\ THE THEORY OF THE STATE BL UNTSCHLI JSon&on HENRY FROWDE OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS WAREHOUSE AMEN CORNER, E.C FOURTH AVENUE THE THEORY OF THE STATE J. K. BLUNTSCHLI 1LATE PROFESSOR OF POLITICAL SCIENCES IN THE UNIVERSITY OF HEIDELBERG AUTHORISED ENGLISH TRANSLATION FROM THE SIXTH GERMAN EDITION SECOND EDITION AT THE CLARENDON PRESS M DCCC XCII PRINTED AT THE C I. A K Ett D O N PRESS BY HORACE HAKT, PRINTER TO THE UNIVERSITY IN MEMORIAM PCItotrc) TRANSLATORS' PREFACE THE ' Theory of the Modern State ' (Lehre vom modernen Stat} by the late Professor Johann Kaspar Bluntschli, of Heidelberg, may be described as an attempt to do for the European State what x\ristotle accomplished for the Hellenic. The material being far more complex, the task is very much more difficult, but Bluntschli's is, at least, the most successful attempt that has been made. We have hardly any works in English which we can put beside it in respect of intention and compass ; and of these, none is equally useful for the student. No writer can escape the influence of his surroundings, and although Germany was only his adopted country, he being a native of Zurich, Bluntschli's pojrrt_o view is sometimes joo exclusively German. But perhaps this is not altogether a disadvantage to us : the endeavour to understand a mode of looking at some political subjects, different from that to which we are accustomed, may not be without its uses. On the whole, Bluntschli is a candid and fair critic both of actual con- stitutions and of political theories. Occasionally he may betray some of the prejudices of German officialism ; occa- sionally, too, he may push to a somewhat amusing extreme his * organic ' or l psychological ' conception of the State. M141414 vi TRANSLATORS' PREFACE, Kut these are slight defects, more likely to throw light on the individuality of the author than to mislead the judicious reader. The work here translated, the Allgemeine Statslehre, is only the first part of the * Theory of the Modern State/ The relation of the other two parts, the Allgemeines Statsrecht and Politik, to it and to one another is explained in Chapter I of the Introduction. This first part goes over the whole ground of what we call ' Political Science, 7 though some subjects are treated in much greater detail in the two other parts *. The translators have not aimed at a rigid uniformity. Where there seemed a risk of misstating the author's ideas, a more literal style has been employed than where the meaning was quite obvious, and occasionally considerable abridgment has been found possible. One of the chief difficulties has arisen from the impossibility of getting exact equivalents to the technical terms of German Law and Politics. As the use of a translation is not limited to those who know nothing of the original language, the practice has been adopted of giving the German words in brackets, after the English, in all cases where this seemed likely to save ambiguity or to help the student. It is a peculiar misfortune of our language to have no precise term for Recht (jus, droit, dirittO) TO 8iKatov) as distinguished from Gesetz (lex, loi, legge, yo>os). We are driven to use ' Law ' and ( legal ' in a conventional way (thus StatsreM= Public Law, Rechtsstat 1 In 1852 Bluntschli published his Allgemeines Statsrecht geschicht- lich begrundet in one volume. It afterwards grew into two volumes. Finally, when a fifth edition (1875) became necessary, he added the volume called Politik, the two other parts corresponding in the main to the two volumes of the original Statsrecht. TRANSLATORS' PREFACE. vii = legal state, etc.), though these terms fail to express the distinction \ Sometimes, but rarely, the word ' Right ' has been used, e. g. where it was necessary to bring out the antithesis between Right and Might. Bluntschli himself remarked on the difference between the German and English uses of Volk and i people,' Nation and ' nation ' (Book II, Ch. ii) ; but it will be found that he goes too far in supposing our use to be the exact converse of the German 2 . The fact is, our word ' people,' though often less political in its signification than Volk, is more political than the German word Nation. Thus we must translate Volksvertre- tung by ' Representation of the people,' and we can only render Populus Romanus by the Roman people.' In many cases where Bluntschli uses the term f State ' (Stat) it would be more idiomatic English to say ' nation,' which is more exclusively political in its meaning than the German Volk ; but the word ' State ' has been advisedly retained everywhere as a technical term to translate Stat, except where it occurs in compounds such as Statsrecht. It should be noted how- ever that Stat is always much wider than our term ' Govern- ment/ with which ( State ' is often used convertibly. 'Government,' again, because of this frequent equivalence with ' State,' is wider than the German Regierung, which 1 A good account of the different terms for ' Law ' will be found in Clark's Practical Jurisprudence, a Comment on Austin. It would be interesting to trace the connexion between some peculiarities of English Jurisprudence and this want of a distinctive word for Jus. On the other side, we have escaped some of the temptations into which the vagueness of the German Recht has led the theorists of Naturrecht. Our phrase ' rights ' is at least shorter than Recht in subjectiver Hin- sicht. (Cp. Sir F. Pollock in his History of the Science of Politics, pp. 114, 115 ; Prof. Holland's Jurisprudence, 2nd edit., pp. 63, 275 note.) 2 Steinthal, Allgemeine Ethik, p. 425, gives a meaning to the German words which is the precise converse of that given by Bluntschli. viii TRANSLATORS' PREFACE. excludes the function of legislation (see Book VII, Ch. vii) and often means little more than i