tº § *** . . * gº K. Yoº* §. l'ſ 3 , Z51 P E 5 183 | A HISTORY OF GREEK PHILOSOPHY WOL. I. LONDON : PRINTED BY SPOTTIS WOODE AND CO., NEW-8TREET 80UARE AND PAR [,][AAFENT STREET l A HISTORY GREEK PHILOSOPHY FROM THE EARLIEST PERIOD TO THE TIME OF SOCRATES WITH A G E W E R A L T W T R O D U 0 7"I O W TRANSLATED . THE GERMAN OF I)R. E." ZELLER PROFESS OR IN THE UNIVERSITY OF B E R LIN fuith the 3mthor's sanction BY S. F. ALLEYNE I N T W O V O L U M ES VOL. I. LONDON L O N G MAN S, G RE EN, A ND CO. 1881 All rights reserved * º as tº ºf : 4 - 27-37 2 ve”, TRANSLATOR'S PREFACE. THE present work is a translation of the fourth and last edition of the first part of Dr. Zeller's “Philo- sophie der Griechen.' That this part, containing the General Introduction to the entire subject and the his– tory of the earliest philosophers, should appear after others dealing with the later periods, is in some mea- sure to be regretted, because Greek Philosophy is best treated as a whole, and gains immensely by being studied in the order of development; yet those who are acquainted with the previously translated portions of Dr. Zeller's work will be the more ready to welcome the introductory volume, without which, indeed, many things in the later philosophy, and in Dr. Zeller's treat- ment of it, would have remained comparatively obscure. There is no need to speak highly of a work so well known. The translator has endeavoured to make her version as literal as possible, considering the require- ments of the English language and its deficiency in precise equivalents for German philosophical terms—a vi TRANSLATOR'S PREFACE. deficiency giving rise to many difficulties which she cannot hope to have always successfully overcome. She desires to express her hearty thanks to Mr. EvelyN ABBOTT, Fellow and Tutor of Balliol College, Oxford, for his valuable assistance in reading over the proof sheets, especially in regard to the Greek notes. It is, perhaps, necessary to add, respecting the numerous references, that Vol. I. and II. stand for the volumes of the present translation, and Part I. II. and III. for the divisions of the German work. CLIFTon : December 6, 1880. AUTHOR'S PREFACE. TWENTY YEARS AGo, when I published in its later form the first volume of this work, originally designed on a different plan, and a far more limited scale, I ex- plained in the following words the principles which had guided me in its composition: “In the treatment of my subject I have constantly kept in view the task which I proposed to myself in my first approaches to it: viz. to maintain a middle course between erudite en- quiry and the speculative study of history: neither, on the one hand, to collect facts in a merely empirical manner; mor, on the other, to construct a priori theories; but through the traditions themselves, by means of cri- tical sifting and historical combination, to arrive at a knowledge of their importance and interdependence. This task, however, in regard to the pre-Socratic philo- sophy was rendered peculiarly difficult by the character of the sources and the divergencies of modern opinions respecting them : it was impossible adequately to fulfil it without a number of critical discussions, often descending to the minutest details. That the clearness viii A UTHOR'S PREFA CE. of the historical exposition, however, might not be thereby impaired, I have consigned these discussions as much as possible to the notes, where also the testi- monies and references respecting the authorities find a fitting place. But the writings from which these are taken are many, and some of them difficult to obtain, so that it has often been necessary to give the quota- tions at length to make it possible for the reader to test the authenticity of my exposition without an unwarrant- able expenditure of time. Thus the amount of notes, and consequently the size of the whole volume, have increased to a considerable extent; but I hope I have chosen rightly in attending before all things to the scientific requirements of the reader, and in doubtful cases preferring to economise his time rather than the printer's paper.” I have kept to the same points of view in the pre- paration of the following volumes, and of the new editions which have since become necessary. The hope that I have therein adopted the proper course has been fully justified by the reception given to my work; and though the principle (not previously quite unknown to me) has recently been pressed upon my attention, that the ancient philosophers must be treated philosophically, I have never yet been able to convince myself that the method hitherto pursued by me has been a mistake. I still hold, more strongly than ever, that the philosophic apprehension of systems of philosophy (which, however, must be distinguished from philosophic criticism) en- A UTHOR'S PREFACE. IX tirely coincides with the historic apprehension of them. I can never indeed consider that a proper history has been written if the author has stopped short at the bare enumeration of isolated doctrines and statements without enquiring as to their centre of gravity, examining their interconnection, or tracing out their exact meaning; without determining their relation and importance to the various systems collectively. But, on the other hand, I must protest against the misuse of the noble name of philosophy for the purpose of depriving his– torical phenomena of their distinctive character, of forcing upon the ancient philosophers inferences which they expressly repudiate, of effacing the contradictions and supplying the lacunae of their systems with adjuncts that are pure inventions. The great phenomena of the past are much too great in my eyes for me to suppose that I could do them any service by exalting them above their historical conditions and limitations. In my opinion, such a false idealisation makes them smaller instead of greater. At all events, nothing can thereby be gained for historic truth, before which every predi- lection for particular persons and schools must give way. Whoever would expound a philosophic system must re- produce the theories held by its author in the connection which they had in his mind. This we can only learn from the testimony of the philosophers themselves, and from the statements of others concerning their doctrines; but, in comparing these testimonies, in examining their authenticity and credibility, in completing them by in- X. A UTHOR'S PREFA CE. ferences and combinations of various kinds, we must be careful to remember two things: in the first place, the inductions which carry us beyond direct testimony must in each case be founded on the totality of evidence in our possession ; and when a philosophic theory seems to us to require certain further theories, we must always examine whether other portions of the author's system, quite as important in his estimation, do not stand in the way. Secondly, we must enquire whether we are justi- fied in supposing that the philosopher we are considering propounded to himself the questions which we are pro- pounding to him, returned to himself the answers which we derive from other statements of his, or himself drew the inferences which to w8 appear necessary. To pro- ceed in this spirit of scientific circumspection has been at any rate my own endeavour. To this end, as will be seen in the later no less than in the earlier editions of my work, I have also tried to learn from those writers who here and there, on points of greater or lesser importance, have differed from me. If I am indebted to these writers for many things that have assisted in the completion and correction of my exposition, it will nevertheless be understood that, in all essential points, I could only re- main true to my own view of the pre-Socratic philo- sophy, and have defended that view as persistently and decidedly as the interest of the subject demanded, against objections which seemed to me unconvincing and untenable. I dedicated the second edition of the present work AUTHOR'S PREFA CE. xi to my father-in-law, Dr. F. CHR. BAUR, of Tübingen. In the third I was obliged to omit the dedication, because he to whom it was addressed was no longer among us. But I cannot refrain from recalling in this place, with affection and gratitude, the memory of a man who was not only to me in all personal relations a friend and father, but also, in regard to my scientific labours, has left for me and for all his disciples a shining example of incorruptible love of truth, untiring perse- verance in research, inexhaustible diligence, penetrative criticism, and width and coherence in the treatment of history. BERLIN : October 18, 1876. CONTENTS () F T H E FIRST V O L U M E. TRANSLATOR's PREFACE AUTHOR's PREFACE . GENERAL INTRODUCTION. *-* CHAPTER I. AIM, scope, AND METHOD of THE PRESENT work CHAPTER TI. ORIGIN OF GREEK PHILOSOPHY. i. Supposed derivation of Greek philosophy from Oriental speculation e e º º e e ii. Native sources of Greek philosophy. 1. Religion º º a. Greek religion e b. The Mysteries . e e e - iii. Native sources of Greek philosophy (continued). 2. Moral life: civil and political conditions iv. Native sources of Greek philosophy (continued). 3. Cosmology * ſº - º & * v. Ethical reflection. 4. Theology and Anthropology in relation to Ethics . PAG # vii xiv CONTENTS OF THE FIRST VOLUME, THE PRINCIPAL PERIODS IN THE DEVELOPMENT OF GREEK INTRODUCTION. ON THE CHARACTER AND DEVELOPMENT OF : CELAPTER III. PAGR, ON THE CHARACTER OF GREEK PHILOSOPHY 129–163 CHAPTER IV. PHILOSOPHY e * tº ſº © * * 164—183 FIRST PIERIOD. THE PRE-SOCRATIC PHILOSOPHY. PHILOSOPHY IN THE FIRST PERIOD e tº tº . 184—210 FIRST SECTION. THE EARLIER IONIANS, PYTHAGOREANS, AND ELEATICS. I. THE EARLIER Ion IAN PHYSICS. . Thales . Anaximander . Anaximenes . . Later adherents of the Ionian School. Diogenes of Apollonia II. THE PyTHAGoREANs. . Sources of our knowledge in regard to the Pythagorean philo- sophy . & . Pythagoras and the Pythagoreans . ſº º sº. ſº sº . The Pythagorean philosophy: its fundamental conceptions: Number and the Elements of Number . Systematic development of the Number system, and its appli- cation to Physics 211 227 266 280 306 324 368 419 CONTENT'S OF THE FIRST VOLUME, XV 7 : . Religious and ethical doctrines of the Pythagoreans . . Retrospective summary: character, origin, and antiquity of the Pythagorean philosophy . - º . Pythagoreanism in combination with other elements: Alcmaeon, Hippasus, Ecphantus, Epicharmus . e & & º III. THE ELEATICS. . Sources in regard to their doctrines. Treatise on Melissus, Xenophanes, and Gorgias . Xenophanes . Parmenides . Zeno . . Melissus tº & tº - - º g . Historical position and character of the Eleatic School PA(; R. 481 496 521 533 556 580 608 627 638 IE R. R. A.T A. Page 4, line 9—for Shepherd Bookoi read herds of grazing Boaxoi. », 54, line 2 from foot—for particulars read particular. ,, 72, line 19—for seventeenth read seventh. ,, 94, 2, line 17—for sup. p. 93 read sup. p. 91, 3 ; cf. 98, 4. ,, 145, 1, line 2—for the Protagoras read Protagoras. ,, 214, n. 1ine 28 (first column)—for Anacolius read Anatolius. ,, 219, 3, line 10 (second column)—for affinity read infinity. ,, 231, m. line 20 (first column)—for 238, 1 read 228, 3. , 247, 1—for 223, 1 read 233, 1. ., 251, line 9—for surrounds read surrounded. , 260, 4—for 151, 1 read 251, 1. , 263, 2—for pp. 197, 200 read 241, 244. , 265, 3–for 197 read 241. , 269, 2, line 8—for 268, 1 read 267, 1. ,, 288, 3—for 241, 1 read 241, 2. ,, 289, 1, line 9—for 291, 1 read 291, 2. , 292, 1–for 290, 4 read 291, 1. ,, 352, 1–for 336, 4 read 336, 5. , 434, 2, line 2—for 426, 6 read 429, 6. , 444, 1, line 3—for conservation read assertion. ,, 444, 2—for 442, 1 read 443, 1. , 468, 1, line 5 from foot (second column)—for 415 read 526. ,, 527, 3–for 372, 1 read 372, 4. , 527, 4, line 4 from foot—for 491 read 528. ,, 531, 2—for 529, 5 read 530, 2. ,, 538, 1—for 547, 1 read 548, 1. , 543, 1, line 14 (second column)—for 547, 1 read 548, 1. ,, 554, 4–for 547, 1 read 548, 1. ,, 554, 4–for 542, 1 read 548, 1. , 560, 1, lines 18 and 19—for infra read supra; for 544, 1 read 545, 1. ,, 566, 1—for 549, 1 read 548, 2; for 560, 2 read 562, 5. ,, 587, line 8—omit therefore , 608, 2, lines 4 and 7—for 543 read 617, n. ; for 590, 1 read 591, 1. , 623, line 19—for connections read connection. THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE GREEKS IN ITS HISTORICAL DEVELOPMENT, IWTRODÚCTION. CHAPTER I. AIM, SCOPE AND METHOD OF THE PRESENT WORK. THE term Philosophy, as in use among the Greeks, varied greatly in its meaning and compass." Originally it denoted all mental culture, and all effort in the direction of culture; * even as orogºta, the word from which it is derived, was applied to every art and every kind of knowledge.” A more restricted significance seems first to have been given to it in the time of the Sophists, when it became usual to seek after a wider knowledge by means of more special and adequate 1. Cf. the valuable evidence of Haym in Ersch and Gruber's Allge- meine Encyklopaedie, sect. iii. b. 24, p. 3 Sqq. * Thus Croesus says to Solon (Herodotus, i. 30) that he had heard &s pixocoq'éav yºv troAAhv 6eapíms eiveksv étrexhAv6as. Similarly, Pe- ricles (Thucydides, ii. 40), in the funeral oration: pixokaAoûuev ytºp ust' siteAetas kai pixooroqoºyiew &vev WOL. I. Maxaktas. The same vague use of the word is long after to be met with even among writers who are not unacquainted with the stricter SeſkSø. * Cf. Aristotle's Eth. Nie. vi. 7, sub init., and the verse quoted by him from the Homeric Margites. Cf. also infra, the section on the Sophists. 2 INTRODUCTION. instruction than ordinary education and the unmethodi- cal routine of practical life could of themselves afford." By Philosophy was now understood the study of things of the mind, pursued not as an accessory employment and matter of amusement, but exclusively and as a separate vocation. The word Philosophy, however, was not as yet limited to philosophic science in its present acceptation, nor even to science in general, for which other designations were much more in vogue: to philo- sophise was to study, to devote oneself to any theoretic activity.” Philosophers in the narrower sense, down to the time of Socrates, were Ordinarily designated as wise men or Sophists,” and, more precisely, as physicists.” A more definite use of the word is first met with in Plato. Plato calls that man a philosopher who in his speculation and his practice has regard to essence, and not to appearance; Philosophy, as he apprehends it, is * Pythagoras indeed, according to a well-known anecdote, had pre- viously assumed the name of phi- losopher; but the story is in the first place uncertain ; and in the second it keeps the indeterminate sense of the word according to which philosophy signified all striving after wisdom. * The expression, for example, in Xenophon (Mem. iv. 2, 23) has this sense; for the philosophy of Euthydemus (according to section 1) consists in his studying the wri- tings of the poets and Sophists; and similarly in Conv. 1, 5, Socrates compares himself, as airoup'yos ris quxoa opias, with Callias, the disci- ple of the Sophists. Also in Cyrop. vi. 1,41, pixogoſpelvimeans generally to cogitate, to study. Isocrates uses it in this way (Paneg. c. 1) when he calls his own activity rºv trepl rows Aóryovs pińooroq tav, or even simply quxogoſpía, piñooroºpeiv (Panath. c. 4, 5, 8; trepi &vrtöoor. 181–186, 271, 285 and elsewhere. Plato himself adopts this wider meaning in Gorgias 484 C and 485 A sqq., Protagoras 335 D, Lysis 213 D. Cf. also the commencement of the Menea:enws. * This name was given, for in- stance, to the seven wise men, to Solon, Pythagoras and Socrates; also to the pre-Socratic natural philosophers. Wide infra, loc. cit. * Pvorikot, pugioxóryot, the recog- nised name for the philosophers especially of the Ionian schools, and those connected with them. DEFINITION OF PHILOSOPHY, 3 the elevation of the mind towards true Reality,+the scientific cognition and moral exposition of the idea. Finally, Aristotle still further limits the sphere of Philo- sophy, by wholly excluding from it practical activity; but he fluctuates between a wider and a marrower definition. According to the wider, Philosophy includes all scientific knowledge and research ; according to the narrower, it is restricted to enquiries concerning the ulti- mate causes of things, the so-called “First Philosophy.’ Scarcely, however, had this beginning been made towards a precise determination of Philosophy when the attempt was again abandoned; Philosophy in the post-Aristotelian schools is sometimes exclusively de- fined as the practice of wisdom, the art of happiness, the science of life; sometimes it is hardly discriminated from the empirical sciences, and sometimes confounded with mere erudition. This confusion was promoted, not only by the learned tendencies of the Peripatetic school and of the whole Alexandrian period, but also and more especially by Stoicism, since Chrysippus had included in the circle of his so-called philosophical enquiries the arts of grammar, music, &e., while his very definition of Philosophy, as the science of things divine and human, must have rendered difficult any precise limitation of its domain." After this period science became more and more involved with mythology and theological poetry, to the increasing disturbance of the boundaries of both these spheres; and the concep- * Appealing to this definition, mathy, says he, is the business of a Strabo, at the opening of his work, philosopher. Further authorities declares geography to be an essen- for the above will be given in the tial part of philosophy; for poly- course of this work, B 2 4 INTRODUCTION. tion of Philosophy soon lost all distinctness. On the one hand, the Neo-Platonists regarded Linus and Orpheus as the first of philosophers, the Chaldean oracles as the primitive sources of the highest wisdom, and the sacred rites, asceticism and theurgic superstition of their school as the true philosophy; on the other, the Christian theologians, with equal right, glorified mo- mastic life as Christian philosophy, and gave to the various sects of monks, including even the Shepherd Bookol, a name which Plato and Aristotle had reserved for the highest activity of the human intellect." But it is not merely the name which is wanting in accurate limitation and fixity of import. Uncertainty of language usually implies uncertainty of thought, and the present case forms no exception. If the extent of the term Philosophy was only gradually settled, Philo- sophy itself only gradually appeared as a specific form of intellectual life. If the word fluctuates between a wider and a narrower significance, Philosophy similarly fluctuates; being sometimes restricted to a definite scientific sphere, and sometimes mingled with alien ingredients of various kinds. The pre-Socratic Philo- sophy developed itself partly in connection with mytho- logical ideas. Even for Plato the mythus is a necessity, * pixooroºpeſv and pixooropta are the ordinary terms employed at that period to designate the ascetic life and its various forms; so that, for example, Sozomenus, in the case above mentioned (Hist. Eccles. vi. 33), concludes his statement about the Boarkoſ with the words kal of wev $6e équxogóqovv. Christianity itself is not unfrequently called quxoaroq'ía; thus Melito, in Euse- bius's Church History, iv. 26, 7, speaks of the Judaic-Christian re- ligion as # kaff huas puxoa opia. Philo similarly (quod omnis pro- bus liber, 877 C, D; vita contemplat. 893 D) describes the theology of the Essenes and Therapeutae, with its allegorical interpretation of Scripture, as piñocoq ety, Trérpios qiaoropia. DEFINITION OF PHILOSOPHY, 5 and after the period of Neo-Pythagoreism, polytheistic theology acquires such an influence over Philosophy that Philosophy at last becomes merely the interpreter of theological traditions. With the Pythagoreans, the Sophists, Socrates, the Cynics and the Cyrenaics, Scientific speculation was connected with practical en- quiries, which these philosophers did not themselves discriminate from their science. Plato reckons moral conduct as much a part of Philosophy as knowledge ; while after Aristotle, Philosophy was so increasingly regarded from the practical point of view, that it ulti- mately became identified with moral culture and true religion. Lastly, among the Greeks, the sciences (in the modern acceptation of the term) were only by slow degrees, and at no time very accurately, discriminated from Philosophy. Philosophy in Greece is not merely the central point towards which all scientific efforts converge; it is, originally, the whole which includes them in itself. The sense of form peculiar to the Greek cannot let him rest in any partial or isolated view of things; moreover, his knowledge was at first so limited that he was far less occupied than we are with the study of the particular. From the outset, therefore, his glance was directed to the totality of things, and it was only by little and little that particular sciences separated themselves from this collective science. Plato himself, excluding the mechanical and practical arts, recognises only Philosophy and the various branches of mathematics as Sciences proper; indeed, the treatment he claims for mathematics would make it simply a part of Philo- sophy. Aristotle includes under Philosophy, besides G INTRODUCTION. mathematics, all his physical enquiries, deeply as these enter into the study of the particular. It was only in the Alexandrian period that the special sciences attained to independent cultivation. We find, however, among the Stoics, as well as the Peripatetics, that philosophic enquiry was blended with, and often hampered by, a great mass of erudition and empirical observations. In the eclecticism of the Roman period, this erudite element was still more prominent; and though the founder of Neo-Platonism confined himself strictly to questions of pure philosophy, his school, in its reliance on the authorities of antiquity, was apt to overlade its philosophic expositions with a superabundance of learning. If, then, we are to include in the history of Greek Philosophy all that was called Philosophy by the Greeks, or that is brought forward in philosophic writ- ings, and exclude all that does not expressly bear the name, it is evident that the boundaries of our exposition will be in part too narrow, and in part, and for the most part, much too wide. If, on the other hand, we are to treat of Philosophy in itself, as we find it in Greece, whether called Philosophy or not, the question arises how it is to be recognised and how we are to distinguish it from what is not Philosophy. It is clear that such a test can only lie in the conception formed of Philosophy. This conception, however, changes with the philosophic standpoint of individuals and of whole periods; and thus it would appear that the sphere of the history of Philosophy must constantly change in like manner and in the same proportion. The dilemma lies in the 1) EFINITION OF PHILOSOPHY. 7 nature of things and is in no way to be avoided; least of all by basing our procedure, not on fixed conceptions, but on confused impressions, and indefinite, perhaps contradictory, ideas; or by trusting, each writer for himself, to an obscure historical sense to determine how much he shall include in his exposition or reject from it. For if philosophic conceptions alter, subjective impressions alter yet more, and the only resource that would at last remain to us in this uncertain method— namely, a reference to learned usage—would not improve matters from a scientific point of view. One thing, at any rate, follows from these reflections. We must have, as the basis of our exposition, as true and exhaustive a theory as we can of the essence of Philosophy. That this is not altogether impracticable, and that some degree of unanimity is attainable on the subject, there is all the more reason to hope, because we are here concerned not with the terms and constituents of any one philosophic system, but with the general and formal conception of Philosophy, as it is assumed, tacitly, or in express terms, in every system. Different opinions are possible, to some extent, even here; but this diffi- culty is common to all walks of knowledge. We can only, each one of us according to his ability, seek out the truth, and leave what we find to be corrected, if necessary, by advancing science. How Philosophy is to be defined, is therefore a question which philosophic science alone can answer. I must here confine myself to a statement of the results at which I have arrived in regard to the matter, so far as this is necessary for the task I have in hand. I con- 8 INTRODUCTION. sider Philosophy, first, as a purely theoretic activity; that is, an activity which is solely concerned with the ascertainment of reality; and from this point of view, I exclude from the conception and history of Philosophy all practical or artistic efforts as such, irrespective of their possible connection with any particular theory of the world. I next define Philosophy more precisely as science. I see in it not merely thought, but thought that is methodical, and directed in a conscious manner to the cognition of things in their interdependence. By this characteristic, I distinguish it as well from the unscientific reflection of daily life as from the religious and poetical view of the world. Lastly, I find the dis- tinction between Philosophy and other sciences is this:– that all other sciences aim at the exploration of some specific sphere, whereas Philosophy has in view the sum total of existence as a whole, seeks to know the individual in its relation to the whole, and by the laws of the whole, and so to attain the correlation of all knowledge. So far, therefore, as this aim can be shown to exist, so far and no farther I should extend the do- main of the history of Philosophy. That such an aim was not clearly evident from the beginning, and was at first abundantly intermingled with foreign elements, we have already seen, nor can we wonder at it. But this need not prevent our abstracting from the aggregate of Greek intellectual life all that bears the character of Philosophy, and considering it in and for itself, in its historical manifestation. There is, indeed, some danger, in this mode of procedure, of doing violence to the actual historical connection; but this danger we may GREEK PHILOSOPHY, 9 escape by allowing full weight to such considerations as the following: the constant interminglement of philo- sophic with other elements; the gradual nature of the development by which science won for itself an inde- pendent existence; the peculiar character of the later syncretism; the importance of Philosophy for culture in general, and its dependence on existing conditions. If due account be taken of these circumstances, if in the several systems we are careful to distinguish what is philosophical from what is merely accessory, and to measure the importance of the individual, in regard to the development of philosophic thought, by the precise standard and concept of Philosophy, the claims of historic completeness and scientific exactitude will be equally satisfied. The object of our exposition having been thus determined on one of its sides, and the Philosophy of the Greeks clearly distinguished from the phenomena akin to it and connected with it, there remains the farther question as to the extent and boundaries of Greek Philosophy; whether we are to seek it only among the members of the Greek race, or in the whole field of Hellenic culture; and, in the latter case, how the area of that field is to be determined. This is, of course, more or less optional; and it would in itself be perfectly legitimate either to close the history of Greek science with its passage into the Roman and Oriental world, or, on the other hand, to trace its effects down to our own time. It seems, however, most natural to call Philosophy Greek, so long as there is in it a pre- ponderance of the Hellenic element over the foreign, 10 INTRODUCTION. and whenever that proportion is reversed to abandon the name. As the former is the case not only with the Graeco-Roman Philosophy, but also with the Neo- Platonists and their predecessors; as even the Judaic- Alexandrian school is much more closely related to the contemporary Greek Philosophy, and had much more influence on its development, than any phenomenon of the Christian world, I include this school in the compass of the present exposition. On the other hand, I exclude from it the Christian speculation of the first centuries, for there we see Hellenic science overpowered by a new principle in which it henceforth lost its specific character. The scientific treatment of this historical material must necessarily follow the same laws as the writing of history in general. Our task is to ascertain and to expound what has happened ; a philosophic construction of it, even if this were possible, would not be the affair of the historian. But such a construction is not possible, for two reasons. First, because no one will ever attain to so exhaustive a conception of humanity, and so exact a knowledge of all the conditions of its historical development, as to justify his deducing from thence the particulars of its empirical circumstances, and the changes undergone by these in time; and next, because the course of history is not of such a nature that it can be made the object of an à priori con- struction. For history is essentially the product of the free activity of individuals, and though in this very activity an universal law is working, and through this activity fulfilling itself, yet none of its special effects, and not even the most important phenomena of history IIISTORICAL METHOD; AGAINST HEGEL. 11 in all their particular features, can be fully explained from the point of view of a priori necessity. The actions of individuals are subject to that contingency which is the heritage of the finite will and under- standing; and if from the concurrence, the collision, and the friction of these individual actions, a regular course of events as a whole is finally produced, neither the particular in this course, nor even the whole, is at any point absolutely necessary. All is necessary in so far only as it belongs to the general progress, the logical framework as it were of history; while as to its chrono- logical manifestation, all is more or less contingent. So closely are the two elements interwoven with each other that it is impossible, even in our reflections, wholly to separate them. The necessary accomplishes itself by a number of intermediaries, any one of which might be conceived other than it is ; but, at the same time, the practised glance can detect the thread of historical necessity in notions and actions apparently the most fortuitous; and from the arbitrary conduct of men who lived hundreds and thousands of years ago, circumstances may have arisen which work on us with all the strength of such a necessity." The sphere of history, therefore, is distinct in its nature from that of Philosophy. Philosophy has to seek out the essence of things, and the general laws of events; history has to exhibit definite given phenomena of a certain date, and to explain them by their empirical conditions. * A more particular discussion moral order of the world.—Theolo- of these questions will be found gisches Jahrbuch, v. vi. (1846 and in my dissertation on the freedom 1847); cf. especially vi. 220 sqq.; of the human will, on evil, and the 253 sqq. 12 INTRODUCTION. Each of these sciences requires the other, but neither can be supplanted by or substituted for the other; nor in its procedure can the history of Philosophy take the same course that would be applicable to the formation of a philosophic system. To say that the historical sequence of the philosophic systems is identical with the logical sequence of the concepts which characterise them,' is to confound two very different things. Logic, as Hegel conceived it, has to expound the pure cate- gories of thought as such ; the history of Philosophy is concerned with the chronological development of human thought. If the course of the one were to coincide with that of the other, this would presuppose that logical or, more precisely, ontological conceptions form the essential content of all systems of Philosophy; and that these conceptions have been attained in the progress of history from the same starting-point, and in the same order as in the logical construction of pure con- cepts. But this is not the case. Philosophy is not merely Logic or Ontology; its object is, in a general sense, the Real. The various philosophic systems show us the sum total of the attempts hitherto made to gain a scientific view of the world. Their content, therefore, cannot be reduced to mere logical categories without 1 Hegel's Geschichte der Philo- sophie, i. 43. Against this asser- tion objections were raised by me in the Jahrbücher der Gegenwart, 1843, p. 209, sq.; and by Schweg- ler in his Geschichte der Philoso- phie, p. 2 sq.; which objections I repeated in the second edition of the present work. This gave occa- sion to Herr Monrad, professor at Christiania, in a letter addressed to me, bearing the title Devi logica rationis in describenda philosophiæ historia (Christiania, 1860), to de- fend the proposition of Hegel. In consequence of this treatise, which I cannot here examine in detail, I have made some changes in the form of my discussion, and also some additions. HISTORICAL METHOD; AGAINST HEGEL. 13 depriving it of its specific character and merging it in the universal. Moreover, while speculative Logic begins with the most abstract conceptions, in order thence to attain to others more concrete, the historical development of philosophic thought starts with the consideration of the concrete, first in external nature, then in man, and leads only by degrees to logical and metaphysical abstractions. The law of development also is different in Logic and in History. Logic is occupied merely with the internal relation of concepts, irrespective of any chronological relation; History treats of the changes effected in course of time in the notions of mankind. Progress, from anterior to posterior con- cepts, is regulated, in the former case, exclusively according to logical points of view ; each conclusion is therefore linked to the next that is properly deducible from it by thought. In the latter case, progression takes place according to psychological motives; each philosopher constructs out of the doctrine inherited from his predecessors, and each period out of that handed down to it by tradition, whatever their own apprehension of the doctrine, their modes of thought, experiences, knowledge, necessities, and scientific re- sources enable them to construct; but this may possibly be something quite other than what we, from our stand- point, should construct out of it. Logical consequence can only regulate the historical progress of Philosophy to the extent that it is recognised by the philosophers, and the necessity of following it acknowledged; how far that is the case depends on all the circumstances by which scientific convictions are conditioned. Over and above 14 INTRODUCTION. what may be directly or indirectly derived from the earlier Philosophy, either by inference or polemic, a decisive in- fluence is often exercised in this respect by the conditions and necessities of practical life, by religious interests, and by the state of empirical knowledge and general culture. It is impossible to regard all systems as merely the consequences of their immediate predecessors, and mo system which contributes special thoughts of its own can in its origin and contents be thus restricted. What is new in those thoughts arises from new experiences having been made, or new points of view gained for such as had been previously made; aspects and elements of these which before were unnoticed are now taken into account, and some particular moment is invested with another meaning than heretofore. Far, them, from assenting to the Hegelian position, we must rather maintain that no system of Philosophy is so constituted that its principle may be expressed by a purely logical conception; not one has formed itself out of its pre- decessors simply according to the law of logical progress. Any survey of the past will show us how impossible it is to recognise, even approximately, the order of the Hegelian or any other speculative logic in the order of the philo- sophic systems, unless we make out of them something quite different from...what they really are. This attempt is, therefore, a failure both in principle and practice, and the truth it contains is only the universal conviction that the development of history is internally governed by regular laws. This conviction, indeed, the history of Philosophy ought on no account to renounce; we need not confine LA WS AND UNITY OF HISTORY. 15 ourselves to the mere amassing and critical testing of traditions, or to that unsatisfactory pragmatic pro- cedure which is content to explain particulars severally in reference to individual personalities, circumstances and influences, but attempts no explanation of the whole as such. Our exposition must, of course, be grounded upon historical tradition, and all that it treats of must either be directly contained in tradition, or derived from it by strictest deduction. But it is impos- sible even to establish our facts, so long as we regard them merely in an isolated manner. Tradition is not itself fact; we shall never succeed in proving its trust- worthiness, in solving its contradictions, in supplying its lacunae, if we do not keep in view the connection of single facts, the concatenation of causes and effects, the place of the individual in the whole. Still less, how- ever, is it possible to understand facts, apart from this interconnection, or to arrive at a knowledge of their essential nature and historical importance. Where, lastly, our exposition is concerned with scientific sys- tems, and not merely with opinions and events, there the very nature of the subject demands, more urgently than in other cases, that the particular shall be studied in relation to the aggregate; and this demand can only be satisfied by the concatemation of every particular known to us through tradition, or deducible from tradition, into one great whole. The first point of unity is constituted by indi- viduals. Every philosophic opinion is primarily the thought of some particular man, and is, therefore, to be explained by his intellectual character and the cir- 16 INTRODUCTION. cumstances under which it was formed. Our first task, then, will be to unite the opinions of each philosopher into a collective whole, to show the connection of those opinions with his philosophic character, and to enquire into the causes and influences by which they were originally conditioned. That is to say, we must first ascertain the principle of each system, and explain how it arose; and then consider how the system was the out- come of the principle: for the principle of a system is the thought which most clearly and fundamentally ex- presses the specific philosophic character of its author, and forms the focus of union for all his views. Every individual thing in a system cannot, of course, be ex- plained by its principle; all the knowledge which a philosopher possesses, all the convictions which he forms (often long before his scientific thoughts become matured), all the conceptions which he has derived from multifarious experiences, are not brought even by himself into connection with his philosophic principles; accidental influences, arbitrary incidents, errors and faults of reasoning are constantly interposing them- selves, while the gaps in the records and accounts often prevent our pronouncing with certainty on the original connection of the various constituents of a doctrine. All this lies in the mature of things; but our problem must at any rate be kept in view until we have exhausted all the means in our power for its solution. The individual, however, with the mode of thought peculiar to him, does not stand alone; others ally them- selves with him, and he allies himself with others; others come into collision with him, and he comes into IA WS AND UNITY OF HISTORY. 17 collision with others; schools of philosophy are formed having with each other various relations of dependence, agreement, and contradiction. As the history of Philo- sophy traces out these relations, the forms with which it is concerned divide themselves into larger or smaller groups. We perceive that it is only in this definite connection with others that the individual became and effected that which he did become and effect; and hence arises the necessity of explaining the specific character and importance of the individual by reference to the group which includes him. But even such an explanation as this will not in all respects suffice; for each individual, besides the characteristics common to his class, possesses much that is peculiar to himself. He not only continues the work of his predecessors, but adds something new to it, or else disputes their pre- suppositions and conclusions. The more important, however, a personality has been, and the farther its historical influence has extended, the more will its individual character, even while opening out new paths, disappear and lose itself in the universal and necessary course of history. For the historical importance of the individual depends upon his accomplishing that which is required by an universal need; and so far only as this is the case, does his work become part of the general possession. The merely individual in man is also the transitory; the individual can only work in an abiding manner and on a grand scale when he yields himself and his personality to the service of the universal, and executes with his particular activity a part of the common work. WOL. I. C 18 INTRODUCTION. But if this hold good of the relation of individuals to the spheres to which they belong, is it not equally true of the relation of these spheres to the greater wholes in which they are comprehended ? Each nation and, generally speaking, each historically coherent por- tion of mankind, has the measure and direction of its spiritual life traced out for it, partly by the inherent specific qualities of its members, and partly by the physical and historical conditions that determine its development. No individual, even if he desires it, can withdraw himself from this common character; and he who is called to a great sphere of historical action will not desire it, for he has no ground for his activity to work on except in the whole of which he is a member ; and from this whole, and thence only, there flows to him by numberless channels, for the most part unnoticed, the supplies by the free utilization of which his own spiritual personality is formed and maintained. But for the same reason all individuals are dependent on the past. Each is a child of his age as well as of his nation, and as he will never achieve anything great if he does not work in the spirit of his nation," so surely will he fail unless he stands on the ground of all previous historical acquirement. If, therefore, the spiritual store of man- kind, as the work of self-active beings, is always subject to change, this change is of necessity continuous; and the same law of historical continuity holds good also of each smaller sphère, so far as its natural development is not hindered by external influences. In this process of * Or of the whole to which he belongs—his church, school, or what- ever it may be. LA WS AND UNITY OF HISTORY. 19 development each period has the advantage of the cul- ture and experience of the previous periods; the historic development of mankind, therefore, is upon the whole a development towards ever higher culture—a progression. But particular mations, and entire groups of nations, may nevertheless be thrown back into lower stages by external misfortunes, or their own internal exhaustion; important tracts of human culture may long lie fallow ; progress itself may at first be accomplished in an in- direct manner, through the breaking up of some imper- fect form of civilisation. In defining, them, the law of historical progress in its application to particular phenomena, we must be careful to explain progress merely as the logical development of those qualities and conditions which are originally inherent in the character and circumstances of a nation, or field of culture. This development in every individual case is not necessarily an improvement; there may come dis- turbances and seasons of decay, in which a nation or a form of civilisation ceases to exist, and other forms work their way forward, perhaps painfully and by long and circuitous paths, to carry on the development of history. Here, too, a law is present in the historic evolution, inasmuch as its general course is determined by the nature of things; but this law is not so simple, nor this course so direct, as we might have anticipated. Moreover, as the character and sequence of the historic periods are the result of law and mot of chance, the same may be said of the order and character of the various developments contained in them. Not that these developments can be constructed & priori in C 2 - 20 º INTRODUCTION. reference to the general concept of the sphere in ques- tion; that of the State, for instance, or Religion, or Philosophy. But for each historic whole, or for each of its periods of development, a definite course is marked out by its own fundamental character, by its external circumstances, by its place in history. That the course thus prescribed by existing conditions should be ac- tually followed, is not more wonderful than the fulfil- ment of any other calculation of probabilities. For, though accidental circumstances often give an impulse and a direction to the activity of individuals, it is natural and necessary that among a great number of men there should be a variety of dispositions—of cul- ture, of character, of forms of activity, of external con- ditions—sufficient to furnish representatives of all the different tendencies possible under the given circum- stances. It is natural and necessary that each historical phenomenon should either, by attraction or repulsion, evoke others which serve to supplement it ; that the various dispositions and forces should display themselves in action; that all the different views of a question that may be taken should be stated, and all the different methods of solving given problems should be tried. In a word, the regular course and organic articulation of history are not an à priori postulate ; but the nature of historic conditions and the constitution of the human mind involve that the historic development should, not- withstanding all the contingency of the individual, follow, on the whole and in the main, a fixed law; and to recognize the working of such regularity in any given case, we need not abandon the terra firma of HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. 21 facts, we need only examine the facts thoroughly, and draw the conclusions to which they themselves contain the premises. - What we ask, therefore, is but the complete applica- tion of a purely historic method. We would have no theoretic construction of history, proceeding from theory to fact; our history must be built up from below, out of the materials that are actually given. It stands to reason, however, that these materials cannot be made use of in their rough state; we must call in the aid of a searching historical analysis to determine the essence and internal connection of all the phenomena concerned. This conception of our problem will not, I trust, be open to the charges raised against the Hegelian construc- tion of history. Rightly understood, it can never lead to the distortion of facts, or the sacrifice of the free movement of history to an abstract formalism, since it is upon historical facts and traditions, and upon these alone, that we propose to base our reasoning as to the relation of past phenomena: Only in what has been freely produced shall we seek for historical necessity. If this be thought impossible and paradoxical, we might appeal to the universal conviction of the rule of a Divine Providence—a conception which before all things implies that the course of history is not fortuitous, but is determined by a higher necessity. In case, however, we are dissatisfied (as we may reasonably be) with an argument resting solely on faith, we have only to examine more closely the concept of liberty to convince ourselves that liberty is something other than caprice or chance, that the free activity of man has its inborn 22 INTRODUCTION. measure in the primitive essence of spirit, and in the laws of human nature; and that by virtue of this internal subjection to law, even what is really fortuitous in the individual act becomes necessity in the grand course of historic evolution. To follow this course in detail is the main problem of history. Whether in regard to the history of Philosophy it is necessary or even advantageous for the writer to possess any philosophic conviction of his own, is a . question that would scarcely have been raised had not the dread of a philosophic construction of history caused some minds to overlook the most simple and obvious truths. Few would maintain that the history of law, for instance, would find its best exponent in a person who had no opinions on the subject of juris– prudence; or political history, in one who embraced no theory of politics. It is hard to see why it should be otherwise with the history of Philosophy. How can the historian even understand the doctrines of the philosophers; by what standard is he to judge of their importance; how can he discern the internal connection of the systems, or form any opinion respecting their reciprocal relations, unless he is guided in his labours by fixed philosophic principles P But the more de- veloped and mutually consistent these principles are, the more must we ascribe to him a definite system; and since clearly developed and consistent principles are undoubtedly to be desired in a writer of history, we cannot avoid the conclusion that it is necessary and good that he should bring with him to the study of the earlier Philosophy a philosophic system of his own. HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. 23 It is possible, indeed, that his system may be too contracted to interpret for him the meaning of his predecessors; it is also possible that he may apply it to history in a perverse manner, by introducing his own opinions into the doctrines of previous philosophers, and constructing out of his own system that which he should have tried to understand by its help. But we must not make the general principle answerable-for these faults of individuals; and still less can we hope to escape them by entering on the history of Philosophy devoid of any philosophic conviction. The human mind is not like a tabula rasa, the facts of history are not simply reflected in it like a picture on a photographic plate, but every view of a given occurrence is arrived at by independent observation, combination, and judgment of the facts. Philosophic impartiality, therefore, does not consist in the absence of all presuppositions, but in bringing to the study of past events presuppositions that are true. The man who is without any philo- sophic stand-point is not on that account without any stand-point whatever; he who has formed no scientific opinion on philosophic questions has an unscientific opinion about them. To say that we should bring to the history of Philosophy no philosophy of our own, really means that in dealing with it we should give the preference to unscientific notions as compared with scientific ideas. And the same reasoning would apply to the assertion that the historian ought to form his system in the course of writing his history, from history itself; that by means of history he is to emancipate * By Wirth in the Jahrbücher der Gegenwart, 1844, 709 sq. . 24 INTRODUCTION. himself from any preconceived system, in order thus to attain the universal and the true. From what point of view then is he to regard history, that it may do him this service P From the false and narrow point of view which he must quit that he may rightly comprehend history 2 or from the universal point of view which history itself must first enable him to attain? The one is manifestly as impracticable as the other, and we are ultimately confined within this circle: that he alone completely understands the history of Philosophy who possesses true and complete philosophy; and that he only arrives at true philosophy who is led to it by understanding history. Nor can this circle ever be entirely escaped : the history of Philosophy is the test of the truth of systems; and to have a philosophic system is the condition of a man’s understanding history. The truer and the more comprehensive a philosophy is, the better will it teach us the importance of previous philosophies; and the more unintelligible we find the history of Philosophy, the greater reason have we to doubt the truth of our own philosophic conceptions. But the only conclusion to be drawn from this is that we ought never to regard the work of science as finished in the historic any more than in the philosophic domain. As in a general manner, Philosophy and Experimental Science mutually require and condition one another, so it is here. Each forward movement of philosophic knowledge offers new points of view to historic reflec- tion, facilitates the comprehension of the earlier systems, of their interconnection and relations; while, on the other hand, each newly attained perception of the IIISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY, 25 manner in which the problems of Philosophy have been solved or regarded by others, and of the internal con- nection and consequences of their theories, instructs us afresh concerning the questions which Philosophy has to answer, the different courses it may pursue in an- swering them, and the consequences which may be anticipated from the adoption of each course. But it is time that we should approach our subject somewhat more closely. ſº 26 INTRODUCTION. CHAPTER II. ORIGIN OF GREEK PHILOSOPHY. § I.—Is Greek Philosophy derived from Oriental Speculation f IN order to explain the growth of Greek Philosophy, we must first enquire out of what historical conditions it arose; whether it evolved itself as a native product from the spirit and culture of the Greek people, or was transplanted from without into Hellenic soil, and grew up under foreign influences. The Greeks, we know, were early inclined to ascribe to the Eastern nations (the only nations whose culture preceded their own) a share in the origin of their philosophy; but in the most ancient period, certain isolated doctrines merely were thus derived from the East." As far as our information extends, not the Greeks, but the Orientals, were the first to attribute such an origin to Greek Philosophy generally. The Jews of the Alexandrian school, edu- cated under Greek influences, sought by means of this theory to explain the supposed harmony of their sacred writings with the doctrines of the Hellenes, agreeably to their own stand-point and interests;” and in the same manner the Egyptian priests, after they had become 1. Cf. infra, the chapters on ject will be found in the chapter Pythagoras and Plato. relating to the Judaic Alexandrian * Further details on this sub- Philosophy. ORIENTAL ORIGIN OF GREEK PHILOSOPHY. 27 acquainted, under the Ptolemies, with Greek Philosophy, made great boast of the wisdom, which not only pro- phets and poets, but also philosophers were said to have acquired from them." Somewhat later, the theory gained admittance among the Greeks themselves. When Greek Philosophy, despairing of its own powers, began to ex- pect its salvation from some higher revelation, and to seek for such a revelation in religious traditions, it was natural that the doctrines of the ancient thinkers should ! We find nothing in Herodotus as to any Egyptian origin of Greek Philosophy. In regard to religion, on the other hand, he not only maintains that certain Greek cults and doctrines (especially the wor- ship of Dionysus and the doctrine of Transmigration, ii. 49, 123) were imported from Egypt to Greece, but says in a general manner (ii. 52) that the Pelasgi at first adored their deities simply under the name of the gods, and after- wards received the particularnames of these gods (with the few excep- tions enumerated in c. 50) from Egypt. That this assertion is chiefly founded on the statements of the Egyptian priest appears pro- bable from c. 50 ; and still more from c. 54, where Herodotus relates from the mouth of these priests a story of two women who, carried off by Phoenicians from the Egyp- tian Thebes, founded the first ora- cles—one in Hellas, the other in Libya. This story manifestly arose from a rationalistic interpreta- tion of the Dodomaic legend of the two doves (c. 55), and was imposed on the credulous stranger through the assurances of the priests, that what they told about the fate of these women they had ascertained by repeated enquiries. As the priests then represented themselves to be the founders of the Greek re- ligion, so at a later period they claimed to be the founders of Greek Philosophy. Thus Crantor (ap. Proclus in Tim. 24 B) says, in refer- ence to the Platonic myth of the Athenians and Atlantides: paptu- podot 3& kal of Tpoq àral rôv Aiyv- Tríav čv oth Nais rais &rt oroſopévals Tajra yeypdq6at Aéyovres—there- with giving a valuable hint for es: timating the worth of such state- ments; and Diodorus asserts, i. 96: the Egyptian priests related, ék Tów &vaypaqāv táv čv rais ispats 8í8Aots, that Orpheus, Musæus, Lycurgus, Solon, &c., had come to them ; and moreover, Plato, Py- thagoras, Eudoxus, Democritus, and GEnopides from Chios, and that relics of these men were still shown in Egypt. These philosophers had borrowed from the Egyptians the doctrines, arts, and institutions which they transmitted to the Hel- lenes; Pythagoras, for example, his geometry, his theory of num- bers, and transmigration ; Demo- critus, his astronomical knowledge; Lycurgus, Plato and Solon, their laws. 28 INTRODUCTION. be ascribed to the same source; and the more difficulty there was in explaining these doctrines from native tradition, the more readily was their origin attributed to races, long since revered as the teachers of the Greeks, and whose wisdom enjoyed the highest reputa- tion, because the unknown has generally a charm for the imagination, and seen, as it must be, through a mysterious haze, is wont to look greater than it really is. Thus, after the period of Neo-Pythagoreism there spread, chiefly from Alexandria, the belief that the most important of the ancient philosophers had been in- structed by Eastern priests and sages, and that their most characteristic doctrines had been taken from this source. This opinion in the following centuries be- came more and more general, and the later Neo- Platonists especially carried it to such an extent that, according to them, the philosophers had been scarcely more than the promulgators of doctrines perfected ages before in the traditions of the Asiatic races. No wonder that Christian authors, even after the time of the Refor- mation, continued the same strain, doubting neither the Jewish statements as to the dependence of Greek Philo. sophy on the religion of the Old Testament, nor the stories which made Phoenicians, Egyptians, Persians, Babylonians and Hindoos the instructors of the ancient philosophers." Modern science has long ago discarded the fables of the Jews respecting the intercourse of the | Among these the Alexandri- the Hellenic philosophers generally ans were again preeminent. Cle- are represented as having borrowed mens dwells with especial predilec- portions of the truth from the He- tion on this theme in his Stromata, brew prophets, and given them out Plato to him is simply 6 €: ‘E8patov as their own (ibid, 312 C, 320 A). ºpiñágopos (Strom. i. 274 B); and OPINIONS OF ANCIENTS AND MODERWS, 29 Greek sages with Moses and the prophets; but the idea that Greek Philosophy partly or entirely originated in the Pagan East has more facts to urge in its behalf. It has also found support in the high opinion of Oriental wisdom induced by our better acquaintance with the Chinese, Persian and Indian sacred records, and by our researches into Egyptian antiquity; an opinion which harmonizes with certain philosophical speculations con- cerming a primitive revelation and a golden age. More sober philosophy, indeed, questioned the truth of these speculations, and thoughtful students of history sought vainly for traces of that high culture which was said to have adorned the childhood of the world. Our admiration, too, for the Oriental Philosophy, of which, according to its enthusiastic admirers, only some frag- ments had reached the Greeks, has been considerably modified by our growing knowledge of its true content and character. When, in addition to this, the old un- critical manner of confusing separate modes of thought had been abandoned, and every notion began to be studied in its historical connection, and in relation with the peculiar character and circumstances of the people among whom it appeared, it was natural that the differ- ences of Greek and Oriental cultivation, and the self- dependence of the Greek, should again be more strongly emphasized by those best acquainted with classical anti- quity. Still, there have not been wanting, even quite recently, some to maintain that the East had a decisive influence on the earliest Greek Philosophy; and the whole question seems by no means so entirely settled that the History of Philosophy can avoid its repeated discussion. 30 INTRODUCTION. One point, however, is to be noted, the neglect of which has not unfrequently brought confusion into this enquiry. In a certain sense, the influence of Oriental conceptions on Greek Philosophy may well be admitted even by those who consider that Philosophy to be purely a Greek creation. The Greeks, like the other Indo- Germanic races, arose out of Asia, and from this their earliest home they must originally have brought with them, together with their language, the general ground- work of their religion and manners. After they had reached their later abodes, they were still open to in- fluences which reached them from the Oriental nations, partly through Thrace and the Bosphorus, partly by way of the AEgean and its islands. The national character of Greece, therefore, was even in its origin under the influence of the Oriental spirit, and Greek religion, especially, can only be understood on the sup- position that foreign rites and religious ideas from the North and South-east were superadded to the faith of Greek antiquity, and, in a lesser degree, even to that of the Homeric age. The latest of these immigrant gods, such as Dionysus, Cybele, and the Phoenician Heracles, can now with sufficient certainty be proved alien in their origin; while in the ease of others, in the present stage of the enquiry, we have still to be content with doubtful conjectures. In considering the Oriental origin of Greek philosophy, however, we can only take into account those Eastern influences, the entrance of which had nothing to do with the early religion of Greece, or the development of the Greek character generally; for the scope of our work involves our re- ORIENTAL ORIGIN OF GREEK PHILOSOPHY. 31 garding the philosophy of the Greeks, at any rate primarily, as a product of the Greek spirit; and to enquire how that spirit was formed would be beside the purpose of the History of Philosophy. Only in so far as the Oriental element maintained itself in its specific character, side by side with the Hellenic element, are we now concerned with it. If, indeed, Röth were cor- rect in asserting, as he does," that Philosophy did not spring from the civilisation and spiritual life of the Greeks, but was transplanted among them as something foreign, and that the whole circle of notions lying at its root came ready made from without, then, and then only, we might derive Greek Philosophy absolutely from the East. But if, on the other hand, it was the immediate product of the Greek philosophers' own re- flection, in that case it has essentially a native origin, and the question can no longer be whether, as a whole, it came from the East, but whether Oriental doctrines had any share in its formation, how far this foreign influence extended, and to what exten we can still recognize in it the Oriental element proper, as distinct from the Hellenic element. These different cases have not always hitherto been sufficiently discriminated; and the advocates of Oriental influence especially have fre- quently neglected to explain whether the foreign element came into Philosophy directly or through the medium of the Greek religion. There is a wide differ- ence between the two alternatives, and it is with the former alone that we are here concerned. Those who maintain that Greek Philosophy origin- Geschichte unserer abendländischen Philosophie, i. 74,241. 32 INTRODUCTION. ally came from the East, support their opinion partly on the statements of the ancients, and partly on the supposed internal affinity between Greek and Oriental doctrines. The first of these proofs is very unsatisfac- tory. Later writers, it is true, particularly the adher- ents of the Neo-Pythagorean and Neo-Platonic Schools, speak much of the wisdom which Thales, Pherecydes and Pythagoras, Democritus and Plato, owed to the teaching of Egyptian priests, Chaldeans, Magi, and even Brah- mans. But this evidence could only be valid if we were assured that it rested on a trustworthy tradition, reaching back to the time of these philosophers themselves. And who can guarantee us such an assurance? The assertions of these comparatively recent authors respecting the ancient philosophers must be cautiously received even when they mention their references; for their historical sense and critical faculty are almost invariably so dull, and the dogmatic presuppositions of subsequent philo- sophy are so intrusively apparent in their language, that we can trust very few of them even for a correct version of their authorities, and in no single instance can we hope for a sound judgment concerning the worth and origin of those authorities, or an accurate discrimination of the genuine from the spurious, the fabulous from the historic. Indeed, when anything, otherwise unknown to us, is related by them of Plato, Pythagoras, or any of the ancient philosophers without any reference to authori- ties, we may take for granted that the story is founded, in the great majority of cases, neither on fact nor on respectable tradition, but at best on some unauthenti- cated rumour, and still oftener, perhaps, on a misunder- ORIENTAL ORIGIN OF GREEK PHILOSOPHY. 33 standing, an arbitrary conjecture, a dogmatic presuppo- sition, or even a deliberate invention. This is true in an especial manner of the question as to the relation of Greek Philosophy with the East; for, on the one hand, the Orientals had the strongest inducements of vanity and self-interest to invent an Eastern origin for Greek Science and culture ; and, on the other, the Greeks were only too ready to allow the claim. It is precisely with such unauthenticated statements that we have here to do, and these statements are so suspiciously connected with the peculiar standpoint of the authors who make them, that it would be very rash to build hypotheses of great importance in history on a foundation so insecure. If we put aside, then, these untrustworthy witnesses, and have recourse to older authorities, the result is no better; we find either that they assert much less than the later writers, or that their assertions are based far more upon conjecture than historical knowledge. Thales may have been in Egypt: we have no certain evidence of the fact ; but it is not likely that he there learned" more than the first rudiments of mathematics. That Pythagoras, visited that country, and that his whole philosophy originated thence, was first asserted by Isocrates, in a passage which is more than suspected of being a rhetorical fiction. Herodotus says nothing about his having come to Egypt, and represents him as having derived from the Egyptians only a very few doctrines and customs, and these at third hand. The distant journeys of Democritus are better attested; but what he learnt in the course of them from the bar- barians we are not certainly informed, for the story of WOL. I. D & 34 INTRODUCTION. the Phoenician Atomist Mochus deserves no credit." Plato's travels in Egypt also seem to be historical, and have at any rate much more evidence in their favour than the subsequent and improbable statements as to his intercourse with Phoenicians, Jews, Chaldeans and Persians. Whatever later authors may have said, or rather surmised, about the fruits of these travels, Plato himself clearly expresses his own opinion of the wisdom of the Egyptians, when he ascribes to the Greeks, as their special characteristic, a taste for knowledge, and to the Egyptians, as to the Phoenicians, a love of gain.” As a fact, he praises them in various passages, not for philosophic discoveries, but for technical arts and poli- tical institutions; * there is not a trace, either in his own writings or in credible tradition, of his having taken his philosophy from them. Thus the assertions as to the dependence of Greek on Oriental Philosophy, when we exclude those that are wholly untrustworthy, and rightly understand the rest, dwindle down to a very small number; even these are not altogether beyond question, and at most only prove that the Greeks in particular cases may have received certain impulses from the East, not that their whole philosophy was imported from thence. A more important result is supposed to be derived from the internal affinity of the Greek systems with Oriental doctrines. But even the two most recent advo- * Further details, infra. —Gesch. der Phil. i. 153 sqq. * Rep. iv. 435 E. A passage on * Cf. Zeller, Phil. der Gr. Part which Ritter, in his careful enquiry ii. a, p. 358, note 2; also Brandis, into the oriental origin of Greek Gesch. der Gr.-röm. Phil. i. 143. philosophy, rightly lays much stress. THEORIES OF GLADISCH AND ROTH. 35 cates of the theory are not agreed as to the precise meaning of this affinity. Gladisch, on the one hand, thinks it evident that the principal pre-Socratic systems reproduced without any material alteration the theories of the universe of the five chief Oriental nations. The Philosophy of the Chinese, he considers, reappears in Pythagoreism ; that of the Hindoos in the Eleatics; that of the Persians in Heracleitus; that of the Egyp- tians in Empedocles; that of the Jews in Anaxagoras. Röth, on the other hand,” no less distinctly affirms that ancient Greek speculation arose out of Egyptian creeds, intermingled, though not to any great extent except in the cases of Democritus and Plato, with the ideas of Zoroaster. In Aristotle, he says, Greek Philo- sophy first freed itself from these influences; but in Neo-Platonism Egyptian speculation once more renewed its youth, while, at the same time, the Zoroastrian doc- trimes, with a certain admixture of Egyptian motions, produced Christianity. If we examine impartially the historical facts, we shall find ourselves compelled to reject both these theories, and the improbability of an Eastern origin and character in regard to Greek Philosophy generally will more and more appear. The phenomenon which Einleitung in das Verständniss der Weltgeschichte, 2 Th. 1841,1844. Das Mysterium der Ægyptischen Pyramiden und Obelisken, 1846. On Heracleitus, Zeitschrift für Al- terthºms-Wissenschaft, 1846, No. 121 sq., 1848; No. 28 sqq. Due verschleierte Isis, 1849. Empedokles wºnd die AEgypter, 1858. Hera- cleitos und Zoroaster, 1859. Anar- agoras undalie Israeliten, 1864 Die Hyperboreer und die alten Schinesen, 1866. Die Religion und die Philo- sophie in ihrer Weltgeschichtlichen Entwicklung, 1852. In what fol- lows I keep principally to this last treatise. * Gesch. alms. Abendl. Phil. i. 74 sqq., 228 sq., 459 sq. In the second part of this work he ascribes to the doctrines of Zoro- aster a share in Pythagoreism. D 2 36 INTRODUCTION. Gladisch thinks he perceives, even supposing it to exist, would admit of a twofold explanation. We might either ascribe it to an actual connection between the Pythagorean Philosophy and the Chinese, between the Eleatic and the Hindoo, &c.; or we might regard the coincidence of these doctrines as naturally resulting, without any external connection, from the universality of the Greek genius, or some other cause. In the latter case the phenomenon would give no clue to the origin of Greek Philosophy, nor, however striking such a fact might appear to us, would it add much to our historical knowledge of Greek science. If, on the other hand, there were really such an external historical connection as Gladisch assumes between these Greek systems and their Eastern prototypes, we ought to be able in some way or other to prove the possibility of such a connection; to show, from a survey of the actual circumstances, that there was a probability of such accurate intelligence concerning Chinese and Hindoo doctrines having reached Pythagoras and Parmenides; we must explain the inconceivable phenomenon that the different Oriental ideas did not become intermingled on their way to Greece, nor in Greece itself, but arrived there and maintained themselves separately, side by side, so as to produce exactly the same number. of Greek systems, and that in the very order corre- sponding to the geographical and historical position of the peoples among whom they arose. Lastly, we must give some kind of answer to the question how theories, so evidently borrowed from Parmenides by Cf. especially, in reference to this, Amaragoras und die Israeliten, x. sq. THEORIES OF GLA DISCH AND RöTH. 37 Empedocles and Anaxagoras, and so deeply rooted in their own doctrines that they must be considered their scientific points of departure (e.g. the impossibility of an absolute origination or decease), could be derived in the case of one philosopher from India, in that of a second from Egypt, in that of a third from Palestine. All this appears equally impossible, whether we suppose the influence of Oriental doctrines on Greek Philosophy to have been indirect or direct. That it is impossible to believe in a direct influence of the kind Gladisch himself admits; appealing, with justice, to the ut- terances of Aristotle and of the other ancient authors concerning the origin of the systems anterior to Plato, and urging the reciprocal interdependence of these systems. But does the theory become more probable if we assume that the Oriental element “entered Philo- sophy through the instrumentality of Greek religion?” Where do we find in Greek religion, especially in the religious tradition of the centuries which gave birth to the pre-Socratic Philosophy (except, indeed, in the dogma of transmigration), a trace of all the doctrines to which the philosophers are said to have been led by it 2 How is it credible that a speculative system like the Vedanta Philosophy should be communicated by means of Greek mythology to Parmenides; and Judaic monotheism, by means of Hellenic polytheism, to Anaxagoras 2 How could the Oriental doctrines after their convergence in the Greek religion have issued from it unchanged in this definite order P And Einleitung in das Verständ- die Isr. xi. sq. miss, &c. ii. 376 sq. Anaa.. und * Anaa.. und die Isr. xiii. 38 INTRODUCTION. if they had done so, how can that which the various philosophies produced from the same source (their na- tional religion), even when they undoubtedly borrowed it one from the other, be referred to utterly different Oriental sources? It is easy to meet these objections, which might be greatly multiplied, by saying,' whether all this be possible, and how it may have come about, we will not here enquire, but content ourselves at present with simply establishing the facts. Such an answer might suffice if the evidence for the facts only included the hearing of unimpeachable witnesses, and a comparison of their testimony. But that is by no means the case. The proofs of the parallelism between Greek and Oriental doctrines which Gladisch claims to have discovered, would, under any circumstances, demand investigations much too complicated to leave the question of its possibility and reasonableness wholly untouched. If we consider his own representation of this parallelism, we are met at decisive points by such uncritical reliance on interpolated writings and untrust- worthy statements, such confusion of earlier and later authorities, such arbitrary interpretation of the theories concerned, that it is plain we have to do not merely with the proof of the historical fact, but with a connec- tion and interpretation extending much farther.” We 1 Loc. cit. xiv. - * Cf. what is said, infra, of Heracleitus, of Empedocles, and of Anaxagoras; also in the text of this passage, as it appeared in the second and third editions, about the Pythagorean and Eleatic Philo- sophy (Zeller, Phil. der Gr. 3rd ed. p. 29 sq.) This I do not repeat here, not because Gladisch's counter- arguments seem to me unanswer- able, but because a thorough refuta- tion of his hypothesis would require more space than I can devote to it, and because the derivation of Py- thagoreism from China, and the THEORIES OF GLADISCH AND ROTH. 39 become involved, as already remarked, in the following contradictions: that characteristics equally to be found in several Greek philosophers must have had an entirely different origin in every case; that doctrines evidently borrowed by one philosopher from another must have been communicated independently to both from an Easterm source, and to each man from a separate Eastern source; that systems which evolved themselves out of one another, in a historic sequence which is indisputable, must each have merely reproduced what it had already received, irrespectively of that sequence, from this or that Oriental predecessor. How little this construction of Gladisch comports with actual facts may also be seen from the impossibility” of bringing into connection with it two such radical and important phenomena in the history of Greek Philosophy as the Ionic Physics before Heracleitus, and the Atomistic Philosophy. As to Röth, his view can only be properly considered in the examination of the separate Greek systems. So far as it is carried out, I am, however, unable, to agree with it, because I fail to see in his exposition of Fgyptian theology a faithful historical picture. I can- doctrines of Parmenides from India is really inconceivable, and has never been elsewhere entertained. Cf. Supra, p. 36. Thus ac- cording to Gladisch, Pythagoras got his doctrine of Transmigration from China (where, however, it did not originate), and Empedocles his from Egypt. * In regard to the Atomistic philosophy, Gladisch attempts to justify this (Amaa.. und die Isr. xiv.) by saying that it was developed from the Eleatic doctrine. But the dependence is in this-case no other and no greater than in the case of Anaxagoras and Empedocles; and Atomistic has an equal right with their doctrines to be considered an independent system. The omis- sion of Thales, Anaximander, and Anaximenes, Gladisch (loc. cit.) leaves unexplained. Yet Thales is the founder of Greek Philosophy, and Anaximander the immediate predecessor of Heracleitus. 40 IAWTRODUCTION. not now enter into a discussion of the philosophy of religion, nor stop to refute the theory' that abstract concepts, such as spirit, matter, time and space, and not presentations of personal beings, formed the original content of the Egyptian"religion, and other religions of antiquity. I must also leave the task of examining the results which Röth derives” from Oriental texts and hieroglyphic monuments to those better acquainted with the subject. For the purposes of the present enquiry, it is enough to notice that the affinity assumed by Röth between the Egyptian and Persian doctrines, and the myths and philosophic systems of the Greeks, can only be proved, even on the author's own showing, if we consent to repose unlimited confidence in untrust- worthy witnesses, uncertain conjectures and groundless etymologies. If, indeed, each transference of the names of Greek gods to foreign deities were an adequate proof of the identity of these gods, the Greek religion would hardly be distinguishable from the Egyptian; if it were permissible to seek out barbarian etymologies, even where the Greek signification of a word is ready to hand,” we might perhaps suppose the whole mythology, together with the names of the gods, to have emigrated from the East to Greece; * * Loc. cit. p. 50 Sq., 228, 131 SQQ- * e.g. p. 131 Sqq., 278 sqq. * As, for instance, when Röth derives Pan and Persephone from the Egyptian language; translating Pan as Deus egressus, the emanated creative spirit (loc. cit. 140, 284), and Persephone (p. 162) as the slayer of Perses, i.e. of Bore—Seth or Typhon; whereas it is clear if Iamblichus and Hermes that the root of II&v is tria, Ion. Taréopal, Lat. pasco; and that IIepareq,óvn, as well as IIéporms and IIeporets, comes from trépôw; and that Greek mythology says nothing of a creator spirit Pan, or of a Perses in the sense of Typhon (if even one of the Hesiodic Titans be so named), or of any slaying of this IPerses by Persephone. * Scarcely, however, even in IMPROBABILITY OF THE ORIENTAL THEORY. 41 Trismegistus were classical authorities for Egyptian an- tiquity, we might congratulate ourselves on the ancient records' with which they acquaint us, and the Greek philosophical sayings which they profess to have dis- covered” in old Egyptian writings; if the Atomistic doc- trine of Moschus the Phoenician were a historical fact, we might, like Röth,” attempt to find in the theories of Phoenician cosmology, respecting the primitive slime, the sources of a doctrine hitherto believed to have been derived from the metaphysic of the Eleatics. But if the universal principle of criticism be applicable to this, as to other cases—viz. that history accepts nothing as true the truth of which is not guaranteed by credible testimony, or by legitimate conclusions from such testimony—then this attempt of Röth will only show that the most indefatigable efforts are in- sufficient to prove a foreign origin in regard to the essential content of so indigenous a production as Greek science.” that case, with the facility of Röth, who on the strength of the above etymologies, and without citing any authority, transfers the whole my- thus of the rape of Persephone and the wanderings of Demeter to the Egyptian mythology, in order then to assert that it first came from Egypt to the Greeks (loc. cit. p. 162). g e.g. the book of Bitys, which Röth (p. 211 Sqq.) (on the ground of a very suspicious passage in the work of the Pseudo-Iamblichus on the Mysteries) places in the eight- eenth century before Christ. If this book ever existed, it was probably a late invention of the period of Alexandrian syncretism, and worth about as much, in the light of Egyptian historical evidence, as the book of Mormon is in regard to Jewish. * For example, the distinction of vows and juxi. Cf. Itôth's Allmar- Kungen, p. 220 sq. * Loc. cit. 274 sqq. * A more detailed examination of Röth's hypotheses will find a fitting place in the chapter on the Pythagoreans; for, according to him, it was Pythagoras who trans- planted the whole Egyptian science and theology into Greece. Cf. also what is said of Anaximander, Infra. 42 INTRODUCTION. A proof. of this kind is, generally speaking, very difficult to establish when it is based solely on internal evidence. It may happen that not only particular motions and customs, but whole series of them may bear a resemblance to another series in some other sphere of civilisation ; it may also happen that fundamental con- ceptions may seem to repeat themselves without thus affording adequate proof that they are historically inter- connected. Under analogous conditions of develop- ment, and especially between races originally related to each other, many points of contact invariably arise, even when these races have no actual intercourse; chance often brings out surprising similarities in de- tails; and among the more highly civilised races scarcely any two could be named between which striking paral- lels could not be drawn. But though it may be natural in that case to conjecture an external connection, the existence of this connection is only probable if the similarities are so great that they cannot be explained by the above more general causes. It must have been very astonishing to the followers of Alexander to find among the Brahmans not only their Dionysus and Heracles, but also their Hellenic philosophy; to hear of water being the origin of the world, as with Thales; of Deity permeating all things, as with Heracleitus; of a transmigration of souls, as with Pythagoras and Plato; of five elements, as with Aristotle; of the prohibition of flesh diet, as with Empedocles and the Orphics;" and no doubt Herodotus and his successors must have 1. Cf. the accounts of Mega- and Nearchus in Strabo xv. 1, 58 sthenes, Aristobulus, Onesicritus sqq., p. 712 sqq. IMPROBABILITY OF THE ORIENTAL THEORY. 43 been often inclined to derive Greek doctrines and usages from Egypt. But for us, all this is not sufficient proof that Heracleitus, Plato, Thales and Aristotle borrowed their theorems from the Hindoos or Egyptians. It is not merely, however, the want of historical evidence which prevents our believing in the Oriental origin of Greek Philosophy; there are several positive reasons against the theory. One of the most decisive lies in the general character of that philosophy. The doctrines of the most ancient Greek philosophers have, as Ritter well observes," all the simplicity and indepen- dence of first attempts; and their ulterior development is so continuous that the hypothesis of alien influences is never required to explain it. We see here no conflict of the original Hellenic spirit with foreign elements, no adaptation of misapprehended formulae and conceptions, mo return to scientific traditions of the past, in short, none of the phenomena by which, for example, in the Middle Ages, the dependence of philosophy on foreign sources is evinced. All developes itself quite naturally from the conditions of Greek national life, and we shall find that even those systems which have been supposed to be most deeply influenced by doctrines from without, are in all essential respects to be explained by the inter- mal civilisation and spiritual horizon of the Hellenes. Such a feature would certainly be inexplicable if Greek Philosophy were really so much indebted to other countries as some writers both ancient and modern have believed. On this theory there would be another strange and unaccountable circumstance,—that the * Gesch. der Phil. i. 172. 44 INTRODUCTION. theological character of Oriental speculation should be entirely absent from Greek philosophy. Whatever science there was in Egypt, Babylonia or Persia, was in possession of the priestly caste, and had grown up in one mass with the religious doctrines and institutions. In regard to mathematics and astronomy, it is quite conceivable that Oriental science should have been de- tached from this its religious basis, and transplanted separately into foreign lands; but it is most improbable that the priests should have held theories about the primitive constituents and origin of the world, capable of being transmitted and adopted apart from their doc- trines concerning the gods and mythology. Now in the most ancient Greek Philosophy we find no trace of Egyptian, Persian or Chaldaean mythology, and its con- nection even with Greek myths is very slight. Even the Pythagoreans and Empedocles only borrowed from the mysteries such doctrines as had no intimate relation with their philosophy (that is, their attempt at a scien- tific explanation of nature): neither the Pythagorean doctrine of numbers, nor the Pythagorean and Empe- doclean cosmology, can be connected with any theologi- cal tradition as their source. The rest of the pre- Socratic philosophy does, indeed, remind us in certain isolated motions of the mythic cosmogony, but in the main it developed itself either quite independently of the religious belief, or in express opposition to it. How could this possibly be if Greek science were an offshoot of the Sacerdotal wisdom of the East 2 We must further enquire whether the Greeks at the time of their first attempts at Philosophy could have IMPROBABILITY OF THE ORIENTAL THEORY. 45 been taught anything considerable in this sphere by Orientals. There is no historical or even probable evidence to show that either of the Asiatic nations with which they came in contact possessed any philosophic science. We hear, indeed, of theological and cosmo- logical notions, but all these, so far as they really appear to go back to antiquity, are so rude and fanciful that the Greeks could scarcely have received from them any impulse towards philosophic thought which their own myths could not just as well have afforded. The sacred books of Egypt probably contained only prescripts for ritual, ecclesiastical and civil laws, interspersed perhaps with religious myths; in the scanty notices remaining of their contents there is no trace of the scientific, dogmatic theology which modern writers have sought to discover." To the Egyptian priests themselves, in the time of Herodotus, the thought of an Egyptian origin in regard to Greek Philosophy never seems to have occurred, eagerly as they strove, even then, to derive Greek myths, laws, and 1 Röth, loc. cit. p. 112 sqq., and p. 122. He appeals to Cle- mens, Strom. vi. 633 B sqq. Sylb., where the Hermetic books being mentioned it is said: there are ten books, rö, eis Thy Tipºv &våkovra Tów trap' airo's 9eóv kal thu Aiyvirtſav eñoré8étav repléxovira otov repl 6vuátov, &rapxóv, iſuvov, eúxöv, troutröv, Šoptóv kal tăv toitous 6poſtov, and ten other books rept Te vöuov kal 6sóv kal Täs 6Ams tratēetas róv ispéov. But that the contents of these books were even in part scientific, cannot be deduced from the words of Clemens; religious ceremonies from even the last-mentioned ten proba- bly treated, not of the nature of the gods, but of religious worship, and perhaps, in connection with this, of mythology: when Clemens says that these writings contained the whole ‘ Philosophy’ of the Egyptians, the word must be taken in the indeterminate sense of which I have spoken above, p. 1 sq. More- over, we do not know in the least how old these books were, or whether they continued up to the time of Clemens without alterations and additions. 46 INTRODUCTION. Egypt, and little as they shrank from the most trans- parent inventions' in pursuance of this end. The scientific discoveries which they claim to have given to the Greeks” are confined to astronomical determinations of time. That the doctrine of transmigration originated in Egypt is only a conjecture of Herodotus;* and when he says (ii. 109) that the Greeks appear to have learnt geometry there, he founds the assertion not on Egyptian statements, as Diodorus does, but on his own observa- tion. This justifies the supposition that in the fifth century the Egyptians had not troubled themselves much about Greek or any other Philosophy. Even Plato, judging from the previously quoted passage in the fourth book of the ‘Republic, must have been ignorant of the existence of a Phoenician or Egyptian Philosophy. Nor does Aristotle seem to have been aware of the philosophic efforts of the Egyptians, will- ing as he was to acknowledge them as forerunners of the Greeks in mathematics and astronomy.” Demo- 1 Thus, (ii. 177) Solon is said to have borrowed one of his laws from Amasis, who came to the throne twenty years later than the date of Solon's code; and (c. 118) the priests assure the historian that what they related to him about Helen they had heard from Mene- laus' own mouth. We have already seen examples of this procedure, supra, p. 27, note 1. 2 Herod. ii. 4. 8 ii. 123. 4 To the astronomical observa- tions of the Egyptians (on the conjunctions of the planets with each other and with fixed stars) he appeals in Meteorol. i. 6, 343, b 28; and in Metaph. i. 1,981, b 23 he says: Öto trepl Atºyvirtov ai p.a6mplattical trpárov réxval ovvé- ormorav. čke? y&p & petón axoxáſeuv to tôv ispéov č6vos. This very passage, however, makes it pro- bable that Aristotle knew nothing of any philosophic enquiry pursued in Egypt. He contends loc. cit. that knowledge is on a higher level when it is pursued only for the end of knowing, than when it serves the purposes of practical necessity, and observes, in connection with this, that purely theoretic sciences therefore first arose in places where people were sufficiently free from anxiety about the necessaries of IMPROBABILITY OF THE ORIENTAL THEORY. 47. critus assures us that he himself, in geometrical know- ledge, was quite a match for the Egyptian sages whose acquaintance he made." So late as the time of Diodorus, when Greek science had long been naturalised in Egypt, and the Egyptians in consequence claimed for themselves the visits of Plato, Pythagoras, and Democritus,” that which the Greeks are said to have derived from Egypt is confined to mathematical and technical knowledge, civil laws, religious institutions, and myths; * these only are referred to in the assertion of the Thebans (i. 50) ‘that Philosophy and the accurate knowledge of the stars was first invented among them, for the word Philosophy is here equivalent to Astronomy. Admitting, then, that the Egyptian mythologists referred to by Diodorus may have given to the con- ceptions of the gods a naturalistic interpretation in the spirit of the Stoics; “that later syncretists (like the life to be able to devote themselves to such sciences. The above-quoted words indirectly confirm this asser- tion. Had Aristotle considered Philosophy as well as Mathematics to be an Egyptian product, he would have been particularly un- likely to omit it in this connection, since it is Philosophy of which he asserts that as a purely theoretical science it stands higher than all merely technical knowledge. That the rudiments of astronomy came to the Greeks from the barbarians, and more particularly from the Syrians and Egyptians, we are told in the Epinomis of Plato 986 Esq. 987 D sq. Similarly Strabo xvii. 1, 3, p. 787, ascribes the invention of Geometry to the Egyptians, and that of Arithmetic to the Phoeni- cians; perhaps Eudemus had al- ready expressed the same opinion, if indeed Proclus in Euclid. 19, o (64 f. Friedl.) took this statement from him. * In the fragment in Clemens, Strom. i. 304 A, where he says of himself after mentioning his distant journeys: kal Aoyſoy &věpátov TAetotov Šohkovga kal ypguuéov êvv6égios uetà &troëéºtos ojöets ká He trapſiAAače, où6' oi Aiyvirtſov raxeóuevo Apteborárrat. The in- terpretation of the last word is questionable, but the term must in any case include those of the Egyptian sages who possessed the most geometrical knowledge. * i. 96, 98. * Cf. c. 16, 69, 81, 96 sqq. * Diod. i. 11 sq. 48 INTRODUCTION. author of the book on the mysteries of the Egyptians, and the theologians quoted by Damascius)" may have imported their own speculations into Egyptian myths; that there may have existed in the time of Posidonius a Phoenician manuscript reputed to be of great antiquity, and passing under the name of the philosopher Moschus or Mochus;” that Philo of Byblus, under the mask of Sanchuniathon, may have constructed a rude cosmology from Phoenician and Greek myths, from the Mosaic history of creation, and from confused reminiscences of Philosophy—such questionable witnesses can in no way prove the real existence of an Egyptian and Phoenician Philosophy. Supposing, however, that among these nations, at the time that the Greeks became acquainted with them, philosophic doctrines had been found, the transmission of these doctrines to Greece was not at all so easy as may perhaps be imagined. Philosophic conceptions, especially in the childhood of Philosophy, are closely bound up with their expression in language, and the knowledge of foreign languages was rarely to be met with among the Greeks. On the other hand, the inter- preters, educated as a rule for nothing but commercial intercourse and the explanation of curiosities, were of little use in enabling people to understand instruction in philosophy. Moreover, there is not a single allusion, on which we can rely, to the use of Oriental works by Greek philosophers, or to any translations of such works. * De Princ. c. 125. Damascius worthy source for the history of expressly calls them oi, Aiyúirtuol Egyptian antiquity. traff' huàsquxóoroqot yeyovótes. They * Wide infra, the chapter on are therefore the most untrust- Democritus. NATIVE SOURCES OF GREEK PHILOSOPHY. 49 If we ask ourselves, lastly, by what means the doctrines of the Hindoos and the other nations of Eastern Asia could have been carried into Greece before the time of Alexander, we shall find that the matter presents numerous difficulties. All such considerations as these would, of course, yield to well-attested facts; but it is a different matter where we are concerned, not with historical facts, but for the present with mere conjec- tures. If the Eastern origin of Greek Philosophy were to be maintained by trustworthy evidence, or by its own internal characteristics, our conception of the scientific condition of the Eastern nations and of the relation in which the Greeks stood to them must be formed in accordance with that fact; but since the fact in itself is neither demonstrable nor probable, it is rendered still more improbable by its want of harmony with what we know from other sources on these two points. § II.-The Native Sources of Greek Philosophy. IRELIGION. We have no need, however, to seek for foreign ante- cedents: the philosophic science of the Greeks is fully explained by the genius, resources, and state of civili- sation of the Hellenic tribes. If ever there was a people capable of creating its own science, the Greeks were that people. In the most ancient records of their culture, the Homeric Poems, we already meet with that freedom and clearness of spirit, that sobriety and mode- ration, that feeling for the beautiful and harmonious, which place these poems so distinctly above the heroic WOL. I. E 50 INTRODUCTION, legends of all other nations without exception. Of scientific endeavour, there is nothing as yet ; no neces- sity is felt to investigate the natural causes of things; the writer is content to refer them to personal authors and divine powers, the explanation that comes upper- most in the childhood of mankind. The technical arts too, which support science, are in a very elementary stage; in the Homeric period even writing is unknown. But when we consider the glorious heroes of the Homeric Poems—when we see how everything, each phenomenon of nature, and each event of human life, is set forth in pictures which are as true as they are artistically per- fect—when we study the simple and beautiful develop- ment of these masterpieces, the grandeur of their plan, and the harmonious accomplishment of their purposes, we can no longer wonder that a nation capable of ap- prehending the world with an eye so open, and a spirit so unclouded, of dominating the confused mass of phe- momena with so admirable a sense of form, of moving in life so freely and surely—that such a nation should soon turn its attention to science, and in that field should not be satisfied merely with amassing knowledge and observations, but should strive to combine particu- lars into a whole, to find an intellectual focus for isolated phenomena, to form a theory of the universe based on clear conceptions, and possessing internal unity; to produce, in short, a Philosophy. How natural is the flow of events even in the Homeric world of gods! We find ourselves, indeed, in the wonderland of imagi- nation, but how seldom are we reminded by anything fantastic or monstrous (so frequent and disturbing an THE RELIGION OF THE GREEKS, 51 element in Oriental and Northern mythology) that this fabled world is wanting in the conditions of reality Amidst all the poetry how clearly we recognise that same and vigorous realism, that fine perception of what is harmonious and matural, to which, in later times, after deeper study of the universe and of man, this same Homeric heaven necessarily proved such a stum- bling-block. Thus, although the intellectual culture of the Homeric period is separated by a wide inter- val from the rise of philosophy, we can already trace in it the peculiar genius out of which Philosophy Sprang. It is the farther development of this genius as manifested in the sphere of religion, of moral and civil life, and in the general cultivation of taste and of the intellect, which constitutes the historical preparation for Greek Philosophy. The religion of the Greeks, like every positive religion, stands to the philosophy of that people in a relation partly of affinity and partly of opposition. What distinguishes it from the religions of all other races, however, is the freedom which from the very beginning it allowed to the evolution of philosophic thought. If we turn our attention first to the public ritual and popular faith of the Hellenes, as it is repre- sented to us in its oldest and most authentic records, the poems of Homer and Hesiod, its importance in the development of philosophy cannot be mistaken. The religious presentation is always, and so also among the | Greeks, the form in which the interdependence of all phenomena and the rule of invisible powers and º! E 2 52 INTRODUCTION. versal laws first attains to consciousness. However great may be the distance between faith in a divine government of the world, and the scientific knowledge and explanation of the universe as a connected whole, they have at any rate something in common. Religious faith, even under the polytheistic form it assumed in Greece, implies that what exists and happens in the world depends on certain causes concealed from sensu- ous perception. Nor is this all. The power of the gods must necessarily extend over all parts of the world, and the plurality of the gods is reduced to unity by the dominion of Zeus and the irresistible power of Fate. Thus the interdependence of the universe is proclaimed; all phenomena are co-ordinated under the same general causes; by degrees fear of the power of the gods and of relentless Fate yields to confidence in the divine goodness and wisdom, and a fresh problem presents itself to reflection—viz. to pursue the traces of this wisdom in the laws of the universe. Philosophy, indeed, has itself been at work in this purification of the popular faith, but the religious motion first con- tained the germs from which the purer conceptions of Philosophy were afterwards developed. The peculiar nature of Greek religious belief, also, was not without influence on Greek Philosophy. The . Greek religion belongs in its general character to the +-class of natural religions; the Divine, as is sufficiently proved by the plurality of gods, is represented under a natural figure essentially of the same kind as the Finite, and only exalted above it in degree. Man, therefore, does not need to raise himself above the THE RELIGION OF THE GREEKS. 53 world that surrounds him, and above his own actual nature, that he may enter into communion with the Deity; he feels himself related to God from the very outset. No internal change of his mode of thought, no struggle with his natural impulses and inclinations, is demanded of him ; on the contrary, all that is in human nature is legitimate in the sight of God—the most godlike man is he who cultivates his human powers most effectually, and religious duty essentially consists in man’s doing to the glory of God that which is ac- cording to his own nature. The same stand-point is evident in the Philosophy of the Greeks, as will be shown further on ; and, though the philosophers as a rule, took few of their doctrines direetly from religious tradition, and were often openly at variance with the popular faith, still it is clear that the mode of thought to which the Hellenes had become accustomed in their religion was not without influence on their scientific tendencies. It was inevitable that from the naturalistic religion of Greece there should arise, in the first in- stance, a naturalistic philosophy. The Greek religion, furthermore, is distinguished from other naturalistic religions in that it assigns the highest place in existence neither to external nature, mor to the sensuous nature of man, as such, but to hu- man nature that is beautiful and transfigured by spirit. Man is not, as in the East, so entirely the slave of external impressions that he loses his own independence in the forces of nature, and feels that he is but a part of mature, irresistibly involved in its vicissitudes. Neither does he seek his satisfaction in the unbridled 54 INTRODUCTION. freedom of rude and half-savage races. But, while living and acting with the full sense of liberty, he con- siders that the highest exercise of that liberty is to obey the universal order as the law of his own nature. Although, therefore, in this religion, Deity is conceived as similar to man, it is not common human nature that is ascribed to it. Not only is the outer form of the gods idealised as the image of the purest beauty, but their essential nature, especially in the case of the Hellenic gods proper, is formed by ideals of human activities. The relation of the Greek to his gods was therefore free and happy to an extent that we find in no other nation, because his own nature was reflected and idealised in them; so that, in contemplating them, he found himself at once attracted by affinity, and elevated above the limits of his own existence, without having to purchase this boon by the pain and trouble of an in- termal conflict. Thus, the sensuous and natural become the immediate embodiment of the spiritual; the whole religion assumes an aesthetic character, religious ideas take the form of poetry; divine worship and the object of that worship are made material for art; and though we are still, speaking generally, on the level of naturalistic religion, nature is only regarded as the manifestation of Deity, because of the spirit which re- veals itself in nature. This idealistic character of the Greek religion was no doubt of the highest importance in the origin and formation of Greek philosophy. The exercise of the imagination, which gives universal significance to the particulars of sense, is the prepara- tory stage for the exercise of the intellect which, ab- THE RELIGION OF THE GREEKS. 55 stracting from the particular as such, seeks for the general essence and universal causes of phenomena. While, therefore, the Greek religion was based upon an ideal and aesthetic view of the world, and encouraged to the utmost all artistic activity in setting forth this view, it must have had indirectly a stimulating and emancipa- ting effect upon thought, and have prepared the way for the scientific study of things. From a material point of view, this idealistic tendency of religion was beneficial principally to Ethics; but from a formal point of view, the influence of religion extended to all parts of Philosophy; for Philosophy presupposes and requires an endeavour to treat the sensible as a manifes- tation of spirit, and to trace it back to spiritual causes. Some of the Greek philosophers may possibly have been too rash in their procedure in that respect ; but this we shall not at present consider. The more readily we admit that their doctrines often give us the impression of a philosophic poem full of bold inventions, rather than a work of science, the more clearly we shall see the connection of those doctrines with the artistic genius of the Greek nation, and with the aesthetic character of its religion. But although Greek Philosophy may owe much to religion, it owes more to the circumstance that its de- pendence on religion never went so far as to prevent, or essentially to restrict, the free movement of science. The Greeks had no hierarchy, and no inviolable dog- matic code. The sacerdotal functions were not with them the exclusive property of a class, nor were the priests the only mediators between the gods and men; but 56 INTRODUCTION. each individual for himself, and each community for itself, had a right to offer up sacrifices and prayers. In Homer, we find kings and chiefs sacrificing for their subjects, fathers for their families, each person for him- self, without the intervention of priests. Even at a later period, when the development of a public cult in temples gave more importance to the sacerdotal order, the func- tions of the priests were always limited to certain offer- ings and ceremonial observances in their particular localities; prayers and sacrifices were still offered by the laity, and a whole class of matters relating to religious ceremonial were left, not to priests, but to public func- tionaries designated by election, or by lot—in part in combination with officers of the community or state— to individuals and heads of families. The priests, therefore, as a class, could never acquire an influential position in Greece at all comparable with that which they enjoyed among the Oriental nations." Priests of certain temples, it is true, did attain to considerable importance on account of the oracles connected with those temples, but, on the whole, the priestly office con- ferred far more honour than influence; it was a politi- cal dignity, in respect to which reputation and external qualifications were more regarded than any particular mental capability; and Plato * is quite in harmony * This, by the way, is one of the most striking arguments against the hypothesis of any considerable transmission of cults and myths into Greece from the East; for these Oriental cults are so closely bound up with the hierarchical system that they could only have been transmitted in connection with it. If this had anywhere been the case, we should find the importance of the priests become greater the farther we went backinto antiquity, whereas in point of fact it is ex- actly the contrary. 2 Polit. 290 C. THE RELIGION OF THE GREEKS. 57 priests, in spite of all the honours accorded to them, merely servants of the commonwealth." But where there is no hierarchy, a dogmatic code, in the sense of a general law of faith, is manifestly impossible; for there are no organs to frame and maintain it. Even in itself, however, it would have been contrary to the essence of Greek religion. That religion is not a finished and per- fected system that had grown up from one particular spot. The ideas and traditions which the Greek races brought with them from their original abodes were carried by each individual tribe, community and family into dif- ferent surroundings, and subjected to influences of the most various kinds. Thus, there arose a multiplicity of local rites and legends; and from these, a common Hellenic faith gradually developed itself, not by the systematising of theology, but by a free convergence of minds; in which convergence the most important factor, beside the personal intercourse and religious ceremonies of the national games and festivals, was Art, and above all, Poetry. This explains the fact, that in Greece there was never, properly speaking, a system o religious doctrine generally admitted, but only a myth- ology; and that the conception of orthodoxy was abso- lutely unknown. Every one was indeed required to honour the gods of the State; and those who were convicted of withholding the prescribed honours, or of trying to overthrow the religion of the State, were | often visited with the severest punishments. But i \º the spirit of his country when he makes the * Cf. Hermann. Lehrbuch der 44 sq. for more detailed proofs of Griech. Antiquitäten, ii. 158 sqq., the above statements. 58 -- INTRODUCTION. though Philosophy itself was thus hardly dealt with, in the person of some of its representatives, on the whole, the relation of individuals to the faith of the community was far freer than among nations who possessed a definite confession of faith guarded by a powerful priesthood. The severity of the Greeks _x-against religious innovation had immediate reference not to doctrines, but to cult; only so far as a doctrine seemed to involve consequences prejudicial to public worship did it become the object of attack. As to theological opinions, properly so called, they were left unmolested. The Greek religion possessed neither a body of theological doctrine nor written sacred records. It was founded entirely upon traditions respecting the temples, descriptions of the poets, and notions of the people: moreover, there was scarcely any tradition which was not contradicted by others, and in that way . lost much of its authority. Thus, in Greece, faith was too indefinite and elastic in its form to admit of its exercising upon reason either an internal supremacy, or an external restraint, to the extent that we find to have been the case in other countries. This free attitude of Greek science in respect to religion was full of important results, as will be evi- dent if we consider what would have become of Greek Philosophy, and indirectly of our own, without this freedom. All the historical analogies that we can adduce will give us but one answer; namely, that the Greeks would them have been as little able as the Oriental na- tions to attain an independent philosophic science. The speculative impulse might indeed have been awake, THE RELIGION OF THE GREEKS. 59 but, jealously watched as it would have been by theology, internally cramped by religious presuppositions, and shackled in its free movement, thought could scarcely have produced anything more than a religious specula- tion akin to the ancient theologic cosmologies; and even supposing that at a much later period it had turned to other questions, it could never have had the acuteness, freshness, and freedom by which the Philo- sophy of Greece became the teacher of all the ages. The Hindoos were the most speculative nation of the East, and their civilisation was of the highest antiquity, yet how greatly inferior were they, as regards philoso- phic achievement, to the Greeks' The same must be said of the Christian and Mohammedan Philosophy in the Middle Ages, though this had the advantage of being preceded by the Greek. In both eases, the principal cause of the inferiority manifestly lay in the depen- dence of science upon positive dogmas; and the Greeks are to be considered as singularly fortunate in having escaped this dependence through the force of their peculiar genius, and the favourable course of their his- torical development. It has been usually supposed that between Philo- sophy and the religion of the mysteries a closer bond exists. In the mysteries, according to this view, a purer, or at any rate a more speculative, theology was imparted to the initiated ; and, by means of the mys- teries, the secret doctrines of Eastern priests were trans- mitted to the Greek philosophers, and through them to the Greek people in general. But this theory has no better foundation than the one we have just been dis- 60 INTRODUCTION. \ \ -\ cussing in regard to Oriental Science. It is proved beyond a doubt, by the most recent and thorough investigations' of the subject, that originally no philo- sophic doctrines were conveyed in these religious cere- monies; and that at a later period, when such doctrines began to be connected with the mysteries, this occurred under the influence of scientific researches. Philosophy, therefore, should be regarded rather as having imparted wisdom to the mysteries than as having received it from them. The mysteries were originally, as we have every reason to believe, ritualistic Solemnities, which, in their religious import and character, differed nothing from the public worship of the gods, and were only carried on in secret because they were designed for some particular community, sex, or class, to the exclusion of any other, or because the nature of the divinities to whom they were sacred demanded this form of cult. The first, for example, applies to the mysteries of the Idaean Zeus and the Argive Here, the second to the Eleusinian mysteries, and especially to the secret rites of the Chthonian deities. Mysteries first appeared in a certain opposition to public religion, partly because elder cults and forms of worship which had gradually disappeared from the one were maintained in the other, and partly because foreign rites like those of the Thracian Dionysus and * Among which the following have been chiefly consulted: Lo- beck's fundamental work (Aglao- phamus, 1829), and the short but thorough exposition of Hermann (Griech. Antiq. ii. 149 sqq.), espe- cially Preller's Demeter und Per- Sephone, as well as his investiga- tions in Pauly's Real-Encyklopædie der Klass. Alterth. (under the headings Mythologie, Mysteria, Eleusinia, Orpheus); lastly, the Griechische Mythologie of the same author. On the mysteries in general, cf. also Hegel's Phil. der Geschichte, 301 sq.; AEsthetik, ii. 57 sq.; Phil. der Rel. ii. 150 sqq. THE RELIGION OF THE MYSTERIES. 61 the Phrygian Cybele were introduced as private cult-º- under the form of mysteries, and blended themselves, in course of time, more or less with the ancient secret rites. But in neither case can the mysteries have com- tained philosophic theorems, or doctrines of a purer theology essentially transcending the popular faith." This is sufficiently proved by the circumstance that the --~~~~ mysteries most frequently celebrated were accessible * { all the Greeks. For even had the priests possessed any higher wisdom, how could they have imparted it to such a mixed multitude 2 And what are we to think of a secret philosophic doctrine into which a whole nation could be initiated without a long course of previous in- struction, and without having its faith shaken in the traditional mythology? Speaking generally, it is not at all in keeping with the habits of the ancients to take advantage of ceremonial observances for the purpose of instructing the people by means of religious discourses. A Julian might make the attempt in imitation of Christian customs; but in classical times there is not a single instance of it, nor does any trustworthy witness ever assert that the mysteries were designed for the in- struction of those who took part in them. Their parti- cular end appears far more in those sacred rites, the witnessing of which was the privilege of the initiated (Epoptae); whatever oral communication was combined with these ceremonies seems to have been restricted to short liturgical formulae, directions for the performance of the holy rites, and sacred traditions (ispo, Aéryot), like * As Lobeck, loc. cit. i. 6 sqq., which distinguishes him, expresses has exhaustively shown. * Leibniz, himself to the same effect in the with the sound historical judgment Preface to the Theodicee, section 2. 62 INTRODUCTION. those which were elsewhere commected with particular acts of worship; tales about the founding of cults and holy places, about the names, origin, and history of the gods to whom this worship was sacred; in a word, my- thological explanations of the cult given by the priests, or even by laymen, to those who asked for them. These liturgical and mythological elements were afterwards made use of to combine philosophical and theological doctrines with the mysteries, but that such was the case from the beginning is a theory without foundation. There is no trustworthy authority for it, and on general grounds it is unlikely that the mythopoeic imagination should ever have been dominated by philosophic points of view; or that at a later period there should have been introduced into mystic usages and traditions ideas and hypotheses which the scientific reflection of the Greeks had not as yet attained. In course of time, indeed, with the deepening of the moral consciousness, the mysteries gradually acquired a higher signification. When the school of the Orphics, whose doctrines from the first are parallel to Greek Philosophy," was founded in the * The first certain trace of the of the Homeric poems) published, Orphic writings, and of the Or- phico-Dionysiac consecrations, is to be found in the well-attested statement (vide Lobeck, loc cit i. 331 sqq., 397 sqq., 692 sqq.; cf. Ger- hard, Ueber Orpheus und die Or- phiker, Abhandlungen der Berl. Acad. 1861; Hist. Phil. Kl. p. 22, 75; Schuster, De vet. Orphica theogoniae indole, 1869, p. 46 sqq.) that Onomacritus (who resided at the court of Pisistratus and his sons, and with two or three other persons, undertook the collection under the names of Orpheus and Musaeus, oracular sayings and hymns (TeAeral) which he had himself composed. This forgery falls somewhere between 540 and 520 B.C. It is probable, however, not only that Orphic hymns and oracles had been in circulation pre- viously to this, but that the union of the Dionysiac mysteries with the Orphic poetry had long ago been accomplished. Two or three generations later, the names of the Orphics and Bacchics were used THE RELIGION 63 OF THE MYSTERIES. century before Christ, or even earlier, the in- fluence of the philosophers upon this mystic theology seems to have been far greater than the reaction of the theologians upon Philosophy; and the more we con- sider particular detail, the more doubtful it becomes whether on the whole Philosophy ever borrowed any- thing considerable from the mysteries or mystic doc- trimes. There are two points especially, in regard to which the mysteries are supposed to have exercised an im- portant influence on Philosophy: these are Monotheism and the hope of a future life. A speculative interpre- tation has also been given to some other doctrines, but they appear to contain nothing beyond the common by Herodotus (ii. 81) as identical, and Philolaus appeals in support of the doctrine of transmigration (vide infra, Pythag.) to the utter- ances of the ancient theologians and soothsayers, by whom we must chiefly understand Orpheus and the other founders of the Orphic mysteries. Aristotle's testimony certainly cannot be adduced in favour of the higher antiquity of the Orphic theology. Philoponus indeed observes (De an. F, 5, in re- ference to a passage from Aristotle, De an, i. 5, 410, b. 28) that Aris- totle, speaking of the Orphic poems, says the poems ‘called Orphic– &reið, whºokei’Oppéos éival tă ărm, &s kal airbs év Tots trepl pix00 o'blas Aéyet attoº uév ydp eiori Tà 56Y.- para raúra öé pmoliv (for which we ought, most likely, to read qaolv) 5voua kpefrtov čvéreaſe kata- reſvai (read 'Ovopadkpitov čv šarea, karaðerval). But the words attoo pºv yiſp eigi rā 56Yuara show by their form that they are not a quo- tation from Aristotle, but a remark of Philoponus; and he is probably only repeating a Neo-Platonic ex- pedient, by which the Aristotelian criticism of the Orphic poems was to be rendered harmless; that Aristotle never so expressed him- self is clear, from the passage in Cicero, N. D. i. 38, 107, which pro- bably refers to the same writing of Aristotle: Orpheum Poétam docet Aristoteles nunquam fuisse. The Orphic theogony is not ascribed to Onomacritus; other Orphic wri- tings are said to have been com- posed by Cercops, the Pythagorean Brontinus, Zopyrus of Heraclea (the same who worked with Ono- macritus at the edition of Homer), Prodicus of Samos, and others. (Suidas, 'Opp. Clemens, Strom. i. 333 A : cf. Schuster loc. cit. and p. 55 sq. For further remarks vide infra.) (34 INTRODUCTION. and ordinary thoughts of all mankind." Even, however, in these two cases, the influence seems neither so certain nor so considerable as has commonly been believed. In regard to the unity of God, the theistic conception proper is as little to be found in the mystic as in the popular theology. It is impossible to imagine how the unity of God in the Jewish or Christian sense 2 could be inculcated at the feasts of the Eleusinian deities, or of the Cabiri, or of Dionysus. It is a different matter, certainly, in respect to the pantheism which appears in a fragment of the Orphic theogony,” where Zeus is described as the beginning, middle, and end of all things, the root of the earth and sky, the substance and essence of air and of fire, the sun and moon, male and female; where the sky is called his head, the Sun and moon are his eyes, the air is his breast, the earth his body, the lower world his foot, the aether his infallible, royal, omniscient reason. Such a pantheism was not incompatible with polytheism, a soil which the mysteries never quitted. As the gods of polytheism were in truth only the various For example, the mythus of the slaying of Zagreus by the Titans (forfurther details cf. Lobeck, i. 615 sqq.), to which the Neo-Platonists, and before them even the Stoics, had given a philosophic interpreta- tion, but which in its original meaning was probably only a rather crude variation of the well-worn theme of the death of Nature in winter, with which the thought of the decay of youth and its beauty was connected. This myth had no influence on the ear- lier philosophy, even if we suppose Empedocles to have made allusion to it—v. 70 (142). * We find the unity of God in this sense affirmed in so-called Orphic fragments (Orphica, ed. Hermann, Fr. 1–3), of which some were probably, and others certainly, composed or altered by Alexan- drian Jews. * Wide Lobeck, p. 520 sqq.; and Hermann, Fr. 6. Similarly the fragment from the Ata.0%ikai (in Lobeck, p. 440; in Hermann, Fr. 4) was eſs Zets, eſs 'Atºms, eſs “HAtos, e’s Atóvvoros, eſs 6ebs év trøvreorgi, THE RELIGION OF THE MYSTERIES. 65 parts and forces of the world, the different spheres of mature and of human life, it is natural that the rela- tions of these spheres among themselves, and the preponderance of one of them over others, should in time be brought to light; and, therefore, in all highly developed naturalistic religions, we see that kindred deities become blended together, and the whole poly- theistic Olympus is resolved into the general concep- tion of an all-embracing divine essence (6sſov). But the Greek religion, because of its plastic character, is just one of those which most resists this fusion of T definite forms of deity. In Greece, consequently, the idea of the divine unity was arrived at less by way of syncretism than of criticism; not by blending the many gods into one, but by combating the principle of polytheism. The Stoics and their successors were the first who sought to reconcile polytheism with their philosophic pantheism, by giving a syncretic interpreta- tion to polytheism; the older pantheism of Xenophanes was, on the contrary, bitterly and openly hostile to the doctrine of the plurality of gods. The pantheism of the Orphic poems, in the form above described, is probably much later than the first beginnings of Orphic literature. The Ala8%kat are certainly not anterior to the Alexandrian Syncretism ; nor can the passage re- specting the theogony, as it now stands, date from the time of Onomacritus, to which Lobeck' assigns the greater part of the poem. For this passage was in close connection with the story of Phanes-Ericapaus, devoured by Zeus. Zeus includes all things in * Loc. cit, 611. WOL. I. F 66 INTRODUCTION. himself, because he swallowed the already created world, or Phanes, that he might then produce all things from himself. We shall presently show that the swallowing of Phanes' originally formed no part of the Orphic theogony. We must, therefore, in all cases distinguish the original text of the Orphic passage from the modifications it may afterwards have under- gone. As part of the original text we may apparently claim the verse so frequently quoted,” and which is probably referred to by Plato:* Zets kepakh, Zets pºéarga, Atos 6’ x travra rérvictat.” The idea in this verse, however, and other similar ideas to be found in those portions of the Orphic writings supposed to be ancient, contain nothing essentially in advance of a conception familiar to Greek religion, and the gist of which was already expressed by Homer when he calls Zeus the Father of gods and men.” The unity of the divine element which polytheism itself recog- nises, was made concrete in Zeus as king of the gods; and so far, all that exists and all that happens is ulti- mately referred to Zeus. This idea may perhaps be expressed by calling Zeus the beginning, middle, and end of all things; but the expression certainly does not * In the enquiry into the Or- the circumstance that the words phic cosmogony, infra. * Ap. Proclus in Timaeus, 95 F, and the Platonic scholiast, p. 451, Bekk. * Laws, iv. 715 E. Further references as to the employment of this verse by the Stoics, Platonists, Neo-Pythagoreans and others, are given by Lobeck, p. 529 sq. * This theory is supported by quoted from Orpheus by Proclus in Timaeus, 310 D; Plat. Theol. 17, 8, p. 363: rö 8& Airm troAirolvos &petrero, coincide with the Pla- tonic passage. Afrn is also called troAirolvos in Parmenides. W. 14. * Cf. also Terpander (about 650 P. c.), Fr. 4: Zeß révrov &pxà wdivºreov &yſtwp. THE RELIGION OF THE MYSTERIES 67 imply that Zeus is himself the ideal complex(Inbegriff) of all things." There is consequently no evidence that the standpoint of the religious motion, which conceives the gods as personal beings, side by side with the world, has here been exchanged for that of philosophic specu- lation, which regards them as representing the general essence of the universe. The case is somewhat different in regard to the second point in question, belief in immortality. The doctrine of metempsychosis seems really to have passed from the theology of the mysteries into Philosophy. Even this doctrine, however, was in all probability originally connected, not with all, but only with the Bacchic and Orphic mysteries. Those of Eleusis, being sacred to the Chthonian divinities, were regårded as specially important in their influence upon man's future- life. The Homeric hymn to Demeter already speaks of the great difference in the other world between the lots of the initiated and uninitiated; * and there are later eulogies of these mysteries, from which it is clear that they guaranteed happiness not only in this life, but in the life to come.” There is nothing here, however, to imply that the souls of the initiated are to come to life again, or that they are immortal in any other sense than was admitted by the ordinary faith of the Greeks. i Even monotheism allows ex- 5x8wos, Šs rā6’ browev čwux8ovíov pressions such as é; attoo ral &v6pótrov" Ši' airoi, kal eis airov rà tróvra s 6 &rexhs iepāv, bs t” upopos, (Romans, xi. 36)—év airé ºpew oštro8° àpoinv ral kivočueða kal équév (Apg. aioav exel, półkeyás rep, Širo (694, 17, 28), without meaning by them eūpāevrt. _{* that the Finite is actually merged * Cf. the references in Lobeck in Deity. i. 69 sqq. p * v. 480 sqq. F 2 68 INTRODUCTION. In this world wealth and fruitful fields' were expected from Demeter and her daughters in return for worship rendered to them; and in a similar manner, after death, the partakers of the mysteries were assured that they should dwell in Hades, in closest proximity to the di- vinities they had honoured, while the uninitiated were threatened with being cast into a marsh.” If these rude notions, at a later period, and among the more educated, received a spiritual interpretation,” there is no reason to suppose that this was so originally, or that the initiated were promised anything in the future except the favour of the infernal gods; the popular opinions about Hades remained quite un- affected by them. Even Pindar's celebrated utterances carry us no farther. For in saying that the partakers of the Eleusinian mysteries know the beginning and end of their life,” he does not assert the doctrine of transmigration,” and though in other passages this doctrine is undoubtedly brought forward,” it is still * Hymn to Ceres, 486 sqq. * Aristides, Eleusin. p. 421 Dind. The same is asserted of the Diony- sian mysteries (to which perhaps this beliefitselfmay originally have been peculiar) in Aristophanes, Frogs, 145 sqq.; Plato, Phaedo, 69 C; Gorgias, 493 A.; Republic, ii. 363 C; cf. Diog. vi. 4. * Thus Plato in the Phaedo and Gorgias, and, in a lesser degree, śs. in the words (in Plu- tarch, aud. poèt. c. 4, p. 21 F): às TptoróA8tol keºvot 3porów, of taota belx0évres TéAm poxodor és "öov' rota 86 yap pièvous exe? (fiv Čorri, toſs 3’ &AAotori rāvr' éke? rakó. * Thren. Fr. 8 (114 Bergk): 5A310s, 80 ris ióðy keºv' eio' into x0óv’ olós uév 8tov rexevrév, oičev 6& Stöoróorov apxºv. * For the words can only pro- perly mean that he who has re- ceived the consecration regards life as a gift of God, and death as the transition to a happier state. Preller's explanation (Demeter und Persephone, p. 236) seems to me less natural. ° Ol. ii. 68 sqq. Thren. Fr. 4, and infra, p. 70, note 4. THE RELIGION OF THE MYSTERIES. 69 questionable whether the poet borrowed it from the Eleusinian theology; and even if he did apply the Eleusinian myths and symbols in this sense, it would not certainly follow that such was their original meaning." In the Qrphie theology, on the contrary, transmigra- tion is clearly to be found, and the probabilities a.I'ê very strongly against its having come there through the medium of the philosophers. Several writers mention Pherecydes as the first who taught immor- tality,” or more precisely, transmigration;” but the testimony of Cicero and other later authors is not suffi- cient, in the absence of older evidence,” to prove this statement. Even if we admit the probability that Pherecydes spoke of transmigration, the assertion of his having been the first to do so rests only cn the fact that no previous writings are known to contain that * The revival of dead nature in the spring was considered in the cult of Demeter as the return of souls from the under world, and harvest was looked upon as the descent of the souls thither (vide Preller, Dem. und Pers. 228 sqq.; Griech. Mythologie, i. 254,483); and this does not apply solely to the souls of plants, to which it prima- rily relates, but to the souls of men. At these seasons also de- parted spirits appear in the upper world. It was easy to interpret these notions as in plying the en- trance of human souls into the visible world from the invisible, and their return into the invisible again. Cf. Plato, Phaedo, 70 C: trañaiās uèv of v čari ris Aóryos, . . às eiolv [ai puxal] v0évôe dºpt- káueva èket ſcal r&Aw ye āeºpo dqukvoúvrai kal yºyvoviral ék Töv Teóved tww. * Cie. Tusc. i. 16, 38, and after him Lactantius, Instit. vii. 7, 8. Augustin c. Acad. iii. 37 (17), Epist. 137, p. 407, B. Mawr. * Suidas; $epekööms; Hesychius, De his qui erud. clar. p. 56, Orelli; Tatian c. Graec. c. 3, 25, according to the obvious correction in the edition of Maurus. Cf. Porphyry, Antr. Nymph. c. 31. Preller also (Rhein. Mus. iv. 388) refers with some appearance of probability what is quoted by Origen (c. Cels. vi. p. 304) from Pherecydes, and Themist. Or. ii. 38, a, to the doc- trine of Transmigration. * Cf. Aristoxenus, Duris and Hermippus-—so far as they have been quoted in Diog. i. 116 sqq. and viii. 1 sqq. 70 INTRODUCTION. doctrine. Still more uncertain is the theory' that Pythagoras was the first to introduce it. Heracleitus clearly presupposes this; Philolaus expressly appeals to the ancient theologians and soothsayers” for the theory that souls were fettered to the body, and as it were buried in it, as a punishment. Plate*-derives the same theory from the mysteries, and more particularly from the Orphic mysteries; and Pindar teaches that certain favourites of the gods are to be permitted to return to the upper world, and that those who thrice have led a blameless life will be sent to the islands of the blest in the kingdom of Cromos.” In this last representation, we perceive an alteration in the doc- trime; for whereas the return to corporeal life is else- * Maximus Tyr. xvi. 2; Dio- genes, viii. 14; Porph. v.; Pyth. 19. * Ap. Clemens, Strom. iii. 433 A, and previously ap. Cicero, Hor- tens. Fr. 85 (iv. 6, 483 Or.) This passage, as well as others from Plato, will be quoted at length in the section on the Pythagorean Metempsychosis, infra. * Phaedo, 62 B; Crat. 400 B. Cf. Phaedo, 69 C, 70 C ; Laws, ix. 870 D; and Lobeck, Aglaoph. ii. 795 sqq. * Pindar's eschatology follows no fixed type (cf. Preller's Demeter wnd Persephone, p. 239), while, in many places, he adopts the usual notions about Hades, in Thren. 2 it is said that after the death of the body, the soul, which alone springs from the gods, remains alive; and in two places transmi- gration is alluded to, viz. in Thren. Fr. 4 (110), quoted by Plato, Meno, 81 B : oia i ö& pepae póva wolvåv traxalog wrév}eos 6éčeral, és Töv širepòey &Atov keſvov évárq àrei &völöof juxāv ráxiv, ék Töv Baat?, fies & Yavol Ical orbével xpatrvol oroq tº piéytotot &vöpes aiſſour” is 5& Töv Aoirov xpóvov #pares àyvoi ºpos &v6pówww. Raxeovral. And Ol. ii. 68, after mention of the rewards and punishments in Hades ãoroi 3’ &róxuaoravčarpts êicatépetl usivayres àrà réutraw &öſcov čxeiv $vxdv, *relaav Atôs 66bv trapū Kpóvov Túparty évêa wakópov vāoos, [vāorov) &keavíðes aſſpai wept- *Peel O'ly. Thren. Fr. 3 (109), where the wicked have the lower world, and the righteous, heaven, assigned as their dwelling-place, cannot be ac- cepted as genuine. THE RELIGION OF THE MYSTERIES. 71 where always regarded as a punishment and a means of improvement, in Pindar it appears as a privilege accorded only to the best, giving them an opportunity of earning higher happiness in the islands of the blest, instead of the inferior happiness of Hades. But this use of the . doctrine presupposes the doctrine itself, and according to the quotations from Plato and Philolaus, we must assume that Pindar derived it from the Orphic mysteries. It is certainly conceivable that it might still have reached the mysteries through Pythagoreism, which must early have been connected with the Orphic cult." But the most ancient testimonies, and the Py- thagoreans themselves, refer it solely to the mysteries; and it is besides very doubtful whether the Pythagorean doctrines could have been prevalent in Thebes, in the time of Pindar,” whereas that city is, on the other hand, known to have been an ancient seat of the Bacchic and Orphic religion. Lastly, the doctrine of metempsychosis is ascribed to Pherecydes, and regarded as anterior to Pythagoras, not only by the writers we have quoted, but indirectly by all those who make Pherecydes the teacher of Pythagoras. * We have, therefore, every reason to believe that it was taught in the omni.” mysteries prior to the date of Pythagoras. According to Herodotus, the Orphics obtained it from Egypt:* * A number of Orphic writings * On which vide infra, Pytha- are said to have been invented by goras and the Pythagoreans. the Pythagoreans; vide Lobeck, * ii. 123: trpárov 68 ka, toirov Aglaoph. i. 347 sqq., and supra, Tov A6)ow Aiyêtriot eign of eiróvres, p. 62, note. &s &v0pórov puxh &6ávatós éoti, 2 Cf. what will hereafter be roo odºuaros 3& karap6tvovtos és said in the history of the Pythago- &AAo (§ow aiel yivöuevov Čačeral' rean philosophy, of the propagation étéâu & trepiéA6m révra tº xepoaſa of that philosophy. . kal 1& 6axárqua kal treretvá, airis 72 INTRODUCTION. but this theory either rests upon a mere conjecture of his own, or a still more untrustworthy statement of the Egyptian priests; as historical evidence, it is of no value whatever. As to the real state of the case, history tells us nothing, and no guess that we can make even approximates to certainty. It is possible that Herodotus may be right in the main, and that the belief in transmigration was really transplanted from Egypt into Greece, either directly, or through certain intermediaries which cannot precisely be de- termined. But in that case, we can scarcely agree with him in supposing the Greeks to have become acquainted with it in the first beginnings of their culture, still less can we connect this acquaintanceship with the mythical personalities of Cadmus and Melampus : the most pro- bable assumption would then be, that the doctrine had been introduced into Greece not very long before the date when we first meet with it in Greek writings— perhaps, therefore, about the seventeenth century. But it is also conceivable that this belief, the affinity of which with Hindoo and Egyptian doctrines indicates an Eastern source, may have originally immigrated from the East with the Greeks themselves, and have been at first confined to a narrow circle, becoming after- wards more important and more widely diffused. It és àv0p6trov géºpia yuáuevov čaršūvetv. Thy repuſix vow 8% airfi yívea 6at év ºrptorxtAfolat reori, roëtq rô A6-yº eior of ‘EAA#vov čxpñoravro, oi wºv mpérepov of 8* iſotepov, &s iótº éovräv čávri Tôv éyò eiðds r& oùvápara oi Ypápo. Cf. c. 81 : rotori 'Oppikolai kaxeoplevotori kal Bakxukoſal, oùor 5* Aiyvirtíotai. Herodotus thought (according to ch. 49) that Melampus had intro- duced the cult of Dionysus, which he had learned from Cadmus and his followers, into Greece ; but, on the other hand, in C. 53, he inti- mates that he considers the Orphic poems more recent than Homer and Hesiod. THE RELIGION OF THE MYSTERIES. 73 might be urged, in support of this view, that similar notions have been found among races which never in any way came under Egyptian influence." Nor can we altogether dispute the possibility of different nations, without any historical connection, having arrived at the same opinions concerning a future state. Even so strange a theory as transmigration seems to us may thus have been reached in several cases independently one of the other. For if the natural desire to escape death engenders a universal belief in immortality, a bolder fancy, in nations not yet capable of spiritual ab- straction, might well shape this desire and belief into the hope and expectation of a return to earthly life.” * According to Herodotus, iv. 94 sq., the Thracian Getae believed that the dead came to the god Zal- moxis or Gebeleizin; and every five years they sent a messenger to this god by means of a special hu- man sacrifice, entrusted with com- munications to their departed friends. That the theory of trans- migration was involved in this cannot be deduced from the state- ment of the Greeks of the Helles- pont, that Zalmoxis was a scholar of Pythagoras, who had taught the belief in immortality to the Thra- cians. Herodotus says that it was the custom of another Thracian tribe (Her. v. 4) to bewail the newly born, and to praise the dead as happy; because the former are about to encounter the ills of life, while the latter have escaped from them. But this custom proves even less than the other in regard to metempsychosis. The Gauls, how- ever, are said to have believed, not only in immortality, but also in transmigration: Caesar, B. Gall. vi. 14, in primis hoc volunt persuadere (Druides) non interire animas, sed aſ aliis post mortem transire ad alios. Diodor. v. 28, sub fin. : éviorxãet ºyàp trap' &üroſs 6 IIv6ayópov A6-yos, §ti rās puxās róv &v0p6trov &6a- várous elval orvuòé8mke kal 6t’ érów &ptop, #vov tróxiv 8toov, eis repov orópa rās bux?s eigõvouévns. On this account many persons, adds Dio- dorus, place letters to their friends on the funeral pile. So Ammian. Marc. xv. 9, sub fin. * If the soul is conceived as a breath-like essence which dwells in the body, and leaves it after death according to the opinion of the ancients, and especially of the Greeks, the question inevitably arises whence this essence comes, and whither it goes. For answer to this question, a child-like imagi- nation is most easily satisfied with the simple notion that there is a place, invisible to us, in which the departed souls remain, and from which the newly born come forth. And we do, in fact, find in many 74 INTRODUCTION. However this may be, it appears certain, that among the Greeks the doctrine of transmigration came not from the philosophers to the priests, but from the priests to the philosophers. Meantime it is a question whether its philosophic importance in antiquity was very great. It is found, indeed, with Pythagoras and his school, and Empedocles is in this respect allied with them; a higher life after death is also spoken of by Heracleitus. But none of these philosophers brought the doctrine into such a connection with their scientific theories as to make it an essential constituent of their philosophic system: it stands with them all for a self- dependent dogma side by side with their scientific theory, in which no lacuna would be discoverable if it were removed. A philosophic basis was first given to the belief in immortality by Plato; and it would be hard to maintain that he would not have arrived at it without the assistance of the myths which he employed for its exposition. From all that has now been said, it would appear that Greek Philosophy in regard to its origin was no more indebted to the religion of the mysteries than to the public religion. The views of nature which were contained in the mysteries may have given an impulse to thought ; the idea that all men need religious con- secration and purification may have led to deeper study of the moral nature and character of man; but as different nations, not merely the this there is but a step to the belief in a kingdom of the dead, theory that the same souls which but the idea that souls return to previously inhabited a body should the body from the lower regions of afterwards enter another body. the earth or from heaven. From THE RELIGION OF THE MYSTERIES. 75 Scientific instruction was not originally contemplated in the tales and practices of the mystic cult, any philosophic exposition of these presupposed that the expositor had already attained the philosophic stand- point; and as the mysteries were after all only made up of general perceptions and experiences accessible to everyone, a hundred other things could really perform for Philosophy the same service that they did. Philo- sophy did not require the myth of Kore and Demeter to reveal the alteriation of matural conditions, the passage from death to life and from life to death; daily observation sufficed for the acquisition of this know- ledge. The necessity of moral purity, and the advan- tages of piety and virtue, needed not to be proclaimed by the glowing descriptions of the priests concerning the happiness of the initiated and the misery of the profane. These conceptions were immediately con- tained in the moral consciousness of the Greeks. Nevertheless, the mysteries were by no means without importance in regard to Philosophy, as the results of our enquiry have shown. But their importance is not So great, nor their influence so direct, as has often been imagined. § III.-The Nulive Sources of Greek Philosophy continued. MORAL LIFE, CIVIL AND POLITICAL CONDITIONS. THE ideality of the Greek religion finds its counter- part in the freedom and beauty of Greek life; it is impossible to regard either of these characteristics, strictly speaking, as the ground or consequence of the 76 INTRODUCTION. other; they grew up side by side, mutually requiring and sustaining one another, out of the same matural temperament and under the same favourable conditions. As the Greek reverenced in his gods the natural and moral order of the world, without therefore renouncing in regard to them his own value and freedom, so Greek morality stands in a happy mean between the lawless license of barbarous and semi-barbarous races and the slavish obedience which subjects the peoples of the East to the will of another and to a temporal and spiritual despotism. A strong feeling of liberty, and at the same time a rare susceptibility to measure, form, and order; a lively sense of community in existence and action ; a social impulse which made it an absolute necessity for the individual to ally himself to others, to subordinate himself to the common will, to follow the tradition of his family and his country—these qualities, so essential in the Hellenes, produced in the limited area of the Greek states a full, free and harmonious life, such as no other nation of antiquity can exhibit. The very narrowness of the sphere in which their moral perceptions moved was in itself favourable to this result. As the individual knew that he was free and had a right to protection only as being a citizen of this or that state, and as, in the same way, his relation to others was determined by their relation to the state to which he belonged, every one from the beginning had his problem clearly marked out for him. The maintaining and extension of his civil importance, the fulfilment of his civil duties, work for the freedom and greatness of his people, obedience to the laws, GREEK POLITICAL LIFE, 77 these constituted the simple end which the Greek definitely proposed to himself, and in the pursuit of which he was all the less disturbed because his glances and endeavours seldom strayed beyond the limits of his home, because he excluded the idea of seeking the rule of his actions elsewhere than in the laws and customs of his state, because he dispensed with all the reflections by which the man of modern times labours to reconcile, on the one side, his individual interests and matural rights with the interest and laws of the commonwealth, and, on the other, his patriotism with the claims of a cosmopolitan morality and religion. We cannot, indeed, regard this narrow conception of moral problems as the highest possible conception, nor can we conceal from ourselves how closely the dismem- berment of Greece, the consuming disquiet of its civil wars and party struggles, not to speak of slavery and the neglect of female education, were connected with this narrowness; but our eyes must not therefore be closed to the fact that on this soil and from these presuppositions a freedom and culture arose which give to the Greeks their unique place in history. It is \ easy also to see how deeply and essentially Philosophy was rooted in the freedom and order of the Greek state. There was not, indeed, any immediate commection be- } tween them. Philosophy in Greece was always the! private concern of individuals, states only troubled, º themselves about it in so far as they interfered with all doctrines morally and politically dangerous; it received no positive encouragement or support from cities and princes until a late period, when it had long 78 INTRODUCTION. passed beyond the highest point of its development. Nor was public education concerned with philosophy, or science of any kind. At Athens, even in the time of Pericles, it scarcely included the first rudiments of what we should call scientific culture; nothing was attempted beyond reading, writing, and a certain amount of arithmetic: history, mathematics, physics, the study of foreign languages, and so forth, were altogether ignored. The philosophers themselves, and especially the Sophists, were the first to induce certain individuals to seek for wider instruction, which, how- ever, was even then restricted almost exclusively to rhetoric. Besides the above-mentioned elementary arts, ordinary education consisted entirely of music and gymnastics; and music was primarily concerned, not so much with intellectual training as with proficiency in the Homeric and Hesiodic poems, and the popular songs, singing, playing on stringed instruments, and dancing. But this education formed complete and vigorous men, and the subsequent discipline of public life engendered such self-confidence, demanded such an exercise of all the powers, such acute observation and intelligent judgment of persons and circumstances, above all, such energy and worldly prudence, as must necessarily have borne important fruit to science when- ever the scientific need arose. That it could not fail to arise was certain; for in the harmonious many- sidedness of the Greek character, the development of moral and political reflection called forth a correspond- ing and natural development of speculative thought ; and not a few of the Greek cities had attained, by GREEK EDUCATION. 79 means of civil liberty, a degree of prosperity which ensured leisure for scientific activity to some at least of their citizens. Although, therefore, in ancient times, the political life and education of the Greeks had no direct concern with Philosophy; and although, on the other hand, the earliest Philosophy, as a rule, neglected ethical and political questions, yet the train- ing of men and the fact that circumstances took the form required for the production of Philosophy were important elements in its history. Freedom and severity of thought were the matural fruits of a free and law-directed life; and the sound and sterling characters which grew up on the classic soil of Greece could not fail, even in science, to adopt their standpoint with decision, and to maintain it clearly and definitely, with full and unwavering purpose." Lastly, it was one of the chief excellences of Greek education that it did not split up human nature, but, by the even development of all the powers of man, songht to make of him a beautiful whole, a moral work—f- of art. This trait we may venture to connect with the fact that Greek science, especially in its commencement, chose the path that is indeed generally taken by thought in its infancy—the path downward from above; that it did not form a theory of the whole from the aggrega- 1 This intimate connection of †† with philosophy is strik- ingly shown by the fact that many of the ancient philosophers were distinguished as statesmen, legis- lators, political reformers and generals. The political activity of Thales and of the Pythagoreans is well known. We are told that Parmenides gave laws to his native city, and that Zeno perished in his attempt to free his countrymen. Empedocles restored democracy in Agrigentum; Archytas was no less great as a general than as a states- man ; and Melissus is probably the same person who vanquished the Athenian fleet. 80 INTRODUCTION, tion of individuals, but sought to gain a standard for the individual from the study of the whole, and at once to shape a collective representation from the existing fragments of cosmical knowledge; that philosophy in Greece preceded the particular sciences. If we examine somewhat more closely the circum- stances which conditioned the progress of Greek culture before the appearance of philosophy, two phenomena especially claim our attention : these are the republi form of the government, and the spread of the Greek races by colonisation. The centuries which immedi- ately preceded the earliest Greek Philosophy, and those which partly coincided with it, are the times of the legislators and of the tyrants, of the transition to those constitutional forms of government on the soil of which Greek political life attained its highest perfection. When the patriarchal monarchy of the Homeric period, in consequence of the Trojan war and the Doric migra- tion, and through the extinction, disqualification or banishment of the ancient royal houses, had entirely given place to oligarchy, the aristocracy became the means of spreading freedom and higher culture through- out the smaller circle of the ruling families. After- wards when the oppressions and internal deterioration of these families had evoked the resistance of the masses, the popular leaders came mostly from the ranks of their hitherto masters, and these demagogues almost everywhere eventually became tyrants. But as the government by a single person, because of its very origin, found its chief adversary in the aristocracy, and, as a counterpoise, was forced to fall back for support POLITICAL LIFE OF THE GREEKS. 81 upon the people, it became itself a means of training and educating the people to freedom. The courts of the tyrants were centres of art and culture; and when their rule was overthrown, which generally happened in the course of one or two generations, their inheritance of power did not revert to the earlier aristocracy, but to moderate constitutions founded on fixed laws. This course of things was as favourable to the scientific as to the political training of the Greeks. In the efforts and struggles of this political movement, all the powers which public life brought to science must have been aroused and employed, and the feeling of youthful liberty imparted to the spirit of the Greek people a stimulus which must needs have affected their specula- tive activity. Thus the laying of the foundations of the scientific and artistic glory of Greece was eagerly carried on side by side with the transformation of her political circumstances; a connection of phenomena which is very striking, and which shows that among the Greeks, as among all healthy nations, culture has been the fruit of liberty. This general revolution was effected more quickly in the colonies than in the mother country; and the existence of these colonies was of the highest importance in regard to it. During the 500 years which elapsed between the Doric conquests and the rise of Greek Philosophy, the Greek races had spread themselves, by means of organised emigration, on all sides. The islands * For example, those of Peri- wise men, there is no tradition of ander, Polycrates, Pisistratus, and the philosophers being connected his sons. But, excepting the story with tyrants before the appearance of Perlander's relation to the seven of the Sophists. WOL. I. G 82 INTRODUCTION. of the Archipelago, as far as Crete and Rhodes; the western and northern coasts of Asia Minor; the shores of the Black Sea, and the Propontis; the coasts of Thrace, Macedonia and Illyria; of Magna Graecia and Sicily, were covered with hundreds of settlements; Greek colonists had penetrated even to distant Gaul, to Cyrene, and to Egypt. Most of these settlements attained to prosperity, culture, and free constitutions, sooner than the states from which they emanated. Not only did the very disruption from their native soil pro- duce a freer movement, and a different organisation of civil society, but their whole situation was much more convenient for trade and commerce, for enterprising activity, and for all kinds of intercourse with strangers than was the case with the cities of Greece proper; it was therefore natural that in many respects they should outstrip the older states. How greatly they did so, and how important the rapid growth of the colonies was in regard to the development of Greek Philosophy, is best seen from the fact that all the Greek philosophers of Il O es, one or two Sophists only excepted, belonged either to the Ionian and Thracian cologies, or to those in Italy and Sicily. Here at the limits of the Hellenic world were the chief settlements of a higher culture, and as the immortal poems of Homer were a gift from the Greeks of Asia Minor to their native country, so also Philosophy came from the east and west to the centre of Greek life; there to attain its highest perfection, favoured by a happy combination of all forces, and a coincidence of all necessary conditions, at an epoch when, for most of the colonies, the COSMOLOGY. 83. brightest period of their history had passed away be- yond recall. How thought gradually developed itself under these circumstances up to the point at which the earliest scientific endeavours, in the strict sense of the word, were made, we learn to some extent from the still existing records of early cosmology and ethics, though our information from these sources is far from being complete. e § IV.-Native Sources of Greek Philosophy continued. COSMOLOGY. In a people so richly endowed as the Greeks, and so eminently favoured by circumstances in regard to their intellectual development, reflection must soon have been awakened, and attention directed to the pheno- mena of nature and of human life ; and attempts must early have been made, not merely to explain the external world in reference to its origin and Čauses, but also to consider the activities and conditions of mankind from more general points of view. This reflection was not, indeed, at first of a specifically scientific kind, for it was not as yet regulated by the thought of any general interdependence of things according to fixed law. Cos- mology, until the time of Thales, and, so far as it allied itself with religion, even longer, retained the form of a mythological narrative; Ethics, until the time of Socrates and Plato, that of aphoristic reflection. The fortuitous, and sometimes even miraculous, interference of imaginary beings took the place of the interdepen- G 2 84 INTRODUCTION. dence of nature; instead of one central theory of human life, we find a number of moral sayings and prudential maxims, which, abstracted from various experiences, not unfrequently contradicted one another, and, at the best, were reduced to no general principles and brought into no scientific connection with any theory of human nature. Though it would be a mistake to overlook this distinction, and to place either the mythic cosmologists or the gnomic poets in the number of the philosophers,' as has been done by some writers, both ancient and modern, yet we ought not, on the other hand, to under- rate the importance of these early attempts, for they were at least useful in calling attention to the questions which science had first to consider, and in accustoming thought to combine particular phenomena under general points of view ; and thus a good deal was done towards a beginning of Science. The most ancient record of mythic cosmology \ \among the Greeks is the Theogony of Hesiod. How much of this work is derived from still more ancient tradition, and how much is invented by the poet him- self and his later revisers, cannot now be discovered with certainty, nor is this the place to enquire. It is * As was certainly done in the most flourishing period of Greek Philosophy by the Sophists and by the adherents of systems of natural Philosophy. Plato is evidence of the former in Prot. 316 D, cf. ibid. 338 E sqq.; and of the latter there is mention in Crat. 402 B; and also in Aristotle, Metaph. i. 3,983 b, 27 (cf. Schwegler on this passage). The Stoics afterwards were especi- ally addicted to representing the ancient poets as the earliest philo- sophers, by the allegorical inter- pretation of their writings; and in the Neo-Platonists this practice passed all bounds. Tiedemann was the first to declare Thales the starting-point of Philosophy, vide his Geist der speculativen Philoso- phie, i. Preface, p. xviii. COSMOLOGY, HESIOD. 85 enough for our purpose to observe that the Theogony, with the exception of a few subsequent interpolations, was undoubtedly known to the earliest philosophers in its present form.' We find in it nothing approaching to a scientific apprehension or solution of the cosmo- logical problem. The poet proposes to himself the question from which all cosmogonies and histories of creation start, and which, indeed, obviously suggests itself even to the most undisciplined intellect, the question as to the origin and causes of all things. But in the Theogony this question has not the scientific importance of an enquiry into the essence and reasons of phenomena. With childlike curiosity the poet asks: Who made all things? and how did He make them P and the answer simply consists in positing as the first being something that cannot be explained away by thought, and making the rest originate from this by means of some analogy drawn from experience. Now experience points out two kinds of origin. All that we see either forms itself naturally, or else is made with a design by definite individuals. In the former case production takes place by the action of the ele- ments, by growth, or by generation ; in the latter, either mechanically by the elaboration of some given material, or dynamically, as we work upon other men * Cf. Petersen (Ursprung und shall hereafter consider) and the Alter der Hesiod: Theog. (Progr.der remarkable utterance of Herodotus—tº Hamburgischen Gymn.), 1862), who li. 53, are decided evidence against seems to me to have proved at any the supposition that the Theogony rate this much, whatever we may is no older than the sixth century; think of his other theories. The the general character of its con- polemic of Xenophanes and Hera- ceptions and language, however, cleitus against Hesiod (which we attest this even more strongly. 86 INTRODUCTION. by the mere expression of our will. All these analogies are applied, in the cosmogonies of different nations, to the origin of the world and of the gods; as a rule, several of them at once, according to the nature of the object in question. To the Greeks the analogy of generation must have been the most obvious, be- cause, in accordance with the particular bent of their imagination, they had personified the various parts of the world as beings akin to humanity, whose origin could be represented in no other way. In any case they must have kept to an analogy drawn from nature, for Greek thought was too naturalistic and polytheistic to maintain, like the Zoroastrian and Judaic religions, that everything had been called into existence by the mere fiat of a creator. In Greek mythology the gods themselves were created, and the deities worshipped by the people belong altogether to a younger race of gods; there is, therefore, no divinity who can be regarded as the first cause of all things, without beginning, and who possesses absolute power over nature. So in Hesiod it is the genesis of the gods on which his whole cosmogony turns. Most of these genealogies, and the myths con- nected with them, are nothing more than the expression of simple perceptions, or picture-thoughts, of the kind that imagination everywhere produces when the know- ledge of nature is in its infancy. Erebus and Nyx are the parents of Æther and Hemera, for day in its brightness is the son of might and darkness. The earth brings forth the sea of herself alone, and rivers in her union with the sky; for the sources of streams are fed by the rain, while the ocean appears to be a mass of COSMOLOGY, HESIO D. 87 water which has been from the beginning in the depths of the earth. Uranus is emasculated by Cronos, for the sun-heat of harvest time puts an end to the fertilising showers of the sky. Aphrodite springs from the seed of Uranus, for the rain in spring awakens the genera- tive impulse of nature. The Cyclopes, Hecatonchires and giants, the Echidna and Typhoeus are children of Gaea; other monsters are the progeny of night or of the waters, partly because of their originally physical import, partly because what is monstrous cannot spring from the bright heavenly gods, but only from darkness and the unfathomable deep. The sons of Gaea, the Titans, were overthrown by the Olympians; for as the light of heaven subdues the mists of earth, so the all- ordering Deity has bound the wild forces of nature. The thought contained in these myths is very limited; whatever in them transcends the most obvious per- ceptions is the result, not of reflection concerning the natural causes of things, but of an activity of fancy from which, even when it produces something really significant, we must be careful not to expect too much. Even in the combination of these myths, which is principally, no doubt, the work of the poet, we fail to discover any leading thought of deeper import." The * Brandis (Geschichte der tion of the higher principle. But Griech-Röm. Phil. i. 75) finds not merely in the beginning of the Theogony, but also in the myths of the dethronement of Uranus, and the conflict of the sons of Cronos with their father and the Titans, the doctrine that the determinate proceeds from the indeterminate, and that there is a gradual evolu- these thoughts are much too ab- stract to admit of our seeking in them the motive of the mythopoeic fancy. The poet does not seem to have been influenced by any specu- lative idea even in the arrangement of these myths; the three genera- tions of the gods merely form the thread on which he strings his 88 INTRODUCTION. passage in the Theogony which sounds most like a philosophic conception of mature, and was almost the only passage employed by the ancient philosophers in that sense, is the commencement of the poem (v. 116 sqq.). Chaos was the first to exist, then came Earth (with the abyss, or Tartarus) and Eros. Of Chaos were born Erebus and Night; Earth first brought forth of herself the sky, the mountains, and the sea; then in marriage with the sky she produced the progenitors of the different families of gods, except the few that are derived from Erebus and Night. This representation certainly attempts to get at some motion of the world's origin, and we may so far consider it as the beginning of cosmology among the Greeks; but as a whole it is very crude and imperfect. The poet asks himself what was really the first of all things, and he finally abides by the Earth as the immovable basis of the Cosmos. Out- side the Earth was nothing but gloomy might, for the luminaries of heaven were not as yet in existence. Erebus and Night are therefore as old as the Earth. In order that another should be produced from this first one, the generative impulse or Eros must have existed from the beginning. Such then are the causes of all things. If we exclude all these beings from our thought, there remains for the imagination only the idea of infinite space, which at this stage of culture it does not con- ceive in an abstract manner as empty mathematical space, but concretely as an immeasurable, waste and genealogies, and by which he con- the edition of Hesiod of Gaisford- nects them together externally. Reiz, verse 116. 1 Proof of this will be found in COSMOLOGY. HESIO D. 89 formless mass. The first of all things, therefore, in reality is Chaos. In some such way as this perhaps the foregoing theory of the beginning of the world may have arisen in the mind of its author." It is founded, indeed, upon a desire for enquiry, an endeavour to attain clear and coherent notions, but the interest which rules it is that of the imagination rather than that of thought. No question is asked concerning the essence and general causes of things, the problem is merely how to learn something about the actual facts relating to the primitive condition of the world and to its ulterior developments; and in the solution of this problem, we naturally find that the poet is guided by the intuitions of his imagination, and not by intelli- gent reflection. The commencement of the Theogony is, considering its date, a thoughtful and pregnant myth, but it is not as yet a philosophy. The next writer after Hesiod of whose cosmology we know anything at all definite is Pherecydes of Syros,” * Whether this author or some older poet was the composer of the Theogony is, as has already been observed, of little importance. Brandis (Gesch. der Gr-Röm. Phil. i. 74) supports the latter theory. It is unlikely, he says, that the poet, had he invented the myth of Tartarus as one of the first princi- ples of the world, or of Eros as the creative principle, would have made no further use of them in his Cos- mology. But not to speak of the doubtful origin of the 119th verse, which mentions Tartarus, but which is wanting in Plato (Symp. 178 B), and Aristotle (Metaph. i. 4, 984 b, 27), I should rather ex- plain this circumstance as showing that the myths subsequently intro- duced belonged to the older tra- dition, and the opening verses to the author of the Theogony itself. * For his life, age, and writings, cf. Sturz, Pherecydis Fragmenta, p. 1 sqq. Preller in the Rhein. Mus. iv. (1846) 377 sqq. Allgem. En- cyclop. of Ersch and Gruber, iii. 22, 240 sqq. Art. Pherecydes, Zim. mermann in Fichte's Zeitschrift für Philosophie, &c. xxiv. B, 2 H. S. 161 sqq. (reprinted in Zimmermann's Studien. Vienna, 1870, p. 1 sqq.). This last, however, credits the old mythographer with much that is 90 INTRODUCTION. a contemporary of Anaximander;" in later story a mira- culous person like Pythagoras.” In a work, the title of which is variously given, he says that there existed before all things, and from etermity, Zeus, Chronos, and Chthon.” alien to him. Conrad, De Pherecy— dis Syrii aetate atque cosmologia. Coblenz, 1857. * He is described as such by Diogenes, i. 121, and Eusebius, Chron. 60 Ol. The former, probably following Apollodorus, places his most flourishing period in the 59th Olympiad (540 B.C.), and the latter in the 60th Olympiad. Suidas (‘Pepek.) in a very obscure passage fixes his birth in Ol. 45 (600–596 B.C.). His age is given by the Pseudo-Lucian (Macrob. 22, a pas- sage where he certainly seems to be meant) as 85. Neither of these statements, however, is altogether trustworthy,though perhaps neither is far from the truth ; and there are besides other reasons against our drawing any such definite con- clusion as Conrad, who thus sums up (p. 14) his careful discussion of this question: Pherecydes was born in the 45th Olympiad or shortly before, and died, ‘octogena- 'rius fere,' towards the end of the 62nd Olympiad. (Between Ol. 45, 1, to 62, 4, moreover, there are only 71–72 years.) Nor does the asser- tion that Pythagoras tended him in his last illness help us at all, partly because it is itself very untrust- worthy, and partly because this occurrence is placed by some before Pythagºras' emigration to Italy, and by others in the last period of his life. Cf. Porph. Vita Pythag. 455 sq.; Iamb. Vita Pythag. 184, 252 ; Diog. viii. 40, By Chthon he seems to have understood the * Cf. the anecdotes in Diog. i. 116 sq. * The commencement of this work, in Diog. i. 119 (cf. Damas- cius, De Princ. p. 384; and Con- rad, p. 17, 21) was as follows: Zebs uèv kal Xpóvos és àel kal X6&v ju. X90win 68 &vopa €yévero Tºj, éretà? airfi Zeus yepas àtö07. By 'yāpas we cannot, with Tiedemann (Griechenlands erste Philosophen, 172), Sturz (loc. cit. p. 45) and others, understand motion; nor with Brandis the original qualita- tive determination, for this latter is far too abstract a conception for Pherecydes, and he can hardly have regarded the earth as moved. Neither interpretation, in fact, can be got out of the word; what it means is: Since Zeus conferred honour upon her. We may either understand by this honour, what always seems to me the most pro- bable, the adornment of her surface, mentioned immediately after (the garment with which Zeus covered the earth); or else, with Conrad, p. 32, the honour of her union with Zeus, by which the Earth became the mother of many gods (p. 74, 2). Pherecydes means to derive the name yū from yépas. This circum- stance of itself forbids the substi- tution of trépas for yépas, proposed by Rose, De Arist. libr. ord. 74; but the sense we should get by this change is, in my opinion, very un- Satisfactory. COSMOLOGY. PHERECYDES. 9] earth ; by Chronos, or Cronos," that part of heaven nearest the earth, and the deity ruling it;” by Zeus, the highest god, disposing and forming the whole universe, and himself at the same * So he is called by Hermias (Irrisio, c. 12), who expressly says that Kpévos is the same as Xpévos. In Damascius, on the contrary, where Conrad, p. 21, also reads Kpóvov, I find in the manuscripts no other reading than Xpóvov. * By the Cronos of Pherecydes is generally understood Time—so Hermias loc. cit. and Probus on Virgil's Eclogues, vi. 31. Phere- cydes himself indicates this signifi- cation when he puts Xpévos instead of Kpóvos. Yet it is scarcely credi- ble that so ancient a thinker should have placed the abstract conception of Time among the primitive causes; and Cronos, in fact, ap- pears as a much more concrete na- ture when it is told of him (vide infra) that he created from his seed fire, wind and water, and that he was the leader of the gods in the conflict with Ophioneus. That this only means that in course of time fire, wind and water arose, and that in course of time Ophioneus was conquered, I cannot believe. If the gods at strife with Ophioneus re- present certain powers of nature, Cronos, their leader, must be something more real than merely Time; and if fire, wind and water were formed from the seed of Chro- nos, this seed must be conceived as a material substance, and Chro- nos must consequently represent a certain part, or certain constituents, of the world. If we consider that fire, wind and water are formed in the atmosphere during tempests, and that the fertilising rain is re- time the highest heaven.” presented in the mythus of Uranus as the seed of the god of heaven ; that Chronos, according to this original import, was not the god of Time in abstracto, but the god of the warm Season, of the time of harvest, of the sun-heat (Preller, Griech. Mythol. i. 42 sq.), and, as such, was a god of heaven—that he was so regarded by the Pythago- reans when they identified the vault of heaven with Xpóvos, and called the sea the tears of Chronos (vide infra, Pythagorean system)— if we consider all this, the opinion given above, concerning which even Conrad's (p. 22) and Brandis's adverse judgment (Gesch. der Entw. der Griech. Phil. i. 59) have not shaken me, will appear to have far the most probability in its favour. * To Zeus, as the divine creator of the universe, the passage in Aris- totle's Metaphysics, xiv. 4, 1091 b, 8, refers: ol ye usuryaevot abrów (scil. Tàu &pxafov troumróv) ſcal T6 u% uvBukós &taura Aéyeuv, otov ‘pepekööms ſcal étépoi twes, to 'yevviorav irpátov Šptorov T.06aori. As the notion of Zeus as god of heaven is based upon the idea of the sky itself, and as the gods of Pherecydes generally represent at the same time certain parts of the world, we may assume that he did not discriminate the world-creating power, which he calls Zeus, from the upper portion of the sky. The assertion of Hermias and Probas (loc. cit.) that by Zeus he under- stood AEther, and of Probus (loc. cit.) that he understood fire, show 92 INTRODUCTION. Chronos produces from his seed fire, wind and water; the three primal beings then beget numerous other gods in five families.” When Zeus, in order that he might fashion the world,” had changed himself into Eros (who, according to the ancient theory, must be the world- that we are here concerned with an interpretation of the Stoics, and not with an original and authentic text. That Hermias should reduce AEther and Earth to the troudāv and tróaxov is also entirely in harmony with the Stoic point of view. Cf. Zeller, Phil. der Gr. Part III. a, 119, second edition. * Damascius, loc. cit. : row 6& Xpóvov trol?iorat éic too yovov Šavrot, Tºp kal truedua kal iſoap, . . . Šć &v év trévre uuzoſs Šimpnuévov troAA}v yeweav orva rival 9eów, rhy TrevTéuvXov ka?\ovuévny. To the same pivXoi (as Brandis thinks, p. 81) the statement of Porphyry perhaps refers (De antro nymph. c. 31), according to which Phere- cydes mentions uvXobs kai 866pous kal &vrpa kal 6&pas kal tróAas; though Porphyry himself sees in them the yevéaeus kal &moyevéoets ºvxóv. Preller (Rh. Mus. 382, Encycl. 243) thinks that Pherecydes here intends to speak of five admix- tures, in various proportions, of the elementary substances (AEther, Fire, Air, Water, Earth), in each of which one of these elementary sub- stances predominates. It seems to me, however, very hazardousto as- cribe to the ancient philosopher of Syra a theory of the Elements in the sense of Empedocles or Aris- totle (a theory which presupposes a far more developed stage of phi- losophic reflection), or to believe that he anticipated Philolaus in fixing the number of these elements at five. Conrad's modification also of this interpretation, by which the five uv Yol are made to signify the five layers, circumfolding each other, of earth, water, air, fire and aether (loc. cit. p. 35), attributes to Pherecydes, as it appears to me, a view of the world that is too scien- tific and too similar to Aristotle's ; the theory, especially, of a fiery sphere invisible to us, and the pre- cise discrimination of aether from fire and air, is, according to all other traces of it, much later. It would be more reasonable to sup- pose that Pherecydes distinguished Olympic gods, fire-gods, wind-gods, water-gods and earth-gods. Suidas says that the work of Pherecydes was named Éirt duvros, from the Auxoſ. Preller (Rh. Mus. 378) conjectures instead trevrépuxos. Conrad (p. 35) adds to the above- mentioned five pluxol the two divi- sions of the lower world, Hades and Tartarus. It is supposed(though this is not quite clear from Origen, C. Cels. vi. 42) that Pherecydes him- self distinguished Hades and Tar- tarus. Nothing certain, however, can be made out on the subject. Blato, in Soph. 242 C: 3 pºv (ušov Sumyelºral) &s rpta rā, śvra, troNeue? 8è &AA#Aous évíore airów &rra tril, Totè 5è kal pixa yiyvöueva yáuovs Te ſcal tăkovs ſcal rpoqās rôv éicyóvov trapexetal, doubtless refers to the exposition we have been considering. * Proclus in Tim. 156 A. COSMOLOGY. PHEIRECYDES. 93 forming force), he made, we are told, a great robe, on which he embroidered the earth and Ogenos (Oceanos), and the chambers of Ogemos; he spread this robe over an oak upborne by wings" (ütróttapos), that is, he clothed the framework of earth floating in space” with the varied surface of land and ocean.” Ophioneus, with His words in Clemens, Strom. vi. 621 A, run thus : Zēs trote: qāpos uéya Te Kai kaxów ſcal év airó toucíAAet yiv kal &ymvov Kal rà & ynvoj 50%para. In reference to this, Clemens (642 A) says: ā Śróirrepos Spös kal to éir' airfi tretroikiWuévov ºpäpos. * The wings in this case denote only free suspension, not swift motion. * Conrad opposes the above explanation on two accounts. First he agrees (p. 40) with Sturz (p. 51), that the winged oak is not merely the framework of the earth, but of the whole universe, and that the woof spread over the oak is the sky. Against this, I can only repeat what I have already, in the second edition of this work, replied to Sturz, that the tissue on which land and sea are embroidered (this alone can be meant by the words év airó troucíAAet; and Clemens also calls the pāpos itself retrol- kixuévov) cannot signify the sky. It would be easier to understand it as ‘the visible things that en- compass the world’— therefore the surface of the earth and sky (cf. Preller, Rh. Mus. 387, Encyklo. 244); but since earth and ocean are mentioned as the only objects embroidered on the woof, we have no ground for thinking of anything besides the terrestrial surface. Secondly, Conrad (p. 24 sqq.) Sup- poses that by x0&v Pherecydes in- tends Chaos, the primitive matter, which contains all matters, except aether, in itself. Out of this, through the working of Zeus or AEther, the elemental matters earth, water, air, and fire were made ; and the earth itself when separated from the primitive matter was called X60uín, as distinguished from X66v. But the words quoted from Diog. p. 72, 3, already ex- clude such a theory; for who would infer from the mere interchange between X6&v and X60Vím that in the one case we are concerned with the mixture of all substances, and in the other with the earth which resulted from this mixture? Damascius, whom we have no right to charge with error in this matter, expressly mentions Zets, Xpóvos and X00via as the three first principles of Pherecydes (De princ. c. 124, p. 384). Again, when Pherecydes, according to Damascius, says that fire, air and water were made by Chronos éic row yovov Šavroſſ, how can it be maintained that Zeus separated them out of X66v P Con- rad, lastly, urges that his theory best explains the statement (vide Achilles Tatius in Phaenom. c. 3, 123 E; Schol. in Hesiodi Theog. 