ſ. , !vvv| }„” •• №rſe. . . . . . _…:…, º…,an,… ſº C tº . º , ºr s: , ; . . * . º unistrºn ſ ſ í 4 × 1 \!\, , · *! § ,í',|-*- ' . .* , }|' .|tſ y Sº . . | || • • • • • – —<=====~~ ~~~~ ~~~~ ~ ~ ~ ~ ~ ~~ Lº * |HTTTTTTTTTTTTF, º º | } CI +. lº § * sº \; TTTTTTTTTIſ: . ſ [… sº º s ”Nºts #/º .. : LIBRARYºº of THE tRNERSITORMICH, jº : J \\ , ſº . . . . . \t, ... . . º.º. ſº * . . ." fºr ºf ſº º º ºc º ** º º D§ § :* *: s %2 % : É Ż § - *...*.* * |. 5 ", 4 . * º <º *\; , , § iſº º 3× [- - & sº sº. tº ,- A tº *** ** Sºś - \\\zā jºuaºs PENInsuunrº º º sº º º … ºf , 3. Nº. - E Af - * % :;Fi # | º E-3 L_2. º : - . § º' ,º s: Cº., - J.J. Mºſ.º.º.º. 3 º' tº =: : sº." ... . #: G Eº * ...'... ?" 6 rººf: sºl º , *, * ſ: - - º dº. wº- ---> . . - - - - . . . . . . - IIIllllllllllllllllllllllllliſDIIIllſlºſſIEIIIHIIIHIIIIIIIIIIHIIIIHIIIIſ º -- • * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * |Eil * biºlº.º. JURIS PRUDENCE T. E. H. O I, I, ANZ) 3.0mb on H E N R Y F. R O W D E OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS WAREHOUSE 7 PATERNOSTER, ROW THE ELEMENTS OF J U R IS P R U D E N C E BY THOMAS ERSKINE HOLLAND, D.C.L. *~ OF LINCOLN'S INN BARRISTER-AT-LAW CEIICHELE PROFESSOR OF INTERNATIONAL LAW AND DIPLOMACY AND FELLOW OF ALL SopDS COLLEGE, OXFORD QB a fortſ AT THE CLAREND ON PRESS M IDCCC LXXX [All rights reserted ) Amplissimum Iuris Oceanum ad paucos revocare fontes limpidos rectae rationis.-LEIBNITZ Ep. ad Magl. xxvii. P. R. E. F. A. C. E. The legal systems of the continent owe to their common derivation from the law of Rome, not only a uniform legal nomenclature, but also a generally accepted method which at Once assigns any newly de- veloped principle to its proper place, and has greatly facilitated the orderly exposition of those systems in the form of codes. In England, on the other hand, legal nomenclature is a mosaic of many languages, and the law itself, as expounded by Coke and Blackstone, except so far as it has been deduced with much logical punctiliousness from the theory of feudal tenure, is little more than a collection of isolated rules, strung together, if at all, only by some slender thread of analogy. The practitioner has been content to find his way through it, as best he might, by the help of the indices of text- books, or of ‘Abridgments, or so-called ‘Digests, arranged under alphabetical titles. It was a step in advance when it occurred to Mr. J. W. Smith to publish a series of ‘Leading Cases,’ a 2. vi PREFACE. selected almost at random, and to group round each a collection of subordinate decisions, in which the rule recognised in the principal case is deviously tracked in its various applications. Of a somewhat similar nature is Dr. Broom’s ‘Selection of Legal Maxims, which explains the workings in different de- partments of law of a string of principles, such as those which are collected in the title of the Digest ‘ de Regulis Iuris.’ It may be remarked that the principles to which reference is made, alike in the “Leading Cases’ and in the ‘Maxims,’ are but what Bacon would call ‘media axiomata, which neither work attempts to exhibit in their mutual relations, or to de- duce from the higher principles of which they are corollaries; also that the search for these principles is an enquiry into the ethical reasons by which English law ought to be moulded, not an analysis and classifica- tion of legal categories. There have been of late years signs of a change in the mental habit of English lawyers. Distaste for comprehensive views, and indifference to foreign modes of thought, can no longer be said to be national characteristics. The change is due partly to a revival of the study of Roman law, partly to a growing famili- arity with continental life and literature, partly to such investigations as those of Sir H. Maine into the origin of legal ideas, but chiefly to the writings of Bentham and Austin. To the latter especially most Englishmen are indebted for such ideas as they possess of legal method. The ‘Province of Jurisprudence Determined,’ is indeed a book which no one can read without improvement. It presents the spectacle of a powerful and conscien- PREFACE. vii tious mind struggling with an intractable and rarely handled material, while those distinctions upon which Austin after his somewhat superfluously careful manner bestows most labour are put in so clear a light that they can hardly again be lost sight of. The defects of the work are even more widely recognised than its merits. It is avowedly frag- mentary. The writer is apt to recur with painful iteration to certain topics; and he leaves large tracts of his subject wholly unexplored, while devoting much space to digressions upon questions, such as the psy- chology of the will, codification, and utilitarianism, which have no necessary connection with his main argument. It may be asserted, without injustice either to Bentham or Austin, that works upon legal system by English writers have hitherto been singularly unsystematic. - It is long since the author formed the hope of attempting to write a treatise upon legal ideas which should at least be free from this particular fault, and the objects which he proposed to himself differed so con- siderably from those aimed at in Mr. Justice Markby's ‘Elements of Law’ that the appearance of that very valuable work did not dissuade him from the prosecu- tion of his design. In carrying it out he has not gained so much assistance as he expected from the legal litera- ture of the continent. He soon discovered not only that the name of Austin was unknown in Germany, but that very little had been written in that country with a direct bearing upon analytical jurisprudence. The latter fact is not so surprising as it may appear, if it be remembered that the continental jurists find in Roman viii PREFACE. law a ready-made terminology and a typical method, upon which they are little inclined to innovate. From treatises upon “Naturrecht,’ which may be described as ‘Jurisprudence in the air,’ he has derived next to nothing; and works upon ‘Encyclopädie’ and ‘Metho- dologie,” are generally too brief, and too much infected with a priori conceptions, to have been consulted with much profit. More help has been found, where it might not at first be looked for, in the numerous works, usually entitled ‘Pandekten, in which the Germans have set forth the Roman law as it has been modified with a view to modern convenience. Foremost among these must be mentioned von Savigny’s ‘System des heutigen Römischen Rechts.” Still less has been derived from the other modern literatures; and after a general survey of the subject the author set to work to think it out for himself, resolving to traverse the whole of it, and to hold a straight course through it, turning neither to the right hand nor to the left into any digression however tempt- ing. He now offers the result of his labours, which has been much delayed by other and more pressing engage- ments, to the indulgence of those who best know the extent and difficulty of the topic of which he has attempted to give a complete and consistent view. T. E. H. OxFORD, March 20, 188o. CON TENTS, PART I. T. A.W. A.INID RIG. H.T. S. CHAPTER I. PAGE JURISPRUDENCE . ë * & & {º e º I CHAPTER II. LAW . ſº ſº s & © & e ſº & I 2 CHAPTER III, LAws As RULES OF HUMAN ACTION . & § ſº 2 I CHAPTER IV. PoSITIVE LAw . ſe e * . . & 6 35 CHAPTER W. THE Sources of LAw & © tº * * * 43 - a 3 X CONTENTS. CHAPTER VI. THE OBJECT OF LAW CHAPTER WII. RIGHTS. CHAPTER VIII. ANALYSIS OF A RIGHT . CHAPTER IX. THE LEADING