity is com- mitted. Our first principle requires, not that all shall have like shares of the things which minister to the gratification of the faculties, but that all shall have like freedom to pursue those things — shall have like scope. It is one thing to give to each an opportunity of acquir- ing the objects he desires; it is another, and quite a dif- ferent thing, to give the objects themselves, no matter whether due endeavor has or has not been made to obtain them. The one we have seen to be the primary law of the Divine scheme ; the other, by interfering with the ordained connection between desire and gratifi- cation, shows its disagreement with that scheme. Nay more, it necessitates an absolute violation of the prin- ciple of equal freedom. For when we assert the entire liberty of each, bounded only by the like liberty of all, we assert that each is free to do whatever his desires dictate, within the prescribed limits — that each is free, therefore, to claim for himself all those gratifications, and sources of gratification, attainable by him within those limits — all those gratifications, and sources of gratification, which he can procure without trespassing upon the spheres of action of his neighbors. If, there- fore, out of many starting with like fields of activity, one obtains, by his greater strength, greater ingenuity, or greater application, more gratification and sources of gratification than the rest, and does this without in any way trenching upon the equal freedom of the rest, the moral law assigns him an exclusive right to all those extra gratifications and sources of gratification; nor can the rest take from him without claiming for themselves greater liberty of action than he claims, and thereby violating that law. Whence it follows, that an equal apportionment of the fruits of the earth amongst all, is not consistent with pure justice. 38 T) ECLARATION. If, on the other hand, each is to have allotted to him a share of produce proportionate to the degree in which ho has aided production, the proposal, whilst it is abstractedly just, is no longer practicable. Were all men cultivators of the soil, it would perhaps be possible to form an approximate estimate of their several claims. But to ascertain the respective amounts of help given by different kinds of mental and bodily laborers, toward procuring the general stock of the necessaries of life, is an utter impossibility. We have no means of making such a division save that afforded by the law of supply and demand, and this means the hypothesis excludes.” § 4. An argument fatal to the communist theory, is suggested by the fact, that a desire for property is one of the elements of our nature. Repeated allusion has been made to the admitted truth, that acquisitiveness is an unreasoning impulse quite distinct from the desires whose gratifications property secures — an impulse that is often obeyed at the expense of those desires. And if a propensity to personal acquisition be really a com- ponent of man’s constitution, then that cannot be a right form of society which affords it no scope. Socialists do indeed allege that private appropriation is an abuse of this propensity, whose normal function, they say, is to impel us to accumulate for the benefit of the public at large. But in thus attempting to escape from one diffi- culty, they do but entangle themselves in another. Such an explanation overlooks the fact that the use and abuse of a faculty (whatever the etymology of the words may imply) differ only in degree; whereas their assumption is, that they differ in kind. Gluttony is an abuse of the desire for food; timidity, an abuse of the feeling which in moderation produces prudence; servility, an abuse of the sentiment that generates respect; obstimacy, of that from which firmness springs: in all of which cases we find that the legitimate manifestations differ from the illegitimate ones, merely in quantity, and not in quality. So also with the instinct of accumulation. It may be quite true that its dictates have been, and still are, fol- lowed to an absurd excess; but it is also true that no 1. These inferences do not at all militate against joint-stock systems of pro- duction and living, which are in all probability what Socialism prophesies. “SOCIAL STATICs "--THE RIGHT OF PROPERTY. 39 change in the state of society will alter its nature and its office. To whatever extent moderated, it must still be a desire for personal acquisition. Whence it follows that a system affording opportunity for its exercise must ever be retained ; which means, that the system of pri- vate property must be retained ; and this presupposes a right of private property, for by right we mean that which harmonizes with the human constitution as divinely ordained. § 5. There is, however, a still more awkward dilemma into which M. Proudhon and his party betray them- selves. For if, as they assert, “all property is robbery” —if no one can equitably become the exclusive pos- sessor of any article — or as we say, obtain a right to it, then, amongst other consequences, it follows, that a man can have no right to the things he consumes for food. . And if these are not his before eating them, how can they become his at all ? As Locke asks, “when do they begin to be his 2 when he digests 2 or when he eats 2 or when he boils 2 or when he brings them home 2 " If no previous acts can make them his property, neither can any process of assimilation do it ; not even their absorp- tion into the tissues. Wherefore, pursuing the idea, we arrive at the curious conclusion, that as the whole of his bones, muscles, skin, etc., have been thus built up from nutriment not belonging to him, a man has no property in his own flesh and blood — can have no valid title to himself — has no more claim to his own limbs than he has to the limbs of another — and has as good a right to his neighbor’s body as to his own | Did we exist after the same fashion as those compound polyps, in which a number of individuals are based upon a living trunk common to them all, such a theory would be rational enough. But until Communism can be carried to that extent, it will be best to stand by the old doctrine. § 6. Further argument appears to be unnecessary. We have seen that the right of property is deducible from the law of equal freedom — that it is presupposed by the human constitution — and that its denial involves absurdities. Were it not that we shall frequently have to refer to 40 DECLARATION. the fact hereafter, it would be scarcely needful to show that the taking away another's property is an infringe- ment of the law of equal freedom, and is therefore wrong. If A appropriates to himself something belong- ing to B, one of two things must take place: either B does the like to A, or he does not. If A has no prop- erty, or if his property is inaccessible to B, B has evi- dently no opportunity of exercising equal freedom with A, by claiming from him something of like value; and A has therefore assumed a greater share of freedom than he allows B, and has broken the law. If again, A’s property is open to B, and A permits B to use like free- dom with himself by taking an equivalent, there is no violation of the law; and the affair practically becomes one of barter. But such a transaction will never take place save in theory; for A has no motive to appropriate B’s property with the intention of letting B take an equivalent: seeing that if he really means to let B have what B thinks an equivalent, he will prefer to make the exchange by consent in the ordinary way. The only case simulating this, is one in which A takes from B a thing that B does not wish to part with ; that is, a thing for which A can give B nothing that B thinks an equiv- alent; and as the amount of gratification which B has in the possession of this thing, is the measure of its value to him, it follows that if A cannot give B a thing which affords B equal gratification, or in other words what he thinks an equivalent, then A has taken from B what affords A satisfaction, but does not return to B what affords B satisfaction; and has therefore broken the law by assuming the greater share of freedom. Wherefore we find it to be a logical deduction from the law of equal freedom, that no man can rightfully take property from another against his will. There is in this, it will be observed, no modification whatever of the strenuous assertion in Chapter IX. of the equal, natural and inalienable right of all men to the use of land. On the contrary, so strongly, so uncompromisingly, does Mr. Spencer insist on the ethical invalidity of private property in land that “SOCIAL STATICs " —THE RIGHT OF PROPERTY. 41 he makes the formal consent of the community and the payment of rent to it a condition precedent to the individual right of property in things produced by labor. And, since no formal consent of this kind can be given until society has been well organized, he even goes to the length of denying that there can be any full right of property, or, indeed, any applica- tion of the principles of abstract morality, in any social condition lower than the civilized. In brief, the argument of this chapter is — 1. That the right of the individual to his labor does not give individual property in the product of labor, because labor can produce only by using land, which does not belong to any individual, but to all. : 2. But under the system of land-tenure previously set forth as the only just one, in which the organized society assigns the use of a portion of land to an in- dividual and collects rent from him for it, the con- ditions of the equal liberty of all are complied with, and the individual acquires a right of property in what remains of the product of his labor after paying I'ent. 3. This system, under which the social organization would let land to individuals and collect rent from them, does not countenance the system under which it would carry on production and divide the product among its members, since, the powers and application of men being different, this would give to some more than they are entitled to, and to others less. 4. This communistic or socialistic system is also condemned by the natural desire to acquire individual property. 42 DECLARATION. 5. The denial of individual property may be brought into the awkward dilemma of a denial of the right of the individual to himself. 6. The right of property having thus been estab- lished, the appropriation by one of property belonging to another is a denial of the law of equal freedom. CHAPTER IV. MR. SPENCER'S CONFUSION AS TO RIGHTS. MY purpose in quoting Chapter X. is to show what were the views on the land question expressed by Mr. Spencer in “Social Statics.” It may, however, be worth while, in passing, to clear up the confusion in which he here entangles the right to the products of labor with the right to land. This confusion he has not yet escaped from, as it is still to be seen in his latest book, “Justice,” where, though evidently anxious to minimize the land question, he still as- sumes that to justify the right of property in things produced from nature the consent of all men must be obtained or inferred. Nor is it the right of property alone that is thus confused. Mr. Spencer really puts himself in the same dilemma that, in Section 5, he pro- poses to Proudhon ; for if, as in this chapter he asserts, no one can equitably become the exclusive possessor of any natural substance or product until the joint rights of all the rest of mankind have been made over to him by some species of Quit claim — Then amongst other consequences, it follows that a man can have no right to the things he consumes for food. And if these are not his before eating them, how 44 DECLARATION. can they become his at all ? As Locke asks, “when do they begin to be his 2 when he digests 2 or when he eats 2 or when he boils 2 or when he brings them home 2 " If no previous acts can make them his prop- erty, neither can any process of assimilation do it; not even in their absorption into the tissues. Wherefore, pursuing the idea, we arrive at the curious conclusion, that, as the whole of his bones, muscles, skin, etc., have thus been built up from nutriment not belonging to him, a man has no property in himself — has no more claim to his own limbs than he has to the limbs of another—and has as good a right to his neighbor's body as to his own. The fact is, that without noticing the change, Mr. Spencer has dropped the idea of equal rights to land, and taken up in its stead a different idea — that of joint rights to land. That there is a difference may be seen at once. For joint rights may be and often are unequal rights. The matter is an important one, as it is the source of a great deal of popular confusion. I.et me, there- fore, explain it fully. When men have equal rights to a thing, as for instance, to the rooms and appurtenances of a club of which they are members, each has a right to use all or any part of the thing that no other one of them is using. It is only where there is use or some indica- tion of use by one of the others that even politeness dictates such a phrase as “Allow me !” or “If you please !” But where men have joint rights to a thing, as for instance, to a sum of money held to their joint credit, then the consent of all the others is required for the use of the thing or of any part of it, by any one of them. MR. SPENCER's CONFUSION AS TO RIGHTS. 45 Now, the rights of men to the use of land are not joint rights: they are equal rights. Were there only one man on earth, he would have a right to the use of the whole earth or any part of the earth. When there is more than one man on earth, the right to the use of land that any one of them would have, were he alone, is not abrogated: it is only lim- ited. The right of each to the use of land is still a direct, original right, which he holds of himself, and not by the gift or consent of the others; but it has become limited by the similar rights of the others, and is therefore an equal right. His right to use the earth still continues; but it has become, by reason of this limitation, not an absolute right to use any part of the earth, but (1) an absolute right to use any part of the earth as to which his use does not conflict with the equal rights of others (i.e., which no one else wants to use at the same time), and (2) a co-equal right to the use of any part of the earth which he and others may want to use at the same time. It is, thus, only where two or more men want to use the same land at the same time that equal rights to the use of land come in conflict, and the adjust- ment of society becomes necessary. If we keep this idea of equal rights in mind — the idea, namely, that the rights are the first thing, and the equality merely their limitation — we shall have no difficulty. It is through forgetting this that Mr. Spencer has been led into confusion. In Chapter IX., “The Right to the Use of the Earth,” he correctly apprehends and states the right to the use of land as an equal right. He says: 46 DECLARATION. Each of them is free to use the earth for the satisfac- tion of his wants, Provided he allows all others the same liberty. Here, in the first clause, is the primary right; in the second clause, the proviso or limitation. But in the next chapter, “The Right of Property,” he has, seemingly without noticing it himself, substi- tuted for the idea of equal rights to land the idea of joint rights to land. He says (Section 1): No amount of labor bestowed by an individual upon a part of the earth's surface can nullify the title of society to that part, . . . no one can, by the mere act of appro- priating to himself any wild, unclaimed animal or fruit, supersede the joint claims of other men to it. It may be quite true that the labor a man expends in catching or gathering, gives him a better right to the thing caught or gathered, than any one other man ; but the question at issue is, whether by labor so expended he has made his right to the thing caught or gathered, greater than the pre-existing rights of all other men put together. And unless he can prove that he has done this, his title to possession cannot be admitted as a matter of right, but can be conceded only on the ground of convenience. Here the primary right—the right by which “each of them is free to use the earth for the satisfaction of his wants’’ — has been dropped out of sight, and the mere proviso has been swelled into the importance of the primary right, and has taken its place. What Mr. Spencer here asserts, without noticing his change of position, is not that the rights of men to the use of land are equal rights, but that they are joint rights. And, from this careless shifting of ground, he is led, not only into hypercritical ques- tioning of Locke's derivation of the right of property, MR. SPENCER's CONFUSION AS TO RIGHTS. 47 but into the assumption that a man can have no right to the wild berries he has gathered on an untrodden prairie, unless he can prove the consent of all other men to his taking them. This reductio ad absurdum is a deduction from the idea of joint rights to land, whereas the deduction from the equality of rights to land would be that under such circumstances a man would have a right to take all the berries he wanted, and that all other men together would have no right to forbid him. Indeed, so great is Mr. Spencer's con- fusion, and so utterly unable does he become to as- sume a clear and indisputable right of property, that he has to cut the knot into which he has tangled the subject, and finds no escape but in the preposterous declaration that the dictates of ethics have no appli- cation to, and do not exist in, any social state except that of the highest civilization. Locke was not in error. The right of property in things produced by labor — and this is the only true right of property — springs directly from the right of the individual to himself, or as Locke ex- presses it, from his “property in his own person.” It is as clear and has as fully the sanction of equity in any savage state as in the most elaborate civiliza- tion. Labor can, of course, produce nothing without land; but the right to the use of land is a primary individual right, not springing from society, or de- pending on the consent of society, either expressed or implied, but inhering in the individual, and result- ing from his presence in the world. Men must have rights before they can have equal rights. Each man has a right to use the world because he is here and wants to use the world. The equality of this right 48 DECLARATION. is merely a limitation arising from the presence of others with like rights. Society, in other words, does not grant, and cannot equitably withhold from any individual, the right to the use of land. That right exists before society and independently of society, belonging at birth to each individual, and ceasing only with his death. Society itself has no original right to the use of land. What right it has with regard to the use of land is simply that which is derived from and is necessary to the determination of the rights of the individuals who compose it. That is to say, the function of society with regard to the use of land only begins where individual rights clash, and is to secure equality between these clash- ing rights of individuals. What Locke meant, or at least the expression that will give full and practical form to his idea, is simply this: That the equal right to life involves the equal right to the use of natural materials; that, conse- quently, any one has a right to the use of such natural opportunities as may not be wanted by any one else; and that the result of his labor, so expended, does of right become his individual property against all the world. For, where one man wants to use a natural opportunity that no one else wants to use, he has a right to do so, which springs from and is attested by the fact of his existence. This is an absolute, un- limited right, so long and in so far as no one else wants to use the same natural opportunity. Then, but not till then, it becomes limited by the similar rights of others. Thus no question of the right of any one to use any natural opportunity can arise until more than one man wants to use the same MR. SPENCER's CONFUSION AS TO RIGHTS. 49 natural opportunity. It is only then that any question of this right, any need for the action of society in the adjustment of equal rights to land, can come up. Thus, instead of there being no right of property until society has so far developed that all land has been properly appraised and rented for terms of years, an absolute right of property in the things produced by labor exists from the beginning —is coeval with the existence of man. In the right of each man to himself, and his right to use the world, lies the sure basis of the right of property. This Locke saw — just as the first man must have seen it. But Mr. Spencer, confused by a careless substitution of terms, has lost his grasp on the right of property and has never since recovered it. Getting rid of the idea of joint rights we see that the task of securing, in an advanced and complex civilization, the equal rights of all to the use of land is much simpler and easier than Mr. Spencer and the land nationalizationists suppose ; that it is not neces- sary for society to take land and rent it out. For so long as only one man wants to use a natural opportu- nity it has no value; but as soon as two or more want to use the same natural opportunity, a value arises. Hence, any question as to the adjustment of equal rights to the use of land occurs only as to valuable land ; that is to say, land that has a value irrespective of the value of any improvements in or on it. As to land that has no value, or to use the economic phrase, bears no rent, whoever may choose to use it has not only an equitable title to all that his labor may pro- duce from it, but society cannot justly call on him 50 I) ECLARATION. for any payment for the use of it. As to land that has a value, or, to use the economic phrase in the economic meaning, bears rent, the principle of equal freedom requires only that this value, or economic rent, be turned over to the community. Hence the formal appropriation and renting out of land by the community is not necessary: it is only necessary that the holder of valuable land should pay to the community an equivalent of the ground value, or eco- nomic rent; and this can be assured by the simple means of collecting an assessment in the form of a tax on the value of land, irrespective of improve- ments in or on it. In this way all members of the community are placed on equal terms with regard to natural oppor- tunities that offer greater advantages than those any one member of the community is free to use, and are consequently sought by more than one of those having equal rights to use the land. And, since the value of land arises from competition and is constantly fixed by competition, the question of who shall use this superior land desired by more than one is virtu- ally decided by competition, which settles clashing individual desires by determining at once both who shall be accorded the use of the superior land, and who will make the most productive use of it. In this way all, including the user of the superior natural opportunity, obtain their equal shares of the superi- ority, by the taking of its value for their common uses; while all the difficulties of state rental of land and of determining and settling for the value of im- provements are avoided. This is the single tax System. CHAPTER W. . MR. SPENCER'S CONFUSION AS TO VALUE. IT seems strange that a man who has touched on so many branches of knowledge, and written so largely on sociology, should even to this time have neglected the primary principles of political economy. But the failure to distinguish between equal rights and joint rights, which has so confused Mr. Spencer, is allied with a failure to comprehend the nature of rent. In “Social Statics " he assumes that all land ought to pay rent to the state, and on this assump- tion, joined with and perhaps giving rise to his trans- mutation of equal rights into joint rights, he bases important conclusions as to the right of property. In his latest book, “Justice,” he is not only no clearer in this but shows plainly — what in “Social Statics” is only to be surmised — his failure to appreciate the nature of the fundamental economic concept—value. Thus, in the chapter in “Justice ’’ entitled “The Right of Property,” he speaks (Section 55) of weap- ons, instruments, dress and decorations as “things in which the value given by labor bears a specially large relation to the value of the raw material,” and thus continues: When with such articles we join huts, which, however, being commonly made by the help of fellow men who receive reciprocal aid, are thus less distinctly products 52 I) ECLARATION. of an individual’s labor, we have named about all the things in which, at first, the worth given by effort is great in comparison with the inherent worth ; for the inherent worth of the wild food gathered or caught is more obvious than the worth of the effort spent in obtain- ing it. And this is doubtless the reason why, in the rudest Societies, the right of property is more definite in respect of personal belongings than in respect of other things. Passing the queer notion that things made by two or more men are less distinctly products of an indi- vidual’s labor than things made by one man, we have here the idea that there is an inherent value in the materials and spontaneous products of nature — i.e., land in the economic category — a value underived from labor and independent of it. The slightest acquaintance with economic literature, the slightest attempt to analyze the meaning of the term, would have shown Mr. Spencer the preposterousness of this idea. The word “value” in English speech has two meanings. One is that of usefulness or utility, as when we speak of the value of the ocean to man, the value of fresh air, the value of the compass in navigation, the value of the stethescope in the diag- nosis of disease, the value of the antiseptic treatment in surgery; or, when having in mind the intrinsic merits of the mental production itself, its quality of usefulness to the reader or to the public, we speak of the value of a book. In this sense of utility there *8 inherent worth or intrinsic value — a quality or qualities belonging to the thing itself, which give it usefulness to man. The other sense of the word “value” — the sense MR. SPENCER's CONFUSION AS TO VALUE. 53 in which Mr. Spencer uses it when he says that the value given by labor bears a specially large ratio to the value of the raw materials, or when, later on, he substitutes the word “worth '' as synonymous in such use for “value” — is that of exchangeability. In this sense value or worth means not utility, not any quality inhering in the thing itself, but a quality which gives to the possession of a thing the power of obtaining other things in return for it or for its use. Thus we speak of the value of gold as greater than that of iron; of a book bound in cloth as being more valuable than a book bound in paper; of the value of a copyright or a patent; of the lessening in the value of steel by the Bessemer process, or in that of aluminium by the improvements in extraction now going on. Value in this sense — the usual sense — is purely relative. It exists from and is measured by the power of obtaining things for things by exchan- ging them. It is therefore absurd to speak in this sense of inherent worth or intrinsic value. Air has the intrinsic quality of utility, or value in use, to the very highest degree; for without an abundant supply of it we could not live a minute. But air has no value whatever in the sense of value in exchange. We speak of a man of worth, or a worthy man, when we mean a man whose inherent qualities entitle him to esteem; but, when we speak of a man who is worth so and so much, or of a wealthy man, we speak of him in certain external relations, purely relative, which give him the power of obtaining things by exchange. A worthy man may retain his worthi- ness through all changes of external conditions; but 54 DECLARATION. a wealthy man is in this the creature of external con- ditions: the same man, in nothing changed, may through external circumstances be wealthy to-day and poverty-stricken to-morrow. Now, what gives to anything the quality of ex- changeability for other things — the quality of worth in exchange, or value 2 — for, having explained the other sense of the word “value,” I will in subsequent use confine it to its common and proper sense, that of value in exchange. That a thing has value, and may be exchanged for other things, is not because of its weight, or color, or divisibility, or any other quality inherent in the thing itself. Nor yet is it because of its utility to man. Utility is necessary to value, for nothing can be valuable unless it has the quality of gratifying some physical or mental desire of man, though it be but a fancy or whim. But utility of itself does not give value. Air, which has the highest utility, has no value, while diamonds, which have very little utility, have great value. If we ask ourselves the reason of such variations in the quality of value; if we inquire what is the attribute or condition concurring with the presence, absence, or degree of value attaching to anything — we see that things having some form of utility or desirability, are valuable or not valuable, as they are hard or easy to get. And, if we ask further, we may see that with most of the things that have value this difficulty or ease of getting them, which determines value, depends on the amount of labor which must be expended in producing them; i.e., bringing them into the place, form and condition in which they are MR. SPENCER's CONFUSION AS TO VALUE. 55 desired. Thus air, which is of the highest utility, since it is at every instant necessary to our existence, can be had without labor. It is the substance of that ocean, enveloping the surface of the globe, in which we are constantly immersed. So far from requiring labor to get it, it forces itself upon us, requiring labor, when we are so disposed, to keep it away. Hence air, in spite of its high utility, has no value. Large and pure diamonds, on the contrary, since they are found only in few places and require much search and toil to get, can be had only with great labor. Hence, although they have very low utility, since they gratify only the sense of beauty and the desire for ostentation, they have very high value. Thus gold, weight for weight, is more valu- able than silver, and much more valuable than iron, simply because it requires on the average more labor to get a given quantity of gold than to get the same quantity of silver, and much more than to get the same quantity of iron. 9 & That as to such things as these the quality of value is derived from the labor required to produce them; and that, consequently, as to them at least, there is no such thing as inherent value — becomes clearer still when we consider how their value is affected by the increase or decrease of the require- ment for labor. Iron as compared to gold used to be much more valuable than it is now. Why? Because improved processes in smelting have lessened the labor of pro- ducing it. A few years since aluminium was more valuable than gold, because it took more labor to get it. Labor-saving improvements have already lowered 56 DECLARATION. the value of aluminium to less than that of silver, and little more than that of copper; and it is alto- gether likely that continued improvement will ere long bring it to that of iron. So the value of steel has been greatly lessened by the introduction of the Bessemer and other processes. So the value of beaver skins, of whalebone, of ivory, etc., has been increased by the growing scarcity of the animals from which they are derived, and the greater labor needed to obtain them. So, too, the improvement in transportation has lessened the value of things where it was a considerable item in the labor required for their production. And so, too, customs duties and other indirect taxes add to the value of things on which they fall, because their effect is to increase the amount of labor required to get such things. It is thus seen, with regard at least to the greater number of valuable things, that there cannot be inherent or intrinsic value; and that value is simply an expression of the labor required for the production of such a thing. But there are some things as to which this is not so clear. Land is not produced by labor; yet land, irrespective of any improvements that labor has made on it, often has value. And so value frequently attaches to the forms of the eco- nomic term “land’’ that we commonly speak of as natural products, such as trees in their natural state, ore in the vein, stone or marble in the quarry, or sand or gravel in the bed. Yet a little examination will show that such facts are but exemplifications of the general principle, just as the rise of a balloon and the fall of a stone both exemplify the universal law of gravitation. MR. SPENCER's CONFUSION AS TO VALUE. 57 To illustrate: Let us suppose a man accidentally to stumble on a diamond. Without the expenditure of labor, for his effort has been merely that of stoop- ing down to pick it up, an action in itself a gratifi- cation of curiosity, he has here a great value. But what causes this value 2 Clearly, it springs from the fact that, as a rule, to get such a diamond will require much expenditure of labor. If any one could pick up diamonds as easily as in this case, diamonds would have no value. Or, here is a grove of natural trees, which, as they stand, and before the touch of labor, have a consider- able value, so that a lumberman will gladly pay for the privilege of cutting them. But has not this value the same cause as in the case of the diamond — the fact that to get such lumber ordinarily (or to speak exactly, to get the last amount of such lumber that the existing demand requires) the lumberman must go so far that the cost of transportation will equal what he is willing to pay for these trees 2 In the naturally wooded sections of the United States trees had at first not merely no value, but were deemed an incumbrance, to get rid of which the settler had to incur the labor of felling and burning. Then lumber had no value except the cost of work- ing it up after it had been felled; for the work of felling had for object the getting rid of the tree. But soon, as clearing proceeded, the desire to get rid of trees so far slackened, as compared with the desire to get lumber, that trees were felled simply for the purpose of getting the lumber. Then the value of lumber increased, for the labor of felling trees had to be added to it; but trees themselves had as yet no 58 DECLARATION. value. As clearing still proceeded and the demand for lumber grew with growing population, it became necessary to go farther and farther to get trees. Then transportation began to be a perceptible ele- ment in the labor of getting lumber, and trees that had been left standing began to have a value, since by using them the labor of transportation would be saved. And, as the requirement for lumber has com- pelled the lumbermen to go farther and farther, the value of the trees remaining has increased. But this value is not inherent in the trees: it is a value hav- ing its basis in labor, and representing a saving of labor that must otherwise be incurred. The reason that the tree at such place has a value is, that obtain- ing it there secures the same result as would the labor of transporting a similar amount of lumber from the greater distance to which resort must be made to satisfy the demand for lumber. And so with the value which attaches to ore or sand or gravel. Such value is always relative to the labor required to obtain such things from points of greater distance or of less abundant de- posits, to which in the existing demand resort is necessary. We thus see the cause and nature of land values, or, to use the economic term, of rent. No matter how fertile it may be, no matter what other desirable quality it may have, land has no value until, whether by reason of quality or location, the relation between it and the most advantageous land to which labor may have free access gives to its use an advantage equivalent to the saving of labor. Or, to state in another way that accepted theory which is sometimes MR. SPENCER's CONFUSION AS TO VALUE. 59 styled Ricardo's theory of rent, and which John Stuart Mill called the pons asinorum of political economy: it is, that the rent of land is determined by the excess of the produce it will yield over that which the same application can obtain from the least productive land in use. To grasp this principle is to see that land has no inherent value; that value can never attach to all land, but only to some land, and may arise on par- ticular land either by reason of production being extended to inferior land, or by reason of the devel- opment of superior productiveness in special local- ities. Thus the phenomena of value are at bottom illus- trations of one principle. The value of everything produced by labor, from a pound of chalk or a paper of pins to the elaborate structure and appurtenances of a first-class ocean steamer, is resolvable on analy- sis into an equivalent of the labor required to repro- duce such a thing in form and place; while the value of things not produced by labor, but nevertheless susceptible of ownership, is, in the same way, resolv- able into an equivalent of the labor which the owner- ship of such a thing enables the owner to obtain or Så Ve. The reason why in rude societies value attaches mainly or wholly to things produced by labor, and there is little or no value to land — or, to use Mr. Spencer's phrase, “the reason why in the rudest societies the right of property is more definite in respect of personal belongings than in respect of other things” — is not, as he puts it, that weapons, implements, dress, decorations, and huts are “about 60 DECLARATION. all the things in which, at first, the worth given by effort is great in comparison with the inherent worth; for the inherent worth of the wild food gathered or caught is more obvious than the worth of the effort spent in obtaining it.” It is that labor products always cost effort, and hence have value from the first; while land costs no effort, and in such societies the growth of population and the development of the arts have as yet attached little or no special advan- tages to the use of particular pieces of land, which at a later stage are equivalent to a saving of effort. Thus, in the absence of the artificial scarcity pro- duced by monopoly, land of practically like quality is easy to obtain and has no value. For in a sparse population and a rude state of the arts, those differences in productiveness between particular pieces of land, which are so marked in our great cities that land on one side of a street may have twice the value of land on the other side, do not exist. Even differences in the original qualities of land, that with us give rise to enormous differences in value, would, with the hunter or herdsman, or even with the agriculturist, be of no moment. Who, until production had passed even the agricultural stage, could have imagined that in the soil of Western Pennsylvania lurked differences that would some time give to one spot a value hundreds of thou- sand times greater than that of seemingly the same kind of land around it; or that a narrow strip in Nevada might be worth millions, while the land about it was worth nothing at all? * It is this confusion of Mr. Spencer as to rent and value that has led him into confusion as to the MR. SPENCER's CONFUSION AS TO VALUE. 61 right of property; and that, at first at least, pre- vented him from seeing that to secure the equal rights of men to land, it is not necessary that society should take formal possession of land and let it out, and, consequently, that the difficulties he anticipated in taking possession of improved land were imaginary. CHAPTER VI. FROM “SOCIAL STATICS ’’ TO “POLITICAL INSTI- TUTIONs.” BUT the crudities and seeds of error in Mr. Spencer's treatment of the land question in “Social Statics” were of little moment beside its sterling merit. It was a clear, and, if we except or explain the one incongruous passage, an unfaltering assertion of a moral truth of the first importance — a truth at that time ignored. If Mr. Spencer had not mastered all the details of its application, he had at least seen and stated the fundamental principle that all men have natural, equal and inalienable rights to the use of land; that the right of ownership which justly attaches to things produced by labor cannot attach to land; that neither force, nor fraud, nor consent, nor transfer, nor prescription can give validity to private property in land; and that equal rights to land are still valid, “all deeds, customs, and laws notwith- standing,” and must remain valid “until it can be demonstrated that God has given one charter of privileges to one generation and another to the next.” He had, moreover, shown that the practical recog- nition of these equal rights, even in the rude way he proposed, involved no community of goods and noth- ing like socialism or communism; but that it may be “SOCIAL STATICs.” To “POLITICAL INSTITUTIONs.” 63 carried out in a way that “need cause no very serious revolution in existing arrangements,” and would be “consistent with the highest civilization.” And this was in England, where the whole struc- ture of society — social, political and industrial— was based on and embedded in private ownership of land, and in the year 1850, when, except by a few “dreamers,” no one thought of making any distinc- tion between property in land and property in other things, and by the vast majority of men of all classes and conditions private property in land was looked on as something that always had existed, and, in the nature of things, always must exist. But beyond the warnings that this was no way to success, which he doubtless received from friends, there is no reason to think that this revolutionary utterance of Mr. Spencer in “Social Statics' brought him the slightest unpleasant remonstrance at the time or for years after. If “Sir John and his Grace”—by which phrase Mr. Spencer had personified British landed interests — ever heard of the book, it was to snore, rather than to swear. So long as they feel secure, vested wrongs are tolerant of mere academic questioning; for those who profit by them, being the class of leisure and wealth, are also the class of lib- eral education and tastes, and often find a pleasing piquancy in radicalism that does not go beyond their own circles. A clever sophist might freely declaim in praise of liberty at the table of a Roman emperor, Voltaire, Rousseau and the encyclopedists were the fashionable fad in the drawing-rooms of the French aristocracy. And at the beginning of this century, and for years afterwards, a theoretical abolitionist, 64 DECLARATION. provided he did not talk in the hearing of the serv- ants, might freely express his opinion of slavery among the cultured slaveholders of our Southern states. Thomas Jefferson declared his detestation of slavery, and, despite amendment, “writ large” his con- demnation of it in the Declaration of Independence itself. Yet that declaration was signed by slavehold- ers and read annually by slaveholders, and Jefferson himself never became unpopular with slaveholders. But when the “underground railway ” got into oper- ation; when Garrison and his colleagues came with their demand for immediate, unconditional emancipa- tion, then the feeling changed, and the climate of the South began to grow hot for any one even suspected of doubting the justice of the “peculiar institution.” So it was with private property in land for over thirty years after “Social Statics" was written. One of the first to congratulate me on “Progress and Pov- erty,” when only an author's edition of a few hundred copies had been printed, and it seemed unlikely to those who knew the small demand for works on eco- nomic questions that there would ever be any more, was a very large landowner. He told me that he had been able freely to enjoy what he was pleased to term the clear logic and graceful style of my book, because he knew that it would only be read by a few philoso- phers, and could never reach the masses or “do any harm.” For a long time this was the fate of Mr. Spencer's declaration against private property in land. It doubtless did good work, finding here and there a mind where it bore fruit. But the question had not passed beyond, and Mr. Spencer's book did not bring “SOCIAL STATICs.” TO “POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS.” 65 it beyond, the point of extremely limited academic discussion. Though it brought Mr. Spencer the appreciation of a narrow circle, and thus proved the beginning of his literary career, “Social Statics” had but a small and slow circulation. The first and only English edi- tion, as is usual with books for which no large sale is expected, was printed directly from type, without making stereotype plates. As Mr. Spencer tells us in the preface to his recent “revision and abridg- ment,” it took some ten years to sell that, after which, the sale not being enough to justify republication, which, in the absence of stereotype plates, would have involved the cost of setting up the type again, the book went out of print in England, without having attracted any general attention. This was but in the nature of things; for the class that profits by any wrong which affects the distribution of wealth must be the wealthy class, and consequently the class whose views dominate the existing organs of opinion. And until recently private property in land has been the sacred white elephant of English respectability, not even to be named without a salaam. The conspiracy of silence was therefore all that such a book could expect until it began to make way among the masses, and that neither the style of “Social Statics' nor the price at which it was published was calculated for. A similar fate to that which “Social Statics' met in England befell a very similar book, covering much the same ground – “The Theory of Human Progres- sion,” by Patrick Edward Dove, published a little before “Social Statics,” but in the same year, and also asserting the equal right to the use of land. 66 DECLAIRATION. While Dove is not so elaborate as Spencer, he is clearer in distinctly disclaiming the idea of compen- sation, and in proposing to take ground rent for public purposes by taxation, abolishing all other taxes. His book must have done some good work on the minds it reached, but it passed out of print and was practically forgotten. “Social Statics,” however, had a happier fate in passing over to the United States. Among those early attracted by Mr. Spencer's writings was the late Professor E. L. Youmans, who in 1861–62 sought his acquaintance and entered into correspondence with him. Professor Youmans's tireless energy, backed by the resources of the strong publishing house of D. Appleton & Co. of New York, with which he was connected, was thenceforward devoted to the task of popularizing Mr. Spencer and his teachings in the United States. Through the efforts of Professor Youmans, D. Appleton & Co. arranged with Mr. Spencer for the publication of his books, and in 1864, making stereotype plates, they re-issued “Social Statics,” and from that time forward kept it in print; and as may be seen, both from the preface of 1877 in their edition of “Social Statics” and from the preface to the abridgment of 1892, such English demand as existed was supplied by the sending-over of sheets printed by them " — a more economical arrangement than that of printing a book of small circulation on * A number of years passed — some ten, I think — before the edition was exhausted; and as the demand seemed not great enough to warrant the setting up of type for a new edition, it was decided to import an edition from America, where the work had been stereotyped. After this had been disposed of a third edition was similarly imported. — Preface to “Social Statics Abridged and Revised,” 7892. “SOCIAL STATICS ’’ TO “POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS.” 67 both sides of the Atlantic. Thus in a larger sphere it continued to circulate, mainly in the United States (where Mr. Spencer's reputation, aided by the active work of Professor Youmans, grew first in popular estimation), and to some small extent at least in Great Britain. But the radical utterances on the land question that it contained gave no evidence of attract- ing active interest or passing for more than an aca- demic opinion. Between 1850 and 1882, during the greater part of which time Mr. Spencer was engaged in developing his evolution philosophy, nothing more that I am aware of was heard from him on the land question. But “Social Statics,” in the United States at least, increased in circulation as Mr. Spencer's reputation grew, and its declarations continued to stand for his opinions without even a suggestion of change. Sev- eral prefaces, or notes, were from time to time added, but none indicating any modification of views with regard to the land question. The last of these was dated January 17, 1877. In this, certain changes in Mr. Spencer's opinions as to teleological implications, the political status of women, the useful effects of war, etc., are noted, but there is no modification of the radical utterances as to the tenure of land. On the contrary, he says: To the fundamental ethical principle expressing in its abstract form what we know as justice I still adhere. I adhere also to the derivative principles formulated in what are commonly called personal rights, of this or that special kind. In “Political Institutions,” which, after some mag- azine publications of chapters, was finally published 68 DECLARATION. in book form in the early part of 1882, Mr. Spencer again spoke of the tenure of land, and in a way that would lead any one acquainted with his previous fuller treatment of the subject to understand that he still adhered to all that he had said in “Social Statics.” “Political Institutions,” like the other divisions of “The Principles of Sociology” to which it belongs, is “in part a retrospect and in part a prospect.” First explaining in accordance with his general theory how social institutions have been evolved, Mr. Spencer proceeds to indicate what he thinks will be the course of their further evolution. In the chapter on “Prop- erty,” after some pages of examination he says, (Sec- tion 539): Induction and deduction uniting to show as they do that at first land is common property, there presents itself the question — How did the possession of it be- come individualized ? There can be jittle doubt of the general nature of the answer. Force, in one form or other, is the sole cause adequate to make the members of a society yield up their joint claim to the area they inhabit. Such force may be that of an external aggressor or that of an internal aggressor : but in either case it implies militant activity. Having thus repeated in a form adapted to the character of the book the declaration of “Social Stat- ics” that the original deeds to private property in land were written with the sword, he proceeds to develop it, showing by the way a comprehension of the fact that the feudal tenures did not recognize the private property in land which has grown up since, or, as he phrases it, that “the private land-ownership established by militancy is an incomplete one,” being “SOCIAL STATICS” TO “POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS.” 69 qualified by the claims of serfs and other dependants, and by obligations to the crown or state, and saying: In our own case the definite ending of these tenures took place in 1660; when for feudal obligations (a burden on landowners) was substituted a beer-excise (a burden on the community). From this, in a passage which will hereafter appear,' he proceeds to consider what is likely to be the future evolution of land tenure. Saying that “ownership established by force does not stand on the same foot- ing as ownership established by contract,” he likens individual property in land to property in slaves, and intimates that as the one has disappeared so the other will doubtless disappear, to make place for land- holding “by virtue of agreements between individuals as tenants and the community as land-owner, . . . . after making full allowance for the accumulated value artificially given.” This is a re-statement of what was said in Section 9 of “Social Statics,” where, speaking of the once uni- versal assumption that slavery was natural and right and the better faith that had been generated, he adds: It may by-and-by be perceived that equity utters decrees to which we have not yet listened, and men may then learn that to deprive others of their rights to the use of the earth is to commit a crime inferior only in wickedness to the crime of taking away their lives or personal liberty. * Thus, in so far as was consistent with the very dif- ferent scope and character of the book, Mr. Spencer *-------- - - - - ----- 1 See Mr. Spencer's letter to the Times, pp. 98–9. 70 DECLARATION. repeated in March, 1882, the views on the land ques- tion that he had set forth in 1850. And in this con- nection the words I have italicized are noteworthy as showing what was really meant in that incongruous passage in “Social Statics” previously discussed. With this re-assertion in “Political Institutions” of the views on the land question set forth in “Social Statics' we must draw a line in our review. IPA ERT II. R. E. P. U D I A TI O N. I. LETTER TO THE ST. JAMESPS GAZETTE. II. “THE MAN VERSUS THE STATE. ** III. LETTER TO THE TIMES. IV. THIS APOLOGY EXAMINED. V. SECOND LETTER TO THE TIMES. VI. MORE LETTERS. There are people who hate anything in the shape of exact conclusions; and these are of them. According to such, the right is never in either extreme, but always half way between the extremes. They are continually trying to reconcile Yes and No. Ifs and buts, and excepts, are their delight. They have so great a faith in “the judicious mean’” that they would scarcely believe an oracle, if it uttered a full-length principle. Were you to enquire of them whether the earth turns on its axis from east to west, or from West to east, you might almost expect the reply — “A little of both,” or “Not exactly either.” It is doubtful whether they would assent to the axiom that the whole is greater than its part, without making some qualification.— JHerbert Spencer, 1850. CHAPTER I. LETTER TO THE ST. JAMES's GAZETTE. WITH the early years of the last decade a marked change in common thought began to show itself; and the doctrine of natural, inalienable and equal rights to land, which Mr. Spencer had avowed as it were in academic groves, began to stir in the hearts and minds of common men, and to make way among the great disinherited. Vaguely and blindly, the land question had come to the front in Ireland, and in this form forced its way into British politics. And “Progress and Poverty,” first published in the United States in 1879, had begun, by the close of 1882, to circulate in Great Britain as no economic work had ever circulated before, re-inforcing what Herbert Spencer had said of the ethical injustice of private property in land with the weight of political economy and the proposal of a practical measure for restoring equal rights. Everywhere, in short, that the English language is spoken, the idea of natural rights to the use of land, that in 1850 seemed dead, was beginning to revive with a power and in a form that showed that the struggle for its recognition had at last begun. Believing in Mr. Spencer's good faith, deeming him not a mere prater about justice, but one who ardently desired to carry it into practice, we who sought to 74 REPUDIATION. promote what he himself had said that equity sternly commanded naturally looked for some word of sym- pathy and aid from him, the more so as the years had brought him position and influence, the ability to command attention, and the power to affect a large body of admirers who regard him as their intellectual leader. But we looked in vain. When the Justice that in the academic cloister he had so boldly invoked came forth into the streets and market-places, to raise her standard and call her lovers, Mr. Spencer, instead of hastening to greet her, did his best to get out of her way, like the young wife in the old story, who charmed the by-standers with her invocations to Death to take her rather than her elderly husband, but who, when Death rapped at the door and asked, “Who calls me?” quickly replied, “The gentleman in the next room l’’ In March, 1882, when Mr. Spencer issued “Politi- cal Institutions,” and even in August of the same year, when he left England for a visit to the United States, there was on the surface of English society nothing to indicate that such views as he had ex- pressed in “Social Statics” were any nearer attract- ing popular attention and arousing feeling than in 1850, for the Irish land movement was considered what it indeed was in the main, – not an attack on private property in land, but an effort of Irish tenants to become land-owners or to get better terms. But when Mr. Spencer returned, towards the close of November, it was to find that the days of contemptu- ous tolerance on the part of Sir John and his Grace had gone, and that all that was deemed “respecta- LETTER TO THE ST. JAMES's GAZETTE. 75 ble” in English society had become roused to the wickedness of those who denied the validity of private property in land. To explain the change that had taken place in this brief interval I must refer to my own books. “Progress and Poverty" was received by the English press, as all such books are at first, in silence or with brief derision. Messrs. Kegan Paul, Trench & Co., who first published it in England, in sheets brought from the United States, were on publication able to sell only twenty copies in all the three king- doms. But ere long it began to make its way, and when, towards the close of August, 1882, a sixpenny edition was issued, it began to sell in tens and scores of thousands, “in the alleys and back streets of England,” the Quarterly Review said – “audibly wel- comed there as a glorious gospel of justice.” Hardly was this cheap edition out and beginning to circulate, when, conjoining with it my pamphlet on “The Irish Land Question,” which had also been pub- lished in England in cheap form, the Times, on Sep- tember 11, 1882, gave to “Progress and Poverty” a long and fair review. At once the silence of the press was broken, and from the quarterlies to the comic papers the British journals began to teem with notices and references, most of them naturally of a kind that made the Duke of Argyll seem mild when he called me “such a preacher of unrighteousness as the world has never seen,” and spoke of my “im- moral doctrines” and “profligate conclusions,” the * Now published under the name of “The Land Question,” since its effort is to show that the Irish Land Question is simply the uni- versal land question. 