116; Tzetz. in Lycophron, 145) that Pherecydes, like Thales, made water his first principle; but this does not help him much. For that statement rests upon suspicious testimony, and is besides entirely 94 INTRODUCTION. his hosts, representing probably the unregulated forces of nature, opposes this creation of the world, but the divine army under Chronos hurls them into the deep of the sea, and keeps possession of heaven." As to any further battle of the gods, between Zeus and Chronos, Pherecydes seems to have erroneous on the chief point, and Conrad himself acknowledges (p.26) that in the chaotic primal matter which he thinks is denoted by the name of X6&v, Earth must have preponderated, to occasion the choice of this name. If there is any error, the cause of it may lie elsewhere, either in the doctrine of Pherecydes himself, or in a misap- prehended account of the doctrine. IEven an antithetical comparison of IPherecydes and Thales, like that in Sextus, Pyrrh. iii. 30, Math. ix. 360 (Pherecydes made earth, and Thales water, the principle of all things), might, by the careless hand of a copyist or compiler, be turned into a parallel between them; or some- one who found Pherecydes classed with Thales, as one of the oldest philosophers, may have ascribed to him Thales' doctrine. Perhaps even what Pherecydes said of Oceanus, or his statement about the seed of Cronos, or some other definition that has not come down to us, may have been explained in this way. Whether Pherecydes thought that the sea oozed out of the earth con- ceived as moist in its primeval condition, or was filled by water from the atmosphere (the water arising from the yovh of Cronos), is not clear from our documents; for it is certainly possible that the production of water by Cronos may not apply to the water of the sea. Celsus ap. Origen c. Cels. vi. This is the 42; Max. Tyr. x. 4; Philo of By- blus ap. EuS. praep. Ev. i. 10, 33 (the latter represents Pherecydes as having borrowed this trait from the Phoenicians); Tertullian, De cor. mil. c. 7. - * Preller (Rh. Mus. 386) seeks to establish the contrary, and I fol- lowed him in my second edition. Put though we find traces, with Apollonius and others (v. infra), of a theogony in which Ophion, Kro- nos and Zeus follow one another as rulers of the universe, we have no right to refer this representation to Pherecydes himself. With him Ophioneus fights indeed for the possession of heaven, but that he had it to begin with is not stated, and it is irreconcilable with the assertion that Zeus had been there from eternity, and still more with the utterance of Aristotle (supr. p. 93); for he adduces as a peculiarity of Pherecydes that in contradistine- tion to the older Theogonies he had declared the first principle to be the most perfect, as they are blamed because Baat?Mečev kal &pxeiv paolv où rows trpátovs, oiov vökra, K.T.A., &AA& rôv Ata, and did not therefore regard the world-ruling power or Zeus as the trpárov. Pherecydes must himself have so regarded him. This, as Conrad rightly observes, also excludes the theory that Zeus first became lord of heaven and king of the gods by the overthrow of Cronos. been silent.” COSMOLOGY. PHERECYDES. 95 essential result to be gathered from scattered fragments and traditions respecting the doctrine of Pherecydes. If we compare it with the Hesiodic cosmogony, it undoubtedly evinces progress of thought. We find, even thus early, a definite attempt to discriminate, on the one hand, between the material constituents of the universe — the earth, and the atmospheric elements; and, on the other, between matter and plastic force. In what is said of the conflict of Chronos with Ophi- oneus, we seem to discern the thought that in the attainment of the present cosmical order the forces of the abyss were limited by the influence of the higher elements." But the expression of all this is mythical, and in accordance with the older cosmological mytho- logy. The world is not formed by the natural operation of original matter and forces; it is wrought by Zeus with the mysterious power of a god; the reduction of phenomena to natural causes, which fs the first real commencement of Philosophy, is not here to be found. It would therefore be of little importance to the history of Philosophy to know that Pherecydes took certain details of his theory, such as the personality of Ophioneus, from Phoenician or Egyptian mytho- logy; but whether important or not, the statement cannot be adequately proved by the testimony of so untrustworthy a writer as Philo of Byblus;” and the distinction between the destroying Serpent god of Pherecydes and the serpent-shaped Agathodaemon is so The serpent is a chthonic loc. cit., and Allg, Encyclo. p. 244. animal, probably signifying Ophi- * In Euseb. loc. cit. oneus. Wide Preller, Rhein. Mus. 96 INTRODUCTION. apparent, that we might as well identify the former with the serpent form of Ahriman, or even, like Origen (loc. cit.), with the serpent of the Mosaic paradise, if so obvious, and among the Greeks so common, a symbol required a foreign derivation to account for it. The impossibility of referring the whole cosmogony of Phe- recydes, in its essential features,' to the Egyptians, will at once appear on an intelligent comparison of his pre- sentations with the Egyptian myths.” The assertions of certain later and untrustworthy writers” as to his Oriental teachers are of little importance as evidence.* If our knowledge is imperfect in regard to Phere- cydes, it is still more so in respect to some others, who contemporaneously, or nearly contemporaneously, with him set up various cosmological theories. Of Epimen- ides, the well-known hierophant of Solon's time,” we * Zimmermann, loc. cit. * Another doctrfme attributed to Pherecydes, and which equally must have come from the East, the dogma of Transmigration, has already been discussed, p. 68 sq. * Josephus, Contr. Apion. 1, 2, end, reckons him as belonging to the Egyptian and Chaldaean schools. Cedren., Synops. i. 94 B, represents him as travelling into Egypt. Suidas (£epek.) says he used the secret writings of the Phoenicians; the Gnostic Isidorus in Clemens, Strom. wi. 642 A, represents him as in- spired by the prophecy of Cham; by which, however, is probably in- tended, not the Egyptian and Phoe- nician wisdom as a whole, but a Gnostic work bearing that title. * We are, in the first place, entirely ignorant on what tradition these statements are based ; and next, it was easy and obvious to connect the teacher of Pythagoras (who was known to have held the Egyptian doctrine of Transmigra- tion), as well as Pythagoras him- self, with the Egyptians. The Chaldaeans, in what concerns Phe- recydes, were perhaps first added by Josephus; while the statement of Suidas probably originates with Philo of Byblus. * On the personality of Epi- menides, his activity in Athens, and the stories that connected them- selves with him, cf. Diog. i. 109 sqq.; Suidas, 'Etruevſöns ; Plu- tarch's Solon, 12; S. Sap. Conv. 14; An Senis. ger. resp. i. 12, p. 784; Def. orac. i. 1, p. 409; De fac. lun. 24, 25, p. 940; Plato, Laws, i. 642 D (and also my treatise on the 1.na- chronisms of Plato, Abhandlungen der Berlinischen Akademie, 1873. EPIMEWIDES. 97 are told by Damascius that,' according to Eudemus, he admitted two first causes, the Air and Night; * and proceeding from these a third, Tartarus. From them sprang two other beings, not precisely designated, whose union produced the egg of the universe ; a denotation of the celestial sphere which is found in several cos- mogonies, and which very naturally resulted from the representation of the world's origin as analogous to the development of animal life. Whether this notion was transplanted from Western Asia to Greece, whether it was arrived at independently by Greek mythology, or whether, lastly, it had been preserved in ancient tra- dition from the earliest sources of the Greek race,—are questions we must leave unanswered. From this egg other existences were produced. The thought contained in this cosmogony, as far as our meagre information enables us to criticise it, is unimportant, whether we consider Epimenides himself to have made the altera- tion in the Hesiodic representation, or, in doing so, to have followed the example of some more ancient predecessor. The same holds good of Acusilaos,” who was much more closely allied to Hesiod, for he repre- sents Chaos as bringing forth a male and a female being—Erebus and Night; AEther, Eros,” Metis, and History of Philosophy, p. 95 sq.) What Damascius quotes from him is taken from his own theogony, Diog. i. 111. † De Princ, c. 124, p. 384, Kopp. 2 These two principles evidently represent, after the manner of the Hesiodic Theogony, a sexual syzygy: the Air, 6 &#p, is the male principle; Night, the female prin- WOL. I. H ciple. *Ap. Damascius (loc. cit.) again according to Eudemus ; Brandis, p. 85, also rightly refers to Plato, Symposium, 178 C, Schol. Theocrit. argum. Id. xiii. Clem. Al. Strom. vi. 629 A. Josephus contra Apio- ºnem, i. 3. * Schol. Theocrit. classes him as the son of Night and Æther. 98 INTRODUCTION. a number of divinities being the result of their union. There are some other traces of cosmogomic tradition;' but we pass them over, in order to proceed at once to the consideration of the Orphic cosmogonies.” Four versions of such cosmologies are known to us under the name of Orpheus. In one of these, the version used by Eudemus * the Peripatetic, and most probably before his time Alluded to by Brandis, loc. cit., p. 86. It is said that Ibycus, Fr. 28 (10), like Hesiod, made Eros spring from Chaos; and that the comic poet Antiphanes, ap. Ire- naeus (adv. Her. ii. 14, 1), differed on some points from Hesiod. 2 For what follows, cf. Schuster, De vet. Orphica Theogoniſe indole. Leipzig, 1869. * Damascius, c. 124, p. 382. That by this Eudemus is intended the pupil of Aristotle, is plain from Diogenes, Prooem. 9. Cf. Damas- cius, p. 384. * Metaph. xii. 6, 1071 b, 26: às Aéyovoiv of 6.e0x6 you of ék vvictos Tyevvövres. Ibid. xiv. 4, 1091 b, 4: of 8& troumral of &pxalot taúrm épotos, j Bagińetely kal &pxeiv paolv oë rows trptºrovs, otov vökta kal oipavov # x40s h &keavov, &AA& Töv Ata. These words cannot refer simply to systems in which Night, though placed among the oldest deities, occupies only a third or fourth place (as is the case in the Hesiodic and ordinary Orphic theogony). They presuppose a cosmology in which either Night alone, or Night in conjunction with other equally original principles, has the first place; for Metaph. xii. 6 treats of the primitive state which preceded all Becoming; and in reference to this, Aristotle says it is equally im- by Aristotle “ and Plato,” possible for the theologians, who make all things arise out of Night, and for the physicists, who com- mence with the mixture of all things, to explain the beginning of motion. Also the second passage agrees so little with the ordinary Orphic cosmology, that Syrianus, commenting on it (Schol. in Aris. 935 a., 18), finds fault with Aris- totle for misrepresenting the Or- phic doctrine. This passage must equally point to a theogony like that spoken of by Eudemus; for here Night is made the first principle; as with Hesiod, Chaos, and with Homer, Oceanus; the sky it cer- tainly is not in either of the repre- sentations known to us; but in the Eudemic Orpheus, the sky occupies the second place, and in Hesiod the third. As the Eudemic Orpheus alone, as far as we know, with the exception of Epimenides, puts Night in the place of Chaos as the first of all things, it is very probable that Aristotle, as well as his scholar Eudemus, may be referring to him. * Schuster (loc. cit. 4 sqq. thinks this is probable from Craf. 402 B, and Tim. 40 D sq. (where by the poets who affirm themselves to be the sons of the gods are meant Orpheus and Musaeus; these are mentioned by name, Rep. 364 E, while nothing of the kind is said ORPHIO COSMOG ONIES. 99 Night is represented as the first of all things. Beside Night are placed the Earth and the sky,' both of which apparently proceeded from Night, as with Hesiod the Earth came forth from Chaos; Night being here sub- stituted for Chaos.” The children of Uranus and Gaea are Oceanus and Thetis;* obviously a very slight departure from the Hesiodic tradition. A second theogony (perhaps an imitation, or possibly the foun- dation of Pherecydes' story of the battle of the gods) seems to be alluded to by Apollonius," for he represents his Orpheus as singing how at first earth and sky and water separated themselves out of the commingling of all things, how sun and moon and stars began their courses, and mountains, rivers and animals came into being; how Ophion and Eurynome, daughter of Oceanus, ruled in Olympus, how they were afterwards hurled into of Hesiod). It is no argument against it (as Schuster shows), that in the verses' quoted by Cratylus, the marriage of Oceanus and The- tys is described as the first mar- riage, whereas they themselves are the children of Uranus and Gaea ; and because the Timaeus begins the sketch of the Theogony with the words, Tús re kal Oüpavoo traſões 'Olceavós re kal Tºm6üs éyevé00mv, it does not follow that Plato denies Night to be the first principle. If the passagerelated to the HesiodicTheo- gony (which does not, like Plato, make Cronos and Rhea children of Oceanus and Thetys), Chaos and Night would still have been passed over; but Plato could as well leave out Night in this passage as Aristotle, Metaph. xiv. 4, the earth; and Metaph. i. 8, 989 a, 10 (pmol 8& kai “Hoto80s thv yiv trpcºrnu ºyevéorðal rôv oropºdrov), Chaos. He begins with those gods who, as parents, open the series of gods springing from sexual union; what was prior to the earth and the heavens he does not enquire. * Eudemus, loc. cit.; Joannes Lydus, De mensibus, ii. 7, p. 19, Schow. His words, Tpets trpátai kar’ 'Oppéa éčegAdat ma'av ćpyal, vot kal ºyā kai oilpavös, are rightly applied to this Eudemic “Theology of Or- pheus' by Lobeck, i. 494. * In favour of this theory, vide Arist. Metaph. xii. 6 (supra, 98, 4), and especially Damascius, p. 382: # 6é trapé, Tó IIepiirarr; tıkö Eööflug, ăvaºye'ypappuévn &s toū 'Oppéos odora 6eoNoyia Tráv to vomrov čawārmarev . &mb 3& Tijs vukrös émothoaro thv &xpfiv. * According to Plato; cf. p. 98,5. * Argonaut. i. 494 sqq. H 2 100 INTRODUCTION. the ocean by Cronos and Rhea, and these in their turn were overthrown by Zeus. Traces of this theogony are also to be met with elsewhere;' but philosophic concep- tions are as little to be detected in it as in the poems of Hesiod. A third Orphic cosmogony” places at the beginning of cosmical development water and primi- tive slime, which latter solidifies and forms the earth. From these two a dragon arises, winged, and with the face of a god: on one side he has the head of a lion, and on the other that of a bull. He is called by the mythologists, Heracles and Chronos, the never-aging one ; with him is united Necessity, or Adrastea (accord- ing to Damascius, in a hermaphrodite form), who is said to be spread abroad incorporeally throughout the universe to its remotest ends. Chronos-Heracles pro- duces a gigantic egg,” which, dividing in the midst, forms with its upper half the sky, and with its lower, the earth. There seems to have been further mention” of a Cf. what is cited by Preller, Rhein. Mus. N. F. iv. 385 sq., from Lycophr. Alear. v. 1192; and Tzet- zes, in h. 1., Schol. Aristoph. Nub. 247; Schol. Æschyl. Prom. 955; Lucian, Tragodopod. 99. Though Orpheus is not named in these pas- sages, we find in them, as in the Orpheus of Apollonius, that Ophion, Chronos and Zeus are regarded as the three kings of the gods, of whom the two first were overthrown by their successor. Perhaps the statement of Nigidius Figulus re- lates to the same theogony (Serv. ad Ecl. iv. 10), namely, that ac- cording to Orpheus, Saturn and Jupiter were the first rulers of the world; the tradition which he fol- lows, however, seems to have set aside Ophion and Eurynome. * Ap. Damascius, 381. nag. Supplic. c. 15 (18). * According to Brandis, i. 67, Chronos first begot Æther, Chaos and Erebus, and afterwards the egg of the world; Lobeck's view of the passage (Aglaoph. i. 485 sq.), however, seems to me undoubtedly correct; according to this view, what is said of the begetting of AEther &c. is referred, not to the cosmogony of Hellanicus, but to the usual Orphic theogony in which it is really to be found. * The confused representation of Damascius leaves it somewhat uncertain whether these features really belong to this theogony. Athe- ORPHIC COSMOGONIES. 101 god who had golden wings on his shoulders, bulls' heads on his haunches, and a huge Snake appearing among various animal forms on his head; this god, described by Damascius as incorporeal, is called Protogomos or Zeus, and also Pan, as bringing order into all things. Here not only is the symbolism far more complicated than with Eudemus, but the thoughts, too, are in advance of the cosmogonies we have been considering. Behind Chronos and Adrastea are the abstract notions of time and necessity; the incorporeality of Adrastea and Zeus presupposes a discrimination of corporeal and spiritual which was unknown even to Philosophy until the appearance of Anaxagoras; the spreading out of Adrastea through the universe reminds us of the Platomic doctrine of the World-soul; and in the con- ception of Zeus as Pan we recognise a pantheism, the germ of which lay, indeed, from the beginning in the naturalistic religion of the Greeks, but which cannot be proved by authentic evidence to have actually existed before the period when the individuality of the various gods had been destroyed by religious syn- cretism, and when Stoicism had done much to spread abroad the pantheistic theory of the universe; for mone of the older systems, however pantheistic in tendency, had so great or so general an influence. The pantheistic element comes out still more clearly in the story of the birth and swallowing of Phanes' (infra, pp. 104, 106). * That this trait was present in mentioning Phanes from any other the Orphic theogony of Hellanicus exposition than that from which is clear from Athenag. c. 16 (20), he had previously made quotations for it is most improbable that he exactly corresponding with the should havetaken the Orphic verses Hellanicus theogony of Damascius. 102 INTRODUCTION. If, therefore, this cosmogony, as is usually supposed,' was known to Hellanicus of Lesbos in the middle of the fifth century, we must assign many ideas which ap- peared only in the later Greek Philosophy to an earlier period. Lobeck, however (loc. cit.), and Müller” rightly question whether such could have been the case. Damascius himself hints at the doubtful source of the account “he follows;" its content bears pretty evident internal traces of an after date, and as we certainly know that spurious writings of a very late period were circulated * under the name Cf. Schuster, p. 32, whose other conjectures, however, p. 83, do not commend themselves to me. * Which Brandis accepts, loc. cit. p. 66. * Fragmenta hist. Graec. i. xxx. * His words, loc. cit., are: Totaúrm pºv ii ouvâ0ms 'Oppukh 9eoNoyta. ii 8è karū tow Ieptévvuov pepouévn kal ‘EAAávikov, eſtrep whical 6 airós éo riv, oùra's #xel. They appear to me to convey that the work of which they are treating was attri- buted to Hieronymus as well as to Hellanicus, and that Damascius himself, or his authority, was of opinion that under these two names one and the same author was con- cealed; who in that case naturally could not have been the ancient logographer of Lesbos. * Wide Müller, loc. cit. Schu- ster, in his excursus on the theo- gony of Hellanicus, loc. cit. pp. 80– 100, conjectures with Lobeck that its author was Hellanicus, other- wise unknown to us, the father of the philosopher Sandon (Suidas, Xàvöwv), whose son (the Stoic Athenodorus of Tarsus) was the instructor of Augustus, and whom of the Lesbian logographer, Schuster calls, I know not why, Apollodorus. This conjecture has in its favour that Sandon, according to Suidas, wrote inrobéorets sis *Oppéa ; and if Hellanicus, like his grandson, and probably also his son, was a Stoic, this would agree with the fact that the theogony (as Schuster, loc. cit. 87 sqq. proves) has points of contact with the Stoic pantheism and treatment of myths. The saying of Damascius, however, quoted in note 3, seems to me to contradict this assump- tion. If Hellanicus of Tarsus, in the end of the second century before Christ, published an Orphic theo- gony under his own name, it is difficult to see how this work could bear the name of Hieronymus as well, and how Damascius could Imagine that the same author was concealed under these two names. Schuster (p. 100) believes that Hellanicus wrote the theogony, but borrowed the material of the first part from a work by Hiero- nymus. But this theogony cannot have been known as the production of Hellanicus, for Athenagoras ex- pressly ascribes to Orpheus the ORPHIC COSMOGONIES. 103 there is every probability that the Orphic theology does not belong to him at all, whatever may be the truth as to its authorship and the time of its composition. verses which Schuster rightly con- siders as having belonged to this work; besides, it was natural that a poem professing to set forth an Orphic theogony should announce itself as a work of Orpheus. Da- mascius does not say that Hellani- cus and Hieronymus were des- cribed as the authors of the theo- gony; but as he calls the theogony used by Eudemus, c. 124: jī trap& Tó trepitrarmtikó Eööhug &vaºye'Ypap- plévn; so by h karð ‘rov ‘Iepdºvvptov qepopuévn kal ‘EAAdvikov, he must mean a theogony, the contents of which Hieronymus and Hellanicus had expounded, but the author of which, as of all the other theogo- nies, was Orpheus. As to the fact that the divergences from the com- monly received Orphic theogony are the same in both cases, and that Damascius conjectures the two au- thors to be one and the same, the easiest explanation seems to be that this exposition may have been found in two manuscripts, of which one bore the name of Hellanicus, and the other that of Hieronymus, and that Damascius believed one of these to have been falsely ascribed to its so-called author by the real author of the other. Now it appears from Porph. ap. Euseb. prap, ev. x. 3, 10, Suidas, Zápoxêts, Athen. xiv. 652 a, and others (cf. Müller, loc. cit. and i. 65 sqq.), that in later times writings about fo- reign nations were in circulation under the name of Hellanicus of Lesbos, the authenticity of which there was good reason to doubt; in particular, the Aiyvirtuakā is mentioned as a work that stands in Epictetus, Diss. ii. 19, 14; cf. Pho- tius, Cod. 161, p. 104 a, 13 sq., for the type of a book of fables, and cannot possibly have emanated from the Lesbian writer, if only because Moses is mentioned in it (v. Justin, Cohort. 9, p. 10 a). We hear, on the other hand (Joseph. Ant. i. 3, 6, 9), of an Egyptian Hieronymus, who wrote an āpxalo- Xoyia powikikh, but who cannot possibly (as Müller, loc. cit., be- lieves) be the same person as the IPeripatetic of Rhodes. It seems a probable conjecture (Müller, ii. 450) that he was the person who, according to Damascius, had trans- mitted this Orphic theogony; and the idea gains considerable support from the observation (Schuster, loc. cit. 90 sqq.) that this theogony in its commencement, just where it differs from the ordinary Orphic theogony, coincides with the Phoe- nician cosmogonies. This Hierony- mus may have affixed the name of Hellanicus to the Aiyvirtuakö at the same time that he published the Phoenician history under his own name, and may have expressed him- self in both works to the same effect concerning the Orphic theo- gony. That he composed such a theogony is, as we have said, un- likely. He seems rather to have confined himself to developing what he took from the common theogony by borrowing the notion of water and primitive slime from the Phoenician cosmology. His exposition must have been used by Athenagoras as well as by Damas- cius, for a Neo-Platonist can hardly be suspected of dependence on the 104 INTRODUCTION. Lobeck considers that we have a more ancient Orphic cosmogony in that designated by Damascius (c. 123, p. 380) as the usual Orphic theogony, or the one contained in the rhapsodies, and of which many fragments and notices' have been preserved. Here Chronos is represented as the first of all existences. He brings forth AEther and the dark immeasurable abyss, or Chaos: from these he then forms a silver egg, out of which, illuminating all things, proceeds Phanes, the first-born god, called also Metis, Eros, and Ericapaeus;” he contains within himself the germs of all gods, and for this reason, as it would appear, is described as her- maphrodite, and endowed with various animals' heads, and other attributes of the kind. Phanes alone begets Echidna, or Night, and, in marriage with her, Uranus and Gaea, the progenitors of the intermediate races of gods, whose history and genealogy are essentially the same as with Hesiod. When Zeus attains sovereignty he devours Phanes, and consequently is himself (as in our previous quotation from Orpheus”) the ideal sum (Inbegriff) of all things. After having thus united all Christian apologist (Schuster, p. 81); and besides, the exposition of Damascius goes farther than that of Athenagoras; what is said in the former of Hellanicus and Hie- ronymus is wanting in the latter. * Cf. Lobeck, loc. cit. 405 sqq. * There have been many conjec- tures as to the signification of this name. Cf. Göttling, , De Ericap. (Jena, 1862), who derives it from ëap and kámos or kārus (breath), ventorum vernalium afflatus; Schus- ter, loc. cit. 97 sq. With the ma- jority of commentators, I consider an Eastern origin probable, though I must leave it an open question whether Delitzsch (cf. Schuster, loc. cit.) has most reason for refer- ring it to the Cabbalistic designa- tion of the first of the ten Sephi- roth, !"Els 'ns (long-visaged), or Schelling (Gotth. v. Samothr. W. W. , i. , Abth. viii. 402 sq.) for preferring the Old Testament bºs Tys (long-suffering). * Cf. Supra, p. 64 sq. ORPHIC COSMOG ONIES. 105 things in himself, he again puts them forth, producing the gods of the last generation, and forming the world. Among the stories of the younger gods (for the rest of which I must refer the reader to Lobeck), the most striking is that of Dionysus Zagreus, son of Zeus and Persephone, who, rent in pieces by the Titans, comes to life again in the second Dionysus, after Zeus has swallowed his heart, which was still entire. The theory that this whole theogony dates from the period of Onomacritus and the Pisistratidae, since the time of Lobeck’ has found much favour, but I am unable to support it. The utterances of ancient authors which are supposed to contain allusions to such a theogony, do not carry us beyond the theogony which Eudemus made use of. Its existence is first distinctly attested in the pseudo-Aristotelian treatise on the world,” subsequently therefore to the Christian era, or at any rate not long before it;* for, as we have seen (supra, p. 65 sq.), the passage from the Platonic Laws (iv. 715 E) proves nothing, and still less can be de- duced from the Aristotelian citation," on which Brandis” relies so much. Since Plato in the ‘Symposium' (178B) does not mention Orpheus among those who assert the antiquity of Eros, we may rather indeed suppose that * Lobeck, however, advances it (p. 611) very cautiously, ut statin cessurus, si quis Theogoniam Orphi- cam Platone aut recentiorem aut certe non multo antiquiorem esse demonstraverit. * C. 7; according to Lobeck (i. 522 and elsewhere) we must sup- pose this to be an interpolation. * The date of Valerius Soranus is rather earlier. Varro in Au- gustine's Civit. Dei, vii. 9, gives us two verses of his, which seem to refer to the Orphic theogony, and perhaps to the particular passage quoted from trepi kāoruow. Yet he was only a later contemporary of Cicero. * Metaph. xiv.4; cf. Supra, p. 98,4, * Loc. cit. p. 69. 106 INTRODUCTION. the doctrine of this theogony, in regard to Eros- Phanes, was unknown to him; and since Aristotle's in- dications, as above noted, only correspond with the theogony used by Eudemus, we cannot refer them to any other. If, however, Plato, Aristotle, and Eudemus did not possess that representation of the Orphic doc- trines, which was at a later period in ordinary use, we must conclude with Zoéga" and Preller,” that it was not in circulation until after their time. I agree like- wise with Zoéga that so learned a mythographer as Apollonius” would scarcely have made Orpheus sing of Ophion and Eurynome as the first rulers of the world, and Cronos and Rhea as the second, if the Orphic tra- dition then current had recognised Phanes and the elder gods. Even subsequently to this there are still traces to show that Phanes, the illuminating one, the centre of the subsequent Orphic cosmogony, was only another name for Helios, who, according to the later representa- tion, was a much younger god.” Lastly, if we consider the story of Phanes, with the description of Zeus that is involved in it, with reference to its internal character and purpose, we shall find that it is impossible to assign | Abhandlungen, edited by Wel- cker, p. 215 sqq. * In Pauly's Real-Encyl. v.999. * Cf. Supra, p. 99. * Diodorus, i. 11 : many ancient poets call Osiris, or the sun, Diony- sus : &v Etſuoxtros uév . . . &orpo- qavº Atóvvorov . . . 'Oppets 5é. roëveká ulv kaxéovori pāvmrå re kal Atºvvorov. Macrob. i. 18: Orpheus solem volens intelligi ait inter cetera: . . . $v 6% viv kaaéovoi pāvmté ré kai Aióvvorov. Theo. Smyrn. De Mus. c. 47, p. 164, Bull, from the Orphic, Špirot: #Atóv te, pávnra Pléyav, kal vökra Méxatvav-ºdvºra uéyav, standing here, as the want of a connecting particle shows, in apposition to ##Atov: Helios the great illuminator. Iamblichus, Theol. Arith. p. 60: the Pythago- reans call the number ten pávnro, kal jºuov. Helios is often named baé909; e.g. Iliad, xi. 735. Od. v. 479; in the epitaph in Diog. viii. 78, and elsewhere. ORPHIC COSMOG ONIES. 107 this story to a very early period. Not only do we clearly discover in it that pantheism of which we have already spoken," but the story can only be accounted for by a desire to reconcile the later interpretation, according to which Zeus is the ideal sum of all things, and the unity of the world, with the mythological tradition which represents him as the progenitor of the last generation of gods. To this end the Hesiodic myth of the swal- lowing of Metis by Zeus (in its origin most likely a rude symbolical expression for the intelligent nature of the god) is introduced, Metis being combined with the Helios-Dionysus of the earlier Orphic theology, with the creative Eros of the cosmogonies, and also perhaps with Oriental divinities, to form the personality of Phames. Such an attempt, it is clear, could not have been made until the period of that religious and philosophic syncretism, which from the third century before Christ gradually gained ground, and was first reduced to a system by the allegorical interpretation of myths among the Stoics.” To that period therefore we In this, however, as 1t * Wide supra, p. 64 sq. 2 Schuster is of a different opinion, though he agrees with me in placing the rhapsodic theogony not earlier than the last century, or last but one, before Christ. The verses, he says (p. 42 sq.), which are quoted in the writing trepl kóo uov, loc. cit., could very well date from the time of the Pisistratidae, as they do not go beyond the well- known fragment of Æschylus (cited Part II. a, 28, 2); and the myth of Phanes-Ericapaeus, as well as that of Dionysus Zagreus, need not have come to Greece from the East earlier than the sixth cen- tury. seems to me, the peculiar character of the Orphic fragments has not been sufficiently attended to. Pan- theistic conceptions are certainly found in the poets of the fitth cen- tury, and even earlier; but it is one thing to say generally, ‘Zeus is Heaven and Earth,’ and quite another to identify Zeus in detail, as these verses do, with all the different parts of the world, and among other things to attribute both sexes to him (Zeis &pormv 'yevero, Zeus épéporos én Aero vöuſpm). No representation of the latter kind can be proved to have 108 INTRODUCTION. must assign the elaboration of the Orphic theogony which we have now been considering. To sum up, then, the results of our enquiry, the direct gain which Philosophy has derived from the ancient cosmologies appears to be less than we may have been disposed to believe. Firstly, because the conceptions on which they are founded are so simple that thought could well have attained to them without any such help, so soon as it began to apply itself to the scientific investigation of things; and, secondly, because these cosmologies in their mythical symbolism are so ambiguous, and intermingled with so many fantastic elements, that they afford a very uncertain foundation for intelligent reflection. If, therefore, the ancient theologians are to be considered the precursors of the later physicists, their merit, as was asserted at the outset of our enquiry, mainly consisted in this: that they turned the current of reflection towards cos- mological questions, and left to their successors the problem of explaining the totality of phenomena by the investigation of its ultimate causes. existed in the more ancient period. We cannot even argue directly from AEschylus, or his son Eu- phorion (the probable author of the fragment), to Onomacritus and the time of the Pisistratidae. Lastly, in the Orphic verses, Zeus is said to be all, because he has concealed all things in himself, and brought them again to light ; and that (as already shown on p. 65) is the true meaning of the stories about Phanes in the later Orphic theogony. There is nothing analo- gous to this thought before the ap- pearance of the Stoic philosophy. It seems the most probable suppo- sition, therefore, that this feature was really imported from the Stoics into the Orphic theology, and was merely a lifeless imitation of the theory (Part III. a, 139, second edition) that the Deity from time to time took all things back into himself, and again put them forth. IETHICAL REFLECTION. 109 § V.—Ethical Reflection. Theology and Anthropology in their relation to Ethics. If the external world roused the Greeks in their lively feeling for nature to attempt cosmological specu- lation, the life and ways of men must no less have occupied the mind of a nation so intelligent and versa- tile, so full of freedom and capability in practical life. It was inevitable, however, that reflection should take a different course in regard to Ethics from that which it followed in regard to cosmology. The external world presents itself even to sensuous perception as a whole,_a building, the floor of which is the earth, and the roof, the vault of heaven ; in the moral world, on the contrary, the unpractised glance sees nothing at first but a confused mass of individuals or small ag- gregates moving about capriciously and promiscuously. In the one case, attention is chiefly fixed upon the cosmos, the grand movements of the heavenly bodies, the varying conditions of the earth, and the influence of the seasons,—in short, upon universal and regularly recurring phenomena; in the other case, the interest centres on personal actions and experiences. There the imagination is required to fill up the lacunae in man's knowledge of nature by means of cosmological inven- tions; here we require the understanding to set rules for practical conduct in specific cases. While therefore, cosmological reflection is from the outset employed upon the whole, and seeks to elucidate its origin, ethical reflection restricts itself to particular observa- tions and rules of life, which are indeed founded on a 110 IWTRODUCTIO.W. uniform manner of regarding moral relations, but are not consciously and explicitly reduced to general prin- ciples; and are only connected with more universal considerations respecting the lot of man, the future destiny of the soul, and the Divine government, in the indeterminate and imaginative mode of religious pre- sentation. Ethical reflection is therefore much more barren than cosmological; starting from a sound and intelligent observation of what is real, it has certainly contributed not a little to the formal exercise of thought; but having arisen from a practical rather than a scien- tific interest, and being concerned rather with particu- lar cases than with general laws and the essential nature of moral action,--from a material point of view its influence on philosophic enquiry has been far less im- mediate than that of the old cosmology. The pre- Socratic Nature-Philosophy was directly connected with cosmology, but it was only in the sequel that there arose a scientific moral Philosophy, as the philo- sophic counterpart of popular wisdom. Among the writings which show the growth of this ethical reflection, the Homeric poems must first be mentioned. The great moral importance of these poems rests, however, far less on the maxims and moral- observations which occasionally appear in them, than on the characters and events which they depict. The tem- pestuous force of Achilles, the self-forgetful love of the hero for his dead friend, his humanity to the suppliant Priam, Hector's courage in death, Agamemnon's kingly presence, the ripe wisdom of Nestor, the inexhaustible cunning, the restless enterprise, the wary persistence of ETHICAL REFLECTION. HOMER. 111 Odysseus, his attachment to home and kindred, the sight of whom he prefers to immortality with the sea- goddess, the faithfulness of Penelope, the honour every- where accorded in the poem to valour, prudence, fidelity, liberality, generosity to strangers and needy persons; and, on the other hand, the woes which ensued from the outrage of Paris, from the crime of Clytem- nestra, from the treachery of the Trojans, from the discord of the Greek princes, from the arrogance of the suitors, these and the like traits made the poems of Homer, in spite of all the barbarism and violence that still prevailed in the spirit of that time, a hand- book of wisdom for the Greeks and one of the principal instruments of their moral education. Philosophy, too, has profited more in an indirect manner from these pictures of human life than directly from the reflections accompanying them. The latter are confined to short scattered moral sayings, like the beautiful utterance of Hector on fighting for one’s country," or that of Alcinous on our duty to desolate strangers,” or exhorta- tions to courage, constancy, reconciliation, and so forth, which are given for the most part, not in a general form, but poetically, in reference to the particular occasion ; * observations on the acts and ways of men, and their consequences,” reflections on the folly of * Il. xii. 243: eis oiovos ūpt- aros, &pſilveréal trepi Târpms. 2 Od. viii. 546: ávrl ſcaa tºyvä- row £eſvás 6' icérms Te Térvktai. Cf. Od. xvii. 485 and elsewhere. * Such as the numerous speeches of the chiefs: ävépes éorrè &c.; or the discourse of Odysseus, téraaffi 8% ºpačín, Od. xx. 18; or the ex- hortation of Phoenix, Il. ix. 496, 508 sqq.; or Thetis' injunction to Achilles, Il. xxiv. 128 sqq. * Such as the sentences: Il. xviii. 107 sqq. on anger. Il. xx. 248, on the use of the tongue ; Il. xxiii. 315 sqq. praise of prudence; the observa- tion in Od. xv. 399, and others. 112 INTRODUCTION. mortals, the wretchedness and uncertainty of life, resignation to the will of the gods, abhorrence of in- justice. Such utterances incontestably prove that not only moral life, but also reflection on moral subjects, had made a certain degree of progress in the time to which the poems of Homer belong, and what has previously been said on the importance of popular wisdom in regard to Philosophy applies with equal force here. We must not, however, on the other hand, overlook the distinction between these incidental and isolated reflections, and a methodical moral Philosophy, conscious of the end it is pursuing. Hesiod's rules of life and moral observations are- of a similar character; but it must be regarded as some approximation to the modes of scientific reflection, that he utters his thoughts on human life, not merely in- cidentally in the course of an epic narration, but in a didactic poem designed for this express purpose. In other respects, even apart from the economic directions, and the various superstitious prescripts, which occupy the second part of the ‘Works and Days, the thoughts are as incoherent, and as much derived from single experiences, as the maxims in the Homeric discourses. The poet exhorts to justice, and warns against in- justice, for the all-seeing eye of Zeus watches over the actions of men; well-doing alone brings blessing ; l Thus in Od. xviii. 129 : oièëv sity as he wills. Od. vi. 188: bear 3kiðvárepov yaſa Tpépel àvöpétroto what Zeus has ordained. On the etc. Il. vi. 146 (cf. xxi. 464): otn rep påNAwv Yevsh tolfiès Kal &vāpāv. Il. xxiv. 525: The fate of mortals is to live among sighs; Zeus decrees prosperity or adver- other hand, cf. Od. 132: Man is wrong to call the gods the authors of evil, which he himself has brought down upon himself by his faults. JHOMER AND HESIOD. II3 crime, on the contrary, will be punished by the gods." He recommends frugality, diligence and contentment, and warmly rebukes the opposite faults; * he says it is better to keep the toilsome path of virtue than to follow the more attractive road of vice; * he counsels prudence in business, friendliness to neighbours, courtesy: to all who are courteous to us.” He complains of the troubles of life, the cause of which he seeks, like the mythologists, in wrong done to the gods by the pride and presumption of men.” In the account of the five ages of the world,” he describes (it may be under the influence of historical reminiscences”) the gradual-de- terioration of man and his circumstances. Though in this Hesiod departs considerably, in many respects, from the spirit of the Homeric poems, yet the stage attained. by moral reflection is in both cases essentially the same. But in Hesiod it assumes a more independent attitude, for which reason only we recognise in him, rather than in Homer, the precursor of the Gnomic poets. * We should be better able to trace the farther de- velopment of this reflection if more remained to us of * “Epya kal huépal, 200–283, contented with his originally happy 318 and childlike state, stretched forth SqQ. * Ibid. 359 sqq. 11 sqq. 296 Sqq. * Ibid. 285 sqq. * Ibid. 368 sqq. 704 sqq. 340 SQQ- * In the myth of Prometheus ("Epya kal juépal, 42 sqq.; Theo- gnis, 507 sqq.), of which the general significance is the same as other mythical explanations of the evils by which we feel ourselves op- pressed; namely, that man, dis- WOL. Is I his hand towards good things which God had forbidden him. * “Epya kal juépal, 108 sqq. * Cf. Preller, Demeter und Per- sephone, 222 sqq.; Griech. Mythol. i. 59 sq.; Hermann, Ges. Abh. p. 306 sqq. and others. We must not, however, be too minute in our conjectures concerning the histo- rical circumstances on which this mythus is founded. 114 INTRODUCTION. the numerous poems written in the next three centu- ries. Very few of such fragments as we possess carry us beyond the beginning of the seventh century, and these contain scarcely anything relevant to our present enquiry. Even from the fragments of the seventh century we can glean but very little. We may listen, indeed, to Tyrtaeus,' exalting courage in battle, and death for one's country; or describing the disgrace of the coward and the unhappiness of the conquered; we get from Archilochus” (Fr. 8, 12–14, 51, 60, 65), from Simonides of Amorgos” (Fr. 1 sqq.), from Mimmermus" (Fr. 2 et passim), complaints of the transitoriness of youth, the burdens of old age, the uncertainty of the future, the fickleness of men; and, at the same time, exhortations to limit our desires, to bear our fate man- fully, to commit the results of our actions to the gods, to be moderate both in sorrow and in joy. We find in Sappho" gnomic sentences, such as these: “The beau- tiful is also good, the good is also beautiful” (Fr. 102); ‘Wealth without virtue does not profit, but in their union lies the acme of happiness.' Nor must we omit to mention in this connection Simonides’ elaborate satire on women (Fr. 6). On the whole, however, the older lyricists, as also the great poets in the end of the seventh century, Alcaeus and Sappho, and long after them Anacreon, seem to have dealt but sparingly in such general reflections. It was not until the sixth century, contemporaneously, or nearly so, with the rise 1 Fr. 7–9 in Bergk's edition of 2 About 700 B.C. Greek lyrics, to which the follow- * Before 650 B.C. ing quotations relate. Tyrtaeus * About 600 B.C. lived about 685 B.C. * About 610 B.C. GNOMIC POETS, SIXTH CENTURY. 115 of Greek Philosophy, that the didactic element in poetry appears to have again attained greater import- ance. To that period belong the Gnomic poets—Solon, Phocylides, and Theognis; their sayings, however, even irrespective of what we know to be interpolated, are mostly of doubtful authenticity. During the first half of the sixth century AEsop also lived, whose legendary form seems at any rate to prove that instructive fables about animals, in connection with the general growth of moral reflection, had then become greatly developed and popularised. In all these writers we find, as compared with the older poets, an advance clearly indicating that thought had ripened by the acquisition of more varied experience, and by the study of more complex situations. The Gnomic poets of the sixth century had before their eyes an agitated political existence, in which the manifold inclinations and pas- sions of men found ample scope, but in which also the vanity and evil of immoderate aims and intemperate conduct had been demonstrated on a grand scale. Their reflections, therefore, are no longer concerned merely with the simple affairs of the household, the village, or the ancient monarchy; the condition of man as to his political circumstances is the prominent and determining element even in their general moral pre- scripts and observations. They heap up lamentations over the misery of life, the illusions and instability of men, and the vanity of all human endeavours; but it is only to assert the more forcibly that the moral problem consists in seeking man’s greatest happiness in the maintenance of just measure, in the order of I 2 116 INTROI) UCTION. the commonwealth, in the impartial distribution of justice, in the reasonable repression of his desires. This tone is already predominant in the elegies ascribed to Solon. No mortal, we are there told, is happy, all are full of trouble" (Fr. 14); each thinks to find the right, and yet no one knows what will be the result of his doings, and no one can escape his destiny (Fr. 12, 33 sqq., Fr. 18); * hardly any can be trusted (cf. Fr. 41), mone keeps measure in his efforts; the people by its own injustice destroys the city, which the gods would have protected (Fr. 3, 12, 71 sqq.). As opposed to these evils, the first necessity is law and order for the state, contentment and moderation for the individual : not wealth, but virtue, is the highest good; superfluity of possessions begets only self-exaltation; man can be happy with a moderate amount, and ought in no case to draw down upon himself the certain punishment of God by unrighteous gains.” The well-being of the state depends upon a similar disposition. Lawlessness and civil discord are the worst evils, order and law the greatest good for a commonwealth; right and freedom for all, obedience to the government, just distribution of honour and influence—these are the points which the legislator should keep in view, no matter what offence he may give by it." * Fr. 14. otö& udicap oëbels in Hesiod, Fr. 43, 5 et passim. aréAeral 8poros, &AA& trovmpol * In Herodotus, 1, 31, Solon Trávres; here trovmpbs, in opposition to uákap, is not to be understood actively (trévos, causing evil), but passively (trévos, suffering evil, érímrovos), as in the well-known verse of Epicharmus (vide infra, chapter on Pythagoreism, sub fin.) distinctly says that death is better for men than life. * Fr. 7, 12, 15, 16, and the well-known story of Herodotus, i. 30 sqq. - * Fr. 3, 30 sqq. 4–7, 34, 35, 40. PHOCYLIDES. THEOGNIS, 117 We meet with the same principles in the few au- thentic fragments that remain to us of the writings of Phocylides (about 540 B.C.). Noble descent is of no avail to individuals, nor power and greatness to the state, unless in the one case wisdom is superadded, and in the other order (Fr. 4, 5). Mediocrity is best; the middle rank is the happiest (Fr. 12); justice is the ideal sum of all virtues." With these ideas Theognis” also substantially agrees; but in this writer we find sometimes his aristocratic view of politics, and some- times his dissatisfaction with his lot (a consequence of his own personal and political experiences), brought into undue prominence. Brave and trustworthy people are rare, Theognis thinks, in the world (v. 77 sqq. 857 sqq.). Mistrustful circumspection is the more to be recommended in our intercourse with our fellow men (v. 309, 1163), the harder it is to fathom their sentiments (v. 119 sqq.). Truth, he complains (v. 1135 sqq.), and virtue, sincerity and the fear of God have deserted the earth; hope alone remains. Vain is the attempt to instruct the wicked, instruction will not alter them.” Fate, however, is as unjust as mankind. The good and the bad fare alike in the world (v. 373 sqq.); good fortune does more for a man than virtue (v. 129, 653); foolish conduct often brings happiness, and wise conduct, misery (v. 133, 161 Sqq.); Sons suffer for their fathers’ crimes; the criminals them- 1 Fr. 18, according to others, Plato remarks in the Meno, 95 D) of Theognis, or perhaps taken from it is not very consistent that The- some unknown writer. ognis should say in v. 27, 31 sqq. * A native of Megara, contem- et passim, that from the good we porary of Phocylides. learn good; and from the evil, evil. * W. 429 sqq., with which (as 118 INTRODUCTION. selves go unpunished (731 sqq.). Wealth is the only thing that men admire;’ he who is poor, be he never so virtuous, remains wretched (137 sqq. 649). The best thing for man, therefore, is never to be born ; the next best to die as soon as possible (425 sqq. 1013): no one is truly happy. But though this sounds very dis- consolate, Theognis ultimately arrives at the same prac- tical result as Solon; not indeed in reference to politics, for he is a decided aristocrat—the nobly born are with him the good; the mass of the people, the bad (e.g. v. 31–68, 183 sqq. 893 et passim). His general moral standpoint, however, approaches very nearly to that of Solom. Because happiness is uncertain, and because our lot does not depend upon ourselves, he tells us we have all the greater need of patience and courage, of equability and self-possession in good fortune and in evil (441 sqq. 591 sqq. 657). What is best for man is prudence, what is worst is folly (895, 1171 sqq. 1157 sqq.); to guard against arrogance, not to overstep the right measure, to keep the golden mean, is the height of wisdom (151 sqq. 331, 335, 401, 753, 1103 et passim). Here, a philosophic moral principle is of course still wanting, for these scattered rules of life are not as yet based upon general enquiries concerning the essence of moral activity, but the various influences and experiences are already beginning to unite, much more consciously and definitely than with the older poets, to form a uniform and connected theory of human life. * W. 699 sqq. Cf., among tan, who by some authors is others, the Fragment of Alcaeus in reckoned one of the Seven wise Diog. 1. 31, and the saying there men. quoted of Aristodemus the Spar- THE SE VIEW SAGES. 119 Antiquity itself marked the importance of the epoch when ethical reflection began to be more decidedly developed, by the legend of the seven sages. Their names, as is well known, are variously given,' and such details as have come down to us respecting their lives” sound so improbable that we must regard them as fiction rather than history. The maxims, too, which are ascribed to them” are intermingled to such an extent * Only four are mentioned in all the enumerations: Thales, Bias, Pittacus and Solon. Besides these, Plato (Prof. 343 A) names also Cleobulus, Myso and Chilo; instead of Myso, most writers (as Demetrius Phalereus ap. Stobaeus, Floril. 3, 79; Pausanlas, x. 24; Diog. i. 13, 41; Plutarch, Conv. S. Sap.) substitute Periander for Myso. Euphorus ap. Diog. i. 41, and the author mentioned anonymously in Stobaeus, Floril. 48, 47, have Anacharsis. Clemens, Strom. i. 299 B, says the accounts fluctuate between Periander, Ana- charsis and Epimenides; the last is mentioned by Leander, who has also Leophantus in place of Cleo- bulus (Diog. loc. cit.); Dicaearchus leaves the choice of the three doubtful sages to be decided be- tween Aristodemus, Pamphilus, Chilo, Cleobulus, Anacharsis, and Periander. Some include also Py- thagoras, Pherecydes, Acusilaus, and even Pisistratus, in the num- ber (Diog. and Clemens, loc. cit.). Hermippus ap. Diog. (loc. cit.) men- tions seventeen names among which the accounts are divided ; viz. Solon, Thales, Pittacus, Bias, Chilo, Myso, Cleobulus, Periander, Anacharsis, Acusilaus, Epimenides, -Leophantus, Pherecydes, Aristode- mus, Pythagoras, Lasus of Her- mione, Anaxagoras; if we add Pam- philus and Pisistratus, and the three named by Hippobotus (ap. Diog. loc. cit., together with nine others), Linus, Orpheus, and Epi- charmus, we get in all twenty-two persons of very various periods, who were counted among the seven wise men. * For instance, the anecdote related in Diog. i. 27 sqq., Phoenix in Athen. xi. 495, and elsewhere in different versions, of the tripod (or, as others say, the goblet, cup, or dish) which was fished up out of the sea, and intended for the wisest, was first given to Thales, passed on by him to another, and so on, until at last it returned to him again, and was dedicated by him to Apollo. Cf. the accounts of the meetings of the four sages in Plutarch; Solon, 4; Diog. i. 40 (where two descriptions of such meetings, probably analogous to those of Plutarch, are quoted from Ephorus and a certain Archetimus; cf. also the statement of Plato (Protag. 343 A) about the inscrip- tions they dedicated together at the temple of Delphi; the interpolated letters, ap. Diogenes, the assertion in Plut. De E. c. 3, p. 385, about Periander and Cleobulus. * Wide Diog. i. 30, 33 sqq.; 58 sqq. 63, 69 sqq. 85 sq. 97 120 INTRODUCTION. with later ingredients, and with proverbial expressions of unknown origin, that very few can be traced with any certainty to either of these men." They are all, however, of the same character, consisting of isolated observations, maxims of prudence, and moral sentences belonging entirely to the sphere of popular and practical wisdom.” This quite accords with the circumstance that most of the seven Sages were celebrated as states- men and lawgivers.” We cannot but agree, there- fore, with Dicaearchus" in regarding them as intelligent men, and capable legislators, but not as philosophers, or wise men in the sense of the Aristotelian School.” They only represent the practical culture which, about the end of the seventh century, received a new impulse in connection with the political circumstances of the Greek nation. sqq. 103 sqq, 108; Clemens, Strom. i. 300 A sq.; the collections of Demetrius Phalereus and Sosi- ades ap. Stobaeus; Floril. 3, 79 sq.; Stobaeus himself in different parts of the same work, and many others. * For example, the lyric frag- ments in Diog. i. 71, 78, 85; the word of Pittacus, which Simonides quotes in Plato, Prot. 339 C; that of Cleobulus, also quoted by Si- monides, ap. Diog. i. 90; that of Aristodemus, quoted by Alcaeus, Diog. i. 31. * The remarkable statement of Sextus (Pyrrh. ii. 65, M X, 45)— which would presuppose physical enquiries in others of the wise men besides Thales; viz. that Bias maintained the reality of motion— stands quite alone, and is probably only an idle and ingenious de- duction from one of his poems or Though they cannot be reckoned philo- apophthegms. * Solon and Thalès were thus distinguished, as is well known; Pit- tacus was Aesymmetes of Mytilene; Periander, tyrant of Corinth ; Myso, according to Hipponax (Fr. 34 b, Diog. i. 107), had been declared by Apollo the most blameless of men ; the name of Bias was used prover- bially for a wise judge (Hipponax, Demodicus, and Heracleitus ap. Diog. i. 84, 88; Strabo, xiv. 12, p. 636 Cas, ; Diodorus, Ea.c. de virtute et vit. p. 552 Wess). Chilo is said by Herod. (i. 59) to have inter- preted a miraculous portent. * Diog. i. 40. Similarly Plu- tarch, Solon, c. 3 Sub fin. The as- sertion to the contrary in the Greater Hippias, 281 c, ascribed to Plato, is manifestly incorrect. * Cf. Arist. Metaph. i. 1, 2; Eth. N. vi., 7. THE SEWEN SAGES. 121 sophers, in the stricter meaning of the term, they stand on the threshold of Philosophy, a relation which tradition has strikingly expressed by distinguishing as the wisest of the seven, to whom the mythic tripod re- turns after completing its round, the founder of the first school of Natural Philosophy. In order to acquaint ourselves thoroughly with the soil from which Greek Philosophy sprang, we have still to consider how far the motions of the Greeks about God and human nature, before the middle of the sixth century, had been altered in the course of advancing culture. That some change had occurred we may take for granted, for in proportion as the moral consciousness is purified and extended, the idea of Deity, from which is derived the moral law and the moral government of the universe, must also become purified and extended; and the more man realises his liberty and his superiority to other natural existences, the more will he be inclined to distinguish the spiritual element of his own nature in its essence, origin and future destiny from the corporeal element. The pro- gress of morals and of ethical reflection was therefore of great moment to theology and anthropology; but their influenee was more broadly apparent when Philo- sophy had attained to an independent development. The older poets, subsequent to Homer and Hesiod, in their motions of Deity, do not essentially transcend the standpoint of their predecessors; we can only discover, by slight indications, that a purer idea of God was gradually forming itself, and the presupposed plurality of gods more and more giving place to the T22 INTRODUCTION. conception of Zeus as the moral ruler of the universe. Under this aspect Archilochus celebrates him when he says (Fr. 79) that he beholds the works of men, both the evil and the good, and even watches over the doings of animals; and the more the poet is convinced that fate and fortune order all things, that the mind of man changes like the day which Zeus allots to him, that the gods raise those that are fallen, and cast down those that stand (Fr. 14, 51, 69)—the more earnest are his exhortations to commit all things to God. So also Terpander consecrates the introduction of a hymn (Fr. 4) to Zeus, as the beginning and director of all things; and the elder Simonides sings (Fr. 1) that Zeus has in his hand the end of all that exists, and orders it as he wills. But similar passages are to be found even in Homer; and in this respect the difference between the two poets is, perhaps, only one of degree. Solon more decidedly passes beyond the older anthropomorphic idea of God, when he (13, 17 sqq.) says, “Zeus, indeed, watches over all things, and nothing is hidden from him, but he is not aroused to anger by individual acts as mortals are ; when crime has accumulated, punish- ment breaks in like the tempest which sweeps the clouds from the sky, and so, sooner or later, retribution overtakes everyone.” Here the influence of moral re- flection reacting upon the notion of Deity cannot be mistaken.” We see the same reflection in Theognis ' A later contemporary of 160, and other passages), but the Archilochus, about 680 B.C. express antithesis of Divine retri- * That the Divine retribution butive justice, and of human pas- is often long withheld is a thought sidn, shows a purer conception of which we continually meet with, Deity. even as early as Homer (Il. iv. ANTHROPOLOGY. 123 with a different result; for the thought of the gods’ power and knowledge leads him to doubt their justice. “The thoughts of men, he says, “are vain (v. 141, 402); the gods bring to pass all things as seemeth them good, and vain are all a man’s efforts if the daemon has destined him to adversity. The gods know the mind and deeds of the just and of the unjust’ (v. 887). This consideration is sometimes connected (as in v. 445, 591, 1029 sqq.) with exhortations to resignation, but in other places the poet irreverently accuses Zeus of treating good and evil alike, of loading sinners with wealth, of condemning the righteous to poverty, and of visiting the sins of fathers on their innocent children." If we may suppose such reflections to have been at all frequent in those times, we can the more easily under- stand that some of the ancient philosophers should contemporaneously have opposed to the anthropomor- phic motions of polytheism an essentially different conception of God. This conception, indeed, could only have come from Philosophy; unphilosophic reflec- tion did no more than prepare the way for it, without actually quitting the soil of the popular faith. The same may be said of anthropology. The history of this order of ideas is completely bound up with the theories about death and a future state. The dis- crimination of soul and body originates in the sensuous 1 W. 373. év Taitfi uotp: röv re Sikatov čxeiv; Zeo pſae, gayadºw ore ori Yap irdv- etc. Tecſ.O’LA) 01/0.0'0'é!S . . ãv6pdºrov 3’ eſſ oio 6a wdow nal 6vuov similarly 731 sqq., where the ques. ékáotov . . . tion is likewise asked: trós 5% gev, Kopovſöm, Toxuá včos kal Tour’ā0avárov 8agiNet, trós &vöpas àAitpous éortl 6tratov K.T.A. 124 INTRODUCTION. man from his experience of their actual separation, from beholding the corpse out of which the animating breath has departed. Therefore the notion of the soul at first contains nothing but what may be immediately derived from that experience. The soul is represented as an essence of the nature of breath or air; as cor- poreal (for it dwells in the body and quits it at death in the manner of something extended"), but without the completeness and power of the living man. In regard to the soul after its separation from the body and de- parture to the other world, we know from the Homeric representations what was thought on the subject; * the substance of the man is his body; * the bodiless souls in Hades are like shadows and shapes of mist, or like forms which appear in dreams to the living, but cannot be grasped; vital power, speech, and memory have deserted them; “the sacrificial blood of offerings restores their speech and consciousness, but only for a little time. A few favoured ones, indeed, enjoy a happier fate; * while * The soul of a murdered per- son, for instance, escapes through the wound. Cf. Il. xvi. 505, 856; xxii. 362, and many other pas- sages in Homer. * Od. x. 490 sqq.; xi. 34 sqq. 151 sqq. 215 sqq. 386 sqq.; 466 sqq.; xxiv. sub init. ; Il. i. 3; xxiii. 69 Sqq. * The airbs in opposition to the juxh, Il. i. 4. * This is the usual description, with which Od. xi. 540 sqq. 567 sqq. is certainly at variance. * e.g. Tiresias, who by the favour of Persephone retained his consciousness in Hades; the Tyn- daridae, who alternately lived above later allegorists have sought so and beneath the earth (Od. xi. 297 sqq.); Menelaus and Rhada- manthus, who, the one as the son- in-law, the other as the son of Zeus, were taken to Elysium instead of dying. (Od. iv. 561 sqq.) The strange statement that Hercules was himself in Olympus, while his shadow remained in Hades (Od. xi. 600)—a notion in which many profound meanings—is to be explained simply from the fact that vv. 601-603 are an interpola- tion of a later period, when the hero had been deified, and it was there- fore impossible to think of him as any longer in Hades ANTHROPOLOGY. 125 the saying of Achilles that the life of the poorest la- bourer is better than dominion over shadows, applies to all the rest. But as this privilege is limited to solitary cases, and is connected not with moral worth, but with some arbitrary favour of the gods, we can hardly seek in it the idea of future retribution. This idea comes out, it is true, more strongly in Homer, when he speaks of the punishments undergone by souls after death; but here again only marked and exceptional offences against the gods' incur these extraordinary penalties, which, therefore, have rather the character of personal revenge; and the future state generally, so far as any part of it, either for good or for evil, goes beyond an indistinct and shadowy existence, is determined far more by the favour or disfavour of the gods than by the merits of mankind. A more important conception of the future life might be found in the honours accorded to the dead, and the idea of universal moral retribution. From the former sprang the belief in daemons, which we first meet with in Hesiod.” This origin of daemons is shown, not only by the hero-worship which afterwards sprang up, but by the passage in Hesiod * which says * The Odyssey, xi. 575 sqq., re- lates the punishment of Tityus, Sisyphus and Tantalus; and in Il. iii. 278, perjured persons are threatened with punishment here- after. **Epya kal juépal, 120 sqq. 139 sq. 250 sqq. * Loc. cit. 165 sqq. Cf. Ibycus Fr. 33 (Achilles we read married Medea in Elysium). The same poet represents (Fr. 34) Diomede, like the Homeric Menelaus, as be- coming immortal. Pindar, Nem. x. 7, says the same thing. Achilles is placed by Plato in the Islands of the Blest (Symp. 179 E; cf. Pindar, Ol. ii. 143); Achilles and Diomede likewise—vide the Scolion of Callistratus on Harmodius (Bergk Lyr. gr. 1020, 10, from Athen. xv. 695 B). 126 INTRODUCTION. that the great chiefs of the heroic times were taken after their death to the Islands of the Blest. The theory of opposite states, not merely for individuals, but for all the dead, is contained in the doctrine we lately considered of the mystic theologians, that in Hades the consecrated ones live with the gods, the unconsecrated are plunged in night and a miry swamp. But this motion must have acquired a moral significance later on ; at first, even when it was not so crudely appre- hended, it was still only a means of recommending the initiatory rites through the motives of hope and fear. Transmigration' took its rise more directly from ethical considerations; here it is precisely the thought of moral retribution which connects the present life of man with his previous and future life. It appears, however, that this doctrine in early times was confined to a somewhat narrow sphere, and became more widely diffused first through the Pythagoreans and then through Plato: Even the more general thought on which it is founded, the ethical conception of the other world as a state of universal retribution, seems to have been slow to receive recognition. Pindar, indeed, presupposes this concep- tion,” and in after writers, as in Plato,” it appears as an ancient tradition already set aside fy the enlightenment of their time. In the Lyric poets, on the other hand, we find, when they speak of the life beyond, that they still keep in all essential respects to the Homeric repre- sentations. Not only does Anacreon recoil with horror from the terrible pit of Hades (Fr. 43), but Tyrtaeus * Wide supra, p. 67 sqq. * Rep. i. 330 D, ii. 363 C. * Wide supra, p. 70, note 4. ANTHROPOLOGY. 127 too (9, 3) has no other immortality to set before the brave than that of posthumous fame; Erinna (Fr. 1) says the glory of great deeds is silent with the dead; and Theognis (567 sqq. 973 sqq.) encourages himself in the enjoyment of life by the reflection that after death he will lie dumb, like a stone, and that in Hades there is an end of all life's pleasures. There is no evidence in any Greek poet before Pindar, of the hope of a future life. We find then, as the result of our enquiry up to this point, that in Greece, the path of philosophic reflection had been in many ways cleared and prepared, before the advent of Thales and Pythagoras, but that it had never been actually attempted. In the religion, civil institutions, and moral conditions of the Greeks, there was abundant material, and varied stimulus for scien- tific thought : reflection already began to appropriate this material; cosmogonic theories were propounded: human life was contemplated in its different aspects from the standpoint of religious faith, of morality, and of worldly prudence. Many rules of action were set up, and in all these ways the keen observation, open mind and clear judgment of the Hellenic race asserted and formed themselves. But there was as yet no at- tempt to reduce phenomena to their ultimate ground, or to explain them naturally from a uniform point of view from the same general causes. The formation of the world appears in the cosmogonic poems as a fortuitous event, subject to no law of nature ; and if ethical reflection pays more attention to the natural connection of causes and effects, on the other hand it 128 INTRODUCTION. confines itself far more than cosmology within the limits of the particular. Philosophy learned indeed much from these predecessors, in regard both to its form and matter; but Philosophy did not itself exist until the moment when the question was propounded concerning the natural causes of things. CHARACTER OF GREEK PHILOSOPHY, 129 CHAPTER III. ON THE CHARACTER OF GREEK PHILOSOPHY. IN seeking to determine the common characteristic which distinguishes a long series of historical pheno- mena from other series, we are at once encountered by this difficulty:-that in the course of the historical development all particular traits alter, and that conse- quently it appears impossible to find any single feature which shall belong to every member of the whole that we want to describe. Such is the case in regard to Greek Philosophy. Whether we fix our attention on the object, method or results of Philosophy, the Greek systems display such important differences among themselves, and such numerous points of contact with other systems, that, as it would seem, we cannot rest upon any one characteristic as satisfactory for our purpose. The object of Philosophy is in all ages the same—Reality as a whole; but this object may be ap- proached from various sides and treated with more or less comprehensiveness; and the Greek philosophers differ in this respect so greatly among themselves, that we cannot say wherein consists their common difference from others. In like manner, the form and method of scientific procedure have so often altered both in Greek and other philosophies, that it seems hardly WOL. I. K 130 3. INTRODUCTION. possible to borrow any characteristic distinction from thence. I cannot, at any rate, agree with Fries' in his assertion that ancient Philosophy proceeds epagogically, and modern epistematically; that the one advances from facts to abstractions, from the particular to the univer- sal, the other from the universal, from principles, to the particular. For among the ancient philosophers, we find the pre-Socratics employing almost exclusively a dogmatic, constructive method; and the same may be said of the Stoics, Epicureans, and, more especially, of the Neo-Platonists. Even Plato and Aristotle so little confine themselves to mere induction that they make science, in the strict sense of the word, begin with the derivation of the conditioned from first principles. On the other hand, among the moderns, the whole of the large and influential empirical school declares the epagogic method alone to be legitimate; while most of the other schools unite induction with construction. This distinction, therefore, cannot be carried out. Nor can we assent to the observation of Schleiermacher,” that the intimate relation persistently maintained between poetry and philosophy is characteristic of Hellenic, as compared with Indian Philosophy, where the two ele- ments are so blended as to be indistinguishable from each other, and with the Philosophy of northern nations, where they never entirely coincide; and that as soon as the mythologic form loses itself, with Aristotle, the higher character of Greek science is likewise lost. The last assertion is indeed untrue, for it was Aristotle who conceived the problem of science most clearly and defi- Geschichte der Phil. i. 49 sqq. * Ibid. p. 18. CHARACTER OF GREEK PHILOSOPHY. 131 nitely; and of the other philosophers, not a few were quite independent of the mythological tradition—for example, the Ionian physicists, the Eleatics, Atomists, and Sophists, Socrates and the Socratic Schools, Epi- curus and his successors, the New Academy, and the Sceptics; others, with the freedom of a Plato, made use of mythology merely as an artistic ornament, or sought, like the Stoics and Plotimus, to support it by a philosophic interpretation, without allowing their philosophic system to be conditioned by it. On the other hand, Christian Philosophy was always depen- Tūent on positive religion. In the Middle Ages, this dependence was far greater than the dependence of Philosophy upon religion in Greece, and in modern times it has certainly been no less great. It may be urged that the Christian religion has a different origin and a different content; but this is a secondary con- sideration in regard to the general attitude of Philoso-, phy to Religion. In both cases, unscientific motions are presupposed by thought without any previous demon- stration of their truth. But, in fact, no such decisive contrast in scientific procedure is anywhere discoverable as would justify us in ascribing one definite method, universally and exclusively, to Greek, and another to modern Philosophy. As little do the results on each side bear out such a distinction. We find among the Greeks, Hylozoistic and Atomistic systems, and these are also to be found among the moderns; in Plato and Aristotle we see a dualistic idealism opposed to ma- terialism, and it is this view of the world which has become predominant in Christendom ; we see the sen- K 2 132 INTRODUCTION. sualism of the Stoics and Epicureams reproduced in English and French empiricism ; and the scepticism of the New Academy in Hume ; the pantheism of the Eleatics and Stoics may be compared with the doctrine of Spinoza; the Neo-Platonic spiritualism with Christian mysticism and Schelling's theory of identity; in many respects also with the idealism of Leibnitz: even in Kant and Jacobi, in Fichte and Hegel, many analogies with Greek doctrines can be shown ; and in the ethics of the Christian period there are few propositions which have not parallels in the sphere of Greek Philosophy. Supposing, however, that in all cases parallels were not forthcoming, still the features peculiar on the one hand to Greek, and on the other to modern Philosophy, could only be regarded as generally distinctive of each, if they existed in all the Greek systems, and were absent from all the modern. And of how many characteristics could this be asserted P. Here again, therefore, we have failed to discover any true mark of distinction. Nevertheless, an unmistakable family likeness binds together the remotest branches of Greek science. But as the countenances of men and women, old people and children, often resemble one another, though their individual features are not alike, so is it with the spiritual affinity of phenomena that are connected his- torically. It is not this or that particular characteristic which is the same; the similarity lies in the expression of the whole, in the formation of corresponding parts after the same model, and their combination in an ana- logous relation; or if this is no longer the case, in our being able to connect the later phase with the earlier, CHARACTER OF GREEK PHILOSOPHY. 133, as its natural consequence, according to the law of a continuous development. Thus the aspect of Greek Philosophy altered considerably in the lapse of years; yet the features which subsequently showed themselves were already present in its earliest shape; and however strange its appearance in the last centuries of its his- torical existence, closer observation will show that the original forms are even then discernible, although time- worn and decomposed. We must not, indeed, expect to. find any particular quality unaltered throughout its whole course, or equally present in each of the systems; the general character of Greek Philosophy will have been rightly determined if we succeed in indicating the pri- mitive type, in reference to which the different systems, in their various declensions from it, are intelligible. If, for this purpose, we compare Greek Philosophy with the corresponding productions of other nations, what first strikes us is its marked difference from the more ancient Oriental speculation. That speculation, the concern almost solely of the priests, had wholly developed itself from religion, on which its direction and content constantly depended ; it never, therefore, attained a strictly scientific form and method, but re- mained partly in the shape of an external, grammatical, and logical schematism, partly in that of aphoristic pre- scripts and reflections, and partly in that of imaginative and poetical description. The Greeks were the first who gained sufficient freedom of thought to seek for the truth respecting the nature of things, not in religious tradition, but in the things themselves; among them first a strictly scientific method, a knowledge that follows 134 INTRODUCTION. no laws except its own, became possible. This formal character at once completely distinguishes Greek Philo- sophy from the systems and researches of the Orientals; and it is scarcely necessary to speak of the material opposition presented by the two methods of conceiving the world. The Oriental, in regard to nature, is not free, and has consequently been able neither to explain phe- momena logically from their natural causes, nor to attain liberty in civil life, nor purely human culture. The Greek, on the contrary, by virtue of his liberty, can per- ceive in mature a regular order, and in human life can strive to produce a morality at once free and beautiful. The same characteristics distinguish Greek Philo- sophy from that of the Christians and Mohammedans in the Middle Ages. Here, again, we find no free en- quiry: science is fettered by a double authority—by the theological authority of positive religion, and by the philosºphical authority of ancient authors who had been the instructors of the Arabians and of the Chris– tian nations. This dependence upon authority would of itself have sufficed to cause a development of thought quite different from that of the Greeks, even had the dogmatic content of Christianity and Moham- medanism borne greater resemblance to the Hellenic doctrines than was the case. But what a gulf is there between Greek and Christian in the sense of the early and mediaeval Church ! While the Greek seeks the Divine primarily in nature, for the Christian, nature loses all worth and all right to existence in the thought of the omnipotence and infinity of the Creator; and nature cannot even be regarded as the pure revelation CHARACTER OF GREEK PHILOSOPHY. 135 of this omnipotence, for it is distorted and ruined by sin. While the Greek, relying on his reason, seeks to know the laws of the universe, the Christian flees from the errors of reason, which to him is carnal, and darkened by sin, to a revelation the ways and mysteries of which he thinks himself all the more bound to reverence, the more they clash with reason and the natural course of things. While the Greek endeavours to attain in human life the fair harmony of spirit and nature, which is the distinctive characteristic of Hellenic <) morality; the ideal of the Christian lies in an asceti- cism which breaks off all alliance between reason and sense: instead of heroes, fighting and enjoying like men, he has saints displaying monkish apathy; instead of Gods full of sensual desires, sexless angels; instead of a Zeus who authorises and indulges in all earthly delights—a God who becomes man, in order by his death openly and practically to condemn them. So deeply rooted an opposition between the two theories of the world necessitated an equal contrast in the ten- dencies of Philosophy: the Philosophy of the Christian Middle Ages of course turned away from the world and human life, as that of the Greeks inclined to them. It was, therefore, quite logical and natural that the one Philosophy should neglect the investigations of nature- which the other had commenced ; that the one should work for heaven, the other for earth ; the one for the Church, the other for the State ; that the science of the Middle Ages should lead to faith in a divine revelation, and to the sanctity of the ascetic as its end, and Greek science to the understanding of nature’s laws, and to the 136 INTRODUCTION. virtue which consists in the conformity of human life to nature; that, in short, there should exist between the two Philosophies a radical opposition coming to light even when they apparently harmonise, and giving an essentially different meaning to the very words of the ancients in the mouths of their Christian successors. Even the Mohammedan view of the world is in one re- spect nearer to the Greek than the Christian is, for in the moral sphere it does not assume so hostile an atti- tude to man's sensuous life. The Mohammedan philoso- phers of the Middle Ages bestowed also greater attention on natural research, and restricted themselves less ex- clusively to theological and theologico-metaphysical questions than the Christians. But the Mohammedan nations were wanting in that rare genius for the intel. lectual treatment and moral ennobling of natural in- stincts by which the Greek was so favourably distin- guished from the Oriental, who was careless of form, and carried both self-indulgence and self-mortification to excess. The abstract monotheism, too, of the Koran is even more directly opposed to the deified world of the Greeks than the Christian doctrine is. The Moham- medan Philosophy, therefore, in regard to its general tendency, must, like the Christian, be pronounced essen- tially different from the Greek. In it we miss the free outlook upon the actual world, and therewith the activity and independence of thought, so natural to the Greeks; and though it starts from a zealous desire for the know- ledge of mature, the theological presuppositions of its dogmatic creed, and the magical conceptions of the latest antiquity, are always in the way. Lastly, the CHARACTER OF GREEK PHILOSOPHY. 137 ultimate aim which it proposes to itself consists far more in the consummation of the religious life and the attainment of mystic abstraction and supernatural illu- mination, than in the clear and scientific understanding of the world and its phenomena. On these points, however, there can be little con- troversy. It is a far more difficult task to determine the specific character of Greek Philosophy as distin- guished from the modern. For modern Philosophy itself arose essentially under Greek influence, and by means of a partial return to Greek intuitions; it is, therefore, in its whole spirit, far more allied to Hellenic—T Philosophy than the Philosophy of the Middle Ages, in spite of its dependence on Greek authorities, ever was. This similarity is heightened, and the difficulty of differentiating them increased, by the fact that the old Philosophy, in the course of its own development, approximated to the Christian conception of the world (with which it has been blended in modern science) and paved the way for that conception. The doctrines which were the preparation for Christianity are often very like Christian doctrine modified by classical studies; the original Greek doctrines resemble in many respects the modern doctrines which subsequently developed them- selves under the influence of the ancients; so that it seems hardly possible to assign distinctive characteristics that are generally applicable. But there appears at the outset this fundamental difference between the two Philoso- phies—viz. that the one is the earlier, the other the later; the one is original, the other derived. Greek Philosophy sprang from the soil of Greek national life and of the 138 INTRODUCTION. Greek view of the world; even when it passes beyond the original limits of the Hellenic sphere and prepares the transition from the ancient period to the Christian, its essential content can only be understood in relation to the development of the Greek spirit. Even at that period we feel that it is the abiding influence of classic ideas which hinders it from really adopting the later standpoint. Conversely, with the modern philo- sophers, even when at first sight they seem wholly to return to the ancient modes of thought, we can always, on closer inspection, detect motives and conceptions foreign to the ancients. The only question is, therefore, where these motives and conceptions are ultimately to be sought 2 All human culture results from the reciprocal action of the inward and the outward, of spontaneity and receptivity, of mind and nature; its direction is, therefore, principally determined by the relation that exists between these two sides, which relation, as we have already seen, was always more harmonious in the Greek race than in any other, by reason of its peculiar character and historical conditions. The distinctive peculiarity of the Greeks lies, indeed, in this unbroken unity of the spiritual and the natural, which is at once’ the prerogative and the confining barrier of this classical nation. Not that spirit and nature were as yet wholly undiscriminated. On the contrary, the great superiority of Greek civilisation, as compared with earlier or con- temporary civilisations, essentially depends on this fact —that in the light of the Hellenic consciousness there disappears, not only the irrational disorder of primitive CHARACTER OF GREEK PHILOSOPHY, 139 and natural life, but also that fantastic confusion and interminglement of the ethical with the physical, which we almost everywhere meet with in the East. The Greek attains his independence of the powers of nature by the free exercise of his mental and moral activity; transcending merely natural ends, he regards the sensible as an instrument and symbol of the spiritual. Thus the two spheres are to him separate; and as the ancient gods of nature were overpowered by the Olympian deities, so his own natural state gives place to the higher state of a moral culture that is free, human, and beautiful. But this discrimination of spirit and nature • does not as yet involve the theory of radical opposition-T and contradiction—the systematic breach between them which was preparing in the last centuries of the ancient world, and has been so fully accomplished in the Chris- tian world. The spirit is always regarded as the higher element in comparison with nature; man looks upon his free moral activity as the essential aim and content of his existence; he is not satisfied to enjoy in a sensuous manner, or to work in servile dependence on the will of another; what he does he will do freely, for himself; the happiness which he strives for he will attain by the use and development of his bodily and mental powers, by a vigorous social life, by doing his share of work for the whole, by the respect of his fellow citizens; and on this personal capability and freedom is founded that proud self-confidence which raises the Hellene so far above all the barbarians. The reason that Greek life has not only a more beautiful form, but also a higher content than that of any other ancient …” 140 INTRODUCTION. t race, is because no other was able to rise with such freedom above mere nature, or with such idealism to make sensible existence simply the sustainer of spiritual. If then this unity of spirit with nature were understood as a unity without difference, the expression would ill serve to characterise it. Rightly apprehended, on the other hand, it correctly expresses the distinction of the Greek world from the Christian Middle Ages and from modern times. The Greek rises above the world of outward existence and absolute dependence on the forces of nature, but he does not on that account hold mature to be either impure or not divine. On the contrary, he sees in it the direct manifestation of higher powers; his very gods are not merely moral beings, they are at the same time, and originally, powers of nature; they have the form of natural existence, they constitute a plurality of beings, created, and like unto men, restricted in their power of action, having the universal force of nature as etermal chaos before them, and as pitiless fate above them ; far from denying himself and his nature for the sake of the gods, the Greek knows no better way of honouring them than by the cheerful en- joyment of life, and the worthy exercise of the talents he has acquired in the development of his natural powers of body and mind. Accordingly moral life also is throughout founded upon natural temperament and circumstances. From the standpoint of ancient Greece it is impossible that man should consider his mature corrupt, and himself, as originally constituted, sinful. There is, consequently, no demand that he should re- nounce his natural inclinations, repress his sensuality, CHARACTER OF GREEK PHILOSOPHY. 141 and be radically changed by a moral new birth; no demand even for that struggle against sensuality which our moral law is accustomed to prescribe even when it is no longer based upon positive Christianity. On the con- trary, the natural powers as such are assumed to be good, and the natural inclinations as such to be legitimate; morality consists, according to the truly Greek concep- tion of Aristotle, in guiding these powers to the right end, and maintaining these inclinations in right measure and balance: virtue is nothing more than the intelligent and energetic development of natural endowments, and the highest law of morals is to follow the course of nature freely and rationally. This standpoint is not a result of reflection, it is not attained by a struggle with the opposite demand for the renºunciation of nature, as is the case with the moderns when they profess the same principles; it is, therefore, quite untrammelled by doubt and uncertainty. To the Greek it appears as matural and necessary that he should allow sensuality its rights as that he should control it by the exercise of will and reflection ; he can regard the matter in no other light, and he therefore pursues his course with full security, honestly feeling that he is justified in so doing. But among the natural presuppositions of free activity must also be reckoned the social relations in which each individual is placed by his birth. The Greek allows these relations an amount of influence over his morality, to which in modern times we are not accustomed. The tradition of his people is to him the highest moral authority, life in and for the state the highest duty, far outweighing all others; beyond the 142 INTRODUCTION. limits of the national and political community, moral obligation is but imperfectly recognised; the validity of a free vocation determined by personal conviction, the idea of the rights and duties of man in the wider sense, were not generally acknowledged until the transitional period which coincides with the dissolution of the ancient Greek standpoint. How far the classical epoch and view of human life are in this respect removed from ours, appears in the constant confusion of morals with politics, in the inferior position of women, especially among the Ionian races, in the conception of marriage and sexual relations, but above all in the abrupt opposi- tion between Greeks and barbarians, and the slavery which was connected with it, and was so indispensable an institution in ancient states. These shadow-sides of Greek life must not be overlooked. In one respect, however, things were easier for the Greek than for us. His range of vision, it is true, was more limited, his relations were narrower, his moral principles were less pure and strict and universal than ours; but, perhaps, on that very account, his life was the more fitted to form complete, harmoniously cultured men and classical characters." The classic form of Greek art was also essentially conditioned by the mental character we have been de- scribing. The classic ideal, as Vischer * well remarks, is the ideal of a people that is moral without any break * Cf. Hegel's Phil. der Gesch. der Phil. s. Kant, i. 79 sqq.; and p. 291 sq. 297 sqq. 305 sqq.; AEs- especially the thoughtful and for- thetik, ii. 56 sqq. 73 Sqq. 100 sqq.; cible remarks of Wischer in his Gesch. der Phil. i. 170 sq.; Phil. Æsthetik, ii.237 sqq. 446 sqq. der Rel. ii. 99 sqq.; Braniss, Gesch. 2 AEsth. ii. 459. - CHARACTER OF GREEK PHILOSOPHY. 143 with nature : there is consequently in the spiritual con- tent of its ideal, and therefore in the expression of that ideal, no surplus which cannot be unrestrainedly poured forth in the form as a whole. The spiritual is not ap- prehended as opposed to the sensible phenomenon, but in and with it; consequently, the spiritual attains to artistic representation only so far as it is capable of direct expression in the sensible form. A Greek work of art bears the character of simple, satisfied beauty, of plastic calm; the idea realises itself in the pheno- menon, as the soul in the body with which it clothes itself by virtue of its creating force; there is as yet no spiritual content which resists this plastic treatment, and which could not find its adequate and direct repre- sentation in the sensible form. Greek art consequently only attained to perfection where, from the nature of the subject, no task was proposed to it which could not be com- pletely accomplished in the way we have just described. In plastic art, in the epic, in classic architecture, the Greeks have remained unrivalled models for all time; on the other hand, in music they seem to have been far behind the moderns; because this art, more than any other, by its very nature leads us back from the fugitive external elements of tone to the inner region of feeling and of subjective mood. For the same reasons their painting seems only to have been comparable with that of the moderns in respect of drawing. Even Greek lyric poetry, great and perfect as it is of its kind, differs no less from the more emotional and subjective modern lyric poetry than the metrical verse of the ancients from the rhymed verse of the moderns; and if, on the one tº nº H1 - " 'oe . / 144 INTRODUCTION. hand, no later poet could have written a Sophoclean drama, on the other, the ancient tragedies of fate as compared with modern tragedies since Shakespeare, fail in the natural evolution of events from the characters, from the temperament of the dramatis personae; and thus, like lyric poetry, instead of fully developing its own particular form of art, tragedy has still in a certain sense the epic type. In all these traits one and the same characteriss manifested : Greek art is distinguished from modern by its pure objectivity; the artist in his creation does not remain within himself, in the inner region of his thoughts and feelings, and his work when accomplished suggests mothing internal which it has not fully expressed. The form is as yet absolutely filled with the content; the content in its whole compass attains determinate existence in the form ; spirit is still in undisturbed union with nature, the idea is not yet separated from the phenomenon. We must expect to find the same character in Greek Philosophy, since it is the spirit of the Hellenic people that created that Philosophy, and the Hellenic view of the world that there receives its scientific expression. This character first shows itself in a trait which indeed is not easy to define in an exhaustive and accurate manner, but which must strike every student in the writings and fragments of ancient Philosophy: in the whole mode of treatment, the whole attitude which the author adopts in reference to his subject. That freedom and simplicity, which Hegel praises' in the ancient philo- sophers, that plastic repose with which a Parmenides, a * Gesch. der Phil. i. 124. CHARACTER OF GREEK PHILOSOPHY. 145 Plato, an Aristotle handle the most difficult questions, is the same in the sphere of scientific thought as that which in the sphere of art we call the classic style. The philosopher does not in the first place reflect upon himself and his personal condition: he has not to deal with a number of preliminary presuppositions and make abstraction of his own thoughts and interests that . he may attain to a purely philosophic mood; he is in such a mood from the very beginning. In the treat- ment, therefore, of Scientific questions he does not allow himself to be disturbed by other opinions, nor by his own wishes; he goes straight to the matter in hand, desiring to absorb himself in it, to give free scope to its working within him; he is at peace as to the results of his thought, because ready to accept whatever approves itself to him as true and real." This objectivity was no doubt far more easily attainable for Greek Philosophy than for our own; thought, having then before it neither a previous scientific development nor a fixed religious system, could grapple with scientific problems from their jectivity, furthermore, constitutes not only the strength, but also the weakness of this Philosophy; for it is essentially conditional on man's having not yet become mistrustful of his thought, on his being but partially * Take, for example, the well- the shortness of human life.’ very commencement with complete freedom. Such ob- ~ known utterances of the Protagoras: ‘Man is the measure of all things, of Being how it is, of non-Being how it is not.’ ‘Of the gods I have nothing to say ; neither that they are, nor that they are not; for here is much that hinders me, the obscurity of the matter and WOL. I. These propositions were in the highest degree offensive at that period; there was in them a de- mand for a complete revolution of all hitherto received ideas. Yet how statuesque is the style ! With what classical calmness are they enunciated 1 146 - INTRODUCTION. conscious of the subjective activity through which his presentations are formed, and therefore of the share which this activity has in their content; in a word, on his not having arrived at self-criticism. The difference, however, between ancient Philosophy and modern is here strikingly and unquestionably displayed. This characteristic suggests further points for re- flection. So simple a relation to its object was only possible to Greek thought, because, as compared with modern thought, it started from a much more incom- plete experience, a more limited knowledge of nature, a less active development of inner life. The greater the mass of facts with which we are acquainted, the more complicated are the problems which have to be solved in attempting their scientific explanation. The more accurately, on the one hand, we have come to in- vestigate external events in their specific character; the more, on the other, has our inner eye become keen for introspection, through the intensifying of religious and moral life; the more our historical knowledge of human conditions widens, the less possible is it to apply the analogies of human spiritual life to natural phenomena, and the analogies of the external world to the pheno- mena of consciousness; to rest satisfied with imperfect explanations abstracted from limited and one-sided ex- perience, or to presuppose the truth of our conceptions without accurate enquiry. It maturally followed, there- fore, that the problems with which all Philosophy is concerned should in modern times partially change their scope and significance. Modern Philosophy begins with doubt; in Bacon, with doubt of the previous science; CHARACTER OF GREEK PHILOSOPHY. 147 in Descartes, with doubt of the truth of our concep- tions generally—absolute doubt. Having this starting- point, it is forced from the outset to keep steadily in view the question of the possibility and conditions of knowledge, and for the answering of that question it institutes all those enquiries into the origin of our conceptions, which at each new turn that they have taken have gained in profundity, in importance, and in extent. These enquiries were at first remote from Greek science, which, firmly believing in the veracity of thought, applied itself directly to the search for the Real. But even after that faith had been shaken by Sophistic, and the necessity of a methodical enquiry had been asserted by Socrates, this enquiry is still far from being the accurate analysis of the intellect undertaken by modern Philosophy since Locke and Hume. Aristotle himself, though he describes how conceptions result from experience, investigates very incompletely the conditions on which the correctness of our conceptions depends; and the necessity of a discrimination between their objective and subjective constituents never seems to occur to him. Even the scepticism posterior to Aristotle gave no impulse to any more fundamental and theoretic investigations. The empiricism of the Stoics and the sensualism of the Epicureans were based as little as the neo-Platonic and neo-Pythagorean speculation on en- quiries tending to supply the lacunae in the Aristotelian theory of knowledge. The criticism of the faculty of cognition, which has attained so great an importance for modern Philosophy, in ancient Philosophy was proportionally undeveloped. Where, however, a clear - L 2 148 INTRODUCTION. recognition is wanting of the conditions under which scientific enquiry must be undertaken, there science must necessarily itself be wanting in that certainty of procedure which due regard to those conditions alone can give. Thus we find that the Greek philosophers, even the greatest and most careful observers among them, have all more or less the failing with which philosophers have been so often reproached. They are apt to cease their enquiries prematurely, and to found general concepts and principles upon imperfect or in- sufficiently proved experiences, which are then treated as indisputable truths and made the basis of farther inferences; to display, in short, that dialectical ex- clusiveness which is the result of employing certain presentations universally assumed, established by lan- guage, and recommending themselves by their apparent accordance with nature, without further enquiring into their origin and legitimacy, or keeping in view while so employing them their real foundation in fact. Modern Philosophy has itself been sufficiently faulty in this respect; it is humiliating to compare the speculative rashness of many a later philosopher with the circumspection displayed by Aristotle in testing the theories of others, and in examining the various points of view that arise out of the questions he is discussing. But in the general course of modern science the demand for a strict and exact method has more and more made itself felt, and even where the philosophers themselves have not adequately responded to this demand, the other sciences have afforded them a far greater mass of facts and laws empirically established; and further, these CHARACTER OF GREEK PHILOSOPHY. 149 facts have been much more carefully sifted and tested, and these laws much more accurately determined, than was possible at the period of ancient Philosophy. This higher development of the experimental sciences, which distinguishes modern times from antiquity, is closely connected with that critical method in which Greek Philosophy and Greek science generally were so greatly deficient. * The distinction of subjective and objective in our conceptions is nearly allied to the distinction of the intellectual and corporeal, of phenomena within us and phenomena without. This distinction, like the other, is generally wanting in clearness and precision with the ancient philosophers. Anaxagoras, it is true, represents spirit as opposed to the material world ; and in the -Platonic School this opposition is developed to its fullest extent. Nevertheless, in Greek Philosophy, the two spheres are constantly overlapping one another. On the one hand, natural phenomena, which theology had considered to be immediately derived from beings akin to men, continued to be explained by analogies derived from human life. On such an analogy were based not only the Hylozoism of many ancient physi- cists, and that belief in the animate nature of the world which we find in Plato, the Stoics and neo-Platonists, but also the teleology which, in most of the philosophic schools since Socrates, has interfered with, and not un- frequently overpowered, the physical explanation of nature. On the other hand, the true essence of psychic phenomena was also not determined with accuracy; and if only a certain number of the ancient philosophers I50 INTRODUCTION. contented themselves with such simple materialistic explanations as were set up by many of the pre-Socratic physicists, after them by the Stoics and Epicureans, and also by individual Peripatetics; yet even in the spiritualistic psychology of a Plato, an Aristotle, or a Plotinus we are surprised to find that the difference between conscious and unconscious forces is almost ig- nored, and that hardly any attempt is made to conceive the different sides of human nature in their personal unity. Hence it was easy to these philosophers to explain the soul as compounded of distinct and radi- cally heterogeneous elements; and hence, too, in their conceptions relating to God, the world-soul, the spirits of the stars, and similar subjects, the question of the personality of these beings is generally so little con- sidered. It was in the Christian period that the feeling of the validity and importance of human personality first attained its complete development ; and so it is in modern science that we first find on this point con- ceptions sufficiently precise to render the confusion of personal and impersonal characteristics so frequently met with in ancient philosophy henceforward impossible. The difference between Greek ethics and our own has been already touched upon ; and it need scarcely be said that all our previous remarks on this subject equally apply to philosophic ethics. Much as Philosophy itself contributed to transform the old Greek conception of moral life into a stricter, more abstract, more general morality, the characteristic features of the ancient view were in Philosophy only gradually effaced, and were always more or less present down to the latest period of CHARACTER OF GREEK PHILOSOPHY. 151 antiquity. Not until after Aristotle was the close union of morals with politics, so inherent in the Greeks, dis- solved; and down to the time of Plotinus, we can still clearly recognise the aesthetic treatment of ethics, which was also essentially distinctive of the Hellenic spirit. The spiritual life of the Greeks in the thousand years that elapsed between the rise and close of their Philosophy certainly underwent great and important changes, and Philosophy was itself one of the most efficient causes by which these changes were brought about. As Greek Philosophy represents generally the character of the Greek spirit, it must also reflect the transformations which in course of time that spirit has undergone ; and the more so, because the greater num- ber and the most influential of the philosophic systems belong to the period when the older form of Greek spiritual life was gradually melting away; when the human mind was increasingly withdrawing itself from the outer world, to be concentrated with exclusive energy upon itself—and when the transition from the classic to the Christian and modern world was in part preparing, and in part already accomplished. For this reason, the characteristics which appeared in the philosophy of the classical period cannot be unconditionally ascribed to the whole of Greek Philosophy; yet the early character of that Philosophy essentially influenced its entire sub- sequent course. We see, indeed, in the whole of its development, the original unity of spirit with nature gradually disappearing; but as long as we continue on Hellenic ground, we never find the abrupt separation L52 INTRODUCTION. between them, which was the starting-point of modern science. In the commencement of Greek Philosophy, it is before all things the external world which claims at- tention. The question arises as to its causes; and the answer is attempted without any preliminary enquiry into the human faculty of cognition; the reasons of phenomena are sought in what is known to us through the external perception, or is at any rate analogous to it. But, on the other hand, just because as yet no exact discrimination is made between the external world and the world of consciousness, qualities are ascribed to cor- poreal forms and substances, and effects are expected from them, which could only in truth belong to spiritual beings. Such are the characteristics of Greek Philo- sophy up to the time of Anaxagoras. During this period, philosophic interest chiefly confines itself to the consideration of nature, and to conjectures respecting the reasons of natural phenomena; the facts of con- sciousness are not yet recognised or investigated as special phenomena. This Philosophy of nature was opposed by Sophistic, which denied man's capacity for the cognition of things, and directed his attention instead to his own practical aims. But with the advent of Socrates, Philosophy again inclined towards a search for the Real, though at first this was not formulated into a system. The lesser Socratic schools, indeed, contented themselves with the application of knowledge to some one side of man’s spiritual life, but Philosophy as a whole, far from maintaining this subjective view of the Socratic CHARACTER OF GREEK PHILOSOPHY. 153 principle, culminated in the vast and comprehensive systems of Plato and Aristotle, the greatest achieve- ments of Greek science. These systems approximate much more closely to modern Philosophy, on which they have had an important influence, than the pre- Socratic physics. Nature is with them neither the sole nor the principal object of enquiry; side by side with physics, metaphysics has a higher, and ethics an equal prominence, and the whole is placed on a firmer basis by the enquiries concerning the origin of knowledge and the conditions of scientific method. Moreover, the unsensuous form is distinguished from the sensible phenomenon, as the essential from the acci- dental, the eternal from the transitory; only in the cognition of this unsensuous essence—only in pure thought—is the highest and purest knowledge to be sought. Even in the explanation of nature, preference is given to the investigation of forms and aims as com- pared with the knowledge of physical causes; in man, the higher part of his nature in its essence and origin is discriminated from the sensual part; and the highest problem for mankind is accordingly found exclusively in the development of his spiritual life, and above all of his knowledge. Although, however, the Platonic and Aristotelian systems show themselves thus akin in many respects to modern systems, yet the peculiar stamp of the Greek spirit is unmistakably impressed on them both. Plato is an idealist, but his idealism is not the modern subjective idealism : he does not hold with Fichte, that the objective world is a mere phenomenon of consciousness; he does not, with Leibniz, place per- 154 INTRODUCTION. cipient essences at the origin of all things; the ideas themselves are not derived by him from thought, either human or divine, but thought is derived from partici- pation in the ideas. In the ideas the universal essence of things is reduced to plastic forms, which are the object of an intellectual intuition, in the same way that things are the object of the sensuous intuition. Even the Platonic theory of knowledge has not the character of the corresponding enquiries of the mo- derms. With them, the main point is the analysis _-of the subjective activity of cognition; their attention is primarily directed to the development of knowledge in man according to its psychological course and its conditions. Plato, on the other hand, keeps almost exclusively to the objective nature of our presentations; he enquires far less about the manner in which intui- tions and conceptions arise in us, than about the value attaching to them in themselves; the theory of know- ledge is therefore with him directly connected with metaphysics: the enquiry as to the truth of the pre- sentation or conception coincides with that respecting the reality of the sensible phenomenon and of the Idea. Plato, moreover, however low may be his estimation of A the phenomenal world in comparison with the idea, is º removed from the prosaic and mechanical modern | view of nature; the world is to him the visible god, the stars are living, happy beings, and his whole expla- nation of nature is dominated by the teleology which plays so important a part in Greek Philosophy posterior to Socrates. Though in his ethics he passes beyond the ancient Greek standpoint, by the demand for a philoso- CHARACTER OF GREEK PHILOSOPHY. 155 phic virtue founded on science, and prepares the way for Christian morality by flight from the world of sense; yet in the doctrine of Eros he maintains the aesthetic, and in the institutions of his Republic the political character of Greek morality in the most decided manner; and despite his moral idealism, his ethics do not disclaim that inborn Hellenic sense of naturalness, proportion, and harmony which expresses itself in his successors by the principle of living according to nature, and the theory of goods and of virtue founded on that principle. The Greek type, however, comes out most clearly in Plato's mode of apprehending the whole problem of Philosophy. In his inability to separate science from morality and religion, in his conception of Philosophy as the complete and universal culture of mind and character, we clearly recognise the standpoint of the Greeks, who made far less distinction between the different spheres of life and culture than the mo– derms, because with them the fundamental opposition of spiritual and bodily perfection was much less de- veloped and insisted on. Even in Aristotle this stand- point is clearly marked, although, in comparison with that of Plato, his system looks modern in respect of its purely scientific form, its rigorous conciseness, and its broad empirical basis. He, too, regards the concep- tions in which thought sums up the qualities of things as objective forms antecedent to our thought ; not indeed distinct from individual things as to their ex- istence, but as to their essential nature, independent; and in determining the manner in which these forms are represented in things, he is guided throughout by the 156 INTRODUCTION. analogy of artistic creation. Although, therefore, he bestows much greater attention on physical phenomena and their causes than Plato does, his whole theory of the world bears essentially the same teleologic aesthetic character as Plato's. He removes the Divine spirit from all living contact with the world, but in his con- ception of nature as a uniform power working with full purpose and activity to an end, the poetic liveliness of the old Greek intuition of nature is apparent y and when he attributes to matter as such a desire for form, and deduces from that desire all motion and life in the corporeal world, we are reminded of the Hylozoism which was so closely related to the view of nature we are considering. His motions about the sky and the hea- venly bodies which he shares with Plato and most of the ancients, are also entirely Greek. His ethics alto- gether belong to the sphere of Hellenic morality. Sen- sual instincts are recognised by him as a basis for moral action, virtue is the fulfilment of natural activities. The sphere of ethics is distinguished from that of politics, but the union between them is still very close. In politics itself we find all the distinctive features of the Hellenic theory of the state, with its advantages and imperfections: on the one hand, the doctrine of man’s matural vocation for political community, of the moral object of the state, of the value of a free constitution; on the other hand, the justification of slavery and con- tempt for manual labour. Thus, while spirit is still closely united to its natural basis, nature is directly related to spiritual life. In Plato and Aristotle we see neither the abstract spiritualism, nor the purely physical CHARACTER OF GREEK PHILOSOPHY. 157 explanation of nature of modern science ; neither the strictness and universality of our moral consciousness, nor the acknowledgment of material interest which so often clashes with it. The oppositions between which human life and thought move are less developed, their relation is more genial and harmonious, their adjust- ment easier, though certainly more superficial, than in the modern theory of the world, originating as it does from far more comprehensive experiences, more difficult struggles, and more complex conditions. Not until after the time of Aristotle does the Greek spirit begin to be so greatly estranged from nature that the classical view of the world disappears, and the way is being prepared for the Christian. How greatly this change in its consequences affected also the aspect of Philosophy, will hereafter be shown. In this period of transition, however, it is all the more striking to observe that the old Greek standpoint was still sufficiently influential to divide the Philosophy of that time very clearly from ours. Stoicism no longer carries on any independent investigation of nature; it withdraws itself entirely from objective enquiry and substitutes the interest of moral subjectivity. Yet it continues to look upon nature as the thing which is highest and most divine; it defends the old religion, inasmuch as it was a worship of the powers of nature; subjection to natural laws, life according to nature, is its watchword; natural truths (bvaucai évvotal) are its supreme authority; and though, in this return to what is primitive and original, it concedes only a conditional value to civil institutions, yet it regards the mutual interdependence of all men, I58 INTRODUCTION. the extension of political community to the whole race, as an immediate requirement of human nature, in the same manner as the earlier Greeks regarded political life. While in Stoicism man breaks with the outer world in order to fortify himself in the energy of his inner life against external influences, he yet at the same time entirely rests upon the order of the universe, spirit feels still too much bound to nature to know that it is in its self-conciousness independent of nature. But nature, consequently, appears as if filled with spirit, and in this direction Stoicism goes so far that the dis- tinction between spiritual and corporeal, which Plato and Aristotle so clearly recognised, again disappears, matter becomes directly animate, spirit is represented as a material breath, or as an organising fire; and, on the other hand, all human aims and thoughts are transferred to nature by the most external teleology possible. In Epicureanism the specific character of the Greek genius is otherwise manifested. Hylozoism and teleo- logy are now abandoned for an entirely mechanical explanation of nature; the vindication of popular re- ligion is exchanged for an enlightened opposition to it, and the individual seeks his happiness, not in sub- mission to the law of the whole, but in the undisturbed security of his individual life. But that which is according to nature is the highest, to the Epicurean as to the Stoic ; and if in theory he degrades his external nature into a spiritless mechanism, so much the more does he endeavour to establish in human life that beautiful harmony of the egoistic and benevolent im- pulses, of sensuous enjoyment and spiritual activity, CHARACTER OF GREEK PHILOSOPHY. 159 which made the garden of Epicurus the abode of Attic refinement and pleasant social intercourse. This form of culture is as yet without the polemical asperities which are inseparable from modern repetitions of it, on account of the contrast it presents to the strictness of Christian ethics; the justification of the sensual element appears as a natural presupposition which does not require any preliminary or particular apology. However much then Epicureanism may remind us of certain modern opinions, the difference between that which is original and of natural growth, and that which is derived and the result of reflection, is unmistakable on closer examination. The same may be said of the scepticism of this period as compared with that of modern times. Modern scepticism has always some- thing unsatisfied about it, an inner uncertainty, a secret wish to believe that which it is trying to disprove. Ancient scepticism displays no such half-heartedness, and knows nothing of the hypochondriacal unrest which Hume himself" so vividly describes; it regards ignorance not as a misfortune, but as a natural necessity, in the recognition of which man becomes calm. Even while despairing of knowledge it maintains the attitude of compliance with the actual order of things, and from this very source evolves the drapašta which is almost impossible to modern scepticism, governed as it is by subjective interests.” 4. Even neo-Platonism, far removed as it is from the * On Human Nature, book i. * Cf. Hegel's remarks on the part iv. section 1, 509 sqq.; subject. Gesch. der Phil. i. 124 Jacobi's translation. Sq. 160 INTRODUCTION. ancient Greek spirit, and decidedly as it approaches that of the Middle Ages, has its centre of gravity still in the antique world. This is evident, not only from its close relation to the heathem religions, the last apologist for which it would certainly not have become had no essential and internal affinity existed between them, but also in its philosophic doctrines. Its abstract spiritual- ism contrasts, indeed, strongly with the naturalism of the ancients; but we have only to compare its concep- tion of nature with that of contemporary Christian writers, we need only hear how warmly Plotinus defends the majesty of nature against the contempt of the Gnostics, how keenly Proclus and Simplicius dispute the Christian doctrine of the creation, in order to see in it an offshoot of the Greek spirit. Matter itself is brought nearer to mind by the neo-Platonists than by the majority of modern philosophers, who see in the two principles essentially separate substances; for the neo-Platonists opposed the theory of a self-dependent matter, and explained the corporeal as the result of the gradual degradation of the spiritual essence. They thus declared the opposition of the two principles to be not original and absolute, but derived and merely quantitative. Again, though the neo-Platonic meta- physics, especially in their later form, must appear to us very abstruse, their origin was similar to that of Plato's theory of Ideas; for the properties and causes of things are here regarded as absolute essential natures, over and above the world and man, as objects of an intellectual intuition. Moreover, these essences bear to each other a definite relation of higher, lower, and CHARACTER of GREEK PHILosophy. 161 co-ordinate, and thus appear as the metaphysical coun- terpart of the mythical gods, whom neo-Platonic alle- gory itself recognised in them, recognising also in their progressive emanation from the primitive essence the analogue of those theogonies with which Greek specu- lation in the earliest times began. To sum up what we have been saying. In the Philosophy of the middle ages, spirit asserts itself as alien and opposed to nature: in modern Philosophy, it strives to regain unity with nature, without, however, losing the deep consciousness of the difference between the spiritual and the natural: in Greek Philosophy is represented that phase of scientific thought in which the discrimination and separation of the two elements are developed out of their original equipoise and har- monious co-existence, though this separation was never actually accomplished in the Hellenic period. While, therefore, in Greek, as in modern Philosophy, we find both the discrimination and the union of the spiritual and the natural, this is brought about in each case in a different manner and by a different connection. Greek Philosophy starts from that harmonious relation of spirit to nature in which the distinguishing characteristic of ancient culture generally consists; step by step, and half involuntarily, it sees itself compelled to discrimi- mate them. Modern Philosophy, on the contrary, finds this separation already accomplished in the most effec- tual manner in the middle ages, and only succeeds by an effort in discovering the unity of the two sides. This difference of starting-point and of tendency de- WOL. I. M 162 . INTRODUCTION. *w- - - termines the whole character of these two great phe- momena. Greek Philosophy finally results in a dualism, which it finds impossible to overcome scientifically; and even in its most flourishing period the development of this dualism can be traced. Sophisticism breaks with simple faith in the veracity of the senses and of thought. Socrates breaks with unreflecting obedience *— A— _------->“” to existing custom. |Plato opposis to the empirical world an ideal world, but is º world any explanation of the other; he can only explain matter as something non-existent, and can only subject human life to the idea by the arbitrary measures of his State. Even Aristotle keeps pure" spirit entirely distinct from the world, and thinks that man's reason is infused into him from . In the lesser Socratic schools and the post-Aristotelian Philosophy this dualism is still more evident. But we have already seen that, in spite of this tendency, the original presupposition of Greek thought asserts itself in decisive traits; and we shall find that the true cause of its incapacity to re- concile these contradictions satisfactorily lies in its refusal to abandon that presupposition. The unity of spiritual and natural, which Greek thought demands and presupposes, is the direct unbroken unity of the classic theory of the world; when that is cancelled there remains to it no possible way of filling up chasm which, according to its own stand-point, canno exist. The Hellenic character proper is not of cours stamped with equal clearness on each of the Greek systems; in the later periods especially, of Gree OHARACTER • OF GREEK PHILOSOPHY. 163 Philosophy it became gradually blended with foreign elements. Nevertheless, directly or indirectly, this character may plainly be recognised in all the systems; and Greek Philosophy, as a whole, may be said to move in the same direction as the general life of the people to which it belongs. M 2 164 INTRODUCTION. CHAPTER IV. PRINCIPAL PERIODS IN THE DEVELOPMENT OF GREEK PHILOSOPHY. WE have divided Greek Philosophy into three periods, of which the second begins with Socrates and ends with Aristotle. The propriety of this division must now be more closely examined. The utility of such a course may seem indeed doubtful, since so eminent a historian as Ritter' is of opinion that history itself recognises no sections, and that therefore all division of periods is only a means of facilitating instruction, a setting up of resting places to take breath ; and since even a disciple of the Hegelian school ’ declares that the History of Philosophy cannot be written in periods, as the links of History consist wholly of personalities and aggregates of individuals. This latter observation is so far true that it is impossible to draw a straight chronological line across a series of historical phenomena without separating what is really united, and linking together what is really distinct. For, in regard to chronology, the boundaries of successive developments overlap each other; and it is in this that the whole continuity and connection of historic as of natural development con- 1 Gesch. der Phil., 2nd edition, * Marbach, Gesch. der Phil., Pref. p. xiii. Pref. p. viii. PRINCIPAL PERIODS. 165 sists. The new form has already appeared, and has begun to assert itself independently, while the old form is still in existence. The inference from this, however, is not that the division into periods is to be altogether discarded, but only that it must be based upon facts, and not merely upon chronology. Each period lasts as long as any given historical whole continues to follow one and the same direction in its development ; when this ceases to be the case, a new period begins. How long the direction is to be regarded as the same must be decided, here and everywhere, according to the part in which lies the centre of gravity of the whole. When from a given whole, a new whole branches off, its beginnings are to be referred to the subsequent period in proportion as they break with the previous historical connection, and present themselves under a new and original form. If any one supposes, however, that this grouping together of kindred phenomena is merely for the convenience of the historian or his reader, and has no concern with the matter itself, the discussions in our first chapter are amply sufficient to meet the objection. It surely cannot be considered un- important, even for the purposes of convenience, where the divisions are made in a historical exposition; and, if this be conceded, it cannot be unimportant in regard to the matter itself. If one division gives us a clearer survey than another, the reason can only be that it presents a truer picture of the differences and rela- tions of historical phenomena; the differences must, therefore, lie in the phenomena themselves, as well as in our subjective consideration of them. It is un- 166 INTRODUCTION. deniable, indeed, that not only different individuals, but also different periods, have each a different character, and that the development of any given whole, whether great or small, goes on for a time in a definite direction, and them changes this direction to strike out some other course. It is this unity and diversity of historical character to which the periods have to conform ; the periodic division must represent the internal relation of phenomena at the different epochs, and it is con- sequently as little dependent on the caprice of the historian as the distribution of rivers and mountains on that of the geographer, or the determination of natural kingdoms on that of the naturalist. What division then shall we adopt in regard to the history of Greek Philosophy It is clear from our second chapter that the commencement of this history ought not to be placed earlier than Thales. He was the first, as far as we know, who, in speaking of the primitive causes of all things, abandoned mythical language;—though it is true that the old custom of making the history of Philosophy begin with Hesiod is not even in our days, wholly discarded.' Socrates is generally considered as the inaugurator of the next great movement, and for this reason the second period is usually said to open with him. Some historians, however, would bring the first period to a close before the time of Socrates; for example, Ast,” Rixner,” and Braniss. Others, again, like Hegel, would prolong it beyond him. ! It is still followed by Fries, * Grundriss éiner Gesch, der Gesch. der Phil., and Deutinger, Phil., 1 A § 43. Geseh. der Phil., Wol. 1. * Gesch. der Phil., i. 44 sq. FIRST PERIOD, 167 Ast and Rixner distinguish in the history of Greek Philosophy the three periods of Ionian Realism, Italian Idealism, and the Attic combination of these two ten- dencies. Braniss starts with the same fundamental dis- tinction of Realism and Idealism, only he attributes both these tendencies to each of the first two periods. According to him, therefore, Greek thought, like Greek life, is determined by the original opposition of the Ionic and Doric elements. Absorption in the objective world is the characteristic of the Ionic ; absorption—in self, of the Doric race. In the first period, then, this ...i. in two parallel directions of Philosophy, the one realistic, the other idealistic ; in Af the second, this opposition is cancelled, and lost in O the consciousness of the universal spirit; and in the | third, the spirit, deprived of its content through So- phistic, seeks in itself a new and more lasting content. iº According to Braniss, therefore, there are three periods of Greek Philosophy. The first, beginning with Thales and Pherecydes, is further represented on the one side by Anaximander, Anaximenes, and Heracleitus; and on the other by Pythagoras, Xenophanes, and Parmenides; a Doric antithesis being opposed at each stage of this period to the Ionic thesis; finally, the results of the previous development are summed up in a harmonious manner by the Ionian Diogenes and the Dorian Empe- docles. It is recognised that Becoming prºmºſ Being, that Being expands itself into Becoming, that the inner and outer, form and matter, unite in the con- sciousness of the universal spirit; the percipient spirit * Gesch. der Phil. 3. Kant, i. 102 sqq.; 135; 150 sq. ...-e-º' S tº hºvº (“ tº 7..… (-,-2' tº 24- 168 INTRODUCTION. stands over against this universal spirit, and has to reflect it in itself. Here the second period commences; and in its development there are three moments. By Anaxa- goras, spirit is distinguished from the extended object; by Democritus, it is opposed to the object as a purely subjective principle; by the Sophists, all objectivity is placed in the subjective spirit itself; the universal is at length completely suppressed, and spiritual life is en- tirely lost in the actual sensible presence. Thus thrown back upon itself, however, the spirit is forced to define its reality in a permanent manner, to enquire what is its absolute end, to pass from the sphere of necessity into that of liberty, and in the reconciliation of the two principles to attain the ultimate end of speculation. This is the commencement of the third period, which extends from Socrates to the end of Greek Philosophy. Much may be urged against this derivation. In the first place, we must question the discrimination of an Tonic Realism and a Doric Idealism. What is here called Doric Idealism is, as we shall presently find,' neither idealism nor purely Doric. This at once de- stroys the basis of the whole deduction. Ast and Rixner, moreover, divide the Ionic and Doric Philo- sophy into two periods: a division quite unwarrantable, since these two philosophies were synchronous, and powerfully reacted upon each other. It is to some ex- tent then more correct to treat them, like Braniss, as moments of one interdependent historical series. But we have no right to divide the series, as he does, into two parts, and make the difference between them * Cf. the Introduction to the First Period. FIRST PERIOD. 169 analogous to that between the Socratic and pre-Socratic Philosophy. Neither of the three phenomena assigned by Braniss to his second period has this character. Atomistic (even as to date, hardly later than Anaxa- goras) is a system of natural Philosophy, as much as any other of the earlier systems; and to the Empedo- clean system especially (by virtue of a similar attitude to the Eleatics) it stands in so close an affinity that we cannot possibly place it in a separate period. It dis- covers no tendency to regard spirit as purely subjective, —its sole concern is the explanation of nature. So, too, in Anaxagoras we recognise a Physicist, and a Physicist anterior to Diogenes, whom Braniss places before him. His world-forming mind is primarily a physical principle, and he makes no attempt to enlarge the sphere of Philosophy beyond the accustomed limits. There is, therefore, no good ground for making as decided a line of demarcation before him as before Socrates. Even Sophistic cannot be separated from the systems of the first period, as will presently appear. The two periods into which Braniss has divided the pre-Socratic Philosophy are followed by a third, com- prehending the whole further course of Philosophy to the end of Greek science. This partition is so rough, and takes so little account of the radical differences of the later systems, that it would of itself furnish a sufficient reason for repudiating the construction of Braniss. On the other hand, however, Hegel goes too far in the contrary direction. He considers these differences so great that the opposition between the Socratic and the pre-Socratic schools has only a secondary importance 170 INTRODUCTION. in comparison with them. Of his three main periods, the first extends from Thales to Aristotle, the second comprehends all the post-Aristotelian philosophy, with the exception of neo-Platonism; the third embraces neo-Platonism. The first, he says,' represents the com- mencement of philosophising thought until its develop- ment and extension as the totality of Science. After the concrete idea has been thus attained, it makes its appearance in the second period as forming and per- fecting itself in oppositions: a one-sided principle is carried out through the whole of the presentation of the world ; each side developing itself as an extreme, and constituting in itself a totality in regard to its contrary. This breaking up of science into particular systems results in Stoicism and Epicureanism. Scep- ticism, as the negative principle, opposed itself to the dogmatism of both. The affirmative is the cancelling of this opposition, in the theory of an ideal world, or world of thought; it is the idea developed into a i totality in neo-Platonism. The distinction between the old naturalistic philosophy and later science is brought forward as a ground of classification in the first period; it is not Socrates, however, who is the inaugurator of a new series of development, but the Sophists. Philosophy attains in the first part of this * Gesch. der Phil., i. 182 (cf. sqq., 290) makes one period from ii. 373 sq.). This, however, does not quite agree with the previous distinction of four stages, i. 118. Similarly Deutinger, whose expo- sition I cannot further discuss, either here or elsewhere (loc. cit. p. 78 sqq., 140 sqq., 152 sqq., 226 Thales to Aristotle (which is the second according to him), and divides it into three parts: 1, Rrom Thales to Heracleitus; 2, from Anaxagoras to the Sophists; 3, from Socrates to Aristotle. FIRST PERIOD. 171 period, in Anaxagoras, to the conception of vods; in the second part, vows is apprehended by the Sophists, Socrates, and the imperfect Socratics, as subjectivity; and in the third part, vods developes itself as objective thought, as the Idea, into a totality. Socrates, there- fore, appears only as continuing a movement begun by others, not as the inaugurator of a new movement. The first thing that strikes us in this division is the great disproportion in the content of the three periods. While the first is extraordinarily rich in re- markable personages and phenomena, and includes the noblest and most perfect forms of classic philosophy, the second and third are limited to a few systems which are unquestionably inferior in scientific content to those of Plato and Aristotle. This at once makes us suspect that too much of a heterogeneous character is included in this first period. And, in point of fact, the difference between the Socratic and pre-Socratic philosophy is in no respect less than that between the post-Aristotelian and the Aristotelian. Socrates not only developed a mode of thought already existing; he introduced into Philosophy an essentially new principle— and method. Whereas all the previous Philosophy had been immediately directed to the object, -while the question concerning the essence and causes of natural phenomena had been the main question on which all others depended,—Socrates first gave utterance to the conviction that nothing could be known about any object until its universal essence, its concept, was determined ; and that, therefore, the testing of our presentations by the standard of the concept—philo- 172 INTRODUCTION. sophic knowledge of self—is the beginning and the condition of all true knowledge. Whereas the earlier philosophers first arrived at the discrimination of pre- sentation from knowledge through the consideration of things themselves; he, on the contrary, makes all knowledge of things dependent on a right view as to the nature of knowledge. With him, consequently, there begins a new form of science, Philosophy based upon concepts; dialectic takes the place of the earlier dogmatic ; and in connection with this, Philosophy makes new and extensive conquests in hitherto unex- plored domains. Socrates is himself the founder of Ethics; Plato and Aristotle separate Metaphysics from Physics; the philosophy of nature—until then, the whole of philosophy—now beeomes a part of the whole; a part which Socrates entirely neglects, on which Plato bestows hardly any attention, and even Aristotle ranks below the ‘first philosophy.’ These changes are so penetrating, and so greatly affect the general con- dition and character of Philosophy, that it certainly appears justifiable to begin a new period of its develop- ment with Soerates. The only question that might arise is whether to make this beginning with Socrates, or his precursors the Sophists. But although the latter course has been adopted by distinguished authors,' it does not seem legitimate. Sophistic is doubtless the * In addition to Hegel, ef K. F. of the first great period with the Hermann, Gesck., d. Platonismus, Sophists; Hermann and Ueberweg i. 217 sqq. Ast (Geseh. der Phil., make them the commencement of p. 96). Ueberweg (Grundriss der their second period; and Ast of his Gesch, der Phil., i. § 9). Hegel, third. however, opens the second section - …' FIRST PERIOD. 173 end of the old philosophy of nature, but it is not as yet the creation or beginning of a new philosophy: it destroys faith in the possibility of knowing the Real, and thereby discourages thought from the in- vestigation of nature; but it has no new content to offer as a substitute for what it destroys; it declares man in his actions, and in his presentations, to be the measure of all things, but it understands by man, merely the individual in all the contingency of his opinions and endeavours; not the universal essential nature of man, which must be sought out scientifically. Though it is true, therefore, that the Sophists share with Socrates the general character of subjectivity, yet they cannot be said to have inaugurated, in the same sense that he did, a new scientific tendency. The closer definition of the two stand-points proves them to be very distinct. The subjectivity of the Sophists is only a consequence of that in which their philosophic achieve- ment mainly consists—viz., the destruction of the earlier dogmatism: in itself this subjectivity is the end of all Philosophy; it leads to no new knowledge, nor even, like later scepticism, to a philosophic temper of mind; it destroys all philosophic effort, in admitting no other criterion than the advantage and caprice of the indi- vidual. Sophistic is an indirect preparation, not the positive foundation of the new system, which was intro- duced by Socrates. Now it is usual, generally speaking, to commence a new period where the principle which dominates it begins to manifest itself positively with creative energy, and with a definite consciousness of its goal. We open such a period in the history of religion 174 INTRODUCTION. X. With Socrates then the second great period of Greek with Christ, and not with the decay of naturalistic re- ligions and Judaism ; in Church history, with Luther and Zwinglius, not with the Babylonian exile, and the schism of the Popes; in political history, with the French Revolution, not with Louis XV. The history of Philosophy must follow the same procedure; and, accordingly, we must regard Socrates as the first repre- sentative of that mode of thought, the principle of which he was the first to enunciate in a positive manner, and to introduce into actual life. t Philosophy begins. On the subject of its legitimate xtent there is even more difference of opinion than on that of its commencement. Some make it end with Aristotle, others with Zeno,” or Carneades; * a third class of historians, with the first century before Christ; * while a fourth is disposed to include in it the whole course of Greek Philosophy after Socrates, including the neo-Platonists.” In this case, again, our decision must depend on the answer to the question, how long the same main tendency governed the development of Philosophy? In the first place the close interconnection of the Socratic, Platonic, and Aristotelian philosophy is unmistakeable. Socrates first demanded that all knowledge and all moral action should start from knowledge of conceptions, and he tried to satisfy this demand by means of the epagogic method, which he introduced. The same conviction forms the starting- 1 Brandis, Fries, and others. * Tennemann (Grundriss), Ast, 2 Tennemann, in his larger work. Reinhold, Schleiermacher, Ritter, * Tiedemann, Geist, der Spek. Ueberweg, and others. Phil. * Braniss, vide supra. SECOND PERIOD. 175 point of the Platonic system; but what in Socrates is merely a rule for scientific procedure, is developed by Plato into a metaphysical principle. Socrates had said: Only the knowledge of the concept is true know- ledge. Plato says: Only the Being of the concept is true Being, the concept alone is the truly existent. But even Aristotle, notwithstanding his opposition to the doctrine of Ideas, allows this : he too declares the form or concept to be the essence and reality of things; pure form, existing for itself; abstract intelli- gence, restricted to itself—to be the absolutely real. He is divided from Plato only by his theory of the relation of the ideal form to the sensible phenomenon, and to that which underlies the phenomenon as its universal substratum—matter. According to Plato, the idea is separated from things, and exists for itself; consequently the matter of things, having no part in the idea, is declared by him to be absolutely unreal. According to Aristotle, the form is in the things of which it is the form; the material element in them must, therefore, be endowed with a capability of receiving form; matter is not simply non-Being, but the possibility of Being; matter and form have the same content, only in different fashion—in the one it is undeveloped, in the other developed. Decidedly as this contradicts the theory of Plato considered in its specific character, and energetically as Aristotle opposed his master, yet he is far from disagreeing with the uni- versal presupposition of the Socratic and Platonic philo- sophy, viz. the conviction of the necessity of knowledge based on concepts, and of the absolute reality of form. 176 INTRODUCTIOA. On the contrary, his very reason for discarding the doctrine of Ideas, is that Ideas cannot be substantial and truly existent, if they are separated from things. Thus far then we have a continuous development of one and the same principle ; it is one main fundamental intuition which is presented in these three forms. So- crates recognises in the concept the truth of human thought and life; Plato, the absolute, substantial rea- lity; Aristotle not merely the essence, but also the forming and moving principle of empirical reality; and in all we see the development of the self-same thought. But with the post-Aristotelian schools this order of development ceases, and thought takes another direction. The purely scientific interest of Philosophy gives place to the practical; the independent investiga- tion of nature ceases, and the centre of gravity of the whole is placed in Ethics: and in proof of this altered position, all the post-Aristotelian schools, so far as they have any metaphysical or physical theory, rest upon older systems, the doctrines of which they variously interpret, but which they profess to follow in all essen- tial particulars. It is no longer the knowledge of things as such with which the philosopher is ultimately concerned, but the right and satisfactory constitution of human life. This is kept in view even in the reli- gious enquiries to which Philosophy now applies itself more earnestly. Physics are regarded by the Epicu- reans only as a means to this practical end; and though the Stoics certainly ascribe a more independent value to general investigations concerning the ultimate grounds of things, yet the tendency of those investiga- THIRD PERIOD, 177 tions is nevertheless determined by that of their Ethics. In a similar manner, the question of a criterion of truth is answered from a practical point of view by the Stoies and Epicureans. Lastly, the Sceptics deny all possi- bility of knowledge, in order to restrict Philosophy entirely to practical matters. Even this practical philo- sophy, however, has changed its character. The earlier combination of Ethics with politics has ceased ; in place of the commonwealth in which the individual lives for the whole, we find the moral ideal of the wise man who is self-sufficient, self-satisfied, and self-absorbed. The introduction of the idea into practical life no longer appears as the highest object to be attained; but the independence of the individual in regard to mature and humanity,+apathy, & Tapašta, flight from the world of sense; and though the moral consciousness, being thus indifferent to the outward, gains a freedom and univer- sality hitherto unknown to it, though the barriers of nationality are now first broken down, and the equality and affinity of all men, the leading thought of cosmo- politism is recognised, yet on the other hand Morality assumes a one-sided and negative character, which was alien to the philosophy of the classic period. In a word, the post-Aristotelian philosophy bears the stamp of an abstract subjectivity, and this so essentially separates it from the preceding systems that we have every right to conclude the second period of Greek Philosophy with ristotle. - It might, indeed, at first sight, appear that an nalogous character-is-already to be found in Sophistic nd the smaller Socratic schools. But these examples vol. 1." N 178 INTRODUCTION. cannot prove that Philosophy as a whole had received its later bent in the earlier period. In the first place, the phenomena which prefigure in this way the after philosophy are few in number, and of comparatively secondary importance. The systems which give the measure of the period and by which the form of Philo- sophy, generally speaking, was determined, bear quite another character. And in the second place, this affinity itself, when more closely examined, is less than it appears on a superficial glance. Sophistic has not the same historical significance as the later scepticism ; it did not arise out of a general lassitude of scientific energy, but primarily out of an aversion to the pre- vailing naturalistic philosophy; and it did not, like scepticism, find its positive completion in an unscien- tific eclecticism or a mystic speculation, but in the Socratic philosophy of the concept. The Megaric philosophers are rather offshoots of the Eleatics than precursors of the sceptics; their doubts are originally directed against sense-knowledge, not against reason- knowledge. A universal scepticism is not required by them, nor do they aspire to & Tapašta as the practical end of scepticism. Between Aristippus and Epicurus there exists this striking difference: the former makes immediate and positive pleasure the highest good, the latter absence of pain, as a permanent condition. Aris- tippus seeks the enjoyment of that which the external world offers; Epicurus seeks man's independence in regard to the external world. Cynicism, indeed, pushes indifference to the outward, contempt of custom, and repudiation of all theoretic enquiry further than the THIRD PERIO D. 179 Stoa, but the isolated position of this school, and the crude form of its doctrine, sufficiently prove how little can be argued from it as to the whole contemporary mode of thought. This remark applies to all these im- perfect Socratic schools. Their influence is not to be compared with that of the Platonic and Aristotelian doctrines; and they themselves prevent the possibility of their more important action, by disdaining to develop the principle of intellectual knowledge into a system. Only after the Greek world had undergone the most radical changes could attempts like those of the im- perfect Socratics be renewed with any prospect of SUICCéSS. The second period then, closes with Aristotle, and the third begins with Zeno, Epicurus, and the contem- porary scepticism. Whether or not it should extend to the conclusion of Greek Philosophy is a doubtful question. We shall find later on," that in the post- Aristotelian philosophy three divisions may be dis- tinguished: the first, including the bloom of Stoicism, of Epicureanism, and of the older Scepticism; the second, the period of Eclecticism, the later Scepticism, and the precursors of neo-Platonism; the third, neo- Platonism in its various phases. If we count these three divisions as the third, fourth, or fifth periods of Greek Philosophy, there is this advantage, that the several periods are much more equal in duration than if we make all three into one period. But though they are thus equalised chronologically, they become even more disproportionate in content; for the one * Wide the Introduction to Part III. * N 2 180 INTRODUCTION. * century from the appearance of Socrates to the death of Aristotle embraces an amount of scientific achieve- ment equal to the eight or nine following centuries put together. And, what is here most essential, Philosophy in these 900 years moves in the same uniform direction. It is governed by an exclusive subjectivity, which is estranged from the purely speculative interest in things, and reduces all science to practical culture and the happiness of man. This character is displayed (as we have just observed), by Stoicism, Epicureanism, and Scepticism. It is seen in the Eclecticism of the Roman period, which selects what is probable out of the different systems entirely from practical points of view, and according to the standard of subjective feeling and interest. Finally, it is an essential part of neo-Platonism. This will be shown more in detail hereafter ; at present it is enough to notice that the attitude of the neo- Platonists to natural science is exactly the same as that of the other schools posterior to Aristotle; and that their physics tend in the same direction as the Stoical teleology, only more exclusively. Their ethical doctrine is also very closely allied to that of the Stoics, being in- deed the kast outcome of that ethical dualism which developed itself after the time of Zeno; and the dualism contained in their anthropology had already been pre- pared by Stoicism. In regard to religion, the position originally adopted by neo-Platonism was precisely that of the Stoa, and even its metaphysic, including the doctrine of the intuition of the Deity approaches much nearer to the other Aristotelian systems than might at irst sight be supposed. The neo-Platonic theory of THIRD PERIOD. 181 emanation, for example, is an unmistakable repetition of the Stoic doctrine of the Divine reason permeating the whole universe with its various forces: the only ultimate distinction between them is the transcendency of the Divine; from which arises for man, the require- ments of an ecstatic contact with Deity. This transcen– dency itself, however, is a consequence of the previous development of science, and of the sceptical denial of all objective certainty. The human spirit, scepticism had said, has absolutely no truth within itself. It must, therefore, says neo-Platonism, find truth absolutely out- side itself, in its relation to the Divine, which is beyond its thought and the world cognisable by thought. But it follows that the world beyond is presented entirely according to subjective points of view, and determined by the necessities of the subject; and just as the dif- ferent spheres of the real correspond to the different parts of human nature, so the whole system is designed to point out and to open the way for man's communion with God. Here too them, it is the interest of human spiritual life, not that of objective knowledge as such, which governs the system; and thus neo-Platonism fol- lows the tendency peculiar to the whole of Philosophy subsequent to Aristotle. While, therefore, I attach no undue importance to this question, I prefer to unite the three sections into which the history of Philosophy after Aristotle is divided into one period, although its outward extent far exceeds that of either of the preceding periods. To sum up, I distinguish three great periods of Greek Philosophy. The philosophy of the first is Physics, or more accurately a physical dogmatism; it 182 INTRODUCTION. is physical, because it primarily seeks to explain natural phenomena from their natural causes, without making any definite discrimination of spiritual and corporeal in things, or the causes of things; it is a dogmatism, be- cause it directly pursues the knowledge of the objective, without any previous enquiry into the conception, pos- sibility, and conditions of knowledge. In Sophistic, this attitude of thought to the external world is at an end, man's capacity for the knowledge of the real is called in question, philosophic interest is averted from mature, and the necessity of discovering a higher principle of truth on the soil of human consciousness makes itself felt. Socrates answers the demand in declaring the cognition of the concept the only way to true knowledge and true virtue; from which Plato further concludes, that only pure concepts can be true reality ; he establishes this principle dialectically in conflict with ordinary presentative opinion, and deve- lops it in a system embracing Dialectic, Physics, and Ethics. Finally, Aristotle discovers the concept in the phenomena themselves, as their essence and entelechy, carries it in the most comprehensive manner into all the spheres of the actual, and establishes the prin- ciples of the scientific method on a firm basis for after times. In place of the former one-sided philosophy of nature there thus appears in the second period a philo- \ sophy of the concept, founded by Socrates and perfected by Aristotle. But since the idea is thus opposed to the phenomenon, since a full essential Being is ascribed to the idea, and only an imperfect Being to the pheno- menon, a dualism arises, which appears indeed more * N GENERAL SUMMA R Y. 183 glaring and irreconcilable in Plato, but which even Aristotle is unable to overcome either in principle or Th" result; for he, too, begins with the opposition of & form and material, and ends with..that of God and the world, of spiritual and sensible. Only the spirit in its absoluteness, directed to no external object and suf- ficing to itself, is perfect and infinite; that which is external to it cannot increase this inner perfection or be otherwise than valueless and indifferent for it. So, too, the human spirit ought to seek its unqualified satisfaction in itself, and in its independence of every- thing external. Thought in pursuing this tendency withdraws from the object into itself, and the second period of Greek Philosophy passes into the third. Or to state the same more succinctly. The spirit, we might say, is, during the first stage of Greek thought, immediately present to itself in the natural object; in the second it separates itself from the natural object, that it may attain a higher truth in the thought of the super-sensible object, iTuring third it asserts itself in its subjectivity, in opposition to the object, as \--~ supreme and unconditioned. The stand-point, however, of the Greek world is thereby abandoned, while at the same time no deeper reconciliation of the opposing elements is possible on Greek soil. Thought being thus separated from the actual, loses its content, and becomes involved in a contradiction, for it maintains subjectivity to be the final and highest form of being, and yet opposes to it the Absolute in unattainable transcendency. To this contradiction Greek Philosophy | ultimately succumbed. 184 THE PRE-SOCRATIC PHILOSOPHY. FIRST PERIOD. THE PRE-SOCRATIC PHILOSOPHY. INTRODUCTION. CHARACTER AND DEVELOPMENT OF PHILOSOPHY DURING THE FIRST PERIOD. Four schools are usually distinguished in the pre- Socratic period—the Ionic, the Pythagorean, the Eleatic, and the Sophistic. The character and internal relation of these schools are determined, partly accord- ing to the scope, partly according to the spirit of their enquiries. In regard to the former, the distinctive peculiarity of the pre-Socratic period is marked in the isolation of the three branches which were afterwards united in Greek Philosophy: by the Ionians, we are told, Physics were exclusively developed; by the Pytha- goreans, Ethics; by the Eleatics, Dialectic : in Sophistic, we are taught to see the decline and fall of this ex- clusive science, and the indirect preparation for a more comprehensive science." This difference of scientific tendency is then brought into connection with the in- 1 Schleiermacher, Gesch. der Phil. p. 18 sq., 51 sq.; Ritter, view, and adopted the following division : 1. The older Ionian Gesch. der Phil. i. 189 sqq.; Bran- dis, Gesch. der Gr.-Röm. Phil. i. 42 sqq.; Fichte's Zeitschr, für Phi- los. xiii. (1844) p. 131 sqq. In his Gesch. der Entwicklungen d. Griech. Phil. (i. 40), which appeared sub- sequently, Brandis abandoned this º JPhysics, including the Heracleitean doctrine. 2. The Eleatics. 3. The attempts to reconcile the opposition of Being and Becoming (Empe- docles, Anaxagoras, and the Ato- mists). 4. The Pythagorean doc- trine. 5. Sophistic. PHYSICS, ETHICS, DIALECTIC. 185 trinsic difference between the Ionic and Doric tribes: 1 some writers” making this the basis of their whole theory of ancient Philosophy, and deriving from the particular traits of the Ionic and Doric character, the philosophic opposition of a realistic and an idealistic theory of the world. How the further division of our period is then connected with this point of view has been shown already. These differences, however, are by no means so real or so deeply seated as is here presupposed. Whether the Pythagorean doctrine was essentially ethical, and the Eleatic, dialectical in character, or whether these elements can be regarded as determining the two systems, we shall presently enquire; and we shall find that they, as much as any part of the pre-Socratic Philosophy, arose from the inclimation of natural science to investigate the essence of things, and especially of natural phenomena. Aristotle makes the general assertion that with Socrates, dialectical and ethical enquiries began, and physical enquiries were discontinued.” Hermann is, therefore, quite justified * Cf. Schleiermacher, loc. cit., p. 18 sq. ‘Among the Ionians,’ he says, “the Being of things in man is the predominant interest, and calm contemplation finds its ex- pression in Epic poetry. Among the Dorians the Being of man in things predominates; man strives against things, asserts his inde- pendence in regard to them, and proclaims himself as a unity in Lyric poetry. Hence the develop- ment of Physics by the Ionians, and of Ethics by the Pythagoreans. As Dialectic, is equally opposed to the two branches of Philosophy, so the Eleatics are neither Ionians nor Dorians, but a union of the two ; they are Ionian by birth, and Dorian by language.” Ritter ex- presses similar opinions, loc. cit. Ritter shares them to some extent (p. 47), and in a less degree, Brandis, p. 47. * Ast, Rixner, Braniss (vide Supra, p. 166 sqq.) Petersen, Phi- lologisch, histor. Studien, p. 1 sqq.; Hermann, Geschichte und System des Plato, i. 141 sq., 160; cf. Böckh's excellent remarks on this subject, Philolaus, p. 39 sqq. * Pará. Amin. i. 1, 642 a, 24: among the earlier philoso- phers there are only scattered fore- 186 THE PRE-SOCRATIC PHILOSOPHY, in saying that it is impossible to maintain, even from the stand-point of the ancient thinkers, that Dialectics, Physics and Ethics came into existence together, and were of equal importance contemporaneously, for there could have been no question of any leading ethical principle until the preponderance of spirit over matter had been recognised ; nor could Dialectic, as such, have been consciously employed, before form in contrast with matter had vindicated its greater affinity to spirit. The object of all philosophic investigation, he con- tinues, in its commencement was nature, and if even enquiry was incidentally carried into other spheres, the standard which it applied, being originally taken from natural science, remained foreign to those spheres. We are, therefore, merely importing our own stand-point into the history of the earliest philosophic systems, in ascribing a dialectic character to one, an ethical character to another, a physiological character to a third; in describing this system as materialistic, and that as formalistic, while all in truth pursue the same end, only in different ways." The whole pre-Socratic Philosophy is in its aim and content a philosophy of nature, and though ethical or dialectical conceptions may appear here and there in it, this never happens to such an extent, nor is any system sufficiently dis- casts of the conception of formal causes: ałrtov Šē too u%) éA6eiv rob: Trpoyevertépous étrl Tov tpétrov too- rov, 3rt to rí ºv sival ical roëptoraoréal Thy oiglav oil, ºv, &AA’ #paro uév Amuákpitos trpºros, &s owic &vayicat- ov 8& rſ, pvaukň 6eaſ-ovoptg, &AA’ ékpepópevos ūr' airrot row trpdypatos, étrl Xokpárovs 6% rooto wºv müşh9m, to 6% (mtéïv tá trepl púgews éamée, trpos 3& Thu Xphoruov &perhu kal Thu troxiruchy &rékatvav of pixogo- q,00vres. • * Gesch, und Syst, d. Plato, i. 140 sq. PHYSICS, ETHICS, DIALECTIC 187 tinguished in this respect from all the others, that we can properly characterise it as dialectical or ethical. This result must at once cause us to mistrust any º of a realistic and an idealistic philo- ophy. True idealism can only exist where the spiritual garded as the more primitive of the two. In that sense, for example, Plato, Leibniz and Fichte are idealists. Where this is the case, there always arises the necessity for making the spiritual as such the object of enquiry; Dialectic, Psychology, Ethics are separated from natural hilosophy. If, therefore, neither of these sciences ttained a separate development previous to Socrates, it roves that the definite discrimination of the spiritual rom the sensible, and the derivation of the sensible rom the spiritual—in which philosophic idealism con- ists—was still alien to this period. Neither the Pytha- oreans nor the Eleatics are, in reality, idealists; at my rate they are not more so than other philosophers, ho are assigned to the realistic division. In com- arison with the older Ionic school, we find, indeed, hat they attempt to get beyond the sensible pheno- enon; instead of seeking the essence of all things ike their predecessors in a corporeak substratum, the Py- hagoreans sought it in Number, the Eleatics in Being ithout further determination. But the two systems o not advance equally far in this direction ; for if the ythagoreans give to Number as the universal form of he sensible, the same position and significance as the leatics subsequently to Parmenides give to the abstract oncept of Being, they stop greatly short of the Eleatics is consciously distinguished from the sensible, and re-_ 188 THE PRE-SOCRATION PHILOSOPHY. in the abstraction of the qualities of the sensible ph nomenon. It would, therefore, be more correct to spea of three philosophic tendencies instead of two : a real istic, an idealistic, and an intermediate tendency. W have really, however, no right to describe the Italian philosophers as Idealists. For although their first principle is, according to our ideas, incorporeal, the precise discrimination of spiritual from corporeal is with them entirely wanting. Neither the Pythagorear Number, nor the Eleatic One, is a spiritual essence distinct from the sensible, like the Platonic ideas; or the contrary, these philosophers maintain that sensible things are according to their true essence, numbers; o that they are one invariable substance." Number and Being are the substance of the bodies themselves, the matter of which the bodies consist, and for this reason they are apprehended sensuously. Conceptions o number and conceptions of magnitude interpenetrat one another with the Pythagoreans; numbers becom something extended; and among the Eleatics, eve Parmenides describes Being as the substance which fill space. So in the further development of the system there is a confusion of spiritual and corporeal. Th Pythagoreans declare bodies to be numbers: but virtu friendship and the soul are also numbers, or numeric proportions; may, the soul itself is regarded as a co poreal thing.” Similarly, Parmenides says,” that reaso * This may be in itself a con- held by the ancient philosophers. tradiction (as Steinhart points out * Aristotle, De An. i. 2, 404 in the Hall. Allg. Literature. 1845, 17. Wide infra, Pythagoreans. Nov. p. 891), but it does not fol- * That Parmenides says th low that it may not have been only in the 'second part of h REALISM AND IDEALISM. 189 in man depends upon the admixture of his bodily parts, for the body and the thinking principle are one and the same ; even the celebrated proposition about the unity of thought and Being has not the same meaning. ith him as in modern—systems—It cannot be, as, Ribbing calls it,” “the principle of idealism, for it is hot derived from the thi iſldu Kill garises fro Thought, but conversely from the theorem that Thought alſº under the conception of Being; in the former ase only could it be idealistic, in the latter it must be onsidered realistic. Again, when Parmenides connects is Physics with his doctrine of Being, he parallels he antithesis of Being and non-Being, not with the ntithesis of spiritual and corporeal, but with that f light and darkness. Aristotle asserts that the ythagoreans presuppose, like the other natural philo- ophers, that the sensible world embraces all reality;” e makes them to differ from Plato in that they hold umbers to be the things themselves, whereas Plato istinguishes the ideas from things; * he describes the ythagorean Number, notwithstanding its incorpore- lity, as a material principle.” He includes Parmenides, tirely to the explanation of nature ël Ll2 allSé OIC oem proves nothing against the bove application of the words. If e had been clearly conscious of e difference between spiritual and pressed himself even in his hypo- etical explanation of phenomena. * W. 94 sqq. * Genet. Darst. der platon. eenlehre, i. 378, cf. 28 sq. * Metaph. i. 8, 989 b, 29 sqq. "he Pythagoreans, it is true, admit on-sensible principles, but they evertheless confine themselves en- rporeal, he would not thus have às àuoMo'youvres toſs &AAois puorio- Aóyous, Šti Tô ye by roor’ or riv ãorov airømtöv čoºri kai trepietamºpe v 6 kaxočaevos oëpavós. * Metaph. i. 6, 987 b, 25 sqq. * Metaph. i. 5, 989 a, 15: ‘patvout at 6% ral oirot Tov čplbubv voutgovres àpx?iv efval kal &s 5Amy toſs of ori, kal &s tra.0m Te Kal éðels. Ibid. b, 6: éoticagº .. 6° às év iſºms etàel r& grouxeia. Tørretv. čk rotºrov Y&p Ös évvirapxávrov avved tâval cal tretradio 9at paal rºw oia'tav. 190 THE PRE-SOCRATIC PHILOSOPHY. with Protagoras, Democritus and Empedocles, among those who held that the sensible only is the real; and it is from this source that he derives the Eleatic theory of the sensible world.” On all these points we must allow him to be fully justified. The Italian philo- sophers likewise commence with an enquiry into the essence and grounds of sensible phenomena; and the seek for these in that which underlies things, and is not perceptible to sense. In so doing, they transcen indeed the ancient Ionian Physics, but not the later systems of natural philosophy. That the true essenc of things is to be apprehended not by the senses, but by the understanding alone, is also taught by Hera cleitus, Empedocles, Anaxagoras, and the Atomisti Philosophy. They, too, hold that the ground of th sensible lies in the not-sensible. Democritus himself thorough materialist as he was, has no other definitio for matter than the Eleatic conception of Being; Hera cleitus considers the law and relation of the whole t be alone the permanent element in phenomena; Anaxa goras is the first who distinguishes spirit clearly an definitely from matter, and he is for that reason, in well-known passage of Aristotle, placed far above al his predecessors.” If, therefore, the opposition of Ma * Metaph. iv. 5, 1010 a. 1 (after speaking of Protagoras, De- mocritus, Empedocles, and Parme- nides): ałrtov Šē ràs 56&ms rotºrous, 3rt repl wºv táv čvrov thu &A#6slav éorkómovy, rô 5’ 8vra. ÖréAaflov sivat T& aio 6mtā uávov. 2 De Coelo, iii. 1, 298 b, 21 ff.: &ceivot 5 [of trept MéAlgorów re ka? IIappeviðmw) ātā ºrb unbºy uév &AA trap. Thu Tów aio.6m rôv oãortav Štro Aapabávelv eival, rotatºras Sé riva [sc. &Kuvárovs] voioſal trpárol pāore, efirep #otal tis yuáo is 3 ppóvmorus oiſta aethveykav ćr raûra roës éke?6ev Aóryovs. * Metaph. i. 3,984 b, 15: vojv 8 tus sitàv éveſval ka0árep &v rois Cºol IONIANS AND DORIANS. 191 terialism and Idealism is to furnish a principle of division for ancient philosophy, this division must be limited not only, as Braniss maintains, to the epoch pre- ceding Anaxagoras, but preceding Heracleitus. Even then, strictly speaking, it is not applicable, nor does it take account of the intermediate position of the Pythagoreans between the Ionians and the Eleatics. This double tendency of philosophic thought is also said to correspond with the opposition of the Ionic and Doric elements, and, accordingly, all the philosophers until the time of Socrates, or rather Anaxagoras, are assigned either to an Ionic or a Doric series of develop- ment. This division is certainly more exact than that of some of the ancient historians," who divided the whole of Greek Philosophy into Ionian and Italian. But even in regard to the most ancient schools, so far as their internal relations have to be represented, such a division can hardly be carried out. Among the Dorians, Braniss counts Pherecydes, the Pythagoreans, the Eleatics and Empedocles. Ast makes the addition of Leucippus and Democritus. Now it is difficult to see how Pherecydes can be placed among the Dorians, and the same may be said of Democritus, and probably kal év tº pörel rov ałrtov roi, kóguov kal Tästä;eas trägms oiovvi'povépávm trap' eikh Aéyovras rows trpátepov. * Diogenes, i. 13; that he is here following older authorities is clear (as Brandis loc. cit. p. 43 shows) from the fact of the schools he mentions only coming down to the time of Clitomachus (129-110 B.C.) cf. Augustine. Civ. Dei, viii. 2; the Aristotelian Scholiast, Schol. in Arist., 323, a, 36, and the Pseudo- Galen (Hist. Phil. c. 2, p. 228) Kühn ; this last further divides the Italian philosophers into Pythago- reans and Eleatics, and so far agrees with the theory of three schools— Italian, Ionian, and Eleatic (Cle- mens, Al. Strom. i. 300 c.) The re- view of the earlier philosophers in Aristotle's first book of Metaphysics follows the order of dogmatic points of view, and would be out of place in regard to our present purpose. 192 THE PRE-SOCRATIC PHILOSOPHY. of Leucippus. Moreover, the founder of Pythagorism was by birth an Ionian of Asia Minor; and though the Doric spirit manifests itself in his mode of life, his philosophy seems to betray the influence of the Ionian Physics. Empedocles was born, it is true, in a Doric colony; but the language of his poem is that of the Ionian epos. The Eleatic School was founded by an Ionian of Asia Minor, it received its final development in an Ionian settlement, and in the person of one of its last great representatives, Melissus, it returned to Asia Minor." There remain, therefore, of pure Dorians, only the Pythagoreans, with the exception of the founder of the school, and, if we will, Empedocles. It has been said that it is not necessary that the philosophers of either division should belong to it also by birth; * and this condition certainly ought not to be insisted on in the case of every individual. But it is surely indis- pensable with regard to each division as a whole; all their members should be either Doric or Ionic, if not by birth, at least by education. Instead of this, we find more than half the so-called Dorian philosophers, not only belonging by birth and extraction to the Ionian race, but receiving their education from it, through national customs, civil institutions, and what is especially important, language. Under these cir- cumstances, differences of tribe are of very secondary moment. They may have influenced the direction of 1 Petersen (Philol. hist. Stu- has been shown by Hermann, dien, p. 15) also thinks he can dis- Zeitschrift für Alterthumsw., 1834, cover an AEolic element in the p. 298. Eleatics. That there is not the * Braniss, loc. cit. p. 103. slightest ground for this conjecture IONIANS AND DORIANS, 193 thought, but cannot be regarded as having determined it." In the ulterior development of these two series, the Ionian and the Dorian, Braniss opposes Thales to Pherecydes, Anaximander to Pythagoras, Anaximenes to Xenophanes, Heracleitus to Parmenides, Diogenes of Apollonia to Empedocles. Such a construction, how- ever, does great violence to the historical character and relation of these men. On the Ionian side, it is incor- rect to place Heracleitus beside the earlier philosophers of that school, for he does not stand in a relation of simple progression to Anaximenes, as Anaximenes stands to Anaximander. Diogenes, on the other hand, was entirely uninfluenced by the philosophy of Hera- cleitus; we cannot, therefore, say with Braniss (p. 128) that he was expressly related to that philosopher, and that he summed up the result of the whole Ionic development. Braniss is even more arbitrary in his treatment of the Dorians. In the first place, Phere- cydes, as has already been said (p. 89 sq.), is not, pro- perly speaking, a philosopher, still less is he a Doric or idealistic philosopher; for what we know of him bears a close relation to the old Hesiodic-Orphic cosmogony, the mythic precursor of the Ionic Physics. Even the dis- crimination of organising force from matter, on which Braniss lays so much stress (p. 108) had been brought forward in a mythic manner by Hesiod, and in a more definite and philosophic form by Anaxagoras the Ionian; whereas it is entirely wanting in the Italian Eleatics,” * So Ritter also decides,i. 191 sq. as plastic force; but this second * The second part of Parme- part speaks only from the point of nides' poem (v. 131) mentions Eros view of ordinary opinion. WOL. I. O 194 THE PRE-SOCRATIC PHILOSOPHY, and is of doubtful value among the Pythagoreans. It is true that the belief in the transmigration of souls was shared by Pherecydes with Pythagoras, but this isolated doctrine, which is rather religious than philosophic, cannot be taken as decisive for the position of Phere- cydes in history. Further, if we connect Xenophanes with Pythagoras, as Parmenides is connected with Xenophanes, or Anaximenes with Anaximander, we ignore the internal difference which exists between the Eleatic stand-point and the Pythagorean. It is manifestly improper to treat a doctrine which has a principle of its own, essentially distinct from the Pythagorean principle, and which developed itself in a separate school, as a mere continuation of Pytha- gorism. Again, as we shall presently show, to place Empedocles exclusively in the Pythagorean-Eleatic series is to close our eyes to all aspects of the question but one. Lastly, what right has Braniss to pass over the later development of Pythagorism accomplished by Philolaus and Archytas; and the development of the Eleatic doctrine effected by Zeno and Melissus, while he recognises men like Anaximenes and Diogenes of Apollonia, who were in no way more important, as representatives of particular stages of development P His scheme is a Procrustean bed for historical pheno- mena, and the Doric Philosophy suffers doubly. At the one end it is produced beyond its natural propor- tions, and at the other it is denuded of members which are essentially part of its growth. The same holds good of Petersen’s' earlier attempt * Philol. hist. Stud. pp. 1–40. p. 285 sqq.), from whom the abov On the other hand. cf. Hermann remarks are partly taken. - . (Zeitschr, für Alterthumsw., 1834, , IONIANS AND DORIANS. 195. to determine the historical relation of the pre-Socratic schools. Here, too, the general principle is the oppo- sition of realism, or rather materialism, and idealism. This opposition developes itself in three sections, each of which is again subdivided into two parts: first, the opposing elements stand over against one another in sharp contrast; and secondly, there arise various at- tempts to conciliate them, which, however, accomplish no real adjustment, but still incline to one or other of the two sides. In the first section, the oppositions begin to develop themselves—the mathematical idealism of the Doric Pythagoreans confronts the hylozoistic materialism of the older Ionians (Thales, Anaximander, Anaximenes, Heracleitus and Diogenes). A reconcilia- tion is next attempted on the idealistic side by the Eleatics; on the materialistic by the physician Elothales of Cos, his son Epicharmus and Alcmaeon. In the second section, the contrasts become more marked; we encounter, on the one hand, pure materialism, in the Atomists; on the other, pure idealism in the later Pythagoreans, Hippasus, CEnopides, Hippo, Ocellus, Timaeus, and Archytas. Between these two, we find on the idealistic side the pantheism of Empedoeles, on the materialistic side the dualism of Anaxagoras. In the third and last section both tendencies pushed to excess equally lead to the destruction of Philosophy through the scepticism of the Sophists. Thus one uniform scheme is undoubtedly carried through the whole pre- Socratic Philosophy, but it is a scheme that scarcely corresponds with the actual order of history. It is unwarrantable, as we have just seen, to divide the philo- O 2 196 THE PRE-SOCRATIC PHILOSOPHY. sophers of this period into materialists, or realists, and idealists. Nor can we, for reasons to be stated more fully later on, admit the propriety of placing Hera- cleitus in one category with the ancient Ionians, among the materialists. On the other hand, we must demur to the separation of the later Pythagoreans from the earlier; because the so-called fragments of their writings, which alone would justify it, are certainly to be re- garded as forgeries of the neo-Pythagoreans. How the Eleatics can be assigned to an intermediate position between the Ionians and Pythagoreans, whereas they carried to the utmost that abstraction from the sensible phenomena which the Pythagoreans had begun, it is difficult to say, nor can we concur in opposing to the Eleatics, Elothales, Epicharmus, and Alcmaeon as ma- terialists with incipient dualism. These men were not, indeed, systematic philosophers; but any isolated philo- sophic sentences they adopted seem to have been chiefly derived from the Pythagoreans and Eleatic doctrines. Lastly, how can Empedocles be considered an idealist ; and Anaxagoras with his theory of votis a materialist P and how can the system of Empedoeles, with its six primitive essenees, of which four were of a corporeal kind, be described as pantheism, and more particularly as idealistic pantheism P' * Steinhart is allied with Bra- ism, but a mixture of the Doric and miss and Petersen (Allg. Encykl. v. Ionic elements. The Ionic Philo- Ersch. und Grube, Art. “Ionische sophy he considers to have had Schule,” Sect. 2, vol. xxii. 457. He three stages of development. In distinguishes, like them, the Ionic Thales, Anaximander, and Anaxi- and Doric Philosophy; in the case menes, he says, we first find obscure of the Pythagoreans, however, and and scattered intimations of a still more in that of the Eleatics, spiritual power that rules in the what he finds is not pure Dorian- world. In Heracleitus, Diogenes, GENERAL CHARACTERISTICS. 197 The foregoing discussions have now paved the way for a positive determination of the character and course of philosophic development during our first period. I have characterised the Philosophy of that period (irre- spectively for the present of Sophistic), as a philosophy of nature. It is so by virtue of the object which oc- cupies it: not that it limits itself exclusively to nature in the narrower sense, that is to say, to the corporeal, and the forces unconsciously working in the corporeal; for such a limit of its sphere would necessarily presup- pose a discrimination of spiritual and corporeal which does not as yet exist. But it is for the most part occupied with external phenomena; the spiritual, so far as that domain is touched, is regarded from the same point of view as the corporeal; and consequently there can be no independent development of Ethics and Dialectic. All reality is included under the conception of Nature, and is treated as a homogeneous mass, and since that which is perceptible to the senses always forces itself first upon our observation, it is natural that everything should at first be derived from those prin- ciples which appear most adapted to explain sensible existence. The intuition of nature is thus the starting- and above all in Anaxagoras, the recognition of the spiritual princi- ple becomes constantly clearer. to me a doubtful proceeding to separate Empedocles from the Atomists and Anaxagoras, to whom Lastly, Leucippus and Lemocritus deny the spiritual principle in a conscious manner, and thus prepare the destruction of this exclusively physical philosophy. Leaving out of the question the opposition of the Doric and Ionic elements, the importance of which Steinhart him- self considerably restricts, it seems he is so nearly related ; nor can I convince myself that the Atomistic Philosophy had its origin in a reac- tion against the theory of a world- forming spirit, and is later in its origin than the Anaxagorean phy- sics. And lastly, as will presently appear, I cannot altogether agree with Steinhart's view of Diogenes. 