THE HISTORICAL INTERPRETATION OF UNABRIDGED FREEDOM OF SPEECH, BY THEODORE SCHROEDER. † K A chapter from “Obscene Literature and Constitutional Law.” Republished from Central Law Journal, March, 1910. FOR FREE-SPEECH LEAGUE, I2O LEXINGTON AWE. *, NEW YORK. SECOND EDITION. Sir Leslie Stephens on Toleration. “The doctrine of toleration requires a positive as well as a neg- ative statement. It is not only wrong to burn a man on account of his creed, but it is right to encourage the open avowal and defence of every opinion sincerely maintained. Every man who says frankly and fully what he thinks is so far doing a public service. We should be grateful to him for attacking most unsparingly our most cherished opinions.” “Toleration, in fact, as I have understood it, is a necessary co- relative to a respect for truthfulness. So far as we can lay it down as an absolute principle that every man should be thoroughly trustworthy and therefore truthful, we are bound to respect every manifestation of truthfulness.”A man must not be punished for openly avowing any principles whatever.” “Toleration implies that a man is to be allowed to profess and maintain any principles that he pleases; not that he should be allowed in all cases to act upon his principles, especially to act upon them to the injury of others. No limitation whatever need be put upon this principle in the case supposed. I, for one, am fully prepared to listen to any arguments for the propriety of theft or murder, or if it be pos- sible of immorality in the abstract. No doctrine, however well es- tablished, should be protected from discussion. The reasons have been already assigned. If, as a matter of fact, any appreciable number" of persons is so inclined to advocate murder on principle, I should wish them to state their opinions openly and fearlessly, because I should think that the shortest way of exploding the principle and of ascertaining the true causes of such a perversion of moral sentiment. Such a state of things implies the existence of evils which cannot be really cured till their cause is known, and the shortest way to discover the cause is to give a hearing to the alleged reasons.” From “The Suppression of Poisonous Opinions” in The Nineteenth Century, March and April, 1883. THE HISTORICAL INTERPRETATION OF UNABRIDGED FREEDOM OF SPEECH, BY THEODORE SCHROEDER. A chapter from “Obscene Literature and Constitutional Law.” &epublished from Central Law Journal, March, 1910. FOR FREE-SPEECH LEAGUE, 120 LEXINGTON AVE. NEW YORK. THEODORE SCHROEDER Return Postage Guaranteed Coscob, Connecticut, U.S.A. THE HISTORICAL INTERPRETATION OF “FREEDOM OF SPEECH AND OF THE PRESS.” The purpose is to re-interpret our constitutional guarantee for an unabridged freedom of speech and of the press, by the historical or scientific method, and with special reference to the specific issue raised by the judicial dogmatism thereon and my different conception of how that phrase ought to be interpreted. To clarify the issues, I restate these contradictory propositions, So the reader may have them constantly in mind during the following discussion. My contention as to the meaning of a constitutionally guar- anteed right to unabridged freedom of speech and of the press, is this: No matter upon what subject, nor how injurious to the public welfare any particular idea thereon may be deemed to be, the constitutional right is violated whenever anyone is not legally free to express any such or other sentiments, either; First, because prevented in advance by a legally created censorship, or monopoly in the use of the press, or by other governmental power, or ; Second, because in the effort to secure publicity for any idea whatever, the equality of natural opportunity is destroyed, in that some, by subsequent legal penalties or other legal limi- tations, are deterred, or are impeded, in the use of the ordinary and natural methods of reaching the public, on the same legal terms, as these are permitted to any person for the presentation of any other idea, or; Third, because the natural opportunity of all is abridged by Some statutory impediment, such as taxes upon the dissemina- tion of information placed upon all intellectual intercourse, as such, or on all of a particular class, or; Fourth, because inequalities in State-created, or State- supported, opportunity is legalized, so that, in the effort to secure publicity for any sentiments and merely because of their 3 nature, literary style, or supposed evil tendency, any one is discriminated against, either by law, or for any cause by any arbitrary exercise of official discretion, in the use of such State- created or State-supported facilities, or; Fifth, because after expressing one's sentiments one is by law liable to punishment, merely for having uttered disap- proved thoughts; Provided always, that the prohibition, abridgment, discrim- ination, subsequent punishment, or other legal disability or disadvantage, is arbitrarily inflicted, or attaches merely because of the character, literary style, or supposed bad tendency of the offending sentiments, and their spread among sane adults, willing to read, see, or hear them, or is the result of arbitrary official discretion, and that they do not attach because of any inseparably accompanying, or other resultant penalized invasive act, constituting an actually ascertained, resultant, material injury, (as distinguished from mere speculative or constructive harm) inflicted, or by overt act attempted to be inflicted, before arrest and punishment, and in either case actually resulting from the particular utterance involved. But, if the injury is to reputation, or loss of public esteem, and among the consequences is material injury to the libeled person, even then, truth and justifiable motive must always be recognized by law as a complete defense; and where the resultant injury consists in violence to person or property, actually attempted or achieved, then the intent to achieve such results must be of the essence of the crime, and punishment of a mere speaker must be only that of an accessory before the fact, if our constitutional guaranty is to be made effective. I do not discuss civil remedies. - THE JUDICIAL INTERPRETATION. The contrary conclusion of the Courts is well summarized by a dictum, perhaps hastily uttered, of the Federal Supreme Court. These are its words: “The main purpose of such con- stitutional provisions is to prevent all such previous restraints as had been practised by other governments, and they do not prevent the subsequent punishment of such as may be deemed contrary to the public welfare”!" In England the licensing acts, which put a previous restraint upon publications, existed for only a short time, and finally expired in A. D. 1694. It seems, therefore, according to the *Patterson v. Colo., 205 U. S. 454, (462). *Stevens’ “Sources of the Constitution of the U. S.,” p. 221; Patterson’s “Liberty of Press and Speech,” 50 and 51 4. definition of our American Courts, that perfect unabridged liberty of speech and press obtained in England after the year 1694, because no licenser prohibited before utterance, and there prevailed a system of subsequent punishment for only such opinions as were deemed contrary to the public welfare, and for nearly a century preceding our Revolution the agitation for larger freedom of speech and of the press was a vain demand for something already enjoyed by the agitators, but not known by them to exist. However ridiculous such judicial implications will appear to some, the official eminence of the many judges who have sanctioned that doctrine, and especially the tremendous con- sequence of it to our liberties, precludes levity. We will there- fore proceed in all seriousness to demonstrate the error of our cQurts by a historical study and a scientific interpretation of the facts. Thus it will be made to appear that unabridged liberty of discussion did not obtain in England, or its American Colonies, from 1694 until the American Revolution, and that our Constitutions were designed to change the prevailing system of an abridged and abridgable liberty of discussion by permission, to an unabridged and unabridgable liberty of dis- cussion as a constitutionally guaranteed, natural right, not to be ignored, as in England, or Russia, where the claim of such freedom was and is denied, on the plea of furthering the public welfare. THE EARLY THEORY AS TO FREE SPEECH. In England, “before public meetings were resorted to as an ordinary exercise of self-government, great looseness pre- vailed in the law, the theory apparently being that free-speech was a species of gift by the Sovereign to the people.” To have the power to control what others may hear or see, is of course to that extent a limitation upon their right to acquire and have opinions—thus abridging the liberty of conscience— since one cannot well acquire opinions the materials of which are withheld from him. Since the right to have a personal judgment and the right to express it existed only as a gift from kings and priests, when the issuing of pamphlets became an extended form of speech nothing was more natural than that at first “printing was treated like the making of salamoniac and apprentices were cautioned not to lay open the principles to the unfaithfill “ *Patterson’s “Liberty of Press, p. 19. *Patterson’s “Liberty of Press,” p. 43, citing, Becket v. Denison, 17 Parl. Hist., 958. 5 The reasons underlying such conclusions are fully appreci- ated only by keeping in mind the English conception of that period as to the nature of the State. The features especially to be remembered are the union of Church and State, and the King's rule of divine right, as vice-gerent for the Almighty, exercising the divinity's political omnipotence, and thus being the giver of all good, including the grant of commercial oppor- tunity and monopoly, and being incapable of doing any wrong. It necessarily followed from such premises that the State- religion be declared the fundamental and controlling part of the laws of England, so that any statute made against “any point of the Christian religion or what they thought was the Christian religion, was void.” From such considerations there grew up naturally laws against blasphemous and seditious utterances. That these found the tap-root of their justification in the union of Church and State is evident from such judicial unreason as the follow- ing : “To say that religion is a cheat, is to dissolve all those obligations whereby civil societies are preserved, and Christian- ity being part and parcel of the laws of England, therefore to reproach the Christian religion is to speak in subversion of the law.” This doctrine no longer obtains in England." Since man can impose no rightful limitations on the exer- cise of power by those who rule by divine right, it follows that under such a State all liberty is necessarily only liberty by permission, never liberty as an admitted natural right, and necessarily to decry religion is to inculcate treason against those whose right to rule is founded in that religion, and to attack a government conducted by divine right is in its turn irreligious and blasphemous. So, then, admitting the premises of their Church-State, the Star Chamber was quite logical when in de famosis libellis the court assumed “that words against the government amount to sedition; and that words against an archbishop are words against the government.” Necessarily, under such a State, those who opposed the existing restrictions upon speech and press were promoting irreligion, and therefore treason against both earthly and heavenly governments. In that controversy, the demand for unabridged, or even larger freedom of heretical religious utter- ance, necessarily included a demand for the right to advocate even treason, and of course logically must include all the lesser crimes. Although in America we boast of having outgrown at *Patterson’s “Liberty of Press and Speech,” p. 67, citing 10 St. Tr. 375. *Reg. v. Taylor, Ventris, 293 *See “Blasphemy and #lasphemous Libel,” by Sir Fitz James Stephens, Fortnightly Review, Mar., 1884. * Mence on Libel, p. 289. 