administration,' though distinguished from it (p. 430). The word Stdnde has been translated ' privileged classes, orders or estates,' though 1 Estates ' is generally limited to the estates as assembled in Parliament (see Book II, Ch. vii). The French version by M. Riedmatten, who has also translated the Allgemeines Statsrecht (Le droit public general) and the Politik, has been of great service, especially in regard to those many political terms which we have in common with the French rather than the German language. The references given by Bluntschli in the foot-notes have been carefully verified as far as possible. Several of them, unfortunately, are to works not easily accessible in this country. In many cases they have been corrected and supplemented. Additional references have been made to Aristotle's Politics. In these the books are quoted accord- ing to the order of the MSS. and the old editions, not the conjectural order of St. Hilaire, etc., adopted by Congreve and Welldon. The chapters and sections are those of the Oxford edition of Bekker, and the pages of the great Berlin edition of Aristotle have in most cases been added. The translation has been made with the sanction of the German publishers : and the translators have had the ad- vantage of using Professor Loning's corrections for a new (sixth) edition of the work, which is in course of publica- tion. Most of Professor Loning's additions and alterations have been adopted. Where new notes are added by him they are marked 1 , etc. Notes and additions for which the translators alone are responsible are enclosed in square brackets. Obvious corrections have been silently made. A marginal analysis has been added, and has helped to free TRANSLATORS 1 PREFACE. ix the text from an excess of italics, and occasionally to simplify the translation. For convenience of reference, this analysis is reproduced in the table of contents. The translation was undertaken primarily in the interests of the School of Modern History. As it was desirable to avoid delay, the work was entrusted to three separate hands, but it has been subjected to a mutual revision by the translators. The original division of labour was as follows : Books I, IV, and VII, by D. G. RITCHIE, M.A., Fellow and Tutor of Jesus College and sometime Tutor of Balliol College. Books II and III, by P. E. MATHESON, M.A., Fellow and Tutor of New College. Books V and VI, by R. LODGE, M.A., Fellow and Tutor of Brasenose College. IN this second edition the opportunity has been taken to correct some slight errors. A few additional references have been inserted by the Translators, chiefly to recent English books on Political Science. No change of importance has been made, except in the Translators' note on Book IV, ch. ix, p. 294, where Locke's form of the Social Contract theory has been more correctly represented than in the first edition. OXFORD, June, 1892. ANALYTICAL TABLE OF CONTENTS INTRODUCTION. PAGE CHAPTER I. Political Science i Political Science denned : it does not include certain sciences which are auxiliary to it. Divided into Public Law and Politics. These distinguished from Ethics : their relation to one another. The Theory of the State in general to be considered first. CHAPTER II. Scientific Methods 5 Methods true and false. False methods : Ideology and Empiri- cism. True methods : The historical and the philosophical : These united by the greatest writers: they supplement and correct each other. CHAPTER III. General and Special Political Science . . 10 General Political Science based on Universal History. What periods and races are significant. BOOK I. THE CONCEPTION OF THE STATE. CHAPTER I. The Conception and Idea of the State. The general Conception of the State The Conception of the State arrived at by history : the idea by philosophy. Characteristics of all States : (i) a number of men; (2) a fixed territory; (3) unity; (4) distinction between rulers and subjects; (5) an organic nature. In what sense the State is an organism : (a) It has spirit and body. () It has members with various special functions, (c) It develops and grows : yet is no mere natural growth. (6) The State is a moral and spiritual organism : it has a personality. (7) It is masculine. Note on the different names for State. xii ANALYTICAL TABLE OF CONTENTS. PAGE CHAPTER II. The human idea of the State. The Universal Empire .......... 25 The common nature of mankind implies the need of a Universal State. Attempts to realise this Universal State in the past : (i) The Empire of Alexander the Great ; (2) The Roman Empire ; (3) The Holy Roman Empire ; (4) The Empire of Napoleon I. Tendencies towards a common organisation of humanity. Notes, (i) Objections of Vinet : answers. (2) Objections of Laurent : answers. CHAPTER III. History of the development of idea of the State. I. The Ancient World 35 A. The Hellenic idea of the State. Political ideas of the Greeks: Plato; Aristotle. Defects of the Greek idea of the State : Too much power was ascribed to it ; Limitations to this absolute power. B. The Roman idea of the State. Influence of the Greeks. Differences from the Greek idea : (i) Law dis- tinguished from morality ; (2) The conception of the people (or nation) ; (3) Tendency to Universal Empire. CHAPTER IV. II. The Middle Ages 41 A. Christianity. Attitude of the Early Church to the State. The Papacy. Pope and Emperor. B. 77ie Teutons. Their power: their character. The idea of individual rights. ' Parti- cularism' in politics. Surviving tradition from antiquity. Feudal law. C. The influence of the Renaissance. The Roman Church kept alive the ideas of the Roman Empire. The Holy Roman Empire. Roman Law. Republican traditions. Greek theories. The Renaissance : Influence of the Classical Revival. CHAPTER V. III. The Modern idea of the State . . .50 A. When does the Modern Epoch