76 REPUDIATION. “unutterable meanness of the gigantic villainy” I advocated, and so on. And from being regarded in this way in the very society in which as a great philosopher he had come to be an honored member, it was evident that Mr. Spencer could not escape if he adhered to his views. For although “Social Statics” was little known in England, the quotations I had made from it, both in “Progress and Poverty” and in “The Irish Land Question * were bringing those views into sharp prominence. This was the situation as Mr. Spencer found it on his return from the United States. The burning ques- tion — a question beside which that of chattel slavery was almost small — had been raised in England. And he must either stand for the truth he had seen, and endure social Ostracism for it, or he must deny it. “Blessed are ye when men shall revile you, and persecute you, and say all manner of evil against you!” For this to the man who has striven to up- root a great wrong — a wrong that by the fact of its hitherto unquestioned existence has necessarily en- listed on its side all the powerful influences that dominate the organs of opinion and rule society—is the sure sign that the day he has hoped for is at hand. When, in 1850, Mr. Spencer had said that the rent of land could be collected by an agent or deputy agent of the community, quite as well as by an agent of Sir John or his Grace, he must have known that if ever his proposition attracted the attention of the interests he thus personified he would be de- nounced in all the established organs of opinion, and in “polite society’ regarded as a robber. Then, I LETTER TO THE ST. JAMES's GAZETTE. 77 am inclined to think he would have hailed with joy such indications of the progress of thought. But in 1882, he no sooner found that Sir John and his Grace had been aroused by such a proposition and were likely to hear that he had made it, than he hastened to get the evidence out of their sight, and as far as he could to deny it. At once, it seems from what he tells us in 1892, he “resolved not again to import a supply” of “Social Statics,” and took the first opportunity to write a letter. The Edinburgh Review, for January, 1883, in an article entitled “The Nationalization of the Land,” re- viewed “Progress and Poverty”—as fairly, it seemed to me, as could be expected, but of course adversely. In doing so it referred to what Mr. Spencer had said on the land question in “Social Statics,” giving him credit for proposing to indemnify land-owners, and quoting with that interpretation the incongruous sentences in Section 9. In concluding it said: Writers like Mr. George and Mr. Herbert Spencer are at war not only with the first principles of political economy and of law, of social order and domestic life, but with the elements of human nature. . . . To attack the rights of private property in land is to attack prop- erty in its most concrete form. If landed property is not secure, no property can be protected by law, and the transmission of wealth, be it large or small, is extin- guished. With it expires the perpetuity of family life, and that future which cheers and ennobles the labor of the present with the hopes of the future. These are the doctrines of communism, fatal alike to the welfare of society and to the moral character of man. 1 Ten years ago, after all copies of the third edition had been sold, I resolved not again to import a supply to meet the still con- tinued demand. — Preface to “Social Statics, Abridged and Re- vised,” 1892. - 78 REPUDIATION. This brought out from Mr. Spencer a letter to the St. James's Gazette of London, an able Tory journal. Since he was writing on the subject, here was an opportunity for Mr. Spencer to correct the misappre- hension (as I now think it to be) that he had in “Social Statics' proposed to compensate land-owners for their land. And, if he wished to defend himself against the charge of attacking property rights and upholding the doctrines of communism, here was an opportunity for him to show, for all of us as well as for himself, that the denial of the justice of private property in land involves no denial of true property rights. Or if he chose to do so, here was a chance for him straightforwardly to recant, to apologize to land-owners, and to plead that he was young and foolish when he asserted, as quoted by the Edin- burgh, that “equity does not permit property in land, and that the right of mankind to the earth's surface is still valid, all deeds, customs, and laws notwithstanding.” But, instead of manfully defending the truth he had uttered, or straightforwardly recanting it, Mr. Spencer sought to shelter himself behind ifs and buts, perhapses and it-may-bes, and the implication of untruths. Here is his letter: To the Editor of the St. James's Gazette : During my absence in America, there appeared in the St. James's Gazette (27th of October, 1882) an arti- cle entitled “Mr. Herbert Spencer's Political Theories.” Though, when it was pointed out to me after my return, I felt prompted to say something in explanation of my views, I should probably have let the matter pass had I not found that elsewhere such serious misapprehensions of them are being diffused that rectification seems imperative. LETTER TO THE ST. JAMES's GAZETTE. 79 Before commenting on the statements of your con- tributor, I must devote a paragraph to certain more recent statements which have far less justification. In old days among the Persians, the subordination of subject to ruler was so extreme that, even when punished, the subject thanked the ruler for taking notice of him. With like humility I suppose that now, when after I have been publishing books for a third of a century “the leading critical organ ” has recognized my exist- ence, I Ought to feel thankful, even though the recog- nition draws forth nothing save blame. But such ela- tion as I might otherwise be expected to feel is checked by two facts. One is that the Edinburgh Review has not itself discovered me, but has had its attention drawn to me by quotations in the work of Mr. Henry George — a work which I closed after a few minutes on finding how visionary were its ideas. The other is that, though there has been thus made known to the reviewer a book of mine published thirty-two years ago, which I have withdrawn from circulation in England, and of which I have interdicted translations, he is apparently unconscious that I have written other books, sundry of them politi- cal; and especially he seems not to know that the last of them, “Political Institutions,” contains passages con- cerning the question he discusses. Writers in critical journals which have reputations to lose usually seek out the latest version of an author's views; and the more conscientious among them take the trouble to ascertain whether the constructions they put on detached pas- sages are warranted or not by other passages. Had the Edinburgh reviewer read even the next chapter to the one from which he quotes, he would have seen that, so far from attacking the right of private property, as he represents, my aim is to put that right upon an unques- tionable basis, the basis alleged by Locke being unsatis- factory. He would have further seen that, so far from giving any countenance to communistic doctrines, I have devoted four sections of that chapter to the refutation of them. Had he dipped into the latter part of the work, or had he consulted the more recently published “Study of Sociology" and “Political Institutions,” he would not have recklessly coupled me with Mr. George as upholding “the doctrines of communism, fatal alike 80 REPUDIATION. to the welfare of society and to the moral character of man’; for he would have discovered the fact (familiar to many, though unknown to him) that much current legislation is regarded by me as communistic, and is for this reason condemned as socially injurious and individ- ually degrading. The writer of the article in the St. James’s Gazette does not represent the facts correctly when he says that the view concerning ownership of land in “Social Stat- ics '' is again expounded in “Political Institutions " — “not so fully, but with as much confidence as ever.” In this last work I have said that, “though industrialism has thus far tended to individualize possession of land, while individualizing all other possession, it may be doubted whether the final stage is at present reached.” Further on I have said that “at a stage still more advanced, it may be that private ownership of land will disappear”; and that “it seems possible that the primi- tive ownership of land by the community . . . will be revived.” And yet again I have said that “perhaps the right of the community to the land, thus tacitly asserted, will, in time to come, be overtly asserted.” Now it seems to me that the words I have italicised imply no great “confidence.” Contrariwise, I think they show quite clearly that the opinion conveyed is a tentative one. The fact is, that I have here expressed myself in a way much more qualified than is usual with me; because I do not see how certain tendencies, which are apparently conflicting, will eventually work out. The purely ethical view of the matter does not obviously harmonize with the political and the politico-economical views; some of the apparent incongruities being of the kind indicated by your contributor. This is not the place to repeat my reasons for thinking that the present system will not be the ultimate system. Nor do I pro- pose to consider the obstacles, doubtless great, which stand in the way of change. All which I wish here to point out is that my opinion is by no means a positive one ; and, further, that I regard the question as one to be dealt with in the future rather than at present. These two things the quotations I have given above prove conclusively. I am, etc., HERBERT SPENCER. LETTER TO THE ST. JAMES's GAZETTE. 81 Mr. Spencer has had much to say of the unfair- ness of his critics. But this reply is not merely unfair; it is dishonest, and that in a way that makes flat falsehood seem manly. From this letter the casual reader would under- stand that the Edinburgh reviewer, on the strength of detached passages, had charged Mr. Spencer with attacking the right of private property and upholding socialism, in a sense unwarranted by the context and disproved by the next chapter; and that the pas- sage quoted from “Political Institutions” covers the same ground and disproves the constructions put on “Social Statics.” The fact is, that the Edinburgh Review had not charged either Mr. Spencer or myself with more than attacking private property in land. This we had both unquestionably done, not only in the passages it had quoted, but in many others. It had made no misconstruction whatever. What it had said of “attacking the right of private property " and “up- holding the doctrines of communism '' was a mere rhetorical flourish, made as an inference from, and by way of reply to, our denial of the right of private property in land. Mr. Spencer ignores the real charge and assumes the mere inference to be the charge. Thus, changing the issue, he cites the next chapter as if it disproved the Edinburgh's charge. This chapter (Chapter X., “The Right of Property”) which has been given in full, contains nothing to lessen the force of the attack on private property in land made in the preceding chapter. On the contrary, in this chapter he reiterates his attack on private property in land, and seeks a basis for property by 82 REPUDIATION. carrying the idea that the community should control land to the length of absurdity. Nor was the writer in the St. James's unjustified in taking the reference to land in “Political Insti- tutions” to be a briefer indorsement of the views more fully set forth in “Social Statics; ” for “Politi- cal Institutions” refers to private property in land as established by force, says that it does not stand on the same basis as ownership established by contract, likens it to slavery and predicts its abolition—ex- pressions which, in the absence of any modification of the views elaborately asserted in “Social Statics,” could be taken in no other way than as indorsing them. The passages Mr. Spencer quotes no more modify the view of land ownership set forth in “Social Statics” than Lord Lytton’s “Coming Race" controverts Adam Smith’s “Wealth of Nations.” In “Social Statics.” Mr. Spencer declares what ought to be done; in the passage he quotes from “Political Institutions” he is prognosticating as to what it is likely will be done. By now substituting prognos- tication for declaration of right, Mr. Spencer seeks to convey the false impression that the Edinburgh reviewer has been guilty of carelessness, and the writer in the St. James’s of misrepresentation, and that he himself has never gone further than to express the guarded opinion that at some time, a great way off, men may substitute a common ownership of land for private ownership. Mr. Spencer is more than unfair, too, in assuming that the charge of upholding communism, etc., is applicable to me, though not to him. For, although my book was too visionary for him to read, he had at LETTER TO THE ST. JAMES's GAZETTE. 83 least read the Edinburgh's article, and knew that the charge against me had no other ground than that against him — the denial of the moral validity of private property in land. Even what he says about such a plain matter of fact as the withdrawal of “Social Statics’ from circu- lation in England conveys untruth. The grievance that Mr. Spencer here alleges is that the Edinburgh Review had commented on a book “published thirty-two years ago, which I have with- drawn from circulation in England, and of which I have interdicted translations.” What is to be under- stood from this, and what Mr. Spencer evidently intended to have understood, is that he had, pre- sumably years before, withdrawn “Social Statics” from circulation — not in the mere territory of Eng- land, as distinguished from Scotland, Ireland or the United States, but — in English. To make sure of this understanding, he adds that he has interdicted translations — which means, not in other places, but in other languages than English. Now the truth is, that at the time he thus wrote, that book was being published by his arrangement in the United States, as it had been for years before, and continued to be for years afterwards; and that up to this very time he had been importing it into England, and circulat- ing it there. The only filament of truth in this statement, which though made incidentally is of prime importance to his purpose, is, as we now dis- cover from his own utterance in 1892, that at this very time, or possibly a few weeks previous, he had resolved not again to import any more copies of “Social Statics" into England from the United 84 REPUDIATION. States, though still keeping the book in circulation there, to be bought by whomsoever would buy As for the rest of this letter, the admirers of Mr. Spencer may decide for themselves what kind of ethical views they are that will not harmonize with political economy, and what kind of political economy it is that will not harmonize with ethics, and what they think of an ethical teacher who, on a question that involves the health and happiness, nay, the very life and death of great bodies of men, shelters himself behind such phrases as, “it may be doubted,” “it may be,” “it seems possible,” and so on, and en- deavors to make them show that he regards the matter of right as one to deal with in the future and not at present. This letter is not a withdrawal or a recantation of what Mr. Spencer had said against private property in land. It does not rise to that dignity. It is merely an attempt to avoid responsibility and to placate by subterfuge the powerful landed interests now aroused to anger. But it does indicate that a moral change had come over Mr. Spencer since he wrote “Social Statics.” In several places in that book occurs the strong, idiomatic phrase, “a straight man.” This letter to the St. James's is not the letter of a straight man. But as hypocrisy is the homage vice pays to virtue, so the very crookedness of this letter indicates Mr. Spencer's reluctance to flatly deny the truth to which he had borne witness. He no more wanted to deny it than Simon Peter to deny his Lord. But the times had changed since he wrote “Social Statics.” From an unknown man, printing with difficulty an unsal- LETTER TO THE ST. JAMES's GAZETTE. 85 able book, he had become a popular philosopher, to whom all gratifications of sense, as of intellect, were open." He had tasted the sweets of London society, and in the United States, from which he had just returned, had been hailed as a thinker beside whom Newton and Aristotle were to be mentioned only to point his superiority. And, while the fire in the hall of the High Priest was warm and pleasant, “society” had become suddenly aroused to rage against those who questioned private property in land. So when the St. James's and the Edinburgh, both of them chosen organs of Sir John and his Grace, accused Herbert Spencer of being one of these, it was to him like the voices of the accusing damsels to Peter. Fearing, too, that he might be thrust out in the cold, he, too, sought refuge in an alibi. * His recreations have been systematic — concerts, operas, theatres, billiards, Salmon-fishing, yachting, city rambles, and country excursions; and it has been his fixed rule, when work grew burdensome, to strike his tasks abruptly and go away for pleasure and amuse himself till work itself again became attractive and enjoyable. — Preface, by Professor E. L. Youmams, to “Herbert Spencer on the Americans and the Americans on Herbert Spencer, being a full report of his interview amal of the proceedings at the ſº Banquet of Nov. 9, 1882.” New York : D. Apple- tom dº Co. - CHAPTER II. “THE MAN VERSUS THE STATE.” MR. SPENCER's letter to the St. James's Gazette seems to have produced the effect he intended, and though in the United States, D. Appleton & Co. con- tinued to advertise and sell “Social Statics,” and to send to Mr. Spencer his royalties upon it;" in Eng- land, Sir John and his Grace were satisfied that he had been much maligned by garbled extracts from an early work that he had since suppressed. But Mr. Spencer himself seems to have felt that to make his position among the adherents of the House of Have quite comfortable, he must do some- thing positive as well as negative. So we find his next work to be one which the Liberty and Property Defence League, a society formed in London for defending private property in land, have ever since been active in pushing. In 1884 Mr. Spencer issued four magazine articles, “The New Toryism,” “The Coming Slavery,” “The Sins of Legislators,” and “The Great Political Su- perstition,” which were then published in a volume entitled “The Man versus the State,” and have since 1 The American people have returned the compliment by pur- chasing more than a hundred thousand of his books reprinted in this country, and upon every volume of which he has been paid as if he had been an American author. — Professor E. L. Youmams : “Herbert Spencer on the Americans and the Americans on Herbert Spencer.” “THE MAN VERSUS THE STATE.” 87 been used (1892) to fill out the revised edition of * Social Statics.” These essays are strongly individualistic, condemn- ing even bitterly any use of governmental powers or funds to regulate the conditions of labor or alleviate the evils of poverty. In this Mr. Spencer was continu- ing and accentuating a line begun in “Social Statics,” and, in the view of those who think as I do, was in the main right; for governmental interferences and regu- lations and bonuses are in their nature restrictions on freedom, and cannot cure evils that primarily flow from denials of freedom. But what in these essays marks a new departure, what makes their individualism as short-sighted as socialism, and brutal as well, is that they assume that nothing at all is needed, in the nature either of palli- ative or remedy; that they utterly ignore the primary wrong from which proceed the evils that socialism blindly protests against. In them Mr. Spencer is like one who might insist that each should swim for him- self in crossing a river, ignoring the fact that some had been artificially provided with corks and others artificially loaded with lead. He is like the preachers who thundered to slaves, “Thou shalt not steal l’” but had no whisper against the theft involved in their enslavement. . 3- The burden of these essays is, “If any would not work, neither should he eat l” This is declared to be a tenet of the Christian religion, justified by science, as indeed, though much ignored by Christians and by scientists, it is. - To whom does Mr. Spencer refer as the idlers who yet eat? 88 IRISL’UI) IATION. “Why, of course,” the reader of “Social Statics” would say, “he refers to Sir John and his Grace, and to the land-holding dukes to whom in ‘Social Statics’ he refers by name — to them and their class, pre-eminently. For they never work, and take pride that their fathers and grandfathers and great-grand- fathers never worked. Yet they eat, whoever else goes hungry, and that of the best.” But the reader of “Social Statics '' would be wrong. Mr. Spencer does not refer to them, nor allude to them, nor seem to think of them. The people on whom he would enforce the command “If any would not work, neither should he eat!” are not the fashionable idlers, whose only occupation is to kill time and “get an appetite,” but the poor idlers who say they have no work. “Say, rather, that they either refuse work or quickly turn themselves out of it!” cries the indignant philosopher, regardless now of what he once insisted on — that these men are dis- inherited; robbed by unjust law of their birthright, of their rightful share in the element without which no man can work ; dependent, therefore, on others for leave to work, and often not getting that leave. In 1850, while condemning the socialistic pallia- tives for poverty, Mr. Spencer at the same time recog- nized the truth that prompts them. He was not con- tent to show the futility of such attempts to assuage the evils of undeserved poverty without pointing out the giant wrong from which undeserved poverty springs. He began his enumeration of the evils of over-government, not as now, by merely denouncing what is done in kindly though misplaced efforts to help the down-trodden, but by recognizing the pri- “THE MAN VERSUS THE STATE.” 89 mary wrong. Beginning this enumeration (page 293, “Social Statics') he says: As the first item on the list there stands that gigantic injustice inflicted on nineteen-twentieths of the com- munity by the usurpation of the soil — by the breach of their rights to the use of the earth. For this the civil power is responsible — has itself been a party to the aggression — has made it legal, and still defends it as right. And of the moral truth involved in theories that in “The Man versus the State ’’ he unreservedly de- nounces, he says (“Social Statics,” pp. 345–46): Erroneous as are these poor-law and communist theo- ries — these assertions of a man’s right to a maintenance and of his right to have work provided for him — they are, nevertheless, nearly related to a truth. They are unsuccessful efforts to express the fact, that whoso is born on this planet of ours thereby obtains some inter- est in it — may not be summarily dismissed again — may not have his existence ignored by those in possession. In other words, they are attempts to embody that thought which finds its legitimate utterance in the law — all men have equal rights to the use of the Earth. The preva- lence of these crude ideas is natural enough. A vague perception that there is something Wrong about the relationship in which the great mass of mankind stand to the soil and to life, was sure eventually to grow up. After getting from under the grosser injustice of sla- very men could not help beginning in course of time, to feel what a monstrous thing it was that nine people out of ten should live in the world on sufferance, not having even standing room, save by allowance of those who claimed the earth's surface. Could it be right that all these human beings should not only be without claim to the necessaries of life — should not only be denied the use of those elements from which such necessaries are obtainable — but should further be unable to exchange their labor for such necessaries, except by leave of their more fortunate fellows 7 Could it be that the majority 90 REPUDIATION. had thus no better title to existence than one based upon the good-will or convenience of the minority ? Could it be that these landless men had “been mis-sent to this earth, where all the seats were already taken " ? Surely not. And if not, how ought matters to stand 2 To all which questions, now forced upon men’s minds in more or less definite shapes, there come, amongst other answers, these theories of a right to a maintenance and a right of labor. Whilst, therefore, they must be rejected as un- tenable, we may still recognize in them the imperfect utterance of the moral sense in its efforts to express equity. The wrong done to the people at large, by robbing them of their birthright — their heritage in the earth — is, indeed, thought by some a sufficient excuse for a poor law, which is regarded by such as an instrumentality for distributing compensation. There is much plausi- bility in this construction of the matter. But . . . why organize a diseased state 2 Sometime or other this morbid constitution of things, under which the greater part of the body politic is cut off from direct access to the source of life, must be changed. Of anything like this there is in “The Man versus the State ’’ no word. Mr. Spencer again takes up his parable against government interference; but he takes it up with every reference to the gigantic injustice inflicted upon nineteen-twentieths of his countrymen omitted; with everything excluded that might be offensive to the rich and powerful. Nor does he shrink from misrepresenting those who stand for the truth he has now virtually, though not openly, abandoned. In his letter to the St. James's Gazette he declared that he had not read my work ; but in “The Coming Slavery" occurs this: Communistic theories, partially indorsed by one Act of Parliament after another, and tacitly if not avowedly favored by numerous public men seeking supporters, are * “THE MAN VERSUS THE STATE.” 91 being advocated more and more vociferously by popular leaders, and urged on by organized societies. There is the movement for land nationalization which, aiming at a system of land-tenure, equitable in the abstract, is, as all the world knows, pressed by Mr. George and his friends with avowed disregard for the just claims of existing owners, and as the basis of a scheme going more than half-way to state-Socialism. And in “The Sins of Legislators” this: And now this doctrine [that society as a whole has an absolute right over the possessions of each member], which has been tacitly assumed, is being openly pro- claimed. Mr. George and his friends, Mr. Hyndman and his supporters, are pushing the theory to its logical issue. They have been instructed by examples, yearly increas- ing in number, that the individual has no rights but what the community may equitably over-ride; and they are now saying — “It shall go hard, but we will better the instruction, and abolish individual rights altogether.” Charity requires the assumption that when Mr. Spencer wrote these passages he had not read anything I had written ; and that up to the present time when he has again reprinted them he has not done so. For in nothing I have ever written or spoken is there any justification for such a characterization. I am not even a land nationalizationist, as the English and Ger- man and Australian land nationalizationists well know. I have never advocated the taking of land by the state or the holding of land by the state, further than needed for public use; still less the working of land by the state. From my first word on the subject I have advocated what has come to be widely known as “the single tax; ” i.e., the raising of public revenues by taxation on the value of land irrespective of the improvements on it — taxation which, as fast as pos- 92 REPUDIATION. sible and as far as practicable, should be made to absorb economic rent and take the place of all other taxes. And among the reasons I have always urged for this has been the simplification of government and the doing away of the injustice of which govern- ments are guilty in taking from individuals property that rightfully belongs to the individual. I have not gone so far as Mr. Spencer in limiting the functions of government, for I believe that whatever becomes a necessary monopoly becomes a function of the state; and that the sphere of government begins where the freedom of competition ends, since in no other way can equal liberty be assured. But within this line I have always opposed governmental inter- ference. I have been an active, consistent, and abso- lute free-trader, and an opponent of all schemes that would limit the freedom of the individual. I have been a stauncher denier of the assumption of the right of society to the possessions of each member, and a clearer and more resolute upholder of the rights of property than has Mr. Spencer. I have opposed every proposition to help the poor at the expense of the rich. I have always insisted that no man should be taxed because of his wealth, and that no matter how many millions a man might rightfully get, Society should leave to him every penny of them. All this would have been evident to Mr. Spencer if he had read any one of my books before writing about me. But he evidently prefers the easier method which Parson Wilbur, in Lowell’s “Biglow Papers,” was accustomed to take with “a print called the Lib- erator, whose heresies,” he said, “I take every proper opportunity of combating, and of which, I thank God, I have never read a single line.” “THE MAN VERSUS THE STATE.” 93 To do him justice, I do not think Mr. Spencer had any desire to misrepresent me. He was prompted to it by the impulse that always drives men to abuse those who adhere to a cause they have betrayed, as the readiest way of assuring Sir John and his Grace that no proposal to disturb their rentals would in the future come from him. Another thing, however, is to be noticed here — the admission that the movement for land nationaliza- tion is “aiming at a system of land-tenure equitable in the abstract.” Mr. Spencer has not reached the point of utterly denying the truth he had seen. The abolition of private property in land he still admits is equitable in the abstract. Now, what is meant by equitable in the abstract 7 Let “Social Statics,” page 64, tell us: \ For what does a man really mean by saying of a thing that it is “theoretically just,” or “true in principle,” or “abstractedly right " ? Simply that it accords with what he, in some way or other, perceives to be the estab- lished arrangements of Divine rule. When he admits that an act is “theoretically just,” he admits it to be that which, in strict duty, should be done. By “true in principle,” he means in harmony with the conduct decreed for us. The course which he calls “abstractedly right,” he believes to be the appointed way to human happiness. There is no escape. The expressions mean this, or they mean nothing. CHAPTER III. IETTER TO THE TIMES. No one can boldly utter a great truth, and then, when the times have become ripe for it, and his utterance voices what is burning in hearts and con- Sciences, whisper it away. So despite his apology to landlords in the St. James's Gazette, and the pains he had taken to make his peace with them in “The Man versus the State,” what he had said on the land question in “Social Statics” came up again to trouble Mr. Spencer. But for a long time his position on the land ques- tion was almost as dual as that of Dr. Jekyll and Mr. Hyde. In his personal circle it was doubtless assumed that he was a staunch supporter of private property in land, and if his earlier opinions were known there it was understood that he was sorry for them. And he had become, if not an active member, at least a valued ally of the Liberty and Property Defence League. But in a wider circle what he had written against private property in land was telling with increasing force. For to this wider circle his St. James's apology had hardly reached, and even when known was not deemed a recantation of the opinions deliberately expressed in “Social Statics,” which he still, through D. Appleton & Co., continued to pub- lish, without any modification whatever. The steady LETTER TO THE TIMES. 95 growth of the movement that began with the publica- tion of “Progress and Poverty” everywhere enlisted active men in the propagation of the idea of the equality of rights to land and called wide attention to what he had said on that subject. They naturally seized on the argument against the justice of private property in land in Chapter IX. of “Social Statics,” and spread it broadcast, as the utterance of one now widely esteemed the greatest of philosophers. Of all else that Mr. Spencer has written, there is nothing that has had such a circulation as has thus been given to this chapter. It was printed and is still being printed by many American newspapers," and was issued in tract form for free distribution in the United States, Canada and Australia; editions of hun- dreds of thousands being issued at a time,” many of which must have reached Great Britain, even if it was not reprinted there. This wide circulation of his condemnation of private property in land did not, it is probable, much trouble Mr. Spencer, since it did not reach his Lon- don circle. But in November, 1889 – six years after his letter to the St. James's Gazette — some echoes of it made their way into the Times, the very journalistic centre of high English respectability. The matter thus got into the Times: Mr. John Morley, Member of Parliament for Newcastle, being * Even as I write I am constantly receiving, especially from the West, copies of papers which contain Chapter IX. of “Social Statics,” and which in ignorance of all he has since said, continue to speak of Mr. Spencer as an advocate of equal rights to land. 2 About the time I ran for Mayor of New York (1SS6) on a platform which attracted great attention to the idea of equal rights to land, one enthusiastic advocate of the idea, Mr. W. J. Atkinson, himself printed some 500,000 copies. 96 REPUDIATION. in that city, was interviewed by some of his con- stituents, representing a labor organization. Among other questions land nationalization was brought up ; Mr. John Laidler, a bricklayer, speaking for it. Mr. Morley expressing dissent, Mr. Laidler cited the authority of Mr. Spencer in support of the ideas that land had been made private property by force and fraud, and should be appropriated by the community for the benefit of all. The Times of November 5th contained a report of this interview. This report in the Times aroused Mr. Spencer at once. For although he had no objection to the cir- culation of his radical utterances in America, where through D. Appleton & Co. he was still publishing and advertising “Social Statics,” it was evidently quite a different matter to him that they should be known in the pleasant circle wherein with Sir John and his ‘Grace and the peers and judges of the Liberty and Property Defence League he was per- sonally dwelling. He promptly sent this letter to the Times. It appeared on the 7th. To the Editor of the Times. SIR : During the interview between Mr. Morley and some of his constituents, reported in your issue of the 5th inst., I was referred to as having set forth certain opinions respecting land ownership. Fearing that, if I remain silent, many will suppose I have said things which I have not said, I find it needful to say something in explanation. Already within these few years I have twice pointed out that these opinions (made to appear by those who have circulated them widely different from what they really are, by the omission of accompanying opinions) were set forth in my first work, published forty years ago; and that, for the last twelve or fifteen years, I have refrained from issuing new editions of that work and LETTER, TO THE TIMES. 97 have interdicted translations, because, though I still adhere to its general principles, I dissent from some of the deductions. The work referred to — “Social Statics " — was in- tended to be a system of political ethics — absolute political ethics, or that which ought to be, as distinguished from relative political ethics, or that which is at present the nearest practicable approach to it. The conclusion reached concerning land ownership was reached while seeking a valid basis for the right of property, the basis assigned by Locke appearing to me invalid. It was argued that a satisfactory ethical warrant for private ownership could arise only by contract between the community, as original owner of the inhabited area, and individual members, who became tenants, agreeing to pay certain portions of the produce, or its equivalent in money, in consideration of recognized claims to the rest. And in the course of the argument it was pointed out that such a view of land ownership is congruous With existing legal theory and practice; since in law every land-owner is held to be a tenant of the Crown — that is, of the community, and since, in practice, the Supreme right of the community is asserted by every Act of Parliament which, with a view to public advantage, directly or by proxy takes possession of land after making due compensation. All this was said in the belief that the questions raised were not likely to come to the front in our time or for many generations; but, assuming that they would some- time come to the front, it was said that, supposing the community should assert overtly the supreme right which is now tacitly asserted, the business of compensa- tion of land-owners would be a complicated one — One that perhaps cannot be settled in a strictly equitable manner. . . . Most of our present land-owners are men who have, either mediately or immediately, either by their own acts or by the acts of their ancestors, given for their estates equivalents of honestly earned wealth, believing that they were investing their savings in a legitimate manner. To justly estimate and liquidate the claims of such is one of the most intricate problems society will one day have to solve. To make the position I then took quite clear, it is needful to add that, as shown in a succeeding chapter, 98 REPUDIATION. the insistence on this doctrine, in virtue of which “the right of property obtains a legitimate foundation,” had for one of its motives the exclusion of Socialism and Communism, to which I was then as profoundly averse as I am now. Investigations made during recent years into the various forms of social organization, while writing the “Principles of Sociology,” have in part confirmed and in part changed the views published in 1850. Perhaps I may be allowed space for quoting from “Political Institutions ° a paragraph showing the revised conclu- sions arrived at : At first sight it seems fairly inferable that the absolute owner- ship of land by private persons must be the ultimate state which industrialism brings about. But though industrialism has thus far tended to individualize possession of land while individualizing all other possession, it may be doubted whether the final stage is at present reached. Ownership established by force does not stand on the same footing as OWnership established by contract ; and though multiplied sales and purchases, treating the two ownerships in the same Way, have tacitly assimilated them, the assimilation may eventually be denied. The analogy furnished by assumed rights of possession over human beings helps us to recognize this possibility. For, while prisoners of War, taken by force and held as property in a vague way (being at first much on a footing with other members of a household) were reduced more definitely to the form of property when the buying and selling of slaves became general ; and, while it might centuries ago have been thence inferred that the ownership of man by man was an ownership in course of being permanently established, yet we see that a later stage of civilization, reversing this process, has destroyed ownership of man by man. Similarly, at a stage still more advanced, it may be that private ownership of land will disappear. As that primitive free- dom of the individual which existed before War established coercive institutions and personal slavery comes to be re-established as militancy declines, so it seems possible that the primitive ownership of land by the community, which, with the development of coercive institutions, lapsed in large measure or wholly into private owner- ship, will be revived as industrialism further develops. The régime of contract, at present so far extended that the right of property in movables is recognized only as having arisen by exchange of ser- vices or products under agreements, or by gift from those who had acquired it under such agreements, may be further extended so far that the products of the soil will be recognized as property only by virtue of agreements between individuals as tenants and the com-. munity as land-owner. Even now, among ourselves, private owner- ship of land is not absolute. In legal theory land-owners are directly or indirectly tenants of the Crown (which in our day is LETTER, TO THE TIMES. 99 equivalent to the state, or, in other words, the community); and the community from time to time resumes possession after making due compensation. Perhaps the right of the community to the land, thus tacitly asserted, will in time to come be overtly asserted and acted upon after making full allowance for the accumulated value artificially given. . . . There is reason to suspect that, while private possession of things produced by labor will grow even more definite and sacred than at present, the inhabited area, which can- not be produced by labor, will eventually be distinguished as some- thing which may not be privately possessed. As the individual, primitively owner of himself, partially or wholly loses ownership of himself during the militant régime, but gradually resumes it as the industrial régime develops, SO possibly the communal proprietor- ship of land, partially or wholly merged in the ownership of domi- nant men during evolution of the militant type, will be resumed as the industrial type becomes fully evolved (pp. 643–646). The use of the words “possible,” “possibly,” and “perhaps' in the above extracts shows that I have no positive opinion as to what may hereafter take place. The reason for this state of hesitancy is that I cannot see my way toward reconciliation of the ethical require- ments with the politico-economical requirements. On the one hand, a condition of things under which the owner of, say, the Scilly Isles might make tenancy of his land conditional upon professing a certain creed or adopting prescribed habits of life, giving notice to quit to any who did not submit, is ethically indefensible. On the other hand, “nationalization of the land,” effected after compensation for the artificial value given by culti- vation, amounting to the greater part of its value, would entail, in the shape of interest on the required purchase- money, as great a sum as is now paid in rent, and indeed a greater, considering the respective rates of interest on landed property and other property. Add to which, there is no reason to think that the substituted form of administration would be better than the existing form of administration. The belief that land would be better managed by public officials than it is by private owners is a very wild belief. What the remote future may bring forth there is no saying; but with a humanity anything like that we now know, the implied reorganization would be disastrous. I am, etc., HERBERT SPENCER. ATHENAEUM CLUB, Nov. 6. - CHAPTER IV. THIS APOLOGY EXAMINED. To drop into one of Mr. Spencer's favorite methods of illustration: “I am told,” said the respectable grandmother, with a big stick in her hand, “that you are the boy who broke down my fence and told all the other boys that they were at liberty to go into my orchard and take my apples.” “It is not true,” replied the trembling small boy; “I didn’t do it. And I didn’t mean to do it. And when I did it I was only trying to mend your fence, which I found was weak. And the reason I did it was to keep bad boys out. And I have always said you ought to be paid for your apples. And I won't do it again And I am certain your apples would give boys stomach-ache.” This letter to the Times repeats the same line of excuse made six years before in the St. James’s Gazette. Emboldened by the success of that apol- ogy, for no one seems to have thought it worth while to point out its misstatements, Mr. Spencer under- takes to face down the Newcastle bricklayer in the same way, and with even bolder crookedness. The question in issue is a question of fact — whether, as asserted by Mr. Laidler, Mr. Spencer had in “Social Statics” advocated land nationalization, and incidentally, whether he had declared that the THIS APOLOGY EXAMINED. . 101 land had been made private property by force and fraud. Without venturing specifically to deny this, Mr. Spencer denies it by implication, and gives an impression thus expressed editorially by the Times on the 9th of November: So without denying that he did once say something of the sort, he (Mr. Spencer) explains that it was forty years ago, and that for the last fifteen years he has been doing all that he can to suppress the book in which he said it, and that he never meant his words to have any bearing upon practical questions. Put into straightforward English, what Mr. Spencer says in this letter to the Times is — That he had not favored land nationalization. That he had been made to appear to have done so by quotations from “Social Statics” divested of their qualifying context. That for the last twelve or fifteen years he had stopped the publication of that work. That “Social Statics” was not intended to suggest practical political action. That what was said therein of land-ownership was said in the effort to find a valid basis for the right of property, and to exclude socialism and communism ; that it involved no departure from the existing legal theory and practice; was said in the belief that the land question would not come to the front for many generations, and admitted the right of the land-owners to compensation. That his present conclusions are, that while pos- sibly the community may some time resume land after due compensation to land-owners, he has no positive opinion as to whether it will or not. 102 REPUDIATION. That as to this he cannot harmonize ethics with political economy, for while a condition may be im- agined under which private land ownership might be injurious, its abolition would require the payment to land-owners of as great and indeed a greater sum than is now paid in rent; would involve the management of land by public officials, and that with humanity anything like that we now know, this would be dis- astrous. All this, so far as it relates to the question in issue, is simply not true. Mr. Spencer, in “Social Statics,” did condemn pri- vate property in land, did advocate the resumption of land by the community, did unequivocally and unre- servedly, and with all his force, declare for what is now called land-nationalization. That he did so does not rest on any forcing of words, any wresting of sentences from their context. It is the burden of all he says on the subject, and of the most vital part of the book. In the whole volume there is no word in modification of the opinions so strongly and clearly expressed in the full quotations I have made. Nor is it true that the conclusion of “Social Statics” concerning land ownership “was reached while seek ing a valid basis for the right of property.” It was reached as a primary corollary of the first principle: the freedom of every man to do all that he wills pro- vided he infringes not the equal freedom of any other man, and was deduced directly from the facts of human existence : Given a race of beings having like claims to pursue the objects of their desires — given a world adapted to the gratification of those desires — a world into which THIS APOLOGY EXAMINED. 103 such beings are similarly born, and it unavoidably fol- lows that they have equal rights to the use of this world. Mr. Spencer's questioning of Locke's derivation of the right of property, so far from being the cause of his denial of the validity of private property in land, grows, as we have seen, out of his idea that the only right to land is that of the community. What he has to say against socialism and communism, instead of being a motive for his advocacy of land nationaliza- tion, is brought in to strengthen land nationalization by showing that it does not involve either. And so, what Mr. Spencer gives the Times to understand as to the congruity of the view of land ownership taken in “Social Statics” with existing legal theory and practice, is so flagrantly untrue that one wonders at its audacity. As to what Mr. Spencer says of the intent of “Social Statics,” the only intelligible meaning that can be put on it is that which the editor of the Times put, “That he never meant his words to have any bearing upon practical questions.” The exact phraseology is — The work referred to — “Social Statics” — was in- tended to be a system of Political Ethics — absolute political ethics, or that which ought to be, as distin- guished from relative political ethics, or that which is at present the nearest practical approach to it. If this means anything, it means that “Social Statics” was written to set forth a system of political ethics that cannot be carried into conduct now, and that no one is under any obligation to try to carry into conduct. 104 IREPUDIATION. The applications of ethics, like the applications of mechanics, or chemistry, or any other science or body of laws, must always be relative, in the sense that one principle or law is to be taken in consideration with other principles or laws: so that conduct that would have the sanction of ethics where one is beset by robbers or murderers might be very different from the conduct that ethics would sanction under normal and peaceful conditions. In the “Data of Ethics,” one of the more recent of the works which set forth the Spencerian Philosophy, written long after “Social Statics,” this distinction between pure ethics and applied ethics is, by one of the confusions that in that philosophy pass for definitions, converted into a distinction between absolute ethics and relative ethics. Yet, if there be any sort of ethics that has no rela- tion to conduct here and now, the best term for it is Pickwickian ethics. - But the question here is not a question of defini- tion. It is a question of fact. Now, however Mr. Spencer's opinions and wishes may have changed since “Social Statics" was writ- ten, that book still shows that, when he wrote it, his intention in exposing the iniquity of private property in land was to arouse public opinion to demand its abolition. In “Social Statics” he denounced not only private property in land: he denounced slavery, then in the United States and other countries, a still- living thing; he denounced protection; he denounced restrictions on the right of free speech, the denial to women of equal rights, the coercive education of children, the then existing restrictions on the fran- chise, the cost and delays of legal proceedings, the THIS APOLOGY EXAMINED. 105 maintenance of poor laws, the establishment of state schools, government colonization, etc. Were all these pleas for reforms, some of which Mr. Spencer has lived to see accomplished, and others of which he is still advocating, Pickwickian also 2 If Mr. Spencer, in what he had to say on the land question in “Social Statics,” was talking mere ab- stract political ethics — something totally different from practical ethics — what did he mean by declar- ing that “Equity does not permit property in land”? What did he mean by saying that pure equity “enjoins a protest against every existing pretension to the individual possession of the soil, and dictates the assertion that the right of mankind at large to the earth's surface is still valid — all deeds, customs, and laws notwithstanding ”? What did he mean by scornfully sneering at those who “are continually trying to reconcile yes and no,” and who delight “in ifs, buts, and excepts”? What did he mean by saying, “In this matter of land-tenure the verdict of morality must be either yea or nay. Either men have a right to make the soil private property or they have not. There is no medium ”? What did he mean in pointing out that what is now called land nationalization “need cause no very serious revolu- tion in existing arrangements,” and that “equity sternly commands it to be done " ? What did he mean by putting, “as the first item on the list” of the injuries which government at the time he wrote was doing, “that gigantic injustice inflicted on nine- teen-twentieths of the community by the usurpation of the soil — by the breach of their rights to the use of the earth’? What did he mean by saying that 106 REPUDIATION. the only plausible defence of the poor laws was “the wrong done to people at large by robbing them of their birthright — their heritage in the earth " — by asking, “Why organize a diseased state 7” — by declaring, “Some time or other this morbid constitu- tion of things, under which the greater part of the body politic is cut off from direct access to the source of life, must be changed.” Did it all relate to the sort of ethics that has no bearing on practical questions 2 Whatever may be the ethical views of Mr. Spencer now that his eyes have been put out, and he has been set to grind in the house of the lords of the Philis- tines, the young Samson of “Social Statics” with locks as yet unshorn by the social Delilah knew noth- ing of any such ethics. Not merely in what I have quoted, but throughout the book, from first page to last, the burden of “Social Statics” is the necessity, the sacred duty of destroying abuses that fetter the equal liberty of men. He sees, indeed — as who does not? — that before liberty can truly reign men must be fit for liberty; and he realizes that there may be social conditions in which liberty might temporarily work ill; but he insists again and again that where- ever there is any yearning for liberty, any perception of the wrong done by its denial, there the time has come for the struggle against injustice to be made, and that the way to fit men for the enjoyment of rights is to destroy wrongs. The central thought of the book, that permeates all its parts, is that of a divinely-appointed order, which men are bound . to obey — a God-given law, as true in the social sphere as the laws of physics are true in the physi- THIS APOLOGY EXAMINED. 107 cal sphere, to which all human regulations must be made to conform ; and that this law is the law of equal freedom — the law from which is deduced the condemnation of private property in land. For those who palter with expediency; for those who would dally with wrong; for those who say that a thing is right in the abstract, but that practical considerations forbid its being carried into effect — Mr. Spencer, from the first page of “Social Statics” to the last, has nothing but the utmost contempt and scorn. Here is one extract from the close of the introduc- tion to “Social Statics (pp. 51, 56, 60–65) which will show how widely different were the ethics taught in “Social Statics” from what the author of the Spencerian philosophy, in 1889, told the Times they WeI'e : And yet, unable as the imperfect man may be to fulfil the perfect law, there is no other law for him. One right course only is open ; and he must either follow that or take the consequences. The con- ditions of existence will not bend before his perversity; nor relax in consideration of his weakness. Neither, when they are broken, may any exception from penal- ties be hoped for. “Obey or suffer,” are the ever-repeated alternatives. Disobedience is sure to be convicted. And there are no reprieves. . . . Our social edifice may be constructed with all possible labor and ingenuity, and be strongly cramped together with cunningly-devised enactments, but if there be no rectitude in its component parts — if it is not built on upright principles, it will assuredly tumble to pieces. As well might we seek to light a fire with ice, feed cattle on stones, hang our hats on cobwebs, or otherwise disre- gard the physical laws of the world, as go contrary to its equally imperative ethical laws. Yes, but there are exceptions, say you. We cannot always be strictly guided by abstract principles, Pru- 108 IREPUI) LATION. dential considerations must have some weight. It is Inecessary to use a little policy. Very specious, no doubt, are your reasons for advocat- ing this or the other exception. But if there be any truth in the foregoing argument, no infraction of the law can be made with impunity. Those cherished schemes by which you propose to attain some desired good by a little politic disobedience, are all delusive. . . . The reasons for thus specially insisting on implicit obedience will become apparent as the reader proceeds. Amongst the conclusions inevitably following from an admitted principle, he will most likely find several for which he is hardly prepared. Some of these will seem strange ; others impracticable ; and it may be one or two wholly at variance with his ideas of duty. Never- theless, should he find them logically derived from a fundamental truth, he will have no alternative but to adopt them as rules of conduct, which ought to be fol- lowed without exception. If there be any weight in the considerations above set forth, then, no matter how seemingly inexpedient, dangerous, injurious even, may be the course which morality points out as “abstractedly right,” the highest wisdom is in perfect and fearless submission. And these are the paragraphs with which (pp. 517, 518,) “Social Statics” closes: Not as adventitious, therefore, will the wise man re- gard the faith that is in him — not as something which may be slighted, and made subordinate to calculations of policy; but as the Supreme authority to which all his actions should bend. The highest truth conceivable by him he will fearlessly utter; and will endeavor to get embodied in fact his purest idealisms : knowing that, let what may come of it, he is thus playing his appointed part in the World — knowing that, if he can get done the thing he aims at — well: if not — well also ; though not so well. And thus, in teaching a uniform, unquestioning obedi- ence, does an entirely abstract philosophy become one with all true religion. Fidelity to conscience — this is the essential precept inculcated by both. No hesitation, THIS APOLOGY EXAMINED. 