6 least the avowed union of Church and State, we still retain that union in fact, by virtue of many repressive laws which Jhave no other foundation than the precedents of a Church- State, and the moral sentimentalizing associated with, or anchored in, religion. In studying the English precedents we must always bear in mind the before-mentioned essential differ- ence in our theories of government and the resultant difference between liberty merely by permission and liberty as a constitu- tionally guaranteed natural right. ON CONSTITUTIONAL DESIGN. Our constitutional guarantees upon this subject are both useless and meaningless except on the assumption that they were designed to repudiate the old theory that freedom of utterance is liberty by permission or grant, and were intended to establish intellectual liberty as a matter of constitutionally guaranteed unabridgable natural right. If it was not the design to change the English system of liberty by permission to one of liberty as a right, then there was no reason for any constitutional provision upon the subject. If the only purpose was to preclude the creation of an official censor, the easiest way would have been to have had the Con- stitution say, “No censor shall ever be appointed,” or, “No previous restraints shall be put upon speech or press.” Thus there would be no restriction upon other modes of abridging freedom of utterance. If the intention had been that a power should remain which, by subsequent punishment, would sup- press those discussions and ideas which were deemed contrary to the public welfare, then, again, there was no need for any constitutional provision upon the subject, because no other opinions than such as had been deemed contrary to the public welfare ever had been suppressed anywhere. If it is possible to assume that the purpose of amending our Federal Constitu- tion was to preclude Congress from punishing men for publish- ing ideas, believed by it to be conducive to welfare, then we might still expect that the most appropriate language would have been used. Then our Constitution might have read thus: “Congress shall make no law abridging freedom of speech or of the press, except in the interest of the public welfare.” But the insistence here is that such exception cannot properly be interpolated into our Constitution by judicial action. I utterly repudiate the dogmatic paradox of our courts, 7 which, while claiming to construe our Constitutions, declare that the words, the legislature “shall make no law abridging,” etc., mean that, in the alleged interest of the public welfare, it may enact any abridging laws it sees fit, if thereby no restraint is imposed prior to publication. It does seem to me that these few suggestions, together with a bit of critical thought on the words themselves, as used in our Constitutions, should be all that is necessary in justifica- tion of my contention. However, the abundance of judicial dogmatism to the contrary, and the general acquiescence there- in, persuade me that a more elaborate study of the historical factors is quite indispensable for most minds, even of the sort that have capacity for logical thinking upon this subject. THE METHOD OUTLINED. In the scientific aspect, our social and political institutions, like all other natural phenomena, are but special manifestations of the all-pervading law of evolution. With enlarged experi- ences, we change our conceptions of what is required by the natural law of our Social relations, and accordingly we change our verbal statements of law. It follows that the laws of a State always seem to be approaching, but never attain, perfec- tion. This seeming corresponds to the reality so long as the dominant conception of the law is nearing the truly scientific. By a scientific conception of the law, I mean one wherein the em- pirical generalizations have all been included in one rational generalization, which is the law upon the subject, because it is derived wholly from the nature of things; and, in every state of facts to which it can be applied, it conclusively determines the how and the why certain judgments must be so, and thus, the result always being derived exclusively by deductions from the ultimate rational generalization, which thus furnishes the only standard of judgment determining the decision in every particular case, that law must always be conformed to, irre- spective of the direct estimate of the beneficence of its results in any particular instance?” I venture the assertion that no one who has understandingly read the foregoing statement of the meaning of “Law,” and who has also read the judicial opinions as to the meaning of unabridged freedom of speech and of the press, will claim that any American court has ever attempted to declare the law of our Constitutions as to the freedom of utterance, because no *See, v. 42, Am. Law Review, p. 360. 8 court has ever attempted, even in a crude way, to furnish us with any comprehensive statement of the criteria for judging the constitutionality of enactments relating to speech or press. In England, where there is no constitutional limitation upon the power of Parliament to abridge freedom of utterance, it was said, after the passage of the Fox libel act, that “Freedom of discussion is little else than the right to write or say anything which a jury, consisting of twelve shopkeepers, think it expedient should be said or written.” That is freedom as a matter of expediency and by permission, the only kind of freedom of speech and press that has ever obtained in Eng- land or Russia. How useless then is our Constitution if, as the Courts quite uniformly assert, unabridged and unabridg- able freedom of discussion is the right to say whatever a legis- lature of mediocre attainments may think it expedient to permit to be said 2 If our constitutional guarantees declare and de- termine rights, then these cannot be destroyed by the arbitrary decree of the legislature, even though done in the alleged interest of the public welfare. If the Constitution is a law of right, then its declarations are always to be obeyed, even though the legislature and court concur in the belief that in a particular case the exercise of a constitutional right is against the public welfare. Neither can such belief invest them with the authority to amend the Constitution so as to make it read, “Congress shall make no law abridging freedom of speech or of the press except as to those ideas which it deems contrary to the public welfare.” If we are to preclude such dogmatic judicial amendments of our Constitutions, we must develop in the judicial mind, by the scientific method, a conception of constitutional law in accord with the conception of the legal scientist. The materials for a scientific interpretation of the Consti- tution are antecedent historical controversies, whose issues the Constitution was intended to decide. The method must be to trace the evolution of the idea of unabridged freedom of dis- cussion, from its inception as a mere personal protest and mere wish of the individual to be personally free from a partic- ular interference, through unnumbered empirical inductions to the impersonal recognition of a general principle underlying all such protests and demands, and determining the rightfulness of them. To achieve this we must study the historical contro- versies and the primitive crude demands for a lesser abridg- 10Dicey, “The Law of the Constitution,” p. 234. 9 ment of intellectual liberty, that we may discover the common elements in all these varying demands, and when we have thus discovered the elements of unification common to all these struggles for a lesser abridgment of intellectual liberty, have studied the various historical means of abridgment from which arose the controversies which were settled by our Constitutions, and have generalized the inhibition against all similar recur- rences, we may achieve a scientific conception of what is meant by an abridgment of freedom of speech. This will be a rational generalization giving us the criteria by which to judge whether or not a particular enactment is, or is not, a breach of the constitutional right of an unabridged freedom of utterance. THE DISPUTANTS CLASSIFIED. I cannot resist the feeling that it is an awful reflection upon the general and the judicial “intelligence” that any argu- ment should be deemed necessary to show the absurdity of the official “construction” of our Constitutions. Manifestly, it is urgently necessary, and it is to this end that we are to make a more precise analysis of the historical controversy which, in America, culminated in the adoption of our constitutional guarantees for unabridged freedom of speech and of the press. In making our analysis of the historical contentions, we must keep in mind at least three main classes of disputants. The first and most popular class consisted of those emi- nently respectable and official persons who asserted, not only the existence of a proper governmental authority to abridge in every manner the intellectual liberty of the citizen, but who also defended every existing method by which the power was being exercised. This class was the only one fortified by official justifications and judicial definitions of the pre-revolutionary period. To the second class belonged those conservative reformers who did not question the existence of a power to control legally the intellectual food-supply of the populace, but who did question some particular manner