198 - THE PRE-SOCRATIC SCHOOLS: point of the earliest philosophy, and even when imma- terial principles are admitted, it is evident that they have been attained through reflection on the data fur- mished by the senses, not through observation of spiritual ife. The Pythagorean doctrine of numbers, for in- stance, is immediately connected with the perception of regularity in the relations of tones, in the distances and movements of the heavenly bodies; and the doctrine of Anaxagoras of the uoils which forms the World has refer- ence primarily to the Wise organisation of the world. and especially to the order of the celestial system. Even the Eleatic theses of the unity and unchange- ableness of Being are not arrived at by opposing the spiritual as a higher reality to the sensible pheno- mena; but by eliminating from the sensible all that seems to involve a contradiction, and by conceiving the corporeal or the plenum in an entirely abstract manner. Here too, therefore, it is, generally speaking, mature with which Philosophy is concerned. To this its object, thought still stands in an imme- diate relation, and considers the material investigation of nature as its first and only problem. The knowledge of the object is not as yet dependent on the self-know- ledge of the thinking subject, on a definite conscious- ness of the nature and conditions of knowing; on the discrimination of scientific cognition and unscientific pre- sentation. This discrimination is constantly spoken of from the time of Heracleitus and Parmenides, but it appears, not as the basis, but only as a consequence of the enquiry into the nature of things. Parmenides denies the trustworthiness of the sensuous perception, GENERALI, CHARACTERISTICS. 199 because it shows us an immoveable Being; Empedocles, because it makes the union and separation of material substances appear as a process of becoming and passing away; Democritus and Anaxagoras, because it cannot reveal the primitive constituents of things. We find in these philosophers no definite principles as to the nature of knowledge which might serve to regulate objective enquiry, in the way that the Socratic demand for knowledge based on conceptions probably served Plato: and though Parmenides and Empedocles in their didactic poems exhort us to the thoughtful con- sideration of things, and withdrawal from the senses, they do so almost always in an exceedingly vague manner; and it does not follow because such a discrimi- nation finds place in their poems, that in their systems it may not be the consequence instead of the presuppo- sition of their metaphysic. Although, therefore, their metaphysic laid the foundation for the after develop- ment of the theory of knowledge, it is not itself, as yet, a theory of knowledge. The pre-Socratic Philºsophy is, as to its form, a dogmatism: thought, fully believing in its own veracity, applies itself directly to the object; and the objective view of the world first gives rise to --~~~ the propositions concerning the nature of knowledge which prepare the way for the later Philosophy of sº ceptions. If we ask, lastly, what are the philosophic results of the first period, we find, as has already been pointed out, that the pre-Socratic systems attempted no accu- rate discrimination between the spiritual and the cor- poreal. The early Ionian jº. everything 200 THE PRE-SOCRATIC PHILOSOPHY. from matter, which they held to be moved and animated by its own inherent force. The Pythagoreans substitute number for matter; the Eleatics, Being, regarded as in- variable Unity: but neither of them, as we have already remarked, distinguished the incorporeal principles as to their essential nature, from the corporeal phenomenon. Consequently, the incorporeal principles are themselves apprehended materially, and so in man, soul and body, ethical and physical, are considered from the same points of view. This confusion is particularly striking in Heracleitus, for in his conception of everiving fire he directly unites primitive matter with motive force and the law of the universe. The Atomistic philoso- phy is from the outset directed to a strictly material explanation of nature, and therefore neither within man nor without him does it recognise any immaterial element. Even Empedocles cannot have apprehended his moving forces in a purely intellectual manner, for he treats them precisely like the corporeal elements with which they are mingled in things; so too in man the spiritual intermingles with the corporeal; blood is the faculty of thought. Anaxagoras was the first to teach definitely that the spirit is unmixed with any material element ; but in Anaxagoras we reach the limit of the ancient Philosophy of Nature. Moreover, ~according to him, the world-forming spirit operates merely as a force of nature, and is represented in a half sensible form as a more subtle kind of matter. This particular example, therefore, cannot affect our previous judgment of the pre-Socratic Philosophy so far as its general and predominant tendency is concerned. GENERAL CHARACTERISTICS. 201 All these traits lead us to recognise as the charac- teristic peculiarity of the first period, a preponderance of natural research over introspective reflection ; an absorp= fion with the outer world which prevents thought from - bestowing separate study on any object besides nature, from distinguishing the spiritual from the corporeal in an exact and definite manner; from seeking out the form and the laws of scientific procedure for themselves. Overborne by external impressions, man at first feels himself a part of nature, he therefore knows no higher problem for his thought than the investigation of nature, he applies himself to this problem, impartially and directly, without stopping previously to enquire into the subjective conditions of knowledge; and even when his investigation of nature itself carries him be- yond the sensible phenomena as such, yet he does not advance beyond nature considered as a whole, to an ideal Being, which has its import and its subsistence in itself. Behind the sensible phenomena, forces and substances are indeed sought which cannot be perceived by the senses; but the effects of these forces are the things of nature, the essences not apprehended by sense are the substance of the sensible itself, and no- thing besides; a spiritual world side by side with the material world has not yet been discovered. - How far this description applies also to Sophistic we have already seen. The interest of natural research and the belief in the truth of our presentments are now at an end, but no new road to knowledge and higher reality is as yet pointed out ; and far from opposing the kingdom of the spirit to nature, the Sophists regard 202 THE PRE-SOCRATIC PHILOSOPHY, man himself as a merely sensuous being. Although, therefore, the pre-Socratic natural philosophy is abolished in Sophistic, Sophistic like its predecessors knows of nothing higher than Nature, and has no other material to work on ; the change consists not in oppos- ing a new form of science to a previous form, but in making use of the existing elements, particularly the Eleatic and Heracleitean doctrines, to introduce doubt into scientific consciousness, and to destroy belief in the possibility of knowledge. Thus we are compelled, by the results of our in- vestigation, to bring the three oldest schools of Philo- sophy—the Ionian, the Pythagorean, and the Eleatic– into a closer connection than has hitherto been cus- tomary. They are not only very near to each other in respect to time, but are much more alike in their scientific character than might at first sight be sup- posed. While they agree with the whole of the early Philosophy in directing their enquiries to the explana- tion of nature, this tendency is in their case more particularly shown in a search for the substantial ground of things: in demanding what things are in their proper essence, and of what they consist; the problem of the explanation of Becoming, and passing away, of the movement and multiplicity of phenomena is not as yet distinctly grasped. Thales makes all things originate and consist in water, Anaximander in infinite matter, Anaximenes in air; the Pythagoreans say that everything is Number; the Eleatics that the All is one invariable Being. Now it is true that the Elea- tics alone, and they only subsequently to Parmenides, GENERAL CHARACTERISTICS. 203 denied movement and Becoming, whereas the Ionians and the Pythagoreans minutely describe the formation of the world. But they neither of them propounded the question of the possibility of Becoming and of divided Being in this general manner, nor in the estab- lishment of their principles did they attempt particular definitions in regard to it. The Ionians tell us that the primitive matter changes; that from matter, originally one, contrary elements were separated and combined in various relations to form a world. The Pythagoreans say that magnitudes are derived from numbers, and from magnitudes, bodies; but on what this process was based, how it came about that matter was moved and transmuted, that numbers produced something other than themselves, they make no scientific attempt to explain. What they seek is not so much to explain phenomena from general principles, as to reduce phe-Î nomena to their first principles. Their scientific in- terest is concerned rather with the identical essence of things, the substance of which all things consist, than with the multiplicity of the phenomena and the causes of that multiplicity. When the Eleatics, there- fore, entirely denied the Becoming and the Many they merely called in question an unproved presupposition of their predecessors; and in apprehending all reality as a unity absolutely excluding multiplicity, they only carried out more perfectly the tendency of the two older Schools. Heracleitus was the first to see in motion, change, and separation, the fundamental quality of the primitive essence; and the polemic of Parmenides first occasioned Philosophy to enquire more H # f : { | , º * * * . . . s l wº- tº- * & “ W | 204 THE PRE-SOCRATIC PHILOSOPHY. thoroughly into the possibility of Becoming." With Heracleitus, then, philosophic development takes a new direction: the three older systems, on the contrary, fall together under the same class, inasmuch as they are all satisfied with the intuition of the substance of which things consist, without expressly seeking the cause of multiplicity and change, as such. This substance was sought by the Ionians in a corporeal matter, by the Pythagoreans in number, by the Eleaties in Being as such. By the first it was apprehended sensuously, by the second mathematically, by the third metaphysi- cally; but these differences only show us the gradual development of the same tendency in a progression from the concrete to the abstract ; for number and mathe- matical form are a middle term between the sensible and pure thought; and were afterwards regarded, by Plato especially, as their proper connecting link. The turning-point which I here adopt in the development of the pre-Socratic Philosophy has been already remarked by other historians in respect of the Ionian schools. On this ground Schleiermacher” first distinguished two periods in the Ionian Philosophy, the *l * From this point of view it conception of Being and Becoming. might seem preferable to commence But the connection between Parme- the second section of the first period nides and Xenophanes would thus with Parmenides, as well as Hera- be broken ; and as the doctrine of cleitus, as my critic in the Reperto. Parmenides, in spite of all its his- rium of Gersdorf (1844, H. 22, p. torical and scientific importance, 335) proposes, seeing that up to the approximates closely in its content time of these two philosophers (as and tendency to the earlier sys- e observes) the question, whence tems, it appears on the whole bet- all things arose, had been answered ter to make Heracleitus alone the by theories of matter, and that starting-point of the second section. i Heracleitus and Parmenides were * Gesch. der Phil. (Worl. v. J. the first to enquire concerning the 1812) p. 33. EARLIER AND LATER PHYSICISTS. 205 second of which begins with Heracleitus. Between this philosopher and his predecessors, he says, there is a considerable chronological gap, probably in consequence of the interruption occasioned to philosophic pursuits by the disturbances in Ionia. Moreover, while the three most ancient Ionians came from Miletus, Philo- sophy now spreads itself geographically over a much wider sphere. Also, in the content of his philosophy, Heracleitus rises far above the earlier physicists, so that he may, perhaps, have derived little from them. Ritter, too, acknowledges that Heracleitus differs in many respects from the older Ionians, and that his theory of the universal force of nature places him quite in a separate order from them. Brandis,” in still closer agreement with Schleiermacher, holds that with Heracleitus commences a new period in the de- velopment of the Ionian Philosophy, to which, besides Heracleitus, Empedocles, Anaxagoras, Leucippus, De- mocritus, Diogenes, and Archelaus likewise belong ; all these being distinguished from the earlier philo- sophers by their more scientific attempts to derive the multiplicity of particulars from a primitive cause, by their more explicit recognition or denial of the dis- tinction between spirit and matter, as also of a Divinity that forms the world; and by their common endeavour to establish the reality of particulars and their varia- tions in opposition to the doctrine of the Eleatic One. These remarks are quite true, and only, perhaps, open to question with regard to Diogenes of Apollonia. But it • Gesch. der Phil. 242, 248; * Gr.-röm. Phil. i. 149. Ion. Phil. 65. 206 THE PRE-SOCRATIC PHILOSOPHY, is not enough to make this difference the dividing-line between two classes of Ionic physiologists; it is deeply rooted in the whole of the pre-Socratic Philosophy. Neither the doctrine of Empedocles, nor that of Anaxa- goras, nor that of the Atomists can be explained by the ; development of the Ionian physiology as such ; their relation to the Eleatics is not the merely negative rela- i tion of disallowing the denial of Reality, Becoming, and f Multiplicity; they positively learned a good deal from the Eleatic school. They all acknowledge the great principle of the system of Parmenides, that there is no Becoming or passing away in the strict sense of the | terms; consequently they all explain phenomena from the combination and separation of material elements, and \ they in part borrow their concept of Being directly from the Eleatic metaphysics. They ought, therefore, to be placed after the Eleatic school, and not before it. In regard to Heracleitus, it is less certain whether, or how far, he concerned himself with the beginnings of the Eleatic Philosophy; in point of fact, however, his posi- tion is not only entirely antagonistic to the Eleatics, but he may generally be said to enter upon a new course altogether divergent from that hitherto followed. In denying all fixedness in the constitution of things, and recognising the law of their variability as the only per- manent element in them, he declares the futility of the previous science which made matter and substance the chief object of enquiry; and asserts the investigation of the causes and laws which determine Becoming and Change to be the true problem of Philosophy. Thus, although the question as to the essence and material EARLIER AND LATER PHYSICISTs. 207 substance of things was not overlooked by Hera- cleitus and his followers, any more than the account of the formation of the world was omitted by the Ionians and Pythagoreans, the two elements stand with each of them in a very different relation. In the one case, the enquiry as to the substance of things is the main point, and the notions about their origin are dependent upon the answer given to this question ; in the other, th chief question is that of the causes of Becoming and Change, and the manner of conceiving the original substance of Being depends upon the determinations which appear necessary to the philosopher to explain Becoming and Change. The Ionians make things arise out of the rarefaction and condensation of a primitive matter, because this best adapts itself to their motion of primitive matter; the Pythagoreans hold to a mathematical construction, because they reduce every- thing to number; the Eleatics deny Becoming and Motion, because they find the essence of things in Being alone. On the contrary, Heracleitus makes fire the primitive matter, because on this theory only can he explain the flux of all things; Empedocles presup- poses four elements and two moving forces; Leucippus and Democritus presuppose the atoms and the void, because the multiplicity of phenomena seems to them to require a multiplicity of material primitive elements, and the change in phenomena a moving cause; Anaxa- goras was led by similar considerations to his doctrine of the épotopspſ, and the world-intelligence. Both sets of philosophers speak of Being and Becoming; but in the one case the definitions respecting Becoming ºrs º 208 THE PRE-SOCRATIC PHILOSOPHY, -Y into more particularly by Empedocles and the Atomists. appear only as a consequence of their theory of Being ; in the other, the definitions of Being are merely pre- suppositions in the theory of Becoming. In assigning, therefore, the three most ancient schools to a first division of pre-Socratic Philosophy, and Heracleitus, and the other physicists of the fifth century to a second, we follow not merely the chronological order, but the internal relation of these philosophers. The course of philosophic development in the second division may be more precisely described as follows:— First, the law of Becoming is proclaimed by Heracleitus unconditionally as the universal law of the world; the reason of which he seeks in the original constitution of matter. The concept of Becoming is next enquired Generation is identified with the union, and decease with the separation of material elements: consequently, a plurality of original material elements is assumed, the motion of which has to be conditioned by a second principle distinct from them; but whereas Empedocles makes his primal elements of matter qualitatively dif- ferent one from another, and places over against them moving force in the mythical forms of friendship and discord, the Atomists recognise only a mathematical difference between the primitive bodies, and seek to explain their motion in a purely mechanical manner from the operation of weight in empty space; space they consider indispensable, because without it, as they believe, no plurality and no change would be possible. This mechanical explanation of Nature Anaxagoras finds inadequate. He therefore sets spirit beside matter as THE LATER PHYSICIST.S. 209 moving cause, discriminates them one from the other as the compound and the simple, and defines primitive matter as a mixture of all particular matters; a mix- ture, however, in which these particular matters exist and are already qualitatively determined. Heraclei- tus explains these phenomena dynamically, from the qualitative change of one primitive matter, which is conceived as essentially and perpetually changing ; Empedocles and the Atomic philosophers explain them mechanically, from the union and separation of different primitive matters; Anaxagoras finally is persuaded that they are not to be explained by mere matter, but by the working of the spirit upon matter. At this point, in the nature of the case, the purely physical explana- ion of nature is renounced; the discrimination of spirit pposition to matter, demands a recasting of science enerally on the basis of this conviction. As, however, hought is as yet incapable of such a task, the imme iate result is that philosophy is bewildered in regard o its general vocation, despairs of objective knowledge, nd places itself, as a means of formal development, in he service of the empirical subjectivity which acknow- edges the validity of no universal law. This is effected n the third section of the pre-Socratic Philosophy by eans of Sophistic." | Tennemann and Fries adopt distinguish the two main currents om matter, and the higher rank which it assumes in is arrangement of the pre-Socratic hools on purely chronological rounds. Hegel bases it on scien- fic observations concerning the ternal relation of the systems. e does not, however, expressly WOL. I. of ancient physics, and, as before noticed, he separates Sophistic from the other pre-Socratic doctrines. It is to be found, too, in Braniss, to whose general presupposition I must nevertheless demur. Among 2}0 THE PRE-SOCRATIC PHILOSOPHY. the more recent writers, Noack, and previously Schwegler, adopt my view; Haym, on the contrary (Allg. Encyk. Sect. 3 B. xxiv. p. 25 sqq.), though in harmony with me in other respects, places Heracleitus before the Eleatics. In his history of Greek Philosophy, p. 11 sq. Schweg- ler discusses: 1, the Ionians; 2, the Pythagoreans; 3, the Eleatics; and 4, Sophistic, as the transition to the second period. He defends the subdivision of the Ionians into earlier and later, for the reasons stated on p. 202 sq.; and assigns to the earlier, Thales, Anaximander, and Anaximenes; to the later, He- racleitus, Empedocles, Anaxagoras, and Democritus. So also Ribbing (Platon. Ideenlehre, i. 6 sqq.) con- siders that since Heracleitus, Empedocles, the Atomists, and Anaxagoras are, in their principles, lower than the Pythagoreans and |Bleatics, they, as well as the older Ionians, must be placed before them. Ueberweg has the follow- ing division: 1, the older Ionians, including Heracleitus; 2, the Pythagoreans ; 3, the Eleatics; 4, Empedocles, Anaxagoras, and the Atomists. The Sophists he places in the second period, of which they form the first chapter; Socra- tes and his successors, as far as Aristotle, constitute the second; Stoicism, Epicureanism, and Scep- ticism, the third. I cannot now enter upon any detailed examina- tion of these differentclassifications. It will be seen in the course of this exposition what are my objec- tions to the theory of Strümpell (Gesch. der Theoret. Phil. der Grie- chen, 1854, p. 17 sq.), in point of chronology as well as the internal aspects of the subject. His expo- sition of the pre-Socratic Philoso- phy is as follows: First, the older Ionian Physiologists, starting from the contemplation of the changes in nature, arrive in Heracleitus at the conception ofcriginall?ecoming. To this doctrine the Eleatics op- pose a system which entirely denies Becoming, whilecontemporaneously the later Physicists, on the one side Diogenes, Leucippus, and De- mocritus; on the other, Empedo- cles and Anaxagoras, reduce it to mere motion. A reconciliation o the opposition between Becoming and Being, and between Opinion and Knowledge, was attempted by the Pythagoreans ; and Sophistic is a dialectic solution of this oppo- sition. It will suffice at presen to say that the position of Hera cleitus, the Eleatics, Diogenes, and more especially the Pythagoreans, appear to me more or less misre- presented by this arrangement. THALLES. 211 § I.—THE EARLIER IONIANS, THE PYTHA- GOREANS AND ELEATICS. THE EARLIER IONIAN PHYSICS.1 I. THALES.2 THALES is reputed to be the founder of the Ionian Naturalistic Philosophy. He was a citizen of Miletus, a contemporary of Solon and Croesus,” whose ancestors * Ritter, Gesch. der Ion. Phil., 1821. Steinhart, Ion. Schule, Allg. Encyk. v.; Ersch und Gruber, Sect. II., vol. xxii. 457–490. * Decker, De Thalete Milesio. Halle, 1865. Older monographs in Ueberweg, Grundriss, der Gesch. der Phil., i. 35 sq., 3rd edition. * This is beyond question; but the chronology of his life (on which cf. Diels on the Chronicle of Apol- lodorus, Rhein. Mus., xxxi. 1, 15 sq.) cannot be more precisely fixed. According to Diogenes i. 37, Apol- lodorus placed his birth in the first year of the 35th Olympiad, i.e. 640–639 B.C. Eusebius places it in the second year of the 35th Olympiad, and Hieronymus also in the 35th Olympiad, Chron. 1. But this statement is probably founded only on some approximate calcula- tion of the eclipse of the sun, which Thales is said to have pre- dicted (vide infr. p. 213, 3). This is not, as used formerly to be supposed, the eclipse of 610 B.C.; but, ac- cording to Airy (On the Eclipses of Agathocles, Thales, and Xerares, Philosophical Transactions, vol. cxliii. p. 179 sqq.); Zech (Astrono- mische Untersuchungen der wich- tigeren Finsternisse, &c., 1853, p. 57, 'ith which cf. Ueberweg, Grund- iss der Gesch. der Phil. i. 36, third edition); Hansen (Alhand- lºngen der Königl sächs. Gesellsch. der Wissenschaft. vol. xi.; Math. phys. Kl. vol. vii. p. 379); Martin (Revue Archéologique, nouv.sér., vol. ix. 1864, p. 184), and other autho- rities, that which occurred on the 28th, or, according to the Grego- rian calendar, the 22nd of May, 585 B.C. Pliny, in his Naturai History, ii. 12, 53, places it in the fourth year of the 48th Olympiad (584-5 B.C.), 170 A.U.C.; Eudemus ap. Clemens, Stromata, i. 302 A, about the fourth year of the 50th Olympiad (580–576); Eusebius in his Chron. in Ol. 49, 3, 582–1; they, therefore, take the second eclipse, which is most accurately calculated by Pliny. About the same time (under the Archon Da- masius, 586 B.C.) Demetrius Phale- reus ap. Diog. i. 22 makes Thales and the rest to have received their designation of the seven wise men. According to Apollodorus, Diog. i. 38, Thales was 78 years old; (Decker's proposal, p. 18 sq., to sub- stitute 95 does not commend itself to me) according to Sosicrates (ibid.), 90; according to Pseudo Lucian (Macrob. 18), 100; according to Syncell. (p. 213 C), more than 100. His death is placed by Dio- genes, loc. cit., in the 58th Olym- F 2 212 THALES. are said to have immigrated to their later home from Phoenicia, but more probably from Boeotia." piad; likewise by Eusebius, Hiero- nymus, and Cyrillus, loc. cit.; but in that case, as is shown by Diels, and confirmed by Porphyry (ap. Abulfaradasch, p. 33, ed. Poeocke), his birth cannot have been assign- ed by Apollodorus to Ol. 35, 1, but to Ol. 39, 1 (624 B.C.; 40 years before the eclipse), and the diver. gent statements must be ascribed to some ancient corruption of the text in the source consulted by Diogenes. As to the manner of Thales's death and his burial-place, some untrustworthy accounts are to be found in Diog. i. 39, ii. 4; Plut., Solon, 12; some epigrams relating to him, in Anthol. vii. 83 sq., Diog. 34. Whether the Thales mentioned in Arist. Polit. ii. 12, 1274 a, 25, as the scholar of Ono- macritus, and the teacher of Ly- curgus and Zaleucus, is the Milesian philosopher, or some other person, matters little; and the unfavour- able judgment, which, according to Aristotle, ap. Diog. ii. 46 (if, indeed, the statement be his at all), Pherecydes passed upon Thales, is equally unimportant. * Herodotus, i. 170, says of him : 0&New &vöpös Mixmaſov, to &véka9ev yewos éévros folviicos; Clemens, Strom. i. 302 C, simply calls him folvić to yévos; and, ac- cording to Diogenes, i. 22, (where, however, Röper, Philol. xxx. 563, proposes to read toxitetſºno av, and fix60w), he seems to have been regarded as a Phoenician im- migrant, settled in Miletus. This statement is probably founded on the fact that his ancestors belonged to the Cadmean tribe in Boeotia, who were intermingled with the The con- Ionians of Asia Minor (Herod. i. 146; Strabo, xiv. 1, 3, 12, p. 633, 636; Pausan.vii. 2,7). According to Pausanias, a great number of The- ban Cadmeans established them- selves in Priene, for which reason the name of the place was altered to Cadme. Hellanicus in Hesychius sub voc. also calls the inhabitants of Priene Kabulou. For Diogenes, i, 22, says: fiv rolvvu 6 Oaxis, és puév ‘Hpóðotos kai Aoûpts kal Amuá- kpitós pma'i, Tarpos uév 'Eğapitov, p.mtpos 3& KAeoBovXívms, ék Töv Onxiāāv (or 0mAvö.) of eign poſvi- kes, eúryevéotatoi Tôv &trö Kääuov ical 'Ayfivopos. He thus explains the poiviš by “descendant of Cad- mus’; following either Duris or Democritus, or, at any rate, some very trustworthy source. Herodo- tus, however, shows by the word &vékaðey that not Thales himself, but only his remote ancestors had belonged to the Phoenicians. If Thales was only in this sense $olvić, his nationality, even if the story of the immigration of Cad- mus have any foundation in his- tory, is Greek and not Phoenician; nor is this statement affected by the circumstance (vide Schuster, Acta Soc. philol. Lips. iv. 328 sq.; cf. Decker, De Thale., 9) that the father of Thales perhaps bore a name that was Phoenician in its origin. Diog., loc. cit., and 1, 29, according to our text, calls him in the genitive’E£aputov. For this we must read 'Eğaušov ; and some manuscripts have 'Eğaplixov or 'EğauvočAov, which certainly points to a Semitic extraction. But this Graeco-Phoenician name, like that of Cadmus and many others, may JBIOGRAPHY. 213 sideration in which he was held by his fellow-citizens is sufficiently shown by the place which he occupies as chief of the seven sages." This has reference in the first instance, it is true, to his practical ability and worldly prudence of which other proofs have come down to us; ” but we hear also that he distinguished himself by his knowledge of mathematics and astronomy;” and that he have been kept up centuries long among the Phoenicians settled in Greece. We cannot infer from it a direct Phoenician descent, either for Thales or his father. His mother's name is wholly Greek. * Cf. p. 119 sq.; Timon ap. Diog. i. 34; Cic. Legg. ii. 11, 26; Acad. ii. 37, 118; Aristophanes, Clouds, 180; Birds, 1009; Plautus, Rud. iv. 3, 64; Bacch, i. 2, 14. In Capt. ii. 2, 124, Thales is a pro- verbial name for a great sage. For sayings ascribed to him cf. Diog. i. 35 sqq.; Stobaeus, Floril. iii. 79, 5; Plutarch, S. sap. conv. c. 9. * According to Herodotus, i. 170, he counselled the Ionians, be- fore their subjugation by the Per- sians, to form a confederation with a united central government to re- sist them ; and, according to Diog. 25, it was he who dissuaded the Milesians from provoking the dan- gerous enmity of Cyrus by an alliamee with Croesus. It is not consistent with this, and in itself is hardly credible that he should have accompanied Croesus in his expedition against Cyrus (as Hero- dotus relates, i. 75), and by plan- ning a canal, should have enabled him to cross the Halys. It is still more incredible that Thales, the first of the seven wise men, should have been such an unpractical theorist, as a well-known anecdote represents him. Plato, Theaetetus, 174 a ; Diog. 34, cf. Arist. Eth. N. vi. 7, 1141 b, 3, &c. Little more, however, is to be said for the story of the oil presses, intended to re- fute this opinion; not to mention the aneedote in Plutarch, Sol. anim. c. 16, p. 971. The assertion (Cly- tus ap. Diog. 25), povăpm airbv 'yeyovéval kal iówaorthv, cannot be true in this universal sense; and the stories about his celibacy, for which cf. Plutarch, Qu. conv. iii. 6, 3, 3; Sol. 6, 7; Diog. 26; Stobaeus, Floril., 68, 29, 34, are equally worthless. * Thales is one of the most celebrated of the ancient mathe- maficians and astronomers. Xeno- phanes eulogises him in this respect, cf. Diog. i. 23: 50ke? §§ kard Tuvas trpáros &0 rpoxo'yūgal ical fixtakās ékMetheus kal Tpor&s trpoettreſv, Šs pmotv Eğ6muos év tá treph Tāv &orpoxo'youpévov igropig' 66ev airby kal Eevoq'dvms kal ‘Hpóðo- ros 6avudget uaprupe; 5' airó kal “Hpdicxettos kai Amuákpitos. Phö- mix ap. Athen. xi. 495, d: ©axis 'yūp, 30 ris àortépav čvářoros etc. (others read &otéov). Strabo, xiv. 1, 7, p. 635: Qaxis . . . 6 trpá- tos (pugioxolytas Špèas év toſs “EAAmori Kal waffnuarukňs. Apuleius Floril. iv. 18, p. 88 Hild. Hippo- lytus Ref. haer. i. 1; Proclus in Euclid. 19 (vide following note). 214 THALES. was the first to transplant the elements of these sciences The anecdote quoted from Plato, Theaet. 174 A, in the previous note, has reference to his reputation as an astronomer. Among the proofs related of his astronomical know- ledge, the best known is the above- mentioned prediction of the eclipse which occurred during a battle be- tween the armies of Alyattes and Cyaxares or Astyages (Herod. i. 74; Eudemus ap. Clem. Strom. i. 302 A.; Cic. Divin. i. 49, 112; Pliny's Hist. Nat. ii. 12, 53); it was probably in consequence of this that the prediction and expla- nation of solar and lunar eclipses generally were ascribed to him. See Diog. loc. cit.; Eusebius, Pr. Ev. x. 14, 6; Augustine, Civ. Dei, viii. 2; Plutarch, Plac. ii. 24; Stobaeus, Ecl. i. 528, 560; Simplicius, in Categ. Schol. in Arist. 64 a, 1, 65 a, 30; Ammonius, ibid. 64 a, 18; Schol. in Plat. Remp. p. 420; Bekk. Cic. Rep. i. 16. Theo in the pas- sage taken from Dercyllides, Astron. c. 40, p. 324 Mart, and re- peated by Anacolius, in Fabric. Bibl. gr. iii. 464. The latter says, following Eudemus: ©axis 6* [eipe TrpáTos] jàtov čica stipu kal Thy karð. Tàs Tporås airrod treptočov [al. Trépobov &s obic form &el ovuòaível. (On this opinion, which we meet with elsewhere, cf. Martin loc. cit. p. 48). In partial agreement with this, Diogenes says (i. 24 sq. 27) that Thales discovered thv &to Tporºs étrº Tporºv rápotov of the sun, and declared the sun to be 720 times as large as the moon. He, or according to others, Pytha- goras, first proved that the triangles constructed on the diameter of a circle are rectangles (ºrpótov kara- 'ypájau kökxov to Tptywyov Šp60- yóviov); that he perfected the theory of the orkaxmva Tpſywya (Cobet : okax. Kai Tpty.), and in general the Ypapputkm 6ewpía; de- termined the seasons, divided the year into 365 days, Imeasured the height of the pyramids by the length of their shadow (this accord- ing to Hieronymus; the same in Pliny, Hist. Nat. xxxvi. 12, 82; a little differently in Plutarch S. sap. conv. 2, 4, 147); Callimachus ap. Diog. 22 says that he was the first to mark out the constellation of the Little Bear, which is repeated by Theo in Arati Phaen. 37, 39, and by the Scholiast of Plato, p. 420, No. 11, Bekker. Proclus as- serts that he first showed that the diameter halved the circle (in Euclid, 44, 157 Friedl.), and that in an isosceles triangle, the angles at the base are equal (ibid. 67 and 250 Friedl.); that the angles at the vertex are equal (ibid. 79, a, 299, according to Eudemus); that triangles are equal when they have two angles and one side equal to one another; and that by means of this proposition the distance of ships on the sea could be measured (ibid. 92 [352]; this is also on the authority of Eudemus). Apuleius, Flor. iv. 18, p. 88 H., says that Thales dis- covered temporum ambitus, vento- Twm flatus, Stellarum meatus, tonitruwm Sonora miracula, siderum obliqua eurricula, Solis annua rever- ticula (the rporal, the solstices of which Theo and Diogenes in the previously quoted passages, the Scholiast on Plato, p. 420 Bekk., speak); also the phases and eclipses of the moon, and a method of de- termining quotiens Sol magnitudine sua circulum, quem permeat, meti- atur. Stobaeus ascribes to him BIOGRAPHY. 215 into Greece from the countries of the east and south." some other philosophical and phy- sical theories hereafter to be men- tioned, also the division of the heavens into five zones (Ecl. i. 502, Plutarch, Plac. ii. 12, 1); the dis- covery that the moon is illuminated by the sun (ibid., 556, Plac. ii. 28, 3), the explanation of her monthly obscuration, and of her eclipses, 560. Pliny, Hist. Nat.xviii.25, 213, mentions a theory of his about the Pleiades, and Theo in Arat. 172, a passage relative to the Hyades. According to Cicero, Rep. i. 14, he made the first celestial globe; and, according to Philostratus, Apoll. ii. 5, 3, he observed the stars from Mycale. How much of these re- ports is true cannot now be ascer- tained ; that the prediction of the eclipse of the Sun cannot be histo- rical, Martin shows in the Revue Archéologique, nouv. Sér. vol. ix. (1864) 170 sqq.; cf. especially p. 181 sq. * Arithmetic, says Proclus, in Euclid. 19, o [65] was discovered by the Phoenicians; Geometry by the JEgyptians, on the occasion of the overflowing of the Nile, Oaxïs 6& Tpótov eis Atºyvirtov čA6&v wethya- 'yev eis rêv ‘EAAáða. Thu 6eapfav Taúrmv, kal troAA& uèv airbs eips, troXAóv 63 Tâs àpx&s roºs uer' airby $qºmyńoraro. Whence Proclus got this information he does not state, and though it is not improbable that Eudemus may be his au- thority, we know not whether the whole account comes from that source, nor who may be the autho- rities of Eudemus. Thales's Egyp- tian journey, his intercourse with the priests of that country, and the mathematical knowledge which he gained from them are spoken of by Pamphile and Hieronymus, ap. Diog. 24, 27; the author of the letter to Pherecydes, ibid. 43; Pliny, Hist. Nat. xxxvi. 12, 82; Plutarch, De Is. 10, p. 354; S. sap. conv. 2, p. 146; Plac. i. 3, 1 ; Clemens, Stromata, i. 300 D, 302; Iamblichus v. Pythag. 12; Scho- liast in Plato, p. 420, No. 11 Bekk. (cf. Decker, loc. cit., p. 26 sq.), a conjecture as to the reason of the overflowings of the Nile was also attributed to Thales, and may perhaps be connected with this statement (Diodor. i. 38; Diog. i. 37). If it be true that Thales was engaged in trade (Plutarch, Sol. 2, asserts this, prefixing ‘‘paolv’), we might suppose that he was first led to Egypt by his commercial jour- neys, and then made use of his opportunity for the advancement of his knowledge. We cannot, however, regard his presence in Egypt as absolutely proved, pro- bable as the assertion may be ; since the tradition on the subject cannot be traced further back than Eudemus, whose date is still 250 or 300 years from that of Thales's supposed journey, still less can his acquaintance with the Chaldaeans be proved by such late and uncer- tain testimony as that of Josephus, Contra Apionem, i. 2; or the length of his stay in Egypt by that of the Placita falsely attributed to Plu- tarch (i. 3, 1). A scholium (Schol. $n Ar. 533, a, 18) states that he was sent for into Egypt as a teacher of Moses—a specimen of the manner in which history was manufactured in the Byzantine pe- riod and even earlier. That he de- rived philosophical and physical theories from the East, as well as geometrical and mathematical knowledge, is not asserted by any 216 THALES. That he inaugurated the school of ancient physicists is affirmed by Aristotle, and seems well established. He is at any rate the first whom we know to have instituted any general enquiry into the natural causes of things, in contradistinction to his predecessors, who contented themselves partly with mythical cosmogonies, and partly with isolated ethical reflections.” of our witnesses, except perhaps Iamblichus and the author of the Placita. Röth's attempt (Gesch. der Abendl. Phil. ii. a, 116 sqq.) to prove this from the affinity of his doctrine with that of Egypt, falls to the ground so soon as we as- cribe to Thales, only what there is good reason for ascribing to him. * Metaph. i. 3, 983 b, 20. Bonitz, in commenting on this pas- sage, rightly reminds us that it is not Greek Philosophy in general, but only the Ionian Physics, the origin of which is here attributed to Thales. Theophrastus says (ap. Simp, Phys. 6 a., m), but only as a conjecture, that there must have been physicists before Thales, but that his name caused them all to be forgotten. Plutareh, on the other hand (Solon, c. 3, end), re- marks that Thales was the only one of his contemporaries who ex- tended his enquiry to other than practical questions (repairépo tºs xpetas Étréabai Tà 6eapfg). Simi- larly Strabo (sup. p. 213, 3) Hip- polyt. Refut. Haer. i. 1; Diog. i. 24. The assertion of Tzetzes (Chil. ii. 869, xi. 74) that Phereeydes was the teacher of Thales has no weight, and is besides contradicted by the chronology. * Thales does not appear to have committed his doctrines to writing. (Diog. i. 23, 44; Alex. In answer to in Metaph. i. 3, p. 21, Bon. The- mist. Or. xxvi. 317, B; Simplicius, De an. 8 a, cf. Philop. De an. C 4; Galen. in Hipp. de Nat. hom. i. 25, end, vol. xv. 69 Kühn.) Aristotle always speaks of him from some uncertain tradition, or from his own conjecture (Metaph. i. 3, 983 b, 20 sqq., 984 a, 2; De caelo, ii. 13, 294 a, 28; De an. i. 2, 405 a, 19, c. 5, 411 a, 8; Polit. i. 11, 1259 a, 18, cf. Schwegler, in Me- taph. i. 3); similarly Eudemus, ap. Proclus in Euclid. 92 (352), Röth (Gesch. der Abendl. Phil. ii. a, iii.) concludes that the supposed Thale- sian writings must be genuine, be- cause of their agreement with the propositions attributed to Thales. This is a strange inference, for in the first place he himself only con- siders two of the writings authen- tic; and as to the contents of these two, nothing has been handed down to us. These writings are the vavrukh &orpoxoyia and the treatise repl rporãs. In the second place it is obvious that traditions about Thales's doctrine might as easily have been taken from spurious writings, as, on the other hand, the authors of such writings might have taken advantage of floating traditions. Among the works as- cribed to Thales the vaurich &orpo- Aoyſa (mentioned by Diog. 23, Simpl. Phys. 6 a., m) seems to have TVA TER AS PRIMITIVE MATTER. 217 this enquiry, he declared water to be the matter of which all things consist, and from which they must have arisen." known by the ancients from historical tradition. As to the reasons of this theory, nothing was Aris- totle * indeed says that Thales may have been led to it been the oldest. According to Simplicius, it was his only work. Diogenes says it was held to be a work of Phocus the Samian. Ac- cording to Plutarch (Pyth. orac. 18, p. 402), who considers it ge- nuine, it was written in verse; it seems to be intended by the étrº, mentioned in Diog. 34. Whether the poem, trepl tre're&pov, ascribed to him by Suidas (Oax.), is or is not identical with the vaurikh &orpoxonyta, cannot be ascertained. Two other works, which many writers consider to be his only writings, repl rporms kal ionuepias, are quoted in Diog. 23 (cf. Suidas). The Pseudo-Galen (In Hippocr. De humor. i. 1, 1, Vol. xvi. 37, R) quotes a work, trepi àpxöv ; but this testimony is itself sufficient to prove that the work is not authen- tic, Neither the verse quoted Diog. 35 (cf. Decker, p. 46 sq.), nor the letter (ibid. 343 sq.) can be considered as genuine. To which of these writings Augustine refers in Civ. D. viii. 2 (where he asserts that Thales left books of instruc- tion) it is not of much consequence to know. The same may be said of the doubtful allusions to books of his in Josephus (C. Apion. i. 2), and of the quotations in Seneca, Nat. qu. iii. 13, 1, 14. 1 ; iv. 2, 22; vi. 6, 1 ; Plutarch, Plac. i. 3; iv. 1; Diodorus, i. 38; Schol. in Apoll. Rhod. iv. 269. 1 Arist. Metaph. i. 3, 983 b, 20 : 0&Aſis ºv 6 Tis rotatºrms &pxmºyös pixooroq tas Ščap sivaſ pnow [sc. orouxetov kal &px?iv ráv čvrov) Cic. Acad. ii. 37, 118: Thales . . . ea aqua dicit constare omnia, and many others (a list of these is given in Decker, p. 64). We find in Stobaeus, Eel. i. 290, and almost word for word in Justin. Coh. ad Gr. c. 5; Plut. Plac. i. 3, 2, the expression: &px?iv Tóv Švtov &reqfivato Tô iſoap, & #6aros yáp qmail travra, eival kal eis iſoap &va- Affeo'6&t ; but this is taken from Aristotle, who, shortly before the words just now quoted, says that most of the ancient philosophers knew only of material causes: é: of y&p éotiv Štravra. Tä, övta kal ěč of yi-yveral trpárov kal eis 8 q6eſperat Texevratov . . . . tooto arouxetov kal Taürmv &px?iv paoſiv eival tăv čvtov. Aristotle is, there- fore, in reality our only source for the kncwledge of Thales's propo- sition. * Loc. cit. z. 22: Aaflöv forws Thy Stróxmipu Čk rod trävrov ôpºv thv Tpoq’hu ärypåv of oav kal aútb to 6epubv éic rońrov yiyvópºevov kal Toârg (ºv . . . kal 61& rô travtov rā ortrépuata rºv qigou 5-ypèv čxeiv, to 6' iſoap &px?iv ràs qāorea's sival roſs trypois. By 6epubv is not to be understood (as by Brandis, i. 114) warmth gene- rally, including that of the stars (see following note); it relates to the vital heat of animals, to which trövtwv is limited by the context. 218 THALES. through observing that the nourishment of all animals is moist, and that they all originate from moist germs; but this he expressly states to be merely his own conjec- ture. It is only by later and less accurate authors that the conjecture of Aristotle is asserted as a fact, with the farther additions that plants draw their nourish- ment from water, and the stars themselves from damp vapours; that all things in dying dry up, and that water is the all-organising and all-embracing element;" that we must assume one primitive matter, because otherwise it would be impossible to explain the trans- formation of the elements one into another; and that that one matter must be water, because everything is derived from water, by means of rarefaction and con- densation.” All this makes it difficult for us to come to any definite conclusion on the subject. It is possible that the Milesian philosopher may have been influenced by the considerations that Aristotle supposes; he may have started from the observation that everything living arises from a liquid, and in decaying, returns to * Plut. Plac. i. 3, 2 sq. (so Eu- sebius, Pr. Ev. xiv. 14, 1, and in essential agreement with this, Stobaeus, loc. cit.); Alex. ad Me- taph. 983 b, 18; Philoponus, Phys. A, 10; De an. A, 4 a ; Simplicius, Phys. 6 a., 8 a ; De calo 273 b, 36; Karst. Schol. in Arist. 514 a, 26. It has been al- ready shown by Ritter, i. 210, and Krische (Forschungen auf dem Ge- biete der alten Philosophie, i. 36) that Simplicius is here speaking only from his own conjecture or that of others, that the subsequent passage where he refers to Theo- phrastus does not relate to the rea- sons of the system of Thales, and that we have consequently no right to conclude (as Brandis does, i. 111 sqq.) the existence of trustworthy documents concerning Thales's rea- soning from the supposed agree- ment of Aristotle and Theophrastus. * Galen. De Elem. Sec. Hoppocr. i. 4, vol. i. 442, 444, 484, speaking simultaneously of Thales, Anax- imenes, Anaximander, and Herac- leitus. It was in truth Diogenes of Apollonia (vide infra) who first proved the unity of matter by the transformation of the elements. WATER AS PRIMITIVE MATTER. 219 a liquid state; but other observations may likewise have conduced to this theory, such as the formation of solid ground from alluvion, the fertilising power of rain and of streams, the numerous animal population of the waters; in conjunction with such observations, the old myth of Chaos and of Oceanos, the father of the gods, may also have had some effect on him; but the exact state of the case cannot be ascertained. Nor can we say whether he conceived his primitive watery matter as infinite; for the assertion of Simplicius * is mani- festly based upon the Aristotelian passage which he is elucidating;” and this passage does not mention Thales. It does not even affirm that any one of the philosophers who held water to be the primitive matter, expressly attributed the quality of infinity to that element. Supposing such an assertion had been made, it would be more reasonable to refer it to Hippo (vide infra) than to Thales, for the infinity of matter is else- where universally regarded as a conception first enter- tained by Anaximander; Thales most likely never raised such a question at all. He is said to have discriminated * from water, as * Phys. 105 b, m: of uèv Év ti orrouxetov Štroriðévres Tooto &melpov ëAeyov tápleyéðel, Šotrep Oaxis pièu iſãwp, etc. * Phys. iii. 4, 203 a, 16: of 8& trepi pigeos àwavres àel Šro rifléaoruv étépav twä (pāoriv ré &reſpº táv Aeyouévov orouxetov, oiov iſoap 3) &épa ) to ustašū rottov. * The question there is (loc. cit.) not whether primitive matter is intinite, but whether the infinite is the predicate of a body from which it is distinguished, or is to be held (with Plato and the Pytha- goreans) as something self-depend- ent, existing for itself. Aristotle, therefore, does not say all the Physicists regard primitive matter as infinite, but all give to the infi- nite some element as substratum; and this he could very well say even if certain physicists had not expressly mentioned the affinity of the first principle. The word âmavres is limited by the context to those Physicists who admit an âtreupov. - 220 THALES. primitive matter, the deity or spirit which permeates this matter, and from it forms the world." Aristotle,” however, expressly denies that the ancient physiologists, among whom Thales stands first, distinguished the moving cause from matter; or that any other philo- sopher except Anaxagoras (and, perhaps, before him Hermotimus) had brought forward the doctrine of an intelligence organising the world. How could Aristotle have used such language if he had known that Thales named God the reason of the world P But if he did not know it, we may be sure that the assertions of later writers are not based upon historical tradition. More- over, the doctrine which is attributed to Thales entirely accords with the Stoic theology;” the very expression in Stobaeus appears to be borrowed from the Stoic termi- nology; “Clemens of Alexandria,” and Augustine,” dis- tinctly declare, that neither Thales nor the physicists 1 Cic. N. De. i. 10, 25. Thales . . . aquam dirit esse initium re- 'rum, Deum autem eam mentem, quae ea aqua cuncta fingeret, a state- ment which, as Krische observes (Forschungen, 39 sq.), is the same in substance, and is apparently taken originally from the same source as that of Stobaeus (Ecl. i. 56): 9axis votiv roi, kāoruov row 6ebv, and the similar passage in Plut. Plac. i. 7, 11 (consequently we must not in Eus. Pr. Ev. xiv. 16, 5, read with Gaisford: ©axis Tby kóopov eival bebv, but votiv too réopov 6eóv). Athenag. Supplic. c. 21; Galen, Hist. Phil. c. 8, p. 251 ; Rühn. 2 Cicero, loc. cit. ef. Stobaeus, 1oc. cit.: to 5% wav ćujuxov Šua kal Saipávay TAñpes' 5thkely 5è kal Biê rod atouxelööows trypoſ, Šávauv 6etav kivm ruchy airow. Philoponus, De An. C. 7 u, makes Thales to have said: ás i tpóvoia uéxpt rôv éoxátov 51%ket kal oi6év airhy A&v6ável. * Metaph. i. 3, 984 a, 27 b. 15. * God is described, for example by Seneca (Nat. qu. prol. 13) as the mens universi; by Cleanthes (vide Tertullian, Apologet. 21) as the spiritus permeator universi; by Stobaeus, Ecl. i. 178, as Sāvapus kivmtikh Tås #Ams; by Diogenes, vii. 138, as vows, which pervades all things (6(mkeiv). * Strom. ii. 364 C; cf. Tert. c. Marc. i. 13, Thales aquam (Deum pronuntiavit). * Civ. D. viii. 2. ORGANISING FORCE. 221 who succeeded him regarded God or the Divine Spirit as the framer of the universe, but that Anaxagoras was the first to hold this doctrine. We may, therefore, certainly conclude that the opposite theory is an error of the post-Aristotelian period, the source of which we shall presently find in some passages of Aristotle. It by no means follows from this that Thales personally be- lieved in no god or gods; but the tradition that credits him with the thesis that God is the oldest of all things, because He has had no beginning, is not very trustworthy. For this assertion is no better attested than the innu- merable other apophthegms ascribed to the seven sages, and was probably attributed to Thales originally in some collection of their sayings in the same arbitrary manner that other sayings were attributed to the rest. Moreover, Xenophanes is elsewhere invariably considered, as the first who, in opposition to the Hellenic religion, declared the Deity to have had no beginning. Accord- ing to certain authors, Thales taught that the world is full of gods. This statement is much more probable than the preceding.” But what are we to understand by 1 Plut. S. sap. conv, c. 9; Diog.i. 35; Stobaeus, Ecl. i. 54. This is no doubt the meaning also of the statements in Clemens, Strom. V. 595 A (and Hippolyt. Refut. haer, i. 1), according to which Thales re- plied to the question: tí Éott to 6elov ; Tô phre &px?iv uſite réAos ëxov. For immediately after, another saying of Thales is quoted concerning the omniscience of God (the same given in Diog. 36 and Valer. Max. vii. 2, 8). Conse- quently, the impersonal 6etov has here the same significance as the personal 6eós. Tertullian (Apolo- get. c. 46) transfers Cicero's story (N. D. i. 22, 60) about Hiero and Simonides to Croesus and Thales; but this is a mere oversight. * Arist. De An. i. 5, 411 a, 7: kai év tá, 8x4, 6é rives abrºv [rhy Wvxhyl Meulx6aſ pagiv, 36ev tows Kal ©ax?s ºf 6m trăvta TAjipm 6eóv eival. Diog. i. 27: Tov kóguov tuyvyov kal Saipºvov trafipm. Simi- larly Stobaeus (vide supra, p. 220, 2). The same proposition is also ap- plied in a moral sense (Cicero, Legg. ii. 11, 26). 222 THALES. the expression, the diffusion of the soul throughout the universe? Aristotle's cautious “perhaps’ shows us how little such an interpretation is supported by tradition. Indeed, it may safely be asserted that not only later writers, but Aristotle himself, in his own way, ascribed notions to Thales which we have no right to expect from him. That he conceived all things as living, and personified all active forces after the analogy of the human soul, is certainly probable, because this is in harmony with the imaginative view of nature which everywhere, and especially among the Greeks, precedes scientific enquiry: it is, therefore, quite credible that he may (as Aristotle affirms) have attributed a soul to the magnet,' on account of its power of attraction—that is to say, regarded it as a living being. In the same manner, doubtless, he conceived his primitive matter as living, so that, like the ancient Chaos, it could beget all things by itself, without the intervention of an or— ganising spirit. It is also entirely consonant with ancient Greek thought that he should see present deities in the forces of nature, and a proof in the life of nature, that nature is full of gods. But we cannot believe that he combined the several powers of nature, and the souls of separate beings, in the notion of a world-soul; for that notion presupposes that the infi- nite multiplicity of phenomena has become a unity in the conception of the world; and that efficient power * De An. i. 2, 405 a, 19: éotice airby kal roºs &#xois Stöðval 88 ral Oaxºs é; &v &touvnuovetſovot juxās rekuaipówevov čk rās uayvärt- kivmtików ri rhy juxhv ŠtroNaßeiv, 80s ical toi hAércrpov. Cf. Stob. Eel. efrep row Atôov čpm buxºv čxeiv, i. 758: Oaxis ical r& pvra guyuza 3rt row otömpov kivet. Diog. i. 24: @a. 'AptorroréAms & kal “Irrías paolv ORGANISING FORCE. 223 is distinguished from matter and conceived as analo- gous to the human spirit, not only in particular indi- viduals, where this is natural in the simpler stages of opinion, but in the universe generally. Both ideas seem to lie beyond the first narrow limits of early philosophy, and the historical evidence does not justify us in attributing them to Thales.' We may con- clude, therefore, that while he conceived his primitive matter as living and generative, while he shared the religious faith of his people, and applied it to the consideration of nature, he knew nothing of a world- soul or of a spirit permeating matter and forming the universe.” As to the manner in which things originated from water, Thales seems to be silent. Aristotle certainly says that the physicists, who hold one qualitatively de- termined primitive matter, make things arise out of it by rarefaction and condensation,” but it does not follow that all these philosophers without exception were of that opinion.” Aristotle might have used the same form of expression if only the majority had held it, 1 Plut. Plac. ii. 1, 2: Oaxis kal oi &r' airot va Töv icóapov can- not of course be taken as historical evidence. * Some such answer must also be given to the question which, in the last century, was so vigorously debated, but which is now almost wholly neglected, whether Thales was a Theist or an Atheist. The truth is no doubt that he was nei- ther one nor the other; neither in his religious faith nor his philoso- phy; his religion is Greek polythe- ism, his philosophy is pantheistic hylozoism. * Phys. i. 4, at the commence- ment: ás 6' oi puorukol Aéryovoru São Tpétrol eioſiv. of uév yöp #v trouh- oravres to by orówa to Širokeſpevov . . . . taxNa yewv&ot trukvármri kal wavórmri troXA& Trotobvres . . . of 6' ék rot, Évös évoča as rās evav- Tiórntas Šickpívea 6al, Šotrep "Avagſ- Alavöpós (pmartv. * Heracleitus, for instance, re- garded things as arising out of fire, not by rarefaction and condensa- tion, but by transformation. 224 THALES. and if it appeared to him the most logical theory of derivation. Simplicius' is the first who expressly con- nects Thales with Anaximenes as having adopted this theory; not only, however, does Theophrastus disagree with him, but Simplicius tells us himself that his state- ment is only based upon the general bearing of Aristotle's words.” What is said by Galen "in a passage of doubt- ful connection, and also by other writers,” in a similar strain, is most likely taken from the same source. It is most probable, on the whole, therefore, that Thales never entertained the question, but contented himself with the indefinite motion that things arose or were produced out of water. What we hear from other sources about the doctrine of Thales consists merely of isolated empirical obser- vations or conjectures, or else of statements so imper- fectly guaranteed that they cannot be considered authentic. The latter holds good not merely of the various mathematical and astronomical discoveries and moral maxims which are attributed to him,” of the assertion" that the heavenly bodies are glowing * Phys. 39 a kal of $v 6: Kal kivočuevov thv 3px?iv Štrobéuevoi, às GaAſis kal 'Avačplēvms, paváget kal trukvåget thv yéveauv trouotivares. So 310 a., u, Pseudo-Alex. in Me- taph. 1042 b, 33, p. 518, 7; Bon. and the anonymous Schol. in Arist. 516 a, 14 b, 14. * Simpl. Phys. 32 a., u : étrl yèp roºrov učvov ['Avačupévous] Oedºppa- gros év tá ‘Iotopig thv uávorw eſpnke kal Thy riſkvoortv. (This saying, moreover, ought only to be applied to the ancient Ionians. Theophrastus ascribed also to Diogenes rarefaction and condensation, vide infra): 37Aov 6é às kal oi &AAoi Tà wavórmti kal Tvkvörmti éxpóvro, ical yèp’Apato- TéAms repl travrov rottaw site icot- wós, &c. - * Wide supra, p. 218, 2. * Hippol. Refut. i. 1; Arnob, Adv. nat. ii. 10; Philop. Phys. C. 1, 14, who, in both passages, so entirely confuses Thales with Anaximenes, that he attributes to Thales the doctrine of air as primi- tive matter. * Cf. p. 120, and p. 213, 3. * Plut. Plac. ii. 13, 1 ; Achill. Tat. Isag. c. 11. I)OOTRINES A TTRIBUTED TO THALES. 225 masses, analogous to the earth, that the moon receives her light from the sun," and so forth ; but even of the philosophic doctrines of the unity of the world,” the infinite divisibility and variability of matter,” the un- thinkableness of empty space,” the four elements,” the mixture of matters,” the nature and immortality of the soul," the daemons and the heroes.* All these originate with such untrustworthy witnesses, and most of them either directly or indirectly so entirely contradict more credible testimony, that we can attach no value to them whatever. What Aristotle” gives as a tradition is more likely to be true, viz. that Thales supposed the earth 1 Plut. Plac. ii. 28, 3; Plut. Conv. sap. C 15 (Ös 5& Oaxis Aéyet, rijs y?s āvaipeBeforms orityxvaſiv Tov &Aov čeiv köopov) can hardly be quoted, as the Banquet of Plutarch is not a historical work. Moreover, the meaning is doubtless merely that the annihilation of the earth would (not will at Some time) be fol- lowed by a destruction of the whole universe. 2 Plut. Plac. ii. 1, 2. * Plut. Plac. i. 9, 2; Stob. Ecl. i. 318, 348. 4 Stob. i. 378, where the older reading, Öréyvoorav, recommended by Röth, Abendl, Phil. ii. 6, 7, is grammatically inadmissible. * According to the fragment of the spurious writing, trepl &pxów (Galen, vide supra, p. 216, 2), and perhaps also Heraclit. Alleg. hom. c. 22, the four elements are expressly reduced to water. Jt will here- after be shown that Empedocles was the first to establish four as the number of the material ele- ments. * Stob. i. 368. In the parallel passage of Plutarch's Placita, i. 17, WOL. I. 1, Thales is not named : oi àpxafot is the expression used, which is evidently more correct, and was probably the original expression of Plutarch. * According to Plutarch (Plac. iv. 2, 1) and Nemes. (Nat. hom. c. 2, p. 28), he described the soul as ºpiois &eikivmtos ?) airokivm ros; ac- cording to Theodoret, Gr. aff, cur. v. 18, p. 72, as pào is àictvm ros (where, however, &etkivmtos possibly ought to be read); an interpolation to which the passage of Aristotle quoted above doubtless gave occa- sion. Tertullian, De Am. c. 5 at- tributes to Thales and to Hippo the theorem that the soul is com- posed of water. Philoponus, De An. c. 7, restricts this to Hippo, while, in another passage, De An. A 4, he ascribes it both to Hippo and Thales. Choerilus ap. Diog. i. 24, and Suidas, Oaxis, says that he was the first to profess be- lief in immortality. * Athenag. Supplic. c. 23; Plut. Plac. i. 8. * Metaph. i. 3, 983 b, 21; De Caelo, ii. 13, 294 a, 29. Q 226 THALES. to float on the water; for this would harmonise per- fectly with the theory of the earth's origin from water, and easily adapt itself to the old cosmological notions: we may also connect with it the further state- ment' that he explained earthquakes by the movement of the water. This last assertion, however, seems to rest entirely on one of the writings falsely ascribed to Thales, and doubtless the ultimate source of other doctrines that have been attributed to him. The statement of Aristotle is better attested, but we gain little information, even from him, as to the doctrine of Thales as a whole.” All that we know of it may, in fact, be reduced to the proposition that water is the matter out of which everything arises and consists. The reasons that determined him to this theory can only now be conjectured; how he more closely defined the process of the origination of things from water is also very uncertain; but it is most probable that he considered primitive matter, like mature in general, to be animate, and that he held to the indeterminate con- ception of beginning or generation, without defining this as brought about by the rarefaction or condensa- tion of the primitive matter. However meagre and insignificant this theory may seem, it was, at least, an attempt to explain phenomena by one general matural principle, and in this light it was of the highest importance; we find that a series of * Plut. Plac. iii. 15, 1; Hippol. militates against the supposition Refut, har. i. 1; Sen. Nat. qu. vi. (Plut. Plac. iii. 10) that he held the 6; iii. 14. The last, however, earth to be spherical, a conception seems to refer to a treatise falsely which is foreign to Anaximander attributed to Thales. . and Anaximenes, and even to * On the other band, this theory Anaxagoras and Diogenes. ANAXIMANDER. 227 $ more extended enquiries are directly connected with those of Thales, and that even his immediate successor was able to attain much more considerable results. II. ANAXIMANDER." WHEREAs Thales had declared water to be the primitive matter of all things, Anaximander” defined this original * Schleiermacher, Ueber Anaari- mandros (1811; Werke, Philos. ii. 171 sqq.); Teichmüller, Studie 2ur Gesch. der Beſſ. Tº O, I re- gret that I cannot make use of Lyng's treatise, “On den Iomiske Naturphilosophi, isſer Anawiman- ders’ (Abdruck aus den Vid. Sels- kabets Forhandlinger for 1866), as I am not acquainted with the lan- guage in which it is written. * Anaximander was a fellow- citizen of Thales, and also his pupil and successor, according to later authorities (Sext. Pyrrh. iii. 30 ; Math. ix. 360; Hippolyt. Refut. har. i. 6; Simpl. Phys. 6 a., m ; Suidas, &c.; this is likewise implied by the epithet étatpos, ap. Simpl. De Coelo, 273 b, 38; Schol. in Arist. 514 a, 28; Plut. ap. Eus. Pr. Ev. i. 8, 1 ; of Sodalis in Cicero, Acad. ii. 37, 118; of yuápipios, in Strabo, i. 1, 11, p. 7; and the latter is actu- ally interchanged with uaônths, ibid. xiv. 1, 7, p. 635). According to Apollodorus (Diog. ii. 2) he was sixty-four years old in the second year of the 58th Olympiad, 546–7 B.C., and died soon afterwards, so that his birth must have occurred in Ol. 42, 2 (611 B.C.), or, as Hippo- lytus (Refut. i. 6) thinks, in Ol. 42, 3. Pliny (Hist. Nat. ii. 8, 3) says he discovered the inclination of the zodiac. The worth of these state- ments we cannot certainly esti- mate; but there is much to be said for the conjecture of Diels (Rhein. Mus. Xxxi. 24) that Anaximander gave his age in his own work as six- ty-four; that Apollodorus (who, ac- cording to Diogenes, had this work in his hands), following some inter. nal evidence, calculated that the work was written in Ol. 58,2; and that the statement of Pliny is based on the same calculation, in- asmuch as he found mention of the obliquity of the ecliptic in this work. But Diogenes adds, as a quotation from Apollodorus: ákuá- oauté "rm uáàtata karð IIoxvkpárnv Töv ×400 tipavyov, which is rather surprising, as Anaximander was considerably older than Polycrates, and died about 22 years before him. Yet we need not, with Diels, loc. cit., assume that these words originally related to Pythagoras (whose &Kuh certainly falls under Polycrates, as he is said to have emigrated in his reign when forty years old), for they are also to be ex- plained as the inexact reproduction of an observation of Apollodorus respecting Anaximander. I am in- clined to suspect that Apollodorus, in order to get a synchronistic date after the manner of ancient chrono- logists, had made the 3xpº of this philosopher (ºrm) pretty nearly co- incide with the commencement of the tyranny of Polycrates, which is Q 2 328 ANAXIMANDER. element as the infinite, or the unlimited." By the in- finite, however, he did not understand,” like Plato and the Pythagoreans, an incorporeal element, the essence of which consists exclusively in infinity; but an in- finite matter: the infinite is not subject but predicate, it designates not infinity as such, but an object to which the quality of being infinite belongs. It is in this sense only, says Aristotle,” that all the physicists generally placed in the third year of the 53rd Olympiad, and in the 44th year of Anaximander's life. Eusebius (Chron.) assigns Anaxi- mander to the 51st Olympiad. Nothing is known of his per- sonal history, but the statement (AElian, V. H. iii. 17) of his being the leader of the Milesian colony in Apollonia indicates that he filled a distinguished position in his native place. His book, Trepl q)`jorews, is said to have been the first philosophical writing of the Greeks (Diog. ii. 2; Themist. Orat. xxvi. p. 317 C. When Clemens, Strom. i. 308 C, says the same of the work of Anaxagoras, he is evi- dently confusing him with Anaxi- mander). Brandis rightly observes, however (i. 125), that according to Diogenes, loc. cit., the work must have been rare, even in Apollodo- rus's time, and Simplicius can only have known it through the quota- tions of Theophrastus and others. Suidas mentions several writings of Anaximander's, but this is doubtless a misunderstanding; on the other hand, a map of the world is attributed to him (Diog. loc. eit. ; Strabo, loc. cit, after Eratosthenes; Agathemerus, Geogr. Inf. 1). Eu- demus, ap. Simpl. De Coelo, 212 a, 12 (Sºhol. in Arist. 497 a, 10) says he was the first who tried to determine the sizes and distances of the heavenly bodies. The in vention of the sundial was as- cribed to Anaximander by Diog. ii. 1, and Eus. Pr. Ev. x. 14, 7; and to Anaximenes by Pliny, Nat. Hist. ii. 76, 187, in both cases er- roneously, as is probable; for the invention, according to Herod. ii. 109, was introduced into Greece by the Babylonians; but it is possible that one of these philosophers may have erected in Sparta the first Sundial ever seen there. * Arist. Phys. iii. 4, 203 b, 10 sqq.; Simpl. Phys. 6 a, and many others; see the following note. * As Schleiermacher, loc. cit. p. 176 sq., exhaustively proves. * Phys. iii. 4, 203 a, 2: Trávres às àpxfiv riva riðéaori rôv čvrov [rö &reipov], of uév čo Trep of IIv6a- 7ópelot kal IIAárov, ka9' airb, oùx ãs orvuòeBmkós tui étépºp, &AA’ oãotav airó by to &melpov . . . . of 8& trepi pāorews àravres àeł Śwortóéaoruv érépav rivă pâgu tę &teſpº Tów As youévov orouxetov, oiov #8wp ſh &épa ) to uerași rotºrwy. Cf. Me- taph. x. 2, 1053 b, 15. According © to the theory of the Physicists the &v was not itself a substance, but had some pious for its substratum, ékeſvov yap 6 uév ris diafav eivaí qmori to $v 6 3’ &épa, § 5% (Anaxi- mander) to &meipov. THE INFINITE. 229 speak of the infinite; and among the physicists he unquestionably reckons Anaximander." According to the unanimous testimony of later authors,” Anaximan- der's main argument for his theory was that the infinite, and the infinite alone, does not exhaust itself in con- stantly producing. This is the very argument that Aristotle quotes” as the chief ground for maintaining an infinite corporeal matter; and he does so in speaking of the theory which we recognise as Anaximander’s, viz. that the infinite is a body distinct from the de- terminate elements. From the infinite, Anaximander (whom Aristotle for that reason places beside Empe- docles and Anaxagoras) derived particular kinds of matter, and the world which is compounded of them, by means of separation * (Aw88cheidwng), a doctrine which would be impossible unless the infinite were itself something material. Lastly, though it is difficult to discover how this philosopher preeisely defined his infinite, all testimony is agreed as to its eorporeal mature; and among the passages of Aristotle which possibly may refer to Anaximander, and of which some must of necessity refer to him, there is none which does not imply this corporeal nature.” That he in- * Cf. loc. cit. p. 203 b, 13; vide infra. * Cic. Acad. ii. 37, 118; Simpl. De Caelo, 273 b, 38; Schol. 514 a, 28; Philop. Phys. L, 12 m ; Plut. Placita, i. 3, 4, and to the same effect Stob. Ecl. i. 292: Aéyet of v: 51& ri &melpóv éotiv ; iva uměčv éAAeſtrm, i. Yéveals i ögºla'rawévm. * Phys. iii. 8, 208, a, 8: oëre y&p iva i. Yéveous uh étrixeirm, divay- kaſov čvepyeig timepov eival orópia aiorówitóv, cf. c. 4, 203 b, 18, and Plut. loc. cit, * Wide inf. p. 234, 3, and p. 250. * In our text of Simpl. Phys. 32 b, o, we have : évoča as Tês évavrićtmtas Év rig introkeſpevº &treſpº 6vri ào'àuart ékkpívea 6aſ qºmotiv 'Avačiuavöpos. Instead of ão 6part Schleiermacher, loc. cit. 178, proposes toread ord part. Bran- dis (Gr. Röm. Phil. i. 130) prefers &owadrº; but this could only be 230 ANAXIMANDER. tended therefore to designate by the infinite a matter infinite as to its mass, cannot be doubted;" and it is admitted on the supposition that Simplicius by the āoróparov here understood that which is not as yet formed into any determinate body. Meanwhile adºpları is not merely better sense, but it has also in its favour that Simplicius in the pre- vious context (p. 32 a, Schol. in Ar. 334 b, 18) has been speaking of Anaximander's orápa to inrokei- wevov; and similarly Aristotle in the passage immediately preceding the one here in question, Phys. i. 4, 187 a, 13, speaks of the orówa. to Širokeiuevov, and elsewhere (vide previous note) of the ātrepov gºpia airómtöv. These words signify: “In the primitive matter conceived; as āmelpow a 6p.a.’ | Michelis (De Amaa. Infinito. Ind. lect. Braunsberg, 1874) indeed asserts the contrary in the tone of one who holds his own infalli- bility to be indisputable. His arguments, however, seem to me insufficient. He maintains that Aristotle, in a passage never hitherto understood (Phys. iii. 4, 204 a, 2 sq.), distinguishes the positive infinite or absolute from the negative infinite, which relates only to the corporeal and the sen- sible, the former being what Anaxi- mander meant by his &meipov. But the passage contains no trace of any such distinction, nor has any writer previously discovered such ; it only says that we may either call that an ātreupov, the measuring of which can never be completed; or that which does not allow of being measured: Tó pººl reqvicéval buiéval, ãotrep pou?) &opatos; in other words (cf. c. 5, 204 a, 12), that which does not fall under the con- ception of magnitude, and, there- fore, can as little be measured or, consequently, limited, as the voice can be conceived of as visible. So understood, the expression àmeipov has nothing at all to do with the Absolute as such : the Štreipov in this sense coincides much more with that of which it is said (Phys. iii. 4, beginning) that it can neither be called &neupov (in the ordinary sense), nor tre+repaguévov, as, for in- stance, the point or the tra,00s. Michelis himself is forced to allow (p. 7 sq.) that Aristotle never again mentions this ‘positive in- finite.” How little Aristotle ever thought of it, Michelis might have seen had he studied the passage in Phys. i. 2, 185 a, 32 sqq., where, without any restriction, it is as- serted of the Štreipov generally, and not of any particular kind of &reupov, that it is to be found only év tá, troorg, oùoríav Šē &tepov eival % trouármra h tré60s oik Övöéxeral ei Wº karð oup18eflmicos, ei äua kai troo’, &rra elev, for the Absolute is oùota, if it is anything; and such an oiota that the troorov cannot, not even karū a vuòeºmicos, belong to it. The conception of the Abso- lute and that of the Štreipov, accor- ding to Aristotle's view, plainly exclude one another; for the Ab- solute is the perfected energy, pure and simple ; the Štreipov, on the contrary, is what is always unper- fected, always Švváuet, never évep- 'yeſ', (Phys. iii. 5, 204 a, 20 c. 6, 206 b, 34 sqq ; Metaph. ix. 6, 1048 b, I4), which, consequently, can be only material cause, and is never employed in any other sense (Phys. iii. 7, 207, 4, 34 sqq.; cf. THE INFINITE. 231 probably in this sense that we should understand the expression àTsupov." He was induced, as we have seen, to determine primitive matter in this way, chiefly by the consideration that primitive matter must be infinite to be able continually to produce from itself new essences. It was easy for c. 6, 206 a, 18 b, 13). Aristotle, unquestionably therefore, neither himself thought of an immaterial &meipov, nor attributed it to Anaxi- mander. Even in respect of that &melpov, which Michelis wrongly regards as his ‘positive Infinite,’ he says expressly, Phys, iii. 5, 204 a, 13: &AA’ oix oitos offre paolv eival of pâgicovires eival to &melpov oùre jueis (mroßprev, &AA’ &s &ötéč0- ãov. As little can it be said that Aristotle, at any rate, did not ascribe to Anaximander's àtreupov, a corporeal materiality, for he manifestly does so in the passages quoted, p. 228, 3, and p. 229, 3. Michelis's argument (p. 11), that the passage in Metaph. x. 2, 1053 b, 15(vide Supra, p. 233, 1) identifies Anaximander with Empedocles (it also identifies him with Anaxime- nes), and that, according to my view, the same opinion is ascribed to him as to Melissus, proves no- thing. We cannot conclude that because the pixta of Empedocles is not a corporeal matter that there- fore Anaximander's &meipov is none; nor can it be pronounced impossible that Melissus should have been led to a determination of Being, which brought him into contact with Anaximander, as Plato was brought with the Pythagoreans by his doc- trine of the Unlimited. In fine (p. 11), Aristotle, of whose words, moreover (Phys. iii. 4, 203 b, 4), Michelis has a wrong conception, Aristotle to show (loc. cit.) must himself, according to this writer, have distorted Anaximan- der's doctrine; and all other autho- rities, especially Theophrastus, in his utterance, quoted p. 233, 1, must be held guilty of the same thing. From this point, however, all pos- sibility of any historic demonstra- tion is at an end, and Michelis substitutes for it a simple sic volo, sic jubeo. * Strümpell (Gesch. der theor. Phil. der Gr. 29); Seydel (Fortschritt der Metaph. innerhalb der Schule des Ion. Hylozoismus, Leipzig, 1860, p. 10); and Teichmüller (Studien zur Gesch. der Begr. 7, 57) believe that the &neupov means with Anaximan- der that which is qualitatively in- determinate, as distinguished from determinate substances. But the word seems to have first received this signification from the Pytha- goreans, and even with them it is a derived signification; the original meaning is ‘the Unlimited' (only that the Unlimited, as applied to numbers, is that which sets no limit to division nor to augmenta- tion, vide infra, Pyth.). For Anaxi- mander this signification results partly from the same cause that he assigns for the &meipia of primitive matter (viz., that it would other- wise be exhausted); and partly from this consideration, that it is precisely because of its infinity that the ātreupov can embrace all things. 232 ANAXIMANDER. that this proof is not conclusive; but it might never- theless have appeared sufficient to the unpractised thought of the earliest philosophers," and we must at any rate allow that Anaximander, "by maintaining the theory, first raised an important question in philo- sophy. - So far there is little room for disagreement; but opinions are greatly divided as to the more precise meaning of Anaximander's primitive matter. The ancients are pretty nearly unanimous in asserting that it did not coincide with either of the four elements;” according to some it was not a determinate body at all, others describe it as intermediate between water and air, or again between air and fire; while a third account represents it as a mixture of all particular kinds of matter; a mixture in which these have been always contained, as distinct and determinate, so that they can be evolved from it by mere separation, without any change in their constitution. This last theory has formed the basis in modern times” of the assertion * The same mistake, however, Anaximander for Anaximenes, re- was made by Melissus, and after- wards by the Atomist, Metrodorus; vide infra, Mel, and Metrod. * Authorities will presently be given. The Pseudo-Aristotelian writing, De Melisso, &c., c. 2, 975 b, 22, alone maintains that his pri- mitive matter is water (vide infra) and in Sextus, Math. x. 313, it is said that he made all things arise, & Švös kal trouot, namely, air. But although his name is twice men- tioned, it seems very probable that the statement may have sprung from the erroneous substitution of peated by a copyist from the text of Sextus, or some other author whom he was transcribing. In the Pyrrh. iii. 30 he gives a correct account of both these Philosophers. * Ritter, Gesch. der Ion. Phil. p. 174 sqq., and Gesch. der Phil. i. 201 sq., 283 sqq., where his former concession that Anaxagoras held things to be contained in primitive matter only as to their germ and capability, and not as distinct from each other, is virtually re- tracted. THE INFINITE. 233 that among the earlier, no less than among the later Ionic philosophers, there were two classes—the Dy- namists and the Mechanists—i.e. those who derived all things from one primitive matter by means of a vital transformation, and those who derived them from a multiplicity of unchanging primitive matters by means of separation and combination in space. To the first belong Thales and Anaximenes, Heracleitus and Dio- genes; to the second, Anaximander, with Anaxagoras and Archelaus. We will now examine this theory, since it has an important bearing not only on the doctrine before us, but also on the whole history of ancient Philosophy. Much may be said in its behalf. Simplicius' ap- pears to ascribe the same view to Anaximander which we find in Anaxagoras, viz. that in the separation of matters from the infinite, kindred elements become united, gold particles with gold particles, earth with earth, and so on, these different and distinct kinds of 'yápas à p’ of 5uakpuðueva roës ºre * Phys. 6 b, u, after a descrip- kóo wous kal Thu Tów &AAwu pāoruv tion of Anaxagoras's doctrine of the primitive elements, he proceeds thus: kai Taijrá pmauv 60éâq)paotos trapatamoria's ró ‘Avačupdvöpp Aéyetv Töv 'Avačayópav. čkeſvos Yép pmoiv év tá 6takptoei Toi) ātretpov Tó. ovyyev'ſ pépeotal mpos &AAmAa, kai ti uév év tá, travti xpvabs ºv, ºyſveoróat Xpworöv, 3 ru 88 y? yńv, ôpioios 3& kai Tôv &AAov čkaarov, &s oi yuouévov &AA’. Strapxóvrwv Tpérepov. Cf. p. 51 b, u: oi 5è troAAö. Pºv čvurápxovira ö, äkkplve- orðai éAeyov rhv yévecru ävaipoovres, às 'Avačíuavôpos kal 'Avačayópas. Tās 5è kiwāorews kal ris yewégews ałriov čtréatmore Tov votiv 6 'Avača- éyévvmorav. ‘Kal otºrw uév, pnot, Aapíšavávrovë6čelev &v 6'Avačayópas Tås uèv Šxukås &pxàs &treſpous troueiv, Thy 6é Tſis kivſio’ews kai Tàs yewéorea's airíav atav row votiv. ei Sé ris Tºw pièu Töv Štrávrov ŠtroAdBot patav eival púoruv &óptorov kal kar’ eiðos kal karū uéyebos, orvuſbaivet 880 Tès àpxès airby Aéyeiv, thv too &metpou qºquy kal row votiv' &ote patveral tà owpatikā Otouxeta trapatamoria's trouév 'Avačupid vôpºſ.’ The same words are quoted by Simplicius, p. 33 a, as borrowed from Theo- phrastus's pugikh iotopia. 234 ANAXIMANDER. matter having been already contained in the original mass. His authority for this statement is supposed to be Theophrastus. We meet with the same view, how- ever, elsewhere,' and Aristotle seems to justify it when he describes Anaximander's primitive matter as a mix- ture.” He also expressly mentions him as one of the philosophers who thought particular kinds of matter were developed from the one primitive matter, not by rarefaction and condensation, but by separation.” This proves, apparently beyond question, that Aristotle himself conceived this primitive matter of Anaximan- der as analogous to that of Anaxagoras; for that which has to be separated from matter must previously have been contained in it. But these reasons, on closer in- spection, are very insufficient.” In regard to the Aris- totelian passages, Aristotle himself tells us” that he uses the expressions “separated ' and “contained, not only where one kind of matter is contained in another * Sidonius Apollinaris, Carm. xv. 83 sqq., according to Augus- time, Civ. D. viii. 2; Philoponus, Phys. C, 4. In Irenaeus C. haer, ii. 14.2, it is not clear what conception of the Šteipov he means: ‘Anawi- "mander autem hoc quod immensum est omnium initium subjecit (šté0e- to) seminaliter habens in semetipso omnium genesin.” * Metaph. xii. 2, 1069 b, 20 : real tour eart to 'Avačayópov čv kal ’Eutrečokxéous to utyua kal 'Avač- Audväpov. * Phys. i. 4: és à’ of pugikol Aéyova, São Tpétrol eioiv. of uév yāp $v trouha'avtes to by gºua to Štokeſ- Auevov, 3) rôv rpiów (Water, Air, Fire) ru, 3 &AA0, 8 €ort trupos uév Trvicvárepov &épos 3& Aerrérepov, TāAAa yewv&ot trukvármti kal wavó- Tnti troAA& trouotivres . . . . of 6’ éic rot, Évos évoča as Tàs évavrićrmºras ékkpívea 6al, Šotrep "Avačuavöpós qmail kal &got 5’ evical troAAá pagu, eival >rep 'Epſtrečok?\ms kal’Avača- ºyópas' ék too pºlypiatos yāp kaloirot ékkpivoval r&AAa. * Cf. Schleiermacher, op. cit, p. 190 sq.; Brandis, Rhein. Mus. of Niebuhr and Brandis, iii. 114 sqq.; Gr. Röm. Phil. i. 132 sq. * De Coelo, iii. 3, 302 a, 15: ëorro è?) orotxeſov Tóv orapudºrov, eis 6 rāAAa orópata Šiaupstral, évv- Trápxov Švváplet h évépyetz . . . . év učv yöp o'apri Šbag Kal ékáorp rów rototrov čveoti čvváuel trip kal 'yń' pavepā yöp Taira é; £keſvow éickpupéueva. THE INFINITE. 235 actually, but potentially; therefore, when he says that Anaximander represents the particular substances as separating themselves from the primitive matter, it does not at all follow that they were, as these definite sub- stances, included within it. The primitive matter can be equally conceived as the indeterminate essence out of which the determinate is ultimately developed by a qualitative change. As to the comparison of Anaxi- mander with Anaxagoras and Empedocles, it may as easily refer to a remote as to a particular resemblance between their doctrines," and it is the former kind of * In the passage just quoted, Phys. i. 4, Aristotle distinguishes those philosophers who place primi- tive matter in a determinate body from Anaximander and those, Šool ev kal troAAd paauw, who maintain that the év (the primitive matter) is at the same time one and many, because it is an assemblage of many substances qualitatively dis- tinct. We may indeed question whether Anaximander is to be counted among these latter; the words, kai Šarou 6', are not conclusive against it; since they may not only be explained, ‘and similarly those,' &c., but also, and ‘generally speaking, those.” But (cf. Seydel loc. cit. p. 13) in the subsequent passage, ék too utyuatos, &c., the kal oitou cannot include Anaxi- mander, for he is the only person with whom the oirot (through the kai) can be compared, since he alone, not the év trouha'avtes to Öv orópia, taught an éickptoſis of the évauTuárm- tes out of the év. If so, however, the philosophers, āool Év Kal troAAd (paatu eival, while they were likened with Anaximander in regard to the ëkkplots, are at the same time dis- criminated from him in another respect ; he cannot, therefore, be counted among those who consider primitive matter to be šu kal troAAá, and he did not conceive it as a mass of various matters, retain- ing their qualitative differences in the mixture. Büsgen (Ueber d. &Teipov Anaasimanders, Wiesbaden, 1867, p. 4 sq.) thinks that in this passage Anaximander must be reckoned among those who admit the év kai troAA&, as there would otherwise be no contrast between him and those who assume one uniform first principle (Anaxime- nes, &c.); but he misconceives the train of ideas. Anaximander is not placed with Empedocles and Anaxagoras in an opposition to Amaximenes and others, in regard to the Unity or Plurality of primitive substances, but in regard to the manner in which things proceed from them (rarefaction and conden- sation or separation); it is, how- ever, at the same time pointed out how Anaximander differs from these two philosophers; and subse- quently how they differ from one another. Büsgen's attempt (p. 6) 236 ANAXIMANDER, reference that is intended. mander's primitive matter In the same way Amaxi- might be called pºlypia, or at any rate might be loosely included under this ex- pression (which primarily relates to Empedocles and Anaxagoras), without ascribing to Anaximander the theory of an original mixture of all particular matters in the specific sense of the phrase.' We cannot there- fore prove that Aristotle ascribed this doctrine to him. Nor does Theophrastus; he to press into his service Phys. i. 2, sub init., and i. 5, sub init. is also a mistake ; for in the first of these passages Anaximander, if he were named at all, would be ranked among those who assume a uto. &pxh ſcuovuévn; and the second does not aim at a complete enume- ration of the different systems: Empedocles, Anaxagoras, and the , Pythagoreans, are none of them mentioned, and it is only in a forced manner that Heracleitus can be brought in under the category of those who hold the rarefaction and condensation of primitive Imatter. * Separation corresponds to mixing (róv yap airów Mišís écriri kal xopioubs, as it said in Metaph. i. 8.989 b, 4; a passage well worth comparing with the one before us); if all things arose by separation from the primitive matter, this matter was previously a mixture of all things. In , the same way, therefore, that Aristotle can speak of a separation or division, when the separated elements were only potentially contained in the primi- tive matter, he can likewise, in the same case, speak of a mixture. It is not the least necessary that the Auſyna should first have been expressly says that Anaxa- brought about by a meeting to- gether of the particular substances, as Büsgen (p. 3, 7, 11 sq. of the treatise mentioned in the pre- ceding note) seems to assume in regard to the Štreipov of Anaxi- mander; this, indeed, is absolutely incompatible with the concept of primitive matter, of the Eternal and the Unbecome. In consider- ing the above-mentioned passage, it must also be observed that here the uſ yua is primarily ascribed to Empedocles, and only in the second place to Anaximander, by the addition kal 'Avačipadvöpov. We might here admit a slight 2eugma, so that the word, which in its full power could only be used of Empedocles, might be ap- plied in its general conception (Unity including in itself a Multi- plicity) to Anaximander, and this is all the more justifiable, since the passage belongs to a section of Aristotle which (perhaps because it was originally a draft intended for his own use) is unequalled among all his writings for scant expression, and in which the proper meaning of the author is often only discoverable by complèting thoughts which he has scarcely indicated, THE INFINITE. 237 goras can only be held to agree with Anaximander on the subject of primitive matter if we attribute to him as his original principle a matter without definite qualities (uta púats àóptotos), instead of a mixture of deter- minate and qualitatively distinct substances." That the doctrine of Anaxagoras might ultimately be reduced to this theory, which is certainly divergent from its primary sense, had already been remarked by Aristotle.” Theophrastus” drew the same inference, and makes his comparison of Anaxagoras with Anaximander contingent on its admission. This shows that he ascribed to Anaximander a primitive matter in which no particular qualities of bodies were as yet present, not a matter that comprehended all particular substances as such within itself. Besides, the text in question does not attribute this latter doctrine to Anaximander ; for the words to which this meaning is ascribed 4 refer to Anaxagoras.” 1 In the words quoted between inverted commas, p. 233, 1, kai otta, aév–’Avačuávöpq, the only passage that Simplicius there cites textu- ally from him. * Metaph. i. 8, 989 a, 30; cf. ibid. xii. 2, 1069 b, 21. * Töv Avačayópav eis rov 'Ava- ëluavöpov ovva,66v, as it is said in Simpl. Phys. 33 a. * Simp. loc. cit. from ékeſvos 7&p to Štrapxóvtov, where Brandis (Gr. Röm. Phil. i. 13) sees a state- ment about Anaximander emana- ting from Theophrastus. * These words may certainly refer to Anaximander, but they may also refer to Anaxagoras; for though ékeſvos usually points to the more remote, it very often ap- Moreover these words are not given by plies to the nearer of two previ- ously named subjects, cf. e.g. Plato, Polit. 303 B; Phaedr. 231 C, 233 A, E ; Arist. Metaph. i. 4, 985 a, 14 sq.; Sext. Pyrrh. i. 213. That this is only possible when the idea indicated by ékelvos and nearer in order of words is farther in the thought of the author I cannot admit (Kern, Beitr. 2 ur Darstellung der Phil. des Xeno- phanes, Danzig, 1871, p. 11: Büs- gen's observations on the same subject, and on the &tepov of Anaximander, I must pass over). When, for example, Aristotle says (Metaph. xii. 7, 1072 b, 22): rö 'yap bektukov too vomro0 kal rijs obotas vows évépyet 8& éxov. čar' érceivo (the éxelv and évépyeºv, ac- 238 ANAXIMANDER. Simplicius as a quotation from Theophrastus, but as an expression of his own opinion. This may be based upon the testimony of Theophrastus, and the conjecture is in itself probable enough. But it can only be main- tual thought) uáAAov rotºrov (in a higher degree than the mere faculty of thinking) & Soke? 6 vows 9etov ëxeuv; –ékeſvo relates not merely to what is the nearer in order of words, but also to the principal idea; totrov to what is farther, and is only introduced in a compa- rison with it. When (Ibid. x. 2, beginning) it is asked whether the #v is a self-dependent substance, as the Pythagoreans and Plato think, à uáAAov Štrökeitat ris pào is, kal trós bei Yuwpipwrépaſs Aex87val kal MāAAov čo Trep of trepi pāorews: éiceſ- vov ydp, and so forth (vide Supra, p. 228, 3), it cannot be supposed that the physicists to which the ékeſvalvrefers, are farther from Aris- totle's thought than the Pythago- reans and Plato. Similarly in the Phaedrus, 233 E, the trpoo attoovres, to which ékéivot relates, are not only the nearest mentioned term, but also the leading idea. Still less could we expect to find this rule of Kern's scrupulously carried out by so recent a writer as Simplicius. In this case it is not Anaximander, but Anaxagoras, of whom he pri- marily speaks. If €keſvos be re- ferred to Anaximander, we make Simplicius say: 1. According to Theophrastus Anaxagoras's doctrine of primitive substances is similar to that of Anaximander. 2. Anaxi- mander admitted that particular substances were contained as such in the &neupov, and were moved in regard to one another when the process of separation took place. 3. But motion and separation were derived (not by Anaximander, but) by Anaxagoras from vows. 4. Anaxagoras, therefore, seems to as- sume an infinity of primitive sub- stances, and one moving force, vows. 5. If, however, we substitute for the mixture consisting of many substances (i. e. the theory which, according to this explanation, be- longed to Anaximander) a simple homogeneous mass, the theory of Anaxagoras would harmonise with that of Anaximander. Of these five propositions, the second would stand in no sort of connection with the third and fourth, and would be in striking contradiction to the fifth ; and in the fourth, the infer- ence that Anaxagoras therefore be- lieved in an infinity of matters, has no foundation in the preceding proposition: ékéivos, therefore, can only be Anaxagoras. Even the &Teipov, of which this ékeſvos is said to have spoken, forms no ob- stacle, for Anaxagoras (vide p 879, German text) maintained the âmeupta of primitive substance very decidedly; and Kern is surprised that the expression, &teipov, gene- rally used to describe Amaximan- der's primitive matter, should designate that of Anaxagoras, but this passage shows (cf. also Me- taph. i. 7, 988 a, 2, where Aristotle applies to his doctrine the expres- sion &relpía Tów arouxetov, as Kern himself observes) how little we need regard that difficulty. Theo- phrastus directly reduces the pri- mitive substances of Anaxagoras to the pāoris roß &tepov. THE INFINITE, 239 tained so long as it opposes nothing that demonstrably comes from Theophrastus. Schleiermacher' and Brandis” have conclusively shown that Simplicius had no accurate and independent knowledge of Anaximander's doctrine, and that his utterances on the subject are involved in glaring contradictions. His evidence, therefore, should not induce us, any more than that of Augustine and Sidonius or Philoponus, to attribute to Anaximander a doctrine explicitly denied to him by Theophrastus. On the other hand, the testimony of so trustworthy a witness as Theophrastus, together with the further evidence hereafter to be cited, justifies us in main- taining that this philosopher did not regard his primitive matter as a mixture of particular matters, and that consequently it is improper to separate him, as an adherent of a mechanical system of physics, from the dynamists Thales and Anaximenes. And this so much the more, as it is improbable, on general grounds, that the view which Ritter attributes to him should belong to so ancient a period. The theory of unchanging primitive substances presupposes, on the one side, the reflection that the properties of the several kinds of matter could have had no beginning, any more than matter as a whole; but among the Greeks we do not meet with this thought until after the period when the possibility of Becoming was denied by Parmenides, to whose propositions on this subject Empedocles, Anaxa- goras, and Democritus expressly go back. On the other side, this theory (of unchanging primitive matter) is united in Anaxagoras with the idea of an intelligence * Loc. cit. 180 sq. * Go". Röm. Phil. i. 125. 240 ANAXIMANDER. that orders the world; and even the analogous motions of Empedocles and the atomists were conditioned by their conception of efficient causes. None of these philosophers could have conceived a primitive matter as qualitatively unchangeable, if each—Anaxagoras in woffs, Empedocles in Hate and Love, the Atomists in the Void—had not also admitted a special principle of movement. No one has discovered any such doctrine in Anaximander; nor can we conclude, from the small fragment known to us of his work,” that he placed motive force in individual things, and supposed them to come forth by their own impulse from the original mixture; it is the infinite itself" that moves all things. All the conditions, therefore, of a mechanical theory of physics" are here wanting, and we have no ground for i Ritter, Gesch. der Phil. i. 284. * Ap. Simpl. Phys. 6 a. 3 & 8& # yéverts eart roſs odori kal Thy (p60pāv eis raira yive,00at Kará to xpedºv. Stöðval yèp airò Tſaw ſcal Sticnwrās &ölkías karū thv toº xpóvov tdºw. Simplicius adds that Anaxi- mander is speaking troºmtikorépous êvéuaoiv. * According to the statement in Arist. Phys. iii. 4, quoted infra p. 248, 1. 4 That is, of mechanical Phy- sics in the sense which Ritter gives to the expression in his division of the Ionian Philosophers into Dyna- mists and Mechanists; by Mecha- nists he understands those who make the determinate matters, as such, preexist in primitive matter; by Dynamists, those who make the distinguishing properties of the de- terminate matters first develope themselves in their emergence from a qualitatively homogeneous primi- tive matter. It is not, however, incompatible with the latter theory that natural phenomena should further be mechanically explained, by the movement and mixing of the matters that have issued from the primitive matter. As Anaxi- mander (this is proved by Teich- muller, loc. cit., p. 58 sq., and will hereafter appear in this work) adopted this latter procedure, it must not surprise us, though the inevitable result is that neither a purely mechanical nor a purely dynamical explanation of nature was proposed and completed by him. Still less ought it to asto- nish anyone (as it does Teich- müller, p. 24) that I should refuse to Anaximander a specific moving principle, while I afterwards (vide infra) make the movement of the heavens proceed from the &meipov. Ideny that Anaximander had a moving principle distinct from ANAXIMANDER. 241 seeking such a theory in Anaximander in opposition to the most trustworthy evidence. If Anaximander did not conceive his primitive matter as a mixture of particular substances, but as a homogeneous mass, we must next enquire what was the nature of this mass. The ancients, beginning with Aristotle, unanimously assert that it consisted of none of the four elements. Aristotle several times mentions the view that the primitive matter in re- gard to its density is intermediate between water and air," or between air and fire,” and not a few ancient writers * have referred these assertions to Anaximan- der; for example, Alexander," Themistius,” Simplicius," Philoponus,” and Asclepius.” But although this theory has been recently defended” against Schleiermacher's objections,” I cannot convince myself that it is well the primitive matter, the Štreipov; and I maintain, precisely for that reason, that he placed the motive power in this primitive matter it- self, and derived the motion of the heavens from that of the Štreipov. Where is the contradiction? * De Caelo, iii. 5, 303 b, 10; Phys. iii. 4, 203 a, 16; c. 5, 205 a, 25 ; Gen. et Corr. ii. 5, 332 a, 20. * Phys. i. 4, 187 a, 12, vide inf. p. 248, 1; Gen. et Corr. loc. cit. and ii. 1, 328 b, 35; Metaph. i. 7, 988 a, 30; i. 8, 989 a, 14. * Cf. Schleiermacher, Joc. cit. 175; Brandis, Gr. Röm. Phil. i. 132. * In Metaph. i. 5, 7, pp. 34, 2; 36, 1 ; 45, 20; 46, 28; and ap. Simpl. 32 a. * Phys. 18 a, 33 a ; 33 b (pp. 124, 230, 232 sp.). The ground of this definition is here, p. 33 a, thus stated: As the elements are WOL. I. R opposed to one another, one element conceived as infinite would an- nihilate all the rest. The Infinite must, therefore, be intermediate among the various elements. This thought can hardly belong to Anaximander, as it presupposes the later doctrine of the elements; it is no doubt taken from Arist. Phys. iii. 5, 204 b, 24. • Phys. 104; 105 b : 107 a ; 112 b ; De Coelo, 273 b, 38; 251 a, 29; 268 a, 45 (Schol. in Ar. 514 a, 28; 510 a, 24. 513 a, 35). * De Gen. et Corr. 3; Phys. A 10; C 2, 3. * Schol. in Arist. 553 b, 33. * Haym, in der Allg. Encykl. iii. Sect. B., xxiv. 26 sq.; F. Kern, in the Philologus, xxvi. 281, and p. 8 sqq. of the treatise mentioned supra, p. 237, 5. * Loc. cit. 174 sqq. 242 ANAXIMANDER. founded. One of the Aristotelian passages quoted cer- tainly seems to contain a reference to expressions which Anaximander employed;' but the reference is itself Questionable, and even if it be admitted, it does not follow that the whole passage relates to him ;” while, * De Coelo, iii. 5, at the begin- ning: éviol yèp év uóvov Štrott0evral kal rotºrov of uév iſãop, oi 8' dépa, of #6aros uév Aertórepov, &épos 6& Trvkvörepov, 6 trepuéxely paal tróvras roës otpavots &teipov čv cf. Phys. iii. 4, 203 b, 10 (supra, p. 248, 1), where the words tepuéxeiv Štravra kai travra kušepváv are, with some pro- bability, ascribed to Anaximander; and Hippolytus, Refut. Haer. i. 6. * The words, 6 Tepiéxelv–ättel- pov čv admit of two interpretations. They may either be referred solely to the subject immediately preced- ing the $6aros Aertórepov, &c., or to the main subject of the whole proposition, the év. In the former case, those who make primitive matter a something intermediate between air and water, would be credited with the assertion that this intermediate something embraces all things. In the latter case, the sense of the passage would be as follows: some assume only one primitive matter—either water, or air, or fire, or a body that is more subtle than water, and more dense than air ; and this primitive mat- ter, they say, embraces all worlds by virtue of its unlimitedness. In point of grammar the second in- terpretation seems to me undoubt- edly the best; but one thing may certainly be urged againstit (Kern, Beitrag, &c., p. 10), that, accord- ing to Phys. iii. 5, 205 a, 26, où0sis to $v kal &meipov trip rotmorev oëbè ºv táv purioMáyov (Heracleitus, ibid. 205 a, 1 sq., is particularly classed among those who regard the All as limited), and that con- sequently the relative clause, 6 tre- piéxeiv, &c., cannot contain any reference to those who made fire their primitive matter. But such inaccuracies are not so very un- common with Aristotle, and in the present instance I do not think it impossible that in a comprehensive statement, such as we have here, he should have ascribed the infinity of matter, either explicitly or im- plicitly admitted by the great majority of philosophers, to all without exception, and should have expressed this doctrine in the words of the man who first intro- duced it. On the other hand, it is quite conceivable that one of the philosophers (or if only one held it, the one philosopher) who made the primitive matter intermediate between water and air, may have adopted Anaximander's expression, trepiéxeiv Trävras robs oipavois, to characterise its infinity (Anaxi- mander himself, Phys. iii. 4, only says, repuéxelv Štravta); in the same way that Anaximenes (vide finfra) says of the air that it 3Aov Töv kóa'uov trepiéxel, and Diogenes (Fr. 6, infra) also applies to the air another expression of the Anaxi- mandrian fragment: Trävra kugep- váv. The passage we have been considering, therefore, does not warrant us in ascribing to Anaxi- mander a doctrine which, as will THE INFINIT.E. * 243 on the other hand, the very next words clearly imply the contrary. For Aristotle here ascribes to the philo- sophers, who believed the primitive matter to be some- thing intermediate between air and water, the theory that things originated from primitive matter by means of rarefaction and condensation; and this he distinctly denies of Anaximander." No other passage can be quoted from Aristotle to show that he found this definition of primitive matter in Anaximander's writ- ings.” As to the statements of later writers, they immediately be shown, is not ascribed to him by Aristotle. * Aristotle thus continues (De Coelo, iii. 5) immediately after the words quoted above: 800i ºu obv to #v rooro trotodoſiv ščap h dépa ) 58aros uév Aerrórepov &épos 6& rvkvárepov, eit' ék rotºrov trukvármti ka) uavótmri TäNAa yewv&oiv, &c. 2 Kern, Philolog. xxvi. 281, thought that the passage (quoted sup. 228, 3), Phys. iii. 4, might be so taken; since, according to this, Anaximander must be reckoned among the philosophers who con- ceive of the Infinite as a body in- termediate between two elements. In the Beitrag zur Phil. der Xen., p. 8, he prefers to interpret, the words thus: the physicists all as- sign as substratum to the Infinite one of the elements, or that which is intermediate between them. I cannot adopt this explanation. I think that Aristotle would have expressed this thought otherwise. IHe would have said perhaps: Öro- ri0éaoru èrépav ruč, pºorly ré àtreſpº, # ru rôv Aeyouévov arouxetov, h to perači, rotºrwy. On the other hand, I still consider that the words, £repay rivă pâoriv táv Aeyouévoy otolxetwv, may have a more general signification, an elemental body, different from itself, so that the matter underlying all particular substances would be included under the expression. The possi- bility of this view appears, not only from Aristotle's comprehensive use of a touxetov (e.g. Metaph. i. 8, 989 a, 30, cf. b, 16, xii. 4; De An. i. 2, 404 b, 11), but also from the definition of the word (Metaph. v. 3); nor does the word Aeyop,évov present any difficulty, for we have no right to find an allusion here to ‘the four elements.’ Aristotle, on the contrary, expressly says, loc. cit., 1014 a, 32; Tô Töv orogórav otolyeſa Aéryovoſiv oi Aéyovres eis & 6taipei Tai Tà oðuata čoxara. Éiceſva 8è unkét’ eis &AAa etóel Suaq,épovra, kal etre év eſte tràefa, rô, rotatºra, raúra arouxeſa Aéyovo w. Similarly, De Coelo, iii. 3, 302 a, 15 sqq. The Aeyóueva arouxeſia are, accord- ing to this, those equally divided bodies, which form the ultimate constituent or constituents of com- pound bodies. Such undoubtedly is Anaximander's &neipov, if we understand by it a matter to which the properties of determinate sub- st 2 244 ANAXIMANDER. appear to be entirely based on the passages in Aristotle. Simplicius, at any rate, cannot be quoting directly from Anaximander, otherwise he could not speak so unde- cidedly as he does," and he could not ascribe to this phi- losopher, as if it were a subject of indifference, the double theory of matter as intermediate between air and fire, and again as intermediate between air and water;” for these two theories obviously exclude one another, and cannot both have been found in Anaximander's work. Nor ean Simplicius have found among his predecessors allusions to that work, otherwise a different turn would at once have been given to the discussion. The same may be said of Porphyry,” who in that case would not have grounded his opinion (which differs from the opinion of Alexander) solely upon the Aristotelian passage. This also holds good of Alexander” and Philoponus.” These later statements, therefore, one and all, depend entirely upon conjecture, and the words of Aristotle were only referred to Anaximander because they seemed to apply to no other philosopher. Now it is elear from the un- doubted testimony of the most trustworthy authorities, that Anaximander did not consider his primitive matter stances do not yet belong. We are almost forced to take this view of Aristotle's words, because the passage would otherwise apply nei- ther to Anaxagoras, nor to the Atomists. For neither the Öuoto- pepſi, nor the atoms, belong to the four elements, or to that which is perašūtoãrwv; but Aristotle himself maintains the ātreupta of the Öuoto- pepſi, and of the atoms; these must also, therefore, be a âtépa pūois, which serves as substratum to the &neupov. * Phys. 32 a. * The former, Phys. 107 a. The latter, Phys. 105, b. De Coelo, 273 b, 38; 251 a, 29. * Simplicius, Phys, 32 a. * In Metaph. 983, a, 11; Schol. 553 b, 22: rhy’Avačudvöpov 66%av, bs &px?iv č6ero Thy usraft pºortv &épos re ſcal trupbs, 3 &épos re ſcal $5atos' Aéyeral yèp &pſporépos. * Even he is uncertain, in the passages quoted, whether Anaxi- mander's Infinite is intermediate be- tween air and fire, or air and water. THE INFINITE. 245 as intermediate between two definite kinds of matter; but that he either was silent as to its nature, or ex- pressly described it as that to which none of the pro- perties of particular substances belongs. For when Aristotle, in the above-mentioned passage, speaks generally of those who posited as primitive matter a definite element, or something intermediate between two elements, and derived all other things from it by the processes of rarefaction and condensation, it is obvious that his design is not to draw a distinction between these philosophers and others who equally as- Sumed a primitive matter of the same kind, but made things to arise out of it in a different manner. On the contrary, in refuting the theory of a derivation of things by means of rarefaction and condensation, he believes that he has refuted the general theory of a primitive matter of definite quality. This is still clearer from the passage in the Physics, i. 4. ‘Some of them, he here says, “starting from the pre-supposition of a determi- mate primitive matter, make things to originate from it by means of rarefaction and condensation; others, like Anaximander, Anaxagoras, and Empedocles, maintain that opposites are already contained in the One primi- tive matter, and are produced from it by means of separation.” Here it is perfectly evident that he con- ceives rarefaction and condensation to be as essentially connected with the theory of a qualitatively determined matter, as separation with that of an original mixture of all things, or of a matter without qualitative deter- minateness. Nor can it be otherwise; for in order to * Wide supra, p. 234, 3. 246 ANAXIMANDER. arise by separation out of the primitive matter, parti- cular matters must either potentially or actually have been contained in it; but this would only be possible if the primitive matter were itself not a particular matter, not merely intermediate between two other particular matters: but including them all equally in itself. If we further consider that this chapter of the Physics is occupied, not with the manner in which things originate from elements, but with the number and nature of primitive substances themselves," it seems beyond question that Anaximander was opposed to the rest of the Ionians, not only from the first point of view, but from the second, and that consequently his infinite can have been neither one of the four elements, which were afterwards admitted, nor an intermediary between two of these elements. This probably explains why Anaximander is passed over in Metaph. i. 3, and also a remark,” which otherwise would have no histori- cal point, and which the Greek commentators” them- selves apply to him. “Some, says Aristotle, “seek the Infinite, not in any particular element, but in that out of which all particular elements arose; because each particular substance, conceived as infinite, must exclude those substances that are opposed to it.’ * This Haym, loc. cit., denies; but it unquestionably results from C 2. Sub init. 2 Phys. iii. 5, 204 b, 22: &AA& pºv oë6é &v kal &m Aoûu évôéxeral eival to &repov orópa, otte às Aé- 'yova'ſ rives to trap& ràortoixeta, ść of raúta yeuvāoriv, où6 &trades, eio l yáp rives, oi tooto trototo, to &meipov, &AA’ oik &épa ) iſãop, Ös ph taxAa “3. This reason, q0eſpnſtal ºrb roß &treſpov airóv. ëxovo's yūp trpos &AAmAa évavittooru, ofov 6 pºv &ºp juxpos, to 5’ iſãop 5-ypov, to 8& trop 6epuðv. &v ei ºv £v &n'eipov čq,0apro èv #öm TäAAa: vov 3’ repov eivaſ paoru è; of Taijra. * Simp. 11 a ; Themist. 33 a, (230 sq.). THE INFINITE. 247 indeed, which points to the later theory of the elements, can hardly have been so stated by Anaximander. But whether Aristotle inferred it, after his manner, from some ambiguous utterance, or arrived at it by his own conjecture, or whether later authors may, perhaps, have interpolated it, the doctrine in support of which it is adduced no doubt belongs originally to Anaximander. Theophrastus expressly says so" in describing Anaxi- mander's Infinite as One matter without qualitative determinateness; and with this Diogenes” and the Pseudo-Plutarch,” and among the commentators of Aristotle, Porphyry, and probably also Nicolaus of Damascus,” agree; of these the two first, at any rate, appeared to have used a special source. Simplicius himself says elsewhere the same thing.” That Anaxi- mander's primitive matter was not a qualitatively determined matter is, therefore, certain ; the only doubt that remains is whether he expressly denied to it all determination, or merely abstained from qualifying it at all. The latter hypothesis is the more probable of the two; it is actually maintained by some of our authorities, and appears simpler and, therefore, more in accordance with so ancient a system, than the other theory, which constantly presupposes considerations like those above cited from Aristotle; it also furnishes the * Ap. Simpl.videsupra, p. 223, 1. * Simpl. Phys. 32 a. * ii. 1 : épaakev &px?iv Kul o'rol- * Phys. 111 a. Aéyovorivoi repl xerov to &reupov, où 5uopiſov &épa h ’Avaštuavópov [to &m supov sival] to $6ap 3) &AAo ‘ri. trapë rà arouxeta é of Tà o'rouxeia * Plac. i. 3, 5: āpaptdvei 58 yewv&oruv. 6 a. Aéyet 6 airhy oiros uh, Aéyov tí Čott to Šteipov, [thv 3px?iv) uhre jöop &AAo róv trörepov &#p éotiv h iſoap # yń ) kańovuévov orotxetwv, &AA’ &répay #AAa riva ord wata. Tuvâ púaiv Štreipov. Also 9 b. 248 AWAXIMANDER. most reasonable explanation of the fact that Aristotle only mentions Anaximander when he is discussing the Question of the finiteness or infinity of matter, and of the production of things from it, and not when he is dealing with its elementary composition; for in the case we are assuming, no distinct utterance of Anaxi- mander would have been known to him on this point, as on the two former (not even the negative state- ment that the Infinite is not a particular substance), and so he prefers to be wholly silent on the subject. I therefore believe that Anaximander held simply to this proposition: that the Infinite or infinite matter existed before particular things. As to the material constitu- tion of this primitive substance, he has given us no precise information. Anaximander further taught that the Infinite is eternal and imperishable." In this sense he is said to have designated the first principle of all things by the expression àpxiſ.” He conceived motive power * Arist. Phys. iii. 4, 203 b, 10 (cf. De Caelo, iii. 5; Supra, p. 242, 2). The Infinite is without begin- ning or end, etc.: bib, ka0&trep Aéyouev, où taúrms &px?), &AA’ airm Töv &AAwvelva. 50ket kal tep t #xe i v à tra vºt a kal tra vra k v 8 ep v 3 v, &s qaa w śoot uh trouovoi trapö. Tö &ret- pov &AAas airtas, olov votiv h pixtav’ kai Tojt’ eival rô 6e?ov' & 6 & v at ov ºy &p kal & v & Ae 6 pov, Ös pmoly 5 'Avačuavópos kal of TAetorrow rôv quotoxóryov. The words in spaced type are probably taken from Anaxi- mander's work; only for &váAe6pov, &yńpo may have been substituted as Hippolytus, Refut. Har. i. 6 Itaúrmy (riv apviv) 5’ &íðuov eival kal dyſpa, kal Távtas reptéxeiv robs kéguous] thinks likely. More recently Diog. ii. 1 : tá pºšv uépm weraßAAelv, to 8è trav duetá8Xmtov sival. * Hippolyt. loc. cit., and Simpl. Phys. 32 b, certainly assert this; and Teichmüller (Stud. 24r Gesch. der Begr. 49 sqq.), who disputes it, does violence, as it seems to me, to the wording of these passages. It is another question whether the statement is true, and this we can scarcely ascertain. Like Teich- müller, I cannot regard it as self- evident, that he employed the ex- pression àpxh; and my doubt is strengthened by the circumstance that a similar remark about Thales PRIMITIVE MATTER. 249 to be combined from the beginning with matter;' or, as Aristotle says (loc. cit.), he taught that the Infinite not merely contained, but directed all things.” He thus regarded matter, after the manner of the early Hylo- zoism, as self-moved and living ; and in consequence of this motion he supposed it to produce all things from itself. When Aristotle (loc. cit.), therefore, designates Anaximander’s Infinite as the Divine essence, he describes it correctly,” though we do not know whether Amaximander himself used that expression.* (that he called water &px?) I can discover neither in Diog. i. 27, nor elsewhere; and consequently I cannot credit it. But if Anaxi- mander did call his Infinite the &px? or the épx?) travrov, or designate it in any other similar manner, this would only be saying that the Infi- nite was the beginning of all things, which is far enough from the Platonic and Aristotelian con- cept of the dpy?, the ultimate cause. 1 Plut. ap. Eus. Pr. Ev. i. 8, 1: 'Avačíuavôpov . . . to &reipov påval Thy Tāorav airtav čxelv Tàs roo Travros yewéoredºs Te kai pºopas. Herm. Irris. c. 4: 'Avač, too 5-ypo? trpeg Burépay &px?iv eival Aéyet thv tov Icívmaruv, kal Taitº, tú Mév 'yevyāg 9at Tö, Öe p6etpea flat. Hip- polyt. l.c. : Tpbs & Tofftºp rivnaiv &fölov efval, év fi orvuòaivet yived 6at rows otpavods. Simpl. Phys. 9, p. : âtrelpöv Tuva pūgiv . . . . dpx?iv ë9ero, is thv diföuov kivmoriv airíav eival ris rôv čvrov 'yevéaea's éAeye. Similarly 107 a ; 257 b. * The expression icv8epvāv, which, in its simplest meaning, signifies the guidance of the ship's movements by the rudder, here re- lates primarily to the movement of the celestial system. * Röth (Gesch. der Abendl. Phil. ii. a, 142) believes that the self- dependent moving force attributed to the Infinite presupposes an in- telligence, a conscious spiritual nature, and that the Infinite of Anaximander must thus be con- ceived as infinite spirit; but this is an entire misapprehension of the contemporary modes of thought, and is contradicted by Aristotle's well-known assertion (Metaph. i. 3, 984 b, 15 sq.) that Anaxagoras was the first who declared vows to be the principle of the world. In appealing for want of any other evidence to the words of Theo- phrastus quoted above (p. 233, 1), he has overlooked the fact that Anaximander is here compared with Anaxagoras only in respect of his definition of the arapatukö, a rol- xeia. Not to mention other inac- curacies, this does away with the discovery, of which Röth (loc. cit.) is so proud, that Anaximander's doctrine of the Štreipov has more theological than physical import- ance, and that it is in complete harmony with the Egyptian theo- logy, as he endeavours to prove. * The text of Simpl. Phys. 107 a, which is only a paraphrase of 250 ANAXIMANDER. We are farther told that he represented particular substances as developing themselves from the primitive matter by means of separation (Éckpivso-flat, àtrokpt- weabat)," and Anaximander himself seems to have used this word;” but what he precisely understood by sepa- ration does not appear. He apparently left this con- ception in the same uncertainty as that of the primitive matter, and that which floated before his mind was merely the general motion of an emergence of the several matters distinct from one another, out of the original homogeneous mass. We hear, on the other hand, that he made the division of heat and cold the first result of this separation.” the passage we have quoted from Aristotle, cannot of course be ad- duced in support of it. I am unable to give such a decided negative to this question as Büsgen does, loc. cit., p. 16 sq.; but Anaximander certainly could not have named his Infinite ºrb 6eſov in the monotheistic sense; he only called it 9eſov, divine. * Arist. Phys. i. 4, vide Supra, p. 234, 3; Plutarch in Eus. loc. cit.; Simpl. Phys. 6 a. oik &AAotov- puévov too ortoixetov riv Yévecru trouet, &AA’ &Irokpwouévov táv čvav- Tlwv Ště, Tâs &föíow kuwägews. And similarly ibid. 32 b ; 51 b (vide supra, pp. 228, 3; 233, 1), where, however, Anaximander's doctrine is too much confused with that of Anaxagoras, Themist. Phys. 18 a ; 19 a (124, 21; 131, 22 sq.); Philo- ponus, Phys. C 2. The incorrect statement of Simplicius that Anax- imander believed in rarefaction and condensation, was no doubt based upon the false supposition that his primitive matter was intermediate From the mixture of between two elements, and that he was consequently alluded to by Aristotle, De Caºlo, iii. 5 (vide Supra, p. 242, 1); Phys. i. 4, at the beginning (vide supra, p. 234, 3); cf. Philoponus, Phys. c. 3. * We gather this partly from the use of the word priori in Arist. loc. cit., and also from considering the manner in which he reduces both the cosmogony of Empedocles and that of Anaxagoras to the concept, €kkpived 6al. Moreover, it is impossible to see how Aristotle and his successor could have been led to attribute the éickpious to An- aximander, unless they had found it in his writings. * Simpl. Phys. 32 b: rös évay- tuármºras . . . Škkpivea'6at pnotiv 'Avačuavöpos . . . Švaviruðtmºres 6é eiot 9epubv, iſvXpov, Šmpov, jºypov Ical ai &AAal. More precisely Plut. (ap. Eus. loc. cit.); qºmal 6& to €k row ââtov yóviptov 6epuoi te łcal juxpod karð. Thu yévéoly Tow8s toū kóapov &Tokpt07val. Stob. Ecl. i. 500 : FORMATION OF THE WORLD. 251 these two he appears to have derived the fluid element," which, like Thales, he regarded as the immediate (though not, like him, as the ultimate) substance of the world. On this account, probably, and perhaps also in imitation of his predecessor, he calls water the seed of the world.” From the fluid universal matter, by successive separations, three kinds of matter were parted off: the earth, the air, and an orb of fire, which surrounds the whole like a spherical crust;” this at least seems to be the meaning of the scattered indications 'A. Šic 6eppot, kal juxpoſſ wiyuaros [eival row oilpavóv]. That Aristotle, as is usually believed, reckoned dryness and moisture among the primordial oppositions, as well as cold and heat, Simplicius does not say: he himself gives, accord- ing to the doctrine of Aristotle, this explanation of the “evavrićrm- Tes.’ * Arist. Meteor. ii. 1, 353 b, 6, mentions the opinion that the trpá- Tov Š-ypov at first filled the whole space around the world, when it was dried up by the sun : Tó uèv 6tarptoſav rvedaara kal Tporås iºtov kal orexhums (paal trouelv, to 6é Aei- q6&v 6&Aatrav sival, and this is why the sea also dries up little by little, Alex. in h, l., p. 91 a (Arist. Meteor. ed. Idel. i. 268; Theo- phrasti Op. ed. Wimmer, iii. fragm. 39) remarks: raûrms Tús Óðims éyévovto, ös ioTope? 6 Oeóppaotos, 'Avačiuavöpós Te Kai Atoyévms. Simi- larly Plac. iii. 16, 1 : ‘A. Thy 64Aaor- oráv pmoliveival tăs trpátims trypacrias Aeſ/avov, is to wºv traetov uépos ăveşāpave to trip, to 8& ŠtroAelq6év 61& Thy kicavoriv pieté8&Aev. This is the Öypôv of which Hermias (vide supra, p. 249, 1) speaks. That in respect to this theory Aristotle or Theophrastus could have said of Anaximander what the work about Melissus (vide supra, 232, 2) says of him; iſèap påuevos éival Tó trav, I cannot admit with Kern (Oeoppé- a row trepl Mexíagov, Philologus, xxvi. 281, cf. Beitr. 2wr Phil. d. Åenoph. 11 sq.); for these words describe water, not only as that out of which the world has arisen, but as that of which it eternally consists, as its a touxetov (in the sense discussed in p. 243, 2), and this contradicts the most distinct declaration of both these philoso- phers. Still less can I allow, with Rose (Arist. libr. ord. 75), that Anaxagoras regarded moisture or water only as the matter of all things, and that the Štreupov, which all our authorities with one accord attributed to him, was foisted upon him by the nomenclature of a later period. * Widel’lutarch, preceding note. * Plut. ap. Eus. according to the quotation, p. 250, 3: kai Tiva èic toūtov ſp?Aoyos orgaipav trepiq oval tº repl rºw yºv &épi, Ös ré 36Vöpp q'Aouáv, fortivos àtroßayeforms ſcal eſs rivas ātrokNeto'6eforms kökxovs inro- orrival rôv #Atov Kai Thy geaftvmw ſcal robs &otépas. 252 ANAXIMANDER. that we find upon the subject." The heavenly bodies were formed of fire and air; when the fiery circle of the universe burst asunder, and the fire was pent up in wheel-shaped husks of compressed air, from the apertures of which it streams forth ; the stoppage of these aper- tures occasions eclipses of the sun and moon, and the waxing and waning of the moon are produced in the same way.” * On the other hand, I cannot agree with Teichmüller (loc. cit. pp. 7, 26, 58) that he conceived his àreupov as originally a great sphere, and the eternal motion of it (supra, p. 248 sq.) as a rotation whereby a spherical envelope of fire was parted off and spread over the surface of the mass. No such notion is ascribed to Anaximander by any of our authorities; for the orqaipa trupés lay, not round the âtreupov, but around the atmosphere of the earth. Indeed, if we say that the Infinite comprehends all things, or all worlds (pp. 242, 1 ; 248, 1), we exclude the presupposi- tion that it is itself comprehended by the limits of our world. But a spherical Infinite is in itself so great and so direct a contradiction, that only the most unquestionable evidence could justify our ascribing it to the Milesian philosopher; and, in point of fact, there exists no evidence for it at all. * Hippolyt. Refut. i. 6; Plut. in Eus. loc. cit.; Plac. ii. 20, 1 ; 21, 1; 25, 1 (Galen. Hist. Phil. 15); Stob. Ecl. i. 510, 524, 548; Theo- doret, Gr. aff. Cur. iv. 17, p. 58 ; Achilles Tatius, Isag. c. 19, p. 138 sq. All these writers agree in what is stated in our text. If, however, we attempt any closer definition of this conception, we find consider- This fire is kept up by the exhalations able divergencies and lacunae in the accounts. Plutarch, ap. Euseb. only says that the sun and moon were formed when the fiery globe burst asunder, and became en- closed within certain circles. Hip- polytus adds that these circles have openings in the places when we see the stars; the stopping up of these occasions eclipses and the phases of the moon. According to the Placiła, Stobaeus, Pseudo-Ga- len, and Theodoret, Anaximander conceived these circles as analogous to the wheels of a cart; there were openings in the hollow circle of the wheel filled with fire, and through these openings the fire streamed out. Finally, Achilles Tatius says that Anaximander thought the sun had the form of a wheel, from the nave of which the light poured in rays (like the spokes) spreading out as far as the circum- ference of the sun. The last theory formerly seemed to me to deserve the preference. I must, however, concede to Teichmüller (Studien, p. 10 sq.), who has carefully ex- amined all the texts on this subject, that that of Achilles Tatius does not look very authentic; and as we are further informed (Plac. ii. 16,3; Stob. 516) that Anaximander made the stars Štrö Töv kölcNov kal Töv orgapóv, €q’ &v čkaoros 8é8mke FORMATION OF THE WORLD. 253 of the earth; and, again, the heat of the sun assists the drying up of the globe and the formation of the sky." That the moon and planets shine by their own light” follows necessarily from Anaximander's theories respecting them. The movement of the heavenly bodies he derived from the currents of air caused q’épearðal, which is confirmed by the Tporal too oëpavoo, attributed to him by Aristotle (Meteor. ii. 2, 355, a, 21), it now appears to me pro- bable that Röth (Gesch. der Abendl. Phil. ii. a, 155) has taken the right view in interpreting the wheel- shaped circles filled with fire (Röth wrongly says encompassed with fire on the outside) as the starry spheres; these spheres, in their rotation, pour forth fire through an aperture, and produce the pheno- menon of a fiery body circling round the earth. As, however, these rings only consist of air, Teichmüller is not wrong (p. 32 sq.) in disputing the theory of solid spheres and a solid firmament (Röth, loc. cit.; Gruppe, Cosm. Syst, d. Gr. p. 37 sqq.) as held by Anaximander. In agreement with this view, there is the statement (Stob. 548; Plac. ii. 25, l ; Galen, c. 15) that, ac- cording to Anaximander, the moon is a circle nineteen times as large as the earth; since it is quite pos- sible that this philosopher, for reasons unknown to us, may have considered the circumference of the moon's orbit (which in that case would coincide with the moon's sphere) to be nineteen times the size of the earth's circumference. When, however, we learn from the same source (Stob. i. 524; Plac. 20, 1 ; 21, 1 ; Galen, Hist. Phil. c. 14, p. 274, 276, 279, K.) that he made the sun's circle twenty-eight times as large as the earth, and the sun itself (the opening of this circle which we behold as the sun's dise) the same size as the earth—this is incompatible with the theory that the sun's circle is the sun's sphere, and its size, consequently, that of the Sun's orbit ; for that the sun's orbit should be only twenty-eight times as large as the sun's disc, is a glaring contradiction of ocular evidence, which we cannot ascribe to Anaximander. Hippolytus, how- ever, says (as Teichmüller, p. 17, rightly observes) eival 5& rov ſcèicAov toū āAtov Štrakaielkogiiraaortova rās orexhums, and if we connect with this the statement that the moon is nineteen times as large as the earth, we shall have the sun's orbit 513 times the size of the earth's circumference, and consequently 513 times that of the sun's circum- ference, which would of course seem sufficient to Anaximander. But from the nature of our evidence we cannot pass certain judgment in the matter. * Arist. Meteor. ii. 1 (cf. p. 251, 1); ibid. c. 2, 355 a, 21, where Anaximander is not indeed men- tioned, but according to Alexan- der's trustworthy statement (loc. cit. and p. 93 b) he is included. * What is asserted in the Pla- cita, ii. 28, and Siob. i. 556, of the moon, is denied by Diog. (ii. 1), but (as appears from the passages we have quoted) without foundation. 254 ANAXIMANDER. by the revolution of the spheres;' his theories on their position and magnitudes” are as arbitrary as we might expect in the childhood of astronomy; if, however, he really taught that the stars were carried round by the movement of circles out of which they received the fires by which they shine, he claims an important place in the history of astronomy as the author of the theory of the spheres. The same would apply to his discovery of the obliquity of the ecliptic,” if this has been rightly * Arist. and Alex., cf. previous note and supra, p. 251, 1. In what way the rotation of the heavens is effected, Aristotle does not say, but his words in c. 2, as also in the passage cited p. 251, 1, from c. 1, can scarcely bear any other construction this: than that the heavens are moved by the rvetua- ra, an idea which is also found in Anaxagoras and elsewhere (Ideler, Arist. Meteor. i. 497). Alexander thus (loc. cit.) explains the words of Aristotle, quoted p. 251, 1: §rypoi, Yêp Švros roß repl thu 'yūv rátrov, rà trpára rās 5)pórmtos 5th Toà j\tov čarpfgeoffat kal ºyſveoróat rô Twetuatd re é; airrot, kal ºrporâs #Atov re ical orexhums, &s 61& T&s &rpitãas raûras kal r&s àvaôupad- orets kāketvov rás Tpotras trotovuévov, ãv6a raûrms attois xopmyſa 'yfveral arepl raúra Tpetropévov. Whether the remark that Theophrastus as- cribes this view to Anaximander and Diogenes, refers to this por- tion of Anaximander's exposition is not quite certain. Teichmüller's theory, loc. cit. 22 sqq., that Anaxi- mander derived the movement of the firmament from the turning of the 3re pov, conceived as spherical, on its axis, I cannot admit, for the reasons given, p. 252, 1, irre- spectively of the testimonies just quoted. Nor can I admit, as Teich- müller alleges, that there is any con- tradiction in my connecting (p. 249, 2) the révra Kv3epváv, ascribed to the Infinite, with the movement of the heavens, while I here derive this movement from the rveſ uara. When Anaximander says that the Infinite by its own movement pro- duces that of the universe, this does not prevent his describing (cf. 250 sq.) more particularly the manner in which that movement is brought about, and seeking accordingly the approximate cause for the revolu- tion of the starry spheres in the currents of the air. * According to Stob. 510, and the Plac. ii. 15, 6, he placed the sun highest, then the moon, and the fixed stars and planets lowest (Röper in Philologus, vii. 609, wrongly gives an opposite inter- pretation). Hippolytus says the same, only without mentioning the planets. On the size of the sun and moon cf. p. 253. The state- ments of Eudemus, quoted p. 234, 2, refer to these theories. * Pliny, Hist. Nat. ii. 8, 31. Others, however, ascribe this dis- covery to Pythagoras; wide infra, Pyth. FORMATION OF THE WORLD. 255 ascribed to him. In accordance with the notions of antiquity, Anaximander, we are told, regarded the stars as gods, and spoke of an innumerable or infinite multitude of heavenly gods." The Earth he supposes to have existed at first in a liquid state, and to have been gradually formed by the drying up of the moisture by means of the surrounding fire; the rest, having become salt and bitter, running - off into the sea.” Its shape he conceives as a cylinder, the height of which is a third part of its breadth; we inhabit its upper surface.” At rest in the centre of all things, its equilibrium is maintained because it is equally distant from the extreme limits of the universe.” The animals also, he thought, originated from primi- tive slime, under the influence of the sun's heat, and as the idea of a gradual succession of animal species cor- responding with the periods of geological formation was 1 Cicero, N. D. i. 10, 25 (after Philodemus), Anaaimandri autem opinio est nativos esse Deos, longis intervallis orientes occidentesque eosque innumerabiles esse mundos. Plac. i. 7, 12: 'Avačíuavöpos toys ãorrépas oipavlovs 6eoûs. Stob. in the parallel passage Ecl. i. 56: *Avačíuavôpos étreqívaro toys &teſ- povs oilpavows 9eoûs; Ps Galen. Hist. Phil. c. 8, p. 251 Ki: ’Avačíuavôpos 6è rolls &teipovs vows (Heeren in Stobaeus, loc. cit. rightly substitutes oùpavows for vows)0sobs elval; Cyrill, c. Jul. i. p. 28 D : 'Avačípavöpos 6ebv biopigeral éival robs dreſpous kóopious. Tert. Adv. Marc. i. 13: Amaarimander universa coºlestia (Deos pronuntiavit). How we are to understand the infinite number of these gods we shall soon more particularly enquire. * Wide supra, p. 251, 1. * Plutarch in Eus. Pr. Ev. i. 8, 2; Plac. iii. 10, 1; Hippolyt. Refut. i. 6. Diogenes (ii. 1) makes the form of the earth spherical instead of cylindrical, but this is an error. Teichmüller goes thoroughly into the subject, loc. cit. 40 sqq. * Arist. De Caelo, ii. 13, 295 b, 10; Simpl. in h. 1. 237 b, 45 sq.; Schol. 507 b, 20; Diog. ii. 1; Hip- polyt., loc. cit. The assertion of Theo. (Astron. p. 324), taken by him from Dercyllides, that Anaxi- mander thought the earth moved around the centre of the universe, is a misapprehension of what he (Anaximander) said as to the sus- pension (ap. Simpl. loc. cit.) of the earth. Alexander expresses himself more cautiously. 256 ANAXIMANDER. naturally beyond his reach, he assumed that the land animals, including man, had at first been fishes, and afterwards, when they were able to develope themselves under their new shape, had come on shore and thrown off their scales." He is said to have regarded the soul as of the nature of air,” and we have no reason to think this improbable; what, however, is more certain, is that in his theories of the origin of rain, of the winds, of thunder and lightning,” almost everything is re- ferred to the influence of air. But these theories have little connection with his philosophic doctrine. As all things were produced from one primitive matter, so must all return to it; for all things, says our philosopher," must undergo, according to the order of time, penance and punishment for their injustice. The separate existence of individual things is, so to speak, a wrong, a transgression which they must expiate by their destruction. Anaxagoras is said to have applied the same principle to the world as a whole, and to have admitted, in consequence, that the world would be destroyed, but that on account of the perpetual motion of the infinite substance, a new world would be 1 Wide Plutarchap. Eus.loc. cit.; Qu. Com. viii. 8, 4; Plac. v. 19. 4; also Brandis, i. 140, but especially Teichmüller, loc. cit. 63 sqq., who rightly calls attention to the points of contact between this hypothesis and the Darwinian theory. But I cannot follow him in his statement (p. 68) that Anaximander, accord- ing to Plutarch, Qu. conv.forbade the eating of fish. Plutarch does not seem to me to say that Anaxi- mander expressly interdicted fish eating, but only that his doctrine of the descent of men from fishes implied that the use of fish as food was unlawful. * Theod. Gr. aff, cur. v. 18, p.72. * Plutarch, Plac. iii. 3, 1,7, 1; Stob. Ecl. i. 590; Hippolyt. loc. cit.; Seneca, Qu, Nat. ii. 18 sq.; Achilles Tatius in Arat. 33; Plin. Hist. Nat. ii. 79, 191, makes Anaxi- mander foretell an earthquake to the Spartans, but adds significantly ‘Si credimus.’ “In the fragment quoted, p. 240, 2. INFINITE SERIES OF JWORLDS. 257 formed; so that there would thus be an endless series of successive worlds. This matter, however, is Open to dispute.' We are repeatedly assured that Anaximander spoke of innumerable worlds, but whether he meant by this, worlds in juxtaposition, or worlds in succession,-- and whether, upon the former theory, he thought of a number of complete systems, separate from each other, or only different parts of one and the same system, are questions that are not easily answered.” Cicero says that Anaximander regarded the countless worlds as gods. This would incline us to the idea of whole systems, like the worlds of Democritus. The countless “heavens’ of which Stobaeus speaks (as also the Pseudo-Galen) seem to necessitate the same interpretation, since Cyrillus substitutes “worlds’ for ‘heavens.’ The Placita, how- ever, have the word ‘stars, and this we must take to have been Anaximander's real meaning. For if he had said the innumerable worlds that are supposed to exist outside our system are gods, he would not merely have stood alone among all the ancient philosophers, but it would be difficult to say how he could have arrived at such a theorem. For in all periods, and without exception, gods have been understood to mean beings that are the objects of human adoration : even the gods of Epicurus are so, though, on their side, they trouble themselves little about men.” But these worlds, entirely with- drawn from our perceptions and sight, and admitted only on the strength of a speculative hypothesis, are not * Wide Schleiermacher, loc. cit. p. 255, 1. 195 sq.; Krische, Forsch. i. 44 sqq. * Cf. Part III. a, 395, second * Wide the texts given, supra, edition. WOL. I. S 258 A NAXIMANDER. capable of inspiring our adoration, and have nothing in themselves that could appeal to the feeling of piety; whereas the ancient worship of the stars, deeply rooted as it was in the Hellenic modes of thought, is to be met with perpetually, as we know, among the philoso- phers. Anaximander's countless gods must, therefore, be the stars. The explanation of his likewise calling these gods “heavens’ may be found in what we have gathered about his conception of the stars. That which we behold under the form of Sun, moon, or stars, is to Anaximander only a luminous aperture in a ring which is formed of air and filled with fire, and rotates at a greater or less distance around the earth. The con- centric light-emitting rings which thus surround us, and together with the earth form the universe, might therefore be properly called heavens, and perhaps they might be called worlds; but it is likewise possible that later writers, adopting the language of their own times, may have substituted “worlds’ for ‘heavens’ by way of explanation or emendation. Besides, Anaximander might well speak in this sense of an infinite number of heavens, since (in accordance with this theory) he must have regarded the fixed stars, not as placed in a single sphere,” but each one as the aperture of its own ring. For at so early a period as Anaximander's, it ought not to surprise us if that which no man could reckon were called infinite in number. * Simplicius, for example, says * Such a sphere must have (in the passage quoted supra, p. 233, been perforated like a sieve, since i) of Anaxagoras, to whom nobody each star indicates an opening in attributed the theory of several it; and (according to p. 254, 3) it systems, that vows, accordingtohim, would have hidden the sun and produced roës re réguous kal Thy moon from us. rów &AAwv pågiv. IWFINITE SERIES OF WORLDS. 259 On the other hand, the assertion which ascribes to Anaximander an infinity of successive worlds seems to be borne out by his system. The correlative of the world's formation is the world's destruction; if the world, as a living being, developed itself at a definite epoch out of a given matter, it may easily be supposed that it will also be dissolved, like a living being, into its constituent elements again. If creative force and movement, as essential and original qualities, be ascribed to this primitive matter, it is only logical to conclude that by virtue of its vitality it will produce another world after the destruction of our own ; and for the same reason it must have produced other worlds prior to the earth. Thus we assume an infinite series of successive worlds in the past and in the future. Plutarch, indeed, expressly says of Anaximander, that from the Infinite, as the sole cause of the birth and destruction of all things, he considered that the heavens and the innumerable worlds arise in endless circulation," and Hippolytus speaks to the same effect.” “The Infi- nite of Anaximander,’ he says, “eternal and never growing old, embraces all the worlds; but these have each of them a set time for their arising, their exist- ! Ap. Eus. Pr. Ev. i. 8, 1: * Refut. i. 6: ośros àpx?iv čpm ('Avaštuavöpóv pagi) to &melpov ºdval rhv traorav airíav čxelv ris roß travros yewéore&s re . . . kal (p60pás. &E of 6% pmol rods re očpavois &mokekpio'0ai kai ka96Xov robs &mav- ras &melpovs $vras kóopovs. štreq’ſ- waro 5& Thy péopây yívea 6al ical troAt Trpárepov rºw yéveauv é; &neipov aióvos àvakvk}\ovuévov ºrdvrov aúróv. Töv Švrov quoru Tuva roß &reipov, & is yívea 6al rows oipavous kal rotºs év airrois kócruous. Taºrmv 6’ &föuov eival kal dyſipw, hw kal Trávras repuéxeiv roës kóorpiows. Aéyet 6* xpóvov &s épio uévris tims Yevéorews kal ris oùortas kal Täs p00pas. These pro- positions seem, by the way, to be taken from another source from what follows. S 2 260 ANAXIMANDER. ence, and their destruction.” Cicero, too,” makes mention of innumerable worlds, which in long periods of time arise and perish; and Stobaeus attributes to Anaximander the theory of the future destruction of the world.” This is also countenanced by the state- ment that he believed in a future drying up of the Sea," for in that case there would be an increasing prepon- derance of the fiery element, which must ultimately result in the destruction of the earth, and of the system of which it forms the centre. The same theory of a constant alternation of birth and destruction in the universe was held by Heracleitus, who approaches more closely to Anaximander than to any of the ancient Ionian physicists, and also most probably by Anaxi- menes and Diogenes. We have reason, therefore, to suppose that Anaximander also held it; and that he already taught the doctrine of a perpetual vicissitude between the separation of | In neither of these passages can the innumerable worlds be un- derstood otherwise than as succes- sive worlds. When Hippolytus directly connects with his mention of the kóo wou the remark that the time of their beginning is deter- mined, this can only mean that these céopot have a definite dura- tion, and we must then explain the plurality thus: there are many worlds, because each world only lasts for a time. The connection of the two propositions, that the &metpov is eternal, and that it em- braces all worlds –points to the same result. It might embrace all coexisting worlds even if it were not eternal; but it could only em- brace successive worlds, if it out- things from the primitive lasted them all. With Plutarch, the arising or passing away too Tavros and the āvakvKMovuévaev trávrav airów, sufficiently show that successive worlds are intended. * In the passage quoted at length, Supra, p. 255, 1, where the words, longis intervallis orientes occidentesque, can only apply to worlds of which one arises when the other disappears, even supposing that Cicero or his authority con- fused these worlds with the Štreipot oùpavol designated as gods by Anaximander. * Ecl. i. 416. Anaximander . . . q6aprov 'rby icóopov. * Theophrastus, and probably also Aristotle, Supra, p. 151, 1. INFINITE SERIES OF WORLDS. 261 matter, and their return to primitive matter; as well as an endless series of worlds in succession, which was the natural result of that doctrine." Whether he likewise maintained the co-existence of an infinite number of systems, or of a plurality of systems apart from one another, as the Atomists after- wards did, is another question. Simplicius, and ap- parently Augustine, assert this of him ; * and some few modern writers have agreed with them.” But Augus- time certainly does not speak from his own knowledge, and he does not tell us his authority. Nor is Simplicius ! What Schleiermacher urges (loc. cit. 197) against this theory does not seem to me conclusive. Anaximander, he thinks (according to the texts quoted, supra, p. 229, 2, 3), could not have supposed a time in which generation was ar- rested, and this must have been the case from the commencement of a world's destruction to the arising of a new world. But in the first place, the words, iva # yéveals wh étriNeſtm, do not assert that ‘gene. ration may never and in no way be arrested, but rather that “the generation of perpetually new beings can never cease.’ It does not cease if it is continued in a new world instead of the one destroyed; and thus it becomes very questionable whether we can attribute to Anaxi- mander a notion which, strictly understood, would exclude a begin- ning as well as an end of the world; namely, the notion that on account of the incessant activity of the first cause (vide Sup. p. 249, 1) the world can never cease to exist. He might think that he was proving this activity all the more conclu- sively by making it always form a new world after the destruction of an old one. Rose's opinion (Arist. lib. ord, 76) that the theory of an alternative formation and des- truction of worlds is a vetustissuma Cogitandi ratione plane aliena has been already answered in the text. We find this theory in Anaximenes, Heracleitus, and Diogenes (to all of whom, however, Rose equally denies it); and moreover in Empe- docles. * Simpl. Phys. 257 b : of wév ºyap &meſpous ré, traj6et rows kóg- povs 5to8éuevoi, &s of trepi 'Avač- tuavópov kai Aevicintrov kai Amuákpi- tov Kal iſatepov of trep) 'Emíkovpov, ºuvouévows airobs kal pſeupowevous itré9evro èr (itempov, &Awu prév &ei Yuvouévov &AAwu 8& pºetpouévov. Cf. inf. p. 262, 2. Aug. Cºv. D. viii. 2: rerum principia singularum esse credidit infinita, et innumerabiles mundos gigmere et quaecumque in eis oriuntur, eosque mundos modo dis- Solvi modo iterum gign existimavit, quanta quisque aetate sua manere potuerit. * Büsgen especially, p. 18 sq. of the work mentioned (supra, p. 235, 1). ANA XIMANDER. quoting from Anaximander's writings,' and he clearly betrays that he is not sure of what he is saying.” No trustworthy evidence from any other source can be cited in favour of this philosopher's having held such a theory,” a theory which his * As already observed on p. 237 sq , and clearly proved by the con- tradiction s resulting from the com- parison of the expressions shown to be his, supra, pp. 233, 1 ; 241, 6; 244, 1, 2. * Cf. De Colo, 91 b, 34 (Schol. in Ar. 480 a, 35): of 5& kal rô TAñ6el & reſpous kóquovs, &s 'Avašt- aavópos pièv Štreipov tº preyéðel thy āpx?iv 0éuevos, &meſpous é; avrov [—tfis] tº trafiðel Kóruous roleſv § 0 k e º Aeſkirtros 3& kai Amuákpt- ros &tetpovs ré, traí6el Tovs köopovs, &c. 1/id. 273, b 43: kal kóguous &metpovs of ros kal ékaotov Tów kóguav čğ direpov too towātov grouxetov Štré6ero, ös 6 o ice t. * The state of the case in re- gard to Cicero and Philodemus has already been investigated, pp. 257; 260, 2; where the passages cited (p. 259, 1, 2) from Hippolytus and Plutarch have also been sufficiently considered. Plutarch indeed says in the preterite: Toàs re oipovows &rokekpío 6al ſcal ſcaflóxov robs &mav- tas dreſpous āvras kóa'uovs, but that proves nothing; for in the first place the kóa'uoi may have the same meaning as oilparol (cf. p. 258), and in the next, it might be said of successive worlds that an infinite number of them had come forth from the étreupov ; for they had already been innumerable in the past. It has also been shown (p. 257) that Stobaeus, i. 56, proves nothing. When Stobaeus (i. 496) says "Avačíuavöpos 'Avačºvávns 'Ap- xéAaos Eevoq'dvms Atoyévns Aeëlcitr- general system not merely tros Amuáxpitos 'Earíkovpos direipovs kóa pious év tá, direfpq cató, traorav treptaya”) hy. Tov 8' dreipovs &moſph- vapiévov toos Kóguous 'Avačuavöpos To toov attoos & réxeiv &AAñAwy, 'Eiríkovpos &viorov eival to we'raču Töv kóo wov čudo-rmua, his meaning no doubt is that Anaximander, like Democritus and Epicurus, believed in numberless coexistent worlds, and this likewise holds good of Theodoret (Cur. gr. aff. iv. 15, p. 58), who attributes to the same philosophers, enumerated in the same order as Stobaeus, troAAoûs kai Greipovs kóopious. Theodoret, however, is evidently not an in-, dependent witness, but has been drawing upon the text, the words of which Stobaeus gives more completely. The account itself also seems here to be very untrust- worthy. For little confidence can be placed in an author who attributes the ātreupou kóguoi to Anaximenes, Archelaus, and Xenophanes, and by the addition of karū traorav Treptaywyhv, which is quite inappli- cable to the Atomists and Epicure- ans, clearly betrays that he is here confusing two different theories, that which makes innumerable sug- cessive worlds to proceed from the replaywyal (the circular motion spoken of by Plutarch, supra, p. 259, 1), and that which main- tains innumerable contemporaneous worlds. What Anaximander really said concerning the equal distance of the worlds, whether his utterance related to the distance in space of INFINITE SERIES OF WORLDS. 263 does not require, but often actually contradicts. We might imagine that it necessarily resulted from the unlimitedness of matter; but the successors of Anaxi- mander, Anaximenes, Anaxagoras, and Diogenes, prove how little such necessity existed at that early stage of thought. None of them find any difficulty in supposing our world to be limited, while the matter surround- ing it, and not formed into any other worlds, extends itself to infinity. The reflection which Schleiermacher attributes to our philosopher,' that there must be many worlds, in order that death and destruction may rule in one, while life and vitality prevail in another, appears much too artifical for the time. It is, therefore, difficult to see how Anaximander could have been led to a theory which is so entirely independent of the sensible intuition, the immediate origin of all ancient cosmology. Such a theory must, indeed, have been peculiarly remote from a philosopher holding so de- cidedly, as Anaximander did, that every particular was derived from one first principle, and returned to it again.” Democritus was quite logical when he made his innumerable atoms, which were guided by no uniform principle, combine with one another in the most diverse parts of infinite space, and so form independent world- systems. Anaximander, on the contrary, starting from his conception of the One Unlimited which rules all things, could only arrive at the theory of a single universe, combined by the unity of the force that forms the world. the vipavoi, or to the distance in Loc. cit. p. 200 sq. time of the successive worlds, we * As Schleiermacher himself cannot determine. acknowledges, loc. cit. 197, 200. 264 ANAXIMANDER. If we now compare Anaximander's doctrine, as re- presented in our present enquiry, with what we know of the doctrine of Thales, we shall find that it is far richer in content, and betokens a higher development of philo- sophic thought. I am not indeed inclined to ascribe any great significance to the conception which is prin- cipally dwelt on by historians as constituting the most convenient designation for Amaximander's principle, viz., the infinity of primitive matter; for the endless succession of natural creations, which chiefly determined Amaximander in adopting it, might have been attained independently of this principle;' and the unlimited extension of the world in space, which would have ne– cessitated it, was not taught, as we have seen, by this philosopher. On the other hand, it is an important fact that Amaximander should have taken for his point of departure, not a determinate substance like Thales, but indeterminate and infinite matter; and whatever may have led him to such a doctrine, it implies an advance on his part beyond merely sensuous observation. Thales said nothing about the manner in which things arise out of the primitive matter. The “separation' of Anaxi- mander is still sufficiently vague, but it is at any rate an attempt to form some notion of the process, to reduce the multiplicity of phenomena to the most general oppo- sitions, and to attain a physical theory of the genesis of the world, free from the mythical elements of the an- cient theogonic cosmology. The ideas of Anaximander on the system of the world, and the origin of living beings, not only show reflection, but have exercised * As Aristotle observes, vide supra, p. 229, 3. HIS HISTORICAL POSITION. 265 important influence on subsequent philosophy. Finally, he admitted a beginning as well as an end of our world, and an infinite series of successive worlds. This doc- trime evinces remarkable consistency of thought. It is besides the first step towards the abandonment of the mythical notion of the origin of the world in time, and through the idea that creative force can never have been idle, it prepared the way for the Aristotelian doc- trine of the eternity of the world. I cannot, however, agree in the opinion that Anaxi- mander should be separated from Thales and from his successors, and assigned to a special order of develop- ment. This opinion has been maintained in modern times and on opposite grounds by Schleiermacher' and Ritter:” by Schleiermacher, because he sees in Anaxi- mander the commencement of speculative natural science; by Ritter, because he regards him as the founder of the mechanical and more experimental physics. With reference to the latter, it has already been shown that Anaximander's theory of nature has as little a mechanical character as that of his predecessor or immediate successors, and that he especially approxi- mates to Heracleitus, the typical dynamist. For the same reasons, Schleiermacher is incorrect in asserting that, in contrast with Thales and Anaximenes, his ten- dency is more towards the particular than the universal; for Anaximander was remarkably strict in upholding the unity of animate nature.” He admits, indeed, that * On Anaximander, loc. cit. p. 177 sq., 202. 188; Gesch. der Phil. 25, 31 sq. * Wide supra, p. 256, and * Gesch. der Phil. i. 214, 280 Schleiermacher on Anaximander, sqq., 345; cf. Gesch. der Ion. Phil. p. 197, who is styled by him the 266 ANA XIMENES. contraries emanate from the primitive substance; but this proves nothing, since Anaximenes and Diogenes hold the same opinion. Lastly, I must dispute the assertion of Ritter that Anaximander owed nothing to Thales. Even supposing that from a material point of view he appropriated none of Thales’ ideas, it was formally of the highest importance that Thales should first have instituted the enquiry concerning the universal principle of all things. We have, however, already seen that Anaxi- mander was probably connected with Thales, not only by his hylozoism, but by the particular theory of the liquid state of the earth in its commencement. If we farther consider that he was a fellow citizen and younger con- temporary of Thales, and that both philosophers were well known and highly esteemed in their native city, it seems unlikely that no impulse should have been received by the younger from the elder; and that Anaximander, standing midway chronologically between his two com- patriots, Thales and Anaximenes, should be isolated from them scientifically. The contrary will become still more apparent when we see the influence exercised by Anaximander over his own immediate successor. III. ANAXIMENES.” THE philosophic theory of Anaximenes is generally de- scribed by the proposition that the principle or ground philosopher ‘whose whole enquiry know hardly anything, except that inclines so decidedly to the side of he came from Miletus, and that his unity and the subordination of all father's name was Euristratus oppositions.' (Diog. ii. 3; Simpl. Phys. 6 a). * Gesch. der Phil. i. 214. Later writers represent him as * Of the life of Anaximenes we a disciple (Cic. Acad. ii. 37, 118; AIR. • 267 of all things is air." That he meant by air something different from the element of that name, and distin- guished air, the elementary substance, from the atmo– spheric air,” cannot be proved, nor is it probable. He says indeed that air in its pure condition is invisible, and that it is only perceptible through the sensations of its coldness, warmth, moisture, and motion; * but this Diog. ii. 3; Aug. Civ. D. viii. 2); friend (Simpl. loc. cit. De Caºlo, 273 b, 45; Schol. 514 a, 33); ac- quaintance (Eus. Pr. Ev. x. 14, 7); or successor (Clem. Strom. i. 301 A. Theodoret, Gr. aff, cur. ii. 9, p. 22, Aug. l.c.) of Anaximander. Though it is probable, from the relation of their doctrines, that there was some connection between the two philosophers, these state- ments are clearly based, not on his— torical tradition, but on a mere combination, which, however, has more foundation than the strange statement (ap. Diog. ii. 3) that he was a pupil of Parmenides. Ac- cording to Apollodorus, in Diog. loc. cit., he was born in the 63rd Olympiad (528–524 B.C.), and died about the time of the conquest of Sardis. If by the latter is meant the conquest by the Ionians under Darius in the 70th Olympiad (499 B.C.), which is used nowhere else as a chronological epoch, Anaxi- menes would have died 45–48 years after Anaximander; on the other hand, in that case, Ol. 63 would seem much too late for his birth. To obviate this difficulty Hermann (Philos. Ion. art. 9, 21) proposes to substitute for Ol. 63, Ol. 55 (as given in Euseb. Chron.); and Röth (Gesch. der Abendl. Phil. ii. a, 242 sq.) Ol. 53. As, however, Hippolytus (Refut. i. 7, end) places the prime of Anaximenes in Ol. 58, 1, Diels (Rhein. Mus. xxxi. 27) is probably right in his conjecture that the passage in Diogenes should be thus transposed: ye yévmºral pºv . . trepi Thy Xépôeavy &Aworiv, érexeirmore 5& rà éémkootfi rpírm ôAvpurić64, and that Suidas thence derives his statement: yé yovev čv ºrf ve ÖAvutrigăt v tí, Zápéeov &Adéo et àre Köpos é IIépons Kpoºrov kaffelaev. Only, says Diels, Suidas or some later interpolator has wrongly introduced Eusebius's date év tá ve ÖAvutridói. The conquest of Sardis that Diogenes means is the conquest by Cyrus (Ol. 58, 3, or 546 B.C.), and the word, yé yovev, or yeyévrral (as is often the case) relates not to the birth, but to the time of life, the ākpah. The work of Anaximenes, a small fragment of which has been handed down to us, was, according to Diogenes, written in the Ionic dialect ; the two insignificant letters to Pytha- goras, which we find in Diogenes, are of course apocryphal. * Arist. Metaph. i. 3,984 a, 5, *Avašupévms 6* &épa kai Atoyévms trpórepov iſãaros kal udator’ &pxhv Tubéag, rôv &m Aóv orwad rov, and all later writers without excep- tion. * As is assumed by Ritter, i. 217, and still more decidedly by Brandis, i. 144. * Hippolyt. Refut. haer. i. 7: 'Avačuptévns 6: . . . &épa štepov špm 208 AWAXIMEWES. is perfectly applicable to the air around us, and our au– thorities evidently so understand it, for they none of them ever allude to such a distinction, and the majority of their texts expressly designate the primitive matter of Amaximenes as one of the four elements, as a qualitatively determined body." On the other hand, he ascribed one property to the air, which Anaximander had already employed to discriminate primitive being from all things derived; he defined it as infinite in regard to quantity. This is not only universally attested by later writers,” but Amaximenes himself implies such an opinion” in saying that the air em- braces the whole world; for when the air is conceived as not comprehended by the vault of heaven, it is much easier to imagine it spread out to infinity than to place any definite bound to so volatile a substance. Moreover definita. Thy cºpyhv eival, é, oi, Tū yevópeva Tà yeyovára kal rà éoróweva kal 6eous kal 6eia yive00al, Tå Öè Aottrö. Ák rôv roštov diroyávov. To hè siè0s toū dépos rouot,Tov Štav učv čua- A&Taros ?, tºyel &3m2 ov, 5mA000.0at 5é ré juxpº kal Tá, 6epu% ſcal T6 votepº kal tº kivovuévg. * E. g. Aristotle, loc. cit., and Phys. i. 4; Plut. ap. Eus. Pr. Ev. i. 8, 3: 'Avačiuévnv 6é pagi thv táv &Awv &px?iv rov &épa sineſv Kal •rodrov eival rig utv yével &meipov Tais 5è treph airbv trouárma w &ptopué- vov. Simpl. Phys. 6 a., u : uſav pºv Thy jirokeupévmy pilotu kal &melpóv qmaiv . . . oilk &éptorov 8& . . . &AA& &ptoruévnv, &épa Aérywv airfiv. So De Caelo, vide infra, p. 270, 3. 2 Plut. and Hippol., vide the two previous notes. Cic. Acad. ii. 37, 118: Anaarimenes infinitum aera ; Sed ea, qua ea eo orirentur N. D. i. 10, 26: Anaari- 'memes aera deum, statuit, eumqué gigmi (a misapprehension on which cf. Krische, i. 55) esseque immensum et infinitum et semper in motu ; Diog. ii. 3: ośros doxhv dépa eitre kal rô &tepov; Simplicius, Phys. 5 b: 'Avačíuavöpov, ka? 'Avačuévnv . §v učv, &meipov 8& Tópleyéðel to orrotxeſov Štrobeuévows ; ibid. 6 a., vide preceding note; ibid. 105 b, vide supra, p. 219, 1; ibid. 273 b: év Tó &retp% . . . tº 'Avačiué- vows kal 'Avačiudvöpov. Also Sim- plicius, De Caelo, vide infra; ibid. 91 b, 32 (Schol. 480 a, 35): 'Ava- Épévms row dépa šmeipov dipx?iv eival Aéyajv. * In the words quoted by Plut. Plac. i. 3, 6 (Stob. Ecl. i. 296): ofov ji juxh ji huerépa &hp of ora orvykpare: huàs, kal 3Xov row itéopov wveſſua kal &hp trepiéxet. AIR. 269 Aristotle' mentions the theory according to which the world is surrounded by the boundless air. This passage, it is true, may also apply to Diogenes or Archelaus, but Aristotle seems to ascribe the infinity of primitive matter to all those who consider the world to be sur- rounded by this matter. We can scarcely doubt there- fore that Amaximenes adopted this conception of Anaxi- mander. He also agrees with him in the opinion that the air is in constant movement, is perpetually changing its forms,” and consequently perpetually generating new things derived from it; but what kind of movement this is, our authorities do not inform us.” Phys. iii. 4; wide supra, p. 219, 2 ; ibid. c. 6, 206 b, 23: ágrep qaolv of pugio.Aóyot, To £o orapua ro5 káguov, oš i obota h &AA0 tº rotojrov, &tepov elvai. Cf. also the passage quoted on p. 242, 1 ; De Caelo, iii. 5. - 2 Plutarch ap. Eus. Pr. Ev. i. 8, according to the quotation on p. 268, 1: Yevvågøal 3& révra kará riva Tüc- vagu rotºrov, kal tróAw &patagu'. +hy ye who kivmotiv č aióvos &T- &pxeiv. Cic. N. D. i. 10 (note 1). Hippolyt, according to the quota: tion, sup. p. 268, 1: Kluetotal 5: Kal &et ot, yapuetaBáAAelvöga Heraß- Aet, ei º Kivoiro. Simpl. Phys. 6 a kívnow 68 kal oitos diólov Troteſ St’?)w kal Thy petafloºr Ytve- orðal. Thereason why he was never- theless reproached, Plut. Plac. i. 3, 7, for recognising no moving cause, is well explained by Krische, Forsch. 54, in reference to Arist. Metaph. i. 3, 984 a, 16 Sqq. * Teichmüller (Studien, &c. p. 76 sqq.) thinks, as in regard to Anaximander (Sup. p. 252, 1), that this was a revolving mo- Lastly, it is said tion; that the infinite air was supposed to rotate from eternity. I cannot acquiesce in this view, if only for the reason that not one of our authorities recognises such a theory. A rotation of the Unlimited seems to me in itself so contra- dictory a notion that we ought not to ascribe it to Anaximenes, except on overwhelming evidence; if we would represent to ourselves the eternal motion of matter, the ana- logy of the atmospheric air would far more readily support the theory of a swinging movement. Telchmüller appeals to Arist. De Caelo, ii. 13, 295 a, 9: (&ort' ei Big vov i yü uévet, kal avv^x6ev Čiri to Mégov qepowevm 5ta rhv 5tvmoriv, raş- tnu y&p thv airlaw ºrdvres Aéryovoriv, ôto 63 kai rºv yiv rávres àorot Tov oùpavöv yewv&oriv, Širl to uéorov orvy- ex0ely partv); but this passage (even apart from what will be observed concerning it later on) seems to me of small importance in the question; for it does not say whether the whirling motion which, in the formation of the world car- 270 ANAXIMENES. of him, as of Amaximander, that he declared his primi- tive matter to be the divinity; whether he expressly did so is questionable and improbable, since like his predecessor (vide supra) he reckoned the gods among created beings. But in point of fact, the statement is not untrue, because, for him also, primitive matter was at the same time primitive force, and so far, the creative cause of the world.” Simplicius says” that Anaximenes made air his first principle because of its variable nature, which especially fits it to be the substratum of changing phenomena. According to the utterances of Anaximenes himself," he seems to have been led to this theory chiefly by the analogy of the world with a living being. It appeared to him (in agreement with the ancient opinion, founded on the evidence of the senses) that in men and animals the expiration and inspiration of the air is the cause of life, and of the cohesion of the body; for when the breathing ' ceases or is hindered, life becomes extinct, * Röth (Gesch. der Abendl. Phil. ii. a, 250 sqq.) opposes Anaximenes ried the terrestrial substances into the centre, existed before these substances; and this by no means necessarily follows. Democritus, for instance, does not conceive the atoms as originally whirling; that movement arises only at certain points from the percussion of the atoms. 1 Cicero, N. D. loc. cit.; Stob. Eel. i. 56 : 'Avač. Tov &épa (6eov âtreqfivaro); Lactantius, Inst. i. 5, p. 18: Bip. Cleanthes et Anarimenes aethera dictint esse Stºmmu'm Dewm. IHere, however, aether is used in the modern sense, Tert. contr. Marc. i. 13, Amazinemes aerum (Deum pronuntiavit). to Xenophanes, and says that he started from the concept of spirit as the primitive divinity. He calls him accordingly the first spiritual- ist. But this gives a very false notion of the import of his prin- ciple, and the way in which he arrived at it. * De Coelo, 273 b, 45; Schol. in Arist. 514 a, 33: Avačluevms 6& éraipos 'Avačipid vôpov kal troAfrns &tepov Pušv kal airbs fºré9ero rhy &px?iv, oi, whv štt &óptorov, &épa y&p *Aeyev elval, oióHevos &okeſv to roſ, &épos et axxoforov trpos uera&oxfiv. * Wide supra, p. 268, 3. RA REFACTION AND CONDENSATION. 271 the body decomposes and perishes. It was natural for Anaximenes to suppose that such might also be the case with the world. For the belief that the world was animate was very ancient, and had already been intro- duced into physics by his predecessors. So in the manifold and important effects of the air, which are patent to observation, he readily found proof that it is the air which moves and produces all things. But philosophy had not yet attained to the discrimination of motive cause from matter. The above announcement, therefore, was equivalent to saying that the air is the primitive matter; and this theory was likewise sup- ported by common observation, and by a conjecture which might easily occur to the mind. Rain, hail, and snow, on the one hand, and fiery phenomena on the other, may equally be regarded as products of the air. Thus the idea might easily arise that the air must be the matter out of which all the other bodies are formed, some of them tending upwards, and others downwards; and this opinion might likewise be based on the appa- rently unlimited diffusion of the air in space, especially as Anaximander had declared the infinite to be the primitive substance. All things then, says Anaximenes, spring from the air by rarefaction or by condensation." These processes i Aristotle (Phys. i. 4, sub init. De Coelo, iii. 5, sub init. vide supra, p. 243, 1) ascribes this theory to a whole class of natural philosophers. It was so peculiar to Anaximenes that Theophrastus assigns it to him alone (perhaps, however, he means alone among the earliest philoso- phers), vide supra, p. 224, 2. For further testimony, cf. Plut. De Pr. Frig. 7, 3, supra, p. 272, 2; Plut. ap. Eus. Pr. Ev. i. 8, 3, supra, p. 269. 2: Hippolyt. Refut. i. 7 ; Hermias, Irris. c. 3; Simpl. Phys. 6 a ; 32 a. The expressions by which rarefaction and condensation are designated are various. Aris- totle says Advooris and trókvooris; in- 272 ANAXIMENES. he seems to have regarded as resulting from the move- ment of the air." Rarefaction he makes synonymous with heating, and condensation with cooling.” The stages through which matter has to pass in the course of these transformations he describes somewhat un- methodically. By rarefaction air changes into fire; by condensation it becomes wind, then clouds, then water, then earth, lastly stones. bodies compound bodies are then formed.” stead of pºd woots, Plutarch and Simplicius have àpators, āpatov- a 6al; Hermias has āpatočgevos kal 6taxeówevos ; Hippolytus, Štav eis To &patótepov 8taxv67. According to Plutarch, De Pr. Frig. (cf. Simpl. Phys. 44 b), Anaximenes him- self seems to have spoken of con- centration, of relaxation, extension or loosening. The Anaximandrian doctrine of separation is only at- tributed to him in Mörbeke's re- translation (Ald. 46 a, m) of Simplicius; De Caelo, 91 b, 43; (Schol. 480 a, 44): the genuine text has instead of 5& éé Évès travra. Tyívea 6a Aéyovort kar’ eißeſav (so that the transmutation of matters only follows one direction, and does not go on in a circle, as with Hera- cleitus): ās’Avačiuavöpos kai 'Avaş- tuévns. In Phys. 44 a, rarefaction and condensation are explained by Simplicius in his own name, as oriry- kpions and bidºpiois. * Wide supra, p.269,2.cf. p. 270. * Plut. Pr. Frig. 7, 3, p. 947: # ka94 rep ’Avačiuévns 6 traXabs $ero, pºſite to juxpov čv oborig u%re to 9eppäv àtroAetropiev, &AA& ré0m kowo, rås iſãms étriylvöueva Tats aeragoNaſs to Yap overtexNéuevov airis ical trukvoúuevov ºvXobv elvaí qmail, to 8& àpatov ſcal to XaAapov From these simple The texts (oira, tra's Övouáo as kal Tô Đàuart) 6epuðv. In support of this, as is further observed, Anaximenesurged that the air which is breathed out with the open mouth is warm, and that which is ejected in closing the lips is cold; the explanation given by Aristotle being that the one is the air inside the mouth, and the other the air outside it, Hippol. loc.cit. (p. 267, 3, and note 3, infra). According to Porphyry, ap. Simpl. Phys. 41 a, Ald. Anaximenes re- garded the moist and the dry as fundamental contraries; this state- ment is, however, open to suspicion; the more so, because Simplicius bases it upon a hexameter, which he says emanated from Anaximenes, but which is elsewhere ascribed to Xenophanes (vide infra, chapter on Xenophanes), and which cannot have been taken from the prose of Anaximenes. Most likely, as Brandis thinks (Schol. 338 b, 31, loc. cit.), Eevoſpávmy should be sub- stituted for 'Avačplēvmv. * Simpl. Phys. 32 a ; and pre- viously in the same terms, p. 6 a : 'Avačuévns àpatočaevov učv Töv &épa trop yived 6at q\mat, trukvoú- uevov 6* &veuov, eita vépos, eita èrt paxxov iſãop, -īra 'yūv, eira Atôovs, to be taxa €ic rotºrwy. Hippol. FORMATION OF THE WORLD. 273 inexact as to this point. the air first produced the for that reason, supported after the passage quoted p. 267, 3: Trvkvoiaevov yap kal &patočaevov Sud- qopov paived 6al 3rav Yap eis rô apatórepov 6taxv0ſ, trip yívea flat, puéora's 5& étrév eis dépa trukvoúuevov é; &épos vépos dirorexeo 0f karū thv tróAmoriv, instead of which, perhaps, we should read: uéows Śē td.Xiv eis dépa, Trvkv. č &ép. véq. atroteWeſtorðat k. T. trixmou—as Röper (Philol. vii. contend—perhaps, however, dvé- povs may be concealed in the Aéorws, and the following words should be otherwise amended: étu 8è uáAAov iſèap, Éirl traetov truk- va,0évra yiv, kal eis to udzuara truk- ydºratov Atôovs. šare rà kvpu%rata Tús Yevéarea's évavría éival 6spuév te kal juxpóv . . . . &véuovsö& Yevvā- oréal, &rav ćiciretrukvouévos 6 &#p āpaia,0els pépmrat (which no doubt means, when the condensed air spreads itself out anew; unless we should substitute for &pata,0ets, &p6els, carried up aloft, which, in spite of the greater weight of the condensed air, would be quite as possible in itself as the presence (p. 274, 2) of earth-like bodies in the heavens), givvex9óvra ö& kai étrl TAeſov traxv6évra vépm yeuvâ0.0at [Yevráv, or, avvex0ávros kal étri TAetov traxv0évros v. yewvāorðat], kal oùrws eis iſãop HeragáàAeiv. ' Cic. Acad. ii. 37, 118: gigni autem terram aquam igment tum exc yeyevia:6at Aé-yely rºv yiv. 610), and Duncker (in his edition) WOL. I. T therefore which suppose Anaximenes to have fixed the number of the elements at four," are to be considered In the formation of the world, the condensation of earth,” which Anaximenes conceived as broad and flat, like the slab of a table, and by the air.” He ascribed his omnia. Hermias loc. cit.; Ne- mes. Nat. Hom. c. 5, p. 74, has the same, but less precisely. * Plut. ap. Eus. Pr. Ev. i. 8, 3 : triXoupévov 8& roß &époc trpcºrnu The same follows from the theory that the stars first arose out of the va- pours of the earth. How the earth came first to be formed, and took its place in the centre of the uni- verse, is not explained. The words triNovuévov roß &épos in Plutarch admit of the notion that in the condensation of the air the densest parts sank downwards. Instead of this, Teichmüller (loc. cit. p. 83) prefers to account for it by the theory of the whirling motion (of which we have spoken supra, p. 269, 3); but the passage from Aris- totle, De Coelo, ii. 13, there quoted, does not seem to me to justify this course; for the word "rdvres in this passage cannot be so strained as to include every individual phi- losopher who ever constructed a cosmogony. For example, Plato (Tim. 40 B) knows nothing of the 6tvmoris. Heracleitus never men- tions it, and the Pythagoreans did not place the earth in the centre of the universe. * Aristotle, De Caelo, ii. 13, 294 b, 13; Plutarch ap. Eus. loc. cit.; Plac. iii. 10, 3, where Ideler, without any reason, would | --------, -, -, ºr r-,--- rary;…---r . . . r. . . ºil 274 ANAXIMENEs. the same form to the sun and stars, which he likewise thought were floating in the air;" in regard to their origin, he supposed that the increasing rarefaction of the vapours ascending from the earth produced fire; and that this fire, pressed together by the force of the rotation of the heavens, formed the stars, to which a terrestrial nucleus was therefore ascribed.” He is said to have been the first to discover that the moon takes her light from the sun, and the reason of lunar substitute 'Avačayópas for 'Avači- Mévns, Hippol. loc. cit. * Hippol. loc. cit.: Thy đê yńv tr}\aretav eival étr' &épos àxoupévmu ôpiota's 5& kal #Atov Kal areaſivmu kal Tà &AAa. Šarpa. Trávra yöp triplva iſvra étroxeto,0ai Tô &épt 51& TAdºros. The flatness of the sun is also spoken of by Stobaeus, i. 524; Plac. ii. 22, 1 tréraxov Tov #Atov). Of the stars, on the contrary, the same authori- ties (Ecl. i. 510; Plac. ii. 14) say that Anaximenes made them àAwv Strmv karatretrnºyéval rô kpwortaX- Aoetàet; and in accordance with this, Galen (Hist, Phil. 12) says: 'Avač. Thy trepiqopäu riv čotármu 'ymtvmweival (Plac. ii. 11, 1). Our text has instead: thv trepiqopāv rºw égordºra, ris yńs eival Tov oùpavóv; but the pseudo-Galen here seems to give the original reading. It is possible then that Anaximenes, as Teichmüller (loc. cit. 86 sqq.) supposes, made only the sun, moon and planets float in the air, and considered the fixed stars as fas- tened into the crystalline vault of heaven, in whatever way he may have explained the origin of this latter (Teichmüller thinks that like Empedocles, Plac. ii. 11, 1, he sup- ('Avač. TAarov &s posed it to be formed of air liqui- fied by the action of fire). But in that case Hippolytus must have expressed himself very inaccu- rately. * Hippol. loc. cit.: ye yovéval 3& t& àorrpa €k yſis 51& To thvircuáða éic raúrms &vío Tao'0ai, Žis āpaiovuévns To trip yivea-6al, ék 5& rod rupbs Peteopºgouévov robs &orépas ovv- to Tao'6at, eival 3& kal yea;6eis pàoets év tái Tôtrº róv >épov a vuqepo- plévas €iceivous (or, according to Stob. i. 510: Tupívnv pºv thv pågiv táv ãortépov, treptéxeiv 6é Tuva kal yetóðm ordpata orvurepiq’spáueva toûtois ã6para). Plut. ap. Eus. loc. cit. : Töv #Atov Kal rhv orexhvny kal r& Aoutrā āorpa Thy &px?iv Tijs Vevéorews ëxelv čk yūs. ātro®aſveral yotiv Tov #Alov yiv, 513, 8& Thy đêeſav ktvmoriy kal uda' iravös 6epuordºrmv kivmoriv (perhaps 9epuðrúta should be read here without kivmoiv) Aa3eiv. Theodoret asserts (Gr. aff, cur. iv. 23, p. 59) that Anaximenes held that the stars consisted of pure fire. This assertion, which was probably taken from the com- mencement of the notice preserved by Stobaeus, must be judged of in the light of the foregoing texts. FORMATION OF THE WORLD, 275 eclipses." The stars, he thought, moved, not from the zenith towards the nadir, but laterally round the earth, and the Sun at night disappeared behind the northern mountains; * the circular form of their * Eudemus ap. Theo. (Dercyl- lides), Astrom. p. 324 Mart. * Hippol. Joe. cit.: oi klveſorbal 3& 5 to yºv tá šarpa Aéyet ka9&s ërepot insixáſpagu, &AA& repl yńv, ãortrepel trepi Thy huetépav ice pax?iv orpéteral to trixtov, kpúrreo 6at te Töv #Atov oix àro yńv yewóuevov, &AA’ into róv Tijs yūs ūymAotépav Mepôv orkerówevov, kal 61& Thy TAeto- va juáv aitoöyevouévny &róa Taoiv. Stob. i. 510: oix Strö Thu yńv Šē, &AA& repl airhu arpéqsoróat rows ãorrépas. According to these tes- timonies (that of Hippolytus espe- cially, seems to come from a trust- worthy source), we should include Anaximenes among those of whom Aristotle says in Meteor, ii. 1, 354 a, 28: To troAAoûs tretorðfival rôv &pxatov ueteopoxórywu Töv #xtov ph q'épé00ai jiro yiv, &AA& repl Thu yńv kal Tov rátrov tootov, diſpavíčeorðat 8& kal trouelv vökta 61& To 5pm Mºhv eival Tpos &pictov thu yńv. Anaximenes is the only philosopher, so far as we know, who had recourse to the mountains of the north, for the explanation of the sun's nightly disappearance, and there is besides so great a similarity between the words of Hippolytus concerning him, and those of Aristotle concern- ing the ancient meteorologists, that we may even conjecture with some probability that Aristotle is here thinking specially of Anaximenes. Teichmüller thinks (loc. cit, p. 96) that the words, &pxaïot uereaſpo- Aóryot, do not relate to physical theories, but like the āpxatou kai 5tarpi Sovres trepl r&s 6eoAoyias, at the beginning of the chapter, to mythical ideas about the ocean, on which Helios fares back during the night from west to east. This in- terpretation cannot be based upon the context, for there is no connec- tion between the two passages, which are besides widely separated from each other. The mode of ex- pression also is decidedly against such a view. Aristotle always calls the representatives of mythi- cal and half-mythical cosmologies theologians; by werewpoxoyla, on the other hand (ueteopoxóryos is never used by him except in this passage), he understands (Meteor. i. 1 sub init.) a specific branch of natural science (prépos Tàs we66öov Taürms), and in this, as he expressly remarks (loc. cit.), he agrees with the ordinary use of the words; me- teorology, meteorosophy, and the like, being common expressions to designate natural philosophers. Cf. for example, Aristophanes, Nub. 228; Xen. Symp. 6, 6; Plato, Apol. 18 B, 23 D; Prot. 315 C. We know that Anaxagoras, Dioge- nes and Democritus also made the Sun go laterally round the earth (infra, vol. ii.). Now it might seem that if Anaximenes conceived the segment of the circle which the sun describes between his rising and setting above the horizon, to be continued and completed into a whole circle, he must necessarily have supposed it to be carried be- neath the earth. But even if this circle cut the plane of our horizon, it would not therefore be carried T 2 276 ANAXIMENES. orbits he attributed to the resistance of the air." In the stars no doubt we must look for the created gods of under the earth, that is, under the base of the cylinder on the upper side of which we live (cf. p. 273, 3); it would form a ring passing round this cylinder, obliquely indeed, but still laterally; it would go not into 'yńv, but trepi yiv. As Anaximenes made this circle dip at a certain distance from the northern edge of the earth's habitable surface, which edge, according to his geographical ideas, would not be very far from the northern shore of the Black Sea, he might well believe that without some elevation of the earth at this, its northern verge, the sun would not entirely disappear from us, and that in spite of such eleva- tion, some of its light would pene- trate to us even at night, if it were not diminished (according to the opinion of Hippolytus) by the great distance. But I by no means exclude the possibility that, ac- cording to Anaximenes, the sun and stars (of the stars, indeed, he expressly says this) and by infer- ence the planets (if he supposed the fixed stars to be fastened into the firmament, vide p. 274, 1) may have descended at their setting, either not at all, or very little be- low the surface of the horizon. As he imagined them to be flat like leaves (vide p. 274, 1) and, therefore, borne along by the air, he might easily suppose that when they reached the horizon, the resistance of the air would hinder their far- ther sinking (vide the following note). What has now been said will, I hope, serve to show the true value of Röth's strictures (Gesch. der ahendl. Phil. 258) on those who cannot see that a lateral motion of the stars is absolutely impossible with Anaximenes. Teichmüller (loc. cit.) admits that he held a lateral rotation of the sun around the earth, a rotation in which the axis of its orbit stands obliquely to the horizon. Only he thinks that after its setting it does not move close round the earth, or upon the earth behind the high northern mountains (p. 103)—a notion which, so far as I know, no one has hitherto ascribed to Anaxi- menes. In the Plac. ii. 16, 4, and therefore, also in Pseudo-Galen, c. 12, we read, instead of the words quoted above from Stob. i. 510: *Avačupévms, Šuotas Širo (Galen, manifestly erroneously, reads ém) Thy yīv kal repl airhu arpéqeoréal robs &otépas. Teichmüller con- cludes from this passage (p. 98) that the motion of the sun (of the heavenly bodies) is the same above and beneath the earth, that the circular movement of the firma- ment has the same radius above and below. But trepi does not mean above, and whatever kind of motion it might in itself characte- rise, as contrasted with Örö (this we have already seen in the passa- ges from Aristotle, Hippolytus and Stobaeus), it can only be used for a circular lateral movement. In the Placita, it seems to me we have simply-an unskilful correction, oc- casioned perhaps by some mutila- tion or corruption of the true text, and authenticated by the other writers. * Stobaeus, i. 524, says: 'Avači- plévns trópivov Štrápxeiv Tov #xtov &teq fivaro, Štrb tren'vkvapiévov 6& &épos kal &vrtrömov čw8o0neva rä FORMATION OF THE WORLD. 