109 no paltering about probable results, but an implicit submission to what is believed to be the law laid down for us. We are not to pay lip homage to principles which our conduct wilfully transgresses. We are not to follow the example of those who, taking “Domine dirige mos” for their motto, yet disregard the directions given, and prefer to direct themselves. We are not to be guilty of that practical atheism, which, seeing no guidance for human affairs but its own limited foresight, endeavors itself to play the god, and decide what will be good for mankind, and what bad. But, on the con- trary, we are to search out with a genuine humility the rules ordained for us — are to do unfalteringly, without speculating as to consequences, whatsoever these require; and we are to do this in the belief that then, when there is perfect sincerity — when each man is true to himself — when every one strives to realize what he thinks the highest rectitude — then must all things prosper. Could there be any sadder commentary upon the Herbert Spencer who in 1889 wrote this letter to the Times 2 I am not objecting that Mr. Spencer has changed his opinions. Such change might be for the better or might be for the worse, but it would at least be within his right. What I point out is that in this letter to the Times, as in his previous letter to the St. James's Gazette, Mr. Spencer does what is not within his right, what a straight man could not do — misstates what he previously did say. And while Mr. Spencer, in this letter to the Times, is thus untruthful in regard to what he had taught in “Social Statics,” he is equally untruthful in regard to his suppression of that book. His words are — For the last twelve or fifteen years I have refrained from issuing new editions of that work, and have inter- dicted translations. 110 REPUDIATION. The plain meaning of this is, that for twelve or fifteen years prior to 1889 Mr. Spencer had stopped the publication of “Social Statics.” There is no other honest construction. And this is the way in which it was understood. The Times, in its editorial comment on Mr. Spencer's letter, taking it to mean that “for the last fifteen years he had been doing all he could to suppress the book; ” and Mr. Frederick Greenwood, who also commented on the letter, taking it to mean that “for the last fifteen years he had not allowed it to appear in any language.” As a matter of fact, this is not true. “Social Statics” was still being printed by Mr. Spencer's authorized publishers, D. Appleton & Co. of New York. The only scintilla of truth in this denial is that, as he has since (in 1892) stated, he had seven years before this resolved that he would import no more copies into England. As for the “interdiction of translations,” I suppose this means that the book bore originally the usual English formula. “Rights of translation reserved ’’; for, judging from its, going out of print in England, and its never having been pirated in the United States, it is not likely that any further interdiction was needed to prevent its translation. That Mr. Spencer should have continued the pub- lication of “Social Statics” for years after he had told the readers of the St. James's and the Times that he had suppressed it, I can only account for on the ground that he did not care to deprive himself of what revenue he was drawing from its sale, and had really no objection to the circulation of his attacks on landlordism, so long as his London friends did not hear of it. Certain it is, that he could have with- THIS APOLOGY EXAMINED. 111 drawn it at any time. Appleton & Co. are not book pirates, but honorable gentlemen, who publish Mr. Spencer's works under arrangement with their author, and even in the absence of a copyright law would certainly have ceased printing “Social Statics,” if he had requested. To any one who knows them this needs no proof. But as a matter of fact, in 1885, when the controversy between Mr. Spencer and Mr. Frederic Harrison appeared in the Nineteenth Cen- tury, the Messrs. Appleton, thinking there would be a large American sale for it in book form, made plates and printed an edition." They had barely published this when they suppressed it, as was under- stood, on a cabled request from Mr. Spencer. Not another copy went out. The copies printed were destroyed and the plates melted, although a rival firm did publish the controversy, and sell a consider- able number. Or, if he had preferred that, D. Apple- ton & Co. would at any time have printed in “Social Statics” any retraction or modification of its expres- sions on the land question he had wished. But, while the preface prefixed to the book in 1864, and the note to Chapter IV. — a reply to Professor Sidgwick, inserted in 1875 — and the additional pref- ace added in 1877, did set forth the modifications of Mr. Spencer's opinions about various other matters, they contain nothing to show any change of his opin- ions on the land question; and the book has con- tinued to be published up to 1892 without any such modification. 1 “The Nature and Reality of Religion. A Controversy between Frederic Harrison and Herbert Spencer. With an Introduction, Notes, and an Appendix on the Religious Value of the Unknow- able, by Count D’Alviella.” New York : D. Appleton & Co., 1, 3 and 5 bond Street. 1885. 112 IREPUDIATION. It is, of course, not for me to object that Mr. Spencer did not withdraw “Social Statics” in the only place where it was being published, or that he did not insert a retraction or modification of its utter- ances on the land question — although to me the won- der is that when, on his return to England in 1882, he seems to have definitely made up his mind to take the side of landlordism if pressed to it, he did not melt every plate and buy up every copy he could. I am only comparing Mr. Spencer's statements in the Times with the facts, because of the evidence the comparison gives of the character of the man, and because of the light it throws on the change in his opinions on the land question. For this letter to the Times not only shows Mr. Spencer's intense desire to be counted on the side of “vested interests” in the struggle over the land ques- tion that was beginning, but it also shows how he was intending to join formally the ranks of the de- fenders of private property in land without the hu- miliation of an open recantation of what he had said in “Social Statics.” By aid of double-barrelled ethics and philosophic legerdemain Mr. Spencer evidently hopes to keep some reputation for consistency and yet uphold private property in land. As compared with the apology in the St. James's Gazette, the new matter in this apology in the Times consists in the conversion of what he said in “Social Statics' (Sec- tion 7, Chapter IX.) as illustrating that “after all nobody does implicitly believe in landlordism,” into a conformity with “existing legal theory and prac- tice”; in the assumption that the compensation of which he had spoken (Section 9) meant compensation THIS APOLOGY EXAMINED. 113 satisfactory to landlords; and boldest of all (for this in Chapter X., Section 3, he had expressly denied), in the assumption that the recognition of equal rights to land means the administration and management of land by public officials. I should like also to call the attention of those who put faith in Mr. Spencer's philosophic acumen to the manner in which in this letter he withdraws to the Scilly Isles, and to the conditioning of the tenancy of land upon “professing a certain creed or adopting prescribed habits of life,” his condemnation of private property in land, as ethically indefensible. They have their choice between intellectual incapacity and intellectual dishonesty. What logical difference is there between a small island and a large island? between the exaction of rent in personal services and the exaction of rent in money? Is it ethically defen- sible to deny to men their birthright, to permit them to live on the earth only on condition that they shall give up for the privilege all that their labor can pro- duce save the barest living, to reduce them to straits that compel their children to grow up in squalor and vice and degradation worse than any heathenism, and to pass out of life in thousands before they are fairly in it ; yet ethically indefensible to compel them to pro- fess a certain creed or adopt prescribed habits of living? Ought it not be clear even to a philosopher's appren- tice that if English landlords to-day do not prescribe the creed or habits of their tenants, it is only because they do not care to, but prefer generally to exercise their power in taking money rent? If the Duke of Westminster wanted to have a thousand retainers, clad in his livery, follow him to St. James's ; if the 114 REPUDIATION. Duke of Norfolk cared to permit no one but Catho- lics to live on his estates; if the Duke of Argyll chose to have a buffoon at his elbow in cap and bells, they could have any of these things as readily, in fact even more readily, than could any Earl or Duke of the olden time. And so indeed could any of our great American land-owners. Did Mr. Spencer never see in London newspapers offers of employment, conditioned on the profession of a certain creed? Did he never, in passing to and from the Athenaeum Club, see coachmen and footmen dressed in fantastic liver- ies and “sandwich men’’ clad ridiculously and shame- fully 2 Does he not know that in the British Isles in his own time men are driven off the land to give place to wild beasts or cattle 2 And does he not know that the power of forbidding the use of his land gives to every land-owner the same powers of pre- scribing the conditions under which he will permit its use as any owner of the Scilly Isles possibly could have 2 The view we thus get of Mr. Spencer's mental progress and processes is interesting both philosoph- ically and psychologically. As, however, we shall find the lines of escape thus indicated amplified in “Justice,” there is no need of examining them now. But what he here says on the matter of compensation has a special interest as throwing light on what he really meant in that incongruous passage in Section 9, Chapter IX., of “Social Statics,” of which I have spoken. In this letter to the Times the only passage from “Social Statics” that is quoted, or indeed more than vaguely alluded to, is this. That Mr. Spencer intends the Times and its readers to understand this THIS APOLOGY EXAMINED. 115 as a recognition in “Social Statics” of the justice of the claim of land-owners to compensation for their land is clear, for he carefully leaves out all mention of the closely-linked sentences that immediately fol- low the passage he quotes: But with this perplexity and our extrication from it abstract morality has no concern. Men having got them- selves into this dilemma by disobedience to law, must get out of it as well as they can, and with as little injury to the landed class as may be. Meanwhile we shall do well to recollect that there are others beside the landed class to be considered. In our tender regard for the vested interests of the few, let us not forget that the rights of the many are in abeyance, and must remain so as long as the earth is monopolized by individuals. Let us remember, too, that the injustice thus inflicted on the masses of mankind is an injustice of the gravest nature . . . inferior only in wickedness to the crime of taking away their lives or personal liberties. But while it is clear that Mr. Spencer wishes the Times and its readers to understand that he not only is, but always was, as good a compensationist as land- lords could desire, he falls later on into an expression that again shows, as does the passage in “Political Institution,” that the explanation I have put upon that seemingly incongruous passage in “Social Stat- ics" is the one really intended. In the last part of the letter he speaks of “compensation for the artificial value given by cultivation amounting to the greater part of its value.” Not compensation for land, but com- pensation only for improvements. But this would never satisfy land-owners, and so, without respect for the axiom that the whole is greater than its part, he proceeds to assert that compensation for this part 116 IREPUDIATION. will equal, and indeed exceed, the value of all they now get. Thus we see both what the question of compensa- tion had really been in Mr. Spencer's own mind, and how he now proposes to settle it, so that he may henceforward take the side of existing landlordism. CHAPTER V. SECOND LETTER TO THE TIMES. IN his letter to the Times Mr. Spencer had surely abased himself enough to have been let alone by those whose favor he had so dearly sought. But even those who profit by apostasy often like to show their contempt for the apostate. Though the Times itself accepted his apology, it added some contemptuous reproof, and gave place to letters from Mr. Green- wood, Professor Huxley and Sir Louis Mallet that must have been extremely galling to a renowned philosopher. Here is the pertinent part of what the Times said: Q. So, without denying that he did once say something of the sort, he explains that it was forty years ago, that for the last fifteen years he has been doing all he can to suppress the book in which he said it, and that he never meant his words to have any bearing upon practical ques- tions. He was in fact engaged in constructing a system of “absolute political ethics, or that which ought to be,” and he feels distinctly aggrieved by the transfer of his opinions from that transcendental sphere to the very different one in which Mr. Laidler and his friends are accustomed to dwell. . . . What Mr. Spencer said in his youth and inexperience he has unsaid in his maturer years and with more deliberate judgment. . . . Were we asked to point a moral for philosophers, we should bid them beware of meddling with the absolute. Forty years ago Mr. Spencer set forth in search of “ab- 118 REPUIDIATION. solute political ethics,” and constructed his system to his own satisfaction. But it turns out to have been the most relative of things after all, since for the last fifteen years it has ceased to be absolute even to the mind that conceived it. . . . Mr. Spencer settled that which ought to be, as regards land ownership, but a quarter of a century later we find him endeavoring, much to the credit of his modesty and candor, to suppress his own version of the absolute. He does not seem, however, to have abandoned the original quest, for he gives us his revised conclusions as to the absolute ethics of land-tenure, which appear to us to contain some of the original identical flaws which were to be found in the older version. The communication from Mr. Frederick Greenwood, an able high-Tory journalist, was published by the Times on the 9th, under the heading “A Caution to Social Philosophers.” Characterizing Mr. Spencer's letter to the Times as “a heavy lesson to political philosophers,” Mr. Greenwood points out that “no matter how sorry Mr. Spencer may be for having misled so many poor men who habitually hang on the authority of great men like himself,” yet the very quotation he makes from his “Political Institutions” contains the same seeds of error in its admission that “ownership established by force does not stand on the same footing as ownership established by con- tract,” and in its admission that “the assimilation of the two ownerships may eventually be denied.” Sir Louis Mallet's letter, published on November 12th, was to similar effect. He pointed out that Mr. Spencer still admitted an analogy between private property in land and slavery, which, of course, to Sir Louis seemed dangerous and wicked. Professor Huxley came at the philosopher in a bull-headed way that must have seemed very unkind. SECOND LETTER TO THE TIMES. 119 Speaking in the name of those “to whom absolute political ethics and a priori politics are alike stum- bling-blocks,” and expressing the certainty that his friend, Mr. Spencer, would be the last person willingly to abet the tendency to sanction popular acts of injustice by antiquarian or speculative arguments, he asked him for a categorical answer to the question whether according to “absolute political ethics,” A. B., who has bought a piece of land in England, as he might buy a cabbage, has a moral as well as a legal right to his land or not? - And he follows with these pertinent questions: If he does not, how does “absolute political ethics” deduce his right to compensation ? If he does, how does “absolute political ethics” deduce the state’s right to disturb him 2 By this time Mr. Spencer must have wished he had not written to the Times, though it is a striking evidence of the little knowledge of “Social Statics” in England (a fact on which Mr. Spencer had evi- dently calculated), that in none of these letters, or in those that followed, do any of the “hecklers,” with the one exception of Mr. Laidler, seem to have any knowledge of what Mr. Spencer had really said in that book — a knowledge that would have roused their ire to a far higher pitch, and enabled them to ask still harder questions. The reader may wonder why in an attempt to deny his utterances in “Social Statics,” Mr. Spencer should have printed the passage from “Political Institutions,” which is in reality a re-affirmation of them. The only explanation I can offer is that he felt that he must 120 REPUIDIATION. print something, and had absolutely nothing else to print. For there is no word in all his works up to this time (“Justice” being yet to come) that gives the slightest evidence of any modification of the views set forth in “Social Statics.” And since he had six years before successfully referred to this passage, as though it indicated a modification of his views, he probably felt safe in so using it a second time. Thinking that it would suffice to settle Mr. Laidler, he evidently did not calculate on its provoking a “fire in the rear,” from his own friends, the adhe- rents of landlordism, when he was giving up every- thing real, and only striving to save a semblance of consistency. Mr. Spencer conveniently ignored the letters of Mr. Greenwood and Sir Louis Mallet, but he did make a pretence of answering Professor Huxley, in a letter published in the Times, November 15th. Here is the letter, which, although the first para- graph only is pertinent to the task I have in mind, I give in full, in order to guard against Mr. Spencer's controversial habit of saying that his utterances have been garbled : To the Editor of The Times. SIR : As Professor Huxley admits that his friend A. B.'s title to his plot of land is qualified by the right of the state to dispossess him if it sees well — as, by implica- tion, he admits that all land-owners hold their land sub- ject to the supreme ownership of the state, that is, the community — as he contends that any force or fraud by which land was taken in early days does not affect the titles of existing owners, and a fortiori does not affect the superior title of the community — and as, conse- quently, he admits that the community, as Supreme owner with a still valid title, may resume possession if SECOND LETTER TO THE TIME3. 121 it thinks well, he seems to me to leave the question standing very much where it stood; and since he, as I suppose, agrees with me that any such resumption, should a misjudgment lead to it, ought to be accompa- nied by due compensation for all artificial value given to land, I do not see in what respect we disagree on the land question. I pass, therefore, to his comments on absolute political ethics. “Your treatment is quite at variance with physiological prin- ciples” would probably be the criticism passed by a modern practi- tioner on the doings of a Sangrado, if we suppose one to have survived. “Oh, bother your physiological principles’’ might be the reply. “I have got to cure this disease, and my experience tells me that bleeding and frequent draughts of hot water are needed.” “Well,” would be the rejoinder, “if you do not kill your patient, you will at any rate greatly retard his recovery, as you would prob- ably be aware had you read Professor Huxley’s “Lessons on Ele- mentary Physiology,’ and the more elaborate books on the subject which medical students have to master.” This imaginary conversation will sufficiently suggest that, before there can be rational treatment of a disor- dered state of the bodily functions, there must be a con- ception of what constitutes their ordered state : know- ing what is abnormal implies knowing what is normal. That Professor Huxley recognizes this truth is, I suppose, proved by the inclusion of physiology in that course of medical education which he advocates. If he says that abandonment of the Sangrado treatment was due, not to the teachings of physiology, but to knowledge empirically gained, then I reply that if he expands this statement so as to cover all improvements in medical treatment he suicidally rejects the teaching of physiological princi- ples as useless. Without insisting upon that analogy between a society and an organism which results from the interdependence of parts performing different functions — though I be- lieve he recognizes this — I think he will admit that conception of a social state as disordered implies con- ception of an ordered social state. We may fairly assume that, in these modern days at least, all legisla- tion aims at a better; and the conception of a better is not possible without conception of a best. If there is rejoicing because certain diseases have been diminished 122 REPUDIATION. by precautions enforced, the implied ideal is a state in which these diseases have been extinguished. If par- ticular measures are applauded because they have de- creased criminality, the implication is that the absence of all crime is a desideratum. Hence, however much a politician may pooh-pooh social ideals, he cannot take steps toward bettering the social state without tacitly entertaining them. And though he may regard absolute political ethics as an airy vision, he makes bit by bit reference to it in everything he does. I simply differ from him in contending for a consistent and avowed reference, instead of an inconsistent and unacknowl- edged reference. Even Without any such strain on the imagination as may be required to conceive a community consisting entirely of honest and honorable men — even without asking whether there is not a set of definite limits to individual actions which such men would severally insist upon and respect — even without asserting that these limits must, in the nature of things, result when men have severally to carry on their lives in proximity with one another, I should have thought it sufficiently clear that our system of justice, by interdicting murder, assault, theft, libel, etc., recognizes the existence of such limits and the necessity for maintaining them ; and I should have thought it manifest enough that there must exist an elaborate system of limits or restraints on conduct, by conformity to which citizens may co-operate without dissension, Such a system, deduced as it may be from the primary conditions to be fulfilled, is what I mean by absolute political ethics. The complaint of Professor Huxley that absolute political ethics does not show us what to do in each concrete case seems to be much like the complaint of a medical practitioner who should speak slightingly of physiological generalizations, because they did not tell him the right dressing for a wound or how best to deal with varicose veins. I can- not here explain further, but any one who does not understand me may find the matter discussed at length in a chapter on “Absolute and Relative Ethics” con- tained in the “Data of Ethics.” It appears to me somewhat anomalous that Professor SECOND LETTER, TO THE TIMES. 123 Huxley, who is not simply a biologist but is familiar with science at large, and who must recognize the reign of law on every hand, should tacitly assume that there exists one group of lawless phenomena — Social phenom- ena. For if they are not lawless — if there are any natural laws traceable throughout them, then our aim should be to ascertain these and conform to them, well knowing that non-conformity will inevitably bring pen- alties. Not taking this view, however, it would seem as though Professor Huxley agrees with the mass of “prac- tical "politicians, who think that every legislative meas- ure is to be decided by estimation of probabilities un- guided by a priori conclusions. Well, had they habitu- ally succeeded, one might not wonder that they should habitually ridicule abstract principles; but the astound- ing accumulation of failures might have been expected to cause less confidence in empirical methods. Of the 18,110 public Acts passed between 20 Henry III. and the end of 1872, Mr. Janson, Vice-President of the Law Society, estimates that four-fifths have been wholly or partially repealed, and that in the years 1870–72 there were repealed 3,532 Acts, of which 2,759 were totally repealed. Further, I myself found, on examining the books for 1881–83, that in those years there had been repealed 650 Acts belonging to the present reign, besides many of preceding reigns. Remembering that Acts which are repealed have been doing mischief, which means loss, trouble, pain to great numbers — remember- ing, thus, the enormous amount of suffering which this helter-skelter legislation has inflicted for generations and for centuries, I think it would be not amiss to ask whether better guidance may not be had, even though it should come from absolute political ethics. I regret that neither space nor health will permit me to discuss any of the questions raised by Sir Louis Mallet. And here, indeed, I find myself compelled to desist altogether. In so far as I am concerned, the controversy must end with this letter. I am, etc., HERBERT SPENCER. ATHENACUM CLUB, Nov. 13. 124 REPUDIATION. Really, this “Answer to Professor Huxley’’ is no answer at all. What Mr. Spencer virtually says is: “I admit all that the land-owners may want me to admit. Let us change the subject.” Yet even in thus changing the subject, he is obliged to give up the distinction he had made between abso- lute political ethics and relative political ethics, for his long-drawn explanation to Professor Huxley means, if it means anything at all, that absolute political ethics do have a bearing on practical political conduct. CHAPTER VI. MORE LETTERS. WITH this Mr. Spencer endeavored to withdraw, and no wonder. But letters from Mr. Greenwood, Professor Huxley, and a number of new participants, including Auberon Herbert for the defence, continued to appear in the Times for some time longer, and Messrs. Greenwood and Huxley succeeded in drag- ging from him another brief confession. Professor Huxley made him give up his illustra- tion from physiological principles, and Mr. Green- wood, pressing him as to whether, as averred by Mr. Laidler, he had ever said that to right one wrong it takes another, first made him declare that he did not remember to have said it, and then, pressing him still farther, made him declare he had not said it and to repudiate it if he had. Although this is a mere side-issue, perhaps it may be worth while, even at this late date, to vindicate Mr. Laidler and refresh Mr. Spencer's memory. In “Social Statics,” Chapter XXI., “The Duty of the State,” Section 8, may be found the doctrine which Mr. Laidler referred to, when, in citing Mr. Spencer against Mr. Morley's objection to land nationaliza- tion, he said, as reported by the Times — Mr. Spencer has said that the land had been taken by force and fraud. That gentleman had also said that to right one wrong it takes another. 126 REPUDIATION. This in effect, if not in exact words, Mr. Spencer certainly does say in Chapter XXI., Section 8, in com- bating the doctrine of non-resistance. He declares all coercion immoral in itself, but (using the same terms in the same sense as Mr. Laidler) justifies govern- ment when “it uses wrong to put down wrong.” He adds: The principle of non-resistance is not ethically true, but only that of non-aggression . . . . We may not care- lessly abandon our rights. We may not give away our birthright for the sake of peace. . . . We may not be passive under aggression. In due maintenance of our claim is involved the practicability of all our duties. . . . If we allow ourselves to be deprived of that without which we cannot fulfil the Divine will, we virtually negative that will. I thus take the trouble to refresh Mr. Spencer's memory and vindicate Mr. Laidler, for, although the latter gentleman was allowed one letter in the Times, it was afterwards that the question was raised by Mr. Greenwood, and I do not suppose that Mr. Lardler got another chance, the Times speaking of him contemptuously, as a Mr. Laidler, and printing his letter in smaller type, although it was he who first brought out Mr. Spencer, and provoked the whole discussion. - Mr. Laidler's letter, of which neither party to the controversy seemed to care to take notice, was pub- lished by the Times on the same day as Mr. Spencer's second letter. He said — To the Editor of the Times. SIR : As one of the deputation of members of the Newcastle Labor Electoral Organization who recently waited upon Mr. John Morley, M. P., to ascertain his MORE LETTERS. 127 opinion on certain political and social topics, I was intrusted by my fellow-members of the deputation with the question of the nationalization of the land, and this subject I discussed with Mr. Morley. In doing so, I sought to back up my position by quoting the ninth chapter of “Social Statics,” by Mr. Herbert Spencer, and I certainly thought I had a good case when I found on my side the most distinguished authority of our time. To my great surprise, I now find that in the letters which he has addressed to you, Mr. Herbert Spencer appears to be very anxious to repudiate the doctrines which he preached so eloquently in 1850. Now, although it is a common thing for the politician of to-day to repudiate principles and deductions which he formerly warmly espoused and to adopt others which he once emergetically condemned, one does not expect the same vacillation on the part of a distinguished philosopher like Mr. Herbert Spencer. I find it difficult to under- stand his position, which seems to be this — that while adhering to his general principles he abandons certain deductions therefrom. Now, to my mind, the ninth chapter of “Social Statics,” which deals with “The Right to the Use of the Earth,” seems as true, as logical, and as unanswerable an argument in favor of the nation- alization of the land as it doubtless appeared to Mr. Herbert Spencer on the day it was written. Let us trace the course of his argument through the ten sec- tions of which the chapter is composed. Giving a short abstract of these ten sections of Chapter IX. Mr. Laidler continued — In the foregoing digest, beyond one or two connect- ing words, the language is that of Mr. Herbert Spencer himself. Does it not constitute an unanswerable argu- ment in favor of the nationalization of the land 2 If the author would permit it to be reprinted, what an admira- ble tract the ninth chapter of “Social Statics" would be for the propagation of socialistic principles | But he * Mr. Laidler uses the term socialistic in the vague way in which it is so commonly used in England, and doubtless means land nationalization principles. 128 - REPUDIATION. now seems to repudiate the offspring of his own genius ! We have, however, a right to ask that, instead of a vague repudiation in general terms, Mr. Herbert Spen- cer should tell us specifically what deductions he has abandoned and why he has abandoned them. We might then endeavor to answer his answers to his own propo- sitions. Yours, JOHN LAIDLER, Bricklayer. How far Mr. Spencer has tried to answer his own propositions, we shall see in “Justice.” L' A TERT III. R. E. C. A N T A TI O N. THE FATE OF “ SOCIAL STATICS.” THE PLACE OF “ JUSTICE * IN THE SYNTHETIC PHI- LOSOPHY. THE SYNTHETIC PHILOSOPHY. THE IIDEA OF JUSTICE IN THE SYNTHETIC PHILOSOPHY. MR. SPENCER’S TASK. “THE RIGHTS TO THE USES OF NATURAL MEDIA.” “JUSTICE * ON THE RIGHT TO LIGHT AND AIR. “ JUSTICE * ON THE RIGHT TO LAND. “JUSTICE * – THE RIGHT OF PROPERTY. THE RIGHT OF PROPERTY AND THE RIGHT OF TAXATION. COMPENSATION. “JUSTICE’” — THE LAND QUESTION. PRINCIPAL BROWN. Equity therefore does not permit property in land. . . . Not only have present land-tenures an indefensible origin, but it is impossible to discover any mode in which land can become private property. . . . Ethical truth is as exact and as peremptory as physical truth ; and that in this matter of land- tenure the verdict of morality must be distinctly aye or may. Either men have a right to make the soil private property, or they have not. There is no medium. We must choose one of the two positions. There can be no half- and-half opinion. In the nature of things the fact must be either one way or the other.— Herbert Spencer, 1850. CHAPTER I. THE FATE OF “social, STATICS.” WE now come to the purpose for which the pre- ceding lengthy examination has been made : the consideration of Mr. Spencer's present opinions on the land question, as set forth with all the weight of the “Synthetic Philosophy’ in its author's most recent volume, “Justice,” which bears date of June, 1891, and was published somewhat later in that year. But it will be best to break the chronological order, and record here the fate of “Social Statics.” Even after Mr. Spencer had made the Times and Mr. Greenwood believe that he had suppressed it years before, that book still continued to be published by Mr. Spencer's authorized publishers, D. Appleton & Co., and their edition of “Justice,” published in October, 1891, contains an advertisement of it in its original form. But now, at last, it has been done for. It has not been killed outright; that would be mercy compared with its present fate. It has — and I cannot but feel that “Progress and Poverty,’” the Edinburgh reviewer, and Mr. John Laidler of New- castle, have been innocent causes of its fate — it has been disembowelled, stuffed, mummified, and then set up in the gardens of the Spencerian Philosophy, where it may be viewed with entire complacency by Sir John and his Grace. 132 RECANTATION. Soberly, the original volume has with this year been withdrawn from publication, to give place to a new “Social Statics,” dated January, 1892, and published in February. This volume, which is, of course, now to pass in the publisher's lists as “Social Statics,” has for full title, “Social Statics, abridged and revised, together with ‘The Man versus the State.’” It con- sists of disjointed fragments of the old “Social Statics,” which, in order to make some approach to the bulk of the original, is padded out with the magazine articles before referred to. In the preface Mr. Spencer says: My first intention was to call this volume, or, rather, part of a volume, “Fragments from Social Statics,” and afterwards, “Selections from Social Statics.” Both of these titles, however, seemed to indicate a much less coherent assemblage of parts than it contains. On the other hand, to call it an abridgment is somewhat mis- leading, since the word fails to imply that large and constructively important parts are omitted. No title, however, appears appropriate, and I have at length de- cided that Social Statics, abridged and revised, is the least inappropriate. If appropriateness was what Mr. Spencer sought, it does seem as if a title much less inappropriate might have been found. For the only discernible principle of revision is the chopping-out of all that might imply a God or offend vested interests, in the same fashion that Russian censors revise distasteful works, the result being a Hamlet from which not only Hamlet himself, but the Ghost, the Queen Mother, and Ophelia, have gone. The “First Prin- ciple '' is left, but everything large or small relating to land is omitted. The only allusion to land is in THE FATE OF “SOCIAL STATICS.” 133 the cavilling at Locke, which is retained, and that what was originally Section 3, Chapter X., now con- verted into a chapter, headed “Socialism,” is left by careless editing to begin, as in the original : The doctrine that all men have equal rights to the use of the earth seems at first sight to countenance a species of social organization at variance with that from which the right of property has just been deduced.* The foot-note indicated by this asterisk is: * Referring to an omitted part of the last chapter, the *: of which, with modifications, will now be found in Part IV. of the Principles of Ethics. Thus revised, “Social Statics” no further con- cerns us. All that Mr. Spencer originally said about the relation between men and the earth having now been definitely withdrawn, we are referred for his present opinions to the book we are about to consider. But the advertising of the revised “Social Statics' is worth noting, as by some blunder it lays before the American reader what was originally intended for English circulation only, and brings to mind the fiction about the suppression of “Social Statics,” which did duty in the St. James's Gazette and the London Times. Here is the advertisement as pub- lished at the head of D. Appleton & Co.'s announce- ments in May, 1892: - 2 S00IAL STATIGS, BY HERBERT SPENCER. New and revised edition, including “The Man versus the State,” a series of essays on political tendencies heretofore published separately. 12mo. 420 pages. Cloth, $2.00. Having been much annoyed by the persistent quotation from the old edition of “Social Statics,” in the face of repeated warnings, of views which he had abandoned, and by the misquotation of others which he still holds, Mr. Spencer some ten years ago stopped 134 RECANTATION. the sale of the book in England and prohibited its translation. But the rapid spread of communistic theories gave new life to these misrepresentations; hence Mr. Spencer decided to delay no longer a statement of his mature opinions on the rights of individuals and the duty of the State. This is a queer statement to come from D. Appleton & Co., who have been publishing and advertising the old edition of “Social Statics” up to this year, with- out the slightest warning to purchasers that the author had changed his views otherwise than as stated in the prefaces and notes, which, as I have before said, made no reference to any change on the land question. It is strange to hear from them, that the annoyed Mr. Spencer ten years ago stopped the sale of his book in England, when it had not been in print for over twenty years, serenely leaving it to be sold in the only country where it was in print, and that he also at the same time prohibited its trans- lation. Why is Mr. Spencer so careful of what Englishmen in the little home island and even the “foreigner’’ may read, yet so careless of what is read by Americans, Canadians and Australians ? And why have D. Appleton & Co., for nearly ten years, been passing off on their great constituency a book that is author would not allow to be sold in his own home or in foreign countries? These are questions this advertisement suggests but does not answer. CHAPTER II. THE PLACE OF “JUSTICE * IN THE SYNTHETIC PHILOSOPHY. “JUSTICE,” to which we are to look for Mr. Spencer's present opinions on the land question, is esteemed by its author his most important book. This volume, the full title of which is, “The Ethics of Social Life — Justice,” is also entitled “Part IV. of Ethics.” It is the tenth of the pon- derous volumes already published, which are adver- tised as “Spencer's Synthetic Philosophy.” The grand divisions of this Synthetic Philosophy, as now advertised, are: “First Principles,” “The Principles of Biology,” “The Principles of Psychology,” “Prin- ciples of Sociology,” and “Principles of Morality.” Of these five grand divisions, the “Principles of Morality,” as it is styled in the advertisements, or “Principles of Ethics,” as it is styled in the title- page of the book itself, is the grand division to which “Justice ’’ belongs in the Spencerian scheme. The first volume of this grand division, “The Data of Ethics,” has been already published. Volume II., “The Inductions of Ethics,” and Volume III., “The Ethics of Individual Life,” have not yet appeared," Mr. Spencer, as he states in the preface to “Justice,” preferring to hasten this volume, as most important. After these two deferred volumes have been com- * They have been published since this was put in plate. 136 RECANTATION. pleted, there are, as he also tells us, two more volumes, “The Ethics of Social Life — Negative Benevolence,” and “The Ethics of Social Life — Positive Benevolence,” to which he will turn his attention, thus completing his full philosophical scheme. This scheme of “Synthetic Philosophy” is the most pretentious that ever mortal man undertook, since it embraces no less than an explanation to man- kind, without recourse to the hypothesis of Originating Intelligence, of how the world and all that is in it contained, including we ourselves, our motives, feel- ings, powers, instincts, habits and customs, came to be. Of this large scheme, the ethical part is the most important, being, as Mr. Spencer tells us, “that to which I regard all the preceding parts as subsidi- ary.” And of this most important part, he also tells us that this volume, “The Ethics of Social Life — Justice,” is the most important. Thus “Justice,” which so far as it treats of the land question we are about to consider, is by its author deemed the very summit and cap-stone of his whole philosophy. And that, indeed, it must be, follows from the supreme importance of its subject-matter. For it treats of right and wrong, of what should and what should not be, in those social relations of men from which spring the most fiercely debated practical questions of our time — questions that involve the happiness or misery, the physical, mental and moral development of vast populations, the advance of civ- ilization or its retrogression. As to the principles of right and wrong in individual relations there is little THE PLACE OF “JUSTICE.” 137 if any dispute; and not merely through Christendom, but “from Paris to Pekin,” mankind are substantially agreed as to what constitutes good or bad. It is when we come to the social relations of men — to those social adjustments which prescribe and control rights of ownership, which affect the production, dis- tribution, accumulation and enjoyment of wealth, which are the main ground of legislation, and which over and above the injunctions of individual moral- ity throw around men a perfect network of shalls and shall nots, that we reach the befogged and debat- able land — the region of burning questions. It is where the philosopher thus passes from the region of mere curious speculation into the arena where, for men living and men yet to come, the issues of want or plenty, of ignorance or enlighten- ment, of slavery or freedom, must be decided, that the ordinary apprehension may best apply to his teachings the tests of usefulness and sincerity. That the proof of the pudding is in the eating, and that the tree is best known by its fruit, are maxims not to be disregarded in philosophy. What matters the teach- ing of any philosophy as to the origin of things, compared with its teaching on matters that affect the fullness, happiness and nobleness of life 2 And how shall we tell whether the philosopher be an earnest man or a mere prater, so readily and so clearly as by noting whether he takes the side of wronger or of wronged, the undeservedly rich or the undeservedly poor 7 Thus, “Justice ’’ is not merely the roof and crown of the Spencerian Synthetic Philosophy; it is its touchstone as well. CHAPTER III. THE SYNTHETIC PHILOSOPHY. I WISH to keep close to the land question. But to fairly understand Mr. Spencer's views on the land question as expressed in “Justice,” and to discover what ground there may be for the changes they show, it is necessary to get some idea of the system of which it is the crown. “Justice ’’ is in fact the real revision of “Social Statics” in the new light of the system of philoso- phy which its author has since elaborated. Both books go over the same ground, that of social eco- nomics, and the title of one might serve for that of the other. This ground it was that first attracted Mr. Spencer, and he went over it forty-two years ago in the temper of a social reformer. He now re- turns to these living, burning questions of the time with the reputation of a great philosopher, after assiduous years spent in what purports to be a wider and deeper survey. For of the philosophy which he has in the meantime elaborated it is claimed not only that “it is more logically complete than any other system,” but that “it is more practical than any other, because it bears immediately upon common experi- ence, takes hold of the living questions of the time, throws light upon the course of human affairs, and THE SYNTHETIC PHILOSOPHY. 139 gives knowledge that may serve both for public and individual guidance.” " I speak of Herbert Spencer in “Social Statics” as a social reformer, to distinguish his attitude at that time from his present attitude. But he was not con- tent in that book to advocate empirical remedies for the disorder, waste and wrong that he beheld about him. He saw that expediency offered no sure guide ; that such was the infirmity of human powers, and such, in the complexity of social actions and reactions, was the impossibility of calculating results, that legis- lation based on mere policy was constantly bringing to naught the best-laid schemes, constantly entan- gling men in blind ways, constantly resulting in the unforeseen and unwished. The burden of “Social Statics” is that there is a better guide in social affairs than the calculations of expediency; that what men should look to is not results but principles; that the moral sense may be trusted where the intellect is certain to go astray. Its central idea is that the universe bespeaks to us its origin in an intelligence of which justice must be an attribute ; that there is in human affairs a divinely appointed order to which, if it would prosper, society must conform ; that there is an eternal rule of right, by which, despite all perturbations of the intellect, social institutions may be safely measured. This rule of right, as expressed in the first prin- ciple of “Social Statics” — this “law of equal lib- erty,’” that “each has freedom to do all that he wills * E. L. Youmans, M.D., “Herbert Spencer and the Doctrine of Evolution,” Popular Science Library. D. Appleton & Co., New York, 140 RECANTATION. provided that he infringes not the equal freedom of any other” — what is it indeed but an expression in primary essential of the Golden Rule 7 What Mr. Spencer declared in “Social Statics” is in fact what the National Assembly of France declared in 1789, “That ignorance, neglect or contempt of human rights are the sole causes of public misfortunes and corruptions of government.” And with clearer vision than the French Assembly, he saw and did not hesi- tate to assert that the most important of human rights from the neglect and contempt of which society to- day suffers, is the natural and equal right to the use of the planet. It is its protest against materialism, its assertion of the supremacy of the moral law, its declaration of God-given rights that are above all human enact- ments, that despite whatever it may contain of crudity and inconsistency make “Social Statics” a noble book, and in the deepest sense a religiously minded book. In the course Mr. Spencer thus entered in his early manhood there was work enough to have engaged the greatest powers for the longest lifetime; but work that would have involved a constant and bitter contest with the strongest forces— forces that have at their disposal not only the material things that make life pleasant, but present honor as well. Mr. Spencer did not continue the struggle that in “Social Statics” he began. He turned from the field of social reform to the field of speculative philosophy, in which he has won great reputation and authority. It is the scheme of philosophy thus developed that forms the basis of “Justice,” as the ideas of a TEIE SYNTHETIC PHILOSOPHY. 141 living God, of a divinely appointed order, and of an eternal distinction between right and wrong, just and unjust, form the basis of “Social Statics.” In its earlier volumes this philosophy was styled “Spencer's Evolutionary Philosophy.” This title has since been abandoned for the less definite but more ambitious one of “Spencer's Synthetic Philoso- phy.” Since synthesis is the opposite of analysis, the putting together, instead of taking apart — a synthetic philosophy is a philosophy which explains the world (a term which in the philosophic sense includes all of which we can become conscious), not by the pro- cess of taking things apart and seeing of what they are composed; but by assuming an Original principle or principles, and from that starting-point mentally building up the world, thus showing how it came to be. The Book of Genesis embodies probably the oldest synthetic philosophy we have record of. Mr. Spencer's is the latest. Spencer’s “Synthetic Philosophy’ is in the main a fusion and extension of two hypotheses — the neb- ular hypothesis of the formation of celestial bodies, and what is best known as the Darwinian hypothesis of the development of species, with a bridging over of such gulfs as the passage from the inorganic to the or- ganic, and from matter and motion to mind, and some infusion of what I take to be Kantian metaphysics. Though Mr. Spencer objects to the characterization, I can only describe this philosophy as materialistic, since it accounts for the world and all it contains, includ- ing the human ego, by the interactions of matter and motion, without reference to any such thing as intel- ligence, purpose or will, except as derived from them. 142 IRECANTATION. It does not, of course, any more than other material- istic philosophies, pretend to explain what matter and motion are, or how they came to be. That, for it, is the unknowable, while it only deals with what may be known by men. But within the region of the knowable, all things to it have come to be, or are coming to be, by the interactions of matter and mo- tion, in a process which it terms “evolution,” and which it describes as “an integration of matter, and concomitant dissipation of motion, during which the matter passes from an indefinite, incoherent homo- geneity to a definite, coherent heterogeneity, and during which the retained motion undergoes a parallel transformation.” - After evolution has reached its limit and all the motion is dissipated, comes a temporary equilibrium, and then dissolution sets in, by the integration of motion and the dissipation of matter, so that, accord- ing to the Synthetic Philosophy, the universe goes on, so far as we can see, to infinity, like one of those disks boys play with, which by means of a twisted string is made to spin around one way, then to come to a momentary stop, and then spin back the other way, the process continuing so long as the boy will gently extend and then gently bring together his hands. What is it that supplies the force furnished in the case of the toy by the boy's hands? And has it, like the boy's hands, conscious will behind it 2 This to the Spencerian Synthetic Philosophy is the unknowable. This unknowable is not God, though Mr. Spencer presents it to the religious sentiment as something with which it may be satisfied, and some of his fol- THE SYNTHETIC PHILOSOPHY. 143 lowers, and sometimes even he himself, speak of it in ways that suggest identity. In “Social Statics,” how- ever, Mr. Spencer frequently uses the term God, but he certainly never thought that he knew God in the sense of comprehending Him, or that it was possible for man so to know Him. And if the unknowable of his philosophy means that — Being above all beings! Mighty One, Whom none can comprehend and none explore Who fill’st existence with Thyself alone — Embracing all, supporting, ruling o'er — Being whom we call God, and know no more!" —why should he, with the development of his philoso- phy have abandoned the use of the old term for that which beneath the myths and fables and creeds by which men have endeavored to formulate spiritual per- ceptions has been always recognized as apparent to the human soul yet transcending human knowledge? This unknowable must be distinguished from the unknown. It is that which not only is not, but never can be known in any way; that which not merely we cannot comprehend, but of which we can know nothing at all, even of its intelligence or non-intelligence, its consciousness or non-consciousness, its nature or its attributes. It is difficult indeed to see how we may predicate even existence of it, as we may of an un- known person or unknown thing. For this requires at least some knowledge. But of the unknowable we lack the capacity of knowing anything whatever. Air is unknowable directly to our sense of sight; we can- not directly see air. But by its resistance, its weight, its chemical and other qualities, it is knowable by our * Derzhavin, Bowring's translation. 144 TECANTATION. other faculties; and it is indirectly knowable even to our sight, through the moving of leaves, the motion of watery surfaces, etc.; while if air were unknow- able, we could not be conscious of it in any possible way. It would be precisely the same to us as no air. By the constitution of the human mind it is im- possible for us in attempting to trace back the line of causation to find any stopping place until we reach that which thinks and wills — that to which the volition is akin which to our consciousness is an originating element in the trains of sequences that we ourselves set in motion, or at least modify and divert. Thus any materialistic or mechanical philosophy must either beg the question by assuming the eternity of matter and motion, or admit something behind them which it must take for granted and leave out of its explanation, simply denying that it can be recognized as intelligence or will apart from matter and motion, i.e. spirit. If the unknowable in the Spencerian Philosophy means anything more than the vacuum that is thus left where a spiritual First Cause is denied, it seems to mean what by some metaphysicians is styled “the thing in itself.” This “thing in itself” is in metaphysical language the noumenon as distinguished from the phenomenon: the thing as it really is, as distinguished from the thing as it is recognized in its qualities by the per- cipient being. But this, if not another name for spirit, really amounts to vacancy. Such idea of “the thing in itself” as opposed to the thing as known in phenomena, seems to come from the habit, to which our use of language leads, of associating in- dependent existence with qualities to which we give THE SYNTHETIC PHILOSOPHY. 145 independent names. Thus no man ever saw white except as a white thing. But as things have other colors we can readily separate the idea white from the idea thing. Forgetting, since we are only dealing with words, that the abstraction of one color implies its replacement by another color, and the abstraction of all colors would render the thing non-existent so far at least as our sight is concerned, we may men- tally separate the idea of color, and imagine the thing in other respects as remaining. Extending the pro- cess of abstraction to all other qualities, we may fancy that we have still remaining the idea of the thing separated from all idea of its qualities. But what we have remaining is really only a verbal simulacruma, that sounds like something, and may be written or parsed, but which on analysis consists of negations, and means really no thing or nothing. This, as well as I can understand it, is that “thing in itself,” of which, in some part, or in some aspects, Mr. Spencer's unknowable seems to consist. But if the Spencerian philosophy is thus indefinite as to what precedes or underlies matter and motion, it certainly shows no lack of definiteness from the appearance of matter and motion onward. With matter and motion begins its knowable, and from thenceforward, without pause or break, it builds up the whole universe by the integration of the one, and the dissipation of the other, in the mode described as evolution, without recourse to any other element. In this elimination of any spiritual element lies, it seems to me, the essential characteristie of the Spen- cerian philosophy. It is not, as is largely supposed, the evolution philosophy, but an evolution philosophy; 146 RECANTATION. that is to say, its rejection of any spiritual element in its account of the genesis of things does not follow from its acceptance of the principle of evolution; but the peculiarity of its teachings as to evolution arises from its ignoring of the spiritual element, from its assumption that, matter and motion given, their inter- actions will account for all that we see, feel or know. In reality the Spencerian idea of evolution differs as widely from that held by such evolutionists as Alfred Russell Wallace, St. George Mivart, or Joseph Le Conte, as it differs from the idea of special and direct creation. It is only when this is recognized that the real point of issue raised by or perhaps rather around the doctrine of evolution is seen. We all see that the oak is evolved from the acorn, the man from the child. And that it is intended for the evolution of something is the only intelligible account that we can make for ourselves of the universe. Thus in some sense we all believe in evolution, and in some sense the vast majority of men always have. And even the evolu- tion of man from the animal kingdom offers no real difficulty so long as this is understood as only the form or external of his genesis. To me, for instance, who, possibly from my ignorance of such branches, am unable to see the weight of the evidence of man's descent from other animals, which many specialists in natural science deem conclusive, it yet appears ante- cedently probable that externally such might have been his descent. For it seems better to accord with the economy manifested through nature, to think that when the soul of man first took encase- ment in physical body on this earth it should have taken the form nearest to its needs, rather than that THE SYNTHETIC PHILOSOPHY. 