of its exercise. These usually believed in a larger liberty of speech and press, but did not demand that it be wholly unabridged, and usually their arguments were directed only to the inexpediency of some particular abridgment and not toward the defense of liberty as an unabridgable natural right. Among these could be found persons who demanded larger liberty for the promotion of 10 their own heresies, but justified the punishment of other her- etics; there were those who demanded liberty for the discussion of religion, but hastened to out-Herod Herod in their justifica- tion of the punishment of the psychologic crime of verbal treason. Others, like Erskine, demanded a larger liberty for the criticism of government, but hastened to give assurance of their entire orthodoxy by joining in the clamor for the punish- ment of religious heretics. Should we mistake any of these disputants as the defenders of unabridged freedom of speech and press, and adopt their definitions of liberty, as a means of Constitutional construction, we should of course be led far astray and reduce our constitutional right to unabridged freedom to a limited liberty by permission. The third class of controversialists was composed of those few who denied the existence of any rightful authority for the punishment of any mere psychologic crimes, and who therefore demanded the establishment and maintenance of unabridged liberty of utterance. It was the contention of these persons which was adopted into our Constitutions, and it is their state- ment of the meaning of “freedom of speech” which should be made the basis for constitutional construction, and not the judicial precedents of the Star Chamber, expressing the Eng- lish practise from the viewpoint of the Church-State, which viewpoint was repudiated by our American States and which precedents were overruled by our American Constitutions. Unfortunately, these precedents are still often followed by our American Courts, whose judges are supposed to be the con- servators, but often act as the destroyers, of our liberty, especially when unpopular and disapproved utterances are in- volved. The varying conceptions of the limits of freedom of utter- ance, as advocated by these classes of controversialists, will now be exemplified by illustrative quotations, that we may show what was meant by an unabridged liberty of utterance, by those whose views were incorporated in our Constitutions. LICENSING THE PRINTER. The press was introduced into England by Henry VII. From this fact, together with the prevailing opinion that the whole matter of freedom of speech was one of permission, or gift from the Sovereign, nothing was more natural than that Edward the VI. should by patent appoint a printer, who was * 11 to print and sell all Latin, Greek, and Hebrew books, as well as all others that might be commanded, and penalties were denounced for infringing his monopoly. Subsequently, the number of licensed printers was enlarged, but for a consider- able time it was limited.” In this form of license, the letter of the law made no discrimination against a book according to. the sentiments expressed. The license seems rather to have been a business monopoly given to some court favorite, and a matter of confidence in the printer, as one having the discretion to publish nothing inimical to the grantors of his special privilege. Of course, this public printer did not publish for future reference any of the arguments against his monopoly. Could we now look back to analyze the opposition to this first form of licensing, we would seek for two possible explana- tions of it. According to one, freedom of the press might mean only the commercial freedom to use the press as a tool of trade, in commercial competition with the Crown-mon– opolists, and a modern judge, adopting that conception as a basis for constitutional construction, might uphold a law cre- ating a censorship over only the character of the printed matter, and not directly and immediately affecting the equality of commercial opportunity in the use of the printing press as an instrument of commerce. According to this first point of view, the abolition of this monopoly was the chief, or only, end in view, and this object would not be in the least interfered. with by a new form of censorship directed against particular psychologic tendencies of opinions, which would leave in- tellectual liberty just as much abridged as before. The other view would be that the opposition to licensing of the printer was based principally upon the demand for a larger intellectual liberty, by equalizing the opportunity of all for using the press as an extended form of speech. In this second view, the mere abolition of the license for printers” monopoly is not an end in itself, but a mere means to the endſ of increasing intellectual liberty and opportunity, a viewpoint quite constantly ignored in our judicial utterances upon this subject. It is unthinkably paradoxical that the few friends. of freedom of speech and of the press who existed at that time should have had no interest in the enlargement of in- tellectual liberty, and were interested only in the enlarged. opportunity for the use of the press as a tool of trade. Of course this view, that enlargement of intellectual op— *Paterson’s “Liberty of Press,” p. 44. 12 portunity was the chief end sought, is confirmed by the related controversial literature of approximately that time. As I write this, I have open before me a volume in which are reprinted the tracts on “Liberty of Conscience” which had been published prior to 1661. These express “the first articulations of infant liberty.” The arguments are in the main very crude, as arguments for liberty. They may be clearly divided into a few general classes: First, “we dissenters are right, therefore ought to be tolerated.” Second, “the Bible teaches toleration, therefore we should be tolerated.” Third, “it is not in the power of man to believe as he wills, but he believes as he must, and he therefore should not be punished for expressing con- victions he cannot escape.” This last is a good argument against the injustice of punishing “dangerous” opinions, even yet. Amid much crude thinking, there are some few very clear perceptions, excluding all mere psychological crimes from the legitimate province of government. To this end, Luther was quoted and his thought is several times restated by dif- ferent authors. Luther’s words are these: “The laws of civil government extend no further than over the body and goods, and that which is external: For over the Soul, [mind] God will not suffer man to rule.” Such were the contentions made in behalf of liberty of speech, or, “the liberty of prophesying,” as it was then often called. One would look in vain through this volume of early tracts for any suggestion that the larger liberty contended for, or an unabridged freedom of discussion, consisted only in the absence of a prior censorship. I do not recall even a single mention of a previous censorship as the essence of the evil, nor mere commercial opportunity to use the press as a tool of trade, as an end to be achieved. Always the demand was for, and, indeed, the arguments were all in furtherance of, a larger intellectual liberty, and sometimes demanded an unabridged liberty of utterance, by excluding all psychological offenses from the jurisdiction of the criminal law. - These early tracts, so far as they go, are a vindication of the contention, stated at the head of this essay, as that relates to the period prior to 1661. It is utterly absurd for our courts to intimate, as they do, that the real friends of unabridged intellectual opportunity were ever concerned only with the mere time or manner (rather than the substance) of the abridgment of liberty. The friends of freedom never sought 13 the abolition of previous restraint in favor of subsequent punishment, as an end in itself, but were seeking to enlarge intellectual opportunity as against abridgment either by prior restraint or subsequent punishment. No doubt it was in this early protest against a licensed printer that the phrase “Freedom of the Press” came into use, for here only does it have a literal signification. When the press was made free, as an instrument of trade, the shifty tyrant saw to it that no enlargement of intellectual opportunity resulted. USURPATION BY THE “STAR CHAMBER.” Prior to 1637 there seems to have been no criminal penalties inflicted by the English secular courts, for mere psychological offenses, such as the expression of unpopular opinions. “The Common Law took cognizance of no injuries but such as affected persons or property.” In 1637 the Star Chamber, which never hesitated to assume the most preposterous powers, usurped the legislative function of penalizing libel, by its decree regulating the press.” This Judicial lawlessness, in usurping the power to punish mere psychologic crimes under- er post facto criteria of guilt, of course provoked criticism from those who loved liberty and knew something of its nature, and no doubt it also secured for “the watchtower of the King” the hearty approval of all tyrants, for the protection of whose reputation and prerogatives this abridgment of free- dom of utterance was inaugurated. This usurped censorship and the accompanying ear post facto penalization of mere- psychologic crimes, were among the last and most hideous of the acts of this infamous “Judicial” body, for the Star Cham- ber was abolished in 1640. No doubt the hostility excited by its outrageous creation and enforcement of laws against mere verbal crimes contributed much towards the downfall, but tyranny did not die with the institution that invented this special means to its end. The co-tyrants of the Star Chamber Court and their successors, prompted by the same inordinate. lust for power and preferring to be relieved of the occasion for defending their official conduct, have continued, with slight modifications and very brief cessations, to this very day to act. upon the precedents of the abhorred Star Chamber. Parlia- mentary enactment along similar lines soon took the place of Star Chamber decrees, and vagueness in the legislative defini- **Mence on Libel, p. 333. *Patterson on “Liberty of Press and Speech,” 45; Mence, “Law of Libel,” 1. enc Chapt. 