commence? (i) The Renais- sance? (2) The Reformation? () The English Revolution? (4) The French Revolution? (5) 1740? The accession of Frederick the Great of Prussia. Notes. The unity of history assumes the unity of mankind. The duration of the human race. History begins with the white man. CHAPTER VI .58 B. Chief differences of the Modern Conception of the State from the Ancient and Mediaeval. Differences between Ancient and Modern State regarding: (i) Rights of man as man; (2) Sphere of State-action ; (3) Individual freedom Private Law; (4) Sovereignty; (5) Direct Government Representative Go- vernment ; (6) The city the nation ; (7) Differentiation of ANALYTICAL TABLE OF CONTENTS. xiii PAGE functions ; (8) International relations. Differences between the Mediaeval and Modern State regarding: (i) Divine human origin; (2) Theology Science ; (3) Theocracy; (4) Religion ; (5) The Church ; (6) Education ; (7) Public and Private Law ; (8) Particularism Centralisation ; (9) Representation ; (10) Li- berties Liberty; (n) Sphere of State-action ; (12) Unconscious custom conscious legislation. CHAPTER VII. The Development of different theories of the State 64 (i) At the Renaissance: Machiavelli ; Bodin ; Grotius. (2) Theories of the law of nature, of contract and association. (3) System of authority. (4) The State as a ' legal State.' Legal State versus Police State. In what sense the State is and is not a ' legal State/ The State must pay regard to public welfare as well as to Law. (5) The historical School. Organic theory of the State. (6) Recent German political philosophy : Hegel ; Stahl. (7) Union of philosophical and historical methods. Criticism of the State from different points of view. Historical criticism. The Juristic method. The Psychological. The Comparative. Natural theory of the State. Notes. The organic or psychological nature of the State (Schmitthenner, Vollgraff, Ahrens, Waitz, Bluntschli). BOOK II. THE FUNDAMENTAL CONDITIONS OF THE STATE IN THE NATURE OF MEN AND OF NATIONS. CHAPTER I. Mankind. The Kaces of Men, and Families of Nations . . . . . . . . . .81 Mankind: its unity and differences. Four main races: (i) Ethiopian ; (2) Red ; (3) Yellow ; (4) White, with its two great families, (a] the Semitic, () the Aryan. These differences of : Race are ' natural ' ; those of Nationality are * historical.' CHAPTER II. The Conceptions ' People ' and ' Nation ' . .86 A People implies a civilisation, a Nation is a political idea. Origin of a People. Origin of a Nation. The influence of (a] Religion ; . () Language ; (c) Habitation, customs, political union, &c. ; (d] Fusion of Races. A People is characterised by its common spirit and common civilisation, the product of an un- xiv ANALYTICAL TABLE OF CONTENTS. PAGE conscious process of growth. Definition of a People. Definition of a Nation. A Nation is distinguished from a People by the sense of political unity. No State, no Nation. A Nation is a collec- tive personality, with a spirit and will of its own ; subject to the changes of organic life. CHAPTER III. The Bights of Nationalities . . . .93 Rights which a people may assert : (i) To its own Language ; (2) To its own Laws ; (3) To its own Customs, within limits determined by the good of the S,tate ; (4) To its Moral and In- tellectual Life. CHAPTER IV. Nationality as a Principle in the Formation of States 97 Nationality always powerful. But not till lately recognised as a principle in politics or in political Theory. Napoleon and the nations of Europe. Nationality since the Forties. United Italy and Germany. The extreme principle ' A State for each People.' Modified by relative limits of Peoples and States : I. One People includes several States ; Tendency to (i) Isolation, (2) Combination. II. One State includes several Peoples : A. exist- ing side by side, (i) Absorption ; (2) Separation ; (3) Union of differences by (a) impartial government, (#) mechanical force: B. intermixed, (4) Assimilation. The claims of Nationality summed up: (i) Political capacity; (2) Diversity of spirit a source of weakness or strength ; (3) Political vocation ; (4) The national State; (5) The ideal State; (6) Unity; (7) Equality; (8) The verdict of History. The State as the embodiment of the Nation must grow with its growth. CHAPTER V. Society 109 Relation of Society (i) to Nature and State ; (2) to People. Gneist's * Society of Industry/ CHAPTER VI. Tribes 112 Tribes express the inner differences of a People. Their influence for good or evil. Tribal antagonism. The tribe as the germ of a new nation. CHAPTER VII. Castes 114 Divisions within the nation and tribe. The Indian Castes : (i) The Brahmans ; (2) The Kshatriyas ; (3) The Visas ; (4) The Sudras Intercourse between Castes. The origin of Castes in differences of Race or of Religion. A stereotyped system dominating the State. Order and permanence. But no progress or freedom. Modern India. ANALYTICAL TABLE OF CONTENTS. xv PAGE CHAPTER VIII. Privileged Classes or Estates . . . 1 20 Estates or Orders widespread in Europe. Their legendary origin. (i) Priests ; (2) Nobility ; (3) Freemen ; (4) Dependents. Estates the basis of mediaeval law and politics. At first hereditary, they become professional, and finally decay. CHAPTER IX. I. The Clergy 124 The Clergy not a national order. They stand outside the State, and above it. Growth of their political power Italy, Germany: (i) The imperial constitution ; (2) Provincial constitutions. The Reformation. England and France. CHAPTER X. II. The Nobility ...... 131 A. The French Nobility. The old Nobility of Birth at Rome be- came a Political Nobility of personal merit. Maecenas* Ideal. The French Nobility : (i) The Merovingian Period, 481-752 ; (2) The Carolingian Period, 752-987; (3) The Period of the Capets, 987-1226 (The higher Nobility ; The lower Nobility) ; (4) From St. Louis to the Revolution : The feudal nobility becomes a court nobility. Noblesse de Lettres. The Revolution. Napoleon I. Louis XVIII. 