CLASSIFICATIONS OF RIGHTS CHAPTER X. RIGHTS AT REST AND IN MOTION PART II. IPIR IV A TIE T. A. W. CHAPTER XI. ANTECEDENT RIGHTS ‘IN REM CHAPTER XII. ANTEGEDENT RIGHTS ‘IN PERSONAM' CHAPTER XIII. REMEDIAL RIGHTS - - CHAPTER XIV. ABNoRMAL RIGHTS CEIAPTER XV. ADJECTIVE LAW PAGE 52 55 62 76 95 Io? I6 I 2 I 2 224 .238 CONTENTS. PART III. PTU BT, IC L.A.W. CHAPTER XVI. THE NATURE OF THE TOPIC . CoNSTITUTIONAL LAW ADMINISTRATIVE Law CRIMINAL LAw THE LAW OF THE STATE As A PERSON PART IV. INTERNATIONAL LAW. CHAPTER XVII. THE NATURE OF THE TOPIC TNTERNATIONAL PERSONs SUBSTANTIVE LAw ADJECTIVE LAW, BELLIGERENCY 35 32 NEUTRALITY PART W. xi PAGE 244 248 25 I 254 26o 263 266 268 272 274 TIHIE AIPIPI,IC A.TION OF I. A.W. CHAPTER XVIII. THE NATURE OF THE TOPIC . THE APPLICATION OF PRIVATE LAW 5 y 25 PUBLIC TIAW 3 * 92 INTERNATIONAL LAW 277 278 289 295 ELEMENTS OF JURISPRUDENCE, C. H. A. P.T. E. R. T. JURISE’RUDENCE. THE present treatise is an attempt to set forth and explain The need those comparatively few and simple ideas which underlie the º infinite variety of legal rules. The search for these ideas is not merely a matter of scientific curiosity. The ever-renewed complexity of human relations calls for an increasing complexity of legal detail, till a merely empirical knowledge of law becomes impossible. The evil has been partially remedied by the formation of Codes. Legislators, more or less imbued with legal prin- ciples, have by their means grouped the legal chaos under genera and species. An uncodified system of law can, how- ever, be mastered only by the student whose scientific equip- ment enables him to cut his own path through the tangled growth of enactment and precedent, and so to codify for his own purposes. In this, as in other departments of knowledge, the difficulty of the subject is due less to the multiplicity of its details than to the absence of general principles under which those details may be grouped. In other words, while legal science is capable of being intelligently learnt, isolated legal facts are capable only of being committed to memory. B 2 JURISPRUDENCE. CHAP. I. For the beginnings of the science which reduces legal ** phenomena to order and coherence the world is indebted to the Romans. It is also from their language that the science derives its name. ‘Iurisprudentia,’ in its original use, was merely one among several phrases signifying a knowledge of the law, just as ‘rei militaris prudentia” signified a knowledge of the conduct of warfare". The sort of knowledge which the term denoted may be gathered from Cicero's description of a jurisconsult as one who must be ‘skilled in the laws, and in the usages current among private citizens, and in giving opinions and bringing actions and taking security ".” From this thoroughly practical conception of legal know- ledge the Roman jurists subsequently rose to a far higher one. The rudiments of this may already be traced in the writings of Cicero, who enumerates the civil law, along with astronomy, geometry, and dialectic, among the arts which have to do with the pursuit of truth *. He tells us that the study of law must be derived from the depths of philosophy, and that, by an examination of the human mind and of human society, principles may be discovered in com- parison with which the rules of positive law are of but trivial importance *. - Thus the way was prepared for Ulpian’s well-known definition of Jurisprudence as ‘the knowledge of things * “Babebat enim magnam prudentiam, tum iuris civilis tum rei militaris.’ Nep. Cim. 2. The following terms are used synonymously with ‘iuris pru- dentia’: ‘legum prudentia, Cic. Rep. ii. 36; ‘legum scientia, Inst. Prooem. 3; * legitima scientia,’ ib. 2 ; ‘iuris notitia, Tac. Orat. 31 ; “cognitio iuris, Cic. de Orat. i. 44; ‘iuris scientia, ib. 55, Pompon. Dig. i. 2. 2.40; ‘civilis scientia.’ Cic. de Orat. i. 43 ; ‘iuris peritia,” Ulp. Dig. i. I. I. Knowledge of a particular department of law is described by such phrases as ‘iuris civilis” (Cic, de Orat. i. 44), “iuris publici' (ib. 60), ‘prudentia.” * Cic. de Orat. i. 48. The same persons who were called ‘iurisconsulti’ or ‘iure periti” were also described as ‘prudentes in iure civili, Cic. Amic. 2; more briefly as ‘prudentes,” Gai. i. 7. The phrase ‘iuris prudens’ is employed by Pomponius (Dig. xxxviii. 15. 2). “Legum prudens’ occurs in Ennius (Gell. xii. 4), and “imprudens iuris’ in Iust. Inst. iv. 2. 3 Cic. de Off. i. 6. * Id, de Leg. i. 5. MEANING OF THE TERM. 3 * human and divine, the science of the just and unjust *.” CHAP, I, Jurisprudence was conceived of as a branch of philosophy; and such an elevation of the idea of legal study was natur- ally accompanied by a corresponding elevation of its profes- sors. Ulpian claims for himself and his learned brethren that they are ‘the priests of Justice, engaged in the pursuit of a philosophy that is truly such and no counterfeit *.” The Romans had, in fact, attained by this time to the idea of a science of those legal principles which exist inde- pendently of the institutions of any particular country. No technical term could be borrowed from the Greek language to denote what was of purely indigenous growth *, and thus it happened that a phrase which at first had been but one among several signifying, in a homely and quite unscientific sense, a ‘knowledge of law,’ came at length by an accident of Latin philology to express the new idea of a legal science. The nations of modern Europe are fortunately in the habit of calling the various branches of knowledge by non- vernacular names, adopted by common consent from the classical languages; so that a science is generally known by the same Greek or Latin term wherever Western civilisa- tion extends. It is therefore natural and convenient that most of the European nations should express the idea of a science of law by a word which they have borrowed from the language of the people by whom the idea was first conceived 4. * Dig. i. I. Io. This is a mere translation of the Stoic definition of oroqta as being 6etov re kal &vépartvav čtvo Tápam (Plut. Plac. Phil. i. pr. ; cf. Cic. de Off. i. 43), modified by the addition of a clause specifying the particular kind of wisdom intended. The first clause of Ulpian's definition has been, with little reason, thought by some to have reference to the distinction be- tween ius sacrum and the other branches of law; see Glück, Pandekten, i. p. I98. * Dig. i. I. I. I. -- * Iurisprudentia is represented in the Basilika, ii. I. I, and in Harmen- opulus, Prompt. i. 1. 18, by goſpía vópov. -- * Even the Germans, who have vernacular names for so many of the sciences, recognise “Jurisprudenz’ as well as ‘Rechtswissenschaft.” IB 2. 