9, (1824); “The Freedom of Speech and Writing,” pp. 47, 49, 99. (Lond., 766). - 1766 14 tion of criminal libel left quite unimpaired the power for an ea post facto creation of the criteria of guilt. So it comes to pass that, while maintaining some of the outward seemings of law, the fundamental evils of judicial despotism still exist, even in those countries whose inhabitants are most vociferous in their stupid boast over a purely imaginary liberty. How- ever, let it be said, that the savagery of the penalties has been a little abated, even though on the whole intellectual liberty has received no substantial enlargement. What has been gained as to some subjects has been lost as to others. Some comparison as to this would be interesting but is not within the Scope of this essay. «» LICENSING THE BOOK. The licensing of one printer was succeeded by the licensing of many and later by the abolition of this system in its entirety, allowing all alike to use the printing press as an instrument of commerce, but maintaining inequalities as to its use in the distribution of ideas. Here I have reference to those various licensing acts, expiring in 1694, which succeeded to the Star Chamber decrees, and by which a censor authorized particular books to be printed, and all publications not so authorized. were penalized. It was against this censorship that Milton directed his immortal essay, “Areopagitica.” Here, again, we must seek an answer to the same old question, Is it true, as our courts generally assert, that Milton and others who opposed these licensing acts were concerned only with the manner and not with the substance of this abridg- ment of freedom of the press? Is it true, as our courts usually imply, that the opponents of these licensing acts demanded only the abolition of the censor and previous restraint, and were quite willing to admit a power to punish subsequent to publication all those opinions which formerly had been denied the necessary license for getting into print? In Milton's time, one might print unpopular opinions, which the licenser had disapproved, and be punished if caught. This the Supreme Court of the United States says is an abridgment of freedom of the press. However, if there is no previous censorship, and although you receive the same penalty, merely for publish- ing the same book, because a legislature or jury deem it contrary to the public welfare, then unabridged liberty of the press is thereby preserved, for “the greatest judicial tribunal 15 on earth” has said that a constitutionally guaranteed natural right to unabridged freedom of press calls for the cessation of “all such previous restraints as had been practised by other governments, and [but] does not prevent the subsequent pun- ishment of such [publications] as may be deemed against the public welfare.” In other words, our courts declare that our constitutional right to unabridged freedom of utterance deals only with the manner and time of the abridgment, or the tribunal which inflicts it, and has nothing to do with unabridged intellectual opportunity to utter, to hear, and to read. Be it remembered, however, that no such distinction in favor of any ex post facto censorship can be deduced from the very words of our Con- stitutions, nor from the historical controversy culminating in their adoption, and, therefore, these exceptions to unabridged freedom are a matter of judicial creation—that is, of judicial constitutional amendment. IN DEFENSE OF THE CENSORSHIP. Then, as now, the advocates for the suppression of un- popular opinions refused to see that to admit the existence of the power to suppress any opinion, is, in the long run, more destructive to human well-being than the ideas against which they would have the power exercised. Then, as now, the alleged immediate public welfare was the justification of every form of censorship, and some dangerous “tendency,” only speculatively ascertained and usually so in a feverishly appre- hensive imagination, was always the test of guilt. “The most tyrannical and the most absolute governments speak a kind parental language to the abject wretches who groan under their crushing and humiliating weight.” To make this clear, it is necessary only to quote a few passages from a publication dated A. D., 1680, and written in defense of the abridgments of freedom of speech and press. Sir Robert L’Estrange in, “A Seasonable Memorial in some Historical Notes upon the Liber- ties of the Press and Pulpit,” quotes Calvin as saying: “There are two sorts of seditious men, and against both these must the sword be drawn; for they oppose the King and God him- self.” He then exhibits the evolution of dangerous tendencies by these words: “First they find out corruptions in the Gov- ernment, as a matter of grievance, which they expose to the people. Secondly, they petition for Redress of those Griev- *Erskine in defense of Carnan. 16 ances, still asking more and more, till something is denied them. And then, Thirdly, they take the power into their own hands of Relieving themselves, but with Oaths and protestations that they act only for the Common Good of King and Kingdom. From the pretense of defending the Government they proceed to the Reforming of it; which reformation proves in the end to be a Final Dissolution of the order both of Church and State. * * * * Their consciences widened with their interest. * * * * First, they fell upon the King's Reputation; they in- vaded his authority in the next place; after that they assaulted his Person, seized his Revenue; and in the conclusion most impiously took away his Sacred Life. * * * * The Transition is so natural from Popular Petition to a Tumult, that the one is but a Hot Fit of the other; and little more than a more earnest way of petitioning. * * * * They Preach the People into murther, sacrilege, and Rebellion; they pursue a most gracious Prince to the scaffold; they animate the Regicides, calling that Execrable villainy an act of Public Justice, and entitling the oly Ghost to Treason.” This argument, backed by the historical fact, is unanswer- le to the point that to permit freedom of criticism of Govern- ent and its officials, and to allow the presentation of petitions fºr the redress of grievances, is to permit that which tends tº promote actual treason and rebellion. It follows that those who were demanding the opportunity to express their senti- ments in criticism of official conduct were in effect demanding tle right verbally to promote treason with impunity, because that was the demonstrated tendency of such utterances. That is what unabridged freedom of speech and of the press meant to its advocates, and our constitutional guarantee for an un- abridged freedom of utterance was a final decision in favor of that view and against all mere psychologic crimes, including even verbal “treason.” THE DEFENSE OF FREEDOM, BY MILTON. In further justification of the contention that unabridged freedom of utterance as a matter of right precludes the Sup- pression of opinions having a “dangerous” tendency, either by direct prior restraint or subsequent punishment—the fear of which always operates as a prior restraint—we should contrast the foregoing argument for restricting speech with the historic argument for freedom made in Milton’s “Areo- 15In addition to “A Seasonable Memorial,” see, for similar argument, “A Discourse of Ecclesiastical Politic, wherein the Mischiefs and Inconveniences of Toleration are Represented,” London, 70 17 pagitica.” Here we can quote only a few paragraphs tending to show what freedom of speech meant to its friends. Not a word can be found to suggest ear post facto punishment as a substitute for previous restraint. Milton writes: “Till then, books were ever as freely ad- mitted into the world as any other birth; the issue of the brain was no more stifled than the issue of the womb. * * * * “To the pure all things are pure,” not only meats and drinks, but all kinds of knowledge, whether of good or evil; the knowledge cannot defile, nor consequently the books, if the will and conscience be not defiled. For books are as meats and viands are, some of good and some of evil substance; and yet God in that unapocryphal vision said, without exception, “Rise, Peter, kill and eat,” leaving the choice to man's discretion. Wholesome meats to a vitiated stomach differ little or nothing from unwholesome, and best books to a naughty mind are not unapplicable to occasions of evil. Bad meats will scarce breed good nourishment in the healthiest concoction; but herein the difference is of bad books, that they to a discreet and judicious reader serve in many respects to discover, to confute, to forewarn, and to illustrate. * * * * All opinions, yea, errors known, read and collated, are of main service and assistan toward the speedy ascertainment of what is truest. * * * * Fqr those actions, which enter into a man rather than issue out 4f him and therefore defile not, God uses not to captivate undºr a perpetual childhood of prescription, but trusts him with the gift of reason to be his own chooser. * * * * “I cannot praise a fugitive and cloistered virtue, unexº. cised and unbreathed, that never sallies out and sees her adversary, but slinks out of the race, where that immortal garland is to be run for, not without dust and heat. Assuredly we bring not innocence into the world, we bring impurity much rather; that which purifies us is trial, and trial is by what is contrary. That virtue which is but a youngling in the con- templation of evil, and knows not the utmost that vice promises to her followers, and rejects it, is but a blank virtue, not a pure; her whiteness is but an excremental whiteness. * * * * “Since, therefore, the knowledge and survey of vice is in this world so necessary to the constituting of human virtue, and the scanning of error to the confirmation of truth, how can we more safely, and with less danger, scout into the regions of sin and falsity, than by reading all manner of tractates, and 18 hearing all manner of reason? " *** Truth and understanding are not such wares as to be monopolized and traded in by tickets and statutes and standards. * * * * Give me the liberty to know, to utter, and to argue freely according to conscience, above all [other] liberties. “Though ye take from a covetous man all his treasure, he has yet one jewel left; ye cannot bereave him of his covetous- ness. Banish all objects of lust, shut up all youth into the severest discipline that can be exercised in any hermitage, ye cannot make them chaste that came not hither so.” And yet Milton, though he made an unanswerable argument for a totally unabridged freedom of utterance, could not get wholly beyond all his religious prejudices, and so, although the argument made no provision for it, he found it necessary dog- matically to provide for one exception. “I mean not tolerated Popery and open superstition, which, as it extirpates all re- ligious and civil supremacies, so itself should be extirpated.” While Milton thus fell short of an unlimited intellectual toler- ation he yet furnished an immortal statement of reasons to guide us to an unabridged freedom of utterance, and to the invalidating of his own exception thereto. SPINOZA. To this same period belong the writings of Spinoza. As is to be expected, his viewpoint is different from the others of