1830 and 1848. Napoleon III. CHAPTER XI 142 B. The English Nobility. Fusion of Races. Power of the Crown. -^William I. Power of the Nobles in Parliament. Magna Charta. The Upper arid Lower House. The enlarge- ment of Parliament. Knights. Gentlemen. Public spirit of the English Nobility. The Peerage confined to one heir. Marriage. New creations. CHAPTER XII 149 C. The German Nobility, (i) Princes. Princes secular and ecclesiastical ; Counts ; Barons. Their political rights. Their selfish and exclusive spirit. Multiplication of titles. Decline. 1797-1803. 1806. 1815. 1815-1866. The new Aristocracy. CHAPTER XIII. . . . . . . , .155 C. The German Nobility. (2) Knights. The lower Nobility becomes hereditary and exclusive. Their privileges. Decline, from the sixteenth century. 1815. The German nobility as it is. Its Reform. CHAPTER XIV. HI. The Citizens 160 Tendency to Serfdom in the country. Freedom in the Towns. Population of the Towns. Growth of the Citizen Class. Rise of Councils in Lombardy, &c. Communes in France. Guild societies. The personal tie supersedes the feudal. Enfranchise- ment of serfs. Citizenship in Germany : Free householders ; xvi ANALYTICAL TABLE OF CONTENTS. PAGE Merchants; Artisans. Citizenship of personal freedom. Pro- vincial and Imperial Towns. Decline of the Towns. Charac- teristics of the mediaeval Citizen Class. The Third Estate. Citizenship in the State. CHAPTER XV. IV. The Peasants . . - .. . . .169 Rise of the serf- class. Enfranchisement. Guilds in France and Germany. Serfdom in the country. Enfranchisement. The peasants acquire private rights. France. England. The German Peasant War. Political rights. CHAPTER XVI. V. Slavery and its Abolition . . -174 Aristotle on Slavery. Roman Law. German Law. Slavery passes into Serfdom. Christianity. The Teutonic spirit. Russia. American slavery. Montesquieu. Jefferson. Wilber- force. American Civil War. Rights of the Negro. The State and Slavery. CHAPTER XVII. VI. Principle of Modern Classes . .181 Privileged classes pass away. Classes and Estates. Property Classes. Modem Classes. CHAPTER XVIII. Survey of Modern Classes . . . 185 (i) The Governing Class; (2) The Aristocracy; (3) The Citizen Class; The 'third estate' in France since 1789; in Germany. The Citizen Class not an Estate, but a popular middle class. Its political power ; (4) The lowest class, ' The People.' Its com- position. Its present importance. Its want of organisation. The Proletariate. Political claims of the Fourth Class. CHAPTER XIX. The Relation of the State to the Family. I. The Tribal State. Patriarchal Government. Mar- riage 195 Differences between the State and the Family. Tribal constitu- tion. The Patriarchal State. The influence of the Family on the State. Marriage, the highest form of which is Monogamy. The law of husband and wife. Marriage ceremony. En- couragement of Marriage. Restraints on Marriage. Marriage and divorce. CHAPTER XX. II. The Position of "Women . . .204 Political rights of women. Mill. The anomaly of queens. Arguments against women's franchise. Indirect influence of women. ANALYTICAL TABLE OF CONTENTS. xvii PAGE CHAPTER XXI. Kelation of the State to Individuals. I. Natives and Aliens . . . . . . . .209 What makes a native : (a) Birthplace ; () Domicile ; (c) Mem- bership in a commune ; (d) Personal relation to the State.- What terminates membership in a State. English Law. French Law. Native rights in two States. Conflict of duties. The position of a Native : (a) Private rights ; () Public rights. CHAPTER XXII. II. Citizens , .217 Full citizenship. Its limits. Independence. Property. Re- ligion. Religious Freedom, not yet fully realised. BOOK III. THE CONDITIONS OF THE STATE IN EXTERNAL NATURE. THE LAND. CHAPTER I. Climate 225 Influence of Climate on national character. The temperate zones. Extremes of cold and heat. Position of capital cities. Climate and legislation. CHAPTER II. Watural Features 229 Rivers. The Sea. Mountains. Inland countries. Man's power over nature. Advantage of a temperate climate. CHAPTER III. The Fertility of the Soil 232 Barren soil. Fruitful soil tends to produce : (i) Indolence ; (2) Degradation of labour; (3) Inequality of property. India, Egypt, Mexico and Peru. Moderately fertile soil the best. Legislation. CHAPTER IV. The Land 237 The State and its Territory. Tendency to large States, pro- moted by modern civilisation. Limits to the size of a territory. Population more important than area. Strength and weakness of large States. Boundaries. Union of several territories. The Ideal Territory. CHAPTER V. Territorial Sovereignty 243 State property. State sovereignty ; its consequences and limita- tions. CHAPTER VI. Division of the Country 246 (i) Provinces; (2) Circles; (3) Districts; (4) Communes. Principles of Division. b xviii ANALYTICAL TABLE OF CONTENTS. PACK CHAPTER VII. The Relation of the State to Private Pro- perty . . 249 The history of Property. Communism. Socialism. The State protects property. Limits of private property. Survival of the idea of State-ownership. Expropriation. Compensation. As- sessment of compensation. BOOK IV. THE RISE AND FALL OF THE STATE. CHAPTER I. Introduction 259 Two questions about the rise of the State : one historical, the other speculative. Three historical forms of the rise of States. CHAPTER II. Historical Formations. I. Original . . 262 (i) Creation of an absolutely new State. (2) Political organisa- tion of the inhabitants of a definite territory. (3) Occupation of tenitory by an already existing nation. Conquest. Might and right. Peaceful settlement. CHAPTER III. II Secondary Formations . . . .268 (A.) Formation of a Composite State by a league between states: (i) Confederation ; (2) Federation ; (3) Federal Empire. Differences between the German Empire and Republican Federa- tions. (B.) Union: (4) Personal Union; (5) Real Union; (6) Complete Union. (C.) Division: (7) National Division; (8) Division by inheritance ; (9) Declaration of Independence. CHAPTER IV. III. Derived Formations . . . . 