4 JURISPRUDENCE. But the term is unfortunately also borrowed by the modern languages to express other ideas, which might be much better expressed in the vernacular. Thus, upon the analogy of certain loose expressions of the Roman writers, who sometimes use ‘iurisprudentia” to denote a current view of the law", there has sprung up in French the use of such phrases as ‘jurisprudence constante,’ ‘jurisprudence des arrêts de la Cour de Cassation’; in the sense of the view which the courts are in the habit of taking of certain questions”. Still less justifiable is the use, so frequent both in French and in English, of “Jurisprudence' as the equivalent of ‘Law.” The imposing quadrisyllable is constantly introduced into a phrase, solely on grounds of euphony. Thus we have books upon ‘Equity Jurisprudence,” which are nothing more nor less than treatises upon the law administered by Courts of Equity; and we hear of the Jurisprudence of France or Russia, when nothing else is meant than the law which is in force in those countries respectively. This sacrifice of sense to sound might more readily be pardoned, had it not misled serious and accurate thinkers. - Bentham, for instance, divides Jurisprudence into ‘exposi- tory,’ which ascertains what the law is, and ‘censorial,’ which ascertains what it ought to be *. Now an exposition of existing law is obviously quite another thing from a science of law, and criticisms upon the law with a view to its amendment are the subject, not of Jurisprudence, but, as Bentham himself states in the next paragraph, of the art of Legislation. Bentham carries the confusion further by pro- ceeding to sub-divide expository Jurisprudence into ‘authori- tative’ and unauthoritative *.’ By ‘authoritative expository jurisprudence’ he means nothing more nor less than law emanating from the legislative power; under unauthori- * “Media iurisprudentia, Iust. Inst. iii. 2. 3. * “La manière dont un Tribunal juge habituellement telle ou telle ques- CHAP. I. Improper uses of the term. tion.” Dict. de l'Académie. * Works, i. p. 148. 4 Ibid. A SCIENCE. 5 tative he would apparently include both text-books upon CHAP. I. the laws of any one country, or, as he would say, upon ‘local jurisprudence,’ and works upon law without special reference to any one country, or, to use his own phrase, upon “universal jurisprudence.” If we are right in considering It is the that “censorial jurisprudence' should be called ‘the art of tº. legislation,” that ‘authoritative jurisprudence’ is nothing more nor less than a body of law, and that “unauthoritative local jurisprudence is mere commentary; it is obvious that what Bentham makes the sub-department of “unauthori- tative universal jurisprudence' is alone entitled to bear the name of the science; and should bear the name simply, without the addition of epithets intended to distinguish it from departments of the subject which are non-existent. ‘Jurisprudence ought therefore to be used, and used with- out any qualifying epithet, as the name of a science. We have next to enquire what kind of a science it is; and This . we shall find that it is a formal, as opposed to a material j sº one; that is to say, that it deals rather with the various relations which are regulated by legal rules than with the rules themselves which regulate those relations. This was not indeed the whole scope of the science as conceived of by its founders". There floated also always before the eyes of the later Roman jurists a vision of a ‘ius naturale;’ a universal code, from which all particular systems are derived, or to which they all tend, at least, to approxi- mate: a set of rules, the matter, or contents, of which is of universal application. But in point of fact, and in the very pursuit of this material unity, they were led to elaborate a system of formal unity; to catalogue the topics with which every system of law has to deal, however each may differ from the rest in its mode of dealing with them. They performed for * Although we find in Cicero the clearest possible description of an analytical Science of law; De Orat. i. 42. 6 - - JURISPRUDENCE. oHAP. I. Law a service similar to that which was rendered to Language by the Greeks of Alexandria, when by observing and tabu- lating the parts of speech, the inflections, moods and syntax, they invented a grammar, under the formulae of which all the phenomena of any language find appropriate places". Whether the possessive case of a noun substantive is expressed by a specific modification of its termination, or by prefixing to it a specific preposition, is a question of the matter of language; but that the possessive idea, however variously expressed, yet finds some expression or other in every family of human speech, is a proposition which relates to linguistic form. i The assertion that Jurisprudence is a formal science may perhaps be made clearer by an example. If any indi- vidual should accumulate a knowledge of every European system of law, holding each apart from the rest in the chambers of his mind, his achievement would be best de- scribed as an accurate acquaintance with the legal systems of Europe. If each of these systems were entirely unlike the rest, except when laws had been, in the course of history, transferred from one to the other, such a dis- tinguished jurist could do no more than endeavour to hold fast, and to avoid confusing, the heterogeneous information of which he had become possessed. Suppose however, as is the case, that the laws of every country contain a common element; that they have been constructed in order to effect similar objects, and involve the assumption of similar moral phenomena as everywhere existing; then such a person might proceed to frame out of his accumulated materials a scheme of the purposes, methods, and ideas common to every system of law. Such a scheme would be a formal science of law, presenting many analogies to Grammar; the science of those ideas of relation which, in greater or less perfection, and often in the most dissimilar ways, are expressed in all the languages of mankind. * Cf. Max Müller, Science of Language, edit. 3, p. 9o. A FORMAL SCIENCE. 7 To each of these formal sciences there ministers a CHAP. I. Science which supplies it with materials. Just as simi- larities and differences in the growth of different languages are collected and arranged by Comparative Philology, and the facts thus collected are the foundation of abstract Grammar; so Comparative Law collects and tabulates the legal institutions of various countries, and from the re- sults thus prepared, the abstract science of Jurisprudence is enabled to set forth an orderly view of the ideas and methods which have been variously realised in actual systems. It is, for instance, the office of Comparative Law to ascertain what have been at different times and places the periods of pre- scription, or the requisites of a good marriage. It is for Jurisprudence to elucidate the meaning of prescription, in its relation to ownership and to actions; or to explain the legal aspect of marriage, and its connection with property and the family. We are not indeed to suppose that Juris- prudence is impossible unless it is preceded by Compara- tive Law. A system of Jurisprudence might conceivably be constructed from the observation of one system of law only, at one epoch of its growth. Such, however, has not been in point of fact the mode of its evolution, which must have been extremely tardy but for the possibility of sepa- rating the essential elements of the science from its historical accidents, by comparing together laws enforced in the same country at different epochs, and indigenous laws with the differing, though resembling, laws of foreigners. Jurisprudence is therefore not the material science of those portions of the law which various nations have in common ", but the formal science of those relations of mankind which are generally recognised as having legal consequences. In the next place, it must be sufficient at present merely It is a f to state, without further explanation, that Jurisprudence is ...” law, * A subject which, under, the description of the ‘ius gentium, largely occu- pied the attention of the Roman jurists. 