his time. - He concludes: “We have shown already that no man's mind can possibly lie wholly at the disposition of another, for no one can willingly transfer his natural right of free reason and free judgment, or be compelled to do so. For this reason the government which attempts to control minds is accounted tyrannical, and it is considered an abuse of sovereignty, and a usurption of the rights of subjects, to seek to prescribe what shall be accepted as true, or rejected as false, or what opinions shall actuate men in their worship of God. All these questions fall within a man's natural right, which he cannot abdicate even with his own consent. * * * * The individual justly cedes the right of free action, though not of free reason and judg- ment. No one can act against the authorities without danger to the State, though his feelings and judgment be at variance therewith. He may even speak against them, provided that he does so from rational conviction, not from fraud, anger, 19 or hatred, and provided that he does not attempt to introduce any change on his private authority. * * * * Thus we see how an individual may declare and teach what he believes, without injury to the authority of his rulers, or to the public peace; namely, by leaving in their hands the entire power of legis- lation as it affects action; and by doing nothing against their laws though he be compelled often to act in contradiction to what he believes, and openly feels to be best. From the funda– mental notions of a State, we have discovered how a man may exercise free judgment without detriment to the supreme power; from the same premises we can no less easily determine what opinions would be seditious. Evidently those which by their very nature nullify the compact by which the right of free action is ceded. * * * * - “If we hold to the principle that a man's loyalty to the State should be judged, like his loyalty to God, from his actions only—namely from his charity towards his neighbors—we cannot doubt that the best government will allow freedom of philosophical speculation, no less than of religious belief. I confess that from such freedom inconveniences may sometimes arise, but was any question ever settled so wisely that no abuses could possibly spring therefrom ? He who seeks to regulate everything by law is more likely to arouse vices than to reform them.” From these quotations it appears that Spinoza did not believe in an unabridged freedom of utterance. His belief in the psychologic crime of a mere verbal treason, though limited within unusually narrow range, followed logically from his erroneous conception of the sphere of government. Of this he said: “The rights of the sovereign are limited by his power.” Since in his theory of government sovereign rights arise out of a cession of freedom of action by the citizen, the opinion which nullified that hypothetical compact could be called treason so long as the sovereign had the power to suppress it as such. It is quite probable, and at least consistent with his theory, that this exception may have been made by Spinoza as a condition of securing tolerance for the rest of the argu- ment in favor of free speech. - However that may be, as Spinoza repudiated the exception to unabridged freedom of utterance reserved by Milton, so the latter annihilated the one exception made by Spinoza. The premises of each exception were specifically repudiated by the 20 American Declaration of Independence and American Consti- tutions, and hence these exceptions to unabridged liberty of utterance also must fall. However, the matter that I now wish specially to emphasize is this: The very nature of these argu- ments for larger freedom is such as utterly to destroy our judical assumption that the friends of unabridged freedom of utterance, who framed our Constitutional Guarantees, meant only to provide for ea post facto punishment as a substitute for previous restraint. MONTESQUIEU. Some years after the death of Milton came the birth of Montesquieu, who “commanded the future from his study more than Napoleon from his throne,” and whose book on “The Spirit of the Laws” “probably has done as much to remodel the world as any product of the eighteenth century, which burned so many forests and sowed so many fields.” In the opinion of Justice O. W. Holmes, “Montesquieu had a possibly exaggerated belief in the power of legislation,” which alone would not predispose him against censorship. The frequent reference to him in The Federalist and other discussions of the revolutionary period, as well as our Constitu- tions themselves, all show how the thought provoked by his book helped to shape our Institutions. This makes it all the more important to ascertain his views upon the province of the State in relation to the liberty of speech and press, because of their quite direct bearing upon the historical interpretation of our Constitution. - On the subject of religion, he emphasizes the essential difference between human and divine laws, and argues reserv- edly for general toleration of all religion, and concludes: “When the legislator has believed it a duty to permit the exercise of many religions it is necessary that he should enforce also a toleration among these religions themselves. * * * * Penal laws ought to be avoided in respect to religion.” In the matter of verbal treason, Montesquieu seems very exact in his statements and comprehensive in his thought. Only a few lines will need quoting. He says: “Nothing renders the crime of high treason more arbitrary than declaring people guilty of it of indiscreet speeches. * * * * Words do not constitute an overt act; they remain only an idea. When considered by themselves, they have generally no determinate 21 signification, for this depends on the tone in which they are uttered. * * * * Since there can be nothing so equivocal and ambiguous as all this, how is it possible to convert it into a crime of high treason? Wherever this law is established, there is an end not only of liberty, but even of its very shadow. * * * * “Overt acts do not happen every day; they are exposed to the naked eye of the public, and a false charge with regard to matters of fact may be easily detected. Words carried into action assume the nature of that action. Thus a man who goes into a public market-place to incite the subject to revolt incurs the guilt of high treason, because the words are joined to the action, and partake of its nature. It is not the words that are punished but an action in which words are employed. They do not become criminal but when they are annered to a criminal action; everything is confounded if words are con- strued into capital crime, instead of considering them only as a mark of that crime.” In this evolution to a clearer conception of the issues and the more exact statement of the claims of contending parties, we have now reached the place where unabridged intellectual liberty is defined by excluding from the category of crime every offense founded upon speech, merely as such. BLACKSTONE AND HIS CRITICS. Blackstone was the victim of most of the popular super- stitions of his time, from witchcraft down. Of course he indorsed the current theory of government and consequently the current abridgments of freedom of speech and press. He had no desire or intention to vindicate man's natural right to such liberties unabridged, but approved and made declara- tions of the laws in operation, as he found them. Thus he wrote: “Everything is now as it should be with respect to the spiritual cognizance, and spirtual punishment of heresy; unless perhaps that the crime ought to be more strictly defined, |and no persecution permitted, even in the ecclesiastical courts, till the tenets in question are by proper authority previous declared to be heretical. Under these restrictions, it seems necessary for the support of the national religion that the officers of the church should have power to censure heretics, yet not to harrass with temporal penalties, much less to exterminate or destroy them.” These spiritual censures and excommunication involved *Vol. I., p. 233, Aldine Edition. 17Vol. 4 Commentaries, p. 49. 2 2 indirect penalties, such as incapacity for “suing an action, being witnesses, making a will, receiving a legacy,” etc., and these indirect consequences it would seem that Blackstone approved. Again he writes: “The [some not unabridged] liberty of the press is indeed essential to the nature of a free state; but this consists in laying no previous restraints upon publications, and not in freedom from censure for criminal matter when published. * * * * To subject the press to the restrictive power of a licenser, as was formerly done, * * * * is to subject all freedom of sentiment to the prejudices of one man, and make him the arbitrary and infallible judge of all controverted points in learning, religion, and government. But to punish, as the law does at present, any dangerous or offensive writings which, when published, shall on a fair and unpartial trial be adjudged of a pernicious tendency, is necessary for the preservation of Deace and good order, of government and religion, the only solid foundations of civil liberty.” It should be apparent from the mere reading that Black- stone was defending and describing only such limited liberty by permission as was then enjoyed in England, and never in- tended either to define or defend unabridged freedom of dis- cussion, as that was contended for by his opponents, whose views, and not Blackstone's, were adopted into our Constitu- tions. For this reason, one may well be surprised to find the foregoing statement from Blackstone quoted by American courts as an authority on the meaning of unabridged freedom of utterance, which he never mentions. One of Blackstone's critics, whose book went through more than one edition and of whom it is said,” “he induced the learned commentator [Blackstone] to alter some positions in the subsequent edition of his valuable work,” had this to say as to the meaning of unabridged freedom of speech: “For, though calumny and slander, when affecting our fellow men, are punishable by law ; for this plain reason, because an injury is done, and a damage sustained, and a repara- tion therefore due to the injured party; yet, this reason cannot hold where God and the Redeemer are concerned; who can sustain no injury from low malice and scurrilous invective; nor can any reparation be made to them by temporal penalties; for these can work no conviction or repentance in the mind of the offender; and if he continue impenitent and incorrigible, *Vol. 4 Blackstone’s Commentaries, p. 151. 19Allibone’s “Dictionary of Authors.” 