147 inorganic matter should be built up. And while I cannot conceive how, even in illimitable time, the animal could of itself turn into the man, it is easy for me to think that if the spirit of man passed into the body of a brute the animal body would soon assume human shape. Let me illustrate the distinction I wish to point Out : Here is a locomotive of the first class, or a great Corliss engine, capable on the pressure of a child's finger of exerting to definite ends a mighty force. How did it come to be 2 “It came to be,” some one might answer, “from the integrations of matter and motion. This matter existed, not to go further back than is necessary, in ores of iron and copper and zinc, and in the wood of trees. Iły motion acting on matter these materials were transported, separated, combined and adjusted, until integrated into this definite, coherent heteroge- neity that you see.” Such answer would not satisfy me. I would in- deed see that it was quite true that from the first wresting of the ores from their beds, to the last touch of file or emery paper, every step in this construction involved the action of motion on matter; but I would know that this was not all, and that what so ordered and directed the action of motion on matter as to bring this construction into being was the intelligence and volition of man. And I would reply, “You do not go deep enough : what this construction really bespeaks is something you have omitted; something to which matter is but the material, and motion the tool — the intelligence, consciousness and freedom of human will.” 148 |RECANTATION. Or, here is a picture. Let it be a reproduction of a Madonna of Raphael's, such as are made or might be made by self-feeding presses. Shall any one ex- plain the impression of grace and beauty and loving purity that it produces on him who contemplates it, by explaining on the undulatory theory of light how im- pressions of color are produced on the retina of the eye 2 Or shall he account for its genesis by telling me that by integrations of matter and motion certain pigments have become disposed on paper in a certain way ? Should he attempt to do so I would say to him, “You are telling me merely of the medium through which in this picture soul speaks to soul; you are merely telling me of the means by which the thought of the painter found expression in outward form.” But suppose he should answer — “You delude yourself. I have investigated the matter, and have been to the place where such pic- tures as this are brought forth. I saw no painter; I saw only a series of revolving cylinders, through which an endless roll of paper was drawn by steel fingers. By the automatic motion of this machinery one cylinder impressed on the paper some patches of one color, and another some patches of another color, till at last, by such successive actions of motion on matter, a picture like this came forth.” Would I be any more convinced that such a pic- ture could have come to be without that power, essen- tially different from matter and motion, which we feel in ourselves and recognize in other men, which draws a deep gulf between man and all other animals; that power which plans, contrives, and by using THE SYNTHETIC PHILOSOPHY. 149 matter and motion creates; that power in short which we call spirit? Would I not say to him, “What you tell me of the way this picture was brought forth by no means lessens my certainty that it could prima- rily have originated only in the mind and soul of a painter, but only shows me in the automatic working of the presses of which you speak a higher expression of the same power of using tools to body forth thought that was shown in the use of palette and brush. In this reproduction, as in each and all of the various processes and machines by which it was brought to be, I see a manifestation of the same essential thing that the original picture would show to me — origi- nating will, adapting mind; in short, not matter and motion, but spirit, or soul. And of what moment would be the question whether this picture came into existence by the direct action of human will upon the paper, or indi- rectly through its action upon automatic machinery, as compared with the question whether its existence involved human action or not 7 It is on this vital point of the existence or non- existence of spirit as a prime motor that the real issue raised by theories of evolution comes. Such evolutionism as is represented by the men of whom I have spoken, sees in evolution only a mode in which the creative spirit works. Such evolutionism as is formulated in the Spencerian philosophy eliminates spirit from its hypothesis, and takes into account only matter and motion. Here is where all materialistic or mechanical theo- ries of the universe ultimately fail. The belief in God, that is to say, in a Spiritual Originator, has no 150 RECANTATION. such utterly inadequate and ridiculous genesis as that which we shall shortly see Mr. Spencer gives for it. It springs from the same primary ineradicable percep- tion that universally leads men, whenever they see in a thing destitute of life the evidence of adap- tation involving choice, to attribute it to man. No civilized man, after inspection, ever took the rudest huts raised by savages for the structures of lower animals. No savage who might at a distance have thought a ship a bird, or a steamer a marine monster, ever failed on closer view to know that it was of man's building. No wandering Bedouin ever attributed to natural forces ruins so vast that they transcended his ideas of man's ability. On the contrary, so clear is the impress and testimony of that creative power which so widely and unmistak- ably distinguishes man from all other animals, that rude peoples invariably attribute constructions which they deem beyond man's ability, to genii, fairies or demons —beings possessing powers of the same kind as man, but in larger degree. And they do this for the same reason that they attribute the bringing into being of the highest of adaptations, those that embody life, to a highest of spiritual beings — the Great Spirit, or God. And when our larger knowledge shows us no wavering or confusion in the line which marks conscious adaptation, so that to the specialist the chipping of a flint taken from a long buried river-drift, or the scratching on a tusk of a pre- glacial animal, shows the same unmistakable evidence of man’s work as does the engine or the picture, how shall we otherwise interpret the evidences of design similar in kind but infinitely higher in degree which THE SYNTHETIC PHILOSOPHY. 151 nature on every hand reveals than as indicating the work of God 2 --- But to return again to our illustration: If when, to him who contends that the engine or the picture has come to be by the integrations of matter and motion, I say that such structures unmistakably be- speak man's work, suppose he should reply to me: “What is man's work but the interaction of matter and motion ? What is man's hand but a certain arrangement of matter? What is the force it exerts but a dissipation of motion? Did they, too, not exist in an indefinite, incoherent homogeneous shape in the primordial mass 2 Do they not come to man from unnumbered transmutations in the food he eats, the water he drinks, the air he breathes; to pass from him into other numberless mutations? If you think man is not included in matter and motion, shut off even for a little while his supplies of matter and motion, and where is your man 7" “Your explanation no better satisfies me than before,” I would reply. “While it may be true as far as it goes, it is inadequate and false in omitting an essential factor, and that a factor which is not last but first. Matter and motion acting to all eter- nity could not bring forth such a structure as this. I know, from all my experience of how things come to be, that this structure had its primary genesis in thought ; that in all its parts, and as a combined whole, it was thought out before it was worked out. I grant you that, at least normally, our perceptions of thought in others are dependent on our percep- tions of matter and motion. But I too think. And I know from perceptions that are even closer and truer 152 REC ANTATION. than my perceptions of matter and motion, that thought is something different from matter and motion, and from any combination of them. I think when my body is still, when my eyes are shut, even when my senses are locked from the external world by sleep. And though I can only look out, not in ; though I cannot tell you what I myself am, any more than you can tell me what matter and motion are ; although I can no more tell you how I came to be than you can tell me how matter and motion came to be, nor in what way this, that I feel is I, is em- bodied in a material frame, I do feel directly, and know from its capacities, that it is something different from and superior to the matter and motion of that frame, and that it endures while they change. And so your explanation of the genesis of things that excludes everything but matter and motion, is to me as superficial as if you were to explain a Caesar or Shakespeare by the food he ate ; an “In Memoriam' by pen and ink; or my recognition of my friend's voice, and our communication of thought through the telephone, by the copper wire and the current of electricity. “So clear, so certain, am I that what I can recognize, better than I can define, as spirit, is alone competent to produce things in which I see conscious, willing intelligence, that if you were to show me a brush that seemed of itself to paint pictures, a pen that seemed of itself to write intelligible words, or even an animal that seemed to show that power which is the essential characteristic of man, I could only account for it as a manifestation of spirit acting in a way unfamiliar to me — if not spirit in a human body, THE SYNTHETIC PHILOSOPHY. 153 playing a trick upon me, then spirit in some other form. And this would be the conclusion of all men.” While less acute thinkers profess to sneer at the evidence from design, Schopenhauer, whose great ability certainly entitles him to high rank among atheistic philosophers, is only able to avoid the con- clusion of an Originating Intelligence by eliminating intelligence from will, and assuming that bare will, or desire unconjoined with intelligence, directly origi- nates, just as the will to make a bodily movement brings about that movement without knowledge or consciousness of how it is brought about." 1 Schopenhauer’s explanation of the origin of species is in inter- esting contrast to that of the evolutionary hypothesis, and to my mind comes closer to the truth. According to him the numberless forms and adaptations of animated nature, instead of proceeding from slow modifications, by which various creatures have been adapted to their conditions, are the expression of the desire or col- lective volition of the animal. I quote from the chapter on Com- parative Anatomy in “The Will in Nature,” Bohn translation: Every animal form is a longing of the will to live which is roused by circumstances. For instance, the will is seized with a longing to live on trees, to hang on their branches, to devour their leaves, without contention with other animals and without ever touching the ground. This longing presents itself throughout endless time in the form (or Platonic idea) of the sloth. It can hardly walk at all, being only adapted for climbing; helpless on the ground it is agile on trees and looks itself like a moss-clad bough in order to escape the notice of its pursuers. . .* The universal fitness for their ends, the obviously intentional design of all the parts of the organism of the lower animals with- out exception, proclaim too distinctly for it ever to have been seriously questioned, that here no forces of Nature acting by chance and without plan have been at work, but a will. . . . [That] no organ interferes with another, each rather assisting the others and none remaining unemployed; also that no subordinate organ would be better suited to another mode of existence, while the life which the animal really leads is determined by the principal organs alone, but on the contrary each part of the animal not only cor- responds to every other part, but also to its mode of life: its claws for instance are invariably adapted for seizing the prey which its teeth are suited to tear and break, and its intestinal canal to digest; 154 RECANTATION. But within the sphere in which we can trace ori- gination does it anywhere appear that will without intelligence can accomplish anything 2 So far as its limbs are constructed to convey it where that prey is to be found, and no organ ever remains unemployed . . . added to the circumstance that no organ required for its mode of life is ever . wanting in any animal, and that all, even the most heterogeneous, harmonize together and are as it were calculated for a quite specially determined way of life, for the element in which the prey dwells, for the pursuit, the overcoming, the crushing and digesting of that prey — all this, we say, proves that the animal’s structure has been determined by the mode of life by which the animal desired to find its sustenance, and not vice versa. It also proves that the result is exactly the same as if a knowledge of that mode of life and of its outward conditions had preceded the structure, and as if therefore every animal had chosen its equip- ment before it assumed a body; just as a sportsman before starting chooses his whole equipment, gun, powder, shot, pouch, hunting- knife and dress, according to the game he intends chasing. He does not take aim at the Wild boar because he happens to have a rifle; he took the rifle with him and not a fowling-piece, because he intended to hunt the wild boar. The ox does not butt because it happens to have horns; it has horns because it intends to butt. Now to render this proof complete we have the additional circum- stance that in many animals, during the time they are growing, the effort of the will to which a limb is destined to minister, mani- fests itself before the existence of the limb itself, its employment thus anticipating its existence. Young he-goats, rams, calves, for instance, butt with their bare polls before they have any horns; the young boar tries to gore on either side, before its tusks are fully developed which would respond to the intended effect, while on the other hand it neglects to use the smaller teeth it already has in its mouth and with which it might really bite. Thus its mode of defending itself does not adapt itself to the existing weapons, but vice versa. . . . Behold the countless varieties of animal shapes. How en- tirely is each of them the mere image of its volition, the evident ex- pression of the strivings of the will which constitute its character! Their difference in shape is only the portrait of their difference in character. . . . Each particular striving of the will presents itself in a particular modification of shape. The abode of the prey there- fore has determined the shape of its pursuer . . . and no shape is rejected by the will to live as too grotesque to attain its ends. . . . As the will has equipped itself with every organ and every weapon, offensive as well as defensive, so has it likewise provided itself in every animal shape with an intellect, as a means of preservation for the individual and the species. . . . I}easts of prey do not hunt nor foxes thieve because they have more intelligence ; on the con- trary they have more intelligence, just as they have stronger teeth and claws, because they wished to live by hunting and thieving. THE SYNTHETIC PHILOSOPHY. 155 we can see clearly, is it not always true that where volition without commensurate intelligence seems to result in accomplishment it is because the needed intelligence has been supplied by another will. Thus an engine-driver desires his train to move forward or backward, fast or slow, and by a motion that seems directly responsive to his will, his desire takes effect through the pulling of a lever. He may know noth- ing of the adjustments of the machine that in re- sponse to his will thus converts heat into motion, and utterly lack the intelligence needed to construct it. But that knowledge and intelligence were none the less necessary to this moving of the train. If not conjoined with his will they were conjoined with other wills — the wills that have constructed a ma- chine by which a train may be moved on the pulling of a lever. The little intelligence needed in use proves the great intelligence exerted in construction. So a lady at the opera puts her glass to her eyes and turns a screw as she wishes to make what she sees appear nearer. She may not know how many lenses her glass contains ; still less their nature and properties; and is utterly without the knowledge required for making such glasses. But that she may accomplish at will results requiring such knowledge is because others possess it. So, if we look through any part of the wide field in which human advance has brought volition nearer to result and lessened the knowledge and intelli- gence required by the will to use, we find its reason in the greater knowledge and intelligence shown in adaptation. If the ordinary ship-master of to-day can with the aid of a quadrant, a nautical almanac 156 RECANTATION. and a table of logarithms learn from the heavens his position on the trackless ocean, it is because of the high intelligence and tireless studies of others. If girls who know only how to strike a key and inter- pret a click, or put a peg in a hole, can talk with each other hundreds of miles apart, it is because of discoverers, inventors and constructors. If, then, in the only field in which we can see ori- gination taking place, we find that the originator is always intelligent, conscious will, and if we find that where the will that uses an adapation does not pos- sess the knowledge or intelligence necessary to ori- ginate it, another will or wills conjoined with deeper knowledge and wider intelligence has done so, what is the reasonable inference as to adaptations of a higher kind, the genesis of which we cannot see, and which so far transcend the knowledge and intelli- gence of the creatures that through them are enabled to give their own wills effect? What are our bodies but a more perfect adjust- ment of parts, such as we see in machines 2 what are our eyes but a more perfect adjustment of lenses, such as we see in opera-glasses 2 If, then, my hand closes when I will to grasp, without any knowledge on my part of the correlated movements that must necessarily intervene; if when I merely will to look, the lenses of my eyes are by delicate and complex machinery directed to the position and adapted to the distance; if all through animal and even vegetable nature I may see utilizations of knowledge and adap- tations of intelligence transcending, not merely the powers of their users, but the highest human knowl- edge and intelligence, shall I infer that these utiliza- THE SYNTHETIC PHILOSOPHY. 157 tions and adaptations come without knowledge and intelligence? or shall I regard them as evidences of a deeper knowledge and wider intelligence, which, since we find intelligence and knowledge invariably associated with consciousness, must pertain to a higher consciousness 2 But to come back to the Book of Genesis that is offered to us in Mr. Spencer's Synthetic Philosophy. First — if we will insist upon a first — comes the unknowable; then force; then from force, matter and motion. Matter first appears, permeated with motion, in a state of indefinite, incoherent homogeneity, from which a principle which is styled “the instability of the homogeneous” starts the “integration of matter and concomitant dissipation of motion,” called evolu- tion, “during which the matter passes from an indefi- nite, incoherent homogeneity to a definite, coherent heterogeneity, and during which the retained motion undergoes a parallel transformation.” This is in brief the whole story: Matter revolving in accordance with the nebular hypothesis gives rise to nebulous aggregations; these to suns, which throw off revolving satellites, that in the course of time cool into earths, on the crust of which continuing evolution separates gases and differentiates the strata of inorganic matter. By the multiplying effects of motion acting on matter, the earth becomes fitted for life; and from the differences in the physical mobilities and chemical activities in the segregations of matter produce in colloid or jelly- like substances, such as starch, the beginnings of life, which is defined as “the definite combination of het- erogeneous changes, both simultaneous and successive, 158 IRECANTATION. in correspondence with external co-existences and se- quences.” And then by forces of various kinds, but all derived from motion, and being its mechanical equivalents, all the forms of life, vegetable and ani- mal, proceed. By this process of evolution man was finally de- veloped from a lower animal — he himself, with all his attributes and social institutions, being like every- thing else an outcome of this process, which, acting through survival of the fittest, heredity and the press- ure of conditions, has been and is moulding him into harmony with those conditions. Of primitive man we have much and very definite information from Mr. Spencer. He was smaller and less powerful, especially in the lower limbs, than man is now, but had a larger abdomen and came earlier to maturity. He was wavering and incon- stant; he had no surprise or curiosity or ingenuity; his imagination was reminiscent only, not construc- tive ; he lacked abstract ideas, was without notion of definiteness and truth, or of benevolence, equity or duty; he was unable to think even of a single law, much less of law in general; had neither the habit of expressing things definitely, nor the habit of test- ing assertions, nor a due sense of contrast between fact and fiction; and for him to deliberately weigh evidence was impossible. He was a cannibal; was entirely promiscuous in his sexual relations; had no idea of any other life or of any supernatural exist- ences or powers, and no care for, no sympathy with, and no idea of the goodness or badness of acts toward any of his fellows, except so far as female primi- tive man was concerned with her offspring during infancy. THE SYNTHETIC PHILOSOPHY. 159 How this sorry monster, this big-bellied, short- legged, bad lot of an ancestor of ours managed to avoid the fate of the Kilkenny cats, and keep in existence, we are not definitely informed; but it seems from the Synthetic Philosophy that he did, and went on evoluting. Various processes of his further evolution are in the Synthetic Philosophy described. Seeing shadows cast by the sun, the primitive man took them for other selves, which, aided by his dreams, brought him to a belief in doubles, more extensive even than that which Mr. Stead has expounded in his “Real Ghost Stories '' and “More Ghost Stories.” This led him to believe in another life, and his fear of chiefs and efforts to propitiate them after they were dead evolved the idea of God. Some regard for others, and some crude notion of property, was also evolved by fear of reprisal from others when he injured them or took their belongings, and by the punishment in- flicted by chiefs. Cannibalism declined as the prac- tice of slavery grew, and it became more profitable to work a captive than to eat him. But primi- tive man was not only a cannibal, he was a trophy- taker, given to the practice of gathering human heads and jaw bones as evidences of his prowess. This led to mutilations of the living, or self-mutila- tions, as marks of respect or deference, and this again led to the giving of presents; and this in its turn evolved on the one side into political and ecclesiastical revenues, and on the other into a greater respect for property, and a recognition of value, and finally into barter, and then trade. In similar ways all our perceptions, feelings, instincts and 160 TECANTATION. habits have arisen. As for the mooted question, whether we have innate ideas or whether all our ideas are derived from experience, the solution of the Syn- thetic Philosophy is, that while all our ideas are origi- nally derived from experience, they are of two kinds — those which the experience of our ancestors has registered in our inherited nervous system, and which therefore seem to us original, or innate, and those which we ourselves derive from experience. Such, in brief, is the scheme of philosophy that in the interval between the publication of “Social Statics" and the publication of “Justice ’’ Mr. Spencer has developed; and which it is the purpose of the last book to apply to the moral questions gone over in the first. Of the inadequacy of such a philosophy to account for human progress or coherently to marshal the great facts of human life and human history I have already treated at some length in Book X. of “Progress and Poverty,” entitled, “The Law of Human Progress.” But what we are now concerned with is the question, Where in such a philosophy is a basis for moral ideas to be found? I cannot see, nor can I find that Mr. Spencer has been able to. Though still continuing to condemn Bentham, as he did in “Social Statics,” all his efforts to obtain something like a moral sanction reach no further than expediency. And how can it be otherwise 2 If, in all We are and think and feel, we are but passing phases of the interactions of matter and motion 7 — if behind the force manifested in matter and motion is nothing but the unknowable, and before us nothing but dissipa- THE SYNTHETIC PHILOSOPHY. 161 tion — personal dissipation when we die, and the matter and motion of which alone we are com- posed seek other forms; and then a death of the race, followed by a dissipation of the globe 7 — why should we not eat, drink, and be merry to the limit of opportunity and digestion ? If our ideas of God and of a future life come merely from the blunders of savages so stupid that they took shadows for other selves and dreams for realities? if we would still be eating each other had it not been discovered that man might use man more profitably as a laborer than as food? if what we call the promptings of conscience are merely inherited habits, the results of the fear of punishment transmitted through the nervous system 7 — why should I not lie whenever I may find it convenient and safe to lie? why should I avoid any omission or commission that will bring no legal or social or personal penalty or inconvenience? why should I refrain from selling my ability, what- ever it may be, to any cause or interest that has power to give me what I desire, whether it be wealth or honor 2 Mr. Spencer's philosophy makes no distinction between motives and results, nor does it admit of any. If it has any gospel, it is the gospel of results, and the results that it treats as to be sought are only re- sults that make life pleasurable. Temperance, chas- tity, probity, industry, public spirit, generosity, love They have in this philosophy no promise and no reward, save as they may directly or indirectly add to the pleasure of the individual. For the self-sacrifice of the hero, the devotion of the saint, the steadfast- ness of the martyr; for the spirit that ennobles the 162 FECANTATION. annals of mankind, that has led and yet leads so many to endure discomfort, want, pain, death, for the love of the true and the pure and the good; for the noble hope of doing something to break the chains of the captive, to open the eyes of the blind, to make life for those who may come after fuller, nobler, hap- pier; for the faith that has led men to dare all things and suffer all things; it has no breath of stimulation or praise. In the cold glare that it takes for light, such men are fools. For it knows no more of human will as a factor in the advance of mankind than it does of the Divine Will. To it what conditions exist, and what conditions will exist, are determined by the irresistible grind of forces that in the last analysis are resolvable into the integration of matter and the dissipation of motion. Its fatalism eliminates free- will. Environment and heredity are everything, human volition nothing. Carry this philosophy to its legitimate conclusion, and the man is a mere automaton who thinks he is a free agent only because he does not feel the strings that move him. That I am a man is because I have been evolved from the brute, as the bowlder is rounded from the rock; as the brute, my ancestor, was evolved from colloid, and colloid from indefinite, incoherent homogeneous mat- ter. And that I am this or that kind of a man, with such and such powers, tastes, habits, ways of think- ing, feeling, perceiving, acting, is simply the result of the external influences that registered in my an- cestors the nerve impressions transmitted to me, and that have continued to mould me. Social institu- tions, the outgrowth of a similar evolution in which free-will had no part, will continue their evolution THE SYNTHETIC PHILOSOPHY. 163 without help or hindrance from anything which is really choice or volition of mine. Extremes sometimes curiously meet. The philos- ophy of Schopenhauer, which in deriving everything from will is the antipodes of the Spencerian philos- ophy, and which, like the philosophies of India, of which it is a European version, holds existence an evil, and looks for relief only to the renunciation of the will to live, would, if it were generally accepted, produce among the European races the same social lethargy, the same hopelessness of reform, the same readiness to bow before any tyrant, that have so long characterized the masses of India. It seems to me that the essential fatalism of the philosophy of ‘Mr. . Spencer would have a similar result." 1 In “Progress and Poverty,’” Book X., Chapter I., I say: The practical outcome of this theory is in a sort of hopeful fatal- ism, of which current literature is full. In this view, progress is the result of forces which work slowly, steadily and remorselessly, for the elevation of man. War, slavery, tyranny, superstition, famine and pestilence, the want and misery which fester in mod- ern civilization, are the impelling causes which drive man on, by eliminating poorer types and extending the higher; and hereditary transmission is the power by which advances are fixed, and past advances made the footing for new advances. The individual is the result of changes thus impressed upon and perpetuated through a long series of past individuals, and the social organization takes its form from the individuals of which it is composed. Thus, while this theory is, as Herbert Spencer says 1 — “radical to a degree beyond anything which current radicalism conceives;” in- asmuch as it looks for changes in the very nature of man; it is at the same time “conservative to a degree beyond anything con- ceived by current conservatism,” inasmuch as it holds that no change can avail save these slow changes in men’s natures. Philos- ophers may teach that this does not lessen the duty of endeavoring to reform abuses, just as the theologians who taught predestinari- anism insisted on the duty of all to struggle for salvation; but, as generally apprehended, the result is fatalism — “do what we may, the mills of the gods grind on regardless either of our aid or our hindrance.” Some years after this was written I had a curious illustration of its truth. Talking one day with the late E. L. Youmans, the great * “The Study of Sociology " — Conclusion. 164 RECANTATION. And as the pessimistic philosophy of the one seems to flow from the abandonment of action for mere speculation, and from the Satiety and ennui which under certain conditions accompany it, so the evolu- tionary philosophy of the other seems to be such as might result from the abandonment of a noble pur- pose — from a turning from the thorny path which an attack upon vested wrongs must open, to embrace the pleasanter ways of acquiescence in things as they are. It is not for me to say what is cause and what is effect; but the correspondence of Mr. Spencer's philosophy, which ignores the spiritual element and knows nothing of duty, with his own attitude as shown in his letters to the St. James's Gazette and the Times and in “The Man versus the State,” is very striking. In “Justice ’’ we shall see more of this correspond- €IlC6. popularizer of Spencerianism in the United States, a man of warm and generous sympathies, whose philosophy seemed to me like an ill-fitting coat he had accidentally picked up and put on, he fell into speaking with much warmth of the political corruption of New York, of the utter carelessness and selfishness of the rich, and of their readiness to submit to it, or to promote it wherever it served their money-getting purposes to do so. He became so indig- nant as he went on that he raised his voice till he almost shouted. Alluding to a conversation some time before, in which I had affirmed and he had denied the duty of taking part in politics, I said to him, “What do you propose to do about it 2 ” Of a sudden his manner and tone were completely changed, as remembering his Spencerianism, he threw himself back, and re- plied, with something like a sigh, “Nothing! You and I can do nothing at all. It’s all a matter of evolution. We can only wait for evolution. Perhaps in four or five thousand years evolution may have carried men beyond this state of things. But we can do nothing.” CHAPTER IV. THE IDEA OF JUSTICE IN THE SYNTHETIC PEIILOSOPHY. As the culminating development of his evolution- ary or synthetic philosophy, Mr. Spencer now comes to treat of those social-economic questions that in- volve the idea of justice, in a book which he entitles “Justice.” But what is justice? It is the rendering to each his due. It pre-supposes a moral law, and its corollaries, natural rights which are self-evident. But where in a philosophy that denies spirit, that ignores will, that derives all the qualities and attributes of man from the integration of matter and the dissipation of motion, can we find any basis for the idea of justice? “Justice,” says Montesquieu, “is a relation of con- gruity which really subsists between two things. This relation is always the same, whatever being considers it, whether it be God, or an angel, or lastly a man.” This, too, in “Social Statics,” was Mr. Spencer's con- ception. Justice he tells us there means equalness — that is to say, a relation of congruity or equality which is always the same, and always apprehensible by men, no matter what be their condition of development or degree of knowledge. As the basis of all his reasoning he postulates an inherent moral sense, which “none but those committed to a preconceived theory can fail 166 RECANTATION. to recognize "—a perception that bears to morality the same relationship that the perception of the primary laws of quantity bear to mathematics; and which enables us to recognize an “eternal law of things,” a “Divine order,” in which, and not in any notions of what is expedient either for the individual or for all individuals, we may find a sure guide of conduct, the apprehension of right and wrong. And this it seems to me is necessarily and universally involved in the idea of justice, so that when a man, whatever be his theories, thinks of right or wrong, just or unjust, he thinks of a relation, like that of odd and even, or more and less, which is always and everywhere to be seen by whoever will look. But this self-evidence of natural rights the Syn- thetic Philosophy denies. It admits the existence of natural rights — that is to say, rights which pertain to the individual man as man, and are consequently equal; but it derives the genesis of these rights, or at least their apprehension by man, from this process of his gradual evolution, by virtue of which they evolve, or he becomes conscious of them, after a cer- tain amount of “social discipline,” and not before. If such rights exist before, it must be potentially, or in some such way as the Platonic ideas. But as this would involve an appointed order; and hence intelli- gent will, to which we must attribute equity; and hence God; it seems inconsistent with Mr. Spencer's present view — not necessarily with that part which derives our physical constitutions from lower animals and primarily from the integrations of matter and motion — for this is a mere matter of external form, and that our bodies come, somehow, “from the dust JUSTICE IN THE SYNTHETIC PHILOSOPHY. 167 of the earth '' as the Scriptures put it, is as clear as that ice comes from water — but with that part which gives to the ego the same genesis, and accounts for our mental and moral qualities by variation, survival of the fittest, the pressure of conditions, social discipline and heredity of acquired character- istics. Mr. Spencer realizes this inconsistency, for, aban- doning altogether his original derivation and expla– nation of justice, he proceeds in “Justice ’’ to make another derivation and explanation in accordance with his new philosophy, devoting to this the first eight chapters, or something more than a fifth of the book. With its validity or invalidity, its coherency or incoherency, I am not here concerned; my object being merely to show how he arrives at the concep- tion of justice and what it is, so that we may judge the teachings of “Justice ’’ from its own avowed standpoint. To present Mr. Spencer's argument as intelligibly as I can, I will make a synopsis of the first eight chapters of “Justice,” as far as possible in his own words, but without quotation marks, employing smaller type where the exact words can be used at some length. These chapters are — 1. – Animal Ethics. During immaturity, benefits received must be in- versely proportioned to capacities possessed. After maturity, benefits must vary directly as worth, meas- ured by fitness for the conditions of existence. The ill-fitted must suffer the evils of unfitness, and the well-fitted prove their fitness. 168 RECANTATION. 2. — Sub-Human Justice. The law of sub-human justice is that each individ- ual shall receive the benefits and the evils of its own nature and its consequent conduct. 3. — Human Justice. Each individual ought to receive the benefits and the evils of his own nature and consequent conduct, neither being prevented from having whatever good his actions normally bring him, nor allowed to shoulder off this evil on other persons. 4. — The Sentiment of Justice. Our feeling that we ourselves ought to have free- dom to receive the results of our own nature and con- sequent actions, and which prompts maintenance of the sphere for this free play, results from inheritances of modifications produced by habit, or from more numerous survivals of individuals having nervous structures which have varied in fit ways, and from the tendency of groups formed of members having this adaptation to survive and spread. Recognition of the similar freedom of others is evolved from the fear of retaliation, from the punishment of inter- ference prompted by the interests of the chief, from fear of the dead chief's ghost, and from fear of God, when dead-chief-ghost worship grows into God wor- ship, and, finally, by the sympathy evolved by grega- riousness. - 5. – The Idea of Justice. It emerges and becomes definite from experiences, generation after generation, which provoke resent- ment and reactive pains, until finally there arises a conception of a limit to each kind of activity up to which there is freedom to act. But it is a long time before the general nature of the limit common to all cases can be conceived. On the one hand there is JUSTICE IN THE SYNTHETIC PHILOSOPHY. 169 the positive element, implied by each man’s recog- nition of his claims to unimpeded activities and the benefits they bring; on the other hand there is the negative element implied by the consciousness of limits which the presence of other men having like claims necessitates. Inequality is suggested by the one, for if each is to receive the benefits due his own nature and consequent conduct, then, since men dif- fer in their powers, there must be differences in the results. Equality is suggested by the other, since bounds must be set to the doings of each to avoid quarrels, and experience shows that these bounds are on the average the same for all. Unbalanced appre- ciation of the one is fostered by war, and tends to Social organization of the militant type, where in- equality is established by authority, an inequality referring, not to the natural achievement of greater rewards by greater merits, but to the artificial appor- tionment of greater rewards to greater merits. Un- balanced appreciation of the other tends to such theories as Bentham's greatest happiness principle, and to communism and socialism. The true concep- tion is to be obtained by noting that the equality concerns the mutually limited spheres of action which must be maintained if associated men are to co-oper- ate harmoniously, while the inequality concerns the results which each may achieve by carrying on his actions within the implied limits. The two may be and must be simultaneously asserted. 6. – The Formula of Justice. It must be positive in so far as it asserts for each that, since he is to receive and suffer the good and evil of his own actions, he must be allowed to act. And it must be negative in so far as, by asserting this of every one, it implies that each can be allowed to act only under the restraint imposed by the presence of others having like claims tº act. Evidently, the positive element is that which expresses a prereq- 170 RECANTATION. uisite to life in general, and the negative element is that which qualifies this prerequisite in the way required, when, instead of one life carried on alone, there are many lives carried on together. Hence, that which we have to express in a precise way is the liberty of each limited only by the like liberties of all. This we do by saying, Every man is free to do what he wills, provided he infringes not the equal freedom of any other man. 7. — The Authority of this Formula. The reigning school of politics and morals has a contempt for doctrines that imply restraint on the doings of immediate expediency. But if causation be universal, it must hold throughout the actions of incorporated men. Evolution implies that a distinct conception of justice can have arisen but gradually. It has gone on more rapidly under peaceful relations, and been held back by war. Nevertheless, where the conditions have allowed, it has evolved slowly to some extent, and formed for itself approximately true expressions, as shown in the Hebrew Commandments, and without distinction between generosity and jus- tice, in the Christian Golden Rule, and in modern forms in the rule of Kant. It is also shown on the legal side, in the maxims of lawyers as to natural law, admitted inferentially even by the despotically- minded Austin. These, it will be objected, are a priori beliefs. The doctrine of evolution teaches that a priori beliefs entertained by men at large Inust have arisen, if not from the experiences of each individual, then from the experiences of the race. Fixed intuitions must have been established by that intercourse with things which throughout an enormous past has directly and indirectly determined the organization of the nervous system, and certain resulting necessities of thought. Thus had the law of equal freedom no other than a priori derivations, it would still be rational to re- JUSTICE IN THE SYNTHETIC PHILOSOPHY. 171 gard it as an adumbration of a truth, if not still literally true. And the inductive school, including Bentham and Mill are, on analysis, driven to the basis of a priori cognitions. - But the principle of natural equity, expressed in the freedom of each, limited only by the like freedom of all, is not exclusively an a priori belief. Examination of the facts has shown it to be a funda- mental law, by conformity to which life has evolved from its lowest up to its highest forms, that each adult individual shall take the consequences of its own nature and actions: survival of the fittest being the result. And the necessary implication is an assertion of that full liberty to act which forms the positive element in the formula of justice; since, without full liberty to act, the relation between conduct and consequence cannot be maintained. Various examples have made clear the conclusion manifest in theory, that among gregarious creatures this freedom of each to act has to be restricted; since if it is unrestricted there must arise such clashing of actions as prevents the gregariousness. And the fact that, relatively unintelligent though they are, inferior gregarious creatures inflict penalties for breaches of the needful restrictions, shows how regard for them has come to be unconsciously established as a condition to persistent social life. These two laws, holding, the one of all creatures and the other of social creatures, and the display of which is clearer in proportion as the evolution is higher, find their last and fullest sphere of manifestation in human socie- ties. We have recently seen that along with the growth of peaceful co-operation there has been an increasing conformity to this compound law under both its positive and negative aspects; and we have also seen that there has gone on simultaneously an increase of emotional regard for it, and intellectual apprehension of it. So that we have not only the reasons above given for concluding that this a priori belief has its origin in the experiences of the race, but we are enabled to affiliate it on the experiences of living creatures at large, and to perceive that it is but a conscious response to certain necessary relations in the order of nature. 172 RECANTATION. No higher warrant can be imagined; and now, accept- ing the law of equal freedom as an ultimate ethical principle, having an authority transcending every other, we may proceed with our inquiry. 8. — Its Corollaries. That the general formula of justice may serve for guidance, deductions must be drawn severally appli- cable to special classes of cases. The several par- ticular freedoms deducible from the laws of equal freedom may fitly be called, as they commonly are called, rights. Rights truly so called are corollaries from the law of equal freedom, and what are falsely called rights are not deducible from it. It is not worth while to examine this argument. It is sufficient for our purpose to see that in “Justice” Mr. Spencer re-asserts the same principle from which in “Social Statics” he condemned private property in land. CHAPTER V. MR. SPENCER's TASK. THE first eight chapters of “Justice,” as we have seen, bring Mr. Spencer by a different route to the same “first principle '' which he had laid down forty years before in “Social Statics,” and from which he had deduced the equal right of all men to the use of land and the ethical invalidity of private property in land — “all deeds, customs, and laws notwith- standing.” We are not concerned now with “Social Statics.” We are not concerned with any of Mr. Spencer's changes in opinion, teleological, metaphysical, or of any other kind. We have here merely the Synthetic philosopher, who from grounds based on the doctrine of evolution lays down as the fundamental formula of justice, the axiomatic principle from which all the rights of men in their relations with each other are to be deduced: that all men have freedom to do as they will, provided they infringe not the equal freedom of all others." What follows, with regard to the use 1 From Appendix A of “Justice,” it seems that Mr. Spencer has hitherto supposed that his statement of this “first principle ’’ of “Social Statics,” was the first time it had been thus put. In 1883 Professor Maitland had, however, pointed out that “ Kant had already enunciated in other words a similar doctrine.” Mr. Spencer tells us that, “Not being able to read the German quotation given by Mr. Maitland,” he was unable to test the statement until, in the 174 RECANTATION. of land, from this fundamental principle of the evolu- tionary philosophy 2 Is it not, unavoidably and irre- sistibly what Mr. Spencer stated years before ?— Given a race of human beings having like claims to pursue the objects of their desires — given a world adapted to the gratification of those desires — a world into which such beings are similarly born, and it una- voidably follows that they have equal rights to the use of this world. For if each of them “has freedom to do all that he wills, provided he infringes not the equal freedom of any other,” then each of them is free to use the earth for the satisfaction of his wants, provided he allows all others the same liberty. And conversely, it is manifest that no one, or part of them, may use the earth in such a way as to prevent the rest from similarly using it; seeing that to do this is to assume greater freedom than the rest, and consequently to break the law. Is there one single deduction in Chapter IX. of “Social Statics" that does not as clearly follow from this reasoning of “Justice ’” — one single word that requires alteration to fit it for a place in the deduc- tions to be drawn from this formula, except the single word God? And the substitution of “The preparation of “Justice,” he reached Chapter VI., when he discov- ered in a recent English translation of Kant certain passages which he gives, that “make it clear that Kant had arrived at a conclu- sion, which, if not the same as my own, is closely allied to it.” I mention this as showing the importance Mr. Spencer yet attaches to the “first principle,” from which he deduced the con- demnation of private property in land. Otherwise the matter is of no interest. His statement of this principle or formula was a good one, and doubtless original with him. Who had stated it before made no more difference than who first stated that one and one equal two. There are some things which to the human mind are self-evident — that is to say, which may be seen by whoever chooses to look — and this is one of them. MR. SPENCER's TASK. 175 Unknowable” or “Evolution ” for “God” would in no wise alter or lessen the force of the reasoning. How, then, shall Mr. Spencer justify private prop- erty in land, which in his letters to the Times he had bound himself to do? How shall he deduce the rights of land-owners to compensation for their land or in any way assert for them rights that will lessen or modify, or in any way condition, the equal right of all their fellows to the use of land 7 To men like Professor Huxley there is a short and easy way of doing this. It is simply to deny the existence of natural rights ; that is to say, rights having any higher or more permanent sanction than municipal regulation. To be sure this opens a most awkward dilemma, for if power, or if you please legislative enactment, be the only sanction of right, what remains for the House of Have, when the House of Want shall muster its more numerous forces, either on the field of brute strength or in legislatures already controlled by popular suffrage 2 But, “after us, the deluge!” and such considerations do not much trouble those who take this short and easy way. Mr. Spencer, however, is debarred from taking it; not by what he has before said on the land question, for that could be unsaid, but by his philosophy. If there is no right but might, what does that philosophy mean and what is it for 2 If there is no law but that of the state, why does he write books to tell us what the state ought and ought not to do? And, furthermore, he has just deduced as his formula of justice, having, he says, the highest imaginable warrant — the same first principle from which in “Social Statics” he deduced the invalidity of private property in land. 176 RECANTATION. The short and easy way of justifying private prop- erty in land, because it exists, or because it is sanc- tioned by the state, is therefore not open to Mr. Spencer, unless he is ready to abandon the last shred and figment of philosophic claim. His is a more difficult task. What he has to do, is to prove that the disinheritance of nineteen-twentieths of his coun- trymen accords with his “ultimate ethical principle having an authority transcending every other ”— his formula of justice, that “Every man is free to do that which he will, provided he infringes not the equal freedom of any other man.” To show that the so-called rights of existing land-owners to monopolize the land on which all must live are real rights, he must, on his own statement, show that they are deducible from the law of equal freedom. Knowing, then, from Mr. Spencer's more recent utterances that he is determined at any cost to get on the comfortable side of the land question, we may be certain in advance that “Justice ’’ will afford a spectacle both interesting and instructive. Interest- ing as the effort of a man of ability to accomplish a feat of intellectual legerdemain equivalent, not to swallowing a sword, but to swallowing himself. Instructive as showing how far a man so able that many people think him the greatest philosopher that has ever yet appeared; a man who has the advantage of knowing what can be said on the other side, can, on grounds which admit the equal right of men to be in the world, succeed in justifying that existing social arrangement which gives to a few the exclusive owner- ship of the world, and denies to the many any right to its use, save as they purchase the privilege of these few world-owners. MR. SPENCER's TASK. 177 A Lord Bramwell or a Professor Huxley or a Duke of Argyll would rush in boldly and proceed frankly. But Mr. Spencer knows that to accomplish his task the attention of the reader must be confused and the real issue avoided. The effort to do this is to be seen at a glance the moment we come to the vital part of “Justice.” In “Social Statics” the discussion of “The Rights of Life and Personal Liberty” occupies hardly 4 more than a single page, being treated as “such self- evident corollaries from our first principle as hardly to need a separate statement.” In “Justice ’’ it is padded out into two chapters — “The Right to Per- sonal Integrity" and “The Rights to Free Motion and Locomotion,” which, by references to the Fijians, the Wends, the Herculeans, the Homeric Greeks, and so on, are made to occupy some twelve or thirteen times as much space. But, although Mr. Spencer also refers to the Abors, the Nagas, the Lepchas, the Jakuns, and other far-off people, he takes no notice of such infractions of the right of free motion and locomotion by land-owning dukes as in 1850 excited his indignation. … In place of the chapter on “The Right to the Use of the Earth,” which stands out so clearly and so prominently in “Social Statics,” we find in “Justice” a chapter on “The Rights to the Uses of Natural Media,” of which only a part is devoted to the right to the use of land, though a short note, having some- thing of the same relation to it that the traditional lady's postscript has to her letter, is inserted in the Appendix. t This treatment of land, or the surface of the earth, 178 It ECANTATION. as but one of the natural media is in the highest degree unphilosophic, and could only be adopted for the purpose of confusion. For so far as man is con- cerned all natural media are appurtenant to land; and the term land in political economy and law comprises all natural substances and powers. To treat land as one of such natural media as light and air is therefore as unphilosophic as it would be to treat it as one of such sub-divisions of itself as water, rock, gravel or sand. The clearest and only philosophic terminology is that adopted in “Social Statics” — the right to the use of the earth, or the right to the use of land. For the right to the use of all natural ele- ments comes from and with, and is inseparably in- volved in and annexed to, the right to the use of land. Mr. Spencer's reasons for thus treating land as but one of the natural media appear as we read. Not merely is the burning question thus minimized and confused, but it becomes easier by means of analogy to slide over the injustice of the present treatment of land — an injustice which, as Mr. Spencer had himself previously seen, is inferior only to murder or slavery — and to bring private property in land into the category of things with which we need not con- cern ourselves. CHAPTER VI. “THE RIGHTS TO THE USES OF NATURAL MEDIA.” HERE in full is Chapter XI. of “Justice ’’: CHAPTER XI. — THE RIGHTS TO THE USES OF NATURAL MEDIA. § 49. A man may be entirely uninjured in body by the actions of fellow-men, and he may be entirely unim- peded in his movements by them, and he may yet be prevented from carrying on the activities needful for maintenance of life, by traversing his relations to the physical environment on which his life depends. It is, indeed, alleged that certain of these natural agencies cannot be removed from the state of common possession. Thus we read : “Some things are by nature itself incapable of appropriation, so that they cannot be brought under the power of any one. These got the name of res communes by the Roman law ; and were defined, things the property of which belongs to no person, but the use to all. Thus, the light, the air, running water, etc., are so adapted to the common use of mankind, that no individual can acquire a property in them, or deprive others of their use.”. (An Institute of the Law of Scotland by John Erskine (ed. Macallan), i., 196). But though light and air cannot be monopolized, the distribution of them may be interfered with by one man to the partial deprivation of another man — may be so interfered with as to inflict serious injury upon him. No interference of this kind is possible without a breach of the law of equal freedom. The habitual in- terception of light by one person in such way that an- other person is habitually deprived of an equal share, implies disregard of the principle that the liberty of 180 RECANTATION. each is limited by the like liberties of all ; and the like is true if free access to air is prevented. Under the same general head there must, however, by an unusual extension of meaning, be here included some- thing which admits of appropriation — the surface of the Earth. This, as forming part of the physical environ- ment, seems necessarily to be included among the media of which the use may be claimed under the law of equal freedom. The Earth's surface cannot be denied to any one absolutely, without rendering life-sustaining activi- ties impracticable. In the absence of standing-ground he can do nothing ; and hence it appears to be a corollary from the law of equal freedom, interpreted with strict- ness, that the Earth's surface may not be appropriated absolutely by individuals, but may be occupied by them only in such manner as recognizes ultimate ownership by other men ; that is — by Society at large. Concerning the ethical and legal recognitions of these claims to the uses of media, not very much has to be said : only the last demands much attention. We will look at each of them in succession. § 50. In the earliest stages, while yet urban life had not commenced, no serious obstruction of one man’s light by another man could well take place. In encampments of savages, and in the villages of agricultural tribes, no one was led, in pursuit of his ends, to overshadow the habitation of his neighbor. Indeed, the structures and relative positions of habitations made such aggressions almost impracticable. In later times, when towns had grown up, it was un- likely that much respect would forth with be paid by men to the claims of their neighbors in respect of light. During stages of social evolution in which the rights to life and liberty were little regarded, such comparatively trivial trespasses as were committed by those who built houses close in front of others’ houses, were not likely to attract much notice, considered either as moral trans- gressions or legal wrongs. The narrow, dark Streets of ancient continental cities, in common with the courts and alleys characterizing the older parts of our own towns, imply that in the days when they were built the shutting out by one man of another man's share of Sun and sky “RIGHTS TO THE USES OF NATURAL MEDIA.” 