277 whom Anaximenes, as well as Anaximander, is said to have spoken;' but the same doubt arises in his case as in Anaximander's, viz., whether the infinitely many worlds ascribed to him * relate to the stars or to an in- finite series of successive systems.” However this may be, we are justified by the testimonies of Stobaeus” and #arpa rās rporâs troueto 6ai. Simi- larly Plac. ii. 23, 1: ‘A. Örö retu- kva'uévov &épos kal &vtitätrov éga,6eto 6al tº &otpa. In both au- thors this stands under the heading repl Tporów iMov (in Stobaeus, Tepl ošo'ías #Atov . . . kal Tporów, &c.), and they probably, therefore, meant what are usually called the two solstices, which Anaximenes might have explained in this man- ner consistently with his notion of the sun. It is noticeable, however, that they both speak of the dis- placement (Stobaeus says also rpo- trai) of the Šarpa, to which rporal in this sense are not elsewhere at- tributed. It is, therefore, probable that the proposition ascribed by these writers to Anaximenes had originally another meaning, and signified that the stars were forced by the resistance of the wind from the direction of their course. The expression employed does not hin- der this interpretation. Aristotle himself speaks (De Caelo, ii. 14, 296 b, 4) of Tporal rôv čo Tpav; Meteor. ii. 1, 353 b, 8, of Tporal #Atov kal orexſivms; and ibid. 355 a, 25, of Tpotral Too oipavoi); and Anaxagoras, who is so often allied with Anaximenes in his astrono- mical theories, taught, according to Hippol. i. 8, line 37: Tporâs 68 trutéto flat kal fixiov kal orexhvnv &ma,00vuévous Štrb toi, &épos. orexívmw 6è troAAákis Tpéreo 9at 61& To u%) 6tſvaa-6ai Kpateſv rod puxpo5. Tooth seems to designate every change in the orbit of the heavenly bodies, which altered the previous direc- tion of their course. Thus the proposition of Anaximenes quoted above must have been intended to explain, not the Sun's deviation at the Solstices, but the circular orbit of the heavenly bodies—those, at least, which are not fixed in the firmament. At the same time, however, it may be that he wishes to explain why their orbits are con- tinued without descending, or in descending very little, beneath the plane of our horizon, vide previous note. By Tpotral he would mean in that case the inflexion in the curves described by them. * Hippol. vide supra, p. 267, 3; Aug. Civ. D. viii. 2: omnes rerum causas infinito aćri dedit: mec deos negavit aut tacuit: non tamen ab ipsis aérem factum, Sed ipsos ea. aëre factos credidit; and after him, Sidon. Apoll. xv. 87; cf. Krische, Forsch. 55 sq. * Stob. Ecl. i. 496; Theod. Gr. aff, cur. iv. 15, p. 58. * That he did not assume a plurality of co-existent systems, is expressly stated by Simplicius, vide p. 278, 1. * Loc. cit. 416: 'Avačſuavöpos, 'Avačuévns, 'Avačayópas, 'ApxéNaos, Aloyévms, Asúncurtros p0aprov Tov kóguov, kal of Xroikol 'p6aprby rov kóapov, kat' éktróportv 6é. The destruction of the world by fire is 278 ANAXIMENES. Simplicius," which mutually support and complete one another, in attributing to him the doctrine of an alter- nate construction and destruction of the world. The hypotheses concerning the origin of rain, Snow, hail, lightning, the rainbow,” and earthquakes,” which are ascribed to Anaximenes, sometimes on good au- thority, are for us of secondary importance; and his theory of the mature of the soul,” based chiefly upon the ordinary popular opinion, he himself does not seem to have further developed. This survey of the doctrines attributed to Amaxi- menes may now enable us to determine the ques- tion already raised: did Anaximenes owe nothing to Anaximander except in some minor points of his en- quiry P* It seems to me that his philosophy taken as a whole clearly betrays the influence of his predeces- sor. For Anaximander had in all probability already expressly asserted not only the infinity, but the ani- mate nature and perpetual motion of primitive matter. Anaximenes reiterates these theories, and, by virtue of them, seems to reach his conclusion that air is the primitive matter. It is true that he returns from the here ascribed, not to Anaximander, &c., but only to the Stoics; though it is not improbable that Anaxi- mander also held it. Wide supra, p. 260. - | Phys. 257 b, : āorot &el uév qaa weival icóruov, où pºv row airov àel, &AA& &AAore &AAov yivénevov icard. Twas xpóvov reptăöous, &s 'Avačip.évms re ical ‘HpókAettos kal Atoyévms. * * Hippol. loc. cit.; Placita, iii. 4, 1, 5, 10; Stob. i. 590; Joh. Damasc. Parall. s. i. 3, 1 (Stob. Floril. Ed. Mein. iv. 151). Theo in Arat. v. 940. * Arist. Meteor. ii. 7, 365 a., 17 b, 6; Plac. iii. 15, 3; Sen. Qu. Nat. vi. 10; cf. Ideler, Arist. Meteorol. i. 585 sq. Perhaps in this also Anaximenes follows Anaximander, vide Supra, p. 256, 3. * In the fragment discussed p. 268, 3, and p. 270, from which doubtless the short statement in Stob. Ecl. i. 796, and Theodoret, Gr. aff, cur. v. 18, is taken. * Ritter, i. 214. HISTORICAL POSITION. 279 indeterminate conception of infinite substance to a determinate substance, and that he represents things as arising out of this not by separation, but by rarefaction and condensation. But at the same time he is evidently concerned to maintain what Anaxagoras had held about the primitive substance; and thus his principle may be described as the combination of the two previous principles. With Thales, he accepts the qualitative determinateness of primitive matter; with Anaximander he expressly asserts its infinity and animation. For the rest he inclines chiefly to Anaximander. Even if we cannot with justice ascribe to him the doctrine of the destruction of the world, and of innumerable worlds in succession, we can still see his dependence on his predecessor" in his ideas concerning the primitive opposition of heat and cold, the form of the earth and stars, on atmospheric phenomena, in what he says of the stars as the created gods, perhaps also in the opinion that the soul is like air in its nature. Yet this depen- dence is not so great, nor his own original achievement so insignificant that we should be justified in refusing to recognise any kind of philosophic progress in his doctrine.” For Anaximander’s motion of infinite matter is too indeterminate to explain particular substances, and the “separation by which he accounts for all pro- duction of the derived from the original, is open to the same charge. The determinate substances, according to him, are not as such contained in the primitive sub- * Strümpell, therefore, in doctrines, as with the chronology. placing Anaximenes before Anaxi- * Haym. Allg. Enc. Sect. iii. vol. mander, is as little in accordance xxiv. 27. with the internal relation of their 280 LATER IOWIANS. stance: separation is therefore only another expression for the Becoming of the particular. Anaximenes at- tempted to gain a more definite idea of the physical pro- cess, by which things are evolved from primitive matter; and to that end, he sought the primitive matter itself in a determinate body, qualified to be the substratum of that process. Such an attempt was certainly of great importance; and, considering the state of enquiry at that period, marked real progress. On this account, the latter Ionian physicists especially followed Amaxi- menes; to such an extent indeed, that Aristotle at- tributes the doctrine of rarefaction and condensation to all those who take a determinate substance for their principle;' and a century after Anaximenes, Diogenes of Apollonia and Archelaus again set up his theory of primitive matter. • . IV. THE LATER ADHERENT'S OF THE IONIC SCHOOL. DIOGENES OF APOLLONIA. AFTER Anaximenes, there is a lacuna in our knowledge of the Ionic school. If we consulted only the chronology, this lacuna would be filled by Heracleitus; but the peculiar nature of his philosophy separates him from the earlier Ionians. Meanwhile the theories of the Milesian physicists must have been propagated during this period, and even have given occasion to farther definitions. This is clear from the subsequent appear- ance of similar doctrines, about which, however, our * Wide supra, p. 243, 1. HIPPO. 281 information is for the most part very scanty. The philosophers whom we have to mention in this connec- tion are chiefly allied with Anaximenes; they make either the air itself, or a body of the nature of air, their primitive matter. But the doctrine of Thales likewise found adherents; for example, Hippo,' a physicist of the time of Pericles,” whose country is uncertain,” and his personal history unknown.” 1. Cf. Schleiermacher, Werke, Abtheilung, iii. 405–410; Bergk, Ireliquide Comaed. Att. 164, 185; . Backhuizen Van den Brink, Varia lectiones ea; historia philosophiſe an- tiqua (Leyden, 1842), 36–59. * This is clear from the state- ment of the Scholiast of Aristo- phanes, Nub. 96, exhumed by Bergk, that Cratinus in the Pa- noptai ridiculed him (infra, p. 283, 3). His theories also point to a later date. The detailed en- quiries concerning the formation and development of the foetus seem to contain some allusions to Empe- docles (vide Backhuizen Van den Brink, 48 sq.). He seems also to be thinking of Empedocles when he combats the hypothesis that the soul is blood (this, however, is less certain ; for that idea is an ancient popular opinion). These enquiries, at any rate, serve to show the ten- dency of the later physicists to the observation and explanation of or- ganic life. The more abstract conception of Thales' principle, which Alexander ascribes to him, is likewise in accordance with this. That he had already been opposed by Alcmaeon (Cens. Di. Nat. c. 5) is a mistake (Schleiermacher, 409). * Aristoxemus ap. Cens. Di. Nat. c. 5, and Iamblichus, V. Pyth. 267, describe him as a Samian, Like Thales, he declared and this is, of course, the most probable; others, perhaps con- fusing him with Hippasus, say that he came from Rhegium (Sext. Pyrrh. iii. 30; Math. ix. 361 ; Hippolyt. Refut. Har. i. 16), or Metapontum (Cens. loc. cit.). The Same blunder may have occa- sioned his being placed by Iambli- chus (loc. cit.) among the Pythago- reans; though the author of that catalogue scarcely needed this ex- cuse. Perhaps Aristoxenus had remarked that he studied the doc- trines of Pythagoras; and Iambli- chus, or his authority, therefore made him out a Pythagorean. The statement that he came from Melos (Clemens, Cohort. 15 A.; Arnob. Adv. Nat. iv. 29) can be more dis- tinctly traced to a confusion with Diagoras (who, in the above-quoted passages, is coupled with him as an atheist), if not to a mere slip of the pen, in the text of Clemens. * From the attacks of Cratinus nothing more can be gathered than that he must have resided for some time in Athens; Bergk (p. 180) farther concludes from the verse in Athen. xiii. 610 b, that he wrote in verse, but it does not follow that he may not also have written in prose. The con- jecture (Backhuizen Van den Brink, p. 55) that Hippo was the 282 HIPPO. water to be the first principle of all things,' or as Alex- ander,” probably with more accuracy,” says, moisture (tò iºpov), without any more precise determination. He was led to this chiefly as it seems by considering the moist mature of animal seed; “it was at any rate for this reason that he held the soul to be a liquid analo- gous to the seed from which, in his opinion, it sprang.” He probably therefore concluded, like Anaximenes, that that which is the cause of life and motion must be also the primitive matter. He made fire originate from water; and the world from the overcoming of water by fire ; * on which account his principles are sometimes author of the writing trepi àpxöv, falsely ascribed to Thales, and quoted supra, p. 216, 2, and p. 226, l, is to me very improbable, be- cause of the expressions, &pxal and otolyetov, which it contains. * Arist. Metaph. i. 3, 984 a, 3; Simpl. Phys. 6 a., 32 a ; De Coelo, 268 a, 44; Schol. in Arist. 513 a, 35; Philop. De An. A, 4; C, 7. * Ad Metaphys. p. 21, Bon. * Aristotle classes him gene- rally with Thales, without defi- nitely saying that he made water his first principle ; this was first said by later writers. But from Aristotle's procedure elsewhere, we can see that he would have had no scruple in identifying the Öypov with the more determinate $60p. * Wide the following note. Simplicius, De Coelo, 273 b, 36; Schol. in Arist. 514 a, 26; and Philoponus, De An. A, 4, say more distinctly that Thales and Hippo held water to be the primitive matter, on account of the mois- ture of the seed and of nourish- ment in general. It has been already observed, however (p. 218), that in so doing they merely turned Aristotle's conjecture (Metaph. i. 3) into a formal statement. * Arist. De An. i. 2, 405 b : Töv 8& poptikorépov kal iſoap rives &teq fivavro [thv juxhv] ka04trep "Introv. Treto'67 vat 5' éotraoru èic ris 'yovſis, 3rt trèvrov trypt. Kai yüp éAéyxel rows aiua pāorkovras rhy Wuxhv, 3rt à yov) oix aiua (he sought to prove, according to Cens. loc. cit., by study of animals, that the seed comes from the marrow) Taºrmv 5' eival rºw ºrpiórmy juxhv. Herm. Irris, c. 1 (cf. Justin, Co- hort. c. 7): Hippo considers the soul to be a úðap yovorouáv. Hip- polyt. loc. cit. : thv 5* buxºv troré uêvéºykéqaxov čxeiv (read Aéyet, or with Duncker: épm éival) roté & §§op, kal yèp to a répua sival to qawópevov juiv ć irypoo, ää of pnot Juxºv yived 6ai. Stob. i. 798 ; Ter- tull. De An. c. 5; Philop. De An. A, 4 C, 7. * Hippol. l. c. : "Introv 6& 6 ‘Pnyivos àpxès éq m ºvºpov ºrb Šēop kal 0epubv to trip. yewv&uevov 33 to HIPPO. 283 asserted to be fire and water." What his more exact opinions were as to the constitution of the universe— whether, the erroneous statement that he held the earth to have been the first,” had any real foundation in fact —whether in harmony with Anaximander and Anaxi- menes, he may perhaps have taught that out of fluid, under the influence of fire, the earth was first formed, and out of the earth, the stars—we have no means of determining.” As little do we know on what ground Hippo was charged with atheism,” as he has been in several quarters. The unfavourable judgment of Aris- totle as to his philosophic capacity,” however, greatly reconciles us to the meagreness of the traditions respect- ing his doctrine. He was no doubt less of a philoso- pher than an empirical naturalist, but even as such, from what we hear of him,” he does not seem to have attained any great importance. trip Širo iſèatos katavikāoral thy roß 'yevvioravros Óðvaulv, a votijo aſ Te Töv kóopov. * Wide previous note and Sex- tus, loc. cit.; Galen, H. Phil. c. 5, p. 243. * Johannes Diac. Alleg. in Hes. Theog. v. 116, p. 456. * This holds good of the state- ment alluded to (p. 281, 2) that Cratinus made the same charge against Hippo that Aristophanes did against Socrates, viz. that he taught that the heavens were a Trviyevs (an oven or hollow cover warmed by coals), and that men were the coals in it. He may have supposed the sky to be a dome resting upon the earth; but how this could be brought into connec- tion with his other notions, we do not know. * Plut. Coomſm. Not. c. 31, 4 ; Alexander, loc. cit. and other commentators; Simpl. Phys. 6 a ; De An. 8 a.; Philop. De Art. A, 4; Clemen. Cohort. 15 A, 36 C ; Arnob. iv. 29; Athen. xiii. 610 b ; AElian, V. H. ii. 31; Eustach. in Il. 4, 79; Odyss. T 381. What Alexander and Clemens say about his epitaph as the occasion of this imputation explains nothing. Pseudo-Alex. in Metaph. vii. 2; xii. 1, p. 428, 21, 643, 24, Bon., as- serts that his materialism was the cause ; but this is evidently a conjecture. * In the passages cited p. 282, 1, 5. * Besides what has been al- ready quoted we should here men- tion his theories on birth and the formation of the foetus, Censor. Di. 284 IDAEUS. As Hippo was influenced by Thales, so Idaeus o Himera appears to have been influenced by Anaximenes. Anaximenes most likely also originated the two theorie mentioned in some passages by Aristotle; * accordin to the one, primitive matter in respect of density stand midway between water and air; according to the other between air and fire. That both theories belong to younger generation of Ionian physicists is probable, fo they occupy an intermediate position between olde philosophers; the one between Thales and Anaximenes the other between Anaximenes and Heracleitus. W must, however, primarily refer them to Anaximenes, since he was the first who raised the question of the relative density of the different kinds of matter, and who explained the formation of particular substances by the processes of condensation and rarefaction. In this way he arrived at the opposition of rarefied and condensed air, or warm air and cold air; if warm air were adopted as the primitive element, the result was an intermediary between air and fire; if cold air, an intermediary between air and water.” Nat. c. 5–7, 9; Plut. Plac. v. 5, 3, 7, 3, into which I cannot now en- termore particularly, and a remark about the difference between wild Atoyévns . . . &épa [äpx?iv ëAečav). Besides this we know nothing of Idaeus. * Wide p. 241, 1, 2. These pas- and cultivated plants in Theophrast. Hist. Plant. i. 3, 5 ; iii. 2, 2. Athen. xiii. 610 b, contains a verse of his against trouxvua£muogºvn, which resembles the famous saying of Heracleitus; he quotes the same verse, however, as coming from Timon, who might have borrowed it from Hippo. 1 Sext. Math. ix. 360: 'Avašt- Aévms 5& kal 'I6aios 6 "Inepaſos kal sages do not relate to Diogenes, as will presently be shown. * In connection with Anaxi- menes we should mention Melesa- goras; according to Brandis, i. 148, Clemens (Strom. vi. 629, A) names him as the author of a book trans- scribed from Anaximenes; and as holding similar doctrines to those of Anaximenes. Clemens also says: rö 8& “Hortóðov werfixNašav DIOGENES OF APOLLOWIA. 285 arly presuppositions, even is reſov Aéryov kal &s tota ééfivey- av Etſum^ós re kal 'AkovoríAaos of Mexmorayópov yūp &Aeyev Topytas & Aeovtºvos kal Eöömuos 6 Nāšios of ioTopikol, kal étrl toūrous 6 IIpokovváguos Bíov . 'Aubiaoxós re kal 'Aptorok??s ſcal Aédvöpios kal'Avačuévns, kal ‘ENAd- wikos, and so on. But this Melesa- goras, who was made use of by various historians, can Scarcely have been any other than the well-known Logographer, who was also called Amelesagoras (see Mül- ler, Hist, of Gr. ii. 21), and the Anaximenes, whom Clemens names among a number of historians, is certainly not our philosopher, but likewise a historian, probably Anaximenes of Lampsacus, men- tioned by Diogenes, the nephew of the orator. It is a question, moreover, whether we ought not to read Eüpfixov instead of Mexm- orayópov, or Mexmorayópas instead of Etſumaos; and whether the words 'Auq (Moxos, &c., are to be con- nected with ēkWeyev, and not with rð ‘Hmorić6ov uérfixAačav, &c. 1 The statements of the an- cients respecting him, and the frag- ments of his work, have been carefully collected and annotated by Schleiermacher (Ueber Diogenes v. Apollonia, third section of his collected works, ii. 149 sqq.) and by Panzerbieter (Diogenes Apollo- ates, 1830). Cf. also Steinhart, Allg. Encycl. of Ersch and Gruber, Sect. I. vol. xxv. 296 sqq.; Mul- lach, Fragm. Philos. Gr, i. 252 sqq. Of his life we know very lit- Diogenes of Apollonia' is a philosopher with whom e are better acquainted; and his doctrine shows in a triking manner that the Ionic school maintained its when other and more de- tle. He was a native of Apollonia (Diog. ix. 57, &c.), by which Ste- phen of Byzantium (De Urb. s. v. p. 106, Mein.) understands Apol- lonia in Crete, but as he wrote in the Ionic dialect, it is doubtful if this can be the city. His date will hereafter be discussed. Ac- cording to Demetrius Phalerius ap. Diog. loc. cit., he was in danger through unpopularity at Athens, by which is probably meant that he was threatened with similar charges to those brought forward against Anaxagoras. But there may be some confusion here with Diagoras. The assertion of Antis- themes, the historian (ap. Diog. l. c.), repeated by Augustine, Civ. Dei, viii. 2, that he attended the instructions of Anaximenes is merely based on conjecture, and is as worthless in point of evidence as the statement of Diogenes (ii. 6) that Anaxagoras was a hearer of Anaximenes; whereas, in all pro- bability, he was dead before Anaxi- menes was born, cf. Krische, Forsch.” 167 sq. Diogenes's work, repl ‘ptorea's, was used by Simplicius, but (as Krische observes, p. 166) he does not seem to have been ac- quainted with the second book of it, which Galen quotes in Hip- pocr. vi. Epidem. vol. xvii. 1 a. 1006 K. That Diogenes composed two other works is doubtless an error of this writer, founded on a misapprehension of some of his utterances (Phys. 32 b), vide Schleiermacher, p. 108 sq.; Pan- zerbieter, p. 21 sqq. - 286 DIOGENES OF APOLLONIA. veloped ideas had been introduced into it. On one side he is closely connected with Anaximenes, on another he in all probability transcends him : not only is his expo- sition more methodical in form and more careful as to details, but he is also distinguished from his predecessor in having ascribed to the air, as primitive cause and primitive matter, certain spiritual qualities, and having tried to explain the life of the soul by the air so appre- hended. To gain a fixed basis for his enquiry," he determined the general characteristics which must belong to the primitive essence. On the one hand he said it must be the common matter of all things, and on the other, an essence capable of thought. His argument for the first assertion was the following. We know that things change one into another, that sub- stances mix, and that things influence and affect each other. None of these phenomena would be possible if the various bodies were distinct as to their essence. They must therefore be one and the same, must have sprung from the same substance, and must be resolved into the same again.” In proof of the second assertion, * According to Diogenes, vi. 81; ix. 57, his work began with the words: Aóryov travros &pxáuevov Sokéet uot xpe&v elva, thv 3px?iv &vauqua Shrmtov trapéxed 6al, thy 8& &pumvrtmv štååv Kal geuvâv. * Fr. 2 ap. Simpl. Phys. 32 b : euo, 5& Sokéel, to uèv šáutraveirety, Trévra rö, äávra &mb row airod &repowojača, Kai To atto eival. kal Toºro etºxov. ei yüp v Tóðe Tó kóguq &6vra viv Yū kal iſoap kal TúAxa, §a'a paſveral év táče tº kéguq àvra, ei Tovtéav Tl fiv, to §repov toà érépov repov čov tí ióſm ºpógei Kal oi to airò £ov were mirré troXAaxós kal itepotooto, oièapti, oùre utoryeo.62 &AA#Aous hôāvaro, otre diſpéAma is rô Érépº otºre 8AdBm . oiâ’ &v otte putov čk tās yīs q oval, otre @ov oſſite &AAo ‘yevé00al oëbèv, ei un oiro ovvioraro, &are Twijrb elvai. &AA& tróvra raûra ék toū aitot, Étepoločaeva &AAore &AAoſa 'yfyveral kal és To airo àva- xopéet. Fr. 6, ap. Simpl. 33 a. où6èv 6' oióv te yevé00al rôv ćrepot- oupévov ćrepov čtépov trply &v ro airo Yévnrat, and Arist. Gen. et Corr. i. 6, 322, b, 12. What Dio- THE PRIMITIVE ESSENCE. 287 Diogenes appealed in a general manner to the wise and felicitous distribution of matter in the world; and more particularly, to this testimony of our experience— that life and thought are produced in all living natures by the air which they breathe, and are bound up with this substance.” He therefore concluded that the substance of which all things consist must be a body eternal, unchangeable, great and powerful, and rich in knowledge.” All these qualities he thought he dis- covered in the air ; for the air penetrates all things, and in men and animals produces life and conscious- ness; the seed of animals, also, is of a nature like air.” He, therefore, with Anaximenes, declared air to be the matter and ground of all things.” This is attested almost unanimously" by ancient writers; and Diogenes himself says" that air is the essence in which reason genes ix. 57, says he taught—viz. that nothing comes from nothing or to nothing—is here indeed pre- supposed, but whether he expressly enunciated this principle we do not know. * Wide notes 1, 2, and 7. * Or as Theophrastus De Sensu 8, 42. Cicero, N. D. i. 12, 29, says the Deity; cf. Arist. Phys. iii. 4 (supra, p. 248, 1). Sidon. Apoll. xv. 91, discriminates the air of Dio- 1 Fr. 4, Simpl. loc. cit.; oil yèp &v oſſºra ösöá00at [sc. Thu äpx?iv] oiáv re ºv &vev vohotos, Šare Trévrov uérpa šxeiv, xeluóvás Te kal 0épeos ical vuktös kal juépms kai jetöv kal &véuov kal eißtów kai Tà &AAa et ris BoöXeral évvoéea 6al, eúptokot &v oita Stakeſpeva Ös &vvotov káAAtoºra. * Fr. 5, ibid.: ári 63 trpos toūrous kal ºrdàe ueydaa a mueſa &v0patros 7&p kal rô &AAa (ga &vatvéovra Øet rô &épt, Kai Tooro airtois kal Juxh éori kai vámoſis . . . kal éâv âmaxNax95 &mo?vhakei kal # vömoris ériMeſtret. * Fr. 3 from Simpl. Phys. 33 a. genes as the matter endowed with creative energy, from God, but this is of course unimportant. * The passages in question are given in extenso by Panzerbieter, p. 53 Sqq. In this place it is sufficient to refer to Arist. Metaph. i. 3, 984 a, 5; De An. 405 a, 21; Theophrast, ap. Simpl. Phys. 6 a. * Fr. 6, ap. Simpl. 33 a kat plot àokést to thv vömov čxov eival 6 &hp kaxeóuevos into táv &v0pátrov, kal Strö Toârou trèvra kal kv6epvāorðal kal travrov kpatéeiv. &tó yöp uoi toūtov Šokéet #60s eivat (instead of atro Panzerbieter here reads airoi; , 288 I) IOGENES OF APOLLONIA, dwells, and which guides and governs all things, because its nature is to spread itself everywhere, to order all and to be in all. Nicolaus of Damascus, Porphyry,' and in one passage,” likewise Simplicius, attribute to Diogenes as his first principle the substance intermediate between air and fire,” so often mentioned by Aristotle. This is unquestionably an error, into which they were probably misled by Diogenes' opinion, that the soul, by analogy with which he defines his primitive essence," was of the nature of warm air. Nor can I agree with Ritter's similar theory,” that the primitive essence of Diogenes was not the ordinary atmospheric air, but a more subtile kind, ignited by heat ; for not only do all the accounts, and Diogenes' own explanations, speak of the air as ‘that which is usually called air; ” but accord- ing to his own principles it would have been impossible for him, while deriving all things from air by rare- faction and condensation, to seek the original principle (that which constituted the basis of all the different forms and changes of the atmosphere), not in the this I prefer to Mullach's amend- ment, which retains dirb, but sub- stitutes vôos for €60s) kal étrº Tráv dqix0at kai rāvra övari0éval ical ev travrl éveſval kal éorrl uměé Év 8 ru ph ueréxel rotºrov . . . . kal tróvtov Töv Çiğov 5& # juxh Tô airá čoºrw, &hp 9epuárepos pév toà éto èv ć éogèv, roi, Hévrol trapà tê hextº troMAöv juxpórepos. This soul is besides very different in different beings: äuws & 13. Távra tº airró kal ºf kal épé kal dicotet Kal rhy &AAmy vámoriv čxei Štrb too airoi, ºrdvra kal épetlis 5eſkvvoru, adds Simplicius: 3ri kal to otéppa rôv @ov rvevuarööés éorri kai vohorels 'yſvoviral row dépos obv rá; aluati to 8xov orópa KaraNapióðvovros Stö. Töv qXeBóv. - * According to Simpl. Phys. 33 b; 6 b. * Phys. 44 a. * Wide supra, p. 241, 1. * Cf. the passage cited, p. 287, 2, 7, and the general canon of Aristotle, De An. i. 2, 405 a, 3, to which Panzerbieter (p. 59) refers in support of his hypothesis. Wide also p. 268, 2. * Gesch, der Phil. i. 228 sqq. THE PRIMITIVE ESSENCE, 289 common aerial element, but in some particular kind of air." Schleiermacher's conjecture also º is improbable, that Diogenes himself held air to be the primitive matter, but that Aristotle was doubtful as to his mean- ing, and so ascribed to him sometimes the air in general, sometimes warm or cold air. Such hesitation on the part of Aristotle respecting the principles of his predecessors is without precedent; from his whole spirit and method it is far more likely that he may have sometimes reduced the indefinite notions of earlier philosophers to definite concepts, than that he should have expressed himself in a vacillating and uncertain manner in regard to their definite theories. Aristotle repeatedly and decidedly declares that the principle of Diogenes was air; he then speaks of some philosophers, without naming them, whose principle was intermediate between air and water. Now it is impossible that these statements can relate to the same persons; we cannot doubt, therefore, that it is air in the common accepta- tion of the word, which our philosopher maintains to be the essence of all things. We find from the above quotations that Diogenes, in his more precise description of the air, ascribed to it two properties which correspond to the requirements * Though he may have gene- rally described the air in compa- rison with other bodies as the Aerrouepérratov or Aetrótarov (Arist. De An. loc. cit.), it does not follow that he held the rarest or warmest air alone to be the primi- tive matter; on the contrary, he says in Fr. 6 (vide infra, p. 291, 1), after having declared the air gene- WOL. I. U rally to be the first principle, that there are different kinds of air— warmer, colder, and so forth. Fur- ther particulars on this point will be given later on. * In his treatise on Anaxi- mander, Werke, 3te Abth. iii. 184. Cf. on the contrary, Panzerbieter, 56 Sqq. 290 IDIOGENES OF APOLLOWIA. claimed by him in general for the primal matter. As the substance of all things, it must be eternal and imperishable, it must be contained in all things, and permeate all things; as the cause of life and order in the world, it must be a thinking and reasonable essence. In the air these two aspects are united; for, according to Diogenes’ view, because the air permeates all things, it is that which guides and orders them; because it is the basal matter of all, all is known to it; because it is the rarest and subtlest matter, it is the most movable, and the cause of all rhotion.' We are expressly told” that he spoke of the air as the Infinite, and the state- ment is the more credible, since Anaximenes, whom Diogenes in other respects follows most closely, employed a similar definition. Moreover Diogenes describes the air in the same way that Anaximander describes his ãºrsipov; and Aristotle says that the infinity of primi- tive matter was held by most of the physiologists.” But this definition seems to have been regarded by him as of minor importance compared with the life and force of the primitive essence; that is his main point, and in it he discovers the chief proof of its air-like nature. On account of this vitality and constant motion, the air assumes the most various forms. Its motion consists, according to Diogenes (who here again follows * Wide p. 287,7, and Arist. De An. i. 2, 405 a, 21 : Atoyévms 6', 30 rep £repot rives, &épa (scil. §réAage rhy Jux}v), roorov oimbels trávrov Aerro- aspérrarov eival kal &pxfiv' ical Stå rooto yiv6orkeiv re ſcal rivetv rhy Juxºv, f uèv trpátáv čari kal ék rotºrov rô Aoirã, yiv6orkeiv, f 6& Aetrºrórarov, kivmtiköv eival. * Simpl. Phys. 6 a. Probably after Theophrastus: rhy be rod travros pūoriv &épa kal oirós (pmoſiv &neipov elval kal &föuov. * Wide p. 26%, 1. PA REFACTION AND COND ENSATION. 29] Anaximenes), in qualitative changes, in rarefaction and condensation;' or, which is the same thing, in heating and cooling; and so there arise in the air endless modifications in respect of heat and cold, dryness and dampness, greater or less mobility,” &c., corresponding to the different stages of its rarefaction or condensation. For the rest, Diogenes does not seem to have enume- rated these differences systematically, after the manner of the Pythagorean categories, though he must have derived the different qualities of things, some from rarefaction, some from condensation, and must so far have coordinated them on the side of heat or cold.” Nor do we find any trace of the four elements; we do not know whether he assumed definite connecting media between particular 1 Plut. ap. Eus. Pr. Ev. i. 8, 13: kooruotroteſ 6% of ros' 3rt too travros kivovuévov kal iſ uév Špaloo m 6& Trvkvod yewopuévov Štrov ovvercüpmare To trvkvov a varpoqºv trothoral, kal oiſt a rö, Aottrö, Katë Töv airov A6)ov T& kovipórara. Thu &va rāštv Aagóv- Tatov #xtov &toreAéoat. Simpl. loc. cit. after the words just quoted : é; of trukuovuévov ſcal pavovuévov kai perağäAAovros roſs tra,6eat thv táv &AAav yívea flat pop piv, kal Tawta pºv Oedºppagºros ioTope? repl rod Aloyévous. Diog. ix. 57, cf. what is cited from Aristotle, p. 243, 1, and Arist. Gen. et Corr. ii. 9, 336 a, 3 SQQ. * Fr. 6, supra, p. 287,7 (after the words 3 ti pº pietéxel rotºrov): Pueréxel 6* oëbè $v Šaotos to repov Tć Štěpºp, &AA& troXAol Tpátrol kal airoi, toº &épos kal ris vohorios eio'ſv. êorti yap troXàtporos, kal 6epuárepos ical puxpótepos kal &mpôtepos kal ūypôrepos kal otaguárepos kal éév- substances and the primi- tépmv kívmortv čxov, ſcal &AAat troXAal étepotóories évetoi ral jiàoväs kal Xpotis &reſpot. Panzerbieter ex- plains #50wh (p. 63 sq.) by taste, as the word also stands in Anaxago- ras Fr. 3; Xenophon, Anab. ii. 3. 16. Still better would be the analogous meaning “smell, which the word has in a fragment of Heracleitus. ap. Hippol. Refut. Har. ix. 10; and in Theophrastus, De Sensu, 16, 90. Schleiermacher, loc. cit. 154, trans- lates it feeling (Gefühl); similarly Schaubach (Anawagor. Fragm. p.86) Affectio; Ritter, Gesch. der Ion. Phil. 50, behaviour (Verhalten); Gesch. der Phil. i. 228, inner dis- position (innerer Muth); Brandis, i. 281, internal constitution (innere Beschaffenheit); Philippson, “TA'm drðpartvm, p. 205, bona conditio interna. * As Panzerbieter sets forth in detail, p. 102 sqq. U 2 292 DIO (; ENES OF APOLLONIA. tive substance, or identified the endless multiplicity of particular substances with the innumerable stages of rarefaction and condensation, so that the air would become at one stage of condensation water, at another flesh, at a third stone. The most probable supposition, however, and the one which seems to result from the above statements of his about the different kinds of air, and also from his opinion on the development of the foetus (vide infra)—is that he employed neither of the two modes of explication exclusively, and, generally speaking, in the derivation of phenomena, followed no fixed and uniform method. The first result of condensation and rarefaction was to separate from the infinite primitive substance, the heavy matter which moved downwards, and the light matter which moved upwards. From the former the earth was produced; from the latter, the sun, and no doubt the stars also." This motion upwards and down- wards Diogenes was forced to derive in the first place from heaviness and lightness, and secondly, from the inherent animation of matter as such. For the moving intelligence with him absolutely coincides with matter; the different kinds of air are also different kinds of thought (Fr. 6); that thought was added to material substances, and set them in motion,” is a view which would have been impossible to him. But after the first division of substances has been accomplished, all motion proceeds from the warm and the light.” Diogenes ex- plained the soul of animals to be warm air; and so in 1 Plutarch, vide Supra, p. 290, 4. 111 sq. 2 As Panzerbieter represents, * Fr. 6, supra, p. 287, 7. FORMATION OF THE WORLD. 293 the system of the world he regarded warm matter as the principle of motion, the efficient cause; and cold dense matter," as the principle of corporeal consistency. In consequence of heat,” the universe he thought had acquired a circular motion from which also the earth took its round shape.” By this circular motion, how- ever, he seems to have intended merely a lateral motion; and by the roundness of the earth a cylindrical, and not a spherical shape; for he assumed with Anaxagoras that the inclination of the earth’s axis towards its surface arose subsequently from some unknown cause (äic Toij attopatov), and that the axis at first ran per- pendicularly down through the earth.” * From the union of these by means of vómous arose (according to Steinhart, p 299) sensible air. I know not, however, on what evi- dence this assumption is based; it seems to me inadmissible for the reasons I brought forward against Ritter on p. 288. Nor do I see any proof of the accuracy of the further observation that ‘ the sensible air is supposed to consist of an infinite number of simple bodies;” for T)io- genes is never mentioned by Aris- totle in the passage, De Part. Anim. ii. 1, to which note 33 refers. * Whether primitive heat or the sun's heat, is not stated, but from Alex. Meteorolog. 93 b, the sun's heat seems to be intended. * Diog. ix. 57: Thy đê yńv orpoy- 'yūAmv, épmpetouévnv čv Tó uégº, thv oráortagu eiàm pvtav karū thv čk too 9epuoi) trepiqopāv kal tričiv Štrb toū Wuxpov, on which cf. Panzer- bieter, p. 117 sq. * According to the Plac. ii. 8, 1 (Stobaeus, i. 358; Ps. Galen, c. 11, to the same effect) Diogenes and He was the Anaxagoras maintained: ustã to ovatāvut Tov icóa'uov cal r& ©a ék Tús yūs éðayayev čºykAtôňvaí tra's Töv kóopov čk too attopadºrov eis to peomuſ pivov attoo uépos (forws, adds the author doubtless in his own name, Širo trpovotas, in order to show the difference between the habitable and uninhabitable zones). Anaxagoras, however, said, accord- ing to Diog. ii. 9: T& 3’ &otpa kat’ &px&s pièv 60xoetóós évéx6ival àote karū kopuqºv rās yńs (perpendicu- larly over the upper surface of the earth, which, like Anaximenes and others, he supposed to be shaped like a cylinder, cf. vol. ii. Anaa..) tow &el pauvéuevov sival tróAov, Šotepov 6è thv čykxtortv Aabeiv; so that, ac- cording to this, the stars in their daily revolution would at first have only turned from east to west late- rally around the earth s disc, and those above our horizon would never have gone below it. The obliquity of the earth's axis to its surface was produced later, and caused the paths of the sun and 294 DIOGENES OF APOLLONIA. more disposed to adopt Anaxagoras's notion as to the shape of the earth, and the original motion of the heavens, since Anaximenes had led him to the same result. Like Anaximander, he conceived of the earth in its primeval state as a soft and fluid mass gradually dried by the sun's heat. This is also proved by its having received its form in course of the rotation. What remained of the primitive liquid became the seas, the salt taste of which he derived from the evapo- ration of the sweet portions: the vapours developed from the drying up of the moisture served to enlarge the heavens." stars to cut the plane of the hori- zon; hence arose the alternation of day and night. What we are to think in regard to the details of this system is (as Panzerbieter, p. 129 sqq. shows) hard to say. If the whole universe, that is, the heavens and the earth, inclined to the south, nothing would have changed in the position of the earth in relation to the heavens, and the temporary disappearance of most of the stars below the horizon, and the alternation of day and night, would be inexplicable. If the heavens (or which is the same thing, the upper end of the earth's axis) had inclined to the south, the sun in its revolution around this axis would have come nearer and nearer the horizon the further south it went. It would have risen in the west and set in the east ; we should have had midnight when it was in the south ; midday when it was in the north. If, on the other hand, the earth had inclined to the South and the axis of the heavens had re- mained unaltered, it would seem The earth is full of passages through which that the sea and all the waters must have overflowed the southern part of the earth's surface. Pan- zerbieter, therefore, conjectures that Anaxagoras made the heavens incline not to the south, but to the north, and that in the passage in the Placita we should perhaps read trpooflápetov or uegoſłópelov, instead of Peo mp3plvöv. But considering that our three texts are agreed upon the word, this is scarcely credible. We shall, however, find (infra, vol. ii.) that Leucippus and Democritus believed in a depression of the southern part of the earth's disc. If these philosophers could discover an expedient unknown to us but satisfactory to them, by which they could escape the obvious difficulties of this hypothesis, Dio- genes and Anaxagoras could also have discovered one ; and on the other hand, their theory of the in- clination of the earth gives us a clue to the opinions of Leucippus and Democritus on the same subject. * Arist. Meteor. ii. 2, 355 a, 21; FORMATION OF THE WORLD. 295 the air penetrates: if the outlets of these are blocked up, there are earthquakes." In the same way Diogenes held the sun and stars” to be porous bodies, of a forma- tion like pumice stone, the hollows of which are filled with fire or fiery air.” The theory of the origin of the stars from moist exhalations,” in connection with that just quoted from Alexander on the growth of the heavens by the evaporations of the earth, would lead us to conjecture that Diogenes supposed the sun alone to have been at first formed from the warm air drawn upwards, and the stars to have afterwards arisen from the vapours evolved by the Sun's heat, by which vapours the sun himself was thought to have been continually sustained. As this nourishment is at times exhausted in each part of the world, the Sun (so at least Alexander represents the doctrine of Diogenes) changes his place, as a beast his pasture.” Alex. Meteorol. 91 a ; 93 b, pro- bably following Theophrastus; cf. Supra, p. 254, 1. * Seneca, Qu. Nat. Vi. 15; cf. iv. 2, 28. * Among which he likewise reckoned comets, Plac. lii. 2, 9; unless Diogenes, the Stoic, is here meant. * Stob. Ecl. i. 528, 552, 508; Plut. Plac. ii. 13, 4; Theod. Gr. off. cur. iv. 17, p. 59. According to the last three passages, meteoric stones are similar bodies; but it would seem that they only take fire in falling; vide Panzerbieter, 122 sq. * So, at least, Stob. 522 says of the moon, when he asserts that Diogenes held it to be a kiorampoet- 8ès āvaupta. Panzerbieter, p. 121 sq., interprets in the same way the statement in Stob. 508 (Plut. loc. cit.) that the stars, according to Diogenes, are àuditvotal (exhalations) toū kóapov; and he is probably more correct than Ritter (i. 232) who, by Sudirvoial, understands or- gans of respiration. Theodoret, loc. cit., ascribes the 6tan vo&s to the stars themselves; it would be easier to connect them with the fiery vapours streaming from the StarS. * Cf. p. 254, 1. Some other theories of Diogenes on thunder and lightning (Stob. i. 594; Sen. Qu. Nat. ii. 20), on the winds, Alex. loc. cit. (cf. Arist. Meteor. ii. 1, beginning), on the causes of the inundation of the Nile (Sen. Qu. Nat. iv. 2, 27; Schol. in Apollon. Rhod. iv. 269) are discussed by Panzerbieter, p. 133 sqq. 296 I) IOGENES OF APOLLONIA. Diogenes shared with Anaxagoras and other phy- sicists the belief that living creatures' and likewise plants” were produced out of the earth, no doubt by the influence of the sun's heat. In an analogous manner he explained the process of generation, by the influence of the vivifying heat of the body of the mother on the seed.” In accordance with his general standpoint, he thought the soul to be a warm, dry air. As the air is capable of endless diversity, souls likewise are as various as the kinds and individual natures to which they belong.” This substance of the soul he appears to have derived partly from the seed,” and partly from the outer air entering the lungs after birth; * and its warmth, according to the above theory, from the warmth of the mother. The diffusion of life throughout the whole body he explained by the theory that the soul or warm vital air streams along with the blood through the veins." In 1 Placita, ii. 8, 1; Stob. i. 358. * Theophrastus, Hist. Plant. iii. 1, 4. * For further details, cf. Pan- zerbieter, 124 sqq., after Censorin. Di. Nat. c. 5, 9; Plut. Plac. v. 15, 4 etc. * Fr. 6, after the words quoted, p. 291, 1: kal travtov Šºšov 8& # juxh ºró airó or riv, &hp 9epuárepos uév toū āśa, Év ć Čauèv, toi, uévrol trapū T6 hexíq, troAAöv juxpárepos. §uotov 8è rooro to 6eppov oičevos Táv Óav éotlv, Štrel oiâè róváv6pótrov &AA#- Aois. &AA& Stapépet wéya uév oë, &AA’ ãate trapatraſota elval, où uévrol &rpskéws ye āuotov čóv . . . &re ošv troxvrpétrov čveoûorms rās repot- &otostroAirpora kal tº Çiğa kal troXA& ſcal otre ióémv &AAñAous éoukóra otre 6taurav cite vömoriv Štrb roi, txh9eos Töv Štepowdºoreov. čudos 88, &c. (supra, p. 287, 7); cf. Theophrastus, De Sensw. 39, 44. * For he expressly remarks that the seed is like air (ºrvevuaróðes) and foam, and derives thence the designation, &ppoètoria. Wide supra, p.287,7; Clemens, Paedag. i. 105 C. * Plac. v. 15, 4. * Simpl. loc. cit.; cf. Theophras- tus, De Sensu, 39 sqq. From these passages it is clear that Diogenes limited the habitation of the soul to no particular organ; the state- ment, therefore, in the Placita, iv. 5, 7, that he transferred the jºyeuo- vikov to the &primptoich coià la răs kapātas, can only be accepted in the sense that this is the chief seat of the vivifying air. Cf. Panzerbieter, 87 sq. VITAL AIR. RESPIRATION. 297 support of this doctrine he entered into a detailed, and according to the then state of anatomical knowledge, an accurate description of the venal system." Sensations he supposed to arise from the contact of the vital air with external impressions,” and sleep and death from the partial or entire expulsion of the air by the blood.” The seat of sensation he sought in the air contained in the brain;* appealing in proof of this to the pheno- menon, that we are not conscious of external impressions when we are occupied with something else.” Desire and disinclination, courage, health, and so forth, were the effect, he thought, of the various proportions in which air mingles with the blood.” The intellectual in- feriority of sleeping and intoxicated persons, of children, and of animals, he attributed to the greater density and moisture, and the less perfect circulation of the vital air." The vital air itself, however, he was of course obliged to presuppose in all living creatures. On this ground he tried to prove, for example, that fishes and oysters have also the power of breathing.” He even * Given by Aristotle, H. Anim. iii. 2, 511 b, 30 sqq., commented on by Panzerbieter, p. 72 sqq. Hearing arises: ärav 6 év roºs &alv &?ip Kumbels ötro row £o Ölašig irpos Töv Yképakov ; sight, when the * The somewhat ambiguous statements, Placita iv. 18, 2 ; 16, 3; confused by the introduction of the Stoic #yepaovikov, are discussed by Panzerbieter, 86, 90; further details are given by Theophrastus, loc. cit.; cf. Philippson, "TAm &věpa- trivn, 101 sqq. * Plac. v. 23, 3. Ö * Smell, says Theophrastus, loc. cit., he attributed rig trepi Tov éºykéqſaxov dépt; Totºrov yūp &6povv eival kal oriupletpov tº dwarvoſ. image that enters the eye combines with the air within (utyvva 9a). * Loc. cit. 42 : §rt 5& à évròs dhp aio 6dueTai pukpóv &v učptov rod 6eoû, ormuelov elval, Šti troAAárcis trpós &AAa Töv votiv čxovtes of 6° ôpópºevoir’ &Kočopiev. * Theophrastus, loc. cit. 43. * Wide supra, p. 296, 2; Theo- phrastus, loc. cit. 44 sqq.; Plac. v. 20. * Arist. De Respir. c. 2, 470 b, 30 ; Panzer. 95. 298 IDIOGENES OF APOLLONIA. ascribed something analogous to respiration to metals, supposing them to absorb damp vapours (ikpuas), and to exude them again, and thus seeking to explain the attractive power of the magnet.* Only animals, how- ever, he considered, can breathe the air as such. Plants are entirely irrational, for the reason that they do not breathe it.” Like Anaximander and Anaximenes, Diogenes is said to have assumed the perpetual alternation of the world's construction and destruction, and an endless number of successive worlds. Simplicius' expressly says this, and the statement that Diogenes believed in an infinity of worlds" must have reference to it, for his whole cosmogony shows, even more clearly than the assertion of Simplicius (loc. cit.),” that he could only conceive the totality of simultaneous things as one whole limited in space. Stobaeus" speaks of a future end of the world, and Alexander,’ of a gradual drying up of the sea, which must both have a similar reference; and even without this explicit testimony, we must have supposed Diogenes on this point, likewise, to have been in agreement with his predecessors. In considering his theory as a whole, we must allow that notwithstanding its superiority to the previous phi- losophic theories in scientific and literary form, and in * Alex. Aphr. Quast. Nat. ii. * Where kóoaos could not be 23, p. 138, Speng. used in the singular if many con- * Theophrastus, loc, cit. 44. temporaneous Worlds like those of * Phys, 257 b : vide supra, p. Democritus were in question. Plac. 278, 1. ii. 1, 6 (Stob, i.440) seems to refer * Diog. ix. 57; Plut, ap. Eus, to Diogenes the Stoic. Pr. Ev. i. 8, 13; Stob. i. 496; * i. 416, vide supra, p. 277, 4. Theodoret, Gr. aff, cur. iv. 15, p. * Meteorol. 91 a, according to 58. - Theophrastus, vide supra, p. 251, 1. IIIS HISTORICAL POSI TI ON. 299 s comparative wealth of empirical knowledge, there is contradiction involved in its fundamental conceptions. f the orderly constitution of the world is only to be naerstood in reference to a world-forming reason, this resupposes that matter as such does not suffice to xplain it; its cause cannot therefore be sought in one lementary body, and so Diogenes is forced to ascribe o this body qualities which not merely from our point f view, but absolutely and directly, exclude one nother ; for on the one hand he describes it as the ubtlest and rarest, because it is the all-permeating nd all-animating, and on the other, he makes things rise from it, not only by condensation, but also by rarefaction, which would be impossible if the primitive lement were itself the rarest in existence." That it is ot merely” the warm air, or the soul, but air in general hat Diogenes calls the rarest, we are at any rate clearly told by Aristotle,” who says that Diogenes held the soul to be air, because air is the rarest element and the rimitive matter; and Diogenes himself (Fr. 6) says that the air is in all things, and permeates all things, which could not be unless it were itself the subtlest element. Nor can rarefaction” refer to a secondary form of air arising from previous condensation; for the ancient philosophers, with one accord, attribute the power of rarefaction, as well as condensation, to primi- tive matter;" and this indeed lies in the nature of * As Bayle has already re- * In the passage quoted, supra, marked, Dict. Diogéne. Rem. B. p. 290, 1. * As Panzerbieter (106) and * As Ritter holds, Ion. Phil. Wendt zu Tennemann, i. 441, sup- p. 57. pose. * Wide supra, p. 290, 4. 30K) DioGENES OF APOLLONIA. things, for rarefaction and condensation mutuall presuppose each other, and a condensation of on portion of a body of air is impossible without th simultaneous rarefaction of another. Thus, there i a contradiction in the bases of the system, resulting from the fact that its author adopted the idea of world-forming reason, without therefore abandoning thi ancient Ionian materialism, and especially the theorie of Amaximenes on primitive matter. This circumstance would in itself lead us to com. jecture that Diogenes' theory did not wholly arise ou of the development of the ancient Ionian physics, but under the influence of another philosophy, having -ā different standpoint; and that contradictory element: had therefore appeared in it. This conjecture becomes still more probable when we see, contemporaneously with Diogenes, the very definitions which contradict his materialistic presuppositions, brought forward by Anax- agoras in connection with a more logical doctrine, We have no certain information, it is true, as to the exact date of Diogenes," but we have the testimony o Simplicius,” based probably upon Theophrastus, that * The only fixed date, the men- tion of the aerolite of Aegospota- mos, which fell 469 B.C. (Stob. i. 508; Theod. Gr. aff, cur. iv. 18, p. 59; and Panzerbieter, p. 1 sq.), leaves an ample margin. * Phys. 6 a. Kal Atoyévns & 6 'AtroAXavidºrms, oxe50w veðtatos rów Tepl raûra axoMaordvrov, rö. pºv traetorra ovutre+opmuévos Yé-ypa- qe, rà uºv karð ‘Avačayópav rá 3& karð Aeëkurtov Aéyov. Cf. Supra, p, 290, 1; p. 291, 1; with the ap- peal to Theophrastus. That Theo phrastus really supposed Diogene. to be later than Anaxagoras seem probable likewise, because in dis cussing their theories he repeatedly places Diogenes after him. So D. Sensu, 39; Hist. Plant. iii. i. 4 vide Philippson."rxmåv6porium,199 Diogenes is also described as younger contemporary of Anaxa goras by Augustine, Civ. Dei, viii 2; and Sidon. Apoll. xv. 89 sqq. and for the same reason apparently HIS HISTORICA I, POSITION. 301 ater than Empedocles. essentially from it.” in Cic. N. D. i. 12, 29, his name comes last among all the pre-So- cratic philosophers. 1 This date is further supported by the circumstance which Petersen has shown to be probable in his Hippocratis Scripta ad Temp. Rat. Disposita, part i. p. 30 (Hamb. 1839, Gym-Progr.), namely that Aristophanes, Nub. 227 Sqq., is al- luding to the doctrine of Diogenes spoken of on p. 297, 6; which doc- trime in that case must even then have attracted attention in Athens. * Panzerbieter, 19 sq.; Schau- e appeared later than Anaxagoras, and wrote in partial ependence upon him. The carefulness of Diogenes in gard to the details of natural science, and especially e great precision of his anatomical knowledge, would ssign him to a period when observation had made ome advances: the period of a Hippo and a Democritus." m the same way we shall find reason to suppose him On these grounds some de- endence of Diogenes on Anaxagoras seems probable, nd the internal evidence of their doctrines is wholly in avour of this view. The striking similarity between hem makes it hardly credible that these doctrines hould have been produced independently of each other.” ot only do Diogenes and Anaxagoras both require a orld-forming reason, but they require it on the same round, that the order of the universe was otherwise nexplicable to them : both describe this reason as the ubtlest of all things; both derive the soul and life We cannot, however, consider naxagoras as dependent on Diogenes, and Diogenes as the historical link between him and the older physicists.” bach, Anaaag. Fragm. p. 32; Stein- hart, loc. cit. 297, considers Dio- genes to be rather earlier than Anaxagoras. * Cf. the section on Anaxagoras, infra. * Schleiermacher on Diog. Werke, 3te Abth. ii. 156 sq., 166 sqq.; Braniss, Gesch. der Phil. s. Kant, i. 128 sqq., vide Supra, p. 167. Krische is less positive, vide Forsch. 170 sq. Schleiermacher, however, afterwards changed his opinion, for in his Gesch. d. Phil. p. 77 he de- scribes Diogenes as an eclectic with- 302 DIOGENES OF APOLLOWIA. Schleiermacher indeed thinks that had Diogenes bee acquainted with the work of Anaxagoras, he must hav expressly opposed Anaxagoras' theory that the air i something composite; but in the first place we have m evidence to show that he did not oppose it; and i the second we have no right to apply the standards o modern philosophy to the methods of the ancients, nor to expect from these latter a profound investigation o theories differing from their own, such as even a Plato did not always impose upon himself. The main prim- ciple of Anaxagoras, however, the separation of the organising reason from matter, Diogenes seems to me clearly enough to oppose, in his 6th Fragment.” Schleiermacher indeed finds no trace in the passage of any polemic of this kind, but merely the tone of a person who is newly introducing the doctrine of vojs; but the care with which Diogenes demonstrates that all the qualities of intelligence belong to the air, gives me the opposite impression. In the same way it seems to me that Diogenes” is so careful to prove the unthink- ableness of several primitive substances, because he had been preceded by some philosopher who denied the unity of the primitive matter. That he is alluding to Empedocles only, and not to Anaxagoras,” is improbable, considering the many other points of contact between Diogenes and Anaxagoras. If, however, he had Empe- docles chiefly in view, that alone would show him to be out principle belonging, with the Phys. 32 b : trpós pugiox6)ovs &vre- Sophists and Atomists, to the third pmkéval, offs Kaxet airòs oroptorrás. section of pre-Socratic philosophy, * Wide supra, p. 287, 7. the period of its decay. * Fr. 2, vide supra, p. 286, 2. ! He says of himself in Simpl. * Krische, p. 171. HIS HISTORICAL POSITION. 303 younger contemporary of Anaxagoras, and his philo- ophy might be supposed to have appeared at a later ate than that of Anaxagoras. Schleiermacher con- siders it more natural that spirit should first have been discovered in its union with matter, and afterwards in opposition to it; but this is hardly conclusive in regard to Anaxagoras's relation to Diogenes; for the direct unity of spirit with matter, which was the starting point of the elder physicists, we do not find in Diogenes; on the contrary, he introduces thought, because the purely physical explanation of phenomena does not satisfy him. But if the importance of thought has once been re- cognised, it is certainly more probable that the new principle should be first set up in abrupt opposition to material causes, than that it should be combined with them in so uncertain a manner as by Diogenes." The whole question is decided by this fact, that the con- ception of a world-forming reason is only logically carried out by Anaxagoras; Diogenes on the contrary attempts to combine it in a contradictory manner, with a standpoint entirely out of harmony with it. This in- decisive sort of eclecticism is much more in keeping with the younger philosopher, who desires to make use of the new ideas without renouncing the old, than with the philosopher to whom the new ideas belong as his original possession.” Diogenes is therefore, in my * This is also in opposition to subsequent inclination of the vault Erische, p. 172. * We cannot argue much from the agreement of the two philoso- phers in certain physical theories, such as the form of the earth, the primitive lateral movement and of heaven; the opinion that the stars are stony masses; or on the doc- trine of the senses, for such theories are, as a rule, so little connected with philosophic principles, that either philosopher might equally 304 DIOGENES OF APOLLONIA. opinion, an adherent of the old Ionian physics, of the school of Anaximenes; sufficiently affected by the philosophic discovery of Anaxagoras to attempt a com- bination of his (Anaxagoras') doctrine with that of Anaximenes, but for the most part following Anaximenes in his principle and the application of it. That there would be a retrograde movement," according to this view, from Anaxagoras to Diogenes proves nothing; for historical progress in general does not exclude re- trogression as to particulars : * that Anaxagoras, on the other hand, cannot be immediately related to Anaxi- memes” is true; but we have no right to conclude from this that Diogenes (rather than Heracleitus, the Elea- tics or the Atomists) forms the connecting link between them. Lastly, though the theory of the 6potopspſ, may be a more artificial conception than the doctrine of Diogenes," it by no means follows that it must be the more recent; it is quite conceivable, on the contrary, that the very difficulties of the Anaxagorean expla– nation of mature may have had the effect of confirming Diogenes in his adherence to the more simple and ancient Ionic doctrine. The same might be con- jectured in regard to the dualism of the principles professed by Anaxagoras; " and thus we must regard well have borrowed them from the other. But Diogenes' explanation of the sensuous perception, at any rate, shows a development of the doctrine of Anaxagoras (vide Phi- lippson, "ran ävěpwrívn, 199), and his superiority in empirical know- ledge marks him rather as a con- temporary of Democritus than a predecessor of Anaxagoras. In his theories also of the magnet he seems to follow Empedocles. * Schleiermacher, loc. cit. 166. * From Anaxagoras to Arche- laus there is a similar retrogression. * Schleiermacher, loc. cit. * Ibid. * On this account, Brandis (i. 272) considers Diogenes, with Ar- chelaus and the Atomists, in the light of a reaction against the dualism of Anaxagoras. CHARACTER AND PLACE IN HISTORY. 305 the theory of Diogenes as the attempt of a later philo- sopher, partly to save the physical doctrine of Anaxi- menes and the earlier Ionians as against the innovations of Anaxagoras, and partly to combine them with each other." However noteworthy this attempt may be, the philosophic importance of it cannot be ranked very high ; * the chief merit of Diogenes seems to consist in his having enlarged the range of the empirical know- ledge of nature, and laboured to prove more completely the life and teleological constitution of nature in de- tail. But these ideas were themselves supplied to him by his predecessors, Anaxagoras and the ancient phy- sicists. Greek philosophy, as a whole, had in the time of Diogenes long since struck out paths that conducted it far beyond the point of the earlier Ionian physics.” * As is thought by most modern writers, cf. Reinhold, Gesch. d. Phil. i. 60 ; Fries, Gesch. d. Phil. i. 236 sq.; Wendt zu Tennemann, i. 427 sqq.; Brandis, loc. cit.; Philippson, loc. cit.,198 sqq.; Ueberweg Grundr. i. 42, etc. * The doctrine that Steinhart (loc. cit. p. 298) finds in him, and considers an important advance, viz., ‘that all the Phenomenal is to be regarded as the self-abnega- tion of a principle that is perma- nent and persistent in itself, goes far beyond any of the actual ex- pressions of Diogenes. In reality, he merely says (Fr. 2; wide supra, p.286, 2) that all becoming and all WOL. I. reciprocal action of things among themselves presupposes the unity of their primitive matter. This is, in truth, a noteworthy and preg- nant thought, but the conception of primitive matter and of the rela- tion of primitive matter to things derived, are the same with him as with Anaximenes. * We are reminded of the phy- sical notions of Diogenes, or, at any rate, of the ancient Ionic school, by the Pseudo-Hippocratic work, repl q ūgios traištov (cf. Petersen, p. 30 sq. of the treatise quoted supra, p. 301, 1). Here also we find evi dence of the continuance of that school. 306 THE PPTHAGOREA.N.S. THE PYTHAGOREANS.] I, SOURCES OF OUR KNOWLEDGE IN REGARD TO THE PYTHAGOREAN PHILOSOPHY. AMONG all the schools of philosophy known to us, there is none of which the history is so overgrown, we may almost say, so concealed by myths and fictions, and the doctrines of which have been so replaced in the course of tradition by such a mass of later constituents, as that of the Pythagoreans. Pythagoras and his school are seldom mentioned by writers anterior to Aristotle,” and even from Plato, whose connection with them was from it. Chaignetºs-careful work displays much more sobriety. But * The recent literature concern- ing Pythagoras and his school is given by Ueberweg, Grundr. i. 48. Of more comprehensive works, be- sides the accounts of Greek philo- sophy in general, and Ritter's Gesch. d. Pythag. Phil. (1826), we have the second volume of Röth's Gesch. d. Abendlichen Philosophie, which treats at great length (Abth. 1, pp. 261–984, and 2, pp. 48–319) of Pythagoras; and Chaignet's work in two volumes, Pythagore et la Philosophie Pythagoricienne. Röth's exposition, however, is so entirely devoid of all literary and historical criticism, launches out so confidently into the most arbi- trary conjectures and the most ex- travagant fancies, and leaves so much to be desired in regard to the intelligent apprehension and the correct reproduction of authorities, that in respect to our historical knowledge of Pythagoreanism, hardly anything is to be learned he places far too great confidence in spurious fragments and untrust- worthy statements, and is thus not seldom misled into theories, which cannot stand before a more search- ing criticism. This could scarcely be otherwise, since he starts from the presupposition (i. 250, 4) that the authorities (without exception) are ‘walables, tant qu'om m'a pas démontré l'impossibilité qu'ils he le soient pas,’ instead of asking in each individual case whether the testimony is based on a tradition, founded on the historical fact, and only in proportion as this seems probable, giving credence to it. * The little that can be quoted respecting them from Xenophanes, Heracleitus, Democritus, Herodotus, Io of Chios, Plato, Isocrates, Anaxi- mander the younger, and Andron of Ephesus, will be noticed in the proper place. EARLIER AND LATER AUTHORITIES. 307 so close, we can glean very few historical details re- specting them. Aristotle, indeed, bestowed much attention on the Pythagorean doctrine; not only dis- cussing it in the course of his more comprehensive re- searches, but also treating it in separate treatises: l yet when we compare what he says with later expositions, it is found to be very simple and almost meagre. While later authors can expatiate at length upon Pythagoras and his doctrines, he is never mentioned, or at most Once or twice, by Aristotle; his philosophic doctrines are passed over in silence, and the Pythagoreans are everywhere spoken of as if the writer were ignorant whether, and how far, their theories were really derived from Pythagoras himself.” Even the accounts which we get from the writings of the older Peripatetics and their contemporaries—Theophrastus, Eudemus, Aristo- * The statements concerning the writings in question, repl rôv IIv6a- 'yopetav, trepi Tūs ‘Apxvteſov pixooro- qtas, rà ék Too Tuatov kal Tów 'Apxvretary, trpès tº 'AAkplatovos, are given in Part. ii. b, p. 48, second edition. As to the treatise, Treph Töv IIv6ayopetov, vide also Alexander in Metaph. 542 b, 5; Fr. 31, 1 Bon. ; Stob. Ecl. i. 380; Theo, Arithm. 30; Plut. ap. Gell. N. A. iv. 11, 12; Porphyry, V. Pythag. 41 ; Diog. viii. 19, cf. Brandis, Gr, Röm. Phil. i. 439 sq.; ii. b 1, 85; Rose, De Arist, libr. ord. 79 sqq. Perhaps the so-called treatises on Archytas and the rest are identical with those on the Pythagoreans, or with certain parts of them. Meanwhile, however probable it may be that the treatise on Archytas is spurious, this is not substantiated by Gruppe (Ueber d. Fragm. d. Arch. 79 sq.), or by Rose's argument from the frag- ment hereafter to be quoted or by what he adduces (loc. cit.) from Damascius. Still more hazardous is Rose's repudiation of all the above writings. The quotation in Diog. viii. 34, 'AptorotéAms repl Töv kvěuov, would equally apply to a portion of the treatise on the Pythagoreans, if, indeed (as is most likely), there be not some misunderstanding or interpolation in the passage. * oi kaAoûuevot IIv6ayópelot ; Metaph. i. 5, at the beginning; i. 8, 989 b, 29 ; Meteor. i. 8, 345 a, 14; oi repl thy ’Iraxtav KaNoëplevot 8è IIv6ayopetot, De Coelo, ii. 13, 293 a, 20; Tów 'IraNuków rives kai ka- Aovuévov IIv6ayopetov, Meteor. i. 6, 342 b, 30; cf. Schwegler, Arist. Metaph. iii. 44. x 2 308 THE PXTHAGOREA.N.S. xenus, Dicaearchus, Heracleides, and Eudoxus –are far slighter and more cautious than the subsequent tradi- tion; nevertheless, from them we can see that legend had already taken possession of Pythagoras and his personal history; and that the later Peripatetics had begun to de- velop the Pythagorean doctrines according to their fancy. These sources (of which it is true we possess only fragments) give us scarcely a single detail which we did not already know through Aristotle. Farther de- velopments of the Pythagorean legend, which relate, however, rather to the history of Pythagoras and his school, than to their doetrines, appear during the third and second centuries, in the statements of Epicurus, Timaeus, Neanthes, Hermippus, Hieronymus, Hippo- botus, and others. But it was not until the time of the Neo-Pythagoreans, when Apollonius of Tyana wrote his Life of Pythagoras, when Moderatus compiled a long and detailed work on the Pythagorean Philosophy, when Nicomachus treated the theory of numbers and theology in accordance with the principles of his own school—that the authorities concerning Pythagoras and his doctrines became copious enough to make such expositions as those of Porphyry and Iamblichus pos- sible.” Thus the tradition respecting Pythagoreanism 1 Röth, Abendl. Phil. ii. a, 270, adds to these lyco, the opponent of Aristotle (cf. Partii. b, 36, 2, second ed.), and Cleanthes the Stoic. But it is more probable that the former was a Neo-Pythagorean than a con- temporary of Aristotle; and the Cleanthes of Porphyry is certainly not the Stoic, but most likely a mis- spelling for Neanthes (of Cyzicus). * To the beginning of this pe- riod belongs also (Part iii. b, 74 sqq.) the work from which Alex- ander Polyhistor (Diog. viii. 24 sq.) has taken his exposition of the Pythagorean doctrine, and on which that of Sextus, Pyrrh. iii. 152 sqq.; Math. vii. 94 sqq.; x. 249 sqq., likewise appears to be based. EARLIER AND LATER AUTHORITIES. 309 and its founder grows fuller and fuller, the farther re- moved it is from the date of these phenomena; and more and more Scanty, the nearer we approach them. With the range and extent of the accounts, their mature likewise changes. At first many miraculous stories about Pythagoras were in circulation. In course of time his whole history developes into a continuous series of the most extraordinary events. In the older statements, the Pythagorean system bore a simple and primitive character, in harmony with the general tendency of the pre-Socratic philosophy; according to the later representation, it approximates so greatly to the Platonic and Aristotelian doctrines that the Pytha- goreans of the Christian period could even maintain that the Philosophers of the Academy and the Lyceum had stolen their so-called discoveries, one and all, from Pythagoras.” It is plain that such a development of the tradition could not have been brought about by history, for how can we suppose that the writers of the Christian period had at their command a mass of authentic in- formation unknown to Plato and Aristotle; and how can we recognise as genuine Pythagorean doctrines, propositions which Plato and Aristotle not only do not attribute to the Pythagoreans, but for the most part * Porphyry, V. Pyth. 53, pro- bably after Moderatus. * It is clear that precisely the opposite was actually the case, and that the ancient Pythagorean doc- trine contained none of the accre- tions which afterwards made their appearance. This is betrayed by the author when he says that Plato and Aristotle collected all that they could not adopt, and omitting the remainder, called that the whole of the Pythagorean doctrine; and also in the statement of Moderatus (loc. cit. 48) that the number theory with Pythagoras and his disciples had been only symbolical of a higher speculation (cf. Part iii. b, 96 sq., second edition). 310 THE PYTHAGOREA.N.S. expressly deny that they held, and claim as their own personal discoveries 2 The so-called Pythagorean doc- trines which are not acknowledged as such by ancient authorities are Neo-Pythagorean, and the miraculous tales and improbable combinations with which Pytha- gorean history is so largely adorned in the later authors, no doubt in great part emanate from the same source. But if the untrustworthy and unhistorical character of these expositions is in the main indisputable, we cannot venture to make use of the statements they contain, even where these statements are not in them- selves opposed to historical probability, and to the more ancient and trustworthy authorities; for how can we, in regard to minor particulars, trust the assertions of those who have grossly deceived us in the most important matters ? In all cases therefore where the later au- thorities, subsequent to the appearance of Neo-Pytha- goreism, are unsupported by other testimony, their statements may generally be supposed to rest, not on real knowledge or credible tradition, but on dogmatic presuppositions, party interests, uncertain legends, arbitrary inventions, or falsified writings. Even the agreement of several such authorities cannot prove much, as they are accustomed to transcribe one from the other without any preliminary criticism; their assertions merit attention only in cases where they may either be directly referred to older sources, or where their internal nature justifies us in the belief that they are founded on historical tradition. * Thus Tamblichus copies Por- tions, copied Apollonius and Mo- phyry, and both of them, as far as deratus. we may judge from their quota- FA RLIER AND LATER AUTHORITIES. 311 What has just been said in regard to the indirect authorities for the Pythagorean doctrine, equally ap- plies to the so-called direct sources. Later writers, belonging almost without exception to the Neo-Pytha- gorean and Neo-Platonic period, speak of an extensive Pythagorean literature, the nature and compass of which we may gather not only from the few writings we possess, but far more from the numerous fragments which exist of lost works." A very small fraction, however, of these writings may with any probability be ascribed to the ancient Pythagorean school. Had this school possessed such a mass of written works, it would be hard to understand why the ancient authors should not contain more distinct allusions to them, and es- 'pecially why Aristotle should be so entirely silent as to Pythagoras' own doctrine,” when several of these * A review of these is given in Part iii. b, p. 85 sqq., second edi- tion. Mullach, however, has printed, in his second volume of fragments, most of those omitted in the first. * Diogenes, viii. 6, mentions three works of Pythagoras: a rat- 6evrtkov, a troAttukov, and a puoi- ków. Heracleides Lembus (about 180 B.C.) besides these speaks of a treatise, trepi rod 3xov, and a ispos Aóyos, in hexameters. How this last is related to the iepòs Aóyos, consisting of twenty-four rhapsodies which, according to Suidas, must be attributed to Orpheus, and ac- cording to others, was written by Theognetus the Thessalian, or Cercops the Pythagorean, and is probably identical with the Orphic Theogony (Lobeck, Aglaoph. i. 714) cannot be discovered. That the fragments of a IIv6ayópelos iſuvos about number (ap. Proclus Žn Tim. 155 C, 269 B, 331 E, 212 A, 6 A, 96 D; Syrian in Metaph. 59 b; Schol. in Arist. 893 a, 19 sqq.; Simplicius, Phys. 104 b ; De Coelo, 259 a, 37; Schol. 511 b, 12; cf. Themist. in Phys. iii. 4, p. 220, 22 sq.; in De An. i. 2, pp. 20, 21; Theo, Mus. c. 38, p. 155; Sext. Math. iv. 2; vii. 94, 109; Iambl. V. P. 162. and Lobeck, loc. cit.) belong to the iepos A6-yos of Pytha- goras, it is impossible to prove; but Proclus distinguishes the Py- thagorean hymn very distinctly from the Orphic poem. Iambl. V. P. 146; cf. Proclus in Tim. 289 B, gives the commencement of a second ispos Aó)0s in prose, which was also ascribed to Telauges. Fragments of this are to be found in Iamblichus, Nicom. Arithm. p. 312 THE PPTHAGOREANS, writings bear his very name." 11; Syrian in Metaph.; Schol. in Ar. 842 a, 8, 902 a, 24, 911 b, 2, 931 a, 5 ; Hierocles in Carm. Aur. p. 166 (Philos. Gr. Fr. ed. Mull. i. 464 b); cf. also Proclus in Euclid. p. 7 (222 Friedl.). This ispos Aóryos, as appears from the above quotations, is chiefly concerned with the theological and metaphy- sical import of numbers. In Diod. i. 98 there is mention of a ispos Aóyos of Pythagoras, by which we must probably understand the one in verse, and not the prose work which seems to have been later. Besides the above-named writings Fieracleides, Joc. cit., notices others; Trepl buxºis, trepi ei oreBetas, “Helo- thales,’ and “Croton’ (these last were dialogues, as it would seem), kal &AAovs; Tamblichus (Thºol. Arithm. p. 19) a a tºy ypaupa trepi 6eóv, probably to be distinguished from the ispol A6-yot; Pliny, Hist. Nat. xxv. 2, 13; xxiv. 17, 156 sq., a book on the influences of plants; Galen, De Remed. Parab. Vol. xiv. 567 K, a treatise trept a kíAAms; Proclus, in Tim. 141 D, a Aóryos Trpès”A8apiv; Tzetzes. Chil. ii. 888 sq. (cf. Harless, in Fabr. Bibl. Gr. i. 786), irpo'yvoorturé, Bu68ta; Ma- lal. 66 D; Cedren. 138 C, a his- tory of the war between the Samians and Cyrus; Porphyry, p. 16, an inscription on the grave of Apollo in Delos. Io of Chios (or more probably Epigenes, to whom Kallimachus attributed the rplay- plot) asserted that he composed pseudo-Orphic writings (Clemens, loc. cit.; Diog. viii. 8), and that Hippasus had stolen from him a Avoritikos A6-yos, and from Asto, the Crotonian, a whole series of works (Diogenes, viii. 7). A ſcard.6ao is eis 38ov seems to have given rise to But we are expressly the tale of the philosopher's jour- ney to Hades (vide infra, 340, 2). Nietzsche (Beitr. 2. Quellenkunde, d. Laërt. Diog., Basel, 1870, p. 16 sq.) refers to the same source the statement in Diog. viii.; airoi, Aéyoval ical rôs orkotridógs, substi- tuting conjecturally a kottas Atóao for a kotić6as. The verses in Jus- tin (De Monarch. c. 2, end) have reference to a poem forged or in- terpolated by a Jewish hand; other fragments of Pythagorean writings are to be found in Just. Cohort. c. 19 (Clemens, Protr. 47 C, &c.; cf. Otto, note on the passage in Justin); Porph. De Abstin. iv. 18; Iambl. Theol. Arithm. 19 ; Syrian, Schol. in Arist. 912 a, 32 b, 4 sqq. It is doubtful whether there was a system of Arithmetic in circulation under the name of Pythagoras, to which the statement of his having written the first work on Arithmetic may refer (vide Malal 67 a ; Cedren. 138 D, 156 B; Isodor. Orig. iii. 2). The numerous moral maxims which Stobaeus quotes in the Flo- rilegium from Pythagoras do not seem to have been taken from any work falsely attributed to him. The so-called golden poem was by many ascribed to Pythagoras, although it does not itself lay claim to such an origin (vide Mullach in his edition of Hierocles in Carm-aur. 9 sq.; Fragm. Philos. Gr. i. 410, and the summaries of the extracts from Stobaeus, loc. cit.), and Iam- blichus, V. P. 158, 198, speaks in a general manner of many books embracing the whole of philosophy, which were some of them written by Pythagoras himself, and some under his name. * For the story of the conceal- JPYTHAGO REAN WRITINGS. 313 told that Philolaus was the first Pythagorean who published a philosophical work, that before his time no Pythagorean writings were known," and that Pythagoras himself wrote mothing ; * nor did Hippasus,” although we possess some supposed fragments of his work. Iam- blichus" says that Pythagorean writings were in exist- ment of these writings (vide infra, note 4), which, according to Iambli- chus, was no longer believed, even in the time of Aristotle, cannot be brought forward, more especially if Io had already been acquainted with them (vide preceding note). Röth's groundless statement that Aristotle and the other ancient au- thorities knew only of the Pytha- goreans, the exoterics of the school, and not of the esoteric doctrines taught to the Pythagoreans—(an indispensable and fundamental presupposition of his whole expo- sition) will be examined infra. If this statement be disproved, there is an end of the attempt to recon- struct the iepos Aóryos of Pythagoras from the fragments of the Orphic poem, said to be identical with it (Röth, ii. a, 609–764); since the Pythagorean origin of this poem is not only wholly undemonstrable, but quite incompatible with all credible accounts of the Pythago- rean doctrine. Disregarding Lo- beck's classical labours, Röth con- fuses in such an uncritical manner statements from Orphic and Py- thagorean works relating to writings entirely distinct, and separated from each other by centuries; so that his whole pretentious and elaborate discussion can only mislead those who are less instructed, while for the learned it is utterly valueless. * Diog. viii. 15, but especially section 85: Tottév pman Amuſºrptos (Demetrius Magnes, the well-known contemporary of Cicero) év ‘Ouavû- Lois trpátov čkö00val rôv IIv6ayo- plków trept piloteas. Iambl. V. P. 199; vide infra, note 4. * Porph. V. Pythag. 57 (re- peated by Iambl. V. Pyth. 252 sq.). After the persecution of Cylon: éčéAutre kai ji étria thum, śāntos év toſs oth9ea w śtt puxax6eloa &xpt Tóte, uðvøv táv Švarovvérov trapſ, toſs Ščo 8tauvmuovevouévov otre 'yöp IIv6ayópov at yºypappa fiv, and so on. Those consequently who escaped from the persecution wrote summaries of the Pythagorean doc- trine for their adherents. But Porphyry himself presupposes that there were ancient Pythagorean writings, and, therefore, adds that the Pythagoreans collected them. In Diog. viii. 6, we read : éviou uév oùv IIv0ayópav uměč Šv karaxeitreºv oriyypapuá pagi. This is more emphatically stated in Plut. Alea’. Fort. i. 4, p. 328; Numa, 22; Lu- cian, De Sulut, c. 5; Galen, De Hipp. et Plat. i. 25; v. 6, T xv.; 68, 478, K (although he, in another place, vide sºpra, p. 312, quotes a work of Pythagoras); Joseph. Con. Ap. i. 22, perhaps after Aristobu- lus; Augustin, De Cons. Evang. i. 12 * Diog. viii. 84: p.mal 3' airby Amujitptos év ‘Ouoviſuous uměčv karaXitreºu a tºyypaupa. * V. Pyth. 199: ©avudgeral 6& kaijitſis puxaxis &kpiBeta év y&p to- 314 THE PPTHAGOREANS, ence, but that until the time of Philolaus they were strictly preserved as secret by the school, but this asser- tion can have no weight against the evidence we have just cited; it is rather indeed a confirmation of the fact that the later writers themselves could find no authen- tic traces of the existence of Pythagorean writings previous to Philolaus. When, therefore, the savants of the Alexandrian or Roman period presuppose that such writings must always have existed, at any rate within the Pythagorean school, this theory is entirely based on the assertions of the so-called ancient works themselves, and on the opinions of a generation which could form no idea of a philosophic school without philosophic literature, because it was itself accustomed to get its science from books. Moreover, the internal evidence of most of these reputed Pythagorean fragments is strongly against their authenticity. The greater num- ber of the fragments of Philolaus indeed, as Böckh has shown in his excellent monograph," must certainly be considered genuine, not merely on the score of external testimony, but also, and far more because in content and mode of expression they agree with one another, and are in harmony with all that we know from well authenticated sources as Pythagorean ; there is only one passage of any importance in a philosophic point of view to which we must make an exception.” On the oraúrats')eveafs érôvoúðels öväevi pat- Seiner Werke, 1819. Cf. also veral rôv IIv6ayopetov Šmouvnudºtov trepire revX&s ºrpo ris biXoAdov #Al- kfas, &AA’ of ros trpátos ééâveyke rô. 6pvXočueva raûta Tpía 88Aſa. * Philolaus des Pythagoreer's Lehren, nebst den Bruchsticken Preller, Philol. ; Allg. Encykl. won Ersch und Gruber, sect. iii., vol. xxiii. 370 sq. * Since the above was first written, the genuineness of these fragments of Philolaus, already de- PHILOLA US. 315 ied by Rose; Arist. libr. ord. p. 2, as been warmly contested by chaarschmidt (Die angebliche Xchriftstellerei des Philolaus, 1864), nd the work to which they belonged as been assigned to the first, or t earliest, the second century be- ore Christ. Though I adhere to y original opinion respecting hem, I cannot fully expound my easons for it in this place, but ill merely indicate the chief oints. To begin with, as regards he tradition concerning the writing f Philolaus, the existence of a work under that name is presup- posed by Hermippus (ap. Diog. viii. 85) and Satyrus (ibid. iii. 9) about 200 B.C., for they tell us that Plato bought the work of Philo- laus, and copied his Timaeus from it. Both speak of this work as well known, and it is difficult to see how, if it did not exist, the statement could have arisen. Be- sides, Hermippus borrowed the as- sertion from an older writer. Already about 240 B.C. the book was known to Neanthes, as is shown by the statement of this author in Diog. viii. 55, that up to the time of Philolaus and Empe- docles the Pythagoreans admitted everyone to their instructions, but that when Empedocles had made known their doctrines in his poem, they resolved never to impart them to any other poet. The design of Neanthes in this story can only be to couple Philolaus with Empedo- cles as one of the first Pythagorean writers; not (as Schaarschmidt, p. 76 thinks) to account for the in- troduction of esoteric doctrines by the oral teaching of Philolaus; Philolaus in that teaching, accord- ing to Neanthes himself, only did ther hand, according to the above quotations, there what everyone else had done up to that time. Diogenes, it is true, afterwards speaks of Empedocles alone, and of the exclusion of poets; but he cannot legitimately conclude from this that Neanthes ‘did not know as yet of any work written by Philolaus.’ Diogenes makes this observation in his bio- graphy of Empedocles; he may perhaps have adopted from Nean- thes only what concerned his sub- ject. Or again, Neanthes may have merely mentioned the prohi- bition to which Empedocles, as the first of the so-called Pythagorean writers, had given rise. According to these authorities, too, we must refer the well-known verses of Timon. ap. Gell. N. A. iii. 17, to the work of Philolaus; for it is hardly conceivable that they should relate to no particular work, but to any Pythagorean book whatso- ever (Schaarschmidt, 75). It is true that Philolaus is never men- tioned by Aristotle, though a word is quoted from him in Eth. Eud. ii. 8, 1225 a, 33 ; and Plato in the Timaeus places his physical theories, not in the mouth of Philolaus, but of a Pythagorean otherwise un- known. But Plato had every rea- son to do this, supposing there existed a writing of Philolaus which would immediately have ex- hibited the great difference of his physical doctrines from those of the Pythagoreans. And with re- gard to Aristotle, though it is im- possible that he can have derived his numerous and minute state- ments about the Pythagorean doc- trines merely from oral tradition, yet he never mentions his authori- ties; just as elsewhere he quotes much from the ancient philosophers 316 THE PPTHAGO REANS, can be mo question as to the without saying whence he gets it. We cannot, therefore, argue from his silence respecting Philolaus, that no work of his was known to him. On the other hand, if we compare Metaph. i. 5, 986 b, 2 sqq. with the fragment of Phi- lolaus in Stob. Ecl. i. 454 sq. (vide infra, 371, 2); Metaph. xiii. 6, 1080 b, 20; xiv. 3, 1091 a, 13 sq., with Stob. i. 468; Metaph. i. 5, 985, b, 29 sq. with the fragment in Iambl. Theol. Arithm. p. 56, 22 (vide infra, § iii.), it will appear very probable that Aristotle in these passages is referring to the work of Philolaus ; and considering the scanty number of the fragments we possess, it is not surprising that further proofs are not forthcoming. (For other details, cf. Zeller, Aris- toteles wºnd Philolaos. Hermes. x. 178 sq.) Xenocrates, too, accord- ing to Iambl. Theol. Arithm. p. 61 sq., occupied himself greatly with the writings of Philolaus; and if this evidence is not quite unim- peachable, yet it has in its favour that Xenocrates agrees with Phi- lolaus in his doctrine of aether (vide Part ii. a, 809, 1). We meet with the same theory in the Platonic Epinomis (vide loc. cit. 894, 2), but there also (977 D, sqq.) there seem to be echoes of Philolaus (ap. Stob. i. 8, infra, 371, 1). The external evidence, however, is decidedly in favour of the supposition that Phi- lolaus really composed the writing attributed to him, and that we have received from tradition genu- ine remnants of it. In his judg- ment of the fragments themselves, I cannot agree with Schaarschmidt, as he assigns them all, without ex- ception, to the same author; and on this presupposition easily de- spuriousness of the writing rives arguments from some agains others; whereas the question o identity of authorship was the ver first he should have determined I, for my part, consider the interva so great between the fragment i Stobaeus, Eel. i. 420 (vide infra), and the large majority of the rest, both in form and content, that could not ascribe all to the same author unless I called them all alike unauthentic. Schaarschmidt himself calls attention to the fact that the utterances of this frag- ment about the world-soul are in contradiction to the doctrine of the central fire elsewhere attributed to Philolaus. It further appears to me that, as he has not sufficiently discriminated between the various fragments, neither has he done sobe- tween the fragments of Philolaus's work, and the accounts given us of that work. He attributes (p. 37) to the ‘fragmentist’ the Stoic hyewo- vuköv, and the Platonic Demiurgus in the text, Stob. Ecl. i. 452, as well as (p. 30) the expressions, eixtkptveta rôv orouxetov, pixoperd- Boxos yéveals, ibid. 488; whereas the author whom Stobaeus follows may in this case, as in many others, have applied to ancient doctrines the language and conceptions of later times. On page 38 the con- clusion drawn by Athenagoras (Suppl. 6), from a quite indefinite expression of Philolaus (the Unity and Immateriality of God), is treated as the saying of the so- called Philolaus himself. On page 53 “Philolaus' is said to speak in Stob. Ecl. i. 530, of a triple sum ; though the narrator clearly distinguishes his own remark ‘ that, according to Philolaus, there was in some sort a triple PHILOLA US. 317 ttributed to Pythagoras; and the scattered fragments un,’ from what Philolaus actually aid ; and he afterwards directly scribes two suns to Empedocles. here may indeed be found in the tatements of writers like Stobaeus, seudo-Plutarch, Censorinus, and Boethius about Philolaus, many inaccuracies, lacunae, and uncer- tainties; but we ought not to consider this (as Schaarschmidt does, e.g. p. 53 sq., 55 sq. 72) a proof of the spuriousness of the writings which they are describing, for their statements have very often the same defects in cases where they can be confirmed by more trustworthy evidence. But Schaarschmidt seems to me not seldom to raise objections which can only be based on an incorrect view of the passages and doctrines in question. He says, for instance (p. 32 sqq.), that the passage in Stob. Ecl. i. 360 contradicts the statement of Aristotle (De Coelo, ii. 2, 285 a, 10), that the Pytha- goreans assumed only a right and a left in the world, and not an above and a below, a before and a behind; but this latter statement is explained by another from the work on the Pythagoreans (Schol. in Arist. 492 b, 39), which even, were it spurious, we could scarcely as- sign to a period so recent as the Neo-Pythagorean. The Pythago- reans (we there read) admitted no above and below in the ordinary and proper sense, because they identified the above with the left side of the world, and the below with the right; and at the same time the above with the circumfe- rence, and the below with the centre. This last conception seems to be precisely the meaning of the mutilated passage in Stobaeus; it resolves the opposition of the above and the below into that of the outward and inward. Schaar- Schmidt (p. 38) also finds it incon- ceivable that Philolaus should have called the Central fire, to rpátov ăpuoq8&v to Év (vide infra), but he might have understood it by the help of Aristotle, who equally speaks of the forming of the év with reference to the central fire; and according to him, it was a re- cognised theory that the number One arose from the odd and the even. Nor can we with Schaar- Schmidt (p. 65) consider it un- Pythagorean that the Štreipov and Trepaivov should be distinguished from the éptuov and reptororów ; for we find the same thing in the table of contraries (Arist. Metaph. i. 5, 986 a, 23). To pass over other instances, Schaarschmidt (p. 47 Sqq.) cannot admit that the five elements of Philolaus belong to the ancient Pythagorean doctrine: 1st, because the Pythagoreans (he says), according to Aristotle, admitted no material element; 2, because Em- pedocles was the first to teach the doctrine of the four elements; and 3, because Aristotle was the first who added to these, as a fifth ele- ment, aether. All three of these reasons I dispute. First, the Py- thagoreans no doubt put numbers in the place of material substances as the ultimate ground of things ; but certain Pythagoreans, for ex- ample Philolaus, may nevertheless have sought to explain more pre- cisely how things arise from num- bers, by reducing the qualitative fundamental difference of bodies to the difference of form in their constituent atoms. Plato does this from a similar standpoint. 3}8 THE PPTHAGOREA.N.S. of these which have come down to us, both in respec The Pythagorean doctrine does not assert that there are no bodies, but only that bodies are something de- rived. Second, in regard to Em- pedocles, that philosopher was un- questionably some decads anterior to Philolaus; why then may not his theory of the elements (as I suggested in my second edition, p. 298 sq., 508 sq.) have given rise to the theory of Philolaus? Third, it cannot be proved that Aristotle first taught the existence of a fifth element, though it played an im- portant part in his doctrine. The origin of this idea is evidently Py- thagorean. AEther is admitted by all the philosophers of the older Academy, who retrograded from Platonism to Pythagoreism; in the Epinomis, and by Speusippus, by Xenocrates, and by Plato himself at the end of his life (Part ii. a, 809, 1 ; 860, l; 876, 1 ; 894, 2, 2nd ed.). For all these reasons, I can only agree with Schaar- schmidt's conclusions to a very limited extent. No doubt the Philolaic fragments have not been transmitted to us free from adulte- ration. I have already (pp. 269, 305, 2nd ed.) questioned the value of the fragment of the repl (buxās, given ap. Stob. Ecl. i. 420 sq. I have also expressed my doubts (Ibid. 271, 4, 6; 247, 3) of the mono- theistic sentence cited by Philo, Mundi Opif 23 A, and of the saying in Iamblichus, in Nicol. Arithm. 11. Of the other frag- ments, what is quoted in the third edition of this work, p. 387, from Theol. Arithm. 22, may perhaps most readily cause hesitation. But such a reflection does not seem impossible at a period when the conception of vows had already been discovered by Anaxagoras; especially as we find Aristotl (Metaph. i. 5, 985 b, 30) nami woos and puxh among the thing which were reduced by the Pytha goreans to particular numbers while, on the other hand, it i deserving of note, that the Platoni and Aristotelian theory of th multiplicity of the parts of th soul which was known to other so called Pythagoreans (vide Par iii. b, 120, 2nd ed.) is absent fro this fragment; the difference which exist between the phe- nomena of life and those of the soul are here directly connected with the corporeal organs. The same argument tells in favour of the genuineness of most of these fragments. The influence of the Platonic and Aristotelian philo- sophy, which is so unmistakeable in all pseudo-Pythagorean writings, is not perceptible in them. We find much that is fantastic and strange to us (for instance, the nu- merical symbolism, vide p. 337, third edition), but nothing that is distinctive of later Pythagoreism, such as the opposition of form and substance, spirit and matter, the transcendant conception of God, the eternity of the world, the astronomy of Plato and Aris- totle, the world-soul and the de- veloped physics of the Timaeus. The tone and exposition (apart from certain particulars which are to be placed to the account of later expositions) entirely accord with the conception we should naturally form of the language of a Pytha- gorean in the time of Socrates; it also contains things which can scarcely be ascribed to a more re- cent author, such as the distribu- PYTHAGO REAW WRITINGS. 319 to their form and content," can only serve to strengthen our suspicion. Opinions are likewise unanimous as to the spuriousness of the treatise on the World-soul, attributed to Timaeus of Locris, but obviously an extract from the Timaeus of Plato. The demonstration of Ten- nemann” in regard to this is amply sufficient. As to Ocellus of Lucania, and his work on the universe, the only question can be whether or not the work itself claims to be of ancient Pythagorean origin; for that it is not, is perfectly evident. Its latest editor, however, rightly maintains that the work claims for its author the so-called Pythagorean, to whom ancient writers with one accord” ascribe it, whenever they mention it at all. Of the other relics of the Pythagorean School, the most important are the works of Archytas; but after all that has been said on this subject in modern times," my tion of chords (discussed by Böckh. Philol. 70), for which, according to Nicom. Harm. i. p. 9, Meib., Pytha- goras had already substituted the octachord. Schaarschmidt's judg- ment on the Philolaic fragments is endorsed by Ueberweg, Grundr. i. 47, 50, by Thilo, Gesch. d. Phil. i. 57, and Rothenbücher, System der Pyth. mach den Angaben des Arist. (Berlin, 1867). Rothenbücher seeks to establish his opinion by a criticism of the fragment, ap. Stob. Ecl. i. 454. I cannot, how- ever, at present enter upon the discussion of this criticism, as there will be opportunity for replying to its chief allegations later on. * The fragments are mostly Doric, but Pythagoras no doubt spoke the Ionic dialect of his na- tive city, where he had lived up to the period of his manhood. * System der Plat. Phil. i. 93 sqq.; cf. the further proof given by Hermann, Gesch. wind Syst. der Plat. Phil. i. 701 sq. * Mullach, Aristot. de Melisso &c.; et Ocell; Luc. De univ. nat. (1845), p. 20 sqq.; Fragm. Philos. i. 383; cf. Part iii. b, pp. 83, 99 115, second edition. * Ritter, Gesch. der Pyth. Phil. 67 sqq.; Gesch. der Phil. i. 377; and Hartenstein, De Archytae Ta- rentini Fragm. (Leipzig, 1833)— both, especially Ritter, discard the greater number of the fragments, and these the most important from a philosophic point of view. Eggers (De Archytae Tar. Vita Opp. et Phil., Paris, 1833); Petersen (Zeitschrift für Alterthumsw. 1836, 873 sqq.); Beckmann (De Pythag. Reliquiis); and Chaignet (loc. cit. i. 191 sqq., 255 sqq.) recognise the greater number. Gruppe (iber die Fragm, des Archytas) repudiates 320 THE PYTHIAGOREA.N.S. judgment is still that among the numerous longer or shorter fragments attributed to him, by far the greater number have preponderating evidence against them ; and those which may be considered authentic can add little to our knowledge of the Pythagorean philosophy as a whole, belonging as they do chiefly to mathematics, or other specific branches of enquiry." This judgment is not to be set aside by the fact that Petersen,” in order to explain the undeniably Platonic element in the so-called books of Archytas, regards him as having anticipated the Platonic doctrine of Ideas, and Beck- mann” makes him out in this respect a disciple of Plato; for not a single ancient authority alludes to this pretended Platonism of Archytas. Where the rela- tion between Plato and Archytas is mentioned, we hear only of a personal relation, or a scientific intercourse which would by no means involve a similarity in philo- sophic theories.” On the contrary, where the philo- all without exception ; and Mul- lach (Fr. Phil. Gr. ii. 16 sq.) thinks it probable that we possess next to nothing of Archytas. Cf. Beckmann, p. 1. 1. Cf. Aristotle, Metaph. viii. 2 g, E, ; and Eudemus, ap. Simpl. Phys. 98 b, 108 a ; , Ptolemaeus, Harm. i. 13; and Porphyry, in Ptol. Harm. p. 236 sq., 257, 267, 269, 277, 280, 310, 313, 315; cf. Part iii. b, 91, second edition. 2 Loc. cit. 884, 890. 3 Loc. cit. 16 Sqq. Similarly Chaignet, i. 208. * This, strictly speaking, is true of the two pieces of evidence on which Beckmann (p. 17 sq.) relies so much, namely that of Eratos- thenes (ap. Eutoc, in Archimed. De Sphaera et Cyl. ii. 2, p. 144 Ox. quoted by Gruppe, p. 120) to the effect that of the mathematicians of the Academy (robs trapö tä IIAárovi év 'Akaënufg yeagérpas) Archytas and Eudoxus were the two who solved the Delian pro- blem ; and that of the Pseudo-De- mosthenes (Amator. p. 1415), who says that Archytas was previously held in contempt by his country- men, but acquired his honourable reputation in consequence of his connection with Plato. The first of these statements is given by Eratosthenes himself as a mere legend; and the second has proba- bly about as much historical foun- dation as another assertion in the same work: that Pericles became the great statesman he was, through the teaching of Anaxagoras. ARCHIVTAS. 321 sophic opinions of Archytas are spoken of, he is always described as a Pythagorean, and that not only by the more recent writers subsequent to Cicero's time,' but even as early as Aristoxenus,” whose acquaintance with the later Pythagoreans is beyond question; indeed Archytas clearly calls himself a Pythagorean,” in a fragment the authenticity of which can scarcely be disputed." It is true that the School of Archytas is also mentiomed as an independent school,” but that does not disprove our thesis. This school is as much a Pythagorean school as that of Xenocrates is Platonic, or that of Theophrastus Peripatetic. If, however, Archytas was a Pythagorean, he cannot have been at the same time an adherent of the doctrine of Ideas; * Among these Beckmann (p. 16) cites the following: Cic. De Orat. iii. 34, 139 (a passage which is remarkable, because while agree- ing in other respects with the above mentioned testimony of the Pseudo- Demosthenes, it makes Philolaus, instead of Plato, the instructor of Archytas; we must read with Orelli, Philolaus Archytam, and not Philolaum Archytas). Ibid. Fin. v. 29, 87; Rep. i. 10; Valer. Max. iv. 1, ext, ; vii. 7, 3, ext. ; Apul. Dogm. Plat. i. 3, p. 178, Hild. ; Diog. viii. 79; Hieron. Epist. 53, T. 1, 268, Mart. Olympiodor. V. Plato, p. 3, Westerm. To these may be added, besides Iamblichus, Ptolemaeus, Harm. i. c. 13 sq. * Diog. viii. 82: yeyóvari 5’ 'Apx.jrat Tétrapes . . . Tov če IIv6a- yopulcov Aptoráčevös pmat umöétrore atparnyolovra iittmbival. Beck- mann's doubt of this passage is unfounded. Cf. also Diog. 79. We should beinclined to read’Apx|rtrov for 'Apxörov in the text of Iambli- WOL. I. chus, V. P. p. 251 (of 5& Aourol Töv IIv0aºyopetov &tégºrmoſav Tijs 'Itaxias TAhv’Apxºtou roi, Tapavrf- vov), for in the time of Archytas there was no longer any necessity for the Pythagoreans to flee from Italy; the passage is, however, so mutilated, that we cannot even discover the connection in which the statement occurred in Aristox- €IlllS. * Cf. Part ii. b, 711 sq., and £nfra, p. 364, 4. Stob. Floril. 101, 4, calls him a Pythagorean, Suidas 'Aptoráč., more precisely, a pupil of Xenophilus, the Pythagorean. * According to Porph. in Pto- lem. Harm. p. 236, his work, trepl waſ nuatukis, began with these words: kaxós uot Sokoúvri [sc. oi IIv6ayópezoil to repl rà ua6%uata ôtayvóvas' kal oë6èv &rotrov, Öp6ós airot's trepi čkaarov 9eapeſv repl ºyàp Tâs róv 3Awy pāorios épôās 8tayvávres éueAAov kai repl rôv karū. piépos oia èvrl & headai. * Wide Beckmann, p. 23. Y 322 THE PIV THAGOREA.N.S. for it is not merely impossible to prove' that this doctrine was known to the Pythagoreans, but Aristotle's evidence is most distinctly to the contrary.” Since therefore in the fragments of the so-called Archytas we encounter Platonic as well as Peripatetic doctrines and expressions, we must consider these a sure sign of a later origin, and consequently reject by far the greater number of the fragments. Even supposing the modern case for their defence were successful, they could not be regarded as records of the Pythagorean doctrines; for if they can only be rescued by making their author a Platonist, we cannot be sure in any given case how far they reproduce the Pythagorean point of view. A contemporary of Archytas, Lysis the Tarentine, has latterly been conjectured by Mullach” to be the author of the so-called Golden Poem ; but the corrupt passage in Diogenes viii. 6 “is no evidence for this, and the work itself is so colourless and disconnected, that it looks rather like a later collection of practical precepts, some of which had perhaps been long in circulation in a metrical form.” In any case, however, it does not * Plato's utterances in the So- * In his edition of Hierocles, phist, 246 sqq. cannot, as Petersen p. 20; Fragm. Philos. i. 413. (loc. cit.) and Mallet (Ecole de * yéyparrat 8& ré IIv6ayáog Mégare, liil, sq) believe, relate to the later Pythagoreans (cf. ii. a. 215 sq.), and the polemic of Aris- totle's Metaphysics against a num- ber-theory bound up with thc doctrines of Ideas is directed not against Pythagoreans, but the va- rious branches of the Academy. * Metaph. i. 6, 987 b, 7, 27 sqq.; cf. c. 9, beginning; xiii. 6, 1080 b, 16, c. 8, 1083 b, 8; xiv. 3, 1090 a, 20; Phys. iii. 4, 203 a, 3. orvyypſippiata tpia, traidevruköv, troAi- Tuköv, purikóv' to 8& pepópevov čs IIv6ayópov Aëotáðs éori rod Tapav- Tívov. * As is certainly true of the well-known Pythagorean oath, v. 47 sq., which is generally con- sidered as the property of the whole school, and, according to Iambl. Theol. Arithm. p. 20, is also to be met with in Empedocles (cf. Ast. in Theol. Arithm. and Mullach, notes on the golden poem, loc. cit.); P}"THAGOREAN FRAGMENTS. 3:33 4 * materially contribute to our knowledge of the Pytha- gorean philosophy. In regard to the remaining fragments, with few and unimportant exceptions, those which bear the names of well-known ancient Pythagoreans, such as Theano, Brontinus, Clinias, and Ecphantus, are certainly spur- ious. Most of them, however, are attributed to men of whom we either know nothing at all, or are ignorant when they lived. But as these fragments precisely resemble the rest in their content and exposition, we cannot doubt that they too claim to be of ancient Pythagorean origin. If they have no such origin, they must be considered deliberate forgeries, and not the genuine productions of a later Pythagoreamism approxi- mating to the Platonic or Peripatetic philosophy. Moreover, the later Pythagoreanism which professes to be older than Neo-Pythagoreanism, has been altogether derived from these fragments, whereas all historical evi- dence agrees that the latest ramifications of the ancient Pythagorean School do not extend beyond the time of Aristotle. In truth, few or no elements of ancient Pythagoreanism are to be found in these numerous passages. Of these fragments and of the other vestiges of Pythagoreanism, so much as claims our attention from a philosophic point of view will be treated further on; we shall also discuss more at length the fragments we possess of the writings of certain philosophers whose relation to Pythagoras is not quite ascertained, such as Hippasus and Alcmaeon. the same may probably hold good it, ap A. Gell, vi. 2, proves nothing of v. 54. Consequently the quota- in regard to the age of the poem. tion which Chrysippus makes from Y 2 PYTHIAGORAS. II. PYTHAGORAS AND THE PYTHAGOREANS. CoNSIDERING the number of traditions in existence respecting the founder of the Pythagorean school, the amount which can be relied on with any historical probability, when separated from the labyrinth of un- certain legends and later conjectures, is very small. We know that his father's name was Mnesarchus,” that Samos was his home and doubtless also his birthplace;” * Heracleitus, ap. Diog. viii. 6, Herodotus, iv. 95, and most of the other authorities. The name, Marmacus, given to him, according to Diog. viii. 1, by several writers, is perhaps founded merely on a scriptural error. Justin (xx. 4) calls him Demaratus, which is most likely also founded on scne confusion or another. * He is called a Samian by Hermippus (ap. Diog. viii. 1), by Hippobotus (Clem. Strom. i. 300, D), and by later writers almost without exception; Iamblichus (V. P. 4) mentions the statement that both his parents were descend- ed from Ancaeus, the founder of Samos; Apollonius. however (ap. Porph. V. P. 2), asserts this of his mother only. His Samian origin may be reconciled with the state- ments that he was a Tyrrhenian (vide Aristoxenus, Aristarchus, and Theopompus, ap. Clement. and Diogenem, loc. cit.; the similar passage in Theodoret, Gr. aff, cur. i. 24, S, 7, together with Eus. Pr. Ev. x. 4, 13, is taken from that of Clemens; Diodor. Fragm. p. 554 Wess.) or a Phliasian (anony- mous writer cited by Porph. Pyth. p. 5); if we suppose with O. Mül- ler (Geschichte der hell. St. u. St. ii. b, 393) and Krische (De Societ. a Pyth. conditæ Scopo politico, p. 3, etc.) that he came of a Tyrrheno- Pelasgic family, which had emi- grated from Phlius to Samos. Pausanias (ii. 13, 1 sq.) actually relates as a Phlian legend that Hippasus, the great grandfather of Pythagoras, went from Phlius to Samos, and this is confirmed by Diog. L. viii. 1; in the fabulous tale of Ant. Diogenes, ap. Porph. V. P. 10, and in the better attested statement, ibid. 2, Mnesarchus is spoken of as a Tyrrhenian who had emigrated from his home. On the other hand, the statement in Plut. Qu. Conv. viii. 7, 2, that he was an Etruscan by birth is evidently a mistake, as also the opinion (ap. Porph. 5) that he originally came from Metapontum ; Neanthes (in- stead of which our text of Por- phyry, as we have seen, gives Cle- anthes) ap. Porph. V. P. 1, makes Mnesarchus a Tyrian, who, on ac- count of his services at Samos, received the right of citizenship there (Clemens and Theod. loc. cit. say incorrectly that he asserted Pythagoras himself to have been a Tyrian or a Syrian); but the state- ment is of little consequence, since it may be explained partly by a HIS DATE. 325 but the time of his birth, death, and removal to Italy can only be approximately determined; "'the statements confusion of Túpios and Tufiñmvös, and partly from an attempt to ac- count for the supposed oriental wisdom of the philosopher by his extraction. Probably in reference to this story, Iamblichus, V. P. 7, represents him as having been born during a journey of his parents to Sidon. The well-known story of Heracleides of Pontus, and of Sosi- crates (ap. Cic. Tusc. v. 3, 8 ; Diog. i. 12; viii. 8 ; cf. Nicom. Arithm. sub. init.) about Pythagoras' con- versation with the tyrant Leo of Phlius, in which he declared him- self to be a pixóoroqos, points to a connection with Phlius. 1 The calculations of Dodwell and Bentley, the former of whom places his birth in Ol. 52, 3, and the latter in Ol. 43, 4, have been sufficiently refuted by Krische, loc. cit. p. 1, and Brandis, i. 422. The usual opinion now is that Pytha- goras was born about the 49th Olympiad, that he came to Italy about the 59th or 60th, and died in the 69th. This is no doubt ap- proximately correct, and greater exactitude cannot be attained; even the statements of the ancients are probably based only upon un- certain estimates, and not upon distinct chronological traditions. According to Cicero, Rep. ii. 15; cf. Tusc. i. 16, 38; iv. 1, 2; A. Gell. xvii. 21 ; Iambl. V. P. 35, Pythagoras came to Italy in the 62nd Olympiad, the fourth year of Tarquinius Superbus (532 B.C.), whereas. Liv. i. 18, represents him as teaching there under Servius Tullius. Others, doubtless after Apollodorus, name the 62nd Ol. as the period in which he flourished (so Clem. Strom. i. 302 B, 332 A.; Tatian, Con. Graec. c. 41; Cyrill. in Jul. i. 13 A ; Euseb. Chron. Arm. T. ii. 201, vide Krische, p. 11). Diodorus (loc. cit.) even gives Ol. 61, 4, and Diogenes, viii. 45, Ol. 60. Both statements are probably founded on the assertion of Aris- toxenus, who, following Porphyry 9, makes Pythagoras emigrate to Italy in his fortieth year, to escape from the tyranny of Polycrates. According to the date assigned to the commencement of the tyranny, the former or the latter date was fixed for Pythagoras (cf. Rohde, Quellen des Iambl. in his Biogr. des Pyth. ; Rhein. Mus. xxvi. 568 sq.; Diels, Ub. Apollodor's Chronika, ibid. xxxi. 25 sq.). If the fortieth year of the philosopher's life be placed in Ol. 62, 1, we get Ol. 52, 1 as the date of his birth (572 B.C.); this would agree with the text of Eusebius, Chron., which states that he died in the Ol. 40, 4 (497 B.C.), if we suppose him to have attained his 75th year (Anon. ap. Syncell. Chron. 247 c.). The traditions as to the length of his life vary exceed- ingly. Heracleides Lembus (ap.Diog. viii. 44) gives it as 80 years (which may have been derived from Diog. viii. 10); but most writers, follow- ing Diog. 44, have 90: Tzetz. Chil. xi. 93, and Sync. loc. cit., say 99; Iamblichus (265) nearly 100 ; the biographer, ap. Phot. (Cod. 249, p. 438 b, Bekk.) 104; a Pseudo-Py- thagorean, ap. Galen. (Rem. Parah. T. xiv. 567 K) 117, or more. If Pythagoras (as asserted by Iambl. 265) was at the head of his school, for 39 years, and if his arrival in Italy occurred in 532 B.C., his death must have occurred in 493 B.C., and supposing him to have been 56 326 PYTHAGORAS. of the ancients as to his teachers seem almost entirely (Iambl. 19) when he came into Italy, we should get 588 as the year of his birth. If, on the other hand (Iambl. 255), the attack on his school, which he is said not to have survived very long (vide infra p. 282, 1, third edition), be brought into direct connection with the destruction of Sybaris (510 B.C.), his death must have taken place in the sixth century. Lastly, Antilo- chus in Clem. Strom. i. 309 B. places the #xurcía of Pythagoras (not his birth as Brandis, i. 424, says) 312 years earlier than the death of Epicurus, which, according to Diog. x. 15, happened in Ol. 127, 2; this would bring us to Ol. 49. 2, and the philosopher's birth must be put back to the beginning of the sixth century. We are ta- ken still farther back by Pliny, who, according to the best attested reading of Hist. Nat. ii. 8, 37, as- signs an astronomical discovery of Pythagoras to the 42nd Olympiad, or the 142nd year of the City; while, on the contrary, his abbre- viator, Solinus, c. 17, says that Pythagoras first came to Italy during the consulate of Brutus, therefore A. U. C. 244–5, or 510 B C. Röth (p. 287 sq.) combines with this last statement the asser- tion of Iambl. (V. P. 11, 19) that |Pythagoras left Samos at the age of eighteen, received instruction from Pherecydes, Thales, and Anaximander; was 22 years in Egypt, and after its conquest by Cambyses (525 B.C.), 12 more in Babylon; and at the age of 56 again returned to Samos. Conse- quently he places his birth in 569 B.C.; his return to Samos in 513 B.C.; his arrival in Italy in 510; and his death in 470. But these statements are entirely destitute of evidence. Röth supposes that Iamblichus may have borrowed them from Apollonius (of Tyana), but even if this were true, we must still ask where Apollonius obtained them? There is no mention even of the so-called Crotonian memoirs on which Apollonius (ap. Iambl. 262) founds his narrative of the expulsion of the Pythagoreans from Croton. This narrative, however, cannot be reconciled with Röth's calculation, as it makes the residence of Pythagoras in Croton precede the destruction of Sybaris (Iambl. 255). Now it is true that his death must be put back at least to 470 B.C.. if, as Dicaearchus and others maintain (vide infra), the attack on the Crotonian Pythago- reans, from which Lysis and Ar- chippus alone are said to have es- caped, took place in the lifetime of Pythagoras; nay, in that case, we must even allow 18 or 20 years more; for the birth of Lysis, as we shall find, can scarcely have oc- curred before 470. The only in- ference from this, however, is that the statement must be discarded ; that Dicaearchus does not here de- serve the credit of trustworthiness which Porphyry (V. P. 56) accords to him ; and that no thoughtful critic could regard this judgment of Porphyry's as decisive in favour of the narrative of Dicaearchus. Pythagoras cannot have lived to the year 470 B c.: this is evident from the manner in which he is spoken of by Xenophanes and Heracleitus, both of whom are before that date (vide infra, p. 381, 1, third edition, 283, 3); their expressions certainly do not give us the impression of re- lating to a person still alive. More- HIS THEA. VELS. 327 destitute of any Secure historic foundation," and even his connection with Pherecydes, which has in its favour an old and respectable tradition,” is not quite beyond a doubt.” over, none of our authorities, except Solinus, who is not to be depended upon, place the arrival of Pytha- goras in Italy later than Ol. 62. For Iamblichus himself (that is to say, Apollonius) does not intend this (V. P. 19) when he says that he first came there twelve years after the conquest of Egypt by Cambyses (therefore after 425 B.C. Even Apollonius, ap. Iambl. 255, as al- ready observed, makes him outlive by very little the destruction of Sybaris), but Iamblichus is too care- less or too ignorant of claronologi- cal matters to remark the contra- diction into which his narrative has fallen. It is clear, however, that none of our informants had at their command trustworthy and exact chronological details as to the life of Pythagoras. Perhaps, indeed, all their statements were inferred from a few notices, e.g. concerning his migration in the time of Polycrates, or the Pythagorean- ism of Milo, the conqueror at the Traës. We must, therefore, leave it undecided whether and how long the philosopher survived the end of the sixth century. * Diog. viii. 2, names Phere- cydes and Hermodamas, a des- cendant of the Homerid Creophy- lus of Samos, and, according to Iambl. 11, himself called Creophy- lus. Neanthes (ap. Porph. 2, 11, 15) adds to these Anaximander, Iamblichus (9, 11, 184, 252) Thales. Instead of Thales, Apuleius (Floril. ii. 15, p. 61, Hild.) names Epime- mides, with whom, according to Of his distant journeyings, which Diog, viii. 3, Pythagoras was ac- quainted. The Scholiast of Plato, p. 420, Bekk. says that he first attended Pherecydes' instructions, then those of Hermodamas, afterwards those of Abaris, the Hyperborean (vide infra). Thus it is plain that as time went on, celebrated names continued to be added to the list. Abaris and Epimenides are, however, also called disciples of Pythagoras (Iambl. 135). * Besides the text already quoted, Diog. i. 118 sq.; viii. 40 (after Aristoxenus), Andron, and Satyrus; the epitaph of which Duris, ap. Diog. i. 120, speaks; Cic. Tusc. i. 16, 38 ; De Div. i. 50, 112 ; Diodor. Fragm. p. 554; Ps. Alex. in Metaph. 828 a, 19, Fr. 800, 24 Bon. &c. * For in the first place it was very natural that the thaumatur- gist, Pythagoras, should have been represented as the pupil of an older contemporary of similar character, who likewise held the dogma of Transmigration; and secondly, the accounts on the subject are not agreed as to details. According to Diog. viii. 2, Pythagoras was brought to Pherecydes at Lesbos, and after Pherecydes' death, handed over to Hermodamas in Samos. Iambl. 9, 11, says that he was instructed by Pherecydes first in Samos, and then in Syros. Por- phyry (15, 56) says, following Dicaearchus' and others, that he tended his master, who was sick in Delos, and buried him before his 328 PYTHAGORAS. are said to have acquainted him with the wisdom and religious ceremonies of the Phenicians,' the Chaldaeans,” the Persian Magi,” the Hindoos, the Arabians,” the departure to Italy; on the other hand, Diodorus (loc. cit.), Diog. viii. 40, and Iambl. 184, 252, following Satyrus and his epitomiser, Hera- cleides, say that shortly before his own death he went from Italy to Delos for that purpose. * According to Cleanthes (Ne- anthes), in Porphyry, V. P. 1, Pythagoras was brought as a boy to Tyre by his father, and there instructed by “the Chaldaeans.” Iambl. V. P. 14, says that when he left Samos on his great travels, he first went to Sidon, and there met with prophets, the descendants of the ancient Mochus (vide supra, p. 48, and infra, chapter on the Atomists, note 2), and other hiero- phants ; that he visited Tyre, Biblus, Carmel, &c., and was initi- ated into all the mysteries of the country. Porphyry (V. P. 6) is more moderate; he merely states that Pythagoras is said to have gained his arithmetical knowledge from the Phoenicians. * According to Neanthes, Py- thagoras had, when a boy, been instructed by the Chaldaeans (vide previous note). According to all other testimony, he first came to Babylon from Egypt, either of his own accord, or as the prisoner of Cambyses. This statement ap- pears in its simplest form in Strabo, xiv. i. 16, p. 638: IIv6ayópaviorto- potow . . . . &meA6etu eis Atyvirrov ical Bağvačva piñouafletas x&piv. Clemens, Strom. 302 C, merely says: XaAbatov rekal Mdywy roºs ãptorous ovveyévero; Eus. Pr. Ev. x. 4, 9 sq.; Antipho, ap. Diog. viii. 3; Schol. Plat. p. 420, Bekk. Porph. 6 say that he learned as- tronomy from the Chaldaeans. In Justin xx. 4, he is said to have travelled to Babylon and Egypt, ad perdiscendos siderum motus ori- ginemgue mund; spectandam. Apul. Floril. ii. 15, states that he was instructed by the Chaldaeans in astronomy, astrology, and medicine. According to Diogenes in the book of Prodigies (ap. Porph. 11) he 1earned the interpretation of dreams from the Chaldaeans and Hebrews (or from the Hebrews only 2). In Iambl. V. P. 19 ; Theol. Arithm. p. 41, we are told that in the con- quest of Egypt by Cambyses he was carried as a prisoner to Baby- lon, remained twelve years in that city, where in his intercourse with the Magi, he not only perfected himself in mathematics and music, but completely adopted their reli- gious prescripts and practices. That Iamblichus is here following some older authority (Apollonius, no doubt), is shown by the state- ment of Apul. Floril. ii. 15. Many maintain that Pythagoras was ta- ken prisoner by Cambyses in his Egyptian campaign, and was only set at liberty a long time after by Gillus the Crotonian ; and that in consequence of this he had the benefit of the instructions of the Persian Magi, especially Zoroaster. *. Pythagoras must early have been brought into connection with the Magi, and especially with Zo- roaster, if what Hippolytus says is true (Refut. Her, i. 2, p. 12 D); cf. vi. 23: Atóðwpos 3& 6'Eperptees a writer otherwise unknown) kal 'Aptoſtóševos 6 povo ticós part irpos HIS TRAVELS. 329 Zapdrav Tov XaAbalov čAmAv6éval IIv6ayópav; he imparted to Pytha- goras his doctrine, which Hippoly- tus proceeds to describe, but in a very untrustworthy manner. This statement of Hippolytus, how- ever, is hardly sufficient to prove that Aristoxenus asserted a per- sonal acquaintance between Pytha- goras and Zoroaster. He may, perhaps, have observed the simi- larity of the two doctrines, and hazarded the conjecture that Py- thagoras was acquainted with Zoroaster; for there is no certainty at all that Hippolytus himself knew the work of Aristoxenus. What he says about the Zoroas- trian doctrines which Pythagoras adopted cannot have been taken as it stands from Aristoxenus, because it presupposes the story about Py- thagoras' prohibition of beans to be true, while, as we shall presently find, Aristoxenus expressly con- tradicts it. Besides, the evidence of Aristoxenus would merely prove that even in his time similari. ties had been discovered between the Pythagorean and the Zoro- astrian doctrine, then well known in Greece (cf. Diog. Laërt. i. 8 sq.; Damasc. De Princ. 125, p. 384, and that these resemblances had been explained after the manner of the Greeks by the hypothesis of a personal relation between the two authors. Plutarch seems to have derived his shorter state- ment from the same source as Hippolytus; there is, therefore, all the less reason to doubt that here too, as in Hippolytus, Zaratas ori- ginally meant Zoroaster; supposing even that Plutarch himself, who (De Is. 46, p.369) makes Zoroaster to have lived 5000 years before the Trojan war, discriminated them. Our most ancient authority for this relationshipis Alexander(Poly- histor), who, according to Clemens, Strom. i. 304 B, said in his work on the Pythagorean symbols: Na- gap&rq, tº 'Agovpiq plaðm rejoral rov IIv6ayópav. This Naçãparos is evi- dently Zoroaster; if, indeed, Zapárg ought not to be substituted. That Pythagoras visited the Persian Magi we are likewise told in Cic. Fin. v. 29, 87 ; cf. Tusc. iv. 19, 44; Diog. viii. 3 (perhaps after Antipho); Eus. Pr. Ev. x. 4; Cy- rill. c. Jul. iv. 133 D; Schol. in Plat. p. 420, Bekk.; Apul. (vide pre- ceding note); Suidas, IIv6. Valer. Max. viii. 7, 2, assert that he learned astronomy and astrology in Persia from the Magi. Anto- nius Diogenes relates, ap. Por- phyry, V. P. 12 (év toſs Štěp ©očAmv &triotous, the well-known book of fables described by Phot. Cod. 166, and treated not only by Porphyry, but also by Röth, ii. a, 343, as a work of the highest au- thenticity), that he met Zd 8paros in Babylon, was purified by him from the sins of his previous life, and in- structed in the abstinences neces- sary to piety, and in the nature and reasons of things. * Clem. Strom. i. 304 B: ákm- kośval re trpos rotºrous Taxatóv Kal Bpaxuávov Tov IIv6ayópav BoöAeral (namely, Alexander in the work quoted in the previous note); after him, Eus. Pr. Ev. x. 4, 10; Apul. Foril. ii. 10 : of the Brahmins whom he visited, he learned qua mentium documenta corportzmgue eacercitamenta, quot partes animi, quot vices vitae, quae Diis manibus pro merito sui cuique tormenta vel praemia. Philostr. V. Apoll. viii. 7, 44, says that the wisdom of Pytha- goras was derived from the Egyp- tian yupuwitat and the Indian sages * Diog, in Porphyry, 11. 330 PYTHAGORAS. Jews,' the Thracians,” the Druids of Gaul,” but above * That Pythagoras borrowed many of his doctrines from the Jews is asserted by Aristobulus in Eus. Pr. Ev. xiii. 12, 1, 3 (ix. 6, 3), and the same is repeated by Joseph. Con. Ap. i. 22, and Clem. Strom. v. 560 A (who thinks that the ac- quaintance of Plato and Pythago- ras with the Mosaic writings is shown in their doctrines). Cyrill. c. Jul. i. 29 D, Jos. appeals in Sup- port of this to Hermippus, who, in his work on Pythagoras, says: raira ö’ étrpatte kal éAeye tas 'Iovöatav Kal Opalcóv Šáčas uplodge- vos kal wetapépov eis éautów. He had also said the same, as Origen, c. Cels. i. 13, relates with the word Aéyeral, év tá, trpátº trepl vouc0e- Tôv, If even these authors derived their statements from Aristobulus, it is not certain that Hermippus really expressed himself thus ; but supposing he did so, it would only prove that this Alexandrian sage, of the early part of the second cen- tury before Christ, had found the assertion among the Alexandrian Jews, and believed it; or else that he had himself observed some similarities between the Pythago- rean and Jewish doctrines, and had inferred from them that Py- thagoras was acquainted with the customs and doctrines of the Jews. * Hermippus, ap. Jos., vide pre- ceding note. This statement was no doubt based upon the likeness of the Pythagorean mysteries to those of the Orphics, and especially in their common doctrine of Trans- migration. In consequence of this likeness, Pythagoras was re- presented as the pupil of the Thra- cians; he had, it is said, received his consecration from Aglaopha- mus in Libethra; as the pseudo- Pythagoras himself (not Telauges as Röth ii. a, 357, b, 77, supposes) says in the fragment of a ispos Aóryos in Iambl. V. P. 146, cf. 151, and following that authority, Procl. in Tim. 289 B; Plat. Theol. i. 5, p. 13. Conversely, in the legend of Zal- moxis (ap. Herod. iv. 95, and others after him, e.g. Ant. Diog. ap. Phot. Cod. 166, p. 110 a ; Strabo, vii. 3, 5; xvi. 2, 39, p. 297, 762; Hippolyt. vide next note), the doctrine of immortality of the Thracian Getae is derived from Pythagoras. * Surprising as this sounds, it is undeniably asserted by Alex- ander in the passage quoted p. 329, 4; and Röth (ii. a, 346) is entirely on a wrong track when he discovers in it a misunderstanding of the statement that Pythagoras met in Babylon with Indians and Calatians (an Indian racementioned in Herod. iii. 38, 97, who, being of a dark colour, he calls also Ethio- pians, c. 94, 101). The idea pro- bably arose in this way. The Pythagorean doctrine of Transmi- gration was found, or supposed to be found (vide Supra, p. 73,1), among the Gauls, as every such simila- larity was thought to be based upon a relation of teacher and taught, either Pythagoras was made a disciple of the Gauls, as by Alexander, or the Druids were made disciples of the Pythagorean philosophy, as by Diodorus and Ammian (vide supra, 73, 1), into which, according to Hippolyt. Refut. har. i. 2, 9 E; ibid. c. 25, they were regularly initiated by Zamolxis. Iambl. (151) says also that Pythagoras was instructed by the Celts, and even by the Ibe- rians. HIS TRA VELS. 331 ll with the mysteries of the Egyptians'—even the ourney to Egypt, though this is comparatively the est attested and finds supporters” among quite recent | The first known author who peaks of Pythagoras being in gyptis Isocrates, Bus. 11 : 5s (IIv6.) &qikówevos eis Aiyvirtov kal uaffnths éketvav yewóuevos tív T' &AAmv pixo- oropſav irpáros eis toūs"EAAmvas €kó- puge, kal Tô trepl r&s 6vorías kai Tàs &yia retas rās év roſs ispots truq'avéo- repov táv &AAwy €atroëacrew. The next testimony, Cic. Fin. v. 29, 87, merely says AEgyptum lustravit; similarly Strabo (vide Supra, 328,1); Justin, Hist. xx. 4; Schol. in Plato, p. 420, Bekk.; Diodorus, i. 96, 98, learned much more from the state- ments of the Egyptian priests, said to be taken from their sacred wri- tings, vide supra, p. 27, 1. ‘Plut. Qu. Conv. viii. 8, 2, 1, makes out that Pythagoras was a long while in Egypt, and adopted the precepts concerning the ispatikal &ytotetal, such as the prohibition of beans and fish. The same authority, De Is. 10, p. 354, derives the Py- thagorean symbolism from Egypt; Ps.-Justin (Cohort. 19) says the Py- thagorean doctrine of the Monad as the first principle came from there. According to Apul. Floril. ii. 15, Pythagoras learned from the Egyp- tian priests carimoniarum poten- tias, numerorum vices, geometriſe formulas; according to Valer. Max. viii. 7, 2, he found in the an- cient books of the priests, when he had learned the Egyptian writing, innumerabilium saculorum observa- tiones; Antipho (Diog. viii. 3 and Porph. V. P. 7 sq.) relates how Polycrates introduced him to Ama- sis, and Amasis to the Egyptian priests; and how he thus after many difficulties, which his perseve- rance at length overcame, gained admittance to the Egyptian mys- teries and holy rites. He says also that he learned the Egyptian language. From this author, Clemens, Strom. i. 302 c, and Theodoret, Gr, aff, cur. i. 15, p. 6, no doubt derive their statement that he was circumcised in Egypt. Anton. Diogenes (ap. Porph. V. P. 11) says that he learned the wisdom of the Egyptian priests, especially their religious doctrine, the Egyp- tian language and the three kinds of Egyptian writing. Iam- blichus, V. P. 12 sqq. (cf. p. 325, note), gives a circumstantial account of his wonderful voy- age from Mount Carmel to Egypt (whither, according to Theol. Arithm. 41, he had fled from the tyranny of Polycrates), and goes on to tell of his 22 years' intercourse with the priests and prophets, in which he learned all that was worth knowing, visited all the temples, gained access to all the mysteries, and devoted himself to astronomy, geometry, and religious exercises. The king in whose reign Pythago- ras came to Egypt is called by Pliny (Hist. Nat. xxxvi. 9, 71.) Psemetnepserphres (for which the manuscripts also give Semetnep- sertes and other forms); the priest who instructed him is said by Plu- tarch, De Is. 10, to have been Oinupheus of Heliopolis. Clem. Strom, i.303 C, names Sonches. Plu- tarch (De Is. 26; Solon, 10) makes Sonches the instructor of Solon. * E.g. independently of Röth, Chaignet (Pythagore, i. 43 sqq.; ii. 353), who is very inaccurate when 332 PYTHAGORAS. writers—cannot be satisfactorily established. The mos ancient evidence for this journey, that of Isocrates, i more than a hundred and fifty years later than th event to which it refers, and moreover is contained not in a historical work, but in a rhetorical oratio which itself makes no pretension to historical credi bility." Such testimony has obviously no weight a all; and even if Isocrates did not himself originat the idea that Pythagoras had been in Egypt, there would still remain the doubt whether the source from which he took it was grounded on historical tradition. This, however, is not only beyond the reach of proof, but is contrary to all probability. Herodotus, it i true, remarks on the analogy of one Pythagorean usag with a custom of the Egyptians; * he also says that th he says (i. 46) that I declare it certain that Pythagoras never went to Egypt. I say it is undemon- strable that he was there; I never said it was demonstrable that he was not there. * The Busiris of Isocrates is one of those works in which the Greek rhetors, after the time of the Sophists, sought to surpass one another in panegyrics on evil or worthless persons and things, and in accusations against men univer- sally admired. The Rhetor Poly- crates had written an apology for |Busiris. Isocrates shows him how he should have handled his theme. He explains his points of view very candidly, c. 12. The adversary of Busiris, he says, has ascribed wholly incredible things to him, such as the diverting of the Nile from its course, and the devouring of strangers. It is true that Iso- crates cannot prove what he affirms of him, but he certainly does not attribute to him impossible deeds, nor acts of bestial savagery: Étrett' e i kal T vy x d v opi e v & u p 6 t e- pot iſ e v 8 fi A €ºyo v Tes, &AA’ ow éyò ačv kéxpmual totrous toſs A6-yois, ois rep Xph toos étalvoovras, at 5’ ois trpoo’ikel rows Aoûopotivtas. It is evident that writings which an- nounce themselves as rhetorical inventions cannot be of the smallesſ, value ; and if we cannot prove from this work that Busiris was the author of the whole Egyptian cul- ture, neither can we accept it as historical evidence for the presence of Pythagoras in Egypt, and his con- nection with the Egyptian priests. * ii. 81. The Egyptian priests wearlinen trousers under their wool- lengarments, in which they were not allowed to enter the temple, or to be buried. Ópoxo-yéovoſt 8& Taijra Toto's 'Oppukoto's kaxeoplévolai Kai Bakxukotoſi, Čobal 5& Aiyvirt{otori, kal HIS TRA VELS. 333 elief in Metempsychosis came from Egypt into Greece; 1 ut he never hints that Pythagoras brought it thither, eeming rather to assume that it had been transmitted o the Greeks” before the time of that philosopher. s to the presence of Pythagoras in Egypt, though here was every opportunity for mentioning it, he pre- erves so strict a silence that we can only suppose he new nothing of it.” ave been aware of it.” v6ayopetouai. That is, “they agree this respect with the so-called rphics and Bacchics, who, how- ver, are in truth Egyptians, and ith the Pythagoreans; ' not, as 6th (ii. a, 381) and (in spite of he previous remark) Chaignet (i. 5) translate it: “They agree in his with the usages of the Orphic nd Bacchic rites of consecration, hich, however, are Egyptian and ythagorean.’ " ii. 123. The Egyptians first aught Immortality and Transmi- ration: roiſt4, T6 A6-yº eio l of AA#vovéxpío avto, of uèv trpátepov, i 8& Ša repov, Ös ióía éovröv éðvrt: &v éyò eióðs r& obváuara oi (t), * Though it is probable that Berodotus, in the passage just Juoted, when speaking of the later philosophers who adopted the doc- rine of Transmigration, was espe- sially referring to Pythagoras, he loes not necessarily mean that Py- hagoras himself acquired it in Egypt. Herodotus names Melam- bus as having imported the Egyp- ian Dionysiac cultus into Greece vide supra, 71, 4); it would seem, herefore, that Melampus is pri- marily alluded to among the ‘an- Nor does Aristoxenus seem to Thus there is an entire dearth f all trustworthy evidence respecting the supposed cients’ who introduced the doctrine of Transmigration into the Orphic Dionysiac mysteries. In that case Pythagoras would not have required to go to Egypt, in order to become acquainted with this doctrine. * For Röth's explanation (ii. b, 74) that Herodotus purposely avoided mentioning Pythagoras from his antipathy to the Cro- toniates, who were hostile to the Thurians, is not only very far- fetched, but demonstrably false. Herod. does mention him in ano- ther place (iv. 95), and with the honourable addition : ‘EAAhvav oi, Tó &00eveord tº oroplatfi IIv6ayópp.; and in ii. 123 (previous note) he passes over his and other names, not from aversion, but forbearance. If he is silent as to his connection with Egypt, the most natural rea- son for his silence is that he knew nothing of any such connection. Also in ii. 81 (vide supra, p. 332, 2), he would doubtless have expressed himself otherwise, if he had derived the Pythagoreans from Egypt in the same manner as the Orphics. * None of our authorities, at any rate, who speak of Pythago- ras' Egyptian journeys, refer to Aristoxenus. 334 PYTHAGORAS. - r all the more indemonstrable. The whole character journeys of Pythagoras in the East; our authoritie become more copious as we recede from the philoso pher's own time, and more meagre as we approaeh it before the beginning of the fourth century they entirel fail. Each later writer has more to tell than his pre decessor; and in proportion as the acquaintance of th Greeks with the Oriental civilised nations increases the extent of the journeys which brought the Samia philosopher to be instructed by them likewise increases. This is the way that, legends are formed and not his- torical tradition. We cannot, indeed, pronounce it im- possible that Pythagoras should have gone to Egypt or Phoenicia, or even to Babylon, but it is on that account of the narratives of his journeys strengthens the Sup- position that, as they now stand, they can have been derived from no historical reminiscence; that it was not the definite knowledge of his intercourse with foreign nations which gave rise to the theories as to the origin of his doctrine; but, conversely, the presupposition o the foreign source of his doctrine which occasioned the stories of his intercourse with the barbarians. There is quite enough to account for such a presupposition, even if it were founded on no actual contemporary tradition, in the syncretism of later times, in the false pragmatism' which could only explain the similarity of Pythagorean doctrines and usages with those of the East by the theory of personal relations between Py- thagoras and the Orientals, and in the tendency to * There is no English equivalent the tendency to explain the history for the German word Pragmatismus, of thought by imaginary combina- which may perhaps be explained as tions of fact.—Note by Translator. HIS EMIGRATION. 335 panegyric of the Pythagorean legend which loved to concentrate the wisdom of the whole human race in its hero." The statement that Pythagoras visited Crete and Sparta, partly to become acquainted with the laws of those countries, partly that he might be initiated into the mysteries of the Idaean Zeus, stands on no better foundation.” The thing is in itself conceivable, but the evidence is too uncertain, and the probability of any historical tradition as to these details too scanty to allow of our placing any trust in the assertion. So, too, the theory that the philosopher owed his wisdom to Orphic teachers * and writings, even though it may not be wholly wrong as to the fact, is doubtless based, as it stands, not on any historical reminiscence, but on the presuppositions of a period in which an Orphic theosophy and literature had formed itself to some extent under Pythagorean and Neo-Pythagorean in- fluences. The truth is, that we possess no document which deserves to be considered a historical tradition concerning the education of Pythagoras and the re- sources at his command. Whether it be possible to supply this want by inferences from the internal nature of the Pythagorean doctrine, we shall enquire later on. The first luminous point in the history of this 1 Because Pythagoras could scarcely have attained that “poly- mathy,' for which he is extolled by Heracleitus (vide infra, p. 336, 4), otherwise than by travels (Chaig- net, i. 40; Schuster, Heracl. 372), it does not at all follow that he went to Egypt, or visited non-Hel- lenic countries. Moreover, Hera- cleitus rather derives his learning from writings which he studied; it is possible, however, that these may have been collected by him previously on his journeys. * Justin. xx. 4; Valer. Max. viii. 7, ext. 2.; Diog. viii. 3 (Epi- menides); Iambl. 25; Porph. 17, cf. p. 363, 2. * Wide supra, p. 330, 2. 336 PYTH A G O RAS. --~~~~~~. --, . . . - * - - * * . - . . . . . . . . . . ; -º-º: philosopher is his emigration to Magna Græcia, the date of which we cannot precisely fix," nor can we do more than conjecture the reasons which led to it.” His activity, however, does not seem to have begun in Italy. The ordinary accounts, it is true, do not leave space for a long period of activity in Samos. Other texts, however, maintain that he at first laboured there successfully * for some time, and if this assertion, con- sidering the fables connected with it and the untrust- worthiness of its evidence, may hardly seem deserving of notice, yet the manner in which Pythagoras is mentioned by Heracleitus and Herodotus would appear to bear it out." Heracleitus soon after the death of this philosopher speaks of his various knowledge and of his (in Heracleitus's opinion erroneous) wisdom, as of a thing well known in Ionia.” Now, it is not likely that the report of it had first reached Ionia from Italy. For, according to other testimony (vide infra), * Wide supra, p. 324, 2. * The statements of the ancients are probably mere arbitrary con- jectures. Most of them assert with Aristoxenus (ap. Porph. 9) that the tyranny of Polycrates occasioned his migration (Strabo, xiv. 1. 16, p. 638; Diog. viii. 3; Hippolyſ. Refut. i. 2, sub init. ; Porph. 16; The- mist. Or. xxiii. 285 b ; Plut. Plac. i. 3, 24; Ovid. Metam. xv. 60, etc.), and that this assertion contradicts the uncertain story of Polycrates's commendatory letters to Amasis is no argument against it. But it cannot be considered as proved, since the combination was perfectly obvious. Others (Iambl. 20, 28) say that he emigrated because the Samians had too little taste for philosophy. On the other hand, Iambl. 28 says he did so in order to avoid the political activity, which the admiration of his fellow-citizens would have forced upon him. * Antipho. ap. Porph. 9; Iambl. 20 sqq., 26 sqq. * As Ritter pertinently re- marks, Pyth. Phil. 31. What Brandis says to the contrary does not appear to me conclusive. * Fr. 22, ap. Diog. viii. 6: IIv6ayópms Munodpxov ioropſ my #arcmo’ev &v0p6trov učAuota trávrov, ical ékNešćuevos Taütas Tās ovyypa- ºp&s étroimaev čovrot goq inv, troAvua- 0minu, kakotexvimv. (Cf. ibid. ix. 1.) The words ékaeś . . . ovyypaſpès, which I cannot think inserted by the narrator, must refer to writings previously mentioned by Hera- cleitus. Cf. p. 227, 2; 2nd edit. PYTHIAGORAS IN ITALY. 337 the spread of Italian Pythagoreanism was brought about by the dispersion of the Pythagoreans long after the death of the master. Again, the well-known and often quoted narrative of Zalmoxis' presupposes that Pythagoras had already played the same part in his own country that he afterwards played in Magna Graecia. In this story a Gaetic divinity takes the form of a man and communicates with Pythagoras. The motive of that fiction evidently is to explain the presumed similarity of the Gaetic belief in immortality with the Pythagorean doctrine (vide supra, p. 73, 1); yet the story could never have been invented if the name of the philosopher had been unknown to the Greeks on the Hellespont, from whom Herodotus received it, and if in their opinion his activity had first commenced in Italy. Whether among his countrymen he found less appreciation than he had hoped for, or whether other reasons, such as the tyranny of Polycrates or the fear of the Persian invasion, had disgusted him with his native city, in any case he left it and took up his abode in Crotona, a city with which he may possibly have had some personal connections, and which may well have commended itself to him on account of the far-famed salubrity of its site and the vigorous activity of its inhabitants.” Here he found the proper soil for 1 Herod. iv. 95. * According to a statement (ap. Porph. 2), he had some previous connection with Crotona, having travelled thither as a boy with his father; but this is hardly more historical than the story mentioned by Apuleius, Floril. ii., 15, that Gillus, the Crotoniate (the Taren- WOL. I. time of that name mentioned in Herod. iii. 138), liberated him from his Persian imprisonment. According to Iambl. 33, 36, 142, Pythagoras visited many other Italian and Sicilian towns besides Crotona, especially Sybaris. That he went first to Sybaris, and thence to Crotona, however (vide Röth, ii. 338 PYTHIAGORAS. his endeavours, and the school he established was until its dispersion so exclusively associated with lower Italy, that it is often described as the Italian school." But this portion of his life is still so much obscured by fabulous legends that it is hard to discover anything with a historical foundation in the mass of pure in- vention. If we may believe our informants, even the person of Pythagoras was surrounded with miraculous splendour. A favourite, and even a reputed son, of Apollo,” he is said to have been revered by his followers as a superior being,” and to have given proof of this his higher nature by prophecies and miracles of all kinds." a, 421), is nowhere stated. Röth deduces from the words of Apollo- nius, ap. Iambl. 255, on which he puts an entirely wrong interpreta- tion, and from Jul. Firmic. Astron. p. 9. (Crotonam et Sybarim erul incoluit), that after the destruction of Sybaris, Pythagoras betook him- self to the estates which the Syba- rites had given him; that, however, and everything else that he says about this country life, is pure imagination. * Aristot. Metaph. i. 5, 987 a, 9, c. 6, sub. init. ; c. 7, 988 a, 25; De Coelo, ii. 13, 293 a., 20; Meteor. i. 6, 342 b. 30; cf. Sextus, Math. x. 284; Hippolyt. Refut. i. 2; Plut. Plac. i. 3, 24. * Porph. 2, appeals in support of this to Apollonius, Iambl. 5 sqq., to Epimenides, Eudoxus, and Xeno- crates; but the first of these three names can only be introduced here through a mere blunder. For the well-known Cretan mentioned by Porph. 29, and Iambl. 135,222, as a disciple of Pythagoras, and by others, vide p. 327, 1, as his teacher, can scarcely have been alive at the date of Pythagoras's birth; the other two names must likewise be considered doubtful. Xenocrates (as I have already observed in Part ii. a, 875, third edition) may perhaps have mentioned the state- ment as a report, but he cannot himself have adopted it. - * Porph. 20; Iambl. 30, 255. After Apollonius and Nicomachus; Diodor. Fragm. p. 554; Aristotle, ap. Iambl. 31, 144, quotes as a Pythagorean classification: too Aoyukot, Cºot, rb uév éott 6eos, to 5’ &v6pwros, to 5’ oiov IIv6ayópas; and AElian. ii. 26, attributes to him the often repeated statement (also in Diog. viii. 11, and Porph. 28) that Pythagoras was called the Hyper- borean Apollo. Cf. the following note. * According to AElian, loc. cit. cf. iv. 17, Aristotle had already re- lated that Pythagoras had been simultaneously seen in Crotona and Metapontum, that he had a golden thigh, and had been spoken to by a river god. This statement, how- PXTHA (? ORAS IN ITALY. 339 He alone among mortals understood the harmony of the spheres;" and Hermes, whose son he was in a prior state of existence, had allowed him to retain the re- membrance of his whole past amidst the various phases ever, has such a suspicious sound, that one might be tempted to con- jecture an error in the words, kā- kelva è trpoo’etriXéºyel 6 rot, Nukoud- Xov, with which Ælian introduces it, and to suppose that Nicoma- chus, the celebrated Neo-Pythago- rean, and not Aristotle, was AElian's authority; had not Apollon. Mirabil. c. 6, likewise quoted the same thing from Aristotle. It cannot possibly have been Aristotle himself, how- ever, who stated these things. He must have mentioned them merely as Pythagorean legends, and then himself have been taken by later writers as the authority for them. This, indeed, is possi- ble, and therefore these statements can furnish no decisive proof of . the spuriousness of the Aristote- lian treatise, trepi Tôv IIv6ayopetwy, which they naturally recall to us. The same miracles are related by Plutarch, Numa, c. 8 ; Diog. viii. 11; Porph. 28 sqq.; Iambl. 90 sqq.; 134, 140 sq. (the two latter after Nicomachus; cf. Rohde, Rh. Mus. xxvii. 44). According to Plutarch he showed his golden thigh to the assembly at Olympia ; ac- cording to Porphyry and Iambli- chus, to the Hyperborean priest of Apollo Abaris. For further par- ticulars, vide Herod. iv. 36 (cf. also Krische, De Societ. a Pyth. cond. 37), who refers the legends of Abaris, told by later writers, with some probability, to Heracleides Ponticus. Many other miracles, often of the most extravagant description, such as the taming of wild beasts by a word, foretelling of the future, and so forth, are to be found in Plutarch, loc. cit.; Apul. De Magia, 31; Porph. 23 sq.; Iambl. 36, 60 sqq., 142, who unfortunately, however, have not named the ‘trustworthy ancient writers’ to whom they owe their information; cf. also Hippol. Re- fut. i. 2, p. 10. It is clear from the statement of Porphyry, ap. Eus. Pr. Ev. x 3, 4, that even in the fourth century there were stories current in proof of Pytha- goras's supernatural knowledge of the future. Andron is said to have spoken in his Tottrovs of the prophe- cies of Pythagoras, and especially of an earthquake which he fore- told from the water of a stream three days before it happened. Theopompus then transferred these stories to Pherecydes. The verses of Empedocles, ap. Porph. 30, and Iambl. 67, relate things much less wonderful. They do not im- ply supernatural knowledge, for the ancients (according to Dioge- nes, viii. 54) were not agreed as to whether the verse referred to Py thagoras or to Parmenides. For the rest it is quite credible that during the lifetime of Pythagoras. and immediately after his death, rumour may have asserted much that was miraculous about him, as was subsequently the case with Empedocles. * Porph. 30; Iambl. 65; Simpl. in Arist. De Coelo, 208, b, 43, 211 a, 16; Schol. in Arist. 496 b, 1. z 2 340 PPTHAGORAS. of his existence." There is mention even of a descent 1–into Hades.” His doctrines are said to have been im- parted to him in the name of his divine protector by the mouth of the Delphic priestess Themistoclea.” It cannot, therefore, be wondered at that on his first appearance in Crotona “ he attracted much atten- ' Diog. viii. 4 sq. after Herac- leides (Pont.); Porph.26,45; Iambl. 63; Horat. Carm, i. 28, 9; Ovid. Metam. xv. 160; Lucian, Dial. Mort. 20, 3, et pass. Tertull. De. An. 28, 31. Aceording to A. Gellius, iv. 11, Clearehus and Dicaearchus, the disciples of Aristotle, asserted that Pythagoras maintained that he had formerly existed as Euphorbus, Pyranderand others; butthewerses of Xenophanes, ap. Diog. viii. 36, say nothing of any recollection of a previous state of existence. He is also said to have kept up con- stant intercourse with the soul of a friend who had died (Herm. in Joseph. Con. Ap. i. 22). Further particulars later on. * By Hieronymus, no doubt the Peripatetic, ap. Diog. viii. 21, cf. 38; Hermippus, vide Diog. viii. 41, in imitation of the story of Zalmoxis (Herod. iv. 95), puts an insipid natural interpretation upon this legend, about which Tertullian, De Aa. e. 28, is unnecessarily angry. Its true origin is probably to be found in a work attributed to Pythagoras, called Katé8agus eis d'âov. Cf. Diog. 14 : &AAè kal airbs Čy rfi Ypapſ, pnot, 6t' étrö, (for which Rohde, Rh. Mus. xxvi. 558, appealing to Iambl. Theol. Arithm. p. 41, would substitute ºkkaidera) kai Siakootww éréwv éé àfösa trapa- weyevija:0ai és àv60&rous. , Ibid. 4: roiráv pmaw ‘Hoakaetºns à IIovrtkos repl atroß rôs Aéyety, às stn work yeyovës Aibaatöms, where the pre- sent Aéyetv points to some writing; cf. what Rohde, loc. cit, further ad- duces. That writings of this kind were not strange to the Pythago- reans is well known. The Orphic Katabasis is said to have been composed by the Pythagorean Cer- cops (Clem. Strom. i. 333 A). * Aristox, ap. Diog. viii. 8, 21; Porph. 41. A statement so mythical, and so improbable in itself, gives us, however, no right to identify Pythagoreanism, with the Delphic philosophy, as Curtius does, Griech. Geschich, i. 427. * Dicaearchus, ap. Porph. 18; cf. Justin. Hist. xx. 4; speaks of lectures, which, in the first instance, he delivered before the Council of Elders (to tav yepávrov &oxeſov), and then by command of the autho- rities before the youths, and finally the women. A lengthy and decla- matory account of the contents of these lectures is given in Iambl. V. P. 37–57, and a modernised paraphrase in Röth, ii. a, 425–450. I do not believe that this enlarged version is taken from Dicaearchus; partly because it seems too poor in content for this philosopher, and partly because Dicaearchus, accor- ding to Porphyry, makes Pythago- ras appear first before the ruling council, and then before the youths; whereas in Iamblichus he is represented to have made his first PYTHIAGORAS IN ITALY. 341 tion,' and soon acquired the highest renown throughout Italy.” Disciples, both men and women,” flocked to him, not only from the Greek colonies, but from the whole of Italy; * the most celebrated legislators of appearance in the gymnasium, and then on the report of his lecture there, to have been commanded to speak before the council. It would seem that a later biographer of Py- thagoras had added to the state- ments of Dicaearchus; and it is probable that this was none other than Apollonius; since Iamblichus in his V. P. 259 sq. adduces a nar- rative from him in a similar style, and (as Rohde, Rhein. Mus. xxvii. 29, remarks) Apollonius, ibid. 264, expressly makes mention of the temple of the Muses, to the build- ing of which, according to section 50, these discourses of Pythagoras had given occasion. Apollonius himself (as is proved by Rohde, loc. cit. 27 sq. from Iambl. Section 56; cf. Diog. viii. 11; and Just. xx. 4, sub, fin. ; cf. also Porph. V. P. 4) seems to have based his own account on an exposition of the Timaeus, and to have also made use of sayings reported by Aris- toxenus and others; cf. Iambl. section 37, 40, 47, with Diog. viii. 22, 23 ; Stob. Floril. 44, 21 (ii. 164, Mein.), section 55 with Stob. 74, 53. * Wide besides what has been already quoted, the legendary ac- count of Nicomachus, ap. Porph. 20, and Iambl. 30 ; Diodor. Fragm. p. 554; Favorin. ap. Diog. viii. 15; Valer. Max. viii. 15, ext. 1. * Cf. Alcidamas, ap. Arist. Rhet. ii. 23, 1398 b, 14: 'Itaxiàrat IIv6ayópav (ériumaav). Plutarch, Numa. c. 8, states, on the authority of Epicharmus, that Pythagoras was presented by the Romans with the right of citizenship; but he has been deceived by a forged writing, vide Welcker, Klein. Schrif- ten, i. 350. According to Plutarch, loc. cit., and Pliny, Hist. Nat. xxxiv. 6, 26, a pillar was subse- quently, at the time of the Samnite war, erected to him in Rome as the wisest of the Greeks. * Porph. 22 : trposìx60w 6 airó, &s pmoiv 'Apiatóševos, kal Aevkavol kal Megadtriot Kai IIevkériot kai ‘Polualot. The same, without the appeal to Aristoxenus, is to be found in Diog. viii. 14: Nic. ap. Porph, 19 sq.; Iambl. 29 sq., 265 sqq. 127 (where mention is made of an Etruscan Pythagorean). * Cf. as to the Pythagorean women, Diog. 41 sq.; Porph. 19 sq.; Iambl. 30, 54, 132, 267, end. As to the most celebrated of them, Theano, who is generally called the wife, but sometimes the daughter of Pythagoras, cf. Hermesinax, ap. Athen. xiii. 599 a ; Diog. 42; Porph. 19 ; Iambl. 132, 146, 265; Clem. Strom. 1. 309; C. iv. 522 D; Plut. Conj. Praec. 31, p. 142; Stob. Ecl. i. 302; Flor.l. 74, 32, 53, 55; Floril. Monac. 268-270 (Stob. Floril. Ed. Mein. iv. 289 sq.). As to the children of Pythagoras, Porph. 4 (where there is a state- ment of Timaeus of Tauromenium about his daughter, repeated in Hieron. Adv. Jovin. i. 42); Diog. 42 sq.; Iambl. 146; Schol. in Plat. p. 420, Bekk. As to his household economy, Iambl. 170. 342 PYTHAGORAS. these countries' owned him for their teacher, and by his influence, order, freedom, civilisation, and law were re-established in Crotona and all Magna Graecia.” Even the Druids of Gaul are called his disciples by later writers.” The Pythagorean school is represented to us not merely as a scientific association, but also, and principally, as a religious and political society.T Entrance into it was only to be obtained by a strict probation, and on condition of several years' silence." The members recognised each other by secret signs; " * Especially Zaleucus and Cha- rondas, of which this is asserted by Seneca, Ep. 90, 6, and also by Posidonius; similarly Diog. viii. 16 (whether this is taken from Aristoxenus cannot be ascer- tained); Porph. 21 ; Iambl. 33, 104, 130, 172 (both probably fol- low Nicomachus): cf. AElian, W. H. iii. 17; Zaleucus is also men- tioned in this connection ap. Diodo- rum, xii. 20. Now Zaleucus was cer- tainly a hundred years earlier than Pythagoras, and so probably was Charondas (cf. Hermann, Griech. Antiquit. i. section 89); if, on the other hand, we recognise this Charondas (vide Diodorus, xii. 11; Schol. in Plat. p. 419), as the law- giver of Thurii (445 B.C.), he would be much too young for a personal disciple of Pythagoras. The ap- pearance of such statements, there- fore, in the above-mentioned writers, is a fresh proof how little real his- torical foundation exists, even for ancient and widely spread accounts of Pythagoras. Some other Pytha- gorean lawgivers are named in Iambl. 130, 172. The story of Numa's relations with Pythagoras is discussed in vol. iii. b, 692, se- cond edition. * Diog. viii. 3; Porph. 21 sq., 54; Iambl. 33, 50, 132, 214; Cic. Tusc. v. 4, 10; Diodor. Fragm. p. 554; Justin. xx. 4; Dio Chrysost. Or. 49, p. 249 R.; Plut. C. Princ. Philos. i. 11, p. 776; cf. the sup- posed conversation of Pythagoras with Phalaris; Iambl. 215 sqq. * Wide supra, p. 73, 1 ; cf. p. 330. * Taurus, ap. Gell. i. 9; Diog. viii. 10; Apul. Floril. ii. 15; Clem. Strom. vi. 580, A.; Hippol. Rafut. i. 2, p. 8, 14; Iambl. 71 sqq. 94; cf. 21 sqq.; Philop. De An. D, 5; Lucian, Vit. Auct. 3. The tests themselves, among which that of physiognomy is mentioned (Hippolytus called Pythagoras the discoverer of physiognomy), and the duration of the silent noviciate, is variously given. The counte- nance of the teachers was hidden from the novices by a curtain, as in the mysteries. Cf. Diog. 15. * Iambl. 238. The Pentagon is said to have been such a sign (Schol. in Aristoph. ; Clouds, 611, i. 249, Dind.; Lucian, De Salut. c. 5). Krische, p. 44, thinks the gnomon also, THE PPTHAGOPEAN SCHOOL. 343 only a certain number of them were admitted into the inner circle and initiated into the esoteric doctrines of the school:" persons not belonging to the society were kept at a distance,” unworthy members were excluded with contumely.” According to later ac- counts, the Pythagoreans of the higher grade had all their goods in common," in obedience to a minutely * Gellius, loc. cit., names three classes of Pythagorean disciples: &kovotticol or novices; uaômwarticol, (pworthcot ; Clem. Strom. v. 575 D; Hippolyt. Refut. i. 2, p. 8, 14; Porph. 37; Iambl. V. P. 72, 80 sqq ; 87 sq.; and Willoison's Anecd. ii. 216—two, the Esoterics and Exoterics; the former were also called Mathematicians, and the latter Acousmaticians; according to Hippolytus and Iamblichus, the Esoterics were called Pythagore- ans, and the exoterics Pythagorists. The unknown writer, ap. Phot. Cod. 249, distinguishes Sebasti, Politici, and Mathematici; also Pythago- rici, Pythagoreans, and Pythago- rists; calling the personal scholars of Pythagoras, Pythagorici; the scholars of these, Pythagoreans; and the ŠNAws #00ev (mAotal, Pythago- rists. On these statements (the recent date of which he does not consider) Röth (ii. a, 455 sq.; 756 sq.; 823 sqq.; 966 b, 104) grounds the following assertion. The mem- bers of the inner Pythagorean school (he says) were called Pytha- gorics, and those of the outer cir- cle Pythagoreans; there was an important distinction between their doctrines, all the systems of the Pythagoreans being founded on the Zoroastrian dualism, which (ac- cording to p. 421 sq., it was im- ported into Crotona by the physi- cian Democedes) is not to be found in the conceptions of Pythagoras, which are genuinely Egyptian. These were the Pythagoreans, and these alone (to them belonged Em- pedocles, Philolaus and Archytas, and Plato and his followers were allied to them), to whom the ac- counts of Aristotle have reference, and who were generally recognised by the ancients before the period of the Ptolemies. Now all the au- thors who mention such a distinc- tion call the exoterics Pythagorists, and the esoterics, the true disciples of Pythagoras, Pythagoreans; and the anonymous writer in Photius applies this name only to the se– cond generation. But Röth finds a way out of this difficulty. We have only to correct the anonymous writer to the extent of understand- ing Acousmaticians under Pytha- goreans; and in respect to Iam- blichus to substitute “Pythagorici for Pythagoreans, and Pythagore- ans for Pythagorists (Röth has overlooked the passage in Hippo- lytus), and all will be right.” On these arbitrary conjectures a the- ory is built up, which is entirely to overturn, not only the hitherto accepted theory of Pythagoreanism, but the testimony of Philolaus, Plato, Aristotle, &c. * Apollon. ap. Iambl. 257. * Iambl. 73 sq., 246; Clemens, Strom. v. 574, D. 4 The oldest authorities for 344 PYTHAGORAS. prescribed rule of life reverenced among them as a divine ordinance." This also enjoined linen clothing,” and entire abstinence from bloody offerings and animal food,” from beans and some other kinds of nourish- ment; * even celibacy is said to have been imposed this are Epicurus (or Diocles) ap. Diog. x. 11; and Timaeus of Tau- romenium, ihid. viii. 10; Schol. in Plat., Phaedr. p. 319, Bekk, Subsequently, after the appear- ance of the Neo-Pythagoreans, who must have taken their notions chiefly from the ideal Platonic state, the statement is universal; vide Diog. viii. 10; Gell. loc. cit.; Hippol. Refut. i. 2, p. 12; Porph. 20; Iambl. 30, 72, 168, 257, &c. Phot. Lear. koué, makes Pythago- goras introduce community of goods among the Inhabitants of Magna Graecia, and cites Timaeus as an authority. * Porph. 20, 32 sqq.; follow- ing Nicomachus and Diogenes, the author of the book of prodigies; Iambl. 68 sq., 96 sqq., 165, 256. The latter gives a detailed descrip- tion of their whole daily life. * Iambl. 100, 149 ; both as it would seem (Rohde, Rhein. Mus. xxvii. 35 sq., 47) originally from Nicomachus, section 100, indirectly from Aristoxenus, who, however, was only speaking of the Pythago- reans of his own time; Apuleius, De Magia, c. 56; Philostr. Apollon. i. 32, 2, who adds to the prescripts of linen clothing a prohibition to cut the hair. Others speak only of white garments, e.g. Ælian, W. H. xii. 32. * First attributed to Pythago. ras himself by Eudoxus, ap. Porph. V. P. 7, and Onesicritus (about 320 B.C.), Strabo, xv. i. 65, p. 716 Cas.; and to the Pythagoreans generally by the poets of the Alex- andrian period, ap. Diog. viii. 37 sq.; Athen. iii. 108 sq.; iv. 161 a, Sqq., 163 d. Later on, the state- ment became almost universal; vide Cic. N. D. iii. 36, 88; Rep. iii. 8; Strabo, vii. 1, 5, p. 298; Diog. viii. 13, 20, 22; Porph. V. P. 7; De Abstin. i. 15, 23 ; Iambl. 54, 68, 107 sqq., 150 ; Plut. De Esu Carm. sub init. ; Philostr. loc. cit.; Sext. Math. ix. 12, 7 sq., and many others. * Heracleides (no doubt of Pon- tus) and Diogenes, ap. Joh. Lyd. De Mens. iv. 29, p. 76; Callima- chus, ap. Gell. iv. 11; Diog. viii. 19, 24, 33, following Alexander, Bolyhistor and others; Cic. Divin. i. 30, 62; Plut. Qu. Conv. viii. 8, 2; Clemens. Strom. iii. 435, D; Porph. 43 sqq.; Iambl. 109; Hip- pol. Refut. i. 2, p. 12; Lucian, V. Auct. 6, etc. According to Her- mippus and others, ap. Diog. 39 sq., Pythagoras was slain in his flight, because he would not escape over a bean field. Neanthes (ap. Iambl. 189 sqq.) relates the same of Pythagoreans in the time of Dionysius the elder. He also tells a further legend, to be noticed infra, as to the pertinacity with which the reason of the bean pro- hibition was kept secret. This last with a little alteration is trans- ferred to Theano, by David, Schol. #n Arist. 14 a, 30. Pythagoras is also said to have prohibited wine THE PPTHAGOREAN SCHOOL. 345 upon them." Older writers, indeed, who are more to be trusted, say nothing of the community of goods,” though they extol the loyalty of the Pythagoreans towards friends and co-associates.” The precepts as to food and clothing (over and above the general principle of moderation and simplicity “) are reduced by these writers to a few isolated ordinances * in connection with (Iambl. 107, 69, and Epiph. Her. p. 1087 B). The prohibition of beans is discussed at length by Bayle, Art. Pythag. Rem. H. * Ap. Clem. Strom. iii. 435 c (Clemens himself contradicts it); cf. Diog. 19 : otitor éºyvá00m (Pyth.) otre àtaxopóv otte &ºppoët- oud ſwu offre ueóvorðeſs. * Wide supra, 343, 4, and Krische, p. 27 sq., who rightly finds a reason for this statement in a misunderstanding of the proverb ková rà rôv pixov, which was pro- bably not peculiar to the Pythago- reans (cf. Aristotle, Eth. N. ix. 8, 1168 b, 6). It is, however, also ascribed to Pythagoras by Timaeus, ap. Diog. 10; Cic. Leg. i. 12, 34, and Ant. Diog. ap. Porph. 33. * Cf. the well-known story of Damon and Phintias, Cic. Off. iii. 10, 45; Diodor. Fragm. p. 554; Borph. 59; Iambl. 233 sq. after Aristoxenus, to whom Dionysius himself told the story, and others. Also other anecdotes, ap. Diodor. loc. cit.; Iambl. 127 sq., 185, 237 sqq., and the more general state- ments in Cic. Off. i. 17, 56; Diod. loc. cit.; Porph. 33, 59; Iambl. 229 sq.; also Krische, p. 40 sq. These stories, however, for the most part presuppose the existence of private property among the Pythagoreans. * Aristoxenus and Lyco, ap. Athen. ii. 46 sq.; x. 418 'e; Porph. 33 sq.; Iambl.97 sq.; Diog. viii. 19. * Aristoxenus, ap. Athen. x. 418 sq.; Diog. viii. 20; Gell. iv. 11, expressly denies that Pythago- ras abstained from meat; he only refused the flesh of ploughing oxen and bucks (the former probably on account of their utility, and the lat- ter on account of their lustfulness). Plutarch (Gell. loc. cit.; cf. Diog. viii. 19) quotes the same statement from Aristotle. According to him, the Pythagoreans merely abstained from particular parts of animals and from certain fishes (so that ap. Diog. viii. 13, only the remark about the unbloody altar, and not the story about Pythagoras, can have been taken from Aristotle). Blutarch, Qu. Conv. viii. 8, 1, 3, and Athen. vii. 308 c, say that the Pythagoreans eat no fish and very little meat, chiefly the flesh of offerings; similarly Alexander, ap. Diog. viii. 33, speaking of many prohibitions of food (often without historical foundation) does not mention abstinence from flesh. Even Ant. Diog. (ap. Porph. 34, 36) and Iambl. 98 (in an account which no doubt is indirectly taken from Aristoxenus) are agreed on this point with these writers, though differing from them on many others, and Plut. Numa, 8, says of the Pythagorean offerings 346 P}^THAGORAS. particular forms of worship; whether these ordinances originated with the Italian Pythagoreans, or only belong that they were, for the most part, bloodless. On the other hand, Theophrastus must have ascribed to the Pythagoreans the abstention from flesh, which is asserted of the Orphic Pythagorean mysteries of his time (cf. Pt. ii. a, 29, 1, 3rd ed. ; Pt. iii. b, 65 sq. 2nd ed.), if all that we read in Porph. De Abstin. ii. 28, is taken from him. Bernays, however (Theoph. v. d. Frömm. p. 88), thinks, probably with jus- tice, that the sentences which treat of the Pythagoreans, 51' 3rep . . . Tapavouías, are added by Porphyry. But, even according to this repre- sentation, they, at least, tasted the flesh of offerings, so that they must have had animal sacrifices. The sacrifice of a bull is ascribed to Pythagoras on the occasion of the discovery of the Pythagorean prin- ciple, and other mathematical dis- coveries (Apollodor. ap. Athenaeum, x. 418 sq., and Diog. viii. 12; Cic. N. D. iii. 36, 88; Plut. Qu. Conv. viii. 2, 4, 3; N. P. Suav. v. 11. 4, p. 1094; Procl. in Eucl. 110 u, 426 Fr. Porph. V. P. 36, infers from this the sacrifice of a graírivos gods), and he is also said to have introduced meat diet among the athletes: vide infra. In regard to beans, Aristoxenus (ap. Gellius, loc. cit.) maintains that Pythago- ras, far from prohibiting them, particularly recommended this vegetable. It is, therefore, pro- bable, that Hippol. Refut. i. 2. p. 12, and Porph. 43 sqq., derived their absurd account (mentioned also by Lucian, Vit. Auct. 6) of the prohibition of beans, not from Aristoxenus, but from Antonius Diogenes, from whom Joh. Lydus, De Mens, iv. 29, p. 76, quotes it in the same words as Porphyry; and though the contradiction of Aristox- enus itself presupposes that such a prohibition was even at that period attributed to Pythagoras, it never- theless shows that it was not ac- knowledged by those Pythagoreans whose tradition he followed. Gell. loc. cit, explains the story of the beans as a misunderstanding of a symbolical expression ; the most probable explanation is that a cus- tom, which really belonged to the Orphics, was transferred to the an- cient Pythagoreans; cf. Krische, p. 35. The statement that the Py- thagoreans wole only linen clothes is contradicted by the account in Diog. viii. 19 (cf. Krische, p. 31), where he excuses them clumsily enough for wearing woollen gar- ments, by asserting that linen at that time was unknown in Italy. According to Herod. ii. 81, the whole matter is reduced to this: that in the Orphic Pythagorean mysteries the dead were forbidden to be buried in woollen clothes. * As Alexander (Diog. viii. 33) expressly says : &lréxea.0al Bpatów 6vmoreiðfav Te Kpeãov kal TpixAöv kai aea avoipov kal 6&v kal Tóv gotókov (ºwy kal Kváuov kal Tów &AAwy &v TapakeMečovrai kai oi rās Texerês év toſs ispoſs étritexotivres, cf. Plut. Qu. Conv. viii. 8, 3, 15. That the Pythagoreans had peculiar reli- gious services and rites, and that these formed the external bond of their society, must be presupposed from Herod. ii. 81. Plato also (Rep. x. 600 B) speaks of a rv0ayó- pelos Tpétros toū 8íov, by which the disciples of Plato were distinguished from others. Such a distinctive peculiarity in their mode of life THE PPTHAGOREAN SCHOOL. 347 would, in itself, lead us to con- ecture something of a religious Bharacter; and this appears still more clearly from such historical accounts as we possess of the prac- ;ical life of the Pythagoreans, and ‘rom what may be accepted as genuine of the ceremonial prescripts n Diog. 10, 33 sqq.; Iambl. 163 sq., 256; also from the early con- nection of Pythagoreanism with the Bacchic Orphic mysteries, the evidence for which is to be found partly in the above references, and partly in the forgery of Orphic writings by Pythagoreans (Clemens, Strom, i. 333 A.; Lobeck, Aglaoph. 347 sqq.; cf. Ritter, i. 363, 293). * Wide supra, p. 341, 4, and usonius, ap. Stob. Floril. 67, 20; f. Diog. 21. * It is scarcely necessary to uote evidence for this, as Arist. etaph. i. 5. Sub init. (oi kaxoß- evol IIv0ayópelot tow pagmpidºtov Jáuevo rpótol taúra trpoſiya- * * * ow kal évtpaq'évres év autois &s roërwv &pxès rêv čvrov pxãs ºff0mgav sival tróvtov), since t is sufficiently proved by the hole character of the Pythagorean octrine, and by the names of o the later Orphics of Pythagorean tendencies; whether, onsequently, they arose from Pythagoreanism or from he Orphic mysteries, we do not certainly know. elibacy of the Pythagoreans is so entirely unrecog- ised even by later writers that they represent Py- hagoras as married," and cite from him and from his school numerous precepts concerning conjugal life (vide ºnfra). Among the Sciences, besides philosophy proper, £he Pythagoreans chiefly cultivated mathematics, which Swes to them its first fruitful development.” By ap- The Philolaus and Archytas. Even at a later period Magna Graecia and Sicily continued to be the principal seat of mathematical and astrono- mical studies. Considerable know- ledge and discoveries in mathema- tics and astronomy were ascribed to Pythagoras himself; cf. Aristox. ap. Stob. Ecl. i. 16, and Diog. viii. 12; Hermesianax and Apollodor. ap. Athen. xiii. 599 a., x, 418 sq., and Diog. i. 25; viii. 12; Cic. N. D. iii. 36, 88; Plin. Hist. Nat. ii. 8, 37; Diog. viii. 11, 14; Porph. V. P. 36; Plut. Qu. Conv. viii. 2, 4, 3; N. P. Suav. Vivi. 11, 4, p. 1094; , Plac. ii. 12; Procl. in Eucl. 19 m (where, instead of &Aórywv, we should doubtless read &vaxá- ºwv), 110, 111 (65, 426, 428 Fr.); Stob. Ecl. i. 502 ; Lucian, Vit. Auct. 2: tº 8& uáxtata oióev; &piðum Tikhv, ãotpovouſav, Tepatetav, Yewpletpiav, uovo.ukhv, yomtetav, uívriv škpov BAéreus. Although Pythagoras unquestionably gave the impulse to the fruitful development of mathematics in his school, it is im- possible, from the fragmentary and wholly untrustworthy statements about him, to form any conception of his mathematical knowledge at 348 PYTHIAGORAS. plying mathematics to music they became the founde of the scientific theory of sound, which enters so deepl into their system." The practical importance of musi however, was quite as great among them ; it wa cultivated partly as a means of moral education, partl in connection with the art of medicine; * for this, too ~~~ all approximating to historical cer- tainty. Even the state of mathe- matical science in the Pythagorean school, at the time of Philolaus and Archytas, could only be described by one accurately acquainted with ancient mathematics, and by such a one only with the greatest caution and reserve. We shall confine our- selves here to what concerns the general principles of the number- theory and harmony, or the concep- tions of the system of the universe. Röth (ji a 962 b, 314) quotes with essential omissions and altera- tions a passage from Varro, L. lat. v. 6, to prove that Pythagoras made a map in Tarentum, of which Warro says not a word. He is there speaking of a bronze image of Europa on the bull which Pytha- goras (Pythagoras of Rhegium, the well-known sculptor of the beginning of the fifth century) made at Tarentum. Marc Capella, De Nupt. Philol. vi. 5, p. 197, Grot., attributes to Pythagoras the determination of the terrestrial zones, and not a map. * According to Nicomachus, Harm. i. 10; Diog. viii. 12; Iambl. 115 sqq. and others (vide infra). Pythagoras himself invented har- mony. What is more certain is, that it was first developed in his school, as is shown by the name and the theories of Philolaus and Archytas, on which more hereafter. Plato says in Rep. vii. 530 D, that Mor. c. 3, p. 441 ; Iambl. 264. the Pythagoreans regarded Ha mony and Astronomy as two sist SCI eIICeS. - * Wide Porph. 32; Iambl. 3 64, 110 sqq., 163, 195, 224; Stri bo, i. 2, 3, p. 16; x. 3, 10, p. 468 Sen. De ira, iii. 9; Quintil. Insti i. 10, 32; ix. 4, 12; Censorin. D Nat. 12; AElian, V. H. xiv. 23 Sext. Math. vi. 8; Chamāleo, ap Athen. xiii. 623 (on Clinias) These accounts, no doubt, contai much that is fabulous, but thei historial foundation is beyond ques tion. The Harmony of the Pytha goreans presupposes a diligen study of music. The moral appli cation of this art corresponds t the character of the Doric life and of the cultus of Apollo; and w elsewhere find that that cultus wa connected with music as a medici mal cure. In accordance with this the Pythagorean music is repre sented as grave and quiet, and the lyre as their chief instrument Athen. iv. 184 e, however, enume rates a whole series of Pythagorean flute-players. * Diog. viii. 12; Porph. 33 Iambl. 110, 163. Apollon. a Celsus, De Medic. i Proºf names Pythagoras amon the most celebrated physicians. C what is said further on about Alc maeon's connection with the Py thagoreans. . THE PPTHAGO REAN SCHOOL. 349 s well as gymnastic," flourished among the Pytha- foreans. As might be expected, after the proof of upernatural wisdom related in the myth of the Samian hilosopher (vide Supra), Pythagoras and his school re said to have applied themselves to prophecy.” As a elp to morality, we are told that strict daily self- xamination was, among other things,” especially en- oined on the members of the society.” Since, however, t that period, ethics were inseparable from politics, we are also told that the Pythagoreans not only occu- pied themselves zealously with politics” and exercised the greatest influence on the legislation and administra- tion of the cities of Magna Graecia,” but also that they constituted in Crotona and other Italian towns a regular political confederation," which, by its influence upon the deliberative assemblies* of these towns, really held the 1. Cf. Iambl. 97; Strabo, vi. 1, 12, p. 263; Justin. xx. 4; also Diodor. Fragm. p. 554. Milo, the celebrated athlete, is well known to have been a Pythagorean. The statement (Diog. 12 sq., 47; Porph. V. P. 15; De Abst. i. 26; Iambl. 25) that Pythagoras introduced meat diet among the athletes, which is, however, scarcely histo- rical, seems to refer to Pythagoras the philosopher. 3 Cic. Divin. i. 3, 5; ii. 58, 119; Diog. 20, 32; Iambl. 93, 106, 147, 149, 163; Clem. Strom. i. 334 A.; Plut. Plac. v. 1, 3; Lucian (vide supra, p. 338, 4). Magical arts were likewise attri- buted to Pythagoras, Apul. De Magia, c. 27, p. 504. * Diodor. Fragm. p. 555. * Carm. Aur. v. 40 sqq., and after this source, Cic. Cato, ii. 38; Diodor, loc. cit.; Diog. viii. 22; Porph. 40; Iambl. 164 sq., 256. * According to Iamblichus, 97, the hours after meals were devoted to politics, and Varro, vide Augus- tin. De Ord. ii. 20, maintains that Pythagoras only communicated his political doctrines to the ripest of his scholars. * Wide supra, p. 341, 5; 342, 1, and Valer. Max. viii. 15, ext. I; ibid. c. 7, ext. 2. * Consisting, in Crotona, of 300 members; according to some ac- counts, of more. * In Crotona, these were desig- nated by the name of oix{Auot (Iam- blichus, V. P. 45,260, after Apollo- nius), which is so large a number for a senate, that it might lead us rather to suppose that the ruling portion of the citizens was intended. Diod. xii. 9, calls them atºykamtos, 350 PYTHAGORAS. reins of government, and employed their power to pro. mote an aristocratic organisation of the ancient Dori type." They no less rigorously maintained the doctrine of their master, and silenced all opposition with the famous dictum airós #4a.” Porph. 18, to róv yepávrov &pxeſov. Both Diodorus and Iamblichus, however, speak of the 67aos and ēkkNmoria, which, according to Iam- blichus, 260, only had to resolve upon that which was brought before it by the xixiot. * Iambl. 249, after Aristoxenus, 254 sqq.; after Apollonius, Diog. viii. 3; Justin. xx. 4. Polybius, ii. 39, menticns the Pythagorean avvé- 8pta in the cities of Magna Graecia. Plut. C. Princ. Philos. i. 11, p. 777, speaks of the influence of Pytha- goras on the leading Italiotes, and Porph. 54 says the Italians handed over the direction of their states to the Pythagoreans. In the con- test between Crotona and Sybaris, which ended in the destruction of the latter, it was, according to Diodorus, respect for Pythagoras which decided the Crotonians to refuse to deliver up the fugitive Sybarite nobles, and to undertake a war with their more powerful rival. It was Milo, the Pythago- rean, who led his countrymen to the fatal battle on the Traés. Cicero, indeed (De Orat. iii. 15, 56; cf. Tusc. v. 23, 66), includes Pytha- goras with Anaxagoras and Demo- critus among those who renounced political activity in order to live entirely for science; but this does not destroy the former evidence, since in the first place it is uncer- tain whence Cicero derived his in- formation; and in the second, Py- thagoras himself held no public We are told, however, that office. Still less does it follow from Plato, Rep. x. 600 C, that the Pythagoreans abstained from political activity; though, accord- ing to this passage, their founder himself worked, not as a statesman, but by personal intercourse. The strictly aristocratic character of the Pythagorean politics appears from the charges against them in Iambl. 260; Athen. v. 213 f (cf. Diog. viii. 46; Tertull. Apologet. c. 46), and from the whole persecution by Cylon. Chaig- net's theory (i. 54 sq.), however, that the government of Crotona was first changed by Pythagoras from a moderate democracy into an aristocracy is supported by no tradition; it is, on the contrary, contradicted by the passage in Strabo, viii. 7, i. p. 384 (after Polybius, ii. 39, 5), where it is said of the Italians : Heră răv ardouv Thu trpos toūs IIv6ayopetous rô. TAeſota rāv vopupiðv werevéykaoréal tapå rotºrov (the Achaeans, who had a democratic constitution), which would not have been neces- sary if they had only required to re-establish their own democratic institutions; while, on the other hand (vide previous note), the ékkâmoria decided many things, even under the Pythagorean ad- ministration. * Cic. N. D. i. 5, 10; Diog. viii. 46; Clemens, Strom. ii. 369 C; Philo. Qu. in Gen. i. 99, p. 70. THE PM THAGO REAN SCHOOL. 351 this doctrine was carefully kept within the limits of the school, and that every transgression of these limits was severely punished." In order that the doctrine might be quite incomprehensible to the uninitiated, the Pythagoreans, and in the first instance the founder of the school, are said to have employed that symbolical mode of expression in which are contained most of the maxims handed down to us as Pythagorean.” * Aristoxenus, Diog. viii. 15, says it was a principle of the Py- thagoreans, whº eival trpos travtas Trávra Ämté, and, according to Iambl. 31, Aristotle reckons the saying about Pythagoras, quoted .338, 3, among the travu ätrömra of the school. Later writers (as Plut. Numa, 22; Aristocles, ap. Eus. Pr. Ev. xi. 3, 1 ; the Pseudo-Lysis, ap. Iambl. 75 sqq., and Diog. viii. 42; Clem. Strom. v. 574 D; Iambl. V. P. 199, 226 sq., 246 sq.; tr. Koiv. pa6. Étriot ; Willoison, Anecd. ii p. 216 ; Porph. 58; an anonymous person, ap. Menage, Diog. viii.; cf. Plato, Ep. ii. 314 A) dilate much on the strictness and fidelity with which the Pythagoreans kept even geometrical and other purely scientific theorems as secrets of their fraternity, and on the abhor- rence and punishment of the gods which overtook every betrayal of this mystery. The first proof in support of this opinion is the asser- tion (sup. p. 315) of Neanthes about Empedocles and Philolaus, and in the legendary narrative of the same author, as also of Hippobotus, ap. Iambl. 189 sqq. (considerably more recent, cf. Diog. viii. 72), according to which Myllias and Timycha suffer to the uttermost, the latter even biting out his own tongue, like Zeno in Elea, in order not to reveal to the elder T)ionysius the reason of Pythagoras's prohibition of beans. On the other hand, it is a question whether the statement of Timaeus, in Diog. viii. 54, on which that of Neanthes is unquestionably founded, that Empedocles, and afterwards Plato, were excluded from Pythagorean teaching, being accused of Aoyokaorta—really re- fers to the publishing of a secret doctrine, and not to the proclaiming improperly of Pythagorean doc- trines as their own. Moreover, we cannot give much credit to the testimony of an author, who, in spite of all chronology, makes Empedocles (loc. cit.) the personal pupil of Pythagoras. * Iamblich. 104 sq., 226 sq. Collections and interpretations of Pythagoreansymbols are mentioned by Aristoxenus in the truða'yoptical &moſpáoets, and by Alexander Poly- histor and Anaximander the younger, ap. Clem. Strom. i. 304, B. Cyrill. c. Jul. iv. 133 D; Iambl. V. P. 101, 145; Theol. Arithm, p. 41; Suidas, 'Avačípavöpos (cf. Krische, p. 74 sq.; Mahne, De Aristoreno, 94 sqq.; Brandis, i. 498); another work, said to be of ancient Pythagorean origin, bearing the name of Androcydes, is dis- cussed, part iii. b, 88, second edi tion. Aristotle's work on the Py- 352 PYTHAGORAS. =zerºzz-rº zºº-- - - - - How much of these statements may be accepted as historical it is difficult to determine in detail; we can only establish approximately certain general results. We see that so early as the time of Aristotle, Aristoxe- nus, and Dicaearchus, many miraculous tales respecting Pythagoras were in circulation ; but whether he himself appeared in the character of a worker of miracles cannot be ascertained. The manner in which he is spoken of by Empedocles and Heracleitus' renders it probable that, for long after his death, he was merely esteemed as a man of unusual wisdom, without any super- matural character. This wisdom seems to have been Tchiefly of a religious kind, and to have served religious ends. Pythagoras appears as the founder of a religious association with its own rites and ceremonies; thus he may have passed for a seer and a priest, and may have declared himself as such : this is extremely likely from the whole character of the Pythagorean legend, thagoreans seems to have given many of these symbols (vide Porph. 