23 he will receive his condign punishment in the day of final retribution. Affronting Christianity, therefore, does not come under the magistrate's cognizance, in this particular view, as it implies an offense against God and Christ.” Here is again a clear recognition and plain statement which, like Montes- quieu's, demands that actual and material injury shall be the basis of prosecution and not mere speculation about psychologic tendencies. g MANSFIELD AND KENYON. Some of our courts, in addition to Blackstone, cite Lords Mansfield and Kenyon, as authorities on the meaning of un- abridged freedom of utterance as though their views had been adopted into our Constitutions. Concerning these opinions, Sir James Fitz James Stephens (after quoting the differing definitions of Lords Mansfield and Kenyon as showing what was the official conception of freedom of the press) says: “Each definition was in a legal point of view complete and accurate, but what the public at large understood by the ex- pression was something altogether different—namely the right of unrestricted discussion of public affairs.” In other words, the judicial conception of free speech was an abridged free speech, and the popular demand was for an tunabridged free speech. It should need no argument to prove that the latter, and not the former, was intended to be adopted into American Constitutions, and to me it is difficult to account for the contrary opinion, often expressed by our courts, which quite uniformly ignore even the existence of the pre-revolu- tionary contention against the English official conception as expressed by the Star Chamber, the English Parliament, Black- stone, Mansfield, or Kenyon. BISHOP HORSLEY, REV. ROBERT HALL, AND THOMAS JEFFERSON. The issue between “freedom of the press” in the official English sense, on the one side, and unabridged freedom of utterance on the other, was made clear in another English controversy following so closely upon the heels of our adoption of the first amendment as to be fairly considered an English aftermath of that agitation and of the American Revolution. Bishop Horsley, on January 30, 1793, delivered a sermon before the House of Lords, wherein he indulged in a severe censure of that “Freedom of dispute” on matters of “such *Furneaux’s “Letters on Toleration,” pp. 70-71, Second Edition. *Vol. 2 “Crim. Law of Eng.,” p. 349. 24 high importance as the origin of government and the authority of sovereigns,” in which he laments that it has been the “folly of this country for several years past” to indulge. Of the divine right of Kings he declared: “It is a right which in no country can be denied, without the highest of all treason. The denial of it were treason against the paramount authority of God.” These premises had recently been repudiated by our Declaration of Independence, by the American Constitutions, and by the friends of unabridged freedom of utterance every- where. One of the conspicuous critics of Bishop Horsley was the Rev. Robert Hall. In arguing against the rightfulness of punishing mere psychologic crimes, he laid down the limits of governmental action which must be adhered to if freedom of speech is to remain an unabridged right, instead of mere limited liberty by permission. He said: “The law hath amply provided against overt acts of sedition and disorder, and to suppress mere opinions by any other method than reasoning and argument is the hight of tyranny. Freedom of thought being intimately connected with the happiness and dignity of man in every stage of his being, is of so much more importance than the preservation of any Constitution, that to infringe the former under pretense of supporting the latter, is to sacrifice the means to the end.” In his discourse, this Reverend author often emphasizes the difference between ideas and overt acts and makes plain. over and over that in his view actual injury should be the criteria of guilt, and not mere apprehension as to a psychologic tendency. Our constitutional definition of Treason and the guarantees of the right to carry arms, of “due process of law,” and of unabridged freedom of utterance, show that it was such views as Milton argued for, and as Montesquieu and the Rev. Robert Hall expressed, and not the views of Blackstone, Mansfield, Kenyon, or Bishop Horsley, that our Constitutions sought effectually to perpetuate. Both before and after these utterances by the Rev. Robert Hall there was most eminent American authority for the same interpretation of the meaning of a “free press.” Thomas Jefferson is popularly supposed to have had much to do with framing the Declaration of Independence and shaping our American institutions. He was a dominant figure in Virginia politics for many years. Those who have familiarized them- 22*An Apology for Freedom of the Press,” p. 18. 25 selves with the religious views of Jefferson,” will not doubt that he encouraged the passage of the Act of the State of Virginia establishing religious freedom. Although drafted with a view only to theological subjects, it contains a summary of incontrovertible reasoning in favor of the general liberty of inquiry and a clear statement as to where the jurisdiction of the state rightfully may be invoked without abridging intellectual liberty. The Virginia enactment says: “To suffer the Civil Magistrate to intrude his power into the field of Opinion, or to restrain the profession or propagation of principles on sup- position of their ill tendency, is a dangerous fallacy, which at once destroys all liberty, because he, being of course judge of that tendency, will make his opinions the rule of judgment, and approve or condemn the sentiments of others only as they shall square with or differ from his own. It is time enough for the rightful purposes of Civil Government for its officers to interfere when principles break out into overt acts against peace and good order.”” The Virginia declaration was made in 1786, several years before the adoption of the first amendment to the Federal Constitution. The Virginia enactment makes it clear that in their opinion the State has no rightful authprity over opinion of any sort, and should not be suffered to interfere until ACTUAL injury has resulted. It was that conception of “freedom of the press” which America adopted, and not the English tyrants’ conception, to which it was opposed, and which originated in the odious Star Chamber, found a palatable justification in Blackstone and the English Judicial decisions, and an official re-echo in American Courts, engaged in ex- plaining away our constitutional guarantee for an unabridged freedom of utterance. When the Federalist party was defeated because of its enactment of the Alien and Sedition Law, and Thomas Jef- ferson became President of the United States, he proceeded to pardon every man who had been convicted under this infamous statute. That the penalized utterances tended to sedition made no difference to him, which indicates that he too indorsed the views of Montesquieu, the Rev. Robert Hall, and the quoted enactment of the Virginia Legislature, as being the correct interpretation of the words “unabridged freedom of speech and of the press.” Jefferson’s own statement as to his conduct is as follows: *See, “Six Historic Americans.” *Requoted from Wortman's, “Liberty of the Press,” p. 173. 26 “I discharged every person under punishment or prosecution under the sedition law, because I considered and now consider that law to be a nullity, as absolute and as palpable as if Congress had ordered us to fall down and worship a golden image; and that it was as much my duty to arrest its progress in every stage as it would have been to have rescued from the fiery furnace those who should have been cast into it for refusing to worship the image. It was accordingly done in every instance, without asking what the offenders had done, or against whom they had offended, but whether the pains they were suffering were inflicted under the pretended sedition law. It was certainly possible that my motives in contributing to the relief of Callandar, and in liberating sufferers under the Sedition law, might have been to protect, reward, and encourage slander; but they may also have been those which inspire Odinary charities to objects of distress, meritorious or not—or, the obligation of an oath ‘to protect the Constitution,’ violated by an authorized act of Congress.” This action on the part of President Jefferson was con- sistent with the issue upon which he was elected, and was required by his own conception of what was meant by an unabridged “Freedom of Speech and of the Press” as applied to verbal treason. His views are thus expressed in his first inaugural address: “If there be any among us who would wish to dissolve this Union or to change its republican form, let them stand undisturbed as monuments of the safety with which error of opinion may be tolerated where reason is left free to combat it.” These discussions again proclaim the historic view that wnabridged freedom of utterance means that every man may say with impunity whatever he pleases, being held responsible and punishable only for actual resultant injury, that being the only abuse of such freedom which can be penalized. TAXES ON KNOWLEDGE. Another form of impairing natural intellectual opportunity, and therefore an abridgment of freedom of the press, was taxes upon knowledge. In America, where to a very large extent we have Government by newspapers, it seems unlikely that such taxes will ever again become a subject of controversy. However, we must briefly consider the matter as an historical See, 4 Jefferson's Complete Works, 556, quoted in Booth’s v. Rycroft, 25 3 Wisconsin 183. 27 issue so that our final generalization as to unabridged freedom of the press may negative also this form of abridgment. George Jacob Holyoake has briefly described the conditions against which he, and other friends of intellectual freedom before him, waged such strenuous battle. These are his words: “Yet every newspaper proprietor was formerly treated as a blasphemer and a writer of sedition, and compelled to give substantial securities against the exercise of his infamous tendencies; every paper-maker was regarded as a thief, and the officers of the Excise dogged every step of his business with hampering, exacting, and humiliating suspicion. Every reader found with an unstamped paper in his possession was liable to a fine of £20. When the writer of this published the ‘War Chronicles' and War Fly Sheets, the Inland Revenue Office bought six copies as soon as each number was out; thus he incurred fines of £120 before breakfast, and when the last warrant was issued against him by the Court of Exchequer he was indebted to the Crown £600,000. Besides, he had issued an average of 2,000 copies of The Reasoner for twelve years, incurring fines of £40,000 a week, which amounted to a considerable sum in twelve years. He who published a paper, containing news, without a stamp, was also liable to have all his presses broken up, all his stock confiscated, him- self, and all persons in his house, imprisoned, as had been done again and again to others within the writer’s knowledge. Neither cheap newspapers nor cheap books could exist while these perils were possible.” In his “History of the Taxes on Knowledge,” Collet in- forms us that “The History of the Taxes upon Knowledge begins with their imposition (1711) in the reign of Queen Anne. The battle against the Press had, indeed, begun before that date.” The year 1855 marked the final repeal of the last of these English stamp acts, and those requiring bonds, etc., from publishers. Those who are interested in this par- ticular battle for larger freedom of the press are referred to Mr. Collet's interesting account.” In all these discussions, it is apparent that the main purpose was not to favor one system of raising revenue as against Some other system, but to in- crease the intellectual opportunities of all, by removing all State-created impediments to the greatest natural freedom for the interchange of ideas. *Taxes on Knowledge, the story of their Origin and Repeal,” Lond., 1899; see also Patterson on “Liberty of Press and Speech,” p. 57. 