2 76 (i) Colonisation: (a] Greek; (#) Roman; (c) Modern. (2) Concession of sovereign rights. (3) Institution by a foreign ruler. CHAPTER V. Fall of States 279 The common cause of the mortality of the State to be found in its organic nature. Special forms of the fall of States : (i) Na- tional disorganisation; Anarchy; (2) Migration; (3) Conquest; (4) Voluntary absorption ; (5) Voluntary separation and Com- pulsory partition ; (6) Withdrawal or renunciation of sovereign rights. CHAPTER VI. Speculative Theories. I. 'The State of Nature' 283 (i) The Golden Age. The State as a necessary evil. (2) The ANALYTICAL TABLE OF CONTENTS. xix PAGE state of nature as a state of war. Both views overlook man's political nature. CHAPTER VII. II. The State as a divine institution . . 286 (l) The State as directly founded by God. (2) As indirectly founded by God. Erroneous views of the divine nature of the State : Monarchical prejudice ; The prince as God's represent- ative ; Authority as such divine ; Divine right ; Irresponsibility. Note. History of the expression f by the grace of God.' CHAPTER VIII. III. The Theory of Force . . . .292 ' Might is right.' Is this the teaching of History ? Element of truth in the doctrine. CHAPTER IX. IV. The Theory of Contract . . . . 294 Influence of the theory of the social contract. The theory un- historical ; illogical ; practically dangerous. Yet contains an element of truth. Note. Haller's views on the State. CHAPTER X. V. The Natural Sociability and Political Con- sciousness of Man ........ 300 The State arises from the social impulses of human nature. This social impulse passes from the unconscious to the conscious stage. This view contains the truth in the various false theories. The State a necessary good. BOOK V. THE END OF THE STATE. CHAPTER I. The State an End or a Means? How far is it End or Means ? 305 Ancient theory : the State as an end. Modern theory : the State as a means. Both these theories are one-sided. Danger of the ancient theory : and of the modern theory. Modern considera- tion of the individual. The State is a reality. The welfare of the State and the individual are inseparable. CHAPTER II. False views of the End of the State . . 310 i. That it is to maintain the ruling power. 2. That it is to carry out the divine will. 3. That it has to secure some external object. CHAPTER III. Insufficient or Exaggerated Views of the End of the State 314 i . That its end is to secure the rights of person and property, b 2 xx ANALYTICAL TABLE OF CONTENTS. PAGE Defects of this view. Its results. 2. That its end is to secure general happiness. Harmful results of this view. CHAPTER IV. The True End of the State . . . .318 There is only one general end of the State. l Justice ' is too narrow. ' Morality ' is too wide. The ' securing of the public welfare ' is not incorrect, but is insufficient in times of crisis. The true definition. This general definition includes special tendencies, e. g. the development of external power ; or of economic interests ; or of intellectual interests ; or of legal guarantees for freedom ; or of national unity. Indirect functions of the State. Limitations of State action. BOOK VI. THE FORMS OF THE STATE. CHAPTER I. The Division of Aristotle 329 Normal States and Perversions. Quality is more important than quantity. Aristotle's division is incomplete. Ideocracy. CHAPTER II. The so-called Mixed State .... 332 The Roman Republic. What is meant by a Mixed State? The English Constitution. The government, not the legislature, is to be considered. CHAPTER III. Later Developments of Aristotle's Theory . 335 Montesquieu. Schleiermacher. CHAPTER IV. The Principle of the Four Fundamental Forms 338 Four forms of State : Ideocracy, Democracy, Aristocracy, Monarchy. Consideration of these forms. CHAPTER V. The Principle of the Secondary Forms of the State 342 Division of States according to the rights of the subjects : Unfree: Half-free ; Free States. Application of this division to the four fundamental forms. CHAPTER VI. Theocracy or Ideocracy 345 Theocracy is natural in early times. It involves the rule of priests. Examples : Meroe ; Egypt ; India ; Persia ; the Jewish Theocracy; Theocracy in Europe; the Mohammedans. General, characteristics of Theocracy. ANALYTICAL TABLE OF CONTENTS. xxi PAGE CHAPTER VII. The Chief Kinds of Monarchy . . . 356 Despotism. Civilised Monarchy. Patriarchal Kingship. Feudal Monarchy. Military and Judicial Principalities. Absolute Monarchy. Limited Monarchy. Kingship and Empire. CHAPTER VIII. I. Family Kingship among the Greeks and Germans 360 Characteristics of early Greek and German Monarchy. Limits to the royal power. The German Comitatus. CHAPTER IX. II. National Monarchy in Ancient Kome . 365 Conception of Roman Monarchy. Administrative power. Ex- ternal ensigns. Legislative power. Judicial power. Military power. Officials. Important position of the Roman King. CHAPTER X. III. The Eoman Empire 370 The Empire was not a mere collection of Republican Offices. Election to the Empire. Analysis of the imperial power. CHAPTER XL IV. The Frankish Monarchy . . . .375 Carolingian Monarchy. Causes of its strength. Hereditary succession. Legislation among the Franks. Government. Military power. Judicial power. Administrative officials. Close connexion with the Empire and the Church. CHAPTER XII. V. Feudal Monarchy and Monarchy Limited by Class Privileges 382 A. Feudal Monarchy : its characteristics : It is based upon Classes. Fealty and homage. Tenure of land. Authority derived from the Kkig. Power of the nobles. Guizot's account of Feudalism. The system was not wholly oppressive. Exist- ence of political rights. B. Monarchy Limited by Class Privi- leges: Legislation. Administration. Jurisdiction. Police. Military powers. Taxation. CHAPTER XIII. VI. Modern Absolute Monarchy . . .391 Rise of Absolutism in the Romance countries, e. g. Spain and France. Principles of Absolute Monarchy. Influence of theorists and clergy. Decline of Absolutism, first in England, then in other countries. Russia. CHAPTER XIV. VII. Constitutional Monarchy . . . 