181 was not thought an offence. And, indeed, it may reason- ably be held that recognition of such an offence was in those days impracticable ; since, in walled towns, the crowding of houses became a necessity. In modern times, however, there has arisen the per- ception that the natural distribution of light may not be interfered with. Though the law which forbids the building of walls, houses, or other edifices of certain heights, within prescribed distances from existing houses, does not absolutely negative the intercepting of light; yet it negatives the intercepting of it to serious degrees, and seeks to compromise the claims of adjacent owners as fairly as seems practicable. . That is to say, this corollary from the law of equal freedom, if it has not come to be overtly asserted, has come to be tacitly recognized. § 51. To some extent interference with the supply of light involves interference with the supply of air; and, by interdicting the One, Some interdict is, by implication, placed on the other. But the claim to use of the air, though it has been recognized by English law in the case of windmills, is less definitely established : prob- ably because only small evils have been caused by ob- structions. There has, however, risen into definite recognition the claim to unpolluted air. Though acts of one man which may diminish the supply of air to another man, have not come to be distinctly classed as wrong; yet acts which vitiate the quality of his air are in modern times regarded as offences — offences for which there are in some cases moral reprobations only, and in other cases legal penalties. In some measure all are severally obliged, by their own respiration, to vitiate the air re- spired by others, where they are in proximity. It needs but to walk a little distance behind one who is smoking, to perceive how widely diffused are the exhalations from each person's lungs; and to what an extent, therefore, those who are adjacent, especially indoors, are compelled to breath the air that has already been taken in and sent out time after time. Hut since this vitiation of air is mutual, it cannot constitute aggression. Aggression occurs only when vitiation by one, or some, has to be 182 RECANTATION. borne by others who do not take like shares in the vitia- tion; as often happens in railway-carriages, where men who think themselves gentlemen Smoke in other places than those provided for Smokers : perhaps getting from fellow-passengers a nominal, though not a real, consent, and careless of the permanent nuisance entailed on those who afterwards travel in compartments reeking with stale tobacco-smoke. Beyond the recognition of this by right-thinking persons as morally improper, it is for- bidden as improper by railway-regulations; and, in virtue of by-laws, may bring punishment by fine. Passing from instances of this kind to instances of a graver kind, we have to note the interdicts against various nuisances — stenches resulting from certain businesses carried on near at hand, injurious fumes such as those from chemical works, and Smoke proceeding from large chimneys. Legislation which forbids the acts causing such nuisances, implies the right of each citizen to unpolluted air. Under this same head we may conveniently include another kind of trespass to which the surrounding medium is instrumental. I refer to the production of sounds of a disturbing kind. There are small and large trespasses of this class. For one who, at a table d'hôte, speaks so loudly as to interfere with the conversation of others, and for those who, during the performance at a theatre or concert, persist in distracting the attention of auditors around by talking, there is reprobation, if noth- ing more : their acts are condemned as contrary to good manners, that is, good morals, for the one is a part of the other. And then when inflictions of this kind are public, or continuous, or both — as in the case of street- music and especially bad street-music, or as in the case of loud noises proceeding from factories, or as in the case of church-bells rung at early hours, the aggression has come to be legally recognized as such and forbidden under penalty : not as yet sufficiently recognized, how- ever, as is shown in the case of railway-whistles at cen- tral stations, which are allowed superfluously to disturb tens of thousands of people all through the night, and often to do serious injury to invalids. Thus in respect of the uses of the atmosphere, the liberty of each limited only by the like liberties of all, “RIGHTS TO THE USES OF NATURAL MEDIA.” 183 though not overtly asserted, has come to be tacitly as- serted; in large measure ethically, and in a considerable degree legally. § 52. The state of things brought about by civiliza- tion does not hinder ready acceptance of the corollaries thus far drawn; but rather clears the way for accept- ance of them. Though in the days when cannibalism was common and victims were frequently sacrificed to the gods, assertion of the right to life might have been received with demur, yet the ideas and practices of those days have left no such results as stand in the way of un- biassed judgments. Though during times when slavery and serfdom were deeply organized in the social fabric, an assertion of the right to liberty would have roused violent opposition, yet at the present time, among our- selves at least, there exists no idea, sentiment, or usage, at variance with the conclusion that each man is free to use his limbs and move about where he pleases. And similarly with respect to the environment. Such small interferences with others' supplies of light and air as have been bequeathed in the structures of old towns and such others as Smoking fires entail, do not appreciably hinder acceptance of the proposition that men have equal claims to uses of the media in which all are im- mersed. But the proposition that men have equal claims to the use of that remaining portion of the en- vironment — hardly to be called a medium — on which all stand and by the products of which all live, is antago- nized by ideas and arrangements descending to us from the past. These ideas and arrangements arose when considerations of equity did not affect land-tenure any more than they affected the tenure of men as slaves or serfs ; and they now make acceptance of the proposition difficult. If, while possessing those ethical sentiments which social discipline has now produced, men stood in possession of a territory not yet individually portioned out, they would no more liesitate to assert equality of their claims to the land than they would hesitate to as- sert equality of their claims to light and air. But now that long-standing appropriation, continued culture, as well as sales and purchases, have complicated matters, the dictum of absolute ethics, incongruous with the state 184 RECANTATION. of things produced, is apt to be denied altogether. Be- fore asking how, under these circumstances, we must decide, let us glance at Some past phases of land-tenure. Partly because in early stages of agriculture, land, soon exhausted, soon ceases to be worth occupying, it has been the custom with little-civilized and semi-civ- lized peoples, for individuals to abandon after a time the tracts they have cleared, and to clear others. Causes aside, however, the fact is that in early stages private ownership of land is unknown : only the usufruct be- longs to the cultivator, while the land itself is tacitly regarded as the property of the tribe. It is thus now with the Sumatrans and others, and it was thus with our own ancestors: the members of the Mark, while they severally owned the products of the areas they respect- ively cultivated, did not own the areas themselves. Though it may be said that at first they were members of the same family gems, or clan, and that the ownership of each tract was private ownership in so far as the tract belonged to a cluster of relations; yet since the same kind of tenure continued after the population of the Mark had come to include men who were unrelated to the rest, ownership of the tract by the community and not by individuals became an established arrangement. This primitive condition will be clearly understood after contemplating the case of the Russians, among whom it has but partially passed away. “The village lands were held in common by all the members of the association [mir]; the individual only possessed his harvest, and the dvor or enclosure immediately surrounding his house. This primitive condition of property, existing in Russia up to the present day, was once common to all European peoples.” — (The History of Russia, A. Rambaud, trans. by Lang, vol. i. p. 45). With this let me join a number of extracts from Wal- lace’s “Russia,” telling us of the original state of things and of the subsequent states. After noting the fact that while the Don Cossacks were purely nomadic — “agriculture was prohibited on pain of death,” appar- ently because it interfered with hunting and cattle- breeding, he says: — “JEach Cossack who wished to raise a crop ploughed and sowed wherever he thought fit, and retained as long as he chose the land “RIGHTS TO THE USES OF NATURAL MEDIA.” l85 thus appropriated ; and when the soil began to show signs of ex- haustion, he abandoned his plot and ploughed elsewhere. As the number of agriculturists increased, quarrels frequently arose. Still worse evils appeared when markets were created in the vicinity. In some stamtzas [Cossack villages] the richer families appropriated enormous quantities of the common land by using several teams of Oxen, or by hiring peasants in the nearest villages to come and plough for them ; and instead of abandoning the land after raising two or three crops they retained possession of it. Thus the whole of the arable land, or at least the best parts of it, become actually, if not legally, the private property of a few families.”—(Ib. ii. 86). Then he explains that as a consequence of something like a revolution : “In accordance with their [the landless members of the com- munity’s] demands the appropriated land was confiscated by the Commune and the system of periodical distributions . . . was in- troduced, By this system each male adult possesses a share of the -land.”—(Ib. ii. 87). On the Steppes “a plot of land is commonly cultivated for only three or four years in succession. It is then abandoned for at least double that period, and the cultivators remove to some other portion of the communal territory. . . . Under such circumstances the principle of private property in the land is not likely to strike root ; each family insists on possessing a certain quantity rather than a certain plot of land, and contents itself with a right of usu- fruct, whilst the right of property remains in the hands of the Com- mune.”—(Ib. ii. 91). But in the central and more advanced districts this early practice has become modified, though without destroying the essential character of the tenure. “According to this system [the three-field system] the cultivators do not migrate periodically from one part of the communal territory to another, but till always the same fields, and are obliged to manure the plots which they occupy. . . . Though the three-field system has been in use for many generations in the central provinces, the communal principle, with its periodical re-allotment of the land, still remains intact.” — (Ib. ii. 92). Such facts, and numerous other such facts, put beyond question the conclusion that before the progress of social organization changed the relations of individuals to the soil, that relation was one of joint ownership and not one of individual ownership. How was this relation changed 2 How only could it be changed ? Certainly not by unforced consent. It cannot be supposed that all, or some, of the members 186 RECANTATION. of the community willingly surrendered their respective claims. Crime now and again caused loss of an individ- ual’s share in the joint ownership; but this must have left the relations of the rest to the soil unchanged. A kindred result might have been entailed by debt, were it not that debt implies a creditor; and while it is scarcely supposable that the creditor could be the community as a whole, indebtedness to any individual of it would not empower the debtor to transfer in payment something of which he was not individually possessed, and which could not be individually received. Probably elsewhere there came into play the cause described as having oper- ated in Russia, where some, cultivating larger areas than others, accumulated wealth and consequent power, and extra possessions; but, as is implied by the fact that in Russia this led to a revolution and re-institution of the original state, the process was evidently there, and prob- ably elsewhere, regarded as aggressive. Obviously the chief cause must have been the exercise of direct or indirect force: sometimes internal but chiefly external. Disputes and fights within the community, leading to predominance (achieved in some cases by possession of fortified houses) prepared the way for partial usurpa- tions. When, as among the Suanetians, we have a still- extant case in which every family in a village has its tower of defence, we may well understand how the in- testine feuds in early communities commonly brought about individual supremacies, and how these ended in the establishment of special claims upon the land subor- dinating the general claims. But conquest from without has everywhere been chiefly instrumental in Superseding communal proprietor- ship by individual proprietorship. It is not to be sup- posed that in times when captive men were made slaves and women appropriated as spoils of war, much respect was paid to pre-existing ownership of the soil. The old English buccaneers who, in their descents on the coast, slew priests at the altars, set fire to churches, and mas- sacred the people who had taken refuge in them, would have been very incomprehensible beings had they recog- nized the land-ownership of such as survived. When the pirate Danes, who in later days ascended the rivers, had burnt the homesteads they came upon, slaughtered “RIGHTS TO THE USES OF NATURAL MEDIA.” T87 the men, violated the women, tossed children on pikes or sold them in the market-place, they must have under- gone a miraculous transformation had they thereafter inquired to whom the Marks belonged, and admitted the titles of their victims to them. And similarly when, two centuries later, after constant internal wars had already produced military rulers maintaining quasi-feudal claims over occupiers of lands, there came the invading Normans, the right of conquest once more overrode such kinds of possession as had grown up, and still further merged communal proprietorship in that kind of indi- vidual proprietorship which characterized feudalism. Victory, which gives unqualified power over the defeated and their belongings, is followed, according to the nature of the race, by the assertion of universal ownership, more or less qualified according to the dictates of policy. While in some cases, as in Dahomey, there results abso- lute monopoly by the king, not only of the land but of everything else, there results in other cases, as there resulted in England, Supreme ownership by the king with recognized sub-ownerships and sub-sub-ownerships of nobles and their vassals holding the land one under another, on condition of military service: supreme own- ership being, by implication, vested in the crown. Both the original state and the subsequent states have left their traces in existing land-laws. There are many local rights which date from a time when “private property in land, as we now understand it, was a strug- gling novelty.” " - * “The people who exercise rights of common exercise them by a title which, if we could only trace it all the way back, is far more ancient than the lord’s. Their rights are those which belonged to the members of the village community long before manors and lords of the manor were heard of.” f And any one who observes what small tenderness for the rights of commoners is shown in the obtainment of Inclosure-Acts, even in our own day, will be credulous indeed if he thinks that in ruder times the lapse of communal right into private rights was equitably ef- fected. The private ownership, however, was habitually incomplete; since it was subject to the claims of the over-lord, and through him, again, to those of the over- . The Land Lars, by Sir Fredk. Pollock, Bart., p. 2. Ibid., p. 6. 4 188 RECANTATION. over-lord: the implication being that the ownership was subordinate to that of the head of the community. “No absolute ownership of land is recognized by our law-books except in the Crown. All lands are supposed to be held imme- diately, or mediately, of the Crown, though no rent or services may be payable, and no grant from the Crown on record.” + And that this conception of land-ownership survives, alike in theory and in practice, to the present time, is illustrated by the fact that year by year State-authority is given for appropriating land for public purposes, after making due compensation to existing holders. Though it may be replied that this claim of the State to supreme land-ownership is but a part of its claim to supreme ownership in general, since it assumes the right to take anything on giving compensation; yet the first is an habitually-enforced claim, while the other is but a nomi- nal claim not enforced; as we see in the purchase of pictures for the nation, to effect which the State enters into competition with private buyers, and may or may not succeed. - It remains only to point out that the political changes which have slowly replaced the supreme power of the monarch by the Supreme power of the people, have, by implication, replaced the monarch's Supreme ownership of the land by the people's Supreme ownership of the land. If the representative body has practically in- herited the governmental powers which in past times vested in the king, it has at the same time inherited that ultimate proprietorship of the soil which in past times vested in him. And since the representative body is but the agent of the community, this ultimate proprie- torship now vests in the community. Nor is this denied by land-owners themselves. The report issued in Decem- ber, 1889, by the council of “The Liberty and Property Defence League,” on which sit several Peers and two judges, yields proof. After saying that the essential principle of their organization, “based upon recorded experience,” is a distrust of “officialism, imperial or mu- nicipal,” the council go on to say that : — “This principle applied to the case of land clearly points to indi- vidual ownership, qualified by State-suzerainty. . . . The land can of course be “resumed ' on payment of full compensation, and man- aged by the “people’, if they so will it.” * The Land Laws, by Sir Fredk, Pollock, Bart., p. 12, “RIGHTS TO THE USES OF NATURAL MEDIA.” 189 And the badness of the required system of administra- tion is the only reason urged for maintaining the exist- ing system of land-holding : the Supreme ownership of the community being avowedly recognized. So that whereas, in early stages, along with the freedom of each man, there went joint ownership of the soil by the body of men ; and whereas, during the long periods of that militant activity by which small communities were con- solidated into great ones, there simultaneously resulted loss of individual freedom and loss of participation in land-ownership; there has, with the decline of militancy and the growth of industrialism, been a re-acquirement of individual freedom and a re-acquirement of such participation in land-ownership as is implied by a share in appointing the body by which the land is now held. And the implication is that the members of the community, habitually exercising as they do, through their representatives, the power of alienating and using as they think well, any portion of the land, may equit- ably appropriate and use, if they think fit, all portions of the land. But since equity and daily custom alike imply that existing holders of particular portions of land, may not be dispossessed without giving them in return its fairly-estimated value, it is also implied that the wholesale resumption of the land by the community can be justly effected only by wholesale purchase of it. Were the direct exercise of ownership to be resumed by the community without purchase, the community would take, along with something which is its own, an immensely greater amount of something which is not its own. Even if we ignore those multitudinous complications which, in the course of century after century, have inextricably entangled men's claims, theoretically considered — even if we reduce the case to its simplest theoretical form ; we must admit that all which can be claimed for the community is the surface of the country in its original unsubdued state. To all that value given to it by clear- ing, breaking-up, prolonged culture, fencing, draining, making roads, farm buildings, etc., constituting nearly all its value, the community has no claim. This value has been given either by personal labor, or by labor paid for, or by ancestral labor; or else the value given to it in such ways has been purchased by legitimately earned 190 RECANTATION. money. All this value artificially given vests in existing owners, and cannot without a gigantic robbery be taken from them. If, during the many transactions which have brought about existing land-ownership, there have been much violence and much fraud, these have been small compared with the violence and the fraud which the community would be guilty of did it take posses- sion, without paying for it, of that artificial value, which the labor of nearly two thousand years has given to the land. § 53. Reverting to the general topic of the chapter — the rights to the uses of natural media — it chiefly con- cerns us here to note the way in which these rights have gradually acquired legislative Sanctions as Societies have advanced to higher types. At the beginning of the chapter we saw that in mod- ern times there have arisen legal assertions of men’s equal rights to the uses of light and air: no forms of social organization or class-interests having appreciably hindered recognition of these corollaries from the law of equal freedom. And we have just seen that by implica- tion, if not in any overt or conscious way, there has in our days been recognized the equal rights of all electors to supreme ownership of the inhabited area — rights which, though latent, are asserted by every Act of Par- liament which alienates land. Though this right to the use of the Earth, possessed by each citizen, is tra- versed by established arrangements to so great an ex- tent as to be practically suspended; yet its existence as an equitable claim cannot be denied without affirming that expropriation by State-decree is inequitable. The right of an existing holder of land can be equitably superseded, only if there exists a prior right of the com- munity at large ; and this prior right of the community at large consists of the sum of the individual rights of its members. NotE. Various considerations touching this vexed question of land-ownership, which would occupy too much space if included here, I have included in Appendix B. “RIGHTS TO THE USEs or NATURAL MEDIA.” 191 Let us take breath and gather our wits. It is like going through a St. Gothard tunnel. Here we are on the other side, sure enough But how did we get there 2 Mr. Spencer brought us in, asserting the law of equal freedom as “an ultimate ethical principle, having an authority transcending every other; ” de- claring that “rights truly so called are corollaries from the law of equal freedom, and what are falsely called rights are not deducible from it.” He brings us out, with a confused but unmistakable assertion that the freedom to use land belongs only to the small class of landlords; with an assertion of the strongest kind of their right to deprive all other men of freedom to use the earth until they are paid for it. How has he got there? Has he shown that the law of equal freedom gives freedom to the use of land only to a few men and denies it to all other men? Has he shown that the right so- called of the small class of land-owners to the exclu- sive use of land is a true right and not a false right, by deducing it from the law of equal freedom 2 Has he met one of the conditions called for by his elaborate derivation and formula of justice in the preceding chapters of this very book 2 Has he shown the in- validity of a single one of the deductions by which he proved in “Social Statics” that justice does not permit private property in land 7 It is worth while to examine this chapter in detail. Its argument is divisible into two parts — (1) as to the right to the use of light, air, etc., and (2) as to the right to the use of land. Let us consider the one part before passing to the other. CHAPTER VII. “JUSTICE * ON THE RIGHT TO LIGHT AND AIR. MR. SPENCER's carelessness of thought is shown in the very opening sentence of this chapter on “The Right to the Uses of Natural Media: ” A man may be entirely uninjured in body by the action of fellow-men, and he may be entirely unimpeded in his movements by them, and he may yet be prevented from carrying on the activities needful for maintenance of life, by traversing his relations to the physical envi- ronment on which his life depends. How 2 To ordinary apprehension, the only way in which men can be deprived of the use of “the physical en- vironment on which life depends” is either by such bodily injuries as killing, maiming, binding, imprison- ing, or by such restrictions on movement as have the threat of bodily injury behind them, like the taboo among the South Sea Islanders, or private property in land among us. Nor have the tyrants of the world, much as they would have liked to, ever been able to find any other way. Without condescending to explain, Mr. Spencer goes on to quote Erskine to the effect that “the light, the air, running water, etc., are so adapted to the common use of mankind that no individual can acquire a property in them or deprive others of their 22 UlS62. “JUSTICE * ON THE RIGHT TO LIGHT AND AIR. 193 This again shows carelessness in apprehension and statement. What Erskine really means is that the law does not, and that because it can not, give property in the substance of matter, so that the molecules or atoms of which it is composed may be identified and reclaimed through all changes in form or place; but that ownership can only attach to matter in its relation to form or place. For in- stance, I buy to-day a dog or a horse. I acquire in this purchase the ownership of what matter is now, or at any time in the future may be, contained in the form of this dog or horse, not the ownership of a certain amount of matter in whatever form it may hereafter assume. That no law could give me, nor could I even set up a claim to it, for it would be im- possible for me to identify it. For the matter which my dog or horse embodies for the moment, like the matter of which my own frame is composed, is con- stantly passing from that form to other forms. The only thing tangible to me or other men is this form. And it is in this that ownership consists. If my dog eats your mutton chop, your property in the chop does not become property in the dog. If the law gives you any action it is certainly not that of reple win. - ...” - The principle of the law that Erskine refers to is thus stated by Blackstone (Chapter 2, Book II.): I cannot bring an action to recover possession of a pool or other piece of water either by superficial measure for twenty acres of Water or by general description, as for a pond or a rivulet; but I must bring my action for what lies at the bottom and call it twenty acres of land covered with water. For water is a movable, wandering thing, and must of necessity continue common by the 194 RECANTATION. law of nature, so that I can only have a temporary, transient, usufructuary property; wherefore if a body of Water runs out of my pond into another man’s I have no right to reclaim it. 13ut the land which that water covers is permanent, fixed and immovable, and there- fore in this I may have a certain substantial property, of which the law will take notice and not of the other. Now the comparatively rough distinctions that are amply sufficient for the purposes of the lawyer are not always sufficient for the purposes of the philoso- pher. If we analyze this principle of the law, we see that no real distinction is made as to ownership between the substance of water and the substance of land — that is to say, between the more or less stable forms of matter of which the body of the universe consists. The distinction is as to tangible form. I may bring an action for ice, which is water that has assumed tangible form by the lowering of tempera- ture, or for water in barrels or bottles, which in another way gives it form. And the real reason why in an action for the possession of a body of water I must describe it as land covered by water is that it is the land which holds the water in place and gives it form. So, on the other hand, if a freshet or a water-burst carry the fertile soil from my field into that of my neighbor, I can no more reclaim it by action at law than I can reclaim the water that runs out of my pond. Or if a volcanic convulsion were to shift the position of a mineral deposit, it would cease to belong to one land-owner and the other would acquire legal possession. The legal result would be precisely the same as the legal result of a change in a rivulet's course. In ruder times, ere the art of surveying was “JUSTICE * ON THE RIGHT TO LIGHT AND AIR. 195 so well developed as now, it was customary to fix the boundaries of legal possession by natural objects deemed immovable, such as mountains, Ocean shores, rivers, etc., and in places where this method has been retained changes in landmarks frequently change the ownership of considerable bodies of land, as on the shifting banks of the lower Mississippi. But our modern surveying takes for its bases latitude and lon- gitude. And this is the essential idea of land owner- ship : It is the ownership, not of certain atoms of matter, be they rock, soil, water or air, or of certain forms of energy, such as heat, light or electricity, but the ownership of a certain section of space and of all that may be therein contained. Mr. Spencer is confusing two essentially different ideas — the idea of substance and the idea of form or locality. In the One sense nothing whatever may be owned — land no more than light or electricity. In the other, all natural substances and powers may be owned — water, air, light, heat or electricity, as truly as land. And they are owned, though, since in our legal terminology space and its contents are known as land, they must in law be described as land. Whoever, under our laws, acquires ownership in land may deprive others of light, air, running water, etc., and does acquire a property in their use, which is frequently a tangible element, and at times the only element in the value of an estate — as where the purity of the air, the beauty of the view, the abun- dance of sunlight which a favorable exposure gives, the presence of mineral springs, or the access to streams, are elements in the price at which land can be sold or rented. 196 RECANTATION. In the next sentence we are told that “light and air cannot be monopolized.” But they are monop- olized in the monopolization of land, and this as effectually as any monopolizer could wish. It is true that air and sunlight are not formally bought, sold and rented. But why? Not that they could not be measured off and determined by metes and bounds, but simply because they are to our physical constitu- tions inseparable from land, so that whoever owns the land owns also the air it is bathed in and the light that falls on it. Light and air are monopolized when- ever land is monopolized ; and the exclusive use to them is bought and sold whenever land is bought and sold. It is not merely that, as the flying-machine has not yet been perfected, the owner of land holds the means of access to the air above it and the light that falls on it; it is that the owner of land is the owner of such light and air, not merely virtually, but for- mally and legally. And were the air-ship perfected, he would have the same legal right to forbid trespass on his light and air, and to demand payment for any use made of it or any passage through it, thousands of feet above the surface, as he now has to forbid trespass on his ground or to demand payment for any use of or any passage through what lies thou- sands of feet below it. In English law, land does not mean merely the surface of the earth within certain metes and bounds, but all that may be above and all that may be below that surface; and under the same legal right by which the land-owner holds as his private property any certain part of the surface of the globe he also holds the rocks and minerals “JUSTICE’’ ON THE RIGHT TO LIGHT AND AIR. 197 below it and the air and the light above it. As Blackstone says: “The word ‘land’ includes not only the face of the earth, but everything under it or over it. . . . By the name of land everything terrestrial will pass.” The land-owner is, in law as well as in fact, not a mere surface owner, but a uni- verse owner. And just as in some places land-owners sell the surface right, retaining mineral rights; or sell mineral rights, retaining surface rights; or sell the right of way, retaining rights to other use: so, where there is occasion, the right to use light and air may be separated, in sales and purchases and title-deeds, from the right to the use of the ground. An invention which would make practicable the use of light and air without possession of the surface, would at once bring out the fact that, legally, they belong to land-owners, just as subterranean mining and the projection of underground railways have brought out the fact that land-owners are legal own- ers of all beneath the surface. In fact, existing deeds furnish instances in which the real thing bought and sold, though properly enough styled land in the conveyances, is not land at all in the narrow meaning, but light and air, or the right to their use. To cite a case: The city of Cleveland, Ohio, some years since, desired to convert the viaduct bridge over the Cuyahoga river into a swinging bridge. To do this it was necessary that one end of the bridge should in its swing pass for a short distance through the air over a strip of land belonging to a private owner. The city of Cleveland had, there- fore, to buy the right to use this air, and I have before me a copy of the deed, executed on the 28th 198 RECANTATION. of February, 1880, by which, in consideration of $9,994.88, Meyers, Rouse & Co. sell and convey to the city of Cleveland the right to swing such bridge over a small area thirty-five feet above the ground. Of this estate in the air the grantors describe them- selves as holding a good and indefeasible title in fee simple, with the right to bargain and sell the same. Were it thirty-five hundred or thirty-five hundred thousand feet above the surface, the legal right of ownership would be the same. For the ownership which attaches to land under our laws is not to be really measured by linear feet and inches, but by parallels of latitude and meridians of longitude, start- ing from the centre of the earth and indefinitely ex- tendible. And while Meyers, Rouse & Co. have sold to the city of Cleveland a slice of their air of perhaps fifteen feet in depth, they still retain the legal owner- ship of all the air above it, and could demand toll of or refuse passage to any flying machine that should attempt to cross it. The same lack of analytic power continues to be shown by Mr. Spencer when he goes on to tell us that the equal rights to the use of light and air, though not recognized in primitive stages, have, in the course of social evolution, come to be completely or all but completely recognized now. So far is this from being true, that in such countries as England and the United States there is no recognition what- ever of the equal right to the use of light and air. To the list of interdictions which he cites as recognitions of this equal right, he might as well have added that of shying bricks through these media at passers-by. For where the interdictions he mentions — of inter- “JUSTICE’’ ON THE RIGHT TO LIGHT AND AIR. 199 ceptions of light and air, of Smoking in certain places, of the maintenance of stenches and fumes, of the making of disturbing noises—are not mere inter- dictions of certain species of assault; they are inter- dictions based on and involved in the ownership of land. Mr. Spencer might have seen this for himself, where he speaks of “the law which forbids the build- ing of walls, houses, or other edifices within prescribed distances of other houses . . . and seeks to compro- mise the claims of adjacent owners as fairly as seem practicable.” Owners of what? Why, owners of land. It is only as an owner of land, or as the tenant of an owner of land, that under our English law any one has a right to complain of the interception of light and air by another land-owner. The owner of land may intercept light and air, may make noises and create stenches to any extent he pleases, provided he infringes not the equal rights of other owners of land, for light and air are considered by English law as what they truly are, so far as human beings are con- cerned, appurtenances of land. No one in England, be he stranger or native born, has any legal right whatever to the use of English light and English air, save as the owner or grantee of an owner of English land. That even on the Queen's highways the public are deemed to have such rights as against adjacent land-holders I am not sure. Certain it is, that one may travel for miles through the public roads, amid wantonly shut out by high and costly walls, erected for the express purpose of intercepting the light, and 200 - IRECANTATION. crowned on their tops with broken glass, to tear the clothes and cut the flesh of any one who dares climb them to get such a view as the unintercepted light would give. The rights to the use of light, air and other natural media are in truth as inseparable from the right to the use of land as the bottom of that atmospheric Ocean which surrounds our globe is inseparable from the globe's surface; and the pretence of treating them separately could only spring from Mr. Spencer's evident desire to confuse the subject he is pretending to treat, to cover with a fog of words his abandonment of a position incapable of refutation, and from the false assumption that the liberty of each to the use of air and light, limited only by the like liberty of all, às practically and legally recognized, to lead to the still more preposterously false assumption that equal rights to the use of land are also fully recognized. But before examining this last assumption, there is one form of it which he incidentally makes that is worth noticing — the assumption that the equal right to personal liberty and freedom of movement is already fully recognized. It is a pity that Mr. Spencer had not intermitted his studies of the Abors, the Bodas, the Creeks, the Dhimals, the Eghas, and other queer people, to the end of the alphabet, of whom his later books are as full as those of the pedants of the last century were of classical quotations, and made some observations in his own country. They would have saved him from the astounding statement that — At the present time, among ourselves at least, there exists no idea, sentiment, or usage at variance with the “JUSTICE’’ ON THE RIGHT TO LIGHT AND AIR. 201 conclusion that each man is free to use his limbs and move where he pleases. The truth is, that instead of every one being free in England “to use his limbs and move about where he pleases,” there is no part of the British Isles, even though it be wild moor, bleak deer-forest or bare mountain-top, where a man is free to move about without permission of the private owner, except it be the highroads, the public places, or other strips and spots of land deemed the property of the com- munity. Mr. Spencer seems to have forgotten this now, but he knew it when in “Social Statics” he denounced . the system that permitted the Duke of Leeds to warn off tourists from Ben-muich-Dhui, the Duke of Atholl to close Glen Tilt, the Duke of Buccleuch to deny Free Church sites, and the Duke of Sutherland to displace Highlanders with deer. “Verily, they have their reward.” The name of Herbert Spencer now appears with those of about all the Dukes in the Kingdom as the director of an asso- ciation formed for the purpose of defending private property in land that was especially active in the recent London County Council election. CHAPTER VIII. “JUSTICE’’ ON THE RIGHT TO LAND. AT last, however, as all men must, even after the flying-machine becomes practicable, Mr. Spencer is forced to come down from light and air to solid earth. - But observe how reluctantly, how tenderly, he approaches the main question, the subject he would evidently like to ignore altogether. Land—to us the one solid, natural element; our all-producing, all- supporting mother, from whose bosom our very frames are drawn, and to which they return again; our stand- ing-place; our workshop; our granary; our reservoir and substratum and nexus of media and forces; the element from which all we can produce must be drawn; without which we cannot breathe the air or enjoy the light; the element prerequisite to all hu- man life and action — he speaks of as “that remain- ing portion of the environment, hardly to be called a medium,” which “by an unusual extension of meaning” is included in the things to which the equal liberty of all extends. Yet, at last, and thus tenderly, after having shown to his own satisfaction that with regard to personal rights and the liberty of movement, “things as they are * in such countries as England do not differ from “things as they ought to be,” except, perhaps, that “JUSTICE’’ ON THE RIGHT TO LAND. 203 there is too much smoking in railway carriages, Mr. Spencer does at last get to the burning question of the land. And no sooner does he get there than the power by virtue of which a truth once recognized can never be entirely forgotten or utterly ignored, forces from him this recognition: If, while possessing those ethical sentiments which social discipline has now produced, men stood in the pos- session of a territory not yet individually portioned out, they would no more hesitate to assert equality of their claims to the land than they would hesitate to assert equality of their claims to light and air. “If, while possessing those ethical sentiments which so- cial discipline has now produced.” This “if” is the assumption of the Spencerian philosophy, that our moral sentiments have been evolved by pressure of conditions, survival of the fittest and hereditary trans- mission, since the time when, according to it, primitive men were accustomed to eat each other. Having told us that social evolution has brought mankind in the Victorian era to the recognition of equal rights to air and light, Mr. Spencer now assumes that the idea of equal rights to the use of land is the product of a similar development instead of being a primary per- ception of mankind. Now this assumption is not merely opposed to all the facts; it is inconsistent with the Spencerian phi- losophy. To consider the philosophy first : It holds that man is an evolution from the animal. He comes to be man by gradual development from the monkey or from some form of life from which the monkeys have also sprung. In the course of this evolutionary 204 REC ANTATION. process, continued since he became man, he has ac- quired his present instincts, habits and powers. Now I will not ask how, since the highest animals that habitually eat their own kind are on the syn- thetic genealogical tree far below any of the animals, existing or extinct, from which man can have de- scended, the oft-repeated assumption that primitive men were habitual cannibals can be reconciled with the assumption that they derived their habits from their animal ancestors. But I will make bold to ask how the assumption that men have only now arrived at the perception of the equality of rights to the use of the natural media, and especially land, can be reconciled with the assumption that our moral perceptions are derived from animals. Animals fight with their own kind, as men fight ; or at least some of them do occasion- ally, though none fight so frequently and so wan- tonly. But is there an animal, from the monkey to the jelly-fish, that does not, with animals of its own kind, and when at peace, fail to claim for itself and accord to others the liberty to use natural media, bounded only by the equal liberty of all? If there is not, how can the assumption that it has taken man all these ages to recognize the equality of rights to the use of natural media be made to harmonize with the assumption that he primarily derives his percep- tions from the animal? I ask this question to emphasize the fact that, in his effort to smooth away the monstrous injustice of private property in land, Mr. Spencer does violence to his own theories — not alone to the theories which he held when he wrote “Social Statics,” but to the “JUSTICE * ON THE RIGHT TO LAND. 205 theories of his Synthetic Philosophy — the theories set forth in “Justice; ” that he stands ready to sacri- fice to his new masters not only his moral honesty, but even what the morally depraved often cling to — the pretence of intellectual honesty. In order to ignore the gist of the land question while pretending to explain it, he is endeavoring to create the impression that the present treatment of land, if not indeed the best, is at least the highest form which the progressive development of the idea of the equality of rights to the use of natural media has assumed. But to say that the idea of equal rights to land is the product of advancing social discipline is to say that it has pro- ceeded from the contrary idea — that of unequal rights, or private property in land. Since the ani- mals show no trace of this idea, this assumption is inconsistent with the doctrine that primitive man came closest to the animals. And to assume, as Mr. Spencer does in this chapter, that men start with the idea of unequal rights to land, and have been working up through social discipline to the idea of equal rights, is likewise inconsistent with all the points in the elaborate derivation of the idea of justice, which occupy the first eight chapters of this very book. The assumption that the idea of equal rights to land is the product of social discipline is at both ends contradicted by the facts. In America, Aus- tralia and New Zealand, men of English speech, pos- sessing “those ethical sentiments which social disci- pline has now produced,” have stood in possession of territory not yet individually portioned out; but, in- stead of asserting the equality of claims to land, 206 RECANTATION. they have proceeded to individually portion out this territory as fast as they could. Thus the effect upon their ethical sentiments of the social discipline to which they have been subjected has been the precise opposite of what Mr. Spencer asserts. Instead of leading them from non-perception to a perception of the equality of rights to land, social discipline, domi- nated by land-owners, and continued steadily and rig- orously, had, within comparatively recent times, almost entirely crushed out the idea of natural rights in land among the English people, and taught them to look on private property in land as in nowise dif- fering from property in other things. Or, try Mr. Spencer's assumption from the other end. Among the aboriginal races in the countries we modern English have overrun, the idea of equal rights to land, and of course to other natural media, has been so clearly perceived that they were unable to comprehend the artificial notion of private property in land—could no more see than could Mr. Spencer in 1850 how land could equitably become private property. To this very day, and in spite of the pressure of the national government and of the sur- rounding whites, the Cherokees, the Choctaws, and other civilized remnants of the aboriginal tribes of the United States, though recognizing fully the right of property in things produced by labor, and recog- nizing also the right of private possession of land, refuse to recognize land as the property of the individual; and no man can hold land among them except while putting it to use. The idea that land itself can become subject to such individual owner- “JUSTICE’’ ON THE RIGHT TO LAND. 207 ship as attaches to things that man produces by labor, is as repugnant to the human mind, undisciplined by generations of cruel repression and undistorted by persistent misteachings, as the idea that air or sunlight may be so owned. Mr. Spencer himself, while stating that the per- ception of the equality of natural rights to land is the product of the social advance that has brought men of the highest civilization to their present ethical condition, goes on in the next para- graph to show at length that “in early stages private ownership of land is unknown,” and that private property in land has arisen from “the exercise of direct or indirect force, sometimes internal but chiefly external.” " What Mr. Spencer thus admits is that private prop- erty in land has no derivation from perceptions of justice, whether these be original or acquired by evolution, but that its only genesis is force. And then comes his supreme effort. In the reference to the feudal system and the assumption that the rights ! It may be worth noting that here Mr. Spencer again confuses equal rights with joint rights. The primitive idea is not that of deeming land the property of the tribe, and the relations of individ- uals to the soil one of joint ownership. Although within generally vague territorial limits each tribe may claim the right to exclude other tribes, yet the idea is not that of property in the land, but of that sort of separation which took place between Lot and Abraham; and the relation of the members to the land is not that of joint ownership, but of equal right to use — such regulations as in the earlier stages become necessary, being merely those which secure this equality in use. Among no primitive people would it be thought that a member of the tribe required the consent of the whole to make use of land no one else was using. He would do that without question, as a matter of individual right. 208 - RECANTATION. of the monarch, as representative of the whole people, are still exercised by the people's representatives, lies the pivotal point of his whole argument. To return to my illustration of the tunnel. This is the way he gets there: We are told that when private property in land did arise, it was habitually incomplete, since it was sub- ject to the claims of the over-lord, the implication being that the ownership was subordinate to that of the head of the community ; and that this conception survives alike in theory and in practice to the present time, since the state now takes land for public pur- poses after making due compensation to existing holders. The supreme power of the monarch having been replaced by the supreme power of the people, the people are now the supreme owners of the land, and may take it, if they please, on payment of full compensation. Thus, individual freedom has been re-acquired with regard to land, and to-day, in the existing theory and practice of English law, and like their equal rights to light and air, the equal rights of all to the use of land are fully recognized. All that has gone before is the by-play of the jug- gler to distract attention. In this the transmogrifi- cation is worked. Here, with one flash of synthetic logic, the horse- chestnut becomes a chestnut horse ! Here is the explanation of what was averred in Mr. Spencer's letter to the Times — that the view of land-ownership he has taken all along is “congruous with existing legal theory and practice.” Here is his reconciliation of his formula of justice — that “each is at liberty to do all that he wills, provided that he infringes not “JUSTICE’’ ON THE RIGHT TO LAND. 209 the equal liberty of any other man’—with the views of that august body, the Land and Property Defence League, “on which sit several peers and two judges.” Both are harmonized in the assumption that the equal rights of all to the use of land are to-day recognized in the right of Parliament to take land for public pur- poses on paying for it. What, it may be asked, has become of the nine- teen-twentieths of the people of England who, as “Social Statics” told us, were being robbed of their birthright—their heritage in the earth — by a gigan- tic injustice inferior only in wickedness to murder and enslavement? Why, having the privilege of voting for members of one branch of the Legislature, which Mr. Spencer has, in this very book, page 49, described as “a motley assemblage of nominees of caucuses, ruled by ignorant and fanatical wire- pullers,” they have been transmogrified into supreme owners of the land. What, it still may be asked, has become of that part of them that do not have even the poor privilege of voting for this motley assemblage of nominees of caucuses 7 There is no answer. We may search Chapter IV. of the “Principles of Ethics — The Ethics of Social Life: Justice,” in vain. They have incontinently dropped out of sight. It may be worth while to examine that part of Mr. Spencer's logical process where it is assumed that the legal theory and practice by which the British Legislature, on the payment of compensa- tion, now takes land for public purposes is identical 210 RECANTATION. with the theory and practice by which the feudal monarch, as representing the whole people, was the supreme owner of land. This is all that he ventures specifically to assert, and the question raised by it is much narrower than the real question, whether the present legal theory and practice does adequately recognize the equal rights of all to land. Yet, even here, Mr. Spencer clearly suppresses the vital fact. The taking of land for public purposes on payment of compensation — or by process of condemnation, as it is termed — is neither an exercise nor recogni- tion of the supreme ownership of land. In the American States where the ownership of land is by their constitutions declared allodial, the same powers of condemning land are exerted, and more freely exerted than in England. If pictures are bought for the national galleries, not condemned, it is merely be- cause there is no need for condemnation. The same legal power exists to take pictures for public use as to take land. In case of necessity, such as war, the power of taking anything is habitually exercised, and ships, horses, railways, provisions, and even men are taken for public uses. The power to do this is a power incident to the Supreme authority and at times necessary to society. When, in 1889, Johnstown, Pennsylvania, was cut off from the rest of the world by the flood that de- stroyed pre-existing organization, a British subject, Arthur J. Moxham, was placed in charge by what a Quaker would call “the sense of the meeting.” His first acts were to seize all food, to destroy all liquor, and to put every able-bodied man at work, leaving the matter of compensation to be determined after- “JUSTICE * ON THE RIGHT TO LAND. 211 wards. He voiced the will of the society, driven by crushing disaster into a supreme effort for self-pres- ervation, and the man who had resisted his orders would, if need be, have been shot. But the theory of English law that the crown is the only owner of English land, and that the highest estate an individual can hold is that of tenancy, though often confused with the right of eminent domain, has in reality a different origin. Now a mere fiction, it had in feudal times expression in practice. When William the Conqueror divided England, he conditioned his grants on the payment of rent in dues or services. This was the essence of the feudal principle. In a rough and partial but still substantial way, it recog- nized the right of the community to rent. It was a rude attempt to carry out that system of land nation- alization which Mr. Spencer in “Social Statics' de- clares the only equitable system of land-tenure. Under it the holding of valuable land entailed pay- ment or service. The crown lands maintained the sovereign and the civil list. From the church lands the expenses of public worship, and of education, the care of the sick and the relief of wayfarers were provided; the holders of military tenures had to maintain the army and do the fighting, and on occa- sions, such as the ransom of the king, the knighting of his eldest son, the marriage of his eldest daughter, etc., were called on for extra payments ; while the right of all Englishmen to the use of some portion at least of English soil was recognized in the numer- ous public commons. This spirit of the feudal system was the origin of primogeniture, of ward- ships and liveries and other feudal incidents, which, 212 IRECANTATION. where they remain on the law-books of to-day are but meaningless and useless survivals. Mr. Spencer, in his “glance at some past phases of land-tenure,” has told us of the Sumatrans, the Don Cossacks, the Russians, the Suanetians, and the Daho- means, but he has failed to tell us how we of the English speech have lost those fragments of the equal right to the use of land that we retained long after the last conquest of England. I do not charge him with ignorance. If he does not tell us, it is not because he does not know, for “Political Institu- tion " shows that he does know." But he does not tell us, because the facts are inconsistent with the juggle by which he is trying to impose on the reader. It was in reality by a gigantic series of no-rent declara- tions on the part of the class that had got possession of English land on condition of paying rent for it. The crown lands were given away by profligate sovereigns without any stipulation of return in rent to the com- munity. Henry VIII. made over the greater part of the church lands to his favorites, and the people were robbed of the services and benefits that they had re- ceived from the former holders. Finally, by act of the Long Parliament, confirmed after the restoration 1 In the chapter on Political Differentiation, page 297, “I’rin- ciples of Sociology,” Volume II., he quotes from Hallam : — “William the Conqueror . . . divided this kingdom into about 60,000 parcels, of nearly equal value [partly left in the hands of those who previously held it, and partly made over to his follow- ers as either owners or suzerains], from each of which the service of a soldier was due.” And again, in the chapter on Property, page 553 of the same book, occurs the passage once before quoted: — In our case the definite ending of these tenures took place in 1660; when for feudal obligations (a burden on land-owners) was substituted a beer-excise (a burden on the community). “JUSTICE * ON THE RIGHT TO LAND. 213 by a close majority, the military dues were abolished; and, growing in power by what they fed on, the land- holders, now actually land-owners, appropriated to themselves, by the simple process of inclosure, nearly all the common lands. The essence and meaning of the supreme owner- ship of the land of England by the crown is thus gone. What remains is but a legal fiction, a mere survival of form, of no more validity than was in the time of George III. the form by which he styled himself King of France. Yet in this empty phrase, and in the taking of land for public use on payment of full compensation, Mr. Spencer tells his disinher- ited countrymen that their equal rights are actually recognized. - º Thus the