8 JURISPRUDENCE. CHAP. I. and is therefore progres- sive. Is it divis- ible into “general’ and ‘par- ticular " : not a science of legal relations & priori, as they might have been, or should have been, but is abstracted & posteriori from such relations as have been clothed with a legal character in actual systems, that is to say from law which has actually been imposed, or positive law. It follows that Jurisprudence is a progressive science. Its generalisations must keep pace with the movement of systems of actual law. Its broader distinctions, corresponding to deep-seated human characteristics, will no doubt be permanent, but, as time goes on, new distinctions must be constantly developed, with a view to the co-ordination of the ever-increasing variety of legal phenomena. We have lastly to consider whether the science is rightly divided into several species, and especially to enquire into the justness of the distinction drawn between ‘general’ and ‘particular Jurisprudence. ‘Particular Jurisprudence,’ says Austin, ‘is the science of any actual system of law or of any portion of it. The only practical Jurisprudence is par- ticular. . . The proper subject of general, or universal, Jurisprudence is a description of such subjects and ends of law as are common to all systems, and of those resemblances between different systems which are bottomed in the common nature of man, or correspond to the resembling points in these several portions".’ Now ‘particular' Jurisprudence may mean either of two things. It may mean: a science derived from an observation of the laws of one country only. If so, the particularity attaches, not to the science itself, which is the same science whencesoever derived, but to the source whence the materials for it are gained. A science of Law might undoubtedly be con- structed from a knowledge of the law of England alone, as a science of Geology might be, and in great part was, con- structed from an observation of the strata in England only: * Lect. On Jurisprudence, iii. p. 356. Cf. Bentham, works, i. p. 149. NOT DIVISIBLE. , 9 yet as there is no particular science of Geology, so neither CHAP. I. is there a particular science of Law. For a science is a system of generalisations which, though they may be derived from observations extending over a limited area, will never- theless hold good everywhere; assuming the object-matter of the science to possess everywhere the same characteristics. Principles of Geology elaborated from the observation of England alone hold good all over the globe, in so far as the same substances and forces are everywhere present; and the principles of Jurisprudence, if arrived at entirely from English data, would be true if applied to the particular laws of any other community of human beings; assuming them to resemble in essentials the human beings who inhabit England. The wider the field of observation, the greater, of course, will be the chance of the principles of a science being rightly and completely enunciated; but, so far as they are scientific truths at all, they are always general and of universal application. The phrase may however, and pro- bably does, mean: an acquaintance with the laws of a particular people; and the impropriety of describing such merely empirical and practical knowledge by a term which should be used only as the name of a science has been already pointed out. In either sense therefore the term is a mis- nomer; and it follows that, the existence of a ‘particular Jurisprudence not being admitted, the employment of the opposed term “general Jurisprudence’ becomes unnecessary. Both expressions should be discarded, and the science should be treated as incapable of being divided into these two branches. A distinction has also been suggested between ‘historical' or into . and ‘philosophical’ Jurisprudence. It is said that the unity º: which makes Jurisprudence a science exists only in idea; that * * while it has a side upon which it is closely allied to Ethics and to Metaphysics, it is, on the other hand, no less in- timately connected with Archaeology and History; that its phenomena grow from many independent roots, and are 10 JURISPRUDENCE. Char. I. formed and coloured according to the character of the various soils from which they have sprung. But to say this is only to say that the facts from which Jurisprudence generalises are furnished by History, the record of human actions. Identical human needs have been satisfied by various means, and all the means of satisfying each of these needs have not been in simultaneous use in every part of the world and in every age. In the satisfaction of their needs mankind have rarely seen clearly the ends at which they were aiming, and have therefore in reaching after those ends invented a vast variety of perverse complications. The unity, in short, which /it is the business of Jurisprudence to exhibit as underlying all the phenomena which it investigates, is the late discovery of . an advanced civilisation, and was unperceived during much of \the time while those phenomena were accumulating. The facts can only be presented by History, and History may be studied with the sole view of discovering this class of facts. But this is not the task of Jurisprudence, which only begins when these facts begin to fall into an order other than the historical, and arrange themselves in groups which have no relation to the varieties of the human race. The province of Jurisprudence is to observe the wants for the supply of which laws have been invented, and the manner in which those wants have been satisfied. It then digests those actual wants and the modes in which they have actually been satis- fied, irrespectively of their historical or geographical distri- bution, according to logical principles of division derived from other sciences of human action. One work on Juris- prudence may contain more of historical disquisition, while in another philosophical argument may predominate; but such differences are incidental to the mode of treatment, and afford no ground for a division of the science itself. But though the science is one, it has as many heads or departments as there are departments of law. It is therefore correct to talk of ‘criminal’ and ‘civil,' ‘public’ and ‘private’ Jurisprudence. IDEFINITION OF THE TERM. 11 To sum up. The term Jurisprudence is wrongly applied to CHAP. I. actual systems of law, or to current views of law, or to * suggestions for its amendment, but is the name of a defined. science. This science is a formal rather than a material One. It is the science of actual, or positive, law. It is wrongly divided into ‘general’ and ‘particular,’ or into ‘philosophical” and ‘historical.’ It may therefore be defined provisionally as ‘the formal science of positive law.” The full import of this definition will not be apparent till the completion of an analysis of the all-important term ‘Law.” Meaning of the term Law. CHAPTER II. T.A.W. ‘LAw, or the Law,’ says Bentham, “taken indefinitely, is an abstract or collective term, which, when it means anything, can mean neither more nor less than the sum total of a number of individual laws taken together".' . This simple statement is in striking contrast with a multi- tude of assertions upon the subject; which however are less frequently made with reference to the English term Law than Ambiguity to its equivalents in other languages. The terms Tus, Recht, of Ius, Recht, Droit. Droit, cannot, in fact, be said to express nothing more than ‘the sum total of a number of individual laws taken together.’ It so happens that all these terms denote not only the sum total of Laws, but also the sum total of Rights (Tura, Rechte, Droits), and the sum total of all that is just (iustum, recht, droit). When therefore we say that Juris- prudence is the science of Ius, Recht or Droit, we may mean in each case that it is the science of any one of three things, VIZ. (1) of Law, (2) of Rights, (3) of Justice; and, unless this ambiguity is borne in mind, many expressions * Works, i. p. 148. Cf., among the meanings of ‘Ius’ enumerated by Puffen- dorf, i. i. § 20, ‘complexus Seu systema legum homogenearum.” A LAW. 13 having apparent reference to law will be quite unintelligible. CHAP. II. A coherent science cannot however be constructed upon an idea which has complex or shifting meanings. One or other meaning must be chosen, and when chosen must be made the sole foundation of the edifice. It is therefore a piece of good fortune that when we say in English that Jurispru- dence is the science of law, we are spared the ambiguities which beset the expression of that proposition in Latin, German, and French, and have greatly obscured its expo- sition in those languages. But if the English abstract term ‘Law is free from any Meaning of suggestion of the aggregate of Rights, or of the aggregate * of just things, it is of course suggestive of all the meanings in which the concrete term ‘a law' is employed in our language; and these have unfortunately been so numerous as to involve the abstract idea in considerable obscurity. Hence it is that so many of the definitions which have been given of that mysterious non-entity strike us as being vague or merely eulogistic. Many of them have reference to that divine order which pervades the inanimate universe even more than the actions of rational beings; and those of them which have reference to human action deal quite as often with the voluntarily observed maxims of society as with rules which are supported by the authority of the State. Heterogeneous however as the senses of the term ‘a law' may at first sight appear, the connection between them is not hard to trace; nor is the earliest use widely different from the latest and most accurate. The shepherd who guides his flock, or, on a larger scale, Its earliest the head of a family who regulates its encampments and “ employments, seems to have been the earliest ‘lawgiver,’ and his directions, as orders given by one who has power to enforce their observance, are the earliest ‘laws".’ The 1 So Homer says of the Cyclopes, Oepuoteſel 6° àicaotos traſbov jö' àAóxov, Odyss. ix. 114; and Plato, Otrol āpa Tův taxatów Śplato vopofféral yeyóvagi, 14 LAW. original, and still the popular, conception of ‘a law,” --- a command prescribing a course of action, disobedience to Which will be punished. In this conception there is of course implied that of a lawgiver, who has power to enforce his commands. From this vague original use of the term has arisen that large development of uses, some proper, some merely metaphorical, out of which the jurist has to select that which he admits into his science. The strongest intellectual tendency of mankind is the anthropomorphic. If man is a mystery to himself, external nature is a still greater mystery to him, and he explains the more by the less obscure. As he governs his flock and his family, so he supposes that unseen beings govern the waters and the winds. The greater the regularity which he observes in nature, the fewer such beings does he suppose to be at work in her; till at last he rises to the conception of one great being whose laws are obeyed by the whole universe; or it may be, that, having thus arrived at the notion of a universe moving according to fixed laws, he holds fast to it, even while he loses his hold on the idea of the existence of a supreme lawgiver. Men have also almost always believed themselves to be acquainted with certain rules intended for the guidance of their actions, and either directly revealed to them by a superhuman power, or gathered by themselves from such indications of the will of that power as are accessible. They have supposed that they have discovered by self-analysis a master part of themselves, to the dictates of which they owe allegiance. They have observed that, in order that CHAP. II. Derivative liSCS. vopleſs re kai troupéves àvöpóv, Minos, p. 320 B. It may be worth while to notice that vöpios does not occur in Homer. Hesiod uses it twice, both times in the singular number; Op. et Dies, 276, 388. The Homeric word most nearly expressive of laws is 6épuares, which however really signifies rather decrees made for special cases. Grote, Hist. ii. p. III ; Maine, Ancient Law, ch. i. It is surely reversing the order of ideas to suppose that the use of vöpios in the sense of “a chant’ is the original one, as does, e.g., Fustel de Coulanges, La Cité Antique, p. 227. DIVISION OF THE SCIENCES. 15 their senses may receive certain impressions from external CHAP. II. objects, those objects must be arranged in certain ways, and no other. It is easy enough, upon consideration of these facts, to account for the existence of such phrases as laws of Nature, laws of God, laws of Morality, laws of Beauty, and others which will at once suggest themselves. The employment of the same name to denote things so The . different may appear to us to imply an extraordinary con-º.tion fusion of the topics appropriate to Theology, to Physics, to * Ethics, to Æsthetics, and to Jurisprudence; but the wonder will be less if we remember that the separation of the sciences to which we are accustomed, and which we take for granted, was unknown to remote antiquity. The world with all its varied phenomena was originally studied as a whole. The facts of nature and the doings of man were alike conceived of as ordained by the gods. The constitutions of states and the customs and laws of all the peoples of the earth were as much of divine contrivance as the paths of the planets. The great problem thus presented for the study of man- kind was gradually broken up into a number of minor problems. There occurred a division of the sciences. A line was drawn between those which deal with external nature, including. Theology and Metaphysics, and those which deal with the actions of men. These latter, the practical, were thus severed from the theoretical sciences”; and the term law, which had been used ambiguously in the discussion of both sets of topics before their severance, has henceforth two distinct histories. In the theoretical sciences, it is used as the abstract idea of the observed relations of phenomena, be those relations instances of causation or of mere succession and co-existence. In the practical sciences the term is used to express the abstract idea of the rules which regulate human action. * They are thenceforth connected only by means of religion, and by specula- tions concerning the faculties of the human mind. 16 LAW, CHAP. II. TJse of the term in the physical Sciences; in the practical sciences. In the theoretical, or as we should rather say in modern phrase, in the physical sciences, Law is used to denote the method of the phenomena of the universe; a use which would imply, in accordance with the primitive meaning of the term, that this method is imposed upon the phenomena either by the will of God, or by an abstraction called Nature. This use of the term may certainly lead to misconceptions. It has long ago been agreed that all we can know of natural phenomena is that they co-exist with, or succeed, one another, in a certain order, but whether this order be imposed im- mediately by a divine will, or mediately through an abstraction called Nature, or through minor abstractions called