397 A. Its origin and progress. Rise of Constitutional Monarchy. I. In England. English Revolutions. Characteristics of Constitutional Monarchy. Results of the Revolution of 1688. II. France. Constitution of 1791. The First Empire. The xxii ANALYTICAL TABLE OF CONTENTS. PAGE Charter of 1814. The Revolution of 1830. Revolution of 1848 and the Second Republic. The Second Empire. Revo- lution of 1870 and the Third Republic. III. Romance Coun- tries, i. Sicily. 2. Spain. 3. Portugal. 4. Brazil. 5. Italy. 6. Belgium. IV. Teutonic countries outside Germany. i. Sweden. 2. Norway. 3. Denmark. 4. Holland. V. German States. The Empire. The rise of Prussia. The Confederation of the Rhine. The Confederation of 1815. Constitutions after 1815. New movements after 1830. Prussia. Austria. Pro- posed German Constitution of 1849. North German Con- federation, 1867. The German Empire, 1871. Resume. CHAPTER XV 426 B. False ideas of Constitutional Monarchy. Errors : i. That the king has executive power only. 2. That the king is purely passive. 3. That the royal power is exercised by the ministers. 4. That the king's personal character is unimportant. 5. That the king 'reigns but does not govern.' 6. That the king must obey the will of the majority. CHAPTER XVI . . 431 C. The Monarchical Principle and the Conception of Constitu- tional Monarchy. The essential characteristics of Monarchy. They allow legislative checks and ministerial responsibility, but not a merely formal or subordinate monarchy. Necessary free- dom of the monarch. His relations with the legislature and ministers. Power and rights of the Constitutional Monarch. General characteristics of Constitutional Monarchy. CHAPTER XVII. Aristocracy. I. The Greek Form. Sparta 439 Origin of the Spartan Aristocracy. Its exclusiveness. Educa- tion. Internal equality. Institutions : the Ecclesia ; the Senate ; Kings and Ephors. Artificial character of the Constitution. Its durability. CHAPTER XVIII. II. The Roman Aristocracy . . . 444 Comparison of the Spartan and Roman constitutions. Aristo- cratic character of the latter is obvious in (i) the relations of classes ; (2) the national assemblies, the Comitia Tributa, the Comitia Curiata, the Comitia Centuriata ; (3) the Senate ; (4) the Magistracies. CHAPTER XIX. III. Remarks upon Aristocracy . . .451 The essential principle of Aristocracy. Its exclusiveness is often fatal. Various forms of Aristocracy. General characteristics : ANALYTICAL TABLE OF CONTENTS. xxiii PAGE (i) external pomp ; (2) harshness of rule ; (3) excessive rigidity ; (4) excessive attachment to hereditary right ; (5) devotion to law. Decline of Aristocracy. CHAPTER XX. Democratic Forms of the State. I. Direct Democracy (Ancient) 458 Difference between ancient and modern Democracy. Demo- cracy in Greece. The Athenian Constitution : the Ecclesia, its powers and character ; the Senate ; the Archons ; the Judicial Courts. CHAPTER XXI. II. Criticism of Direct Democracy . . 464 Characteristics of Direct Democracy. Danger of popular passion and caprice. Importance of national character. The love of equality. Ostracism. Direct Democracy can only thrive in a small and backward state. CHAPTER XXII. III. Representative Democracy and the Modern Bepublic 469 Direct has been superseded by Representative Democracy. I. Representative Democracy originates in America. Causes of its origin. New England. Virginia. Carolina. New York and Pennsylvania. Common elements of the Colonial Constitutions. The Union. 2. France. 3. Switzerland. Differences of ancient and modern Democracy. The sovereignty in representative Democracies. The administrative power. Jurisdiction. Local administration. CHAPTER XXIII. IV. Consideration of Representative Demo- cracy ..... ...... 480 Difficulty of securing the best representatives. Danger of re- garding quantity rather than quality. Practical rules. Advan- tages and disadvantages of Representative Democracy, (i) The weakness of authority. (2) Want of pomp and concentration. (3) Excellence of public institutions. (4) Neglect of culture. (5) Elevation of public character. CHAPTER XXIV. Composite Forms of the State . . .485 Various forms of Composite States. i. The Absolute rule of one State over others. 2. The suzerainty or protectorate of one State over others. 3. The rule of the Mother-country over Colonies. 4. Confederation and Personal Union. 5. Federation, Federal Empire, and R.eal Union. Necessary conditions of Composite States. xxiv ANALYTICAL TABLE OF CONTENTS. BOOK VII. SOVEREIGNTY AND ITS ORGANS. PUBLIC SERVICES AND PUBLIC OFFICES. CHAPTER I. The Conception of Sovereignty .... 493 The term ' Sovereignty.' Conception of Sovereignty in France. Sovereignty as absolute power. German terms for Sovereignty. Characteristics of Sovereignty. CHAPTER II. Sovereignty of the People or of the State, and Sovereignty of the Ruler 497 (i) Sovereignty of the People as the sum of individuals. This is anarchy. (2) Sovereignty of the People as citizens in their assemblies. This only possible in direct Democracy. (3) Yet these views have been put forward as universally valid. (4) The Sovereignty of Reason or Justice ? (5) Of the People as a unity. (6) Sovereignty of the Nation or the State. (7) Sovereignty of the Ruler. CHAPTER III. I. Analysis of the Sovereignty of the State . 