41 ; Hieron. c. Ruf. iii. 39, T. ii. 565, Wall.; Diog. viii. 34), and va- rious authors (as Demetrius of Byzantium mentioned by Athen. x, 452 c) have spoken of them inci- dentally. From these ancient com- pilations probably came the greater part of the sentences ascribed to 12ythagoras and the Pythagoreans by later writers, as Plutarch (es- pecially in the ovuºroalakā), Sto- baeus, Athenaeus, Diogenes, Por- phyry, and Iamblichus, Hippolytus, &c. These senteices, however, cannot be much relied upon as re- presenting the Ethics and religious doctrine of the Pythagoreans; for in the first place their meaning is very uncertain, and in the second, what is genuinely Pythagorean is hard to distinguish from later in- gredients. In regard to the Py- thagorean Philosophy, they are of little importance. Collections of these sentences are to be found in Orelli, Opusc. Graec. Vet. Sent. i., 60 sq.; Mullach, Fragm. Philos. i. 504 sqq.; Göttling, Ges. Ahhand. i. 278 sq., ii. 280 sq., has subjected them to a thorough criticism. But his interpretations are often too artificial, and he is apt to seek unnecessarily for hidden meanings in prescripts, which originally were of a purely ritualistic cha- racter. Cf. also Rohde, Rh. Mus. xxvi. 561. * Wide supra, p. 336, 4; 338, 4. THE PXTHAGOREAN SCHOOL, 353 and from the existence of Pythagorean orgies in the fifth century; but that does not make him by any means the extraordinary phenomenon presupposed by the later tradition ; he merely stands in the same category with Epimenides, Onomacritus, and other men of the sixth and seventh centuries. Further, it seems certain that the Pythagorean Society distinguished f itself above all other similar associations by its ethicakſ tendency; but we can get no true idea of its ethical aims and institutions from the later untrustworthy authorities. Pythagoras doubtless entertained the design of founding a school of piety and morality, temperance, valour, order, obedience to government and law, fidelity to friends, and generally for the en- couragement of all virtues belonging to the Greek, and particularly to the Doric conception of a good and brave man; virtues which are particularly insisted on in the sentences attributed with more or less probability to Pythagoras. For this purpose he appealed first to the religious motives which resulted from the belief in the dominion of the gods, and especially from the doctrine of transmigration; then he had recourse to the educa- tional methods and usages of his native country, such as music and gymnastics. We are assured by the most trustworthy traditions that these two arts were zealously practised in the Pythagorean school. With these may have been also connected (vide Supra) the use of cer- tain therapeutic and secret remedies. Incantation, song, and religious music probably played the part attributed to them in the myths; this is rendered probable by the whole character of the art of medicine in ancient times, WOL. I. A A - 354 PYTHAGORAS. # { closely allied as it was with religion, sorcery and music ; while, on the other hand, the statement that the Pytha- gorean art of medicine consisted mainly of dietetics' is confirmed, mot merely by its connection with gymnastic and by the whole character of the Pythagorean mode of life, but also by Plato's similar view.” It is probable too, that the Pythagoreans adopted the practice in their society of common meals, either daily or at certain times; * but what later authors have said about their community of goods is certainly fabulous; and the peculiarities ascribed to them concerning dress, food, and other habits of life must be reduced to a few traits of little importance.” Furthermore, although the politi- cal character of the Pythagorean society is undemiable, yet the assertion" that its entire design was of a purely political kind, and that every other end was subordi- nated to this, goes far beyond any proofs deducible from history, and is neither compatible with the physical and mathematical bent of the Pythagorean science, nor with " Iambl. 163, 264. * Rep. iii. 405 C sqq.; Tim. 88 C sqq. * Cf. on the medical art of the Pythagoreans and their contempo- raries, Krische, De Societ, a Pyth. Cond, 40; Forschungen, &c. 72 sqq. * As Krische supposes, De Societ. &c. 86, relying on the muti- lated passage of Satyrus, ap. Diogº viii. 40; cf. Iambl. 249; vide the writers quoted, p. 343, 4, who throughout presuppose community of goods. * Cf. p. 344 sqq. * * & Krische, 1. c., p. 101, con- cludes thus: Societatis (Pythagori- cae) scopus fuit mere politicus, ut lapsam optimatium potestatem non modo in pristinum restitueret, sed firmaret amplificaretgue ; cum sum- ſmo hoc scopo duo conjuncti fuerunt, moralis alter, alter ad literas spec- tans. Discipulos Suos bonos pro- bosque homines reddere voluit Pythagoras et ut civitatem mode- Tantes potestate Sua non abuterentur ad plebem opprimendam, et ut plebs, intelligens Stſis commodis consuli, conditione Sua contenta esset. Quo- niam vero bonum sapiensque mode- ramen (non) nisi aprudenteliterisque ea culto viro easpectari licet, philoso- phiae studium necessarium durit Samius is, qui ad civitatis clavum tenendum se accingerent. THE PPTHAGO REAN SCHOOL. 355 the fact that the most ancient authorities represent Pythagoras to us rather as a prophet, a wise man and a moral reformer, than as a statesman." The alliance of Pythagoreanism with the Doric aristocracy seems to me the consequence and not the reason of its general tendency and view of life, and though the tradition which bids us recognise in the Pythagorean societies of Magna Græcia a political combination may in the main be worthy of credit, yet I find no proof that the religious, ethical, and scientific character of the Pytha- goreans was developed from their political bias. The contrary seems, indeed, more probable. On the other hand, it is difficult to admit that scientific inquiry was the root of Pythagoreanism. For the moral, religious, , and political character of the school cannot be explained by the theory of numbers and mathematics, in which, as we shall presently find, the distinguishing pecu- liarities of the Pythagorean science consisted. Pytha- goreanism seems rather to have originated in the moral and religious element, which is most prominent in the oldest accounts of Pythagoras, and appears in the early Pythagorean orgies, to which also the sole doctrine which can with any certainty be ascribed to Pythagoras himself-i-the doctrine of transmigration—relates. Py- thagoras desired to effect, chiefly by the aid of religion, --a reform of the moral, life; but as in Thales, the first physical speculation had connected itself with ethical reflection, so here practical ends were united with that form of scientific theory to which Pythagoras owes his place in the history of philosophy. Again, in their * Wide supra, texts quoted pp. 336; 346, 1; 350, 1. A A 2 356 PYTHIAGORAS. religious rites alone must we seek for the much talked of mysteries of the Pythagorean Society. The division of esoteric and exoteric (if this indeed existed among the ancient Pythagoreans) was purely a religious dis- tinction. It resulted from the traditional distinction between greater and lesser initiations, between com- plete and preparatory consecrations." That philosophic doctrines or even mathematical propositions, apart from their possible religious symbolism, should have been held secret, is in the highest degree improbable; * Phi- lolaus at any rate, and the other authorities from whom Plato and Aristotle derived their knowledge of Pytha- goreanism, can have known nothing of any ordinance of this nature.” The political tendency of the Pythagorean com- munity was fatal to its material existence and to a * In regard to the later con- ception of the importance of this distinction, I cannot agree with Rohde (Rh. Mus. xxvi. 560 sq.) in explaining it from the supposed fact that after there appeared a Pythagorean philosophy the adhe- rents of this, philosophy regarded the original Pythagoreanism, which was limited to religious prescripts and observances, as merely a pre- paratory stage of the higher know- ledge; this seems to me to be an invention of the Neo-Pythagoreans, who thus attempted to represent as the opinion of Pythagoras what they themselves had foisted upon him. and to explain away the entire silence of ancient tradition on the subject. It is only in their writings that these two classes of Pythago- reans are recognised; and it is they who, in the passages discussed p. 309, 2, declare the celebrated pro- positions of the Pythagoreans to be something exoteric, the true mean- ing of which can only be discovered by regarding them as symbols of deeper doctrines kept up as a mys- tery by the school, and lost from general tradition. That the true philosophy of the Pythagoreans should be represented as an occult doctrine, only imparted to a select minority even of the disciples, is quite in harmony with this ten- dency, which, indeed, is its most obvious explanation. * So also Ritter, Pyth. Phil. 52 sq. &c. * What Porphyry, 58, and Iamblichus, 253, 199, say in its de- fence, carries on the face of it the stamp of later invention. Cf. Diog. viii. 55 (supra, p. 315). THE PIV THAGOREAN SCHOOL. 357 great part of its members. The democratic movement in opposition to the traditional aristocratic institutions, which in time invaded most of the Greek States, de- clared itself with remarkable rapidity and energy in the populous and independent Italian colonies, in- habited by a mixed population, excited by ambitious leaders. The Pythagorean avvéöpua formed the centre of the aristocratic party: they therefore became the im– mediate object of a furious persecution which raged with the utmost violence throughout lower Italy. The meeting houses of the Pythagoreans were everywhere burnt; they themselves murdered or banished, and the aristocratic constitutions overthrown. This continued until at length, through the intervention of the Achaeans, an agreement was brought about by which the re- mainder of the exiles were allowed to return to their homes." As to the date and more precise details of this persecution, accounts differ considerably. On the one hand, Pythagoras himself is stated to have been killed * in it ; and, on the other, it is said of certain * So much we can gather from the detailed accounts presently to be noticed, and also from the state- ments of Polybius, ii. 32, who says (unfortunately only incidentally,and without any mention of date): ka9. offs yūp kapoos év rols karū thv 'Iraxtav Tótrous karū thv pleyāAmv ‘EAAdôa tête irposa'yopewouévnv évé- Tpmaav rô avvéöpia Tău IIv6ayopetov, perä raúra ös Yuvouévov civiuatos 6Aoaxepods repl r&s troAiretas, Štep eikös, Ös &v Tóv trptºrov &vöpóv é; ékdoºrms tróAews oftw trapaxóyws ôuaq,6apévrov, ovvé8m rās kar’ exeſvous rot's Tótrovs ‘EAAmvikås TóAels &vatAma 6ival påvov Kal orráorews ical travrobatrâs rapax.js. On this rests the assertion that the Achaeans united Crotona, Sybaris, and Caulonia in a league and con- vention, and thus introduced their constitution into those cities. * The various accounts are these : 1st, according to Plut. Stoic. Hep. 37, 3, p. 1051 ; Athenag. Supplic. c. 31 ; Hippolyt. Refut. i. 2, sub fin. ; Arnob, Adv. Gent. i. 40; Sohol. in Plat. p. 420, Bekk. and a passage in Tzetz. Chil. xi. 80 sqq., Pythagoras was burned alive by the Crotoniates. Hippo- lytus adds that Archippus, Lysis, and Zamolxis escaped from the 358 PXTHAGORAS. Pythagoreans of the fourth and fifth centuries that they had escaped from the persecution. conflagration, and Plutarch's words seem to admit the possibility that he only meant an attempt at burning, 2. Nearest to this comes the account of Diog. viii. 39, that Pythagoras and his people were in the house of Milo when the enemy set fire to it; that he escaped in- deed, but was intercepted in his flight, and killed; the greater number of his friends (forty of them) were also put to death : only a few, among whom were Archippus and Lysis, escaped. 3. According to Porph. 57 and Tzetz. loc. cit., others think that Pythagoras him- self escaped from the attack in Cro- tona to Metapontum, his disciples making a bridge through the fire for him with their bodies; and all, except Lysis and Archippus, being destroyed; that he there starved himself to death, being weary of life, as Porphyry says; or died of want, according to Tzetzes. 4. Accordingtol)icaearchus, ap. Porph. 56 sq., and Diog. viii. 40, Pytha- goras at the time of the attack on the forty Pythagoreans, was in the town, but not in the house; he fled to the Locrians, and thence to Ta- rentum, and was rejected by both. Proceeding to Metapontum, he there, after forty days' starvation (āorithaavta, says Diogenes; ev otrável Tôv &vaykatov Šiauetvavita, says Porphyry; hence, no doubt, Tzetzes' theory), died. . This view is followed by Themist. Orat. xxiii. p. 285 b ; the account in Justin's Hist. xx. 4, seems also to have arisen from it; here sixty Pytha- goreans are said to have been destroyed, and the remainder banished. Dicaearchus also says Crotona is most that more than the forty were put to death. He, like most of the other authorities, seems to mention Cylon as the author of the persecu- tion. As to the sojourn of Pythago- ras in Tarentum, Röth, ii. a, 962, refers to Claudian, De Consul. Fl. Mall. Theod. xvii. 157: At mon, Pythagora monitus annique silentes jamosum Oebali; luaum pressere Tarent: ; but these words appa- rently only attest the well-known fact that Tarentum was afterwards a chief centre of Pythagoreanism. IRöth moreover makes out of Oeba- lium Tarentum a Tarentine of the name of Oebalius, whose luxurious life Pythagoras vainly attempted to regulate, which is even a greater discovery than that about the map of Europe, which the philosopher is said to have made in Tarentum (vide supra, p. 347, 2). 5. Accord- ing to the mutually complementary accounts of Neanthes, ap. Porph. 55; of Satyrus and Heracleides (Lembus), ap. Diog. viii. 40; and of Nicomachus, ap. Iambl. 251, Pythagoras at the time of Cylon's attack was not in Crotona at all, but in Delos with Pherecydes, to tend in his illness and bury him; when on his return he found that his followers, with the exception of Archippus and Lysis, had been burned in Milo's house or slain, he betook himself to Metapontum, where (according to Heracleides, ap. Diogenein) he starved himself to death. 6. According to the ac- count of Aristoxenus (ap. Iambl. 248 sqq.), Cylon, a tyrannical and ambitious man, being angry that Pythagoras had refused him ad- mission into his society, commenced I).EATH OF PIPTHAGORAS. 359 generally named as the place where the first decided attack was made, and Metapontum as the place where a violent struggle with the philo- sopher and his followers during the last years of Pythagoras's life. In consequence of this, Pythagoras himself emigrated to Metapontum, where he died; but the struggle continued, and after the Pythago- reans had maintained themselves for some time longer at the head of the states, they were at last attacked at Crotona during a po- litical consultation in the house of Milo, and all, except the two Ta- rentines, Archippus and Lysis, were destroyed by fire. Archippus retired to his native city, and Ly- sis to Thebes; the rest of the Py- thagoreans, with the exception of Archytas, abandoned Italy and lived together in Rhegium (which, however, is also in Italy), until the school, as the political conditions became worse and worse, gradually died out. (The confusion at the end of this account Rohde, Rh. Mus. xxvi. 565, explains by an inversion, which commends itself equally to me. The true mean- ing is that the Pythagoreans lived at first together in Rhegium, but when things became worse, they, with the exception of Archy- tas, left Italy.) This was the ac- count which Diodorus, Fragm. p. 556, had before him, as appears from a comparison with Iambl. 248, 250. Apollonius, Mirab. c. 6, makes Pythagoras fly to Meta- pontum before the attack which he foretold. In Cic. Fin. v. 2, we are told that the dwelling of Pythago- ras and the place of his death were shown in Metapontum; in Valer. Max. viii. 7, ext. 2, that the whole city of Metapontum attended the funeral of the philosopher with the deepest reverence; in Aristid. Quint. De Mus. iii. 116 Meib. that Pythagoras before his death re- . commended the use of the mono- chord to his disciples. These ac- counts agree best with the present version, as they all presuppose that the philosopher was not per- sonally threatened up to the time of his death, and when Plut. Gen. Socr. 13, p. 583, speaks of the ex- pulsion of the Pythagoreans from various cities, and of the burning of their house of assembly in Me- tapontum, on which occasion only Philolaus and Lysis were saved— though Metapontum is substituted for Crotona, and Philolaus for Ar- chippus—the silence in regard to Pythagoras himself, and the placing of the whole persecution in the period after his death, are both in accordance with the statements of Aristoxenus. So Olympiodorus in Phaed. p. 8 sq. mentions the Pytha- goreans only, and not Pythagoras, as having been burned; Philolaus and Hipparchus (Archippus) alone, he says, escaped. 7. The account of Apollonius, ap. Iambl. 254 Sqq., resembles that of Aristoxenus. According to this, the Pythagorean aristocracy very early excited dis- satisfaction; after the destruction of Sybaris and the death of Pytha- goras (not merely his departure : étrel 6& 37 exeºtmarev, it is said, and in connection with étexeſºrmorev, the previous éreśńuet and ārāA6e are to be explained), this dissatisfac- tion was stirred up by Cylon and other members of noble families not belonging to the society, and on the partition of the conquered 360 PYTHAGORAS. & Pythagoras died; but there are so many discrepancies as to details, that a complete reconciliation of the various statements is impossible. What is most pro- bable is that the first public outbreak must have taken place after the death of Pythagoras, though an opposi- tion to him and his friends may perhaps have arisen during his lifetime, and caused his migration to Meta- pontum. The party struggles with the Pythagoreans, thus begun, may have repeated themselves at different times in the cities of Magna Graecia, and the varia- tions in the statements may be partially accounted for as recollections of these different facts. The burning of the assembled Pythagoreans in Crotona and the general assault upon the Pythagorean party most likely did not take place until the middle of the fifth century; and, lastly, Pythagoras may have spent the last portion of his life unmolested in Metapontum.” lands broke out into open hostility. The Pythagoreans were dispersed during one of their assemblies, then defeated in combat, and after ruinous disturbances, the whole Pythagorean party was driven out of three neighbouring cities by the judges, who had been corrupted, and a distribution of lands and re- mission of debts was decreed. Not till after many years did the Achaeans accomplish the return of the exiles, of whom about sixty came back; but even these fell in an unfortunate encounter with the Thurians. 8. Lastly, Hermippus (ap. Diog. viii. 40; cf. Schol. in Plat. loc. cit.), differing from all other accounts, says that Pythago- ras was with his friends, fighting at the head of the Agrigentines against the Syracusans, and was killed in flight, while the remainder of the Pythagoreans, to the numb of thirty-five, were burned i Tarentum. * As is now generally supposed, according to Bockh. Phi * The above suppositions are chiefly based on the following grounds: Firstly, by far the greater number, and the most creditable authorities, maintain that Pytha- goras died in Metapontum (cf. Iambl. 248); and even those who place the burning of the house in Crotona in his life-time, for the most part assert that he himself escaped. Although it is clear from the contradictoriness of these latter statements that no univer- sally accepted tradition existed at the time, yet the fact itself that Pythagoras fled to Metapontum I) ISPERSION OF THE PPTHAGOREANS. 361 It was only after the dispersion of the Italian asso- ciations, and in consequence of this dispersion that the must have been pretty firmly es- tablished, since the most improba- ble expedients were resorted to by the authors of these statements to reconcile it with their other theo- ries. Other accounts say that he was put to death in Crotona or Sicily, but this is no doubt an in stance of what so often happens in regard to Pythagoras—that facts about his school, or a portion of his school, are transferred to him personally. Secondly, the occasion of Pythagoras's retreat to Meta- pontum could not have been the incendiary attack on the assembly at Crotona; the attack must have occurred many years after his death. Aristoxenus and Apollo- nius say this expressly. Aristoxe- nus, however, is the authority whom we should most expect to reproduce the Pythagorean tra- dition of his time. With what right Apollonius appeals in section 262 to Tö. Töv Kpotaviatóv Štropavā- Mata, we do not know. If even any work that might be so desig- nated were within his reach, the designation might apply to any Crotoniate writing whatsoever. Roth, however, thinks it manifestly implies ‘contemporary records,' and he deduces from them, not only the somewhat unimportant point for which they were cited, but the whole narrative of Apollo- nius. Moreover, the different ac- counts assert with singular unani- mity that only Archippus and Ly- sis escaped from the massacre; and as this is maintained even by those who place that event in the life- time of Pythagoras, it must, at any rate, be based on an ancient and universal tradition. Now Lysis, at an advanced age, was the instructor of Epaminondas (Aris- tox. ap. Iambl. 250; Diodor. loc. cit.; Neanthes, ap. Porph. 55; Diog. viii. 7; Plut. Gen. Socr. 13; Dio Chrysos. Or. 49, p. 248; R. Corn. Nepos. Epam. c. 1), and the birth of Epaminondas cannot be supposed earlier than 418–420 B C.; not only because he fought vigorously at Mantinea in 362, but also because Plut. De Lat. Viv. 4, 5, p. 1129, names his fortieth year as the period at which he began to be important, and this period (ac- cording to Vit. Pelop. c. 5, end, c. 12; De Gen. Socr. 3, p. 576) could not have been before 378 B.C., the deliverance of Thebes. Supposing Lysis to have been fifty years older than his pupil, we thus arrive at 468–470 B.C. as the earliest date of his birth, and the attack in Crotona could scarcely, even in that case, have occurred before 450 B.C. It is more probable, however, that the difference between the ages of Ly- sis and Epaminondas was not so great (according to Plut. Gen. Socr. 8, 13, Lysis died shortly before the deliverance of Thebes), and that the Crotonian massacre must be placed about 440 B.C., or even later. The statement of Aristoxenus abcut Archytas and that of Apol- lonius—that a portion of the Py- thagoreans, who had been expelled from Crotona, returned after the re- conciliation effected by the Achaeans —points to some such date. For although, according to Polyb. ii. 39, 7, the attacks of Dionysius the Elder (who came to the throne in 406) left the three Italian cities 362 THE PPTHAGOREA.N.S. Pythagorean philosophy became more widely known in Greece, although the Pythagorean rites had previously (Crotona, Sybaris, and Caulonia) no opportunity for the consolida- tion and maintenance of the new institutions borrowed from the Achaeans some time (uerá rugs xpóvovs) after the adjustment of the Pythagorean troubles—yet the Achaean mediation could scarcely have occurred earlier than from ten to fifteen years previous to the end of the Peloponnesian war; but Polybius himself seems to assume that the troubles to which the burning of the Pythagorean houses gave the signal, were not very dis- tant chronologically from the in- tervention of the Achaeans. It matters not that the Pythagorean assembly which was burned is universally placed in the house of Milo, and that the authors of the deed are also called by Aris- toxenus Cylonians; for Milo's house may have remained the meet- ing place of the Pythagoreans after the death of its owner, as Plato's garden was that of the Academy; and “Cylonians’ seems, like Pytha- goreans, to have been a party name, which survived the chief from whom it was derived; cf. Aristox. loc. cit. 249. Thirdly. It is never- theless probable that before the death of Pythagoras, a party ad- verse to the Pythagoreans was formed by Cylon in Crotona, which party may have been strengthened mainly by the demand for a divi- sion of the conquered lands, and by the victorious conflict with the Sybarites; and that this disturb- anóe may have determined Pytha- goras to remove to Metapontum. This is admitted by Aristoxenus and Apollonius, though the former makes the burning of Milo's house take place an indefinite time after the death of Pythagoras; and the latter, instead of the burning, re- Iates another incident in the time of Cylon. Even Aristotle (ap. Diog. ii. 446, cf. viii. 49) inci- dentally mentions Cylon's enmity against Pythagoras, which had be- come proverbial. These earlier conflicts, however, cannot have oc- casioned the overthrow of the Py- thagoreans in Lower Italy. This can only have happened (even ac- cording to Polybius) when the burning of the council house in Crotona gave the signal for similar acts in other places, and a universal storm broke out against the Py- thagoreans. When, therefore, Aristoxenus says that the Pythago- reans kept the lead of public affairs in the cities of Magna Graecia for some time after the first attack upon them, there is every reason for crediting the statement. Fourthly. If the first popular movement against the Pythagoreans was con- fined to Crotona, and if they finally maintained themselves there, it is not probable that Pythagoras, con- trary to the principles of his school, should have starved himself to death, or even have died of hun- ger. It rather seems as if, even in Aristotle's time, tradition had been silent as to the particular circumstances of his death, and that the lacuna was subsequently filled by arbitrary conjectures; so that Aristoxenus is here most worthy of credit, when he restricts himself to the remark: kåke? Aéye- rai karaatpéthat Töv 8tov. Chaignet i. 94, objects to the foregoing that IATER PIV THAGOREA.N.S. 363 gained entrance there," and certain individuals had turned their attention to the philosophic doctrines of the school.” At this period, at all events, we first hear of Pythagorean writings “and of Pythagoreans who lived elsewhere than in Italy. The first of these with whom we are acquainted, is Philolaus.* We know that he was a contemporary of Socrates and Democritus, and probably was older than either; that in the last decade of the fifth century he resided in Thebes,” and that he if the Pythagoreans had been banished from Italy for seventy years, they would not have been called the Italian philosophers (vide Supra, p. 338, 1). I know not with what eyes he can have read a discussion, which expressly at- tempts to show that the Pythago- reans were not expelled till 440, and returned before 406. * Wide supra, p. 346, 1. * Wide the expression of Hera- cleitus, quoted p. 336, 5, and the assertions of Thrasyllus, Glaucus, and Apollodorus, ap. Diog. ix. 38, according to which Democritus was acquainted with Philolaus, that he spoke with admiration of Pythago- ras in a treatise called after him, and, in general, had made indus- trious use of the Pythagorean doc- trines. Democritus, however, was certainly younger than Philolaus, and it is doubtful how far Herac- leitus had knowledge of Pythagoras as a philosopher. His words seem rather to refer to the founder of the religious association. He charges Pythagoras with kaicote- xvin; and the ovyypaſpal, from which he is said to have gained his false wisdom, may either mean Orphic hymns, or the ancient my- thological poems, of which Hera- cleitus generally speaks so slight- ingly; or, at any rate, the writings of Pherecydes and Anaximander. The passage concerning Pythagoras and his universal knowledge per- haps stood in the same connection as the polemic against the ancient poets. * Wide supra, p. 313. * For Archippus, who is repre- sented in Hieron. c. Ruf. iii. 469, Mart. (vol. ii. 565, Wall.) as teach- ing with Lysis in Thebes, was a somewhat younger contemporary of Lysis. The statement seems to have arisen from the two names being elsewhere mentioned to- gether; for all other authorities agree that Archippus returned to Tarentum after the conflagration in Crotona, and that Lysis went alone to Thebes. Wide the passa- ges quoted supra, p. 357, 2. * Plato, Phaedo, 61 D; Diog. loc. cit. Diog, viii. 84, names Cro- tona as the native city of Philo- laus ; all other authorities, Taren- tum. Cf. Böckh, Philol. p. 5 sqq., where the erroneous statements that he escaped from the fire in Crotona (Plut. Gen. Socr. 13, vide supra, p. 359); that he was the instructor of Plato (Diog. iii. 6), and a personal pupil of Pythagoras 364 IATER PPTHAGOREA.N.S. was the author of the first exposition of the Pythagorean system." Lysis must also have come to Thebes about the same time as Philolaus, and probably resided there up to the second decade of the fourth century.” Plato” assigns Timaeus the Locrian to the same period, but it is not certain whether or not this Timaeus was a his— torical personage. Among the disciples of Philolaus is mentioned Eurytus,” of Tarentum or Crotona, who must also be supposed to have spent a part of his life out of Italy, since those of his pupils who are known to us came, one of them from Thrace, the others from Phlius.” (Iambl. V. P. 104), with others of a similar kind, are refuted. Ac- cording to Diog. viii. 84, Philolaus was put to death in Crotona on suspicion of aiming at the Tyranny. He must, therefore, have returned to Italy, and become implicated in the final party conflicts with the Pythagoreans. * Cf. Supra, pp. 313; 314, 2; and Böckh, Philol. p. 18 sqq., who rightly contests the assertion that the work of Philolaus was first brought to light by Plato. Preller (Allg. Encycl. iii. Sect. vol. xxiii. 371), at any rate, does not convince me of the contrary. The result of Böckh's enquiry, p. 24 sqq., is, that the work bore the title tep pigeos, that it was divided into three books, and is identical with the writing to which Proclus gives the mystical name of 84*.xai. * Cf. p. 361, and Iambl. V. P. 185; ibid. 75 sqq.; Diog. viii. 42, a portion of a letter said to be his. Further details as to the writings attributed to him, p. 322, Part iii. Jo, 37, second edition. . . .* These scholars of Eurytus are called by Aris- * In the Timaeus and Critias; •cf. especially Tim. 20 A. * Iambl. 139, 148, calls him a scholar of Pythagoras. He also, in section 148, names Crotona as his native city; in section 67, how- ever, agreeing with Diog. viii. 46; Apul. Dogm. Plat. (sub init.); Tarentum ; section 266 represents him, together with a certain Thea- rides, as living in Metapontum; this statement, however, stands in a very doubtful connection. Diog. iii. 6, and Apul. loc. cit. mention him among the Italian instructors of Plato. Some tenets of his will be mentioned further on. The frag- ments in Stob. Ecl. i. 210, and Clem. Strom. v. 559 D, do not belong to him, but to an imaginary Eurysus, and are no doubt spurious. * We know little more of them than what is said in Diog. viii. 46 (cf. Iambl. Vita Pythag. 251): rexeuratot yºp yévovºro róv IIv6a- yopetww offs ſcal 'Aptoráčevos eiðs, Bevöqtads 6' 6 XaAktöews &trö Opticms kal pávrov 6 fºuágios kaſ 'Exekpárms kal Atokańskał IIoMüuvaaros, ºxida- DIODORUS, CLINIAS. 365 toxenus the last of the Pythagoreans, and he says that with them the school, as such, became extinct." The school, according to this, must have died out in Greece proper soon after the middle of the fourth century, though the Bacchic Pythagorean rites may have con- tinued" to exist some time longer, and may have fur- nished a pretext to Diodorus of Aspendus,” for desig- nating his cynicism as Pythagorean Philosophy. Even in Italy, however, the Pythagorean school was not annihilated by the blow which destroyed its political ascendency. Though the persecution may have ex- tended to most of the Greek colonies, it can hardly to kal airoi. 70'av 6’ &kpoatal pixo- Adov kal Eöpárov Tóv'Tapavrivov. Of Xenophilus we are told (Plin. Hist. Naț. vii. 50,168; Valer. Max. viii. 13, 3; Lucian, Macrob. 18) that he at- tained the age of 105 in perfect health. The two last authorities appeal to Aristoxenus, in support of this statement. Pliny and the Pseudo-Lucian call Xenophilus the musician ; according to the lat- ter, he lived in Athens. Eche- crates is the same person who is mentioned in the Phaedo and in the ninth Platonic letter. Cic. Fin. v. 29, 87, wrongly calls him a Locrian, cf. Steinhart, Plato's Werke, iv. 558. * Wide previous note, and Iambl. loc. cit. : épáxašav učv obv rd & 3pxis #0m kai Tà uo.6%iuata, katrol ékAeitroëorms rās aipéaews ws evre Mós hºpavío.6morav railra uèv ošv 'Aptoráčevos Sumyeºrai. Diodor. xv. 76. The last Pythagorean philo- sophers lived in the third year of the 103rd Olympiad (366 B.C.). * As will be shown later on. * This Diodorus, who came from the city of Aspendus, in Pamphylia, is mentioned by Sosi- crates, ap. Diog. vi. 13, as the in- ventor of the Cynic garb, or, as Athen. iv. 163, more accurately says, the person who first wore it among the Pythagoreans. With this Timaeus, ap. Athen. loc. cit. agrees. Iambl. 266 calls him a pupil of Aresas, the Pythagorean; but this is manifestly false, as Aresas is said to have escaped from the persecution of Cylon, and Dio- dorus, according to Athenaeus, must- have lived about 300. To the same period Lyco seems to belong, who is called by Diog. (v. 69) IIv6ayopukös, and whose attacks upon Aristotle are spoken of by Aristocles, Eus. Pr. Ev. xv.2, 4 sq. The latter says of him, Atkovos roo Aéryovros sival IIv6ayopikov Šavrów, and includes him among those adversaries of Aristotle who were contemporary with him, or somewhat later. (This was overlooked, supra, p. 308, 1.) It is probably the same person who is called in Iambl. 267 a Tarentine. ºr _^ 366 LATER PIPTHAGOREA.N.S. have done so to all, and in certain cities Pythagorean teachers would seem to have maintained their position even before the restoration of peace. At all events, if the sojourn of Philolaus in Heraclea," for instance, be a historical fact, it perhaps may have occurred previously to that epoch. In this same town is said to have lived Clinias the Tarentine,” who in any case was no doubt a near contemporary of Philolaus.* As to his philosophical importance, we can decide nothing. Many proofs have come down to us of the purity, gentleness, and mobility of his character; * but we possess very few of his philosophic propositions, and these are by no means of unquestionable authenticity.” Prorus is men- tioned as another of his contemporaries in Cyrene," to which city, if this statement be true, Pythagoreanism must have spread from its original centre. In the first half of the fourth century, it even attained, in the person of Archytas,” to new political importance. We know 1 Iambl. 266, where from the context the Italian Heraclea can alone be meant ; this city was a colony from Tarentum and Thurii, founded in the fourth year of the 86th Olympiad. 2 Iambl. 266 sq. * As is presupposed by the apocryphal story in Diog. ix. 40, that he and Amyclas restrained Plato from burning the writings of Democritus. - 4 Iambl. V. P. 239; cf. 127, 198; Athen. xiii. 623 sq. after Chameleon; AElian. V. H. xiv. 23; Basil. De Leg. Graec. libr. Opp. ii. 179 d (Serm. xiii.; Opp. iii. 549 c.); cf. note 3. 5 The two fragments of an ethical character in Stob. Floril. i. 65 sq. are evidently spurious, as may be seen from the mode of ex- pression. So no doubt is the state- ment about the One in Syrian, on Metaph. Schol. in Ar. 927 a, 19 Sqq. A small fragment, which we find in Iambl. Theol. Arithm. 19, bears no definite mark of being spurious; but, on the other hand, its authenticity cannot be demon- strated. Lastly, Plut. Qu. Conv, iii. 6, 3, is a passage of small im- portance, whether genuine or not. * According to I) iodorus, Fragm. p. 554, Wess., Clinias, learning that Prorus had lost his property, journeyed to Cyrene to the relief of this brother Pythagorean, who was personally unknown to him. * What we know of his life is ARCHIVTAS. 367 liutle, however, with certainty concerning his scientific theories; nor can we determine how far a philosophic impulse was connected with this renewed life of the school. Soon after the period of Archytas the Pytha- gorean school, even in Italy, seems to have died out, or at any rate, to have been represented only by some isolated followers. Aristoxenus, at least, speaks of it as an entirely extinct phenomenon," and we have no in- formation from other sources as to the longer continu- ance of the school,” although the knowledge of its doc- trines was not confined to the sages of Greece.” Besides those Pythagoreans we have spoken of, limited to a very few statements. Born in Tarentum (Diog. viii. 79, &c.), a contemporary of Plato and of Dionysius the younger (Aristox ap. Athen. xii. 545 a ; Diog. loc. cit.; Plato, Ep. vii. 338 c), said to be Plato's instructor (Cic. Fin. v. 29, 87; Rep. i. 10; Cato, 12, 41); according to ano- ther equally untrustworthy account (vide supra, 320, 4) his pupil—he was equally great as a statesman (Strabo, vi. 3, 4, p. 280: trpoéotn Tâs tróAews troXèv xpóvov; Athen. loc. cit.; Plut. Praec. Ger. Reip. 28, 5, p. 821; AEI. W. H. iii. 17; Demosth. Amator. vide Supra, p. 320, 4) and as a general (Aristox. ap. Diog. viii. 79, 82, vide Supra, p. 321, 2; AElian, V. H. vii. 14). He distinguished himself in math- ematics, mechanics, and harmony (Diog. viii. 83; Horat. Carm, i. 28; Ptolem. Harm. i. 13; Porph. in Ptol. Harm. 313; Proclus in Euc. 19 [66 Friedl. after Eude- mus]; Apul. Apol. p. 456; Athen. iv. 184 e), of a noble and well balanced character (Cic. Tusc. iv. 36, 78; Plut. Ed. Puer. 14, p. 10; Des. Num. Vind. 5, p. 551; other particulars ap. Athen. xii. 519 b ; AEl. xii. 15; xiv. 19; Diog. 79). His death by drowning is well known from Horace. As to his writings, vide supra, p. 320 sqq., and Part iii. b, 88 sqq., second edition. * Wide supra, p. 364, 4. * For Nearchus the Tarentine, to whom Cato (ap. Cic. Cato, 12, 41) refers the tradition of a discourse of Archytas against pleasure, is probably an imaginary person, and is not even called by Cicero a Py- thagorean. It is Plutarch who, in repeating Cicero's statement (Cato Maj. c. 2) first so describes him. This discourse, the pendant to the hedonistic discourse which Aristo- xenus, ap. Athen. xii. 545 b sqq., puts into the mouth of Polyarchus in the presence of Archytas, no doubt arose, either directly or in- directly, out of this passage of Aris- toxenus. - * Wide infra, Part iii. b, 68 sq., second edition. 368 THE PPTHAGOREAW PHILOSOPHY, many others are named in the confused and ill-arranged catalogue of Iamblichus,' and elsewhere. But several of these names evidently do not belong to the Pytha- goreans at all; others have possibly been introduced by subsequent interpolators; and all are worthless for us, because we know nothing further about the men they designate. There are, however, some few men who are connected with the Pythagorean school, but do not properly belong to it, whom we shall have to notice later on. THE PYTHAGOREAN PHILOSOPHY : ITS FUNDA- NUMBER AND THE ELE- III. MENTAL CONCEPTIONS ; MENTS OF NUMBER, IN order to estimate rightly the philosophy of the Pythagoreans, it is of the highest importance that we should distinguish in their doctrines and institutions that which is philosophical in the narrower sense from that which has arisen from other sources and motives. The Pythagoreans constitute primarily not a scientific, but a moral, religious, and political association; * and though a definite tendency of philosophic thought was developed in this association at an early period, and probably by its very founder, yet its members were not all philosophers, nor were all the doctrines and opinions their enemies. This seems to ex- * Wit. Pyth. 267 sqq. plain, Aristotle's expression, oi 2 Wide supra, 352 sq. The name ‘Pythagoreans’ or ‘Pythagorici’ seems to have been originally, like Cylonists or Orphici, a party de- signation of a political or religious, rather than a philosophical kind, bestowed on them, perhaps, by kaaotuevo IIv6ayópelot (vide supra, p. 307, 2), cf. Dicaearch. ap. Porph. 56 : IIv6ayópelot 6' ékAhômorav ovaraqis #maga i ovvakoxov6#aaaa airró. AWUMBER. 369 which they entertained the result of philosophic enquiry. On the contrary, many of these may have arisen inde- pendently of such enquiry, and may have related to objects with which the Pythagorean philosophy never concerned itself. Although, therefore, in considering these doctrines and opinions, we ought not to lose sight of their possible connection with the purely philosophic doctrines, yet we must not reckon all that is Pythagorean as belonging to the Pythagorean Philo- sophy. As well might we regard all that is Hellenic as Greek philosophy, or all that is to be found among Christia.n peoples as Christian philosophy. We have consequently to enquire in each particular case how far any Pythagorean doctrine is philosophic as to its content, that is, how far it may or may not be ex- plained by the philosophic character of the school. The most generally distinctive doctrine of the Pythagorean philosophy is contained in the proposition that number is the essence of all things, that every- thing, in its essence, is number." How we are to under- * Aristot. Metaph. i. 5: év Šē Tois àpiðuois étafveto Thy pāoriv toūrous kal trpo rotºtov oilcoxoſpevot IIv6ayópelot Táv uaômudºtov &bduevot trpótol ratra trpoſiyayov ſcal évrpa- q’évres év airois rās toūrov &pxès Töv čvarov &px&s ºf 9morav sivat Távrov. čtrel 6& roërwv of &piðuoi ºtſoel Trpiórou, Év roſs &pifluois éöökovv 6ewpeiv Šuotápata troXA& roºs ojos Kai yuyvouévois, uáAAov # év Tupi kal yń kal iſèatu, 3rt to pièv Totovöl rôv àpiðuóv trg60s Sukatooriivn, To 5* rotovë, yuxh kai vois, Érepov *ē kalpos kal Töv &AAwv &s eitreſv exagºrov Šuotws' éri 8& Töv špplovuków év &piðuois àpóvres r& ré0m kal robs A6/ovs, étreið) rā uév šAAa WOL. I. &qoptotôorðal trao av, oi 6 &piðuoi traorms tºis pºorea's trpátov, rö. Töv āpuðuðv ortoixeto, rôv Švtov o'rouxeia travrov eivat 5téA&801, kal Töv ŠAov oùpavöv špuovíav sival ſcal &piðuóv. Cf. ibid. iii. 5, 1002 a, 8: oi uèv troAAo kal of Trpárepov thu oivorſaw kal to 6 v Govt.0 to orópa eival . . . of 6' 50-repov ka? oroq &repot Toºrov elva, 66%avres robs àpiðuoiſs. Cf. the following note. It seems un- necessary to add to these Aristo- telian passages the explanations of later writers, such as Cicero, Acad. ii. 37, 118, Plut. Plac. i. 3, 14, &c. B B 370 THE PYTHIAGOREA.N.S. stand this formula, however, is a point on which our authorities are in appearance not fully agreed. On the one side, Aristotle frequently asserts that, according to the Pythagorean theory, things consist of numbers,' or of the elements of numbers; * that numbers are not merely qualities of a third substance, but immediately, and in themselves, the substance of things; and form the essence of things; yet for that very reason, do not exist apart from things, like the Platonic ideas.” He, therefore, in considering the relation of the Pytha- gorean numbers to his four kinds of causes, places them among the material, as well as the formal causes; for the Pythagoreans, he says, sought in numbers at * Wide previous note, and Me- taph. xiii. 6, 1080 b, 16: kal of IIv6ayópelot 5’ eva. Tov uaômuatukov [äpiðubv] TAhv oi kexaptopičvov, &AA’ &K Tošrov rās aiorémrås oia'tas ovved-raval qaorfu (or, as in 1. 2: às ék Töv Špiðuðv évvirapxóvrov &vra rà airómré). Wgl. c. 8, 1083 b, 11: to 8& rô a 6para é; āpuðuáv eival ovykeſpeva kal Tov àpiðubv roſtov eivat p.a6muatikov ääävaróv čorriv . . . keivot 3& Tov àpiðubv rà èvra Aéryovoivº Tú yotiv 6eophuara trpoor&m touri roſs atºpiaatu às ét éketvov čvrov rôv àpiðuóv. xiv. 3, 1090 a., 20: of 5& IIv6ayó- petol ātā ºrb épév troAA& rôv àpiðuáv Trá0m irdpxovira rols aio.6mroſs ord waoru, elval uév čplēuous érot morav rå Övra, où xopia robs 6*, &AA’ & àpiðuðv rà èvra, whence the cen- sure in 1. 32: trouetv čá čplēuðv rà qvorikā oréuara, ći, Hºi éxávrov Bápos am8& Kovºpórnta éxovta coupôrnta kal Bápos. i. 8,990 b, 21: &piðubv 3’ &AAov um0éva sival trapd Töv &piðubv roorov, & of ovvéotnicev 6 kóguos. * Wide previous note, and Me- taph. i. 5, 987 a, 14: Tooroúrov 8& rpoo’etré0sorav [of IIv6ayópelot] § ical touðv éorriv airóv, 3rt to tremepa- opuévov kal to &reupov kal to evoix érépas rivās ºf 9morav sival pāorets, ofov trip 3) yiv # ri rotodrov repov, &AA’ airb rb &meipov kal airo to èv oãortav eival rotrav &v karmyopodv- rat, Šub kal &piðubveivat thvoirotav âtrávrov. Similarly Phys. iii. 4, 203 a, 3, of the Štreipov alone; Metaph. i. 6, 987 b, 22; iii. 1,996 a, 5; ibid. c. 4, 1001 a, 9; x. 2 init. of the by and the év. * Metaph. i. 5 (vide previous note), c. 6,987 b, 27: 6 uév [IIAá- tov] robs àpiðuois trapá tê airømtā, oi [IIv6ayópelot] 3’ &piðuois sivaí qaqiv air& rà irpáypiata . . . to uèv ošv to $v kai robs &piðuous trapò rô. Trpáyuata trothoral ſcal pººl &otep of IIv6. &c. Aristetle often makes use of the same distinction to dis- criminate the Pythagorean doc- trine from the Platonic; cf. Metaph. xiii. 6 (vide note 1), c. 8, 1083 b, 8; xiv. 3, 1090 a, 20; Phys. iii. 4, 203 a, 3. NUMBER. 371 once the matter and the qualities of things." With this Philolaus in substance agrees; since he not only describes number as the law of the universe, and that which holds it together, the power that rules over gods and men, the condition of all definition and know- ledge,” but he calls the Limit and the Unlimited, which * Metaph. i. 5, 986 a, 15 : qaſvoviral 83 kai of rot Tov &piðubv vopuigovres àpx?iv eival kal és àAmy roſs of art kal &s trä0m Te kal éðels. To this belongs also the passage in 986 b, 6 : éoikaart 6’ &s év šAms etàet 7& a Touxela rărretv' ék rotºrov yap &s évvirapyávrov ouvearáva kal tre- TAda:0at (paal thv oia'tav : whether we refer these words, with Bonitz, in the first instance, to the ten oppositions previously enumerated (vide infra), or directly to the otot- Xeſa toû dpiðuoi (mentioned, 986 a, 17), the Uneven or Limited, and the Even or Unlimited; for the ten opposites are only the ulterior de- velopment of the fundamental opposition of the Limited and Un- limited. Aristotle probably had in his mind the passage from Phi- lolaus, quoted p. 372, 1, as has already been observed, p. 316. * Fr. 18 (Böckh, 139 sqq.) ap. Stob. Ecl. i. 8 : 6eapeſv Šeſ rê špya kal r&v éoaſtav Tó àpt016 ſcattáv 6övauv, &rus évrl év tá Šekdār aeyā- Aa y&p kal travtex?s kai travtoepyös kal 6eta, kai oilpavlo 8to kal div6po- tríva dpx& kal &yepièv . . . &vev 6& Tai'ras travra &melpa kal &ömAa kal dq'avī’ vouk& yöp & piſa is rô &pið- Má, kal &yepovicë, kal Stöaoka Nikā. Tā ātropovuéva, travros kal &yvoov- Mévo travtſ. oë yöp is 872 ov oë9evi où9év táv trpayud row oire airów troð' air& otºre &AAw mor' &AA0, ei ph is àpiðubs kal d rotto èqala: vöv 5& oiros kattøv juxāv špuášov airóñorel trèvra yuwara kai trotáyopa &AAáAous katē Yvágovos pūow (cf. Böckh, l.c.) &tepyáçetal, oroplarów kal oxiſov toos Aóyovs xaphs ékáq- Tovs Tāv trpayuátov táv re &reſpov kal Táv Tepatvövtov. thous āś kai oë Aévvv čv toſs Saipovious kal 6etois trpáygaari Täv Tó &pt016 q &giv ka? Töv Ščvapuv ioxºſovo av, &AA& kal év Toſs &v6pwiriko’s pyous kal Aó)ous träori ird vra kal karð ràs Saulovpyías tàs texvikēs trägas kal karū tav plovaukáv. peočos 6' oi,6&v 6éxetal & Tô &pt046 pāoris oièë Špuovía of ºyap oiretov airo’s évri rās yap âmețpa kal &vohra (-dra) kal &Aérya, qºorios to jedöos kal 6 p.66vos évrí, and similarly afterwards, probably taken from another place, we read, theoãos 3& obôapiás és àpiðuby étruirevº. troAéulov yöp kal éx6pov airá rà ºpioi & 6’ &Ad.6ela oikeſov kal oriuqv- Tov rá rà épiðuó yeyeº. Fr. 2 (Böckh, 58) ap. Stob. i. 456: kai Távra ya Pºv tº yi-yvoorkóueva āpuðubv čxoviri oi yüp 6ttàv offiv re où6èvoire vom6%iaev oire yua orðīuev ãvev toãra. With the above agrees substantially the assertion of Iam- blichus, in Nicom. Arithm. p. 11 (ap. Böckh, p. 137), which is re- peated by Syrian, in Metaph. (Schol. in Ar. 902 a, 29, 912 b, 17): PixéAaos 6é pnow &piðubv éival Täs róv kooplików aiwvías ëlauoviis rhv kpatuatedovoav kal airoyevº avvoxfiv, but these words cannot have occurred in a genuine work of Philolaus. B B 2 372 THE PPTHAGOREA.N.S. are the two constituents of numbers, the things from which all is formed." On the other hand, however, Aristotle likewise says that the Pythagoreans represent things as arising from the imitation of numbers, the manifold similarities of which with things they per- ceived.” In another place he seems to confine the immanence of numbers in things to one portion of the Pythagorean school; * and in later accounts the state- . ment that all things consist of numbers, is opposed by the assertion that things are formed, not out of numbers, but after the pattern of numbers." * Fr. 4, ap. Stob. i. 458 (Böckh, 62): â wºv ša rē [= oiota] révºſpa- ºyuárov &fötos égora kai air& uèv & qºg is 9etav re (Mein. conj. 6éía évt.) ical of k &v6potſvav čvāéxet at yuágiv TAéov (Mein. TAdv) ya, h 8tt oix oiów T’ 7s oi6evl rôv éóvrov kal 'yvyvooricopévov Šd' duðv yuoorðfiaev, ań śrapxoão as airás [ths àpuovías) évros róv trpayuárov č &v čvvéota 6 kóogos róv Te repaivévtwv Ical tăv &reſpov (according to Böckh's cor- rection). Meineke reads uh Ürap- xoto as Tās éarońs róv trpayuárev, and Rothenbücher, System des Pythag. p. 72, founds upon the ab- surdity of this merely conjectural reading, a proof of the unauthen- ticity of the fragment. In the commencement of the fragment the words air& uèv & púa is are not very good sense, and even Mein- eke's amendment, uðva è pilots, does not satisfy me.' I would sooner (as already observed in Hermes, x. 188) discard the uév as a repetition of the words before érra, but it would be better still to read &fötos éoroa kal &el éaouéva qūris: the essence of things, as a nature which is eternal and which We are will always exist, is divine. * Metaph. i. 6, 987 b, 10, con- cerning Plato, thv 5è ué9etty (the participation of things in the Ideas) tośvoua pāvov ueré8a Nev. of uèv yöp IIv6ayópelot uphorel to ëvra (paalu eival rôv &piðuóv, IIA&- Twy Śē ge6éčel rotºvoua ustaðaxóv. Aristoxenus, ap. Stob. i. 16: IIv6a– ºyápas . trāvta rā trpáygara âtrelká(ov roſs &piðuois. Cf. the expressions, Óplot&pata and āqo- plotova 6at in the passage quoted above from Metaph. i. 5, and the àpiðu% 8é te tróvt’ étréolkev, ap. Plut. De An. Procr. 33, 4, p. 1030; Theo. Mus. c. 38; Sext. Math. iv. 2; vii. 94, 109; Iambl. V. Pyth. 162; Themist. Phys. 32 a (220, 22 Sp.); Simpl. De Caºlo, 259 a, 39 (Schol. in Arist. 511 b, 13). * De Caelo, iii. 1 sub. fin. : éviol ºy&p thv púaivé: &piðuóv avvuorrãorty &otrep rôv IIv6aºyopetov rivés. * Theano, ap. Stob. Eel. i. 302: ovXvows uèv ‘EAA#vov tréteigual voutoral pával IIv6ayópav č; āpiðuoi, tróvra púea 6al . . . 6 & [so Hee- ren] oik Šć &ptôuoi, k at & 6, &piðuby ëAeye travta yin/vegéal, etc. The pseudo-Pythagoras is represented NUMBER. 373 also informed that the Pythagoreans distinguished between numbers and the things numbered, and es- pecially between Unity and the One.' From this it has been inferred that they developed their doctrine of numbers in different directions; one division of the school holding numbers to be the inherent ground of things, and another seeing in them merely prototypes.” Aristotle, however, gives no countenance to such a theory. In his work on the heavens, indeed, he is only speaking of a portion of the Pythagoreans when he says they made the world to consist of numbers; but it does not follow that the rest of the school explained the world in a different way. He may very possibly have expressed himself in this manner, because all theories of numbers were not developed into a con- struction of the universe,” or because the name of Pythagoreans denoted others besides the Pythagorean philosophers,” or because he himself had access to the cosmological writings of some only among these philo- koa uotolias and kpurikov koguoup'yo5 6eoû &pyavov. * Moderatus, ap. Stob. Eel. i. 20; Theo. Math. c. 4. Further as saying the same thing in the iepos Aóyos, vide Iambl. in Nicom. Arithm. p. 11, and Syrian in Me- taph. (Schol. in Ar. 902 a, 24), when he describes number as the ruler of forms and ideas, the stan- dard and the artistic faculty by which the Deity created the world, the primitive thought of the Deity. Wide also Hippasus (whose doc- trine on this point is not opposed to that of Pythagoras, as was main- tained after Brandis, in the first edition of this work, i. 100 ; iii. 515; but is treated as a develop- ment of it); ap. Iambl. loc. cit.; Syn. Schol. ºn Ar. 902 a, 31, 912 b, 15; Simpl. Phys. 104 b, when he calls number trapdbevyua Trpátov details later on. * Brandis, Rhein. Mus. v. Nie- buhr wºud Brandis, ii. 21.1 sqq.; Gr. Rom. Phil. i. 441 sqq.; Her- mann, Geschich, und Syst. d. Plat. i. 167 sq., 286 sq. * He does not really say that only a portion of the Pythagoreans made things to consist of numbers, but : éviol thy pija w ść dpiðuðv ovviotăort, or as it stands pre- viously: é; dpiðuáv ovvt10éagi Tov oùpavóv. * Wide supra, p. 369. 374 THE PETHAGOREANS. * & sophers.' But he elsewhere attributes both doctrines— viz., that things consist of numbers, and that they are copied from numbers—to the Pythagoreans generally ; and the two statements appear not in widely separated passages, but in such close juxtaposition, that if they had been in his opinion irreconcilable, their contradic- toriness could not possibly have escaped him. Because the Pythagoreans discovered many similarities between numbers and things, he says (Metaph. i. 5; xiv. 3) they held the elements of numbers to be the elements of things; they perceived in number (he adds in the same chapter) both the matter and the qualities of things; and in the same place that he ascribes to them the doctrine of the imitation of things by numbers, Metaph. i. 6, he asserts that they differed from Plato in considering numbers, not as Plato did the ideas as separate from things, but as the things themselves. From this it is evident that the two statements “num- bers are the substance of things,’ and “numbers are the prototypes of things,’ do not, in Aristotle's opinion, ex- clude one another;” the Pythagoreans, according to his * Aristotle is fond of employ- these words that Aristotle believed ing limitations and guarded ex- pressions. Thus we continually find tows and similar words where he is giving utterance to his most decided opinions (e.g. Metaph. viii. 4, 1044 b, 7); and the same is the case with ēviot, when he says, for instance, De Gen. et Corr. ii. 5 init.: ei ydp &rri rôv puoruków orwudºrov #Am, &orrep kal 60ket évious, iſãop kal &hp kal rô rotavra, or, as in Metaph. i. 1, 981 b, 2 : T 6 v & J & x a v ë v i a roleſv učv, oùk eiðóra Śē roleſv & role. As we cannot infer from some lifeless things to act with consciousness, neither does it fol- low from the passage in De Caelo that some Pythagoreans made the world to consist of something other than numbers. * Thus in Metaph. i. 5 (to which Schwegler in his commen- tary on this passage rightly calls attention), the conception of the Öpiofoua itself is transferred to the corporeal elements, for it is said the Pythagoreans thought they observed in numbers many simi- NUMBER. 375 representation, considered things to be the copies of numbers, for the very reason that numbers are the essence of which things consist, and the properties of which must therefore be cognisable in them. Philolaus places number in this same relation to things when he describes it (loc. cit.) as their law and the cause of their properties and relations; for there is the same relation between law and its fulfilment as between pro- totype and copy. Later writers, indeed, conceive the Pythagorean numbers entirely after the manner of the Platonic ideas—as models external to things. There are traces, however, even among those writers of the contrary opinion.' But we cannot attach much im- portance to the testimony of persons who are evidently unable to distinguish earlier theories from later, or the Pythagorean doctrines from those of the Platonists and Neo-Pythagoreans.” The meaning of the Pythagorean fundamental doc- trime then is this:—All is number, i.e., all consists of numbers; number is not merely the form by which the constitution of things is determined, but also the larities to things, uſixAov h év trup, fi kal 56&ti, and on the other hand, Aristotle (Phys. ii. 3, 194 b, 26) calls the Form which he regards as the immanent essence of things, trapáčelyua. * Theo, for example, loc. cit. p. 27, remarks on the relation of the Monad to the One: ’Apxūras 6& ical pixóAaos &ötapópws to èv kal pováða kań000 i kal Tiv pováða #v. Also Alexander (ad Metaph. i. 5, 985 b, 26, p. 29, 17. Bon.) pre- supposes the same when he says of the Pythagoreans: tow votiv uováða Te kal év čAeyov ; and concerning the Ideas, Stob. Ecl. i. 326, asserts that Pythagoras sought them in numbers and their harmonies, and in geometric proportions, &x&ptota Töv goad tww. * For this reason I consider it unnecessary to discuss the mani- festly incorrect statements of Syrian and Pseudo-Alexander in regard to Metaph. xiii., xiv., which continu- ally confuse the Pythagoreans and Platonists. In Xiii. 1, indeed, they call the theory of Ideas, as well as the Xenocratic distinction of the Mathematical sphere and the Sen- sible, Pythagorean. 376 THE PPTHAGOREA.N.S. substance and the matter of which they consist. It is one of the essential peculiarities of the Pythagorean standpoint that the distinction of form and matter is not as yet recognised. We regard numbers only as an expression for the relation of substances, they directly seek in them the essence and substance of the real. The Pythagoreans (as we are told by Aristotle," and also by Philolaus”) were doubtless led to this theory by perceiving that all phenomena are ordered according to numbers; that especially the relations of the heavenly bodies, and of tones, and, generally speaking, all mathematical conceptions, are governed by certain numbers and numerical proportions. This observation is itself connected with the ancient use of symbolic round numbers, and with the belief in the occult power and significance of particular numbers,” which belief was current among the Greeks as among other nations, and probably existed from the very commencement in \ the Pythagorean mysteries. gave substance to the Idea—as the Eleatics made the But as Plato subsequently real, which was at first conceived as a predicate of all things, the sole and universal substance—so by virtue of the same realism, which was so natural to antiquity, the Pythagoreans regarded mathematical, or more ac- ëurately, arithmetical determinations, not as a form or * Metaph. i. 5, xiv. 3, vide supra, p. 369, 1, 370, 1. * Wide the passages quoted p. 370 sq. Further particulars here- after. ' * In proof of this we need only call to mind the importance of the number seven (so celebrated among the Pythagoreans), especially in the cult of Apollo (vide Preller, Mythol. i. 155); the many triple orders in the mythology — Hesiod's exact prescripts concerning lucky and unlucky days of the year (’Ep. kai jiu, 763 sqq.); Homer's preference for certain numbers, and the like, mentioned in Ps. Plut. V. Hom. 145. NUMBER. 377 a quality of things, but as their whole essence, and without any discrimination or restriction, said gene- rally :-All is number. This is a mode of presentation which sounds strangely enough to us; if, however, we consider how great an impression must have been pro- duced upon the receptive mind by the first perception of a universal, and unalterable mathematical order in phenomena, we shall better understand how number came to be reverenced as the cause of all order and definiteness; as the ground of all knowledge; as the divine power that rules in the world; and how thought accustomed to move, not in the sphere of abstract conceptions, but in that of intuitions, could hypostasise number, as the substance of all things. All numbers are divided into odd and even, to which, as a third class, the even-odd (áptuottéptoratov) is added," and every given number can be resolved either into odd or even elements.” From this the * Philol. Fr. 2. ap. Stob. i. 456, &c. & ya aav ćpt0abs Éxei 350 uév töta etón, Treptororov kal &priov, Tpirov 8è &T' &uſpotépov utx0évrov &ptio- trépio'a ov. čicatépa Sê rô etöeos troNAal pop paí. By the &prioré- purorov we must understand either the One, which was so called by the Pythagoreans (vide infra, p. 379, 1), but which we should scarcely ex- pect to be described as a separate species; or those even numbers, which, when divided by two, give an uneven result. Wide Iambl. in Micom. p. 29 : &priorépugolos 6é éotiv 6 kal airbs uév eis 880 to a kai & ro koivöv 6tapoſuevos, où piévrot ye rà. pépm étu biatpetd. Xov, &AA’ si60s ékárepov treptoroºv So in Nikom. Arithm. Isa.g. i. 9, p. 12; Theo, Math. i., p. 36; cf. Moderatus ap. Stob. i. 22: āorte év tá, 6taipeio 6at 5tza troAAoi Tôv àpríaveis repugolois Thy &váAvoriv Aguſłóvovoruvés à è; ſcal 6éka. This is the true reading. Gaisford would keep Ščicaíðeka, which is against the sense; and Heeren, with whom Meineke agrees, conjectures, not very happily, Ökta- katēeka. * Cf. the words in the passage from Philolaus ap. Stobaeus, l. 456: r& uèv yöp airóv čk trepaivávrov Irepaívovira, rå Ö' éic repaivévrwv te kal &teipov trepaivovird Te kal oi, trepaívovira, to 5 # &reſpov &telpa ‘pavéovrat. Among numbers, of which Philolaus is chiefly thinking, those which result from uneven factors only belong to the first 378 THE PYTHAGOREA.N.S. Pythagoreans concluded that the odd and the even are the universal constituents of numbers, and furthermore, of things. They identified the uneven with the limited, and the even with the unlimited, because the uneven sets a limit to bi-partition, and the even does not." class; those which result from even and uneven factors, to the second ; those which result from even fac- tors only, to the third. * This is the reason given by the Greek commentators of Aris- totle. Simpl. Phys. 105 a oirrot 8è to &repov Töv šptuov dpuðubv ëAeyov, Ště, rb trav pºv šptuov, Šs q'aqu oi éémyntai, eis fora ötaipoºpºe- vov &teipov katē thv 6tzotopfav. # 'yūp eis to a kal jutom blaſpeats tr' &Teipov, to be trepitrov Tposteðev Trepaivet airb, kaoxtet yap airoi, thu sis rô to a 5uaipeou, oito pºv oſſºv of éénymºral (to whom Alexander doubtless belongs). Similarly, Philop. Phys. K. 11, ibid. 12: Tö ačv yöp trepitrov trepatof Kal Öpigel, rö 8& &priov rās étr' &n'eipov Topſis atrióv éa riv, &el Tºv Sixoto- pºſav čexöuevov. Themist. Phys. 32 a, p. 221 Speng. The Pytha- goreans, declare the Šptios àpiðubs only as unlimited: Toorov Yap elval rfis eis rô to a roufis atriov fit is &re pos. Aristotle himself says, Phys. iii. 4, 203 a, 10: oi uºv (the Pythagoreans) to &reupov elval to &priov' rooro yöp ŠvatroAapflavéuevov (the uneven included) trapéxeiv roſs ofort Thu ärelpíav. This, indeed, asserts that the even must be the eause of unlimitedness, but not why it should be so ; nor do we gather this from the additional words, onjuelov 8 elva toûrov to ovußaïvov trl rôv àpiðuðv' reputi- Beuévav yūp rôv yvouðvøv repl rô Thus they arrived at the proposition that ev kal xopis 6th pºp &AAo yiver6al To eiðos, Ště 8& év. These words were explained by the Greek com- mentators (Alex, ap. Simpl. 105 b, Schol. 362 a, 30 sqq. and Sim- plicius himself; Themist. loc. cit. Philop. K. 13) unanimously as follows: A gnomon is a number which, being added to a square, gives another square; and as this is a property of all uneven num- bers (for 1* + 3 = 2*, 2* + 5 = 3% 3°4-7 = 4” and so on) such num- bers (as Simpl. 105 a, Philop. K. 13, expressly assert) were called by the Pythagoreans 'yváuoves. By the addition of odd numbers to one, we get only Square numbers (1 + 3 = 2*; 1 + 3 + 5 = 3° and so on), and therefore numbers of one kind; whereas in any other way— whether by adding together odd and even numbers (so Philop. says), or by adding even numbers only to the one (so say Alexan- der, Simplicius, and Themist.), we obtain numbers of the most diffe- rent sorts, étépouſinesis, tpſyovot, étr+dºyovoi, &c., and consequently an unlimited plurality of etón. This interpretation seems to me preferable to those of Röth, loc. cit. and Prantl (Arist. Phys. 489). To bring them into harmony with the text of Aristotle was a difficulty, even to the old commentators. The most probable supposition appears to be that the words, which are obscure, from the excessive con- I, IMITED AND UNLIMITED. 379 all consists of the Limited and the Unlimited." ciseness of kal xopls, mean this: that if on the one hand the yuáploves be added to the one, there arises one and the same kind of numbers, but if, on the other hand, the other numbers, without the yuáploves, different kinds. So that kai xopls would signify: kal trepitiéepwévov rów Śpiðuðv xopls róv yuapévov. * Arist. Metaph. i. 5, 986 a, 17: roi, 5è &piðuoß [vouſ ſovoſil orrotxeſ a ré te àptuov kai to trepit- tov, rottov Šč to uév tretrepaopiévov To 5& Wirelpov, to 5’ ev ć; áuporépov eival rotºrov (kal yèp &priov sival kai trepitrov), Tov 6’ &piðubv ék too évös, Öp'9Movs 6*, ka0&mep eſpntal, tov ŠAov otpavév. Philol. Fr. 1, ap. Stob. i. 454 : āvāyka rà éóvra eluev Trävra h repaívovira 3 &trelpa, # Trepatvovrd Te kal &telpa. This is probably the commencement of his work, succeeded by the proof of this theorem, of which the follow- ing words only have been preserved by Stobaeus, &telpa Sê uóvov oir àel [of ka eſſm Mein.], and these in ad- dition by Iambl. in Nicom. 7, and in Willoison, Anecd. ii. 196: āpx&v 7&p oë6è to yuaoroúaevov ča orefrai Trávrov &reſpov čávrov, vide Böckh, p. 47 sqq. Schaarschmidt, on the other hand (Schrift. des Philol. 61), reproduces the text of Stobaeus without any mention of the lacunae in it; and Rothenbücher, Syst. d. Pyth. 68, makes objections to this text, which immediately disappear upon a right apprehension of what Philolaus really said : étrel rotuvv qatveral otºr' k repaivávrov travrov éávra oër’ é; direţpov tróvrov, 67,261, t’ &pa Śri ék repaivávrov Te Kal direpov 8 re kóguos kal rà év airó ovvapuðx0m. SmNo. 68 kal tº €v roſs &pyois. Tô Hévºyāp, etc., vide previous note; cf. Plato, Phileb. 16, C : of uév With traxalol, Kpeſtroves huôv kal éyyu- Tépa 6eóv oikoúvres, raûrmy påumv trapéðoorav, &s é; Évös pºv kal ék troAAóv čvrov táv čel Aeyouévalv elval, Trépas 6* ſcal &tepfav čv éauro's §§uſpvrov čxóvrov. Ibid. 23. C: Töv Bebu èAéyouév trov to uév &teipov ãeſ;at rôv Švrov, to 8& répas. The latter is also called, 23 E, and 26 B, trépas àxov; and the different kinds of the Limited are (p. 25 D), included under the name trepa- Toetóēs. Aristotle, like Plato (Me- taph. i. 8, 990 a, 8 ; xiv. 3, 1091 a, 18), has trépas for what he had called, Metaph. i. 5, retrapaopºvov. There is, in fact, no difference be- tween these various appellations; they are all intended to denote the idea of Limitation, which, how- ever, as a rule, is apprebended, after the manner of the ancients, as concrete, and might be expres- sed either actively or passively, either as Limiting or Limited, for that which limits another by its admixture with it must in itself be something Limited (cf. Plato, Tim. 35 A, where the indivisible substance as such is the binding and limiting principle). Ritter's observations, impugning the au- thenticity of Aristotle's expressions (Pyth. Phil. 116 sqq.), are, there- fore, hardly well founded. Nor is it of any consequence that in the above quotation sometimes num- bers, sometimes the constituents of number (the Limited and Unlim- ted), and sometimes (as we shall see further on) the unity of these elements, Harmony, are mentioned as the ground and substance of things; for if all things consist of numbers, all things must necessa- rily be composed of the universal elements of number—the Limited 380 THE PPTHAGO REANS. this proposition is connected the following observation: that everything unites in itself opposite characteristics. These characteristics they tried to reduce to the funda- mental opposition of the limited and the unlimited, odd and even. The limited and the uneven was held, however, by the Pythagoreans, in agreement with the popular belief, as the better and more perfect, the un- limited and the even as the imperfect." Wherever, therefore, they perceived opposite qualities, they re- garded the better as limited or uneven, and the worse as unlimited and even. Thus, according to them, all things were divided into two categories, of which one was on the side of the limited, and the other on that of the unlimited.” The number of these categories was then more precisely fixed by the sacred number ten, and Unlimited; and as these ele- ments only constitute number in their harmonic combination, all things are likewise Harmony, cf. p. 369, 1; 370, 2; 384, 1. Lastly, if Böckh (Philol. 56 sq.) objects to the exposition of Aris- totle that odd and even num- bers must not be confounded with the Unlimited and the Limited, because being determined they all participate in Unity and are limi- ted; and Brandis, on the other hand, conjectures (i. 452) that the Pythagoreans sought for the Limi- ting principle in uneven numbers, or gnomic numbers (which are also uneven numbers) or in the decad, we may reply that the Even and the Odd are not the same as odd and even number; the latter is ne- cessarily and always determinate; the former are constituents of all numbers, whether even or odd, and so far are identical with the Limi- ted and Unlimited. * Wide next note, and Arist. Eth. N. ii. 5, 1106 b, 29: To Y&p trakov rod & reſpov, Ös of IIv6ayópelot ełkaſov, to 6’ &ya6öv too retrepa- opiévov. It will be shown further on that among the Greeks and Ro- mans odd numbers were considered more lucky than even. * Arist. Eth. N. i. 4, 1096 b, 5: Tribavòrepov 3’ &oticaa'iy of IIv6a- 'yópelot Aéyely trepi airoß [toi, Évös], tuffévres év tá ràv &ya6&w orvoroux{g to Év. Metaph. xiv. 6, 1093 b, 11 (on Pythagoreans and Academics with Pythagorean tendencies): ékelvo uévrol totation pavepov, 3rt to eč Štrápxel Ical rās a voºrouxias Čori Tâs toū ka?.00 rb trepittöv, to eißt, to torov, ai Övváuels ēvíov &piðuðv, not to mention later writers, such as Ps. Plut. V. Hom. 145. TABLE OF OPPOSITES. 381 and the ten fundamental oppositions were as follows:– 1. Limited and Unlimited ; 2. Odd and Even ; 3. One and Many; 4. Right and Left ; 5. Masculine and Feminine ; 6. Rest and Motion ; 7. Straight and Crooked ; 8. Light and Darkness; 9. Good and Evil; 10. Square and Oblong." It is true that this classi- fication belongs only to a portion of the Pythagoreans, who were probably later members of the school; ” but * Arist. Metaph. i. 5, 986 a, 22 (directly after the quotation on p. 379, 1): érepot 8& rôv airów roßtov rås &pxàs 5éka Aéyovoſiv sivat rās karð ovarotxſav (in two series di- rectly opposed to one another, the Good and the Evil) Aeyouévas, Trépas kal &meipov, trepºrtöv kai &ptuou, ev kal TA700s, Sešibv Kal āplatepov, §§§ev kal 07Av, hpspotiv kal cuotaevov, eiði kal KaputröAov, q6s kal orkóros, &ya.6bvical kakov, Te- Tpdywvov kal étépôumices. That the Pythagoreans derived motion from the Unlimited is also asserted by Eudemus, ap. Simpl. Phys. 98 b : IIA&rov 8& To uéya kal to utkpov kal to whbv kal To &vápaxov Kal ãora roſtols étri Tairo (pépet rhy kivma w Aéyet . . . 8éArtov Šē ałria [sc. rās Kivägeøs] Aéyetv Tatra ão Trep Apxötas, kai per’ 6Afyov to 6 &óptorrów, pngi, kaaés étri Thy kivmarty of IIv6ayópelot kal 6 IIA drov étudépova'u, &c. Brandis (i. 451; Rhein. Mus. ii. 221) concludes from this passage that Archytas referred motion to the Limiting; but he is deceived by the expression, airtov, which, in any case, should be com- pleted by rās kivhaews, even if we adopt his reading, airtov Aéyetv &otrep ’Apxöras. (In the Gesch, der Entw. der Griech. Phil. i. 169, he has modified his view of this passage. He must, however, have somewhat forgotten his previous utterances, for he says: ‘That Archytas referred motion to the Unlimited I still maintain, in spite of Zeller's objection.") This derivation of motion we also find in Arist. Phys. iii. 2, 201 b, 20 : éviol étépôtmta Kal &viorátmra kal to uh bv ºpdorkovtes eival thy kivmoriv, which Simpl. Phys. 98 a, b, and Philop. Phys. i. 16, connect with the Pythagoreans, and Plato agrees with them, cf. Part ii. a, 808, 1. There is all the less reason to con- test the assertion of Eudemus (with Chaignet, v. 146), since, ac- cording to Alcmaeon, the gods and the stars are always moving (vide infra), and the soul, too, is in con- stant motion. The ceaselessness of this motion, the fact that, as Alcmaeon says, it connects the be- ginning with the end, might be con- sidered a perfection, even though motion itself were an imperfection; it shows that the heavenly bodies themselves consist of the Limiting and Unlimited. Röth's statement (Philol. Fragm., trepi iluxās, 21) that in the table of the ten oppo- sites it is only motion externally produced, which is placed on the side of the &meipov, is entirely groundless. * Chaignet ii. 50 sq. Questions this, because, according to Aristo- 382 THE PPTHAGOREA.N.S. it was universally admitted both by earlier and later Pythagoreans that things are compounded out of opposing elements; and ultimately, out of the odd and the even, or the limited and the unlimited; and there- fore they must all have reduced the given phenomena to these and similar opposites." tle (vide infra $vii.) Alcmaeon had already admitted the ten opposi- tions, “tels que mous venoms de les eaposer.' But Aristotle asserts, as is quite obvious, not that Alcmaeon admitted the ten opposites, but that, in agreement with the Pytha- goreans, he assumed human life to be ruled by oppositions; which, however, he did not like them re- duce to fixed and definite cate- gories. Aristotle, in short, asserts pretty nearly the contrary of what Chaignet finds in him. ' Wide sup. p. 378 sq. Brandis thinks he discovers in this a trace of a different manner of conceiving the Pythagorean philosophy(Rhein. Mus. ii. 214, 239 sqq.; Gr. rom. Phil. i. 445, 502 sqq.). All, how- ever, that can be inferred from the words of Aristotle is this: that all the Pythagoreans did not hold the decuple table of oppositions, but some of them held only the funda- mental opposition of the Odd or the Limited, and the Even and the Unlimited. This does not exclude the possibility that these latter Bythagoreans may have applied that fundamental opposition to the explanation of phenomena, and may have reduced to it the oppo- sites which they observed in things. Such attempts, indeed, were so directly necessitated by the gene- ral theory of the school that things are a combination of the Limited and the Unlimited, the Odd and The drawing up of a the Even, that we can hardly con- ceive of the one without the other. How could this doctrine of the Pythagoreans ever have arisen, and what importance would it have had for them had it not been ap- plied to concrete phenomena? Granting that Aristotle may, per- haps, in the passages cited from the Nicomachaean Ethics, have had primarily in view the table of the ten opposites; granting that less stress is to be laid on Metaph. xiv. 6, because this passage does not relate merely to the Pythagoreans: granting that the slight difference to be found in the enumeration in Plutarch (1)e Is. c. 48) is to be regarded as unimportant, and that the septuple table of Eu- dorus (ap. Simpl. Phys. 39 a ; vide infra, p. 388, 1) as well as the triple table, Diog. viii. 26, prove little, because these writers evidently mix up later doctrines; granting that, for the same reason, we cannot attach much weight to the text of Ps. Alex. in Metaph. xii. 6, 668, 16; and lastly, that the different arrangement of the seve- ral members in Simpl. Phys. 98 a, and Themist. Phys. 30 b, 216, is immaterial to the present question; yet it lies in the nature of things that even those who had not the decuple table, must have applied and developed the doctrine of op- posites; not, indeed, according to that fixed scheme, but in a freer TABLE OF OPPOSITES. 383 table of such opposites was nothing more than a formal development; for the comprehension of the fundamental doctrines of Pythagoreanism this table is of the less importance, since in it the separate numbers are not the result of any deduction according to a definite principle, but out of all the opposites that are given to us empirically, certain of the most prominent," chosen in a somewhat arbitrary manner, are enumerated, until the number ten is complete. So also the apportion- ment of the particular concepts to the several series is to a great extent arbitrary, although generally speaking we cannot mistake the leading point of view, which consists in an attempt to assign the uniform, the perfect, the self-completed, to the Limited; and the opposite categories of these, to the Unlimited. According to this theory the primary constituents of things are of a dissimilar and opposite nature; a bond was therefore necessary to unite them, and cause manner. That other oppositions, p. 288 (and similarly De Ei. ap. D. besides the ten, were observed is clear from Aristotle, ap. Simpl. De Coelo, 173 a, 11 ; Schol. in Arist. 492 a, 24, rb of v Šešlov kal &va, kal épurpoo'6ev &yaôov ékáNovv, to 8& &ptorrepov Ical kāta, kal &mid-6ev kakov ëAeyov, &s airbs 'Aptorroréams iotó- pmarev čv rà rôv IIv0ayopetous (for which Karsten, clearly unjustifi- ably, reads, IIv6ayópg), &peakóvrov oruvayooyń. The prohibition of placing the left thigh over the right (Plut. De Vit. pud. 8, p. 532) is connected with the preference of right and left. * As may easily be shown, even irrespectively of the reasons for which, e.g. Plutarch, Qu. rom. 102, c. 8, p. 388) derives the comparison of the uneven with the male, and the even with the female, yóvipos 'ydp &ott [6 repurrës àpiðubs] kal kpateſ roß &priov ovvribéuevos, kal 6taipovuévov eis rās uováðas, 6 uév &ptios, ka9árep to 0.7xv, x&pav uetašū keväv évötöwori, too 8& repur- toū uðptov &et tº Taipes àtroAetre- Tat. It is said that Pythagoras designated odd numbers, and espe- cially the Monad, as male; and even numbers, especially the Dyad, as female, vide Ps. Plut. V. Hom. 145; Hippol. Refut. vi. 23, i. 2, p. 10; Alex. ad. Metaph. i. 5, 29, 13; Bon. Schol. 540 b, 15; Philop. Phys. K. ii. cf. Sext. Matt. v. 8. 384 THE PPTHAGOREANS, them to be productive. This bond of the elements is harmony, which is defined by Philolaus as the unity of the manifold, and the accord of the discordant.” As therefore the opposition of the elements is present in all things, so must harmony be present likewise; and it may with equal propriety be said that all is number and that all is harmony,” for every number is a definite union, or a harmony of the odd and the even. But, as with the Pythagoreans, the perception of the inherent contradictions in things primarily connects itself with the idea of number, so the recognition of the harmony which reconciles these contradictions is connected with the idea of musical relations; harmony as conceived by Philol. ap. Stob. i. 460, in continuation of the passage quoted supra, p. 372, 1 : étrel Šá te àpxal iträpxov oëx époſal oiâ’ 6p16¢vNot #aaat, #87 &öövarov is &v kal airtats Kogunghuev, eigh #puovía éreyévero, Grivi &v rpétrº èyévero. Tà uèv čv Öuola kal 6164 vºla Špplovías oë6èv éteåéovro to 8& divouala wºměč ăuáq.vxa umbè io'otex?) diváyka ºrë. Towaira àpuovíg ovykelcNeto 6al, ei puéAAovti év köopaq, karéxea 6&t. The proposition that contraries only, and not similar things, require Harmony is thought so strange by Rothenbücher (Syst, d. Pyth. 73) that it seems to him a decided argument against the authenticity of the fragment. But this singu- larity only arises because Rothen- bücher, manifestly against the opinion of the author, substitutes the repaivovira for the Šuota, and the Štreipa for the divápola. For the rest, not only do Heracleitus (vide infra) and others, following him, maintain that every Harmony presupposes an Ópposite, but Aristotle (De An. i. 4) himself quotes the theory that the soul is a harmony, kal yèp thv špuovíav kpāoriv Rai o ºv6eorw évava toy eival (just so Philolaus, vide following note), kal Tö orópa ovykeſorðat é; évavtſov, and Plato puts the same into the mouth of a pupil of Philo- laus (Phaedo, 86 B). * Nicom. Arithm. p. 59 (Böckh, Philol. 61) śati yüp &pwovía troAvut- 'yáov čva'a is kal 6txà qpovsövtwy a ſuppaais. This definition is often quoted as Pythagorean, vide Ast. ân hoc loc. p. 299. Böckh ascribes it to Philolaus, with probability, on the strength of the above pas- Sage. * Arist. Metaph. i. 5: Töv 3Aov oùpavöv špproviav eival kai dpiðuáv. Cf. Strabo x. 3, 10, p. 468 Cas. : Movorukhv čkáAege IIAárov kal ºri Tpôtepov oi IIv6ayópelot Thy pixogo- ‘ptav, kal ka? §puovíav toy káguov ovvertéval pagi. Athen. xiii. 632 b : IIv6ayápas . . . kal r}v toº travros ojoſav Ště uovo.ucijs dro- qaivet ovyketplévmv. FIARMONY. 385 them is nothing else than the octave," the relations of which therefore Philolaus proceeds at once to expound, when he wishes to describe the essential nature of har- mony.” Strange as this may seem to us, it was natural enough to those who were not as yet accustomed to distinguish definitely general concepts from the par- ticular phenomena, through which they arrived at the perception of these concepts. the Pythagoreans recognise the general law of the union—T In the concord of tones of opposites: they therefore call every such combination harmony (as Heracleitus and Empedocles likewise do),” * “Appovía is the name for the octave, cf. e.g. Aristox. Mus. ii. 36: Tóv étr+axépôov & KáAovu āpuovías. Nikom. Harm. Introd. i. 16: of traXauðrato. . . . &puovtav pºv kaxoovres thv Ště, traordov, etc. * Ap. Stobaeus, i. 462 (Nicom. Harm. i. 17); he thus continues, immediately after the passage just quoted: āpuovías Sè uéyeffés évri ovXAabà (the fourth) kal 6t’ 6éetáv (the fifth) to 3& St &etáv uéſſov Tás orvXXabás étroyöóg (a tone = 8 : 9) āori yip &mö itáras €s uégav ovXAağä, äiro Sé pléo as troti vedraw 6t' 3&etav, &to 8& vedras €s Tpitav ovXXağä, ärö 8& Tpitas €s Örd raw 6, 6&etav' to 8° àv uéorg wea as ical rpíras &mdyöoov' & Sé auxA28& émírpurov, rö 5& 6t’ 6éetáv hutóXtov: To Stå traorév 8& Sutrāčov (the fourth = 3: 4, the fifth = 2: 3, the oc- tave = 2: 4). oitas Špuovía trévre £iró'yöoa kal 6üo Stéories, 6t' àáetáv Šē Tpſ &mdyö0a kai 5teoris. auxAagö, Öé 36' tróvãoa kal 8teats (the lesser semi-tone called afterwards Aetupua = 243: 256). An explanation of this passage is given by Böckh, Philol. 65–89, and after him, by Brandis, i. 456 sqq. Perhaps the WOL. I. passage in Sextus, Math. iv. 6, may also refer to it; this passage like- wise correctly explains the mean- ing of Harmony: Ös y&p top 3Aov káguov karū āpuovíav Aéyovo. 510t- keto 6at, oùra kal Tô (gov puxodoréal. ãoice? §§ 7, TéAetos dpuovía év rpial ovudovías Aageſv thu ºróa Taoiv, Tà re 61& Tetrópov kal tº 61& Trévre kal Tā ātā traordºv. As to the har- monic system, vide infra. * Bockh, Philol. 65, has rather a different interpretation of this. He says: “Unity is the Limit, but the Unlimited is indefinite Duality, which becomes definite Duality since twice the measure of Unity is included in it; Limitation is, therefore, given through the deter- mination of Duality by means of Unity; that is, by fixing the pro- portion, 1 : 2, which is the mathe- matical proportion of the Octave. The Octave is, therefore, Harmony itself, through which the opposite primitive causes were united.’ What prevents me from adopting this ingenious view is my inability absolutely to identify the Limit and Unlimited with Unity and Duality. C C 386 THE PXTHAGOREA.N.S. and transfer to it the relations of musical harmony, which they were the first to determine." * Before we go further, however, it seems necessary to examine some different opinions concerning the Pythagorean doctrine of first principles; opinions founded partly on the statements of ancient authors, and partly on the conjectures of modern scholars. Ac- cording to our exposition so far, the Pythagorean system started from the proposition that all is, in its essence, number. From this results the doctrine of the primi- tive opposites; and consequently, the opposition of the crooked and the straight, the limited and the unlimited precede all others. The unity likewise of these oppo- sites was sought in number alone, which was therefore defined more particularly as harmony. Many of our authorities, however, represent the matter differently. They assert that the entire system was founded on the opposition of unity and duality, which is then reduced to the opposition of spiritual and corporeal, of form and substance, of the Deity and matter, and is itself derived from the Deity as the original Unity. According to another theory, the starting point of the system was not the arithmetical conception of number and its constitu- ents, but the geometrical conception of the limits of space and of unlimited space. A third opinion bases the system not on the consideration of number, but on the distinction of the limited and unlimited. We have now to enquire how much in all this is in accordance with historical evidence and internal probability. The first of the above-mentioned theories is found * Further details hereafter, UNITY AND DUALITY. 387 two principles. soon after the commencement of the first century be- fore Christ in Alexander Polyhistor. The Pythagoreans, he tells us, appealing to statements of the Pythagoreans, regarded Unity as the beginning of all things; from Unity arose indefinite Duality, which was related to Unity as matter to the efficient cause; from Unity and Duality sprang numbers, and from numbers, points, &c." This view is developed in the extensive excerpts in Sextus” from a Pythagorean work. According to it, the Pythagoreans, in a full discussion of the subject, maintained that the causes of sensible phenomena can lie neither in what is sensibly perceptible, nor in any- thing corporeal, nor even in mathematical figures, but only in Unity and indeterminate Duality, and that all logical categories are in the end reducible to these They, therefore, regarded Unity as efficient cause, and Duality as passive matter, and sup- posed not merely numbers, but also figures, bodies, elements, and the world itself, to originate from the co-operation of the two principles.” These principles i Diog. viii. 24 sq.; pmol 5’ 6 x. 249–284; vii. 94, 109. It is 'AAé$ov8pos év rais Töv pixogóqov §taSox.aſs, kal ratra sipmkéval év IIv0ayopticots intouviuagiv. &px?iv pºv dirávrov wováða' ék 8& Tās pová60s &óptorov čváča às &v ŠAmy rfi powdāl airíq àvri Štrootival ékóē tis Mová60s kai rās &oplarov čvá60s rows &piðuois &Köètóvãpiðuðv rô a mueta, etc. In the same sense the mythical Zaratas, the instructor of Pythago- ras, ap. Plut. Procr. An. 2, 2, p. 1012, called the One the father, and indeterminate Duality the mother of numbers, cf. p. 389, 3. .* Pyrrh. iii. 152–157; Math. evident that these three texts are based upon the same work. * Cf. Math. x. 261 : 6 IIv0ayópas àpx?iv čq morev eival rôv Švrov rhy wováða, fis katē we'roxhy cagºrov Töv Švrov čv Aéyéral, kal ºrgårmy kat' airótmta uév Šavrijs voovuévnv pováða voeſorbal, étriovvrefleforay 3’ éavrfi ka9 repôtmta ätroteAeſv rhy kańovuévnv &dplatov Švaña, etc. Section 276: éé &v yivea'6aſ page té tº év roſs àpiðuois Év Kal rhv ćirl Totrous trixiv čváða, &mb uév rºs trpárms uova 60s to èv, &to 5& rºls Mováàos kal ris àopfotov Svá60s rê. % c c 2 388 THE PPTHAGOREA.N.S. receive a further interpretation from the Neo-Pytha- goreans and Neo-Platonists. The Pythagoreans, says Eudorus," reduced all things ultimately to the One, by which they understood nothing else than the highest Deity; they derived from this two principles, the One and indefinite Duality, God and matter; under the former they classed everything that is good, under the latter everything evil. Consequently they used various names to designate these principles. The One they called the uneven, the masculine, the ordered. That which is opposed to unity they called the even, the feminine, the unordered, &c. Inasmuch, however, as this second element is derived from the One, the One alone is to be regarded as first principle in the true sense of the word. Similarly, Moderatus” asserts that 380° 5's yap to £v Ščo . . . katē. Tajra (l. Tairã) 58 kal of Aoitrol &piðwo ºr roßrov &terexévông av, toū uév čvös àel trepitratobvros, Tās 8& &optotov Švá60s 500 yewv&oms kai eis &teupov traj00s robs &pt011obs ékreivočams. 36ev paolv čvtats &pxats raúrats rov plºv rod Spövtos airtov Aó)ov ćiréxeuv Thy uovdāa, Tov 6* Tâs traoxotions iſans thv čváða. Wide ibid. on the formation of figures and things from numbers. ! Simpl. Phys. 39 a ypáqel 8& repl rotºrov 6 Eööwpos Táče karð. Töv &vard to A6'yov patéov rows IIv0ayopticobs to èv &pxhv Tóu trèv- Tov Aéyev, karð 8& Töv Šećrepov A6) ov Şū0 åpx&s róv &roteAovuévov eival, ré reev kal thv čvavríavtotrºp qūgiv, Širotégorea'6al 8è travrov ráv karð evavrfoortvérivoovuévov to uév &a reſov rá, évl rô 6è qauāov rā trpos roºro èvavriovuévn pàorei: 5ub uměč eival to advoxov tatras &px&s karð. Toys &vãoas' ei yöp # pºv rôvöe, # ôé Tó, vöe éotiv &px?) oil, eial koual Trávrov &pxal &a trep to Év. kai trčAuv. 616, pnoſi, kal karū āAAov rpátov &px?iv čqaorav Tów Trévrov to èv čás &v kal Täs iſans ical rôv čvrov tróvitov €è airo5 yeyevmuévov, Tooro Sé eival Töv Útrepāva 6eóv . . . p.mu) roſvvy Tovs trepi Tov IIv6ayópav to uév čv trövtov &px?iv &m oxitreſv kar’ &AAov 8è rpátov Ščo Tö, ävoráto grouxeia trapeuodyeiv, kaxeſv Šē rô São Taijra oTouxeta troNAats trpoo`myopiais: rö pºv Yap airóv Švouáçeoréat retayué- vov, &piouévov, Yvoortov, &jev, reputröv, Šešlov, pós, rö 8& évavtſov Tottº &rakrov etc. &orre &s wel &px?) To #v Ös 6* or rouxeta to #v ka # &óplotos Svěs àpxal, Šuqa, §v čvre tröAlv, kal 67&ov 3rt &AAo uév éat, év # 3pxh rôv rávrov, &AAo 8& #1 to thºváài èvruceiuevovt. Kai uováčo ka?\ovoiv. * Porph. Vita Pythag. 48 sqq. UNITY AND DUALITY. 389 the Pythagoreans briefly designated by the One the rela- tion of unity, identity and equality, the ground of all concord and of all fixed consistency; and by duality, the principle of all multiplicity, inequality, division, and change. In agreement with this, we read in the Plutarchic Placita” that of the two principles of Pytha- goras, Unity denoted the good, reason, or deity; and indefinite Duality, evil, matter, and the daemons. Of these two writers, the former only is at the pains to tell us that the doctrines he ascribes to the Pythago- reams were not stated by them in so many words, but are merely hinted at in their number-theory. Other writers of later times express themselves to the same effect.” | Porphyry says himself, sec- tion 38 : ékáAel yèp Töv &vruketº- vav čvváueov thv učv Bext{ova pováša kal pås kal 6eśtov Ical foov kal uévov kal eiðv, thv 5è xeipova 8vdāa kal orcótos ſcal épio'repov ſcal repubépès kal pepôuevov. * i. 3, 14 sq. (Stob. i. 300): IIv- 6ayápas . . . &pxès toūs dpiðuois . . . TrčAlv 5& Thu uováða kai thu dépuatov $váða év rais &pxaſs. ortreč6el 5’ attø Töv dpxöv iſ uév étrº to troumtiköv ałrtov kal eiðuköv, Štrep earl vows, 6 9ebs, # 3’ et) to tra6m Tuköv kal 5Auköv, ãortrep early 6 Špatós Káguos. i. 7, 14 (Stob. i. 58; Eus. Pr. Ev. xiv. 15, 6; Galen. c. 8, p. 251): IIv0a- ºyápas Tāv àpxöv thu uév uováða 6eov (so Hippolyt. Refut. i. 2, p. 8; Epiph. Erp. Fid. p. 1087, A) kal Tâya.00w, # rus égriv h Toà évès qāorts, airós 6 vows thv 5 déptorov ãvá6a Satuova kal rô Kakov, trepi àu garri ºrb 5Atköv TA760s, ott öé kai à éparös käquos. * Cf. the Pseudo-Plutarch (per- haps Porphyry) . Vita Homeri, 145, according to whom Pythagoras trávra eis &piðuois &vaq’épov . . . 8to tés àvord to 3px3s éAáušave, thv učv &ptopičvmu uováða, thv 3& &6- plotov 8vdāa kaaßv. Tºv učv dya%w, thvöé calcóvoúa'av 3pxiv, because, as is afterwards explained, everything good is ovuſpovías oikeſov, and everything evil arises from discord and strife. Hippol. Refut. vi. 23: IIv0. Toivuv dipx?iv Tóv ŠAwy &yev- vmtov &reqfivato rºw wováða, yew- vmthv 5è thv Švdāa kal ºrdvras toūs ūAAous épiðuois. Hai Tàs uév ðváðos trarépa pnolv eival rhy uováða, travtov Šē Töv yeyvouévov untépa Śváða, Yevvmthu Yeuvnróv. His teacher, Zaratas, also called Unity, Father, and Duality, Mo- ther; cf. p. 387, 1 ; Ps. Justin. Cohort. 19 (cf. ch. 4): thv yöp uováða āpx?iv &trövtwv Aéyav (sc. IIv6ay.) kal Tairmv Tów &ya66v dirávrov airíav elval, 5t' GAA myopias āva Te kal uávov Stöðakel 9eov eival; Syrian, ad. Metaph. Sohol. in Arist. 842 a, 8; cf. 931 a, 5:-Most of the hagoreans call the cause of all things the Monad and the Dy- 390 THE PIPTHAGOREANS, The pseudo-Archytas' differs only from this interpre- tation in making the distinction more prominent between the primitive essence and the two derived principles, and in apprehending the latter not in the Pythagorean, but in the Aristotelian form. He indi- cates as the most universal principles, form and matter; form corresponds to the regulated and determinate, and matter to the unregulated and indeterminate; form is a beneficent, and matter a destructive nature ; but he discriminates both from the Deity, which, stand- ing above them, moves matter towards form, and moulds it artistically. Lastly, numbers and geometrical figures are here represented, after the manner of Plato; as the intermediate link between form and matter. ad; Pythagoras himself in the ispos A6)0s calls it Proteus (from Trpátos) and the Dyad or Chaos. Other Pseudo-Pythagorean fragments, of which the contents are similar, are given in Part iii. b, 99, second edition. * In the fragment quoted, ap. Stobaeum, i. 710 sq. The spurious- ness of this fragment has been ex- haustively shown by Ritter (Pythag. Philos. 67 sq.; Gesch. der Phil. i. 377 sq.) and by Hartenstein (De Arch. Fragm. 9 sqq.). The only fault of the latter is his attempt to save a portion of the fragment. Petersen's remarks (Zeitschrift jºir Alterthumsw. 1836, 873 sqq.) contain nothing weighty enough to contravene this judgment, in which Hermann (Plat. Phil. i. 291)rightly concurs, The Aristotelian and IPlatonic element in the thoughts and expressions is so evident that any further demonstration seems superfluous; and even the influence * It of Stoicism is betrayed in the identification of iſam and oivoría, which is never met with in the earlier philosophers. Even if Pe- tersen could succeed in tracing a part of the questionable termino- logy in Arist. Metaph. viii. 2, 1043 a, 21, to Archytas (which is impos- sible if we duly distinguish in this passage Aristotle's own comments from his quotations of Archytas); even if Petersen's conjecture were well founded that the fragments in Stobaeus are taken from Aristotle's excerpts from Archytas (although the Doric dialect still appears in them), there would still be grave reason to doubt the authenticity of the passage. Archytas did not separate the motive cause from the elements of number, as Her- mann well observes, in citing a text (vide supra, p. 381, 1), according to which that philosopher character- ised inequality and indeterminate- mess as the cause of motion, GOD AND MATTER. 39] is affirmed in more than one place' that the Pytha- goreans exalted the Deity above the opposition of principles, and derived the principles from Deity. Unity as Deity, and antecedent to this opposition, was called the One. Unity as opposed to duality, and as a member of the opposition, was called the Monad.” Syrian in Met. Schol. 927 a, 19: §§tov Šil totrous à Tê KAeuvíov Too IIv6ayopetov trapabáAAelv, . . #vika &v airò [to èv] aspuévov &px&v eival Tóv čvtov Aéym kai voatáv uérpov kai &yévntov kai âtówov Ical uðvov ſcal kupię8es, airb to (rejected by Usener. I should my- self prefer airó re) éavro ŠmAoûv h tº toū befov IIAdºrovos &c. Also ibid. 925 b, 23: ÖAws 5& oëöé àtro Tóv &aavel ávttkeipićvow oi ävöpes àpxov- to, &AA& kal Tóv 800 ovoitouxióv to èrékelva jöeorav, Ös uaprupeſ ‘pix@Aaos Töv 6eov Aéywv trépas kal âtreuptav Štroorºoral, . . . kai étu Tpö täv Šio &pxóv Tāv čviatav airíav Kai Tavrwv čmomuévnu irpoétattov, %u 'Apxaſvetos (or, according to the conjecture of Böckh, Philol. 54, 149, in which Hartenstein, Arch. Fragm. 12, concurs: 'Apxöras, a reading which Usener had ad- mitted in the text) uév airíav trpo airías elvaí pmat, pixóAaos 6& tar trövtov Špxèv elva, 5uo Xupigetal, Bpotivos 6& &s roo travros kai oi- orias 5uvâuel kal trpedºeſq ūrepéxel (Röth's corrections of this passage are superfluous and mistaken). Cf. also ibid. 935 b, 13: éott uèv Štre- poiſotov trapd re ré IIA&ravi rb év kai rāya.0öv kal trapë Bpovrtvº ró IIv6aºyopetº ral trapā tragiv ćis eitreſu Toºs &mb row $16aoka)\etov rod Tāv IIv6ayopetov Špºwpievous. Pseudo- Alex. in Metaph. 800, 32 : oi uév, &ortrep IIAárov kal Bporivos 6 IIv6a- Tyópelos, paalv Šti rb &yaôov airo to €v éoti kai oia'twrai év tá, év eival. Cf. also the &iólos 6ebs ap. Plut. Plac. iv. 7, 4 ; Pseudo-Butherus ap. Stob. Ecl. i. 12 (Unity is the uncreated, the Supreme cause, &c.); Theol. Arithm. p. 8, and Athenag. Suppl. c. 6: Aio is 6é Kal ūſei ("Opuos cf. Iambl. V. P. 267) & Hºv diplôubv šáñntov (an irrational number, here, doubtless an irra- tional numerical root) 6píſerai Tov £eov, 6 5& too pierytotov Tóv dpiðuðv. thv trapö. Töv ćyyvtårov [roß &yºyv- Táta Štrepox?iv, which Athenagoras. explains, no doubt correctly, by saying that the highest number designates the decade, and the number nearest to it nine, so that the whole is only a fanciful cir- cumlocution for Unity. * Eudorus, loc. cit. Sup. p. 388, 1; Hippol. Réfut. i. 2, p. 10:..dpububs 7éyove trpátos apx?), btrep &otiv čv, déptoros dicatáAmmtos, Šxwv év Šavré, trövtas toūs étr' &neupov Svyapuévous éA6eiv dpiðuous karū to TAñ60s, táv ôé àpiðuovápx?lºyé yove kaff inróa ragw # Tpdºrm uovas, #tus éatl uovas āpany 'yevvöga trarpikós travtas tobs &AAous āpiśaoiſs. Bettepov Šč i öväs 67Avs àpiðubs &c. Syrian (in Metaph. Schol. 917 b, 5) quotes as from Archytas the following text: śrt to èv kx, il pověs ovyyevi čávra. Stapépel &AAhawv, and appeals to Moderatus and Nicomachus in sup- port of this distinction. Proclus in Tim. 54 D sq., The first Being is, according to the Pythagoreans, 3 9 2 THE PETHAGOREANS. But although these statements have found much favour with modern writers, they are not sufficiently attested to warrant our adopting even their essential substance. It has already been observed that we can trust the information of later writers about the Pytha- gorean philosophy, and especially of Neo-Pythagorean and Neo-Platonic writers, only to the extent that their sources are known to us. But these sources are in the present instance either not mentioned, or else they are contained in writings the authenticity of which is more than doubtful. In regard to the long fragment of Archytas, this has already been shown ; there can scarcely be any question of it in the case of the quo- tations from Brotinus, Clinias, and Butherus : " the the év, which is above all opposi- tions; the second, the ideal Monad or the Limit, and indeterminate duality or the Unlimited. Simi- larly Damasc. De Princ. c. 43, 46, p. 115, 122: the év, according to Pythagoras, precedes the Monad. On the contrary, Moderatus ap. Stob. Eel. i. 20, says if these words belong to him : ruvès Tov &piðuáv àpx?iv &treqfivavro Thy uovdāa Tów 3& 3plbum Tów to ºv. Theo. Math. c. 4, also agreeing with this says in his own name that the Monad is above the One. Sextus (vide supra, p. 387, 3), the Cohortatio of Justin. c. 19, and the anony- mous author ap. Photius, Cod. 249, p. 438 b, consider the Monad to be the highest, when they say that the Monad is the divinity, and that it stands above the One: rhy aëv yöp uováða év toºs vonroſs elval To 8& £v év rois àpiðuois (Just.) Röper in the Philol. vii. 546, thinks that we should substitute &piðumtois for &piðuois, but this is the less likely, as Photius has the same. It is plain that here all is caprice and confusion. The com- mentators of Aristotle, such as Pseudo-Alexander (in Met. 775, 31, 776, 10 Bon.), Simpl. (Phys. 32 b), are accustomed to consider the doc- trine of Unity and indeterminate Duality as Pythagorean. * In Clinias the spuriousness is evident even from the expres- sion puérpov táv vomtöv. In the fragment given by Brotinus the proposition that the primitive essence is superior to Being in force and dignity is taken word for word from the Republic of Plato, vi. 509 B; and when to Being is added vows, the Aristo- telian divinity, this addition clearly proves that this is a writing of the period of Neo-Pythagoreanism or Neo-Platonism. The words āti To &ya.0öv &c., can only belong to that period. . . UNITY AND DUALITY. 393 artificial character of the citation in Athenagoras is a sufficient reason for mistrusting it ; even in the short saying of Archaenetus (or Archytas) the language and standpoint of a later period are clearly discernible; " and lastly, in a passage said to be from Aristotle, a definition of matter is attributed to Pythagoras him- self, which, in accordance with the doctrine of the older academy, presupposes the distinction between form and matter,” evidently showing either that the writing is itself a forgery, or that it contains a false statement. The expositions, too, which Sextus and Alexander Polyhistor have followed, bear unmistakeable marks of the eclecticism which after the second half of the second century before Christ began to blend the philosophical systems together, and to confuse the ancient with the recent.” * The language, for this use of airía without any particular quali- fication, is first found in Plato and Aristotle, and presupposes their enquiries concerning the idea of cause: the point of view, for in the expression airla trpo airias the divinity is elevated above all cos- mic principles in a manner never known before the time of the Neo- Pythagoreans. * Damasc. De Princ. Arist. Fragm. 1514 a, 24: 'AptorotéAms 8è év roſs 'Apxvreious iotope? kal IIv6ayópav &AAo thv iſºmy kaxeiv és àevotiv Kal &el &AAo ‘yºyduevov. Chaignet, ii. 73 sq. takes this as certain. In my opinion, the cir- cumstance that Aristotle is here affirming something about the doc- trine of Pythagoras, and above all, the substance of this affirmation, clearly seems to show either that the For these reasons the testi- work on Archytas (of which we do not possess elsewhere the smallest fragment) was spurious ; or else that Damascius had wrongly attri- buted to Pythagoras what was said in that work, and was, perhaps, only known to Damascius at third hand. What he makes Pythagoras say could not even have been said by the Pythagoreans, before Plato. Aristotle, on the other hand, tells us (Metaph. xiv. 1087 b, 26) that certain Platonists opposed to the ëv the étepov and the #MAo as the material principle ; and Ps. Alex. (777, 22 Bon.) applies this asser- tion to the Pythagoreans. It would seem that the statement of Damascius, or of the work used by him, has occasioned a similar misunderstanding. * This is especially evident in Sextus. Even the dialectic charac- 394 THE PPTHAGOREA.N.S. monies in question are valueless; and neither the doc- trime of Unity and indefinite Duality, nor the identifi- cation of the primal Unity with Deity, and all that depends upon it, can any longer be attributed to the ancient Pythagoreans. Among the later Pythagoreans whose tendencies were Platonic, Unity and Duality, as we see from what has been quoted above, play an important part; but among the earlier philosophers, Plato is the first who can be proved to have employed them, and the Aristo- ter of his argument definitely indi- cates a recent date. Moreover, not only the Atomists, but Epicurus and Plato, are mentioned by name, and allusion is made to their works (P. iii. 152; M. x. 252, 257, 258). We find in Math. vii. 107, a very improbable anecdote of the sculptor of the Colossus of Rhodes, a pupil of Lysippus. Contrary to all the statements of Aristotle, the separa- tion of numbers from things, and the participation of things in num- bers (M. x. 263 sqq., 277; vii. 102), are attributed not merely to the Pythagoreans, but to Pythagoras himself (P. iii. 153; M. x. 261 sq ). The Pythagoreans are represented as freely making use of Pytha- gorean and even of Aristotelian categories. There is no doubt, therefore, that this exposition is of recent date, and quite untrust- worthy, and that the defence of it, which Marbach (Gesch. d. Phil. i. 169) has attempted, superficially enough, is altogether inadmissible. In the exposition of Alexander these recent elements are less striking, but, nevertheless, they are unmistakeable. At the very commencement of the extract which he gives, we find the Stoic and Aristotelian distinction of matter and efficient cause. This distinction, as with the Stoics, enters even into the One primitive essence. Further on, we find the Stoic doctrine of the universal transformation of matter (tpéreo 6a, 6’ 3Awy), a doc- trine which is wholly foreign to the ancient Pythagorean cosmo- logy, as will presently be shown ; then the Stoic couceptions of the eipiappuévn, ot the ideutity of the Divine with the vital warmth or aether; its immanence in things (öuñkeuv), and the kinship of men with the Divine, which is founded upon this immanence. We also find the Stoical notions of the pro- pagation of Souls, an analogous opinion to that of the Stoics on sensation, and the purely Stoical theory, according to which the faculties of the soul are resolved into currents of air (rows A6-yous juxis &véuous eival). These traits sufficiently prove the impossibility of regarding the exposition of Alexander as an ancient Pytha- gorean document. Other details will be given further on. UNITY AND DUALITY. 395 telian passages which might seem to ascribe them to the Pythagoreans, and which were constantly explained in this sense by the ancient commentators, relate entirely to Plato and the Academy." Neither in Alexander's excerpts from Aristotle's work on the Good,” in which the Platonic doctrine of Unity and indefinite Duality is developed at length, nor in what Porphyry “ says on the same subject, are the Pythagoreans mentioned; * and though Theophrastus once alludes to indefinite Duality, after previously naming the Pythagoreans to- gether with Plato, the brevity with which he sums up the doctrines of both prevents our drawing any in- ference from this allusion. Moreover, according to the statements of Alexander and Porphyry, Plato places this doctrine in close connection with the theory of the Great and Small, which Aristotle declares categori- * Metaph. xiii. 6, 1080 b, 6, The commencement of the chapter shows clearly that there is no question in this passage of the Pythagoreans. Aristotle only speaks of them in the sequel, and in reference to something else. It is the same with the passage, c. 7, 1081 a, 14 sqq.; 1082 a, 13. This whole chapter treats solely of the Platonic theory of numbers. Lastly, xiv. 3, 1091 a, 4, also refers to Plato, and to him only. * Comment, on Met. i. 6, p. 41, 32 sq. Bon; and Simpl. Phys. 32b; 104b. * Ap. Simpl. Phys. 104 b. * Met. (Frag. 12, Wimm.) 33, p. 322, 14 Brand.: IIAátov Šē kal oi IIv6ayópelot, Pakpāv thu ätréata- ow émipupietorðat ye 0éAew &mavta. kairoi ka0&ntep <6eorív riva troiodori Tús &opiatou 8váðos kai row évés' év kal to #mepov kal to &raktov kai rāora ös eitreſv ćuoppía kað’ aštív. ÖAws 8& oix oióv re &veu Toºrms thu Tai, ŠAou pågiv [eival], ãAA’ oiovio ououpeſv tís Érépas à ka) tàs àpx&s àvarrías. This is the reading adopted by Brandis. Wim- mer has: Tâs étépas &c. Perhaps the right reading of the passage may be : ionouotpetv T. &px. €vavttas h kal inspéxelv thu ètépav. Ötö kal où5& Töv 6ebv, Šarol rig 9eó rhy airíav čvártoval, 6&vagóal travt’ &ml To &ptorov &yeiv, &AA’ efirep, p’ ão'ov évôéxeral: táxa 6' oit’ &v TpoéNott’, strep &vaipeio 6al ovuòji- aretal Thy đAmvoúatav č évayrtov ºve kal [éu] evavirious of gav. The last words, beginning at tdºxa, are most likely added by Theophrastus himself, but in the whole text there is such a mixture of Pythagorean- ism and Platonism that it seems impossible to determine from this passage alone what was peculiar to each of the two factors. 396 THE PPTHAGO REAWS. cally to be a conception peculiar to Plato and unknown to the Pythagoreans. Aristotle and Philolaus always cite the odd and the even, or the limited and unlimited, and these alone as elements of number.” Even where Aristotle speaks of numbers being produced from the One,” he understands by the One only the number one and never adds to it duality, which he could not possibly have omitted if the One were incapable of pro- ducing number except in combination with duality; lastly, many authorities expressly deny that the Pytha- goreans held the theory of Unity and Duality.” It may be considered almost unquestionable them that this doctrine did not belong to the ancient Pytha- goreans.” The subsequent interpretations which iden- * Metaph. i. 6, 987 b, 25: to 3& àvirl too &tepov &s évos Sváða trotſioſal kal to &repov čk weyāAov kal ukpot, toot’ totov (sc. IIAátovt). Phys. iii. 4, 203 a, 10: oi uèv [IIv- 6ayópetol) to &repov eival to &ptuou . . . IIAgtov Šč 600 rà &melpa, to Auéya kal to ukpóv; cf. ibid. iii. 6, 206 b, 27. The first of these passages does not directly assert that the Pythagoreans were not ac- quainted with the dyad, that is to say, the Övös &6puatos, but that they were unacquainted with the dyad of the Great and Small. * Wide supra, p. 377. * Metaph. i. 5, vide Supra, p. 378, 1. Cf. the lemarks, xiii. 8, 1083 a, 20; xiv. i. 1087 b, 7 ; c, 4, 1091 b, 4, relative to an opinion similar to that of the Pythago- reans. It is clear from the text, xiii. 8, 1083 a, 36 sq., that it is not the Pythagorean opinion itself. * Theo. Smyrn.i.4, p. 26: ārāās bé àpx&s āp.6pºw of uèv šo repôv part Thu re uovdöa kal Thy 6váða of 6& âtró IIv6ayópov trgo as karū to £is T&s róv Špov čk6éoets, 6t’ &v &ptioſ Te Kal trepitto) vootivtat, oiov Tóv év aio.6mtois Totòv àpx?iv Thy Tpudôa. &c. Ps.-Alex. in Metaph. xiv. 1, p. 775, 29; ibid. 776, 9: rois uév oùv trepi IIAárova yewvávra oi àpt0- pºol ék Tös toū āviorov čváö0s, Tó 6è IIv6ayópg. # yévégis Tów Śpiðuðv éariv čk roi, TAff00vs. Similarly Syrian ad h. l. Schol. 926 a, 15. * Wide Brandis, De perd. Arist. libr. p. 27; Ritter, Pythag. Phil. 133; Wendt. De rer, princ. sec. Pyth. 20 sq.; and others. Böckh, on the contrary, regarded the One and indeterminate Duality as belonging to the Pythagorean doc- trine (Philol. 55); and Schleier- macher considers those two prin- ciples as synonymous with God and matter, the principle deter- mining and the principle deter- mined (Geschich, der Phil. p. 56). GOD AND MATTER. 397 tify the One with Deity, and Duality with matter, are utterly to be discarded. For this radical distinction of the corporeal and spiritual, of matter and efficient force, is quite at variance with the theory which chiefly determines the character of Pythagoreanism, viz. that numbers are the essence of which things consist. If once a discrimination were admitted between matter and the formal principle, numbers would become, like the Platonic ideas, mere forms, and could no longer be considered as the substantial elements of the corporeal. Such a distinction, however, is only ascribed to the Bythagoreans by writers to whose evidence, as we have seen, very limited credence can be given. Aristotle on the contrary emphatically declares' that Anaxagoras was the first philosopher who discriminated spirit from matter, and he on this account includes the Pytha- goreans among those who recognised only sensible existence.” But most of the statements that have come down to us respecting the Pythagorean doctrine of the divinity are immediately connected with the theory of Unity and Duality, of spirit and matter. The divinity seems to have been conceived partly as the first term of this opposition, and partly as the higher unity which precedes the opposition, engenders the two opposing elements as such, and brings about their union. If, therefore, this discrimination was first added to Pythagoreanism by the later adherents of the school, the same must have been the case in regard to the Pythagorean conception of God; and the question is whether the idea of God had generally any philo- * Metaph. i. 3, 984 b, 15. * Wide Supra, p. 189. 398 THE PPTHAGOREA.N.S. sophic import for the Pythagoreans, and especially, whether it was involved in their theory of ultimate causes. This question cannot be answered by an appeal to the religious character of Pythagoreanism, nor by the citation of passages, which express, in a religious form, the dependance of all things on God, the duties of Divine worship, the greatness, and the attributes of God; for we are not at present concerned with the enquiry how far the Pythagorean theology co-existed side by side with the Pythagorean philosophy, but how far it had any logical connection with the philosophic doctrines of the school; whether, in short, the idea of God was deduced by the Pythagoreans from their philosophic theory of the universe, or was used by them to explain it." General as this latter assumption may be, it appears to me unfounded. The Deity, it is thought by some, was distinguished by the Pythagoreans as absolute unity, from unity conceived as in opposition, or from the limit ; consequently, it was also dis- tinguished from the world, and exalted above the whole sphere of opposites.” * It is no refutation of my views to say, as Heyde says (Ethices Pythagorea Vindicia, Erl. 1854, p. 25), that every philosopher borrows considerably from common opinion. The opinions which a philosopher derives from this source are only to be considered part of his philo- sophic system if they are in some way connected with his scientific views. Apart from these, they are merely personal opinions, imma- terial to the system; as, for ex- ample, the pilgrimage of Descartes to Loretto is immaterial to Car- Others say " that the first one, tesianism. Heyde likewise main- tains, ibid., that we ought only to leave out from a philosophic sys- tem such points as the author of the system expressly declares not to belong to it. This would at once render any discrimination of the essential and the accidental in such matters impossible. * Böckh, Phil. 53 sq.; Brandis, i. 483 sq. * Ritter, Pythag. Phil. 113 sq., 119 sq., 156 sq.; Geschich. d. Phil. i. 387 sq., 393 sq.; Schleiermacher, foc. cit. GOD AND MATTER. 399 or the limited, was at the same time apprehended as Deity. This, however, is asserted only by Neo- Pythagorean and Neo-Platonic authorities, and in fragments of interpolated writings emanating from the same circle." Aristotle, in 1 Besides the fragments already quoted, the fragment of Philolaus, repl juxiàs, ap. Stob. i. 420 (Böckh, Philol. 163 sq.), is, in my opinion, in the same case. It bears so many marks of a recent origin that I cannot consider it authentic, nor can I even adopt as probable Böckh's theory (defended by Brandis, Geschich. d. Entw. i. 173 sq ) that the foundation was authentic, but that something has been added by one authority in quoting it. The very commence- ment recalls the Timaeus of Plato (33. A sq.; 34, B) and still more Ocellus Lucanus, c. i. 11. The words (p. 422), to 3’ & &pidotépov rotºrwy, too uév čel 9éovros 6etov, rot, 5è &el we'ro.84MAovros yewvarot, kóa'aos, remind us in the most striking manner of the text, c. 2, sub fin. of Ocellus Lucanus, and the Cratinus of Plato, 397 C. To dispose of this coincidence (Chaignet, ii. 81) by the substitu- tion of éévros for 9éovros would in itself be arbitrary and unjustifi- able, even if the 6etov had not been designated previously as the Četicſ- varov, which é; aiovos eis aidºva repitroxe? (cf. § iv. Cosm.). The eternity of the world (and not merely its endless duration, as Brandis, loc. cit., maintains; the words are: 7s 66e 6 kóa'aos éé aiévos kal és aidºva Stauévet), which is taught in the fragment in ques- tion, a favourite theme of the Neo- Pythagoreans, was, according to all the indications of Aristotle, intro- the various passages where duced into Philosophy by Plato's idea of the world-soul. These two doctrines were, as we shall pre- sently see ($ iv. Cosm.), unknown to the true Pythagoreans; and, in- deed, what our author says of the world-soul presents in its details a decidedly Platonic and Aristotelian character, while Pythagorean theo- ries, properly so-called, are wholly wanting. The discrimination made by the pseudo-Philolaus between the world above file moon, which he calls the épierd 8Xmtov or &eticſ- wntov, and the world below the moon, which he calls the pueraßd A- Aov, or àeutraffès, doubtless resembles the Pythagorean ideas, but the manner in which it is apprehended has greater affinity with Aristotle (cf. for example, what is quoted Part ii. b, 331, 3; 338 sq., second edition), and especially the trea- tise II. Réopov, c, 2, 392 a, 29 sq. The influence of the Aristotelian terminology is unmistakeable in these words: kóopov fuev čvépystav &föuov 6eó Te ral yewégios karð. ovvakoxov6íav tas ueragxagºrukås qūorios. The opposition of the karð. To airò ical &gatros éxov and the 'ylvéueva kal (p6eipóueva troAA& does not belong, it is certain, to the epoch anterior to Plato: the obser- vation that by means of generation the perishable receives its form in an imperishable manner is found even in Plato and Aristotle, and seems to presuppose the distinc- tion made by both these philoso- phers between form and matter. 400 THE PYTHAGOREANS. he expounds the Pythagorean theory of the ultimate reasons of things, never says a word about their doc- trine of God." Lastly, Böckh remarks that the closing words, tº Yevvioravt. trarépt ical Smpuoup'yó, are derived from Timaeus, 37 C.; but we can scarcely for this reason attribute them to the person who reports them. Ad- mitting that some of these coinci- dences cannot be explained except on the theory of an interpolation, it would still be very difficult to believe in the authenticity of this work when we consider how much is united there, which, striking enough, per se, is inconceivable in combination, except on the supposi- tion that the work is of recent date. Rohr (De Philol. Frag., repl juxās, Lpz. 1874, p. 12 sq.) thinks that by sacrificing the last sentences from the words Ötö kal kaxós éxel, he can save the rest as a work of Philolaus ; but this is a vain at- tempt, as I shall prove, in reference to the most decisive points—the eternity of the world and the world-soul. But if this fragment is interpolated, there is no reason to suppose that the fixóñaos év tá, Tep) juxās, from which it is bor- rowed, according to Stobaeus, is the third volume of the known work of Philolaus. Böckh and Schaar- schmidt assert this—the former (loc. cit.) on the pre-supposition that the fragment is authentic ; the latter believing that none of the fragments of Philolaus are so. It is probable that this treatise was a separate work, distinct from the source of the authentic fragments. Claudianus Mamertus probably had it before him in his confused state- ments, De Statu An. ii. 7, quoted by Böckh, Philol. 29 sqq., and he Theophrastus even seems to draw an most likely borrows from it what we shall cite further on. But this only proves that the book was known by this writer of the fifth century A.D., and regarded by him as an authentic work of Philolaus ; and even if, in the manuscript he was using, it was joined with Philo- laus' real work, this is no proof of its authenticity. * It is said in Metaph. xiii. 8, 1083 a, 20, that numbers are the primitive element, kal &px?iv airów eival airb to ºv, but this One is not designated as the Divinity; and besides, the passage is not con- cerned with Pythagoreans, but with a fraction of the Platonists who followed the doctrines of Pytha- goras. Similarly, Metaph. xiv. 4, 1091 b, 13 sqq., when Aristotle speaks of those who identify the Absolute One with the Absolute Good (at to to èv rô &yaôov airb eivaí bagw), he means the adherents of the theory of Ideas, as is proved by the expressions airò To ev, &kſum- to oia'tal, pºéya kai utkpov (l. 32). This opinion is the view of the Platonists; vide Schwegler and Bonitz ad. h. l. and Zeller, Plaf. Stud, p. 278. In a third text, Metaph. i. 5 (vide supra, p. 379, 1 : cf. xiii. 6, 1080 b, 31 : To £v or rol- xetov kal &px|v pagu sīval Tów ãvrov) it is said that the Pytha- goreans deduce numbers from the One; but this is the number one which cannot be the Divinity, be- cause it must itself result from the Odd and Even. Ritter (Gesch. d. Phil. i. 388) makes, in reference to this point, the following objec- tion: As number, that is to say, GOD AWD MATTER. 401 express distinction * between the Pythagoreans and those who represent the Deity as efficient cause.” Philolaus indeed calls the one the beginning of all things,” but he can scarcely mean anything more by this than what Aristotle says: viz., that the number one is the root of all numbers, and therefore, since all things consist of numbers, it is also the principle of all things.” the ‘Even and the Odd, only re- Sults from the One, the One cannot have resulted from these: the words éé àpaporépov roſſroov do not therefore signify derived from both, but consisting of both. This ob- jection is based upon a manifest confusion: the Even and Odd number is not the Even and the Odd ; the expression, “that is to say, is consequently not legiti- mate, and the only sense which the words of Aristotle can have, ac- cording to the context, is the fol- lowing: first, the One arises out of the Odd and the Even, and then the other numbers proceed from the One. Wide Alexander ad h. i. Lastly, in Metaph. xiii. 6, 1080 b, 20; xiv. 3, 1091 a, 13, the first corporeal unity is spoken of, but it is characterised very dis- tinctly as derived, for in xiv. 3, we read, oi uév oëv IIv6ayópelot trórepov oë rotojo, ) rotočari yéveriv[roń śvös] où be?6to tdgetv'pavepāsºy&p Aéyovoriv, &s toū āvos avorra.0évros efºr’ & ‘tri- tréðav eſt’éic xpotas eſt’ék a trépuaros eſt’ & &v &topodov eitreiv, eú6ts rô êyyugara row &treſpov 3rt eißkero kal &repaivero Šro too réparos. Here, again, I am obliged to contradict the remark of Ritter (loc. cit.) 389 that, according to the text, Met. xiii. 6, this One cannot be anything derived. But Aristotle in that WOL. I. He further describes God as the sole place simply says: 8tra's to trpárov ëv ovvéotm éxov uéyé00s &topeſv éoſkaoiv. In the first place this does not mean that they regard the One as not derived, but that the problem of its derivation puz- zles them; whence it would rather follow that this problem is based upon their other definitions in re- spect to the One. In the second place, the question in this passage is not whether Unity in general is derived from first principles, but whether the origin of the first cor- poreal unity, as such, the formation of the first body in the midst of the universe (that is to say, the central fire), has been explained in a satisfactory manner. * In the passage quoted, p. 395, 4. * Plato and his School. Cf. the words : 610 kal oë8& row 9ebv &c., Tim. 48 A.; Theaet. 176 A. - * In the fragment ap. Iambl. in Nicom. 109 (cf. Syrian in Me- taph. Schol. 926 a, 1 ; vide supra, p. 391, 2, and Böckh, Philol. 149 sq.), the authenticity of which, in- deed, is not quite certain, though there is nothing absolutely against it : év àpx& travtww. * It is thus that the biographer in Photius Cod. 249 a, 19, under- stands the passage : thv uováða wdvtwv àpx?iv čAeyov IIv6ayópelot, D D 402 THE PPTHAGOREA.N.S. ruler of the universe, exalted above all things," em- bracing , all things with his care; * but this proves nothing in respect to the philosophic import of the concept of God in his system. For the first of these propositions, if it really comes from Philolaus,” merely étrel to pièv or muetov &px?iv čAeyov ºpappuis, thv 5& étritréðov, to 6* . . orópatos. Too 5% or muetov trpoetri- voeirai ji uovºs, Šote àpx?) Tów orapudºrov ji wovds. If even these words referred to the Divinity, it would be necessary to know the connection in which they stand, in order to say whether the One is here designated as the Divinity, or if the sense is not simply this: ‘One thing is the beginning of all other things, and this one thing is the Divinity.” In the first case only would the passage have a philosophic bearing; in the second it would be a religious proposition, such as we find elsewhere (e.g. in Terpander, vide Supra, p. 122). • Philo, mund; opif. 23 A: uap- Tupel àé uov tá, A6).4 kal PixéAaos év rotºrous éoth ydp, pnoriv, 6 ye- Pºv kal &pxov &rdvrov 6ebs eſs, del &v, uáviſuos, drivntos, airbs airó âuotos, repos Tów &AAwv. The Pythagorean conception of God is similarly expounded in Plut. Numa, c. 8. * Athenag. Supplic. c. 6: kal $1XóAaos 3& àotrep v (ppoupé travra §tro rot, 6.e00 trepielWiig,0at Aéywy, cf. Blato, Phaedo, 62 B: the A670s év &mośńrous Aeyóuevos, dºs év rive qpoupé, éoplew oi &v6pwrot is hard to understand, où uévrol d'AA& Tööe 7é got 50ke? . . . et Aéyegbai, rô 6eoës eiva, Śwów toi's étriplexouévows kal juás robs &v6pótrovs #v táv termudrav roſs 6eois eival. - * This is not guaranteed quite certainly by the assertion of Philo; for the Jewish and Christian Alexandrians often avail them- selves of falsified writings to prove Monotheism. Böckh also conjec- tures that the passage may not be a verbal quotation; but there are no decisive proofs of its spuriousness, for I cannot consider the airbs aúró 3plotos, &c., as ‘Post Platonic modern categories’ (Schaarschmidt, Schrift. des Philol. 40). The pro- position that the universe or the Divinity is &ei Šuotov, travrm šuotov is attributed already to Xeno- phanes. Parmenides calls Being trav Šuotov (vide infra, Parm.). Moreover, the opposition of the aúró &Motos, Érepos Táv &AAwy does not presuppose more dialectic cul- ture than the opposition éavré, trövtoge routov, tº 5’ répq, wh Twvrov (Parm. v. 117, in relation to one of Parmenides' elements), and not nearly so much as the arguments of Zeno against Multi- plicity and Motion. If it be ob- jected that a strict Monotheism is incompatible with the theological point of view of the Pythagoreans, we may fairly enquire whether the fragment is to be understood in this sense, and whether the expres- sion jyeuðv Kal &pxov štávrov 6eos excludes other gods. It may be that this fragment only presents to us that belief in a supreme God which we find before and contempo- rary with Philolaus, in AEschylus, Sophocles, Heracleitus, Empedocles, and others, and which was not in- compatible with Polytheism. GOD AND MATTER, 403 expresses in a religious form a thought which was then no longer confined to the schools of philosophy, and which sounds more like the language of Xenophanes than anything peculiarly Pythagorean. The second proposition taken from the Orphico-Pythagorean mys- teries' is entirely of a religious and popular nature.” Neither one nor the other is employed as the basis of philosophic definitions. If, lastly, Philolaus asserted that the Deity brought forth limit and unlimitedness,” this certainly presupposes that all is to be referred to the Divine causality; but as no account is given how God brought forth the first causes, and how he is related to them, this theorem merely bears the character of a religious presupposition. From a philosophic point of view it merely shows that Philolaus knew not how to explain the origin of the opposition of the Limited and |Unlimited. He seems to think that they, as he says in another place of harmony," arose in some way which it is impossible accurately to define. Even in the time of Neo-Pythagoreanism the prevailing distinction of the supra-mundane One from the Monad was not universally acknowledged.” We cannot but admit, therefore, that * This clearly appears from pra, p. 389, 3, whose testimony is Plato, loc. cit. * Here again it may be ques- tioned whether Athenagoras exactly reproduces the words that he quotes, and if instead of Too 6eod, the original text may not have con- tained rôv 9eóv, as in Plato. We are not even sure whether the quotation is from the work of Philolaus at all. It may be merely a vague reminiscence of the pas- sage in Plato. * According to Syrian, vide su- confirmed by the evidence of Plato in the Philebus, 23 C (supra, p. 379, 1). On the other hand, Pro- clus, Plat. Theol. p. 132, only quotes as coming from Philolaus the proposition that all consists of the Limited and Unlimited. The proposition that God has engen- dered these elements he gives as Platonic. * Wide supra, p. 383, 2. * Supra, p. 375; cf. p. 391, 2. D D 2 404 THE PYTHAGOREA.N.S. the Pythagoreans believed in gods. It is also probable that they followed the monotheistic tendency (which after the time of Xenophanes exercised such an im- portant influence on Greek philosophy) so far as amidst the plurality of gods to proclaim, with greater emphasis than the popular religion, the unity (60sos, Tô 6sſov);' at the same time, however, the import of the idea of God in relation to their philosophic system seems to have been small,” nor does it appear to have been closely interwoven with their enquiry concerning the first prin- ciples of things.” I am consequently the less able to believe that the Pythagoreans taught a development of God in the universe, by which He gradually arrived at perfection through imperfection.* This theory is closely connected * But certainly in connection with the popular belief; so that for them, as for the generality of people, the 6eſov is identical with Zeus. Cf. their theories as to the oversight exercised by Zeus and all connected with it. * Böckh, Phil. 148, observes that without the theory of a higher Unity, above the Limited and Unlimited, there would re- main no trace in the system of the Pythagoreans, renowned as they were for their religious ideas, of the Divinity. This remark does not prejudice my opinion in the least. I do not deny that they reduced everything to the Divinity, but I contend that in so doing, they did not proceed in a scientific manner; and this seems to me the easier to understand, because by virtue of their religious character, this dependance of all things in respect to the Divinity was for them an immediate postulate, and not a scientific problem. Röth (ii. a, 769 sqq.) himself, repugnant as this assertion naturally is to him, is obliged to confess that the sacredness and inviolability of Pythagoras' circle of ideas, in re- gard to religious speculation, left little room for the free intellectual development of his school; and that among the writings (authentic according to Röth) left to us by the Pythagoreans, there is none which has properly a speculative character; but that they are all religious and popular works. Is not this to say, as I do, that the- ological convictions here appear primarily as the object of religious faith, and not of scientific enquiry? * Cf. what is said in the next section on the theory that the Py- thagoreans taught the existence of a world-soul. * Ritter, Pyth. Phil, 149 sqq.; I) EVELOPMENT OF GOD IN THE WORLD. 405 with the statement that they held the One to be the Deity. For the One is described as the Even-Odd, and as the Odd is the perfect, and the Even the imperfect, so, it is argued, they supposed not only the perfect but the imperfect, and the reason of imperfection, to be in God, and accordingly held that the perfect good can only arise from a development of God. I must protest against such an inference, if only upon the ground that I dispute the identity of the One with the Deity. But even irrespectively of this, it could not be true, for though the number one was called by the Pythagoreans the even-odd, the One which is opposed as one of the primitive causes to indefinite Duality is never so called, and never could he ; and the number one, as that which is derived from the primitive causes, and compounded of them, could in no case be identified with the Deity.” Aristotle certainly says that the Pythagoreans, like Speusippus, denied that the fairest and best could have existed from the beginning ; * and as he mentions this theory in connection with his own doctrine of the eter- Gesch. d. Phil. 398 sqq., 436; this assertion originally belongs. 2 Cf. against Ritter, vide Brandis, Rhein. Mus. of Niebuhr and Brandis, ii. 227 sqq. * Not even in Theophrastus (supra, p. 395,4). The statements of Theophrastus would prove no- thing in regard to this question, even if they could as a whole be considered as applying to the Py- thagoreans. For it does not follow, because God is unable to conduct all things to perfection, that he is, therefore, himself imperfect. Other- wise he would be imperfect more especially with Plato, to whom p. 400, 1. * Metaph. xii. 7, 1072 b, 28: ©auèv 8& row 6eby eiwat Øov &fölov &ptorov . . . §oot 6% froxau5&vov- oriv, Šotrep of IIv6ayópelot kal Xtreč- ourtros, rô káNAuorov kal &ptorov ph Čv àpxfi elval, Ötö. Tö ical rôv qvröv kai Tºv Ǻwv ràs &pxas alria pºv eival, to 6* ſca?\öv kal réAetov év roſs ék rotºrwu, otic àp6ós olovrat. The ethical interpretation of this passage, attempted by Schleierma- cher (Gesch. d. Phil. 52), is not worth discussing. 406 THE PPTHAGOREA.N.S. mity of God, it has the appearance of having also been applied by the Pythagoreans to the motion of Deity. In the first place, however, it does not at all necessarily follow from this that the Divinity was at first imperfect, and afterwards attained to perfection. As Speusippus concluded from this proposition that the One as the first principle must be distinct from the good and from the Deity," so the Pythagoreans may in like manner have separated them.” But it is also a question whether the theorem which Aristotle disputes was ever advanced by the Pythagoreans with respect to the Deity; for Aristotle does not always quote the definitions of the earlier philosophers quite in the connection in which their authors originally stated them, as may be proved by numerous examples.” We do not know what sense may have been given to this proposition in the Pythago- rean system. It may have referred to the development of the world from a previous state of imperfection, or to the production of the perfect number (the decad) from the less perfect; * or to the position of the good in the table of opposites,” or to some other object. We * Wide the chapter on Speusip- pus, Part ii. a, 653 sq. 2 A. * This is also the opinion which Aristotle attributes to them when he says that they did not consider the One as the Good itself, but as a certain kind of good. Eth. N. i. 4, 1096 b, 5: Triðavdārepov 6' oikao w of IIv6ayópelot Aéºyeuv trepi airoij, rtóévres év tá têvãºya%v avorouxtº: Tô ev (in the table of the ten con- tradictories) ois 63 kal Xtrečourtros étrakoxov670 at Šoke. * Chaignet, ii. 103, identifies the Pythagoreans with those theo- logians who, according to Metaph. xiv. 4, 1091 a, 29 sqq., maintained that airò To &ya6öv kai Tô &ptorrow are 50tepolyevi, and that they only appeared in the course of the de- velopment of the cosmos. But it results from the preceding context, as well as from the expression airb &ya3bv, that the Platonists are here intended (Speusippus). Aristo- tle explicitly says: trapá ràv 9eo- Aóryov táv vov two iv. * As Steinhart says, Plato's Werke, vi. 227. * Cf. note 2. I) EPELOPMENT OF GOD. 407 are not therefore justified by this Aristotelian passage, in ascribing to the Pythagoreans a doctrine which not only contradicts Philolaus' representation of the Deity, but is quite unknown to antiquity;” though, if it had really existed among the Pythagoreans, it might on that very account be expected to receive all the more definite mention from the ancient writers. Having in the foregoing pages opposed the theolo- gico-metaphysical interpretation of the Pythagorean first principles, I must now declare myself no less strongly against the theory that these principles pri- marily refer to space-relations, and side by side with the arithmetical Telement, or instead of it, denote something geometrical, or even altogether material. Aristotle says the Pythagoreans treated numbers as space-magnitudes; * he often mentions the theory that geometričāTàgúies are the substantial element of which bodies consist,” and his commentators go further, * The ancient philosophers, it is true, frequently maintain that the world was developed from a rudimentary and formless state, but never that the Divinity was developed The doctrine of Hera- cleitus and the Stoics contained no such teaching. For the successive forms of the T)ivine essence are something entirely different from a development of that essence out of an imperfect state. The primi- tive fire which, as the germ of the world, is antecedent to the world, is here regarded as the most per- fect existence, the kópos. Lastly, if the Theogonies represent parti- cular gods as generated, this doc- trine cannot be directly transferred to the Deity, conceived as One. * Metaph. xiii. 6, 1080 b, 18 sqq. after the quotation on p. 370, 1: Töv yöp 3Aov oipavov ka- Tao-Keväçovalv čá ápióuðv, TXhv of plovačuków, &AA& Tàs ſtováðas Štro- Aapºdvovorty éxely uéyeffos - 6tra's he to trpátov čv avvéatm éxov ačye60s, &topeiv čoikaoiv . . . plovačukovs 6* Tobs &piðuous sival travres rifféaqi trajv Tów IIv6ayopetov, Šoot to ev otolyetov kal &pxiiv paolveival tor àvrav čkéivot 3' xovira Auéyebos. Cf. next note, and what has been quoted p. 400, 1, from Metaph. xiv. 3. * Metaph. vii. 2, 1028 b, 15: 80ke? 6é riot q & Too ord paros trépara, ofov Čiriq'dveta kal Ypappuh kal atlyuh kal uovás, eival oigtai MaxNov, h to adua kal rô otépedy; iii. 5, 1002 ha- ~, “sº &: *) zy - º ** **-* .# fºr 2-tº 408 THE PYTHAGOREANS, declaring that the Pythagoreans held mathematical figures to be the principle of the corporeal, and reduced them to points or units; that they regarded these units partly as something extended in space, and partly also as the constituents of numbers ; and consequently taught that corporeal things consist of numbers." We find similar thoughts among other writers of the later period,” though they do not precisely attribute them a, 4: &AA& u}v Tó ye oróua ñtrov oùota t is étruqavetas, kal airm tis 'ypaupils, kal # ypapºpº Tiis pová80s kai rās arriºuis' roötous yöp &ptotal to a 6aa, kal r& Mév Švev ord watos évôéxeoréal boke? eival, rö 5& orówa. &vev troërov eival &öövarov. 616trep of uèv troAAol &c. (vide Supra, p. 369, 1), xiv. 3, 1090 a, 30 (supra, p. 370, 1), ibid. 1090 b, 5: eioſi Bé rives of éic rod Trépara elval kal éoxara, thy ortyuhu ſvěv Ypappuis, Taúrmv 6’ 3ritréðov, Tooro 6% too a repeod, otovrat eival &váykmv totaú- tas qigorets eival. De Coelo, iii. 1, 298 b, 33: eior) Sé rives, oi kal trav orðua yew.vmtöv trotovoi, orvutt0évres kal 6taxłovres é: étruiréðov kai eis erſtreča. Aristotle, however, seems to be thinking only of Plato, and quotes expressly the Timaeus. At the end of the chapter, after having refuted this opinion, he says: rö 8' airò orvuòalvet kal toſs éé àpuðuðv oruvrifleſort Töv oipavóv. čviol yèp rºw pūow éº &piðuáv ovvioraoru, &atrep róv IIv6ayopetov rivés. Metaph. xiv. 5, 1092 b, 11, can hardly refer to this subject. Wide Pseudo- Alex. ad. h. 1. 1 Alex. in Metaph. i. 6, 987 b, 33; p. 41 Bon. : 3px?s uév táv ëvrov toos &piðuois IIAárov te kal oi IIv6ayópetol interíðevro, öti éööket aëtoſs to trpárov &px?, eival kal to ào'àv6erov, rôv 8& orandºrov trpóra r& £rſtreča sival (tà y&p &tx000 repú re ka) uh ovvavatpot wena trpáta Tij qūoet) étruiréðwy Śē Ypappai karð rov oùröv Aóyov, Ypaupiðv 5& ortlywal, &s of uaômuatikol onweta, airol 3& Mováðas #Aeyov . . . ai 3& Mováðes aptówol, of dipté pºol &pa trpárov táv ãvrov. PS.-Alex. in Metaph. xiii. 6, p. 723 Bon. : kal oi IIv6ayópelot 8è Éva apifluov eival voutſovoi, kal Tíva roorov ; rôv paômuaruköv, tr}\hv oi kexaptoruévoy rôv aio.6m rév, &s of trepl Eevokpármv, où'ěš wovačuköv, tov'réativ šuep? kal doróparov (uova- ðuköv Y&p rô &peoës kal &aguarov, ëvraúða 5mx07), &AA& T&s uováðas kai ÖmAovári kal rows &piðuois àtro- Aapſ3&vovites uéyebos éxeiv čk toirwy rès aiorðmºrås oioſtas kal rôv Štravra. oùpavöv eſval Aéyovoiv. čxeiv 8& ràs Mováðas uéyebos Karea ketaſov of IIv6. Stå rotofºrov twos Aóryov. čAeyov of v 3rt éretë ic rod trpárov čvös ağral ovvéormorav, to 8& irpárov ev uéyebos éxel, àváykm kal air&s ue- Meyeſ}vapiévas elval. In the other passages of the Metaphysics which we have quoted in the preceding notes, Alexander and his epitomiser do not speak of the Pythagoreans. * Nikom. Inst. Arithm. ii. 6, p. 45; Boeth. Arithm. ii. 4, p. 1328; Nikom. ii. 26, p. 72, does not relate to this question. NATURE OF THEIR PRINCIPLES. 409 to the Pythagoreans. Philolaus attempts to derive sometimes the corporeal in general, and sometimes the physical fundamental qualities of bodies from figures, and figures from numbers. From this Ritter concludes,' and Hermann " and Steinhart” agree with him, that the Limiting principle of the Pythagoreans was the unit, or, viewed in regard to space, the point; and the Unlimited, the interspace or the void; when, therefore, they said that all things consist of the Limit and the Unlimited, they meant that all things are composed of points and empty interspaces, and when they asserted that all things are number, this was only to express that these points together form a number. Reinhold * and Brandis" contest this, not because they maintain more strongly the arithmetical nature of the Pythagorean numbers, but because they would have them regarded as material; for in their judgment, the Pythagoreans understood by the Unlimited, the material cause of the corporeal,” and accordingly numbers, of which all things consist, must have been conceived by them as some- thing corporeal : number, Reinhold considers, arises from the determination of the indeterminate matter by Lnity or Limit, and things are called numbers because all things consist of a manifold element determined by Unity. Against this, Ritter rightly urges” that we ought to distinguish between the Pythagorean doctrines them- Pyth. Phil. 93 sqq., 137; Metaphysik, p. 28 sq. Gesch. der Phil. i. 403 sq. * Gr. Rein. Phil. 1, 486. * Plat. Phil. 164 sqq., 288 sq. * According to Brandis, some- * Haller. Allg. Literature. 1845, thing similar to breath or fire. 895 sq. Similarly, Chaignet ii. According to Reinhold, indetermi- 33; 36, 1; 39, 1. nate, manifold, unformed matter. 4 Beitrag zur Erl, d. Pyth. . * Gesch. der Phil. i. 405 sq. 410 THE PPTHAGOREANS, selves and Aristotle's conclusions from them. The ma- teriality of the Pythagorean numbers was first deduced by Aristotle from the doctrine that all is number; the Pythagoreans can never have explained numbers and their elements as something corporeal; for Aristotle ex- pressly says that they did not intend, by their concept of the Limited, the Unlimited and the One, to describe a substratum of which these concepts were predicated; * and this would unquestionably have been the case if the Unlimited had been, in their opinion, merely un- limited matter. He observes that the number of which all things consist must, according to their theory, have been mathematical number, and he charges them on this account with the contradiction of making bodies arise from the incorporeal, and the material from the immaterial.” This conclusion, however, can only be valid from an Aristotelian or some other later standpoint. To anyone accustomed to discriminate between corporeal and incorporeal, it must seem evident that bodies can * Arist. Metaph. xiii. 6, inter- éoriv, De Carlo, iii. 1, end: the mingles his own explanations with Pythagorean doctrine, according to the Pythagorean doctrine, as Ritter which all is number, is as illogical remarks, loc. cit. This appears in the use of such expressions as: p.a6muaticos &piðubs (opposed to the &p. vonrös), &piðubs oi kexaplopévos, aiorómral oigtai. This procedure is very usual with him elsewhere. * Wide supra, p. 370, 1. * Metaph. xiii. 8, 1083 b, 8: 68& rôv IIv6aºyopetov Tpétros Tſ wºv éAdºrrows éxel Svoxepeias rôv troë- repov eipmuévov tí, ók ióías &répas. ró uév yöp whyapuatáv troteiu roy àpiðuðv &qaipeirai troAA& Tóváčvvá- tov Tó Sé Tó, odºuata éé àpiðuðv eival avykefueva kal Tov ćpiðubv toū- tov eiwat waſnuaruków &öövatów as the Platonic construction of the elementary bodies: Tâ wév yêp qvarikā ord plato, paiveral Bápos #xovra kal coupótºmta, rås 6é uovd- 6as otre oºpa Troteſv oióv re ovvriès- Mévas otºre Bápos éxeiv. Metaph. i. 8, 990 a, 12, even supposing that magnitudes could result from the Limited and the Unlimited, riva Tpétrov čo Tai Tà uév kotºpa Tè, 5è Bápos éxovta Tóv orogórav; ibid. xiv. 3 (vide Supra, p. 370, 1), where also the Pythagoreans are reckoned among those who only admitted mathematical number. NATURE OF THEIR PRINCIPLES. 411 only be compounded out of bodies, and so it inevitably follows that numbers and their elements must be some- thing corporeal if bodies are to consist of them. The special characteristic of the Pythagorean Philosophy however lies in this, that such a distinction is as yet unrecognised, and that, in consequence, number as such is regarded not only as the form, but as the matter of the corporeal. Yet number itself is not on that account necessarily conceived as corporeal; for it is clear that qualities and relations which no one except the Stoics, or before their time, ever considered as bodies, were expressed in the Pythagorean Philosophy by numbers. The Pythagoreans not only defined man, or plants, or the earth by numbers, but asserted that two is opinion, four justice, five marriage, seven the opportune time, etc." Nor is this simple comparison. The meaning in both cases is that the specified number is properly and directly the thing with which it is compared. It is a confounding of symbol and concept, a mixture of the accidental and the substantial, which we cannot discard without mistaking the essential peculiarity of Pythagorean thought. As we cannot assert that bodies were regarded as immaterial by the Pythagoreans, be- cause, according to them, bodies consisted of numbers, so neither, on the other hand, can we infer that num- bers must have been something corporeal, because they could not otherwise have been the elements of bodies. Bodies meant to them all that presents itself to the sense-perception; numbers meant that which is appre- hended by mathematical thought; and the two things * Wide infra, § iv. 412 THE PPTHAGOREANS, were directly identified, while the inadmissibility of such a procedure was unnoticed. For similar reasons, it is of no avail to prove that the One, the Unlimited and the Void receive a material signification in the Pythagorean physics. We read, it is true, that in the forming of the world, the nearest part of the Un- limited became attracted and limited by the first One," and that outside the world was the Unlimited, from which the world inhaled empty space and time.” In this connection the One certainly appears as material unity, and the Unlimited to some extent as unlimited space, to some extent also as an infinite mass; but it by no means follows that the two conceptions have always the same meaning apart from this order of ideas: on the contrary, we have here an instance of what we so often find with the Pythagoreans—that a general conception receives a special determination from its application to a particular case, although this determi- nation does not on that account essentially belong to the conception, nor exclude other applications of it, in which it may be used in a different sense. It was only by the help of such a method that the Pythagoreans could apply the theory of numbers to concrete phe- momena. It is possible that in certain cases the One, the Unlimited, Number, &c., may have been regarded as corporeal. But we cannot conclude from this that they were wrviversally conceived as such. We must remember that numerical determinations are very va- riously employed by the Pythagoreans, and that the * Wide supra, p. 400, 1, and Cf. iii. 4, 203 a, 6; Stobaeus, Eel. p. 407, 2. i. 380; Plut. Plac. ii. 9, 1. Further * Arist. Phys. iv. 6, 213 b, 22. details, infr. Cosmology. MATURE OF THEIR PRINCIPLES. 413 unlimited and the limited are of different kinds," which are not clearly distinguished because the language of Philosophy was as yet too unformed, and thought too unpractised in logical deduction and the analysis of concepts. For similar reasons I must contest Ritter's theory. That the Pythagoreans derived bodies from geometrical figures is true, and will be shown later on ; it is also true that they reduced figures and space-dimensions to numbers, the point to Unity, the line to Duality, and so on, and that they reckoned infinite space, intermediate space, and the void under the head of the Unlimited.” But it does not follow from this that by Unity they understood nothing but the point, by the Unlimited nothing but empty space; here again all that we have just said as to the application of their principles to phenomena holds good. They themselves designate by the name of the Unity not the point merely, but the soul; by that of Duality, not the line merely, but opinion; they make time as well as empty space enter the world from the Unlimited. It is evident that the conceptions of the Limit, the Unlimited, Unity, Number, have a wider compass than those of the point, the void and figures; figures, at any rate, are expressly distinguished from the numbers by which they are | Ritter says (i. 414) that the Indeterminate as such can have no species; but in the first place this expression is in itself incorrect; for the unlimited in space, the un- limited in time, qualitative un- limitedness, &c., are so many kinds of the Unlimited. And in the second place it could not possibly be said of the Pythagorean system. * Cf. p. 414, 2, and Arist. De Caelo, ii. 13, 293 a, 30, where it is spoken of as an opinion of the Pythagoreans that the limit is more noble (tipudºrepov) than that which lies between. From this we may conclude that the uérači is closely related to the Unlimited. 414 THE PPTHAGOREANS. defined; and the void is spoken of in a manner that, strictly interpreted, must apply to the Limiting, and not to the Unlimited.” Not much stress, however, can be laid upon the last-mentioned circumstance, because the Pythagoreans seem to have here involved themselves in a contradiction with their other theories. But the most decisive argument against the in- terpretations we have been enumerating is derived from the consideration of the Pythagorean system as a whole; for its arithmetical character can only be understood if we suppose that the conception of num- * Arist. Metaph. vii. 11, 1036 b, 12: &váyoval ºrdvra eis rows àpiðuot's kal Ypaupis row Aéryov row rôy 680 elval pagw. Cf. xiv. 5, 1092 b, 10 : &s Eüpvros érarte, Tſs àpiðubs Tſvos, oiov 66l uèv čv6pótrov, 66, 6& introv. Plato spokein a simi- lar manner of a number of the plane and of the solid, but he did not therefore regard numbers as extended or corporeal (Arist. De An. i. 2, 404 b, 21 ; cf. Part ii. a, 636, 4; 807, 2, third edition). In Metaph. xiii. 9, 1085 a, 7 figures, from the point of view of Platonists who favoured Pythagoreanism, are expressly called rå Öorepov yevn rod diplôuod, the class which comes after number (the genitive àpt0400 is governed by datepov, not by ºyévn; cf. Metaph. i. 9, 992 b, 13). * The void is considered as se- parating all things, from each other. Arist. Phys. iv. 6, 213 b, 22: eiwat 6' pagav kal of IIv6ayópelot keybv, ical étreloiéval airro tº otpavá, ëk roß &teſpov rvetuatos (which Chaignet [ii. 70, 157], as it seems to me unnecessarily, would have omitted or changed into trveijua. Tennemann [Gesch. d. Phil. i. 110] also prefers truedux) &s dwarvéovri kal to Kevöv, & Stopfges r&s pūgels . kal tour' elval trpórov čv Tols dpuðuois to yop kevöv 8topſgeuv Thy qāorw airów (which Philop. De Gen. An. 51 a, develops no doubt merely according to his own fancy). Similarly Stobaeus, i. 380. Now the separating principle as such is also the limiting principle; for the assertion of Brandis that the difference of numbers is derived from the Unlimited, and their determination from Unity, is un- tenable. What constitutes the distinction of one thing from another, except its determination in regard to that other thing? If then we hold to the proposition that the void is the principle of separation, it must itself be placed on the side of the limiting, and con- sequently that which is separated by the void must be placed on the opposite side. We must, with Ritter, i. 418 sq., consider the One as a continuous magnitude split up by the void. But this would manifestly be to change each into its contrary. NATURE OF THEIR PRINCIPLES. 415 ber formed its point of departure. Had it started from the consideration of unlimited matter, and of particles of matter, a system of mechanical physics, similar to the Atomistic system must have been the result. Nothing of this kind is to be found in pure Pythagoreanism. The number-theory, on the other hand, the most essential and specific part of the system, could never in that case have arisen: the proportions of bodies might perhaps have been defined accord- ing to numbers, but there would have been no pos- sible reason for regarding numbers as the substance of things. This, the fundamental conception of the whole system, can only be accounted for, if the system be dominated by the idea of numerical relations, if its original tendency were to regard bodies as numbers, and not numbers as bodies. We are expressly told that Ecphantus, a later philosopher, who scarcely can be Thumbered among the Pythagoreans at all, was the first to explain the Pythagorean Monads as something corporeal." The ancient Pythagoreans cannot have held such an opinion, for in that case they must have believed the corporeal to have been something original, instead of deriving it, as we have just shown that they did, out of mathematical figures.” Nor can they have 1 Stob. Eel. i. 308: "Ekpavros >upakoëorios eſs rôv IIv6ayopetov ºrgvrov [äpx&s] tº &ötaipeta ord para kal to kevöv. (Cf. ibid, p. 448.) Tàs yop IIvBayopticas wováðas oitos rpáros &tedſivaro gouattkás. For further details on this philosopher, vide § vii. The statement, ap. Plut. Plac. i. 11, 3 ; Stob. i. 336, that Pythagoras regarded the first principles as incorporeal, stands in connection with other statements of a very suspicious character, and can- not, therefore, be made use of here. * This would still be true, even if the conjecture of Brandis (i. 487) were well founded—viz., that besides the attempt already quoted, other attempts were made by the Pythagoreans to explain the deri- 416 THE PITHAGOREA.N.S. originally meant by the Unlimited infinite matter. The Unlimited must have acquired this import indirectly in its application to the cosmos; otherwise it is in- comprehensible how they came to explain the Unlimited as the Even. The same considerations hold good as against the theory of Ritter. Since geometrical figures were derived from numbers, the elements of figure—that is to say the point and the interspace— must be posterior to the elements of number, and so they were unquestionably regarded by the Pythagoreans. For the odd and the even cannot be derived from the point and the interspace, whereas it is quite con- ceivable from the Pythagorean point of view that the odd and the even should first have been discriminated as elements of number, that the more general antithesis of the Limiting and the Unlimited should thence have been attained, and in the application of this to space re- lations, that the point should have been regarded as the first limit of space, and empty space as the unlimited. Had the Pythagorean philosophy taken' the opposite course, and proceeded from space dimensions and figures to numbers, the geometrical element in it must have predominated over the arithmetical; figure, instead of number, must have been declared to be the essence of things; and the system of geometrical figures must have taken the place of the decuple numerical system. Even harmony could no longer have had the great significance that it possessed for the Pythagoreans, vation of the thing extended; for this point, for the passage in Arist. the thing extended would remain Metaph. xiv. 3 (vide p. 400) does in this case something derived; not justify this conclusion; cf. but we have no certain evidence on Ritter, i. 410 sq. STARTING-POINT OF THE SYSTEM. 417 since the relations of tones were never reduced by them to space relations. Having thus shown the essentially arithmetical character of the Pythagorean principles, it only re- mains to enquire how these principles were related to one another, and wherein lay the specific point of departure of the system ; whether the Pythagoreans were led from the proposition that all is number to the discrimination of the elements of which numbers and things consist, or conversely from the perception of the primitive opposites to the doctrine that the essence of things lies in number. The exposition of Aristotle tells in favour of the first opinion; for, according to him, the Pythagoreans first concluded from the simi- larity of things to numbers, that all things were num- bers, and afterwards coupled with this proposition the distinction of the opposite elements of which numbers consist.' Philolaus, on the contrary, began his work with the doctrine of the Limit and the Unlimited,” which might incline us to presuppose that this, or an analogous definition, contained the proper root of the Pythagorean system, and that the Pythagoreans had only reduced all things to number because they thought they perceived in number the first combination of the limited and the unlimited, of unity and multiplicity.” This, however, is not necessarily the case; Philolaus, for the sake of logical argument, may very likely have placed * Wide supra, p. 369, 1; 370, 1. Duality, or of Unity and Multi- * Supra, p. 39, 1. plicity, as the principle of the Py- * Cf. Marbach, Gesch. d. Phil. thagorean doctrine—e.g. Braniss, i. 108, Ritter, Pyth. Phil. 134 sq., Gesch. der Phil. S. Kant, i. 110 sq., and generally all those who con- 114 sq., &c. sider the opposition of Unity and WOL, I. -4 - E E. 418 - THE PYTHAGOREANS, that last which, historically, was the beginning of the system. On the other hand, we must certainly consider the exposition of Aristotle as primarily his own view, not as direct evidence establishing a fact. Yet there is every probability that this view is based upon an exact knowledge of the real interconnection of the Pytha- gorean ideas. It is, indeed, most likely that the start- ing point of a system so ancient, and so independent of any earlier scientific developments, would have been formed by the simplest and most obvious presentation; that the thought which was less developed therefore, and more directly connected with relations sensibly perceived, the thought that all is number, would have been prior to the reduction of number to its ele- ments; and that the arithmetical distinction of the even and the odd would have preceded the more abstract logical distinction of the unlimited and the limited. If we maintain this latter distinction to have been the fundamental idea from which sprang the further development of the system, it is hard to see why it should immediately have taken an arithmetical turn, instead of a more general and metaphysical direction. The proposition that all is number, and composed of the odd and the even, cannot possibly be derived from the theories concerning the limited and unlimited; but these might very easily and naturally have arisen out of that proposition." The exposition, therefore, of Aristotle, is fully justified. The funda- mental conception from which the Pythagorean philo- sophy starts, is contained in the proposition that all is * Cf. Supra, p. 376 sq. APPLICATION OF THE WUMBER—THEORY. 419 number; in the next place, the opposite determinations in number—the odd and the even—were distinguished and compared, at first indeed very unmethodically, with other opposites, such as right and left, masculine and feminine, good and evil; the more abstract ex- pression of the limited and unlimited, although at a later time this opposition was placed by Philolaus at the head of the system, and so appears in the decuple table of categories, must belong to a more developed stage of reflection. Thus the principal ideas of this system are developed simply enough from one thought, and that thought is of a kind which might easily occur to the reflecting mind from the observation of the external world, even in the childhood of science." IV. THE PYTHAGOREAN PHILOSOPHY (continued). SYSTEMATIC DEVELOPMENT OF THE NUMBER—THEORY, AND ITS APPLICATION TO PHYSICS. IN the further development and application of their number-theory, the procedure of the Pythagoreans was for the most part unmethodical and arbitrary. They sought in things, says Aristotle,” a similarity with * After the remarks on p. 312, 1; 343, 4, I think it is unnecessary to append a criticism of the exposition of the theory of numbers and of the Pythagoreantheologygiven by Röth (ii. a, 632 sq., 868 sq.). It is im- possible to enter on a discussion of the primitive form of the Pytha- gorean doctrine with an author who seeks true Pythagoreanism in the Orphic fragments, and sees in the texts of Aristotle and Philolaus only spurious Pythagoreanism. Such a discussion becomes absolutely out of the question when the historian intermingles in an entirely arbi- trary manner his own ideas with the sources he adopts. * Metaph. i. 5 (cf. p. 369, 1): ral 3a a sixov ćuoxo'yočwea vöeukvi vat $v re rois àpt0aois ſcal rats àpuo- wiats trpos ré, rot, oùpavoi, Trdón ral is E 2 420 THE PYTHAGOREANS numbers and numerical relations; and the category of numbers which in this manner they obtained as an object, they regarded as the essence of that object. If, however, in any case reality did not entirely agree with the presup- posed arithmetical scheme, they resorted to hypotheses like that of the counter-earth to procure agreement. Thus they said that justice consisted of the equal multi- plied by the equal, or in the square number, because it re- turns equal for equal ; and they therefore identified jus- tice with four, as the first square number, or nine, as the first unequal square number. So seven was the critical time, because in the opinion of the ancients, the climacteric years were determined by it; five, as the union of the first masculine with the first feminine number, was called marriage; one was reason, because it is unchangeable; two, opinion, because it is variable and indeterminate.” By further combinations of such Aépm kal irpos thv ŠAmu 5takéopºmoriv, in the sequel to make the definition Tajra ovvdyovres éqipuottov. kāv of justice also from the inverse e? Tí trov ŠléAeltre trpoo’eyAixovto toū avvelpouévnv traorav airtois eival Thy Trpayuareíav, which is immedi- ately proved by the example of the counter-earth. * They also denominated justice the &vritretrov66s, Arist. Eth. Nic. v. 8, sub init. ; M. Mor. i. 34, 1194 a, 28; Alex. in Met. wide next note. Here, however, not the in- verse ratio in the mathematical sense, but simply remuneration, seems to be intended: for there results from the judge doing to the offender what the offender has done to the offended, not an inverse, but a direct ratio A: B = B: C. But it is possible that the expression &vritrerov6bs led the Pythagoreans proportion. The same thought of remuneration is expressed in the complicated, and evidently later, definition ap. Iambl. Theol. Arithm. p. 29 sq. * Arist. Metaph. i. 5; vide p. 369: ibid. xiii. 4, 1078 b, 21 : oi ôè IIv6ayópelot trpórepov trepſ twov ãxt yov (éſàrovv ka0óNov Špigeo (al), ôv roës A6-yous eis rºs &piðuous ăvătrov, oiov tí Čorti kalpos ?) to 6tratov 3 yduos. Similarly, ibid. xiv. 6, 1093 a, 13 sq., where the Pythagoreans are not named, but where they are certainly al- luded to. M. Mor. i. 1, 1182 a, 11, where the definition of justice as āptôubs iodicus toos is attributed to Pythagoras. Alex- APPLICATION OF THE NUMBER—THEORY. 421 analogies, there resulted theorems like these : that this or that conception had its seat in this or that part of the world; opinion, for example, in the region of the earth; the proper time in that of the sun, because they are both denoted by ander, in Metaph. i. 5, 985 b, 26, p. 28, 23 Bon: tíva 6% to Öpotówara ev toºs &pifluois &Aeyov eival trpos té. $vta Te kal yivöweva, śājiàoore. Tijs pºv yūp 5ticaloa tºwns towov ŠtroAgušć- vovires éival to &vºritretrov6ós Te Kal to ov, Šv toºs àpiðuo's rooro eipia- Icovres bv, Šuš Towto kai Töv iodicus Žorov &piðubv trpárov čAeyov eival St- Katoo wivny... totrov 8& of wév Töv Téo- orapa šAeyov (so also Iambl. Th. Ar. p. 24, from a more complicated rea- son). . of 8& Töv čvvéa, §s éort trpátos Terpäyovos. (This is a ‘reading of Bonitz, instead of ortepebs, as given by the manuscripts.) ātro arepittoo toi, Tpía ép' airby yewoué- vov (cf. Iambl. p. 29) kapov 8& ard Niv čNeyov Töv čírtá čokeſ y&p rà. quatic& rows Texeious kalpots to xely tral yewéorea's kal Texeiðorews karð. é9öopuděas, Ös én áv6póirov. kai yüp ríkretal étraumviata, kal 650yroqve? ºrogovtåv étáv, kal #840 kel treph Thy Sevrépav č8öopºdóa, ſcal yewetā trepi Thy Tpírmy kal Töv #Atov Šč, ćitel airbs attio's eival Töv captröv, p.mol, ãokeſ, évraú6á pagiviðpü00at ka9'? § §8öopas àpiðués éa riv (in the seventh place of the periphery of the world) by kalpöv Aéryovoriv . . . trel 6è oëre yevvá rivö. Töv čv tí Šeköt &piðuáv 6 árrà of Te yevvårat āró rivos airtóv, Šuš Tooro kal 'A6mvāv ëAeyov airby (cf. Th. Ar. p. 42, 54, &c.) . . . yduov 8& éAeyov Tov Trévre, 3rt à pièv yduos oºvoãos #ffevós éatt Ical 6% Aeos, Štt ö& kat' airobs &#ffew uèv to trepitrov 678w 6è to &priov, irporos 3& oftos é; àptſov toº 300 tp%tov kai irpátov the same number." In a Too Tpta treptºrtoi, Thy yéveauv čxel . vojv Šē kal oia'tav čAeyov to év' Thu yöp (buxhv ćis rôv votiv eitre (Arist. l. c.). Ötö. Tö p.69ipov 8& kal To Špotov távrm Rai Tô &pxuköv row woov uováða re kai év čAeyov (simi- larly, Th. Ar. p. 8, where further details will be found. Philolaus, however [vide infra], assigned Reason to the number seven) &AA& kal oia'tav, 3rt trpótov ji oiota. 668av 6é Tó, 600 Suð. To T' &udo we'ra- BAmriju eival Aeyov 6& kal kivmotiv aüthy kal étríðeariv (?). But here, already, especially in the reasons adduced for the support of the various designations, many recent elements seem to be intermingled. This is still more largely the case in regard to the other commenta- tors of the passage in Aristotle (Schol. in Arist. p. 540 b sqq.) and such writers as Moderatus ap. Porph. Wit. Pythag. 49 sqq.; Stob. i. 18; Nicomachus ap. Phot. Cod. 187; Jambl. Theol. Arithm. 8 sq.; Theo, Math. c. 3, 40 sqq.; Plut. De Is. c. 10, 42, 75, p. 354, 367, 381; Porph. De Abstin. ii. 36 &c. I therefore abstain from making further citations from these au- thors, for although in what they quote there may be many things really belonging to the ancient Pythagoreans, yet we can never be certain on this point. In general, the text that we have quoted above, from Aristotle, Met. xiii. 4, should make us mistrustful of these state- Inent S. . 1. Cf. on this point what is said 422 THE PPTHAGO REANS. similar manner, certain numbers,' or certain figures and further on, of the relation of the terrestrial region to Olympus, and Arist. Metaph. i. 8, 990 a, 18. How is it possible to explain the celestial phenomena on the Pytha- gorean hypotheses? §tav yūp év Tººl wºv tº uépel 66&c. Kal Kapòs auro's fi, pukpóv Šē &va,6ev h kärw8ev a jurcía (al. &vurcía, according to Iambl. Theol. Arithm. p. 28, we might conjecture &velicía, but Alex. thinks &vikia more probable, cf. p. 429, 6), kai kpia is à uºus, &tóðelčiv 6è Aéyaoiv, 3rt roſtav pºv čv ékao- Tov &pt046s éoti, a vpgaivet 8& Katë. -öv Tótrov To 0 ºr o y # 6 m. TA760s cival Tów avvuatapévov we’ye6ów 8 i & ºr 0 rô Trø0m raßTa &rcoxověeiv Tols rótrous ékáo rous, trórepov oitos é aúrós éotiv &piðubs 6 &v Tó oëpavó, §v Šeſ Aabeiv Šti Toitov čkao Tév éotiv, 3) trapo roorov &AAos. This passage has never been fully ex- plained, either by recent commenta- tors, or by Christ, Stud. in Arist. libr. metaph. coll. (Berlin, 1853), p. 23 Sq. The best expedient seems to be to substitute for Suð. To ‘5ub (as, perhaps, was done by Alexan- der), and to insert ‘Tooto’ before #öm (I formerly conjectured roël, instead of jöm, but Alexander is in favour of #5m). The meaning be- comes then : ‘If the Pythagoreans place in certain determinate parts of the heavens opinion, the proper time, &c., and in support of this doctrine assert that each of these concepts is a determinate number (opinion, for example, is the num- ber two), and that furthermore, this or that portion of the universe comprehends in itself precisely that number of celestial bodies (the terrestrial region, for example, is the place of two, because the earth occupies the second place in the series of celestial bodies), and that consequently these concepts belong to these regions (opinion to the earth, and the proper time [vide preceding note] to the sun): does it follow from all this that the corresponding spheres of the uni- verse are or are not identical with these concepts? ' * Joh. Lydus, De mens. iv. 44, p. 208, Röth, buwóAaos thv čváða. Kpóvov oſtveuvov (Rhea, the Earth, vide the following note) elval Aéyet (because the Earth is the second celestial body counting from the centre). Moderatus ap. Stob. i. 20: IIv6ayópas . . . Tois 6eois àtrel- kášov ćiravöuagev [Toys &piðuous], às 'AtróAAova uév Thy uðvača of gav (according to the etymology which he assigns to the name of the god, a privative and troAffs, and which is very common among later writers, cf. vol.iii.a,306, 6, 2nd ed.)"Aprepuy ôè riv Švača (perhaps because of the resemblance of "Apreputs and &ptios) Tºv 8& éčáða yduov kal 'Aq poètºrmv, Thy đê é8öopadāa kalpöv kal 'A6mvåv. 'Aorq6Atov Šē IIoaetóóva rºw &yö0áða (the number of the cube ; the cube [vide infra] is the form of the Larth, and Poseidon is the yai- #oxos), kal rºw belcáða IIavréAelav. The Theol. Arithm. give many names of this sort for numbers. The assertions of Moderatus in respect of the numbers one, two, seven, and eight, are confirmed by Blutarch De Is. c. 10, p. 354; in part also by Alexander (vide the note before the last). Alexander says in the same place, c. 75 (cf. Theol. Arith. p. 9), that the Dyad was also called Eris aud rôxpm. On the other hand, Philo, De Mundi Opif. 22 E, affirms that the other philosophers compare the APPLICATION OF THE NUMBER-THEORY. 423 their angles,' were assigned to particular gods; here number seven to Athene, but that the Pythagoreans compare it to the Supreme God, which they do for the same reason, because it neither begets nor was begotten. This last interpretation is manifestly of later origin. As to the general fact, that numbers were designated by the names of the gods, there seems no doubt. 1 Plut. De Is. c. 75: of 6& IIv6a- yópelot kal &piðuous kal oxhuata 6eóv ékógumorav trpoo`myopials. To Aév y&p igóttàewpov rptywyov čkůNovv 'A0mvāv kopupa'yevi, kal Tpitoyévetav, âtt rpial ka9érois &to róv rpiów 'ywvióv &yopuévals ötaipeirai. Ibid. c. 30: Aéyoval yèp (oi IIv0.), Évêpt{q, pérpº errº kai trevrmkoortg'veyovéval Tuqāva kai trčAw, thv pèv too Tplºydºvou (se. Yovíav) "Abov Kal Atovão'ou kal "Apeos eival' rºv 8& rod Terpayóvov ‘Péas kal 'Appoèttºms kal Aftwmrpos kal ‘Eortlas kal"Hpas' rhy 8& Too Sobekayóvov Atós' Thy 6è ēkkaitrevrmkovrayavíou Tuq6vos, &s Eööoč0s ioTópmkev. Procl. in Eucl. i. p. 36 (130 Fr.) : kai yüp trapá toºs IIv0ayopetous eñphorouev &AAas 'yovías &AAous 6eois àvancelpwévas, $ortrep kal 6 pixóAaos retroimke toſs aëv rºw rpuyavikhv yovíav roſs Šč thv retpayovukhv & piepāoras, kal &AA&s &AAous kal rºw airhv tràefoot 9eois. Ibid. p. 46 (166 f. Fr.): eikóTws &pa 6 pixóxaos thu Toi Tpt- 'ydºvou yovíav réttapo w &vé6mke 6eois, Kpóvº kal "Aön Kal”Apei kal Atovágg. Ibid. p. 48 (173 Fr.): Sokeſ 3& roſs IIv6ayopetous toūro [rb Terpdºwvov Staqepóvrws rôv rerpa- TAetºpov eikóva (pépelv 0etas oia'tas . . kal trpos rotºrous 6 pixóAaos . . . T}v roß retpayávov yovíav ‘Péas kal Aftwmrpos kai ‘Earías &trokaxe. Ibid. p. 174 Fr.: thv učv rplywVikhv ºyovíav 6 pixóAaos rértapgiv čvākey [ävé0mke] 6eois Thy đê retpayavikºv Tptoſiv. Ibid.: thvºyöp rot, 8vočeka- ºyóvow yovtav Atos éivaí pnow 6 pi- AóAaos, &s karū uíav Évooru roi, Aubs 6Aov ovvéxovros rov Tijs 5vočekáö0s àpiðuáv. As to the reasons for these assertions, tradition tells us nothing. What Proclus says on the subject is evidently based on his own conjectures, springing for the most part from the sphere of Neo- Platonic ideas. It would seem the most probable solution to admit that the angle must have been con- secrated to Rhea, Demeter, and Hestia, as goddesses of the earth; because the square is the surface which limits the cube, and the cube, as we shall see, was, according to Philolaus, the primitive form of the earth. But this explanation does not agree with the names of the goddesses, Hera and Aphrodite, mentioned by Plutarch. Was the acute angle of the triangle conse- crated in the same sense to Hades, Dionysos, Ares, and Cronos ? (Per- haps because the primitive form of fire is the tetrahedron limited by four equilateral triangles, and that in these gods we find the destructive, and also the warming, nature of fire.) This is a question we cannot now discuss. As to the dodecagon, Böckh (Philol. 157) has already remarked that it cannot be reduced to the dodecahedron, which Philc- laus designates as the primitive form of Æther and of the celestial sphere; for the dodecahedron is limited by regular pentagons. Nevertheless, the agreement of these two witnesses, both much versed in mathematics, leaves no doubt that they really found this fact in the source they were con- sulting. But this difficulty does 424 THE PPTHAGOREA.N.S. again, only isolated and arbitrary points of comparison are in question. It was unavoidable from the capri- cious irregularity of this whole procedure, that among all these comparisons there should be numerous contra- dictions; that the same number or figure should receive various significations,” and on the other hand, that the not authorise the modifications of the text, and the forced interpre- tations which Röth, ii. b, 285 sq., advocates on the ground of common sense; they could hardly be based on the Pythagorean mathematics, from which it is by no means self- evident that the angle of the triangle could only have been consecrated to three deities, and the angle of the square to four. (Plutarch and Proclus both have rºw yovíav, and not tës youtas; and Proclus ex- pressly adds that the same angle could be assigned to many gods; their opinion, therefore, is not that each of the three angles of the tri- angle, and each of the four angles of the square, had its special divi- Inity.) On the other hand, this difficulty gives us no right to reject the whole statement of the his- toric Philolaus, and to ascribe it to a Pseudo-Philolaus, author of the fragments (Schaarschmidt, Schriftst. d. Philol. 43 sq.). The truth is that we are ignorant of the source of these strange assertions: it does not follow that they may not have had some foundation which Philolaus, from his own point of view, may have thought sufficient. If we once enter the region of imagination, it is difficult to set bounds to arbitrary caprices. Those we have been considering were doubtless not so arbitrary as what Aristotle (wide infra, p. 425, 2) quotes from Eurytus. Schaar- Schmidt is especially perplexed by the attribution of the dodecagon to Zeus, while the fragments of Phi- lolaus regard the decad as the number which rules the universe. This presents to me no greater difficulty than to find in the theory of Philolaus respecting the ele- ments, the dodecahedron made the primitive form of Æther, or in the theory of harmony the octave divi- ded into six tones instead of ten. The system of number could not be directly applied to geometrical figures. In the same way that, among solids, the dodecahedron was attributed to the universal element, so among plane figures, bounded by straight lines, the equilateral dodecagon, easy to con- struct out of a square by means of equilateral triangles, taking a square as point of departure; easy also to inscribe in a circle—and the angle of which (= 150 degs.) is equal to the angle of the square (90 degs.) and of the equilateral triangle (60 degs.), might have been chosen as the symbol of the universe and of the Supreme god who rules the world as a whole (the twelve gods of the myth). * Cf. Arist. Metaph. xiv. 6, 1093 a, 1: ei 3’ &vdºykm trăvra &pið- woo koivovelv, &váyirm troAA& ovuflat- velv Tà aird. That which is desig- nated by the same number must be similar. * Compare in this respect with APPLICATION OF THE WUMBER—THEORY. 425 same object or concept should sometimes be denoted by one figure and sometimes by another; what whim- sical vagaries were permitted in regard to this subject even in the ancient Pythagorean school, we can see from the example of Eurytus, who attempted to prove the signification of particular numbers by putting together the figures of the things they designated out of the corresponding number of pebbles." The Pythagoreans, however, did not content them- selves with this arbitrary application of their principles, but sought to carry them out methodically by more precisely defining the numerical proportions according to which all things are ordered, and applying them to the different classes of the Real. We cannot indeed assert that the whole school entered on these discus- sions, and observed in their procedure the same plan ; even with regard to the work of Philolaus, which alone what results from the preceding notes, the statements that justice is designated by the number five (Iambl. Theol. Arith. p. 30, 33) or three (Plut. Ms. 75); health by the number seven (Philolaus, ap. Iambl. Th. Ar. p. 56) or six (ibid. p. 38); marriage by the numbers five, six, or three (Theol. Arithm. p. 18, 34); the sun by the decad (Th. Ar. p. 60); light by the number seven (Philolaus, loc. cit.) and by the number five (Theol. Ar. 28); the spirit by the monad, the soul by the dyad, opinion (66&a) by the triad, the body or sensation by the tetrad (Theo of Smyrna, c. 38, p. 152; Asclep. loc. cit. 541 a, 17, cf. p. 420, 2). It is true that the last-mentioned passage is certainly posterior to Plato; and that, as re- gards the rest, it is impossible to say what really belonged to the ancient Pythagoreans. * According to Aristotle, Me- taph. xiv. 5, 1092 b, 10 (where the words, Tóv puróv, l. 13, seem more- over to involve a fault certainly very ancient), and Theophr. Me- taph. p. 312 Br. (Fr. 12, 11); vide the excellent commentary of Alex- ander (in this case, the real Alex- ander) ad. Met. p. 805, Bon. ; cf. also Syrian in Metaph. Schol. 938 a, 27. I cannot understand how Chaignet, ii. 125, can deny to me the opinion that the ancient Pytha- gorean school ‘avait au moins Semé le germe d'où est sortie toute cette symbolique de fantaisie,” in spite of the preceding demonstrations, cited by himself (p. 126). 426 THE POYTHIAGOREA.N.S. could give us any clue on this subject, our knowledge is too scanty to allow of our determining with certainty the position which particular enquiries assumed in it. We shall, however, be adhering pretty closely to the natural connection of these enquiries if we first con- sider the number-system as such; next its application to tones and figures; thirdly, the doctrine of the ele- mentary bodies and motions about the universe; and finally, the theories on the terrestrial natures and man. It would be easy to reduce these divisions to more general points of view, but this I think ought not to be done, since we know nothing of any division of the Pythagorean system of philosophy corresponding with the later discrimination of three principal parts, or any other classification of the kind. In order to reduce numbers themselves to a fixed schema, the Pythagoreans employed the division of odd and even, and also the system of decads. The former has been already alluded to (p. 377); in its further development various species were discriminated from the even as well as from the odd ; whether these species were the same as are enumerated by later writers' is not quite certain, nor can we be sure how * Nicom. Inst. Arithm, p. 9 sq. : Theo. Math. i. c. 8 sq. Three kinds of numbers are here distin- guished among the even numbers, the āprudkus &priov (the numbers that can be divided by even num- bers down to Unity, like 64); the Treptororóptuov (the numbers which, divided by 2, give even numbers, but which, divided by any even number higher than 2, give uneven numbers like 12 and 20); and the ăpriotrépio'orov (vide supra, p. 377, 1), Similarly three kinds of numbers are distinguished in regard to un- even numbers, the trpárov kal &aiv6erov (the first numbers); the Seirepov kai oriv6erov (numbers which are the product of several uneven numbers, and are, there- fore, not divisible merely by unity, as 9, 15, 21, 25, 27); and lastly, the numbers divisible separately by other numbers than unity, but THE WUMERICAL SYSTEM. 427 many of the other divisions' of numbers which we find in more recent authors” belong to the ancient Pytha- gorean doctrine. Many of these ideas, no doubt, really belonged to the Pythagoreans.” But all these arith- metical principles, if we except the general distinction of odd and even, were far less important in regard to the Pythagorean cosmology than to Greek arithmetic, which here also followed the direction given to it by this school. The importance of the decuple system in relation to the Pythagoreans is much greater. For as they considered numbers over ten to be only the repe- tition of the first ten numbers,” all numbers and all powers of numbers appeared to them to be comprehended in the decad, which is therefore called by Philolaus,” great, all-powerful and all-producing, the beginning and the guide of the divine and heavenly, as of the terrestrial life. the relation of which to others is only to be defined by unities, as 9 and 25. * On the one hand, Philolaus in the fragment quoted on p. 377, 1, speaks of many kinds of even and odd; on the other, he does not, like more recent writers, give the ăpriotrépio'orov as a subdivision of the even, but as a third kind, side by side with the odd and the €V6I1. * Such as the distinction of square, oblong, triangular, poly- gonal, cylindric, spherical, corpo- real, and superficial numbers, &c., together with their numerous sub- divisions. &piðubs 58waus, kū80s, &c. Cf. Nicomachus, Theo, Iamblichus, Boethius, Hippolyt. Refut. i. 2, p. 10, &c. According to Aristotle," it is the * For example, the theory of gnomons (supra, p. 378, 1) of square and cubic numbers, &piðuol, Terpáyovoi and étépouſikets, of dia- gonal numbers (Plato, Rep. viii. 546 B sq.; cf. p. 429, 6). * Hierocl. in Carm. Aur. p. 166 (Fragm. Phil. i. 464): roi 38 &piðuoi, to metrepaguévov Štáortmua ñ 6ercás. 6 yap &m tračov &piðueſv é6éAov čva- káutrel argxiv ćirl to €v. It is for this reason that Aristotle blames Plato, and indirectly also the Py- thagoreans, for only counting num- bers up to ten. Phys. iii. 6, 206 b, 30; Metaph. xii. 8, 1073 a, 19; xiii. 8, 1084 a, 12: ei uéxpt Sekdāos é àpiðubs, &otrep Tivés paoruv. * Wide supra, p. 371 2. * Metaph. i. 5, 986 a, 8: éretón 428 THE PITHAGOREA.N.S. perfect and complete, which includes in itself" the whole essence of number; and as nothing, generally speaking, would be knowable without number, so in particular, we are indebted solely to the decad that knowledge is possible to us.” Four has a similar importance, not merely because it is the first square number, but chiefly because the four first numbers added together produce the perfect number, tem. In the famous Pythagorean oath, Pythagoras is therefore celebrated as the revealer of the quaternary number (Tetractys), and this in its turn is praised as the source and root of the etermal nature.” réAetov i öekäseival Sorce? kal traorav trepieuxmibéval thvºrów Śpiðuðv púgiv. Philop. De An. C, 2, u : TéAetos y&p àpiðubs 66era, Tepiéxel yèp tróvra dpiðubv évéavré. Whether this is taken from Aristotle's treatise on the good, as Brandis, i. 473, con- jectures, is uncertain. * Hence the decuple classifica- tions, in cases where the totality of the Real is in question ; as in the table of opposites and the system of the heavenly bodies. * Philol, loc. cit.; and doubtless in regard to this passage, Iambl. Theol. Ar. p. 61 : triotis ye uživ ka- Aetral, &rt karð Tov pixóNaov Šeköt kai roſs airãs uopious repl rôvövtww où trapépyws kataAapſ3avouévous trfor- Tuv čxopwev. Cf. what is said in the same place about the work of Speusippus, who shared the opinion of Philolaus. Theo of Smyrna, c. 49, also says that Philolaus spoke at length of the decad, but we know nothing of the treatise attri- buted to Archytas on this subject, and quoted by Theo. *"Où uð Tov &pietépg yeveó Tapa- Later Pythagoreans are fond of arranging all 6óvra retpaktöv, tray&v devãov qi- otos $1%uar’ (or: Étgapid r’) ëxova'av. On this oath and the quaternary number vide Carm. Aur. v. 47 sq.; Hierocles in Carm. Aur. v. 166 f. (Fragm. Phil. i. 464 sq.); Theo, Math. c. 38; Lucian, De Salut. c. 5; V. Auct. 4; Sext. Math. 94 sqq.; iv. 2; Plut. Plac. i. 3, 16; Iambl. Th. Ar. p. 20; cf. Ast. on the passage and Müllach in loc. cit. of the golden poem. The date of these verses cannot be determined with certainty. According to the Theol. Ar., they were found in Em- pedocles, and from his point of view the four elements should be regarded as the four roots of the universe. Butin this case, instead of yeweg, it would be necessary to read with Sextus, iv. 2, and others, Juxá (cf. Fabricius in loc. cit. of Fa- bricius), and by the word, trapabows to understand (with Mosheim, in Cudworth. Syst. Intell. i. 580) the Deity. It seems to me more likely that Pythagoras is here celebrated as the inventor of the Tetractys. It is, perhaps, on account of these THE WUMERICAL SYSTEM. 