Gravitation, Electricity, and the like, the phenomena themselves are unable to inform us. It is therefore necessary to realise that when we talk of the laws of Gravity or of Refraction, we mean merely that objects do gravitate and that rays are refracted. We are using the term law merely to convey to our minds the idea of order and method, and we must beware of importing into this idea any of the associations called up by the term when it is employed in the practical sciences. Its use in these sciences is, speaking very generally, to express a rule of human action; and the sciences of human action being those in which the term is most used, and indeed is most needed, it is reasonable to say that this is its proper meaning, and that its use in the theoretical sciences is improper, or metaphorical merely. But just as its metaphorical use, as meaning ‘order,’ is sometimes obscured by associations derived from its proper use as signifying ‘a rule,” so is its proper use as ‘a rule' occasionally confused by an imagined parity between a rule and the invariable order of nature. The first step therefore towards clearing the term Law of ambiguity for the purposes of Jurisprudence, is to discard the meaning in which it is employed in the physical sciences, where it is used, by a mere metaphor, to express the method ITS TWO MEANINGS. 17 or order of phenomena; and to adopt as its proper meaning chAP, II. that which it bears in the practical sciences, where it is employed as the abstract of rules of human action. The opposition between these two meanings will be best seen The two by grouping together, under the heads of Order and Rule meanings. respectively, a few characteristic specimens of the vague em- ployment of the term Law. I. Law as the order of the Universe. Nóuos, 6 Távrov 6agu)\ets G)watów Te kai &0avátov.–Pindar". - ‘O vöpſos Ó kolvös, Öo Tep &otiv Ó Öp60s A&yos 6ta Távrov Order. épxówevos, 6 airós &v Tó Ati kaðnyepºv. Totſtºp tis Tów ŚAov ôtoukſjøeos évrt.-Chrysippus *. Lex vera atque princeps, apta ad iubendum et ad vetandum ratio est recta summi Iovis.-Cicero *. Lex aeterna nihil aliud est quam summa ratio divinae sapientiae, secundum quod est directiva omnium actuum et motionum.—S. Thomas *. Of Law there can be no lesse acknowledged, than that her seate is the bosome of God, her voyce the harmony of the world, all things in Heaven and Earth doe her homage, the very least as feeling her care, and the greatest as not exempted from her power; both angels and men and creatures of what condition soever, though each in different sort and manner, yet all with uniforme consent, admiring her as the mother of their peace and joy.—Hooker*. II. Law as a rule of Acţion. Lex est recta ratio imperandi atque prohibendi.-Cicero". Rule, Lex nihil aliud nisi recta et a numine deorum tracta ratio, iubens honesta prohibens contraria.-Cicero". Ius estars boni et aequi.-Celsus *. * Apud Plat. Gorg, 484 B. * Apud D. Laert. vii. 88. * De Leg. ii. 4. * I. 2. qu. 93. art, 1. * Eccl. Pol. i. c. 18. * De Leg, i. 15. 7 Phil. xi. I 2. - * Dig. i. I. I. C 18 LAW. CHAP. II. Diversity of rules called laws. That which reason in such sort defines to be good that it must be done.—Hooker*. Der Inbegriff der Bedingungen unter denen die Willkühr des Einen mit der Willkühr des Anderen nach einem allge- meinen Gesetze der Freiheit vereinigt werden kann.—Kant”. Der abstracte Ausdruck des allgemeinen, an und für sich seienden Willens.—Hegel 8. Das organische Ganze der aiiseren Bedingungen des ver- nunſtgemässen Lebens.—Krause *. Die Regel wodurch die unsichtbare Grenze bestimmt wird innerhalb welcher das Daseyn und die Wirksamkeit jedes Einzelnen einen sichern freien Raum gewinnt.—Savigny ". The term Law is employed in Jurisprudence not in the sense of the abstract idea of order, but in that of the abstract idea of rules of conduct. But of these rules only a particular class are ‘laws’ in the strict sense of the term ; so that although the jurist is in no danger of getting entangled in questions of physical science, he is obliged to busy himself in marking the boundary which separates his own department of study from the wider field of morality. His task is so to narrow and deepen the popular conception of ‘a law, in the sense of a rule of action, as to fit it for his own purposes. This task will be undertaken in the next chapter; before entering upon which it may perhaps be as well to point out how various in character are those precepts for the guidance of the life and conduct of men to which the term law is with more or less propriety applied. While some of these precepts are received wherever human beings are gathered together, others are limited to the followers of a particular religion, or to the inhabitants of a * Eccl. Pol. i. c. 8. * Rechtslehre, Werke, ix. p. 33. * Propädeutik, Cursus i. § 26. * Abriss des Systems der Philosophie des Rechtes, p. 209. * System, i. p. 332. - AS A RULE OF ACTION. 19 definite portion of the earth’s surface. While some of them chap. II. deal with the fundamental institutions of society, others are occupied with the pettiest details of ceremonial or deportment. Some are enforced by the whole power of great empires, whilst others may be violated by any one who is not afraid to encounter the banter of his acquaintance. They possess, however, certain characteristics in common, which must be briefly enumerated. They all either are, or may be, expressed as distinct Character- propositions. They are, further, propositions addressed to the . will of a rational being. of them. Of the two kinds of propositions which may be so addressed, they are commands; that is to say, precepts in which the cause of obedience depends on the will of him who commands; not counsels, which are precepts in which the reason of obedience is taken from the thing itself which is advised". Being commands, they are accompanied by a sanction; that is to say, they imply, if they do not express, an intimation that their author will see to their being obeyed”. Lastly, they are general commands. They relate to courses of conduct, as opposed to special commands, which enjoin only a particular action”. Laws, therefore, in the vague sense of rules of human action, are propositions commanding the doing, or abstaining from, certain classes of actions; disobedience to which is followed, or is likely to be followed, by some sort of penalty or inconvenience. * Hobbes, Works, ii. p. 183. On ‘Imperium' and “Consilium, cf. Thoma- sius, Fundamenta I. Naturae et G. I.705, p. 133. * Not necessarily by a threat of punishment, as such, but also by a promise of interference to prevent disobedience, or to reinstate things in the position in which they were before the act of disobedience. * Austin, i. p. 11. On the other hand, Blackstone, i. p. 44, makes the gene- rality of a law depend on its being addressed to a class of persons. So Cicero, de Leg. iii. Ig, “legis haec vis est Scitum et iussum in omnes; ' and A. Gellius, x. 20, takes Capito’s definition of lex as ‘generale iussum' to imply that it must be ‘de universis civibus. Cf. Dig. i. 3. I and 8, and Bentham, Nomo- graphy, c. I, Works, iii. p. 233. C 2. 20 LAW. oHAP. II. There are many propositions of this kind which no one is likely seriously to mistake for laws. It is generally under- stood that such phrases as the laws of honour, or of etiquette, are employed, by way of analogy merely, to indicate rules which, either by their trifling importance, or from the limited circle in which they are recognised, differ widely from precepts which are of such vital moment, either on account of the penalties attached to their violation, or of the general acceptance which they find, as to be more ordinarily talked of as ‘laws.’ Uses most The rules of human action which are most often confused ...” with laws proper, are those which are called laws of God, *. laws of nature, and laws of morality. So closely indeed are these topics connected with those proper to Jurisprudence, that many of the older works on the subject are occupied as much with the law of God, or of nature, as with laws proper. Sir Walter Raleigh, for instance, begins a dissertation upon Law, by stating that laws are of three kinds—the eternal or uncreated; the natural or internal; and those which are im- posed, or of addition. These last, which are explicatory and perfecting to the law of nature, are either divine or human ; both of which kinds are again variously subdivided". It will therefore be necessary to touch briefly on those classes of so-called laws which are occasionally confused with laws properly so called. * Works, iii. p. IoI. Cf. Hooker, Eccl. Pol. i. c. 15; Locke, Hum. Underst. ii. § 6; Hobbes, Works, ii. p. 186. CHAPTER III. LAWS AS RULES OF HUMAN ACTION. THE use of the term Law in any but the sciences called . of #: practical or moral, that is to say which have to do with the pººl € human will, is thus merely metaphorical, and irrelevant to sciences. our enquiry". Our only real difficulty is to draw a sharp line between the meaning in which the term is used in Juris- prudence and that in which it is used in the other practical sciences. The task is the more difficult that the line has not at all times been so sharply drawn as it is now possible and desirable to draw it *. The common characteristics of the moral sciences, covering as they do collectively the phenomena of human action, using that term in the widest sense, as including all volitions, whether accompanied or not by external movement, may be summed up as follows: They postulate a will; free at any rate so far as to be influenced by motives presented to it. * The reader need hardly be reminded that by a ‘practical science’ is not meant a body of rules for the government of practice (which would be an art), but the study of the principles upon which, as a matter of fact, human action is governed. r * The expression in Greek writers coming nearest to what we mean by Jurisprudence is probably ‘Politics.” g 22 LAWS AS RULES OF HUMAN ACTION. CHAP. III, They postulate the determination of that will by other causes than the mere sensations of the moment, and, more specifi- cally, by respect for rules of life and conduct. They have many fundamental ideas in common, such as freedom, act, obligation, sanction, command; ideas which they are not bound to analyse exhaustively, but employ in accordance with the usage of ordinary language, and in senses which might be accepted by widely opposed schools of speculation. Each science must define and classify such ideas so far as is necessary for its own purposes, leaving their full and final investigation to Psychology or Metaphysics. Unless the sciences so far respect each other's boundaries, a treatise upon any one of them must be preceded by a sketch of all the rest; and thus it has ha º ed that systems of Juris- prudence have been encumbered with digressions and pole- mics upon questions lying wholly outside of its appropriate province. & Division The resemblances and differences in the employment of of the º º º practical the term ‘a law' in the several practical sciences must be * explained by the resemblances and differences between the sciences themselves. The grand division of these sciences is between that which deals with states of will, irrespectively of their outward manifestation in act, and those which deal with states of the will only so far as they are manifested in action". The former regards, while the latter disregard, those internal acts of the will which do not result in outward acts of the body. The former kind of science is “Ethic.” The latter kinds possess no received collective name, and can therefore be only provisionally designated ‘Nomology.’ The essential difference between them is that Ethic deals not only with the outward results of the determination of that faculty of respect for a rule which is the basis of all the moral sciences, but also, and rather, with the balance of inward forces by which those results are produced. It looks not * Including therein willed inaction. ETHIC AND NOMOLOGY. 23 only to the sort of acts which men do, but also to the sort of CHAP. III. men who do them". Nomology, on the other hand, deals entirely with the conformity or non-conformity of outward acts to rules of conduct. Ethic is the science of the conformity of human character to a type. Nomology, of the conformity of actions to rules. Ethic is the science mainly of duties; while Nomology looks rather to the definition and preservation of rights. The terms right and duty are of course correlatives, and are common to both Ethic and Nomology; but the former science, in accordance with its more inward nature, looks rather to the duties which are binding on the conscience; the latter looks to the rights which are the elements of social life. Ethic has been well described by Kant as concerned with the Ethic. laws for which external legislation is impossible”. It is the science of those rules which when known are themselves adopted by the will as its objects or aims. This rightness of will can never be enforced by external legislation, but must be the free choice of the individual. All that external legislation can do is to affect the external expression of the will in act; and this, not by a rectification of the aim itself of the will, but by causing the will to follow out another aim in act. The science of this office of external regulation is what Nomology. we have called ‘Nomology.” It may be defined as ‘the science of the totality of the laws for which an external legislation is possible”.’ * So Arist. Eth. Nic. ii. 4. Law commands not divöpetav, but rà roß Övöpetov. Ib. iii. 8. I; v. I. I.4. * Tugendlehre, Werke, ix. p. 222. * This definition is applied by Kant, Rechtslehre, ib. p. 31, to the science of Law. He opposes ‘Rechtslehre’ to ‘Tugendlehre, making these two species exhaust the genus ‘Sittenlehre.” Now we have endeavoured to explain that this genus contains the two species “Ethic,’ and what we have called ‘Nomology,’ which latter, besides Jurisprudence, contains other sub-species. We submit that Rant's definition as he applies it is too wide. There are rules of action which can be imposed by external authority, and yet are not laws. His definition should apply, as we have applied it, to a class of sciences, of which Juris- prudence is only one. 24 LAWS AS RULES OF HUMAN ACTION. CHAP. III. The moral sciences having thus been grouped under the head of Ethic, when the object of investigation is the con- formity of the will to a rule; and of Nomology, when the object of investigation is the conformity of acts to a rule, we pass by the former, as foreign to our subject, and confine our attention to the latter. Rules of Nomology, the science of external action, must be divided, º according to the authority by which the rules of which it treats are enforced, into— I. A science of rules enforced by indeterminate authority. II. A science of rules enforced by determinate authority. enforced by I. What may be vaguely called ‘moral laws’ are of very indetermi- * tº º ſº * sº tº a $º nate various origin