506 (i) Majesty. (2) Independence. (3) Power of choosing and altering the form of government : Reform : Revolution. Is there a ' right of revolution '? (4) Legislation. (5) Dependence on it of all other powers in the State. (6) Irresponsibility. (7) Re- sponsibility to it of all other powers in the State. CHAPTER IV. II. Sovereignty of the Prince . . . .511 The Sovereignty of the chief of the State not recognised in modern Republics, but in all Monarchies, elective as well as here- ditary. -It may be either (i) Original, or (2) Derived. CHAPTER V. The Division of Powers. I. The Primary As- semblies of Antiquity . . . . . . -513 Direct legislative assemblies : inferior to representative. * CHAPTER VI. II. Ancient Distinction of Political Functions 515 Ancient Distinction of Political Functions. Aristotle's division. Different functions often exercised by the same persons in Greece and Rome. Distinction between Civil and Military offices in the Byzantine Empire. In the Middle Ages little differ- entiation. Bodin urges the separation of the judicial functions, CHAPTER VII. III. The Modern Principle of division of Powers . . . . . . . . . .518 Montesquieu. The higher organism has the more differentiated functions. Distinction, not separation. The threefold division. ANALYTICAL TABLE OF CONTENTS. xxv PAGE Additions to it. These different powers not equal. Not the propositions of a syllogism. A. The legislative power. Views of Rousseau and Stein criticised. B. The other powers of the State. I. Government or Administration. The term i Execu- tive' criticised: The essence of Government. II. The Judicial power. Other powers : III. and IV. Superintendence of intel- lectual and material interests. CHAPTER VIII. Public Service and Public Functions . .526 Public Service in a wider and narrower sense. Not all public servants are State officials. Difference between administrative and judicial functionaries. Official assistants. Distinction be- tween civil and military offices. Distinction between collegiate and individual offices. Distinction according to locality. What office implies. Relation between the State and its servants. Salary. CHAPTER IX. Appointment of Officials 531 Hereditary offices. Distinction between professional and hon- orary offices. Officials in Germany ; in England ; in the United States; in France. In Republics appointments generally for a definite period. Liberty of acceptance or refusal. When an ap- pointment begins. CHAPTER X. Bights and Duties of Public Officials . .537 Exercise of functions. Title and rank. Indemnity for expenses. Salary. Pension. Duties of Obedience, Fidelity. Secrecy. Punishment and discipline. CHAPTER XI. Termination of Public Service . . . 545 i. Suppression of an office. 2. Resignation 3. Retirement. 4. Dismissal. 5. Suspension. THE THEORY OF THE STATE INTRODUCTION. CHAPTER I. POLITICAL SCIENCE. POLITICAL Science (die Statswissenschaft) in the proper Political sense is the science which is concerned with the State, fined" 06 which endeavours to understand and comprehend the State in its conditions (Grundlageri), in its essential nature ( Wesen\ its various forms or manifestations (Erscheinungs- formeri], its development. Thus many sciences, which are sometimes regarded as it does not political sciences, are not really such, although they relate certafn to the State and must of course be taken account of as whlSTare auxiliary. Such are : ?" h iHary (a) The History of a people or nation, except in so far as it is exclusively political or constitutional history. The general course of events in a people's life, the acts of individuals, the history of art, science, economic conditions, morals, diplomatic and political struggles, military affairs all these form no part of political science. (b) Statistics, so far as they include social and private matters and are not exclusively political. (c) Political Economy (Nationalokonomie), so far as it is an enquiry into economic laws which are applicable to every one and not merely to the State. B 2 INTRODUCTION. [Chap. I. (cl) The study of society, so far as the life of society goes on of itself and is; not .identical with the life of the State. Political The ancient Greeks applied the name TroXmio; to all videlTimo' political science. We [Germans] distinguish Public Law SdFoliSS. (Statsrechf] and Politics (PolitiK) as two special sciences. Alongside of these we put many special branches with distinct names, e. g. Political Statistics, Administration, International Law ( Volkerrecht\ Police, &c. Public Law and Politics both consider the State on the whole, but each from a different point of view and in a different direction. In order to understand the State more thoroughly, we distinguish its two main aspects its existence and its life. We examine the parts in order more completely to comprehend the whole. In this procedure there are not only theoretic but practical advantages. Law (das Rechf) has gajned in clearness, moderation, and strength, since it has been more sharply distinguished from politics ; and Politics has gained in fullness and in freedom by being considered separately. Public Law (Statsrechf) deals with the State as it is, i.e. its normal arrangements, the permanent conditions of its existence. Politics (PolitiK], on the other hand, has to do with the life and conduct of the State, pointing out the end towards which public efforts are directed and teaching the means which lead to these ends, observing the action of laws upon facts and considering how to avoid injurious consequences and how to remedy the defects of existing arrangements. Public Law is thus related to Politics as order to freedom, as the tranquil fixedness of relations to their complex move- ment, as bodies are related to their actions and to the various mental movements. QPublic Law asks whether what is conforms to law : Politics whether the action conforms to the end in view.