429 things in series of four: how far this is derived from the ancient Pythagoreans cannot be determined. But each of the other numbers has its particular value. One is the first from which all the other numbers arise, and in which the opposite qualities of numbers, the odd and the even, must therefore be united ; * two is the first even number; three the first that is uneven and perfect, because in it we first find beginning, middle and end;” five is the first number which results by addition from the first even and the first uneven number." Six is the first number which results from them by multiplication. Six multiplied by itself gives a number which again ends in six; all the multiples of five end either in five or ten ;” three, four, and five, are the numbers of the most perfect right-angled triangle, which together form a particular proportion;" verses that Xenocrates calls his second principle to &evvaov (cf. Part. ii. a, 866, 1, third edition). e.g. Theo and Theol. Arithm. l.c. * Wide supra, p. 401, and re- specting the dpriorépto.gov, Theo, p. 30: 'AptorroréAns be v rá rv0a- *opulcó to év pnow épºqorépov peréxelv ris pàorews &priq, wēv Y&p rpoore&v reputröv troteſ, reputré à #priov, 6 oik &v jöövaro, ei uh &uſpoºv Tatv pigeolv uetetxe, a proof which is as singular as the proposition it is intended to demonstrate orvuſpé- peral 3& Totºrous kal’Apxtras. Plu- tarch gives the same reason. Plut. De Ei. c. 8, p. 388. 3 Arist. De Coelo, i. 1, 268 a, 10 : ka9ámep yap paal kai oi IIv6a- yópelot. To trav kal rà ravra rols Tptolv Šptotal texevrh yāp kal piéorov Kal &px?) Töv Špiðubv čxel Tov ro5 travros, raûra öö. Töv Tſis ºrpić60s. Theo, p. 72: Aéyeral 3& kal 6 rpía TéAetos, étrelë, trpáros &px?iv kal pléora kai Trépas àxel. Iambl. Theol. Arithm. p. 15, gives an improbable and confused reason, wearóirm'ra kal āvaao'ytav airiv trpoaryópevov. * Wide supra, p. 420, 1; 422, 1 ; Anatol. ap. Iambl. Th. Ar. p. 34 (be- sides many other properties of the number 6): éé àptſov kal repuorood Töv trpátov, Šáševos kal 6% Asos, ëvváuel kal troAAaTAaqtaaluq, yºveral, hence it is called ågåev60mAvs and 'yduos. These denominations are also found loc. cit. p. 18; Plut. De Ei. c. 8; Theo, Mus. c. 6; Clemens. Strom. vi. 683 C; Philop. Phys. R., 11. * Plut. De El. c. 8, p. 388, * Iambl. Theol. Arithm. p. 26, 43; Procl. in Eucl. 111 m (428 Fr.), who attributes to Pythagoras him- self the construction of this trian- 430 THE PETHAGOREA.N.S. seven" is the only number within the decad which has neither factor nor product; this number is moreover compounded out of three and four, the significance of which has just been discussed; lastly, to pass over other things, it is together with four the mean arithmetical proportion between one and ten.” Eight is the first cube,” and the great Tetractys is formed out of the four first uneven and the four first even numbers, the sum of which (36) equals the sum of the cubes of one, two, and three.* Nine, as the square of three, and the last of the units, must have had a special import- ance.” With the Pythagoreans themselves, of course, these arithmetical observations were not separated from their other researches on the significance of numbers; and, judging from individual examples, we may suppose that they carried them much farther in a mathematical gle, according to an uncertain fra- dition. Cf. Alex. in Metaph. i. 8, 990 a, 23; Philo. De Vit, Contempl. 899 B (41). According to this passage the perfect right-angled triangle is that of which the sides = 3 and 4, and of which conse- quently the hypothemuse = 5. This last is called Övvauévn, because its square is equal to the sum of the squares of the sides. The sides are called Övaorévôpieval ; the hy- pothenuse is also called &vikia (ap. Alex.); this denomination is pro- bably more primitive than the &vetkia of the Pseudo-Megillus, ap. Iambl. Theol. Arithm. p. 28; this &veikſa, like yáuos, indicates the combination of the odd and the even. The expressions we find in Plato, Rep. viii. 546 B: aikhosis 8vváueva! re kal fivvao revågsval. This proves these opinions to be- long to the ancient Pythagoreans, ' Wide supra, p. 420, 2, and Iambl. Theol. Arithm. p. 43 sq. Be- cause the number 7 has no factors, Philolaus called it & whºrap, ac- cording to Joh. Lydus, De Mems. ii. 11, p. 72; cf. also Clemens, Strom. vi. 683 D ; Chalcid. in Tim. 35, p. 188; Mull. sqq. * For 1 + 3 = 4, 4 + 3 = 7, 7 + 3 = 10. - * Widesupra, 422, 1; Iambl. Th. Ar. p. 54; Clemens, loc. cit, &c. * Plut. De Is, c, 75; Schol. p. 38; # 88 kaxovuévn terpakros, rö. & kal TpidKovra, uéytotos ºv Špkos, às teópúAntal ral kóa'uos &váuaarai, recordpov učv àptíov táv trpátov, teoro.dpov 8& róv reptororóv eis ro aútb ovvre?\ovpuévov &toreAoûuevos. For further details, cf. De An. Procr. 30, 4, p. 1027. * Wide Iambl. Th. Ar. p. 57 sq. HA RMONY. 431 direction than could be shown in the present exposi- tion. The later writers, however, give us very little certain information on this subject. Even what I have now taken from them very possibly does not altogether originate with the primitive school, but there is no doubt that it truly describes the character of the ancient Pythagorean theory of numbers. Number and Harmony being with the Pythagoreans almost equivalent conceptions, their arithmetical system was closely connected with their system of Harmony." The different mature of the two spheres however necessitated for each a separate mode of treatment. While therefore the numbers were arranged according to the number ten, the measure of tones is the octave. The chief divisions of the octave are the fourth and the fifth : the relation of tones in it is measured according to the length of the resonant strings, for the fourth as 3 : 4; for the fifth as 2 : 3; for the whole octave as 1 : 2.” Other details, such as the variation of par- * The Pythagoreans called the harmonic theory ravovirch, accord- ing to Porphyry, in Ptol. Harm. (in Wallisii Opp. Math. ii.), p. 207, and Ptolemais of Cyrene, who is cited by Porphyry. Notwith- standing, the word, éppovirch, must also have been in use among them. Aristoxenus (Harm. Elem. sub init. ; ibid. p. 8) gives this as the ordinary designation for the theory of tones (ä kaxoupévm épuovinch). In the same way he constantly calls the adherents of the Pythagorean theory of āpuovikol, oi kaAoûuevo āppovikoi; we find even in Archy- tas the expression, dippovik? &vaxo- ºyſa, for a certain numerical relation. * This arrangement of the tones in the octave certainly belongs to the ancient Pythagorean school, vide the passage from Philolaus, quoted p. 385, 2. As to the discovery and measure of the octave, however, there is much uncertainty. Ac- cording to one account, which is found in Nicom. Harm. i. 10 sq.; Iambl. in Nicom. 171 sq.; Vit. Py- thag. 115 sq.; Gaudent. Isag. 13 sq.; Macrob. in Somn. Scip. ii. 1; Censorin, De Die Nat. c. 10; Boeth. De Mus. i. 10 sq.; it was Pytha- goras himself who discovered the harmonic system. He is said to have observed that the sounds of the blacksmith's hammer in the forge produce a fourth, a fifth. and g’º 432 THE PIV THAGOREANS, ticular tones; the concords that result from them ; the an octave. On further examination he discovered that the weight of the hammers was in the same pro- portion as the acuteness of the tones which they produce. He then, by means of different weights, extended strings of the same thickness and length, and found that the acuteness of the tones was proportionate to the weight. To obtain an har- monic proportion of a fourth be- tween the most elevated string of the heptachord, and that of the fourth (uéorm), a fifth between this and the lowest (vºirm), and inversely a fourth between the vitm and the fifth string from above (trapauéon, or according to the ancient division and the ancient denomination, Tp(rm), a fifth between this and the highest string, and a tone between the uéorm and the trapauéoºm (= 8:9), a weight is required for the Śrātm of 6, for the uéorm of 8, for the trapauéon (ºrpºrm) of 9, for the vitm of 12. Similarly, say Boethius and Gaudentius, other experiments have shown that in regard to one string equally extended (the mono- chord canon, the invention of which is attributed to Pythagoras, Diog. viii. 12), that the height of the tones is in inverse proportion to the length of the vibrating string. Boethius gives some further experi- ments with bells. In this account the story of the Smith's hammer is manifestly a story which is at once refuted by the physical impossibi- lity of the fact. It is also singular that the height 6f the sounds is given as proportional to the tension of the strings, or to the weight which produces this tension, while in reality it is only proportional to the square root of the forces of tension. If then it is true that the Pythagoreans held this opinion, they could not have based it upon experiments; but observing in a general manner that the height of the tones increased with the tension of the strings, they concluded that both increased in the same propor- tion. It is also possible, however, that this hasty conclusion was drawn by their successors. Lastly, the opinion that Pythagoras him- self discovered the arithmetical proportion of tones had been al- ready enunciated, according to Heracleides, ap. Porph. in Ptol. Harm. (in Wallisii Opp. Math. ii.) c. 3, p. 213, by Xenocrates; and whoever this Heracleides may have been, whether Heracleides Lembus or the grammarian of that name who lived at Rome under Claudius and Nero (Suid. H. c. 1)—Hera- cleides Ponticus it certainly was not—we have no reason to doubt that Xenocrates really said this of Pythagoras. But the accuracy of the statement is not better proved by the testimony of Xenocrates than by more recent testimony. We cannot say that the thing is impossible, but we may well sus- pect that here, as in many other instances, a discovery made by the successors of Pythagoras has been attributed to himself. The last assertion is well established. The Bythagoreans must have started from observations on the propor- tion of the length of strings which, being the same in thickness and tension, produce sounds of different acuteness. We gather this from the testimony of ancient writers, drawn from the Pythagorean sources themselves. In no other way can the indications which we find in Philolaus respecting the fourth, the fifth, and the octave, be explained. It is for this reason FIG URES. 433 different species and musical modes' I may leave to the history of musical theories, since these details do not stand in any close connection with the philosophic view of the world adopted by the Pythagoreans.” that among the ancient musicians the highest number designates the lowest sound; and that in the harmonic series (vide the Timaeus of Plato) the progression is not from the lower tones to the higher, but from the higher to the lower. The number by which a sound is designated has no relation to the vibrations of the air of which they are compounded, but to the length of the string which creates them. It is only at this point that we can form any exact idea of the dis- coveries of the Pythagoreans con- cerning sounds. The Pythagoreans were ignorant of the fact that the height of sounds depends on the number of vibrations of the air. Archytas, for example, in the frag- ment quoted ap. Porph. l. c. p. 236 sq. (Mullach. Fragm. Phil. i. 564 b), and in Theo, Mus. p. 94, expressly says that sounds become higher in proportion as they move more rapidly; and the same hypothesis is the basis of the doctrine of the spheral harmony, as it is explained by Plato (Tim. 67 B), Arist., and much later by Porph. (in Ptol. Harm. 217, 235 sq.) and the Pla- tonist AElianus, quoted by Por- phyry (p. 216 sq.), Dionysius the musician (p. 219), and many others. What the Pythagorean theory of sounds established is merely this: that all other conditions being equal, the height of the sounds is in inverse proportion to the length of the vibrating strings, and that the intervals of sound in the octave, determined by this measure, are WOL. I. such as have been given above. Moreover it had not escaped the Pythagoreans that the concord of two sounds is greater in proportion as the integral numbers expressing their proportion are small. Porph. (in Ptol. Harm. 280) gives us a Pythagorean explanation from Ar- chytas and Didymus of this prin- ciple. The artificial character of this explanation should not make us doubtful as to its antiquity. * The species (yevn) depend on the distribution of strings, the modes (Tpétrol, &pgovía) depend on the pitch of the instruments. There were three kinds—the diatonic, chromatic, and enharmonic ; and three modes—the Doric, the Phry- gian, and the Lydian. Already, in Plato's time, accessory modes had been added (Rep. iii. 398 E sqq.). At a later time they became con- siderably increased. The distinc- tion of the yávn, at any rate, belongs to the Pythagoreans. Ptol. Harm. i. 13 (cf. Porph. in Ptol. 310, 313 sq.) speaks of this in regard to Archytas. * Wide besides the passages quoted p. 431, 2; 388, 2; and from Ptol. Harm. i. 13 sq., the explana- tions of Böckh, Philol. 65 sqq., and Brandis, Gr. Röm. Philol. i. 454 sq., and particularly on the ancient theory of sounds; Böckh, Stud. and Daub and Creuzer, iii. 45 sq. (Klein. Schrift. iii. 136 sq.); De Metris Pindari, p. 203 sqq.; and Martin, Etudes sur le Timée, i. 389 sq.; ii. 1 sq. F F 434 THE PPTHAGOREA.N.S. After tones, the number theory was next applied to geometrical figures, and it is not necessary to be a Pythagorean to see that the form and relations of figures are determined by numbers. If, therefore, the Pythagorean and the Greek mathematicians in general were accustomed to apply geometrical terms to numbers,' and to discover arithmetical and har- monical proportions in figures,” the habit was perfectly natural. The Pythagoreans, however, did not stop here, but as they saw in numbers generally the essence of things, they sought to derive figures and bodies immediately from definite numbers. ' Wide supra, p. 427, 2, 3. * We have already found an ex- ample of this, p. 426, 6, in the Py- thagorean triangle. The demon- stration of the harmonic proportion in the cube is somewhat similar. By harmonic proportion (āva)\oyia ëpuovuch, called also Štrevavría) is understood, as distinguished from the arithmetical and geometrical proportion, a proportion between three quantities so that the diffe- rence between the middle number and first is to the first as the difference between the middle number and the last is to the last. This is found when the quantities are of such a kind §ore 6 &v Trpätos épos Tá čevrépa štrépéxm éavrò puépel, Taitº 6 uégos rô Tpital 5tepéxei Tô Tpſtw pºpel (Archyt. ap. Porph. in Ptol. Harm. p. 267; Fragm. Phil. ii. 119). A similar indication is to be found in Nicom. Inst. Arithm. ii. 25, p. 70, in a de- tailed explanation of the three proportions; Iambl. in Nicom. Arithm. p. 141; Plut. De An. Proor. 15, p. 1019. We find a less exact notice in Plut. De Mus. 22, p. Aristotle at any 1138, who sees harmonic propor- tion in the relation of the numbers 6, 8, 9, 12 a puovukh aegórms is # Taité uſipet rôv škpav airów ūrepéxova'a kal inrepexogévm, as Plato, Tim. 36 A.; cf. Epinom. 991 A, characterises it. This propor- tion is called harmonic, because the first numbers between which they exist (3, 4, 6, or 6, 8, 12) ex- press the fundamental proportions of the octave (àpuovía). For, on the one hand, 8 is greater than 6 by a third of 6, and less than 12 by a third of 12; on the other hand, 6 : 8 is the fourth, 8: 12 the fifth, 6 : 12 the octave. The same numbers are to be found in the cube, which has 6 surfaces, 8 angles, and 12 terminal lines, and is, therefore, called yeaperpukh āppovía by Philolaus according to Nicom, Inst. Arith. ii. 26, p. 72 (cf. Cassiodorus, Earp. in Psalms. ix. vol. ii. 36 b, Gar. Böckh, Philol. 87 sq.); Simpl. De An. 18 b; Boëthius, Arith. ii. 49 (cf. Philop. De An. E 16) also remark that the cube was sometimes called āpuovia or harmonia geometrica. FIG URES. 435 rate tells us that they defined the line as the number two ; 1 Philolaus we know explained four as the number of the body;” and Plato seems to have called three and four “the number of the surface, and ‘the number of the solid.” Plato furthermore derived the line from two, the plane from three, and the solid from four ; * and Alexander ascribes the derivation of solids from planes, planes from lines, and lines from points or monads, alike to Plato and the Pythagoreans.” We may, therefore, certainly assume that the Pythagoreans, in regard to the derivation of figures, identified one with the point, two with the line, three with the plane, * Metaph. vii. 11, 1036 b, 7. It is often difficult to determine whether the matter of an object should, or should not, be included in its definition; hence ātropoto'ſ Tives #3m kal étri roo kök?\ov kal too Tpuyóvov, Ös oë trpoo’ikov Ypappa's ôpigeo-0at kal rô ovvexe? (as if the definition that a triangle con- tained within three lines did not sufficiently designate the essential nature of the triangle) . . . ſcal &váyoval travra eis toūs ūpuðuous, kal Ypappuis Tov Aóryov Tov Tów 500 eivaſ paoſiv. Tuvès, it is certain, means the Pythagoreans; the Pla- tonists are subsequently expressly distinguished from the Pythago- I’08, IlS. * In a passage which we shall consider further on, Iambl. Th. Ar. p. 56 : PixóAaos 6* uetà to uaffnua- tukov pléyé60s Tpixà Staatöv čv Terpáöl, trolótmta kal Xpógiv ćirtàet- £auévns tis pàorea's év trevráði, Jºzooiv Šč év čáöl, votiv 8& kal à-yetav kal to Ötr' airoi, Aeyóuevov qºs évé8öopadāl, were railrd pmoly #para kal biatav kal uitiv kai étri- votav čv 3-yôodót ovubºval roºs ojaw. Asclep. Schol. in Arist. p. 541 a, 23: Töv Šē réorgapa &piðuov čAeyov [of IIv0.] Tö orópa &n Aós, rov 6& trévre to puorikov ordjua, row 5& éº to êuyvXov. It is true that a very improbable reason is given for this, viz., because 6 = 2 x 3, and that the even designates the body, and the uneven the soul. * Arist. quotes (De An. i. 2, 404 b, 18), as borrowed from Plato's lectures on philosophy: votiv pièv to ºv, Štrigrhumv 6é ré, São . Tov 8& too tritéðov &piðubv 6óław, ałoºmgiv Šē row roi, orépeoû. * Arist. loc. cit.; Metaph. xiv. 3, 1090 b, 20; Ps.-Alex. in Me- taph. xiii. 9, p. 756, 14 Bon.: thu 8è katē to Év, pnow épx?iv oix ôuotws eio fivov &ntavres, dAA’ of uèv airows tois &piðuous rà etón toſs ple- 'yā6egiv čAeyov Čiriq'épeiv, oiov čváða pºv Ypaupifi, rpióa 88 €tritréâq, re- Tpáðaðū arepeg. totaúra yap Év Tots trepl pixooroºpſas iotopeſ trepi IIAd- tovos. Cf. Zeller, Plat. Studien, 237 sq.; Brandis, De Perd. Arist. lib. p. 48 sq. * Wide p. 408, 1. F F 2 436 THE PXTHAGO REAWS. four with the solid; their reason for this being that the straight line is limited by two points, the first rectilinear figure by three lines, the simplest regular body by four surfaces, whereas the point is an indivisible unity.' But by virtue of their general tendencies they must necessarily have believed that this derivation of the figures of bodies involved a similar derivation of the corporeal itself,” for, as we have before remarked,” they supposed bodies to consist of the lines and planes enclosing them, as they supposed lines and figures to consist of numbers. According to Philolaus, the elementary nature of bodies depends upon their form. Of the five regular bodies, therefore, he assigned the cube to the earth, the tetrahedron to fire, the octohedron to air, the icosahedron to water, the ! It is thus that this doctrine is always explained by the ancients; cf. p. 407, 3;408, 1; and the passages quoted by Brandis, l. c. and Gr- Töm. Phil. i. 471 ; Nikom. Arithm. ii. 6; Boëth. Arithm. ii. 4, p. 1328; Theo. Math. 151 sq.; Iambl. Th. Ar. p. 18 sq.; Speusippus, ibid. p. 64; Sext. Pyrrh. iii. 154; Math. iv. 4, vii. 99 (x. 278 sqq.); Joh. Philop. De An, C, 2; Diog. viii. 25. No doubt these passages imme- diately apply to the derivation of geometry, so common after the time of Plato. But it is probable that the Platonic doctrine was the same on this point as the Pythagorean; for the combination in question certainly rests on the standpoint of the theory of numbers. * As is presupposed in the passages quoted. Such a construc- tion of bodies from surfaces is no dodecahedron” to the fifth doubt referred to in the question put by Aristotle to the Pythago- reans (vide p. 400), viz., Whether the first body arose from surfaces or from something else? * Wide p. 407 sq. * Ap. Stob. i. 10 (Böckh Philol. 160): kal r& év tá or patpg ord uata (the five regular bodies) arévre évri. Tā āv tá orgaípg (the bodies which are in the world—Heeren and Meineke would omit these words) tröp, #8wp ical ya kal &hp kal 6 rās orgapas àxicas (such is the text of codex A. Böckh, and others read & rās a paipas àAkás; Meineke, & Tás orbatpas kvkÅás; Schaarschmidt, Fragm. d. Philol. p. 50, 6 rās orgapas àykos, or even à . . . . ÖAóras; Heeren, à Tâs orgalpas 8Arcos, which according to him designated aether as that which draws and moves the globe of the THE ELEMENTS. 437 element which embraces all the others; that is to say, he held that the smallest constituent parts of these different substances had the supposed form." If we might assume that Plato, who borrowed these definitions from Philolaus, also followed him in the particulars of his construction, we must believe that Philolaus adopted a somewhat complicated procedure” in the derivation of the five bodies; but this theory is not only unsupported by any adequate evidence,” but even in the exposition of Plato there are consider- able arguments against it.” Whether this derivation world. Perhaps we should read: à T. orb. kūkaos, or to t. a p. 3Aas) tréatrrow. Plut. Plac. ii. 6, 5 (Stob. i. 450, Galen. c. 11): IIv6ayópas Trévre axmudrov čvrov a repeau, ãmep kaAetral kal waffnuatuca, ćic pºv roſ, kū8ov prior yeyovéval thu yºv, Čk & rās rvpapíðos to trip, Ér 8è tod ókraéðpov row &épa, ćic 6& roj eikogačāpov to $60p, k 8& Too Sobekaéðpou thu roi, travros aſpalpav. Cf. Stobaeus, i. 356, where, as in Diog. viii.25 (Alex. Polyh.), there is no mention of the fifth element: oi âtro IIv0ayópov Tov kóo uov orgaipav karð axiua têvtegorápov grouxetov. 1 In what concerns the four elements, there can be no doubt that the words of Philolaus have this meaning. It is only in regard to the fifth of the regular bodies, the dodecahedron, that a question might be raised. Are we to un- derstand that the elementary par- ticles of the substance which, ac- cording to Philolaus, has formed the globe of the world (i.e. the outer shell of the globe) present this form 2 or is it the globe itself which does so? There is one cir- cumstance which favours the first of these theories, viz. that among the disciples of Plato all those who in- cline the most to Pythagoreanism, so far as our information extends on this subject, admit the fifth element, aether, in addition to the other four. This circumstance equally contradicts the idea that the author of the passage in ques- tion borrowed the fifth body from Aristotle. Wide p. 317. * Wide Part ii. a, 675 sq. 3rd edition. * For Simpl. De Caelo, 252 b, 43 (Schol. in Arist. 510 a, 41 sq.), can scarcely have taken his state- ment from Theophrastus, to whom he refers merely for his assertion about Democritus. It is more pro- bably derived from the pseudo- Timaeus (De An. Mundi), from whom he has previously (452 b, 14) quoted a passage (p. 97 E Sq.). This is most likely the source of the statement of Hermias, Irris, c. 16, which attributes to Pytha- goras and his school the whole Platonic construction. * The Platonic construction of the elementary bodies by means of right-angled triangles cannot be 4.38 THE PPTHAGOREA.N.S. of the elements belonged to the earlier philosophers, or was originated by Philolaus, and whether in connec- tion with this the four elements, omitting the fifth, came from the Pythagoreans to Empedocles, or conversely with the addition of the fifth, from Empedocles to the Pythagoreans, is a question that the historical evidence does not enable us to decide;" there are grounds, how- ever, for preferring the second of these alternatives. The theory of Philolaus presupposes too high a develop- ment of geometrical knowledge to be compatible with great antiquity, and we shall hereafter find that Empedocles was the first who introduced the more accurate conception of the elements, and maintained that they were four.” This construction, therefore, is probably to be attributed to Philolaus. This conclusion is confirmed by the fact that the Pythagoream notions concerning the origin and con- stitution of the world, so far as we are acquainted with them, connect themselves with the other presuppositions of the system, independently of the doctrine of the applied to the dodecahedron. Con- sequently, if this construction were made the point of departure, it would be impossible to see in the dodecahedron a specific elementary form ; and, in fact, Plato sets aside the dodecahedron, Tim. 55 C, cf. 40 A, in a manner which seems to imply that this fifth body was known to him from another source, but that he was unable to make use of it in his exposition. Inde- pendently of the Platonic method of reducing the elements to certain figures, there existed a second and simpler method, as is proved by the passage in Aristotle, De Caelo, iii. 5, 304 a, 9 sq. * The celebrated verses of the Golden Poem are of uncertain origin, vide p. 428, 3 ; 322. Evi- dence like that of Vitruvius, viii. Praef. (cf. Sextus, Math. x. 283; Diog. viii.25), which attributes the doctrine of the four elements to Py- thagoras and Epicharmus, as well as to Empedocles, cannot, of course, be taken into account. The frag- ment of the pseudo-Athamas, ap. Clem. Strom. vi. 624 D, is cer- tainly not authentic. * Wide infra, Emped, THE ELEMENTS. 439 elements. A fragment of Philolaus,' indeed, in regard to the origin of the world, maintains that the world always has been, and always will be; which would incline us to believe the statement” that the Pythago- reans in what they said of the formation of the universe intended only to assert the logical dependence of the derived in respect to the primitive, and not an origin of the universe in time.” But as we have before shown the spuriousness of the passage, and as Stobaeus does not give us the sources or the reasons for his statement, no argument can be based on this evidence. On the other hand, Aristotle distinctly says that mome of the earlier philosophers held the world to be without begin- ning, except in the sense of the doctrine which is never ascribed to the Pythagoreans, viz., that the substance of the world is eternal and imperishable, but that the world itself is subject to a constant vicissitude of generation and destruction; * and what we know of the theories * Ap. Stob. 1, 420 (vide supra, p. 399, 1): 7s 65e 6 kóguos é; aiévos kal eis aidova Staplevel . . . . eis éðv kal avvexhs ical púa'i Stattveóuevos kal replayeduevos éé àpxtöío. It is immaterial in regard to the ques- tion before us, whether we read with Meineke, instead of &px16tw, čičía, or, still better, with Rose (Arist. lib. ord., p. 35), āpxas tw. * Stob. i. 450: IIv6ayápas pnal 'yevvmtöv kar’ trivotav Töv kóopov ow karū xpóvov. That Pythagoras regarded the world as never having had a beginning is often affirmed by later writers, vide inf. p. 440, 2, e.g. Varro, De re rust. ii. 1, 3, who ascribes to him the doctrine of the eternity of the human race; Cen- sorin. Dr. Nat. 4, 3 ; Tertull. Apologet. 11; Theophilus, Ad Autol. iii. 7, 26, who for that reason ac- cuses Pythagoras of setting the necessity of nature in the place of Providence. * So Ritter thinks, i. 417. But in maintaining at the same time (ibid. p. 436, vide supra, p. 404) that the Pythagoreans held the gradual development of the world, he evidently contradicts himself. Brandis, i. 481 ; Chaignet, ii. 87; Rohr, De Philol. Fragm. Trepl Wvx?s, p. 31. * De Caºlo, i. 10, 279 b, 12: 'yevówevov učv Štravtes eivat £aoiv [rov otpavöv], &AA& Yevéuevov oi pºv tov, of 68 pèaptov . . . of 6' évaAA&E Örè uèv airws à tê 8& &AAws ëxeiv pºsipópevov, kal tooto &ei öta- 440 THE PPTHAGOREA.N.S. of his predecessors only confirms this assertion." The expedient, also, by which Stobaeus, or rather the Neo- Pythagorean whom he here follows,” endeavours to save Texeiv oitos &rarep 'Eutrečokai's 6 'Akpayavtºvos kai ‘Hpdicxettos é 'Eq,éorios. In regard to these last, it is said, p. 280 a, 11, that their opinion accords with the theory which represents the world as eter- nal, and only subject to a change of form. Cf. Phys. viii. i. 250 b, 18: &AA 80'ot uév Štreſpovs Te Kóo- Hous elvaí (paal ral toos pév yºyveo- 6al Tovs 6% pºetpea 6at Táv icóguov, &et (paariv eival ktvmaſiv . . . Šalou 5’ êva (sc. cóo uov sival), h oùk &el (=?) &teipov čvrov oik &el rows uév 'ylyveg 6al, etc. the doetrine of Em- pedocles) kal repl Täs Kivägews ūtroríðevrai karð Aó'yov. | Chaignet (i. 249; ii. 84) ap- peals, in opposition to this opinion, to the well-known saying of Herae- leitus (inf. vol. ii. Her.), But as I have already observed in Hermes, x. 187, that which Heracleitus here characterises as uncreated and im- perishable is not the system of the world, the eternity of which was taught by Aristotle and the pseudo- Philolaus, but only the trip &eigwov, the primitive substance which, in developing itself, formed the world, and into which the world resolves itself. All the physicists presup- pose such an uncreated principle, without deducing from it the eter- nity of the world, cf. on Xenoph. The same answer may be given to Rohr's objection (p. 31), urging , that in the fragment quoted p. 372, 1, Philolaus called the éorè rôv Trpaypºtov eternal. Töv trpayuárov, the Limit and the Unlimited, may be eternal; but it does not follow that the The éorró, world formed from it is also eter- nal. Lastly, if Aristotle (Metaph. xiv. 3, 1091 a, 12) says, against the Platonic theory of numbers, &rotrow 5& kal yèveauv troteſv číötav ëvrov, we cannot conclude from this passage, as Chaignet does (ii. 87; in his citation he is more than inaccurate) that the Pythagoreans, in describing the formation of the world, did not intend to discuss a creation of the world in time. This remark (even if it were cer- tainly proved to refer to the Py- thagoreans) is not concerned with the formation of the world, but with the origin of numbers from the Great and Small. Now Aris- totle, speaking in his own name, describes numbers as eternal. If Chaignet thinks he can prove by the help of the passage (De Caelo, i. 10; vide preceding note) that the eternity of the world was taught before Aristotle, he com- pletely misunderstands the sense of the passage; āţătos there means infinite duration, not the absence of commencement, which alone is here in question. * We have elsewhere shown (Part iii, b, 114 sq.) how general the doctrine of the eternity of the world was among the Neo-Pytha- goreans. That the statement of Stobaeus only reproduces their opinion, is proved by his attri- buting to Pythagoras, whose doc- trine is unknown to Aristotle, a distinction which greatly trans- cends the standpoint of his epoch, and in reality is only affirmed by the Platonic school. Chaignet FORMATION OF THE WORLD. 441 the eternity of the world for the Pythagorean system, is attributed by Aristotle to the Platonists' only; neither he nor his commentators ever mention the Pythagoreans in that connection. This would surely have been impossible if he had been acquainted with an exposition of Philolaus or any other Pythagorean, which not only maintained that the world was without beginning or end in the most decided manner, but on the very grounds brought forward in his own system. Irrespectively of this objection, however, it is most im- probable that the ancient Pythagorians should have conceived the universe as an eternal product of the world- creating energy. The distinction between the logical dependence of things on their causes, and their origin in time, requires a longer practice and a finer develop- ment of thought than we can suppose possible among the earliest thinkers. If they enquired into the origin of the world, it was natural for them to think of its commencement in time : as we see from the ancient theogonies and cosmogonies. Not till some time had elapsed was it necessary to abandon this point of view, and then on two considerations: 1. That matter must and Rohr consider that they have found in the testimony of Stobaeus sufficient evidence as to the doc- trine of Pythagoras and the ancient Pythagoreans. But we cannot trust writers, whose sources it is impossible to trace beyond the Neo-Pythagorean epoch; and least of all, can we trust so recent a compiler. ! De Coelo, i. 10, 279 b, 30 : %w 6é rives Božibetav ćtrixelpotori pépew §avroſs rôv Aeyóvrww &p6aptov pºv eival yewówevov 8*, oùk éorriv &Améâs. ðuota's ydp paat roſs rö, äuaypdupara 'ypáqovoſt kal orgas eipnicéval repl ràs 'yevégews, oùx às yewouévov toté, &AA& Stöarkaxias xàpiv &s uáAAov ºyvapiévrov, Šotrep to Sidypaupa ºtyvápºevov 6eagrapévows. It is clear from what follows that certain Platonists are hereintended. Sim- plicius and other writers say that Xenocrates is alluded to, and also Speusippus. 442 THE PXTHAGORIEANS. be without origin, and 2, that the world-forming energy can never be conceived as inactive. The former idea, as far as we know, was first enunciated by Parmenides, the latter by Heracleitus; and the conclusion drawn thence even by them and their successors was not the eternity of our universe: Parmenides inferred from his propo- sition the impossibility of becoming and passing away, and accordingly he declared the phenomenal world gene- rally to be illusion and deception. Heracleitus, Empe- docles, and Democritus maintained, each in his own way, an infinity of worlds of which every one had had a beginning in time. Lastly, Anaxagoras, adopting the ordinary theory of a sole and unique world, supposed this likewise to have shaped itself at a definite period out of the unformed primitive matter. On the other hand, Aristotle never thought of attributing a description of the origin of the world to the philosophers who main- tained its etermity so consciously, and on principle, as the reputed Philolaus. There is, therefore, little reason to doubt that what is stated concerning the Pythagorean theory of the formation of the world really refers to a beginning of the world, in time. In fact, any other interpretation of the texts is inadmissible. According to the Pythagoreans, the central fire was first formed in the heart of the universe; this is also called by them the One or the Monad, because it is the first body of the world; the mother of the Gods, because it is this which engenders the heavenly bodies; they also call it Hestia, the hearth or the altar of the universe, the guard, the citadel or the throme of Zeus, because it is the central point in which the world-sustaining energy FORMATION OF THE WORLD. as its seat." How this beginning of the world itself ame about, Aristotle (loc. cit.) says they were unable o explain, and we cannot certainly discover from his anguage whether they even attempted an explanation.” After the formation of the central fire, the nearest portions of the unlimited, which according to the obscure notions of the Pythagoreans signified at once infinite space and infinite matter, were constantly being attracted to this centre, and becoming limited through * Wide p. 444, 4; 446, 1; Arist. Metaph. xiv. 3; xiii. 6 (supra, p. 400; 407, 2); Philol. ap. Stob. i. 468: to ºrpátov dippoo 6év to èv év 76 uéog tas a patpas (the sphere of the world) ‘Earía kaxeſ rai, The same, ibid. 360: 6 kóo uos eſs éotiv" #pèaro às yt yueq6al &xpt too uéorov. The text may be more exact, but ättö roi, Mérov would certainly be clearer. Ibid. p. 452; wide infra, p. 446, 1; Plut. Numa, c. 11 : kóquou oë piégov of IIv6ayopticol to trip iöpú00al vouíſovºri, kal rotto 'Eotſav kaxodori kal uováða. Cf. Iambl. Th. Arithm. p. 8: Tpos toūrous paal [of IIv6.] trepi to uéorov táv record- pov grouxetov ketorðaſ two Évačukov 6tórupov kū8ov. of thv ued 6tmta Tús 6éas (instead of this word, we should doubtless read 6égea's) kal *Oumpov eiðéval Aéryovra (Il. viii. 16). Therefore, continues the author, Parmenides, Empedocles, and others say: rhv uovačukhu púaiv ‘Earías Tpárov čv uéog iópio 6al kal 6ix to iorógãorov puxago'eiv Tiju aithw $6pav. We see from these passages how the trpárov čv in Aristotle is to be understood. The central fire, because of its place and its importance for the universe, was called the One in the same sense that the earth, for example, was called two, and the sun, seven (vide supra, p. 421). But how this determinate part of the world was related to the number one, or distinguished from it, was not stated. Wide p. 410 sq. * Aristotle says (Metaph. xiv. 3), vide sup. p. 400: Tot, Évos ovo- Taffévros eſt’ & ‘truméöwy eſt” ex Xpoiás, which signifies indeed much the same thing as é; étritréðav ; cf. Arist. De sensu, 3, 439 a, 30: oi IIv6ayópelot thv étruq divetav xpoiâu ékáAovv efºr’ ic airépuatos eit’ & &v &tropodaruv eitreºv. But we cannot infer from this (as Brandis does, i. 487) that the Pythagoreans really followed all these methods to ex- plain the formation of the body, still less that all these modes of explication had reference to the Central fire. But Aristotle might express himself in this way, even had the Pythagoreans said nothing as to the manner in which bodies were formed. Similarly in Metaph. xiv. 5, 1092 a, 21 sq., he puts the question to the adherents of the number-theory—‘how numbers re- sult from their elements,’ uttei or a vuòéo et, Ös é; évvrapxóvtwv, or òs ämö aréouaros, or ös ék Too éravtſov ; 444 THE PYTHAGOREA.N.S. this attraction,' until by the perpetual continuation and extension of that process (thus we must complete the accounts) the system of the universe was at last finished. The universe was conceived by the Pythagoreans as a sphere.” In the centre of the whole they placed, as we have seen, the central fire; around this ten heavenly bodies” moving from west to east describe their orbits; * farthest off, the heaven of fixed stars, next the five planets; then the sun, the moon, the earth, and tenth, and last, the counter-earth, which the Pythagoreans invented in order to complete the sacred number of tem. The extreme limit of the universe was formed by the fire of the periphery, which corresponded to the central fire.” * Arist. loc. cit.; cf. Supra, p. 400, 1. The same doctrine seems to be the foundation of the conserva- tion in Plut. Plac. ii. 6, 2: IIv6ayó- pas àtro Trupos kai rod Trépºrtov a touxetov [&pèao'0at thv yéveau roi, kóaptov], only that here the unlimi- ted is confounded with the tepuéxov of Aristotle, the AEther. * Xºpaipa is the usual expression, p. 442, 1 ; 436, 4. * The Pythagoreans are said to have been the first to determine their order in a precise manner. Simpl. De Colo, 212 a, 13 (Schol. 497 a, 11): ás Eöönuos ioTopei, rhy Tús 6éorews ºrdély eis robs IIv6ayo- pstows trpérous āvatépov. * As follows as a matter of course in regard to the earth and the other bodies of the universe. For the apparent diurnal motion of the sun, from east to West, could not be explained by the motion of the earth around the central fire, The stars they believed were unless that motion was from west to east. Whether the Pythagoreans, like Aristotle (cf. Böckh, d. Kosm. System, p. 112 sq.), understood this movement from west to east as a movement from east to east, or from right to right, and called the east side the right, because the movement starts from that side; as Stobaeus thinks, Eel. i. 358 (Plut. Plac. ii. 10; Galen, c. 11, p. 269), seems to me doubtful. * Arist. De Caelo, ii. 13, sub init.: röv traetortov ćirl rod piéarov ketorðat Aeyóvarov [thy yīv] . . . évavríos of trepl rºw 'Iraxſav, cańoiſ- pevol 6* IIv6ayópelot Aéyov'riv. čarl pºv yap too uéorov trip elval paat, thv 5è yńv év táv šarpov oſſo'av kūkāq, pepopuévnv repl rô uéorov vökra re kal juépav trouetv. čtv 3’ evavríav &AAmv tattºn karaokevágovort yºv, hv &vrix60.ya óvoua kaxojow, où Tpos to pauvéueva rows A6-yous kal rès airías (mroovres, &AA& Trpás SYSTEM OF THE WORLD. 445 fixed in transparent circles or spheres, by the revolu- tion of which upon their axes they were carried round." Tuvas A6-yous kal 66&as airév tá. paiváueva trpoo’éNkovres kal Telpé- Revol ovykoope?v (which is explained in the following manner in Metaph. i. 5, 986 a, 8): étrelë, a €Aetov i öe- käseival Soiceſ kai rāorav trepieuxmºbé- vat Thu rôv àpiðuóv pågiv, kal T& (pepópeva karū tow oilpavov 6éka pučv eivaí (paalu, üvrov č Švvéa w8vov rôv pavspöv Ště roßto Šekdtmu thv ãvrtzôova troloßgiv), Tó yöp tip-to- Tárq, otoviral trpoofirceiv thu tutotd- tnv Štrópxeiv x&pav, eival 6& trºp pºv yis rutórepov, to 68 trépas Tów perači, rö 6 oxarov ical to uéorov Trépas . . . &ri 3 of ye IIv6ayópelot kal Stö. Tö uáAuota trpoofirew puxat- Teoréal to kvpuétarov too travtós' to 6% uéorov sival rowbrov' & Aubs qvXakºv čvouáçoval, to taútmv čxov thv x&pav trip. Ibid, 293, b, 19 : [rºv yºv qadi) kiveto flat kūkāq Tepi To uéorov, où uávov 8& Tatºrmv &AA& kai Thy &vríx60ya. Stob. Ecl. i. 488: puñóAaos trip Šv pléog trepi to kévrpov, Štep ‘Eatíav toº travtos kaAeſ kai Aibs oikov kal Mmtépa 6eóv, 8wpºvtekalovvox?ivical uérpov qºorea's kal tróAlv trip repov &votá- to to trepiéxov. Trpárov 6'eival púget to uéorov, repl 3& rotto 6éka adºplato. 6eia xopečely (hence probably the xopetal of the stars, ap. Plato, Tim. 40 c) oëpavöv (that is to say, the heaven of fixed stars; it is clear from the end of the passage which will be quoted farther on, that the expression belongs to the narrator), traavāras, ueſ ois àAlou, Éq’ & ore- Aïvny, Öq' fi Thy yiv, Öp' fi thv &vríx60va, ué6 & oriºuTravta rö Tüp ‘Earías ātri tā kévrpa [ré kévrpg] tdºw étréxov. Alexander ad Me- taph. i. 5, p. 20, Bon. (vide supra, p. 402, 2), on the subject of the sun : . é866 amv yöp at Töv ráču èxely [paalu of IIv0.] Töv repl rô pléorov kal Thu ‘Eattav kivovaévov 6éka orwudravº Kiveto 6al yèp per& rhy Töv &taavāºw aq’aipav kal r&s arévre Tès Tāv TAavátov, web' ºv [? 8v) öyöömy Thy gexívny, kal rºw yūy évármy, ple6' ºu Thy &vrtkóova. Böckh has already refuted (Philol. 103 sq.) the anonymous author in Photius, p. 439 b, Bekk, who at- tributes to Pythagoras twelve Dia- cosms and passes over the counter- earth,the fire of the centre and of the circumference, and places instead a circle of fire, a circle of air, and a circle of water, between the moon and the earth. * Alexander treats this opinion as Pythagorean ; Theo (Astron. p. 212, Mart.) mentions Pythagoras himself as having been the first to discover cat’ iótov Tuðv kūkaa v kal év ióías 5* a patpals (Cod. ió. 6tagopaſs) évôečegeva kai Si' ékeſvow kivoúueva (sc. Tà TAavépceva) Sokéïv huív (pépeo:6at Ötö rôi" (w8íov. We find these ideas in Plato and Par- menides, which confirms their antiquity, and proves that the Pythagoreans, perhaps after the example of the founder of their school, were the authors, or, at any rate, the chief representatives, of the theory of the spheres, which was of such importance in Greek philosophy. It is impossible to decide whether, in their opinion, all the heavenly bodies were carried along by spheres, i.e. by hollow globes; or whether the fixed stars alone were fastened to a hollow globe, and the planets to simple circles, as Plato supposed. Röth (ii. a, 808 sq., 244) attributes to the 446 THE PRTHAGOREANS. Among the bodies of the universe the central fire occupies the first place, not only from its position, but because, on account of this position, it is the centre o gravity and support of the whole, the measure and bond of the universe,' which indeed sprang solely from it and through its operation. The Pythagoreans were accustomed to conceive all such relations not merely mathematically and mechanically, but at the same time dynamically; we should therefore have expected that they would attribute to the central fire an im- portant influence upon the whole, even if this were not confirmed by the analogy of their doctrine of the forma- tion of the world, and their opinions (presently to be considered) on the origin of the fire of the sun.” Later accounts, however, in connection with this, assert that the soul, or the spirit of the universe, was supposed to Pythagoreans, and even to Pytha- goras, the theories of eccentric circles, and epicycles. Not only are we without sufficient evidence on this point (for Nicomachus and Iamblichus ap. Simpl. De Coelo, 227 a, 17; Schot. 503 b, 11, are not trustworthy), but the theory is opposed to the whole tenor of an- cient astronomy. As to the opinion of Röth (l.c.), according to which Eudoxus, Callippus, and Aristotle were acquainted with the theory of epicycles, it becomes quite untena- ble after due consideration of the passages in question in Aristotle and his commentators. Wide Part ii. 344 sqq., 2nd ed. - | Wide p. 441, 1 ; 444, 4 ; also Stob. i. 452: to 5& iryegovikov [æt- AóAaos épmoevl v Tó uégaitáriº trup, Štrep Tpótrea's 8temv trpoère- 8áAAero ris row travtos a paipas, 6 Smutovpyós, where the hyenovikov is certainly Stoic and the Demiurgus Platonic ; but the comparison of the central fire with the keel of the ship of the universe seems to be truly Pythagorean. Nicom. (ap. Phot. Cod. 187, p. 143 a, 32) also, among many later documents, brings forward a statement, according to which the Monad was called by the Pythagoreans Zavos Túpyos, which must have come from some ancient tradition. Proclus, in Tim. 172 B: kal oi IIv6ayópelot 5& Zavos Tripyov h Zavos puxakhv &rekáAovy Tö Aégov. * This is confirmed by the testimony of Parmenides (the Py- thagorean origin of this testimony will be shown in its proper place), according to which the divinity that regulates the whole has his seat in the midst of the universe. SYSTEM OF THE WORLD. 447 be diffused throughout the whole from the central fire, or from the circumference; but this is probably a subsequent expansion and modification of the aneient doctrine, and the source of this modification must be sought in the doctrines of Plato and of the Stoics.” * For example, the Pseudo- Philolaus ap. Stob. i. 420 (cf. p. 438, 3) éxel 3& kal r&v ãpxãv tas kivſouás Te kal ueta}oAås 6 kóo uos eis éðv kal ovvexhs kal púa'i Starveduevos kai treplayedwevos é àpxás &ötw. Kal to uév &uetá80Aov (the unchange- able part of the world) &rö täs to 3Aov replexoto as puxas uéxpt ore- Advas Trepatotral, to 6% uérabáAAov &Tö rās areAdvas uéxpt tas yas' étrel Sé ye kal to kivéov čº aidºvos eis aiºva trepitoxeſ, to 8& civeówevov, às to cuvéow &yet, oita, 6tat{6erat, &väyka rö pºv &eikſvatov (Chaignet, ii. 81, proposes to substitute &ict- varov for this word, but the im- mobility of the kivéov is not to be proved by alleging that it é: aidºvos trepitroxeſ), to 8& àeutraffès eluev, Kal Tö uèv vó kal ºvXàs &várcoua(?)"rāv, Tö 86 yewégios kal ueta}oxás. Alex. Polyh. ap. Diog. viii. 25 sqq.: kó0- pov čupuxov, voepov, agaipoetőfi . . &v6pétrous eival trpos 6eous ovyyá- veuav karð Tö uétéxeiv čvápotov 6epwoo, ölö kal trpuvoeſoróat Töv 6eov ju6v . . . Suákely t” &trö too fixtou &ktíva 51& rod aidépos Toi Te luxpod kai Taxéos (air and water) . . . Taºrmv Šē Thy &krīva kal eis Tó. Bévôm Šáeoróat kal Stö. Tooro Çavoiroteſy ird vra eival 3& Thy buxhv âtróo tragua aiffépos ſcal row bepuot, kal rod juxpoſ . . &0ávaróv T’ eival aút?iv, retóñtrep kai to &q’ of &m éo- traortal &0&varóv éori. Cic. N. D. i. 11, 27: Pythagoras, gui censuit, animum esse per naturam rerum omnem &ntemium et commeantem, ea: quo nostri animi carperentur. Cato, 21, 78: Audiebam Pythagoram Pythagoreosque . . nunquam dubi- tassé, quin ea universa mente divina delibatos animos haberemus. Plut. Plac. Qu. viii. 4, 3, p. 1007 : to the question, ‘What is Time?’ Pythagoras replied, “The Soul of the World.’ Plac. iv. 7, 1: IIv0. IIAárov & pôaprov eival Thy juxhv. étodorav yop eis thv too travros Wuxhu &vaxopéiv Tpos to Öuoyevés. Sext. Math. ix. 127: The Pytha- goreans and Empedocles teach that men are not only related to each other and the gods, but also to the animals, ev Y&p inrápxelv ºrveijua Tö 61& travros toū Köopov 6tſicov tºuxſis Tpdrov, to kal évotiv huàs trpos ékéiva for this reason it is wrong to kill and eat animals. Stob. i. 453; Simpl. De Caelo, 229 a, 38 (Schol. in Arist. 505 a, 32) : oi Ös yumorld repov airów (Tów IIv6ayopticów) wetao Xóvres trip pºv čv Tó uéo & Aéyova, thv 3mutovp- ºuchv 5ivagu, Thy đc géorov Trägav thv yńv ſwo-yovoúa'av kai Tô &repvy- puévov airfis &va63Xtrovoſav 5ub of A&v Zavos Túp:/ov airò caxodoriv, &s airbs év roſs Hvěayopticots ioT6pmaev, of Śē Aubs puxarchy, &s év Totºrous, oi 8è Aubs 606vov, &s &AAot pagiv. Cod. Cois!. Schol. 505 a, 9: §to kal TAex- 9%ual r}v rod travtos ºvXºv ék pléorov trpos Töv čoxarov oipavév. * In regard to the fragment of Philolaus and the testimony of Alexander, it has already been shown (p. 393, 2; 399, 1) that they cannot be considered authentic. As to the question before us, it must, 448 THE PPTHAGOREA.N.S. Aristotle, in discussing the theories of the ancient philosophers about the soul," quotes from the Pytha- goreans only the celebrated assertion that the particles emanating from the Sun are souls, and he infers from hence, not without difficulty, that they regarded the soul as the moving principle. Now it is very improbable that Aristotle should have confined himself to this apart from what is said in the text, at once appear strange that the Soul (in agreement with Plato and Aristotle) should be relegated to the periphery of the world, with- out mention being made of the central fire, with which the author seems wholly unacquainted. It is equally strange that the soul and the 6etov should be regarded as the eternally moved and the eternally moving (the Pythagoreans con- sidered the 6eia orópara, or the constellations, but not the 6etov in the absolute sense of the word as subject to movement. On the con- trary, they placed movement on the side of the Unlimited, cf. p. 402, 1 ; 381, 1). It is easy to see in this a reproduction of a passage in Plato (Crat. 397 c), and of another in Aristotle (De An. 1, 2, vide infra, p. 458, 4), on Alcmaeon, the result of a misunderstanding. Nor can we fail to recognise the influence of Platonic and Aristotelian ideas in the doctrine of the eternal move- ment of the soul in a circle, and the language used to express that doctrine. In the exposition of Alexander, and in the short state- ‘ment of Sextus, the Stoic element is equally apparent; witness the Tveijua Slö. Travros Suffircov, the con- ception of the human soul origi- nating from the Divine soul by emanation, the cosmology, so dif- ferent from that of the Pythago- reans, which we shall discuss fur- ther on, and the number four applied to the element. Cicero speaks in quite the same manner; and it is very possible that this writer, who did not hesitate to use the most recent, and the most con- venient documents in his exposition of ancient systems, may have in this instance referred to Alexander himself. The definition given in Plutarch does not seem to belong to the ancient Pythagoreans. The #yeuovikov of Stobaeus is evidently Stoic. Simplicius, and the writer who reproduces his evidence, clearly did not know how to distinguish the original doctrines of Pythago- reanism from the new. Nor can we mistake the recent origin of a frag- ment quoted by Clemens, Cohort.47, c: á uèv 6ebs eis' x' oitos 3& oix, fºs Tuves àtrovooja tv, Šictos Tás 6takoor- photos, &AA’ v airá, 3Aos év ŠAq, Tó kūkāq, trio Kotros Táo as yewéatos, kpāoris Táv ŠAwv' &el &v kal épy&tas Töv attoo 6vváuwu kal épyov &trév- Tov, Šv oëpavó (poorthp kal travrov trathp, vows kal ºxalais tº 8X4, kūkāq, (Tó-w-w), travrov kívaois. (The same in the recension of Po. Justin, Part iii, b, 102, 1, 2 A.) The polemic of the Stoic Pantheism against the Aristotelian Deism is manifest here. * De An. i. 2; wide inf. p. 476, 2. THE WORLD-SOUL. 449 assertion, if such important and fully-developed con- ceptions as those we have quoted were known to him ; and it is equally unlikely that conceptions of such importance should have escaped the notice of anyone so intimately acquainted as Aristotle was with the Pythagorean doctrine.' The second hypothesis is evi- dently impossible. The first loses any probability it might seem to have, if we consider with what care and completeness Aristotle quotes everything which his predecessors have said on the subject of the soul. At the commencement, and at the end of the chapter, he expresses his intention of enumerating all pre- vious opinions: T&s Töv Tpotépww. 6óżas orvutrapaxapagávely 60'ot tº trept airfis &me pívavro, and at the end : ºré učv učv trapaşeāopiéva "repl ºvXīs . Taijt’ or rív. That which the pseudo-Philolaus asserts so de- cidedly, namely, that the soul is the kuntukov, is precisely what Aristotle dares not attribute cate- gorically to the Pythagoreans (404 a, 16: áo t ke 88 ſeal to tropi, Tāv IIvöayopetov Aeyóuevov thu airhu #xeiv 61&votav). It would be very surprising that the Pythagoreans should not be named among those who regarded the soul as one of the elements, if they had really said what Alexander Polyhistor, Cicero, and others, attributed to them. The only thing that might be objected is that Aristotle was speaking of the human soul, and not of the soul of the world. But this is not the case. He speaks of the soul in general, and notably of the soul of the world : the pre- tended Pythagoreans speak also of the human soul. Now Aristotle expressly distinguishes the Pytha- WOL. I. We cannot therefore ascribe goreans from those who considered the soul as the épxh Tiis kivāorea's (for example, the pseudo-Philolaus) when, after describing their ideas on the soul (404 a, 20), he pro- ceeds thus, 404 a, 20 : étrº rairb 8è q’épovrat Kal &got Aéyovari rhy Wuxºv to airò fewoov, &c. He could not have expressed himself in such a manner if they had been the ear- liest precursors of Plato on this point; cf. Hermes, x. 190. The objections made by Chaignet and Rohr have no great weight. The former says (ii. 176): Since Aris- totle concludes from the Pythago- rean conception of solar corpus- cles that the soul is endowed with motive force (404 a, 21, €oíkaori 'yūp oirot trèvres insixmpéval rhy kivmaſiv oikeiôratov eival ri yuxià), it necessarily follows from this that he attributes to the Pythago- reans a World-soul. Rohr speaks in a similar manner (l. c., p. 21). But the fact that Aristotle is here making a simple deduction, of which he himself is not certain, is enough to show the impossibility of his having had in his possession so precise an explication as that of our fragment. Chaignet (ii. 84) ap- peals to the other fact that, accord- ing to Aristotle (vide infra, Alc- maon), Alcmaeon also ascribes to . the stars a soul eternally in motion. But Aristotle says nothing of the kind. He merely affirms that, ac- cording to Alcmaeon, the beſa, the G. G. 450 THE PPTHAGORE ANS. the doctrine of the world-soul to the Pythagoreans, and even if they supposed that heat and vital force flowed into the universe from the central fire, this ancient materialistic motion is very different from the theory of a world-soul conceived as a particular incor- poreal essence. - Around the central fire, the earth, and between the two, the counter-earth, revolve in such a manner, that the earth always turns the same side to the counter- earth and the central fire; and for this reason, the rays of the central fire do not come directly to us, but in- directly from the sum. When the earth is on the same side of the central fire as the sun, we have day; when it is on the other side, night." sky and the stars, are in perpetual movement, which does not at all imply that this philosopherreduced all movements to a unique spiritual principle, distinct from the body of the world, and diffused throughout the universe. Lastly, Rohr (l. c. p. 21) cites Plato's Phaedo, 86 B sqq., to prove that the opinion spoken of by Arist, De An. i. 4, and according to which the Soul is regarded as the harmony of the body, belonged to the Pythago- reans. But I do not see how we can infer from this that the Pytha- goreans admitted a soul of the world (did Aristoxenus and Di- caearchus admit one 2). We shall presently see that , we have no right to attribute such a doctrine to the Pythagorean school. 1 Arist. De Coelo, ii. 13; vide supra, p. 444, 4; Simpl. in h. l. 229 a, 16 (Schol. 505 a, 19): of IIv0ayópeio. . . . v . Hºw tº uégº Toº travros trip elvaí pagi, trepi 6* Some accounts, To uéorov thu &vr£3:00pa (pépearðat (pool, yºv oſſo av kal airhv, &vríx90wa. ôè kaxoupévmv Ště to é; ávavrías Tjöe Tā yñ eival' were 6& Thy &vr£300wa. # yń #öe, tepouévn kal air? repl ro puéorov, pietà 5& Thy 'yūv # orexhum (oiſta, yap attos év tá, répart rôv IIv6ayoptków io'rope?) rºw 88 yńv &s ëv Tów &otpov oſſaav Kluovuévny trept To uéorov karū Thy Trpos Tov #Atov axéauv vökta kal huépav troleſv" i. 6& ăvríx0av civovuévn repl rô uéarov ſcal étouévn rì yī oëx āpārat āq’ huôv ölö. Tö étruirpoorðeiv juiv &el to Tſis 'yūs orðua. According to this pas- sage the side of the earth which we inhabit is always turned away from the central fire and the counter-earth. Plut. Plac. iii. 11, 3 (Galen, c. 21): pixóAaos é IIv%a- 'yópelos, to uév trip uéorov' roºro y&p feval too travros éoºrtav. Sevrépav 6& Thu ävrix0ova' rptºrmv 6&#v oikoduev 'yāv éč Švavrías kelpºunv Te Ical re- pitepouévny ti, &vríx0ovi" trap 8 kal ph 6p300a, Širo róv év Tjöe roºs év SYSTEM OF THE UNIVERSE. 451 it is true, reject the central fire and the motion of éketvm. Ibid. 13: oi uév &AAot uévetv Thy yºv pixóA. §§ 6 IIv6ay. kök}\g trepiq’épearðat repl to trop katē kū- k}\ov Aočod ówouotpétros fixiº Kal orexívn. Stob. i. 530 (similarly IPlut. Plac. ii. 20, 7; Galen, c. 14, p. 275): pixóAaos é IIv6ayópelos ūa- Aoetóñ Töv #Atov, Šexóuevov učv too év tá, kóo wº, trupbs Tºv &vraúyetav, 6tm600vra ö& Trpos juás Tó Te q6s kai Thy &Aéav, Šare rpárov twä, öurrows #Aíows yºyveg 6al, ré Te év tá, oùpavó Trupóðes, kal to &r' airoo trvpoetóēs Karö. Tö éoottpoetóés' ei aſ Tus kal Tpírov Aéfet Thy &rb row évôttpov kar’ &vákNao’iv 8tao trelpopuévnv trpos huās airyńv. Achill. Tat, in Ar. Prolegg. c. 19, p. 138 Pet.: pixó- Aaos 3& (Töv #Atóv pmol) to Tupéâes kal Suavyès Aap. 8&voura &va,6ew àtrö Tot, aiéeptov trupós trpès huas tréutretv Thu airyhv Štá Tivov &patoudrov, ãorte kar’ attöv Tpura by eival Tov #Atov, etc. (the sense is the same as in Stobaeus, but the text appears de- fective). In considering these state- ments, the first question that pre- sents itself is: How did the Pytha- goreans conceive the position of the counter-earth in regard to the earth and the central fire P From the na- ture of these things in themselves, two courses seem open. They might have placed it either between the earth and the central fire on the radius of the terrestrial orbit which goes from one to the other; or they might have placed it on the other side of the central fire, at the extremity of a line going from the earth through the central fire, and prolonged as far as the orbit of the counter-earth. Schaarschmidt (Schrift. d. Philol. 33) quotes the évavríav, Šć Čvavrfas of Aristotle and Simplicius to prove that such, according to the Pythagoreans, should in reality be the position of the counter-earth, but this interpre- tation seems to me mistaken. We may very well suppose, with Böckh, that this expression means that the earth turns its face from the central fire, and turns it towards the exte- rior circumference; and that the contrary holds good of the counter- earth. If even we refer this expres– sion simply to the situation of the counter-earth in regard to the earth, it simply implies that it is diametri- cally opposite to the earth; that is to say, is on the prolongation of the earth's axis (not on the side of it); whether on this side or that of the central fire is left undetermined. The opinion of Böckh is confirmed, not only by the word Étrouévny in the text of Simplicius, but also by the whole analogy of the Pytha- gorean doctrine, according to which the series of heavenly bodies was continued without interruption from the periphery as far as the central fire, and not terminated on the other side of the central fire (cf. Böckh, Kl. Schr. iii. 320 sq., where some other objections of Schaarschmidt against the earlier exposition of Böckh are refuted). As to the sun and the solar light, Achilles Tatius (as well as Stobaeus and the author from whom he takes his information) seems to admit that the solar light is the reflection of the fire of the circumference. Böckh (Philol. 124 sq.) thinks that this opinion is erroneous, and believes that the central fire is the luminous source, the rays of which the sun reflects to us; he afterwards (Unters. ib. d. kosm. Syst. d. Pla- ton, 94) gave the preference to the opinion of Martin (Etudes sur le Timée, ii. 100), according to which G G 2 452 THE PPTHAGO REANS, the earth, and make the counter-earth the moon,' or the second hemisphere of the earth.” But this is an erroneous interpretation of the old Pythagorean doctrine, from the standpoint of later astronomy. It is impossible that these accounts can be based upon any tradition as to the theories of the ancient Pytha- goreans, or of Pythagoras himself.” the sun concentrates and reflects, not only the light of the central fire, but also that of the external fire. No doubt the 6tm6eiv would not exclude a reflection of the central fire (as Böckh has suf- ficiently shown, Philol. 127 sq.), but, on the other hand, the reflec- tion of the triple sun (a doctrine which could not have come from Philolaus himself, cf. p. 316) is no proof that the solar light is de- rived from the central fire, and not from the fire of the periphery. Only it would seem that if this latter fire can enlighten the sun, it must also be visible to us. But we shall see further on that the Pythagoreans perhaps really thought they saw this fire in the milkyway. This belief accords with the opinion (contained in all the pas- sages quoted) that the rays of this fire, as well as those of the central fire, are concentrated and sent back by the sun, as by a sort of burning glass. It is not stated whether the Pythagoreans supposed that the other planets and fixed stars were foci of the same kind, but less in- tense, for these rays. Simpl. l. c. 229 a,37; Schol. 505 a, 32; ital oftw pièv airbs tº Töv IIv6ayopetov &teåétaro' of 6s 'yvnortórepov airów wetaoxóvres, etc. (vide sup. p. 447, 1) śarpov 8& thv yīv čAeyov &s āpyavov Kal It is only among airthy xpóvov huspóv ydp &otiv airm ka) vuktów airſa . . . &vríx60va 6& Thy gexhumv ékáNovvoi IIv6ayópelot, àortrep kal aiéeptav yiv, etc. As the doctrine here given as purely Pythagorean is expressly distin- guished from the Aristotelian ex- position, we are all the more certain as to the origin of the former. Clemens (Strom. v. 614 C), even thinks that the Pythagoreans meant by the counter-earth, heaven, in the Christian sense of the word. * Alex. Polyhistor. ap. Diog. viii. 25. The Pythagoreans taught kóa'uov . . . uéormv repléxovra thu ºyāv kal aithv gºalpoetőfi kal trept- outcovaévmv. elva. Śē Kal &utſtroëas, kai Tà juiv kata, Šicetwois &va. Similarly the anonymous author, ap. Phot. Cod. 249 (vide p. 444, 4) says that Pythagoras teaches the existence of twelve spheres, which are: the heaven of fixed stars, the seven planetary spheres (including sun and moon), the circles of fire, of air, and of water, and in the centre the earth. The other de- tails clearly show Aristotelian influence. * As Martin thinks (Et, sur le Timée, ii. 101 sqq.), and Gruppe (D. Kosm. Syst, d. Griechen, p. 48 sq.). According to their view, Py- thagoras and the oldest Pythago- reans represented the earth as an immovable sphere in the centre of CEWTRAL FIRE. COUNTER-EARTH, 453 the Pythagoreans of the fourth century that we find the doctrine of the earth's revolution on its axis,' which presupposes that the counter-earth and the central fire were abandoned as separate parts of the universe. It matters little whether they were absolutely suppressed, or the counter-earth regarded as the western hemisphere, and the central fire placed in the interior the universe. The do strine of the central fire, and the revolution around this fire, was subsequently advanced, Gruppe believes, by Hip- pasus or some other predecessor of Philolaus, but at first without the counter-earth; it was only a corruption of this doctrine which inserted the counter-earth between the earth and the central fire. The groundlessness of these hypotheses, which Böckh has refuted (l.c. p. 89 sqq.) very effectually, is manifest when we examine from a critical point of view the evidence on which they are based. The doctrines which Gruppe takes for traces of true Pythagoreanism are rather indica- tions of a period which was unable to place itself at the ancient Py- thagorean standpoint. Lastly, when Röth (ii. a, 817 sq. b, 247 sq.) maintains that Pythagoras and his school understood, by the counter-earth, the hemisphere op- posite to ours; that they placed the earth in the centre of the uni- verse, and ascribed to it a move- ment around its axis—this asser- tion is not worthy of a refutation. It is now universally recognised that Copernicus and others were wrong in attributing to the Pytha- goreans the doctrine of the rotation of the earth on its axis, and the revolution of the earth round the sun. Wide Tiedemann (Die ersten Philosophen Griechenlands, p. 448 sq.; Böckh, De Plat. Sysſ. Coel. Globor. p. xi. sq.; Kl. Schrif. iii. 272); Philol. 121 sq.; Martin, Etudes, &c. ii. 92 sq. * According to Cic. Acad. ii. 39, 123, Theophrastus named as the author of that opinion the Sy- racusan Hicetas. Later on we find it in Ecphantus (Hippolyt. Réfut. i. 15, p. 30; Plut. Plac. iii. 13, 3), and Heracleides (Part ii. a, 887, third edition). Martin, l. c. 101, 125, and Gruppe, l. c. 87 sqq., think we may attribute also to Hicetas the central fire and the planetary movement of the earth around that fire. Cf. however Böckh, D. kosm. Syst. Pl. 122 sqq. He shows that in the passage of Plutarch, Pac. iii. 9 (where, in- deed, Eusebius, Pr. Ev. xv. 55, gives our actual text, but where Pseudo-Galen. Hist. Phil. 21, p. 293, does not mention the name of Hicetas), an error has probably crept in, by the omission of some words; and that the original text may have stood thus: “Icérms 6 IIv0ayópeios ut a v, p 1A 6A a os 3 & 6 IIv6 a y 6pe to s 600, etc. Tradi- tion tells us nothing as to the date when Hicetas lived; but Böckh's conjecture (l. c. 126) that he was the teacher of Ecphantus and younger than Philolaus seems probable. 454 THE PV THAGOREA.N.S. of the earth. To the same period may perhaps belong the theory that the comet is a separate planet;" this eighth planet might serve, when the counter-earth had been discarded, to maintain the number ten in regard to the heavenly bodies.” The conjecture may, however, have emanated from those who were ignorant of the system of the ten heavenly bodies and the counter-earth, or rejected it. considered the shape of the * Arist. Meteorol. i. 6, 342 b, 29: Tów 6' 'IraNików rives ka? Kaxovuévay IIv6ayopetov čva Aéyov- oiv airby (sc. Töv kopfitny) sival táv waavítwv&otépov. A similar opinion is said to have been expres- sed by Hippocrates of Chios (circ. 450), and his disciple, AEschylus. Also Alex. in h. l. (Arist. Meteor ed. Idel. i. 180); Plut. Plac. iii. 2, 1 ; Stob. Ecl. i. 576. These last added that others of the Py- thagoreans regarded the comet merely as a luminous reflection. Olympiodorus (p. 183, Idel.) transfers to Pythagoras himself what Aristotle says of ‘some Py- thagoreans.’ The Scholiast ad Arat. Diosem. 359 (ap. Idel. l. c. p. 380 sq.), doubtless through an error, gives a general appli- cation to the text relative to the JPythagoreans, and counts Hippo- eratus among the philosophers of that school; and it is probably in this sense that he is called, ap. Alex. eſs röv plaffnpatticóv. * The central fire might still preserve its significanee, even if it were conceived as surrounded by the earth as by a hollow sphere. * Böckh (Kl. Schr. iii. 335 sq.) thinks that the Pythagoreans con- ceived the earth and the counter- earth as two hemispheres which, There is no doubt that the Pythagoreans earth to be spherical:” its separated by a space more or less great, turn their plane sides towards each other. He has been led to this opinion merely by the presup- position (l. c. 329 sq.) that the IPythagoreans arrived at their doc- trine of the counter-earth by the partition of the earth into two hemispheres. He afterwards ad- mits that Aristotle had no idea of such an opinion, but represents the earth and the counter-earth of the Pythagoreans as two complete spheres. But there is no ground at all, in my judgment, for this supposition of Böckh as to the origin of the Pythagorean doctrine. If they once conceived the earth as a sphere, it was certainly more natural—in case a tenth heavenly body seemed necessary—to admit the counter-earth as a second sphere than to divide the earth it- self into two hemispheres. The analogy of the other stars also makes it probable that the earth and the counter-earth were con- ceived as spheres, as well as the sun and moon. Lastly, if Aristotle has represented the matter thus, we can scarcely give the preference to any other testimony. Alex. (ap. Diog. viii. 25 sq.) says that the Pythagoreans regarded the earth as spherical, and inhabited in its SOLAR ECLIPSES. 455 position towards the central fire and the sun was such that it should turn its western hemisphere to the central fire." At the same time, they did not overlook the in- climation of the earth's orbit towards the sun’s ;” this was necessary in their cosmical system, not merely to explain the changes in the seasons, but because the earth would otherwise have every day prevented the light of the central fire from reaching the sun, by its passage between them. Solar eclipses were accounted for by the passing of the moon between the earth and sum ; and lunar eclipses by the interposition of the earth or other heavenly bodies between the sun and moon.” The Pythagoreans circumference (which implies the idea of antipodes). Favorinus says (ap. Diog. viii. 48) that Pythagoras affirmed it to be round (otpoyºyöAm). But neither of these assertions should outweigh the evidence of Aristotle. * Gruppe, loc, cit., p. 65 sqq., thinks that the earth presented to the sun the northern hemisphere, and to the central fire the southern ; he also thinks that the Pythagoreans regarded the side turned towards the central fire as the upper. But Bockh has completely refuted this hypothesis (D. kosm. Syst. Pl. 102 sqq.; cf. Kl. Schr. iii. 329). * Plut. Plac. iii. 13, 2 (Galen, c. 14, 21) : pixóAaos . . . kūkāq, trepiq’épea9at [thy yīv] repl to trip karū kök}\ov Aošov. Ibid. ii. 12, 2 (Stob. i. 502; Galen, c. 12): IIv6a- 'yápas trpátos étruevonkéval Aéyétat thv Aéoguv too (wèiakov reticAov, #vruva Oivotiëns 6 Xtos és ičíav étri- volav gºetepigetat. Cf. c. 23, 6. According to others, Anaximander had already made this discovery held the sun and moon to (vide Supra, p. 254, 3). According to Theo (Astron. p. 322 Mart. end ; Fragm. ed. Spengel, p. 140), Eudemus attributed it to OEnopides – if we may read in the fragment Aóšoortv instead of Šid (waiv. The assertion of the Placita, that Eu- demus had taken it from Pythago- ras, would incline us to suppose (as Schäfer justly observes) that Eudemus had claimed it for him- self (Schäfer, Die Astron. Geogra- phie der Griechen &c., Gymn. progr. Flensb. 1873, p. 17). In Diod. i. 98, some Egyptian sages assert that CEnopides had learned the in- clination of the ecliptic in Egypt, which equally presupposes that he must have been the first to intro- duce it into Greece. In that case the Pythagoreans would have de- rived it from him. According to Proclus (in Eucl. 19, 66th Fragm.) CEnopides was a little younger than Anaxagoras, and a little older than Philolaus. * On eclipses of the sun, vide Stob. i. 526; on those of the moon 456 THE PYTHAGOREANS, be vitreous spheres,' which reflected back light and warmth to the earth.” At the same time we are told that they conceived the stars as resembling the earth, and surrounded like the earth by an atmosphere;” wide Arist. De Caelo, ii. 13, 293 b, 21. He says, after speaking of the counter-earth: évíows 8& Öoke. Kat arãeſo orépara totaúta évôéxeoffat q,épeo:6al repl to uéorov, juiv Šē &ömāa Suð. Thy trutſpéorèmoivºrºs yús. 6to kal r&s tºs orexhvms ékNetheus traetovs 3) rās rot fixtov yi-yverbal qaqiv táv yūp (pepouévov čkaorov &vtiqpdºttetv airtºv, &AA’ oil uávov thv yiv. Similarly Stob. Eel. i. 558 (Plac. ii. 29, 4; Galen, c. 15). Schäfer thinks he has diseovered the reason of this opinion (l.c. p. 19), independently of the greater number of lunar eclipses, in the phenomenon mentioned by Pliny, H. Nat. ii. 13, 57, and the date of which we do not know. Pliny says that the moon was in eclipse at her setting, while the rising sun was already visible above the ho- rizon, a phenomenon explicable by refraction. We find the same opinion in Anaxagoras, vide infra, vol. II. * Wide p. 450, 1, and Plut. Plac. ii. 25, 7 (Stob. i. 552): IIv6ayópas karottpostöès orópa rās o'exhvns. (Similarly Galen, c. 15.) As re- gards the form of the sun, the Placita (ap. Euseb. Pr. Ev. xv. 23, 7) describe it as a vitreous disc (8toricos); but this description is not found in any other text, and expressly contradicts what is said in Stob. i. 526: oi IIv6. org/wipoetőfi Töv #Atov. Moreover, the Pytha- goreans must have attributed to the sun the same shape as to the moon, the spherical form of which is never disputed. We must, therefore, consider the statement of Eusebius as erroneous. * Whence came light and heat to the sun and the moon? We have already discussed this ques- tion in regard to the sun (p. 450, 1). As to the moon there can be no doubt that her light was supposed to be derived, not direetly from the central fire, but from the sun which, in the time of Philolaus, had long been regarded as the source of the moon's light. For if the moon had received her light from the central fire, she must always have been enlightened, since she pre- sents the same side to the cen- tral fire as to the earth. Aris- totle mentions also (vide Supra, 455, 3) the opinion (incompatible with the assertion of Philolaus of ten heavenly bodies) that other bodies besides the earth cause eclipses of the moon. We cannot perceive in this, as Böckh does (Philol. 129) and Martin (Etudes, 99), an interposition of these small planets between the central fire and the moon, but the interposition of these planets between the sun and the moon. Why the moon is not enlightened by the central fire, or is enlightened too faintly to be visible to us without the light of the Sun, is not explained by any document that we possess. * Stob. i. 514: ‘Hpakaetóns kal oi IIv6ayópelot exagºrov rôv čo Tépov kóopov Štröpxely yńv reptéxovta. &épa re (Plut. Plac. ii. 13, 8; Galen, c. 13, add: kai aiéépa) év tá, âtreſpº aiéépu' raúra öö tä 567.pata. THE STAZS. 457 they attributed to the moon, plants and living beings far larger and fairer than those on the earth." This theory was founded, it would seem, partly on the ap- pearance of the moon’s disc, which resembles the earth; and partly on the desire to discover a special abode for the souls who had quitted the earth, and for the daemons.” Also they thought that the stars, which like the earth were planets, but which belonged to a better portion of the universe, must possess everything that serves to adorn the earth, in a more perfect manner. Of the planets, the order of which the Pythagoreans were the first to determine,” Mercury and Venus, the two which later astronomy places be tween the sun and the earth, were placed by them between the sun and Mars.” Pythagoras is said to év Tols 'Oppiko’s pépetal' kooru.0- trouotoi Y&p ékaotov Tów >épov. * Plut. Plac. ii. 30, 1 (Galen, c. 15): oi IIv6ayópelot (Stob. i. 562: Töv IIv6ayopetov rivés, &v éutt ‘puadaaos) yet'.8m patveq6at thv ore- Aftwmv. 61& To trepioikeforéal airhy ka04 rep a hu trap' haiv yiv, pleíſoori §§ous kai purois RaxAtoo weival yèp Trevrekaušekatraaortova rā Śr' airfis (£& Tā āuvâuel uměčv trepitrouattkov &mokpívovira real thv jiuépav roo attmv Tó uſiket. Böckh (131 sq.) suspects with reason some error in the last statement. For if one terrestrial day corresponds with one revolu- tion of the earth around the central fire, the moon, whose period of revolution is 29 times and a half greater, ought to have days as long as a terrestrial month—that is, in round numbers, 30 terrestrial days. The size and strength of the in- habitants correspond to the length of the day. But perhaps the ex- pression may be inexact, and the author means to say that the dura- tion of the day light is equal to 15 complete terrestrial days. In any case, however (as we have ob- served p. 317), the inaccuracy of our document proves nothing against the authenticity of the work of Philolaus. * The first remark is to be found in the passage quoted in the previous note; the second notion comes from the Orphic poems, and the saying ascribed to Pythagoras by Iambl. V. P. 82: tí Čorriv at Hakápov viorot; #xios, orexivm. * Eudemus, ap. Simpl. De Coelo, 212 a, 13; Schol. 497 a, 11. * Cf. on this subject, besides the texts cited p. 444, 4; 420, 2, Plato, Rep. x. 616 E.; Tim. 38 D; Theo Astron. c. 15, p. 180. Against these testimonies we have the fol- lowing: Nicom. Harm. 6, 33 sq.; Plin. Hist. Nat. ii. 22, 84; Censorin. 458 THE PPTHAGO REANS, have discovered that Venus is both the morning and the evening star." The heaven of fixed stars, in common with the other heavenly bodies, revolves around the central fire ;” but as its apparent diurnal revolution is interrupted by the movement of the earth, the Pytha- goreans must have here conceived a far longer period of revolution, imperceptible in relation to the daily revolution of the earth : they seem however to have been led to this theory not by actual observations, but merely by dogmatic presuppositions on the nature of the stars.” They reckoned motion among the essential qualities of the heavenly bodies, and in the unchange- able regularity of their courses found the most obvious proof of the divinity of the stars, in which they believed, like most of the ancients.” According to the period of revolution attributed to the fixed stars, they seem to have determined the universal year, a conception Di. Nat. 13, 3; Chalcid. in Tim. c. 71, p. 155 (197 Mull.), and other statements of more recent origin, which follow the order that was afterwards adopted. But these texts have as little authority as the verses of Alexander of Ephesus (contemporary of Cicero, as to whom cf. Martin, in his edition of Theo's Astronomy, p. 66 sq.; Meineke, Anal. Alear. 371 sq.; Müller, Hist. Gr. iii. 240); ap. Theo, loc. cit. (where they are wrongly attributed to Alexander the AEtolian); Chal- cid. loc. cit. (who attributes them to Alexander of Miletus, the well- known Polyhistor); Heraclit. Alleg. Hom. c. 12. Alexander does not once mention the Pythagoreans. * Diog. viii. 14; cf. ix. 23; Plin. ii. 8, 37. * This certainly results from the evidence quoted p. 444, 4, Wide Böckh, D. Kosm. Syst. I’l. p. 99 sq. (as against Gruppe, l. c. 70 sqq.). * The precession of the equi- noxes, of which Böckh is thinking (loc. cit. p. 93, 99 sqq.; Philol. 118 sq.), was only discovered at a much later time by Hipparchus, as we find from other sources. * Wide (besides Neo-Pythago- rean writers, such as Onatas, ap. Stob. i. 96, 100 ; Ocellus, c. 2, and the Pseudo-Philolaus, ap. Stob. i. 422). Plato, who, especially in the Phaedrus, 246 E sqq. (Böckh proves this, Philol. 105 sq. and most wri- ters have agreed with him), has in- contestably followed Pythagorean ideas; and Aristotle, De An. i. 2, 405 a, 29; cf. 455, 1, 3, 4 ; wide also Supra, p. 444, 4. THE STARS. 459 hich Plato no doubt borrowed from them." At any ate it is closely connected in the Platonic philosophy with the doctrine of metempsychosis, in which he chiefly followed the Pythagoreans, and is also dominated by the number ten, in a manner so entirely Pythagorean, that the supposition has much in its favour.” * Wide part II. a 684, 4. * We must, however, distinguish from this cosmical year the cycle of 59 years, in which were 21 inter- calary months—that is to say, the great year invented by Philolaus, or even as some say, by Pythagoras, in order to make the solar and lunar months coincide. Plut. Plac. ii. 32; Stob. i. 264; Censorin. Di. Mat. 18, 8; vide for further details, Böckh, Philol. 133 sqq. The re- volution of Saturn was also called the great year; l’hot. Cod. 249, p. 440 a, 20. According to Censo- rinus, loc. cit., and 19, 2, Philolaus reckoned the duration of the solar year at 364 days and a half. Böckh thinks this incredible, be- cause the year of 365 days had then long been known in Egypt, and he gives an explanation of the passage in Censorinus, which cer- tainly does not remove all difficul- ties. Schaarschmidt, p. 57, natu- rally sees nothing in this theory but a proof of ignorance in the Pseudo-Philolaus. It seems to me by no means established that the Egyptian year was known to Philolaus, and still less, that he had such decisive reasons for main- taining the Egyptian reckoning that no considerations could have in- duced him to deviate from it. Such considerations might be found by a Pythagorean, who placed numbers and characteristic numerical paral- lelisms above all things, in this (cf. Böckh, p. 135); that the 29 and a half days of the lunar month give 59 half days—i.e., the same number as the 59 years of the cycle; that the 59 years and 21 months are equal to 729 months; and the 364} days of the solar year are equal to 729 half days; lastly that 729 is the cube of 9 and the square of 27, or the first cube of an uneven number (hence the number 729 has for Plato also—Rep. ix. 587 E—- an especial significance). However this may be, I am disposed to think (as Böckh does) that it is more likely that some Pythagorean of the fifth century, whether from his imperfect knowledge or other causes, may have reckoned the year at 364; days, than that a well-informed writer of the first or second century B.C., a time when the year of 365 days had become quite usual, should from ignorance have shortened this period by half a day. This seems to me so wholly improbable that if there were no means of connecting this computation of 364; days with Philolaus (which I do not admit), I should be content with the fol- lowing conjecture. Censorinus, or the author whom he follows, must have arrived at these 364; days by a calculation founded on state- ments relative to the great year of Philolaus. These statements may have been altered through the fault of a copyist or in some other way; and Philolaus, in reality, 460 THE PYTHAGOREA.N.S. Compared with the ordinary motions of the ancients, this theory shows a remarkable progress in astronomy. For while they, presupposing that the earth was at rest, derived the changes of day and night and the seasons exclusively from the sun, an attempt was here first made to explain day and night, at any rate, by the motion of the earth; and though the true explanation, the revolution of the earth on its axis, was not as yet discovered, yet the Pythagorean doctrine in its imme- diate astronomical result directly led up to this, and as soon as the phantastic ideas, which alone resulted from the speculative presuppositions of Pythagoreanism, had been given up, the counter-earth as western hemi- sphere necessarily merged into the earth ; the central fire was transferred to the earth’s centre, and the move- ment of the earth around the central fire was changed into a revolution on its own axis." The famous harmony of the spheres was a conse- quence of the movement of the heavenly bodies. For as every quickly moved body produces a tone, the Pythagoreans believed it must be the same with the heavenly bodies. They supposed the acuteness of these tones to be according to the rapidity of motion, and this again to be in proportion to the distance of the several planets, the intervals of the planets corresponded with the intervals of sounds in the octave. Thus they arrived at the theory that the heavenly bodies in their may have made 59 solar years moon, we get for the year 365 equal to 59 lunar years, plus 22 days, as exactly as we get 364}, if months (instead of 21), and, there- we make 59 years equal to 729 fore to 730 revolutions of the months. moon ; in which case, if we take * As Böckh well observes, 29; days for the revolution of the Philol. 123. HARMONY OF THE SPHERES. 461 rotation produce a series of tones,' which together form an octave, or, which is the same thing, a harmony.” | Arist. De Caelo, ii. 9, sub init.: pavepov 3’ ex rotºrov, Šti kal rö pdvat yived 9at ºpepouévov ſtav >pov] §puovíav, &s ovuqºvov 'ylvouévov ráv jópov, Kouyás ºv ełpmrat kal reputrós into róv eitróv- Tov, où why oira's #xei Täxm6és. ãokeſ ydp rioriv, and farther on, more precisely : rows IIv6ayopetous &vaykalov elval, traucotºrww pepopué- vov orwuátwv yiyveabat póqov, Štrel Kal rôv trap' juiv oëre rows tºykovs éxóvrav trous otºre rototrº Téxel q)spouévov iiNtov Šē kal orexhums, éti re roo'oùrov to wx760s &otpov real To uéye 00s (pepowevov tá, taxel Towattmv popāv, &öövarov whºyfyve- 0.0a ||6 pov &pſixovév two to Méyé00s. Öroðéuevo, 5è raúra Kal T&s taxvtſitas Éic Töv &troordiq'eav ëxeiv toys róv ovudwViðv Aérous, évapuáviáv paori yived 6al thy povhv qepopuévov kūkāq, tàv &otpav. Or, according to the commentary of Alexander (Ad Metaph. i. 5, p. 29, 6 Bon. 542 a, 5 ; cf. 31 Bon. 542 b, 7): tóv Yap orwud twv Töv trepi Tô wéorov qepopuévov čv &vaAoyig ràs àtrogrógeis éxóvray . trouotvrov 6é ſcal págov ći tº kiveto 6al rôv učv 8paôvrépov 8aptiv, Töv 6& Taxvtépov ščüv, toos péqovs toūrous karū thv Tóv &Tootáaewy âvaxo'ytav yivouévous évapuávtov Tów é; airröv fixov troueiv. čírel 6' 3Aoyov *6ákei rb whº ovvakočeiv huàs ris qovſis tatt me, airtov Totºrov qaqiv eival to yewouévous ei60s jirópxely Töv påqov, Šote už övdānxov sival trpès rêvévavitſav oriyâv trpos &AAm- Aa y&p pavis ical orityńs eival rhy 614-yvajoriv, &ote Ka8átrep rois XaA- korémous 6ta avv^6etav ot,0&v Šoke? 6tapépeiv, kal Tois àv6párous rairo orvuòaivetv. We shall presently The find other proofs which, however, are hardly necessary, after this detailed explanation from our principal authority. * It has already been observed (p. 385,1,2) that the Pythagoreans primarily understand by harmony the octave. It is also the octave which is in question in the har- mony of the spheres In the first place the name itself indicates this, and in the second the comparison of the planets with the seven strings of the ancient lyre was too obvious to be overlooked by the Pythagoreans. It is also clear, from the evidence of the an- cients. In the passage just quoted from Aristotle, the words A6-you rôv ovuſpovićv can scarcely mean any- thing else than the relations of the octave; for, according to Aristox- enus the Peripatetic (ii. 45) of the eight symphonies of which the later theory treats (Aristox. Harm. i. 20; Euclid. Introd. Harm. p. 12 sq.; Gaudentius, Isag. p. 12), the harmonists before his time only employed the first three, called the Diatessaron, Diapente, and Diapa- son (fourth, fifth, octave). Simi- larly in the verses of Alexan- der of Ephesus (mentioned supra, p. 457, 4), despite the musical errors in the further development of the thought, which Martin (Theo, Astron. 358 sq.) exposes, following Adrastus and Theo, the tones of the Seven planets and their intervals correspond with those of the seven-stringed lyre. Moreover, Nicomachus (Harm. 6, 33 sq.), followed by Boethius (Mus. i. 20, 27), says expressly that the seven planets correspond exactly 462 THE PYTHAGOREA.N.S. fact that we do not hear these tones, they explaimed b saying that we are in the condition of people who liv in their distances and their tones with the strings of the heptachord. In contrast with the ancient system (vide p. 457, 4) he places the sun in the centre; of the seven strings, the lowest, having at the same time the highest tone (vitm), corresponds with the moon ; the highest, but having the gravest tone (örárm), corresponds with Saturn. But Ni- comachus does not forget to re- mark that his predecessors made the moon in dºrm (Alex. Ephes. l. c. says carelessly the Earth), and thence ascended to Saturn the vàrn ; this is admitted by Alex. Aphr. among others(vide preceding note). From the same ancient source, as it appears, Aristides Quint. Mus, iii. 145, derives his explanation, to Ště tragöv thu rôv TAavnTöv čupexh kivmaſiv [rpooroºm- Matveij, and it is likewise from ancient sources that Emmanuel Bryennius, Harm. (Oxon. 1699), Sect. i. 363, explains more particu- larly which of the planets corre- sponds with each of the seven strings as to tone, assigning the lowest tone to the moon, the high- est to Saturn, the puéorm to the sun. Cicero, or an ancient author whom he takes as guide ( Somn. c. 5), is manifestly thinking of the hepta- chord and of the octave when he says of the eight celestial bodies endowed with motion, that two of them, Mercury and Venus, have the same tone; there are consequently in all, seven different sounds: quod docti homines nervis imitati atque cantibus aperuere sibi reditum in hunc locum. Only he makes the heaven of fixed stars take part in the music; to them he ascribes the highest sound, and the lowest to the moon. In Pliny, Hist. Nat. ii. 22, 84, Pythagoras determines, ac- cording to the same system, the distance of celestial bodies. The distance of the moon from the earth (reckoned by Pythagoras at 126,000 stadia according to c. 21), being taken as equivalent to one -tone, that between the sun and moon is placed at 23 tones, and that be- tween the heaven of fixed stars and the sun at 3}: ita septem tomos effici quam diapason harmoniam vocant. No doubt this last is a misunderstanding; but a misun- derstanding that might easily arise, if we reflect that the earth, be- ing immovable, could not produce any sound; that consequently the real distance of the sonorous bodies answers exactly to that of the chords; for, from the moon to the sun is a fourth (the sun only takes this place in the new theory), from the sun to the heaven of fixed stars a fifth, and the eight sounds united form an octave of six tones. The other calculation (according to Plut. De An. Procr. 31, 9, 102, 8 sq., and Censorin. Di. Nat; c. 13), which reckons from the earth (placed as the Tpoo Aaußavópepos one tone lower than the Štrárm).to the sun three tones and a half, and from thence to the heaven of fixed stars, 23– gives, it is true, the correct number of tones—six ; but it omits the muteness of the earth (for we have nothing to do here with the theory of Philolaus of the movement of the earth), and it does not agree with the division of the octachord which requires a fifth, from the Aéorm to the virm. These authors, PIARMONY OF THE SPHERES, 463 in a smith's forge; from our births we are unceasingly hearing the same sound, and so are never in a position to take note of its existence from the contrast of silence.1 like Cicero and Pliny, make the fixed heaven, the ātrāavés, partici- pate in the celestial music. On the other hand, at the commencement of the chapter, Censorinus restricts it to the seven planets, which is correct. The contradiction of this with what he elsewhere says, is another proof that he is following an ancient source, the meaning of which he does not fully compre- hend. According to Martin (Etudes sur le Timée, ii. 37), the sounds of the octave, being produced simul- taneously, do not form a symphony. But the Pythagoreans did not allow their imaginations to be fettered, either by this difficulty or by others we have mentioned, and which are for the most part examined by Aris- totle. Macrob. Somn. Scip. ii. 1, sub fin., reckons the extent of the celes- tial symphony at four octaves, and a fifth (departing from the system of harmonic numbers in the Tºmaus, ii. 37 by one tone only, vide part II. a, 653 sq.). Anatolius, ap. Iambli- chum, Theol. Arithm. 56, distribu- ting after his manner the tones among the celestial bodies, makes it two octaves and a tone. Plu- tarch, l.c. c. 32, quotes an opinion afterwards contested by Ptolemy (Harm. iii. 16), according to which the sounds of the seven planets answer to those of the seven inva- riable chords in the lyre of fifteen strings; then he quotes another opinion, according to which the distances of the planets would be analogous to the five tetrachords of the complete system. These ideas cannot possibly have belonged to the ancient Pythagoreans, for the development of the harmonic sys- tem and the augmentation of the number of chords which they pre- Suppose, are of a later date. Ac- cording to an opinion ascribed to Pythagoreans by Plutarch (l.c. 31), each of the ten celestial bodies, animated by movement, is sepa- rated from the body below it by a distance three times as great as the distance separating this from the next lowest. This opinion has nothing to do with the calculation of tones in the spheral harmony, and the same remark applies to what Plato says (Rep. x. 616 C sqq.; Tºm. 36 D, 38 C sqq.) of the distancesandvelocity of the planets, though harmony is mentioned in the first of these passages. Among moderns, cf. on this question, first the classical essay of Böckh in the Studien v. Daub und Creuzer, iii. 87 sqq. (now K. Schr. iii. 169 sq.), where the correspondence of the celestial harmony with the dis- tances of the heptachord is also explained in regard to the ancient system ; and lastly, Martin, Etudes, ii. 37 sqq. * This is the opinion of Aris- totle and Heracleitus, Alleg. Hom. c. 12, p. 24 Mehl. The latter adds, as a possible reason, the great distance of the heavenly bodies. Simplicius, it is true, De Coelo, 211, a, 14; Schol. 496 b, 11 sqq. thinks this too ordinary a reason to be held by a school, the founder of which had himself heard the har- mony of the spheres, and gives this sublimer reason (also indicated by Cicero, Somn, c. 5, together with that of Aristotle) that the 464 THE PYTHIAGOREAAWS, This notion of the spheral harmony had no connection originally with the system of the ten heavenly bodies," but related only to the planets; for ten tones would have resulted from the motion of ten bodies; whereas seven sounds are required for harmony, according to the ancient harmonic system which is based on the heptachord; and eight, if the octachord be adopted. Now one or other of these numbers is always assigned to the harmony of the spheres by all who discuss it particularly.” The number must originally have been seven ; for down to the time of Philolaus, the Pythagorean theory recognises only the seven notes of the heptachord.” The testimony of Aristotle + does not contradict this. It is possible, in the first place, that he had Plato or certain Platonists in his mind as music of the heavenly bodies is not perceptible to the ears of ordinary mortals. Porphyry expresses this idea in a physical manner (in Ptol. Harm, p. 257) when he says that our ears are too narrow to perceive these powerful sounds. Archytas seems to have anticipated him in this, wide the fragment quoted in Porph. l. c. and supra, p. 306 sq. | Perhaps it is for this reason that Philolaus does not mention it (so far, at least, as we can discover from the fragments that remain of him). What Porph. V. Pyth. 31, placing himself at the point of view of the geocentric system, says of the nine sonorous celestial bodies, called by Pythagoras the nine muses, betrays a recent ori- gin, if only by the un-Pythagorean interpretation of the Avrixflav. 2. Cf. on this subject (besides what has been cited. p. 461, 2), |Plato Rep. x. 616 sq., who re- fers the celestial harmony to the heaven of fixed stars and to the planets; Hippol. Refut. i. 2, p. 8, who refers it solely to the planets. Censorin. Di. Nat. c. 13: (Pythag.) hunc omnem mundum enarmonion esse ostendit. Qware Dorylaus scripsit esse mundum organum Dei : alii addiderunt, esse id Širrd- Xopbov, quia Septem sint vagae 8tellae, quae plurimum moveantur. * As Böckh shows, Philol. 70 sq., appealing to the passage of Philolaus quoted p. 385, 2. Arist. Probl. xix. 7; Plut. Mus. 19; Ni- com. Harm. i. 17, ii. 27; cf. Boeth. Mus. i. 20. The assertion of Bryennius, Harm. sect. i. p. 365, that Pythagoras was the discoverer of the octachord cannot here be considered. * Who, it is true, must be also thinking of the fixed stars when he uses the expression roo'oùrov 'rb TA760s &orpov. FIRE OF THE PERIPHER P. 465 well as the Pythagoreans; and it is a question, in the second place, whether, supposing him to mean the Pythagoreans only, he simply reproduces their theory without any admixture of his own presuppositions. But the theory of the spheral harmony, though it primarily related to the planets alone, was based on a universal thought, the very thought that Aristotle attributes to the Pythagoreans (Metaph. 1, 5), viz., that the whole universe is a harmony. This thought directly resulted, as we have seen, from the perception or presentiment of a regular order in the distances and movements of the heavenly bodies: what the eye sees in observing the stars, that the ear hears in the concord of tones." Engrossed with symbols, and little con- cerned with the precise discrimination of concepts, the Pythagoreans identified harmony with the octave; after this it was easy for them to regard the celestial harmony also as an octave, and the seven planets as the golden strings of the heavenly heptachord. This poetical thought doubtless came first ; the intellectual arguments which, according to Aristotle, were brought forward to justify it are certainly posterior. The chief function of the fire of the circumference, in the Pythagorean theory, was to hold the cosmos together as a covering embracing the whole, and on this account they seem to have called it necessity.” It * Plato, Rep. vii. 430 D : kiv- 8vvetet, æq.mv, &s trpès &otpovopatav ăupata trémyev, &s trpos évappuéviov qopāv &ra retrnyéval, kal airal âAA#Awy &öexpaí tºwes ai étriotăual elval, is of Te IIv6ayópelot part kai jueſs, & TAačkov, avyxwpoupev. Cf. Archytas ap. Porph. in Ptolem, WOL. I. Harm. p. 236 (Fragm. Philos. i. 564): Trept re 63) tas rôv &otpov Taxurāros kai éiritoxãv kal 660 ww. trapéðakav ćuiv Štáyvoortv; cal repl " Tauerpías kal &piðuðvical ovX #Riata trepi uovo.ukås raira yöp tº ua&#- gara öokoúvri eluev &öexped. * This appears to me to result BI H 466 THE PPTHAGORPAWS. is not improbable also that they derived the light of the stars from it, and in a certain degree that of the sun; there are reasons too for supposing that they believed that this fire, or a radiation from it, was seem in the milky Way.” from the mutilated passage ap. Plut. Plac. i. 25, 2 (Stob. i. 158; Galen, c. 10, p. 261; Theod. Cur. Gr. Aff. vi. 13, p. 87): IIv6ayápas. äväykmu èqm treptireto 6al ºrg Köopaq. Ritter (Pyth. Phil. 183) finds in this passage the thought that the Unlimited in embracing the world transforms it to something limited, and subjects it to matural neces- sity. But according to the Pytha- gorean doctrine, the Unlimited cannot be conceived as that which embraces or limits ; trepaivov and &trepov are diametrically opposed to each other. Similarly, the &vdºkm, by which Plato in the Timaeus certainly means natural necessity as distinguished from the divine activity working to an end, cannot have had this significa- tion with the Pythagoreans; for the idea of this opposition is, as we have seen (supra, p. 397), alien to them. Necessity seems rather to mean, with them, the bond of the universe; and when they say that it embraces the world, we think most naturally of the fire of the periphery. Plato seems to confirm this view when (Rep. x. 617 B), inspired with the Pytha- gorean spirit, he makes the spin- dle with the circles of the cosmos turn upon the knees of 'Aváykm, which consequently here embraces all the spheres alike. In the same manner Iambl. writes (Th. Arithm. p. 61): thy ’Aväykmy of 0soxóryol tſ, roſ, Travros oëpavoj čotátn &vrvyi (circle) éirmxoşat. Wendt. (Jahr- Beyond the circle of fire lay the batch f wissensch. Krit. 1828, 2, 379) regards 'Avdºyich as synony- mous with harmony. But although Diog. says (viii. 85) that, according to Philolaus all things take place &váykm kal &puovíq, we must not conclude from this that Philolaus identified necessity with harmony; for it could not be said of harmony that it envelopes the world. * Wide p. 450, 1. * This conjecture, which we already find in Böckh (Philol. 99), is founded upon the intimation which he also gives (Kl. Schr. iii. 297 sq.) that Plato, in speaking of the light which envelopes the world (Rep. x. 616 B sq.), as the âtroſópata of a ship, in all proba- bility is thinking of the milky way. Of this light it is said that in its bosom the circles of heaven unite —and it is from these circles that the spindle of 'Aváykm proceeds, that spindle which (617 B) turns upon the knees of 'Avdylcm. If we combine these passages with those quoted in the preceding note, it seems probable that the fire of the periphery, which, as the bond of the world, was called 'Avâykm, is the same as the milky way. With this passage of Plato we may also connect the statement ap. Stob. Eel. i. 256: oi ätrö IIv0ayópov toy icóapov a palpaw . . . uévov 8& To &váratov trüp covoetőés. According to Böckh, Plato compares this light to a column, because the vertical cone of the milky way would appear so if seen from some particular point THE UNLIMITED. 467 Unlimited, or the unlimited air (Tvsåpa), from which the universe draws its breath." outside the world. It is a ques- tion, however, whether the Pytha- goreans did not rather believe that the fire of the periphery flamed up from the northern summit of the milky way, in a great column rest- ing on a wide base and terminating in a point, and whether this opinion did not influence the exposition of Plato. I cannot agree with the alterations in the text próposed by Erohn (D. Platon. Staat, p. 282 sq.). This doctrine of the fire of the periphery, or at least of its identity with the milky way, seems to have been confined to a part of the school. For in what concerns the milky way, Aristotle, although the fire of the periphery was not unknown to him (vide De Caelo, ii. 13; the words to 5’ oxarov kal to uégov Trépas, cited p. 444, 4, evidently relate to this fire). quotes (Metereol. i. 8) from the Pythago- rean school (Töv kańovuévay IIv6a- yopetov twks) the opinion that the milky way is the trace or course of one of the stars that fell in the catastrophe of Phaeton; or else a course once traversed by the sun, but now abandoned. This opinion is also found in Olymp. and Philo- ponus ad h. l. (i. 198, 203, Id.), and in Stob. Fel. i. 574 (Plut. Plac. iii. 1, 2), without any other indica- tion of its source. Such opinions cannot be attributed to Philolaus. * Arist. Phys. iii. 4, 203 a, 6: of uév IIv6ayópelot . . . eival to &a toû oùpavow tºreupov. Ibid. iv. 6; wide supra, p. 414, 2; Stob. i. 380: év Šē ré trepi rās IIv0ayópov quxoroq (as irpºtº Ypédei ['Aptorro- téxms], Tov oëpavov sival éva, Éirel- ordyearðat 6' éic too &reſpou xpóvov Te Kai Tuohy kal to kevov, & Stopfget That there must be ékáortov tás x&pas àeſ. Plut. Plac. ii. 9 (Galen. c. 11): of uév &mb IIv6ayópov, Šicros éival roi, kóruov revöv (cf. next note), eis 8 &vatve? 6 kāquos ical é; oš. But, for the reason already given, p. 465, 2, we ought not to identify this Unli- mited with the fire of the peri- phery, for it is nowhere described as being fiery, but as the boundless air (Arist. Supra, p. 414, 2), from which the world inhales its Tvoji. It is true that the passage in Sim- plicius, which will presently be cited, makes the heaven of fixed stars to be immediately bounded by the &repov; but it is a question whether Archytas understood by êoxarov the heaven of fixed stars, and not the outermost circle of fire. For the words #yovv rá &rAave? oùpavó are certainly a gloss of the historian ; a Pythagorean would not have called the external part of the world oëpavós. Röth thinks (ii. a, 831 sq.; b, 255) that by the &Teipov placed outside the world we should understand the primitive divinity as the infinite spirit. But this opinion is evidently erroneous, together with all that depends upon it—for the Štreipov as compared with the Limited is, from the Py- thagorean point of view, something evil and imperfect; the āvāntov kal #Aoyov (Philol. ap. Stob. Ecl. i. 10). In the Pythagorean fragments, even the most recent, the word âtelpos is never applied to the Deity. If Aristotle speaks of the &Telpop true Jua outside the world. this does not tell in favour of Röth's opinion, but against it. Does Aristotle, or any other philosopher anterior to the Stoics, ever call the spirit Tveijua? H. H. 2 468 THE PETHAGOREANS. an Infinite of this kind outside the world, Archytas had proved. From it, time as well as the void had entered the world.” But this motion is exceedingly obscure and vague, for which, not only our authorities, but the Pythagoreans themselves are doubtless respon- sible. On the one hand, by the void we must under- stand empty space, which here, as often besides, is not distinguished from space filled with air; on the other hand, the void divides all things, even numbers, from each other. Thus two different meanings of the ex- pression, the logical and the physical, are confused together; and with the same confusion of thought, time, on account of its successive infinity, is said to come * Simpl. Phys. 108 a 'Apxöras 6é, &s pmolv Eöömpos, oùra's #para Töv A6)ov. čv Tó éoxárq #yovu ré &TAavel oipavá yevópevos, Tótepov écºreſvaul &v thv xeſpa h Tov Ād.66ov eis rô £a, h oùic &v; to uév oſſºv wh ékretvelv, &rotrov. ei Šē ékretva, #To a 6pua ñ rátros to ékrös a rai. 8toloret 5% oièëv, às uab morów.e6a. &el of v Babie?ral rôv airby rpánov ćirl Tô &el Aauðavöuevov uépos, kal raû- rov ćpothaei, kai ei del repov &rral, ép' 8 h fidgö0s, 5mAovört kal &repov, ſcal ei ułv gaua, Sébeuktai Tô trpoketaevow: ei & réiros, art 6? Tótros rô &v $ 0.6ad a riv # 88wait' &v eival, rô 5& 5vváuel às by xp? ru6&val étri Tôv číðtwv, kai oiſºrws &v ełm gópa &meupov kal tătros. The explanations of Eudemus are here added to the demonstration of Archytas, as is proved by the ex- pressions 825tetral and épothaei, and the Aristotelian phrase (Phys. iii. 4. 203 b, 30; Metaph. ix. 8, 1050 a. 6): to 8vváue Ös àv, &c., and as it is precisely on that phrase that the proof of the corporeal nature of the Unlimited rests, all relating to that idea must belong to Eudemus ; the only thing which belongs to Archytas is the ques- tion : év tá, éoxárq — oãk &v; We find another proof in favour of empty space in Arist. Phys. iv. 9, a statement reproduced and com- mented on by Themist. in h. l. 43 a (302 sq.); Simpl. Phys. 161 a ; De Coelo, 267 a, 33. According to him, Xuthus said that without the Void, there could not be rare- faction or condensation, and that in order that there might be move- ment, some bodies must transcend the boundaries of the world, to make room for the bodies in motion. The world must overflow (kuſtave? to 8Xov). Simplicius calls this Xuthus Eot,00s & IIv6ayopticós. But it is not stated whether he was a true Pythagorean, or had merely (vide infra, p. 415), in the manner of Ecphantus, combined the theory of atoms with the Pythagorean doctrine. * Arist. Phys, iv. 6; Stob. i. 380. SYSTEM OF THE UNIVERSE. 469 from the Unlimited, that is, from infinite space. In this we see the fantastic method of the Pythagorean school, of which we have already had so many proofs. We have no right to attempt to destroy it by a precise definition of the concepts, nor to draw from it conclu- sions, which have no other certain warrant within the system." For the same reason it ought not to surprise us that time, which, according to the above representa- tion, entered the firmament from the Unlimited, should itself again be identified” with the celestial sphere; the former doctrine involves the concept of time as without limit; the latter asserts that the sky is by its motion the measure of time:* the perfect reconciliation of these * Cf. p. 411 sq. * Plut. Plac. i. 21 (Stob. i. 248; Galen. c. 10, p. 25): IIv6ayó- pas Tov xpóvov thv ordaipav roß trepiéxovros (Galen. : T. reptéx. juás oùpavod) gival, a statement which is confirmed by Aristotle and Sim- plicius. For Aristotle says, Phys. iv. 10, 218 a, 33: of pºv yūp thv roß &Aov kivmarty éivaí paatu [Tov xpóvov], oi 3& Thy gºalpav aithv, and Simplicius further remarks, p. 165; of uèv thv too &Aov kivmotiv ical trepiq'opäu Töv xpóvov sivat qaau, äs Tov IIAátova vouí(ovoiv Š Te Eßmuos, k. T. A., oi Śē Thu oqaipav airthv too oipavoi), ās Tows IIv6ayopicobs intopovoi Aéyely oi trapakoúa'avres forws toū ‘ApxöTov (the categories falsely ascribed to Archytas ; cf. Pt. iii. b, 113, 2 ed.) Aéyovros kaflóAou Töv xpóvov čudo- Tnua Täs too travtos pºorews. In a similar manner, according to Plut. De Is. 32, p. 364; Clem. Strom. v. 571 B; Porph. Vit. Pyth. 41, the sea was spoken of by the Pythago- reans as the tears of Cronos. Cronos is the god of the sky whose tears (the rain) had, as they con- ceived, formed the sea, vide supra. p. 91, 2. I cannot recognise my opinion in the terms employed by Chaignet, ii. 171 sq., to reproduce the above remark. Nor can I dis- cuss either his objections or his attempt to find the sense of the Pythagorean definition in Pseudo- Pythagorean writings. * Arist. l. c., gives another mo- tive: â 5& roß &ov orgalpa šāoše pºv tols eitrova weival 6 xpóvos, Štt ëv Te T6 xpóvg. trāvra éoºr kal év tá roß &Aov orgaípg, and the definition attributed to Archytas in Simpli- cius may be interpreted in this sense. But this reason does not seem to have come from Archytas. I should rather conjecture it to have been given after his time. Cronos must at first have been with the Pythagoreans, as with Pherecydes, a symbolical name for the sky. Wide preceding note. -- 470 THE PITHAGOREANS. two doctrines was doubtless not attempted by the Pythagoreans." This theory necessitated the abandonment of the original view of the world as a surface vaulted over by a hemispherical cavity; and the conception of upper and lower was reduced to that of greater or lesser distance from the centre;” the lower, or that lying nearer to the centre, was called by the Pythagoreans the * I cannot regard them as ac- cordant, nor can I agree with Böckh (Philol. 98) that the Py- thagoreans called Time the sphere of the embracing, so far as it has its foundation in the Unlimited. For, on the one hand, the Unli- mited could not be designated as gºalpa toû repuéxovros; and, on the other, this expression is other- wise explained in the passage of Aristotle hitherto overlooked. The indication of Plutarch (Plat. Qu. viii. 4, 3, p. 1007), according to which Pythagoras defined Time as the soul of the All or of Zeus, merits no reliance. Cf. p. 466 sq. * This point, it is true, is not established by the testimony of Aristotle, De Caºlo, ii. 2, 285 a, 10. Aristotle, in considering the ques- tion whether the heavens have an 'above and a below, a right and a left, a before and a behind, finds it strange that the Pythagoreans 680 Móvas Taffras &px&s éAeyov, to Seftov kai to &ptortepov, rös 6* Tétrapas trapéAutov oi6év fittov kvpías otolas. IBut this means to say that in the table of opposites, vide p. 381, these two categories alone are mentioned. In fact, however, the Above and the Below in the uni- verse were reduced to the Exterior and the Interior. Philol. ap. Stob. Eol. i. 360 (Böckh, Philol. 90 f; D. kosm. Syst. 120 sq.): ātro Toº Mégou Tà &va, 61& Tów airów toſs kdro èotl, Tå &va toû puégou inte- vavría's ketueva toſs Káro (i.e., the order of the spheres, from above to the centre, is the contrary of the order from the centre to the lowest point) tois yūp kāta, Tâ katatürw puéora éotiv Šotrep Tà &vatdºra, ral Tà &AAa &gattos. Trpos yöp to uégov Taird, éotiv čkdºtepa, Šo a whº pere- whvekrai (= trºv Štu pletev ; cf. Böckh, Philol. 90 sq.; D. kosm. Syst. 120 sq.). In the words toſs ºyāp kāra, etc., the text is evidently corrupt. To correct it, I should propose, (1) either to strike out uéga, which is only a conjecture for uéya, and is entirely wanting in several manuscripts; so that the sense would then be : ‘for to those who are on the under side, the lowest seems highest ; ' or else (2), to read roſs Yāp kato (for those who inhabit the region of the world, which, according to the or- dinary opinion is below, and which from our point of view is on the other side of the centre) karatáta, T& Méda éotlv čo Trep Tois &va, kal tà &AAa &gaútws. The corrections proposed by leop. Schmidt, Quaest. Epicharmea, Bonn, 1846, p. 63, and by Nutzhorn (Philol. xxii. 1865, p. 337), seem to me not very happy. - THE UNIVERSE. 471 right side of the world; that which was farther from the centre, the left; for they regarded the movement of the heavenly bodies from west to east as a progressive motion, and accordingly they assigned to the centre, as befitted its importance in the universe, the place of honour on the right side of the bodies of the world." They also held the upper portions of the universe to be the most perfect, and distinguished the outermost circle of fire from the circles of the stars, dividing these again into the circles above and below the moon ; so that the universe was divided into three regions, Olympus, Cosmos, and Uranos.” * Simpl. De Calo, 175 b, 31; Schol. 492 b, 39 : (of IIv6ayópstol) às airbs év Tó Öevrépq, Täs ouva- ºyayyús Tóv IIv6ayopticów ioTopei, too §Aov otpavoi Tô pièv čva, Aé'yovatv eival r& 6é kätaw, kal To uév Kára, toū oãpavoi, Seštěv eival, to 58 &va, àpigºrepov, kal huas €v Tó Káta, eival. These words seem to con- tradict what Aristotle says, De Coelo, ii. 2, 285 b, 25 : (oi IIv0ay.) huās &vo Te trototal ſcal év tá, 6ešić wepet, Toys 5’ exe? kāta, kai év tá, épio tépé. Böckh, however (d. kasm. Syst. 106 sq.), has shown how the two assertions are compatible, and how the objections are to be met, which, according to Simplicius, loc. cit., both he and his predecessor, Alex- ander, and more recently Gruppe, d. kosm. Syst. d. Gr. 65 sqq., brought forward. The mention of the avva-ya'yh, in Simplicius, relates to the division of the Uni- verse into an upper or external, and a lower or internal region, the latter, including the earth and the counter-earth, is on the right. The statement of the treatise on the heavens, on the contrary, refers Olympus contained to the opposition of the superior and inferior hemispheres of the earth; in regard to this, the Py- thagoreans maintain, in opposition to Aristotle, that our hemisphere is turned towards the periphery of the world, and is in ordinary lan- guage the superior hemisphere. Aristotle, from his standpoint, called it the right; the Pythago- reans must have called it the left. * Wide preceding note and Stob. i. 488, the continuation of the text cited p. 444, 4: To uèv of v &votátw Mépos toū trepiéxovros, év ć rºw eixt- kivetov eiual Tów a rouxetov *OAvp- tov kaxeſ [pixóAaos] tº §§ {Trö Thu Tot; 'OAffairov qop&v, év ć rows trévte TAavhras ué6’ #xfov kal orexivns - Teráx6ai, kóguov, to t” Štrb rotºrous ūtroo’éAmvöv Te Kal treptºyetov uépos, év ć to tºs (pixoperaßóAov yevéoeos, oùpavóv. kal trepi uèv tº tetayuéva Töv wered pou Yiyveabat thv orogºtav trepi 6& rà yewópeva rās &tašlas Tºv ãperhu, Texetav A&v éketvmv, &tex? 8è raútmv. Cf. on this point Böckh, Philol. 94 sq., and supra, p. 316. The opposition of the terrestrial and celestial spheres appears also 472 THE PPTHAGOREA.N.S. the elements in their purity; Cosmos” was the place of Ordered and uniform motion, Uranos that of Becoming and Change.” Whether the central fire was included in Olympus and the heaven of fixed stars in Cosmos, we do not know; but both conjectures are probable: the position of the counter-earth is more doubtful; it is possible that the Pythagoreans, who were chiefly com- cerned with the opposition of the terrestrial and supra- terrestrial, never considered this question. Finally, in the extract of Stobaeus a movement of Olympus is in the exposition (full of Stoical opinions) of Diog. viii. 26, and in the semi-peripatetic exposition, ap. Phot. 439 b, 27 sqq., but the tripartite division of Philolaus is here wanting. It is, on the con- trary, implied in the Epinomis of Plato, 978 B, by the words: éðv ºyāp in Tus ér 6eapíav Šp6%iv rhy Todèe, eite köopov eite ”OAvutrov efºre oipavov čv jiàovi, Ta Aéyetv, precisely because the author dis- cards it. Parmenides, v. 141, 137 (vide infra, Parm.), calls the outer- most envelope, Avutros éaxatos; on the other hand, he calls the starry heaven, not kóquos, but oùpavés. We must not, however, infer from this, as Krische does (Forsch. 115), that Philolaus can- .not have used the word oilpavós in speaking of the lower region; his terminology is not necessarily always the same as that of Parme- nides. * That is to say it consisted of the purest substance; for the ter- restrial elements evidently do not exist in Olympus; even the word otolyela is scarcely to be consi– dered Pythagorean. Or are we to understand by this expression the Limited and Unlimited 2 For the Unlimited only, the Štreipov out- side the world (vide p. 467, 1), of which Böckh is thinking, could not be designated by the plural artouxeia. * The Cosmos, that is, in the narrower sense of the word. For in general the word Cosmos has with the Pythagoreans its ordinary meaning of the universe (e.g. Philol. Fr. 1, cf. p. 379, 1). It is even said that Pythagoras was the first to use this expression (Plut. Plac. ii. 1 ; Stob. i. 450; Galen. c. 11; Phot. 440 a, 17). What is true in the statement is probably this, that the Pythagoreans were fond of employing the word to designate the harmonious order of the world. But even at the time of Xenophon it was not in general use, as is plain from Xen. Mem. i. 1, 11; 6 kaxoſ- Mevos ūtro rāv oroquotöv kóo wos, cf. Plato, Gorgias, 508 A. * What Epiph. Erp. fid. p. 1087 B, says, using a later ter- minology, is not altogether inexact: ëAeye be (IIv6.) Tă ătro orexívms kāra, traffnt& elval ºrdvra, rå Ös & repāva, Tās areaſivms &taff, eival, THE UNIVERSE. 473 spoken of, but it is uncertain whether he is not here transferring to Olympus what is applicable only to the heaven of fixed stars. This astronomical theory of the universe is con- nected, as we have seen, with the idea of the respiration of the world and of its right and left sides. In this we see the favourite ancient comparison of the world with a living creature; but, after our previous enquiries concerning the world-Soul, we cannot allow that this thought had any important influence on the Pytha- gorean system. - - It might be inferred from a passage of the Placita attributed to Plutarch, that the Pythagoreans, like Anaximander and Heracleitus, believed in the periodic generation and destruction of the world. This passage, however, probably asserts nothing more than that the vapours into which, by the effect of heat and moisture, earthly substances are resolved, serve for nourishment to the world or the stars.” It therefore relates only to the destruction of individual things: in regard to the * II. 5, 3: puñóAaos Surrºw elval T}v q,00pāv, Totè pièv é; ovpavoi, Tupbs Évévros, Totè 6' é; $6aros ge?\mutakov trepiot popff too &épos &Toxv0évros' kal Towrav sival r&s &vaðvuićgets rpoºpós toū kóguov. This statement, both here and in Galen. c. 11, is preceded by the words tró6ev Tpéq's rat 6 kóagos. Under the same title Stobaeus says, Ecl. i. 452: pix8Aaos épmore, rouév é; otpavot trupos fivévros, to 8& é; #5atos gexmviakos Treptarpopſ, row &épos &toxv6évros sivat rās &vaðv- Aidaeis Tpopås toū kóo wov, whereas in the chapter on Becoming and Perishing, i. 418, he cites the words quxóA.—&m oxv6évros, as they are cited in the Placita, only after q,00påv he adds toū kóopov. As to the sense of the obscure words, which have perhaps been inexactly reported, I follow Böckh (Philol. 110 sq.), whose interpretation seems to me more probable than that of Chaignet, ii. 159. Chaignet ex- plains the passage thus: il y a delta: causes de dépérissement, l'une quand le feu s'échappe du ciel, l'autre quand ce few . . . se répand de l'eau de la tune. * As was said by Heracleitus and the Stoics. - 474 THE PPTHAGOREA N.S. universe generally, it would appear that the Pythago- reans did not believe in any destruction of the world; what the Pseudo-Plutarch' tells us on the subject is no doubt merely derived from Timaeus the Locrian, or other similar sources. It is clear on the contrary, from Eudemus, that they thought, as the Stoics did after- wards, not only that the same persons who had lived in the world would re-enter it at a later period; but that they would again do the same actions and live in the same circumstances;” this is confirmed by a passage in Porphyry, not in itself of much weight.” This theory was no doubt connected with the doctrine of Trans- migration and of the great year of the world : if the heavenly bodies were to occupy the same place as before, everything else would return to the same condi- tion, and consequently the same persons would be present under the same circumstances. But it is a question whether this doctrine belonged to the whole school, or only to a portion of it. } The Pythagoreans appear to have occupied them- 21–selves very little with the study of terrestrial nature: at any rate, with the exception of one slight attempt on the part of Philolaus, tradition is silent on the subject. * Plac. ii. 4, 1 (Galen. c. 11, p. 265). - * In the fragment of his Phy- sics ap. Simpl. Phys. 173 a, he enquires whether the same time which has been, shall be again, or not ? and the answer is : that which comes after is only qualita- tively the same as that which has gone before : Ei 6é ris trioteñorete Toſs IIv0ayopetois, és träAuv rá air& &piðug, Kūyā plv60Aoyàow to Éašátov ëxov Špiv kaðmuévois oira (this is the right punctuation), ſcal rô &AAa. trövta Öuoiws #el, kai Töv xpóvov stao'yöv éart Tov airov sival. * V. Pyth, 19. Of the doctrines of Pythagoras, those of immortality and the transmigration of souls are the best known: trpós 5& Toºrous àri kató, trepióðous Tuvès rê, yewówevá trote tréAlv yivetal, véov 6' oióēy âtr?\ós éoti. TERRESTRIAL WATURE. THE SOUL. 475 In regard to Philolaus, we are told that in the same way that he derived geometrical determinations (the point, the line, the surface, the solid) from the first four numbers, so he derived physical qualities” from five, the soul from six ; reason, health, and light” from seven ; love, friendship, prudence, and inventive faculty from eight. Herein (apart from the number schematism) is contained the thought that things represent a graduated scale of increasing perfection ; but we hear nothing of any attempt to prove this in detail, or to seek out the characteristics proper to each particular region.” Nor, in all probability, did the Pythagoreans carry their enquiries respecting the soul and man very far. Later writers indeed descant much on the origin of the soul from the world-soul, and on its ethereal, divinely- related, eternally-moved, immortal nature. There is even a fragment of Philolaus which contains these statements.” I have already shown,” however, that this fragment can scarcely be considered genuine, and that " Iambl. Theol. Ar. 56 ; cf. As- clep. in Metaph. i. 5. These pas- sages have been quoted, p. 435, 2. In Theol. Ar. p. 34 sq., it is stated that six is regarded by the Pytha- goreans as the number of the soul, and perhaps, Aristotle may be al- ready alluding to Philolaus when he speaks (Metaph. i. 5, quoted on p. 369, 1) of the assertion: āti to Totovël (sc. &piðuáv trgºos) juxh Kal vows. * Trotórnta kal Xpógiv. The colour no doubt describes in a general manner the external nature (cf. Arist. De Sensu, c. 3, 439 a, 30: of IIv6ayópetol Tºv Čiriq divetav xpověv ékáNovu), and trouárms, which does not appear to belong to Philo- laus, is a later interpretation of this expression. * To itſ' airod Aeyóuevov qājs, therefore not light in the ordinary sense, but some quality or state of man; or in general, health, well- being. * We find only an isolated trace of any discussions in regard to living beings in the passage, Arist. De Sensu, 5, 445 a, 16, according to which certain Pythagoreans Sup- posed some animals lived upon odours. Wide infra, p. 480, 2, for other quotations. * Cf. the texts cited, p. 447, 1. * Wide pp. 447, sq.; 399, 1 ; 390, 1; 393, 3. 476 THE PPTHAGOREANS. consequently the theory of his having devoted a special book of his work to the soul must remain doubtful; I have also shown that the other authorities are apt to intermingle the doctrines of the Stoics and Platonists with the Pythagorean tradition. If we consult our most trustworthy source, Aristotle, we find him to have been little acquainted with the Pythagorean psycho- logy." For in his comprehensive survey of all that his predecessors had taught on the nature of the soul, he simply says of the Pythagoreans that some of them held the solar corpuscles to be souls, and others that which sets them in motion.” The doctrine that the soul is a harmony, is alluded to by Aristotle, without mention of any name,” and in Plato' it is maintained by a pupil of Philolaus. * Wide supra, p. 447 sq. * De An. i. 2, 404 a, 16, after having mentioned first of all the Atomists among those who con- sidered the soul as the motive principle, and self-moved: éolice Śē ical to trap& Töv IIv6ayopetov Aeyó- pºevov Thy at thv čxelv Sudvowav. ěqaqav yūp rives airów juxhv eival Tà év rá, éépt £50 para, of 6% to Taota civoúv, a conception which Aristotle (most likely it is merely his own conjecture) derives from the fact that the solar corpuscles move, even when the wind is per- fectly still. I do not understand the censure which Schlottmann passes upon me (D. Vergängliche w. Unvergängliche in d. menschl. Seele mach Arist. Halle, 1873, p. 30). He says that I misinterpret this text, and the text cited, p. 448, in asserting that the definition of the soul as the moving principle Macrobius” ascribes it to Philolaus himself, is only an induction of Aristotle. But Aristotle himself gives this as his own induction: he only quotes, as belonging to the Pytha- goreans, jux?iv eival to Taora kivoúv. It is not the same thing to say: the solar corpuscles are moved by a soul, and the soul is, generally, the moving principle. * De An. i. 4, sub init. : kal &AAm 6é ris 66&a Trapadéðotal treph Juxis . . . &pgovíavyáp two airhy Aéyovoſt' ral yèp thvāpuovtav kpāoriv kal gºv6eau èvavriov elval, kal to orðua orvyice to 6a, Čš Čvavríov. Polit. viii. 5 a 8tb troXAoi qaori rôv orogów of uév špuovíav sival rhy juxhv, of 5’ exeiv šppovíav. 4 Phaedo, 85 E sqq. * Somm. i. 14: Plato diarit ami- onwm, essentiain se movemtem, Åemo- crates ºwmérwºn Se moventem, Aris- toteles évrexéxetc.v, Pythagoras et Philolaus harmoniam. THE SOUL. 477 and even to Pythagoras. Philoponus connects with it the statement also made by Stobaeus, that the soul is a number." This statement in itself is not at all im- probable: if everything is number and harmony, the soul may well be so. But the general proposition that the soul is harmony or number, says nothing; we only get a specific determination concerning the essence of the soul, when it is described as by Plato and Aristotle (loc. cit.) as the number or harmony of the body to which it belongs. That it was so defined by the Pythagoreans we are never told, and such a view would ill accord with their belief in immortality; * if, there- fore, it had been found within the school, it would have been a departure from the primitive doctrine which we cannot ascribe to Philolaus. It is more likely that he said what Claudianus Mamertus” quotes from him, and what may also be deduced from our previous citations," that the soul is united with the body by means of number and harmony.” The further assertion, however," that Pythagoras defined the soul as a self- 1 Philop. De Am, B, 15: ágrep ošv špuovíav Aéyoutes tºw bux?iv [of IIv6ayópetoll oil paal Taürmy Špuovíav rºv čv rais xopägis, etc. Cf. C, 5, where it is said that Xenocrates borrowed from Pytha- goras the idea that the soul is a number. Stob. Ecl. i. 682 : some Py- thagoreans call the soul a number. 2 In Plato, at any rate, Sim- mias only concludes from it that the soul perishes after the destruc- tion of the body, as the harmony ceases after the destruction of the instrument; and it is difficult to say how this conclusion can be evaded; it was also drawn by Aristoxenus and Dicaearchus, cf. Part II. b, 717 sq. 2nd ed. . * De Statu An. ii. 7 (ap. Böckh, Philol. p. 177): ‘Anima inditur corpori per numerum et immortalem eandemqite incorporalem convenien- tiam.’ * Wide supra, p. 475, 1; 431. * Here again we are uncertain whether Claudian borrowed his statement from the true Philolaus; cf. p. 399, 1. * Plut. Plac. iv. 2. Nemes. Nat. hom. p. 44. Theodoret, Cur. gr. aff, v. 72, with whom Steinhart, Plato's Werke, iv. 551, in the main agrees. 478 THE PPTHAGOREA.N.S. moving number must absolutely be rejected. Aristotle, who was the first to quote this definition," was evidently, when he did so, not referring to the Pythagoreans;” and other writers expressly mention Xenocrates as its author.” It is likewise improbable that Archytas defined the soul as the self-moved," though the Pytha- goreans would certainly appear to have noticed its continuous motion, and interrupted life;" and the statements that Pythagoras called it a square, and Archytas a circle or a sphere, are both equally ques- tionable." Lastly, an expression quoted from Archytas to the effect that the soul is not extended in space, is no doubt taken from a spurious work.” * De Aw. i. 2, 4, 404 b, 27; 408 b, 32. Anal. post. ii. 4, 91 a, 37. 2 For (De An. i. 2, 404 a, 20), he continues, after the text relative to the Pythagoreans, quoted p. 476, 2 : étrº rairo 5è (pépovrat Ral $got Aéyovo's Thy jux?iv ro añto kivoßv. He distinguishes therefore this opinion from that of the Pytha- goreans. As to the latter, he elsewhere expresses himself in a manner that would have been im- possible if he had had before him so exact a definition of the nature of the soul. 3 Cf. Part II. a, 672, 2, 2nd ed. * Joh. Lyd. De Mens. 6 (8), S, 21: Juxh &věpátrov, pnaiv 6 IIv6a- 7ópas, éoth retpáyovov eiðuyáviov. *Apxöras & puxās Tov Špov oik ev Terpayáve &AA’ v RiſkAº &roötöoot 8t& rooro ºvXà ro airò [l. atrol rivojv, äväyka 6° to trpárov rivojv, trökAos 6& rotiro à oðaºpa.’ Accord- ing to the remark we have just made, Aristotle can have known nothing of this definition attributed to Archytas. The definition of the soul as airò kivotiv is certainly taken from Plato (Phaedrus, 245 C), There too we find the observation that the self-moving is also in re- gard to other things triryū kal épx? Rivāorea's ; in regard to which the Pseudo-Archytas employs the Aris- totelian expression trpárov kivoúv. * Wide the remark of Aristotle quoted p. 476, 2, and particularly what he says of Alcmaeon, infra. * The statement relative to Py- thagoras is in itself suspicious, like all the recent information which we possess as to the per- sonal opinions of this philosopher. The statement relative to Archytas is so, first, because it is in itself eccentric, and secondly, because it has an evident connection with Pla- tomic and Aristotelian ideas. * Claud. Mam. De Statu An. ii. 7 (cf. Pt. iii. b, 90, 2 Aufl.) quotes from Archytas: Anima ad even- plum units composita est, quae sic itlocaliter dominatur in corpore, sicut unus in numeris, But to ANTHROPOLOGY. 479 Concerning the parts of the Soul, various theories are ascribed to the Pythagoreans by more recent writers which I cannot admit them to have originally held. According to some, they were acquainted with the Pla- tonic distinction of a rational and an irrational soul, and the analogous distinction of Reason, Courage, and Desire; together with the Platonic division of the intellectual faculty into voffs, Šarlo Trium, 8óša, and ałorémats; * we are told by another writer” that they divided the soul into Reason, Mind, and Courage (vojs, ºppéves, 6vpios); Reason and Courage being in men and prove the authenticity of the writ- ing from which this passage is taken, more evidence is required than the testimony of Claudian ; it is not in itself probable that Ar- chytas, or any other Pythagorean, should have enunciated a doctrine of which we first hear, not even from Plato, but from Aristotle, viz., that the presence of the soul in the body is not a juxtaposition in space. The statement ap. Stob. Eel. i. 790; Theodor. Cur. gr. aff. v. p. 128, according to which Py- thagoras makes vows 60paffew eiokpt- verbai, contains no doubt an inference drawn from the doctrine of Metempsychosis. Schlottmann p. 24 sq. and the treatise cited p. 476) has wrongly made use of it to prove the improbable and un- founded conjecture, that Aristotle borrowed the expression 6&pagev eiortéval in respect to the union of the soul with the body from the Pythagoreans. 1. Cf. Posidonius ap. Galen. De Hipp. et Plat. iv. 7; v. 6, T. xv. 425. 478 K. ; Iambl. ap. Stob. Eel. i. 878; Plut. Plac. iv. 4, 1, 5, 13. On the distinction of the rational and irrational part, cf. Cicero, Tusc. iv. 5, 10; Plut. Plac. iv. 7, 4; Galen. Hist. Phil. c. 28. Other passages taken from Pseudo-Pytha- gorean fragments will be found in Part III. b, 112, 2, 2nd edition. * The Pseudo-Archytasap Stob. Ecſ. i. 722, 784, 790, and Iambl. tr. kow. Mað. Tiar. (in Willoison, Anecd. ii.) p. 199: Brontinus ap. Iamb. C. C. 198; Theodoret, Cur. gr. aff, v. 197 Gaisf, who adds, as a fifth part, the Aristotelian ppó- vmaris. Plut. Plac. i. 3, 19 sq., in an extract from an exposition which is evidently Neo-Platonic, founded upon the celebrated Pla- tonic propositions cited by Aristo- tle, De An. i. 2, 404 b, 21. Photius gives another and more recent division, p. 440 b. 27 sqq.; cf. Part III. b, 120, 8. * Alex. Polyhistor ap. Diog. viii. 30. It has already been shown, pp. 393, 3; 447, 2, that this exposition is not authentic. The whole division is confused, and con- tains many Stoical definitions, for example, that the senses are emana- tions from the soul, that the soul is nourished by the blood, &c. 480 THE PYTHIAGOREANS, beasts, Mind in men only; Courage having its seat in the heart, the two other faculties in the brain. There is more warrant for supposing that Philolaus placed the seat of Reason in the brain ; of life and sensation in the heart; of seed and germination in the navel; of generation in the sexual parts: in the first of these re- gions, he said, lay the germ of men; in the second, that of beasts; in the third, that of plants; in the fourth, that of all creatures." With this, our knowledge of the philosophic anthropology of the Pythagoreans is exhausted. What we are further told concerning their anthropological theories belongs altogether to the sphere of religious dogmas, the importance of which in the Pythagorean system we have now to consider.” 1 Iambl. Theol. Arithm. 22 : Téagapes &pxal too &ov rob Aoyl- icoſ, Šotrep kai pixóAaos év tá, repl púaea's Aéyet, Éyképaxos, kapāla, Öpºpaxos, aiboſov. Keq ax& uév vöw, kapöta ää juxás kai aid 6%atos, dupaxos 3& 51%gios kai &vapúaios Tà trptºtal, aiãotov Šē otépuatos KaragoNäs Te Kai 'yevuáotos éyké- qaxos 3& T&v &v0p6tra àpx&v, kap- 6ía 3& rêv Çiğa, Öpºpaxos 3& T&v qvró, aiāotov Šē tav čvvatrávrov, travra y&p kal 6&AAovoru Kal 3Åaatá- vovorty. By the word trävra or $vvátravra we must understand the three kinds of living beings, collec- tively, i.e., men, beasts, and plants. On the authenticity of the frag- ment (which commences with the words kepax& uèv v6o; what goes before is a preliminary remark of Iamblichus), cf. p. 317. * We can only discuss in a sup- plementary manner certain theories which have been omitted in the preceding exposition as not forming & an integral part of the physical system of the Pythagoreans, but which were either incorporated by later writers from other sources into their own doctrine, or stand isolated without philosophical foun- dation, and are based merely on observation. We should regard as an addition of later writers, for example, the story given by Alex. Polyhistor ap. Diog. viii. 25 sqq. vide Part III, b, 74 sq., 2nd ed. The same may be said of the Stoic definition of the body (to oiáv te traffeiv h Staffeival) attributed to Py- thagoras by Sextus, Math. ix. 366. The Placita ascribed to him the Stoic doctrine : Tperthy Kal &AAow- Thu kai werc.gxmthu kal fievorrºw 3Amv 6t' àAov thv ŠAmv. The same treatise i. 24, 3, gives, as coming from Pythagoras, a proposition which he could not have expressed in this form, viz. that on account of the variation and metamorphosis of the elements, a Becoming and IETHICS. 481 V. THE RELIGIOUS AND ETHICAL DOCTRINES OF THE PIXTHAG OREANS. OF all the Pythagorean doctrines, none is better known, and mone can be traced with greater certainty to the founder of the school, than that of the Transmigration of Souls. It is mentioned by Xenophanes," and later by Io of Chios;” Philolaus speaks of it, Aristotle describes it as a Pythagorean fable,” and Plato unmistakably Perishing in the proper sense of the word is produced. Lastly, i. 23, 1 (Stob. i. 394), the Placita ascribe to Pythagoras a definition of move- ment posterior to Aristotle. We may also instance what is said about colours : Placita, i. 15, 2 (cf. Stob. i. 362; Anon. Phot. Cod. 249, p. 439 a, cf. Porph. in Ptol. Harm. c, 3, p. 213; Arist. De Sensu, c, 3, 439, a, 30); on the five zones of heaven and earth, Plac. ii. 12, 1 ; iii. 14 (Galen. H. ph. c. 12, 21, cf. Theo Čn Arat. ii. 359) : on sight, and the reflections of the mirror, Plac. iv. 14, 3 (Stob. Ecl. i. 502, and in the extracts of Joh. Damasc. Parall. p. 1, 17, 15; Stob. Floril. ed. Mein. iv. 174; Galen, c. 21, p. 296); on the voice, Plac. iv. 20, 1 (G. c. 26); on seed, Plac. v. 3, 2, 4, 2, 5, 1 (G. c. 31); on the five senses, Stob. Ecl. i. 1104; Phot. 1. c.; on the rainbow, AElian, V. H. iv. 17; on the nutrition of animals by smell, Arist. De Sensu, 5 (vide supra, p. 475, 4); on the origin of maladies, Galen. c. 39. If even these notices really reproduce the doctrines of the ancient Pytha- goreans (which can only be sup- posed in regard to a portion of them), they have no connection WOL. I. with the Pythagorean philosophy. Similarly the definitions of the calm of the air and of the sea, given by Arist. Metaph. viii. 2, ad fin., as those of Archytas, all of Small importance; and the state- ment according to which (Arist. Probl. xvi. 9) this philosopher showed that the round form of certain organs in animals and plants was the result of the law of equality which governs natural movement, stands entirely alone. As to the pretended logic and philosophy of language of the Pythagoreans, vide infra, § vi. * In the verses quoted Diog. viii. 36: kai troté puv otvq?ext{ouévov oköAa- kos trapuávta. q'ao iv Štroikreſpat kal Tóðe pda'6at âtros. tratoral uměč Šáruſ étreth plaqv &vé- pos Éoth juxh, nºw éyvov (p6eyśauévns &tov. * In Diog. i. 120, where the words, efirep IIv6ayópms érüuws 6 goqos repl révrov &v6pótrov yuápas eiðe kai ééép.a6ev, refer to the beli f in immortality. * De An, i. 3, ad fin. : áo nep I I 482 THE PIV THA GOREANS. copied his mythical descriptions of the condition of the soul after death from the Pythagoreans. As Philolaus says,' and Plato repeats,” the soul is confined in the body and buried in it, as a punishment for faults. The body is a prison in which it has been placed by God as a penalty, and from which it consequently has no right évôexówevov karū toys IIv6ayopticobs pºiſ00us thv Tuxodoray ºvzhv eis to Tuxby évööeo-0at oºga. * Clemens, Strom. iii. 433 A.; Theod. Cur. gr. aff, v. 14 (Böckh, Philol. 181) : paptupéoviral 5& kai of taxatoi 9eoAéryol re kal uávries, &s 6tá rivas Tuwpías & pv)& ré ord wart ovvéſevictat kal ka94trep ev arduart toirº Té0atrºrai. The veins are called, ap. Diog. viii. 31, the bonds of the soul. The rest does not seem to belong to the ancient Pythagoreans. * Gorg. 493 A: §trep #6m Tov êywye kai fikova'a Tów orogów, Ös vöv hueis Téðvapwev kal to uév oróuá éortiv hufu qiua, Tâs 5& Juxºis toūro èv š Čirićvutat eigh rvyxável by oiov &vatretøeoróat kal wet attarretv &va, kāra. ital Tooro &pa ris uv60Xo- vöv koulos &vhp, to as Xuke?\ós tus # Itaxurbs, trapáyov rá, Övöuatl 6t. to tru6avóv Te kal Tretoºrucov &vápage tríðov, Toys 6é àvoñTovs àuvátovs Tāv 8’ &uvīray . . . as retpmuévos elm tri- 60s . . . kal (popotev sistöv Terpmuévov Tſ60w iſãop érépºp rototrº terpmuévg kookſvg). It is a question whether in this text it is merely the com- parison of the orópa with the oriua, and the mythus of the punishment of the āuiſm'rol, that comes from IPhilolaus or some Pythagorean, or whether the moralinterpretation of this myth also comes from him. This interpretation is attributed to Philolaus by Böckh (Philol. 183, 186 sq.); Brandis (Gr. Röm. Phil. i. 497); Susemihl (Genet. Entw. d, P'at. Phil. i. 107 sq.), and others. Brandis is less positive in the Gesch. d. Entw. i. 187. The interpreta- tion, as a whole, seems to me to have a purely Platonic character, and to be out of harmony with the treatise of Philolaus. Plato does not say that he borrowed from the koutpos &vhp the interpretation of the myth, but the myth itself. When, connecting this myth with a popular song, XuceXös koulos &vhp trot) rāv patépa šqa, Timoc- reon, Fr. 6 b ; Bergk, Lyr. Gr. p. 941, he makes a mythus, >ticeabs h 'Ira Aukös; he means to say that the myth of the perforated vessel into which the unconsecrated were to put water with a sieve—i.e., the tradition which extends the punishment of the Danaids to all the profane—belongs to the Or- phico-Pythagorean cycle. In the Cratylus, 400 B, Plato refers for the comparison of orópa with a fina to the Orphics, whom Philolaus also had in view : kal yèp oriud. rivés paoſiv airo [to a 6pal sival Tăs Juxºis, &s Teóaupévms év Tó vov tapávri . . . Šokoúa'i uévrot wou ud- Atoºra 6éorðat of &aſp? 'Oppéa rotiro to $voua, Ös 8th my Stöočams Tās Juxis &v 8% ºvera ötöwort roorov 8& treptSoxov čxelv, tva ord'ſ mºral, Öeopa- Tmptov eikóva. TRANSMIGRATION OF SouLs. 483 to free itself by a presumptuous act.' So long as the soul is in the body it requires the body; for through the body alone can it feel and perceive; separated from the body it leads an incorporeal life in a higher world.” This, however, is of course only the case when it has rendered itself capable and worthy of such happiness; otherwise it can but look forward to the penance of material life, or the torments of Tartarus.” The Pytha- gorean doctrine was therefore, according to these the most ancient authorities, essentially the same that we afterwards find associated with other Pythagorean notions, in Plato;" and which is maintained by Empe- docles,” viz., that the Soul on account of previous trans- gressions is sent into the body, and that after death each soul, according to its deserts, enters the Cosmos or Tar- 1 Plato, Craf. l.c.; Id. Phaedo, 62 B (after having remarked that Philolaus forbade suicide): 6 pºv ošv év &rośńrous Aeyóuevos trept airóv A6-yos, &s év Tuvi (ppoupé £opaev of &v6potrot kal of Sež ö, äavrov čk raúrms Aſſelv oiâ’ &roötöpdarketv, which Cic. (Cato, 20, 73 ; Somn. Scip. c. 3) reproduces rather inac- curately, without, however, having any other authority than this pas- sage. Clearchus (ap. Athen. iv. 157 c) attributes the same doctrine to an unknown Pythagorean named Euxitheus. * Philol. ap. Claudian. De Statu An. ii. 7: diligitur corpus ab anima, quia sine éo non potest uti sensibus : a quo postguam morte deducta est agit in mundo (kóoruos as distinguished from otpavos, sup. p. 471,2) incorporalem vitam. Carm. Aur. v. 70 sq. : #v 6' àtroAsſipas orâua és aidép' éAeë6epov čAëns, ëageal &0ávaros 6eos #48poros, ob- Kért 60mtés. Perhaps this is the origin of the statement of Epipha- nius (Erp., fid. 1807), according to which Pythagoras called himself a god. * Euxitheus, ap. Athen, l.c., threatens those who commit sui- cide: Stetraoréal row 0eów, &s eigh Prevodow ém Toºrous, Éas &v čkºv airois Aſſam, TAéoot kal wet ſociv éutrea otivtat téte Aſſuats, and ac- cording to Arist. Anal. Post. ii. 11, 94 b, 32, Pythagoras thought that thunder frightened sinners in Tar- tarus. For I agree with Ritter (Gesch. d. Phil. i. 425) that if the parallel passage, in Plato, Rep. x. 615 D. f. be duly considered, we must suppose that the sinners, and not the Titans, are here meant. * Cf, Part II. a, 691, 3rd ed. * Wide infra, vol. ii. Emped. I I 2 484 THE PYTHAGOREA.N.S. tarus, or is destined to fresh wanderings through human or animal forms." When, therefore, we meet with such a representation of the doctrine, among recent writers,” we have every reason to accept it” as true, without on that account admitting all that they combine with it.” The souls, we are told, after departing from the body, float about in the air ; * and this no doubt is the foun- dation of the opinion quoted above, that the solar corpuscles are souls;” an opinion which must not be * The Pythagoreans are said to have denominated this return into the body by the word Taxiſyyeveata. Serv. Aen. iii. 68 ; Pythagoras non persuſpáxoov sed traxty'yeveatau esse dicit, h. e. redire [animam] post teampus. Vgl. p. 474, 3. * E. g. Alexander, who seems here to reproduce the Pythagorean ideas with less admixture than usual, ap. Diog. viii. 31 : ékpiq6eto'av 8’ abrºv [thy ºvzhu] tº yīs TA4– {e06a, 6aotav Tó ord pati (cf. Plato, Phaedo, 81 C ; Iambl. V. P. 139, 148): Töv 6’ ‘Eppiv tapitav sival Tów Juxāv kal 61& rooto troutraſov Aéyeo- 6al kal TrvXatov Kal x86vtov, Štreičítep oiros eiotréutrel &Tö täºv orapid rov t&s Juxās &tró Te yńs kal ék 9a)\dºt- tns. Kal &yearðai Tàs uèv ka9ap&s éri Tôv Špia rov, Tâs 6’ &ka9áptovs Aft' ékeſvg trexégetv uſit’ &AAñAals, 6eforóat 6' év čášíktois Seguois im’ 'Epivyčov. Porph. V. P. 19: Trpá- Tov učv &0&varov elvaí qmail thv ºvX}v, eita ueta}d^\ovoraw eis &AAa 'yevn Cºov. Porphyry, it is true, adds: 8tt travra tº yivéueva èupuxa ôuoyevſ, bei vouſſeiv. Plut. Plac. v. 20, 4 (Galen. c. 35) interprets this to mean that the souls of ani- mals are indeed rational in them- selves, but are incapable, on ac- count of their bodies, of acting rationally. Plut. Plac. 1.4; Galen. c. 28; Theodoret, Cur. gr. aff, v. 123, represent only the rational part of the soul as existing after death; but these, like the asser- tions of the equality of the spirit in men and animals (Sext. M. ix. 127; wide sup. p. 417, 3) are sub- sequent inferences. The myths about the personal transmigration of Pythagoras have been noticed, p. 340, 1. ° Our exposition will likewise refute what Gladisch says (Noack's Jahrb. f. Spek. Philos. 1847, 692 sq.) to prove that Empedocles was the first philosopher who taught the doctrine of Metempsychosis. * For instance, what is said about the prohibition to kill and eat animals (vide sup. p. 344, 3). Only we must not, like Gladisch, conclude that Pythagoras, there- fore, could not have admitted the transmigration of souls. Plato and others admitted it, and yet ate meat. Empedocles does not forbid the eating of plants, although he held that human souls passed into plants. * Alex. ap. Diog. l. c. p. 484, 1; 487, 3. * Ritte c(Gesch.d. Phil.i.442 R) cites in regard to this the passage Wide TRANSMIGRATION OF SOULS. 485 regarded as a philosophic doctrine,' but simply as a Pythagorean superstition.” The belief in subterranean abodes of the departed was undoubtedly maintained by the Pythagoreans.” What was their precise conception of the future state, whether like Plato they supposed that some of the souls underwent refining punishments in Hades, and that a definite interval must elapse between the departure from one body and the entrance into another; whether they conceived the union of the soul with the body as conditioned by choice, or by natural affinity, or only by the will of God, tradition does not say, and it is a question whether they had any fixed or in Apuleius De Socr. c. 20: Aris- totle says that the Pythagoreans thought it strange for any one to pretend he had never seen a daemon; but it, seems to me that apparitions of the dead in human form are meant, which, according to Iambli- chus, V. P. 139, 148, the Pytha- goreans regarded as perfectly na- tural. * As Krische does (Forschungen, &c. i. 83 sq.). He connects the texts above quoted with the ideas of the central fire and the world- soul by this hypothesis: that, ac- cording to the Pythagorean doc- trine, the souls only of the gods proceeded directly from the world- soul or central fire, and the souls of men from the sun, heated by the central fire. I cannot accept this combination, for I do not admit that the world-soul was a conception of the ancient Pythagoreans. What is further added, that the souls were precipitated from the sun upon the earth, is not affirmed by any of our witnesses. * This Pythagorean theory has great affinity with what Aristotle (De An. i. 5, 410 b, 27) calls a Aóryos év tols 'Oppikois Raxoupévois êtreat : thu Pvxhv čk too &Aov eio té- vat &varve&va ov, q'epopuévriv Štrö täv &véuov. If the soul originally floats in the air, and enters the body of the newly-born with the first breath, it escapes equally from the body of the dying with the last; and if it does not ascend to a supe- rior abode, or sink to an inferior place, it must float about in the air until it enters another body. This Qrphic conception itself seems to be connected with an ancient popular belief: the invocation in use at Athens of the Tritopatores, or gods of the wind, to make mar- riages fruitful (Suid. Tpitot.; cf. Lobeck. Aglaoph. 754), presup- poses that the soul of the child was brought by the wind, cf. p. 73, 2. * According to AElian. V. H. . iv. 17, Pythagoras derived earth- quakes from the assemblies (Jüvo- êot) of the dead. 486 THE PPTHAGOREANS. complete theory at all on the subject. The doctrine that each soul returned to earthly life under the same circumstances as previously, once in each cosmical period, is more distinctly ascribed to them." Important as the belief in Transmigration un- doubtedly was to the Pythagoreans,” it seems to have had little connection with their philosophy. Later writers seek the point of union in the thought that souls, as the effluence of the world-soul, are of a divine and therefore imperishable nature;” but this thought, as before remarked, can hardly be considered as be- longing to the ancient Pythagoreans, since in all the accounts it is bound up with Stoical ideas and ex- pressions, and neither Aristotle in his treatise on the soul, nor Plato in the Phaedo, ever allude to it, though they both had many opportunities for so doing.” Apart from this theory it would be possible to conceive that the soul might have been regarded as an imperishable essence, because it was a number or harmony.” But as the same holds good of all things generally, it would involve no special prerogative of the soul above other essences. If, on the other hand, the soul was in a more precise manner conceived as the harmony of the body, all that could be inferred from this is what Simmias * Cf. p. 474 sq. * Schleiermacher's notion(Gesch. d. Phil. 58) that we ought not to take this literally, but as an ethical allegory of our affinity with the animal kingdom, is contrary to all historical testimony, including that of Philolaus, Plato, and Aristotle. * Wide supra, p. 475, 417 sq. * As has been already shown in regard to Aristotle. As to the Phaedo, it is very unlikely that Plato, who delighted in referring to Orphic and Pythagorean tradi- tions (vide p. 61 C, 62 B, 69 C, 70 C), would, in expressing a thought so similar (79 B, 80 A), have en- tirely abstained from all allusion to the Pythagoreans if his doctrine of immortality had been taken from them. ! * Wide Supra, p. 477. IMMORTALITY. DAEMONS, 487 infers in the Phaedo, that the soul must come to an end with the body of which it is the harmony." It seems very doubtful, therefore, whether the doctrine of immor- tality and transmigration was scientifically connected by the Pythagoreans with their theories of the essential nature of the soul, or with their number-theory. The ethical importance of this doctrine is undeniable. But ethics, as we shall presently See, was equally neglected by them, so far as any scientific treatment is concerned. This dogma appears therefore to have been, not an ele- ment of the Pythagorean philosophy, but a tradition of the Pythagorean mysteries, originating probably from more ancient orphic traditions,” and having no scientific connection with the philosophic principle of the Pytha- goreans. The belief in daemons, to which the ancient Pytha- goreans were much addicted,” must also be included 1. Cf. p. 477,2. Still less can we, with Hermann (Gesch. d. Plato, i. 684, 616), find proof in Ovid. (Me- tam. xv. 214 sq.), and in Plut. (De ei, c. p. 18), that the Pythagoreans based metempsychosis on the doc- trine of the flux of all things, and especially on the change of form and substance of our bodies. Cf. Susemihl, Genet. Entw. d. Plat. Phil. i. 440 * Wide p. 67 sq. * Already Philolaus, Fr. 18 (supra, p. 371, 2), seems to distin- guish between daemons and gods. So does Aristoxenus (ap. Stob. Floril. 79, 45), when he recommends that we should honour our parents as well as gods and daemons. The Golden Poem (v. 1 sqq.) says in a more definite manner that we should honour the gods above all; after them the heroes and the sub- terranean daemons (katax66wlot Baiuoves, manes). Later writers, like Plutarch, De Is. 25, p. 360; Placita, i. 8, combine the Pytha- gorean doctrine with the doctrines of Plato and Xenocrates, but on this very account they cannot be considered trustworthy as regards Pythagoreanism. The testimony of Alexander ap. Diog. xiii. 32, touching daemons and their influ- ence on men seems to come from a more primitive source: elvaí te trövta Töv &épa ) vxów épatrāeov" Ical taútas Satuovás Te kal ipo- as āvoud ſea 9at Kai útro Toºrov tréputégéal &věpátrols toſs tº Öv- etpous kai Tà a mueta v6orov re kal 5)ietas, kai oi Mävov &vöpétrols 488 THE PXTHAGOREA.N.S. among their mystic doctrines. As far as we know on the subject, they thought that daemons were bodiless Souls which dwell, some of them under the earth, and Some in the air, and which from time to time appear to men ; but spirits of nature as well as the souls of the dead seem to have been called by this name.” The Pythagoreans derived revelations and soothsaying from the daemons, and connected them with purifications and expiations:* the high estimation in which they held soothsaying is frequently attested.* To the class of daemons belonged also the heroes,” but there appears to have been nothing particular in the worship accorded &AA& kal trpoğdrous kai toºs &AAots kráveaſiv eſs re Tottovs yívea (al toūs Te ka9apuous kal &motportag- plots, pavrikāv Te Tao'av Kal KAffö0- vas kal rà époua. Cf. AElian. iv. 17: 6 troAAdkus épºrtarrow rots &alu fixos (IIv6ay. (paakev) pavi, Tāv kpelt- Tövov. How far the famous Platonic exposition, Symp. 202 E, is of Pythagorean origin, cannot be determined. * Cf. preceding note and pas- sages quoted, p. 483, 6. * Cf. the assertion of Porphyry V. P. 41 : Töv 5' etc XaAkoú kpovo- Hévou fixov povhv eivaſ Tivos Tów 3alpióvov čvareikmuſiévnu rô XaXkó, an ancient and fantastic notion which reminds us of the opinion of Thales on the soul of the mag- net. - * Aristoxenus ap. Stob. Ecl. i. 206: repl 8& Túxms tdö' épaakov: eival uévrol kal 3alpióvtov uépos airis, yewégéal yèp étrítvotáv twa tapå rot, 3alpovíov Tów &v6pátov évious étrº To BéAtlov h ét) to xeipov. Brandis (i. 496), in oppo- sition to Böckh, Philol. 185, thinks that this higher influence is re- ferred to by Philolaus ap. Arist. (Eth. Eud. 6, ad fin.), eivat Twas Aóyous kpeſtrous juáv. Alex. (l.c.) attributes revelations and expia- tions to the daemons and not to the 8aluóviov; but the exclusiveness of this opinion seems to betray, the stand-point of a later period, which would not admit any direct inter- course between gods and men. We find besides in Alex. a perceptible likeness to the text in the Sympo- sium of Plato, 202 E. * Wide supra, p. 349, 2. The greater number add that Pytha- goras refused to allow the interro- gation of victims (in Galen. H. ph. c. 30, p. 320, we should read ac- cording to the text of the Plac. v. 1, 3, oùx éºykptvet instead of uðvov to 60tucöv oik &vipel). But this opinion rests entirely on the sup- position that he forbade bloody sacrifices, and in general the killing of animals, which has no founda- tion in history. * Wide supra, p. 487, 3. IETHICS. 489 to them." The opinion that daemons occupied an inter- mediate place between gods and men” already existed in the more ancient popular faith. If we turn from the daemons to the gods, we find, as has already been observed,” that the Pythagoreams, in all probability, brought their theology into no scientific connection with their philosophical principle. That the conception of God as a religious idea was of the highest significance to them, is indubitable ; meverthe- less, apart from the untrustworthy statements of later writers, of which we have before spoken, very little has been handed down to us about their peculiar theological tenets. Philolaus says that everything is enclosed in the divinity as in a prison ; he is also said to have called God the beginning of all things; and in a fragment the authenticity of which is not certain, he describes him in the manner of Xenophanes as the one, eternal, un- changeable, unmoved, self-consistent ruler of all things." From this it is evident that he had advanced beyond the ordinary polytheism to that purer conception of Deity, which we not unfrequently meet with among philosophers and poets before his time. The story in the Pythagorean legend,” that Pythagoras when he went into Hades saw the souls of Homer and Hesiod under- going severe torments for their sayings about the gods, is to the same effect. We cannot, however, lay much stress upon this, as the date of the story is unknown. * At any rate what Diog. (viii. tie, supra, p. 338, 3. 33) says is the general Greek * Wide p. 387 sq. opinion; vide Hermann, Gr. Ant. ii. * Supra, p. 402, 1. s sect. 29 k. * Hieronymus ap. Diog. viii. * Wide quotation from Aristo- 21, vide supra, p. 340, 2. 490 THE PV THAGOREANS, Some other particulars are related of Pythagoras and his school, which are still more uncertain, and the evidence of which collectively proves nothing more than we have already admitted, viz., that the Pytha- goreans indeed purified and spiritualised the popular belief, and strongly insisted on the Unity of the Divine, but cannot be said to have consciously attempted to arrive at any philosophic theory of God. This purifica- tion, however, was not connected in their case, as in the case of Xenophanes, with a polemic against the popular religion; and though they may not have agreed with everything that Homer and Hesiod said about the gods, yet the popular religion as a whole formed the basis of their own theory of the world and of life; in this respect it is hardly necessary to refer particularly to their worship of Apollo, their connection with the Orphics, their predilection for religious symbolism,” and their myths about the lower world. Consequently, their theological opinions cannot, strictly speaking, be con- sidered as part of their philosophy. The religious belief of the Pythagoreans stood in close connection with their moral prescripts. Human life, they were convinced, was not only, like everything | Such as the expression attri- tion of Pythagoras, e.g., in Plut. buted to Pythagoras by Themist. (Or. xv. 192, b) eikóva Tpos 9eby eival &v0p6trovs, with which the so- called Eurysus in the fragment ap. Clem. Strom. v. 559 D, agrees; or what we find in Stob. (Eel. ii. 66), Iambl. (V. P. 137), Hierocles (In Carm. Aur. Præf. p. 417 b, M), on the destiny of man—to be as like God as possible. The formula Éirov 66% is often quoted, without men- De Aud. i. p. 37; Clem. Strom. ii. 39() D. * Cf. the passages quoted, p. 421, 444, 4 ; 469, 2; also the state- ment ap. Clem. Stron. v. 571 B; IPorph. V. P. 41 (after Aristotle), ac- cording to which the Pythagoreans called the planets the dogs of Perse- phone, the two Bears the hands of Rhea, the Pleiades the lyre of the Muses, the sea the tears of Cronos. ETHICS. 491 else, in a general manner under the Divine care and protection; but was also in a particular sense the road which leads to the purification of the soul, from which no one, therefore, has any right to depart of his own choice." The essential problem of man’s life, consequently, is his -moral purification and perfection; and if during his earthly life, he is condemned to imperfect effort; if, instead of wisdom, virtue merely, or a struggle for wisdom, is possible,” the only inference is that in this struggle man cannot do without the support which the relation to the Deity offers to him. The Pythagorean ethical doctrine therefore has a thoroughly religious character : to follow God and to become like Him is its highest principle.” But it stands in no closer rela- tion to their philosophy than their dogmatic doctrine does. It is of the greatest moment in practical life, |but its scientific development is confined to the most elementary attempts. Almost the only thing we know about it, in this respect, is the definition, already quoted, of justice as a square number, or as āytutstrov6ós.” But that is only an arbitrary application of the method, which elsewhere prevailed in the Pythagorean school— that of defining the essence * Wide supra, p. 483, 1; 402, 2. * So Philolaus, sup. p. 471, 2. For the same reason, we are told, IPythagoras repudiated the name of Sage, and called himself instead quxóa'ogos. Cie. Tusc. v. 3, 8; j)iog. i. 12; viii. 8 (after Hera- clides and Sosicrates); Iambl. 58, 159 ; Clemens, Strom. i. 300 C ; cf. iv. 477 C; Valer. Max. viii. 7, 2; Plut. Plac. i. 3, 14; Ammon. of a thing by an analogy In Qu. v. Porph. 5, b. * Wide sup. p. 490, 1. We find the same idea (according to the exact explanation given, ap. Phot. p. 439 a., 8), in the saying ascribed to Pythagoras, and quoted by Plut. De SuperSt. c. 9, p. 169 ; Def. Orac. c. 7, p. 413, that the best for us is to get near to the gods. * Wide sup. 420, 2. 492 THE PIV THAGO REAAWS, of number; there is scarcely the most feeble germ of any Scientific treatment of ethics. The author of the Magna Moralia says that Pythagoras attempted in- deed a theory of virtue, but in so doing, did not arrive at the proper nature of ethical activity.' We must go farther and say that the stand-point of Pythagoreism in general was not that of scientific ethics. Nor can we argue much from the proposition * that Virtue con- sists in Harmony, for the same definition was applied by the Pythagoreans to all possible subjects; besides, the date of the proposition is quite uncertain.” Whether the moral tendency of the myths about the vessel of the Damaids, which we find in Plato, is really derived from Philolaus or any other Pythagorean is doubtful,” and if it is, no conclusion can be drawn from it. From all that tradition tells us, it is evident that ethics with the Bythagoreans, as with the other Pre-Socratic philoso- phers, never advanced beyond popular reflection; in regard to any more developed ethical conceptions, they are only to be found in the untrustworthy statements of more recent authors,” and in the fragments of writings * M. Mor. i. 1. 1182 a, 11: 6eóv. Similarly in Iambl. 69, 229, arpátos pév of v čvexeſpnoe IIv6ayópas arepi àpetàs eitreºv, oùk épôós 6é. T&s yöp &perås eis toys &piðuous &váryov ošic oiketav Tóv àpetóv Tiju 9ewpfav Étoietro of , ºváp éotiv # 5ucatoróvn àpiðubs iodicts toos. The statement that Pythagoras was the first to speak of virtue seems to have arisen from the passage quoted, p. 420, 2, from Metaph, xiii. 4. * Alexander, ap. Diog. viii. 33: Tāv t” &perºv špplovíav sival kal rhy $yielav kal to &Yabby &may kal toy Pythagoras demands that there should be friendship between the soul and the body, between reason and sense, etc. * For the evidence, as we have shown, is untrustworthy, and the silence of Aristotle on the subject, though it is not decisive, makes it all the more doubtful. * Sup. p. 482, 2. * Among these we must reckon the assertion of Heracleides of Pontus (ap. Clem. Strom. ii. 417, A), that #º defined hap- JETHICS. 498 which partly by their empty diffusiveness, and partly by their large use of later theories and expressions, betray their date too clearly to be worth noticing in this place.” Of the remaining authorities on the ethics of the Pythagoreans, the statements of Aristoxenus merit the greatest attention. Though he may perhaps describe the principles of the school in his own forms of expres- sion, and probably not without some admixture of his own thoughts, yet on the whole the picture which we get from him is one which agrees with historical prob- ability, and with the statements of others. The Pytha- goreans, according to Aristoxenus, required before all things adoration of the gods and of daemons, and in the second place reverence to parents and to the laws of one's country, which ought not to be lightly ex- changed for foreign laws.” They regarded lawlessness as the greatest evil; for without authority they believed the human race could not subsist. Rulers and the ruled should be united together by love; every citizen should have his special place assigned to him in the whole; boys and youths are to be educated for the state, adults and old men are to be active in its service.3 Loyalty, fidelity, and long-suffering in friendship, subordination of the young to the old, gratitude to parents and benefactors are strictly enjoined.* There piness as éirio Thun täs reaetórntos Töv šperóv (al. &ptôuðv) Tâs ºvXàs. Heyder ( Eth. Pyth. Vindic. p. 17) should not, therefore, have appealed to this text. * Wide Part III. b, 123 sqq., se- cond edition. * Ap. Stob. Floril. 79, 45. Similarly the Golden Poem, v. 1 sq.; Porph. V. P. 38; Diog. viii. 23; these latter, no doubt, after Aristoxenus. * Ap. Stob. Floril. 43, 49. * Iambl. V. P. 101 sqq. No doubt, after Aristotle, for these prescripts are repeatedly called Trv6ayopikal &topdorets. 494 THE PYTHAGOREANS, must be a moderate number of children, but excess in sensual indulgence, and without marriage, is to be avoided. He who possesses true love for the beautiful will not devote himself to outward show, but to moral activity and science; * conversely, science can only succeed when it is pursued with love and desire.” In many things man is dependent on Fortune, but in many he is himself the lord of his fate.” In the same spirit are the moral prescripts of the Golden Poem. Reverence towards the gods and to parents, loyalty to friends, justice and gentleness to all men, temperance, self-command, discretion, purity of life, resignation to fate, regular self-examination, prayer, observance of consecrating rites, abstinence from impure food, such are the duties for the performance of which the Pythagorean book of precepts promises a happy lot after death. These, and similar virtues, Pythagoras is said to have enforced, in those parabolic maxims, of which so many specimens are given us,” but the origin of which is in individual instances as obscure as their meaning. He taught, as we are elsewhere informed,” 1 Ap. Stob. Floril. 43, 49, 101, 4, M; cf. the Pythagorean word quoted, ap. Arist. (OEcon, i. 4 sub init.), and the statement that Py- thagoras persuaded the Crotoniats to send away their concubines. Iamb. 132. 2 Stob. Floril. 5, 70. 8 Aristox. in the extracts from Joh. Damasc. ii. 13, 119 (Stob. Floril. Ed. Mein. iv. 206). 4 Stob. Eel. ii. 206 Sqq. 5 Wide Diog. viii. 17 sq.; Porph. V. P. 42 : Iambl. 105; Athen. x. 452 D ; Plut. De Educ, Puer, 17, *jº p. 12; Qu. Conv. viii. 7, 1, 3, 4, 5; and supra, p. 340, 4. • Diog. viii. 23; Porph. V. P. 38 sq. These two texts, by their agreement, point to a common source, perhaps Aristoxenus, Diod. Eac. p. 555 Wess. In the same passage, Diog. 22 brings forward the prohibition of the oath, of bloody sacrifices; but this is cer- tainly a later addition. As to the oath, Diodorus, l.c., seems the more accurate. What Diog. says (viii. 9), following supposed writings of Pythagoras, as to the time of con- ETHICS. 495 reverence to parents and the aged, respect for the laws, faithfulness and disinterestedness in friendship, friendli- ness to all, moderation and decorum ; commanded that the gods should be approached in pure garments and with a pure mind; that men should seldom swear, and never break their oaths, keep what is entrusted to them, avoid wanton desire, and not injure useful plants and animals. The long moral declamations which Iamblichus puts into his mouth, in many passages of his work,' for the most part carry out these thoughts: they are exhortations to piety, to the maintenance of right, morals and law, to moderation, to simplicity, to love of country, to respect to parents, to faithfulness in friendship and marriage, to a harmonious life, full of moral earnestness. Many more details of this kind might be added;” in almost every instance, however, the evidence is too uncertain to allow of any dependence upon it. jugal intercourse, appears Scarcely worthy of credit. The statement of Diog. 21 is more likely to have belonged to the ancient Pythago– I'ê3,IlS. * In great part following an- cient writers, cf. with Iambl. 37– 57; Porph. 18; Justin. Hist. xx. 4; and Supra, p. 344, 4. * E. g. the famous kotua Tö. Töv ‘ptxov (supra, p. 345, 2); the saying that man should be one, ap. Clem. Strom. iv. 535 C ; cf. Proclus in Alcib. iii. 72; Conv. in Parm. iv. 78, 112 (the end of life is, accord- ing to the Pythagoreans, the évôtms and pixta); the exhortation to truthfulness, ap. Stob. Floril. 11, 25, 13, 21 ; the saying as to the evils of ignorance, intemperance, But, according to the unanimous testimony and discord, which Porph. 22, Iambl. 34 (cf. 171) attributes to Pythagoras, and which Hieron (c. Ruf, iii. 39, vol. ii. 565, Wall.) at- tributes to Archippus and to Lysis; the apophthegms of Theano on the duty and position of women; ap. Stob. Floril. 74, 32, 53, 55; Iambl. V. P. 55, 132; Clemens, Strom. iv. 522 D; the utterance of Clinias, ap. Plut. Qu. Conv. iii. 6, 3; the comparison attributed to Archytas of the judge and the altar, ap. Arist Rhet. iii. 11, 1412 a, 12; the sentences given by Plut. De Audiendo, 13, p. 44; De Easil. c. 8, p. 602; De Frat. Am. 17 p. 488; Ps. Plut. De Vita Hom. 151, 496 THE PPTHAGOREANS, of our authorities, and to what has already been said on the political character of the Pythagorean associa- tion, we may consider it proved that the school of Pythagoras, believing in the almighty power of the gods, and in future retribution, enforced purity of life, moderation and justice, minute self-examination and discretion in all actions, and especially discouraged self-conceit; that it also required unconditional ob- servance of moral order in the family, in the state, in friendship, and in general intercourse. Important, however, as is the place it thereby occupies in the history of Greek culture, and in that of mankind, yet the scientific value of these doctrines is altogether inferior to their practical significance. VI. RETROSPECTIVE SUMMARY. CHARACTER, ORIGIN, AND ANTIQUITY OF THE PYTHAGOREAN PHILOSOPHY, WHAT has been remarked at the close of the last section, and previously at the beginning of this exposi- tion, on the difference between the Pythagorean life and the Pythagorean philosophy, will be confirmed if we take a general survey of the doctrines of the school. The Pythagorean association, with its rule of life, its code of morals, its rites of consecration, and its political endeavours, doubtless had its origin in ethico-religious- motives. It has been previously shown (p. 149 sq.) that, among the gnomic poets of the sixth century, complaints of the wretchedness of life and the vices of mankind, on the one hand; and on the other, the demand for CHARACTER OF PYTHAGOREAN PHILOSOPHY. 497 order and measure in moral and civil life, were more prominent than with their predecessors; and we recog- mised in this a deepening of the moral consciousness, which naturally went hand in hand with the contemporary revolution in political conditions, and in the intellectual life of the Greeks. The transformation and spread of the Orphico-Bacchic mysteries point the same way; for they at the same period undoubtedly gained much in religious content and historical importance." To the same causes in all probability Pythagoreanism owed its rise. The lively sense of the sorrows and short-comings inseparable from human existence, in conjunction with an earnest moral purpose, seems to have begotten in Pythagoras the idea of an association which should lead its members by means of religious rites, moral pre- scripts, and certain special customs, to purity of life and respect for all moral ordinances. It is, therefore, quite legitimate to derive Pythagoreanism in its larger sense—the Pythagorean association and the Pythagorean life—from the moral interest. But it does not follow that the Pythagorean philosophy had also a predomi- \mantly ethical character.” The Ionie naturalistic phi- losophy sprang, as we have seen, from the Ionic cities with their agitated political life, and from the circle of the so-called seven sages. In the same way the Pytha- gorean association may have had in the beginning a moral and religious end, and yet may have given birth to a physical theory, since the object of scientific en- quiry was at that time the nature of the physical world, * Wide Sup. p. 61 sq. * As some modern writers have thought, sup. p. 184, 1. WOL. I. K K 498 THE PRTHAGOREANS. and not Ethics. That such was the case must be con- ceded even by those who regard Pythagoreanism as an essentially ethical system;" and the passage quoted above from the Magna Moralia, which, moreover, is far from having the weight of a genuine testimony of Aristotle, cannot overthrow this assertion.” The object of Pythagorean science was, according to all our pre- vious observations, identical with that of the other pre-Socratic systems—namely, natural phenomena and” their causes; Ethics was treated by it only in a guite isolated and superficial manner.” Against this no argument can be drawn from the undoubtedly i Ritter, Gesch. d. Phil. i. 191. “It is true that the Pythagorean philosophy is also chiefly occupied with the reasons of the world and the physical phenomena of the universe,' etc. The same author, p. 450, says: “Those parts of morals which they (the Pythagoreans) de- veloped scientifically, seem to have |been of little importance.' Bran- dis, i.493: ‘Although the tendency towards ethics of the Pythago- reans must be regarded as essen- tially characteristic of their aims and efforts, we find only a few iso- lated fragments of a Pythagorean doctrine of morality; and these are not even of such a nature that we might suppose them to be the re- mains of a more comprehensive sys- tem of doctrine now lost to us,” etc. 2 Cf. p. 491, 2. What Brandis says in Fichte's Zeitschrift, xiii. 132, in favour of the statement in the Magna Moralia cannot outweigh the known spuriousness of this work, and the fact that Aristotle nowhere mentions the personal doctrine of Pythagoras (though he may sometimes refer some Pytha- gorean customs to him). This text, in fact, does not tell us anything that we have not learned from other sources. * This has been already shown, p. 490 sqq. When, therefore, Hey- der (Ethic. Pythag. Vindic. p. 10 sq.) appeals in favour of the oppo- site opinion to Arist. Ethic. N. i. 4; ii. 5 (vide supra, p. 380, 1, 2), he attributes far too much importance to the expression, ovatouxta rôv ãºyabâv. Aristotle designates by these words the first of the two series of ten numbers, the oppo- sition of which arranged in pairs constitutes the Pythagorean table of contraries (the Limited, the Odd, etc.). But it does not follow from this that the Pythagoreans themselves made use of this desig- nation, or that they understood the &yaôów and kaków in the ethical sense, and not in the physical sense as well. Still less does it follow (as Heyder says l. c. and p. 18), that they invented a table of goods and set up a scientific principle for ethics, something like that of |Plato. CHARACTER OF PETHAGOREAN PHILOSOPHY, 499 ethical tendency' of the Pythagorean life, nor from the great number of Pythagorean moral maxims; for the question is not how the Pythagoreans lived, and what they thought right, but whether, and how far, they sought to understand and to account for moral activities scientifically.” The conclusion that Pythagoras, in order to make life moral, must also have given account to himself of the nature of morality,” is in the highest degree uncertain ; it does not at all follow from his practical course of action that he reflected in a scientific manner upon the general nature of morality, and did not, like other reformers and law-givers, content himself with the determination of special and immediate pro- blems. For the same reason the mythical doctrine of transmigration, and the theory of life dependent upon it, cannot here be considered ; these are not scientific propositions, but religious dogmas, which moreover were not confined to the Pythagorean school. So far as the Pythagorean philosophy is concerned, I can only assent to the judgment of Aristotle,“ that it was entirely devoted to the investigation of nature. It may be objected that this was not pursued in a physical manner; 1 On which Schleiermacher re- lies, Gesch. der Phil. 51 sq. ? Otherwise we must also reckon, among the representatives of moral philosophy, Heracleitus and Democritus, because of the moral sentences which they have transmitted to us; and Parmenides and Zeno, because their manner of life was like that of the Pythago- reans; not to speak of Empedocles. * Brandis, Fichte's Zeitschr. f. Phil. xiii. 131 sq. * Metaph. i. 8,989 b, 33: 6ta- AéYoural uévrot ſcal trpayuarečoviral Tepl bºoea’s Trávra. Yevvært re yap top of pavöv kal repl rà rotºrov uépm kai tā Tá0m kal rà épya Starmpotia. to ovuòaïvov, kal r&s àpx&s kal r& attia eis raira katavaxtokovoriv, &s Ö90Aoyoovtes, etc. (supra, p. 189, 3). Metaph. xiv. 3, 1091 a, 18: étreſ3} Koguoroiodori Kal pugikós BoöAovrat Aéyetv, Šikatov abrovs ééetáſelv ri Tepl biºgeos ék 5& Tijs vov & pelva, weóðov. Cf. Part. Anim. i. 1; Supra, p. 185, 3. * ~) t (~ } * K K 2 500 THE PYTHAGOREANS, that the object of the Pythagoreans was to enquire how law and harmony, morally determined by the concepts of good and evil, lie in the principles of the universe: that all appeared to them in an ethical light, that the whole harmony of the world was regulated according to moral concepts, and that the entire order of the uni- verse is to them a development of the first principle into virtue and wisdom." In reply to this view of Pythagoreanism, much may be said. In itself such a relation of thought to its object is scarcely conceivable. Where scientific enquiry proceeds so exclusively from an ethical interest, as it is supposed to have done in the case of the Pythagoreans, it must also, as it would seem, have applied itself to ethical questions, and produced an independent system of ethics, instead of an arithmetical metaphysic, and cosmology. But this hypothesis also contradicts historical fact. Far from having founded their study of nature on moral con- siderations, they rather reduced the moral element to mathematical and metaphysical concepts, which they originally obtained from their observation of nature— resolving virtues into numbers, and the opposition of good and evil” into that of the limited and unlimited. This is not to treat physics ethically, but ethics physically. Schleiermacher, indeed, would have us regard their mathematics as the technical part of their ethics. He thinks that all virtues and all ethical relations were expressed by particular numbers; he sees Ritter, l. c. 191, 454, and numbers should be understood similarly Heyder, Ethic. Py- symbolically. thag. Vindic. p. 7 sq.; 13, 31 sq., * As Ritter substantially con- who thinks that the Pythagorean cedes, Pyth. Phil. 132 sq. CHARACTER OF PPTHAGOREAN PHILOSOPHY. 501 an evidently ethical tendency underlying the table of opposites." But as these assertions are devoid of all foundation, it is unnecessary to refute them ; how arbitrary they are, must have already appeared from our previous exposition. Ritter observes,” more correctly, that the mathematics of the Pythagoreans were con- nected with their ethics by the general idea of order, which is expressed in the concept of harmony. The only question is whether this order was apprehended in their philosophical system as a moral or a natural order. The answer cannot be doubtful when we reflect that, so far as scientific determinations are concerned, the Pythagoreans sought this order anywhere rather than in the actions of men. For it finds its first and most immediate expression in tones, next in the universe ; while, on the other hand, no attempt is made to arrange moral activities according to harmonical proportions. Ip cannot, therefore, be said that the Pythagoreans founded physics and ethics upon a common higher prin- ciple (that of harmony),” for they do not treat this principle as equally physical and ethical: it is the in- terpretation of nature to which it is primarily applied, and for the sake of which it is required ; it is only applied to moral life in an accessory manner, and to a far more limited extent.* Number and harmony have here an essentially physical import, and when it is said ! Ibid. p. 51, 55, 59. wārisque superius, quod &amen ſloºt * Gesch. d. Phil. i. 455. appellarint nisi nomine a rebus * Heyder, l.c. p. 12 sqq. physicis repetito. Why should they * Heyder himself indirectly have chosen a merely physical de- confesses this when he says, p. 14: signation, if they had equally in Et physica et ethica ad principium view the moral element? eos revocassé utrisqué commune et 502 THE PPTHAGOREA.N.S. & that all is number and harmony, the meaning is not that the order of nature is grounded upon a higher moral order, it simply expresses the nature of the physical world itself. Although, therefore, I willingly admit that the Pythagoreans would not perhaps have arrived at these definitions if the ethical tendency of the Pythagorean association had not quickened their sense of measure and harmony, yet I cannot on that account regard their science itself as ethical : I must consider it in its essential content as purely a system of physics. Nor can I allow that the Pythagorean philosophy originally sprang from the problem of the conditions of knowledge, and not from enquiries concerning the nature of things: that numbers were regarded by the Pythagoreans as the principle of all Being, not because they thought they perceived in numerical proportions the permanent ground of phenomena, but because, without number, nothing seemed to them cognisable: and, because according to the celebrated principle, “like is known by like, the ground of cognition must also be the ground of reality.” Philolaus, it is true, urges in * We must not, however, over- Metaph. p. 79 sq.). This assertion look the fact that other philosophers who were famous for their Pytha- gorean manner of life, as Parme- nides and Empedocles, as well as Heracleitus, whose ethics are very similar to those of Pythagoras, arrived at perfectly different philo- sophic conclusions. 2 Brandis Rhein. Mus. ii. 215 sqq.; Gr.-röm. Phil. i. 420 sq., 445; Fichte's Zeitschr. f. Phil. xiii. 134 sqq.; Gesch. d. Entw. i. 164 sq. (cf. IReinhold, Beitrag 2. Erl, d. pyth. is connected with the theory of which we have just spoken (viz. that Pythagoreanism was chiefly ethical in character), by the follow- ing remark (Zeitschr. f. Phil. 135). Since the Pythagoreans found the principle of things in themselves, and not outside themselves, they were led to direct their attention all the more to the purely internal side of moral activity; or con- versely. Here, however, strictly speaking, Brandismakes the general CHARACTER OF PETHAGOREAN PHILOSOPHY. 