equal right of Englishmen to the use of English land amounts to the privilege of buying it at its full value! What, then, has the Englishman as Englishman? A Russian or a Turk, a Winans or a Carnegie, may use land in England by paying for it. If we put the conclusion as to the right to the use of land to which Mr. Spencer thus comes in “Justice" in the same form which he uses in “Social Statics,” we have this: Given a race of beings having like claims to pursue the objects of their desires — given a world adapted to the gratification of those desires — a world into which such beings are similarly born, and it unavoid- ably follows that they have the right to use this world as soon as they have paid the full value of it to those of their number who call themselves its OWIlêI’S. But this telling the disinherited masses that their equal rights to land are already acknowledged seems 214 RECANTATION. hardly satisfactory to Mr. Spencer himself, for he at once proceeds to re-enforce it, by the plea that for them to claim any more than the right of buying land at its full value would be ethically wrong. This is a putting of the cart before the horse. For a wrong is only the violation of a right. Rights, as Mr. Spencer has just before told us, are the particular freedoms deducible from the law of equal freedom, and to assert Wrong he must show violation of that law. Let us, however, follow his reasoning. The first proposition is that — Since equity and daily custom alike imply that exist- ing holders of particular portions of land may not be dispossessed without giving them in return its fairly estimated value, it is also implied that the wholesale resumption of the land by the community can be justly effected only by the wholesale purchase of it. Is it? By equity and custom when the state takes any part of the wealth of a particular person it compensates him. But when it takes part of the wealth of all persons, or of all persons of a special class, as it is constantly doing by taxation, does it compensate them 2 The reason for compensation, when land is taken from particular owners, is that otherwise a discrim- ination would be made between them and other land- owners. Equity, as Mr. Spencer once told us, means equalness. It would not be equitable for the com- munity to resume possession of the land of this or that particular land-owner without compensation, while leaving to other land-owners their land, for while this would be to leave unredressed the unequal- ness between land-holders and others, it would be to “JUSTICE’ ON THE RIGHT TO LAND. 215 treat land-owners unequally as between themselves. But if all land were resumed equity would require no compensation, for while land-owners would be treated equally as between themselves, the inequality between them and other members of the community would be removed, and all would be treated with equalness. And since they, too, are members of the community, the resumption of all land by the com- munity would place all in a condition of equalness with respect to the land. But, continues Mr. Spencer—herein admitting that the community may in equity take the land — Were the direct exercise of ownership to be resumed by the community without purchase, the community would take, along with something which is its own, an immensely greater amount of something which is not its own. - How so? The proposition is only to take the land, not to take anything else. Because, Mr. Spencer continues — Even if we ignore those multitudinous complications which, in the course of century after century, have inextricably entangled men's claims theoretically con- sidered — even if we reduce the case to its simplest theoretical form — Well, all classes of land resumptionists would quickly reply, we are quite willing to do so. Since, as laid down in “Social Statics,” men derive their equal rights to the use of the world, from their equal presence in the world, there can be no compli- cations that can entangle their equal claims to the use of land, either considered theoretically or in any other way. 216 R.ECANTATION. But without heeding this, Mr. Spencer goes on to say, that even if we ignore what no one proposes to consider, and even if we reduce the case to simple theoretical form — We must admit that all which can be claimed for the community is the surface of the country in its original unsubdued state. To all that value given to it by clear- ing, breaking-up, prolonged culture, fencing, draining, making roads, farm-buildings, etc., constituting nearly all its value, the community has no claim. This value has been given either by personal labor, or by labor paid for, or by ancestral labor; or else the value given to it in such ways has been purchased by legitimately earned money. All this value artificially given vests in exist- ing owners, and cannot without a gigantic robbery be taken from them. If, during the many transactions which have brought about existing land-ownership, there have been much violence and much fraud, these have been small compared with the violence and the fraud which the community would be guilty of did it take possession, without paying for it, of that artificial value which the labor of nearly two thousand years has given to the land. What does Mr. Spencer mean 2 If he means that all that can be claimed by the community is the land itself, and that land-owners should retain the value of their improvements, and of all things else that they may possess, we admit it — not entirely as a matter of strict justice, for much of things other than the land itself, which existing land-owners now possess, they have obtained by their unjust appropriation of land. But we wish to be within our right, and to let bygones be bygones, and so all that we propose is just what Mr. Spencer in “Social Statics' proposed — the resumption of equal rights in land, leaving to existing land-owners, without “JUSTICE’’ ON THE RIGHT TO LAND. 217 question as to how it was obtained, the whole value of their improvements in or on land, and all their other property. But what, then, does Mr. Spencer mean by talking of “the surface of the country in its original unsub- dued state,” as all the community can claim 2 What does he mean by talking of that “artificial value which the labor of nearly two thousand years has given to the land?” Vague as are his notions of value, can it be that he means that, even if their natural rights are admitted, the people of England are only entitled to what value the land had before there were any people? and that they must pay the land-owners for the value of all the labor that has been expended on that land since Caesar landed? What the people of England are entitled to by natural right, and what we propose by the single tax to take for their use, is the value of land as it is, ex- clusive of the value of improvements as they are in or on the land privately owned. What would thus be left to the land-owners would be their personal or movable property, the value of all existing improve- ments in or on their land, and their equal share with all other citizens in the land value resumed. This is perfectly clear, and if not perfectly fair, is only so because it would leave to the land-owners in their per- sonal property and the value of their improvements much not due to any exertion of labor by themselves or their ancestors, but which has come to them through the unjust appropriation of the proceeds of others’ labor. The value of the land when the country was in its original unsubdued state has nothing to do with the 218 - RECANTATION. matter; what we have to deal with is the value of the land as it is. Nor has the labor expended since Caesar's time anything to do with it; the value of im- provements to be left to land-owners is the value of existing improvements. Surely if Mr. Spencer were to try to formulate his notions it would be too prepos- terous even for him to contend that in resuming our rights in the land — not the rights of the ancient Britons, nor the rights of primitive man, nor the rights of the animals that existed before man was — we should credit the existing land-owners with the value which attaches to the land from our presence, and charge them only with what value the land might have if we did not exist. And surely he would not contend that the land-owners are alone entitled to the value which the existing social environment gives to land — to the sole benefit of the introduction of Chris- tianity, the extirpation of wolves, the beating off or civilizing of the Danes, the defeat of the Spanish armada, the building of public roads and the lighting of public streets, the introduction of vegetables and fruits and the improvement of domestic animals, the utilization of steam and electricity and labor-saving appliances, the discoveries of science and the progress of the arts | Nor yet would he formally assert the notion that in addition to the present value of their improvements the land-owners must be credited with the value of all such improvements when they were new, and with the cost of all the draining, hedging, fencing, digging, manuring, building, etc., that has gone on for two thousand years — that the owner of land in the city of London, for instance, must be credited, not only “JUSTICE’’ ON THE RIGHT TO LAND. 219 with the present value of his houses, but with the value of the houses that existed before the great fire, and from the time of the first Roman camp ! This would be equally preposterous. It is hard to say what Mr. Spencer really does mean. But he is evidently trying to get some sort of vague excuse for assuming that it would not pay the disinherited to claim their rights in land, since to compensate land-owners would take more than the land is worth. Let us, therefore, try to form some idea of what would be the present value of the land of England in its “original, unsubdued state,” popu- lation and social environment, and the existing build- ings, which we propose to leave to the land-owners, remaining as they are. & If, whenever a house was pulled down, or destroyed by fire, in Threadneedle street or Lombard street, in Cheapside or at Charing Cross, the ground on which it stood were to spring into its original condition, how much less would be its value to those who, in renting or buying it, seek not so much soil or rock or sand, but so many square feet of standing-place in those centres of population and trade? How much less would be the value of the land that around London and Manchester and Liverpool and Birming- ham and Leeds and all the growing English towns is being turned from agricultural uses into house- sites, were it to revert to its condition in Roman times 2 While as for the country outside the cities and towns, would it not, could such a miracle be worked, become more rather than less valuable 2 Something of draining, hedging, walling, manuring and digging would be lost; but would not the ac- 220 - RECANTATION. cumulated richness of virgin soil, the great forests that in England now would have enormous value, the stores of coal and iron and other minerals that have now been exhausted or can only be worked at great depths, much more than make up? If Mr. Spencer would go to the greater Englands growing up in Australia and the American West, he would cease thinking of Romans, or Saxons or Normans as having anything to do with the present value of English land; for he would see that it is not what has been done in the past, but the population and activity of the present, that give value to land. He would see from Chicago or Johnstown that Lon- don might be swept by fire or flood, and yet, if the causes that concentrate population and trade there still remained, land, instead of being less valuable, would really become more valuable, from the better improvements that the clearing would bring about. He would see that, if the population and business of London could be transported to a newly-risen island in the antipodes, land there would become as valuable as land in London now; and that, though all improve- ments were to be left behind, the value of land in London would disappear. What the new countries will show us is, that as man lives in the present so he lives by the labor of the present and the immediate past, truly from hand to mouth ; and what we get from our ancestors is , little more than language, traditions, laws, habits, and the store of transmitted knowledge, including also prejudices and superstitions. And thus rich and poor, learned and ignorant, we are alike “the heirs of all the ages.” While if some of us are richer than “JUSTICE’’ ON THE RIGHT TO LAND. 221 we ought to be, and more of us are poorer than we ought to be, it is not because of the wrongful appro- priations of wealth that took place in a dead and gone past, but from the wrongful appropriations of wealth that are taking place now. Barring the appendix, which is yet to be considered, we have now gone through Mr. Spencer's defence of existing landlordism — his answer, in his maturest years, to the arraignment of private property in land which he made in “Social Statics.” Stripped of its padding it amounts simply to the assumption (1) that the equal rights of all to the use of land are recognized in the right of the state to take land for public purposes on paying compensation ; which is backed by the assumption (2) that equity requires that existing owners shall be paid the full value of the land they hold before equal rights to land can be acknowledged. Of the first assumption, the only attempt at sup- port is in the last paragraph, the reasoning of which on analysis will be found to be this: The equal right of all electors to the use of land is recognized by implication in the right asserted by Parliament to take land for public use on paying full compensation for its value ; because — If it is not, there is no equitable warrant for the state so taking land for public uses, since the only right by which the land-owners can be superseded is the right of the community at large : hence — As the state has this right, which it can only get as the sum of the individual rights of its members; therefore, by its exercise, the individual rights of 222 RECANTATION. members of the state to the use of land are now recognized. Of the second assumption, the only attempt at Sup- port is another obviously false assumption — that the value of land cannot be distinguished from the value of improvements. This is the argument of the lauded Synthetic Philosophy in the most important part of the most important book of its most important sub-division. I commend the study of such logical processes to those who on authority of Herbert Spencer's phi- losophy believe that man is an evoluted monkey, who got the idea of God from observing his own shadow. As for anything deserving the name of reasoning, anything on which may be founded either a denial of the equal right of all to the use of land, or an affir- mation of the exclusive right of existing land-owners, there is nothing whatever. It is not merely that the reasoning of “Social Statics” is not impugned: it is that the reasoning of “Justice” itself is utterly ig- nored. No connection whatever is made between the conclusions here assumed and the formula of justice, the law of equal freedom, which in preceding chapters of this very book has been declared the ultimate ethical principle. The reader has just been told that rights are the particular freedoms deducible from the law of equal freedom; that what are truly called rights are dedu- cible from it, and that what are falsely called rights are not deducible from it. But where does Mr. Spencer, or how can he, deduce the right which he asserts for land-owners, the right to the exclusive use of land “JUSTICE * ON THE RIGHT TO LAND. 223 until they are paid its full value, from the law of equal freedom? Or, if we go back through all the links of his derivation of the formula of justice can we find any connection between what he now asserts as right, and what he has just asserted as justice in any of its evolutionary stages? Does not the ownership by some to the exclusion of others, of elements essential to all life, the legal giving of the products of labor to those who do no labor, by taking it away from those who do labor, violate what he declares to be the principle of animal ethics—that the ill-fitted must suffer the evils of unfitness, and the well-fitted prove their fitness? Does it not violate what he declares to be the prin- ciple of sub-human justice, that each individual shall receive the benefits and evils of its own nature and consequent conduct? Does it not violate what he declares to be the principle of human justice, that no one should be prevented from having whatever good his actions normally bring to him, nor allowed to shoulder off on other persons whatever evil they bring? Does it not violate what he declares to be the sen- timent of justice, the feeling that we ourselves ought to have freedom to receive the results of our own nature and consequent actions, and which prompts the maintenance of this sphere of free play for others ? Does it not violate what he declares to be the idea of justice, the equality as to mutually limited spheres of action, the inequality in the results which each may achieve within these mutual limits? Does it not establish inequality by authority—an inequality 224 RECANTATION. referring not to the natural achievement of greater rewards by greater merits, but to the artificial appor- tionment of rewards to no merits at all? Does it not violate what he declares to be the for- mula of justice, that every man is free to do that which he wills, provided he infringes not the equal freedom of any other man? Does it not set at defiance what he declares to be the authority of this formula, the relation between conduct and consequence, which he bases on his com- pound law? Private property in land, which Herbert Spencer in “Justice” defends by the darkening of counsel and baseless assumptions ! . Does it not openly, notori- ously, flagrantly, deny to men the equal use of nat- ural opportunities to live their lives, develop their powers, and reap the rewards of their conduct? Does it not give to the idle, the stupid, the profligate, the vicious, through the accidents of birth or luck, or successful forestalling, the natural rewards of indus- try, energy, temperance and thrift? Does it not pro- portionately, and far more than proportionately (for it involves enormous wastes), deny these rewards to those who have really earned them? Does it not give wealth, honor, the command of everything that labor in a high civilization can produce, to idlers, idiots, gamesters, profligates? Does it not, on the other hand, condemn toil to penury, and honest labor, to contempt and grinding want? Does it not, wherever our civilization extends, make the mere op- portunity to work a boon? keep men in idleness whose strongest desire is to earn a living? fill prisons and almshouses? condemn to ignorance minds that might “JUSTICE’’ ON THE RIGHT TO LAND. 225 enlighten and bless mankind? debase and embrute great masses of men and women? rob little children of the grace and sweetness and glory of life, and force them before their time out of a world in which monopoly denies them room? Try Herbert Spencer by the ideas that he once held—the idea of a Living God, whose creatures we are, and the idea of a divine order, to which we are bound to conform. Or try him by what he now pro- fesses—the idea that we are but the evolutionary results of the integrations of matter and motion. Try him by the principles of “Social Statics,” or try him by the principles of “Justice.” In this chap- ter he proves himself alike a traitor to all that he once held and to all that he now holds—a conscious and deliberate traitor, who assumes the place of the philosopher, the office of the judge, only to darken truth and to deny justice; to sell out the right of the wronged and to prostitute his powers in the defence of the wronger. Is it a wonder that intellectually, as morally, this chapter is beneath contempt? CHAPTER IX. “JUSTICE.”—THE RIGHT OF PROPERTY. IN “Justice” as in “Social Statics,” the chapter on the right to land is followed by a chapter on the right of property. That in “Social Statics " I have reprinted in full, to meet Mr. Spencer's subsequent assertion that it modified the radical conclusions of the preceding chapter. But it is hardly necessary thus to treat the similar chapter of “Justice.” It begins (Section 54): Since all material objects capable of being owned are in one way or other obtained from the earth, it results that the right of property is originally dependent on the right to the use of the earth. While there were yet no artificial products, and natural products were therefore the only things which could be appropriated, this was an obviously necessary connection. And though, in our developed form of society, there are multitudinous pos. sessions, ranging from houses, furniture, clothes, works of art, to bank-notes, railway-shares, mortgages, govern- ment bonds, etc., the origins of which have no mani- fest relation to use of the earth; yet it needs but to remember that they either are, or represent, products of labor, that labor is made possible by food, and that food is obtained from the soil, to see that the connection, though remote and entangled, still continues. Whence it follows that a complete ethical justification for the right of property is involved in the same difficulties as the ethical justification for the right to the use of the earth. Since all material things capable of being owned consist either of land or products of land, the round- “JUSTICE.” — THE RIGHT OF PROPERTY. 227 about connection between such things as are here specified and the earth, through the food consumed by laborers, is a queer one, which indicates what in some parts of “Social Statics” may be suspected, that in speaking of land Mr. Spencer, as is often the case with English writers, is really thinking only of agricultural land. The difficulties of which he speaks are the diffi- culties he raises in “Social Statics,” by confounding equal rights with joint rights, and he here again takes issue with Locke and assumes, as before, that for production to give title, the right of the producer to the use of material must be shown to be “greater than the pre-existing rights of all other men put to- gether.” The forty-one years that have elapsed have left Mr. Spencer still entangled by this self-raised difficulty. But he now goes on to say that the dif- ficulty arising from the question whether by labor “a man has made his right to the thing greater than the pre-existing rights of all other men put to- gether' . . . may be avoided however. There are three ways in which, under savage, semi-civilized, and civilized conditions, men's several rights of property may be established with due regard to the equal rights of all other men.” * Mr. Spencer speaks of such usages as that an unsuccessful hunter in passing might take a deer from a trap for food, leaving head, skin, and saddle for the owner, as implying the belief of the tribesmen that “this prey was in part theirs before it was killed.” But it no more implies this than the custom by which, among the early California rancheros, any traveller might catch a fresh horse, transfer his saddle and leave the tired one implied common prop- erty in horses, or than the kindly customs of essentially the same kind that are to be found wherever the struggle for existence that has developed with our civilization has not become intense. 228 RECANTATION. In the savage condition, he says there is a tacit agreement that having equal opportunities of utiliz- ing such products, appropriation achieved by one shall be passively assented to by the others. As to the semi-civilized condition, he says: We meet with usages having the same general impli- cations. . . . It is perceived that the assent of the clan to ownership of food grown on an appropriated portion by any one, is implied in the assumptions of kindred ownership similarly established by all others. . . . In this case then as in the first, the right of property arises in conformity with the law of equal freedom. So far then Mr. Spencer derives, and properly de- rives, the right of property from the exertion of labor under conditions in which all are equally free to make use of land. He now comes to his third divis- ion, where he is to show how in civilized conditions the right of property “may be established with due regard to the equal rights of all other men.” I will quote this in full: Though we cannot say that ownership of property, thus arising, results from actual contract between each mem- ber of the community and the community as a whole, yet there is something like a potential contract; and such potential contract might grow into an actual contract if one part of the community devoted itself to other occu- pations, while the rest continued to farm : a share of the produce being in such case payable by agreement to those who had ceased to be farmers, for the use of their shares of the land.” We have no evidence that such a relation between occupiers and the community, with consequent 1 Here is another instance of the habit of thinking of land as only agricultural land. The assumption here is that farmers are the only users of land, whereas the obvious truth is that there is no occupation that can be carried on without the use of land, and that many other occupations require the use of much more valuable “JUSTICE.” — THE RIGHT OF PROPERTY. 229 authorized rights of property in the produce which re- mained after payment of a portion equivalent to rent, has ever arisen; for, as we have seen, the original owner- ship by the community has habitually been usurped by internal or external aggressors, and the rent, taking the shape, if not of produce, then of labor or military ser- vice, has been habitually paid to the usurper, a state of things under which equitable rights of property, in com- mon with equitable rights of all kinds, are submerged. But out of such usurpations there has grown up, as we have seen, ownership by the state and tenancy under it ; from which there may again arise a theoretically equitable right of property. In China, where “the land is all held directly from the Crown " " on payment of an annual tax,” “with composition for personal service to the gov- ernment,” the legitimate proprietorship of such produce as remains after payment of rent to the community, can be asserted only on the assumption that the emperor stands for the community. In India, where the govern- ment is supreme land-owner, and where, until the zemin- dar system was established, it was the direct receiver of rents, the derivation of a right of property by contract between the individual and the community can be still less asserted without a strained interpretation. Nor at home, where the theory that each land-owner is a tenant of the crown is little more than a theory, is there any better fulfilment of the ethical requirement. Only here and there, where state-ownership is not potential but actual, and ordinary rents are paid by occupiers to the Crown (which has now in such cases come to be identi- fied with the community), has there been consequently established that kind of use of the earth which gives a theoretically valid basis to the right of private property. Now what is it that Mr. Spencer here says? It is that a theoretically equitable right of property does not now exist in civilized conditions; but that it may arise if the now nominal and potential supreme own- land than does farming. In the occupancy of his London apart- ments Mr. Spencer himself is more of a land user, value con- sidered, than many a small farmer, 230 RECANTATION. ership of land by the state is made real and actual by the taking for the use of the community, by the rep- resentatives of the community, of the rents that are (or should be) paid by occupiers of land. Truly “Justice ’’ is a suprising book. Here we have Mr. Spencer going back to the very principle he has just recanted. In one sentence of this paragraph he says that we have no evidence that this equitable adjustment of the rights to land in conformity with the needs of the civilized state has ever arisen, since the original own- ership of land by the community has been habitually usurped, and in another sentence he says vaguely that it has arisen only here and there. But that it may arise and ought to arise, and would give an even theo- retically perfect basis to the right of property, this section states, if not as clearly, but yet on careful reading as unmistakably as does “Social Statics” itself. The paragraph just quoted is followed by this recapitulatory paragraph, with which the section closes: But admitting that the establishment of an ethically complete right of property is beset with difficulties like those which beset the establishment of an ethically com- plete right to the use of the earth, we are nevertheless shown by a survey of the facts which existing primitive Societies present, and the facts traceable in the early histories of civilized societies, that the right of property is originally deducible from the law of equal freedom ; and that it ceases to be so deducible only when the other corollaries from the law of equal freedom have been disregarded. Or to put this statement of the propositions of this section in fuller form, they are : (1) That the estab- “JUSTICE.” — THE RIGHT OF PIROPERTY. 231 lishment of the right of property is beset by the diffi- culties of showing that the right of a man to the material element from which property is obtained is greater than the rights of all existing men put together. (2) But in primitive societies and in the early his- tory of civilized societies, where the use of land is open to all, this equality of access to land enables us to deduce the right of property in things produced by labor from the law of equal freedom ; and (3) it ceases to be so deducible where equality in the use of land is denied, as in civilized societies at present; but would again become deducible from the law of equal freedom if the rent of land were taken for the use of the Society. If Mr. Spencer had written “Justice ’’ under coer- cion; if imprisoned in the chambers of an Inquisi- tion, and under fear of the rack, he had been forced against his will, like Galileo, to recant what he still held to be true, we might well believe that this Sec- tion 54 of “Justice ’’ contained his sign to posterity that in spite of the denials he had just been compelled to make he in his heart held to the truth. But though, unfortunately, the conditions do not admit of such a conclusion, this section is perhaps an even stronger testimony to the power of truth. In the preceding chapter Mr. Spencer has forced back his better nature, and defended landlordism as well as the man who had written “Social Stat- ics' could. But when after an interval of over forty years he begins to rewrite his old chapter on “The Right of Property,’” the truth he once held reasserts its sway, and though he cuts out all that might give open offence to his new clients, the per- 232 RECANTATION. ception of truth, as by “unconscious cerebration,” causes him in the very first section to relapse, and to tell us – unmistakably, if not clearly — that in the civilized state it is only the appropriation of rent to the use of the whole community that can give to property an ethical basis. But Mr. Spencer soon recovers himself. Having in Section 54 shown that in rude societies there is a substantial basis for the right of property, but that in highly civilized countries, such as England, the equi- table right of property has been submerged by the usurpation of land-ownership, he proceeds in Sec- tion 55 to assert, as he did in the preceding chap- ter, that the course of modern civilization has been more fully to establish this right. Section 55 begins: This deduction [i.e., of the right of property from the law of equal freedom through the equal right to the use of land], early recognized in custom and afterwards formulated by legislators, has come to be elaborated and enforced more and more fully as Society has developed. Then comes something about primitive societies, the patriarchal group and the house community, in which occurs the reference to inherent value already quoted on page 51, and the section thus closes: To trace the development of the right of property as established by rulers and administered by their agents, setting out with the interdict on theft in the Hebrew commandments, and continuing down to modern days, in which proprietorships of all kinds have been legally formulated in multitudinous detail and with great pre- cision, would be no less out of place than it would be superfluous. It suffices for present purposes to note that this implication of the principle of justice, perceived from the first perhaps more clearly than any other, has “JUSTICE.” — THE RIGHT OF PROPERTY. 233 gained in the course of social progress increased definite- ness of recognition as well as increased extension and increased peremptoriness; so that now, breach of the right of property by unauthorized appropriation of a turnip or a few sticks, has become a punishable offence; and there is ownership of a Song, of a pattern, of a trade- mark. The principle of justice in the right of property perceived from the first, as Mr. Spencer has just ex- plained, is equality in the use of natural opportunities. Has this principle gained by a social progress, which as exemplified in England, now denies nineteen- twentieths of the people of all right whatever in the land of their birth, punishes them if they take a hand- ful of wild fruit or a few sticks from the abundant offerings of nature, creates private ownership in a salmon fishery, a coal mine, an advowson or a hereditary pension, and condemns millions to chronic pauperism? This is what Mr. Spencer's examination of the right of property in “Justice ’’ amounts to: First showing that the right of property in civilized socie- ties has to-day no ethical basis, he goes on to make believe that it has, and from this basis of make- believe to assume the ethical validity of existing conditions. And then he virtuously turns on the communists. They are a feeble folk and have no friends. In this he follows the order of “Social Statics,” but the spirit is that of “The Man versus the State.” He ignores what he once saw plainly, the incentive to communistic and socialistic schemes in the bitter wrong and widespread suffering of the existing order, declares their motive to be the desire to take from the 234 RECANTATION. & worker the produce of his work, and assumes that between them and existing social conditions lies the only choice. Here is the section : $ 56. Supposing themselves to be justified, and indeed enjoined by moral principle, many in our days are seeking to over-ride this right. They think it wrong that each man should receive benefits proportionate to his efforts — deny that he may properly keep possession of all which his labor has produced, leaving the less capable in possession of all which their labors have produced. Ex- pressed in its briefest form, their doctrine is — Let unlike kinds and amounts of work bring like shares of produce — let there be “equal division of unequal earnings.” That communism implies violation of justice as de- fined in foregoing chapters, is manifest. When we assert the liberty of each bounded only by the like liberties of all, we assert that each is free to keep for himself all those gratifications and sources of gratification which he procures without trespassing on the spheres of action of his neighbors. If, therefore, one obtains by his greater strength, greater ingenuity, or greater applica- tion, more gratifications or sources of gratification, than others, and does this without in any way trenching on the spheres of action of others, the law of equal freedom assigns him exclusive possession of all such extra grati- fications and sources of gratification ; nor can others take them from him without claiming for themselves greater liberty of action than he claims, and thereby violating the law. • In past times the arrangements made were such that the few superior profited at the expense of the many inferior. It is now proposed to make arrangements such that the many inferior shall profit at the expense of the few superior. And just as the old social system was assumed by those who maintained it to be equitable, so is this new social system assumed to be equitable by those who propose it. I3eing, as they think, un- doubtedly right, this distribution may properly be estab- lished by force; for the employment of force, if not avowedly contemplated, is contemplated by implication. “JUSTICE.” — THE RIGHT OF PROPERTY. 235 With a human nature such as has been known through- out the past and is known at present, one who, by higher power, bodily or mental, or greater endurance of work, gains more than others gain, will not voluntarily sur- render the excess to such others: here and there may be found a man who would do this, but he is far from being the average man. And if the average Superior man will not voluntarily surrender to others the excess of benefit gained by his superiority, the implication is that he must be obliged to do this, and that the use of force to oblige him is justifiable. That the many inferior are physically able thus to coerce the few superior is agreed on both sides, but the assumption of the communists is that the required coercion of the minority who are best by the majority who are worst would be equitable. After what was said in the early chapter of this Part, it scarcely needs pointing out that a system established in pursuance of this doctrine would entail degeneration of citizens and decay of the community formed by them. Suspension of that natural discipline by which every kind of creature is kept fit for the activities demanded by the conditions of life, would inevitably bring about unfitness for life and either prompt or slow disappearance. An old fable tells us that when the plague raged among the animals they concluded that among them was some great criminal, who must be sacrificed to the wrath of heaven, and agreed that to discover him all should confess their sins. The fox volunteered to act as judge. He listened with equanimity to the lion's recital of flocks devoured and men slaughtered, declaring his majesty blameless, and in the same way excused all that the tiger, the hyena, the wolf, and the bear confessed. At length came a poor ass, who told how, when his master had forgotten to give him his breakfast, he had nibbled a few leaves from his load of cabbages. “You impious rascall ” cried the fox, “it is you beyond doubt who have brought on us the anger of the gods !” and applauding the de- 236 RECANTATION. cision and following his lead, the lordly animals threw themselves on the poor ass and tore him to pieces. As the nibbling of a cabbage leaf is to Herod's slaughter of the innocents, so is the dream of a few communists compared with what the monopoly of land is actually doing. In the highest civilization in other respects that the world has yet seen this monopoly is, even now, entailing the degradation of citizens and decay of the community, so that Mr. Spencer cannot look out of the windows of his club without seeing men turned into advertising signs; or get into a cab without having some miserable wretch officiously hasten to close the door in the hope of a penny; or travel through the three king- doms without beholding the decay of population in the country and its congestion in the slums of towns? It is, even now, suspending “that natural discipline by which every creature is kept fit for the activities demanded by the conditions of life,” so that men are being destroyed, on the one side by repletion and debauchery, and on the other side by privation and the denial of opportunities for honest work. It is, even now, taking the produce of their work from superior worker and inferior worker alike, and is giving the gratifications and sources of gratification earned by work to those who do no work —is piling up wealth in the hands of those who do nothing to produce wealth, who as land-owners are useless appropriators and worse than useless destroyers. To this giant wrong, this most monstrous of all denials of the law of equal freedom, Mr. Spencer is as complaisant as the fox was to the lion, while he vents his indigna- tion on the poor ass of communism. “JUSTICE.” — THE RIGHT OF PROPERTY. 237 The next and final chapter shows how far Mr. Spencer really wishes to assert the right of property. It was, as he knows, by violating the right of prop- erty in putting taxes on the products of labor that the larger tenants of English land made themselves its virtual owners and that private property in land has come to be established in those wide regions to which English institutions have been extended. And it is on the line of abolishing this taxation of labor and the products of labor that, as is now evident, the struggle for the resumption of equal rights in land will in English-speaking countries be made — nay, is already beginning to be made. So in the next section Mr. Spencer brings out his double-barrelled ethics to break down the right of property and to open the door for what is essenti- ally socialism and communism in the interests of the rich : § 57. While absolute ethics thus asserts the right of property, and while no such breach of it as is implied by the schemes of communists is warranted by that relative ethics which takes account of transitional needs, relative ethics dictates such limitation of it as is neces- sitated for defraying the costs of protection, national and individual. The truth recognized at the outset, that the preser- vation of the species, or that variety of it constituting a nation, is an end which must take precedence of indi- vidual preservation, has already been cited as justifying that subordination of the right to life which is implied by exposure to possible death in defensive war, and as also justifying that subordination of the right to lib- erty which military service and subjection necessitate. Here it must be again cited as affording a legitimate reason for appropriating such portions of the posses- sions and the earnings of individuals, as may be re- quired for adequately resisting enemies. But while 238 RECANTATION. there is thus a quasi-ethical justification for whatever encroachment on the right of property is necessitated for the purposes of defensive war, there is no justifica- tion for any such encroachment for the purposes of offensive war. No less manifest is it that the right of property is legitimately subject to one further restriction. Prop- erty must be trenched upon for supporting those pub- lic administrations by which the right of property, and all other rights, are enforced. In a society wholly com- posed of men who duly respected one another's claims, no such partial invasion of the right of property would be called for ; but in existing societies and in such societies as are likely to exist for a long time to come, the nearest approach to fulfilment of the law of equal freedom is made when the various deduced rights are sacrificed to the extent needful for preservation of the remainders. Relative ethics, therefore, warrants such equitably-distributed taxation as is required for main- taining order and safety. Since the ethical commands, thou shalt do no mur- der and thou shalt not steal, mean also, thou shalt not permit thyself to be murdered or to be stolen from, the justification of defensive war needs no invention of relative ethics. Nor is this needed to justify under extraordinary circumstances what under ordinary circumstances would be violations of the right of property. Take Johnstown, when the sun rose on wreck and ruin and death in their most awful forms, and on men and women half crazed with lis- tening all night long to the shrieks that came from the flaming mass of float-wood into which the flood was sweeping their nearest and dearest. In ordering the destruction of all liquor, the seizing of all food, and the impressment, should that be necessary, of all who could work, in a systematized effort to succor who still might be succored and to bury what remained to “JUSTICE.” — THE RIGHT OF PROPERTY. 239 bury of the dead, was not Arthur Moxham acting, in the name of the reason and conscience of the com- munity, on the same eternal principles of right and wrong that in ordinary conditions would have forbid- den these things? What in form was a denial of the rights of property and person was in its essence respect for life and property. But while changing conditions may change the application of ethical principles, it is only as the change in a ship's course turns the compass card in her binacle. The change is in the conditions not in the principles. And if there be an ethical right of property, then, except under conditions of immi- ment danger and dire stress, a community cannot be justified in taking property by force from the individual. What Mr. Spencer does in this section, in the name of his convenient fiction of relative ethics, is to jus- tify the habitual violations of the right of property which are committed under the name of government in all civilized countries, and thus to make his phi- losophy of things as they ought to be, conform the better with things as the ruling classes desire to maintain them. And he does this effectually, for he leaves the right of property without defence, save in idle platitudes, against those forms of taxation which have everywhere proved so efficient in robbing the many and enriching the few. * To be sure Mr. Spencer justifies the taking of prop- erty by taxation only for purposes of defensive war and the maintenance of order and safety. But such limitations are practically no limitations. Neither an English jingo nor an American protectionist would 240 RECANTATION. quarrel with them. No invading foot has trod English soil, no hostile fleet has fired a shot at an English town, since the English national debt began to form. Yet what one of all the wars for which the English masses have paid in blood and privation and of which this great debt is the reminder, has not been advocated at the time as a defensive war? Is not our monstrous American tariff declared by its advo- cates to be necessary to the maintenance of order and safety 2 What has been the assigned reason for the maintenance of every fat English sinecure but order and safety 2 Granted that Mr. Spencer would abolish the more flagrant abuses of taxation ; or, as in the light of his changes on the land question we may more certainly say, granted that he is in favor of abolishing them so long as Sir John and his Grace do not seriously object; yet in admitting that the right of property may justly be set aside by the state for ordinary public needs and uses, he opens the door for every abuse that the ruling power — the majority, if you please — may at any time choose to deem a use. He leaves no principle save the shifting one of expe- diency to guard the right of property against any interest or desire or whim that may gain control of the legislative power. But the reign of relative ethics, like that of the old-fashioned devil, to which it bears some analogy, is not to be forever, for we are given to understand that when evolution has carried the descendants of what are now the human race to a point as far above us as it has carried us above the monkey, and brought on the agnostic millennium, relative ethics are to “JUSTICE.” — THE RIGHT OF PROPERTY. 241 vanish in the unknowable pit. So Mr. Spencer tells us that “in a society composed of men who duly respected one another's claims, no such partial inva- sion of the rights of property would be called for.” But then, he continues, it is called for “in existing societies and in such societies as are likely to exist for a long time to come.” What ground does that give me to assert that I am robbed directly by the blackmail demanded in the name of duty at the American post-office every time a friend sends me a book from a foreign country, or even from Canada, and am robbed indirectly every day of my life in the purchases I make 2 The protectionist, if a Spence- rian and disposed to argue, would simply reply, “You are talking absolute ethics, whereas, as Her- bert Spencer has shown, we are now under the rule of relative ethics.” It is true, but in a sense that Mr. Spencer does not mean, that if men duly respected one another's . claims, no taking of individual property in taxation by the state would be necessary. For if men duly respected one another's claims to the use of land, all necessity for invading the right of property by taxa- tion would disappear. Either by the single tax on land values or by the crude and clumsy scheme of land nationalization proposed by Mr. Spencer himself in “Social Statics,” enough revenue would accrue to the state to defray all needed expenses without taking a penny of any man's property. But if men are to continue to disregard each other's claims to the use of land, and to continue to treat that element as be- longing to a few individuals—and this Mr. Spencer now insists on — then there is no possible improve- 242 RECANTATION. ment in society or in the race that could dispense with the taking of property by taxation. Mr. Spencer evidently entertains the innocent notion that could the soldier and the policeman be done away with, there would be no further need for public revenues, and all organized government could be dispensed with. But would not civilized societies still need revenues for building and keeping roads and bridges, for paving and cleaning streets, for establishing lighthouses and supporting a fire ser- vice, and doing the many things which become increasingly necessary to the public health, safety, comfort, and convenience, as 'social integration goes on 2 Or in the millennium of the Spencerians, as in the millennium of the anarchists, is each one to pave, clean and light the street before his door, when and how he pleases 2 are roads, bridges and public works, as to which competition is impossible, to be left to private individuals and companies, charging what they please and rendering what service they choose? and are all other public functions to be dependent on volunteer service or voluntary subscription ? CHAPTER X. THE RIGHT OF PROPERTY AND THE RIGHT OF TAXATION. OF such primary and practical importance is the question just raised, that it is worth while to discuss it more fully. Mr. Spencer, in a book he has re-issued this year, has flippantly accused “Mr. George and his friends' with asserting the absolute right of the community over the possessions of each member. Yet in nothing is the divergence between us and the common opin- ion more sharply shown than in this, that we utterly deny the right of the community to take the property of the individual for any purpose whatsoever, except under circumstances where all rights must yield to the supreme right of self-preservation. There may be circumstances of such sudden stress and danger as would justify an individual in taking the horse or boat of another individual, in making use of his house, his goods, or anything that is his ; and so there may be similar circumstances that will justify such taking of individual property on the part of a community. But short of this, which is not a limitation but an abrogation, we hold the right of property to be abso- lute, and deny the proposition which Mr. Spencer in the chapter just quoted asserts, and which is commonly conceded, that the right of property is limited by the right of the state to take in taxation what it may 244 RECANTATION. think it needs. Thus we are to-day the defenders of the right of property as against communists, protec- tionists, and socialists, as well as against such moderate deniers of the right of property as the revenue tariffites of the Cobden Club class, and such half-way individualists as the Liberty and Property Defence League and Mr. Auberon Herbert's associations. How then is it that we are called deniers of the right of property 2 It is for the same reason that, when I was a boy, caused nine-tenths of the good people in the United States, north as well as south, to regard abolitionists as deniers of the right of property; the same reason that made even John Wesley look on a smuggler as a kind of robber, and on a custom-house seizer of other men's goods as a defender of law and order. Where violations of the right of property have been long sanctioned by custom and law, it is inevitable that those who really assert the right of property will at first be thought to deny it. For under such circumstances the idea of property becomes confused, and that is thought to be property which is in reality a violation of property. That such confusion exists to-day may be seen in the way in which the great struggle for better condi- tions of life for the masses, that all over the civilized world has begun or is impending, is generally regarded by both sides. Except by the single-tax men, and possibly by the philosophic anarchists, it is thought of as a struggle between capital and labor — a contest between the rights of man and the rights of property. It is not merely that one side charges the other side with proposing to impair the right of property. It is, PROPERTY AND TAXATION. - 245 that, with the exceptions noted, those who would better secure the rights of men, do propose restric- tions and denials of the right of property. So, from the thorough-going socialists who would have the state appropriate all capital and direct all industry, to those milk-and-water socialists who are willing to play at doing something, by encouraging trades unions, and by two-penny alms and restrictions, and by attempts to make the rich less rich, and conse- quently as they think the poor less poor, through income and succession taxes and Irish Land Acts, we find those who aim, or profess to aim at improv- ing the conditions of the laboring masses, advocating measures which are violations of the right of property. In this confusion of thought we who hold that the right of property is an absolute right, we who say that the command “Thou shalt not steal" applies to the state as fully as to the individual, are looked upon by one side as deniers of the right of property, and by the other—even by the poor, timid university social- ists—as not radical enough. Yet to whoever will grasp first principles it must be evident : That there can be no real conflict between labor and capital — since capital is in origin and essence but the product and tool of labor; That there can be no real antagonism between the rights of men and the rights of property —since the right of property is but the expression of a funda- mental right of man ; That the road to the improvement of the conditions of the masses cannot be the road of restricting and denying the right of property, but can only be that 246 RECANTATION. of securing most fully the right of property; and that all measures that impair the right of property must in the end injure the masses — since while it may be possible that a few may get a living or be aided in getting a living by robbery, it is utterly impossible that the many should. It is not as deniers, but as asserters of the equal rights of man, that we who for want of a better name call ourselves single-tax men so strenuously uphold the right of property. It is not because we would palter with a social system that condemns the masses to hard work and low wages, to absolute want and starvation more or less disguised; but because we would bring about a social system in which it would be impossible for any one to want or to starve unless he deserved to. It is not because we are less radical, but because in the true sense we are more radical than the socialists of all degrees. Let me ask those who think there is any conflict between the rights of men and the rights of property to name any denial of the rights of men which is not or does not involve a denial of the rights of property; or any denial of the rights of property which is not or does not involve a denial of the rights of men. Take chattel slavery. Was that an assertion of the right of property or a denial of the right of property 2 Or, consider any system of tyranny or oppression by which the personal liberties of men have been denied or curtailed. Take out of it the element which infringes the right of property and is not its efficacy gone? On the other hand, take anything which denies or impairs the right of property – robbery, brigandage, PROPERTY AND TAXATION. 247 piracy, war, customs duties, excises, or taxes on wealth in any of its forms — do they not all violate per- sonal liberty, directly and indirectly 7 This is not an accidental, but a necessary connec- tion. The right of life and liberty — that is to say, the right of the man to himself — is not really one right and the right of property another right. They are two aspects of the same perception — the right of property being but another side, a differently stated expression, of the right of man to himself. The right to life and liberty, the right of the individual to him- himself, presupposes and involves the right of prop- erty, which is the exclusive right of the individual to the things his exertion has produced. This is the reason why we who really believe in the law of liberty, we who see in freedom the great solvent for all social evils, are the stanchest and most unflinching supporters of the rights of property, and would guard it as scrupulously in the case of the millionnaire as in the case of the day laborer. But what is property 2 This we must keep clearly in mind if, in attempting to see what the right of property does and does not permit, we would avoid confusion. The question is not what the state sanc- tions, but what it may rightfully sanction. There are those who say that the right of property, as all other rights, are derived from the state. But they do not really think this ; for they are as ready as any one else to say of any proposed state action that it is right or it is wrong, in which they assert some standard of action higher than the state. Property — not property in the legal sense, for that may be anything which greed or perversity may have 248 IRECANTATION. power to ordain ; but property in the ethical sense — is that which carries with it the right of exclusive ownership, including the right to give, sell, bequeath or destroy. To what sort of things does such right of owner- ship rightfully attach 2 Clearly to things produced by labor, and to no other. And that this rightful ownership can only attach to things produced by labor is always shown by those who try to assert such right of ownership in other things. For invariably, instead of proving a right of ownership in such other things, they devote them- selves to proving the right of ownership in things produced by labor, and then assume that in some way the right thus accruing has become transferred to things of a different nature. Mr. Spencer is an example of this, as are all with- out exception who have ever written on the side he has now assumed. He wishes in this book to justify property in land. But he only justifies property in the products of labor, and then insinuates what he dares not clearly state—that by some process of trans- fer or conjoinment the right of ownership in the pro- ducts of labor has become transmuted into a right of ownership in land. In this, however, he does as well as any one who ever attempted it. The logical processes of those who attempt to prove a right of exclusive ownership in land are always akin to those of the bum-boat man, who, having agreed to bring the sailor a white mon- key, brought him instead a yellow dog which he in- sisted had eaten a white monkey. They are like a PROPERTY AND TAXATION. 