28 * THE CENSORSHIP OF MAILS. We next consider the method of creating inequalities in intellectual opportunities, and of abridging them, by means of a State-created postal censorship, which is fast becoming an important issue in the contest for intellectual freedom in America. The American postal censorship over mail matter began in 1873, when a law was passed, without debate, making “obscene” matter unmailable. I am informed that the original draft of this bill included “blasphemy” in the unmailable list, thus again emphasizing the origin in religious intolerance, and pointing to the ultimate purpose of those who are so per- sistently advocating and securing extensions of our postal censorship. This censorship has already been extended, so that now even political literatue, which in European monarchies is spread without hindrance, has been excluded from Amer- ican mails and penalized. The statutes heretofore have only provided ea post facto punishment for use of the mails; they did not authorize the postal authorities to prevent the trans- mission of prohibited matter. In several Congresses, the Postal Department asked an amendment to the laws such as would give the postmaster power to refuse transmission to forbidden matter. The amendment never was passed. Not abashed by the refusal of the Congress to confer the power, the authorities proceeded to usurp it, under the usual guise of a new “construction” of existing statutes. This usurped power, having been calmly acquiesced in by the public, soon received judicial confirmation and gradually has been extended, so that it now assumes to override the judical department by excluding from the mails publications which the courts have decided are mailable, and has excluded matter without the warrant of any statute, relying upon the absence of a remedy for the afflicted persons. Under our modern conditions of living, with their cheap printing and postal facilities, to be denied the use of the mails for the spread of one's ideas creates a relatively greater in- equality and abridgment of intellectual opportunity than ever was created by any prior form of censorship. Since private competition with our public mail service is prohibited by law, and since in these times of a cheap periodical press no one can hope ever to attain a favorable public opinion, in competition with his intellectual opponents, except by publication through 29 the mails, therefore it follows that a postal censorship is the most effective possible abridgment of freedom of the press. Moreover, since the postal authorities now exercise a usurped censorhip over postal matter prior to publication through the mails, we have quite effectively, though unconsciously, re- establihed in some fields of thought a “previous censorship,” substantially like that against which Milton wrote nearly 300 years ago. If this previous censorship is upheld, in spite of our Constitutions and judicial dictums against the legal possibility of a “previous censorship,” then its spread into other, and finally all, fields of thought is only a matter of time. Under present conditions, the difference between a censorship previous to printing and one after printing but previous to publication by mail, is one of no practical import, because a book that cannot get publicity by mail might as well never be printed, since without facilities for distribution by post, interstate com- merce, or private competitors of the postal system, the securing of readers is practically impossible. Furthermore, a censorship after printing, and before publication by mail, is worse than one before printing, because it inflicts the needless loss of the cost of printing. The infamous Licensing Act of England, against which Milton wrote, was passed September 20, 1649, and provided, among its pernicious abridgments of freedom of the press, that “no person whatever should presume to send by the post, carriers, or otherwise, or endeavor to dispense, any unlicensed book,” etc., on penalty of forfeiture, fine,and imprisonment. As if to add insult to injury, every printer was required to give a bond to “The Keepers of the Liberties of England,” to insure against the violation of the licensing act. It was precisely this censorship previous to publication by mail against which Milton wrote his “Areopagitica.” Our courts have said that the ab- sence of “such previous restraint as had been practised” is the one thing, at least, against which our constitutional guarantees protect us, and yet in spite of Courts and Constitutions we have for some thme acquiesced in just such a usurped postal censorship previous to publication by mail. Furthermore, ow- ing to the uncertainty of the statutory criteria of mailability, this censorship previous to publication by post is in practise an arbitrary discretion. So, then, we do not even have left the one lonely element of freedom which our courts too often have mistaken for all there is to unabridged freedom of the 30 press. Even that little “all” has disappeared, and only the blank paper of our Constitutional guarantee remains. When the issue is squarely presented, will our courts confirm also the destruction of this last element of freedom of the press, and SO vest Congress and our Federal bureaucracy with all the powers over the press which our Constitution was supposed to withhold? An English Barrister-at-law gives us this brief account of the postal censorship in England: “The right of free speech and writing can scarcely exist in perfection without mechanical facilities for exchanging letters and printed matter between correspondents. * * * * What is desired by each and every citizen is, that he shall be entitled to send and receive all com- munications which he thinks material to his own interest, and that no third party shall be allowed to tamper or interfere with this operation—so that a message sent in writing or print shall be secret and inviolable from the moment it is despatched till , the moment it is delivered. This has for two centuries been more or less attained. The great medium for this communica- tion between the subjects began in 1635, on a small scale, at the suggestion of the Crown, but Parliament soon saw its im- portance, and in 1649 passed a resolution that the office of post- master ought to be [at] the sole disposal of Parliament. In 1710 a statute laid down the chief rules, and one of these, continuing as it did the first sketch of a plan projected under Charles I., forbade all other persons to carry and deliver letters for hire. * * * * “It appears to have been a century ago the common complaint of leading statesmen that their political opponents made a practise of opening their letters when they had the power. * * * * “In 1822 complaint was made by a member of Parliament that a letter sent him by a prisoner had been opened. And, though the Government claimed the right to do so for precau- tion, yet many urged that it should be deemed a breach of privilege; this step, however, was not taken.” Again, in 1844, instances of private letters being opened were complained of, and Parliamentary committees investigated the practise, and found sufficient confirmation of the suspicion that such a prac- tise was not unfrequent, especially in connection with foreign refugees.” Sir R. Peel said that no rule could be laid down on such a subject, and successive Secretaries of State of all 276 Parl. Deb. (2d), 282, 646. 2875 Parl. Deb. (3) 1264; 76 Ibid. 212, 296. 31 parties had been in the habit of exercising this power at dis- cretion.” Thus, this great authority on freedom of the press informs us that, according to the English conception of it, the period of our revolution found it a matter of constant complaint that there was a post-office censorship. Those who thus complained were the friends of a larger intellectual liberty and it was their view that was adopted into our constitutional guarantee for the security of papers against unreasonable searches, and against all abridgments of freedom of utterance. These two clauses together, until judicially explained away, would seem clearly to preclude the search of unsealed as well as sealed mail-matter for the purpose of creating inequalities of right to the public service, according to whether the ideas transmitted are officially approved or disapproved. This is the self-evident meaning of our Constitution when viewed in the light of the issues that were agitating the public at the time of its adoption. The manifest purpose was the increase of intellectual oppor- tunity, even though it protected such as might be inclined to sedition, and just as manifestly it was not the purpose merely to change a business policy in relation to a department of government. To show that the advocates of unabridged freedom of the press included a mail service free from censorship as a part of their conception of freedom of speech, I will content myself with one quotation from Jeremy Bentham, as confirming the foregoing historical interpretation. After explaining that the only check to tyrannous government is “instruction, excitation, and facility of correspondence” that “the national mind be kept in a state of appropriate preparation; a state of prepar- ation for eventual resistance,” he later continues thus: “Neces- sary to instruction—to excitation—in a word to a state of preparation directed to this purpose is (who does not see it?) the perfectly unrestrained communication of ideas on every subject within the field of government—[which includes the discussion of sexual physiology and psychology as a founda– tion for sex ethics, and the latter even from the viewpoint of the free-lover and polygamist because a democratic govern- ment must leave itself free to change even its marriage laws] the communication, by vehicles of all sorts—by signs of all sorts; signs to the ear—signs to the eye—by spoken language— by written, including printed, language—by the liberty of the *Rep. of Secret Com. 1845; Patterson, “Liberty of the Press, Speech, and Public Worship,” pp. 58-59. 