503 proof of his theory of numbers, that without number no knowledge would be possible, that number admits of no untruth and alone determines and makes cog- misable the relations of things." But he has also pre- viously shown,” quite in an objective manner, that everything must be either limited or unlimited, or both together, and it is only to prove the necessity of the limit that he brings forward this fact among others, that without limit riothing would be knowable. Aris- totle says” that the Pythagoreans regarded the elements of numbers as the elements of all things, because they thought they had discovered a radical similarity between numbers and things. This observation, however, indi- cates that their theory started from the problem of the essence of things, rather than that of the conditions of knowledge. But the two questions were in fact not separated in ancient times; it is the distinctive pecu- liarity of the Pre-Socratic dogmatism that thought directs itself to the cognition of the real, without in- vestigating its own relation to the object, or the subjec- tive forms and conditions of knowledge. Consequently no distinction is drawn between the grounds of know- ledge and the grounds of reality; the nature of things is sought simply in that which is most prominent to the philosopher in his contemplation of them ; in that which he cannot separate from them in his thought. The Pythagoreans in this procedure resemble other Schools, idea of an internal or idealistic * Fr. 2, 4, 18, Supra, p. 371, 2; tendency the starting-point of 372, 1. Pythagoreanism, and not the pre- * Fr. i. supra, p. 379, 1. cise question of the truth of our * Metaph. i. 5, Supra, p. 369, 1. knowledge. 504 THE PPTHAGOREA.N.S. for example, the Eleatics, whose objective starting- point Brandis contrasts with the so-called subjective starting-point of the Pythagoreans. Philolaus says that all must be number to be cognisable. In the same way, Parmenides says that only Being exists, for Being alone is the object of speech and cognition." We can- not conclude from this that the Eleatics first arrived at their metaphysic through their theory of know- ledge; nor is the conclusion admissible in the case of the Pythagoreans. It eould only be so, if they had investigated the nature of the faculty of cognition as such, apart from that of the object of cognition; if they had based their number-theory upon a theory of the faculty of knowing. Of this, however, there is no trace; * for the incidental remark of Philolaus, that the sensuous perception is only possible by means of the body,” even if genuine, cannot be regarded as a fragment of a theory of knowledge, and what later writers have related as Pythagorean," on the distinc- tion between reason, Science, opinion, and sensation, is as untrustworthy as the statement of Sextus,” that 1 W. 39 :— oëre yāp &v yvoims ré ye u% éov (oi, 7&p équicrów), oùre ſppda'ats. To Yap airò voeſy to- riv Te Kal gival. * Brandis also concedes this, Zeitschr. f. Phil. xiii. 135, when he says that the Pythagoreans did not start from the definite question of the conditions of knowledge. Only he has no right to add that they found the principle of things in themselves, and not outside themselves. They found it in numbers which they sought as well within themselves as without : numbers were for them the essence of things in general. * Supra, p. 483, 1. * Supra, p. 479, 3. * Math. vii. 92 : of 3& IIv0ayo- puncil Tov A6)ov uév parly ſkpurhplov eival], oi koués àé, rov & &rö rów padmuárov trepiyivéuevov, kaflātep ëAeye ical pixóAaos, beapmºruków Te ëvta rās rôv ŠAøv påorews éxew rivă ovyyávelav Trpès Taºrmw. It is evident that the criterion here is added by the writer, and that the whole is taken from the propo- CHARACTER OF PPTHAGOREAN PHILOSOPHY. 505 the Pythagoreans declared mathematical reason to be the criterion. Had the Pythagorean philosophy started from the question—What is the unconditionally cer- tain element in our ideas º instead of the other ques- tion, What is the permanent and essential element in things, the cause of their being, and of their quali- ties?—the whole system, as Ritter observes," would have had a dialectic character, or at any rate would have been constructed on some basis involving method- ology and a theory of knowledge. Instead of this, Aristotle expressly assures us that the Pythagoreans restricted their enquiry entirely to cosmological ques- tions; ” that dialectic and the art of determining the concept were unknown to them as to all the pre- Socratics—only some slight attempts in that direction having been made by them in their numerical ana- logies.* All that we know of their doctrine can only serve to confirm this judgment. The Neo-Pytha- gorean school adopted and elaborated" after their 4, 1078 b, 17 sqq.; Socrates was the first to define concepts: tów wév y&p purikóv Čiri Pukpov Amuá- sitions of Philolaus (quoted above) on number, as the condition of knowledge. * Pyth. Phil. 135 sq. * Supra, p. 499, 2. * Metaph. i. 5, 987 a, 20: repl too ri éo riv #pèavro uév Aéºyeuv kal ôpigeo-0ai, Atav 6 &txàs étrpayua- regómoav. čpígovré ré y&p émitro- Aatos, kal & trpátº Širépéelev 6 Aex9sis àpos, root’ eival thv oùoríav Too trpáyuatos évépuſov. Ibid. c. 6, 987 b, 32. The difference be- tween the theory of ideas and the Pythagorean theory of numbers results from Plato's occupation with logical enquiries: of y&p trpárepot Blakektukſis ov Petetxou, Ibid. xiii. kpitos #paro piévov . . . oi 8& IIv6a- 'yópelot trpórepov rept twov čAfyov, &v robs A&yous eis Tobs &piðuous &vämtov, oiov tí Čori kalpös # ro 6tratov h yduos. It is from this passage no doubt that the state- ment of Favorin. is taken, ap. Diog. viii. 48. [IIv6ayópavl 8pois Xph- oraoréat 81& ràs piaffnuatukis iſans, &n tračov 5* >wkpármv. In the texts, De Part. An. i. 1 (supra, 185, 3), and Phys. ii. 4, 194 a, 20, the Pythagoreans are not once men- tioned with Democritus. * Cf. Part III. b, lll, 2nd ed. 506 THE PYTHIAGOREA.N.S. manner, among other later doctrines, the Stoico- Peripatetic logic and the Platonic theory of know- ledge; but no one will now believe in the authenticity of writings which put into the mouths of Archytas and other ancient Pythagoreans theories which are manifestly derived from Plato, Aristotle or Chrysippus." What we certainly know of Philolaus and Archytas gives us no right to suppose that the Pythagoreans were in advance of the other pre-Socratic philosophers - in logical practice and the development of the scientific method.” And there certainly is not any reason for attributing the commencement of linguistic enquiries to Pythagoras.” 1 Röth (ii. a, 593 sq.; 905 sq.; b, 145 sq.), however, takes the pseudo-Pythagorean fragments and the assertions of Iamblichus, V. P. 158, 161, for authentic evidence. * Philolaus in his discussion of the Limiting and Unlimited (supra, p. 379, 1) makes use of a disjunctive process of reasoning; but this is no sign of a post-Platonic origin (as Röthenbücher, Syst. d. Pyth. 68, believes); nor is it even re- markable in a philosopher of that. epoch. We find Parmenides em- ploying the same mode of reason- ing (v. 62 sqq.), and the demon- strations of Zeno are much more artificial than those of Philolaus above mentioned. In the latter, it is true the disjunctive major pro- position is first announced. Then of the three cases which the author puts as being possible, two are excluded. But this detail is of little importance, and it has a sufficient parallel in the manner in which Diogenes (vide Supra, p. 286, 2) at this same epoch first If, therefore, Aristotle describes the determines generally the qualities of the First Being, and then proves that these qualities belong to the air. Aristotle (vide sup. p. 480, 2) quotes from Archytas a few defini- tions, adding that these definitions have respect to the matter as well as the form of the objects in ques- tion. But in this he is not bring- ing forward a principle of Archytas, but making a remark of his own. Porph. is only reiterating this re- mark when he says (In Ptol. Harm. 196): The definitions of the con- cept characterise its object, partly in form, partly in matter: of 6& karð to avvauqétepov, oùs uáAtata 6 Apyūras &trečexero. But inde- pendently of this remark the de- finitions of Archytas prove very little. * Pythagoras, it is said, con- sidered the wisest man to be he who first gave their names to things (Cic. Thisc. i. 25, 62; Iambl. V. P. 56, 82; Procl. in Crat. c. 16; AElian, V. H. iv. 17; Eac. e scr. Theod. c. 32, at the end of Clemens Al. p. 805, CHARACTER OF PPTHAGOREAN PHILOSOPHY. 507 Pythagoreans as neither dialectical nor ethical philoso- phers, but purely and simply as Physicists,' we can but agree in the statement, and approve of the later writers who have followed him in this particular.” Accordingly our conception of the origin of the Pythagorean system must be as follows. From the spiritual life of the Pythagorean Society arose the endeavour for an independent pursuit of the enquiry concerning the causes of things, which had already been stimulated from another side: this enquiry was primarily directed by the Pythagoreans to the expla- nation of nature, and only secondarily to the establish- ment of moral activity; but as it seemed to them that law and order were the highest element in human life, so in mature it was the order and regular course of phenomena, especially as displayed in the heavenly bodies, and in the relation of tones which arrested their attention. They thought they perceived the ground of all regularity and order in the harmonical relations of numbers, the scientific investigation of which was inaugurated by them, but which were already invested with great power and significance in the popular belief of the Greeks. Thus by a natural D, Sylb.). But even were this state- ment true, we could not infer from it (as Röth does, ii. a, 592) the ex- istence of specific enquiries into language among the Pythagoreans. The assertion of Simplicius (Categ. Schol. in Arist. 43 b, 30) that the Pythagoreans regarded names as arising pào'ei and not 6éoet, and recognised for each thing but one name belonging to it by virtue of its nature, cannot be considered as a tradition concerning the ancient Pythagoreans. It refers, no doubt, to the categories falsely attributed to Archytas. * Metaph. i. 8, wide Supra, p. 189, 3. * Sext. Math. x. 248, 284; Themist. Or. xxvi. 317 B; Hip- polyt. Refut. i. 2, p. 8 ; Eus. Praep. Ev. xiv. 15, 9; Phot. Cod. 249, p. 439 a, 33 ; Galen, Hist. Phil. sub init. 508 THE PYTHAGOREA.N.S. sequence of thought they arrived at the theory that all things, according to their essence, are number and harmony." This presupposition was then applied by them to other adjacent spheres; they expressed the nature of certain phenomena by numbers, and classified whole series of phenomena according to numbers, and so there gradually resulted the totality of doctrines, which we call the Pythagorean system. This system is therefore, as it stands, the work of various men and various periods; its authors did not consciously attempt from the beginning to gain a whole of scientific propositions mutually supporting and explaining one another, but as each philosopher was led by his observation, his calculations, or his imagination, so the fundamental conceptions of the Pythagorean theory of the universe were developed, sometimes in one direction, sometimes in another. The traces of such an origin are not entirely obliterated even in our imperfect traditions of the doctrine of the Pythagoreans. That their principle was apprehended * Cf. p. 376. Brandis (Gesch. d. Entw. d, gr. Phil. i. 165) here makes an objection which I cannot endorse. ‘The remark,’ he says, ‘that all phenomena are regulated according to certain numerical re- lations, presupposes observations quite foreign to that epoch.” Long before Pythagoras, it was known that the revolutions of the sun, moon, and planets, the succession of day and night, the seasons, &c., take place according to fixed times, and that they regularly recur after the lapse of intervals of time marked by the same number. Certainly human life was divided into several ages before Pythagoras. The Pythagoreans themselves mea- sured the numerical relations of tones; and at any rate in the num- ber of tones and chords, a definite standard must have been given to them. It is impossible, moreover, that they should not have had in their possession other proofs that all order is based on measure and number. Philolaus says so ex- plicitly, and it is on this ob- servation that Aristotle founds the Pythagorean theory of num- bers (cf. pp. 369, 1; 370, 1; 376 sq.). CHARACTER OF PYTHIAGOREAN PHILOSOPHY. 509 in many different ways in the school we cannot indeed admit ; but the development of it was certainly not from the same type. The table of the ten oppo- sites belonged, according to Aristotle, only to some, who were, it would seem, later Pythagoreans. The geometric construction of the elements, and the dis- crimination of four organs and of four vital functions in man, were introduced by Philolaus; the doctrine of the ten moving heavenly bodies seems to have been less ancient than the poetical conception of the spheral harmony; as to the relation of particular numbers to concrete phenomena, little agreement is to be found. So far therefore the question might suggest itself, whether the Pythagorean system can rightly be spoken of as a scientific and historical whole, and if this be conceded on account of the unity of the leading thoughts, and the recognised inter-connection of the school, there would still remain the doubt whether the system originates with the founder of the Pythagorean association; and therefore, whether the Pythagorean philosophy is to be classed with the ancient Ionian physical philosophies, or with later systems." This doubt, however, must not carry us too far. Our his- torical authorities indeed allow us to pronounce no de- finite judgment as to how much of the Pythagorean doc- trine belonged to Pythagoras himself. Aristotle always ascribes its authorship to the Pythagoreans, never to Pythagoras, whose name is not mentioned by him at * It is for this reason that tem, and that Strümpell (vide sup. Brandis, for example (i. 421), only p. 209, 1) sees in Pythagoreanism speaks of Pythagoreanism after an attempt to reconcile Heracleitus having spoken of the Eleatic sys- with the Eleatics, 510 THE PYTHIA G O REANS. all except in a very few places." Later writers” are untrustworthy in proportion as they pretend to a know- ledge of Pythagoras; and the scanty utterances of earlier writers are too indefinite to instruct us as to the share taken by Pythagoras in the philosophy of his school. Xenophanes alludes to his assertions on trans- migration as a singularity; * but this belief, of which Pythagoras can scarcely have been the author, furnishes no argument as to his philosophy. Heracleitus men- tions him “ as a man who laboured beyond all others to amass knowledge,” and who by his evil arts, as he calls them, gained the reputation of wisdom ; but whether this wisdom consisted in philosophic theories, or in empirical knowledge, or in theological doctrines, or in practical efforts, cannot be gathered from his words. Nor do we gain any information on this point from * Among the authentic writings which have been preserved, the only passages where Pythagoras is mentioned are Rhet. ii. 23 (vide supra, 341, 1) and Metaph i. 5 (vide infra, 510, 5). As to the works which have been lost, we should cite besides the texts of AElian, Apollonius, and Diogenes (of which we have spoken, supra, p. 338, 3, 4; 345, 5), the Pythago- rean traditions we have extracted (p. 345, 1; 338, 3) from Plutarch and Iamblichus. But these texts do not prove that Aristotle him- self knew anything of Pythagoras. There is also the statement of Porph. V. P. 41, which perhaps ought to be corrected so as to mean that Aristotle spoke of the symbols of the Pythagoreans, and not of Pythagoras. * > * Even the contemporaries and disciples of Aristotle, as Eudoxus, Heracleides, and others, whose as- sertions concerning Pythagoras have been already quoted; also the author of the Magna Moralia, vide Supra, p. 491, 4. * * Wide supra, p. 481, 1. * Wide supra, p. 336, 5, and Fr. 23 ap. Diog. ix. 11 (cf. Procl. in Tim. 31 F; Clemens, Strom. i. 315 D; Athen. xiii. 610 b): Troxvua- 6 mtm včov of 6,840 kel (cf. on this reading, Schuster, Heraclif. p. 65, 2). ‘Hatošov yap by éðiðaše kal IIv6ayópmv, ač0ís te Eevoq &vea kal ‘Ekatafov. * The words ioTopia and troxv- wdôsta describe the man who en- quires from others, and seeks to learn, in opposition to the man who forms his opinions himself by his own reflection. CHARACTER OF PYTHAGOREAN PHILOSOPHY. 511 Empedocles, when he celebrates the wisdom in which Pythagoras surpassed all men, and foresaw the distant future. But though direct evidence fails us yet on general grounds, it is probable that at any rate the fundamental thoughts of the system emanated from Pythagoras himself.” In the first place this furnishes the best explanation of the fact that the system, so far as we know, was confined to the adherents of Pytha- goras, and, among them, was universally disseminated; and moreover, that all that we are told of the Pytha- gorean philosophy, in spite of the differences on minor points, agrees in the main traits. Secondly, the in- ternal relation of the Pythagorean theory to other systems gives us reason to suppose that it originated previously to the beginning of the fifth century. Among all the later systems, there is none in which the influence of the Eleatic doubt concerning the possibility of Becoming does not manifest itself. Leu- cippus, Empedocles, and Anaxagoras, however their views may differ in other respects, are all at one in admitting the first proposition of Parmenides, viz., * In the verses ap. Porph. V. kat re 6ék’ &v6pátrov kal tº eticoaty P. 30; Iambl. V. P. 67. We are âtdºvecrat. not, however, absolutely certain that these verses really relate to * This opinion is found in the Pythagoras (cf. p. 338, 4)— same words, and founded on the Ży 6é ris év keivotaly &v?ip trepidºgua eiðbs, 6s 6%) uſiktorov trpatríðwv ékthorato TAoûtov, Travrotov re uáAtara orogów Śrthpa- vos épywv, àm Tóre yūp tróoratoruv Špéčairo trpa- tríðeorol, field, ye róv čvtwv rávrov Aeña geo- kev ćicagºra, same proofs, in the 2nd and 3rd editions of this work. This does not prevent Chaignet (i. 160) from saying : Zeller veut, que l'élément Scientifique, philosophique de la con- ception pythagoricienne ait été pos- térieur à Pythagore et étranger & ses vues personnelles et & Son dessein primitif, tout pratique, Selon lui. 512 THE P}THAGOREANS, the impossibility of Becoming, and consequently in reducing birth and decay to mere change. The Py- thagoreans might be supposed to be especially open to the influence of these profound doctrines of their Eleatic neighbours; but not a trace of this influence is to be found. Empedocles, who alone, while ad- hering to the Pythagorean life and theology, is as a philosopher allied to Parmenides, on this very account departs from the Pythagorean School, and becomes the author of an independent theory. This tends to prove that the Pythagorean philosophy not only did not arise out of an attempt to reconcile the Heracleitean and Eleatic doctrines, but that it was not even formed under the influence of the Eleatic system. On the | other hand, the Eleatic system seems to presuppose Pythagoreanism; for the abstraction of reducing the multitudinous mass of phenomena to the one concept of being, is so bold that we cannot avoid seeking for some historical preparation for it ; and no system adapts itself better to this purpose, as has already been shown (p. 204), than the Pythagorean, the principle of which is exactly intermediate between the sensible intuition of the ancient Ionians, and the pure thought of the Eleatics. That the Pythagorean cosmology was known to Parmenides, at any rate, is probable from its affinity with his own, which will hereafter be noticed. We have, therefore, every reason to believe that the Pythagorean theory is earlier than that of Parmenides, and that in regard to its main outlines Pythagoras is really its author. We shall also presently find that Heracleitus owes not a little to the Samian philosopher ORIGINT OF PYTHAGOREAN PHILOSOPHY. 518 of whom he speaks so harshly, if what he says about the arising of all things from contradictories and from harmony, is really connected with the analogous doc- trines of the Pythagoreans. How far the philosophic development of doctrine was carried by Pythagoras, cannot of course be discovered ; but if he is to be regarded as the founder of the Pythagorean system, he must at least have enunciated in some form the funda- mental definitions that all is number, that all is harmony; that the opposition of the perfect and im- perfect, the straight and the crooked, pervades all things; and since these definitions themselves can only have arisen in connection with the Pythagorean arith- metic and music, we must also refer the beginning of arithmetic and music to him. Lastly, we shall find that Parmenides placed the seat of the divinity which governs the world in the centre of the universe, and made the different spheres revolve around the centre; we may therefore suppose that the central fire and the theory of the spheres had also been early taught by the Pythagoreans, though the motion of the earth, the counter-earth, and the precise number of the ten re- volving spheres were probably of later origin. Whether Pythagoras himself had teachers from whom his philosophy either wholly or partially sprang, and where these are to be sought, is matter of contro- versy. As is well known, the later ages of antiquity believed him to have derived his doctrines from the East." In particular, either Egypt, or Chaldaea and * Cf. p. 326 sq. WOL. I. L L 514 THE PETHAGOREANS. Persia, would soonest occur to the mind; and ancient writers especially mention these countries when they speak of the travels of Pythagoras in the East. To me such an origin of his doctrine seems unlikely. There is, as has been already shown, an utter absence of all trust- worthy evidence in its favour, and the internal points of contact with Persian and Egyptian philosophy, which may be found in Pythagoreanism, are not nearly sufficient to prove its dependence upon these foreign influences. What Herodotus says of the agreement between Pythagoreans and Egyptians' is confined to the belief in transmigration, and the custom of in- terring the dead exclusively in linen garments. But transmigration is found not merely in Pherecydes, with whose treatise and opinions Pythagoras may have been acquainted, if even he were not a scholar of his in the technical sense ; * it was certainly an older Orphic tradition,” and the same may very likely be true of the customs in regard to burial: in no case could we infer from the appropriation of these religious tra- ditions the dependence of the Pythagorean philosophy upon the alleged wisdom of the Egyptian priests. Of the distinctive principle of this system, the number- theory, we find no trace among the Egyptians; the parallels, too, which might be drawn between the Egyptian and Pythagorean cosmology are much too in- definite to prove any close historical interconnection between them : and the same holds good of the Pytha- gorean symbolism, in which some have also seen traces * ii. 81, 123. vide p. 69, 3; 327 sq. * On Pherecydes and his pre- * Wide Supra, p. 67 sq. tended relations with Pythagoras, ORIGIN OF PETHAGOREAN PHILOSOPHY. 515 of Egyptian origin." The system of caste and other social institutions of the Egyptians were not imitated by the Pythagoreans. We might indeed compare the zeal of these philosophers for the maintenance and re- storation of ancient customs and institutions, with the fixed invariability of the Egyptian character; but the reasons of this phenomenon lie nearer to hand in the circumstances and traditions of the colonies of Magna Graecia; and the difference of the Doric and Pythagorean element from the Egyptian is, on closer observation, so important, that there is no warrant for deriving the one from the other. The same may be said of the Persian doctrines. The Pythagorean oppo- sition of the uneven and the even, of the better and the worse, &c., might find a parallel in the Persian dualism ; and it is apparently this similarity which gave occasion, in ancient times, to the theory that the Magi, or even Zoroaster, were the teachers of Pytha- goras. But it surely did not require foreign instruc- tion to observe that good and evil, straight and crooked, masculine and feminine, right and left, exist in the world; the specific manner, however, in which the Pythagoreans designated these opposites; their reduc- tion to the fundamental oppositions of the uneven and the even, the limited and unlimited, the decuple classi- fication, generally speaking, the philosophic and mathe- matical treatment of the subject, is as foreign to the doctrine of Zoroaster as the theological dualism of a goo and evil Deity is foreign to Pythagoreanism. Other similarities which might be adduced, such as the signifi- * As Plutarch does, Qu. Conv. viii. 8, 2; De Is. 10, p. 354. L. L 2 516 . THE PF THAGOREANS, cance of the number seven, the belief in a future exist- ence, and many ethical and religious apophthegms collec- tively, prove so little, and differ from each other so greatly as to details, that they cannot be discussed in this place. The life and science of the Pythagoreans are only really to be understood in connection with the specific character and conditions of culture of the Greek people in the sixth century. Pythagoreanism, as an attempt at ethico-religious reform,' must be classed with other endeavours which we meet with contemporaneously or previously in the work of Epimenides and Onomacritus, in the rise of mysteries, in the wisdom of the so-called seven wise men, and of the Gnomic poets; and it is distinguished from all similar phenomena by the manysidedness and force with which it embraced all the elements of culture of the time, religious, ethical, political, and scientific, and at the same time created for itself, in a close society, a fixed nucleus and aim for its activity. Its more precise characteristics resulted lf from its connection with the Doric race and Dorie- | institutions.” Pythagoras himself, it is true, came from the Ionian island of Samos, but as we have already seen, it is probable that his parents, though of Tyrrhene race, had emigrated thither from Phlius in Peloponnesus, and the principal theatre of his own activity was in Doric and Achaean cities. At any rate his work displays the essential traits of the Doric character. The worship of the Dorian Apollo,” the aristocratic politics, the * Wide p. 496, 352. sq.; 392 sq.; Schwegler, Gesch. d. 2 Cf. the excellent remarks of gr. Phil. 53 sq. O. Müller, Gesch. Hellen. Stämme * Wide Supra, p. 338, 340. und Stütte, ii. a, 365 sq. b; 178 2- ºr **" ORIGIN OF PETHAGOREAN PHILOSOPHY. 517 Syssitia, the gymnastics, the ethical music, the prover- bial wisdom of the Pythagoreans, the participation of women in the education and Society of men, the strict and measured moral code, which knows no higher duties than the subordination of the individual to the whole, respect for traditional customs and laws, reverence for parents, for constituted authority, and for old age—all this plainly shows us how great a share the Doric spirit had in the origination and development of Pythago- reanism. That this spirit is also unmistakeable in the Pythagorean philosophy has already been observed; but the union in Pythagoras of a scientific effort for the interpretation of nature, with his moral and religious activity, is probably due to the influence of the Ionic physiologists, who could not have been unknown to a man so erudite and so far beyond all his contemporaries” in his passion for knowledge. The statement, however, that Anaximander was his instructor” can scarcely be more than a conjecture, based on chronological proba- bility and not on any actual tradition. But it is very likely that he may have been acquainted with his elder contemporary, who was so prominent among the earliest philosophers, whether we suppose the acquaintance to have been personal, or merely through Anaximander’s writings. The influence of Anaximander may perhaps be traced, not only in the general impulse towards the study of the causes of the universe, but also in the Pythagorean theory of the spheres (vide p. 445, 1), which has an immediate connection with the theory of * P. 502, 507 sq. * Neanthes ap. Porph. Cf. p. * As Heracleitus says, vide 326, note. supra, p. 336, 5 ; 510, 4. 518 THE PYTHAGORIEANS. which Anaximander is supposed to be the author (vide 252, 1). And if the distinction of the limited and un- limited originally belongs to Pythagoras, Anaximander may nevertheless have had a share in inspiring it ; only from Anaximander's conception of the unlimited in space Pythagoras would have abstracted the general concept of the unlimited, which is an essential element of all things, and primarily of number. By Pythagoras physics or philosophy (for they were identical at that period) became first transplanted from their most ancient home in Ionian Asia Minor into Italy, there to be further developed in a specific manner. That in this development, side by side with the Hellenic element, the peculiar character of the Italian races by whom the birthplace of Pythagoreanism was surrounded, may have made itself felt, is certainly conceivable; but our his– torical evidence' in favour of this conjecture is not sufficient even to render it probable.” If anything was 1. Cf. Schwegler, Röm. Gesch. i. 561 sq., 616. Klausen, AEneas und die Penaten, ii. 928 sq., 961 sq.; O. Müller, Etrusker, ii. 139 A, 53, 345 A, 22. * Even the ancient tradition that Numa was a disciple of Py- thagoras (vide Part III. 6, 69, 2nd edition) seems to presuppose a certain likeness between the Ro- man religion and Pythagoreanism. Plut. (Numa, c. 8, 14) cites the following points of resemblance between Numa and Pythagoras. * Both,” he says, “represented them- selves as plenipotentiaries of the gods (which many others have also done). Both love symbolic pre- scripts and usages (this also is very common; but the Roman symbols are explained by Plutarch in a very arbitrary manner). As Pythagoras introduced Éxeptibia, so Numa es- tablished the worship of the muse Tacita (who is not a muse, and has no connection with the pre- script of silence, vide Schwegler, p. 562). Pythagoras conceived the divinity (Plutarch asserts) as a pure spirit; Numa, from the same point of view, prohibited images of the gods. (Pythagoras did not prohibit them; and if the ancient Roman cultus was devoid of images, the reason of this is not to be found in a purer conception of the Deity, but, as with the Germani and In- dians, and other barbarous peoples, in the absence of plastic arts, and in the special character of the Roman. OIZIGIN OF PPTHAGOREAN PHILOSOPHY. 519 contributed from this side to Pythagoreanism, it can only have consisted in some details of a quite subordi- religion.) The sacrifices of Numa, were scarcely any of them bloody; nor were those of the Pythagoreans. (This does not seem certain, ac- cording to our previous observa- tions, and it would be of little con- sequence if it were. For the Greeks, especially in ancient times, had many unbloody sacrifices, and the Romans not only sacrificed animals in great numbers, but had also hu- man sacrifices.) Lastly, not to men- tion other insignificant similarities, Numa placed the fire of Vesta in a round temple, “to represent the form of the world and the position of the central fire in the midst of it.” (But the ancient Romans cer- tainly were unacquainted with the central fire, and it is impossible to prove that the form of the temple of Vesta was intended to symbolise that of the world. At any rate, the apparent roundness of the ce- lestial vault was perceptible to every one by immediate observation, and on the other hand, if the Pytha- goreans called their central fire Hestia, they would naturally be thinking, not of the Roman Vesta, but of the Greek Hestia.) It is the same with certain other analo- gies between Roman and Italian customs and those of the Pythago- reans. Beans were forbidden to the flamen ſ)ialis, as they were among the Pythagoreans, according to a later tradition and custom. But the Pythagoreans no doubt borrowed this custom, as well as their asceti- cism generally, from the Orphic mysteries. They are said to have followed the Roman and Etruscan usage of turning to the right when they prayed. But it is clear from Plut, 7. c., that such a custom was unknown to them. Even were it otherwise, the coincidence would prove little. This holds good of other coincidences, by which Plut. Qu. Conv. viii. 7, 1, 3, seeks to prove that Pythagoras was an Etruscan. The Roman doctrine of Genii and Lares may in many respects resemble the Pythagorean belief in daemons; but the Pytha- goreans found this belief already in the Greek religion. This resem- blance, then, simply points to the general affinity of the Greek and Italian peoples. Still less can be deduced from the circumstance that the Pythagoreans, like the Romans (and the Greeks and most nations), regarded the interment of an un- buried corpse as a sacred duty; but what Klausen (p. 362) quotes to prove traces of Metempsychosis in the Roman legend is not conclu- sive. We might, with more reason, compare the ancient Roman motion that Jupiter, the prince of spirits, sends souls into the world and re- calls them (Macrob. Sat. i. 10), with the doctrine said to have been taught by the Pythagoreans, of the soul proceeding from the world- soul (supra, p. 447, 1). But first we may ask whether this doctrine was really held by the ancient Py- thagoreans, and next we must re- member that the belief in the celestial origin of the soul and its return to aether was not unknown to the Greeks (wide supra, p. 69, 1; 70, 4). Some of the Roman institutions and opinions may also remind us of the Pythagorean theory of numbers. But the like- ness is not so great that we can 520 THE PPTHAGOREA.N.S. mate importance; for the Greeks of Lower Italy were as little inclined to adopt philosophic doctrines from the surrounding barbarians, as the barbarians were in a condition to impart them. legitimately regard this theory merely as the philosophic expres- sion of the ancient Roman and Italian superstitions about num- bers. Among the Romans, as among the Pythagoreans, uneven numbers were considered lucky (vide Schwegler, l. c., 543, 561 ; Rubino, De Augur. et Pontif ap. wet. Rome. Num. 1852, p. 6 sq.; , cf. also Plin. Hist. Nat. xxviii. 2, 23), and for this reason the Romans and the Pythagoreans assigned to the superior deities an uneven number, and to the inferior deities an even number, of victims (Plut. Numa, 14; Porph. v. Pyth. 38; Serv. Bucol. viii. 75; v. 66). But this idea and that custom were not exclusively Pythagorean: they be- longed to the Greeks in general. Plato, at any rate, says (Laws, iv. 717 A): Tois X00utois àv Tus 6.e0?s &ptua kal bettepa kal &plorepò véuov àp66tara roß rās eice&etas oritoroi, Tvyxãvot, roºs 3& rotºtov Šva,6ev rà. trepitté, etc.; and it is not pro- bable that he is merely following a Bythagorean tradition. It is much more likely that in this, as in his other laws, he is adhering as much as possible to the customs of his own country. Lastly, in the division of the Roman city, we see carried out a rigorous numerical schematism, of which the bases are the number three and the number ten ; and the religious ritual has in it something analogous (Schwegler, p. 616). But this is not peculiar to Rome and Italy. In Sparta, for example (not to mention more distant nations, All the more favourable like the Chinese or Galatians), the population was divided according to the numbers three and ten ; there were 9,000 Spartans and 30,000 Periaeci. In the nine days’ festival of the Käpueta, they eat in nine arbours, nine men in each (Athen. iv. 141 E). Ancient Athens had four tribes, each tribe three ºpparpiai (?), each pparpía thirty gentes, each gens thirty families. The smallest round number, with the Greeks as with the Romans, was three (with the Pythagoreans, four had a higher value), then came ten, then 100, then 1,000, then 10,000. One of the highest num- bers of this kind was Tptorutpuot. Hesiod had a good deal to say of the significance of certain numbers (vide supra, 376, 3). The predi- lection for numerical schematism might well exist among different peoples without being the result of any direct historical connection between them. Among the Pythago- reans, it sprang chiefly from specu- lative motives; among others, e.g. the Romans, it arose from the practical sense of order. I cannot, therefore, agree with the theory which attributes to the peoples and religions of Italy an important in- fluence on Pythagoreanism. On the other hand, as we shall see later on (Part III. b, 69 sq , 2A, 2nd ed.), and as we have already seen in the quotation (p. 341, 1), the name of Pythagoras was known to the Ro- mans before that of any other Greek philosopher, and was greatly vene- rated by them, ALCMAEON. 521 was the soil which philosophy found in the Magna Grecian colonies themselves, as is proved by the growth it there attained, and by all that we know of the culture of these cities. If further proof, however, be required, it lies in the fact that, contemporaneously with the Pythagorean, another branch of Italian philo- sophy was developed, which also owed its origin to an Ionian. But before we proceed to examine this systern, We must direct our attention to certain men who have a connection with Pythagoreanism, although we cannot precisely include them in the Pythagorean school. WII. PYTHAGOREANISM IN COMBINATION WITH OTHER ELEMENTS. ALCMAEON, HIPPASUS, ECPHANTUS, EPICHARPM US. THE physician Alcmaeon,’ of Crotona, is said to have been a younger contemporary, by some even a disciple, of Pythagoras.” Both statements, however, are uncer- tain,” and the second cannot possibly in the stricter * Vide, in regard to Alcmaeon: Philippson, "TAm &v6patrívm, p. 183 sqq.; Unna, De Alcmaeone Crotoni- ata in the Phil.-Histor. Studien von Petersen, pp. 41–87, where the statements of the ancients and the fragments of Alcmaeon have been carefully collected. Krische, For- Schungen, etc., 68–78. We know nothing of Alcmaeon's life, except his origin and the name of his father (IIelp!600s, IIsipiðos or IIé- piðos). Aristotle wrote against him, we are told, Diog. v. 25. * Arist. Metaph. i. 5, 986 a, 27 (after enumerating the ten Py- thagorean opposites): ávarep rpá- trov čolice kal 'AAirplatov š Kporović- Tns intoxafletv ſcal #rot oitos trap' ékeſvay 3) ékeºvot trapſ, rotºrov trapé- Aašov Tov Aéryov tootov ical yèp êyéveto thv jºurcíav’AAkuaſav ćirl 'yepovti IIv6ayópg, &reqfivaro 5& Tra- paramatos toūrois. Diog. viii. 83 : IIv6ayópov 6thkovore. Iamblichus, V. P. 104, reckons him among the wabnteto avres Tó IIv6ayópg Tpear- Súrm véo ; and Philop. in Arist. De An. c. 8, calls him a Pythagorean. Simplicius, in his remarks on the same treatise, p. 8, says more cau- tiously that others call him a Pytha- gorean, but that Aristotle does not. * Diogenes and Iamblichus both no doubt derived their information, the one directly, the other indi- rectly, from the passage in Aris- totle. Now in this passage the §22 THE PPTHAGORIEANS. sense be true; for Aristotle (loc. cit.) expressly dis- criminates Alcmaeon from the Pythagoreans, and his theories are by no means invariably in agreement with theirs; yet it is plain, even from the little we know of him and his writings,' that the Pythagorean doctrine was not without influence on him. Besides the anatomical and physiological enquiries, in which his chief merit seems to have consisted,” we find mention, words é-yéveto . . . IIv6ayópg, and the 5& after éteq fivato, which are wanting in the excellent codex Ab, are not mentioned by the Greek commentators: they seem superflu- ous, and like an interpolation. Wide Brandis, Gr. Röm. Phil. i. 507 sq.; Gruppe, Fragm. d. Arch. 54 sqq.; Schwegler in h. l. Yet the first words of the writing of Alcmaeon, in which he dedicates his work to Brotinus, Leo, and Bathyllus, prove that the date as- signed is approximately correct. Wide next note, and Unna, p. 43; Frische, p. 70. * This work, the beginning of which is given by Diog. l. c. after IFavorinus, was entitled, according to Galen. (in Hipp. de Elem. t. i. 487; in Hºpp. De Nat. Hom. xv. 5 K), repl púaews. Diog. and Clem. (Strom. i. 308 C) designate it also as 'pwaukös Aó70s. But Clemens is wrong in asserting, as he does, Theodoret, Cur. Gr. Aff. 1, 19, Gaisf., that Alcmaeon is the first who wrote on physics, for if even Xenophanes is not to be regarded as a Physicist, Anaximander, and Anaximenes (perhaps also Hera- cleitus), certainly wrote before Alc- maeon. But, according to Clemens, even Anaxagoras had been men- tioned as the first author of a phy- sical treatise. * According to Chalcid. (in Tim. c. 244, p. 233 Mull.), he was the first to make dissections, vide Unna, p. 55 sqq. As to his physi- ological opinions we learn from tradition the following particulars. He taught that the seat of the soul is in the brain (Plut. Plac. iv. 17, 1), to which all sensations are transmitted by means of the chan- nels which lead from the organs of sense (Theophrast. De Sensu, sec- tion 26). How he sought to ex- plain the different senses we are told by Theophrastus, l.c. 25 sq.; Plut. Plac. iv. 16, 2; 17, 1 ; 18, 1 ; wide the parallel passages in the Pseudo-Galen and Stobaeus. For this reason the head is first formed in the embryo (Plac. v. 17, 3). The seed comes from the brain (Plac. v. 3, 3). Alcmaeon occupied himself greatly with the subject of the embryo, how it is formed and how nourished (vide Censorinus, loc. cit. c. 5, 6 ; Plut. Plac. v. 14, 1, 16, 3). He compared puberty to the florescence of plants, and the milk of animals to the white of an egg (Arist. H. Anim. Wii. 1, 581 a, 14; Gener. Anim. iii. 2, 752 b, 23). He explained sleep by the reple- tion of the blood-vessels,and waking by the emptying of them (Plut. Pl. v. 23, 1). He is also said to have believed that goats breathe through ALCMAEON. 523 not only of isolated astronomical' and ethical pro- positions,” but also of general philosophical theories which are very closely allied to those of the Pytha- goreans. The leading point of view in these theories is, on the one hand, the opposition between the perfect or celestial, and the imperfect or terrestrial; and on the other, the spiritual affinity of man with the eternal. The heavens and the heavenly bodies are divine, because they uninterruptedly revolve in a motion that returns into itself; * the race of their ears, Arist. H. Anim. i. 11, sub init. It is possible that Alc- maeon may be referred to by Alex. (in Arist. De Sensu, ii. 12, p. 23, Thur.) in the statement that certain physicians shared the Pythagorean opinion, mentioned p. 475, 3 ; but this conjecture is uncertain. That of Hirzel (Hermes, xi. 240 sq.), on the contrary, seems admissible; he thinks that Plato was referring to Alcmaeon, when in the Phaedo, 96 B, he speaks of the opinion accord- ing to which 6 €yképañós éotiv 6 t&s aio 6%gets trapéxov too &Kočeiv kai épáv kal 60 ppaívea 6al, ék rotºrwy 8è yíºyvoito uvâum kai 66&c., ák 6& uviums kal 668ms A&60ſons to hpspielv karð taúra 'yūyveo'6at étriotiumv. The distinction of étriotăum and alo 6 morts accords, as Hirzel well ob- serves, with the text cited p. 524, 3. What is said at the commencement of this note agrees with the theory that the brain is the seat of the faculty of knowing ; but Alcmaeon (cf.p.523,3; 524,2) must necessarily have regarded the soul alone as the knowing subject. We cannot, how- ever, be sure that Plato did not add something of his own to the opin- ion which he reports; the deriva- tion of éiriotſium from hpspielv–i.e., man, on the contrary, is the fastening of ideas in the soul, repeated by Arist. Anal. Post. ii. 19, 100, a 3—is perhaps an addition of this kind ; cf. Crat. 437 A.; Meno, 97 E sq. * According to Plut. Plac. ii. 16, 2; Stob. i. 516, he maintained that the fixed stars move from east to west ; the planets (among which we must suppose the earth, which revolves around the central fire) from west to east. According to Stobaeus, i. 526, 558, he attri- buted, like the Ionians, to the sun and moon a plane surface shaped like a boat, and explained eclipses of the moon by the shift- ing round of the Iunar boat. Simpl. says (De Caºlo, 121 a, Ald.) that he calculated the interval of time between the solstices and the equinoxes; but this is according to the ancient texts. Ap. Karsten, p. 223 a, 15, and Brandis, Schol. 500 a, 28, we find instead of 'AAkuatovi, Eükthuovu, which seems more eXà.Ct. * Clemens (Strom. viii. 624 B) cites the following from him : éx6pöv čvöpa šov pukášaq 0at # pixov. º * Arist. De An. i. 2, 405 a, 30: p.mal yèp airthy [thv jux}\vl 524 THE PPTHAGO REANS, transitory, because we are not in a position to unite the beginning with the end—to begin a new course' after the expiration of our period of life. Our soul, however, is exempt from this transitoriness: it moves etermally, like the stars, and is therefore immortal.” So also its knowledge is not limited to the sense-perception—but it has also understanding and consciousness.” But everything human is on this account imperfect. The gods know what is hidden, we can only conjecture it : * they enjoy a uniform existence; our life moves between contraries,” and its healthfulness depends on the equi- &6ávarov etvai Ötö. Tö éolkéval roſs &6avárots, routo 6’ 3rdpxetv airfi és àel kivovuévy' kivetotal yèp ka? Tô Đeta rāvta ovvexós àel, orexhumv, #Atov, rows ào répas, row oipavov &Aov. This text is doubtless the sole foundation for the assertion of the Epicurean, ap. Cic. N. D. i. 11, 27: Soli et lunae reliquisque sideri- ôtts animoque praeterea divinitatem dedit, and of Diog. viii. 83 : kal thv orexhumv ka9óAov raúrmy (this pas- sage seems to be mutilated; it may have originally stood thus : k.t.a. kal &Nov tow oilpavov) exeiv &tówov qºotv. Clem. Cohort. 44 A: ‘A. 6eo)s jero robs &a répas eival épºpt- xovs &vros. Cf. the following note. * Arist. Probl. xvii. 3, 916 a, 33: Tobs yöp &v0p6trous pnolv 'AA- !cuatov Ště roºro &nda Avorðau, ätt ot, 8èvaviral rhv Špx.hu ré réAet Tpoordial. The sense of these words exactly determined by Phi- lippson, 185; Unna, 71, is clear from the whole connexion of the passage. * Arist. l. c. and, after him, Boethius, ap. Eus. Pr. Ev. xi. 28, 5; Diog. viii. 83; Stob. Ecl. i. 796; Theodoret, Cur. gr. aff, v. 17, and the Greek commentators of Aristotle, among whom Philoponus (in De An. i. 2 C, 8) expressly re- marks that he is not acquainted with the writings of Alcmaeon, and knows nothing of him except what Aristotle says. * Theophr. De Sensu, 4, 25: táv 8è uh rá, époſq, trotočvrwu Thy ato- 6mauv (as Empedocles did, vide infra)'AAkuatov učvirpátovãºpoptºel Thy trpos rô (ºja 5uaq opáv' &vôpotov ºyáp pmol rôv &AAwy 6taq’épelv Štt uóvov (l. uévos) £vvimori, rö. 3’ &AAa aioróðveral uèv of Čuvimori Šć. * Alcm. ap Diog. viii. 83: trept Töv &qavéov [trepi Tôv 6vntóv] ora- ‘pivetav učv 6eol āzovti, &s 6* &v6p3- trous rekuaipeg 6at. * Arist. Metaph. i. 5 (Sup, p. 521, 2) continues: prior yop eival São Tà troAA& Tóv &vôpatríva'u, Aéyav Tès évauruármras oix àortrep oirot bioptoſuévas &AA& Tès rvxotoras, oiov Aevkov uéAav, YAvici tukpov, & yabbw kaköv, utºpov uéya. oitos uév obv &öloptotos étré65upe trepi Tàu Aottröv, oi ö& IIv6ayópelot kal tróoral kai Tives ai évavrićtmºres &reqívavro. Isoe. says wrongly: tr. &vrtóóo. 268: ‘A. 8è Ščo uáva (pmaly eival tă ăvta). FIIPPASUS. 525 librium of opposite forces; when, on the contrary, one of its elements gains a preponderance over the others, sickness and death are the result." We certainly cannot consider Alcmaeon a Pythagorean because of these pro- positions, for we find nothing about the number-theory, the distinctive doctrine of the Pythagorean system, in any of our accounts of him. Moreover, his astronomi- cal opinions, mentioned above, only partially agree with the Pythagorean cosmology; and we must, therefore, hold Aristotle to be in the right when he discriminates him from the Pythagoreans. But the observations of Alcmaeon on the relation of the eternal and the mortal, on the oppositions in the world, on the divinity of the stars, and the immortality of the soul, coincide in substance almost exactly with the Pythagorean doctrine. That a contemporary of the Pythagoreans, from their especial city Crotona, should have arrived at these theories independently of Pythagoreanism, is incredible. Although, therefore, Aristotle does not venture to decide whether the doctrine of opposites came from the Pythagoreans to Alcmaeon, or vice versá, the former alternative is much the more probable ; * and we accord- 1 Plut. Plac. v. 30 (Stob. Floril. 101, 2; 100, 25): 'A Tàs uèv Öyetas eival avvercrukhv thv (so Stob.) iorovopºtav Tóv Švudueov, Öypov, 6ep- u00, £mpoo, juxpoſſ, trikpot, yāvkéos kal Tów Aoutrów. Thu 6' év airois povapxtav vögov troumrukhvº pºopo- troubv yöp Šicatépov uovapxſa' cal vágov airta, Ös pièv šp’ fis, Štrepòox3) 6epuðrntos # puxpótºmºros &s à é fis, Stå tañ90s (Stob. wrongly: rxm0. Tpopis)? §vöstav dis 6 y of s, aiwa Övöéov (Stob.reads preferably: % Avexöv) # ykéqſaxos (St.--ov). thv 5è Öystav oriºuſastpov Tóv trouſov Thy kpāoriv. (Stob. has : yīvea:0ai 6é trore kal imb Tév šša,0ev airlöv, 56&rov totów # x&pas ?) kóTov ) äväyrms htów rotºrous traparamotov.) Plato, Symp. 106 D, puts the same thoughts into the mouth of his Eryxainachus. The mention of the four Aristotelian causes and of the Stoic trouot clearly shows that here we have not Alcmaeon's own words. * There is no question here of the Pythagorean table of the ten 526 THE PPTHAGO REANS. ingly regard Alcmaeon as a man who was considerably influenced by the Pythagorean philosophy, without having actually adopted it in its totality. Respecting Hippasus and Ecphantus our informa- tion is still more scanty. As to the former, the ancient writers themselves seem to have known no more than is to be found in Aristotle—namely, that, like Heracleitus, he held fire to be the primitive matter." The farther statements, that he declared fire to be the Deity;” that he made derived things arise out of fire by rare- faction and condensation; * that he thought the soul was of a fiery nature; * that the world was limited and eternally moved, and subject to a periodic transforma- tion : * all these must be mere inferences from the comparison of him with Heracleitus, since even the scholars of the Alexandrian epoch possessed no writing of his.” It was perhaps this approximation to the Heracleitean doctrine which made later writers call him a spurious Pythagorean, and the head of the so-called opposites, but only of the general principle that everything is full of opposites. * Arist. Metaph. i. 3, 984 a, 7 : “Ittraoros 3& Tüp [äpx?iv ráðmou] 6 Meratovtºvos kal ‘Hpdºxettos & 'Eq'éorios. The same is reproduced by Sext. Pyrrh, iii. 30; Clemens, Strom. i. 296 B; Theod. Cur. gr. aff. ii. 10, p. 22; Plut. Plac. i. 3, 25. What the last writer adds in regard to the metamorphoses of fire only applies to Heracleitus. 2 Clem. Cohort. 42 C. * Simpl. Phys. 6 a. * Theodoret, Cur. gr. aff, v. 20; Tert. De An. c. 5. * Diog. viii. 84; Simpl. l. c.; Theod. iv. 5, p. 58, where, however, instead of &icſvntov & st k i v m r ov is to be read. ° Diog. l.c. pnal 3' airov Amu'ff- tpuos év “Ouavčuous ſamāśv kataAlireſv a tºyypapua. Theo, Mus. c. 12, p. 91, mentions, but only as a report, the experiments of Lasos of Hermi- one und Hippasus (or his school) for determining the relations of tones. If Iambl. (in Nicom. Arithm. 141, 159, 163 Tennul) attributes to the mathematicians, Archytas and Hippasus, the distinction of arithmetical, geometrical and har- monic proportions, his assertion is not based on any writing of Hip- paSuS. IECPHANTUS. 527 Acusmatics; elsewhere he is spoken of purely and simply as a Pythagorean,” and fragments of writings are adduced which were falsely attributed to him on this supposition.” If we enquire by what means he could have been led, as a Pythagorean, to the theory ascribed to him, it is most obvious to think of the doctrine of the central fire. According to the Pythagoreans, this fire was the germ of the universe, to which everything else had reference ; and Hippasus seems for this reason to have regarded it as the matter of which all things consist. There is every probability, however, that he was also influenced by the example of Heracleitus, and that his theory thus resulted from a combination of the Pythagorean and Heracleitean doctrine. Ecphantus occupies a similar position. He, too, is included among the Pythagoreans; * but their number- theory appears to have been too abstract and un- physical for him, and he therefore sought, like Hippasus, to complete it with the theories of later physicists; only that instead of Heracleitus, he chose the Atomistic philosophy and Anaxagoras, influenced perhaps by the Pythagorean derivation of space-magnitudes. He understood by the units, which are the original con- stituents of numbers, and furthermore of all things, * Iambl. V. Pyth. 81. Simi- larly Willoison, Anecd.ii. 216. On the other hand, Iambl. (in Nicom. 11 b); Stob. Eel. i. 862; and Sy- rian, in Metaph. xiii. 6, borrow even from his reputed writings testimonies concerning the Pytha- gorean doctrine. * E. g. by Diog and Theo, l.c. * Wide sup. p. 372, 1. * Röth, ii. a, 812, with his usual recklessness, calls Ecphantus and Hicetas ‘immediate disciples of Pythagoras.” Not only is this as- sertion entirely without proof; but it seems most probable, from the texts quoted on p. 491 sq., that both these philosophers lived after Philolaus, and at the same time as Archytas. 528 THE PYTHAGOREA.N.S. material atoms, differing among themselves in size, form, and force. The proposition (which we must understand in the sense of the analogous sayings of Democritus"), that the essence of things cannot be known (that is, sensibly perceived), probably refers to the invisibility of these atoms. To the atoms he added the void—a conception already recognised in the ancient Pythagorean doctrine—but this did not appear to him sufficient as an explanation of phenomena, or else Pythagorean piety prevented his resting in it; he therefore assumed, with Anaxagoras, that the move- ment of the atoms and the shaping of the universe was produced by mind or the soul. On account of the unity of this moving cause, he preferred the ordinary notion of the unity and spherical shape of the world to the atomistic theory of many worlds.” All this, how- ever, shows that he must have belonged to the latest generations of the Pythagoreans, with whom he is also identified by the statement that, in agreement with 1 For further details, vide infra. Cf. for the present, Arist. Metaph. iv. 5; 1009 b, 11 ; Amuákpitós yé qmoriv, #rot obbèv sival &Am6&s h juïv y &5mAov. 2 The testimonies on which the above assertion is founded are as follows:—Stob. Ecl. i. 308 (8wp., p. 415, 1); ibnd. 448: "Exp. it uév rów &róuov avverrával tow kóo wov, Stouceſo 0&t 8& Örö Trpovoſas. Ibid. 496: "Eicq. iva röv káguov. Hip- polyt. Refut. i. 15, p. 28: "Ekpav- tós ris Xupakovo tos éqºm wheival &Amówhy rôv čvrov Aabetv yuáoruv' Öpf{el 6* &s vopfget tº uév trpára &öuaípera sival oréuara ſcal trapaRAa- ºy&s atrów rpets intrópxeiv, uéye60s, orxāua, Sövapuy, Čš &y tº giorðmrå ºyſveoréal. elvat 8% to TA;60s airāv éptoſuévov kal Touro [l. kal oik) &meipov. Iciveto 6at 8& Tö ordºnata. uñte ürb Bāpovs wite tram'yūs, &AA’ §tro 6etas Švváuews, v votiv kai Wvxhv trpoo`ayopsiel. Toi) uév oſſºv Töv kóo wou eiðéval ióeſu (or as Roper, Philologus, vii. 6, 20, happily con- jectures: Tottov učv oſſy T. kógu. eival ióéav), 31' 3 agaipoetóñ Štrb atās 8vváuews yeyovéval (this after Plato), thu 88 yūv uéorov (perhaps év weap) kóopov kiveto 6al trepi to airis Kévrpov &s trpos àvatoxfiv. Instead of the last three words (which, however, are not impossi- ble) we might conjecture, the rest of the text being very incorrect: &mb ðūorews irpos àvaroAhv. PYTHAGO REANS. 529 Heracleides the Platonist (and with Hicetas), he believed the earth to rotate upon its axis." He himself reminds us of Plato in some particulars.” The celebrated comic poet Epicharmus” is called by many authors a Pythagorean." It is not improbable that the Pythagorean doctrine had something more than a superficial influence on him, and that the incli- nation to general reflections and apophthegms, which may be perceived in the fragments of his works,” was fostered by it. But we are not justified by what we know of him, in supposing that he had any definite phi- losophical system. According to Diogenes III., 9 sqq., Alcimus" attempted to show that Plato borrowed greatſ part of his doctrine from Epicharmus. His authorities are not only insufficient for this purpose, but fail to prove that Epicharmus was a philosopher at all in the proper sense. * Wide sup. p. 453, 1. * Another trace of Pythagorean Atomistic doctrines may perhaps be found in what has been quoted p. 468, 1, concerning Xuthus. * Grysar. De Doriens Comodia, 84 sqq.; Leop. Schmidt, Quaest. Epicharmea, Bonn, 1846; Welcker, K/eine Schrift. i. 271–356; Lorenz, L. und Schr. d. Koers Epicharmos, Berl. 1864. The life of Epicharmus falls, according to Schmidt, between the 59th and the 79th Olympiad (556–460 B.C.). Grysar places his birth in the 60th Olympiad (540 B.C.), Lorenz, Ol. 60–62. All that we know with certainty is that he died shortly after Hiero, and therefore shortly after the year 467 B.C., at an advanced age. His age at his death was, according to Lucian (Macrob. 25), 97; according WOL. I. Of the four passages which he quotes," to Diog. viii. 78,90. Born at Cos, he came while still a child to Me- gara in Sicily. The last half of his life was passed at Syracuse. * Diog, viii. 78, calls him even a disciple of Pythagoras. Plut. Numa, 8; Clem. Strom. v. 597 C, at any rate, call him simply a Pytha- gorean. According to Rambl. V. P. 265, he belonged to the exoteric school. Schmidt, Op. C. p. 935, justly censures Ilorenz, pp. 44–52, for giving unhesitating credence to the statement of Diogenes. * Cf. Diog. l. c. : oiros ūrog- vàuata karaxéAoûrev čv ois pugio- Ao’ye”, yyapoxoyeſ, iaTpoxo'yeſ, and dazu Welcker, p. 347 sq. * Concerning Alcimus, vide the index to this work, p. 3. * On the authenticity, text and interpretation, vide the dissertation IM M \ * * 530 THE PM THAGOREA.N.S. the first" says that the gods are eternal, since the first being, had it become, must have arisen out of nothing; and that men are subject to continual change, and never remain the same.” Another passage says: As the art is something other than the artist, and as man only becomes an artist through learning the art, so the Good is something in itself (Ti Tpāypua kaff attö),” and man becomes good by learning it. The third con- cludes from the instinct of animals that all living creatures possess reason.* The fourth observes that each creature delights most in itself; as man regards man as the most beautiful, so does the dog regard the dog, and the ox the ox, &c. These sayings certainly give evidence of a thinker, but they do not prove that the thoughts of the poet had their centre in any philo- sophic principle. Still less can we infer from them that this principle was that of the Pythagoreans; the remark about the eternity of the gods reminds us more of Xenophanes, to whose verses the fourth quotation also of Schmidt, Gött. Anz. 1865, 940 sq.; Lorenz, 106 sq.; Bernays in Rhein. Mus. viii. 1853, 280 sq.; Steinhart (Plato's Leben, 13 sq., 264 sq.) says that the two first passages are , certainly spurious, that the third is perhaps authentic, and the fourth undoubtedly so. 1 A dialogue in which one of the interlocutors represents the Bleatic point of view, the other that of Heracleitus. 2 Plato is perhaps thinking of this passage; at any rate he is thinking of the opinion expressed in it, when. in Theaet. 152 E, he places Epicharmus among those who maintain that there is no Being, but only Becoming. It is in the same text that Chrysippus (ap. Plut. Comm. notif. 44, p. 1083) finds the A6 yos añavópºevos. * The conjecture of Schmidt (Qu. Epich. 49 sq.), according to which the verse containing this proposition should be rejected, seems to me unnecessary; it is not connected, any more than the others, with the theory of Ideas; the word trpayua is employed in the same sense as by Plato, Prof. 330 C sq.; 349 B. * What Lorenz, p. 106, sees in this passage is not to be found there. JEPICHARMUS. 531 bears a striking analogy." What is said about the vicissitude to which man is subject, alludes no doubt to the doctrine of Heracleitus,” from whom the theorem that the character of man is his damom” may likewise have been borrowed. The utterances of this poet con- cerning the state after death, on the other hand, indicate Pythagorean influence ; the body, he says, returns to the earth, and the spirit to heaven; * a pious life is man’s best preparation for the journey: * the proposition about the reason of animals in the third of the above quotations may have a like origin. All that we can further gather in regard to Epicharmus either has no * Cf. infra, notes 4 and 6 on Xenophanes. That Epicharmus was acquainted with Xenophanes is proved by the passage of Arist. Metaph. iv. 5, 1010 a, 5 (after enumeration of the philosophers, who confound the sensible phe- nomenon with truth): Öto eikóra’s gºv Aéryovoiv oik &Am07, 6& Aéyovoiv. ošra, yāp &pgårtet gåAAov siteſv, % $ortrep 'Ettzapºos eis Eevoq'dumv. ërt 5& traorav Špávres raútmv ſci- vovuévny thv påortv, &c. What Epicharmus wrote about Xeno- phanes we cannot discover from this passage. The most natural conjecture is that he said of some opinion of this philosopher, that it might indeed be true, but that it was not probable. We have no reason to suppose from the passage that he wrote against Xenophanes; still less to conclude, with Lorenz, p. 122 sq., that Xenophanes attri- buted a certain value to the percep- tions of sense, and, for that reason, was attacked by Epicharmus. Our text contains nothing of the sort. As to the awbitrary conjecture of Karsten (Xenoph. Rell. 186 sq., endorsed by Polman-Kruseman, Epicharmi Fragm. 118): ošta, ye āppºrtet uáAAov eirely, } ãotrep 'Etréxapºos h Eévoq'. eitrov, Trägay ôpôvres, &c., it is contrary to the sense and to the context (cf. 1. 10 sq.), and is rightly rejected by Schwegler (adh. l.). * Cf. p. 529, 5, and Bernays, doc. cit. * Ap. Stob. Floril. 37, 16: 3 Tpótos évôpárotori Satuov &ya08s, ois à Kal kakós. Cf. Heraclit. Fr. 57. Schleierm.: #60s yap &v6párq, §aſuav. & * Fragm, inc. 23, from Clem. Strom. iv. 541 C: eige6}s row vojv trequk&s oi ré6ous y ot,8&v kakov karðavöv čva, to Tveijua Stauévet kar’ oioavóv. Fr. 35 ap. Plut. Consol. ad Apoll. 15, p. 110: kaxós oëv 6 'Emixapuos, ovvekpt0m, p.mal kal Stekotóm ical &mix9ev 89ey #x0e TáAlv, Yā uèv eis Yāv, Tveijua 5’ āva" rí távöe XaAeróv; oióē gy. * Fr. 46 in Boissonade Anecd. i. 125: eigeºis 8tos uéyarov eq6- Stov 6pmroſs Švi. M. M. 2 532 THE PPTHAGOREAWS. definite philosophic character," or else leaves us in uncertainty whether it emanates at all from him,” or was meant to express his own personal opinion.” On the whole we can clearly see that while Epicharmus was no stranger to the philosophy of his time, he was * E.g. Fr. 24 in Clem. Strom. v. 597 C : oëbèv éicqeives to 6etov rooro yiv6orkelv ore be? airbs orð’ &uáv Štróttas' &övvareſ 5’ obôºv 9eós. Fr. 25 (ibid. vii. 714 A); ka9apov &v row votiv čxms ārav to orópa Kabapos ei. Cf. the similar passage from an anonymous poet ap. Clem. Strom. iv. 531 C: to 0. pºl Aoutpá &AA& v64 kaðapós; the passage so often quoted, vows Śpé ical vows &kovſet TáNAa Koºpó Ical a vºxd (vide Polman-Kruseman, l.c. 82 sq.), which certainly contains nothing contradictory to the ot;\os ôpá, &c., of Xenophanes, as Welcker supposes l. c. p. 353; the famous saying: oiàels ēköv trovmpès (ibid. p. 10 sq., cf. Arist. Eth. N. iii. 7, ill 3 b, 14; Plato, Tim. 86 D), which, moreover (cf. p. 116, 1), really signifies that no one is volun- tarily miserable; lastly, the asser- tion that Epicharmus called the stars and the elements gods (Me- nander ap. Stob. Floril. 91, 29). * This holds good especially of the verses cited ap. Clem. Strom. v. 605 A, on the human and divine A6)0s. For, according to Aristox. ap. Athen. xiv. 648 d, the work from which these verses are taken, the Polity, was foisted upon Epicharmus by a certain Chryso- gonus; and Schmidt, Qu. Epicharm. 17, confirms this assertion on metrical grounds. It is probable that the commencement only of the work belongs to Chrysogonus, where we find Pythagorean ideas, 6 Blos &v6párois Aoytoplot kāo.6400 betral tróvv, etc., the rest, on the contrary, from the words, si èrt’ &v6pétrº Aoytopads, £ati kal 6eios Aóryos, looks very like a Jewish or Alexandrian Christian interpola- tion. The statement according to which (Vitruv. De Archit. viii. pref. 1) Epicharmus held that there were four elements, as Empedocles did, is evidently based upon an ac- cidental juxtaposition, such as we find elsewhere (e.g. in AEschylus, Prometh. 88 sq.). This is not enough to justify our attributing to Epicharmus the idea of the ele- ments as conceived by Empedocles. I know not what can have given rise to Lorenz's assertion that the fragments of the Epicharmus of Ennius must be reckoned among the most interesting writings that remain to us of this Epicharmus. * For example, the doctrine of the flux of all things, professed by Heracleitus, is humorously inter- preted by this poet to mean (as shown by Bernays, l.c. 286, from |Plut. De s. mum. wind. c. 15, p. 559) that a man need not pay his debts because he is not the identical person who incurred them. It is perhaps the same with the passage in Cic. Tusc. i. 8, 15 : Emori molo sed me esse mortuwm mihil astimo (Sext. Math. i. 273, has incorrectly, no doubt, &toflavéiv h rebvávat oùuot Stapépet). This last propo- sition, at any rate, seems to accord very ill with the Pythagorean be- lief in immortality. Welcker, l.c. 304 sq., well remarks (and Grono- TREATISE ON MELISSUS, ETC. 533 yet no exclusive adherent of any school,' but freely appropriated from the opinions of his contemporaries whatever seemed to him worthy of consideration. T H E E L E A TIC S. I. SOURCES. THE TREATISE ON MELISSUS, AENOPHANES, AND GORGIAS. THE works of the Eleatic philosophers have only been handed down to us in isolated fragments.” Beside these, the statements of Aristotle are our principal source of information in regard to their doctrines. Then come the supplementary accounts of more recent authors, among whom Simplicius, through his personal know- ledge of the Eleatic writings, and his careful employ- ment of ancient authorities, ranks first. Full of lacunae as all these sources are, they yet contain too much ; and this superabundance has, at least in respect to the founder of the school, been more prejudicial to a correct estimate of the Eleatic doctrines than the scarcity of original documents. We possess a treatise,” under the vius and Lobeck agree) that the stars, wind, &c., are called gods by Epicharmus, not in his own name, but when he is expounding the Persian religion. * Perhaps this is the reason why Iambl., V. P. 266, reckons him among the exoteric members of the school ; but it may also be because later writers found him deficient in what they considered true Py- thagoreanism. * Those of Xenophanes, Parme- nides, and Melissus have been col- lected and annotated by Brandis (Comment. Eleat.); those of Xeno- phanes and Parmenides by Kar- sten, Philosophorum Graec. Reliq. They are given with a short com- mentary by Mullach in his edi- tion of the treatise, De Melisso, etc.; and in the Fragm. Philos. Gr. i. 99 Sqq.; 259 sqq. * According to the usual title, De Xenophane, Zenone et Gorgia; Mullach in his edition, repeated Fragm. i. 271 sqq., substitutes for this, De Melisso, Xenophane et Gorgia. On the text, authenticity, and contents of this work, cf. F. 534 THE ELEATICS. name of Aristotle, which expounds and criticises the doctrines of two Eleatic philosophers, and the similar arguments of Gorgias. But who these two philoso- phers are, and what is the historical value of the trea- tise, there is no certain evidence to show. The greater number of texts give the title of the work thus: “Con- cerning Xenophanes, Zeno and Gorgias.” Others have only the more general title, ‘Concerning the opinions,' or ‘Concerning the opinions of the philosophers. Of the particular divisions of this work, the first section (c. 1, 2) is usually thought to relate to Xenophanes; but in some of the manuscripts, and especially in the Leipzig Codex, which is the best, to Zeno; while the second section (c. 3, 4), to which the name of Zeno is most frequently attached, is referred by the same authorities to Xenophanes." There can be no doubt, however, that the first section treats neither of Xeno- phanes nor of Zeno, but of Melissus. This is clearly asserted” in the work itself, and the contents are of subh a nature that they can relate to no other person. For as we learn from the express testimony of Aris- totle,” it was Melissus who first maintained the un- limitedness of the One Being (c. i. 974 a, 9), whereas Kern : Quapstionum Xenophanearum capita duo. Naumb. 1864. Symbolæ critica ad libell. Arisiot. T. Eevoºp. etc., Oldenb. 1867. Osoſppdatov tr. Mexigorov Philologus, vol. xxvi. 271 sqq.; Beitrag 2. Darst, d. Philoso- phie d. Xenoph. Danzig, 1871. Ueber 2 enophanes v. Kol. Stettin, 1874. Cf. the proofs in Bekker and Mullach. - 3. * C 4, 977 b, 21 ; cf. c 1, sub init. and 974 b, 20, c. 2, 975 a, 21 ; c. 6, 979 b, 21 ; cf. c. 1, 974 a, 11 b, 8. In c. 2, 976 a, 32 a. clear distinction is drawn between the philosopher whose doctrine had been expounded in the chapter, and Xenophanes; and c. 5, 979 a, 22 presupposes that Melissus has pre- viously been spoken of. * Metaph. i. 5, 986 b, 18; cf. Phys, iii. 5, 207 a, 15. TREATISE ON MELISSUS, ETC. 535 Xenophanes gave no opinion on this question, and the reasons which are here, according to the ordinary theory, placed in the mouth either of Xenophanes or Zeno, belong, according to the undoubtedly authentic state- ments of Aristotle, and the fragments of Melissus which Simplicius has preserved, to Melissus." For the rest, this harmony with ancient testimony serves to ratify the contents of this chapter, if we connect it with Melissus; and there seems no alternative in that case but to suppose a wrong title. In the second section, on the contrary, not only the person to whom it relates, but also the credibility of the contents, is questionable. The various texts, as we have seen, connect it some- times with Zeno,” sometimes with Xenophanes. * As has been shown by Bran- dis (Comment. Eleat. 186 sqq., 200 sq.; Gr. Röm. Philos. i. 398 sqq.), and previously by Spalding (Vindi- cite Philosoph. Megaricorum Sub- jecto Commentario in priorem parti libelli de Xenoph. Zenone, et Gorgia, Berlin, 1793). Our discussion on Melissus later on will also make it clear. Röth, Geschicht. d. Abendl. Phil. ii. b, 28, sees not the smallest reason to refer c. 1 sq. to Melissus. This was to be expected, since he (ibid. a, 186) contemptuously dis- misses all doubt as to the authen- ticity of the work; but it does not alter the state of the case. His detailed examination of Xeno- phanes also (l.c. a, 174–242 b, 22– 42) contains scarcely anything which is either not already known, or which is tenable. His chief dis- covery (a, 188, 216, &c.) that Xenophanes developed his opinions in persistent opposition to those of Anaximander, and formed his The theory of God especially, with con stant reference to Anaximander's ‘viereinigen’ conception of God— apart from its want of any histori- cal foundation—is inadmissible, since it starts from wholly arbi- trary and wrong notions of Anaxi- mander. We cannot, however, hope for much aid in the comprehension of the writing attributed to Aris- totle, from a commentary which can so deal with its text, as to find (p. 208) in the proposition that ‘nothing is nowhere’ (that is, in no space) the identity of infinite space with nothing. * In the chapter on Gorgias (c. 5, 979, a, 21) we read: āti oilk ëorrup otte èv oëre troXA&, oùre &yévvmta otte yevöueva, tº uév &s MéAlagos r& 5’ &s Zīva v čtrixelpe? ôelkview weró. Thu tätov attoo &tró- 6etćiv, etc.; c. 6, 979 b, 25: p.m- 6apoi, 5è by oiâèv eival (sc. Topyías Aapóðvel) kata tou Zhuovos Aóyov trepi Tàs x&pas; ibid. line 36, ac- 536 THE EI.E.A.TICS. ty author himself subsequently alludes to communications concerning Zeno, which we might suppose to be con- tained in the third chapter : but his allusions are much more explicable on the theory that a part of the work which is now lost related to Zeno; and this would agree with the fact that in the chapter before us Zeno is brought forward in a manner that would be im- possible' if the context directly treated of him. cording to Mullach's continuation : Tö yöp &Gróaaróv, pnotiv, où6év, #xau yvápmy trapatama tav Tó row Zīva wos Aóryº. That other demonstrations of Zeno are here meant, which are not spoken of in our treatise, I cannot believe. With what right could the author assume in readers who had been first instructed by himself concerning the opinions of Melissus and Xenophanes—such intimate acquaintance with the doctrines of Zeno, that he might thus refer to them, as to something they knew perfectly well ? Were there no better solution, I should prefer to admit the possibility (as in the first editions of this work) that these allusions refer to passa- ges in the second section, and, therefore, not to Xenophanes but to Zeno. The passage from c. 5 would then (with c. 1, 974 a, 2, 11) have to be referred to c. 3, where the unity and eternity of God are proved. Our author indeed says that Gorgias partly follows Zeno and partly Melissus, in proving that Being is neither one nor many, neither become nor unbecome. But this is no obstacle ; for neither Zeno nor Melissus can have ad- vanced arguments against the unity and eternity of Being. Gorgias, therefore, could only have employed their demonstrations in Ought support of the thesis that Being is not a Plurality and not become; not to prove that Being is not a Unity and not underived. Conse- quently if even the words of our author assert the latter doctrine, he must certainly be expressing his meaning inaccurately. (The objec- tion of Kern, Qu. Xen. 42 to this opinion is irrelevant, and is directed against an interpretation of the passage for which I am not respon- sible.) The passages from c. 6 might be referred to c. 3, 977 b, 13: To yap wº) by oiöapu?, sivat ; these words, however, would not be sufficient to explain the allu- Sions, even if we call to our assist- ance the fundamental proposition (ibid. l. 5): oiov to whov oik &v sival Tö jv. It seems to me more likely that the passages cited from c. 5 sq. allude to a lost portion of this work, which treated of Zeno. Perhaps c. 2, 976 a, 25, also refers to this lost portion. In Diog. v. 25, a book, trpès rê Zīvovos, is actu- ally mentioned among the writings of Aristotle, together with the trea— tises on Melissus, Gorgias and Xe- nophanes. * In his criticism (c. 4, 978 b, 37) of the opinions expounded in c. 3, the reply which the author makes to the assertion (977 b, 11 sqq.) that the Deity cannot move, TREATISE ON MELISSUS, ETC. 537 we then to infer that the author is alluding in this sec- tion, not to Zeno, but to Xenophanes? In that case it is somewhat strange that in an exposition of the Eleatic doctrine the founder of the school should occupy a place between Melissus and Gorgias. This, however, may be explained on the hypothesis that the order in which the writer discusses the Eleatic philosophers is regu- lated, not according to their historical connection, but because all motion presupposes a plurality of things, of which one moves into the other (i.e. the place of the other), is as follows. The Deity also could move into another oãauðs yöp Aéyet är i čv ſuávov (so Yern, Quast. 35, completes the text), &AA’ 3rt eſs uévos 6ebs ei Šč kal airbs (instead of this we should probably read with Bergk, De Arist. lib. de Xen. Zen. et Gorg. Marb. 1843, p. 36 sq.) si èë kal u% airbs, if even he himself dots not move into another—other conjectural reading, in Kern, l.c. Tí kwxWei eis &AAmAa kivovuévov ráv wepôv toº . . . kū- KAq, pe . . . 6eov (here might be read : T. u. Tod travros [or roß ãAov] kūkaq, pépeo 6al Tov 0eóv. FCern, on account of Felician's translation, quid vetat partes omitia ambientis Dei in Sese mutuo moveri, conjectures: T. p. rob travra trepié- Xovtos 6800; but this translation, if it be literal, would necessitate a great alteration in the text; if it be not so, ambientis may be refer- red to the KökAq, which is not otherwise translated) of y&p 6% to Totoorov, the év čotrep & Zhvav troAA& eival phael. (So in Cod. Lips. and elsewhere, the Vulgata is q)`joret) airbs yúp orópa sival Aéo et Tov 6eóv, etc. In the second edition of this work I objected to the words, $grep & Zhvav, because the asser- tion that the one would become a multiplicity if it changed its place (and this assertion can alone be in question here: the rotoorov čv would be the kūkāq, pepópevos 6eós) is to be found in the extract from Melissus, c. 1, 974 a, 18 sqq., and is nowhere (not even ap. Themist. Phys. 18 o, p. 122 Sp.) attributed to Zeno. I conjectured, therefore, that àortrep ought to be rejected; or MéAtooros substituted for Zhvav ; or still more probably, as it seemed to me, that the words āoritep 6 Zīvov, which certainly relate to an earlier passage of the book, had been added by the person who re- ferred c. I to Zeno. If, however, the work originally contained a discussion on Zeno (vide previous note), the conjecture is superfluous. The words would then relate to that discussion. The particular meaning of the words is immaterial in regard to the present enquiry. Meantime I see no reason to aban- don my former explanation, ac- cording to which the words oë 7&p, etc., assert the following: ‘for our adversary cannot object, like Zeno, that such a One revolving in a circle would not be One at all (more cor- rectly is not, for there is no àv be- fore sival), for he himself calls the Deity spherical.’ 538 THE ELEATICS. from a dogmatic point of view. Just as in a famous passage of the Metaphysics, Aristotle mentions Par- menides first, then Melissus, and after them Xeno- phanes; so, in this work, the author deals first with those Eleatics who maintain that Being is limited—viz., Zeno, and no doubt Parmenides; * next with Melissus, who also maintains that it is unlimited; next with Xenophanes, who says that it is neither limited nor un- limited; and, lastly, with Gorgias, who not only denies that Being is cognisable, but also denies Being itself. But if this destroys the theory that Zeno is the philosopher indicated in the third chapter,” still less can we discover in the exposition any accurate account of his doctrines." The philosopher here mentioned is represented as having denied Becoming and Multiplicity, “ in reference to the Divinity,’” and he is accordingly made to develope the * Wide infra, p. 547, 1. * Philoponus, Phys. B, 9, is the only authority who says that there existed a treatise on Parmenides attributed to Aristotle: pag i ö& Kal ºyeydq6al airó ibíg 8138tov trpós Tºv IIappevičov 66&av. The statement, however, has much in its favour, as it is scarcely credible that any one who treated of the Eleatics would pass over Parmenides. If we accept it as true, we might refer c. 2, 976 a., 5 ; c. 4,978 b, 8 of our treatise to this portion of the work. Only it must have been lost at a very early period, for it is not men- tioned in the catalogue of Diogenes. 3 Cf. Fries. Gesch. d. Phºl. i. 157 sq. 167; Marbach, Gesch. d. Phil. i. 145 sq.; Schleiermacher, Gesch. d. Phil. 61 sq.; Ueberweg, vide next note, and see also the first edition of the present work. * This is presupposed by Fries and Marbach. Schleiermacher l.c. says more cautiously that we have here the opinions of Zeno ex- pressed in the language of Xeno- phanes, and that the whole is merely patched together. More recently Ueberweg, Ueber d, histor. Werth der Schrift De Melisso, &c. (Philologus, viii. 104 sqq.) tried to establish the above-named theory more firmly. Eventually, however, he altered his opinion on the sub- ject, and declared that the author was probably treating of Xeno- phanes, but gave no trustworthy 1nformation either of him or of Zeno (Grundriss, i. section 17). As he expressly alludes to my counter-remarks, I cannot well omit them in the present edition. * Tooro Aéyov ćirl roß 6eoû, c. 3, Sub init. TREATISE ON MELISSUS, ETC. 539 proof of his assertion primarily in relation to this alone, although his reasons for the most part admit of a more general application. No such restriction of Zeno's doc- trimes is recognised by any of the ancient accounts: they all agree that Zeno, like Parmenides, denied Be- coming and Multiplicity in general. Xenophanes alone, as we shall see, connected his whole polemic against the ordinary point of view with the theological question; whereas, with the exception of what we find in the treatise we are considering, not a single theological pro- position has been handed down to us as Zemo's. Al- though, therefore, it is quite conceivable that Zeno may have called the One Being also God, yet it is not probable that in his demonstration he limited himself to proving that the Deity is eternal, sole, &c. On the contrary, what he aimed at was to show generally that Plurality and Becoming are nowhere possible." Our text consequently maintains, in respect of the Eleatic philosopher it discusses, that which could only be said of Xenophanes; and the further development of his propositions is connected with Xenophanes in a manner which we cannot assume in the case of Zeno.” It is * As Plato says, Parm. 127 C Fr. 4 (according to Karsten's S amendments): aiel 5' év tatt & Te Q. * In the passage De Mel. c. 3, 977 a, 36, we find this statement: éva 3’ &vra [Tov 9ebv) &Motov sival tdvt m, Öpáv Te Kai &kočev tás Te &AAas aio.6%iorets #xovra travrm, a manifest imitation of Xenophanes (Fr. 2): of Aos épé, of Aos 3& voeſ, očAos 6é T' &kočei. Cf. p. 454, 2; 457, 3; 3rd ed. ; also,977 b, ll: The Deity is not moved, kiveiròat 8& rà. traeto èvra évos, Tepov, yāp eis érepov čeſv kweto 6ai. Cf. Xenoph. prevew kivoguevov oièëv oběč uétép- xeo (at utv étutpéret &AAore &AA). Further, what relates to the proof of the unity of God, 977 a, 23 sqq., is quite in accordance with what Plut. (ap. Eus. Pr. Ev. i. 8, 5) says of Xenophanes: ätro- qatveral 3& kal trepi 6eóvá's oièepuās h'yeptovías €v airgi's oiſorms of y&p ãotov Šeatrógeq 0aí riva Bečv, for Xenophanes could only draw from it the conclusion he did, on the 540 THE ELEATICS. true that Parmenides and Melissus attribute to Being the same unity, uniformity, and immobility, that Xenophanes does to God. But the fact that they attri- bute these qualities not to God, but to Being, shows most clearly how great was the advance from Xeno- phanes to Parmenides. There is no doubt that Zeno strictly adhered to the doctrine of Parmenides. That he should have abandoned the metaphysical view of the fundamental doctrine of the Eleatics, wherein the chief merit of Parmenides consists, and should have gone back to the more imperfect theological view, is not probable. But the manner in which the Deity is here spoken of is no less surprising. It is described as neither limited nor unlimited, neither moved nor unmoved; but although it is without limit, it is said to be spherical in form. How is this possible? In his critique of ordinary opinion, Zeno regards as a sufficient proof of its falsity the fact that it attributes opposite predicates to the same things at the same time." Is it likely then that he himself would have attributed such mutually ex- clusive predicates to the Deity ? Ueberweg thinks that he did not intend to attribute them, but to deny them, in order thus to exalt the Deity above the whole sphere of extension and temporality.” But this inten- supposition that he did not hold a plurality of gods. That the Deity is underived, was also first declared by Xenophanes. Lastly, the state- ment that the Deity is neither limited nor unlimited, neither moved nor unmoved, must be re- garded as a misapprehension of the utterances of Aristotle, and of Theophrastus concerning Xeno- phanes; it must, however, be con- nected with Xenophanes and not with Zeno, who, as far as we know, gave no opening for such a state- ment. * Plato, loc. cit., other authori- ties will be cited infra. * Similarly, on the supposition that we have here a true report of Xenophanes, cf. Kern, Qu. Xen. TREATISE ON MELISSUS, ETC. 541 tion is so little shown by our Eleatic philosopher, that he expressly describes the Deity as globe-shaped; the historical Zeno, moreover, denies all reality to that which is not extended." It is incredible that Zeno should have maintained these theories of his master, if the idea of God being uncontained in space were admitted by him; and still more incredible is it that so acute a thinker should have believed in the spherical form, while he denied the limitation of the Deity. Internal contradictions can be discovered in Zeno as in other philosophers, but they can be recognised as contradictions only by means of inferences which he did not himself draw. There is no example in his doctrines of so palpable and direct a combination of what is contradictory, as this work imputes to him.” Nor is this work a trustworthy authority for the doctrines of Xenophanes. A guarantee for the authen- ticity of its exposition is indeed supposed” to be found 11 sqq. But Kern has since (Beitrag, 17) considerably modified this opinion. Wide infra, p. 548, 1. 1. Cf. the following note. Fur- ther details in the chapter on Zeno. * Ueberweg says that Zeno, according to Themist. Phys. 18 a (122 sq.), and Simpl. Phys, 30 a. declared the Real to be indivisible and extended, and yet, according to Arist. Metaph. iii. 4, 1001 b, 7, maintained that the One could not be indivisible, for if it were so, it would not be a quantity, and con- sequently would be nothing. But Aristotle does not say that Zeno actually asserted this ; he only says that from the presupposition of Zeno, “that which, being added to another, does not increase that other, and being taken from another, does not make that other less, is nothing;' it would follow that the One must be a quantity, and therefore not indivisible. This is undoubtedly the meaning of the Aristotelian passage, as is clear not only from the words themselves, but from what Simplicius adduces, l. c. p. 21. The expression quoted by Themistins would be irrelevant here, for it relates to the many and not to the One. Cf. p. 498, 1, 3rd ed. * This holds good of the ancient writers without exception; also of Steinhart, Pl. W. W. iii. 394, 10, and Mullach, Praef. xiv. (Fragm. Philos. Gr. i. 271 sqq., where the Praefatio of the year 1845 is 542 THE ELEATIOS. in Theophrastus, from whom the similar statements of Simplicius and Bessarion as to Xenophanes are said to be borrowed. But this theory is very improbable. Bessarion was unmistakeably quoting, not from some writing of Theophrastus now lost, but solely and entirely from the passage in Simplicius’ Physics, in which that commentator, appealing to Theophrastus, expounds the doctrine of Xenophanes in harmony with the third chapter of our treatise.” Simplicius, however, is not indebted to Theophrastus for all that he says about printed without alteration), though he doubts the authenticity and entire credibility of this treatise. IKern, Beitr. 2; Xenoph. 8; cf. Qu. Aon. 48 sq., derives the statement of Simplicius from the Physics of Theophrastus, and accounts for its similarity with our writing, by conjecturing the latter to have been a sketch of Theophrastus, which he himself used for that particular passage in the Physics. 1 C. Calumniat, Plat. ii. 11, p. 32 b (printed in Brandis, Comm. El. 17 sq.; Mullach, p. xi. of his separate edition, i. 274 Fragmenta; Hern. Qu. 44 sq.): [Theophrastus] Memophanem, quem Parmenides au- divit aſque secutus est, nequaquam inter physicos numerandum sedalio loco constituendum censet. Nomine, inquit, unius et universi Deum Aºnophanes appellavit, quod unum ingenium-immobile aeternum dirit; ad haec, aliquo quidem mode, neque #nfinitum megue finitum, alto vero modo etiam finitum, tum etiam con- globatum, diversa. Scilicet motitiae ratione, mentem etiam universum hoc idem esse affirmavit. t 2 Kern, Qu. Xen. 44 sqq. (in agreement with Brandis, l, c., Kar- sten, Xenoph. Rell. 107, and others), has indeed sought to prove the contrary, in opposition to Krische, Forsch. 92 sq., and myself; but he has now withdrawn this opinion (Beitr. 6 Ann.). Bessarion's ac- count of Xenophanes really con- tains nothing that might not have been taken from Simplicius, only that Bessarion seems to have been careless in the use of his authority. Even what he adds immediately after the words quoted above can only have come from Simplicius (l. c. and p. 7 b, 15 b), though he reproduces his statements very in- accurately when he says: Nee vero Theophrastus solus haec dia'if; sed Nicolaus quoque Damascenus et Alexander Aphrodisiensis eaden de A'enophane referunt (for the real state of the case, cf. p. 549, 1), opusque Melissi de ente et natura inscriptum dicunt (this is said only by Simplicius, 15 b). Parmenidis de veritate et opinatione (this is said neither by Simplicius, nor the others; but Simplicius does say, 7, 6: Metex8&v . . . 6 IIappevſöms . &to &Amfleias, Ös airós (pmoiv, éri 865&v). In the same way as Rern has already shown, Qu. 47, the foregoing is merely a repro- duction of Simpl. Phys, 7. TREATISE ON MELISSUS, ETC, 543 Xenophanes, but only for an introductory remark, which tells us nothing more than we find in Aristotle's Meta- physics." * His words are, Phys. 5 b: wſaw ös thy &px?iv firot ev to by Ical Tràu, kal otre retrepaguévov otte &trepov, oùre kivotſuevov otte hpe- padv, Eevoſpávmu Töv KoMoq6vtov Tov IIappevíðou StădakaAov Štrotíðeorðaſ qmoriy 6 0eóqpao ros, ÖpioWoryöv čté- pas sival uáAAov 3) Tâs trepi pāorea's iorropſas Thy pºvhumv ràs toūtov 66öms. These words may easily be taken to mean nothing more than what Aristotle says, Metaph. i. 5, 986 b, 21 : Xenophanes never an- nounced whether he conceived the One primitive essence as limited or unlimited ; Theophrastus adds that he also never explained whether he conceived it as at rest or in motion. Nothing obliges us to conclude from these statements that Xeno- phanes expressly taught that the One was neither limited nor un- limited, neither at rest nor in motion. This is certainly asserted by the treatise, De Melisso. Sim- plicius, in putting the statement of Theophrastus into the third person, may have condensed it or altered it : this is not at all un- likely. But even supposing Theo- phrastus really to have written, atav 8& Thu &px?iv . . . hpeuotiv E. 6 Koxopóvios é IIappeviñov Štědaka- Aos ūtrott0etal. I do not see what hinders us from translating it thus: “Yenophanes regards the principle as One, i.e. he regards the totality of Being as One; and neither as something limited nor unlimited, neither as something moved nor unmoved.” The objec- tion of Kern, Qw. x.50; Beitr. 4, 6 : that because the verbal conception is not denied it must be explained The rest he brings forward in his own name, thus: ‘He considers the 8v Ical trav as neither limited nor unlimited, I confess I do not understand. In the sentence, oùre tretrepaguévov offre &repov in ottòeral, the nega- tion may as well refer to the firo- Tíðetal as to the retrepagu. and the &repov; it may either mean, He conceives it neither as limited nor unlimited; ' or, ‘he conceives it as neither limited nor unlimited.' It must mean the former, unless Theo- phrastus is to contradict the state- ment of Aristotle (vide p. 547, 1). This is highly improbable, for Theophrastus, in the very chapter on Physics from which our frag- ment is taken, is in close agree- ment with the first book of Aristotle's Metaphysics. Wide his observations on Parmenides and Anaxagoras (infra, § Parm., and Sup?'a, p. 233, 1), compared with Arist. Metaph. i. 5, 986 b, 18 sqq.; c. 8, 989 a, 30 sqq., and his Fr. 48 (ap. Simpl. Phys. 6 b); cf. Arist. Metaph. i. 6 sub init. It cannot be urged that, because Xenophanes (in Fr. 4, quoted p. 539, 2), de- clared God to be unmoved, he never could have been said to have withheld his opinion as to the movement of the Śv kal trav. Xeno- phanes, in Fr. 4, is combating the mythical notions about the wander- ings of the gods, such as those of Zeus and Poseidon to AEthiopia, and maintains as his opinion that the Deity remains unmoved, év Taütó; whether the world, the ºv kal trav is also unmoved, he does not say. It appears from other accounts, however, that he was far from denying movement to the 544 THE ELEATICS. without saying whence he derives it; but his mode of expression shows” that it was not from the same source (namely, the Physics of Theophrastus) as the more general quotation. world, and consequently we have no right to apply to the world what he says of God (l.c.). If it be so applied, however, Kern's explanation of the passage in Theophrastus is excluded as well as mine. For, if Xenophanes had said that the trav remained un- moved, and for ever in the same place, or in other words, that it was not moved, but at rest ; in that case no one could have said that Xenophanes declared it to be neither unmoved nor at rest. g Simplicius proceeds immedi- ately after 66;ms, with the direct narration, to Yap *w toºto ſcal trów, &c. p. 475. Although it does not follow that that which comes next cannot have been borrowed from Theophrastus, it is, the more cer- tain, that the exposition of Simpl. does not justify usin asserting that it was borrowed from him. 2 It clearly results from the ad- dition, Öpoxoyöv, &c. (p. 541, 3), that the previous citation is taken from Theophrastus, qvourh ia topia, which, we know from other sources, contained mention of Xenophanes and Parmenides, and of most of the ancient philosophers, vide Diog. ix. 22; Stob. Ecl. i. 522; Alex. Aphr. in Metaph. i. 3, 984 b, 1, p. 24 Bon; Simpl. Phys. 25 a, etc.; in this treatise, however, ac- cording to his own declaration, Theophrastus cannot have spoken very fully of Xenophanes, Kern (Bär. 3) says that Theophrastus may have had a reason for his criticism, and subsequent Omission The source, it is evident from of the philosophy of Xenophanes in his Physics in his having given a short exposition of it to his readers. But such a procedure seems to me improbable, and the analogies which Kern (l. c.) adduces from Aristotle, irrelevant. It may be thought (Brandis, Comm. El. 17; Rern, Quast. 00; Beitr. 2) that Simplicius would have said the same, even if his further state- ments had not been founded upon Theophrastus. But it might rather be expected that he would some- where have indicated it, if he had found the same in Theophrastus. He only says, however, that Theo- phrastus in his Physics declined the discussion of Xenophanes' philosophy. Kern thinks that the agreement of the account of Xeno- phanes (to Yap ev, etc.), with the words previously quoted from Theo- phrastus, is incomprehensible if this account be not taken from Theophrastus. But the question is whether the words are to be understood in the same sense as this account. Kern lastly remarks: Simplicius not only names Theo- phrastus before the discussion con- cerning Xenophanes; but he names Nicolaus and Alexander after it. I know not what this re- mark is intended to show. He names his sources where he intends to support his opinion upon their evidence. But it does not follow that he supports his opinion on their evidence when he does not mention them. TREATISE ON MELISSUS, ETC. 545 the similarity both of the ideas and the language in the two expositions, can be 1. Cf. the two texts, Simpl.: To 'yūp #v Toºro kal trav row 6eov čAeyev ô Eevo pávns, 8v čva pºév Šetkvvaty ék Toi trčvrov kpóttarov eiwat TAeté- pov ydp, pnoſiv, Üvrov, Öpioios àváy- km intrópxelv Träori to kpateſv' to 6& trövtov kpáttoºrov kai &ptorov 66eós. &yevntov Šē éðeticvvev čk rot be?v to ºvywówevov h éé àpotov h éé àvouotov ºyſºyveg 6al &AA& To uév Šuotov &tra- 6és quoruv Štrb roo 6plotov oièëv y&p uāAAov yeuvâv 3 yevvaa flat trpooikei Tô 6potov čk row Śpotov. ei 6 &# &vo- *otov yi-yvouro, #otal to by éic too wh Övros. kal oitos &yévmtov Kal &íðtov čeſkvv. kal oire 68 &treupov oùre retrepaguévov eival: 5tóri &repov puév to u% ov, &s otte (uſite) &px?iv ëxov uſive uéorov white téaos, Tepal- weiv 8& irpos &AAm?\a rā traeto. And a little further on : &AA’ 3rt pºv otte &Teipov oëre retrepaguévov airo Set- icvvoriv, Čk Töv trposipmuévov 67Aov. "retrepaguévov 8& kal orgapoeiðès airb 61& to travrox60ev Šuotov Aéyet.) traparamoria's 5è kai civnow & pape? ical peptav' &cívntov prev Yap eival To uh Üv oire yūp eis atto èrepov, oùre airo trpos &AAo èA9etv' kiveto 9at 6é Tó, TAeta toû £vós' repov yūp eis *repov were 84AA iv. De Xenoph. c. 3: āśāvaróv pnoſiv eival, et Ti čott, 'yevéoréal, Totto Aéyav ćirl too 6600. . . . ei 3’ &otiv 66eos àtrávrav icpá- Two row ºva pnoſiv airby irpoofirely eival. ei yüp São h TAetous elev, oùic &v éri Kpdºria row kai 8éAtlatov airby eival tróvrov. čkaa tos yöp &v Töv troAAóv Šuotas &v totooros eim. Tooro y&p 6ebv Kal 6.e00 6twauiv eival, kparetv, &AA& un kpateto 6at, kai trčvrov kpátiatov sival, etc. &öövarov-6eoû (vide sup.) &váykm 7&p #To £3 6ſlotov h é; &vouotov ºyevé00ai to yiyväuevov. Övvarov Šč WOL. I. *g ſº gº no other than the work on où6érepov offre yap &pouov šq’ 6plotov trpoofikely Tekwoffival páñAov 7) re- Kvægat Taita yap &mavta roſs ye tools ical 6potots oix Stépxely trpos &AAmAa ott' àv é; ávouotov tává- uotov yevégéal. ei hºp yiyvouro €; ão 9eveotépou to ioxupérepov, etc. . . . to by éé oik Švros &vºyevéa 9am, 8trep &öövarov' &tauov pièv obv Ště. Taira eival Töv 6eóv. . . . tov 6° àvra kal éva kal orgapoeiðfjoir' &Teipov eival oite tretrepdv6at. &ret- pov učv to pººl by eival route yāp oire &px?iv oište uéorov oãre réAos oiſte §AAo uépos oióèv éxeiv . . ofov 8& To u}, by oik &v eival ºrb Šv. Trepaively 8& Tpos &AAmAa ei TAsia, elm . . . To 5% rotodrov by év . . . oùre kiveto 6al otre &Kívmtov sivat. &kivmtov učv yöp sival to ph v. ošte 'yūp eis airb érºpov, oùr' airb eis &AAo èA6eiv. Kiveto 6al 6&T& TAetw ãvra évés' repov yap eis repov beiv kiveto 6at, etc. This resemblance in the two accounts cannot be ex- plained by a common use of the work of Xenophanes (as Bergk well observes, Comment, de Arist. lib. de Xen. 6), for this work, being a poem, had quite another form. Our comparison will also show that there is absolutely nothing in the account of Simpli- cius which might not be regarded as an extract from the so-called Aristotelian writing. The order of the arguments is sometimes dif- ferent, and the expressions are once or twice altered——but that is of little consequence; and what Simplicius adds: śare kal &rav čv raité uévetv Aéym kai uh kiveforbal (aiel 5’ &v Taité te pléveuv, etc.) où karū rºv hpepfav thu ävruketué- vmy Tä kuſho'el uévely airów pmgiv, N N 546 THE ELEATICS. Melissus, &c., which we are considering. We need not therefore resort to the theory that Simplicius attributed this work to Theophrastus,' or that the work actually originated with this Peripatetic philosopher,” in order to explain his evidence.” etc., is not an extract, but his own reflection. But even if it be ad- mitted that Simplicius has been dependent upon the work concern- 1ng Melissus, there is not the least ground for making this direct de- pendence (Kern, vide sup. p. 541, 1) indirect by conjecturing, that Simplicius first made use of Theo- phrastus’ Physics, and that Theo- phrastus in his Physics made use of the treatise repl Mex. For, on the one hand, there is no proof of Simplicius having used the Physics of Theophrastus; indeed, the con- trary may be proved from his own words; and on the other hand, the agreement between his exposition and the treatise trepi MeN. is so complete, that it can only be fully explained on the supposition that Simplicius made direct use of that treatise, and we have no right to ignore this most obvious and simple theory in favour of some other that is more recondite and artificial. The contents of the treatise on Melissus we know; that Simplicius was acquainted with this treatise is beyond question; that it is adequate for the expla– nation of his account is obvious. When such a simple result is ob- tained by reckoning with known quantities, there can be no possi- ble inducement or justification for introducing such unknown and un- certain elements as the supposed exposition of Xenophanes in the Physics of Theophrastus, and the dependence of that exposition on His statements merely prove the treatise tr. Mextorolov —even if Theophrastus had not expressly declared that such an exposition did not belong to the Physics. And the same holds good against Teichmüller's theory (Stud. 2. Gesch. d. Begr. 593 sq.), that Sim- plicius had before him, besides the treatise tr. Mea. the same exposi. tion as the writer of that treatise— viz., an exposition of Xenophanes' doctrine, which was composed by some later Eleatic. His account contains nothing whatever that cannot be explained by his having used the Pseudo-Aristotelian book, and the verse of Xenophanes, though not word for word. We have, therefore, no right to seek out other sources, traces of which, had they existed, must somewhere have been evident in the work. * As is done by the Vatican IMS. * As Brandis (Gr. Röm. Phil. i. 158; iii. a, 291); Cousin (Fragm. Philos. i. 25, 7); and more deci- dedly Kern (sup. p. 544, 2) conjec- ture. In the Comment. El. 18, Brandis refuses to admit Aristotle's authorship of the work, yet he refers it only indirectly to Theophrastus. In the Gesch. d. Entw. d. Gr. Phil. i. 83, he allows the possibility of its having been written by some later Peripatetic. * The objection of Brandis (Comment. El. 18) that Simplicius would not have mentioned Theo- phrastus as his source and omitted the name of Aristotle, had he at- TREATISE ON MELISSUS, ETC. 547 that he was acquainted not only with the remark of Theophrastus in his Physics which he mentions, but also with the work on Melissus, &c., no matter under whose name it passed ; that he regarded this work as a genuine source of history, and that in his copy the third and fourth chapters referred to Xenophanes. This precedent, however, cannot, it is plain, furnish any criterion for us. The contents of the chapter do not agree with what we know on ancient authority re- specting Xenophanes. While Xenophanes himself de- clares the divinity to be unmoved," this work says it is neither moved nor unmoved; * tributed the work he was using to Aristotle, is hardly well founded. Simplicius tells us much about the ancient philosophers, which he only knew from Aristotle, without naming his authority. * In Fr. 4, quoted p. 539, 2. * What Simplicius says (sup. p. 546), and Kern (Quast. 11) adopted, but has since, Beitr., p. 17, abandoned, in solution of this contradiction, explains nothing, and credits Xenophanes with distinc- tions of ideas, which are unknown before the time of Aristotle. Kern, therefore, has another theory ready, to which he comes back in Beitr. 4 —viz., that Xenophanes at first denied motion of the Deity, and subsequently, rest. Now we cannot but allow the possibility that this philosopher may have changed his opinion. But to establish the fact of such a change, we must have distinct signs and evidences of it; and these are to be found neither in the verse of Timon, discussed p. 464, 1, third edition, nor in the fragment of Xenophanes (on which cf. p.inf. p. 559). None of our autho- and while Aristotle rities in regard to Xenophanes mention any alteration in his point of view, nor does the work we are considering. All, except this work and the passage in Simplicius, which depends upon it, assert that he denied motion, and not rest, to the Deity (cf. p. 455, 6, third edi- tion). We have, therefore, no right to suppose that our authorities were in possession of utterances to the contrary. This theory is a conjecture intended to reconcile the statements of our treatise with other evidence; but the conjecture would only be justifiable, if we were sure of the accuracy of those statements. Lastly, Teichmüller, Stud. 2. Gesch. d. Begr. 619 sq., attempts to avoid the contradiction by remarking that Xenoph. indeed denied the movement of the uni- verse, but not movement within the universe. But this way of escape is closed by the fact that the writing on Melissus does not deny movement and rest to different subjects—(movement to the uni- verse; rest to its various parts— but to one and the same subject— N N 2 548 T HE ELEATICS. assures us that Xenophanes gave no opinion as to the Limitedness or Unlimitedness of the One," both predicates are here expressly and categorically denied in respect to it. This last statement is all the more strange since it manifestly contradicts itself, and also the assertion immediately the év, by row 6eby eival Aéºyei. This is clear from c. 3, 977 b, 8; c, 4, 978 b, 15, 37. * Metaph. i. 5, 986 b, 18: IIap- pºevtåms uév yöp othee roi, karð Tov Aóryov čvös &m reoréal, Méxiorgos 6& roo Karā rhv jamv. Ötö Kal 6 ułv retrepaguévov, 6 6 &melpóv pmoiv airó. Eevoq'dvms 5& trpáros toūtww évſoras oë6&v fileo'aqfivuorev, où6é ris qāorews rotºrwy 056erépas àource 61)etv, &AA’ eis rov 32Aov oëpavovátogxébas to św elvaí pmol row 6eóv. This does not assert merely that Xeno- phanes left it uncertain whether he conceived the One as a formal or a material principle; but that he refused to define it as limited or unlimited. Even Parmenides and Melissus had not said the former; but Aristotle concludes from what they said regarding the second point, that the obôèv Šteoraphviore can only refer to this. Nor can we (with Kern, Qu. 49) explain these words by alleging that Xeno- phanes was self-contradictory in his utterances about the deity. Aristotle might doubtless have charged him with this contradic- toriness, but he could not have said that, in regard to the question whether the Deity is limited or un- limited, he was wanting in clear- ness. How is it possible to express oneself more clearly than Xeno- phanes, according to our treatise, has done? In Kern's more recent reply (Beitr. 6) these considerations preceding it,” namely, that are not brought forward. The words obôév Šteoraq fivuorev, he says, cannot relate to the question of the Limitedness or the Unlimitedness of the év, for in that case repl toūrov, or something similar, would have been added; but the doctrine of Xenophanes ‘is described as generally obscure.” But the addi- tion which he misses is found in the words: oièë ris pào eas toūrov où6erépas àouke 61 yeſv, the meaning of which can only be that Xeno- phanes did not discuss those ques- tions on which Parmenides and Melissus disagree with one another. Yern further tries to show that Xenophanes really expressed him- self contradictorily on the Limited- ness and Unlimitedness of the One, because he calls God, ap. Timon (inf. p. 561, 1), iorov &rdvrm, which Sext. Pyrr. l. 224, explains by orq alpoetőfi ; and, on the other hand, he holds that the roots of the earth extend to infinity (vide #nf. p. 565, 5). But the orgalpoetőfi of Sextus no doubt comes directly or indirectly from this treatise itself (c. 3, 977 b, 1 : travrn 8' 8plotov čvna aqalpoetóſ, eival); in Timon's ionov &mdvrm there is no allusion to the shape, it seems rather to relate to the of Aos épé, &c. As regards the unlimited extension of the earth, it will presently be shown that we have no right to apply this defini- tion to the Deity. * Ritter (Gesch. der Phil. i. TREATISE ON MELISSUS, ETC. 549 the Deity is spherical. Moreover, it is highly impro- bable that Aristotle should have passed over such a singular opinion in passages like Metaph. i. 5, Phys. i. 3. We know that as late as the third century of our era the most learned commentators of Aristotle were not agreed whether Xenophanes held the Deity to be limited or unlimited ; ' and this phenomenon would be incom- prehensible if they had possessed, in addition to the work of Aristotle, such definite and detailed explana- 476 sq.) indeed thinks that Xeno- phanes, in the spherical form which he attributed to God, meant to imply the unity of the Limited and Unlimited ; for the sphere is self-limited; and when he denied that God was unmoved he was merely asserting that God has no permanent relation to another. The possibility of such a meaning in these definitions, however, could not easily be proved; it is besides far too subtle for so ancient a thinker. Kern's interpretation (Beitr. 17; cf. Xenoph. 10 sqq.) is equally untenable : * xenophanes denied Limitedness only within Being and in opposition to a some- thing cast out from Being and ex- ternal to it, and Unlimitedness only in relation to the One which is the All.’ He, therefore, con- ceived his One or God as uninter- rupted (never finding in itself a limit), globe-shaped, and filling all space. In order to distinguish his Being from Non-Being and from the Many, and probably in oppo- sition to the Pythagorean doctrine, he declined to place it in the cate- gories of trépas and āmeipov. This means that the limitedness which Xenophanes denied of Being is to be explained as limitedness through Something else, and is to be re- stricted to this. Our text, how- ever, does not say of Being; it is not limited by another, but also- lutely (977 b, 3) otºr' &metpov eival oùre retrepávtal. Thus, according to the universal meaning of the word, it is this absolute limiting, and not the limiting through another, which is denied of it; and when in proof of this proposition it is said: As the Many are limited each by each, but the One is not like the Many, so the One must be unlimited, it does not necessarily follow that the otre tremapávěat it- self signifies not limited by another, and consequently that it is also denied of the spherical One. Not one passage has been quoted in which tretrapáv6al or tretrepaguévov eival (c. 3) means, without further addition, “to be limited by some- thing else.' But the refuting of the proposition attributed to Xeno- phanes c. 4, 278 a, 16 Sqq. abun- dantly shows that the author never contemplated such a limitation. * Simpl. Phys. 6 a. NukóAaos 3& 6 Aamaakmvös, Ös &meipov kal &Ki- vurov Aéryovros airoß rºw &px?iv čv tfi trepl 9eów &topºv'muovečer 'AAéčav- àpos 3& és retrepaguévov airo Kal orgapoeiðés. B50 THE ELEATICS. tions from Xenophanes himself as this treatise pre- supposes. Even had there existed a work of this kind by Xenophanes, it must have been greatly retouched and altered in the treatise," otherwise all traces of the poetical expression and epic form of Xenophanes' work could never have been so entirely obliterated.” But, apart from the contents of this exposition, it is unlikely that there ever was such a work. A dialectical discus- sion so methodically conducted, and proceeding in so regular a manner from beginning to end in the scholas- tic form of a refutation, by means of dilemmas and deductio ad absurdwm, could not, except in defiance of all laws of historical analogy,” be ascribed to the prede- cessor of Parmenides, to the philosopher whom Aristotle censures “for his want of practice in thought. * That this may be the case. even Brandis admits (Gesch.d. Entw. i. 83), when he says that the author may have brought together all that was isolated or loosely connected in the poem. Cf. Kern, Qu. p. 52, who says that the words and many parts of the argument may belong to the author. Where is our guarantee that the author has, in other respects, truly reproduced the doctrine of Xenophanes? We shall find no such guarantee in the author's name, for it is question- able whether the treatise has any right to it; nor (vide following note) in the poetical expressions on which Brandis bases his view. * Brandis, l. c. 82, believed he could point out in this work a number of forms manifestly poeti- cal and corresponding with some in the fragments of Xenophanes. But Kern, Qu. 52, remarks that of those he quotes only the word &Tpepelvis of any importance. An isolated word like this, however, can scarcely be taken into consider- ation, and even the words which Rern adds, où6% yap oièë rāvta. 8&vaotai &v & BoöAouro (977 a, 35), do not, for my part, remind me that ‘the author is giving an ac- count of a poetical work.’ * Metaph. i. 5, 986 b, 26: The Eleatics are àqeréot trpós Thy vöv trapovaav Çfirmauv, oi uły 350 kai wdutrav, &s Švres unkpov &ypotkó- Tepot. Eevoq àvms kal Méxiorgos. * It was principally this diffi- culty which determined Wendt (p. 163 of his edition of the first volume of Tennemann's Gesch. d. Phil. 18 sq.) in his judgment that the author of this work was proba- bly a later philosopher, who in common with Simplicius was draw- ing from some indirect source, and gave the form of conclusion to the opinions here quoted; that TREATISE ON MELISSUS, ETC. , 55.1 For all these reasons it seems most improbable that the work we are considering was written by Aristotle or he was not acquainted with the poem of Xenophanes itself. Rein- hold (Gesch. d. Phil. i. 63, 3rd edition, and in the Programm v. J. 1847, De genuina Xenophanis disciplina) and Vermehren (Autor- schaft der dem Arist. 2wgeschriebenen Schrift. tr. Eevop. Jena, 1861, p. 43) among the reasons they adduce (in agreement with Bergk, Comment. de Arist. lib. de Xen. &c., Marb. 1843; Rose, Arist. Libr. Ord. 72 sqq.) for discarding this work, dwell especially on its dialectical and unpoetical form. Kern, Qu. 53, says, with some plausibility, that Melissus was included in Aristotle's judgment on Xeno- phanes, and yet we find in his fragments a purely dialectical ex- position. I cannot admit that the discussions of Melissus display the same amount of logical ability as those ascribed in this writing to Xenophanes (cf. Kern, Beitr. 16). But, even supposing they did, there would still be a great difference between Melissus and Xenophanes, and it would be impossible to say with Kern: “Cur paullo ante Par- menidem idem fieri potuisse negan- dum sit, quod atate Parmenidea factum esse certissimis testimoniis constet, non video.' Between the literary activity of Melissus (who was not contemporary with Par- menides, but about thirty years younger) and that of Xenophanes, there apparently lies an interval of at least fifty years; and in this interval we find not only Hera- cleitus and the beginning of the Atomistic philosophy, but also the energetic activity of Parmenides and Zeno, through whom the strictly metaphysical character and the dialectical method of the Eleatic school was first established. That we cannot, indeed, expect at the commencement of this interval what we find at the end of it, that no dialectical method can have been laid down in the poems of Xenophanes, surpassing even that of. Parmenides in its form, but of which there is no trace in the frag- ments of Xenophanes' writings, all this seems to me self-evident. I am quite ready “to admit the in- ternal possibility of such profound philosophising at so early a period, if only its existence be sufficiently proved” (Kern, Beitr. 16), but I cannot admit it when, as in the present case, there is not sufficient proof. Not only all historical analogy, as it seems to me, but the judgment of all antiquity, is on my side. Kern is quite logical in placing Xenophanes as a philoso- pher above Parmenides, on the ground of the treatise tr. Mexico ov. If, however, Xenophanes had really said all that this treatise ascribes to him, and in the sense that Kern supposes, he would not only have surpassed his successor in dialecti- cal ability, but he would have taught, in respect to the Deity and the world, essentially the same doctrine that Parmenides taught concerning Being, thus greatly diminishing the personal merit of IParmenides, though he might not altogether have destroyed it. In this case it would be difficult to explain why not only Aristotle (whom Kern censures for his low estimate of Xenophanes as com- pared with Parmenides), but also 552 THE ELEATICS. Theophrastus." Moreover, it contains much that it would be impossible to connect with either of these philosophers. The assertion that Anaximander supposed water to be the substance of all things contradicts all their statements about Anaximander ; * what is said of Empedocles sounds very unlike Aristotle; * Anaxagoras Plato (vide infra, § Parm. note 1), should place Parmenides so far above all the other Eleatics. * Mullach, indeed, thinks dif- ferently. “Aristotle, he remarks, p. 12 sq. (Fragm. Philos. i. 274) in opposition to Bergk, ‘in expound- ing the opinions of others, is often guilty of contradiction, and says much that we should hesitate to ascribe to him.’ Similarly Kern, Qu. 49. That Aristotle ever so misrepresented either of his prede- cessors, or fell into such contradic- tions in speaking of him, as the author of this book has done in re- gard to Xenophanes, I must dis- pute. The objections brought by Mullach against his exposition of Parmenides are groundless, as will hereafter be shown. Kern urges that he often arbitrarily reduces the definitions of his predecessors to categories of his own system, and is not always just in his criti- cism of them. This, however, is not the same as denying that Xenophanes expressed his opinion on a point on which, according to our treatise, he expressed it fully and clearly—or, ascribing to him in that treatise a Dialectic entirely beyond his point of view. If, how- ever, we even grant that Aristotle might really have written what we find in the treatise on Melissus, there is no reason to suppose that this treatise was merely an extract from larger Aristotelian works; the theory of Karsten, p. 97, would be much more probable, viz., that it was a sketch made by Aristotle for his own use. § * Cf. p. 251, 1; 232, 2; 234, 3. * C. 2, 976, b 22 : áuota's 5& kal 'Eutrečokx?is kiveto 6at plºv &et qnot avykpwéueva (so Cod. Lips. reads instead of ovykivoúp.) rov âtravra évôexexás xpóvov . . . §tav ôè eis pºtav wop phy ovykpiófi &s év elval, où6év pmoſt ré ye keveev tréAet où'ěe treptororów. If this means that Empedocles really held the doc- trine of endless motion, it contra- dicts the express statements of Aristotle, who elsewhere attributes to him an alternation of motion and rest (infra, vol. ii. § Emp.). On the other hand, if (with Kern, Symb. Crit. 25) we take it to mean that during the coming together of mat- ter, motion went on uninterrupt- edly; the words rov Šmavra évôexe- xós Xpóvov contain a pleonasm very unlike Aristotle. And it is diffi- cult to see how the author (in the &rav 68, etc.), in order to prove that motion is possible without the void, can argue that in the agaipos of Empedocles, there was also no void, for in the Sphairos motion has come to Rest. As to the de- sign of ‘proving that the doc- trine of Empedoeles can only, to a certain extent, be employed against Melissus’ (Kern, Beitr. 13), I can- not discover any trace either in words or context. t TREATISE ON MELISSUS, ETC. 553 is spoken of as if the author only knew of him by hear- say;" and among the doctrines discussed and criticised, side by side with much that is important, we find not a little that is trivial and unworthy of Aristotle or Theo- phrastus.” 1 C. 2, 975 b, 17 : &s kal Tov 'Avačayópav p aq t t t ves Aéyetv ć &el úvrwv kal &metpov rà yuvéueva ºyſveorðat. No one can believe that Aristotle or Theophrastus would either of them use such expressions about a philosopher with whom they were so accurately acquainted, and to whom (as we shall see) they elsewhere distinctly ascribed this doctrine. Kern, Beitr. 13, appeals to Arist. Metaph. iv. 3, 1005 b, 23 : &6övarov yūp Övruvotºv raûrov ūroxaufléveuv elvat kal whº eival, ka94mep T : v š s of ov'ral Aéyeuv ‘HpdikAettov. This analogy disap- pears as soon as we examine the passage more closely. Aristotle frequently ascribes to Heracleitus the proposition that the same thing at the same time is and is not; or is at the same time its own opposite (vide infra, p. 550, third edition). But he does not believe that Heracleitus held this in ear- nest; he reckons it among the 6é- gets Aóyov čveka Aeyóueval (Phys. i. 2, 185 a, 5); he supposes that Heracleitus has not made his meaning clear, even to himself (Metaph. xi. 5, 1062 a, 31), and in order to indicate this he chooses the expression (Metaph. iv. 3) ruès ofoviral Aéyeuv. Aéyetv here signi- fies: to express something as his opinion, to maintain something, as is clear from the way in which Aristotle, l. c., proceeds: oik #orti ºy&p &vaykalov, & ris Aéyet taúra. kal iroMaußdvetv. If the ques- tion were simply, whether the Thus the judgment which we formed of the words quoted corresponded to those of Heracleitus, Aristotle would merely have said: ka9&mep ‘Hp. Aéyet; as he says instead: tives otovrat Aéyew, the reason must be that he does not profess to be reproducing his own opinion. On the other hand, there was no necessity at all for the author of our treatise, in his remarks on Anaxagoras, to disclaim his respon- sibility in regard to them by such a mode of expression. * How trivial, for instance, is the discussion of the question, whether anything can arise out of non-Being (c. 1, 975 a, 3 sqq.), and how little indication there is here of Aristotle's reply—viz., that nothing comes from absolute non- Being, but all things come from relative non-Being, the Övváuel Šv How strange is the question in c. 4 sub init. Tt kwāśst wit’ & 6potov pºſit’ & &vouotov to yiyvöuevov yiyve- oréat, &AA’ ºr uh wros; and the objection raised in c. i. 975 a, 7, that Becoming is frequently sup- posed to have proceeded from nothing. Elsewhere neither Aris- totle nor Theophrastus ever men- tions, even as a hypothesis, or a possibility, such an origin from the a?, 5v without any further definition. How superfluous and disturbing is the remark, c. 2, 976 a, 33 sqq., that there might be several Infi- nutes, as Xenophanes presupposed when he spoke of the Infinity of the earth beneath and of the air above, followed by a citation of 554 THE EI, E.4 TICS. genuineness of this work from its main contents is con- firmed by these secondary traits; and if neither of them separately is decisive, yet together they constitute an amount of circumstantial evidence which cannot be outweighed by the testimony of manuscripts and later authors, so often found on the side of undoubtedly spurious writings. When and by whom the three treatises were com- posed is uncertain. That they emanated from the Peripatetic school is probable, both from their nature and also from the mention of them in the catalogue of Diogenes.' They appear to have included two frag- ments, which have been lost, on Parmenides and Zeno;” so that the author must have aimed at a complete representation and criticism of the Eleatic doctrines. The order adopted in their discussion seems to have been that indicated in the passage from Aristotle Quoted above,” except that Zeno and Gorgias are added to the philosophers there mentioned. The author has taken their opinions chiefly from their own writings, and has given the essential content of these cor- rectly when it presented itself to him in the form of an argument logically developed, as was the case with Melissus and Gorgias. In regard to Xenophanes, on the contrary, he appears to have misapprehended the statements of Aristotle and Theophrastus,” and to have started from the presupposition that this philosopher the verses in which Empedocles a', trpós ra. Eevopdvows a', trpos rà censures this utterance. Zhvovos a'. Diogenes mentions among the * Cf. p. 535 sqq. writings of Aristotle (v. 25): "rpós * Cf. p. 537; 547, 1. 7& Mexíagov a' . . . trpós rā Topytov * Supra, p. 547, 1 ; 542, 1. TREATISE ON MELISSUS, ETC. 555 expressly denied, in respect to the Deity, limitedness as well as unlimitedness, and movement as well as rest ; and then to have developed the proofs of this statement from the indications which he found, or thought he found, in the poems of Xenophanes. But it is also possible that some other author may have anticipated him in so doing, and that this exposition, and not Xenophanes himself, may have been his immediate source. What is really derived from Xenophanes we can only discover from a comparison of this treatise with other accounts. Its testimony as to supposed propositions of his is not sufficient to establish their authenticity in cases where it stands alone. The development of the Eleatic philosophy was completed in three generations of philosophers, whose activity extended over about a century. Xenophanes, the founder of the school, first expresses their generai principle in a theological form. In opposition to Poly- theism, he declares the Deity to be the One, underived, all-embracing Being ; and in connection with this, the universe to be uniform and eternal. At the same time, however, he recognises the Many and the Mutable as a reality. Parmenides gives to this principle its meta- physical basis and purely philosophic expression; he reduces the opposites of the One and the Many, the Eternal and the Become, to the fundamental opposite of the Existent and non-Existent; derives the qualities of both from their concept, and proves the impossibility of Becoming, Change and Plurality in a strictly uni- versal sense. Lastly, Zeno and Melissus maintain the propositions of Parmenides as against the ordinary 556 XENOPHANES. opinion; but carry the opposition between them so far that the inadequacy of the Eleatic principle for the explanation of phenomena becomes clearly apparent. II, XENOPHANES. 1 OUR knowledge of the doctrine of Xenophanes is de- rived from two sources, viz., such fragments as have * Colophon is universally named as the native city of Xenophanes; his father is called by Apollodorus Orthomenes; by others, Dexius, or Dexinus (Diog. ix. 18; Lucian, Macrob. 20; Hippolyt. Refut. i. 14; Theodoret, Cur. gr. aff. iv. 5, p. 56). As to his date, Apollodorus says, ap. Clem. Strom. i. 301 C : karū. Thu Teorgapakoothv’OAvutridóa yewó- pºevov trapatetakéval #xpt tow Aa- peſov re kal Kûpov xpóvov. We cannot suppose that Eépêous is here intended for Köpov, or that Aapetov is to be erased; for Hippolyt. l. c. also mentions Cyrus. It cannot, however, be regarded as any proof of the great age of Xenophanes (trapaterarcéval sc, rov 8íov), that having been born in the 40th Olympiad, he should have been living in the time of Cyrus. The peculiarity of placing Darius before Cyrus is sufficiently explained on metrical grounds (Apoll. wrote in trimeter), cf. Diels, Rhein. Mus. xxxi. 23. On the other hand, the 50th (N) Olymp. must certainly be substituted for the 40th (M), as the time of his birth; for (Diels, p. 23) the statement that he flourished in Ol. 60 (Diog, ix. 20) also origi- nates with Apollodorus; and the ăruh is usually placed in the 40th year of a man's life. But as Sext. Math. i. 257 also names Ol. 40 as the time of his birth, the error must previously have crept into the text used by Sextus and Clemens. The date of the ākuh, according to which Apoll. probably calculated the year of birth, was determined by the founding of Elea, sung by Xenophanes (cf. Diels, l.c.). This we infer from Diog. l.c. Eusebius mentions Xenophanes in Ol. 60 and also in Ol. 56; but that is unim- portant. He is also mentioned more indefinitely by Sotion, ap. Diog. ix. 18, as a contemporary of Anaximander. Eus. Pr. Ev. x. 14; xiv. 17, 10, says that he was contemporary with Pythagoras and Anaxagoras (who is elsewhere placed too early by Eus.). Iambl. Theol. Arith. p. 41, names Pytha- goras only. Hermippus, ap. Diog. viii. 56 ; cf. ibid. ix. 20, makes him the teacher of Empedocles, Timaeus, ap. Clem. l. c.; and Plut. Reg. Apophth. Hiero, 4, p. 175, the con- temporary of Hiero and Epichar- mus, Ps. Lucian, even the disciple of Archelaus; and the Scholiast in Aristophanes (Peace, v. 696) as- cribes to him a saying concerning Simonides, on which little stress is to be laid, cf. Karsten, Phil. Graec. Rell. i. 81 sq. He himself seems to speak of Pythagoras as deceased, whereas he (Xenophanes) is named by Heracleitus as one of his pre- decessors (vide supra, p. 481, 1 ; 510, 4). He also mentions Epi- LIFE AND WRITINGS, 557 been preserved of his works, and the accounts of ancient writers. menides after Epimenides' death (Diog. i. 111; ix. 18). He as- serts that the beginning of the conflict between the Ionian colonies and the Persians took place in his early life (Fr. 17, ap. Athen. ii. fi4, e), for when he is asked ºrna {kos joró', 39' 6 M780s & pinceto, this can- not of course refer to a recent oc- currence, but to something long past (cf. Cousin, Fragm. i. 3 Sqq.; Karsten, p. 9). This agrees with the statement in Diog. ix. 20, that he celebrated the founding of Elea (Ol. 61) in 2000 hexameters, and with the anecdote, ap. Plut. De Vit. Pud. c. 5, p. 530, according to which he was acquainted with La- sus of Hermione (about 520–500). All things considered, the greater part of his lengthened activity may most probably be placed in the se- cond half of the sixth century; his birth may have occurred in the third or fourth decad of this cen- tury; his death must have hap- pened in the following century; for it is certain that he died very old. In the verses, ap. Diog. ix. 18, he says he has been roaming about in Greek lands for 67 years—since he was 25. Lucian, therefore, loc. cit., errs in giving the length of his life as 91 years. According to Censorin. Di. Nat. 15, 3, he was more than a hundred. As to his personal history, we are informed that he was driven out from his native city to different places, and resided at various times in Zancle, Catana and Elea (Diog. ix. 18; Aristot. Rhet. ii. 23, 1400 b, 5; Karsten, p. 12, 87); that he be- came very poor (Diog. ix. 20, after Demetrius and Panaetius; Plut. These two sources are not always in agree- Reg. Apophth. 4, p. 175). The statement of his having been the disciple of Telanges, the Pythago- rean (Diog. i. 15), of Boton, an unknown Athenian, or even of Ar- chelaus (Diog. ix. 18; Ps. Lucian, l.c.) deserves no attention. When Plato (Soph. 242 D) says of the Eleatic school, &ró Eevoq &vous re ral éti Tpóo.6ev &pääuevov, he can scarcely be alluding to any par- ticular predecessor of Xenophanes. Cousin (p. 7) thinks he means the Pythagoreans, but Plato could not have called them the founders of the Eleatic doctrine of the Unity of Being. He is probably speaking in accordance with the general pre- supposition that doctrines like his had been held before his time; it was then customary to seek the doctrines of the philosophers in the ancient poets. Lobeck conjectures (Aglaoph. i. 613) that he is speci- ally referring in this passage to the Orphic Theogony, but with this I cannot agree. A story of Plu- tarch's, which involves an Egyptian journey (Amator. 18, 12, p. 763; De Is. 70, p. 379, and the same, without the name of Xenophanes, ap. Clem. Cohort. 15 B), arbi- trarily transfers to Egypt, what, according to Arist. l. c., happened in Elea. On the other hand, it is quite possible that even in his own country he may have been led to the beginnings of the Ionic natural philosophy by his passion for en- quiry. Theophrast, following Diog. ix. 21, calls him a disciple of Anaximander, and we have no rea- son to doubt the assertion ; and the statement of his having contra- dicted Thales and Pythagoras 558 A ENOPHANES. ment with each other; for while in the fragments of his didactic poem theological opinions are predominant, and only a few physical theories are introduced, the ancient writers ascribe to him general metaphysical statements which closely connect him with his successor Parmenides. Our view of the relation of these two representations must chiefly determine our conception of Xenophanes. Let us first examine the sayings of Xenophanes himself which have been handed down by tradition. In these, his main position seems to be that conflict with the popular polytheistic belief by which he was known even in antiquity." (Diog. ix. 18) may be founded on the fact that he censures, not only Pythagoras (p. 481, 1), but Thales. (Farther details later on.) That he possessed more than ordinary knowledge may be inferred from the remark of Heracleitus (p. 510, 4). To his contemporaries he was chiefly known through his poems, which, according to ancient usage, he recited (Diog. ix. 18) on his journeys. All kinds of poems have been ascribed to him by later writers—Epics, Elegies, and Iambics (Diog. l. c.; cf. Kern, Menoph. 18); Tragedies (Eus. Chron. Ol. 60, 2); Parodies (Athen. ii. 54 e); a taxoi (Strabo, xiv. 1, 28, p. 643; Schol. in Aris- toph. Knights, v. 406; Prokl. in Hes. Opp. et Di. v. 284; Eustath. on II.ii.212; Tzetz. in Bernhardy's edition of the Geograph. Min. p. 1010); or, as Apul. Floril. iv. 20, says (the manuscripts, however, read here Xenocrates), satires. Cou- sin (p. 9) and Karsten, 19 sqq., will not admit the orix}\ot; but cf. He opposes his doctrine of Wachsmuth, De Timoſze Philasio, 29 sq. His philosophic opinions were contained in a didactic poem in Epic metre, of which we possess fragments ; that it bore the title trepi pºorews is only asserted by the more recent writers (Stob. Ecl. i. 294; Poll. Onomast. vi. 46), and their evidence is the more suspi- cious, as the work itself seems to have been early lost. Cf. Brandis, Comm. El. 10 sqq.; Karsten, 26 sqq. (Simplicius, e.g., mentions that he had not seen it; De Coelo, 233 b, 22; Schol. in Arist. 506 a, 40). In Diog. i. 16, where, according to the former reading, Xenophanes was enumerafed among the most fruitful of the philosophic writers, Xenocrates is to be substituted; cf. Nietzsche, Rh. Mus. xxv. 220 sq. The judgment of Athen. xiv. 632D, on the verses of Xenophanes, is more favourable than that of Cicero, Acad. ii. 23, 74. * Cf. among other texts, Arist. Poet. 25, 1460 b, 36. The utterances of the poets are defended on the POLEMIC AGAINST POLY THEISM. 559 the unity of God to the supposed plurality of gods; to their origin in time, the etermity of God; to their variability, his unchangeableness; to their anthropo- morphic nature, his sublimity; to their physical, intel- lectual, and moral limitations, his infinite spirituality. One God rules over gods and men, for the Deity is the highest, and the highest can be but one." ground that they represent things as they are, or as they ought to be, ei Šē pumöetépas, Šti oiſta paoriv, ofov tº trepi 6eóv. forws yap oite BéArtov oira Aéºyeuv, oùr' &Amói, &AA’ &ruxev Šotrep Eevoq &vms (sc. Aéyet ; the most recent editors, however, on account of the Eevo- q,4vel, or m, of most of the MSS. read with Ritter: ás rapi, Eevoºd- vet) &AA’ of pagi. These words have been unnecessarily altered by modern authors, and have received many false interpretations (cf. Karsten, p. 188). They are trans- lated quite simply as follows: ‘For it may well be that the usual notions about the gods are neither good nor true, but that it is with the gods as Xenophanes believes, but the many are of another opinion.' Ritter thinks that the whole chapter is a later addition, but even in this case it must have been based on something authentic, and the words we have quoted have an Aristotelian ring in them. * Fr. 1 ap. Clem. Strom. v. 601 C :— eis 6eos #v re 6eotori kal &vôpétrotot plényiotos, oùre 6éuas 6Vmtotoiv Šuo'íos otºre vómua. Arist. De Melisso, c. 3, 977 a, 23 sqq.: el 5’ to ruv 66ebs trävrww icpá- This God is Tuotov, Šva pmolu airby irpooſicely eival, ei yüp 5üo # TAetovs elev, oùk &v éti kpóttarov kai BéAttarov airby eival tróvrov, &c. Plut. ap. Eus. Pr. Ev. i. 8, Sup. p. 539, 2; cf. 554, where it is also shown why and in what sense we can accept the Pseudo- Aristotelian writing as evidence concerning Xenophanes. That Xe- nophanes spoke in his writings of the Unity of God is clear from Aristotle's words, quoted p. 539, 2. The conjecture, however. that he only became a strict Monotheist in later life, having previously believed, not in one God, but in a supreme God far above the other deities (Kern, Beitr. 4), finds no support in this fragment. The many gods, of whom one is the highest, need not necessarily be conceived as real gods. If, accord- ing to the theory of Xenophanes, they only existed in human imagi- nation, the true God might still, especially in poetical language, be compared with them, and said to be greater than they. “The greatest among gods and men’ must mean the greatest absolutely. When Heracleitus, for instance (vide infra, vol. ii.), says none of the gods nor of human kind made the world, he only means to express that it was not made at all; and even in a Christian hymn God is called the God of gods. 560 XENOPHANES. uncreated, for what is created is also perishable, and the Deity can only be conceived as imperishable." Nor is he subject to change: what beseems him is to remain unmoved in one place, and not to wander hither and thither.” Moreover, what right have we to attribute to him a human form 2 Each man represents his gods as he himself is: the negro as black and flat-mosed, the Thracian as blue-eyed and red-haired ; and if horses and oxen could paint, no doubt they would make gods like horses and oxen.” Just so it is with the other imperfections of human nature, which we transfer to the gods. * Fr. 5 ap. Clem. ... c., and, with some variations, ap. Theod. Cur. Gr. Aff. iii. 72, p. 49 : &AA& 8potol Sokéouai 6eous yeuvâ06al . . . . Thy orderépmy 5' 0.0%ra (Theod. preferably ato 6 mov) exeiv q,w}v re 6éuas re. Arist. Rhet. ii. 23, 1399 b, 6: E. ÉAeyev, Štt ögotos &orefloodiv of 'yevéo 6al pºokovtes rows 9eous rois àtroßavely Aéyovoivº âuſpotépa's yap ovubaivet u%) eival Tows 9eoûs trote. Ibid. 1400 b, 5 : E. 'EAedrals épwtóriv ei 6tagi tì Aevico8ég kal 6pmvögly, 3) pºi, a vue- BoöAevev, ei prºv 6eby intoxapºdvoval, Au% 9pmvely, ei 5’ &vöpwrov, u} 06eiv. (For the version in Plutarch of this story, vide infra, p. 557, mote, De Mel. c. 3, cf. p. 544, 1), where, however, the demonstration is not that of Xenophanes. Diog. ix. 19: Trporás T' &teq fivato, 3rt trav To 'yiváue ov péaptów éott. * Fr. 4 ap. Simpl. Phys. 6 a. (vide sup. p. 539, 2). Cf. Arist. Metaph. i. 5, 986 b, 17, where it is stated of the Eleatics generally: &kivmtov eivaí pagi (to Év). * Fr. 1, 5, and Fr. 6 ap. Clem, Not only the immoral conduct related by Strom. v. 601 D, Theod. l. c. ; Eus. Pr. Ev. xiii. 13, 36:— &AA’ eitol xeipás y eixov Bóes à è Aéovres, * Ypéyal xeſpervi kai épya Texeiv êtrep &vöpes (Sc. eixov), in not pºév 6' in trouot 86es 6é te Bovorºv ôuotas (so Theod., the others ðuotol), kai ke bećºv ióéas āypaqov kal adºplar' étrotovy, Totaú6' oióv trep kaitol 6éuas eixov §uotov. For the rest, cf. Theod. l. c. and Clem. Strom. vii. 711 B. Also what is said in Diog. ix. 19: oãotav 6eoû a palpoetóñpmööv Šuotov čxovoav &v0pétrº &Aov 5' 6pāv kal &Aov âkočeiv, p. 3) u á v to 1 & vair ve?v, if the last definition is really founded on some expression of Xenophanes. That it is aimed against the Py- thagorean doctrine of the respira- tion of the world (sup. p. 467, 1), I do not believe (vide Kern, Beitr. 17; Xenoph. 25). UNITY OF A LL BEING. b61 Homer and Hesiod,' but all limitation is unworthy of them. God is as unlike to mortals in mind as in form. The Deity is all eye, all ear, all thought, and through his intellect he rules everything without exertion.” Thus a pure monotheism is here confronted with the religion of nature and its many gods, while, at the same time, we should not be justified in ascribing to this monotheism a strictly philosophic character on the strength of the assertions we have quoted, taken alone.” Other testimonies, indeed, carry us beyond this point, and apply the utterances of Xenophanes on the unity and eternity of God in a general manner to the 1 Fr. 7 ap. Sext. Math. ix. 193, i. 289:— ºrdvra 6eois &vé6mkav "Oumpós 6' ‘Horto66s re 3ao'a trap' &v6pároto w śvetóea kal ibó')os éo riv, o? (this is the reading of Steph., the MSS. have às, Karst. and Wachsm. p. 74, kal), TrAetorr' épôéyèavro 9eów &6epfortua épya, kAérretv, wouxetely re kal &AAñAous ătrateúeiv. On account of this hostility to the poets of the national religion, Xenophanes is called by Timon ap. Sext. Pyrrh. i. 224; Diog. ix. 18 : ‘Oumpatárms éturicóttmy (prefer- ably €trikóttmv) and Diog. l.c. says of him : yéypaq’s 6* . . . kað’ ‘Howdāou kal ‘Oujipov Čirikártov aúróv rà repl 6eów sipmuéva. The observation of Aristotle, discussed sup. p. 558, 1, refers to these and similar passages. * Fr. 1, vide sup, p. 559, 1; WOL. I. Fr. 2 ap. Sext. ix. 144 (cf. Diog. ix. 19; Plut. ap. Eus. Pr. Ev. i. 8, 4) : o3Aos épé, of Aos 3& voet, oùAos 6é T' &koúsi. Fr. 3 ap. Simpl. Phys. 6 a &AA’ &rdvev6e tróvo vóov ppevi trčura kpaśaivet. Cf. Diog. l. c. : atºptravrá tº eival [Töv 6ebv) votiv kal qpévmauv kal &fölov. Timon. ap. Sext. Pyrrh. i. 224: éktos &n’ &věpárov (accord- ing to the emendation of Fabricius; Wachsmuth, De Tim. 64, reads with Röper: 6s toy &rd vôpatrov) 6eov étradarar' forov &mdurm &orkmóñ . . . woepérepov he vömua (cf. Wachs- muth, for some attempts to com- plete the last verse, none of which commend themselves to me). Fur- ther details, p. 562, 5. Perhaps the assertion ap. Diog. has this same meaning pm bě kal to troAA& #aaa, vot, eival. * Among these may also be reckoned the attack on sooth- saying which Cic. Divin. i. 3, 5; Plut. Plac. v. 1, 2, attribute to Xenophanes. O O 562 XENOPHANES. totality of things. Plato includes his theory with that of his successors in the expression that all is One.' So also Aristotle calls him the first founder of the doctrine of the unity of all things, and observes that he brought forward his propositions concerning the unity of God with reference to the universe.” In agreement with this, Theophrastus” alleges that in and with the unity of the primitive principle he maintained the unity of all existence, and Timon represents him as saying of him- self that wheresoever he turned his gaze all things resolved themselves into one and the same eternal, homogeneous essence.” We have no right to mis- trust these unanimous statements of our most trust- worthy authorities (with whom, moreover, all the later writers agree),” merely because a pantheism of this Soph. 242 D: To be trap' #Liv 'EAeatikov č6vös, Ötro Eevoq'4- vows re kai éri trpóg 6ev &pgåuevov, às évos ūvros Tóv tróvtov kańoupé- wav oita, 6te;épxeral toſs uß60is. * Metaph. i. 5, 986 b, 10: eia! 8é rives of trepi rod travros és àv puãs otia ms pūorea's &m eqívavro. In regard to these persons it is then said that their uniform primitive essence is not, like the primitive matter of the Physicists, a cause of Becoming, but dictvntov eii aſ qaqiv . Eevoq àvms 6* ſpätos toūtav čvioras, &c., vide Supra, p. 548, 1. * Ap. Simpl. supra, p. 543, 1. * Ap. Sext. Pyrrh. i. 224, at- tributes to him these words:— — 3rtm y&p Šubv v6ov eipúa'alut eis $v rairó re trav &veXàeto' trav ' éow aiel trövtm &veakóuevov putaw eis piſaw iotaff Öpoſaw. * Cic. Acad. ii. 37, 118: Xeno- phanes . . unum esse omnia neque Žd esse mutabile et id esse Deum, meque natum unquam et Sempiter- num, conglobata figura. N. D. i. 11, 28: tum. Xenophanes, qui mente ad- juncta omne praeterea, quod esset in- finitum, Deum voluit esse. That the former passage also is quoted from the Greek, is proved by Krische, Forsch. i. 90. There is a Greek exposition (naturally from a more ancient source) which pretty nearly coincides with it, ap. Theod. Cur. gr. aff. iv. 5, p. 57 Sylb.: E. . . . . ev elval to trav čºmore, ordaipoetóēs ical retepaguévov, où yewvmtöv, &AA' &íðuov kal trautav čkſvntov. Plu- tarch ap. Eus. Pr. Ev. i. 8, 4: Eev. 3& . . . otºre yéveauv otºre pºopæv &rońettrel, &AA’ eival Aéyet to trav &el Šuotov. ei Yêp yiyvouro Tooro, qºmolv, &vaykalov trpo rotºrov wº eival' to uh by §§ oik &v yévoiro, ow8 &v rb pah by trouſ oral ru, ofire Širó G () D AND THE WORLD. 563 kind is incompatible with the pure theism of Xeno- phanes." How do we know that his assertions of the unity, eternity, unlimitedness, and spirituality of God were intended to be understood in a theistic, and not in a pantheistic sense ? His own expressions leave this quite undecided ; but the probabilities, even apart from the testimony of the ancients, are in favour of the pantheistic view. For the Greek gods are merely personified powers of nature and of human life; and, therefore, it was much more obvious for a philosopher who objected to their plurality to unite them in the conception of universal physical force, than in the idea of a God external to the world. Thus we have every reason to suppose that Xenophanes, in his pro- positions concerning the unity of God, intended to rot, whº Švtos yévolt’ &v ri. Sext. Pyrrh. i. 225 (cf. iii. 218): éðo- 'yºdºr.Qe 5& 6 E. . . Šv ćival Tô trav kai rôv 9eów orvpaq v'ſ Toſs traoruv' elva. Śē orgapoetőfi kal &tra67 kal ăuerá8Amtov Kai Aoyuków. Hippo'yt. Refut. i. 14 : Aéyet 8& 6tt ovöèv ºyiveral oióē (p6eſperat oilà è kiveirat, kal &ti év rô Tráv čo Tuv šča, uera- Boxfis. p.mal 6& kai Töv 6eów elval ăţöuov kal Éva kal &Motov trgutm Kal Tretrepaguévov kal ordaipoetën Távtm kal traort rols uopious aio 6 mTukóv. Ga- len, H. Phil. c. 3, p. 234: Éevoſpaumv pièv trepi Trévrov htropnkóta, 80) wa- rto avºra ö& puffvov Tó elva, trøvra ev kal rooto 5trópxelv 0eov, tretrepao- Mévov, Aoyukov, &pietà8Amtov. All these accounts seem to emanate from the same source. The unity of all Being is likewise ascribed to Xenophanes by Alexander Me- taph. 23, 18 Bon. (934 a. 29): Aéºyet uév trepl Eevoq àvous kal Me- Atagov kal IIaouevičov obrot yüp Šv to trav Štreqfivavro. Ibid. 32, 17 (986 b, 8): Töv čv rô by eival 6epuévay . . . Ös too travros pºtas ºpéarea's oiſons' &v fiväevoqāvms re kal Méxiora os kal IIappeviðms. Ibid. 33, 10 (986 b, 17, vide sup. p. 548, 1) To & ‘Evioras’ forov čari Tig irpáros eveival to by eitróv. Cousin, Fragm. Phil. i. 37 sqq.; Karsten, 134 sqq. Similarly Brandis doubts (Gr. Röm. Phil. i. 365) that Xenophanes taught the unity of Being, since he could not have identified the Divided, which manifests itself in the Becoming, with the One simple Being ; and Rrische, Forsch. 94, will not allow him to have been a Pantheist be- cause he would only admit Being, as separated from Becoming, to be the Deity. But it is a question whether Xenophanes distinguished between Being and Becoming so definitely as this would imply. o o 2 564 XENOPHANES. assert at the same time the unity of the world; and from his point of view it is easy to see how the second of these assertions would appear to be directly involved in the first. In his speculations on the cause of all things, he sought that cause, herein agreeing with the popular faith, primarily in the rule of the gods. But he could not reconcile their plurality, restriction, and an- thropomorphic nature with his concept of Deity. At the same time, the unity of the world, which even to the sensible intuition asserts itself in the apparent limita- tion of the world by the vault of heaven, and which deeper reflection discerns in the likeness and inter- connection of phenomena, seemed to him to necessitate the unity of the force that formed the world,'—which force he did not conceive as separate from the world. God and the world are here related to one another as essence and phenomenon. If God is One, things ac- cording to their essential nature must be One ; and conversely the polytheistic religion of nature becomes a philosophic pantheism. In connection with his doctrine of the unity of God, Xenophanes is said to have described the Deity as homogeneous; in other words, he maintained the qualitative simplemess (Einfachheit) of the divine essence simultaneously with * This is indicated not only by Timon in the verses quoted above, but also by Aristotle, l.c., in the words: eis Tov Šxov oipavov &to- 8Aépas, which primarily only assert that Xenophanes exclusively re- garded neither the form nor the matter of things, but fixed his attention without further discrimi- its unity. Although, how- nation of these aspects on the world as a whole ; the words, how- ever, also imply that he arrived at the Unity of God through the con- sideration of the world. This is confirmed by his doctrine of the eternity of the world, which we shall shortly discuss. UNITY OF A LL BEING. 565 ever, this statement is supported by proportionately ancient testimony,' it is questionable whether it is not in this form merely an inference from the words used by Xenophanes in describing the divine knowledge.” On the other hand, the statement that he called the Deity spherical and limited, or contrariwise, as others contend, unlimited and infinite,” contradicts the ex- press declaration of Aristotle and Theophrastus.” It is hardly possible, however, that both these statements can be wholly without foundation. On the one hand, Xeno- phanes attributes to the world infinite extension—for he says that the air above, and the roots of the earth beneath, extend into infinity: * on the other hand, we hear that he, at the same time, describes the universe as a 1. Cf. the quotations on p. 539, 2; 561, 2; 562, 4; 562, 5; from the treatise on Melissus, Timon, and Hippolytus. 2 This conjecture is favoured by the treatise on Melissus, which bºth in its exposition and criticis:m of Xenophanes' doctrine couples the proposition concerning the homogeneous nature of God with the of Aos épév, &c. Cf. c. 8, 977 a. 36 (supra, p. 539, 2); c. 4, 978 a, 3 (after Mull.): éva è? §vta tróvrm āpāv kal &kočev ovačv trpoof- ke: . . . &AA’ to as Totto BoöAetal no ºrdvrm aid 63ved 6al, Öri oiſtws &v BéAtto ta éxot, Šuotos &v távrm. Similarly Timon, in the verses quoted p. 560, 1, connects the igov àirávºrm with the voepérepov jë vómpa. * Wide supra, p. 549. 1; 560, 2; 562, 1. The limitedness of the primitive essence is ascribed by |Philop. Phys. A. 5 (ap. Karsten, p. 126), both to Xenophanes and Parmenides. * Supra, p. 548, 1 ; 543, 1. * He himself, it is true, says this of the earth; cf. Act. Tat. Isag, p. 127 E, Pet. : 'yaims uèv Tóðe treſpas &va, Tâ9 toa- orly Šparat aiðépt trporträdgov, Tô icóra, 6’ &s âtepov icóvei. But Arist. De Coe'o, ii. 12, 294 a, 21, applies to him, when speaking of those who &Ireupov to káta Tijs ºyās elvaí (paau, är" &melpovo irºv é551(300al Aéryovres, Šotrep Eevoq'., the censure of Empedocles against the opinion that &reipova yńs te Bá9m kal 6alpiños aidiip. Similarly, De Mel. c. 2, 976 a, 32: ás kai Eevoqāvms & Teipov tá Te Bá90s Tās 'yńs kal too &épos (pmov eival, &c. The same is repeated by Plut. ap, Eus. Pr. Ev. i, 8, 4 ; Plac. iii. 9, 4 (Galen, c. 21); Hippolyt. i. 14; Kosmas Indicopl. p. 149; Georg. Pachym. p. 118; vide Brandis, Comm. E. 48; Karsten, 1.54; Cousin, 24 sq. 566 XENOPHIA WES. sphere.' But the very contradiction between these two sayings proves that they are not scientific propositions, but incidental utterances which occurred in different portions of the poems of Xenophanes. He may at one time have spoken of the spherical form of the heavens, and at another, of the immeasureable extent of the world beneath, and of the space of the air above, without troubling himself about the mutual compati- bility of these two conceptions. Nor is it probable that he meant to express by either of them any fixed conviction in regard to the shape and extension of the world—still less that they had reference to the Deity. The statement that he declared the world to be un- derived, eternal, and imperishable,” may, with more reason, remind us of the similar definitions of the Deity. The etermity of the world might seem to him to be implied in that of God, because God was to him the immanent cause of the world. But he appears to have attributed etermity to the world, only in a general manner, in regard to its substance; and not to have taught, as a consequence of this, that the wrviverse in its present condition was underived.” Also the pro- position that the All remained like to itself” may have been enunciated by him in regard to the regularity of the course of the world and the invariableness of the universe. But that he absolutely denied all genera- tion and destruction, all change and movement in the * Wide p. 549, 1; 560, 2. IIappavíðms MéA.) &yévvmtov kal * Supra, p. 562, 1, and Plut. &fötov kal & pôaptov rov kóquov. Cf., Plac. ii. 4, 3 (Stob. i. 416), Eevo- however, p. 570, 1. oãvns (Stob. has instead MéAlogos; * Cf. p. 570, 1. in one MS., however, there is writ- * Plut., Cic., Hippol.,and others, ten in the margin, Eevo pdvms, vide p. 562, 5. PHYSICS. 567 world, as more recent authors assert," we cannot think possible. There is no mention of such a denial in ancient authorities or in the fragments of Xenophanes' writings;” and, moreover, a number of statements of a physical nature respecting the origin of individual things, and the changes of the material earth are attributed to this philosopher, while no remark is ever made * in connection with these that, like Parme- nides in his physics, Xenophanes was speaking of illu- sory phenomena, and not of the reality. None of our authorities maintain that he opposed Being to non- Being in the manner of his successor, or taught that Being alone was reality. These physical theories of Xenophanes have scarcely any connection with the fundamental ideas of his philo- sophy. They are isolated observations and conjectures, sometimes pregnant and suggestive, but sometimes of a rudimentary and child-like kind, such as we might expect in the commencement of natural science. We will now, however, shortly state what has been preserved of them. According to some, Xenophanes said that earth was the primitive substance of all things ; according to others, earth and water.” * The references, l. c., vide p. 539, 2. * Aristotle indeed says of the Eleatics generally, &kivmtov eivaí qaqiv, but the subject of &lcívmtov is not to trav, but to Év. * As Braniss says (Gesch. d. Phil. Kant, i. 115), and Ritter i. 477, fancies he sees in Fr. 15, 18. * Both opinions are mentioned by Sextus Math. x. 313 f; Hippol. But the verses on which Refut. x. 6 sq., p. 498, who each quotes the verse of Xenophanes from which they are severally taken, the one from Fr. 8 : éic 'yaíms yúp tróvra kai eis yºu trèvra TeXevtá, the other from Fr. 9: trövtes yao yaims Te Kai úðaros ékºyevöueoróa. Cf. Fr. 10 : yī kal #6ap travé àoroa yívoviral hö& púov- Tai. For the first (cf. Brandis, Comm. 44 sq.; Karsten, 45 sqq.; 508 ACENOPHANES. these statements are founded appear to deal only with terrestrial things,' and, therefore, to assert nothing but what we find very commonly elsewhere.” Ari- stotle, in enumerating the elementary primitive sub- stances of the ancient philosophers, not merely does not mention Xenophames, but says” that none of those philosophers who admitted only one primitive sub- stance, adopted the earth as such. Thus he expressly excludes the first of the above statements; and we cannot suppose him to be confirming the second* when he names the dry and the moist among the primitive substances;” for he repeatedly designates Parmenides as the only philosopher of the Eleatics who, side by side with the One substance, admitted two opposite elements.” On the other hand, later writers had some reason for interpreting the verse of Xenophanes in this sense, since Xenophanes supposed the stars (vide infra) to originate from the vapours of the earth and water. The theory that he regarded the earth itself as a com- bination of air and fire" is certainly incorrect,” and it 146 sqq.) we have Plut. ap. Eus., 150, states), he is right, and l. c.; Stob. Ecl. i. 294; Hippol. i. 14; Theod. Cur. Gr. Aff. ii. 10, p. 22; iv. 5, p. 56; for the second, Sext. Math. ix. 361; Pyrrh. iii. 30; Porph. ap. Simpl. Phys. 41 a ; Philop. Phys. D, 2 (Schol. in Arist. 338 b, 30; 339 a, 5, cf. Sup. p. 272, 2); Ps.-Plut. (possibly Porphyry) V. Hom. 93; Eustath. in Il. vii. 99; Galen, H. Phil. c. 5, p. 243; Epiph. Earp. fid. p. 1087 B. * When, therefore, Sabinus ap. Galen in Hipp. De Nat. Hom. i. p. 25 K, says that Xenophanes de- clared earth to be the substance of men (not of all things, as Karsten, Galen's severe censure is, as Bran- dis acknowledges, undeserved. * We need only remember the words in 1 Mos. 3, 19, or Il. vii. 99 : iſãop kai yata yévola 6e. * Metaph. i. 8, 989 a. * As Porphyry maintains, l.c. * Phys. i. 5, 188 b, 33: of uév ºyèp 6epubu kal juxpov of 6' 5"ypov ical &mpöv (&px&s Aapabávovort). * Metaph. i. 4, 5, 984 b, 1 ; 986 b, 27 Sqq. * Plut. Plac. iii. 9 (Galen, c. 21): éé &épos kai Tupos ovutrayā- !/Cºl. * Brandis, Gr. Röm. Phil. i. PHYSICS. 569 may, perhaps, be in consequence of a similar misappre- hension that the doctrine of the four elements came to be ascribed to him." It was, no doubt, easy for later writers to find their four primitive elements in every cosmology; but this doctrine is distinctly asserted by Aristotle * to have originated with Empedocles, and its connection with the metaphysics of Parmenides is too obvious for us to suppose that a predecessor of Parme- mides should not merely have mentioned in an inci- dental manner fire, water, etc., but should have ex- pressly designated the four elements as the basis of all compound bodies. There is, doubtless, more foundation for the theory that Xenophanes supposed the earth to have passed from a fluid condition into its present solid state, and that in time it would again by means of water be changed into mud. He had observed petrified marine creatures on land, and even on mountains, and knew not how to account for this phenomenon except on the supposition that the world, or at any rate the surface of the world, was subject to a periodical transition from the fluid state to the solid, and back to the fluid state again; in which transition the human race, to- gether with its dwelling place, must sink into the water 372, conjectures that Xenophanes, as often elsewhere, is here con- fused with Xenocrates; but Plut. Fac. lun. 29, 4, p. 944, does not countenance this opinion. Karsten, p. 157, explains the remark by saying that Xenophanes thought air and fire, i.e., steam and heat, were developed out of the earth. The most probable explanation, however, seems to me that of Ritter, i. 479 ; cf. Brandis, Comm El. 47. According to this, the words in their original connection only signify that the earth passed from a fluid condition to a solid by the action of air and of fire. * Diog. ix. 19. * Metaph. i. 4, 985 a, 31. 570 ACENOPHANES. and begin afresh at each restoration of the dry land." He might have brought this theory into connection | Hippolyt. i. 14: 68& E. użiv This yūs trpos thv 6&Aaorgav yewéa 6al 80ket kai Tô xpóvg. ātro roi, jºypot, Aijeg flat, pāorkov touairas #xeiv &Toàelēets, éti év géan yń kal tipegiv eūptorkovtat köyxa, kal év Xupakoú- orals öé év rais Aarouía is Aéyet eūpā06al rôtov ix600s kal qajków, év Šē IIápa, Tâtrov &qºms év tá, 849et Too Atôov, Šv Šē MeXtºrm TAdkas orvu- Távrov 6axagoríov. (These facts of palaeontology seem first to have been observed by Xenophanes; that they gave matter of reflection to later writers may be seen from Herod. ii. 12; Theoph. Fr. 30, 3; Strabo, i. 3, 4, p. 49 sq.) Taura 6é pmol yewéorèal öre travra étrºX6- 6magv trg)\al, röv 5è titrov čv Tó wnxó &mpavóñval, &vaipeia:6al 5& rows âv6pórows travras ātav i y? Icare- vex0elora eis rºv 64Aago'av trnābs 'yávntal, eira tráAlv &pxeo 6ai Tàs 'yevéorea's kal toiro tróat Tots kóa- pious yiver6al cataflāAAew (Dunck. : ſcaragoxhv, perhaps it should be kataAAñAws). Cf. Plut. ap. Eus. Pr. Ev. i. 8, 4 : &lroqatveral 6& kal Tô xpóvº kataqepouévny ovvexós kai kat' àAt yov Thy yīv eis Tºv 6&Aao'o av xopelv. These statements seem too explicit to leave room for Teichmüller's theory that Xeno- crates believed in man's having eternally existed on the earth (Stud. 2. Gesch. d. Begr. 604; Neue Stud, etc. i. 219) There is no evidence of such a theory, and it does not follow from the eternity of the world, even if Xenophanes held that doctrine. For Hippolytus says (and there is no ground for contradicting him) that Xeno- phanes supposed the human race to have, been destroyed at each periodical submerging of the earth, and to have begun anew at each renovation. But even the eternity of the world is not proved to have been a doctrine of Xenophanes, either by the testimony of the Placita, quoted p. 566, 2, or by the statements of more recent authors, quoted p. 562, 5, who make no distinction between what the philosopher asserts about God and what he says of the universe. At any rate, we cannot, on the strength of such evidence, charge Aristotle, who denies that any of his predecessors held the eternity of the world (De Caelo, 1, 10, 279 b, 12) with an error, or, as Teichmüller does, with a malicious and wilful misunderstanding (vide Teichmüller, Neue Stud. etc. i. 218, cf. p. 239 and 229 sqq., dis- cussions which, however, contain nothing new, and pay no regard to my explanation in Hermes, x. 186. sq., nor to that of my present work, p. 352, 3rd edition). In reality there is no irreconcilable contradiction between Aristotle's assertion and the opinion attri- buted to Xenophanes. When Aris- totle speaks of the eternity of the world, he means not merely eternity in regard to its matter, but in re- gard to its form ; the eternity of this our universe; and he therefore reckons Heracleitus, in spite of his famous declaration, among those who believe the world to have had a beginning (cf. inf. vol. ii.). It is impossible that a philosopher like Xenophanes, who held that the earth from time to time sank into the sea, and was periodically formed anew, and that the Sun PHYSICS. 571 with his philosophic opinions through the doctrine that the one divine essence is alone unchangeable, while everything earthly is subject to perpetual change." Later writers see in the innumerable formations of the world an innumerable succession of worlds,” which is certainly incorrect; yet this statement may have been due to the theories of Xenophanes about the constella- tions. He regarded the sun, moon and stars (as well as the rainbow * and other celestial phenomena)," as and stars arose afresh each day and night, and again disappeared, could have conceived this world as having had no beginning. He might say that the All, i.e., the collective mass of matter, had no beginning; but the form assumed by this matter he must have Sup- posed to change. Aristotle, there- fore, could not have ascribed to him the doctrine of the eternity of the world in his (Aristotle's) scrise, any more than to Heracleitus and Empedocles. Diog. (vide infra, note 2) and Hippolytus (i.e. the authors whom they follow) find in him the theory of many (succes- sive) worlds. * We have seen the same in Ppicharmus, p. 531, 1. * Diog. ix. 19 : kóopovs 6 &treſ- povs & TapaxN &ictovs 6é. Instead of &mapa NA. Karsten reads obic & Tap., Cobet trapa NAdictovs. If we read &rapañAdkrovs, we make Xeno- phanes to have held that each suc- cessive world was exactly like its predecessor, as the Stoics thought (cf. Pt. iii. a, 141, 2 A); according to the reading of Karsten and Cobet, he must have denied this. Brobably both readings are incor- rect, and &TrapaxNdiktovs or oik &TrapaxAdkrovs may have been evolved out of some unimportant expression by a later writer who, when he heard of Xenophanes' in- numerable worlds, immediately wished to know how he regarded the vexed question of their likeness or unlikeness. Cousin, p. 24, translates &tapańAdictous as ‘ºm- 'mobile,’ and understands by the âtelpot kóa plot &trapdx?\arctoi the immeasurabie substructure of the earth, which naturally has no con- cern with either view. Stob. Ecl. i. 496 (supra, p. 262, 3), and after the same authority, Theod. Cur. Gr. Aff. iv. 15, p. 58, class Xeno- phanes, Anaximander, Anaximenes, etc., and Democritus and Epicurus together (without farther distinc- tion) as adherents of the doctrine of innumerable worlds. * Fr. 13 ap. Eustath. in Il. xi. 27, and other Scholiasts: #v T’’Ipu, kaxéovoſt, vépos ical tooto tréquke tropºpúpeov kai pouvºiceov ical XAwpov iöégéal. 4 Stob. i. 580; Plac. iii. 2, 12 (under the title : trepi kopamtöv kai 6tattévrav Kal rôv Tototrov) : E. trövta rā rotavra veſpóv Tretupa- puévav avathuata à Kiväuata (trixhu. Cf. Plac. ii. 25, 2; Stob. i. 510). 572 XENOPHANES. aggregations of burning and luminous vapours, in a word as fiery clouds," which at their setting were extin- guished like embers, and at their rising were kindled,” or rather formed, anew ; * this occurred likewise, he thought, in solar and lunar eclipses.” These masses of vapour (this is, at any rate, expressly said in regard to the sun) were not supposed to move in a circle around the earth, but in an endless straight line above it ; and if the course appears to us circular, this is only an optical delusion, as in the case of the other clouds which, when they approach the Zenith, seem to our eyes to ascend, and when they go under the horizon, to sink. It follows from this that new stars must be continually appearing above our horizon, and that parts of the earth widely separated from each other must be enlightened by different sums" and moons. Concerning lightning and the Dioscuri, cf. Stob. p. 514, 592; Plut. Plac. ii. 18; Galen, c. 13. | Stob. Eel. i. 522: E. &h vegów Tetrupwaévov eival Töv #Alov . . ©eóppartos év toºs puquico's yéypa- q'ev (Töv #Atov eival, after Xeno- phanes) éic truptătov učv Tów avva- 6poiſouévov čk tās inſpås àvaðupid- orews a vuaôpoićvrav Šē Töv #Atov. Similarly as to the moon, p. 550. The same is asserted in Hippol. l. c.; Plut. ap. Eus. !. c.; Plac. ii. 20, 2, 25, 2; Galen, H. phil. c. 14, 15. Instead of Öypå &vaðuptaois, Galen has £mpol &tuoi. Cf. on this point, Karsten, p. 161 sq. * Achill. Tat. Isag. in Arat. c. 11, p. 133: E. §§ Aéyet toys &a répas ěk vegóv ovved tâval épatrúpov Kal or 6évvvoróat kal &vátteorðal &v6eakas kal &te uév &rtoviral pav- Taqiau juás éxeiv &vatoxfis, Šte 6& ãorel - o Bévvvvrat 550 eas. Somewhat to the same effect, Stob. i. 512; Plut. Plac. ii. 13, 7 ; Galen, c. 13, p. 271; Theod. Cur. Gr. Aff. iv. 19, p. 59; Hippol. l. c. : Töv Šē #Atov ék wikpóv Tuptătwv &6poiſouévov 'y(vegöal ka0 €káortmu juépav. * Wide p. 572, 5. 4 Stob. i. 522, 560; Plut. Plac. ii. 24, 4 ; Galen, c. 14, p. 278; Schol. ad Plato Rep. 498 A. (p. 409 Bekk.). * Such is the inference from Stob. i. 534 (Plac. ii. 24, 7; Galen, c. 14); E. troXAous eival #Aious ſcal orexh, as kata. Tä k\{uata Tůs yńs kai &motouts ical (&vas, karū 6é Tuva kalpöv čktíttetv Töv Štokov eis Tuva &trotophy Tās yńs owk oikov- Mévnv Šq’ huàv, kal oitos éotrepel revep Satočvra ékAeriptu Ütroºpaíve vº ô 8' airbs Tov #xtov eis &treupov učv trpoiéval Solceiv Šē kukAéto 6a, 61& Thy PHYSICS. 573 As to the rest of the physical propositions attributed to Xenophanes, some, it is certain, do not belong to him," and others contain too little that is characteristic of his doctrine, to require particular mention.” &méa rariv. Cf. Hippol. l.c. : &lret- pous jiàious elva, kal areAjivas. That Xenophanes really entertained these notions would not be ade- quately proved by such recent and untrustworthy evidence, if the agreement of all these cosmological indications and their peculiar cha- racter belonging to the first child- hood of astronomy did not vouch for their truth. Even the obvious suspicion of some confusion with FIeracleitus must vanish on closer examination, for the ideas of the two philosophers, though in many respects similar, have much that is essentially distinct. The remark of Karsten, p. 167, that Xeno- phanes could not have believed there were several suns and moons in the heavens at the same time, and that consequently this state- ment must have arisen from a con- fusion between snccessive suns and moons, and suns and moons side by side with one another.—is re- futed by what has been said in the text. Teichmüller (Stud. 2. Gesch. d. Begr. 601, 621) observes that since the earth, according to Xeno- phanes, was unlimited in a down- ward direction, the heavens could not revolve around it, and conse- quently Xenophanes must have denied the rotation of the heavens, but this is not to the point. The infinite extent of the earth (con- ceived as shaped like a cylinder) downward, did not interfere with the notion of the stars revolving around it in orbits which, some- times rising above the plane of The the horizon, sometimes sinking below it, turn around the earth laterally, provided only that the inclination of these orbits in re- gard to the horizon were not such as to cause the stars to go under the earth itself. That the revolution of the heavens is lateral was the opinion also of Anaxi- menes, Anaxagoras, Diogenes, and Democritus. * For instance, the statement of the Pseudo-Galen (H. Phil. c. 13), that Xenophanes believed all the orbits of the stars to lie in the same plane ; in regard to a pas- sage where Stob. i. 514, and Plut. Plac. ii. 15, have more correctly Xenocrates instead of Xenophanes, and the assertion of Cicero, Acad. ii. 39, 123, repeated by Lactantius, Instit. iii. 23, and defended by Cousin, 22, that the moon was said by Xenophanes to be inhabited. Brandis, Comm. 54, 56, and Kar- sten, p. 171, remark that both these authors confuse Xenophanes with other philosophers (e.g. Anaximander, Anaxagoras, Philo- laus). * We are told that he attri- buted the salt taste of sea water to its mixture with terrestrial elements (Hippol. l. c.); clouds, rain, and wind, he thought, arose from vapours, which the sun's heat caused to escape from the sea (Stob. extracts from Joh. Damasc. Parall. i. 3.; Floril. vol. iv. 151, Mein. ; Diog. ix. 19); the moon shines by her own light (Stob. i. 556), and has no influence on the 574 MENOPHANES. ethical portions of his fragments cannot, strictly speak- ing, be included in his philosophy, because admirable and philosophical as is the spirit revealed in them, he never brought his ethics into scientific connection with the universal bases of his cosmical theory. The poet censures the former luxury of his compatriots; he deplores on the other hand that bodily strength and agility bring more honour to a man than wisdom, which is far more valuable to the state;” he disapproves oaths as a means of proof, because he sees in them a reward for godlessness.” He advocates cheerful feasts, seasoned with pious and instructive talk, but he condemns empty conversation, together with the mythical creations of the poets.” Although this betrays the friend of science and the enemy of myths, yet on the whole these say- ings do not transcend the point of view of the popular gnomic wisdom. It would be more important, were the assertion correct, that Xenophames either wholly denied the possibility of knowledge, or restricted it to the doctrine of the Deity; or, as others say, that he recognised the truth of the perception of reason only, and not of the perception of Sense.” earth (ibid. 564). The soul, ac- The expressions, Wit. Pud. 5, p. 530. cording to the ancient notion, he considered to be air (Diog. ix. 19; cf. Tert. De An. c. 43). Brandis Comm. El. 37, 57, deduces from this passage, and Xen. Fr. 3, that Xenophanes placed vows above the Juxh, and the ppéves above vows ; but I can find it neither in Dio- genes nor Xenophanes, nor can I consider it to be the real doctrine of this philosopher. 1 Fr. 20, ap. Athen. xii. 324 b; cf. the anecdotes, ap. Plut. De * Fr. 19 ; ap. Athen. x. 413. * Arist. Rhet. i. 15, 1377 a, 19, of which Karsten most arbitrarily makes a verse. * Fr. 17, 21; ap. Athen. ii. 54 e; xi. 462 c. 782 a (1036 Dind.). * Diog. ix. 20: pmol 5& Xortov Tpætov airby eitreºv &karáAmirt’ eival Tà travra, TAavdépevos. Ibid. ix. 72 of the Pyrrhonists: oi, whv &AA& Ical =evoq'dums, etc., kar’ airobs aſke- Tikol Tuxávovoiv. Didymus, ap. Stob. Ecl. ii. 14: Xenophanes first SCEPTIOISM. B75 however, from which the statement is derived have by no means this scope and compass. Xenophanes ob- serves that truth is only discovered by degrees." He thinks that perfect certainty of knowledge is not pos- sible; if even a man should hit upon the truth in a . matter, he is never absolutely certain that he has done so ; and, therefore, Xenophanes designates his own views, even on the weightiest questions, merely as pro- babilities.” But this modesty of the philosopher ought not to be mistaken for a sceptical theory, though it taught that és àpa 6eys usu olös Thy ax#9elav, Sókos 3' étrl Tägt Té- rvictat. Sext. Math. vii. 48, f: Kal 8% &veixov učv airò [to Kpltfiptov] Eevoqāvmste, etc. Similarly Pyrrh. ii. 18: &v Eevoſp. uèv Kará tipas eitrov rávra &karáxmirta, etc. Ibid. 110 : Eevoq'. 68 kata tows &s étépa's airby Émyovuévous . . . baſveta, ph trägav karáAmply &vaipeiv, &A^& +}v 3rigºrmuovukáv Telcaláštártotov, &moxetiret thv Šoćaotiv. According to this, adds Sextus, he would have made Aéryos 60&aatös the criterion. The former theory is adopted by Hippol. l. c.; oitos épm ſpºros &karaxmiſtav elva, tróvrov, Epiph. Erp. Fid. 1087 B: elva. 3. . . . oščev &Am6és, etc., and Plut, ap. Eus. l. c. : &lroſpatveral 6* Kal tăs airò%gets ſevöeſs kal Ka86Nov giv abraſs kal airby Tov A670V ÖlašáA- Aet; the second by Proclus in Tin. 78 B. Disagreeing with both, Timon censures Xenophanes (vide infra, p. 576, 1) for admitting on the one hand the incognisability of things, and on the other the unity of Being; and the Hist. Phil. of Galen, c. 3, p. 234, says the same of him. Aristocles lastly (Eus. Pr. Fv. xiv. 17, 1) includes his point of view with that of the other Eleatics and Megarics in the pro- position: Öeiv Tâs uév aic:6%aeus kai tês q'avtaatas katağäAAetv, airtó 5è uóvov Tó A6).4 Trioſteſſelv. In the utterance of Aristotle with which this passage is connected (infra, § Melissus) Melissus alone is in question. It has already been shown (p. 531, 1 ; 558, 1) that Arist. Me- taph. iv. 5, Poet. 25 has no connec- tion with it. - 1 Fr. 16 b ; Stob. Ecl. i. 224 ; Floril. 39, 41 :— où to &r' àpxis ºrdvra 6eol 0umroſs ūréðelčav, &AA& xpóvá, ºntoâvres éqevpto Kovoſiv ãueivov. * Fr. 14, ap. Sext. l. c. :— kal rô ačv oſſu oraq’s oiſtus &vhp ºyévet' oi,6é Tus égºral eióðs, &pſpl 9eóv Te kal &gora Aéyo Trepl travrov. ei Y&p kai Tà uðAtata tºxoi Tetexe- opévov eitröv, aërës 6aſºs oik olòe 56tcos 3' étri Trāat térvictat (to have an opinion is free to all), ap. Fr. 15; Plut. Qu Conv. ix. 14, 7 : Tajra öeóóšaotai Wěv éotkóta Toſs étáuouai. 576 XENOPHANES. arose, no doubt, from a sceptical temperament. For the uncertainty of knowledge is not here based on a general enquiry into the intellectual faculty of man, it is simply maintained as the result of personal experi- ence; consequently, the philosopher is not hindered, by the consideration of it, from advancing his theological and physical propositions with full conviction. Even the later division of the cognition of reason from the deceptive perception of sense has not been made as yet —philosophic theories are placed on an equality with all other theories; for this division is founded by the Eleatics on the denial of Becoming and Plurality which the senses show us ; and to this denial, as we have already seen, Xenophanes did not proceed." * This is otherwise explained by Cousin, p. 48 sq., and by Kern, Beitr. 4; Xenoph. 13. Cousin thinks that the verses of Xeno- phanes refer to the polytheistic notions of his contemporaries, and that Xenophanes was only scepti- cal in regard to these. But his words seem to have a more general meaning, and his criticism of poly- theism cannot be called sceptical, as his attitude is not uneertain to- wards it, but hostile. Kern is of opinion that Xenophanes distinctly enunciated his doctrine of the One only in his later life, after having long contented himself with doubt- ing the views of others. In sup- port of this, he appeals to Timon's verses, ap. Sext. Pyrrh. i. 224, which represents him as complaining: és ical éyèv čqe^ov rvicivot v6ov &vti- Boxforal àuqorepô8Aerros' 30Åſm 6' 636 &amath9qv trpeg Svyev’s éréov kal &piev6%ptoros (unmindful, proba- bly) &mdams orkertoovvhs. &ntrm yap, etc. (vide sup. p. 562, 4). But Trperflvyevils does not imply that he first arrived at the theory of the unity of Being in his old age, having previously been a sceptic, but that in spite of his age (or also from the weakness of age) he had maintained the standpoint of scep- ticism. This could not have been said if he had brought forward his doctrine of the Unity of Being at the same time and in the same poem, as the utterances (quoted above) which have a sceptical in- terpretation. He himself, Fr. 14 (vide previous note), in the words which sound most sceptical, refers to what he had taught respecting the gods and the world (for even if &publ 6eów is primarily to be con- nected with eið3s, the words ‘con- cerning the gods, and concerning all of which I speak,’ imply that he had also spoken of the gods); we can- not, therefore, suppose that his sceptical utterances belong to an earlier epoch than his dogmatical. CHARACTER OF HIS DOCTRINE. 577 There is all the less reason for ascribing to him, as some of the ancient writers do, logical enquiries as well as physical,' or for classing him with the later Eristics.” His doctrine is rather Physics in the ancient and more comprehensive sense, and though it is far removed from other pwrely physical theories, yet its physical character comes out so clearly, when we compare it with the more abstract propositions of Parmenides, that it has been not inaptly described as the link of transition from the Ionian enquiry to the completed Eleatic doc- trime of pure Being.” Xenophanes, according to Theo- phrastus, was himself a disciple of Anaximander," and there is nothing against the theory that he was first in- duced by that philosopher to study the nature and causes of the world. It is true that he followed his predeces- sor only in regard to a few comparatively subordinate points, whereas the main tendency of his thought pur- sued another course, and led to other results. Like Anaximander, he supposed the earth and its inhabi- tants to have originated from the drying up of the primitive slime;” Anaximander held that the universe alternately sprang from the primitive matter, and | Sext. Math. vii. 14 : Töv 6é the system of Xenophanes a union 6tuep? Thy pixooroq tav Štroorma'apaé- vav E. Lev ć KoMoq &vios to puorukov ãua kal Aoyukov, &s part Tives, Hetfipxeto. * Aristocles, ap. Eus. Pr. Ev. xi. 3, 1: E. 5è kal of ātr Čketvov robs épio Tikovs ſcivioravires A6-yovs troXby uèv évé8&Aov favy You rois qux006 pois, où pºvěrápuráv yé riva Boh9elav. * Brandis, Gr. Röm. Phil. i. 359. The view of Cousin is less correct (l.c. p. 40, 46). He sees in WOL. I. of Ionian and Pythagorean ele- ments, but the theological doctrines of Xenophanes are more likely to have come from him to the Pytha- goreans than vice versä. The chronology also is against this theory, especially if Cousin is right in placing Xenophanes' birth in the year 617 B.C. * Cf. Diog. ix. 21, quoted infra, Parm, note 1. * Cf. p. 569, with p. 255, 251, 1. P P 578 MENOPHANES. returned to it again, and Xenophanes taught the same in regard to the earth, which for him is the most im– portant part of the universe. His opinion that the heavenly bodies are merely masses of vapour' reminds us of the earlier doctrine that their fires are nourished by the exhalations of the earth ; * and the infinite extension of the earth beneath, and the air above,” recalls the unlimitedness of Anaximander's primitive matter. But the theories of Xenophanes about the universe generally are widely different from the system of Anaximander. Anaximander makes, at any rate, an attempt to explain the formation and constitution of the universe in a physical manner. Of Xenophanes we are told nothing of the kind, and his conception of the stars shows clearly how little the naturalistic treatment of phenomena suited his mental tendency. He enquires, indeed, concerning the principle of things, but the enquiry immediately takes a theological turn, leading him to test the current opinions concerning the beings in whom the ultimate cause is usually sought, to the criticism of the belief in gods—and thus to the thought of the One eternal unchangeable Being who is not to be compared with any finite thing. His philosophy is only maturalistic in regard to its point of departure; in its development it becomes a theological metaphy- 1. Cf. p. 252. * According to the Plag. ii. 25, 2, Xenophanes thought the moon was a vépos retrixmuévov, and that the comets and similar phenomena were trixhuata vegöv, in the same way that Anaximander, according to Stob. Ecl. i. 510, regarded the stars as triańuara &épos. This seems to me of little consequence; for we do not know whether Xenophanes himself used the expression; and if he did, his meaning could not have been the same as Anaximan- der's. He meant a firm combina- tion, and Anaximander merely a loose aggregation. * Sup. p. 565, 5. CHARACTER OF HIS DOCTRINE. §79 sic." But since the primitive essence is not apprehended in a purely metaphysical manner as Being without further specific determination, but theologically as the Deity, or as the divine spirit ruling in the universe, Xenophanes is not obliged to dispute the reality of the Many and the changeable, or to declare the pheno- menon to be a deceptive appearance. He says, it is true, that every thing in its deepest principle is eternal and One, but he does not deny that, side by side with the One, there exists a plurality of derived and transitory things; and he passes over, apparently without observing it, the difficulty which, from his own point of view, is involved in this theory and the problem which it pro- poses for enquiry. Parmenides was the first who recog- i Teichmüller (Stud. 2. Gesch. d. Begr. 612) is so far quite right in his remark that ‘metaphysics with Xenophanes sprang, not from the consideration of nature, but from the conflicts of Reason with the existing theology.” Only it is rather inconsistent with this that we should be told also, in relation to Xenophanes (ibid. 620, 598), “If we would understand the meta- physics of the ancient philosophers, we must first study their theories of nature.' Even in itself, as it seems to me, this proposition is not universally true of the pre- Socratics (it is only in a certain sense that we can ascribe to them any distinction between metaphy- sics and natural enquiries at all); and among those to whom it is in- applicable, I should name Parme- nides, Heracleitus, and Xenophanes. I cannot discover from Teichmül- ler's exposition in what manner his theories of the Deity and the unity of the world can have arisen out of the very few physical propositions that have come down to us. Even Anaximander's &meipov is in no way connected with them. Teichmüller (p. 620 sq.) indeed thinks that Xenophanes denied the movement of the universe, because the circular motion ascribed to it by Anaxi- mander would only be possible if the earth hung in the midst of the air, and this seemed to him much too improbable. The idea appears to me far-fetched, and it has two considerations against it—1, that Xenophanes (as observed on p. 570, 1), though he denied the crea- tion and destruction of the world, yet expressly maintained a periodi- cal change in its conditions; and 2, that Anaximander (cf. p. 252, 1) did not believe in a circular movement of the universe, and the rotation of the heavens, which, he taught, would be quite compatible with the un- limitedness of the subterranean region of the earth (cf. p. 572, 5). P P 2 580 PARMENIDEs. mised this, and who carried out the Eleatic doctrine in opposition to the popular notions with logical consis- tency, and regardless of results. PARMENIDES. I THE great advance made by the Eleatic philosophy in .* _* | Parmenides of Elea was the son of Pyres or Pyrrhes, Theo- phrast, ap. Alex. in Metaph. i. 3, 984 b, 1; Diog. ix. 21; Suid. Sub voc.; Theod. Cur. Gr. aff, iv. 7, p. 57; also ap. Diog. ix. 25, where (ac- eording to the usual reading) he is called the son of Teleutagoras; whether, with Cobet, who may or may not be following the evidence of MSS., we omit the words IIöpm- ros rov 6& IIappeviðmu, or with ECarsten, Phil. Graec. Rell. i. b, 3, alter their position thus: Závov 'EAedºrms' rootov'AtroAAóöwpós (pmotu eival év xpoviko’s púa'el uèv Texev- Tayópov, 0éget 5& IIappevſöov. Tov 6& IIappeviðmu IIºpmros. He came of a wealthy and distinguished family, and we are told first joined the Pythagoreans. At the instance of Ameinias, the Pytha- gorean, he embraced the philoso- phic life, and conceived such a veneration for Diochaites, likewise a Pythagorean, that he erected a mpgov to him at his death (Sotion ap. Diog. l. c.). By more recent authors he is himself called a Py- thagorean (Strabo, 27, 1, 1, p. 252: 'Exéav . . ; fis IIapuevſöms kal Závov čºyévovro &vöpes IIv6ayópelot. Callimachus ap. Procl. in Parm. t. iv. 5 Cous. ; Iambl. V. P. 267, cf. 166; Anon. Phot. Cod. 249, p. 439 a, 35), and a Parmenidean life Parmenides ultimately consists in this, that the unity is spoken of as synonymous with the Pythagorean (Cebes, Tab. c. 2: IIv6ayópelów Tuva kal IIappeviðetov émAwk&s 8tov). In his philosophic opinions, however, he mostly re- sembled Xenophanes, whose scholar and acquaintance he is asserted to have been, though less decidedly by Aristotle (Metaph. i. 5, 986 b, 22: 6 yap II. Totºrov AéyeTai plaðm- ths) than by others: Plut. ap. Eus. Pr. Ev. i. 8, 5; Eus. ibid. xiv. 17, 10, cf. x. 14, 15 ; Clem. Strom. i. 301 D; Diog. l.c.; Simpl. Phys. 2 a ; Sext. Math. vii. 111 ; Suid. IIapp.; on the other hand, Theo- phrast, ap. Alea’, l. c. says only: toūrq [Eevoſpavel] triyevópevos IIappa. He could not, however, have remained altogether unac- quainted with him, as both lived to— gether for some time in Elea. The two assertions are compatible, if we suppose Parmenides to have been closely and personally connected with the Pythagoreans, and to have learned much from them in regard to his moral life; but in regard to his philcsophic convic- tion, to have been chiefly in- fluenced by Xenophanes, and, like Empedocles, to have approved of the Pythagorean life, but not to have been an adherent of the Py- thagorean system. (This is pro- bably the meaning of Diogenes, JHIS LIFE. 581 of all Being, the fundamental idea of the Eleatics, was apprehended by him in a much more definite manner l. c., when he says: äuws 6' oiv âkośa as 'cal Eevoq'dvovs oilk hkoxoiſ- 9morew airó, &coxov6eºv designating here, as also in what follows, inti- mate and personal relation.) On the other hand, it is inconsistent with all that we know as to the date of the two philosophers, that Parmenides should have been taught by Anaximander. When, therefore, Diog. l. c. says: IIappe- wièms 5uſikovore Eeloq &vows, routov Oeóqpaotos év rà éxitoufi 'Avašt- advöpov pngly &Kotoral, rotºrov must not be applied to Parmenides, but to Xenophanes; and when Suidas says of Parmenides that, according to Theophrastus, he was a disciple of Anaximander, he has evidently misunderstood the passage of Diog. which he quotes. There is a sur- prising statement (cf. Marc. Ca- pella, De Nupt. M. et V. i. 4) by some scholastics that Parmenides learned logic and astronomy in Egypt, on which cf. Brandis, Comm. 172; Rarsten, p. 11 sq., Notices et Ea:- traits des Manuscrits, t. xx. b, 12 (from Remigius of Auxerre); cf. Schol. in Arist. 