249 lawyer who, called on to prove his client's title to an estate, should go on to prove his client's title to the money which he gave for the estate. The ethical right of property is so perfectly clear as to be beyond all dispute — as to be testified to by all who attempt to assert some other right of prop- erty. It springs from the right of each man to use his own powers and enjoy their results. And it is a full and absolute right. Whatever a man produces belongs to him exclusively, and the same full and exclusive right passes from him to his grantor, assignee or devisee, not to the amount of eighty or fifty or any other percentage, but in full. And as is shown by reason and as is proved by the experience of the world, the advance in civilization depends upon the recognition of this right. Therefore for the State to levy taxes on that which is truly property, that is to say, upon the possession of wealth in any of its forms, is unjust and injurious — is a denial and viola- tion of the right of property and of the rights of man. But it may be said: In an isolated condition it is true that a man is entitled to all that he produces, and that it is robbery to take any part of it from him against his will. But in the civilized condition it is not alone the exertion of the individual that contri- butes to his production. Over and above what the producer receives from other producers, and for which he recompenses them in the various ways by which the claims between man and man are settled in ordered society, he is aided, in an indefinite yet tan- gible way, by society as a whole. Does he not there- fore owe to society as a whole some return? Is not organized society, or the state, entitled therefore to 250 RECANTATION. claim and to take some portion of what in an isolated condition would be rightfully his exclusive property? We reply: There is such a debt, but the producer cannot escape paying it, even though there be left to him in full what is his by the right of property. Here is a man who gives to a painter an order for a beautiful picture. Can he alone enjoy it? Here is another man who builds a factory, or works out a beneficial invention. Do what benefits he may re- ceive, even if he be untaxed, represent the sum total of its benefits? Does not what he has done also benefit others and benefit society at large 2 And if society helps the individual producer, does not the individual producer also help society? These diffused benefits, these benefits which society as a whole re- ceives, are something separate from what the right of property accords to the producer. They become tangible in the value of land, and may be taken by society without any curtailment of the right of prop- erty. To bring one beautiful picture to a town might not perceptibly increase the value of land. But bring a number, or even one famous picture, and the value of land will perceptibly increase. Place the pictures of one of the great European galleries on a piece of American land that you might now buy for a hundred dollars and you will soon find a value of millions attaching to that land. And that the erection of a factory, or even of a dwelling-house, or the utilization of a beneficial invention, will perceptibly add to the value of land every one knows. Look at the millions on millions which the elevated roads have added to the value of New York lands. Again, it may be said, as Mr. Spencer now says, that PROPERTY AND TAXATION. 251 it is necessary for organized society to have revenues, and that therefore the society must take some part at least of the property of individuals. The proposi- tion we admit, but the conclusion we deny. Organ- ized society must have revenues; but the natural and proper and adequate source of those revenues is not in what justly belongs to individuals, but in what justly belongs to society — the value which attaches to land with the growth of society. Let the state take that, and there will be no need for it to violate the right of property by taking what justly belongs to the individual. Mr. Spencer's admission in “Justice ’’ of the right of the state to take from innividuals their property by taxation — an admission which makes impossible any clear assertion of the right of property —is forced upon him by the radical change in his teachings that his fear of Sir John and his Grace has compelled him to make. He made no such surrender of individual rights to the state in “Social Statics.” On the con- trary he there emphatically — though as to details not very clearly, for in many things he only saw men as trees walking — asserts the rights of the individual as against Society. But in “Justice” he is compelled to admit the right of the state to take property by taxation, because of his desire to admit the right of land-owners to appropriate the revenues which are the natural provision for the needs of the state. For the state is natural and necessary, and the state must have revenues. Hence any one who does not see, or who chooses to deny, that the natural rev- enue of the state is the value which social growth gives to land, is compelled to admit that for the pur- 252 IRECANTATION. pose of obtaining revenue the state may take the property of individuals, and thus to deny the right of property. - Suppose some one to have asked the Herbert Spencer who wrote “Social Statics: ” “Where shall the state get its necessary revenues if it scrupulously observes the right of property and does not continue to take by force what it needs of the property of individuals 2 ° He would have promptly replied, for the answer is in that book, “By taking through its own agents for its own purposes the rent of land, which is now taken by the agents of Sir John and his Grace for their purposes.” But the Herbert Spencer who now writes “Justice” could find no answer to such a question, since he writes for the purpose of defending the appropriations of Sir John and his Grace. Hence he is compelled to deny the right of property — justifying its appropria- tion by an agency which in another place in this same book he calls “the many-headed government appointed by multitudes of ignorant people ; ” and which, in- deed, owing to the poverty, ignorance, greed and immorality which are the results of ignoring the right of property, is not undeserving of such a contemptuous characterization. But that he really knows better; that he really sees that the taxation of the products of labor is a violation of the right of property which differs from slavery only in degree ; and that he is only advocat- ing it in the interests of that privileged class to gain whose tolerance now seems to be his supreme ambi- tion, is clearly shown further on in this same book, PROPERTY AND TAXATION. 253 where in opposing what he deems unnecessary taxa- tion he clearly states the principle that condemns all taxation of what belongs to individuals. I quote from Chapter XXVI. of “Justice,” “The Limits of State-duties,” Section 121, pp. 222–224: If justice asserts the liberty of each limited only by the like liberties of all, then the imposing of any further limit is unjust ; no matter whether the power imposing it be one man or a million of men. . . . In our time the tying of men to the lands they were born on, and the forbidding any other occupations than the prescribed Ones, would be considered as intolerable aggressions on their liberties. But if these larger inroads on their rights are wrong, then also are smaller inroads. As we hold that a theft is a theft whether the amount stolen be a pound or a penny, so we must hold that an aggres- sion is an aggression whether it be great or small. . . . We do not commonly see in a tax a diminution of free- dom, and yet it clearly is one. The money taken represents so much labor gone through, and the product of that labor being taken away, either leaves the indi- vidual to go without such benefit as was achieved by it or else to go through more labor. In feudal days, when the subject classes had, under the name of corvées, to render services to their lords, specified in time or work, the partial slavery was manifest enough ; and when the services were commuted for money, the relation remained the same in substance though changed in form. So is it now. Tax-payers are subject to a state corvée, which is none the less decided because, instead of giving their spe- cial kinds of work, they give equivalent sums; and if the corvée in the original undisguised form was a deprivation of freedom, so is it in its modern disguised form. “Thus much of your work shall be devoted, not to your own pur- poses, but to our purposes,” say the authorities to the cit- izens; and to whatever extent this is carried, to that extent the citizens become slaves of the government. “But they are slaves for their own advantage,” will be the reply — “ and the things to be done with the money taken from them are things which will in one way 254 - RECANTATION. or other conduce to their welfare.” Yes, that is the theory — a theory not quite in harmony with the vast mass of mischievous legislation filling the statute books. But this reply is not to the purpose. The question is a question of justice; and even supposing that the benefits to be obtained by these extra public expenditures were fairly distributed among all who furnish funds, which they are not, it would still remain true that they are at variance with the fundamental principle of an equi- table social order. A man’s liberties are none the less aggressed upon because those who coerce him do so in the belief that he will be benefited. In thus impos- ing by force their wills upon his will, they are breaking the law of equal freedom in his person ; and what the motive may be matters not. Aggression which is flagi- tious when committed by one, is not sanctified when committed by a host. Thus, in the same book, does Herbert Spencer answer Herbert Spencer. CHAPTER XI. COMPENSATION. WHILE not needed in reply to Mr. Spencer, for his own scornful denial that there is any way in which land can equitably become private property remains unanswered by him, the wide prevalence of the idea that justice requires the compensation of land-owners if their exclusive ownership be abolished, makes it worth consideration; the more so as the same principle is involved in other questions, which are already, or may soon become, of practical im- portance. That this idea will not bear examination Mr. Spen- cer himself shows, even when, as now, he is more than willing to be understood as accepting it. While anxious to find some ground, any ground, for as- suming that land-owners are entitled to compensation for something equal or more than equal to the value of their land, he nowhere ventures to assert that they are entitled to compensation for their land. Such a notion is too preposterous to be stated by any one who has ever realized the relation of men to land. Yet to those who have not, it seems at first most reasonable, for it accords with accustomed ideas. If it were ever customary for primitive man to eat his grandmother, as the Synthetic Philosophy would lead us to suppose, she must have been thought a wicked 256 ſº RECANTATION. old woman who without compensation to the would-be eater tried to avoid that fate. In a community such as Edmond About pictured in his “King of the Mountain,” where brigandage was looked on as a most respectable business, the captive who tried to escape without ransom would be deemed a violator of his captors’ rights. And many a man now living can appreciate Mark Twain's portrayal of the pangs of conscience felt by Huckleberry Finn as he thought that in not denouncing his negro companion he was helping to rob a poor widow. The habitual confusion of thought where violations of property have long been treated by custom and law as property, requires time and effort to escape from, and while justice is yet struggling for recognition there is with many a desire to compromise between the right that ought to be and the wrong that is. Thus there are to-day, in England at least, even among those who to some extent have become con- scious of the injustice of denying the equal right to the use of land, many who think that before this natural right can be equitably asserted present land- owners must be compensated for their loss of legal rights. This idea does not apply to the land question alone. It was carried out in England in the com- pensation paid to West India slave-owners on the abolition of slavery ; in the compensation paid to the owners of rotten Irish boroughs at the time of the Union for the loss of their power to sell legislation; in the capitalization of hereditary pensions; and in the compensation paid to their holders when profitable sinecures are abolished. COMPENSATION. 257 Nor are we without examples of the same idea in the United States. It is often contended that it would be wrong to abolish protective duties where capital has been invested on the expectation of their continuance; and not many years since, even in the North, good, honest people, so far awake to the crime of slavery that they deemed the original enslavement of a man wickedness so atrocious as to merit death — which indeed was the penalty denounced by our laws against engaging in the external slave trade — really believed that slave-owners must be compensated be- fore existing slavery could be justly abolished. Even after the war had fairly begun, this idea was so strong that the nation compensated owners when, in 1862, slavery was abolished in the District of Columbia, and subsequent efforts to apply the same principle to the slave States that adhered to the Union were only defeated by the opposition to any national interfer- ence with slavery. Let us see clearly what this question of compensa- tion is : It does not involve the validity of any contract or agreement or promise formally made by the state. This does not exist and is not pleaded by the advo- cates of compensation in the cases we are considering. If it did, the question would arise how far legisla- tive power may bind legislative power, and one gen- eration control the action of succeeding generations. But it is not necessary to discuss that here. It is not a question of all right of compensation. That the state should compensate when it destroys a building to make way for a public improvement, or takes goods or provisions or horses or shipping for \ 258 RECANTATION. which it may have sudden need, or demands of some citizens Services which it does not demand of others, is not in question. The right of compensation in such cases is not disputed. That is to say it is not a question whether the state should pay for its destruction of property having moral sanction, for the assertion of moral sanction in- volves the right of compensation. Where the right of compensation itself becomes the issue is only where the want of moral sanction in the property in question is conceded. Thus the belief in the rightfulness of compensation for the abolition of slavery bore no determining part in the minds of those who believed in the rightfulness of slavery. The pro-slavery men, who asserted that slavery was of God’s ordinance, that it was the nat- ural right and duty of the stronger to enslave the weaker so they might paternally care for them, who insisted not merely that slavery ought not to be abol- ished where it existed, but that it ought to be extended where it did not exist, were not affected by belief in the rightfulness of compensation. That slave-owners ought to be compensated if slavery was abolished followed from their assertion that slavery was right and ought not to be abolished. It was only in the minds of those who had come to think that slavery was wrong and ought to be abolished, that the idea that slave-holders must be compensated assumed importance, and became the pivotal question. So as to land. The idea of compensation is raised and has importance only where it serves as a sec- ondary defence of private property in land. If a man believes in private property in land it is needless COMPENSATION. 259 to address to him any argument for the necessity of compensation on its abolition. He does not believe in its abolition, but in its continuance and extension; and as the greater includes the less, he already believes in the necessity of compensation if it be abolished. But if he has come to doubt its justice and to favor its abolition, then the raising of the question of compen- sation, as though it were a new and separate moral question, may serve the purpose of a second embank- ment or second ditch in military defence, and prevent him from advocating abolition, or at least abolition that would cause any loss to vested interests. And the intermediate character of this defence of vested wrong gives it of course great attractions for those timid and prudent souls who when moral right comes in conflict with powerful interests like to keep out of the battle. Thus the idea of compensation with which we are concerned is the idea of compensation for the abolition of something in itself conceded to be wrong. Yet it is based on moral grounds, and raises what is purely a moral question. Those who assert this necessity of compensation for the abolition of what in itself they concede to be wrong contend that the state has incurred a moral ob- ligation by its previous acquiescence. They say that while it would be right for it to refuse such acquies- cence in the first place — as to prohibit slavery where it does not yet exist; to refrain from making private property of new land; to refuse to grant new pen- sions or impose new protective duties or grant new special privileges — yet where it has already done such things the state is morally bound to those who 260 RECANTATION. have accepted its action; and for it to destroy the value of property already acquired under its sanction would be in the nature of a retroactive law. But in this there is evident confusion. If it were proposed that the state should undo what has already been done under its sanction — as, for instance, that it should declare invalid titles to the proceeds of slave labor already rendered, and give the slaves legal claim for previous services; or if it should call on the beneficiaries of protective tariffs for profits they had already acquired—then this reasoning might have weight. But it is not retroactive to declare that for the future the labor of the slave shall belong to him- self, nor that for the future trade shall be free. To demand compensation for action of this kind is to as- sert, not that the state must be bound by what it has already done, but that what it has already done it is morally bound to continue to do. The loss for which compensation is in such cases asked is not the loss of a value in hand, but the loss of an expectation. The value of a bale of cotton is an actual existing value, based on work done. But the value of a slave is not actual, but prospective; it is not based on work done, but on the expectation that the state will continue to compel him to work for his owner. So the value of a house or other improve- ment represents the present value of the labor thus embodied. But the value of land itself represents merely the value of the expectation that the state will continue to permit the holder to appropriate a value belonging to all. Now, is the state called on to com- pensate men for the failure of their expectations as to its action, even where no moral element is involved? COMPENSATION. 261 If it make peace, must it compensate those who have invested on the expectation of war. If it open a shorter highway, is it morally bound to compensate those who may lose by the diversion of travel from the old one? If it promote the discovery of a cheap means of producing electricity directly from heat, is it mor- ally bound to compensate the owners of all the steam engines thereby thrown out of use and all who are en- gaged in making them? If it develop the air-ship, must it compensate those whose business would be injured? Such a contention would be absurd. Yet the contention we are considering is worse. It is that the state must compensate for disappointing the expectations of those who have counted on its contin- uing to do wrong. When the state abolishes slavery or hereditary pensions or protective duties or special privileges of any kind, does it really take from the individuals who thereby lose, anything they actually have 2 Clearly not. In the abolition of slavery it merely declines for the future to compel one man to work for another. In the abolition of hereditary pensions it merely de- clines for the future to take property by force from those to whom it rightfully belongs and hand it over to others. In the abolition of protective duties it merely declines for the future forcibly to interfere with the natural rights of all in order that a few may get an unnatural profit. In the abolition of special privi- leges it merely declines for the future to use its power to give some an advantage over others. See, then, for what in such cases compensation is really asked. It is not for any attempt to right past wrongs; it is for refusing to do wrong in future. It 262 RECANTATION. is not for the unequal treatment of individuals; it is for refusal to continue unequal treatment. That there may be a loss of Salable value to individuals in this refusal is true. But it is not a loss of anything they now have ; it is a loss of what they expected to get. It is not a loss for which these individuals can justly demand compensation or the state can justly make compensation. It is a loss of the kind that the sil- versmiths of Ephesus sustained from Paul’s preach- ing; a loss of the kind that comes to liquor-sellers from the spread of a temperance movement ; a loss of the kind that falls on some individuals with every beneficial invention and every public improvement. Such demand for compensation is a denial of any right of reform. It involves the idea that the state, having once done wrong, is morally bound to continue it — not merely that it must continue to do wrong or else compensate; but that it must continue to do wrong anyhow. For compensation implies equivalence. To com- pensate for the discontinuance of a wrong is to give those who profit by the wrong the pecuniary equiv- alent of its continuance. Now the state has nothing that does not belong to the individuals who compose it. What it gives to some it must take from others. Ab- olition with compensation is therefore not really abo- lition, but continuance under a different form — on one side of unjust deprivation, and on the other side of unjust appropriation. When on the abolition of a hereditary pension the holder is compensated, he re- ceives in money or bonds a sum calculated to yield him in interest the same power of annually commanding the labor of others that the pension gave. So compen- COMPENSATION. 263 sation for the selling value of a slave, which disap- pears on the refusal of the community longer to force him to work for the master, means the giving to the master of what the power to take the property of the slave may be worth. What slave-owners lose is the power of taking the property of the slaves and their descendants; and what they get is an agree- ment that the government will take for their ben- efit and turn over to them an equivalent part of the property of all. The robbery is continued under another form. What it loses in intention it gains in extension. If some before enslaved are partially freed, others before free are partially enslaved. That confusion alone gives plausibility to the idea of compensation for refusal to continue wrong, is seen in the fact that such claims are never put forward in behalf of the original beneficiaries of the wrong, but always in behalf of purchasers. Sometimes the con- fusion is that of direct substitution. Thus it is some- times said, “Here is a man who, presuming on the continued consent of the state, invests his earnings in property depending on that consent. If the state withdraws its consent, does it not, unless it compen- sates him, destroy the products of his hard labor?” The answer is clear: It does not. Let the property be, for instance, a slave. What the state destroys in abolishing slavery is not what may have been given for the slave, but the value of the slave. That the purchaser got by honest work what he exchanged for the slave is not in point. He is not injured as laborer, but as slave-owner. If he had not exchanged his earnings for the slave the abolition of slavery would have caused him no loss. When a man exchanges 264 RECANTATION. property of one kind for property of another kind he gives up the one with all its incidents and takes in its stead the other with its incidents. He cannot sell bricks and buy hay, and then complain because the hay burned when the bricks would not. The greater lia- bility of the hay to burn is one of the incidents he accepted in buying it. Nor can he exchange property having moral sanction for property having only legal sanction, and claim that the moral sanction of the thing he sold attaches now to the thing he bought. That has gone with the thing to the other party in the exchange. Exchange transfers, it cannot create. Each party gives up what right he had and takes what right the other party had. The last holder obtains no moral right that the first holder did not have. “But,” it may be said, “the purchaser of what has been long treated as property stands in a different position from the original holder. In our adminis- tration of justice between man and man, this differ- ence between the wrongful appropriator and the innocent purchaser is recognized, and long possession is held to cure defects of original title. This prin- ciple ought to be recognized by the state in dealing with individuals, and hence when, even by omission, it deprives innocent purchasers of what has long been held as property it ought to compensate them.” Innocent purchasers of what involves wrong to others' Is not the plurase absurd 2 If in our legal tribunals, “ignorance of the law excuseth no man,” how much less can it do so in the tribunal of morals and it is this to which compensationists appeal. And innocence can only shield from the punishment due to conscious wrong; it cannot give right. If you COMPENSATION. 265 innocently stand on my toes, you may fairly ask me not to be angry; but you gain no right to continue. to stand on them. Now in merely abolishing property that involves wrong, the state imposes no penalty, it does not even demand recompense to those who have been wronged. In this it is more lenient than the principles on which we administer justice between man and man. For they would require the innocent purchaser of what belonged to another to make resti- tution, not only of the thing itself, but of all that had been received from it. Nor does the principle of market overt, which gives to the purchaser of cer- tain things openly sold in certain places, possession even against the rightful owner unless he proves fraud; nor the principle of statutes of limitation, which refuses to question ownership after a certain lapse of time, deny this general principle. The principle of “market overt” is, not that pas- sage from hand to hand gives ownership, but that there are certain things so constantly passing from hand to hand by simple transfer that the interests of commerce and the general convenience are best served by assuming possession to be conclusive of ownership where wrongful intent cannot be proved. The principle of statutes of limitation is not that mere length of possession gives ownership, but that past a certain point it becomes impossible certainly to adjudicate disputes between man and man. This is one of the cases in which human law must admit its inadequacy to more than roughly enforce the dictates of the moral law. No scheme of religion and no theory of morals would hold him blameless who relied on a statute of limitations to keep what he knew 266 RECANTATION. belonged morally to another. But legal machinery cannot search into the conscience, it can only inquire into the evidence; and the evidence of things past is to human perceptions quickly dimmed and soon obliterated by the passage of time. So that as to things whose ownership must depend on what was done in the past, it is necessary, to avoid intermin- able disputes, that the state should set some limit beyond which it will not inquire, but will take pos- session as proof of ownership. - In our ordinary use of words everything subject to ownership and its incidental rights is accounted property. But there are two species of property, which, though often ignorantly or wantonly con- founded, are essentially different and diametrically opposed. Both may be alike in having a selling value and being subject to transfer. But things of the one kind are true property, having the sanction of natural right and moral law independently of the action of the state, while things of the other kind are only spurious property, their maintenance as property re- quiring the continuous exertion of state power, the continuous exercise or threat of its force, and involv- ing a continuous violation of natural right and moral law. To things of the one kind the reasonable prin- ciple of statutes of limitation properly applies; for, being in their nature property, any question of their ownership is not a question of general right, but only a question of transactions between man and man in the past. But to things of the other kind, and as between the individual and the state, this principle does not and cannot apply, for holding their character as property only from the action of the state, that COMPENSATION. 267 character is gone the moment the state withdraws its support. The question whether this support shall or shall not be withdrawn is not a question of what was done in the past, but of what shall be done in the future — a question of general rights, not a question between individuals. Things which are brought into existence by the exertion of labor, and to which the character of property attaches from their origin as an extension of the right of the man to himself, are property of the first kind. Special privileges by which the state empowers and assists one man in taking the proceeds of another's labor, are property of the second kind. A question of the ownership of a coat, a tool, a house, a bale of goods, is a question of the ownership of the concrete results of past labor. We know from the nature of the thing that it must be owned by somebody, but after lapse of time we cannot from the weakness of human powers undertake in case of dis- pute to determine who that may be ; and hence, refus- ing to inquire so far back, we assume the right to be in the possessor, of which we have at least pre- Sumptive evidence. But a question of the mainten- ance or abolition of slavery or private property in land, of the continuance or non-continuance of a trade monopoly, a hereditary pension, or a protective duty, is a question whether the state shall or shall not in the future lend its power for the wrongful appropria- tion of the results of labor yet to be performed. There is in this no place for the principle of statutes of limitations. No indistinctness as to the past can affect the decision. It is not a question of what has been done in the past, but of what shall be done in the 268 RECANTATION. future. And so far from the presumption being that the possessor of this species of property is entitled to it, the moral certainty is the other way. Again it is said, “Here is a man who invests in a slave and another who invests in a building, both being alike recognized as property by the state. The state by refusing longer to give its former sanction destroys the value of one investment while the other continues profitable. Have not these two men been treated with inequality, which in justice should be remedied by compensation? If there was a wrong involved in the one species of property, was it not a wrong of which by state sanction all were guilty? Is it just therefore that those who have happened to invest in it should bear the whole loss?” To other confusions there is here added confusion as to the relation between the state and its members. If the maintenance by the state of a species of property that involves wrong is to be considered as the action of all its members, even of those who suffer by it, so must the resolve of the state to do so no longer be considered as the resolve of all, even of those who relatively lose by it. If the one cannot demand recompense, how can the others demand compensa- tion ? Passing this, the moral law appealed to in the de- mand for compensation must be the moral law that binds individuals. Now the moral law cannot sanc- tion immorality. It must hold as void even a spe- cific contract to do wrong. But in the cases we are considering there is no contract. The claim is merely that the state by its wrongful action having given rise to the expectation that it would continue such wrong- COMPENSATION. 269 ful action, is morally bound, should it decline to do so, to compensate those who have invested in this expectation. Would such a claim hold as between individuals 2 If, for instance, I have been accustomed to spend my earnings in a gambling-house or rum-shop till the proprietor has come to count on me as a source of regular profit, am I morally bound to compensate him if I stop? Or if an innocent purchaser has bought the business on the expectation that I would continue, does that bind me to compensate him 2 Consider further: If a moral right of property is created by the acquiescence of the state in a wrong, then it must be morally binding on all. If the state would violate the moral law in abolishing slavery without compensation, so would the slave violate the moral law in attempting to escape without first com- pensating his master, and so would every one who aided him, even with a cup of cold water. This was actually held and taught and enacted into law in the United States previous to the war, and with reference to the white slaves of Great Britain is held and taught by the foremost men and journals of that country, who declare that for the masses even by strictly legal forms to resume their natural rights in the land of their birth, without compensation to present legal owners, would be a violation of the Ten Command- ments! That the state is not an individual, but is composed of individual members all of whom must be affected by its action, is the reason why its legitimate sphere is that of securing to those members equal rights. This is the equality which it is bound to secure, not equality in the results of individual actions; and 270 RECANTATION. whoever chooses to invest on the presumption of its denial of equal rights does so at his own risk. He cannot ask that, to secure equality of profits between him and investors who did not take this risk, the state should continue to deny equality of rights. It is the duty of the state to secure equality of rights, not to secure equality of profits. - Of the investments of all kinds constantly being made under the equal sanction of the state some re- sult in loss and some in gain. Supposing it to be asked, “Why should not the state secure equality by compensating those who lose?” The answer would be quick and clear. It is not the business of the state to secure investors from loss, and it would be grossly unjust for it to attempt to do so. For this would be to compel those who had made good investments to make up the losses of those who had made bad ones. It would be to take from pru- dence and care their natural reward and make them bear the losses of recklessness and waste; to punish forethought, to put a premium on ignorance and ex- travagance, and quickly to impoverish the richest community. But would it not be even more unjust and unwise for the state to compensate those who up to the last moment had held and bought property involving wrong, thus compelling those who had refrained from holding and buying it to make up their losses 2 Is it true that the acquiescence of the state in a wrong of this kind proves it equally the wrong of all 2 Did that part of the community consisting of slaves ever acquiesce in slavery? Did the men who were robbed of their natural rights in land ever really acquiesce? COMTENSATION. 271 Are not such wrongs always instituted in the first place by those who by force or cunning gain control of the state? Are they not maintained by stifling liberty, by corrupting morals and confusing thought and buying or gagging the teachers of religion and of ethics? Is not any movement for the abolition of such wrongs always and of necessity preceded by a long agitation in which their injustice is so fully de- clared that whoever does not wilfully shut his eyes may see it? “Caveat emptor” is the maxim of the law — “Let the buyer beware!” If a man buys a structure in which the law of gravity is disregarded or mechanical laws ignored he takes the risk of those laws asserting their sway. And so he takes the risk in buying prop- erty which contravenes the moral law. When he ignores the moral sense, when he gambles on the con- tinuance of a wrong, and when at last the general conscience rises to the point of refusing to continue that wrong, can he then claim that those who have refrained from taking part in it, those who have suf- fered from it, those who have borne the burden and heat and contumely of first moving against it, shall share in his losses on the ground that as members of the same state they are equally responsible for it? And must not the acceptance of this impudent plea tend to prevent that gradual weakening and dying out of the wrong which would otherwise occur as the rise of the moral sense against it lessened the pros- pect of its continuance ; and by promise of insurance to investors tend to maintain it in strength and energy till the last minute 2 Take slavery. The confidence of American slave- 272 TECANTATION. holders, strengthened by the example of Great Britain, that abolition would not come without compensation, kept up to the highest point the market value of slaves, even after the guns that were to free them had begun to sound, whereas if there had been no paltering with the idea of compensation the growth of the sentiment against slavery would by reducing the selling value of slaves have gradually lessened the pecuniary interests concerned in supporting it. Take private property in land. Where the expec- tation of future growth and improvement is in every advancing community a most important element in selling value, the effect of the idea of compensation will be to keep up speculation, and thus to prevent that lessening in the selling value of land, that gradual accommodation of individuals to the coming change, which is the natural effect of the growth of the demand for the recognition of equal rights to land. The question we are discussing is necessarily a moral question. Those who contend that the state is the source of all rights may indeed object to any proposed state action that it would be inexpedient, but they cannot object that it would be wrong. Nevertheless, just as we find the materialistic evolu- tionists constantly dropping into expressions which imply purpose in nature, so do we find deniers of any higher law than that of the state vociferous in their declarations that it would be wrong, or unjust, or wicked, for the state to abolish property of this spurious kind without compensation. The only way we can meet them with any regard for their profes- sions is to assume that they do not quite understand COMPENSATION. 273 the language, and that by such expressions they mean that it would be inexpedient. Their argument, I take it, may be most fairly put in this way: Expe- rience has shown respect for property rights to be greatly conducive to the progress and well-being of mankind, and all rights of property resting (as they assert) on the same basis, the recognition of the state, the destruction of a recognized right of property by action of the state would give a shock to and cast a doubt over all rights of property, and thus work injury. But even if we ignore any moral basis, and assume that all rights of property are derived from the state, it is still clear that while some forms of property do conduce to the general wealth and prosperity, others may be recognized by the state that lessen the gen- eral wealth and impair the general prosperity. The right of piracy, which at times and places has been recognized by the state, does not stand on the same basis of expediency with the right of peaceful com- merce. The right of hereditary jurisdiction, or “the right of pit and gallows” as it was called in Scotland, where it was actually bought out by the state as a piece of valuable property; the right, long having a salable value in France, of administering justice; the right, at times recognized by the state as belonging to every petty lordling, of making private war, of col- lecting local dues and tolls and customs, and com- pelling services; the right of trampling down the fields of the husbandman in the pursuit of game ; the monopolies which made valuable privileges of permissions to manufacture, to trade and to import, were certainly not promotive of the general prosper- 274 RECANTATION. ity. On the contrary the general wealth and pros- perity have been greatly enhanced by their abolition. Even if we grant that all rights of property have the same basis and sanction and eliminate all moral distinction, reason and experience still show that there is but one right of property that conduces to the prosperity of the whole community, and that this is the right which secures to the laborer the product of his labor. This promotes prosperity by stimulat- ing production, and giving such security to accumu- lation as permits the use of capital and affords leisure for the development of the intellectual powers. It is respect for this, not respect for those forms of property which the perversion or folly of legislative power may at times sanction, and which consist in the power of appropriating the results of others' labor, that universal experience shows to be essential to the peace, prosperity and happiness of mankind. So far from the destruction of those spurious and injurious rights of property which have wound around the useful rights of property, like choking weeds around a fruitful vine, being calculated to injure that respect for property on which wealth and pros- perity and civilization depend, the reverse is the case. They are not merely directly destructive of what it promotes, but to class them with it and to insist that the respect due to it is also due to them is to give rise to the belief that all rights of property are injurious to the masses. The history of mankind shows that the respect for property which is essential to social well-being has never been threatened, save by the growth of these noxious parasites. And this to-day is the only thing that threatens it. Why are COMPENSATION. 275 the socialists of to-day so hostile to capital? It is for no other reason than that they confuse with what is really capital legalized wrongs which enable the few to rob the many, by appropriating the products of labor and demanding a blackmail for the use of the opportunity to labor. To teach that the good and the bad in legal recognitions are indistinguishable, that all that the state may choose to regard as property is property, is virtually to teach that property is robbery! And what is this state, to whose control by selfish- ness or ignorance or dishonesty or corruption these deniers of moral distinctions would give the power of binding men in the most vitally important matter for all future time 7 Caligula was the state. Nero was the state. Louis XIV. truly said, “The state, it is I.” And according to Herbert Spencer the state in England consists of “a motley assemblage of nominees of caucuses, ruled by ignorant and fanatical wire-pullers.” Practically, the state is always what man, what combination, what interest, may control its machinery. Hence the expediency of strictly limiting its power; and, if indeed there be no moral principle, no higher law, that will give us clear guidance as to what the state may or may not do, then it becomes all the more expedient that we carry the principle of state omnipotence over rights to its logical conclusion, and assert the power of the state in any present or any future time utterly to annul any stipulation, contract, regulation or institution of the state at any past time. If there be no moral right, no higher law, to check the action of the state, then is it all the more needful that it should be subject at least to the prospective check of sharp and com- 276 T.ECANTATION. plete reversal. For the more permanent and there- fore the more valuable are the special privileges which the state has power to grant, the greater is the inducement to selfish interests to gain control of it. Nothing better calculated to corrupt government and to strengthen a most dangerous tendency of our time can well be imagined than the doctrine that state grants which enable one man to take the labor and property of others can never be abolished without compensation to those who may hold them. Of different nature is the plea sometimes made, that compensation, by disarming opposition, is the easiest and quickest way of abolishing a vested wrong. As to this, not only is compensation not abolition, not only does its advocacy tend to keep in full strength the pecuniary interests which are the greatest obstacles to the reform, but it renders it im- possible to arouse that moral force which can alone overcome an intrenched wrong. For to say that men must be compensated if they are prevented from doing a thing is to say that they have a right to do that thing. And this those who intelligently advo- cate compensation know. Their purpose in advocat- ing compensation is to prevent abolition. It is sometimes said that it would have been cheaper for us to pay for the Southern slaves, as Great Britain did in the West Indies, than incur the civil war. But the assumption that American slavery might thus have been got rid of and the war avoided, is far from being true. An aristocratic government, such as that of Great Britain in 1832, may abolish slavery in a few small dependencies by imposing the burden on its own people, but in a popular govern- COMPENSATION. 277 ment and on a great scale this cannot be done. Great Britain saved no war by paying compensation, for the West Indian planters could not have fought emancipation, and if the West Indian slaves were freed more quickly with compensation than they could have been without, it was solely because the class concerned in the maintenance of vested wrongs was overpoweringly strong in the British Parliament. With even such representation as the masses now have it would have been easier to abolish slavery in the West Indies without compensation than with it. In the United States abolition with compensation was never a practical question, nor could it have become a practical question until the sentiment against slavery had reached even a stronger pitch than that which led to war. The war came before more than a small minority had seriously thought of abolishing slavery, let alone of paying for it; before either section really dreamed of war. It came from the unstable equilibrium which legalized wrong be- gets, from the incidental issues and passions which it always arouses when the moral sense begins to revolt against it, even before the main question is reached. It came, not from a demand for compen- sation on one side and a refusal to give it on the other, but from the timidity with which the moral Question had been treated by those who really saw the essential injustice of slavery, and which by con- cessions and compromises had so strengthened and emboldened the slavery interest that in revolt at measures far less threatening to it than the discus- sion of abolition with compensation could have been, it flung the nation into war. 278 RECANTATION. And even if the alternative of compensation or war had been fairly presented to the American peo- ple, who shall say that it would have been really wiser and cheaper for them to surrender to such a demand 2 Could the Nemesis that follows national wrong have thus been placated? Might not the car- rying out of such a measure as the compensation for three million slaves have given rise to political strug- gles involving an even more disastrous war? And would the precedent established in the conscious viola- tion of the moral sense ultimately have cost nothing 2 The cost of the war, in blood, in wealth, in the bit- terness aroused and the corruptions of government engendered, cannot well be estimated; yet who cannot but feel that the moral atmosphere is clearer and that the great problems which still beset the republic are easier of solution than if with the alternative of com- pensation or war, like a pistol at its head, the nation had consciously and cravenly surrendered to wrong? What this plea for compensation amounts to is, that it is cheaper to submit to wrong than to stand for right. Universal experience shows that whenever a nation accepts such a doctrine of submission it loses independence and liberty without even gaining peace. The peace it will secure is the peace that declining Rome bought of the barbarians, the peace of fella- heen and Bengalees. Even in personal matters it is difficult to say what will be the result of action based on mere expediency; in the larger and more intricate scale of national affairs it is impossible. This is why, as contended by Mr. Spencer in “Social Statics " the course of true wisdom in social affairs is to follow the dictate COMPENSATION. 279 of principle — to ask, not what seems to be expedient, but what is right. If a law or institution is wrong, if its continuance involves the continuance of injustice, there is but one wise thing to do, as there is but one right thing, and that is to abolish it. To come back to the main question : All pleas for compensation on the abolition of unequal rights to land are excuses for avoiding right and continuing wrong; they all, as fully as the origi- nal wrong, deny that equalness which is the essential of justice. Where they have seemed plausible to any homestly-minded man, he will, if he really examines his thought, see that this has been so because he has, though perhaps unconsciously, entertained asympathy for those who seem to profit by injustice which he has refused to those who have been injured by it. He has been thinking of the few whose incomes would be cut off by the restoration of equal right. He has forgotten the many, who are being impoverished, degraded, and driven out of life by its denial. If he once breaks through the tyranny of accustomed ideas and truly realizes that all men are equally en- titled to the use of the natural opportunities for the living of their lives and the development of their powers, he will see the injustice, the wickedness, of demanding compensation for the abolition of the monopoly of land. He will see that if any one is to be compensated on the abolition of a wrong, it is those who have suffered by the Wrong, not those who have profited by it. Private property in land — the subjecting of land to that exclusive ownership which rightfully attaches to the products of labor — is a denial of the true 280 RECANTATION. right of property, which gives to each the equal right to exert his labor and the exclusive right to its re- sults. It differs from slavery only in its form, which is that of making property of the indispensable nat- ural factor of production, while slavery makes prop- erty of the human factor; and it has the same purpose and effect, that of compelling some men to work for others. Its abolition therefore does not mean the destruction of any right but the cessation of a wrong —that for the future the municipal law shall conform to the moral law, and that each shall have his own. I have gone over this question of compensation — this “last ditch '' of the advocates of landlordism —because it is so persistently raised, not that it arises in anything I have advocated. We who propose that natural and therefore easy method of restoring their equal rights to men, which for the purpose of clearly differentiating it from all schemes of land nationali- zation we call the single tax, do not propose to take from land-owners anything they now have. We pro- pose to leave to land-owners whatever they actually have, even though it be in their hands the fruits of injustice; we propose not even to change the forms of land tenure, and greatly to simplify instead of enlarging the machinery and functions of the state. We propose, in short, only so to change present meth- ods of raising public revenues that they shall conform to the requirements of the right of property, taking for the use of the state that which rightfully belongs to the state, leaving to individuals that which right- fully belongs to the individual. But that clumsy mode of abolishing private prop- erty in land which is properly called land nationali- COMPENSATION. 281 zation requires the taking of rightful property in the improvements that have been annexed to land. In this it calls for compensation in a way that confusion of thought may carry to the ownership of land itself. And even the taking of land it proposes would be in form a taking of property. The land would have to be formally appropriated by the state and then rented out. Now we are accustomed to the compensation of owners when particular portions of land are taken for the use of the state, and this indeed as I have before pointed out is rightful, so that it is easy for the superficial to think that when the state shall take all the land for the purpose of renting it out again it should compensate all owners. Thus the scheme of land nationalization gives to the idea of compensation a plausibility that does not properly belong to it. This is the reason why in England, where there has been a good deal of talk of land nationalization, the notion of compensation is strong among certain classes, while in America, where the movement for the recognition of equal rights to the use of land has gone from the beginning on the lines of the single tax, there is almost nothing of it, except as a reflec- tion of English thought. And this is the reason why, although even in England the advocates of land nationalization are few and weak as compared with the great body that is advancing on the unjust privi- leges of landlords by the way of taxation, the English advocates of landlordism always endeavor to discuss the land question as though the actual taking of land by the state were the only thing proposed. It will be observed for instance that Mr. Spencer, in “Jus- tice,” never so much as alludes to the proposition to 282 RECANTATION. secure equal rights in land by taking land values, not land. Yet he cannot be so ignorant of what is going on about him as not to know that this is the line which the advance against landlordism is taking and must take. He ignores it because there is on that line no place for proposing or even suggesting com- pensation. Compensation to the ultimate payers of a tax is something unheard of and absurd. The primary error of the advocates of land nation- alization is in their confusion of equal rights with joint rights, and in their consequent failure to realize the nature and meaning of economic rent — errors which I have pointed out in commenting on Mr. Spencer's declarations in “Social Statics.” In truth the right to the use of land is not a joint or common right, but an equal right; the joint or common right is to rent, in the economic sense of the term. There- fore it is not necessary for the state to take land, it is only necessary for it to take rent. This taking by the commonalty of what is of common right, would of itself secure equality in what is of equal right — for since the holding of land could be profitable only to the user, there would be no inducement for any one to hold land that he could not adequately use, and monopolization being ended no one who wanted to use land would have any difficulty in finding it. And it would at the same time secure the individual right, for in taking what is of common right for its revenues the state could abolish all those taxes which now take from the individual what is of individual right. The truth is that customs taxes, and improvement taxes, and income taxes, and taxes on business and occupations and on legacies and successions, are mor- COMPENSATION. 283 ally and economically no better than highway robbery or burglary, all the more disastrous and demoralizing because practised by the state. There is no necessity for them. The seeming necessity arises only from the failure of the state to take its own natural and adequate source of revenue — a failure which entails a long train of evils of another kind by stimulating a forestalling and monopolization of land which creates an artificial scarcity of the primary element of life and labor, so that in the midst of illimitable natural re- sources the opportunity to work has come to be looked on as a boon, and in spite of the most enor- mous increase in the powers of production the great mass find life a hard struggle to maintain life, and millions die before their time, of over-strain and under-nurture. When the matter is looked on in this way, the idea of compensation — the idea that justice demands that those who have engrossed the natural revenue of the state must be paid the capitalized value of all future engrossment before the state can resume those rev- enues—is too preposterous for serious statement. And while in the nature of things any change from wrong-doing to right-doing must entail loss upon those who profit by the wrong-doing, and this can no more be prevented than can parallel lines be made to meet; yet it must also be remembered that in the nature of things the loss is merely relative, the gain absolute. Whoever will examine the subject will see that in the abandonment of the present unnatural and unjust method of raising public revenues and the adoption of the matural and just method even those who rela- tively lose will be enormous gainers. CHAPTER XII. “JUSTICE’” — “THE LAND QUESTION.” WHILE “Justice ’’ shows no decadence of intellect- ual power, and those who have seen the utterances of a great thinker in preceding volumes of the Synthetic Philosophy will doubtless have as high an opinion of this, there is in it everywhere, as compared with “Social Statics,” the evidence of moral decadence, and of that perplexity which is the penalty of delib- erate sacrifice of intellectual honesty. But it were wearying, and for our purpose needless, to review the subsequent chapters of “Justice,” and to show the con- tradictions and confusions into which Mr. Spencer falls at every turn,' and the manner in which he re- cants his previously expressed opinions on such sub- jects as the political rights of women, and even the equal political rights of men. To complete the ex- amination of that cross-section of his teachings which in the beginning I proposed, let us proceed to the 1 One of these may be worth quoting as particularly interesting in view of what has gone before and what is yet to come. In Chapter XVI., “The Right of Gift and Bequest,” pp. 122–124, Mr. Spencer says : - Few will deny that the earth’s surface and the things on it should be owned in full by the generation at any time existing. Hence the right of property may not equitably be so interpreted as to allow any generation to tell subsequent generations for what purpose or under what conditions they are to use the earth’s sur- face or the things on it. . . . One who holds land subject to that supreme ownership of the community which both ethics and law assert, cannot rightly have such power of willing the application of it as involves permanent alienation from the community. “JUSTICE’” – “THE LAND QUESTION.” 