and obligation. Their common characteristic * is that, although no definite authority can be appealed to in case of their infraction, yet those who obey them are regarded with favour, and those who disobey them with disfavour, either by society in general or by a section of it. Under this large category may be classed the laws of usage in the pro- nunciation of words, of fashion in the choice of dress, of social demeanour, of professional etiquette, or of honour between gentlemen, as well as the gravest precepts of morality, specifically so called. All of them possess the common characteristic of being generally received in certain circles of society, while anything done in contravention of them exposes the transgressor to various shades of ridicule, hatred, or coercion. #: º: The weakest sort of these rules are undoubtedly those of fashion and etiquette; deviation from which is called eccen- tricity or vulgarity, and is visited by penalties varying from a smile to ostracism from society. - of honour, A somewhat stronger force may be attributed to the so- called law of honour, deviations from which are in this country stigmatised as ‘conduct unbecoming a gentleman.” This however, so far as it exceeds in delicacy the dictates of ordinary morality, is recognised by a comparatively small MORAL LAWS, 25 class, and, as has been well observed, regulates only the duties betwixt equals". Far more important are those pre- cepts which are more usually called principles of morality, and the infraction of which is called vice. As to the origin and authority of the laws of fashion, and of the code of honour, there is no mystery. Every one admits that these are, though in different degrees, conventional, and have grown up in particular circles and states of society to which they were found beneficial. With reference to those wider formulas called moral principles, there is by no means CHAP. III. of morality. the same consent. This great body of maxims, regulating the relations of man to man in all the intercourse of life, would seem to have grown up partly under the influence of religion, partly out of speculative theories, partly out of the necessities of existence. Which of these ingredients is the essential, or the most essential, element of morality, may well be questioned. It is at any rate certain that morality is not due to the direct interposition of political authority. Into the battles which are perpetually raging as to the essential quality of virtue in itself, and as to the faculty by which the virtuous quality of actions is discerned 4, it is not the business of the jurist to enter. He is not obliged to decide whether the criterion of virtue be conduciveness to utility, or accordance with nature; nor need he profess his belief, or disbelief, either in an innate moral sense, or in a categorical imperative of the practical reason. These are the hard questions of Metaphysics. *The business of the jurist is, in the first place, to accept as an undoubted fact the existence of moral principles in the world, differing in many particulars in different nations and at different epochs, but having certain broad resemblances; and, in the second place, to observe the sort of sanction by which these prin- ciples are made effective. He will then be in a position 1 Paley, Mor. Phil. book i. ch. 2. Cf. Thering, Der Kampf ums Recht, P. 25. * See Dugald Stewart, Philosophy of the Active and Moral Powers. 26 LAWS AS RULES OF HUMAN ACTION. CHAP. III. to draw unswervingly the line which divides such moral laws from the laws which are the subjects of his proper science *. While the broad resemblance of the moral principles of mankind is universally admitted, the occasional divergencies between them are frequently lost sight of. The truth upon this point is admirably expressed by Paley. “Moral approba- tion,’ he writes, ‘follows the fashions and institutions of the country we live in ; which fashions also and institutions them- selves have grown out of the exigencies, the climate, situation, or local circumstances of the country, or have been set up by the authority of an arbitrary chieftain or the unaccountable caprice of the multitude”.” As to the sanction of moral rules, in the wide sense of the term, it was well said by Locke that “no man escapes the punishment of their censure and dislike who offends against the fashion and opinion of the company he keeps, and would recommend himself to it *.” Such rules are thus by no means without their appropriate sanction. We cannot therefore, with Thomasius, see in the presence or absence of com- pulsion the dividing characteristic between morality and Law 4. Enough has perhaps been said with reference to moral rules generally. One class of these rules has however exer- cised so wide an influence, and is so intimately connected with our more immediate subject, as to demand a more extended notice. That portion of morality which supplies the more important and universal rules for the governance of the outward acts of mankind is called the ‘Law of Nature.” The law of Nature. * Cf. Kant, Tugendlehre, Werke, ix. p. 217. - * Mor. Phil. book i. ch. 5. Cf. Herodotus, iii. 38; Arist. Eth. Nic. v. 7; Pascal, Pensées, vi. 9; Montaigne, Essais, i. ch. 22. * Human Understanding, book ii. §§ 1–12, where he scarcely does justice to the effects produced by sympathy with the sentiment of our fellow-creatures. * Fund. I. Nat. ii. c. 6. § 3. THE LAW OF NATURE. - 27 This is a plain and, it is submitted, true account of a subject upon which a vast amount of mystical writing has been ex- pended. Such of the received precepts of morality relating to overt acts, and therefore capable of being enforced by a political authority, as either are enforced by such authority or are supposed to be fit so to be enforced, are called ‘laws of Nature.’ They are precepts obedience to which, whether it be or be not commanded by the State, is insisted upon by a deep-rooted public sentiment. Resting essentially upon public sentiment, they are rules of morality; but having reference only to such outward actions as are thought fit for political enforcement, they form only one class of such rules. After what has been said as to the origin and authority of moral rules in general, it will be unnecessary to discuss at length the origin and authority of such moral rules as are called natural laws. Whatever may be the objective charac- ter of those laws", whether they should be identified with the will of God, or should be supposed to be in some sort the guides even of that will, it is enough for the jurist that they certainly rest, like other moral rules, upon the support of public sentiment. While there has been much difference of opinion as to the contents of the Law of Nature, the existence of such a law has been very generally admitted. At the time when the social were first separated from the physical sciences, speculation recognised in the former nothing but what is variable and arbitrary. Thus Demo- critus taught that legal institutions were of human devising, while atoms and vacuum exist by Nature”. It was the stock sophistical doctrine that moral distinctions, especially Justice, are the creatures of law; which is itself a mere compromise, securing each man against injury on condition 1 Whether for instance it be more true to say with Cicero, De Leg. ii. 4, ‘Lex vera, ratio est recta summi Tovis,” or with Horace, Sat. i. 2, 98, ‘Utilitas iusti prope mater et aequi.’ * IIointá Šč véulpa elval, pögel 68 drópous kai keväv. Diog. Laert. ix. 45. & CHAP. III.