533 a, 18 sqq. The time at which–Parmenides lived is, indeed, known in general, but to fix "it précisely is difficult. Diog. ix. 23, places his prime (doubtless after Apollodorus) in the 69th Olympiad (504-500 B.C.), and, therefore, to assign the 79th (in accordance with Scaliger ap. Harsten, p. 6; Fülleborn, Beitr. vi. 9 sq.; Stallbaum Plat. Parm. 24 A sq.; Theſet. 183 E. Soph. 217 C) appears to me exceedingly hazardous. Whether Apollodorus, however, founds his calculation on definite data, and not merely (as Diels thinks (Rh. Mus. xxxi. 34 sq.), on the general synchronism with Heracleitus, is uncertain. On the other hand, Plato (Parm, 127 A sq.; Theaet. 183 E: Soph. 217 C) represents Socrates in very early youth (ordóðpa véos) as meet- ing Parmenides and Zeno in Athens; Parmenides being then about 65, and Zeno about 40: and on this occasion the dialectic dis- cussions in the dialogue bearing his name are placed in the mouth of Parmenides. Supposing So- crates at that date to have been only 15, we should have the year of Parmenides' birth in 519 or 520 B.c. If, with Grote (Hist. of Gr. viii. 145 sq., ed. of 1872), we assign as the date of the dialogue 448 B.C., we should get 513 B.C. If with Hermann (De Theoria Del. 7; De Philos. Ion. Ætatt. 11), we ac- cept the remark of Synesius (Calv. Encom. c. 17) that Socrates was 25 years old, as historical evidence, we should get 510 B.C. But there is nothing to justify our accepting this Platonic exposition as histori- cal evidence. Even Athen. ix. 505 sq. and Macrobius, Sat. i. 1, question its chronological accuracy. For if the content 3 of the conver- sations said to have been held be- tween Socrates and Parmenides are not historical,—if the gist of the Platonic story, viz., the definite scientific influence of Parmenides upon Socrates, must certainly be an invention, why should not its setting, the meeting of the two men, and the more specific circumstances of this meeting, to which their particular ages at that time be- long, be also an invention ? This bj82 PARMEN IDES. than by Xenophanes, and that it was based upon the concept of Being. Xenophanes, together with the would not make Plato guilty of a ‘deliberate falsehood’ (Brandis, i. 376) in the one case more than in the other ; otherwise we must also condemn the apparent cir- cumstantiality of the openings of the Protagoras, Theaetetus, Sym- posium, and other dialogues as falsehood. The poetical license is equally great in both instances. Alberti (Socrates, p. 16 sq.) is of opinion that Plato did not so entirely renounce the laws of pro- bability as to make his fictions contain historical impossibilities. In reply to this, we need only ask, What, then, are all the numerous and striking anachronisms in Plato's dialogues (cf. Zeller, Abh. d. Berl, Acad. 1873; Hist, Phil. Kl. 79 sqq.) but historical impossi- bilities? What can be conceived more improbable than that So- crates and the Eleatic philosophers held all the conversations which Plato puts into their mouths 2 How do we know that Plato and his disciples were sufficiently ac- quainted with the precise chrono- logy of Parmenides to make these statements, though they may have been invented, appear impossible to them ż Why, lastly, should Plato have hesitated to represent Par- menides as younger than he really was, while he makes Solon, in a similar case, and with the same appearance of historical exactitude (Tim. 20 E sqq.), at least twenty years too young 2 There would be amply sufficient motive for Plato's exposition even if, in fact, Par- menides never met Socrates, or came to Athens (a point we can- not decide). To explain to his disciples the relation of the Eleatic system to his own, it was necessary that Socrates should be confronted with the teachers of the Eleatic doctrine, and, preferably, with the head of the school; and if once this were done, the rest inevitably follows. (Cf. Steinhart, Plato's Werke, iii. 24 sqq.; and Zeller; Abhand'ung, p. 92 sqq.) The histo- rical accuracy of the Platonic ex- position was at first defended by Steinhart, Allg. Enc. v. Ersch. und Grüber, sect. iii. B, xii. 233 sq., and by myself, Plat. Stud. 191. In its favour, vide Schleiermacher, Plato's W. W. i. 2, 99; Karsten, Parm. 4 sq.; Brandis, l. c.; Mul- laeh, Fragm. Philos. Gr. i. 109; Schuster, Heraklit. 368, &c. Cousin, Fragm. Philos. i. 51 sq., would, at any rate, hold to the presence of the two Eleatics in Athens, though he fixes their date in Ol. 79, and gives up their con- versation with Socrates. Schaar- schmidt does the same, while contesting the genuineness of the Parmenides. Perhaps the state- ments of Eusebius, Chron. Ol. 80, 4, and Syncellus, 254 C, are traceable to Plato: these place Parmenides, together with Empe- docles, Zeno, and Heracleitus, in the period mentioned. On the other hand, Eus. Ol. 86, Syric. 257 C, make him even 25 years later, contemporary with Democritus, Gorgias, Prodicus, and Hippias. We know nothing more of the life of Parmenides, except that he gave laws to the Eleans (Speusippus ap. Diog. ix. 23; cf. Strabo, l. c.), which they swore afresh every year to obey (Plut. JBEING, 583. \,; unity of the world-forming force or deity, had also maintained the unity of the world; but he had not therefore denied either the plurality or the variability of particular existences. Parmenides shows that the All in itself can only be conceived as One, because all that exists is in its essence the same. But for this reason he will admit nothing besides this One to be a Adv. Col. 32, 3, p. 1126). It does not follow, however, from this that he only applied himself to philo- sophy in his later life (Steinhart, A. Enc. l. c. 234), which is not asserted by any of our authorities. The opinion of Deutinger (Gesch. d. Philos, i. a, 358 sqq.), that he was originally a Physicist, and was first led to his doctrine of the One by Anaxagoras, is as contrary to chronological possibility as to the internal relation of the two sys- tems. All antiquity is unanimous in paying homage to the personal and philosophical character of Par- menides. The Eleatic in Plato, Soph. 237 A, calls him IIapuevſöms ô uéyas; Socrates says of him in Theſet. 183 E: II. 6é uot païveral, Tö tot; 'Oujipov, aiãolós re &ua 6euvós Te . . . kai pºol épáum 8400s ri éxetv travrátraort yewvalov ; in Parm. 127 B, he is described as an old man of noble appearance; and Aristotle, Metaph. i. 5, 986 b, 25, gives him decidedly the preference scientific- ally to Xenophanes and Melissus; not to mention more recent authors. Parmenides expounded his philo- sophic opinions in a didactic poem, fragments of which have been col- lected and explained by writers mentioned sup. p. 534, 3, and also by Theod. Watke, Parm. Vel. Doc- trina (Berl. 1864), and by H. Stein, Symb. Philol. Bonnens. 763 sqq. . Callimachus, according to Diogenes ix. 32, doubted its genuineness; but that is uncertain and unimportant for us. The title trepi pāorews, which cannot with certainty be deduced from Theoph. ap. Diog. viii. 55, is ascribed to the work by Sext. Math. vii. 111; Simpl. De Caelo, 249 b, 23; Schol. in Arist. 509 a, 38, and others. Porph. Antr. Nymph. c. 22, calls it ºpworthcov; Suidas purioxolyſa ; the Platonic designation repº Töv Švros ëvrov (Procl. in Tim. 5 A, cf. Simpl. Phys. 9 a) refers only to the first part; the koo woxoyia (Plut. Amator. 13, 11, p. 756) to the second. These two parts we shall discuss further on. The statement that Parmenides also wrote in prose (Suidas, sub voc.) is no doubt based upon a misunderstanding of what Plato says in Soph. 237 A. The supposed prose fragment in Simpl. Phys. 76, is certainly spu- rious. The ancients recognised only one work of this philosopher, vide Diog. Proom. 16; Plato, Parm. 128 A, C; Theophr. ap. Diog. viii. 55; Clemens, Strom. v. 552 C; Simpl. Phys. 31 a. Opinions as to the artistic character of the work are to be found in Cic. Acad. ii. 23, 74; Plut. De Aud. po. c. 2; De Audiendo, c. 13 (p. 16, 45); Procl. in Parm. iv. 62 Cous. Further de- tails respecting the work and its history are given, ap. Karsten, l, c. 15 sqq. * - 584 PARMENIDES. reality. Only Being is: non-Being can as little exist as it can be expressed or conceived; and it is the greatest mistake, the most incomprehensible error, to treat Being and non-Being, in spite of their undeniable difference, as the same." 1 Parm. V. 33 :- ei ö’ &y éyòv épéo, kópugal 5& ort, Hobov &Kočoas, airep 660) woovat Suđoriós eiori voſīoal. 35. ii aev, 3ra's #orriv re kal &s oëk ëort uh elval, Tretë00s éorri kéAev60s, &Am6eim yop - Štrºměe. # 6’ &s oik torriv re kal &s xpedºv éort uh elval, rhv 5é rot pp4(w travareiðéa Šuplev &Tapiróv' oùre yöp &v yuoins ró ye pºl éöv, où 7&p équicrov (al. &vvorov), 40. otre (ppáorals' to yap airb voeir éorriv re kal éival. That does not mean, however, ‘Thinking and Being are the same; " the context shows that ēorruy is to be read, and the translation should stand thus: “For the same thing can be thought and can be,” only that which can be, can be thought. W. 43: Xph ºrb Aéyetu ºrb voelv ºrb by ăupreval (So Simpl. Phys. 19 a ; Mullach prefers Aéyetv re voev r" éov šup. Stein's reading is still simpler: xph to Aéryew to vaeiv t” ébv čupeval. Grauert, ap. Brandis, i. 379, reads: xpſ, ore Aéyeuvre voeſt, T', ºbv čupeval, or, xpſ tº Aéyeiv. It is impossible to decide with cer- tainty, as we do not know the con- nection in , which these verses originally stood). #orri yüp elval plmöèv 3 oikelval' ré ré ore ppdged 6al &voya' 45. Trpárov 'rior3’ & p’ 6600 31ſhortos elpye vámua, - This once recognised, every- airãp Štreit' &mb ris, hy 6% Bporol eiðóres oběšv - trädgourai 6trºpavor Šumzavín yöp ºv aútáv oth9eoriv ióðvel TAaykrov v6ov. of 83 q}opeſſivrat kwoboi Špios Tv tº of re reëmiróres, &kpita púAa, ois to tréAew re kal oikeival rairov vevåuto rai k’ oi rairov, révrwv 3& Traxſurporás éorri RéAev60s. V. 52:- où yöp uhrore rotiro Safis, eival uh éóvra (This verse I agree with Mullach in placing here. His enumeration differs from that of Karsten by one. In regard to the reading, rooro Safis eival seems to me the most proba- ble, according to Bergk's observa- tions, Zeitschr, fir Alterthumsw. 1854, p. 438. Stein, l. c. 485, pre- fers ðapſ.) &AA& ort rāoró’ &p' 6600 Sºhaios elpye vómua, Amöé o' é00s roxbºreupov 66öv karū, rfivöe 8táo 6a, 55. vouáv šakorov čupa kal hyńeo- oray &kovºv kal y\@ooravº kpival 5& Aóryp troA5- 6mplv čAeyxov ét éué0ev Šmóéura. Lówas 6 &rt uß60s 60ſo Aeſtretal, &s éotiv. The fundamental idea in this de- monstration is expressed by Aris totle, Phys, i. 3, 187 a, I; cf. 186 BEING. 585 thing else follows by simple inference." Being cannot begin, or cease to exist. It was not, it will not be, but it is, in a full undivided Present.” Whence could it have been derived 2 Out of non-Being 2 But non- Being does not exist, and cannot produce anything. Out of Being 2 This could not produce anything ex- cept itself. And the same holds good of destruction.” Speaking generally, however, what has been or will be is not ; but it cannot be said of Being that it is not.” a, 22 sqq. in the proposition, Ött Trávra èv, ei Tô by év a muatvel. Similarly Theophrastus and Eude- mus, p. 474, 1, third edition. * Verse 58:— raúrm 8' étri orhuat' aori troAA& Max', Ös &yévntov čāv kal &váAe6póv éorriv, of Aov, povvoyevés Te Kal &rpepºs má' &TéAeortov. 2 W. 61 :— où mor' émy oiâ’ #orral, étrel vov čarriv Öplot trav &včvvexés; $vvexés denotes, as is clear from W. 78 sqq., the undivided; and in this place, not the undivided in space, but in time. Being is undivided; there- fore no part of its existence can lie in the future or in the past. 8 W. 62 :— ºrſva yöp yévvmy Suſãoreal airo5; trfi tróēev atºm6év ; oiſt’ &ic wheóvros édow dºdoróat o' oběš voetv' of y&p parby où6è vomitáv 65. §orriv Štra's obic ēorri' ºrt 6 &v pup kal xpéos àporev $orrepov h trpóa'6ev rod uměevös &pid- Awevov pov’; oùTws h tréutraw tréAegev xpedºv čotiv 3) oikſ. # oëöé trot' éic roſ, Šávros éqſhore, trfortuosio'Xbs ºyveg (at ri trap' airó. too elvekev (Preller has this instead of Totºveicev. Hist. Phil. p. 93) ofºre yevéorðas oër’ &AAvorðal &vijke 6them. In W. 66, too umö, äpä, means ‘beginning from nothing.” (pov I take to be a contraction of ºptival, governed by &pgev. Watke, l. c. 49, and appa- rently Preller, Phil. Gr. Röm. No. 145, make it a participle, which causes difficulty in the construc- ºr ly" êotiv 3 oilº &otiv. itéspiral 3' of v, ãortrep &váykm, The pºv čáv &vómrov, &váuvuov, oë 'yūp &Amöhs éotiv 66bs, rhv 3’ &orre TréAeuy ital ērārvuoy elvai. 75. Trós 6’ &v Štreita TréAoi to Čáv trós 6’ &v ice yévotto; et ye yávour’ oik Šoºr', oiâ’ eſſ tors MéAAet éore&0&1. Tös yévsorus uév &méo Seoral real &mi- orros ūAs8pos. On account of this denial of Be- coming, Plato (Theſet. 181 A) calls 586 PARMENIDES. Being is moreover indivisible; for there is nowhere anything distinct from it by which its parts might be divided : all space is filled by Being alone." It is im- movable, in one place, for itself and identical with itself; * and since it cannot be incomplete or defective, it must be limited.” Nor is Thought separate from Being ; for there is nothing outside Being, and all * ºf the Eleatics of roń śAou araguárat ; and Aristotle, according to Sext. Math. x. 46, designates them as a tagldºtas rās púaea's kal &qvorikovs. Cf. what is cited from Aristotle, p. 587, 3, and from Theophrastus, p. 542, 1. ! W. 78 :— où8& 6tauperóv écriruv, ºre. Trāv éortly §potov, où6é ri rii wańAov rá key stpyot utv Švvéxeoróat oë5é Ti xeipótepov trav & TAéov éotiv čávros. rig $vvexes trav čo Tuv, ºbv y&p éðurt TreMáſel. (Cf. Karsten, l.c., as to the reading of W. 79, which is not improved by substituting trm for Tú, according to the suggestion of Mullach.) This verse I agree with Ritter, i. 493, is to be connected with W. 90:- Aejarge 6’ 3Mays &meóvra våg trape&vra Bebaios (considered the distant as something present) oi y&p &Toruñáel to €ov Toij čovros éxeoróat, oùre orcièvéuevov Trävrm trăvrws karð. kóquov oire ovvigºrduevov. (&troTuftësi is to be taken intransi- tively, or else we should, with Kar- sten, substitute for &torp. To ' ãºrotamäeºtal); cf. V. 104 sqq. , * W. 82 f:— aütőp &kivmtov ueyāAov čv tetpacri ôeoplôv éortly, àvapxov, &tavorov, Šire, yéve- orus kal &Aeópos tàAe padā’ TAdyx6morav, &majors Šč Trío ris &Am3%s" rwurov 8' év Tavré, re uévov ka? éavré ré keſtat. How Parmenides proved the im- mobility of Being, we are not told. The passage in Theat. 180 E, leaves it undecided whether the reason there given belongs to him, or primarily to Melissus. Favori- nus, ap. Diog. ix. 29, ascribes one of Zeno's arguments to Parme- mides, vide infra, Zeno. * V. 86 sqq. :— oùros éutrečov at 6, Mével' ºpateph yöp &váyicn treipatos év Šeapotoriv čxel, Tó pup àupls éépyet. (According to Simplicius, 9 a., whereas p. 7 a., 31 b, te is sub- stituted for rö. Other changes are unnecessary. To refers as a rela- tive to reſpatos):— oùvekev oik &TeXeóttirov to éðv 6éuis eival' éarl 'yap oilk tidevés, éov 3é (sc. âtexeſtmrov) ke travros éðeiro. Further details later on. When Epiph. Exp. Fid. 1087 C, says of Parmenides to &tepov čAeyev &px?iv rów Trávrov, he is confusing him with Anaximander. BEING. B87 thought is thought of Being." Being is in a word, therefore, all that really exists as Unity without be- coming or passing away, without change of place or of form: a whole, throughout undivided, homogeneous, on all sides equally balanced, and in all points equally perfect. Parmenides therefore compares it to a well- rounded sphere.” Consequently the unanimous testimony, therefore, of later writers that according to Parmenides Being exists and nothing besides, and that the All was regarded by him as one eternal immovable essence,” * W. 94 sqq.:— Twurov 6' éorrl voev re kal oiſvekév éori vámu.a. oš yap &vew roñéévros év ć treqaria- puévov čarly ešphaels to voeiv. oiâév y&p éotiv # êorral &AAo trape; rot, €67tos, (sup. p. 584, 1). 2 W. 97 : — érel ré ye uolp' étréðmorev olov (Simpl. of Aov) &ctvnrów T’ . êueval, & tróvt’ &vou' éotiv, Šmara 8poro, Karé9evro, tre+010ótes eival &Amb?, 100. Yºyveo-0aí Te kal &AAvoróat, eivaí Te kai oilcl, kal Tóirov &AAáo getv Štá Te xpóa qavöv &pießeiv. aërëp étri (Karsten for éire) reſpas trúpatov Terexeguévov čotl, ardvtoffew sitcákxov agaipms évaxtºy- - Klov tºykº, pleagóðey ionotraxés travrm' to yap oùre ru ueſſov 105. otºre ri Batórepov areAéval xpedºv čari Ti, 3) Th. oùre yap oil, éðv čari ré key train puv icefor6al eis Šubv, oùr' éov čorriv Štros eſſm key éévros (Mull, for: kevöv čávt.) Cf. W. 43 TÉ uáAAov tº 3’ floorov, emel trav 3. éotiv &ovXov. # yöp travró9evio'ov čudºs év treſpaori Icupet. * Plato, Parm. 128 A : orb usu ‘yöp v toſs trothytaoiv čv pſis eival to trav ſcal rotta'v tekuñpuz trapé- Xet. Theaet. 180. E. : MéAuoroot te Ical IIapueviðat . . . Štioxupígovtat, às év Te travra éoºrſ. Kal éortmicev aúto év airó, oùk éxov x&pav čv fi kiveirai. Soph. 242 D (sup. p. 523, 2); Arist. Metaph. i. 5, 986 b, 10 (ibid. note 2); ibid. l. 28: trap& ºyöp to by Tö uh by oi6&v čudºv eival IIapp., ÉÉ &váykms voteral, eizai to tiv Kal &AAo oš0év. iii. 4, 1001 a, 31. If Being as such is absolute substance, how are we to conceive the Many? to yap Érepov too Švtos oùk éativ, &ote katē Töv IIappreviðou Aóryov orvpgaively āvāykm év Štravra. eival r& Švra kal Tooto eival to $v. Phys. i. 2, sub init.: äväykm 6’ firot pitav sival thv &px?iv h TAetovs, kai ei utav, fitou äktvmtov, &s pmol IIap- peviðms kai MéNugaos, etc. The criticism of this opinion, however, does not properly belong to Phy- sics, nor yet to the investigation of first principles: oi, Yêp Éri àpxá 588 PARMENIDES. is, in fact, correct; but the proposition that the world is eternal and imperishable cannot, strictly speaking, be attributed to this philosopher; for if all plurality or change are denied there can be no question of a world at all. For the same reason it appears that Parmenides did not designate Being as the Deity: we give the name of the Deity" to the primitive essence to distinguish this from the world; a philosopher who wholly denies égºriv, si èv puðvov kal off-ros év ča riv (similarly Metaph i. 5). Ibid. 185 b, 17; and Metaph. l. c. 986 b, 18, on the Limitedness of Being, with Parmenides; cf. Simpl. Phys. 25 a, and 29 a és à 'AAéðavöpos io- Topet, 6 uèv Osóqpaotos oira’s éic- Tíðetal (sc. Tov IIappevičov Adºyov) év tá, trpárq, Tâs pugikās in topias' to trap& To ovoik Öv, to oilk by oiöèv, #v špa to §v, Eöömuos 3& oita's to Trap& Tö by oik Öv. &AA& kal uovaxós Aéyéral rô Šv. čv špa rô $v. Sim- plicius adds that he did not find this in the Physics of Eudemus; but he quotes a passage from that work which censures Parmenides for not having distinguished the different senses in which the con- cept of Being is employed, and as- serts that even had it only one sense, the unity of all Being could not be demonstrated. This is also objected by Aristotle, Phys. i. 3, 186 a, 22 sqq., and c, 2. The words &AA& kal uovaxós Aéyeral rô by are in any case only an emendation of Eudemus ; of Parmenides he says himself, l. c., and Aristotle says, Phys. l. c., that he did not think of the various senses of Being, from which it naturally follows that he did not expressly discriminate them. It is unnecessary to quote the statements of more recent authors; they are to be found in Brandis, Comm. El. 136 sqq., and JKarsten, Parm. 158,168. Concern- ing a proof of the unity of Being, wrongly attributed to Parmenides by Porphyry, we shall speak fur- ther on. | Stob. Eel. i. 416; Plut. Plac. ii. 4, 3 (Sup. p. 565, 3). It is more correct to call the All, one, eternal, unbecome, unmoved, etc., as we find in Plato. Theſet. 181 A (oí too 3Mov otaguárat); Arist. Metaph. i. 3, 984 a, 28 sqq. (§v pågicovres eival to trav); Theophr, ap. Alex, in Metaph. i. 3, 984 b, l; Alex. ibid. Plut. Plac. i. 24; Hippol. Refut. i. 11 ; Eus. Pr. Ev. xiv. 3, 9; for Parmenides attributes the predi- cates, 3Åov and trav, to Being also. The expression (Arist. l. c.) Thy qāoriv ŠAmu &kivmtov eival, is less exact. * In the fragments of Parme- nides, this designation is never found, and whether or not more recent writers make use of it, is of little consequence, Stob. Eel. i. 60. Ammon. tr. Épumv. 58 (cf. Brandis, Comm. 141 ; Gr. Röm. Phil. i. 382; Karsten, 208; cf. Parm. v. 61, 75 sq.), Boëth. Consol. iii. sub fin. The passage in De Melisso, Zeno et Gorgia, c. 4, 978 b, 7 would prove nothing, even were the genuineness of that work more certain than it is. REING. §89 that the Finite exists side by side with the Eternal does not require such a term." It might more reason- ably be asked whether Parmenides really excluded from his concept of Being all that from our point of view seems to involve a plurality, and to transfer sensible determinations to the immaterial essence. This question we must answer in the negative. Even if the compa- rison of Being with a globe considered in itself, simply as a comparison, proves nothing, all that Parmenides says of the limitedness, homogeneousness, and indivisi- bility of Being,” shows that he conceived it as extended in space, and never formed the idea of a Being un- contained in space. For far from avoiding space- determinations as inadmissible, he expressly describes Being as a fixed and homogeneous mass, symmetrically extended from its centre on all sides—which within its limits always occupies one and the same place, nowhere interrupted by non-Being, and at no point contain- ing more Being than at another. We should be justi- fied in rejecting this description as metaphorical only if we could find any indication that Parmenides con- ceived Being as incorporeal, and if in other parts of his philosophic discussion he made use of a figurative mode of expression; but neither is anywhere the case. More- over, as we shall presently see, Zeno and Melissus * It is not necessary to assume that Parmenides was hindered by religious feelings or considerations of prudence from declaring himself as to the relation of Being to the Deity (Brandis, Comm. El. 178). The answer is more obvious. He did not do so because he was a universal, plastic philosopher, and his philosophy gave no opportunity for the statement of theological definitions. * Sup. p. 584 sq. What right Strümpell (Gesch. d. Theor. Phil. d. Gr. p. 44) has to deduce from these passages that Being is not extended in space, I do not see. * 690 PARMENIDES. also attribute to Being magnitude in space, and the Atomists, clearly referring to the doctrine of Par- menides, identify Being with the body, and non-Being with empty space; we can therefore scarcely hesitate to ascribe to this philosopher the opinion which his own words seem intended to convey. His Being is not a metaphysical concept, devoid of all sensuous admix- ture, but a concept that has been developed from an intuition, and still bears clear traces of this origin. The Real is to Parmenides the Full (TAéau, that which fills space. The distinction of the corporeal and incor- poreal is not only unknown to him, but incompatible with his whole point of view; for the unity of Being and Thought, which he maintained as a direct consequence of his doctrine of Unity, is too realistic to be possible, except on the presupposition that the corporeal and the incorporeal had not as yet been discriminated. Ac- cording to the excellent remark of Aristotle," it is the substance of the corporeal itself, not a substance dis- tinct from the corporeal, with which he is concerned; and when he says “Only Being is, this signifies that we attain to the true view of things when we abstract from the separation and variableness of the sensible phenomenon, in order to maintain its simple, undivided and unchangeable substratum as the only Reality. This abstraction is no doubt a bold step ; but in making it, Parmenides does not so entirely depart from the whole previous tendency of philosophic enquiries as if he had started with a purely metaphysical concept, without any regard to the data of the senses. * Wide sup. i. 190, 1, 2, and in regard to the above generally, 187 sq. SENSE AND REASON. 591. So far, then, as the knowledge of the Real is only possible by means of this abstraction, the abstract intel- lectual study of things can alone lay claim to truth: judgment belongs solely to rational speech (A6)os)— the senses, on the contrary, which reflect the show or appearance of plurality and mutability, of generation and destruction, are the cause of all error. Parmenides earnestly warns us therefore to trust, not the senses, but reason alone;" and thus, like Heracleitus, he gives occasion to a discrimination which in the sequel was of the highest importance, both for the theory of know- ledge and for metaphysics generally. In his own sys- tem, however, it has not this great importance ; it is there merely a consequence of the material and meta- physical results, not the foundation of the whole; the jºk cognition of sense, and that of reason, are not opposed +. in respect of their formal characteristics, but solely in respect of their content; and the psychological investi- gation of the faculty of knowing is so greatly neglected, as we shall presently see, that the philosopher ascribes to Thought the same origin as to Perception, and derives both from the mixture of material substances. Although Parmenides so abruptly opposes reality to the phenomenon, intellectual thought to the decep- tions of the senses, he cannot forbear pointing out, in the second part of his didactic poem, what theory of * Parm. v. 33 sqq., 52 sqq. iv. 234, cf. Arist. Gen. et corr. i. (supra, p. 584, 1), to which little is 8, 325 b, 13). Many sceptics added by later writers (e.g. Diog. counted Parmenides as well as his ix. 22; Sext. Math. vii. 111; Plut. teacher Xenophanes in their ranks ap. Eus. Pr. Ev. i. 8, 5. Aristocles, (Cic. Acad. ii. 23, 74; Plut. Adv. ibid, xiv. 17, 1; Joh. Dam. parall. Col. 26, 2); but this is not of much ii. 25, 23, in Stob. Floril, ed. Mein. importance. 592 PARMENIDES. the world would result from the standpoint of ordinary opinion, and how individual phenomena would in that case have to be explained." The right view allows us to recognise in all things but One, Being; ordinary opinion adds to this, non- Being.” It therefore regards things as compounded of opposite constituents, to only one of which, in truth, Reality belongs;” and consequently, to ordinary opinion (vide supra), the One appears as a plurality, the in- variable as becoming and changeable. If we place ourselves therefore at this point of view, we shall have to admit two elements, of which one corresponds with Being, and the other with non-Being. Parmenides calls the former light or fire, and the latter night ; and in the fragments of his writings which we possess he describes the former as the rare, and the latter as the dense and the heavy.” They are also named, by other authorities, the warm and the cold, or fire and earth; * and it would seem that Parmenides likewise * We find this same opinion, though it is clumsily expressed, in Plut. ap. Eus. Pr. Ev. i. 8, 6: Happ. ... à étalpos Eevoſpávows àua uév Kal rów rotºrov Sočáv &vretrothorato, äua 8è kal thv čvavtſav čvexeſpnoe ordaiv, as appears from the clearer but imperfect parallel passage ap. Theod. Cur. Gr. Aff. iv. 7, p. 57. * W. 33 sqq., 45 sqq. (supra, p. 584, 1). $ W. 113:— poppès yap karé0evro 500 yuáups Övoudgetv, (rāv uíav of xpedºv čariv, Šv $ Tetraavnuévot eio'ív) &vrta 5’ exptvavro 5éuas ka gåuar’ ë6evro xwpts &m’ &AA#Aww. 4 W. 116 :— Tú ačv p^oyös aibépiov trop #triov čov, wéy àpatov, Šavré, tdv- Toge tavrov, Tº 5’ Tépq, whº touróv' &rāp kāiceºvo kat' airb &vría vökt’ &öañ truktubv 5éuas épépt0és re. 5 W. 122 :— air&p étrelë irávra pdos kal vić övéuaa tal kai tā karð orderépas àvváuels ērl Totoſí Te kal Tois, tráv TAéov éotiv Šplot, páeos kal vvktos & pavrov, łowy &pidotépwv, étrel oiberépºp uéra wmöév. Karsten is no doubt right in PHYSICS. 593 made use of these latter names." Aristotle, however, tells us that the more abstract expressions, ‘warm and cold,’” which correspond to his own derivation of the elements, were first adopted by him in place of the more concrete explaining the latter, according to v. 117 sq. thus: Both are homo- geneous and unmixed. The same is asserted in the gloss which Simpl. (Phys. 7, b) found in his MS. between the verses : étrº Tööé éorti to &patov kai to 6epubv kai Tô 4,40s kal to pax0aköv kal to coopov, étrº Sé Tó, tvkvá &vápagºral rô puxpóv kal to $6 pos kai Tô orkampôv kal rô Bapt. Taira yöp &tekplôm éicatépa’s ércátépa. * Arist. Phys. i. 5, sub init.: kal yèp II. 6epubu kal juxpów &px&s trouet, taúra öö trpoaſayopetſet trip Kal ºyāv. Metaph. i. 5, 986, b, 31, after the quotation, p. 543, 1: ávay- kaſáaevos 6’ &coxověeiv roſs paivo- Aévous kai to Év učv ſcatt, Tov Aéryov Tr}\eta, 6& karð Thy alo'6motiv ŠtroXau- Bávov eival, São Tàs airías kal 600 r&s àpx&s td.Alv tíðmori, 9epubv Ical Juxobv, oiov trip cal yńv Aéyov. Cf. also, Metaph. i. 3, 984 b, 1 sqq., iv. 2, 1004 b, 32. Theophrast ap. Alex, vide infra, p. 594, 4. Simpl. Phys. 7 b : Töv učv yeuvntów &px&s kal airbs atolyetőöels uèv Thy Tpdºrmy &vt/9ea w ś9ero, #v pås kaxeſ cal okótos, trip ral yńv, # Trvkvöv kal &patov, h Taitov ſcal ërepov (the last is evidently a mis- conception of v. 117 sq.). Simi- larly Simpl. Phys. S, 6 b, 38 b ; Alex. in Metaph. i. 5, 986 b, 17; iv. 2, 1004 b, 29; xii. 1, 1069 a, 26 (33, 21, 217, 34, 643, 19 Bon.). Ibid. ap. Philop. Gen. et Corr. 64 a ; Philop. Phys. A, 9, C, 11 ; I’lut. Adv. Col. 13, 6, p. 1114; where the two elements are called: to Aguirpov kal orcoreivöv, and De WOL. I. An. Procr. 27, 2, p. 1026, where they are called q6s and orkóros. This is the foundation of the mis- take of Clemens, Cohort. 42 C : II. . . . 6eois eia myſia aro trip kal ºymv. * Brandis, Comment. 167; Kar- sten, p. 222, and other writers doubt this, partly on account of the word ofov ap. Arist. Metaph. l. c. and partly because Simpl. Phys. 6 b, says: II. Šv roſs trpos 66éav trip kal yńv, uſiXAov 8& pás ical oricóros (àpx&s tí0mgu); cf. Alex. inf. p. 594, 1. But the words of Simplicius and Alexander may be also interpreted as we have indicated in the text; and in regard to oiov, Bonitz has shown (Bonitz on the Metaphysics, p. 76) that Aristotle not unfrequently uses it when he neither intends to express a comparison nor a doubt. The words of v, etc., therefore assert only : “he calls the one fire, the other earth,’ and are in no way in- consistent with the plain expres- sions in the Physics and in the treatise on generation and decay. On the other hand, it is quite pos- sible, judging from Aristotle's usual procedure in regard to the opinions of other philosophers, that Parme- nides may have first called the dark element earth, in the place where he was speaking of the for- mation of the earth; inasmuch as he asserted that the earth arose out of darkness. This is borne out by Plutarch, ap. Eus. i. 8, 7 : Aéyet 8& rºw yiv rod rvkvoo karaśāvévros &épos yeyovéval. - Q Q 594 PARMENIDES. designation. He associated light, we are informed by Aristotle," with Being, and Night with non-Being, and this statement is confirmed by the fragments. In these he declares that truth and reality belong only to one of the two elements from which things are commonly derived, and that the existence of the other element, on the contrary, has been falsely assumed.” Conse- quently, he regards the one element as existing, the other as not existing; and for this reason he ascribes to the fiery element the same characteristics as to Being in describing it throughout as homogeneous.” He is further said to have regarded the fiery element as the active principle, and darkness as the passive or material principle.* This, however, can scarcely be quite correct. * Arist. Metaph. l.c. continues: rońray 5è karð uèv rô by ré 6epubv rárrel, 64tepov 5& karð rô whº v. Ibid. Gen. et Corr. i. 3, 318 b, 6 : &orrep IIapp. Aérye, São, rô by kal to pº) by eival páorkww, trip kal yńv. Alexander in Metaph, 986 b, 17, cannot be received as a separate testimony, since it is manifestly taken from Aristotle. So, doubt- less, Philop. Gen. et Corr. p. 13 a. The statement of Aristotle is con- tested by Karsten, p. 223, and still more decidedly by Mullach on v. 113 (also by Steinhart, Allg. Enc. sect. iii. vol. xii. 233 sq.; Plato's Werke, vi. 226), on the ground that neither of the twd elements of the perishable can be identified with the existent. There is no sufficient foundation for this, as we have. shown above. * W. 114. The word kara.0éorðal must be supplied after the words Töv wtav of xpedºv čorri. These words however will not bear the inter- pretation of Simplicius, Krische (Forsch. 102), Karsten, Mullach, Steinhart (Allg. Enc. 240) and others, which is this: “to admit only one of which is wrong.” For it is here brought forward as the common error of mankind that two kinds of Reality are assumed by them ; as in v. 37, it was said to be the path of deception, to admit non-Being side by side with Being. The words rather mean: of which the one cannot be admitted, be- cause the theory of it is based on deception. * W. 117. Cf. v. 85, 109 (sup. p. 592, 3; 586, 2; 587, 2). * Aristotle remarks, Metaph. i. 3, 984 b, 1 : röv učv of v čv pao- kóvrov sival ºrb träv oë0evl avvé8m thv totatºrmv [rºv Kºvnrikhvl avvi- beiv airíav trºv ei Špa IIapuevíðn kal rotºrq, karū rooroorov 30 ov oë uóvov čv &AA& kal 850 tra's ríðmariv airías eival. roſs 5& 8) traeta, rotojo', paxxov čvāéxetal Aéyeuv, otov roſs THE LIGHT AND THE DARK. 595. He may perhaps have attributed a vivifying and forma- tive influence generally to warmth in the origination of organic beings, and in the formation of the universe; but it is self-evident that he can neither have used these Aristotelian expressions, nor intended to explain movement universally, as Heracleitus did, from the warm element as such. For in that case it would have been unnecessary to assume a particular mythical figure, by which all combination of substances is brought about"—the goddess who is enthroned in the centre of the universe and rules its whole course.” 6epuby kal juxpov h trip kal yńv. xpavrai yüp &s kivmtikºv *xovri ró trup, rºv qigoriv. §§art 5& kal •yfi kal toſs rouotrous roëvavtſov. Theophrastus, ap. Alex., comment- ing on this passage, p. 24, 5 Bon. says more definitely: IIapuevſöns . . . &m’ &pſporépas àA6e ràs 6800s. kal yèp &s &tºuév čari rb trav &ro- qaſverai kal yèveow &modièóval arelpāral rôv čvrov, oùx Öuoia's repl &pſporépov Šošáçov, &AA& kar’ &Aftóetav wºv čv to trav ſcal &yévvm- tov kal orgapoeiðūs ūroxaußdvov, rară 66%av' & rôv troAAöv eis to yéveriv &roö00val rôv paivopévov 600 totôy ràs àpx&s trip ral yńv, to pºv &s iſºmy, to 58 &s airtov Kal rotojv. This is repeated by the more recent writers, Cic. Acad. ii. 37, 118: P. ignem qui moveat, terram quae ab eo formetur. Diog. ix. 21 : 500 re elval orouxeta, trip kal yºv, kal to uév 6mutovpyot, raftiv čxeiv, rhv 5& Wams. Hippol. Refut. i. 11. indirectly, no doubt, from Theophrastus, who is also mentioned by Diogenes: II. §v pºv To trav Štrorſ6eral &fölöv re kal &yévvmtov kal orgapoetőés, oëbè airbs ékpetſywy rºv táv troAAów The mixture 6óław, trip Aéyav kal yiv ràs roº travtos àpxás. Thy uév yiv &s 5Amv, to 8& trip &s atriov kal trolodv. Alex. ap. Simpl. Phys. 9 a ; katē 8& Thu rôv troAAóv 66;av kai Tô paivé- preva ºbvarioMoyáv . . . &px&s róv Tylvouévov imé9ero trºp kai yiv, thv pºv yiv ćis iſºmy úroriðels, to 8& trip &s troumrukov alrlov. kai àvo- adget, pnal, rb uév trip pås rºv 8& 'yńv aſkóros. Philop. Gen. et Corr. 12 a, o : rºw uév yńv u%) by &vöpia- aev, &s iſºms A6-yov ćiréxovo av, to 6è trip by, Ös trouotiv kal eiðukó- repov. Arist. Gen. et Cor. ii. 9, 336 a, 3 sqq., does not seem to be alluding specially to Parmenides, but rather to Anaximenes (sup. p. 272, 2) and Diogenes (p. 291). * As Simpl. Phys. 9 a, remarks against Alexander. * W. 128:- - év 8& uéga-rotºrov (on this point, cf. p. 600, 3) Aaſuav h ºrdvra rv8epvá. trávrm yüp orvyspoto Tókov kal uíčios &pxh, tréumovo’ &ffevi 67Av uryūval, évav- Tſo. 6’ aff6is &pgév 04Avrépg. Q & 2 596 IPARMENIDES. of the light and the dark he represents in a symbolic manner as a sexual union; describing Eros as the first creation of the world-ruling goddess,' and these elements themselves as the masculine and feminine.” He seems to have introduced other symbolic beings as gods,” be- sides Eros; but we are not told what part they played in the formation of the world. That Parmenides borrowed his doctrine of the two elements from an older physical theory is not probable; for in the first place we know of no theory which would have adapted itself to this purpose; * and, secondly, he himself says that the ordinary opinion of mankind gene- rally, is the object of his exposition in the second part of the poem. Accordingly, this exposition is founded on a fact which could not well escape observation, viz., that the sense perception and common opinion see in According to Stob. Ecl. i. 482 sq., parall. cf. p. 158; Theod. Cur. Gr. Aff. vi. 13, sect. 87, this goddess of Parmenides was called kvéepvirus, kAmpooxos (for which Karsten, p. 241, would substitute kånö00xos), 5them, and &váykm; but other things, especially the introduction to the poem, would seem to be brought inhere. Cf. Krische, Forsch. p. 107. W. 132 (Plato, Symp. 178 B; Arist. Metaph.i.4,984 b, 25; trpátia- rov pièv špara 6eów amrioraro trav- row). The subject of amriorato is, according to the express statement of Simplicius, l.c., the Satuwv, V. 128; Plut. Amator. 13, 11, p. 756, says instead 'Appoãfrn, but this is sufficiently explained by the des- cription of the goddess, and espe- cially by the circumstance that she is the parent of Eros. * This more general interpreta- tion of v. 130 sq. seems to be re- quired by the connection of this verse, and the universal cosmical significance which manifestly be- longs to Eros. * The evidence of Cicero, or rather that of Philodemus (Cic. N. D. i. 11, 28), quippe qui bellum, qui discordian, qui cupiditatem ceteraque generis ejusdem ad Deum Tevocat, would not of itself be con- clusive ; it is a question whether Parmenides is not here confused with Empedocles; but the words trpdºriotov 6eóv tróvrov in Parm. v. 132 show that other gods followed Eros. Wide Krische, l. c. 111 sq. * The texts in Aristotle which were supposed to refer to such theories, otherwise unknown to us (supra, p. 594, 1), may be explained in another way. Further details, p. 599, 3rd ed. COSMOLOGY. 597 all things opposite substances and forces united. The explanation of this fact—the reduction of these oppo- sites to the fundamental opposite of Being and non- Being, of light and dark, and the introduction of the creating divinities—all this is to be regarded as his own addition. Yet, in the ancient cosmogonies," in the early Ionian theories of the creation, and in the Pytha- gorean doctrine of the primitive opposites,” there are points of similarity which may have had some influence on his exposition. In the further development of physical motions, Parmenides extended his investigation to everything which occupied the enquiry of that period.” * Such as the statements in Hesiod, Acusilaos, and Ibycus on Eros; the utterances of Acusilaos on Eros and Night, and the like. Wide supra, pp. 87, 97. * Among which, as is well known, we find that of light and darkness. * He himself promises in v. 120 sq. :— Töv got £y& 5udicoopov čoukóra trávra. qatiga', às oi pºſitroté ris ore 8potöv yvápm trapex.do on. 133 sq. :— eform 8' aiéept my re (pêorly ré T' év aiðépu Trôvra orhpara kai ka9apas eia!yéos hextolo, Aapatráðos épy’ &föm Na kal étriróðey éčeyévovro, épya re kūkaaſtros reign trepiqoura orexhums kai pāorivº eiðhorels ö& kal oipavov &pſpls ēxovira àv6ev čºv kal &s puv &yovo” ºréðmorev äväykm sº treipar’ xely āorpov, This por- 140 :— trós yata kal fixios #88 orexhvn aidiip re Švvos yd Aa tº oilpdviov kal &\vutros êoxaros hô’ &orpov 6eppubv uévos &ppºſióma'av ºvíyveg 6al. Blut. Adv. Col. 13, 6, says of him: §s ye kai čudicooruov tretrointai, Kal orotxeſa Mi'yvös, to Aguirpov kai. okoreivöv, Šic roſtov Tó, paivéueva trövta kal 61& rotºrwy &roteWei. Kal 'yöp trepi Väs eipnice troAA& kal trept oùpavoi, kai jatov ſcal orexiivns kal &growu, kal yéveriv &v0p6trov &@ft- "mºral kai oiâèv #35mtov . . . tav kuptov trapſikev. In v. 141, the Py- thagorean distinction of otpavos and ÖAvutos is seen, as has been already observed, p. 471, 2. In Stobaeus (vide following note), that part of the sky which lies nearest to the earth is called oipavas, whereas, in v. 137, oùpavös is the extreme limit of the universe. Stein, p. 798 sq., unnecessarily refers v. 133–139 to Empedocles. 598 PARMENIDES. tion of his doctrine, however, has been transmitted to us in a very imperfect state. In his description of the universe, he allies himself with the Pythagorean system, though he does not invariably follow it. He conceives the universe as compounded of several globes or circles' placed around each other. The innermost and outermost of these consist of the dense and dark element, and form the fixed kernel and external wall of the universe. Around the innermost circles, and be- neath the outermost circle, lie circles of pure fire; in the intermediate region between them, are circles com- posed of the dark and the fiery element mixed.” * It is not clear from the au- thorities (vide following note), which of the two is intended. The “expression a requivn which Parme- nides uses would point to the idea of circular bands. But as the outermost of these circles, the con- cave vault of heaven, in accordance, not only with our perceptions, but with Parmenides' doctrine of Being (supra, p. 587, 589), must be con- ceived as spherical (for which rea- son it is called in v. 137, oùpaves ºutpls éxwv), and as the earth (according to 598, 2) must also be a sphere, it is difficult to say what the intermediate layers can be except hollow globes. (Cf., how- ever, the observations on p. 445, 1.) * Stob. Eol. i. 482 (the com- mencement is also ap. Plut. Plac. ii. 7, 1 ; Galen, c. 11, p. 267): II. orreqāvas eival trepitretraetypiévas éraxxâxovs, Thu uév čk roß &paloo Thy 6% ºr roi tukuot” puktās 6& #AAas €k poros kal okórous Aeroft, Totºrwu kal to treptéxov 6é traoras Teixovs 6themv or repebv Štrépzelv, Üq' § trupéðms are påwn, kal to uégatra- rokéa By rov traoráv [sc. or repeow inrápxsw], trepl $v (l. 6) tróAuv trupéöms. Tov 8è orvupuyáv rhv plea atrármv štáorals (Davis commenting on Cic. N. D. i. 11, substitutes this for re kal; Krische proposes airíav, in accordance with Parm. v. 129– vide sup. p. 595, 2—we might con- jecture instead of &mdo as re kai: àpx?iv rákov re kal) traorms kivſarea's ral yewéorews Śrāpyeiv, #vruva kai Bafuova kal kvéepvitiv kal kxmpouxov étrovoudget, 6tremu Te Kal &váykmv. (Cf. 595, 2.) ital ris uév yis rºw &tókptoriv sival rov &épa, Ötö thu Bialotépav airms ééarpua 6:vra tri- Amoru, too 8& trupos &vairvoºjv row #Atov kal row yaxačíav kūkaov. orvuſui'yū 5' éé àpiq'oïv sival thv orexhvny toº r" &épos kal roi, trupés. treptorrávros & &vardra trávrov toū aiðépos ūr' airó ro trupóðes tºrotayfival, roß6 &mep kekańkauev oëpavöv, Öq' of #6m rò, treptºyeta. This account (in the interpretation of which Krische, Forsch. 101 sqq., seems to me to have best suc- ceeded, and to have essentially improved on that of Brandis, COSMOLOGY. 599 the outermost of these circles we must understand the vault of heaven conceived as fixed; by the circle of fire under this, the circumambient fire of the Pytha- goreans; the fixed circle in the centre can only be the earth, which we are elsewhere told Parmenides consi- dered to be a globe at rest in the midst of the universe.” According to this, the circle of fire surrounding it must be the air which, as contrasted with the earth, might well be described as the rare and the luminous.” Be- tween these two extreme points is the heaven of fixed stars.” How the particular spheres were placed in these, and whether Parmenides departed from the opinion usually held as to their succession, cannot be determined Comment. 160 sqq., and Karsten, 241 sqq.) is partially confirmed by fle confused statement of Cicero, N. D. i. 11, 28, nam Par- menides guidem commenticium quid- dam coronae similitudine efficit : Stephanen adpellat, continente ardore lucis orbem, qui cingit, coelum, quem adpellat Deum (this is either wholly false, or an entire misapprehension of some genuine passage) but especially by v. 126 of Parmenides:— ai yüp a retvárepai [sc. are påvat] tretroinviro trupòs ākpitolo, ai 6' émi rais vuktös, uera 3& p?\oyös * fetal aiqa. €v 5è uéorg, &c. (Supra, p. 595, 2). Cf. v. 113 sqq., supra 592, 3. | arxatos “OAvutros, as it is called in v. 141, * Diog. ix. 21: Trpáros 6' oiros Thy yºv &mépmve orgapoetóñ real év uéorg ketorðal. Plut. Plac. iii. 15, 7. Parmenides and Democritus maintain that the earth is kept in an equilibrium, and does not move, because it is equidistant from all parts of the universe. When Schäfer (Astron. Geogr. d. Griechen, Flensb. 1873, p. 12 sq.) says, fol- lowing the precedent of Schaubach and Forbiger, that Parmenides as- cribed to the earth the form of a disc, and not of a sphere, he for- gets that the statement of Dioge- nes originates with Theophrastus. Theophrastus, according to Diog. viii. 48, asserted of Parmenides: trpárov čvouáort rºw yiv orpoyyúamv; orpoyyūany must here mean, as it does with Plato, Phaedo, 97 D (tré- repov i yü tractetá čotiv h orpoy- ºyvan), the spherical form, as Par- menides was by no means the first philosopher who thought the earth was a round dise. * This especially, and not heat, appears also in v. 116 sq. (vide sup, p. 592, 4), as the distinguishing characteristic of the fire of Parme- nides; he even calls it #triov. * Called ap. Stobaeus, l.c., tru- póðss and otpavés. 300 PARMENIDES. with certainty." This is also the case with other astro- nomical and cosmological theories attributed to him.” In the midst of the universe” the goddess that rules it * Stob. i. 518, says: II. Tparov pºv rártel row ‘Eóov, row airby 5& wopuçõuevov Štr'airoi, kal “Eotrepov, év tái aibépi. Me6 by Töv #Atov, Öq’ & toūs év tá, ruptéðel &a répas, Štrep oùpavöv kaxeſ (cf. p. 570). If this representation is correct, we might suppose that Parmenides had placed the milky way highest, after the steadfast arc of heaven, and the other fixed stars lowest; the pla- nets, sun and moon, between the two. It is questionable, however, whether the informant of Stobaeus derived his statements from ac- curate knowledge of Parmenides’ poem, or constructed for himself, from the verses quoted p. 598, 2, and from other passages, an astronomi- cal system, far transcending Par- menides' own doctrine. Cf. Krische, p. 115. * According to Stob. i. 484 (sup. p. 598, 2), 524, he ascribed to the milky way and to the sun a fiery nature, and to the moon a mixed nature; but as all three be- long to the mixed spheres, there could only be question of more or less of the fiery or of the dark ele- ment. In p. 574 (Plac. iii. 1, 6; Galen. c. 17, p. 285), Stobaeus says that the colour of the milky way arises from the mixture of the dense and the rare, and he makes Parmenides (s. 564) account for the face in the moon from this cause. According to p. 532, Parmenides thought the sun and moon were produced from the milky way—the Sun from the rarer, the moon from the denser part of its admixture. In p. 550 (Plac. ii. 26, parall.) we find; II, Tupivny [thy geańvnv] ſonv 6é rég ſixtó, kal yöp &m' airod qart- Georéat (this also ap. Parm. v. 144 sq.), where, however, we must either omit yap, which is wanting in the other texts, or we must suppose that io"my with Parmenides did not refer to the magnitude, but to the orbit of the moon. (Karsten, p. 284.) The opinion of Parme- nides on the nature of the stars is thus expressed by Stob. i. 510; he regarded them (like He- racleitus, Xenophanes, Anaximan- der and others) as trixhuata Twpos, that is, fiery masses of vapour, which are nourished by the evapo- ration from the earth (if this is truly reported of him). The iden- tity of the morning and evening star, on which he certainly must have given some opinion, was, ac- cording to some authors, discovered by him (Diog. ix. 23; cf. viii. 14; Suidas, "Eatrepos); others ascribe this discovery to Pythagoras (vide sup. p. 458, 1). Also the division of the earth into five zones, the author of which is sometimes said to be Parmenides (Posidon. ap. Strabo, ii. 2, 2, p. 94; Ach. Tat, ad. Arač. c. 31, p. 157 C ; Plut. Plac. iii. 11, 4), is by others attributed to the Pythagoreans (Sup, p. 480, 2), who might indeed have arrived at it through Parmenides. * Stob. (sup. p. 598, 2) says, in the centre of the mixed spheres. This statement is rightly explained by Krische, Forsch. 105 sq., as a misunderstanding of rotºrwy in v. 128, quoted sup. p. 595, 2. Also Simpl. Phys. 8 a, says of Parme- nides : troumrukov attlov. . . Šv Kouyov, rīv év uéoºp mavrww ièpuſ.évny ka? AWTHROPOLOGY.. " 60i —the parent of the gods and of all things (vide supra) —has her dwelling place. She undoubtedly corresponds to the central fire of the Pythagoreans, the mother of the gods and former of the world. Besides these cosmological motions, we have some anthropological theories handed down to us as those of Parmenides. He seems to have conceived the begin- ning of the human race as a development from primitive slime, brought about by the heat of the sun; and his opinion on this subject has therefore been identified with that of Empedocles.” What he says on the differ- ence of the sexes” and the origin of this difference in generation is unimportant.” It is of more consequence trams yewéorea's airfav Šaiuova Tſ6m- oiv, and similarly Iambl. Theol. Arithm. p. 8, after a mention of the central fire: éoíkagi 8& Katd, ye to dra karmkoWv0mkéval toſs IIv6ayo- petous of re repl 'EpſtrečokAéa kal IIappreviðmu . . . p4aevoi Thu uova- Sukhu pāoriv ‘Earías Tpótrov čv puéorg, iöpúa'6ai. The opposite view of Apelt. Parm. et Emp. doctrina de mund; Structura (Jena, 1857), p. 5 sqq., I cannot agree with. ' Diog. ix.22 says, probably after Theophrastus : yéveau &věpátrov č #Atov trpárov yewéo 6al; but instead of fixtov we should probably read iXùos, with the Basle edition and many modern writers; or, accord- ing to Steinhart's conjecture (Allg. Enc. l. c. 242), fixiou re kai ixãos. But even if we accept åAtov, we need not adopt with Krische, Forsch. 105, the idea of the production of souls out of the Sun—a conception which can hardly lie in the words, and which neither the supposed precedent of the Pythagoreans (sup. p. 476, 2), nor the utterance, ap. Simpl. Phys., 9 a., mentioned p. 448, 2, 3rd ed., can justify us in attributing to Parmenides. We must rather understand with Kar- sten, p. 257, a production by means of the sun's heat. Plutarch (vide sup. p. 597, 3) also says that Par- menides spoke of the origin of men. * Cens. Di. Nat. 4, 8, after having quoted the famous opinion of Empedocles: haec eadem opinio etiam in Parmenide Veliensi fuit, pauculis exceptis ab Empedocle dis- sensis (dissentientibus & cf. on this subject pp. 256, 296, 569). * Although he regarded the fiery element as the nobler, he yet held that women were of warmer nature than men: hence their more sanguine temperament, etc. (Arist. Part. Anim. ii. 2, 648 a, 28; cf. Gener. Anim. iv. 1, 765 b, 19). For this reason, at the first form- ing of mankind, he represents men as originating in the north, and women in the south, Plut. Plac. v. 7, 2; Galen, c. 32, p. 324. - * According to v. 150, boys 602 PA RMEN IDES. to us to learn that he derived the phenomena of the life of the soul, perception and reflection, from the mixture of substances in the body. He supposed that each of the two primitive substances is sensible of that which is akin to it, and that therefore the notions and thoughts of men are of this or that nature, recollec- tions remain or are lost, according as the warm or cold element predominates in the body: he sought the cause of life and of intelligence in the warm element ; * but even where this is entirely absent, as in the corpse, there must still be sensation; only that sensation is them to be referred, not to light and heat, but to the cold, dark element.” proceed from the right side, and girls from their left of the organs in both sexes; the statement, ap. Plut. Plac. v. 11, 2, and Cens. Di. Naț. 6, 8, that children derived from the right side resemble their fa- ther, and those from the left their mother, is a mere misunderstand- ing. What Censorinus says, c. 6, 5; cf. 5, 4, is more likely to be true, viz., that the seed of both parents struggles for the mastery, and the child resembles whichever part is victorious. The verses (a Latin version, ap. Coel. Aurelian, De Morb. Chron. iv. 9, p. 545, v. 150 sqq. Karst.) are also to be con- sidered genuine, which attribute a right constitution of body to the harmonious blending of male and female seed, and malformations and blemishes to their strife. The statement in the Plac. v. 7, 4, on the origin of the difference of the sexes, is certainly incorrect. ' Stob. Eel. i. 796, therefore says, adopting later terminology, IIappeviðms trupéöm (Thy juxiv). He We see from this that even Par- also explained sleep and age as re- sulting from the decline of warmth. Tert. De An. c. 43; Stob. Floril. 115, 29. * Parm. v. 146 sqq. :— és yūp ékáaré, éxel kpāoris ueAéwy troAvicduirrov, T&s v6os &věpátroval trapéorrmicev to ºyàp airb éortlv Štrep ppovéet plea ov pious âvôpátrotori kal traoru kal travrí to yop tràéov éarl vömua. The best elucidation of this frag- ment is given by Theophrastus, De Sensu, 3 sq. ... IIapp. uèv yöp 3Aws oùöèv &@dºpticev (he did not treat of eaeh of the senses separately) &AA& pºdwov, 3rt 6volv čvrouw ortoixetow karð to Örep8áAAov čotiv i yuágis’ é&v y&p Örepaipm rò 6eppov. 3) to tºuxpov, &AAmy yived flat rhv 5udvowv" geWria, 5è ical ka9apwrépav thu äuä to 9epuðv' oi, whv &AA & kal raúrmy 8storðaſ rivos orvuuetpias’ &s y&p éká- atº, pnotív etc. to . yap aio'6&ve- orðal ſcal to ºppovetv &s rairo Aéyet ANTHROPOLOGY. 603 menides is still far from discriminating between the spiritual and the corporeal, and that he does not attempt to distinguish perception and thought in regard to their origin and formal character, though he entirely recog- mises the superiority of the rational assertion to the sensuous intuition; for that such a view is only enun- ciated in the second part of his poem is unimportant for this point. If he had been aware of the distinction, he would not have passed it over in this place, but would have sought to explain it from the standpoint of ordi- nary opinion." But he has instituted no further enquiries into the nature of opinion, and of the activity of the soul.” 6to kal rºw uviumv kal Thu Añ6my &mb roëtww yívea 6at 61& ràs kpdaea's. &v 5’ iméſwort tº uſéet trótepov ša ral qpovely 3 ot), kal ris i öld.6eoris, où6èv črt Sidºpticev” 3rt 5& kal T6 évavría, ka0' airb trole? Thy ata'6moriv, ºpavepov čv ois pnot row verpov (po- rös ačv kal 6epuot kal povăs owk aia 6&ved 6a, 61& Tºv čkAetºw roi, Tru- pos, juxpod 8& kai orioris kal Tów évavríav aid 6&ved 6at kal &Aws 6& Trāv rô by éxelv rivă yvågiv. Cf. Alex. in Metaph. 1009 b, 21, who concludes his commentary on the verse with the words (p. 263, 22 Don.): to yap tračov Aéyétat vómua. às yºp (?) too ppovetv hptmuévov ths orwuatikis kpáorews kal &el kará to traéovášov kal étrukparody év tá orwuattic; 6taðéo et airoo ye- vouévov. Ritter, i. 495, translates traéov as the full; Hegel, Gesch. d. Phil. i. 277, the most ; Brandis, Gr. Röm. Phil. i. 392, the mightier; Steinhart, l. c. 243, the prepon- derant fiery. It rather signifies, however, as Theophrastus rightly explains, to irepšáNAov, the pre- ponderating, and the whole pro- position asserts that of the two elements, the one that prepon- derates and overcomes is thought, which engenders and determines opinions. On account of this theory, Theophrastus reckons Parmenides among those philo- sophers who regard perception as produced by that which is of like kind. * Theophrastus says: rö aio 64- ver6al ſcal to ppovetv. Ös Tairo Aéyet ; Arist. Metaph. iv. 5, 1009 b, 12, 21, reckons Parmenides among those who considered ºppé- vmous to be the same as ała 6ma is ; and Diog. ix. 22, following Theo- phrastus, and agreeing with Stob. i. 790, tells us rhv juxºv ical Tov votiv rairov eival (II. &mépmve). This is, as a matter of fact, quite correct; but we must remember that he did not observe the dis- tinction between perception and thought, and consequently did not expressly deny it ; and that in v. 148, perception is included under the word ºppovéet. * Cf. p. 602, 2. According to 604 PARMENIDES. Whether in his physics he inculcated the doctrine of metempsychosis or of pre-existence is uncertain.” The statement that he believed in a destruction of the universe * seems to be founded on a misunderstanding.” What significance Parmenides ascribed to his phy- Joh. Damasc. Parall. ii. 25, 28. (Stob. Floril. Ed. Mein. iv. 235), Parmenides, like Empedocles, ac- counted for sensation by the theory of pores in the organs of sense. The name of Parmenides, how- ever, is no doubt wrongly placed in this connection; it is absent ap. Plut. Plac. iv. 9, 3, and Galen, c. 14, p. 303. Ib. No. 30, we find IIapp. 'Eutrečok??s éAAeſthet Tpoq’īs Thu èpečiv, a notice on which, even if it is true, nothing could be based: for Karsten's explanation (p. 269) that desire arises when one of the elements is present in too small measure, is very uncertain. Lastly, Plut. Plac. iv. 5, 5, says: II. ev 8X4, T6 6&pakt (to jºyeuovuköv) kal 'Etríkovpos, but this is evidently a mere inference from some saying of Parmenides, and not the saying itself. * Simpl. Phys. 9 a. says of Parmenides' Deity: cal r&s juxās Tréutely troté pºv ćic roi, Čupavods eis rô &eiàs, trot & 5& àváraxty ºpmori. Ritter, i. 510, and Karsten, p. 272 sqq., understand this to mean that éuqavès was the light or aether, and &etőés the dark or the terrestrial world; and that, accordingly, Parmenides regarded birth as a sinking from the higher world, and death as a return to it. But the expressions éupavés and àetö&s do not signify the light and the dark, but that which is manifest to us, and that which is hidden; the one consequently the upper 'world, and the other the lower, Hades. The words of Simplicius, therefore, assert that God sends souls now out of this life, and now into it. And though these words, strictly speaking, certainly imply pre-existence, it is still doubtful whether we ought so to interpret them, and not as a poetical mode of expression. At the same time, it is quite possible that Parmenides may have adopted in his exposition of the ordinary theories the doc- trine of transmigration. Also the expression ortuyepès Tókos (Parm. v. 129, Sup. p. 595, 2) does not necessarily, as Ritter thinks, ex- press that it would be better for men not to be born: it may simply refer to birth pangs. Trávrm al- ready carries us beyond our human world. 2 Hippol. Refut. kóavov čºpm pºetpea 6al, 11 : row 8è rpétrº, 1. º q) 3' ºr oùic eitrev. * As the Philosophumena them- selves say that Parmenides did not give his opinion particularly on the destruction of the world, it is probable that the statement has no other foundation than the clos- ing verse of Parmenides' poem:— oira rot karð 5óšav čqv táöe vöv Te éaori, f 5 * * * kal puerétrelt' &md roße TeXevthorovoſt Tpaq’évra. Toſs 5 §vou’ &v6pwtrol étría muov čkdoºrg. karé6evrº These verses, however, seem to refer to the destruction of indi- viduals and not of the universe. PHYSICS. 605 sics is a point on which opinions have been divided from the earliest times." Some suppose that in them we have throughout only the standpoint of delusive opinion, and not the personal convictions of the philo- sopher. Others think that he did not intend to deny all truth to the world of phenomena as such, but only to discriminate its divided and variable Being from the One and undivided Being of true existence. This second theory has had many advocates in modern times,” but I cannot support it. Parmenides himself declares too ex- plicitly that he acknowledges only the one unchangeable essence as a reality; that he does not concede a particle of truth to the ordinary notion which shows us plurality and change; and that, consequently, in the second part of his poem he is stating the opinions of others, and not his own convictions.” Aristotle apprehended his doctrine * The opinions of the ancients are given most fully by Brandis, Comm. El. 149 sqq.; cf. Gr. Röm. Phil. i. 394 sqq.; and also by Kar- sten, p. 143 Sqq. I have not thought it necessary to discuss them, as the judgment of Aristo- tle, which we shall presently examine, must, after all, be con- clusive for us. * Schleiermacher, Gesch. d. Phil. 63. ‘But the truth is that all this holds good only of abso- lute Being; and, therefore, the Plurality is not a plurality of ab- solute Being,' etc.; Karsten, 145: ille nec unam amplexus est verita- tem, nec sprevit omnino opiniones; neutrum eacelusit, utrigue swum tribuit locum. Parmenides (cf. p. 149) distinguished the eternal from the mutable, without exactly defining the relation of the two spheres, but it never occurred to him to regard the Phenomenon as deceptive appearance. Cf. Ritter, i. 499 sqq. According to the Eleatics we can never grasp divine truth except in a few general pro- positions; when, according to man's usual method of thinking, we as- sume plurality and change, this is only falsehood and deception of the senses. On the other hand, we must acknowledge that even in what appears as Many and Change the Divine exists, although veiled and misapprehended. * Cf. on this point the quota- tions Sup. pp. 584, 1; 587, 2; 604, 3; especially the verses with which the first part of his poem, the doc- trine of Being, concludes, v. 110 Sqq. :— év tá orot traúw triarov Aóyov #8& vánua 606 PARMENIDES. in this same way; Plato tells us” that in contradict- ing the ordinary view, Zeno was entirely at one with his master; and it is entirely beyond question that Zeno absolutely denied plurality and change. It may seem strange, on this view of the matter, that Parme- mides should not only give a detailed account of opinions which he considers altogether worthless, but should construct a specific theory from their point of view; it may also seem unlikely that he should entirely deny the truth of the sense perception, and that in his few propositions concerning the One, which are rather negative than positive, he should believe himself to have exhausted the whole of the truth.” But what else could be said, and how could he express himself dif- ferently on the subject of reality, having once started from the proposition that only Being is, and that non- Being is absolutely, and in all respects, non-existent, when he had not attained to those more precise dialectical distinctions with which Plato and Aristotle afterwards opposed his doctrine P. His reason for never- theless entering at length upon the consideration of the world of phenomena is sufficiently explained by himself: ăups &Ambeſms' 36%as 3 &to roße Bporeſas Adv6ave, káguov ćuáv čtréav Štratm- Aovákoúww. Cf. the passages quoted, Sup. p. 561, 3; 587, 3; and De Caelo, iii. i. 298 b, 14 : oi uèv y&p airóv 32Aws &vetNov yeweariv kai q,00páv ot,0&v yöp otºre yfyveo'6aſ qaow otºre pºetpea 6al rôv čvrov. #AA& uðvov Sokeſv juiv. olov of repl MéAurorów re ral IIappevièmv. Similarly, Gen. et Corr. i. 8, 325 a, 2. He then proceeds to mention the determinations of the world of phenomena, and praises Parme- nides for having extended his ob- servations to that world also (Metaph. i. 5, Sup. p. 592, 1), but this is not to the purpose, for nothing is said by him of the re- lation in which Parmenides placed the Phenomenon and Reality. * Parm. 128 A. * Ritter, l.c. PHYSICS. 607 he purposes not to overlook even hostile opinions." The reader is to have both theories set before him, the true and the false, in order that he may the more surely de- cide for the true. The false theory of the universe is not indeed not represented as it is actually found with any of the previous philosophers, but as, according to the opinion of Parmenides, it ought to be expressed. This, however, we find in other ancient authors. Plato often corrects the opinions that he combats, both as to their content and the manner of apprehending them. Thu- cydides does not put into the mouth of his characters what they really said, but what he would have said in their place. Parmenides adopts the same dramatic procedure; he represents the ordinary view of the world as he himself would regard it if he placed himself on that standpoint, but his design is not to expound his own opinions, but those of others; his whole physical theory has a merely hypothetical import. It is designed to show us how the world of phenomena would present itself to us if we could regard it as a reality. But it is clear from the exposition that the world of phe- nomena can only be explained on the theory of two primitive elements, one corresponding to Being, and the other to non-Being ; and consequently, that it pre- supposes at all points the Being of non-Being. And therefore it is the more evident that the world of phe- nomena itself, as distinct from the One and eternal Being, has no claim to Reality. Parmenides, however, did not attempt that thorough dialectical refutation of the ordinary mode of presentation, which, we are told * W. 121 (sup, p. 597, 3). 608 ZENO. by the most trustworthy testimonies, was the special achievement of Zeno." When a dialectical procedure of this kind, therefore, is ascribed to Parmenides by later writers,” they are confusing him with Zeno; only the beginnings of such a method can be recognised in his argument against the Being of non-Being. ZENO. BARMENIDEs had developed the Eleatic doctrine to a point beyond which it could not be materially carried. It only remained for his successors to defend his views as opposed to the ordinary presentation, and to establish them more precisely in their particular details. The more minutely, however, the relation of the two stand- points was considered, the more distinctly must their entire incompatibility, and the inability of the Eleatic doctrine to explain phenomena, have appeared. On the other hand, where an understanding with ordinary opinion was attempted, the purity of the definitions concerning Being must have immediately suffered. To have seen this constitutes the merit of Zeno and Melissus. For the rest, these two philosophers are agreed both with each other and with Parmenides. The only difference between them is that Zeno, who far excelled Melissus in dialectic ability, maintained * Authorities will be cited be- Favorin. ap. Diog. ix. 23, ascribes low ; for the present it is sufficient to him the Achilles puzzle, and to recall Plato, Parm. 128 A sqq. Porph. ap. Simpl. Phys. 30 a (vide * According to Sext. Math. vii. p. 543), the argument from bi- 5 sq., some wished to reckon him section. We shall find, however, not only among the Physicists, but that both belong to Zeno. Cf. p. also among the Dialecticians. 590, 1. HIS WRITINGS. 609 the standpoint of his master uncompromisingly, and in sharp opposition to the ordinary view; while Melissus, with less acuteness of intellect, approached somewhat more nearly to the ordinary view, and diverged in some not unimportant respects from the doctrine of Parme- nides. Zemo, the intimate friend and disciple of Par- ! Zeno of Elea, the son of Te- leutagoras (Diog. ix. 25, vide p. 580, I), according to Plato (Parm. 127 B) was twenty-five years younger than Parmenides, and at an epoch which must have been about 455–450 B.C., forty years old. This would imply that he was born about 495–490 B.C., and in Ol. 70 or 71. This indication, however, as already observed (loc. cit.), is hardly to be regarded as histori- cally accurate. Suidas places Zeno's prime in the 78th Ol.; Diog. ix. 29, in the 79th ; Eusebius, in his Chron., in the 80th Olympiad. But these statements are not always very definite, and it is sometimes questionable whether they are based upon actual tradition, or are merely inferences drawn from JPlato, or derived from a calcula- tion (Diel's Rhein. Mus. xxxi. 35) which makes Zeno forty years younger than his master, whose &ku?) was placed in Ol. 69. It can only be stated with certainty, that Zeno was born about the beginning of the fifth century, and appeared as a teacher and author consider- ably before the middle of that century. His relation to Parme- nides is described as very intimate; Plato, l.c., says he was reported to have been his favourite (tratăukd). Athen. xi. 505 sq. takes great of- fence at this statement; but it VOL. I. need not be taken in a bad sense. According to Apollodor, ap. Diog. l. c. Zeno had been the adopted son of Parmenides. Though this is quite possible in itself, yet Plato's silence on the matter makes us suspect that “adopted son’ may have been substituted for favour- ite, in order to obviate miscon- struction of this relationship: and the misapprehended expression. Soph. 241 D, may also have related to this. Zeno shares with Parme- nides the honourable designation of an āvīp IIv6ayópelos (Strabo, vi. 1, i. p. 252) and the glory of hav- ing promoted law and order in Elea. He is praised in Diog. ix, 28 for having, from attachment to his home, spent his whole life in Elea without once visiting Athens (obic tièmuñoras to trapárav irpos airoës). But this statement can hardly be true. For if the First Alcibiades be too doubtful a source to guarantee the fact (119 A) that Pythodorus and Callias each paid 100 minae to Zeno for his instruc- tions, which Callias must certainly have received in Athens, Plutarch, Per. c. 4, c. 5, tells us of a residence of Zeno in Athens, during which Pericles associated with him ; and this fact may have given occasion to Plato's story of the visit of Par- menides to that city. Zeno is said to have displayed great firmness R R 610 ZEWO. menides, seems to have agreed with him on all points. Plato, at any rate, expressly says that he sought in his under tortures, inflicted on him in consequence of a rebellion against a tyrant in which he had been implicated. The occurrence itself is abundantly attested: by Herac- lides, Demetrius, Antisthenes, Her- mippus and others, ap. Diog. ix. 26 sq.; Diodor. Erc. p. 557; Wess. Plut. Garrulit. c. 8, p. 505; Sto. Rep. 37, 3, p. 1051 ; Adv. Col. 32, 10, p. 1126; Philo, Qu. Omn. Pr. Lib. 881 C f. Hösch. ; Clemens, Strom. iv. 496 C ; Cic. Tusc. ii. 22, 52; N. D. iii. 33, 82; Wal. Max. iii. 3, 2 sq.; Tert. Apo- loget. c. 50; Amm. Marc. xiv. 9; Philostr. V. Apoll. vii. 2; Suidas, *EAéa, etc. The more precise details, however, are variously given. Most of our authorities make Elea the scene of the event; Valerius says Agrigentum, Philo- stratus, Mysia; Ammianus, con- founding Zeno with Anaxarchus, Cyprus. The tyrant is called some- times Diomedon, sometimes Demy- lus, sometimes Nearchus; Valerius names Phalaris; Tertullian, Diony- sius. Some assert that Zeno gave up his friends to the tyrant; others that, in order to betray no one, he bit out his own tongue; others that he bit off the tyrant's ear. As to the manner of his death also, there is much division of opinion. According to Diogenes, the tyrant was killed; according to Diodorus, Zeno was set free. Wa- lerius represents the occurrence as happening twice, first to this Zeno, and afterwards to a namesake of his (cf. Bayle, Dict. Zenón d'Elée, Rem. C). Although therefore the occurrence seems to be historical, nothing further can be determined in regard to it. Whether the allusion ap. Arist. Rhet. i. 12, 312 b, 3, refers to this event, and what is the true explanation of it, we do not know. Plato mentions a work which Zeno composed in his early life (Parm. 127 C sqq.) as if it were his only known work (it is called simply tº Zhvovos Ypdwuara, to otºy'ypapºua). Simpl. (Phys. 30 a) also mentions a work (to a tºy- 'ypappa) apparently the same spoken of by Plato. It was devoted to a polemic against the ordinary view, refuting by inference the presuppositions of that stand-point. It was divided into several parts (called A6)ot by Plato), and each part into different sections (called by Plato intoffégets, and by Simpl. étrixelphuata), in each of which one of the hypotheses of the ordinary point of view was designed to be reduced ad absurdum (Proclus in Parm. iv. 100 Cous., who by Aóryot understands the several ar- guments, and by Štro8éosis the premisses of the several, conclu- sions; he speaks of 40 Aóyot, and can hardly have seen Zeno's work. David, Schol. in Arist. 22 o, 34 sqq., no doubt copies from him). That the work was in prose, we know from Plato, and from the extracts in Simplicius. It is no doubt identical with the book al- luded to in Arist. Soph. El. c. 10, 170 b, 22, in the words, kal 6 &n orpwéuevos kal 6 €potöv Zhvov; for even though there might be questions and answers in this book, yet it need not have been on that account an actual dialogue, and Zeno need not have been the first author of the dialogue, as Diog. PHYSICS. 611 writings to refute the plurality of things, and by this means to prove indirectly the unity of all Being main- tained by Parmenides.' Thus his conception of Being must have been, in general, the same as that of his master. What we are told of his physical propositions, also, in part coincides with the hypothetical physics of Parmenides. As some of these statements, however, are manifestly untrue, and as our most trustworthy authorities never quote a single physical theory of Zeno's, it is most probable that he did not pursue further this portion of the doctrine of Parmenides.” iii. 48, asserts with the prefix of ºpdori. Aristotle himself, if we may judge from this passage of Diog. and Athen. xi. 505 c, did not designate him as such. That Zeno wrote many books does not follow from the use of the plural BigAta ap. Diog. ix. 26, for this may refer to the several parts of his one known work. On the other hand, Suidas names four writings pièes, éâymoris 'Eutrečok- Aéovs, trpos toūs ‘pixogóqovs, tr. qāorews. Of the éthyma is 'Eutrečok- Aéovs, which, however, is certainly spurious, we find traces elsewhere, vide p. 612. The three others, mentioned only by Eudocia, may be merely different names for the book we have already spoken of. Stallbaum's proposal however(Plut. Parm. p. 30) to read #ypayev čplēas Tpos Tovs pixogóqous repl púorews, in Suidas, not only contradicts the received text, but disagrees entirely with the manner in which Suidas and similar authors generally cite the titles of books. According to Simpl. l.c., Alexander and Porphyry cannot have seen Zeno's work; nor does Proclus even seem to have been acquainted with it. Simplicius himself, however, had probably something more than extracts from it, although (vide p. 21 b) he may not have been quite certain that his text was complete. At p. 131 a, he is quoting only from Eudemus. Parm. 127 E: ápa toûró Éotiv BoöAovrat orov of Aðyol, oùk &AA0 tº # 6tauáxeoréal trapā travta. Tà Aeyóueva, Ös oil troAAd Éati ; Kal toūrou airoo olei oroi tekuſpiov eival ëkaotov táv Aó)wy, $orre Kal jºye7 Toorajra Tekuňpia trapéxeoróat 60 ovs trep Aóryovs yéypaſpas, Ös oëk éott troAAd; Oik, &AA&, pdval Töv Zīva wa, kaxás ovvikas &Aov to Ypduna è RočAetat. Socrates on this remarks that Parmenides and Zeno say the same, the former directly, the latter indirectly. ov Pºv yip (Parm.) év toſs trouhuagiv čv pſis eival to iráv . . . 86e 68 at of troAA& qmoiv eival, and Zeno practically concedes it when he explains more particularly how he came to com- pose his work (vide p. 613, 1). * Our information on this point is confined to a few passages. Diog. ix. 29, says: âpérket 8 airé réðe. R R 2 612 ZEWO. We can only with certainty ascribe to him those de- monstrations which are intended to defend Parmenides’ doctrine as opposed to the ordinary presentation." kóopovs sival, kevöv te uži sival' ºyeyev;0.0at 8& Thy rôv travrov pāoriv ék 0epuoi, kal juxpoſſ Kai čmpoo ral à-ypoſ, Aappavóvrwy eis &AAmaa Tºv perað0A#v. Yévéatv T' &v6pótrov ćic 'yūs elval kal juxºv kpāua, Širdpxetv ék Töv Tpoetpmºvévov kot & ſimäevös Toštov Čirikpármoly. Stob. Eel. i. 60 : Méxtoratos kal Závov to èv Kal Trāv kai uávov &fölov Kal &melpov to £v kal to pièv év thv čváykmv, iſºmy 8è airtàs r& réorgapa orotxela, etón 8è to veikos kal Thy pixtav. Aéyet 8è kai Tô a rotxela 6eobs, ſcal rô pſyua toûrwu Töv kóopov, kai trpos Tajra &vańv6%geral (perhaps Aveo- 0at) to uovoeiðés" (all that is appa- rently of the same kind, as wood, meat, flesh, &c., that which Aris– totle calls ögououepès resolves itself finally into the four elements) kal 6etas uèv offeral Tês juxás, 6etovs 6* kai toys ueréxoviras airóv ka9apot's ka9após. This last exposition re- minds us so much of Empedocles, that Heeren (in h. 1.) thought of substituting the name Empedocles for the singular words iN my 6é airms. It seems to me the name of Empedocles may have dropped out, either in that place, as Sturz (Emped. p. 168) supposes, or more probably (Krische, Forsch. i. 123) ibefore the words to uévêy, etc. Or perhaps the whole passage may have been taken from the ééhymous 'Eu- arešokAéovs (p. 609, 1, end), ascribed to Zeno. But this work cannot have been genuine; it must originally have borne the name of Zeno the Stoic. In the first place, it is very improbable and wholly without precedent in ancient times, that a philosopher like Zeno should have written a commentary on the work of a contemporary of his own age ; and next, it is very strange that, if he did so, he should have selected not the work of his master, but one that was so little in harmony with his own views. Further, it appears from what has been already quoted, p. 610, that Zeno wrote only one book; and the utter silence of Aristotle and his commentators as to any physical utterances of Zeno shows that none were known to them. Lastly, it is clear that, in Stobaeus, propositions are as- cribed to Zeno which are entirely unknown to him. The same holds good in part of the statements of Diogenes, but the greater number of these are, so far, less improbable, as they agree with the doctrine of Parmenides. Parmenides likewise denied empty space, held the warm and cold to be elements, and taught that mankind arose in the first instance from the earth, and that souls were compounded from the elements. The proposition: kóo- pious eival, however, cannot have belonged to an Eleatic philosopher, whether we understand by kóguou a number of synchronous worlds, or successive worlds; Zeno the Eleatic seems to be here confounded with Zeno the Stoic ; and what is said of the elements bears evidence of the Stoic-Aristotelian doctrine. . There seems also to have been a confusion between the two Zenos in Epiph. Exp. Fid. 1087 C : Zhvov 6 °EAeárms à éptorturbs to a ré répg Zhvavi kal thy yiv &kivmtov Aéyet Kal uměéva Tótrov kevöv eival. * Stallbaum, Plat. Parm. 25 DIAL ECTIO. 613 Zeno adopted for this purpose an indirect method. Parmenides had derived his determinations of Being directly from the concept of Being. Zemo proves the same doctrine indirectly by showing that the opposite theories involve us in difficulties and contradictions, and that Being does not admit of our regarding it as a Plurality, as something divisible and changeable. He seeks to prove the Eleatic doctrine by reducing the prevalent mode of presentation to absurdity." Because of this method, which he employed with masterly skill, Zeno was called by Aristotle the inventor of Dialectic,” and Plato says that he could make one and the same appear to his hearers as like and unlike, as one and many, as in motion and at rest.” Though this Dialectic afterwards furnished many weapons to the Eristic of sqq. thinks it was chiefly directed against Anaxagoras and Leucippus; but in the demonstrations of Zeno there is nothing that specially points to either of these men. * In the Parm. 25 sqq., Xeno thus continues: éoºrt 5& Tó ye &Amóēs 80%6eld ris Taota Tà ypdu- para Tó IIappreviðov A6).q, trpos toys étrixelpodytas attöv kopºeiv, &s ei ev čott toxA& kal yeXota avuòaivet traorxeiv Tó Aóyº kai évautía airó. &vti/\éyet 5% of v Tooto Tô Ypduua trpos toys Tā troAA& Aéryovras ical &vratroëtöwal taota kal TAeto, Tooto BovXópevov Šmxotiv, &s éri yeaotótepa trö0'xoi &v airów i ötróBeats, ei troAA& éotiv, # h too &v eival, et Tus incavós éirečíot. * Diog. viii. 57; ix. 25; Sext. Math. vii. 7, cf. Timon ap. Diog. l. c. (Plut. Pericl. c. 4; Simpl. Phys, 236 b):— āpubotepoyadéogov Te uéya ordévos oùk &Aatraëvov Zīva wos trèvrov čtrixáTTopos, hēē Mexford ov, troAAów pavrao uáv étávo, traúpov 'ye pºèv efora. * Phaedr. 261 D : Töv oſſºv 'EAeatucov IIaxapahāmy Aéyovra oilk to wet, Téxvn Śare paívea 0at Tots ākočovoi Tà air& Šuota kal &vöuolo, ical év kal troAA&, uévourd te ań kai £epóweva. That Zeno is here meant, and not Alcidamas (as Quintil. iii. 1, 2, thinks), is evident. More- over, Plato himself says in Parm. 127 E: trós, pdvai & Zhvov, Tooto Aéysis; ei troAAd €orri Tä, övta, Ös &pa šeſ air& Šuoud teeival kal &vá- pola, rotto 8& 83 &öövarov; . . . . oira, pdval row Zhvava. Similarly, Isocr. Enc. Hel. Sub init. : Zhuova, Töv Taiºtă 6Vyat & kal tróAlv &öövara trelpópevov što paivetv, for these words no doubt refer, not to any particular argument, but to Zeno's antinomistic procedure generally. 614 ZEWO. the Sophists, it is itself distinguished from that Eristic" by its positive object; and still less, for the same reason, can it be identified with Scepticism.” The dialectic argument with Zeno, though it does not altogether dis- dain Sophistic applications, is never anything but a means to establish a metaphysic conviction, the doc- trine of the unity and invariability of Being. In particular, the arguments of Zemo, so far as we are acquainted with them, are concerned with multi- plicity and motion. The arguments against the multi- plicity of things which have been transmitted to us have respect to their magnitude, number, Being in space, and co-operation. The arguments against motion are likewise four, which Zeno did not arrange in the best order, nor according to any fixed principle. I now proceed to examine these arguments collec- tively:- A. The Arguments against Multiplicity. 1. If Being were many, it must be at the same time infinitely small and infinitely great. Infinitely small; for as every plurality is a number of unities, but a true unity alone is indivisible— so each of the Many must either itself be an indivisible unity, or be made up of such unities. That which is indivisible, however, can have no magnitude; for all that has magnitude is infinitely divisible. The particular parts of which the * With which it is too closely ºrdinary statement, perhaps, arose identified by Plut. Per. 4, and ap. from a misunderstanding of some Eus. Pr. Ev. i. 8, 7; and with passage like that quoted from which Seneca confuses it, Ep. 88, Aristotle, p. 615, 1. 44 sq., when he attributes to Zeno * Which, according to Diog. ix. the assertion of Gorgias: Nihil 72, laid claim to it, whereas Timon, esse ne unum quidem. This extra- l.c., does not. * AGAINST MULTIPLICITY. 615 many consists have consequently no magnitude. If they are added to anything it will not become greater, nor if they are taken away will it become less. But that which, being added to another, does not make it greater, and being taken away from another does not make it less, is nothing. The Many is therefore infinitely small; for each of its constituent parts is so small that it is nothing. On the other hand, however, these parts | Simpl. Phys. 30 a év uévrol Tô ovyypáupati airod troAA& #xoviri étrixelpfuata ka0° àicagºrov čeſkvvoruv, §tt T3 troAA& eival Aéryovri orvuòaivet Tà évavitſa Aéyetv. čv év éorriv ćirt- Xeipmua, Év ć Šetkvvoru, 3ri ei troXAd . éoti kal ueydºa €otl ſcal purpś, weyāAa uèv šare &relpa to uéyé90s eival, utºp? §§ oitas, Šare uměčv ëxeiv uéye60s. v 33 roërg (in the section which proves that it is in- finitely small) befkvvaru, ärt of uſire pléyé60s uſite triºxos pºſite &ykos un- 6eſs é o ru, oiâ’ &v ein rooto oi y&p ei &AAq àvri, pnori, trpoo’yévouro, où6èv &v weigov trouſoele, ueyé00vs 'yöp uměevos ūvros, trpoo'yevouévov 8è (this 6* should no doubt be omitted; it seems to have arisen from the oibév which follows) oiâèv ofäv re eis uéyé0os étribooval, kal oùros &v #öm to trpoo’yuánevov où6èv etm. (Zeno must have added here : ‘nor could anything become smaller, by its being taken away from it.') ei Šč àtoylvouévov to #Tepov uměčv čAartóv čarri, uměč aß Tpoorylvopévov aiºhoretat, SmNovótt to trpoo'yevópºevov oë6&v ºv, où6ë to &toyevópºevov. (This part of the exposition is confirmed by Eude- mus, vide infra, and by Arist. Metaph. iii. 4, 1001 b, 7 : étu ei &ötalpetov airb to èv, karð uèv to Závavos &éíopia oi6&v &v eſſm. 6 y&p pañre trpoo ribéuevov uſite & patpotſue- vov trouet weigov uměš éAartov, ot qmaiw elval tooto róv čvrov, &s 678 ov Štt övros weyā0ous roß &vros.) ical raûra oix. To ev &valpóv à Zh- vov Aéyet, &AA’ 3rt, ei uéyé60s exel ékao'rov Tóv troAAów ical &treſpov, où5év čotal &kpı8ós v Ště rºw étr' &Teipov rouív. čeſ 5& eveivat. § ôetkvvori, trpoãetëas ātl oièëv éxel puéyebos, éic too kaatov Tóv troAAów éavré, Taitov eival kal év. Kai à Oeuto rios 3& Töv Závovos A6-yov čv eival to Öv karaokeväſelv pmolv čk roo ovvexes to (b. Te) airo elval kal &öuaíperov. ei yöp 6taipoºró, qmoriv, où6èv čo rat ākpubás &v Ště. Thy k &lreupov touhy Tāv orwudrav. êouke 68 waxNov ć Závov Aéyeuv, &s où6è troAA& #ortal, The passage in Themist. Phys. 18 a, p. 122 Sp., runs thus: Zhvavos, Šs éic too ovvexés re eival kal &öuaíperov čv eival to by categicetaſe, Aéyov, &s ei öuaipeiral oiâé àotal &kpi}^s ºv 61& thv étr' &repov touńv táv orwººd- tov. From the connection in which this assertion of Zeno's stood (according to Simplicius), it appears that Simplicius' criticism of Themist. is correct. Zeno is not speaking primarily of the One Being; but starting from the pre- supposition of Multiplicity, he is telling us how each of the many things must then be conceived. So far as he at the same time shows 616 ZEWO. are also infinitely great. For since that which has no magnitude is not, the Many, in order to be, must have a magnitude : its parts must consequently be sepa- rated from one another—that is, other parts must lie between them. that each thing, in order to be one, must also be indivisible, his asser- tion might likewise be applied to the One Being; this, too, in order to be one, must be indivisible (Év ovvexés). Eudemus seems to have had this argument in view when he says, ap. Simpl. Phys. 21 a (cf. 30 a, 31 a): Zhvavd. ºpaqi Aéyetv, et tus airó to Šv &toãoſm tº Troté Éott Aéčeiv [éotiv, *getvl Tä, övta. Aéyéiv: htrópel 6* @s éolice (Bran- dis, i. 416, has this from MSS. In the printed text these words are wanting, but they occur p. 30 a.) ôtà To Töv Pušv aiorêmtöv čkao Tov Katmyopikós Te troAA& Aévé00al kal peptopºg, Thu 8& ortlyphy amáš Šv Tubéval. 6 yap pºſite trpoo Tifféuevov aúčet uſire & palpodpºevov ueto? oik Østo Töv čvrov eival. Simpl. 21 b, observes on this: 6 wºv too Zīva'wos Aóryos &AAos Tis outcev oftos éival trap' ékéivov row év BigAiq, pepôuevov of kal 6 IIA4t ov čv Tó IIapuevtåg uéuvmtal. Ékeſ utv yöp Šti oil, éart troAA& 6eſkvvoru . . . Švraúða 6é, és Eöömuós (pmoi, kal &viſpel to Év. Thu yöp at typºv &s to èveival Aéyet, tà 8è troXA& eival ovyxopeſ. 6 uévrol 'AAéðavöpos ical évraúða toû Zhvavos &s to troAA& &vaipoovtos prepavāoróat Töv Eöömuov offetal. “às yopiatopeſ, ‘pmotv, Eöömpos, Zhvov Ó IIappreviðov Tyvápipios étrelpâto Öeukvěvat 3rt uh oiáv re rà èvra troAA& eival, Tô um- Śēv eival év Tots of guy ev, Tå Ö& troAA& TA700s eival évôww.” Ical öti uév oëx &s tº toxXà &vaipoovros Zhvavos Eöömuos uéuvmtal,viv 87Xov ěk tās airod Aéews. oiual be uſite But the same thing holds good of [umöè] év tá, Závovos Bu63 tº Toudo- tov Čirixeſpnua pépé00al, otov 6 'AAéčavöpós (pmat. It is clear, how- ever, from this passage that Alex- ander correctly apprehended the meaning of Zeno's proposition, and no doubt that of Eudemus, and that Simplicius here makes the same mistake which he afterwards himself corrects in Themistius. Zeno says: In order to know what things are, we must know what the smallest parts are out of which they are compounded; but this does not imply that since they are the smallest parts, they are indivi- sible points, and, as invisible points, are without magnitude, and consequently nothing. He wants to prove (as Philop. Phys. B, lo, 15, observes, not without some interpo- lation of his own comments) that there can be no multiplicity, for every multiplicity consists of uni- ties; but among all the things which present themselves to us as a multi- plicity, among all ovvex?, nothing is really One. Brandis, i. 416, wrongly constructs an independent demonstration out of what Eude- mus and Aristotle, l. c., say; and. Ritter, i. 522, deduces from the statement of Eudemus the bold theory that Zeno, like Parmenides, acknowledged that the full and true knowledge of the One was not contained in his definitions of it. My reasons for disagreeing with both these opinions will appear in the course of the present exposi- tion. - A GAINST MULTIPLICITY. 617 these parts: they also must have a magnitude, and be separated from one another, and so on to infinity. Thus we get an infinite number of magnitudes, or an infinite magnitude." 2. By the same process, Zeno shows also that the Many in respect of number must be as much limited as unlimited. Limited, for it is just so much as it is ; not more and not less. Unlimited, for two things are two, only where they are separated ; and in order that they may be separate, something must be between them ; similarly between this and each of the two, and so on ad infinitwm.” As in the first argument, the determination of infinite magnitude, so here the determination of infinite number is attained by ap- prehending plurality as a multiplicity of separate magnitudes, and by introducing between each two of these separate magnitudes a third separating mag- Y] itude. * Simplicius, l. c. 30 b, after having discussed the argument from division, which will be quoted im- mediately—proceeds thus: Ical oita pºv to karū to trää90s &teipov ćic ris Sixotoutas Ščeiše. To be carā To wéyé90s aſpörepov Katë, Thy at thu étrixeſpngly. T206et{as Yāp, Öti ei uh ëxel to by uéye60s oiâ’ &vein, Érd yet. “ei 3& £ativ, &váykm, kaotov påye66s ti čxelv kal traxos kal &tréxetu attoo to repov &tó rod Étépov, kai trepi toū ſpoëxovros 6 airbs A6-yos' kai 'yāp kelvo £et uéyebos ſcal trpoéget airoi; tı, Šuotov 83, rooto &raš Te eitrely kal &ei Aéyeiv. oilà èv y&p airtoi, Totoorov čoxatov čotal otte érepov Trpos érepov oint écºral. oitos, ei troXAá éativ, &váykm air& purpſ; te eival kal ueydaa.. utºp& Pºv čote wh The ancients usually designate this portion éxelv máye60s, aeyāAa 5& &aſte ämelpa eival.” By Trpoéxov I understand that which lies before another, and thereby keeps that other at a dis- tance from a third. * Simpl. l. c. 30 b : betkvěs y&p, §ti ei troXAá éott rà air& tretrepa- opéva èatl Kal &telpa, Ypdqet Taota karð Aéâly 6 Závov “ei troAAá, éotiv, &váykm rogaora, eival 60'a €oti kal oùre TAetova airóv otre éAdºttova. ei ö& Tooraúrá čortly 30 a €ortl, Tetépa- awéva &v etn. Kal triNiv, ei troAAd éotiv, &relpa Tó, úvra éatív. &ei ºyap repa usta;v táv čvrov čotl, ical tróAtv ékeſvov čtepa wetašū, Kal oiſta's & Telpa rā āvra éotſ.” Kal ošta, uév, etc. (vide preceding note). 618 ZEWO. of Zeno's two arguments as the argument from bi- section." 3. Since all that exists, exists in space, space must itself be in a space, and so ad infinitwm. As this is inconceivable, the existent generally cannot be in space.” * Arist. Phys. i. 3, 187 a, 1, after Parmenides and Melissus’ doctrine of the unity of the one has been discussed in detail: éviot 6' (the Atomists) évéðoorav roſs A6-yous &pſporépous, T6 uèv šta trávra èv, ei To by év ornuaível, §rt égºr) to pººl ov, Té à ék Tös 5txotoutas &roua troth- ogures weye 9m. Simpl. p. 30 a., observes on this passage: Töv Šē 8stºrepov Aóryov Tov ćic rās 5uxorouſas ~00Závayos elvaí pmoliv 6’AAéðavöpos Aéryovros, &s ei uéyé60s Xot rô by kal 6taipoºro, troAA& Tô by kal oilcért êv čarea 6al kal &id. Tottou Seikyūvros, §rt pumöèv Tóv Švrav ča-Tl to Év. This last is rightly questioned by Simpl. and the source of the error is traced to the passage of Eude- mus, quoted p. 616. Then follow the statements quoted p. 615, as to the argument of Zeno, and then, p. 30 a., this observation: 6 Mévrol IIoppípios icoi Töv ćic tàs 61%0Topºtas Aóyov IIapuevíðov pnolveival, év to by éic taúrms trelpopuévov Seikyūval. ºpädel 3& oirws: “ repos 6& fiv Aóryos Tó IIoppeviðm é Ötö täs 5uxotogías, oiáuevos Seikvåval to ov čveival uávov ical rooto &uepès Kal &öuaíperov. ei ºyap elm, p.mail, 5ualperov, Tetuño.6a, 6ixa, kāteira Tów wepºv čkdrepov 6txa kal Toà row &el yivouévov 678-69, qma'iy, Ös firvi ämtoweve? ruvê ša zara Meyã0m éA&xiora kal &ropa TAftbel 6é &reipa kal to 8Xov č, ćAaxtotav TAftöet 88 &treſpov orvoºrhoetal, # q'poodov čotal kal eis oièëv črt 5uaxv- 0forerai kal ék too uměevös avatāore- tal, &rep &rotra. oilk &pa Śualpebhore- tal, &AA& uévet év. kal yèp 3% étretón Tévrm épouáv čarriv, efirep Stat- petov Štrápxel révrm épotos éotal ôtaperov, &AA’ oi Tà uév tá 6' oi. Simpſorów travtºm. 37Aov of v táAuv, dis où6év Štropieveſ, &AA’ oral ppoi,60v, ical eſtep ovathastal ird Alv čk toº uměevös ovotha'etat. ei yüp Širopteve? tu, oi,5étra yewhaetal travt m bumpm- Mévov šare kal éic toirov q'avepāv, qmoruv, dis &ötaíperóv te kal &pspès Kal évêa ral to Šv’. . . (the remainder of the quotation does not belong to this subject) équotdvely 6é úštov, ei IIappevſöov kal uh Zīva w8s éotiv 6 Aóyos, &s kal Tó ‘AAešávöp? §oke. oire yap Év 'rois IIappeviðetous éreat AéyeTaí ri rowbrov, kal ji traetortm io Topta Thy Éic tàs buxotouſas ātroptav eis rôv Závova &vatréutrel, ſcal 63, Kal év toſs trepi kwho eas A6-yous dis Zh- valvos &tropavnuoveterat (cf. infra, the first and second arguments against motion) kal tí óeſ troAA& Aéyéiv, Šte ſcal év airó (péperat rô toū Závovos avypáupati. Selkvěs 7&p, etc. These reasons of Sim- plicius are quite convincing. Por- phyry thinks that the argument from dichotomy must belong to Parmenides, simply because Aris- totle, l. c., mentions it in his crit- ique on the doctrine of Parmenides, without mentioning Zeno. He himself is unacquainted with Zeno's work; what he says about this argument he derives from other sources, and he does not give it in the original acceptation of Zeno. * Arist. Phys. iv. 3, 210 b, 22: § 5& Závay hirópel, à Tu si èoti ri à róiros, év tív. čarat, Adew oi x2Ae- AGAINST MOTION. 619 4. A fourth argument is indicated in the statement that if the shaking out of a bushel of corn produces a sound, each individual grain and each sub-division of a grain must likewise produce sound, which seems to contradict our perceptions." The general question here is—How is it possible that many things together can produce an effect which each of them taken separately does not produce 2 B. The Arguments against Motion. As the arguments just quoted were directed against multiplicity in order to prove the unity of Being, the first main principle of the Eleatic doctrine, so the next four are directed against motion, in order to tróv. c. 1, 209 a, 23: # yöp Závayos âtropia ºnteſ Tuva A6 yov' ei yüp trav ºrb by év Tótrø, 67Aov Štu kal Too Tóirov Tótros éotal kal Toºro sis &melpov trpóstoriv. Eudemus, ap. Simpl. Phys. 131 a étrº Taitov Šē ical # Zhvavos &ropta paíveral &yeuv' āštov [k cf. in what follows: ei pºv oſſºv čv Tótº #twicev eival Tö. &vra] yap trav to by troń sival, ei à 6 Tótros Tóv čvrov, troß &velm oikoúv év &AAq, Tóirq. kākelvos 6%) Šv &AAq, kai oiſta's eis To trpóga. Simpl. 130 b : 6 Zhvovos Aóryos &vaipeiv éööket rov rátrov ćpatów oira's ei êotiv 6 Tótros év tív. čarat; trav yap bv čv Tuvu' to 6é šu rivi kal év rátrº- êort at Špa kal 6 rôtros év rátrºp kal roöto éir' &neupov obk &pa ša riv 6 róiros. Similarly ibid. 124 b. * Arist. Phys. vii. 5, 250 a, 19: ătă totro à Závovos A6-yos oëk &Am. 631s, Ös pope; tās kéyxpov Št toºv uépos. Simpl. in h. l. 255 a, says: 6tà rooro Aſſet kal rov Závovos Toà 'EAéâtov Aóryov Šv #pero IIpwtayópav Töv Goſptortifivº eitrè ydp uot, Éq.m, à IIpotaſyópa, śpa Ś eis Kéryxpos kata- Treoróv påqov trouet, h to uvpiogtov Too kéxpov; roo 5& eitróvros, uh troueiv. 6 6& uéöluvos róv kéyxpov karameo &v trouet péqov 3 ot; ; roo 8è hopeſv eitróvros Tov uéðiplvov, Tí oßv, *@m 6 Závov, oùic ēoti A670s toū ue^{uvov Tów kéyxpov trpos Tov éva kal to uvptootbv rod Évés; too 6é píoſavtos éival: tí of v, *@m 6 Zhvov, oi kal Tóv póqov čoovtat Aó)ot trpos &AAñAous of arrot ; &s yöp tº hoſpoëvra kal oi ſãºol. Toitov 6è oitos éxoviros, ei 6 p.éöuvos Too kéyxpov poq’él pophorel kal 6 eis kéy- xpos kal to uvptootbv roi, kéyxpov. (The latter also, p. 256 b.) Ac- cording to this representation we cannot suppose that this argument was to be found in Zeno's book; and its more complete development in Simplicius may have belonged to some later philosopher. But its essential thought is certified by Aristotle. 620 ZEWO. prove the second fundamental basis of the system, the unchangeableness of Being." 1. The first argument is this:—Before the body that is moved can arrive at the goal, it must first have arrived at the middle of the course; before it reaches this point it must have arrived at the middle of the first half, and previously to that at the middle of the first quarter, and so ad infinitwºm. Every body, there- fore, in order to attain to one point from another, must pass through infinitely many spaces. cannot be passed through in a given time. But the infinite It is con- sequently impossible to arrive at one point from another, and motion is impossible.” 2. The so-called Achilles argument is only another application of this.” The slowest creature, the tortoise, * Cf. in regard to these, Ger- ling, De Zen, paralogismis motum spectant. Marb. 1825; Wellmann's Zeno's Beweise gegen die Bewegung wnd ihre Widerlegungen. Frankf. 1870. * Arist. Phys. vi. 9, 239 b, 9: Tétrapes 5’ eigh A6 you trepi kluharews Závayos of trapéxovres tas Švoicoxias Toſs Ačovorty. Trpºros pièv 6 trepi 105 a?, civeto 6al Stå To Tpórepov eis to àuta v. Öeiv &quicéo-0at to pepôuevov # Tpos to TéAos, repl of Stetxopaev čv Toſs trpórepov Aóyots, especially c. 2, 233 a, 21, where we read: Ötö kal 6 Závovos A6-yos pejöos Aguſłóvel Tô u?) évôéxeoróat T & &melpa Stex0eiv ? &pagflat Töv &treſpov ka9 icagºrov év tretrepaguévº Xpóvg. Simpl. 236 b (cf. 221 a, 302 a). Themistius gives a shorter and more obscure comment (Phys. 55 b, 392 sq.): ei ëati kivmons, &váykm to kivoúuevov év tretrepaguévy xpóvº &trelpa 5ue- Čičval toſſ to 38 &6úvatov: oik Špa éo Tl ictvmoris. 36 sticvv Šē To avvmuſié- vov (the hypothetical major pre- miss) éic toi, to kivoúuevov čudorm- p.d. tu kiveto 6au, travrösöé Ötao Thuaros ém’ &reupov čvros Stauperod to kivot- pºevov &váykm to juov trpárov Štea- 0elv of kivetrat Siao Thuaros kal Tóte to 3Aov. &AA& kai irpo Tod hut- Gews toū āNov to éketvou jutov, kal toūTov trgºw To jutorv. ei of v šTelpa Tö, äuſan Ötö. Tö Tavros roſ, Amdóév- tos 6vva Töv eival Tô julov Aabetv, T& ôè &relpa &öövarov čv retrepagpiāvg xpévº, 5texéeſv, tooto 8& Ös évapyès éAduSaveu & Zhvaju, &öövatov Špa. kivmoiv eival. Arist. Top. viii. 8, 156 b, 7, and Sext. Math. x. 47 refer to this proof. * Favorinus, ap. Diog. ix. 29, says that Parmenides had already employed this argument ; but the statement is certainly false. All other evidence ascribes it to Zeno. Diog. l. c. says expressly that it was discovered by him; and all AGAINST MOTION. 621 could never be overtaken by the swiftest, Achilles, if it had once made a step in advance of him. For in order to overtake the tortoise, Achilles must first reach the point where the tortoise was when he started; next the point to which it had progressed in the interval, then the point which it attained while he made this second advance, and so on ad infinitwm. But if it be impossible that the slower should be over- taken by the swifter, it is, generally speaking, impos- sible to reach a given end, and motion is impossible." The whole argument turns, as in the other case, upon the assertion that a given space cannot be traversed unless all its parts are traversed; which is not possible, because there is an infinite number of these parts.” The only difference is that this assertion is applied in the first case to a space with fixed boundaries, and in the second, to a space with movable boundaries. 3. So long as anything remains in one and the same space, it is at rest. But the flying arrow is at every moment in the same space. It rests, therefore, at every moment of its flight: therefore its motion that we know of Parmenides (cf. the often quoted passage, Parm. 128 A) proves that he did not ap- ply himself in this manner to the dialectical refutation of the ordi- nary standpoint. i Arist. l. c. 239 b, 14: Sevrépos 3° 5 caxočaevos 'Axixxets &ott ö’ ošros, 3rt to 8paôörepov oë5érote karaxmp6%geral 6éov Šro too taxi- arov. čuirporðev Yap &vaykalov éx9e?v to 6tókov, 36ev špumore to qejyov, &ar' &ei ti "poéxeiv čvary- kalov to 8paôtrepov. Simpl. 237 a, and Themist. 56 a, explain this in the sense given in our text. * As Aristotle rightly observes in the words: écriri 6é kal oiros & airbs Aéryos tº 6txotouelv (the same as the first argument based upon bi-partition) 8taq’épel à év tá, 6taipeiv whatxa to trpoo Aap gavópe- wov uéye60s . . . Šv &pſpotépous yap ovuòaivet pºl &qukveto 6a, trpos to trépas àtapovaévov tra's roß Meyā- 00vs’ &AA& Tpéokeitat év roërg, &rt où6è to rdxtortov retpaygömplév- ov čv rá čudºkeiv To Bpaôtratov. Similarly, the commentators. 622 ZENO. during the whole course is only apparent." This argument, too, is based on the same process as the two previous arguments. In them, the space to be tra- versed, and here the time of the movement, is resolved into its minutest parts; and it is shown upon this pre- supposition, that no motion is thinkable. The latter argument is, as Aristotle acknowledges, quite correct. * Arist. 239 b, 30 : rpſtos 8' 5 vöv fimbels ári i öiorbs ºpepop.évm ãormicev. Cf. l. 5: Závay 6é trapa- Aoyiğeral ei yüp &ei, pnaiv, hpspieſ Tāv # kiveirai, 8tav fi karð to to ov, ãort 3’ &el to q'epópºevov čv Tó vov, ākāvmtov rhy pepopuévnveival éiotóv. For év tá vov &kiv. others read : év ºrg vov tº Katë to ov &kivmrov. Gerling, l.c. p. 16, would substi- tute § kiveirai for 3 kiveirat. I am inclined to think that the text, which in its present form presents many difficulties, and has not been, to my mind, satisfactorily explained even by Prantl., origi- nally ran thus: ei yáp, pnow, hpepel trav, 3rav fi karū to forov, ëa ºri 5’ &el to pepópevov čv rô vov karū to forov, &kivmtov, &c., from which would result the meaning given above. Themistius (p. 55 b, p. 392 Sp.) likewise seems to pre- suppose this form of the words, when he paraphrases them thus: ei yüp hpeueſ, pngly, Śwavra ötav fi karū to torov airé àidotnua, Šari 5* &el tº pepôuevovkarð to torov Šavré 6táortmua, āktvmtov čváykm thv čío- Töv eival thy pepopuévny. Similarly, p. 56 a, 394 Sp.: áel Rév yöp era- arov táv kivoupévov čv tº vov to forov Šavrò catéxei Šidotmua. Aris- totle's observation against Zeno, l. c., that his whole argument is based upon the false theory of time being compounded of particular moments (ék Töv vov táv &ötaipé- tov) is quite in harmony with this. On the other hand, Simplicius says, 236 b, agreeing with the text of our MSS. : 68& Zhvavos A6-yos ºrpo- Aaflöv, 3rt trav Štav fi karū to torov ěavrá, 3 kiveirat # hpepei, kal &rt oë6èv év tá vov kiveirau, kal 3rt rô ºpepäuevov ćel év tá toº airá čart ka8 Kaorrow vov, Šºšket ouxAoyſge- orðat oil ros' to pepôuevov 8éAos év. travrl vov kata to torov šavté, érriv, &ote kai év travrl Tó xpóvg. To 6& év tá, vov karð rô to ov Šavrá, by oi kivetrat, hpepel àpa, Étretół, wºv čv t& vov kiveiral, to 6é º kivočuevov àpeptet, Étretóh trav h kueiral à hpe- pºet. To Špa pepópºevov 8éAos éas qéperat hpeuet karð irávra row riis qopas xpóvov. This deduction has none of the seeming conclusiveness which we always find in Zeno's demonstrations. Simplicius, it is true, deserves attention because he was acquainted with Zeno's work; but, on the other hand, we must not forget the excellent remark of Schleiermacher (Ueber Anaximan- dros, Werke 2. Phil. ii. 180) that Simplicius in the later books of his work took no account of the sources he had used in the earlier books. I agree with Themistius and Sim- plicius in understanding sival karð. to foov to mean, “to be in the same space’ as previously, not to alter its place. AGAINST MOTION. 623 • In the moment as such, no movement, no change generally speaking, is possible; if I ask where the flying arrow is at this moment, the answer cannot be in the transition from the space A to the space B, or in other words, in A and B; the answer can only be in the space A. Consequently, if time is conceived as an infinite series of successive moments, instead of a fixed quantity, we necessarily get, instead of the transition from one space to another, merely a successive Being in separate spaces: and motion is just as impossible as if (similarly to the first and second of Zeno's argu- ments) we suppose, instead of the line to be traversed, an infinite number of successive and separate points." The argument before us is therefore not so sophistical as it appears to be ; at any rate it is not more sophisti- cal than the others. It starts, like them, from the per- ception of a philosophic problem in which more recent thinkers have also found considerable difficulties; and it stands in the same connections with Zemo's general point of view. If Unity and Multiplicity be once regarded in the manner of the Eleatics as absolute contradictories positively excluding one another, separation in time and space may easily be looked upon as a plurality devoid of unity; space and time as an aggregation of separate points of space and time, and a transition from one of these points to another, a motion,--becomes impossible.” 1 That this is really the force of the argument is also implied by Aristotle, in his short counter- observation (vide previous note). 2 There is a reference to the fundamental thought of this argu- ment in what is quoted as from Zeno in Diog. ix. 72 (as Kern, Xenoph. 26, 74, reminds us): rö kivočuevov oft' év (; āott Tórg, ki- ve?ral oit’ &v ć whº fort : for that it cannot move in the space in | 624 2ENO. 4. The fallacy in the fourth demonstration is more apparent. This refers to the relation of the time of movement to the space which has to be traversed. According to the laws of motion, spaces of equal size must be traversed in equal time if the speed be equal. But two bodies of equal size move past one another twice as fast if they are both moving at equal speed, as if one of them is still, and the other with the same motion passes by it. Hence Zeno ventures to conclude that in order to traverse the same space,—the space taken up by each of these two bodies, -at the same speed, only half the time is necessary in the one case that is necessary in the other. Consequently, he thinks, facts here contradict the laws of motion." which it is, is proved by the obser- vation that it is in the same space in every moment. 1 Arist. 239 b, 33: Térapros 6’ 6 trepi Tôv čv rá, a tačíq, kivovuévov č évavttas to ov tºykov’ trap' to ous, Tów pey &ro TéAovs roi, oračíov Tów 5’ &Tö uérov (on the meaning of this expression vide Prantl, in h, l. p. 516) to q, räxel, év (; orvu}atveiv ofetal, forov eival xpóvov tá 6ttagoríº Töv jutoruv. čott 6' 6 trapaxoyto ºbs £y 16 to wºv trapū Rivoſuevov to 8& trap' hpeuotiv to taov uéyebos &éloïv ró forg taxel Töv toov böpea9al xpóvov toàro à éat, theºdos. That the argument referred to in these words has the meaning we have assigned to it is beyond question; but the manner in which Zeno more precisely explained it is doubtful, partly on account of the uncertainty of the reading, and partly because of the extreme brevity of Aristotle's elucidation. Simplicius seems to me to give the best text and the truest explana- tion of it (p. 237 b sq.), and even Prantl’s view of the passage, in other respects satisfactory, may find its completion here. Accord- ing to Simplicius, Zeno's argument runs thus : Let there be in the * D . . . . . . . E A1 A2 A3 A4 B4 B3 B2 B1 C1 C2 C3 C4 2 A1 A2 A3 A4 B4 B3 B2 B1 C1 C2 C3 C4 space, or in the course, D . . . E, three equal rows of equal bodies, A1 . . ., B1 . . ., C1 . . ., as shown in figure 1. Let the first row A1, remain still; while the two others, with equal velocity, move past it in a parallel and opposite direction to it and to one IMPORT OF HIS ARG UMENTS. 625 The falsity of this conclusion strikes us at once; but we must not therefore suppose that Zeno was not per- fectly in earnest regarding it. For the whole fallacy is based upon this: that the space traversed by one body is measured according to the size of the bodies which it passes, whether these be in motion or at rest. That this is not allowable might well, however, escape the notice of the first philosopher who studied the laws of motion generally ; especially if, like Zeno, he were convinced, to start with, that his enquiry would result in contradictions. Similar paralogisms have been over- looked even by modern philosophers in their polemic against empirical conceptions. This is not the place to criticise the scientific value of Zeno's demonstrations, the censures of Aristotle in regard to them, or the judgments passed by the moderns' on both. Whatever the absolute worth of these arguments may be, their historical importance is, in any case, not to be underrated. On the one hand, another. C1 will arrive at Al and B4 at the same moment that B1 has arrived at A4 and C4 (vide figure 2). B1 has, therefore, passed all the Cs, and Cl all the BS in the same time that each of them passed the half of the As. Or, as Zeno seems to have expressed it, C1 has passed all the Bs in the same time, in which B1 has passed half of the As; and B1 has passed all the Cs in the same time in which C1 has passed half of the As. But the row A takes up the same space as each of the other two rows. The time in which C1 has passed through the whole space of the row A, is consequently the same as WOL. I. that in which B1, with equal ve- locity, has passed through the half of this space, and vice versá. But since the velocities being equal, the times of movement are to one another as the spaces traversed, the latter time can be only half as great as the former ; the whole time, therefore, is equal to the half. E.g. Bayle, Bict. Zénon d'Elée Rem. F.; Hegel, Gesch. d. Phil. i. 290 Herbart, Metaphysik, ii. § 284 sq.; Lehrb. 2. Einl. in d. Phil. § 139; Strümpell, Gesch, d. theoret. Phil. b. d. Gr. 53 sq.; Cousin, Zénon d'Elée Fragm. Phil. i. 65 sqq.; Gerling, l. c.; and Wellmann, l. c. 12 sq., and 20 sq. S S 626 ZENO. the opposition of the Eleatic doctrine to the ordinary point of view attains in them its climax; multiplicity and change are not opposed by Zeno as by Parmenides with general arguments which might be met by other general propositions; their impossibility is proved by these notions themselves; and thus any impression which might still be left by the exposition of Parme- nides that side by side with the One Being the many and the variable may still somehow find place, is en- tirely done away." * Cousin, indeed, says exactly the contrary (l.c., cf. especially p. 65, 70 sqq.) when he maintains that Zeno meant to dispute not multiplicity in general, but only multiplicity devoid of all unity. But of such a limitation there is no trace either in Zeno's arguments. or in the introduction to Plato's Parmenides. His arguments are directed quite universally against the notion of plurality, of motion, &c., and if, for the purpose of confuting these notions, pure separation without continuity, pure multiplicity without unity, is pre- supposed, this pre-supposition is not the point which is attacked, but the point from which the attack starts. If plurality generally be assumed, Zeno thinks the theory must necessarily lead to the can- celling of unity, and to contradic- tions of all kinds; he does not mean, as Cousin asserts, if a plurality devoid of all unity be assumed, no motion, &c., would be possible. If such had been Zeno's opinion, he must before all things have discriminated the plurality devoid of unity from the plurality limited by unity. But it is the unavoidable consequence of the On the other hand, however, pro- Eleatic standpoint, that he did not, and cannot, do this. Unity and plurality, persistence of Being and motion, stand, with the Eleatics, wholly in opposition. Plato first recognised that these apparently opposite determinations could be united, and must be united, in one and the same subject; and in the Sophist and Parmenides he argues this expressly as against the Eleatic doctrine. Zeno is so far from a similar conviction that his arguments are all directed pre- cisely to the opposite end, to do away with the confused uncertainty of the ordinary notion which re- presents the One as many, and Being as becoming and variable. Plurality devoid of unity was maintained in his time by Leucip- pus (only, however, in a limited sense)—but Zeno never alludes to Leucippus. Heracleitus, whom Cousin regards as the chief object of Zeno's attacks, but to whom I can find no reference in his writ- ings, is so far from maintaining plurality without unity that he emphatically asserts the unity of all Being. Cousin is, therefore, wrong in his censure of Aristotle, l. c., p. 80:-Aristote accuse Zénon MELISSUS. 627 blems were thus proposed to philosophy in regard to the explanation of phenomena, the consideration of which it has never since been able to evade. The apparent insolubility of these problems afforded welcome support to the Sophists in their denial of knowledge; but they afterwards gave a lasting impulse to the most search- ing enquiries of Plato and Aristotle, and even modern metaphysics has constantly been forced to return again and again to the questions first brought under discussion by Zeno. However unsatisfactory for us may be the immediate result of his Dialectic, it has therefore been of the highest importance to science. V. MELJSSU.S. MELISSUs resembles Zeno in his attempt to defend the doctrine of Parmenides against ordinary opinion. While, however, Zeno had sought to effect this in- directly by the refutation of the usual theories, and had thus strained to the utmost the opposition of the two points of view, Melissus' seeks to show in a direct de mal raisonner, et lui-même me adversaries' standpoint. This is raisonne guères mieua et n'est pas ea empt de paralogisme: car Ses réponses impliquent toujours l'idée de l'unité, quand l'argumentation de Zénon repose sur l'hypothèse ea:- clusive de la pluralité. It is pre- cisely the exclusiveness of this pre- supposition, which Aristotle, with perfect justice, assails. Like Cousin, Grote, Plato, i. 103 (who more- over has misunderstood the pre- ceding remarks), believes that Zeno admitted the pre-supposition of plurality without unity, not in his own name, but merely from his in a certain sense true. He desires to refute his adversaries by draw- ing contradictory inferences from their presuppositions. But the middle terms, which he employs for this purpose, belong not to them, but to himself. Their con- tention is merely: there is a plurality—a motion; he seeks to prove that the Many, the Many being assumed, must consist of infinitely many parts, and that in motion, an infinite number of spaces must be traversed, &c. | Of the life of Melissus we s s 2 628 MELISS U.S. manner that Being can be conceived only as Parme- mides defined its concept ; and as this direct proof in order to convince an adversary must be deduced from pre-suppositions common to both sides, he tries to find in the representatives of the ordinary mode of thought points of union with the Eleatic doctrine." But for this reason he cannot entirely avoid admitting into the Eleatic doctrine definitions which imperil its purity. know little. His father was called Ithagenes, his native place Wà,S Samos (Diog. ix. 24). Diogenes, l. c. (cf. AElian, v. 4, vii. 14) de- scribes him as a statesman of note, who had especially distinguished himself as a navarch. This elucidates Plutarch's distinct and reiterated assertion (Pericl. c. 26; Themist. c. 2, here with an appeal to Aristotle; Adv. Col. 32, 6, p. 1126; cf. Suid. Méxitos Adpov), which there is not the slightest reason to disbelieve, that Melissus commanded the Samian fleet in the victory over the Athenians, 442 B C. (Thuc. i. 117). On this circumstance is probably founded Apollodorus's calculation, ap. Diog. l. c., which places the prime of Melissus in Ol. 84 (444–440 B.C.). He was, con- sequently, a contemporary, most likely a younger contemporary, of Zeno. His doctrine of the unity and invariability of Being is al- luded to by the Pseudo-Hippo- crates (Polybus) De Nat. Hom. c. 1; end vi. 34 ; Littré. Parme- nides was possibly the teacher of Melissus, as well as of Zeno; but this is not established by Diog. l.c.; Theod. Cur. Gr. Aff. iv. 8, p. 57. The other statements of Diogenes that Melissus was acquainted with Heracleitus does not seem abso- lutely impossible; but he adds that the Ephesians had their attention first drawn to their fellow citizen through his means, which is most improbable. A treatise of Me- lissus, doubtless his only work, is mentioned by Simpl. Phys. 22 b, simply as to a tºyypapua. Suidas sub voce Méxmtos calls it repl toū āuros, Galen, Ad. Hippocr. De Naț. Hom. i. p. 5; De Elem. Sec. Hipp. i. 9, p. 487, Kühn; Simpl. De Caºlo, 249 b, 23; Schol. in Arist. 509 a, 38: Trepl púgeos; Simpl. De Celo, 249 b, 42; Phys. 15 b : tr. qāorea's h tr. too Švros ; from the last passage, Bessarion. Adv. cal. Plat. ii. 11, seems to have invented this statement, cf. p. 542, 2. The somewhat important fragments contained in Simplicius have been collected and commented on by Brandis, Comm. El. 185 sqq.; Mul- lach. Arist. De Mel. &c. p. 80 sqq.; Fragm. Phil. i. 259 sqq. * Simpl. l. c. : toſs yúp rôv ‘puquiców &étéugot Xpma'duevos 6 Mé- Atagos trept yewéoews kal (p60pās *pxeral too ovyypáupata's otºrws. Cf. in Fr. 1, the words ovyxopéeral 'yāp kai tooto Örö rôv purików. The ical tooto shows that Melissus had already appealed in the context to the assent of the physicists. JBEING. 629 All that has been transmitted to us of Melissus’ doctrine of Being may be reduced to the four deter- minations of its eternity, its infinity, its unity, and its invariability. That which is, is underived and imperishable. For, were it derived, it must have come either from Being or from non-Being. Now that which arises from Being is not derived, but has existed previously; and from non-Being nothing can be derived; least of all Being in the absolute sense." Similarly, if it passed away, it must be resolved either into something existent or something non-existent; but Being cannot become non- existent, as all admit ; and if it passed over into a Being, it could not be said to perish.” If Being is eternal, it must also, Melissus thinks, “otre ék uh éðvros oiáv re yi- ven 6aſ ru, oùre &AAo uèv oëbèv éov (this is of course intended by Me- lissus in a purely hypothetical man- ner, in the sense of ordinary opin- jon), troXA@ 8& HäAAov to &m A^s éðv.” * Mel. Fr. 1, ap. Simpl. l. c. The conclusion of the Fragment is as follows: ošre pôaphoretal to éóv. oùre yūp és to pººl éöv of v Te Tb éov peraßd AAeuv' avyxopéetal yöp kal rotºro Širo róv puorukóv. oite és éóv. p.évol yèp &v trgxiu oita, ye kai où p6eſpotto. oire épa yé yove To éov otre (p6aphoretal. aiel Špa fiv re kai čo rai. The first part of the above argument is given in the Treatise, De Melisso, c 1, sub init., in a somewhat more extended form : āţătov sivaí braſiv et ri éa riv, etirep whºvöéxeoréal 'yevéo 6al uměčv gic uměevás' e?ve yūp &mavra yé yovey ełre pººl ºrdvra, beiv &uqotépos é; oùöevös yewéorðat &vain &v yi-yvápleva (before yºyvöueva, tà ought prob- ably, as Brandis thinks, to be inserted: vide Mullach in h. l.) âtrávrov re yūp yuyvouévov oièëv trpoiſtrópxelv. ei 3’ &vrov rivāv &el érepa Trpoo’yſºyvouro, TAéov &v kal peſ(ov to £v yeyovévai’ & 6), traéov kal ue^{ov, Tooro yewéorðat &v é; où6evös' of y&p év tá, éAdºrrovi T traéov, où6' év tá ulicporépº ro uéſgow inrápxeiv. This addition probably is taken from a later portion of the work, which, accord- ing to the excellent remark of Prandis (Comm. 186), seems to have presented the main ideas and course of the argument, and then to have developed particular parts more accurately. The small Frag- ment 6, agreeing with a portion of Fr. 1, belonged probably to the same later section. It is clear from p. 585, 3, that in the above doc- trines, Melissus was closely allied to Parmenides. 630 MELISSU.S. be infinite, for what has not been derived and does not pass away, has neither beginning nor end; and what has neither beginning nor end, is infinite." This definition, in which Melissus diverges from Parmenides, has drawn down upon him the severe censure of Aristotle,” and it * Fr. 2: &AA' étrető rö 'yev6- Revov &px?iv čxel, rö uh yewówevov &px?iv obit #xet, to 6’ 63v oë yé yove, oök &v éxot &pxñv. čari 8& rô p6elpó- pºevov rexeutºv čxei, ei 6é rí Čati àq6aptov, TeXeurºv oik #xel, to €ov âpa &q6aptov čov TeXevthy ošic xel' to 6* ſuffre &px?iv čxov uſite Texev- Thy &melpov rvyxãvel éóv' &ceipov #pa to éðv. Similarly in Fr. 7, the conclusion of which, où Yùp aiei eival &vvorov 8 ru uh trav čott, only asserts this: if Being were limited in point of magnitude, it could not be eternal: but to explain why it could not, Melissus seems to have given no other reason than that already quoted, viz. that the eternal must be unlimited, because it could not otherwise be without beginning or end. Fr. 8 and 9 are apparently small portions of the same more complete discussion, to which Fr. 7 belonged. Fr. 8 seems to me to contain the opening words of the discussion ; this Fragment ought properly therefore to be placed before Fr. 7. Aristotle who fre- quently refers to this demonstra- tion of Melissus expresses himself in regard to it as if he considered the words étrelë—éxel as the pro- tasis, and the following words: rô ah—oëk éxel as the apodosis. Cf. Soph. E. c. 5, 167 b, 13: otov 6 Mexico'ou A6).os 3rt &repov to Tāv, Aagöv to pièv Šmav čyévmtov (ék yöp uh &vros ow8&v &v yewégéal), Tô 5& yewówevov ć &pxãs yewéobar ei u% of v yé yovey, &px?iv obic ēxel [—eiv) to trav, 30t’ &neupov. oint āvāykm 6% rotiro oup8afvetv' oi, yāp (for it does not follow that) ei ºrb ºyevówevov štav &px?iv čxel, ital et ri āpx?iv čxel yé yover. So c. 28, 181 a, 27: Phys. i. 3, 186 a. 10: 3ri Aév oëv trapaxo'yſgeral MéAtooros 87Aov' offeral yèp sixmpéval, ei Tô 'yevöue ov čxel àpx?iv &mav, &rt kal Tö u% yevöpievov oil, éxel. So Eu- demus, ap. Simpl. Phys. 23 a oë 'yap, ei Tô yevöuevovápxhv čxel, to uh 'yevópevov &px?iv oëk #xel, MaxAov 6& To pººl #xov &px?iv oin éyévero. There can be no doubt, and the parallelism of the next proposition (éri 3& Tô pöelp etc.) proves it— that the words Tö pah Yi'y. etc., be- long to the protasis: “As the Be- come has a beginning and the Unbecome none,' etc. Aristotle, therefore, has either been guilty of a wrong construction, or he has presupposed that Melissus con- cluded that the Unbecome had no beginning, from the fact that everything Become has a beginning. On the other hand, what is said in Arist. Soph. El. c. 6, 168 b, 35: às év tá, Mexforgov Aóryg rö airto Aapſ3ável Tô yeyovéval Ital &px?iv éxeiv, and also in the treatise, De Melisso, l. c., agrees with the phi- losopher's own utterances. The passages in recent authors in re- gard to this theory of Melissus are to be found in Brandis, Comm. El. 200 sq. * Metaph. i. 5, 986 b, 25: oërol pºv of v . . . & peréol trpès rºw vºv BEING. 63} is evident that it approved itself to Aristotle neither in itself nor in regard to the arguments on which it is based. In these, the confusion between infinity in time, and infinity in space, is apparent. Melissus has proved that Being must be according to time without begin- ning or end; and he concludes from thence, that it can have no limits in space. That this is the sense he gives to the infinity of Being there can be no doubt." He supports his statement, however, by the further observa- tion that Being can only be limited by the void, and as there is no void, it must be unlimited.” But if the limited extension which Parmenides attributes to Being was hard to reconcile with its indivisibility, this unlimited extension is much harder. Although, there- fore, Melissus expressly guards himself against the corporeality of Being,” yet the observation of Aristotle' that he seems to conceive it as material, is not alto- gether unjust. We may rather suppose that the Ionian physics, in spite of his hostility to them, had had some influence on Melissus, and had given rise to this theory trapova'av Čármolu, oi uév 600 kal tráutraw ös Švres ukpov &ypotkóTepot, Eevoqāvms kal MéAuoroos. Phys. i. 3, sub init. : &piq6tspol yèp épio'Turcós ovXAoyſ; ovrai, kal MéAtooros ſcal IIappeviðms' kal yèp ſevöſ, Aap,84- vovoru kal &avAAórylato! eigtv airóv of Aó-You. MāAAov 6' 6 Mexico'ov popti- kös kal oil, éxov &tropiav (he con- tains nothing difficult, he bases his doctrines on nothing that really requires consideration, and he is, therefore, easy to refute), &AA’ vbs ărătrov 309&vros rāAAa orvuòaivet' rooro 6' oi6&v xańetróv. 1 This is clear from Fr. 8: &AA’ &airep £ortl aiel, oita kai to Héya- 60s &neupov aiel xpi elvat, and from the express and repeated assertions of Aristotle (vide inf. p. 632, 2, and Metaph. i. 5, 986 b, 18; Phys. i. 2, 185 a, 32 b, 16 sqq.). * Wide inf. p. 632, 2. * Fr. 16: ei ºv čáv čott, 6e? aúrò &v eival’ ev Šē éöv Šeſ airb oëua uh éxeuv' si èë Éxot tróxos, éxoi &v uápia ital oilcéri àv eſſm év. * Metaph. l. c. vide Sup. p. 548, 1. In criticising this passage, it should be remembered that the concept iſ \m is with Aristotle wider than that of orápa, cf. Part ii. b, 243 sq., second edition. 632 MELISS U.S. of his, which did not accord with the Eleatic doctrine of the unity of Being. It is true that our philosopher directly infers the unity of Being from its unlimitedness. If there were several Beings, he says, they would necessarily all be limited in regard to each other; if Being is unlimited, it is also one." In his opinion multiplicity also is in itself inconceivable. For in order to be many, things must be separated by the void; but there cannot be a void, for the void would be mothing else than non- Being. Even if we suppose that the parts of matter directly touch one another, without having anything between them, the argument gains nothing. For if matter were divided at all points and there were con- sequently no unity, there could also be no multiplicity, all would be empty space; if, on the other hand, matter were only divided at certain points, there is no reason why it should not everywhere be so. Finally, Melissus also attains fore, be divided at all.” Fr. 3: ei 83 &teipov, v' ei y&p Šáo sºm, oùk &v jūvairo & reſpa sival &AA’ #x01 &v Trépata trpos &AAmAa: &reipov. 5% to éðv, oùk Špa TAéw Tö. éávra ev Špa to éðv. Fr. 10: ei phév et m, trepavée, trpos &\Ao. Arist. De Melvsso, i. 974 a, 9. * Arist. Gen. et Corr. i. 8, 325 a, 2 : évíois yap rôv àpxaſov ëöoče to by é; āvāykms &v eiva, kal &rcívmtov" To uéy y&p kevöv oër by, kivmºval 6' oir àv Šávaoréau whivros kevoo kexaplowévov, oiâ’ at troAA& eival whivros roß Stelp yovros. rotto 6' oiáčv Staq’épetv, et Tis offeral mº, avvex's sival ºrb trav &AA’ &m reordat Simpmuévov, roi; pgval troAA& kal uh ev elva. Kal keväv. ei uév Yêp tróvrn It cannot, there- 5ualperov, où0&y eival ev, &are othè woxXà (similarly Zeno, sup. p. 615,1) &AA& kevöv to 3xov ei 8& Tà uèv Tij 6% uh, tre+rxaguévº Tuvl root’ ot- kéval' Méxpt tróorov Yap ſcal Stå Tí rô pºv oitos éxei Too $Aov Ital mºmpés éoºrt, rö 8& 6 ppmuévov; &ri Špiota's ºpdvai &vaykaiou pº sival rivnoiv. čk pºv obv roërav Tów A6-yop, Örep8&v- res thv aforémoiv ral rapióðvres aúthy &s ré, A6).4, 8 ov &ncoxov6eiv, ev kal &kſwmtov to trav elvaí page kal &me pov čvuot to yiep Trépas we- patvely &v rpès rê Revöv. That Aristotle in this exposition is thinking chiefly of Melissus, and not (as Philop. in h. l. p. 36 a, supposes, probably from his own JBEING. 633 the same result in the following manner. If the so- called many things really were what they seem to us, they could never cease to be so. Since our perception shows us change and decease, it refutes itself, and con- sequently deserves no faith in regard to what it says about the multiplicity of things." conjecture) of Parmenides, seems most likely for the following rea- sons: 1. The last proposition un- mistakeably refers to the doctrine of Melissus on the unlimitedness of Being. 2. What is here said about motion agrees with what will presently be quoted (p. 635. 1) from Melissus' writings. 3. This whole argument turns upon the theory of empty space, which Parmenides in- deed rejected, but to which neither he nor Zeno, as far as we know, attributed so much importance for the criticism of the ordinary point of view. How little ground there is for the assertion of Philoponus we see from the fact that, though he recognises the relation of the foregoing demonstration to the Atomistic philosophy, this does not prevent his ascribing it to Parme- nides: Tooro Sé &vaipóv 6 IIappevſöms qmolu, 3ri Tô oišta’s irroríðeo Bat ow8&v ôuaq'épet too &Touc, kal Revöveia (pépeiv. • Fr. 17 (ap. Simpl. De Coelo, 250 a, f : Schol. in Arist. 509 b, 18. partly also Aristockes ap. Eus. Pr. Ev. xiv. 17. I here follow Mul- lach): uéytotov učv čv or muetov oiros 6 Aó)os, Šti čv uóvov čari. &rèp kai réðe a muera si yüp fiv woxxâ, Totaúra xpmy air& eival, oiów rep yd3 qºnut To eveival. ei yüp ort yū ka? iſãop nal oríðmpos real xpvabs kal trip kai to uév (wov to 8& Teóvmkos cal AuéAav kal Aevkov kai Tà &AAa trávra. ãoro'a oi äv6potrot page sival &Am0éa. ei ö, raûra éoºri kal juées àp0ós This remark, how- épéoptev kal &kočouev, eival Xph ºrca- arov Totodrov, oióv rep Tö tipórov ëö0ćev juïv, kal whaeratrítrew uměč 'ylver6at étépolov, &AA’ aiei eivat #kagrov oiáv Trep &otiv. vov 6é (pauev ôp66s 6pfiv Kal & coiſeu, kal avvuévai’ Šokéet 68 juïv Tó Te 6epubv ºvXpov 'ytved'6at kal to juxpov 6epuby Kal to orkampov wax0aköv kal rô wax0akov orkXmpov, ital rô (obv &roëwho sely kal éic u} @vros yívea 6at, Kai Tatra. trövta étepowworéal. Kal & Ti ſãv Te kai & vov čoºri oiâév Šplotoy eival, &AA’ & ‘re giàmpos okxmpos éðy tº ãaicrúAq, karatp:Beo'6ai époi Béat, (so the editions read, Mullach con- jectures épcot, €62, or preferably étrapmpdºs; Bergk, De Xen. 30, ôpovpéov; but none of these amend- ments satisfy me; perhaps there may be an io9 in the Öuoß): kai Xpvoº's kal &XXo 6 ru io'Xupěv Šokées eival Tráv, é, íðatós re y?, kal Xí60: 'ytved 6al, Šote a vuògive pºſite épfiv pºſite Tá čávt a yupdgkeiv. oi, Toívvy Taota &XXàAois àu.0x0)ée" papaévois 'yap sivat troXA& ta (? perhaps we should read aiel) kaleiðed re kal ioxby ëxovira trávta érepołowo 9as juiv 80icée. kal pretatrírrely €x row ékáators Öpeopévov. 37Aov totvvv 8th eiº &p6ós épéouev, où8& éketva troAA& 6p6&s Šokée, eivat. oi, Yêp &v were trante ei &Am6éa ºv, &AA’ ºv, oidu wep Šâânces exagºrov, rotoirov' rot, yūp éévros &Amélyot, repégorov oãév. 3), 6% aera- tréan. To uév čov & réAeto, to 6% oilk éov yeyove. oëTws &v ei troXAö ºw rotatº a Xpſy elval oióv rep to $v. 634 MELISSU.S. ever, which he himself designates merely as a secondary proof, encroaches on the ground which Melissus had already occupied in his polemic against the possibility of motion and variability in general. Being cannot move, it can experience no increase, no change of its condition, no pain; for every move- ment is a transition to another, a cessation of the old and the arising of something new. But Being is One, and there is mone besides; it is eternal, so that it neither ceases nor arises; it is necessarily, therefore, changeless, and always like itself; for all change, even the slowest, must in time lead to an entire cessation of that which changes." In regard to motion in the narrower sense— motion in space,—this, Melissus thinks, cannot be con- ceived without the theory of an empty space. For if a thing has to move to another place, this place must be 1 Fr. 4: &AA& why ei čv, kal &ktvmtov" to Yap Év čov čuoſov aiei £aijró' to 5& àuotov oit’ &v &róAotro, oùt’ &v uéov yivotto, otte ustakoo- puéotro, oùre àAyéot, oùre àvićto. ei ‘Yáp tº roſtav ráozot oilk &v év eſſm. To yūp jvruvaoüy rivnow kiveóuevov #ic rivos kai és àrepôv Ti pºeta}d^Aet. oëbèv 8& fiv čtepov trapö. Tö éöv, oëk &pa rooro kivſio’etat. So Fr. 11 (ap. Simpl. Phys. 24 a, u; cf. De Coelo, 52 b, 20; Schol. 475 a, 7), with the corresponding proof: el yèp Tu Toºray tréaxot, oùk &v ér evetm. ei yüp Tepotatºral, &váykm rb éov uh 6|aoſov eival, &AA’ &róAAvoróat to ºrpāq-6ew ébv, to 68 oëk ébu Yívea 6ai. ei Toivvy rptopuptotori &reat érepozov 7tvouro to trav, ÜAotto èv év tá, Travrl Xpéve. Fr. 12 then shows the same in regard to the wetaké- opºmoris, by which we are to under- stand each previous change in the condition of a thing; the words are: &AA’ oièë uérakoopméïval &vv- orrávº 6 y&p kóouos (the whole, which is founded upon a definite arrange- ment of its parts, the complex) { trpégéew éðv oix &tróAAvrat, oùre à an éðv yiveral, etc. Fr. 13 adds to this what seems to us the very su- perfluous argument that Being can- not experience pain or grief, for what is subject to pain cannot be eternal, or equal in power to the healthy, and must necessarily change, since pain is partly the con- sequence of some change, and partly the cessation of health and the arising of sickness. Evidence at third hand for the immobility of matter as held by Melissus (cf. Arist. Phys. i. 2, sub init. ; Me- taph. i. 5, 986 b, 10 sqq.) it is needless to quote. JBEING, 635 empty in order to receive it. If, on the other hand, it withdraws into itself, it must become denser than it was previously, that is to say, it must become less empty, for rarer means that which contains more empty space, denser that which contains less. Every movement presupposes a void; that which can receive another into itself is void ; that which cannot receive another is full; that which moves can only do so in the void. But the void would be the non-existent, and the mom- existent does not exist. Consequently there is no void, and therefore no motion. Or, in other words, Being can move itself neither in Being (that which is full), for there is no Being besides itself; nor in non-Being (that which is empty), for non-Being does not exist." Melissus also expressly shows, as a result of the denial of multiplicity and motion, that no division of Being or mixture of substances is possible.” He was, no doubt, 1 Fr. 5: kal kar’ &AAov 5& Tpó- Troy oi,6&v kevedv čart rod Édvros' Tö 7&p keveev oë9év éori oilk &v &vein Tó ye uměév. oi klvéeral &v Tö éóv. itroxophoral yèp ović Šxel oióawn keveeſ, wheóvros. &AA’ oiáč Šs éovto orvoraxfivat Suvaróv eim yap &v ośra's ăpatórepov štovtov cal trvicvárepov. toūto 6é &öövarov. To yap &patów &öðvatov Šuota's eival trà?ipes Tó Tru- kvá, &AA' #öm Tööpatóvºys keved tepov 'ytveral rod Turvoi Tô 5* Revelov oëk fort. ei 5& TAfipés éati to éov h uh, kpively xp}. Tá čo 6éxerflat Ti airò &AAo huñ' ei'yöp pºi éorèéxeral, TX?- pes, ei 5& éorèéxoltó ru, où TAñpes. ei čv éorri pºh Revečv, &váykm trañpes eival. ei 5& Tobro, whº kivéea 6al oix 3rt uh 5vvaröv Ště, trafipeos civéeorðal, às émil rôv orwudºrww Aéyouer, &AA’ ôrt trav Tó éöv otte és éðv čávarai kivéeorðal, oi, Y&p £ati r1 trap' airb, oùre és to pººl éöv, où y&p éott rô pº éðv. So Fr. 14, in part word for word. From this and the foregoing passages is taken the extract, De Melisso, c. 1, 974 a, 12 sqq., where the doctrine is specially insisted on, which Melissus himself advances in Fr. 4, 11, and which, as it would appear, he has expressly demon- strated in a previous passage : that Being as One is Šplotov rávrm. Aristotle refers to these same expo- sitions, Phys. iv. 6, 213 b, 12: Mé- Auororos ułv oſſu Rai Šetkvvoruv Štt to Tāv &ktvarov čk Toºrov (from the impossibility of motion without empty space) si y&privãoetal, &váy- km eival (4 mal) kevöv, to 68 revov où rév távrov. * Wide, in regard to the mixture, 636 MELISSU.S. led to this by the doctrine of Empedocles, for Empe- docles thought he could escape the Eleatic objections to the possibility of Becoming, by reducing genera- tion and destruction to mixture and separation. He may, however, have been referring likewise to Anaxa- goras if he were acquainted with the writing of that philosopher. In his arguments against motion, the proposition that all motion presupposes a void, and that the void would be non-Being, clearly betrays a knowledge of the Atomistic doctrine. For it is not likely that the Atomists borrowed this, their funda- mental theory, from Melissus (vide infra). On the other hand, the remark about rarefaction and conden- sation points to the school of Anaximenes. From this it is clear that Melissus occupied himself to a consider- able extent with the doctrines of the physicists. On the whole, with the exception of the statement that the One is unlimited, we find that our philosopher adhered strictly to the doctrine of Parmenides. This doctrine, however, was not developed further by him, and though he undertook to defend it against the physicists, his arguments are unmistakeably inferior to those of Zeno in acuteness. But they are not wholly valueless; his observations especially concerning motion and change give evidence of thought, and bring out real difficulties. Besides Parmenides and Zeno, he appears only as a philosopher of the second rank, but still, considering his date, as a meritorious thinker. It is obvious that he also agreed with the above- the extract, De Melisso, l. c. 3, 24 Suffpmra, rb éov, rivéeral, kiveóuevov $qq.; on the division, Fr. 15: ei Šč oik &v eſſm Šua. BEING, 637 mentioned philosophers in rejecting the testimony of the senses, inasmuch as they delude us with the appearance of multiplicity and change; he probably attempted no thorough investigation of the faculty of cognition, and nothing of this kind has been attributed to him. Some of the ancients ascribe to Melissus physical propositions. According to Philoponus, he first, like Parmenides, treated of the right view, or the unity of all Being ; then of the motions of mankind, and in his third section he named fire and water as the primi- tive substances.” Stobaeus ascribes to him, in common with Zeno, the Empedoclean doctrine of the four ele- ments and of the two moving forces; and that in a sense which at once suggests a later origin.” Stobaeus also says that he maintained the All to be unlimited, and the world to be limited.* Epiphanius represents him as having taught that nothing is of a permanent nature, but all is transient.” These statements, how- ever, are exceedingly suspicious; first because Aristotle expressly mentions as characteristic, of Parmenides, in contradistinction from Xenophanes and Melissus, that side by side with Being he enquired into the causes of phenomena; " and secondly, because they are indivi- * Fr. 17 (sup. p. 633, 1); Arist. Gen. et Corr. i. 8; sup. p. 632, 2; De Melisso, c. 1, 974 b, 2.; Aristocl. ap. Eus. Pr. Ev. xiv. 17, 1 ; cf. p. 591, 1. * Phys. B, 6: 6 Méx. év toſs mpos &A#6elav čv elval Aéywv to by év roſs trpos Sáčaw öö0 pmolveſval T&s àpxès rêv čvrov, trop kai iſãwp. * Sup. p. 611, 2. * Ecl. i. 440: Aloyévns kal Mé- Algoros to uèv trav Štreipov, Tov 6& kóouov retrepaguévov. * Erp. Fid. 1087 D. * Metaph. i. 5, according to the quotation on p. 626, 1: IIapaevſöns 8è uáAAov 8Aérov čolké Tov Aéyeiv. Tapi, Yêp to by, etc. (Wide sup. p. º f 593, 1 ; cf. also c. 4, 984 , 1. (3:38 THE EI, EATIC PHILOSOPHY. dually so untrustworthy; we may, therefore, unhesi- tatingly set them aside. Another statement, that Melissus avoided all mention of the gods, because we can know nothing about them,--sounds more probable; * but here again the evidence is inadequate. If Melissus really expressed himself thus, he no doubt intended, not to assert his philosophical conviction of the un- knowableness of the Divine—which he must have be- lieved himself to have known in his doctrine of Being, —but like Plato, in the Timaeus (40 D), to avoid any dangerous expression concerning the relation of his own theory to the popular faith. VI. HISTORICAL POSITION AND CHARACTER OF THE ELEATIC SCHOOL. ZENO and Melissus are the last of the Eleatic philo- sophers of whom we know any particulars. Soon after them, the school as such appears to have died out ; * * This has already been shown, p. 612, in regard to the statement of Stobaeus, i. 60. The second pas- sage in Stobaeus attributes to Me- lissus a definition, for which there is no foundation whatever in his system, and which was first intro- duced by the Stoics (Partiii. a, 174. 1). As Melissus is here named with Diogenes, we might conjecture that the statement perhaps arose from Diogenes the Stoic, in some passage where he brought forward this doc- trine, having mentioned the defini- tion of Melissus and explained it in the spirit of his school. As regards Philoponus, he is very untrust- worthy in respect to the most an- cient philosophers. In the present, instance the titles themselves, rà trpès &Aftóelav, rà rpbs 66tav, prove that there is a confusion with Par- menides. The statement of Epi- phanius is perhaps founded on a misapprehension of the discussion quoted p. 632, 2, or perhaps on some confusion with another philo- sopher. * Diog. ix. 24. * Plato indeed in the introduc- tion to the Parmenides names a certain Pythodorus as the disciple and friend of Zeno; and in the, Soph. 216 A, 242 D (sup. p. 562, 1} he speaks of the Eleatic school as if it were still in existence at the supposed date of this dialogue, the latest years of Socrates. Little, ITS CHARACTER AND POSITION. 639 and what remained of it was lost in Sophistic,” for which Zeno had already prepared the way, and sub- sequently through the instrumentality of Sophistic, in the Socratico-Megarian philosophy. Partly in this indirect manner, and partly directly, through the writings of Parmenides and Zeno, the Eleatic School furnished its quota to the Platonic philosophy of the concept, and afterwards to the Aristotelian physics and metaphysics. But previously to this, it had considerably influenced the development of the pre-Socratic philo- sophy of nature. Heracleitus seems to have received impulses, not merely from the Ionians, but also from Xenophanes; in Empedocles, the Atomists, and Anaxa- goras, the connection with Parmenides asserts itself more definitely. All these philosophers pre-suppose the concept of Being which Parmenides had introduced; they all admit that the Real is, in the last resort, etermal and imperishable ; they all deny, for this reason, its qualitative change, and they are thus forced into the theory of a multiplicity of unchangeable primitive substances, and into that mechanical direction which thenceforward for a long period was predominant in physics. The conception of the element and the atom, however, can be inferred from this, as Plato may have been led to represent the matter thus from the form of dialogue which he is using. Another philosopher, Xeniades of Corinth, who perhaps came forth from the Eleatic school, and, like Gorgias, blended the Eleatic doc- trine with Scepticism, will be spo- ken of later on in the chapter on Sophistic. * As Plato himself indicates in the opening of the Parmenides, for after the Eleatic stranger has been described as étalpos Táv &pſpl IIap- paevſömy kai Zhvava, Socrates en- quires ironically whether he is not perhaps a 6ebs éAeykrikós; and Theodorus replies that he is uerpić- repos róv trepi rās pièas €ortrovčakó- Tov, which it seems from this that the Eleatics, as a rule, must then have been. 64() THIE ELEATIC PHILOSOPHY. the reduction of change to combination and separation in space, originated with the Eleatics. The Eleatic doctrine forms therefore the main turning point in the history of ancient speculation, and after its completion by Par- menides, no philosophic system arose which was not essentially determined by its relation to that doctrine. This circumstance would alone prevent our separat- ing the Eleatic doctrine as to its general aim from the contemporary matural philosophy, and attributing to it, instead of a physical, a dialectical or metaphysical character; and a more particular examination will at once show how far removed its founders were from a pure philosophy of the concept, or ontology. We have seen that Xenophanes proposed to himself essentially the same problem as the physicists, to determine the cause of matural phenomena, the essence of things; we have found that even Parmenides and his disciples conceive Being as extended in space; we have learned the ver- dict of Aristotle on the Eleatics generally, that their Being is merely the substance of sensible things. From a, is it is clear that these philosophers, too, were originally concerned with the knowledge of nature; that they also start from the given and actual, and from thence alone, in their search for its universal cause, attained their more abstract definitions. We must therefore regard the Eleatic doctrine in its general tendency, not as a dialectical system, but a system of natural philo- sophy.” Zeno, it is true, made use of the dialectic method in its defence, and was therefore called by Aristotle the discoverer of dialectics; * but the Eleatic * Wide sup. p. 100, 1, 2. * Sup. p. 613, 2. * Cf. with what follows, p. 185 sq. ITS CHARACTER AND POSITION. 641 philosophy as a whole is still far from being a system of dialectics. In order to be so, it should be dominated by a more definite view of the problem and method of scientific knowledge; its physical and metaphysical enquiry should be preceded by a theory of knowledge, and its view of the world should be regulated by the definition and discrimination of concepts. But all this is wholly absent. The Eleatics after the time of Parmenides distinguish the sensible and the rational contemplation of things, but this distinction has with them only the same import as with Heracleitus, Em- pedocles, Anaxagoras, and Democritus; it is not the basis, but the consequence, of their metaphysical pro- positions, and is developed as little into a real theory of knowledge, as by the other physicists. Of the principle by which Socrates struck out a new way for philosophy—viz., that the investigation of concepts must precede all knowledge of objects—we find no trace, neither in the explicit declarations of the Eleatics, nor in their scientific procedure. All that we know of them tends to confirm the view of Aris- totle, who regards Socrates as absolutely the first founder of the philosophy of the concept ; and seeks the imper- fect germ of that philosophy which can be detected in the earlier science, not in the Eleatics, but in Democritus, and to some extent also in the Pythagoreans." In the 1 Part. Anim. i. 1 (Sup. p. 185,3); Metaph. xiii. 4, 1078 b, 17: Xokpá- Tovs 6* Trepl r&s hôukås àper&s trpay- parevouévov kal trepitoötovëpíšegóat ka968 ov Çnroëvros ºrpdºrov (róv wév ºyap puoruków Śrī utºpov Amuákpitos #jaro P.6vov kai éptorató aros to 6ep- WOL. I. pov kal to puxpóv' of 8& IIv6ayópelot Tpórepov trepi rivav čAfyou . . .) éke?vos súAóryos égºiret to Tº eativ . . . 6üo yáp éo ruv & ris &v &toãotm X wrpátel Šikatos, roës ºr émakrikovs Aóryovs kal ºrb épſed.6at rcabóNov. Similarly ibid. i. 6, 987 b, 1 ; cf. T T 642 THE ELEATIC PHILOSOPHY. Eleatic system it is not the idea of knowing, but the concept of Being, that dominates the whole ; and this system forms no exception to the dogmatism of the pre-Socratic philosophy of nature. We must therefore speaking generally, class the Eleatics among the Physicists, as was sometimes done even in ancient times; " although in their material results they stand widely apart from the rest of the physical philosophers. In other respects, the historical position of this school, and its importance in the development of Greek thought, have been already considered in the introduction. xii. 9, 1086 b, 2; Phys. ii. 2, 194, 1 Plut. Pericl. c. 4; Sext. Math. i, 20, and what is quoted on p. vii. 5, in regard to Parmenides. 550, 3. END OF THE FIRST WOLUME. * i.ONDON : PRINTED BY spottiswoop E AND O., NEW-STREET SQUARE AND PARLIAMENT STREET The Authorised English Translation of DR. E. ZELLER'S WORK ON THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE GREEKS, SOCRATES and the SOCRATIC SCHOOLS. Translated by O. J. REICHEL, M.A. B.C.L. Sometime Scholar of Queen's College, Oxford. Second Edition, enlarged from Materials supplied by the Author. Crown 8vo. 10s. 6d. “This is a wholly new translation from the third German edition, and the trans- lator has done his work with such exceed- 1ng carefulness, and yet with such success in rendering the sometimes Crabbed and often involved German into idiomatic English, that his workmanship reads with PLATO and the OLDER ACADEMY. Translated by SARAH F. ALLEYNE, and ALFRED GooDWIN, B.A. Fellow and Lecturer, Balliol College, Oxford. Crown 8vo. 18s. “The compliment of translation is well deserved by the patient erudition and masterly arrangement of the original, which is an indispensable aid to the readers of PLATO and ARISTOTLE. Of this trans- lation it can be said that in all essential respects it may be relied on as an equivalent of ZELLER'S book.’ ACADEMY. ‘This is a translation of Dr. EDUARD ZELLER’s Plato und die altere Akademie, a work of great value to students of PLATO, but hitherto only in part accessible to English readers. The text has been admir- ably translated by Miss ALLEYNE, who has proved herself fully competent to deal with the philosophical terminology of the German original, and to execute a transla- tion which does not, like Some translations, proclaim itself as such by any un-English structure of its phrases and Sentences. Copious notes and references have been added by Mr. Goodwin, Fellow of Balliol College, who shares with Miss ALLEYNE the responsibility of the work. The value of Dr. ZELLER’s work has been amply acknowledged by Professor JOWETT in the Preface to the second edition of his PLATO ; and this translation of it will be a great boon to many students of PLATO who (as its Authors suggest in their Preface) are less familiar with German than the Greek.’ GUARDIAN. The STOICS, EPICUREANS, and SCEPTICS. Translated by O. J. REICHEL, M.A. B.C.L. sometime Scholar of Queen's College, Oxford. Second Edition, thoroughly revised. Crown 8vo. 15s. The PRE-SOCRATIC SCHOOLS. Being a History of Greek Philosophy from the Earliest Period to the Time of SOCRATES. Translated from the German of Dr. E. ZELLER by SARAH F. ALLEYNE. 2 Vols. Crown 8vo. 30s. ARISTOTLE and the ELDER PERIPATETICS. Trans- lated from the German of Dr. E. ZELLER by B. F. C. CoSTELLOE, Balliol College, Oxford. Crown 8vo. all the flowing ease of a well-written ori- ginal composition. . . . Taken as a whole, the book is one of profound value and interest, and while specially so to the phi- losophical student, may be commended to all thoughtful readers.” BRITISH QUARTERLY REVIEW. ‘The work must become indispensable to the student of PLATO. It consists of sixteen chapters, in which Plato's life, the order of his writings, the character of his Philosophy, his Physics, his Ethics, and his Religion, are treated with great detail and minuteness. It is, of course, impossible in these pages to do more with so vast a Work—not vast, however, in bulk, being a book of 600 pages—than to call attention to it, and, if possible, to give some idea of its style.” EDUCATIONAL TIMES. “In all its departments Dr. ZELLER’s book is both comprehensive and trust- Worthy. He seems to have said the last word on Greek philosophy; and his volumes are among those monuments of nineteenth century German research which make one Wonder what will remain for the scholars of the twentieth century to do. He brings to his task the two essential qualities— vast learning, and the power of moving at pleasure in the rarified atmosphere of ab- stractions. . . . It is evident that Mr. GOODWIN, to whom this part of the under- taking fell, had no sinecure in his work of translation and verification. He has gone bravely through with it, however, and both his work and that of Miss ALLEYNE, who translated the text, leave almost nothing to be desired.” SATURDAY REVIEW. [In the press. *** The volume announced above will complete the English Translation of Dr. ZELLER's Work on the Philosophy of the Greeks. London, LONGMANS & CO. * oCºTo BER 18so. GENERAL LISTS OF NEW WORKS PUBLISHED BY MESSRS. LONG MANS, GREEN & CO. PATERNOSTER ROW, LONDON. -—oo:6-ºo-o- HISTORY, POLITICS, HISTORICAL MEMOIRS &c. Armitage's Childhood of the English Nation. Fop. 8vo. 2s. 6d. Arnold’s Lectures on Modern History. 8vo. 7s. 6d. Bagehot's Literary Studies, edited by Hutton. 2 vols. 8vo. 283. Browning's Modern France, 1814–1879. Fop. 8vo. 18. Buckle's History of Civilisation. 3 vols, crown 8vo. 24s. Chesney's Indian Polity. 8vo. 218. — Waterloo Lectures. 8vo. 10s. 6d. Epochs of Ancient History:— Beesly's Gracchi, Marius, and Sulla, 2s. 6d. Capes’s Age of the Antonines, 2s. 6d. — Early Roman Empire, 2s. 6d. Cox's Athenian Empire, 2s. 6d. — Greeks and Persians, 28. 6d. Curteis's Rise of the Macedonian Empire, 2s. 6d. Ihne's Rome to its Capture by the Gauls, 2s. 6d. Merivale's Roman Triumvirates, 2s. 6d. Sankey's Spartan and Theban Supremacies, 2s. 6d. Epochs of English History, complete in One Volume. Fep. 8vo.'5s. Grºß ins History of England (Introductory Wolume). Cp. 8VO. Is. Browning's Modern England, 1820–1875, 9d. Cordery's Struggle against Absolute Monarchy, 1603–1688, 9d. Creighton's (Mrs.) England a Continental Power, 1066–1216, 9d. Creighton's (Rev. M.) Tudors and the Reformation, 1485–1603, 9d. Rowley's Rise of the People, 1215–1485, 9d. Rowley's Settlement of the Constitution, 1688–1778, 9d. Tancock's England during the American & European Wars, 1778–1820, 9d. York-Powell's Early England to the Conquest, 1s. Epochs of Modern History:— Church’s Beginning of the Middle Ages, 2s. 6d. Cox's Crusades, 23. 6d. Creighton’s Age of Elizabeth, 2s. 6d. Gairdner's Houses of Lancaster and York, 2s. 6d. Gardiner's Puritan Revolution, 2s. 6d. — Thirty Years' War, 2s. 6d. Bale’s Fall of the Stuarts, 2s. 6d. Johnson's Normans in Europe, 28. 6d. Ludlow's War of American Independence, 2s. 6d. Morris's Age of Queen Anne, 2s. 6d. London, LONGMANS & CO. 2 General Lists of New Works. Epochs of Modern History—-continued, Seebohm's Protestant Revolution, 2s. 6d. Stubbs's Early Plantageuets, 2s. 6d. Warburton's EdwardíII., 2s. 6d. Froude's English in Ireland in the 18th Century. 3 vols. 8vo. 483. - History ef England. 12 vols. 8vo. £8. 18s. 12 vols. crown 8vo. 72s. — Julius Cæsar, a Sketch. 8vo. 16s. – Two Lectures on South Africa. 8vo. 5s. Gairdner's Richard III. and Perkin Warbeck, Crown 8vo. 10s. 6d. Gardiner's England under Buckingham and Charles I., 1624–1628. 2 vols. 8vo.24s. – Personal Government of Charles I., 1628–1637. 2 vols. 8vo. 24s. Greville's Journal of the Reigns of George IV. & William IV. 3 vols. 8vo. 36s. Hayward's Selected Essays. 2 vols. crown 8vo. 12s. Ihne's History of Rome. 3 vols. 8vo. 45s. Lecky's History of England. Wols. I. & II. 1700–1760. 8vo. 36s. tº- — — European Morals. 2 vols. crown 8vo. 16s. - — — Rationalism in Europe. 2 vols. crown 8vo. 16s. Lewes's History of Philosophy. 2 vols. 8vo. 32s. Longman's Lectures on the History of England. 8vo. 15s. — Life and Times of Edward III. 2 vols. 8vo. 28s. Macaulay’s Complete Works. Library Edition. 8 vols. 8vo. £5.5s. -* - — Cabinet Edition. 16 vols. crown 8vo. £4.16s. * History of England:— Student's Edition. 2 vols. cr. 8vo. 12s. Cabinet Edition. 8 vols. post 8vo. 488. People's Edition. 4 vols. cr. 8vo. 16s. Library Edition. 5 vols. 8vo. £4. Macaulay's Critical and Historical Essays. Cheap Edition. Crown 8vo. 3s.6d. Student’s Edition. 1 vol. cr. 8vo. 68. Cabinet Edition. 4 vols. post 8vo. 248. People's Edition. 2 vols. cr. 8vo. 8s. Library Edition. 3 vols. 8vo. 36s. May's Constitutional History of England, 1760–1870. 3 vols, crown 8vo. 18s, — Democracy in Europe. 2 vols. 8vo. 32s. Merivale's Fall of the Roman Republic. 12mo. 7s. 6d. — General History of Rome, B.C. 753—A.D. 476. Crown 8vo. 7s.6d. — History of the Romans under the Empire, 8 vols. post 8vo. 48s. Minto (Lord) in India from 1807 to 1814. Post 8vo. 12s. Phillips's Civil War in Wales and the Marches, 1642–1649. 8vo. 16s. Rawlinson’s Sixth Oriental Monarchy—Parthia. 8vo. 16s. * Seventh Great Oriental Monarchy—The Sassanians. 8vo. 28s. Russia. Before and After the War, translated by E. F. Taylor. 8vo. 14s. Russia and England from 1876 to 1880. By O. K. 8vo. 14s. Seebohm's Oxford Reformers—Colet, Erasmus, & More. 8vo. 14s. Sewell's Popular History of France to the Death of Louis XIV. Crown 8vo. 7s.6d. Short's History of the Church of England. Crown 8vo. 7s. 6d. Smith's Carthage and the Carthaginians. Crown 8vo. 10s. 6d. Taylor's Manual of the History of India. Crown 8vo. 7s.6d. Todd's Parliamentary Government in England. 2 vols. 8vo. 37s. - *- -* — the British Colonies. 8vo. 218. Trench's Realities of Irish Life. Crown 8vo. 2s. 6d. Trevelyan’s Early History of Charles James Fox. 8vo. 18s. Walpole's History of England, 1815–1841. Wols. I. & II. 8vo. 36s. Wol. III. 18s. Webb's Civil War in Herefordshire. 2 vols. 8vo. Illustrations, 42s. London, LONG MANS & CO. General Lists of New Works. 3 BIOGRAPHICAL WORKS. Bagehot's Biographical Studies. 1 vol. 8vo. Burke's Wicissitudes of Families. 2 vols. crown 8vo. 218. Gleig's Life of the Duke of Wellington. Crown 8vo. 68. Jerrold’s Life of Napoleon III. Wols. I. to III. 8vo. price 18s. each. Jones's Life of Admiral Frobisher. Crown 8vo. 63. Lecky's Leaders of Public Opinion in Ireland. Crown 8vo. 7s.6d. Life (The) and Letters of Lord Macaulay. By his Nephew, G. Otto Trevelyan, M.P. Cabinet Edition, 2 vols. post 8vo. 12s. Library Edition, 2 vols. 8vo. 368. Marshman’s Memoirs of Havelock. Crown 8vo. 38. 6d. Memoirs of Anna Jameson, by Gerardine Macpherson. 8vo. 12s. 6d. Mendelssohn’s Letters. Translated by Lady Wallace. 2 vols. Cr. 8vo. 5s. each. Mill's (John Stuart) Autobiography. 8vo. 7s. 6d. Missionary Secretariat of Henry Venn, B.D. 8ve. Portrait. 18s. Newman's Apologia pro Vitā Suá. Crown 8vo. 68. Nohl's Life of Mozart. Translated by Lady Wallace. 2 vols. crown 8vo. 21s. Spedding's Letters and Life of Francis Bacon. 7 vols. 8vo. £4. 48. Stephen's Essays in Ecclesiastical Biography. Crown 8vo. 7s.6d. Stigand's Life, Works &c. of Heinrich Heine. 2 vols. 8vo. 288. MENTAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY. Amos's View of the Science of Jurisprudence. 8vo. 183. – Fifty Years of the English Constitution, 1830–1880. Crown 8vo. 10s. 6d. — Primer of the English Constitution. Crown 8vo. 63. Bacon's Essays, with Annotations by Whately. 8vo. 10s. 6d. — Works, edited by Spedding. 7 vols. 8vo. 73s.6d. Bagehot's Economic Studies, edited by Hutton. 8vo. 10s. 6d. Bain’s Logic, Deductive and Inductive. Crown 8vo. 10s. 6d. PART I. Deduction, 48. | PART II. Induction, 6s. 6d. Bolland & Lang's Aristotle's Politics. Crown 8vo. 7s. 6d. Brassey’s Foreign Work and English Wages. 8vo. 10s. 6d. Comte's System of Positive Polity, or Treatise upon Sociology, translated:— VoI. I. General View of Positivism and its Introductory Principles. 8vo. 213. VOL. II. Social Statics, or the Abstract Laws of Human Order. 14s. WOL. III. Social Dynamics, or General Laws of Human Progress. 218. WOL. IV. Theory of the Future of Man; with Early Essays. 24. Congreve's Politics of Aristotle; Greek Text, English Notes, 8vo. 18s. Grant's Ethics of Aristotle; Greek Text, English Notes. 2 vols. 8vo. 320. Griffith's A B C of Philosophy. Crown 8vo. 5s. Hillebrand's Lectures on German Thought. Crown 8vo. 7s. 6d. Hodgson's Philosophy of Reflection. 2 vols. 8vo. 213. Ealisch’s Path and Goal. 8vo. 12s. 6d. Lewis on Authority in Matters of Opinion. 8vo. 143. Leslie's Essays in Political and Moral Philosophy. 8vo. 10s. 6d. Macaulay’s Speeches corrected by Himself. Crown 8vo. 3s. 6d. Macleod's Economical Philosophy. Wol. I. 8vo. 15s. Wol. II. Part I. 123. Mill on Representative Government. Crown 8vo. 2s. — — Liberty. Post 8vo. 7s.6d. Crown 8vo. 1s. 4d. Mill's Analysis of the Phenomena of the Human Mind. 2 vols. 8vo. 28s. — Dissertations and Discussions. 4 vols. 8vo. 46s. 6d. London, LONG MANS & CO. 4. General Lists of New Works, Mill's Essays on Unsettled Questions of Political Economy. 8vo. 6s. 6d. – Examination of Hamilton's Philosophy. 8vo. 16s. – Legic, Ratiocinative and Inductive. 2 vols. 8vo. 25s. — Principles of Political Economy. 2 vols. 8vo. 30s. 1 vol. crown 8vo. 58. - Subjection of Women. Crown 8vo. 68. — Utilitarianism. 8vo. 5s. Morell’s Philosophical Fragments. Crown 8vo. 5s. Müller's (Max) Chips from a German Workshop. 4 vols. 8vo. 36s. * — Hibbert Lectures on Origin and Growth of Religion. 8vo. 10s. 6d. Sandars's Institutes of Justinian, with English Notes. 8vo. 18s. Swinbourne's Picture Logic. Post 8vo. 5s. Thomson's Outline of Necessary Laws of Thought. Crown 8vo. 6s. Tocqueville's Democracy in America, translated by Reeve. 2 vols. crown 8vo, 168. Twiss's Law of Nations, 8vo. in Time of Peace, 12s. in Time of War, 21s. Whately’s Elements of Logic, 8vo. 10s. 6d. Crown 8vo. 4s. 6d. *- — — Rhetoric. 8vo. 10s. 6d. Crown 8vo. 4s. 6d. * =- English Synonymes. Fop. 8vo. 3s. Williams's Nicomachean Ethics of Aristotle translated. Crown 8vo. 7s. 6d. Zeller's Socrates and the Socratic Schools. Crown 8vo. 10s. 6d. — Stoics, Epicureans, and Sceptics. Crown 8vo. 15s. — Plato and the Older Academy. Crown 8vo. 188. MiscELLANEOUS AND CRITICAL WORKS. Arnold's (Dr. Thomas) Miscellaneous Works. 8vo. 7s.6d. — (T.) Manual of English Literature. Crown 8vo. 7s.6d. — English Authors, Poetry and Prose Specimens. Bain’s Emotions and the Will. 8vo. 15s. — Mental and Moral Science. Crown 8vo. 10s. 6d. — Senses and the Intellect. 8vo. 15s. Becker's Charicles and Gallus, by Metcalfe. Post 8vo. 7s.6d. each. Blackley's German and English Dictionary. Post 8vo. 7s.6d. Buckle's Miscellaneous and Posthumous Works. 3 vols. 8vo. 52s. 6d. Cetshwayo's Dutchman. By C. Wijn. Translated by Bishop Colenso. Cr. 8vo. 5s. Conington's Miscellaneous Writings. 2 vols. 8vo. 288. Contanseau's Practical French & English Dictionary. Post 8vo. 7s.6d. - Pocket French and English Dictionary. Square 18mo. 3s. 6d. Farrar's Language and Languages. Crown 8vo. 6s. Froude's Short Studies on Great Subjects. 3 vols. crown 8vo. 18s. German Home Life, reprinted from Fraser's Magazine. Crown 8vo. 6s. Gibson’s Cavalier's Note-Book. Small 4to. 14s. Greville's (Lady Violet) Faiths and Fashions. Crown 8vo. 7s.6d. Hume's Essays, edited by Green & Grose. 2 vols. 8vo. 28s. — Treatise on Human Nature, edited by Green & Grose. 2 vols. 8vo. 288. Latham's Handbook of the English Language. Crown 8vo. 6s. — English Dictionary. 1 vol. medium 8vo. 248. 4 vols. 4to. £7. Liddell & Scott's Greek-English Lexicon. Crown 4to. 36s. — — — Abridged Greek-English Lexicon. Square 12mo. 7s. 6d. Longman's Pocket German and English Dictionary. 18mo. 5s. London, LONGMANS & CO. General Lists of New Works. 5 Macaulay’s Miscellaneous Writings. 2 vols. 8vo. 213. 1 vol. crown 8vo. 4s. 6d. Macaulay’s Miscellaneous Writings and Speeches. Crown 8vo. 6s. Macaulay’s Miscellaneous Writings, Speeches, Lays of Ancient Rome, &c. Cabinet Edition. 4 vols. crown 8vo. 24s. Mahaffy's Classical Greek Literature. Crown 8vo. Vol. I. the Poets, 7s.6d. Vol. II. the Prose Writers, 7s.6d. Müller's (Max) Lectures on the Science of Language. 2 vols. Crown 8vo. 16s. Noiré on Max Müller’s Philosophy of Language. Crown 8vo. 6s. Rich's Dictionary of Roman and Greek Antiquities. Crown 8vo. 7s.6d. Rogers's Eclipse of Faith. Fop. 8vo. 5s. — Defence of the Eclipse of Faith Fop. 8vo. 3s. 6d. Roget's Thesaurus of English Words and Phrases. Crown 8vo. 10s. 6d. Savile's Apparitions, a Narrative of Facts. Crown 8vo. 58. Selections from the Writings of Lord Macaulay. Crown 8vo. 6s. The Essays and Contributions of A. K. H. B. Crown 8vo. Autumn Holidays of a Country Parson. 3s. 6d. Changed Aspects of Unchanged Truths. 3s. 6d. Common-place Philosopher in Town and Country. 3s.6d. Counsel and Comfort spoken from a City Pulpit. 3s. 6d. Critical Essays of a Country Paison. 38. 6d. Graver Thoughts of a Country Parson. Three Series, 3s.6d. each. Landscapes, Churches, and Moralities. 3s.6d. Leisure Hours in Town. 3s.6d. Lessons of Middle Age. 3s. 6d. Present-day Thoughts. 3s.6d. Recreations of a Country Parson. Three Series, 3s.6d. each. Seaside Musings on Sundays and Week-Days. 3s. 6d. Sunday Afternoons in the Parish Church of a University City. 3s.6d. White & Riddle's Large Latin-English Dictionary. 4to. 21s. White's College Latin-English Dictionary. Royal 8vo. 12s. — Junior Student's Lat.-Eng. and Eng.-Lat. Dictionary. Square 12mo, 128. The English-Latin Diction 53. 6d. Separately { The #; #;%. ; Wit and Wisdom of the Rev. Sydney Smith, 16mo. 3s.6d. Yonge's English-Greek Lexicon. Square 12mo. 8s. 6d. 4to. 218. ASTRONOMY, METEOROLOGY, POPULAR GEOGRAPHY &c. Dove's Law of Storms, translated by Stott. 8vo. 10s. 6d. Herschel's Outlines of Astronomy. Square crown 8vo. 12s. Keith Johnston's Dictionary of Geography, or General Gazetteer, 8vo. 428. Neigon’s Work on the Moon. Medium 8vo. 31.s. 6d. Proctor's Essays on Astronomy. 8vo. 12s. Proctor's Moon. Crown 8vo. 10s. 6d. Larger Star Atlas. Folio, 15s. or Maps only, 12s. 6d. New Star Atlas. Crown 8vo. 5s. Orbs Around Us. Crown 8vo. 7s. 6d. Other Worlds than Ours. Crown 8vo. 10s. 6d. Saturn and its System. 8vo. 14s. Proctor's Sun. Crown 8vo. 148. Transits of Venus, Past and Coming. Crown 8vo. 8s. 6d. Treatise on the Cycloid and Cycloidal Curves. Crown 8vo. 108. 6d. – Universe of Stars. 8vo. 10s. 6d. Schellen's Spectrum Analysis. 8vo. 288. Smith's Air and Rain, 8vo. 24s. The Public Schools Atlas of Ancient Geography. Imperial 8vo. 7s.6d. — — — Atlas of Modern Geography. Imperial 8vo. 5s. London, LONGMANS & CO. 6 General Lists of New Works, NATURAL HISTORY & POPULAR SCIENCE, Arnott's Elements of Physics or Natural Philosophy. Crown 8vo. 12s. 6d. Brande's Dictionary of Science, Literature, and Art. 3 vols. medium 8vo. 638. Buckton's Town and Window Gardening. Crown 8vo. 2s. Decaisne and Le Maout's General System of Botany. Imperial 8vo. 31.s. 6d. Dixon's Rural Bird Life. Crown 8vo. Illustrations, 7s.6d. Ganot's Elementary Treatise on Physics, by Atkinson. Large crown 8vo. 158. — Natural Philosophy, by Atkinson. Crown 8vo. 7s.6d. Gore's Art of Scientific Discovery. Crown 8vo. 15s. Grove's Correlation of Physical Forces. 8vo. 15s. Hartwig's Aerial World. 8vo. 10s. 6d. Polar World. 8vo. 10s. 6d. tºº Sea and its Living Wonders. 8vo. 10s. 6d. * Subterranean World. 8vo. 10s. 6d. Tropical World. 8vo. 10s. 6d. Haughton’s Principles of Animal Mechanics. 8vo. 218. -- Six Lectures on Physical Geography. 8vo. 15s. Heer’s Primaeval World of Switzerland. 2 vols. 8vo. 16s. Helmholtz's Lectures on Scientific Subjects, 2 vols. cr. 8vo. 7s.6d, each. Helmholtz on the Sensations of Tone, by Ellis. 8vo. 36s. Hullah's Lectures on the History of Modern Music. 8vo. 8s. 6d. — Transition Period of Musical History. 8vo. 10s. 6d. Keller's Lake Dwellings of Switzerland, by Lee. 2 vols. royal 8vo. 424. Kirby and Spence's Introduction to Entomology. Crown 8vo. 58. Lloyd's Treatise on Magnetism. 8vo. 10s. 6d. sº º- on the Wave-Theory of Light, 8vo. 10s. 6d. Loudon's Encyclopædia of Plants. 8vo. 42s. Lubbock on the Origin of Civilisation & Primitive Condition of Man. 8vo. 18s. Macalister's Zoology and Morphology of Vertebrate Animals. 8vo. 10s. 6d. Nicols’ Puzzle of Life. Crown 8vo. 3s. 6d. owº ºve Anatomy and Physiology of the Wertebrate Animals. 3 vols. WO. 738. 6d. Proctor's Light Science for Leisure Hours. 2 vols. crown 8vo. 7s.6d, each. Rivers's Orchard House. Sixtebnth Edition. Crown 8vo. 58, — Rose Amateur’s Guide. Fop. 8vo. 4s. 6d. Stanley's Familiar History of British Birds. Crown 8vo. 6s. Text-Books of Science, Mechanical and Physical. Abney's Photography, 3s.6d. Anderson's (Sir John) Strength of Materials, 3s.6d. Armstrong's Organic Chemistry, 3s.6d. Ball’s Astronomy, 68. Barry’s Railway Appliances, 3s.6d. Bloxam's Metals, 3s.6d. Goodeve's Elements of Mechanism, 38. 6d. — Principles of Mechanics, 3s.6d. Gore's Electro-Metallurgy, 6s. Griffin's Algebra and Trigonometry, 3s.6d. Jenkin's Electricity and Magnetista, 38. 6d. Maxwell's Theory of Heat, 3s.6d. Merrifield's Technical Arithmetic and Mensuration, 3s. 6d. Miller's Inorganic Chemistry, 3s.6d. Preece & Sivewright's Telegraphy, 3s. 6d. Rutley's Study of Rocks, 4s. 6d. Shelley's Workshop Appliances, 3s. 6d. London, LONGMANS & CO. General Lists of New Works. * 7 Text-Books of Science—continued. Thomé’s Structural and Physiological Botany, 6s. Therpe's Quantitative Chemical Analysis, 4s. 6d. Thorpe & Muir's Qualitative Analysis, 3s.6d. Tilden’s Chemical Philosophy, 3s. 6d. TJnwin’s Machine Design, 3s. 6d. Watson's Plane and Solid Geometry, 3s.6d. Tyndall on Sound. Crown 8vo. 10s. 6d. Contributions to Molecular Physics. 8vo. 163. Fragments of Science. 2 vols. post 8vo. 16s. Heat a Mode of Motion, 6th Edition, 13th Thousand. Crown 8vo. 12s. Notes on Electrical Phenomena. Crown 8vo. 1s. sewed, 1s. 6d. cloth. Notes of Lectures on Light. Crown 8vo. 1s. Sewed, 1s. 6d. cloth. Lectures on Light delivered in America. Crown 8vo. 7s.6d. Lessons in Electricity. Crown 8vo. 2s. 6d. Won Cotta on Rocks, by Lawrence. Post 8vo. 14s. Woodward's Geology of England and Wales. Crown 8vo. 14s. Wood’s Bible Animals. With 112 Vignettes. 8vo. 143. – Homes Without Hands. 8vo. 14s. Insects Abroad. 8vo. 14s. — Insects at Home. With 700 Illustrations. 8vo. 14s. — Out of Doors. Crown 8vo. 7s.6d. Strange Dwellings. Crown 8vo. 7s.6d. CHEMISTRY & PHYSIOLOGY. Auerbach’s Anthracen, translated by W. Crookes, F.R.S. 8vo. 12s. Buckton's Health in the House, Lectures on Elementary Physiology. Cr. 8vo. 2s. Crookes's Handbook of Dyeing and Calico Printing. 8vo. 42s. * Select Methods in Chemical Analysis. Crown 8vo. 12s. 6d. Kingzett's Animal Chemistry. 8vo. 18s. -> History, Products and Processes of the Alkali Trade. 8vo. 12s. Miller’s Elements of Chemistry, Theoretical and Practical. 3 vols. 8vo. Part T. Chemical Physics, 16s. Part II. Inorganic Chemistry, 243. Part III. Organic Chemistry, Section I. price 313. 6d. Thudichum’s Annals of Chemical Medicine. Vol. I. 8vo. 14s. Tilden’s Practical Chemistry. Fop. 8vo. 1s. 6d. Watts's Dictionary of Chemistry. 7 vols. medium 8vo. £10. 16s. 6d. – Third Supplementary Volume, in Two Parts. PART I. 36s. THE FINE ARTS & ILLUSTRATED EDITIONs. Bewick's Select Fables of AEsop and others. Crown 8vo. 7s.6d. demy 8vo. 18s. Toyle's Fairyland; Pictures from the Elf-World. Folio, 15s. Dresser's Arts and Art Industries of Japan. [In preparation. Ingelow’s Poems, Illustrated Edition. Fop. 4to. Woodcuts, 21s. Jameson's Sacred and Legendary Art. 6 vols. square crown 8vo. Legends of the Madonna. 1 vol. 21s. — — — Monastic Orders. 1 vol. 21s. — — — Saints and Martyrs. 2 vols, 31s. 6d. — — — Saviour. Completed by Lady Eastlake. 2 vols. 42s. Longman's Three Cathedrals Dedicated to St. Paul. Square crown 8vo. 21s. Macaulay's Lays of Ancient Rome. With 90 Illustrations. Fop. 4to. 218. Macfarren's Lectures on Harmony. 8vo. 12s. Miniature Edition of Macaulay’s Lays of Ancient Rome. Imp. 16mo. 10s. 6d. Moore's Irish Melodies. With 161 Plates by D. Maclise, R.A. Super-royal 8vo. 21s. London, LONGMANS & CO. s 8 General Lists of New Works. Moore's Lalla Rookh, illustrated by Tenniel. Square crown 8vo. 10s. 6d. Berry on Greek and Roman Sculpture. 8vo [In preparation. THE USEFUL ARTS, MANUFACTURES &c. Bourne's Catechism of the Steam Engine. Fop. 8vo. 6s. — Examples of Steam, Air, and Gas Engines. 4to. 70s. — Handbook of the Steal Engine. FCp. 8vo. 9s. — Recent Improvements in the Steam Engine. Fop. 8vo. 63. — Treatise on the Steam Engine, 4to. 42s. Cresy’s Encyclopædia of Civil Engineering. 8vo. 25s. Culley's Handbook of Practical Telegraphy. 8vo. 16s. Eastlake's Household Taste in Furniture, &c. Square crown 8vo. 14s. Fairbairn's Useful Information for Engineers. 3 vols. crown 8vo. 31.s. 6d. - Applications of Cast and Wrought Iron, 8vo, 16s. - Mills and Millwork. 1 Vol. 8vo. 25s. t Gwilt's Encyclopædia of Architecture. 8vo. 52s. 6d. Hobson’s Amateur Mechanic’s Practical Handbook. Crown 8vo. 2s. 6d. Hoskold's Engineer's Waluing Assistant. 8vo. 31.s. 6d. Kerl’s Metallurgy, adapted by Crookes and Röhrig. 3 vols. 8vo. £4.19s. Loudon’s Encyclopædia of Agriculture. 8vo. 21s. - tº-e – Gardening. 8vo. 21s. Mitchell’s Manual of Practical Assaying. 8vo. 31.s. 6d. Northcott's Lathes and Turning, 8vo. 18s. Payen's Industrial Chemistry Edited by B. H. Paul, Ph.D. 8vo. 42s, Piesse’s Art of Perfumery. Fourth Edition. Square crown 8vo. 21s. Stoney's Theory of Strains in Girders. Royal 8vo. 36s. Thomas on Coal, Mine-Gases and Ventilation. Crown 8vo. 10s. 6d. Ure's Dictionary of Arts, Manufactures, & Mines. 4 vols. medium 8vo. £7. 7s. Wille on Artificial Manures. By Crookes. 8vo. 218. RELIGIOUS & MORAL WORKS. Abbey & Overton's English Church in the Eighteenth Century. 2 vols. 8vo. 36s. Arnold's (Rev. Dr. Thomas) Sermons. 6 vols. crown 8vo. 5s. each. Bishop Jeremy Taylor's Entire Works. With Life by Bishop Heber. Edited by the Rev. C. P. Eden. 10 vols. 8vo. £5.5s. Boultbee's Commentary on the 39 Articles. Crown 8vo. 6s. - History of the Church of England, Pre-Reformation Period. 8vo. 15s. Browne's (Bishop) Exposition of the 39 Articles, 8vo. 16s. Bunsen’s Angel-Messiah of Buddhists, &c. 8vo. 10s 6d. Colenso’s Lectures on the Pentateuch and the Moabite Stone, 8vo. 12s. Colenso on the Pentateuch and Book of Joshua. Crown 8vo. 68. — — PART VII. completion of the larger Work. 8vo. 24s. Conder’s Handbook of the Bible. Post 8vo. 7s. 6d. Conybeare & Howson's Life and Letters of St. Paul :— Library Edition, with all the Original Illustrations, Maps, Landscapes on Steel, Woodcuts, &c., 2 vols. 4to. 42s. Intermediate Edition, with a Selection of Maps, Plates, and Woodcuts. 2 vols. Square crown 8vo. 213. Student's Edition, revised and condensed, with 46 Illustrations and Maps, I Vol. Crown 8vo. 7s. 6d. Ilondon, LONG MANS & CO. General Lists of New Works. 9 Drummond's Jewish Messiah. 8vo. 15s. Ellicott's (Bishop) Commentary on St. Paul’s Epistles. 8vo. Galatians, 8s. 6d. Ephesians, 8s. 6d. Pastoral Epistles, 10s. 6d. Philippians, Colossians, and Philemon, 10s. 6d. Thessalonians, 7s.6d. Ellicott's Lectures on the Life of our Lord. 8vo. 12s. Ewald's History of Israel, translated by Carpenter. 5 vols. 8vo. 63s. – Antiquities of Israel, translated by Solly. 8vo. 12s. 6d. Gospel (The) for the Nineteenth Century. 4th Edition. 8vo. 10s. 6d. Hopkins's Christ the Consoler. Fep. 8vo. 2s. 6d. Jukes's Types of Genesis. Crown 8vo. 7s.6d. - Second Death and the Restitution of all Things. Crown 8vo. 3s.6d. Kalisch's Bible Studies. PART I. the Prophecies of Balaam. 8vo. 10s. 6d. *- -º- - PART II. the Book of Jonah. 8vo. 108. 6d. * Historical and Critical Commentary on the Old Testament; with a New Translation. Vol. I. Genesis, 8vo. 18s. or adapted for the General Reader, 12s. Vol. II. Eacodus, 15s. or adapted for the General Reader, 12s. Vol. III. Leviticus, Part I. 15s. or adapted for the General Reader, 8s. Vol. IV. Leviticus, Part II. 15s. or adapted for the General Reader, 8s. Lyra Germanica: Hymns translated by Miss Winkworth. Fop. 8vo. 58. Manning's Temporal Mission of the Holy Ghost. 8vo. 8s. 6d. Martineau’s Endeavours after the Christian Life. Crown 8vo. 7s. 6d. - Hymns of Praise and Prayer. Crown 8vo. 4s. 6d. 32mo, 1s. 6d. - Sermons, Hours of Thought on Sacred Things. 2 vols. 7s.6d. each. Merivale's (Dean) Lectures on Early Church History. Crown 8vo. 5s. Mill's Three Essays on Religion. 8vo. 10s. 6d. Missionary Secretariat of Henry Venn, B.D. 8vo. Portrait. 18s. Monsell's Spiritual Songs for Sundays and Holidays. Fep. 8vo. 5s. 18mo. 28. Müller's (Max) Lectures on the Science of Religion. Crown 8vo. 10s. 6d. Newman's Apologia pro Vitā Suá. Crown 8vo. 68. Passing Thoughts on Religion. By Miss Sewell. FCp. 8vo. 3s.6d. Sewell's (Miss) Preparation for the Holy Communion. 32mo. 3s. Smith's Voyage and Shipwreck of St. Paul. Crown 8vo. 7s.6d. Supernatural Religion. Complete Edition. 3 vols. 8vo. 36s. Thoughts for the Age. By Miss Sewell. Fep. 8vo. 3s.6d. Waughan's Trident, Crescent, and Cross; the Religious History of India. 8vo.9s.6d. Whately’s Lessons on the Christian Evidences. 18mo. 6d. White's Four Gospels in Greek, with Greek-English Lexicon. 32mo. 5s. TRAVELS, VOYAGES &c. Baker's Rifle and Houndin Ceylon. Crown 8vo.7s.6d. – Eight Years in Ceylon. Crown 8vo. 7s.6d. Ball's Alpine Guide. 3 vols.post 8vo. with Maps and Illustrations:—I. Western Alps, 65. 6d. II. Central Alps, 7s.6d. III. Eastern Alps, 10s. 6d. Ball on Alpine Travelling, and on the Geology of the Alps, 1s. Bent's Freak of Freedom, or the Republic of San Marino. Crown 8vo. 7s.6d. Brassey's Sunshine and Storm in the East. 8vo. 21s. – Voyage in the Yacht ‘Sunbeam.” Cr. 8vo. 7s.6d. School Edition, 2s. London, LONGMANS & CO. 10 General Lists of New Work,. Edwards's (A.B.) Thousand Miles up the Nile. Imperial 8vo. 42s. Hassall's San Remo and the Western Riviera. Crown 8vo. 10s. 6d. Macnamara's Medical Geography of India. 8vo. 21s, Miller's Wintering in the Riviera. Post 8vo. Illustrations, 12s. 6d. Packe's Guide to the Pyrenees, for Mountaineers. Crown 8vo. 7s.6d. Rigby’s Letters from France, &c. in 1789. Crown 8vo. 10s. 6d. Shore's Flight of the ‘Lapwing', Sketches in China and Japan. 8vo. The Alpine Club Map of Switzerland. In Four Sheets. 42s. WORKS OF FICTION. Blues and Buffs. By Arthur Mills. Crown 8vo. 6s. Hawthorne's (J.) Yellow-Cap and other Fairy Stories. Crown 8vo. 6s. The Crookit Meg. By Shirley. Crown 8vo. 6s. Cabinet Edition of Stories and Tales by Miss Sewell:— Amy Herbert, 2s. 6d. Cleve Hall, 2s. 6d. The Earl's Daughter, 2s. 6d. Experience of Life, 2s. 6d. Gertrude, 2s. 6d. Novels and Tales by the Right Hon. the Earl of Beaconsfield, K.G. Ivors, 2s. 6d. Katharine Ashton, 2s. 6d. Laneton Parsonage, 36, £d. Margaret Percival, 3s.6d. Ursula, 38. 6d. Cabinet Edition, complete in Ten Volumes, crown 8vo. price £3. Lothair, 6s. Coningsby, 63. Sybil, 68. Tancred, 68. Venetia, 6s. Elein’s Pastor’s Narrative. The Modern Novelist's Library. Each Translated by Marshall. Henrietta Temple, 6s. Contarini Fleming, 68. Alroy, Ixion, &c. 6s. The Young Duke, &c. 6s. Vivian Grey, 63. Crown 8vo. Map, 68. Work in crown 8vo. A Single Volume, complete in itself, price 2s. boards, or 2s. 6d. cloth :— By the Earl of Beaconsfield, K.G. Lothair. Coningsby. Sybil Tancred. Venetia. Henrietta Temple. Contarini Fleming. Alroy, Ixion, &c. The Young Duke, &c. Vivian Grey. By Anthony Trollope. Barchester Towers. The Warden. By the Author of ‘the Rose Garden.” Unawares. Lord Beaconsfield’s Novels and Tales. Whispers from Fairy Land. By the Right Hon. Lord Brabourne. Illustrations. Crown 8vo. 3s. 6d. By Major Whyte-Melville. Digby Grand. General Bounce. Rate Coventry. The Gladiators. Good for Nothing. Holmby House. The Interpreter. The Queen's Maries. By the Author of ‘the Atelier du Lys.” Mademoiselle Mori. The Atelier du Lys. By Various Writers. Atherstone Priory. The Burgomaster's Family. Elsa and her Vulture. The Six Sisters of the Walleys. 10 vols. cloth extra, gilt edges, 308. With Nine Higgledy-Piggledy; or, Stories for Everybody, and Everybody's Children. By the Right Hon. Lord Brabourne. With Nine Illustrations from Designs by R. Doyle. Crown 8vo. 3s. 6d. London, LONGMANS & CO. General Lists of New Works. 11 POETRY & THE DRAMA. Bailey’s Festus, a Poem. Crown 8vo. 12s. 6d. Bowdler's Family Shakspeare. Medium 8vo. 14s. 6 vols. fop. 8vo. 21s. Cayley's Iliad of Homer, Homometrically translated. 8vo. 12s. 6d. Comington’s AEneid of Virgil, translated into English Verse. Crown 8vo. 9s. Cooper's Tales from Euripides. FCp. 8vo. 38. 6d. Horace’s Epistles, Book II. and ars Poetica, annotated by Cox. 12mo. Ingelow's Poems. New Edition. 2 vols. fop. 8vo. 12s. Macaulay's Lays of Ancient Rome, with Ivry and the Armada. 16mo. 3s.6d. Ormsby’s Poem of the Cid. Translated. Post 8vo. 5s. Southey's Poetical Works. Medium 8vo. 14s. Yonge's Horatii Opera, Library Edition. 8vo. 218. RURAL SPORTS, HORSE & CATTLE MANAGEMENT &c. Blaine's Encyclopædia of Rural Sports, 8vo. 218. Francis's Treatise on Fishing in all its Branches. Post 8vo. 15s, Horses and Roads. By Free-Lance. Crown 8vo. 6s. Miles's Horse's Foot, and How to Keep it Sound. Imperial 8vo. 12s. 6d. — Plain Treatise on Horse-Shoeing. Post 8vo. 2s. 6d. — Stables and Stable-Fittings. Imperial 8vo. 15s. — Remarks on Horses’ Teeth. Post 8vo. 13. 6d. Nevile's Horses and Riding. Crown 8vo. 63. Ronalds's Fly-Fisher's Entomology. 8vo. 14s. Steel's Bovine Pathology, or Diseases of the Ox. 8vo. Stonehenge's Dog in Health and Disease. Square crown 8vo. 7s.6d. - Greyhound. Square crown 8vo. 158. Youatt's Work on the Dog. 8vo. 68. -> — — — Horse. 8vo. 7s. 6d. Wilcocks's Sea-Fisherman. Post 8vo. 12s. 6d. WORKS OF UTILITY & GENERAL INFORMATION. Acton's Modern Cookery for Private Families. FCp. 8vo. 6s. Black's Practical Treatise on Brewing. 8vo. 10s. 6d. Buckton’s Food and Home Cookery. Crown 8vo. 2s. Bull on the Maternal Management of Children. FCp. 8vo. 2s. 6d. Bull's Hints to Mothers on the Management of their Health during the Period of Pregnancy and in the Lying-in Room. FCp. 8vo. 2s. 6d. Campbell-Walker's Correct Card, or How to Play at Whist. Fop. 8vo. 2s. 6d. Crump's English Manual of Banking. 8vo. 15s. Johnson's (W. & J. H.) Patentee's Manual. Fourth Edition. 8vo. 10s. 6d. Longman's Chess Openings. FCp. 8vo. 2s. 6d. Macleod’s Economics for Beginners. Small crown 8vo. 2s. 6d. - Elements of Economics. Small crown 8vo. [In the press. London, LONGMANS & CO. 12 General Lists of New Works. Macleod's Theory and Practice of Banking. 2 vols. 8vo. 26s. tºm- Elements of Banking. Fourth Edition. Crown 8vo. 58. M’Culloch's Dictionary of Commerce and Commercial Navigation. 8vo. 63s. Maunder's Biographical Treasury. Fop. 8vo. 6s. Historical Treasury. Fep. 8vo. 6s. Scientific and Literary Treasury. Fep. 8vo. 63. Treasury of Bible Knowledge, edited by Ayre. Fop. 8vo. 6s. Treasury of Botany, edited by Lindley & Moore. Two Parts, 12s. Treasury of Geography. Fop. 8vo. 6s, Treasury of Knowledge and Library of Reference. Fop. 8vo. 6s, Treasury of Natural History. Fep. 8vo. 6s. Pereira's Materia Medica, by Bentley and Redwood. 8vo. 25s. Pewtner's Comprehensive Specifier; Building-Artificers’ Work. Crown 8vo, 34. Pierce's Three Hundred Chess Problems and Studies. Fop. 8vo. 7s.6d. Pole's Theory of the Modern Scientific Game of Whist. Fop. 8vo. 2s. 6d. Scott's Farm Valuer. Crown 8vo. 53. — Rents and Purchases. Crown 8vo. 6s. Smith’s Handbook for Midwives. Crown 8vo. 58. The Cabinet Lawyer, a Popular Digest of the Laws of England. Fop. 8vo. 9s. West on the Diseases of Infancy and Childhood. 8vo. 18s. Wilson on Banking Reform. 8vo. 7s.6d. — on the Resources of Modern Countries 2 vols. 8vo. 24s. MUSICAL WORKS BY JOHN HULLAH, LL.D. Chromatic Scale, with the Inflected Syllables, on Large Sheet. 18. 6d. Card of Chromatic Scale. la. Exercises for the Cultivation of the Voice. For Soprano or Tenor, 2s. 6d. Grammar of Musical Harmony. Royal 8vo. 2 Parts, each 1s. 6d. Exercises to Grammar of Musical Harmony. 18. Grammar of Counterpoint. Part I. Super-royal 8vo. 2s. 6d. Hullah's Manual of Singing. Parts I. & II. 2s. 6d. ; or together, 58. Exercises and Figures contained in Parts I. and II. of the Manual. Books I. & II. each 8d. Large Sheets, containing the Figures in Part I. of the Manual. Nos. 1 to 8 in a Parcel. 68. Large Sheets, containing the Exercises in Part I. of the Manual. Nos. 9 to 40, in Four Parcels of Eight Nos. each, per Parcel. 68. - Large Sheets, the Figures in Part II. Nos. 41 to 52 in a Parcel, 98. Hymas for the Young, set to Music. Royal 8vo. 8d. Infant School Songs. 6d. Notation, the Musical Alphabet. Crown 8vo. 6d. Old English Songs for Schools, Harmonised. 6d. Rudiments of Musical Grammar. Royal 8vo. 3s. School Songs for 2 and 3 Voices. 2 Books, 8vo. each 6d. Time and Tune in the Elementary School. Crown 8vo. 2s. 6d. Exercises and Figures in the same. Crown 8vo. 1s. or 2 Parts, 6d. each. London, LONG MANS & CO. Spottiswoode dº Co. Printers, New-street Square, London. § i Y. { s