285 consideration of his very last word on the land ques- tion, the note to which he refers the reader at the close of the chapter on “The Rights to the Uses of Natural Media.” This note is to be found among the appendices to “Justice,” which consist of Appendix A, “The Kant- ian Idea of Rights,” before referred to (page 173); Appendix B, “The Land Question; ” Appendix C, “The Moral Motive,” a reply to a criticism by the Rev. J. Llewelyn Davis; and Appendix D, “Con- science in Animals,” which is a collection of dog stories. The idea that for the genesis of all there is in man, even his moral perceptions, we must look down, not up, permeates the Synthetic Philosophy, seeking to obliterate the gulf between man and other animals by greedily swallowing every traveller's tale that tends to degrade man and every wonder-monger's story that ascribes human faculties to brutes. Thus “Justice ’’ begins with “Animal Ethics” and ends with dog sto- ries, the appendix devoted to them being twice as large as that devoted to “The Land Question” and illustrated with diagrams." 1 The dog stories which close this crowning book of the Syn- thetic Philosophy are sent to Mr. Spencer by Mr. T. Mann Jones, of Devon, with this introduction : DEAR SIR: The following careful observations on animals other than man, may be of interest to you as supporting your idea that the idea of “duty '' or “ought '' (owe it) may be of non “super- natural” origin. “Supernatural ” is used in the usual sense, without committing the writer to any opinion. These “careful observations” are indorsed by Mr. Spencer as highly remarkable and instructive, and as supporting his own con- clusion, and he tells us, apparently on the faith of them, that Mr. Jones is a careful, critical and trustworthy observer. To give a 286 RECANTATION. These dog stories are, however, fit companions to the savage stories with which, by the assistance of a corps of readers, the volumes of the Synthetic Phi- losophy are profusely embellished. The wooden lit- eralness with which, to suit himself, Mr. Spencer interprets the imagery and metaphor of which the language of all peoples who come close to nature is full, is perhaps the most comical thing in this un- consciously comic collection. I hesitate to give an instance, such is the embarrassment of riches; but here, to quote at random, is one. It is from the chapter on “The Religious Idea” in “Principles of Sociology.” Mr. Spencer has been showing to his own satisfaction, and doubtless to that of the gentle- men who regard him as greater than Aristotle, how from the adoption of such family names as Wolf, and the habit of speaking of a strong man as “a bear,” the less civilized peoples, whom he generically lumps as “savages,” have come to believe that their ances- tors passed into animals. He goes on to show “how naturally the identification of stars with persons may occur.” Recalling first, what he declares to be “the belief of some North Americans that the brighter stars in the Milky Way are camp-fires made by the dead on their way to the other world,” this is the fashion in which he does it: sample, here is one of the observations, which as it has no dia- grams, I may quote as printed: The “ought” may be established as an obligation to a higher mind in opposition to the promptings of the strongest feelings of the animal; e.g. — A bitch I had many years ago showed great pleasure at the attentions of male dogs, when in season. I checked her repeat- edly, by voice only. This set up the “ought '' so thoroughly, that though never tied up at such times, she died a virgin at thirteen and a half years old. “JUSTICE *— “THE LAND QUESTION.” 287 When a sportsman, hearing a shot in the adjacent wood, exclaims, “That's Jones 1’’ he is not supposed to mean that Jones is the sound ; he is known to mean that Jones made the sound. But when a Savage, pointing to a particular star originally thought of as the camp-fire of such or such a departed man, says, “There he is,” the children he is instructing naturally suppose him to mean that the star itself is the departed man; especially when receiving the statement through an undeveloped language. — Principles of Sociology, Vol. II., page 685. “Lo, the poor Indian l’” What would happen to the beliefs of Savage chil- dren if their undeveloped language enabled them to receive such information as is often conveyed through our developed language —such, for instance, as “She’s a daisy l’’ or “He’s a brick l’’ or “You would have to use a pick-axe to get a joke through his head ‘’” But I am keeping the reader from “The Land Question.” This is, for our purpose at least, the most important utterance of what its author deems the most important book of the great Synthetic Evolutionary Philosophy — a book that begins with “Animal Ethics,” and ends with dog stories. I Quote this appendix in full: APPENDIX B.—THE LAND QUESTION. The course of Nature, “red in tooth and claw,” has been, on a higher plane, the course of civilization. Through “blood and iron ’’ small clusters of men have been consolidated into larger ones, and these again into still larger ones, until nations have been formed. This process, carried on every where and always by brute force, has resulted in a history of wrongs upon wrongs: savage tribes have been slowly welded together by savage means. We could not, if we tried, trace back the acts of unscrupulous violence committed during these thou- 288 RECANTATION. sands of years; and could we trace them back we could not rectify their evil results. Land-ownership was established during this process; and if the genesis of land-ownership was full of iniqui- ties, they were iniquities committed not by the ancestors of any one class of existing men but by the ancestors of all existing men. The remote forefathers of living Englishmen were robbers, who stole the lands of men who were themselves robbers, who behaved in like man- ner to the robbers who preceded them. The usurpation by the Normans, here complete and there partial, was of lands which, centuries before, had been seized, some by piratical Danes and Norsemen, and some at an earlier time by hordes of invading Frisians or old English. And then the Celtic owners, expelled or enslaved by these, had in bygone ages themselves expropriated the people who lived in the underground houses here and there still traceable. What would happen if we tried to restore lands inequitably taken — if Normans had to give them back to Danes and Norse and Frisians, and these again to Celts, and these again to the men who lived in caves and used flint implements 2 The only imaginable form of the transaction would be a restor- ation of Great Britain bodily to the Welsh and the Highlanders; and if the Welsh and the Highlanders did not make a kindred restoration, it could only be on the ground that, having not only taken the land of the aborigines but killed them, they had thus justified their ownership ! The wish now expressed by many that land-ownership should be conformed to the requirements of pure equity, is in itself commendable ; and is in some men prompted by conscientious feeling. One would, however, like to hear from such the demand that not only here but in the various regions we are peopling, the requirements of pure equity should be conformed to. As it is, the indig- nation against Wrongful appropriations of land, made in the past at home, is not accompanied by any indignation against the more Wrongful appropriations made at pres- ent abroad. Alike as holders of the predominant polit- ical power and as furnishing the rank and file of our armies, the masses of the people are responsible for those nefarious doings all over the world which end in “JUSTICE *— “THE LAND QUESTION.” 289 the seizing of new territories and expropriation of their inhabitants. The filibustering expeditions of the old English are repeated, on a vastly larger scale, in the filibustering expeditions of the new English. Yet those who execrate ancient usurpations utter no word of pro- test against these far greater modern usurpations — nay, are aiders and abetters in them. Remaining as they do passive and silent while there is going on this universal land-grabbing which their votes could stop; and sup- plying as they do the soldiers who effect it; they are responsible for it. By deputy they are committing in this matter grosser and more numerous injustices than were committed against their forefathers. That the masses of landless men should regard private land-ownership as having been wrongfully established, is natural ; and, as we have seen, they are not without warrant. But if we entertain the thought of rectifica- tion, there arises in the first place the question — which are the wronged and which are the wrongers ? Passing over the primary fact that the ancestors of existing Englishmen, landed and landless, were, as a body, men who took the land by violence from previous owners; and thinking only of the force and fraud by which cer- tain of these ancestors obtained possession of the land while others of them lost possession; the preliminary question is — Which are the descendants of the one and of the other ? It is tacitly assumed that those who now own lands are the posterity of the usurpers, and that those who now have no lands are the posterity of those whose lands were usurped. But this is far from being the case. The fact that among the nobility there are very few whose titles go back to the days when the last usurpations took place, and none to the days when there took place the original usurpations; joined with the fact that among existing land-owners there are many whose names imply artisan-ancestors; show that we have not now to deal with descendants of those who un- justly appropriated the land. While, conversely, the numbers of the landless whose names prove that their forefathers belonged to the higher ranks (numbers which must be doubled to take account of inter-marriages with female descendants) show that among those who are now without land, many inherit the blood of the land-usurp- 290 RECANTATION. ers. Hence, that bitter feeling towards the landed which contemplation of the past generates in many of the landless, is in great measure misplaced. They are them- selves to a considerable extent descendants of the sin- ners; while those they scowl at are to a considerable extent descendants of the sinned-against. But granting all that is said about past iniquities, and leaving aside all other obstacles in the way of an equi- table re-arrangement, there is an obstacle which seems to have been overlooked. Even supposing that the English as a race gained possession of the land equita- bly, which they did not; and even supposing that exist- ing land-owners are the posterity of those who spoiled their fellows, which in large part they are not ; and even supposing that the existing landless are the posterity of the despoiled, which in large part they are not ; there would still have to be recognized a transaction that goes far to prevent rectification of injustices. If we are to go back upon the past at all, we must go back upon the past wholly, and take account not only of that which the people at large have lost by private appropriation of land, but also that which they have received in the form of a share of the returns — we must take account, that is, of Poor-Law relief. Mr. T. Mackay, author of The English Poor, has kindly furnished me with the follow- ing memoranda, showing something like the total amount of this since the 43d Elizabeth (1601) in England and Wales. Sir G. Nicholls (History of Poor Law, appendix to Vol. II.) ventures no estimate till 16SS. At that date he puts the poor rate at nearly £700,000 a year. Till the beginning of this century the amounts are based more or less on estimate. 1601–1630. say 3 millions. 1631–1700. (1688 Nicholls puts at 700,000.) 30 { % 1701–1720. {} Nicholls puts at 900,000.) 20 6 & 1721–1760. 1760 Nicholls says 1 1-4 millions.) 40 64 1761–1775. (1775 put at 1 1-2 million.) 22 6 & 1776–1800. (1784 2 millions.) 50 46 1801–1812. (1803 4 millions; 1813.6 millions.) 65 46 1813–1840. (based on exact figures given by Sir G. Nicholls.) 170 “ 1841–1890. (based on Mulhall's Dict. of Sta- tistics and Statistical Abstract.) 334 64 734 millions. “JUSTICE *— “THE LAND QUESTION.” 291 The above represents the amount earpended in relief of the poor. Under the general term “poor-rate,” moneys have always been collected for other purposes — county, borough, police rates, etc. The following table shows the annual amounts of these in connection with the annual amounts expended on the poor : Total levied. Expended on Other purposes poor. balance. Sir G. In 1803. 5,348,000 4,077,000 1,271,000 2 Nicholis ** 1813. 8,646,841 6,656,106 1,990,735? o “ 1853. 6,522,412 4,939,064 1,583,341 ? Total spent. Sum spent. Statistical | “ 1875. 12,694,208 7,488,481 5,205,727 abstract. “1SS9. 15,970,126 8,366,477 7,603,649 In addition, therefore, to sums set out in the first table, there is a further sum, rising during the century from 13 to 7% millions per annum “for other purposes.” Mulhall, on whom I relied for figures between 1853 and 1875, does not give “other expenditure.” Of course of the £734,000,000 given to the poorer members of the landless class during three centuries, a part has arisen from rates on houses; only such portion of which as is chargeable against ground rents, being rightly included in the sum the land has contributed. From a land-owner, who is at the same time a Queen's Counsel, frequently employed professionally to arbitrate in questions of local taxation, I have received the opinion that if, out of the total sum received by the poor, £500,000,000 is credited to the land, this will be an under-estimate. Thus even if we ignore the fact that this amount, gradually contributed, would, if otherwise gradually invested, have yielded in returns of one or other kind a far larger sum, it is manifest that against the claim of the landless may be set off a large claim of the landed — perhaps a larger claim. For now observe that the landless have not an equitable claim to the land in its present state — cleared, drained, fenced, fertilized, and furnished with farm-buildings, etc. — but only to the land in its primitive state, here stony and there marshy, covered with forest, gorse, heather, etc.; this only, it is, which belongs to the com- 292 RECANTATION. munity. Hence, therefore, the question arises — What is the relation between the original “prairie value " of the land, and the amount which the poorer among the landless have received during these three centuries 2 Probably the land-owners would contend that for the land in its primitive, unsubdued state, furnishing nothing but wild animals and wild fruits, £500,000,000 would be a high price. When, in Social Statics, published in 1850, I drew from the law of equal freedom the corollary that the land could not equitably be alienated from the com- munity, and argued that, after compensating its existing holders, it should be re-appropriated by the community, I overlooked the foregoing considerations. Moreover, I did not clearly see what would be implied by the giving of compensation for all that value which the labor of ages has given to the land. While, as shown in Chapter XI., I adhere to the inference originally drawn, that the aggregate of men forming the community are the Supreme owners of the land — an inference harmonizing with legal doctrine and daily acted upon in legislation — a fuller consideration of the matter has led me to the conclusion that individual ownership, subject to state- suzerainty, should be maintained. Even were it possible to rectify the inequitable doings which have gone on during past thousands of years, and by Some balancing of claims and counter-claims, past and present, to make a re-arrangement equitable in the abstract, the resulting state of things would be a less desirable one than the present. Setting aside all finan- cial objections to nationalization (which of themselves negative the transaction, since, if equitably effected, it would be a losing one), it suffices to remember the in- feriority of public administration to private administra- tion, to see that ownership by the state would work ill. Under the existing system of ownership, those who manage the land, experience a direct connection between effort and benefit ; while, were it under state-ownership, those who managed it would experience no such direct connection. The vices of officialism would inevitably entail immense evils. “JUSTICE *— “THE LAND QUESTION.” 293 Was ever philosopher so perplexed before ? Mr. Spencer started out in 1850 to tell us what are our rights to land. And, excepting that he fell into some confusion by carelessly transforming equal rights into joint rights, he clearly did so. But now, in 1892, and in the climax of the Spencerian Syn- thetic Philosophy, he has got himself into a maze, in which the living and the dead — Normans, Danes, Norsemen, Frisians, Celts, Saxons, Welsh, and High- landers; old English and new English; plebeians, with aristocratic names, and aristocrats with plebeian names, and female descendants who have changed their names; ancient filibusters and modern filibus- ters — are all so whirling round that, in sheer despair, he springs for guidance to “a land-owner who is at the same time a Queen's counsel,” and is led by him plump into the English poor law and a long array of figures. Yet, in the mad whirl he still pretends to consist- ency. “I adhere,” he says, “to the inference origi- nally drawn, that the aggregate of men forming the community are the supreme owners of the land.” Here is that inference in his own words — the in- ference originally drawn in “Social Statics: ” Given a race of beings having like claims to pursue the objects of their desires, given a world adapted to the gratification of those desires — a world into which such beings are similarly born, and it unavoidably fol- lows that they have equal rights to the use of this world. . . . Equity therefore does not permit private property in land. . . . The right of mankind at large to the earth’s surface is still valid; all deeds, customs, and laws not- withstanding. What is it that Mr. Spencer here asserts? Not that men derive their rights to the use of the earth 294 REC ANTATION. by gift, bequest or inheritance, from their ancestors, or from any previous men, but that they derive them from the fact of their own existence. Who lived on the earth before them, or what such predecessors did, has nothing whatever to do with the matter. The equal right to the use of land belongs to each man as man. It begins with his birth; it continues till his death. It can be destroyed or superseded by no human action whatever. And this is the ground on which, without excep- tion, stand all who demand the resumption of equal rights to land. Where there has been any reference on their part to the wrongfulness of past appropria- tions of land, it has merely been —as in the case of Mr. Spencer himself in “Social Statics” — by way of illustrating the origin of private property in land, not by way of basing the demand for the rights of living men on the proof of wrongs done to dead men.” Neither Mr. Spencer in his “straight" days, nor any one else who has stood for equal rights in land, ever dreamed of such a stultifying proposition as that the right to the use of land must be drawn from some 1 I, for instance, have uniformly asserted that it made no differ- ence whatever whether land has been made private property by force or by consent; that the equal right to its use is a natural and inalienable right of the living, and that this is the ground, and the only ground, on which the resumption of those rights should be demanded. Thus in “The Irish Land Question,” in 1881, I said: The indictment which really lies against the Irish landlords is not that their ancestors or the ancestors of their grantors robbed the ancestors of the Irish people. That makes no difference. “I let the dead bury their dead.” The indictment that truly lies is, that here and now, they rob the Irish people. . . . The great- est enemy of the people’s cause is he who appeals to national passions and excites old hatreds. He is its best friend who does his utinost to bury them out of sight. “JUSTICE *— “THE LAND QUESTION.” 295 dispossessed generation, for this would be to assert what he so ridiculed, that “God has given one charter of privilege to one generation and another to the next.” Yet, now, this same Herbert Spencer actually as- sumes that the only question of moral right as to land is, who robbed whom, in days whereof the very memory has perished, and when, according to him, everybody was engaged in robbing everybody else. He not only eats his own words, denies his own per- ceptions, and endeavors to confuse the truth he once bore witness to, but he assumes that the whole great movement for the recognition of equal rights to land, that is beginning to show its force wherever the English tongue is spoken, has for its object only recti- fication of past injustices — the ridiculous search, in which he pretends to engage, as to what ancestor robbed what ancestor — and that until that is discov- ered, those who now hold as their private property the inalienable heritage of all may hold it still. And in the course of this “argument,” this advocate of the rich against the poor, of the strong against the weak, declares that the toiling masses of England, made ignorant and brutal and powerless by their dis- inheritance, have lost their natural rights by serving as food for powder and payers of taxes in foreign wars waged by the ruling classes. This is bad enough; but more follows. Mr. Spencer discovers a new meaning in the English poor laws. In “Social Statics,” be it remembered, he declared that the equal right to the use of land is the natural, direct, inalienable right of all men, having its derivation in the fact of their existence, and 296 IRECANTATION. of which they can in no possible way be equi- tably deprived. He declared that equity does not permit private property in land, and that it is impossible to discover any mode by which land can become private property. He scouted the idea that force can give right, or that sale or bequest or prescription can make invalid claims valid; saying that, “though nothing be multiplied forever, it will not produce one'; asking, “How long does it take for what was originally wrong to grow into a right? and at what rate per annum do invalid claims become valid 2 ” He declared that neither use nor im- provement, nor even the free consent of all existing men, could give private ownership in land, or bar the equal right of the next child born. And he, more- over, proved that land nationalization, which he then proposed as the only equitable treatment of land, did not involve state administration. Not one of the arguments of “Social Statics " is answered in “Justice ’” — not even the showing that land nationalization merely involves a change in the receivers of rent, and not the governmental occupa- tion and use of land. There are two things, and two things only, that Mr. Spencer admits that he over- looked—the relation of the poor law to the claims of land-owners, and the amount of compensation which the landless must give to the landed “for all that value which the labor of ages has given to the land.” Mr. Spencer has discussed the poor law before. One of the longest of the chapters of “Social Statics,” from which I have already quoted," is de- voted to it; and in recent writings he has again 1 pp. 89–90. “JUSTICE *— “THE LAND QUESTION.” 297 referred to it. In “Social Statics” he declares that the excuse made for a poor law — that it is a com- pensation to the disinherited for the deprivation of their birthright — has much plausibility; but he objects, not only that the true remedy is to restore equal rights to land, but that the poor law does not give compensation, insisting that poor rates are in the main paid by non-landowners, and that it is only here and there that one of those kept out of their inheritance gets any part of them. In 1884, in “The Coming Slavery,” he repeats the assertion that non-landowners get no benefit from the poor law, saying — The amount which under the old poor law the half- pauperized laborer received from the parish to eke out his weekly income was not really, as it appeared, a bonus, for it was accompanied by a substantially equiv- alent decrease of his wages, as was quickly proved when the system was abolished and the wages rose. In “The Sins of Legislators,” he repeats that instead of being paid by land-owners, the poor rates really fall on non-land owners, saying — As, under the old poor law, the diligent and provi- dent laborer had to pay that the good-for-nothings might not suffer, until frequently, under this extra burden, he broke down and himself took refuge in the workhouse — as, at present, it is admitted that the total rates levied in large towns for all public purposes, have now reached such a height that they “cannot be exceeded without inflicting great hardship on the small shopkeepers and artisans, who already find it difficult enough to keep themselves free from pauper taint.” But in Appendix B Mr. Spencer ignores all this. He assumes that land-owners have been the real 298 RECANTATION. payers and the disinherited the real receivers of the poor rates; and, adding together all that the land- owners have paid in poor rates since the time of Queen Elizabeth, he puts the whole sum to their credit in a ledger account between existing landlords and existing landless. He begins this account at 1601. He credits the landlords and charges the landless with all that has been collected from land for poor rates between 1601 and 1890. Now, if this is done, what is to be put on the other side of the ledger? We must take the same date, the ordinary book-keeper would say, and charge the landlords and credit the landless with all the ground rents the land-owners have received from 1601 to 1890. To this we must add all that the land-owners have received from the produce of gen- eral taxes between 1601 and 1890, by virtue of their political power as landlords." And to this we must again add the selling value in 1890 of the land of England, exclusive of improvements. The difference will show what, if we are to go back to 1601, and no farther, existing landlords now owe to existing land- less. This would be the way of ordinary, every-day book-keeping if it were undertaken to make up such a debtor and creditor account from 1601 to 1890. But this is not the way of Spencerian synthetic book- keeping. What Mr. Spencer does, after crediting 1 The Financial Reform. Almanac has given some idea of what enormous sums the British land-owners have received from the offices, pensions and sinecures they have secured for themselves, and from their habit of providing for younger sons and poorer relatives in the army, navy, church, and civil administration. “JUSTICE *— “THE LAND QUESTION.” 299 landlords and charging the landless with the amount collected from land for poor rates between 1601 and 1890, is, omitting all reference to mesne profits, to credit the landless and charge the landlords with the value of the land of England, not as it is, but “in its primitive, unsubdued state, furnishing nothing but wild animals and wild fruits " — that is, before there were any men. This — though by what sort of synthetic calculus he gets at it he does not tell us — Mr. Spencer estimates at £500,000,000, a sum that will about square the account, with some little balance on the side of the landlords ! Generous to the poor landless is Mr. Accountant Spencer' — so generous that he ought to make a note of it in writing Part VI. of his “Principles of Ethics " — “The Ethics of Social Life : Positive Beneficence.” For is it not positive beneficence to those who are to be credited with it to say that £500,000,000 would be a high estimate of the value of England when there was nothing there but wild animals and wild fruit? To one of less wide mag- nificence two and threepence would seem to be rather more than a high estimate of the value of the land of England before man came. CHAPTER XIII. PRINCIPAL BROWN. REALLY, this final close of the most important dis- cussion of the most important book of the most important grand division of the great Spencerian Synthetic Philosophy can only be fitly treated by calling on the imagination for an illustration: Mr. J. D. Brown, for some time before our civil war a prominent citizen of Vicksburg, Mississippi, was a native of Connecticut, of Puritan stock and thrifty habits. Beginning life as a clock-maker, he emigrated when a young man to that part of Ohio, settled from New England, which is still in those regions known as the Western Reserve. There he went to school-teaching, joined a local literary society, and made some speeches which were highly applauded, and in which he did not hesitate to de- nounce slavery as the sum of all villanies, and to declare for immediate, unconditional emancipation. Somewhat later on, he went South and settled at Vicksburg, where he became professor of moral philos- ophy in a young ladies’ seminary, and, finally, its principal. Being prudent in speaking of the peculiar institution, and gaining a reputation for profundity, he became popular in the best society, a favorite guest in the lavish hospitalities of the wealthier planters, and, in the Southern manner, was always PRINCIPAL BROWN. 301 spoken of to visitors with pride as “Principal Brown, one of our most distinguished men, sir! — a great educator, and a great authority on moral philoso- phy, sir!” The slavery question was in the mean time grow- ing hotter and hotter. There were no abolitionists in Vicksburg or in the country about, for any one suspected of abolitionism was promptly lynched, or sent North in a coat of tar and feathers. But slaves were occasionally disappearing, among them some of especial value as mechanics; and even a very valuable yellow girl, whose beauty and accomplishments were such that her owner had refused $5,000 for her, had been spirited off by the underground railroad. And “society'' in Vicksburg was becoming more and more excited. Though no one yet dreamed that it was destined ere long to redden the Mississippi, and light the skies of Vicksburg with bursting bombs, the cloud on the northern horizon was visibly swelling and darkening, and in “bleeding Kansas" a guerrilla war had already crimsoned the grass. Still, the lines of Principal Brown were cast in pleasant places, and he received the honors due to a great philosopher, deemed all the greater by those who in their secret hearts did not find his moral philosophy quite intelligible ; for he not only made a practice of using the longest words and of interlard- ing his discourses with references to people of whom his auditors had never heard, and of whom he could say anything he pleased, but he had taken Balzac's hint, and every now and again he strung together a series of words that sounded as though they might mean something, but really had no meaning at all. 302 RECANTATION. He had thus gained a reputation for great profundity with those who vainly puzzled over them, and who attributed their difficulty to an ignorance they were ashamed to admit. But one woful day there came to Vicksburg some echo of one of his debating-club speeches in the Western Reserve, and some of the leading citizens deemed fit to interrogate him. He had to lie a little, but succeeded in quieting them ; and as not much was said about the matter, his standing in Vicksburg society was, in general, unchanged. Following this, however, something worse hap- pened. The Rev. Dr. Sorely, one of the most elo- quent divines of the Methodist Church South, made a trip to Ohio, and in the Western Reserve delivered a lecture on the biblical and patriarchal system of labor as practised by our Southern brethren. Among the auditors was a man who remembered and quoted some of the eloquent utterances, on the other side, of the reverend doctor's friend, Principal Brown. The matter might have passed unheeded, but that the Vicksburg Thunderbolt, anticipating much glory to the South from the Northern visit of its eloquent defender, had sent a special correspondent with him; and a report of the lecture, including the reference to Principal Brown, duly appeared in its columns. This was indeed a serious matter, and the Princi- pal wrote immediately to the Thunderbolt with feel- ing and vehemence. He said that he feared that if he remained silent many would think he had said things he had not said ; intimated that he had never been in Ohio, and what he had said when he was there he had said for the purpose of finding a PRINCIPAL BIROWN. 303 secure basis for slavery ; that he had only been talk- ing of transcendental ethics, and not of sublunary ethics at all; that he had always insisted that the slave-owners of the South should be paid in full for their slaves; that he had never supposed that the question would come up for millions of years yet; and that the most he had said was that, “It may be doubted, if it does not possibly seem inferable, that perhaps there may be reason to suspect that at some future time the slaves may be liberated, after paying to their owners more than they are worth ; but I have no positive opinion as to what may hereafter take place, and am only sure that, if emancipation ever does take place, the negroes must pay to their owners far more in interest on their purchase money than they now pay in work.” To most of the citizens of Vicksburg this seemed entirely satisfactory, but there were some dissen- tients. Colonel F. E. Green strongly urged patriotic citizens not to think of such a thing as treating the Principal to a coat of tar and feathers, and Professor Bullhead, of the leading young men's seminary, wrote to the Thunderbolt, requesting his respected colleague to give a categorical answer to the ques- tion “whether, when A B went to the slave pen and bought a negro, the negro was or was not his prop- erty, morally as well as legally.” If yes, then Pro- fessor Bullhead wanted to know what his learned and respected friend meant by admitting the possibility of emancipation even some millions of years hence; and if no, then Professor Bullhead wanted Principal Brown to tell him why the slaves, before regaining their freedom, must pay their owners more than they 304 RECANTATION. were worth. And Professor Bullhead closed with Some sarcastic references to transcendental ethics. Principal Brown did not answer this plain ques- tion of his friend Professor Bullhead, but got rid of him as quickly as he could, telling him that there was no dispute between them, since they both insisted on the right of any citizen to work and whip his own negro, and then luring him off into a long discus- sion of transcendental ethics vs. sublunary ethics. But it was evident that something more had to be done, and the papers soon contained an announce- ment that Principal Brown proposed to forego for a time the publication of Volumes XXIV. and XXV. of his great work on Moral Philosophy, and imme- diately to bring out Volume XXVI., containing a chapter on the slavery question, which he proposed to read to the citizens of Vicksburg at a public meeting. The lecture drew a large audience of the first citi- zens of Vicksburg. There was also a sprinkling of rougher citizens, some of whom before entering the hall deposited in a rear lot a long rail that they had brought with them, and some pails that smelled like tar, with a number of large but evidently light sacks. However, the lecture was a great success, and at the close, Principal Brown's hand was nearly shaken off, and he was escorted to his home by an enthusiastic and cheering crowd, who vowed that nothing like such a “demolisher to the nigger-lovers” had ever been heard in Vicksburg before. But although the stately periods of the Principal are occasionally marred by what is evidently a repor- torial tendency to the slang of the time, let me quote PRINCIPAL BROWN. 305 from the papers of the next day, which contained long reports of the speech, accompanied with glow- ing encomiums: — [From the Vicksburg Thunderbolt, June 19, 1859.] The wealth and beauty and fashion of Vicksburg turned out in full force last evening to listen to a lec- ture on the slavery question by our distinguished townsman, Principal J. D. Brown, the widely hon- ored writer on moral philosophy. In the audience our reporter counted thirty-seven colonels, two majors, and thirty-two judges, besides the pastors of all the leading churches. It is a great pity, as many of the enthusiastic hearers said, while congratulating Prin- cipal Brown and each other at the conclusion, that William Lloyd Garrison and Wendell Phillips them- selves could not have been there; for if their miser- able nigger-loving hides could be penetrated by the solid blocks of learning, the unanswerable logic, and the mathematical demonstrations which Principal Brown poured into his audience, they would have sung exceedingly small; even if they had not seen the full wickedness of their efforts to rob the widow and the orphan by interfering with our beneficent domestic institution. Much of Principal Brown's lecture it will be impos- sible to give to our readers this morning, for our re- porter, not being well versed in Moral Philosophy, finds himself unable from his notes to make sense of some of the more profound passages, and is uncertain as to how some of the authorities cited spell their names. There was some confusion, too, in the hall when Principal Brown touched on the subject of transcendental ethics, and said that he had always held, and always would hold, that, in transcendental ethics all men were pretty much alike. But Colonel Johnson rose in his place and stilled the disturbance, asking the audience to keep their coats on till the 306 RECANTATION. Principal got through ; and when Principal Brown explained that transcendental ethics related to the other side of the moon, while sublunary ethics related to this side of the moon, there was silence again. It was in the wind-up, however, that the professor got in his best work, and roused his audience to the high- est pitch of delight and enthusiasm. He said: — There are people who contend that these negro slaves of the South, after they have paid their owners in full the compensation due them, ought to be put back in their native land. But how are we to find who brought them here ? Some were brought in Spanish vessels, some in Portuguese vessels, some in Dutch, Some in English, and some in American vessels; and these vessels are all by this time sunk or destroyed, and their owners and crews are dead, and their descendants have got mixed. Besides, they only got the negroes from the barracoons on the African coast. Who is to tell where the ancestor of each one was taken from and who took him to the coast 2 Many of these slaves bear such names as Brown, Smith, Jones, and Simpson, names borne by the very men who brought their progenitors here. Then they have such given names as Caesar, Han- nibal, Dick, Tom, Harry, Ephraim, Alexander, and Nebuchadnezzar, so that no one can tell from their names whether they originally came from Africa or England, Italy, Jerusalem, Greece, or Assyria. And what have these negroes ever done for freedom ? Did any one ever hear of them expressing any sympathy for the independence of Greece, or protesting against the Rus- sian invasion of Hungary, or even contributing for the conversion of the Jews, or for sending missionaries to the South Sea Islands, where only man is vile 2 Con- trariwise, when British tyranny invaded our shores did not these negroes work just as readily for the hirelings of King George as they did for their own patriotic mas- ters who were fighting the battles of liberty ? And to-day when a nigger runs away, where does he head for ? Does he not make a straight streak for Canada, a country groaning under the government of an effete monarchy, and with a full-fledged aristocrat for governor- PRINCIPAL. BROWN. 307 general 2 One would like to know that these negro slaves, whom it is proposed to send back to their native land when they have compensated their owners, have some real love for free institutions, before thrusting freedom upon them. To think that slavery was wrongly established is natural, and not without warrant in transcendental ethics. But if we entertain the thought of rectification, there arises in the first place the question — who enslaved them 2 Their owners did not. They only bought them. These negroes were enslaved by negroes like themselves, — likely enough by their own mothers, cousins, and aunts. Now which are the descendants of the one and which of the other ? and where are they to be found 2 But sup- posing that they could be found, there would still have to be recognized a transaction which goes far to prevent rectification. If we are to go back upon the past at all, we must go back upon the past wholly, and take account of what it has cost to feed and clothe and keep these negroes since they have been here. I have consulted one of our most eminent negro traders, a gentleman who has probably bought and sold more negroes than any one in the Southwest, and after a close calculation, he informs me that taking men, women, and children together, and considering the loss of their labor which their owners have to suffer in the rearing of children, sickness, and old age, and the cost of overseers, drivers, patrols, and an occasional pack of bloodhounds, the average negro costs the average owner a fraction over $267,57 per annum. But as I wish to be generous to the negro I have thrown off the 57 cents and a fraction, and will put their cost to their masters at only $267 a year. .. Now, the first cargo of negro slaves was landed in Jamestown, Virginia, in the year 1620, and the external slave trade was abolished in 1808. We may therefore as- Sume the average time during which each negro has been in this country as one hundred and fifty years. Saying nothing whatever about interest, it is thus clear that each living negro owes to his owner, as the cost of keep- ing him, $267 a year for one hundred and fifty years, which, excluding interest, amounts at the present time to just $40,050. (Great applause.) 308 REC ANTATION. Here a man in a back seat rose, and in a decidedly Yankee accent asked Principal Brown if he included negro babies? The Principal replying in the affirma- tive, the intruder began : “How can a negro baby just born owe any one forty thou’” — The rest of the sentence was lost by the sudden exit of the intruder from the hall, over the heads of the audience. There was quite an excitement for a few moments, but Colonel Johnson again rose and restored order by asking the young men in the rear not to escort the interrupter further than the vacant lot adjoining until the close of the proceedings, as the audience were intent on enjoying the remainder of the logical feast which their distinguished townsman was laying be- fore them. All being quiet again, Principal Brown resumed : Observe that the negroes have not an equitable claim to themselves in their present condition — washed, clothed and fed, civilized, Christianized and taught how to work — but only to themselves in their primitive wild and uncivilized condition. Now, what is the relation be- tween the original “wild nigger " value of each slave and what each one of them has received from his owner during one hundred and fifty years ? We know that they were bought at the barracoons, delivered on board ship at prices ranging from a half-pound of beads to a bottle of rum or a Manchester musket, the owners being at the cost of transporting them to America, including the heavy insurance caused by the necessarily great mortality, items which as you will observe I have not charged against the existing slaves. My friend the slave merchant estimates that on an average 15s. 9d. English money would be a high rate. Let us call it, however, $4 American money. Thus we see that an equitable rectifi- cation would require that each negro in the South should pay his owner a balance of $40,046 (Loud and long- continued applause.) Now, when in the Western Reserve many years ago, I drew from transcendental ethics the corollary that the ownership of a man could not be equitably alienated PRINCIPAL I3 IROWN. 309 from the man himself, and argued that after the slaves had compensated their owners they should be freed, I had overlooked the foregoing considerations. Moreover, I did not clearly see what would be implied by the giving of compensation for all that during these one hundred and fifty years it has cost the owner to keep the slave. While, therefore, I adhere to the inference originally drawn — that is to say, as far as transcendental ethics is concerned — a fuller consideration of the matter has led me to the conclusion that slavery, subject to the right of the slave to buy himself on payment to his owner of what he has cost, say $40,046, should be main- tained. But it may be readily seen that such a transac- tion would be a losing one to the slaves themselves, for at the present market price of negroes, they are not worth, big and little, more than $1,000 each. And, whereas I have also said that I really did not know but that in the course of some millions of years it might possibly be that the slaves could be allowed their freedom on paying to their owners full compensation, I now see, since what is due from them to their masters is con- stantly increasing, that with humanity as it now is, the implied reorganization would become more and more unprofitable. (Still louder and longer applause, led by Professor Bullhead, who called for three times three cheers, which were given with a will, the audience rising and the ladies waving their handkerchiefs.) I also wish to point out that all this talk about giving their freedom to the slaves is as foolish as it is wicked. Since under our laws the slave himself is the property of the master, the slaves already have their freedom in the freedom of the master. Thus the equal freedom of each to do all that he wills, provided that he in- terferes not with the equal freedom of all others, as taught by transcendental ethics, is already recognized by the laws of the South, and nothing more remains for us to do, except to keep abolitionist theories from Spreading in this “land of the free and home of the bravel ” The uproarious enthusiasm of the audience could no longer be restrained, and, led by Professor Bull- head, who rushed on the stage and embraced Princi- 310 RECANTATION. pal Brown, our best citizens crowded round him. During this time the wretch who had interrupted the Principal was tarred and feathered in an adjoining lot, and ridden on a rail to the levee. Unfortunately all efforts of the police to discover the perpetrators of this reprehensible proceeding have failed. It is generally supposed to have been the work of some negroes who were listening through the open windows and whose feelings were hurt by the slighting insin- uation of the stranger as to the value of colored infants. While thus calling attention to the similarity be- tween Mr. Spencer's philosophic methods and those of Principal Brown, I do not wish to make any personal comparison between the two philosophers. Since he was under fear of tar and feathers, that would be unjust to Principal Brown. CONCLUSION. THE MORAL OF THIS EXAMINATION. I had rather believe all the fables in the legend, and the Talmud, and the Alcoran, than that this universal frame is without a mind. . . . It is true that a little philosophy inclineth man’s mind to atheism, but depth in philoso- phy bringeth men’s Iminds about to religion; for while the mind of man looketh upon second causes scattered it may sometimes rest in them and go no further; but when it beholdeth the chain of them confederate and linked together, it must needs fly to Providence and Deity. — Bacon. CONCLUSION. THE MORAL OF THIS EXAMINATION. I HAVE laid before the reader enough to show what weight is due to Mr. Spencer's recantation of his earlier declarations on the land question. But even his high reputation and great influence would not have led me to make so elaborate an exami- nation, did it relate only to him. My purpose has been more than this. In abandoming his earlier opinions Mr. Spencer has adopted those which have the stamp of the recognized authorities of our time. In seeking for excuses to justify his change he has taken the best he could find ; and the confusions and fallacies and subter- fuges to which he resorts are such as pass for argu- ment with the many men of reputation and ability, who have undertaken to defend the existing system. Examination will show that no better defence of that system has been made or can be made. Taking Mr. Spencer as the foremost representa- tive of those who deny the justice and expediency of recognizing the equal right to land — a pre-eminence given him by his great reputation, his accorded ability, and the fact that he once avowed the opinions he now seeks to discredit — I have set forth his utterances on the land question, from his first book to his last, printing them in full in order to do him the amplest 314 CONCLUSION. justice, and subjecting them to an examination which any one of ordinary ability and information is com- petent to test. I have thus given the best example to be found in the writings of one man, of what may be said for and what may be said against the equal right to land. It is not the example of intellectual prostitution thus disclosed that I would dwell upon. It is the lesson that prompts to intellectual self-reliance. It is not merely the authority of Mr. Spencer as a teacher on social subjects that I would discredit; but the blind reliance upon authority. For on such sub- jects the masses of men cannot safely trust authority. Given a wrong which affects the distribution of wealth and differentiates society into the rich and the poor, and the recognized Organs of opinion and education, since they are dominated by the wealthy class, must necessarily represent the views and wishes of those who profit or imagine they profit by the wrong. - That thought on social questions is so confused and perplexed, that the aspirations of great bodies of men, deeply though vaguely conscious of injustice, are in all civilized countries being diverted to futile and dangerous remedies, is largely due to the fact that those who assume and are credited with superior knowledge of social and economic laws have devoted their powers, not to showing where the injustice lies but to hiding it; not to clearing common thought but to confusing it. - It is idle to quarrel with this fact, for it is of the nature of things, and is shown in the history of every great movement against Social Wrong, from that THE MORAL OF THIS EXAMINATION. 315 which startled the House of Have in the Roman world by its proclamation of the equal fatherhood of God and the equal brotherhood of men, to that which in our own time broke the shackles of the chattel slave. But it is well to recognize it, that those who would know the truth on social and economic subjects may not blindly accept what at the time passes for authority, but may think for themselves. It is not, however, in regard to social problems only that I trust this examination may do something to enforce the need of intellectual self-reliance. It is in regard to those larger and deeper problems of man's nature and destiny which are, it seems to me, closely related to social questions. Stepping out of their proper sphere and arrogating to themselves an authority to which they have no claim, professed teachers of spiritual truths long pre- sumed to deny the truths of the natural sciences. But now professed teachers of the natural sciences, stepping in turn out of their proper sphere and arro- gating to themselves an authority to which they have no claim, presume to deny spiritual truths. And there are many, who having discarded an authority often perverted by the influence of dominant wrong, have in its place accepted another authority which in its blank materialism affords as efficient a means for stilling conscience and defending selfish greed as any perversion of religious truth. Mr. Spencer is the foremost representative of this authority. Widely regarded as the scientific philoso- pher; eulogized by his admirers as the greatest of all 316 CONCLUSION. philosophers—as the man who has cleared and illumi- nated the field of philosophy by bringing into it the exact methods of science — he carries to the common mind the weight of the marvellous scientific achieve- ments of our time as applied to the most moment- ous of problems. The effect is to impress it with a vague belief that modern science has proved the idea of God to be an ignorant superstition and the hope of a future life a vain delusion. Now, the great respect which in our day has attached to professed scientific teachers, and which has in large degree given to them the same influence that once attached to the teachers of religion, arises from the belief in the truthfulness of science —from the belief that in the pure, clear atmosphere in which its votaries are supposed to dwell they are exempt from temptations to pervert and distort. And this has been largely attributed to them where they have passed the boundaries of what is properly the domain of the natural sciences and assumed the teaching of politics and religion. It is his reputation as an hon- est, fearless thinker, bent only on discovering and proclaiming the truth, a reputation which he derives from his reputation as a scientific philosopher, that gives to Mr. Spencer the powerful influence which, having been exerted to deny all hope of a world to come, is now exerted to deny the right of the masses to the essentials of life in this world — to maintain the wrong, wider than that of chattel slavery, which condemns so many not merely to physical, but to mental and moral privation and want, to undeveloped and distorted lives and to untimely death. While the examination we have made has only THE MORAL OF THIS EXAMINATION. 317 incidentally touched the larger phases of Mr. Spencer's philosophy, it has afforded an opportunity to judge of the very things on which his popular reputation is based — his intellectual honesty and his capacity for careful, logical reasoning. It has, so to speak, brought the alleged philosopher out of what to the ordinary man is a jungle of sounding phrases and big words, and placed him on open ground where he may be easily understood and measured. In his first book, written when he believed in God, in a divine order, in a moral sense, and which he has now emasculated, he does appear as an honest and fearless, though some- what too careless a thinker. But that part of our examination which crosses what is now his distinct- ive philosophy shows him to be, as a philosopher ridiculous, as a man contemptible — a fawning Vicar of Bray, clothing in pompous phraseology and arro- gant assumption logical confusions so absurd as to be comical. If the result be to shatter an idol, I trust it may also be to promote freedom of thought. As there are many to whom the beauty and har- mony of economic laws are hidden, and to whom the inspiring thought of a social order in which there should be work for all, leisure for all, and abundance for all — in which all might be at least as true, as generous and as manful as they wish to be — is shut out by the deference paid to economic authorities who have as it were given bonds not to find that for which they profess to seek, so there are many to-day to whom any belief in the spiritual element, in the existence of God and in a future life, is darkened or destroyed, not so much by 3.18 CONCLUSION. difficulties they themselves find, but by what they take to be the teachings of science. Conscious of their own ignorance, distrustful of their own powers, stumbling over scientific technicalities and awed by metaphysical terminology, they are disposed to accept on faith the teachings of such a man as Mr. Spencer, as those of one who on all things knows more and sees further than they can, and to accord to what they take to be intellectual pre-eminence the moral pre-eminence that they feel ought to accompany it. I know the feeling of such men, for I remember the years when it was my own. To these it is my hope that this examination may be useful, by putting them on inquiry. In its course we have tested, in matters where ordinary intelligence and knowledge are competent to judge, the logical methods and intellectual honesty of the foremost of those who in the name of science eliminate God and degrade man, taking from human life its highest dig- nity and deepest hope. Now, if in simple matters we find such confusion, such credulity, such violation of every canon of sound reasoning as we have found here, shall we blindly trust in deeper matters—in those matters which always have and always must perplex the intellect of man 7 Let us rather, as I said in the beginning, not too much underrate our own powers in what is concerned with common facts and general relations. While we may not be scientists or philosophers we too are men. And as to things which the telescope cannot resolve, nor the microscope reveal, nor the spectrum analysis throw light nor the tests of the chemist discover, it is as irrational to blindly accept the dictum of those TEIE MORAL OF THIS EXAMINATION. 319 who say, “Thus saith science 1” as it is in things that are the proper field of the natural sciences to bow before the dictum of those who say, “Thus saith religion 1’’ I care nothing for creeds. I am not concerned with any one's religious belief. But I would have men think for themselves. If we do not, we can only abandon one superstition to take up another, and it may be a worse one. It is as bad for a man to think that he can know nothing as to think he knows all. There are things which it is given to all possessing reason to know, if they will but use that reason. And some things it may be there are, that — as was said by one whom the learning of the time sneered at, and the high priests persecuted, and polite society, speaking through the voice of those who knew not what they did, crucified — are hidden from the wise and prudent and revealed unto babes. New York, October 12, 1892. / - T- f | ||||||III 3618 *—. *—- 0R MUTILATE CARD : ;t : :