32 tongue, by the liberty of the writing desk, by the liberty of the post office—by the liberty of the press.” He repeats that this is necessary, “not only for instruction, but for excitation”; all “for keeping on foot every facility for eventual resistance.” Bentham then pointed to the United States as a place where such liberties existed, but he could not do so now were he alive. The Declaration of Independence, the constitutional guarantees for the right of assembly, due process of law, the right to bear arms, and against searches and seizures; the declarations of the conventions of several of the States, the constitutional guarantees of unabridged freedom of speech and of the press—all proclaim the intention to protect the right of the citizen against punishment for mere psychologic crimes, to the end that he always may be prepared for eventual re- sistance, even of government itself.” PSYCHOLOGIC TENDENCY AS CRITERION OF GUILT. Historically considered, an inseparable part of the conten- tion for a larger, or an unabridged, liberty of speech and of the press was the condemnation of that practise in the prosecu- tion for libels which made the guilt of the accused depend upon “the evils which may be imaginatively and prospectively at- tributed to the influence of his opinions.” The opposition to this uncertainty in the criteria of guilt was not limited to persons who believed in unabridged freedom of speech, but was often very forcibly urged by those who desired only a little or no enlargement of intellectual opportunity. Even Blackstone believed that the criteria of guilt for heresy and seditious utterances should be made more certain. The protest against the uncertainty of the tests of crimin- ality in prosecutions for seditious and blasphemous utterances was upon two distinct grounds. The first and most general of these was the historical retrospect, and was an appeal to expediency. The argument ran thus: Books once condemned for their supposed evil tendencies are now believed to have been good and useful. In making the psychologic tendency of an utterance the test of its criminality, we are again opening the door for a repetition of such error. Therefore, such criminal laws are inexpedient and should be abolished. The second reason for objecting to the tendency-test in penalized utterances was from the point of view of that larger demand for liberty which was founded upon the idea that no freeman *Jeremy Bentham, “On Liberty of the Press and Public Discussion.” *Stevens, “Sources of the Constitution, of the United States,” pp. 223-224; Blackstone’s Commentaries, v. 1, p. 154; Cooley, “Constitutional Law,” 270. 33 should be deprived of his liberty except by lawful judgment of his peers, or by the law of the land. This was predicated upon the conception that every man should in justice be forewarned that his act is penalized. It could not be the law of the land if it did not impart that advance information, and could not accomplish this except an exact statement of the criteria of guilt was a part of every criminal statute. By such means the lovers of Liberty hoped to obtain freedom under law in contra- distinction to a mere liberty by permission under lawless despot- ism. To such persons, it was self-evident that a speculative opinion about the psychologic tendency of an utterance upon a future, undescribed, hypothetical, reader, or hearer, when used as a criterion of guilt, could be no restraint upon the moral idiosyncracies, stupid bigotry, unreasoned hysterical apprehen- Sion, personal interest, or even the superstitious malice, of those charged with the duty of determining whether or not a verbal crime had been committed. It was seen that under such circumstances guilt must be determined by ex post facto standards, personal to the individuals passing judgment. This, it was argued, was government according to the lawless despotism of man, and the friends of freedom demanded as one of the conditions without which there could be no liberty of speech or press, or liberty of any sort, that the criteria of guilt be so certain that every man should know in advance, from the very letter of the law, by what standard his conduct would be adjudged criminal. It goes without saying that so long as an er post facto judicial guess as to the psychologic tendency of a speech, book, or picture is the test of guilt, there can be no such thing as liberty under the law. Even from those to whom “free speech” meant a limited liberty by per-T mission, there came a protest against tyranny, and the demand for the freedom of every man's opinion from that arbitrary power for the penalizing of words by standards of an ex post facto guess or pretense about “the evils which may be inmaginatively and prospectively attributed to the in- fluence of his opinions.” As proof of the assertion that a demand for certainty in the criteria of guilt always was a part of the agitation for more freedom of speech and press, we need but to point out that vast literature which was brought into being against constructive treason and seditious libel. Erskine’s speeches are replete with the glorification and demand for such certainty. 34 Here it is only necessary to call attention to its existence as a part of the agitation for enlarged liberty. The discussion of the question is better treated as a subdivision of an argument to support the contention that “Due Process of Law” does not obtain unless every criminal statute prescribes the criteria of guilt with mathematical certainty. IN CONCLUSION. This historical review of the contentions which resulted in the adoption of our constitutional guarantees for an unabridged freedom of speech and of the press, is already too long for comfortable reading, and not long enough to be anything like an exhaustive treatise. I believe, however, that it adequately establishes the following propositions: I. The contention for an UNABRIDGED freedom of utterance was always founded upon a demand for unrestrained intellectual opportunity, and never concerned itself primarily with preferences between different methods of abridging that freedom. II. It opposed all past and existing restrictions upon in- tellectual intercourse, such as licensing printers or books, censoring the post or other means of transmission, putting taxes upon knowledge, and inflicting ex post facto punish- ments; and our Constitutions not only sought to prevent a recurrance of any of these former methods of abridging in- tellctual opportunity, but the antecedent discussion and the language used clearly express the determination to preclude the enforcement of any other, even theretofore untried, methods of curtailing intellectual intercourse, although again claimed to be advocated for the furtherance of the public welfare. III. The demand for unabridged freedom of utterance always was a demand for the abolition of all mere psychologic crimes and all that uncertainty which attended them from the fact that the criteria of guilt were usually “the evils which may be imaginatively and prospectively attributed to the in- fluence of one's opinions”; and the co-related demand that crime should always be predicated upon a certainty, such as an actual and material injury, or perhaps also the imminent danger of such, according to the known laws of the physical universe. * 35 If we generalize all these contentions for a larger and an unabridged intellectual opportunity, we shall have a compre- hensive statement of the historical interpretation of unabridged freedom of speech and of the press, and if the form of state- ment is such as to furnish us with the criteria for determining a breaching of the constitutional guarantee, we shall have a statement in substance like that at the beginning of this chapter. If then we wish to determine whether or not any given law is violative of the free-press clause of our constitutions we must deductively apply to the law the several tests stated at the beginning of this chaper. Doing this, with reference to our laws prohibitive of sex-discussion I find them, in their separate parts, to be unconstitutional, under the second, fourth, and fifth, test of constitutionality. A. J. Willard, on Free Speech. “The most general office of speech is to reproduce the thoughts and feelings of one in others. In this sense the liberty of speech is absolute, according to the principles of the law. It is impossible to conceive of an actionable wrong existing solely on the ground that one has attempted to impart his thoughts and feelings to another, unless some public law affords such remedy, or unless such speech is accompanied by some action that is an aggression on the nights of another. * * * “It is a means of combining and constituting the common or mutual action of individuals, and therefore, must be examined as among the means of performing such actions as depends upon co- operation. It would follow that, when an action is unlawful, speech used as a means to such end would partake of that unlawful charac- ter. This results from the fact that what is said, as well as what is done, may form a part of a transaction, and thus the lawful or un- lawful character imputed to such transaction must effect all the elements of that transaction. Speech in this way may be part of the means of connecting the action of rioters or conspirators against governments. It may even point the nature and tendency of the actions which it accompanies, and thus become a means of con- ferring upon them the legal character of lawfulnesss or unlawful- ness. * * * * “In all these cases eyen of where the character of what is spoken determines the legal character of what is done, it is the act alone that can convert the mere use of words into violations of -right. Again, speech may be used for purposes of deception, and in that case, as in the cases previously mentioned, the act of wrong is not con- summated by the speech alone, but by the action produced by the speech. “In the instance of slander, words uttered may be attended by consequences rendering them injurious to the right of character. In these cases the wrong consists in what is actually or presumably done by individuals, by society at large, or by the community as a consequence of words spoken, the words in such a case being the cause of injurious consequences, are regarded as in themselves injurious.”—WILLARD, on The Law of Personal Rights, pp. 349-351.