^ Public Law Both Public Law and Politics have a moral content (em distingd^cd sittlicher Gehalt\ The State has a moral nature (ist ein from Ethics. ^///^ Weseri) and moral duties. But Law and Politics Chap. I.] POLITICAL SCIENCE. 3 are not determined solely nor completely by moral laws (Sittengesetz}. They are independent sciences, and not simply chapters of a Moral Philosophy. On the contrary, their basis and their end are to be found in the State : they are Political Sciences. Ethics, however, is not a Political Science, because its fundamental principles cannot be explained out of the State, but have a wider and nobler basis in the universal nature of mankind and in the divine ordering of the world. Public Law and Politics must not be absolutely separated Their rek- from one another. The actual State lives, i. e. it is a com- another?" bination of Law and Politics. Again, Law is not absolutely fixed or unalterable ; and the movement of Politics has rest as its aim. Law is not merely a system, it has a history ; on the other hand, Politics has to do with legislation. As with all organic beings, the influence is reciprocal. The difference we have recognised is not thereby set aside, but is better explained. The distinction between the history of Law (Rechtsgeschichte) and political history is just this : the former has only to point out the development of the normal and established existence of the State and to describe the rise and change of permanent institutions and laws : the latter lays stress chiefly on the changing fortunes and cir- cumstances of the nation, the motives and conduct of its statesmen, and the actions and sufferings of both the nation and its statesmen. The highest and purest expression of Public Law is 10 be found in the Constitution or enacted positive laws (die Verfassung: das Gesetz] : the clearest and most vivid manifestation of Politics is the practical conduct or guidance of the State itself, viz. Government (Regierun^. \ Politics is more of an art than a science. Law is a pre- supposition of Politics, a fundamental (though not of course the only) condition of its freedom. Politics in its course must have regard to legal limits, caring as it does for the varying needs of life. Law, on the other hand, requires the help of Politics in order to escape the numbness of death and to keep step with the development of life. B 2 4 INTRODUCTION. Without the animating breath of politics the corpus juris (Rechtskorper) would be a corpse ; without the foundations and the limits of Law, Politics would perish in unbridled selfishness and in a fatal passion for destruction. The Theory It is solely for the sake of clearness and simplicity that inrZterai before these two branches of the Theory of the State siderecTfirst. Public Law and Politics we place a third, or rather a first, division of Political Science, viz. The Theory of the State in general (Allgemeine Statslehre). In this we consider the State as a whole without as yet distinguishing its two aspects (Law and Politics). The conception of the State, its basis, its principal elements (the people, the country), its rise, its end or aim, the chief forms of its constitution, the definition and the division of sovereignty (Statsgcwalf) form the subjects of the Theory of the State in general, and this in turn is at the base of the two special political sciences, Public Law and Politics. The first part of this work is devoted to the Theory of the State in General, the second to Public Law, and the third to Politics. [Note. The present translation only comprises this first part.] CHAPTER II. SCIENTIFIC METHODS. THE scientific study of the State may be undertaken from different points of view and in different ways. There are two sound methods of scientific enquiry, and two false Methods methods which are the one-sided perversions of them. The fd s e e . an correct methods, we may call the philosophical and the historical. The perversions come from pushing to an extreme one prominent aspect of the first two methods. Abstract ideology is the exaggeration and caricature of the philosophical, mere empiricism of the historical method. The contrast between the two methods is connected partly with the characteristics of both Law and Politics, partly with the difference in the intellectual temperaments of those who have pursued these studies. All Law and all Politics have an ideal side a moral and spiritual element, but both at the same time rest on a real (actual) foundation and have a material form and value. This latter side is misunderstood and disregarded by the ideologist, who thinks out some political principle in its ideology, abstractness and draws from it a series of logical con- sequences without paying any regard to the facts of actual political society. Even Plato in his Republic has fallen into this error and adopted opinions contrary to nature and the needs of mankind ; and yet the richness of Plato's spirit and his feeling for beauty have saved him from those miserably arid formulas which we find so often in the INTRODUCTION. [Chap. II. political philosophy of modern writers. The State is a moral organism and not the product of mere cold Logic : Public Law is not a collection of speculative opinions. This method leads to unfruitful results in theory, and when transferred to practice gives a most dangerous in- fluence to fixed ideas and tends to break up and destroy existing political institutions. In times of revolution men's passions are set free and they are attracted by these abstract doctrines, the more so that they hope by their aid to break through the bounds of law : and this sort of ideology easily obtains a terrible force, and, incapable of creating a new organism, throws down everything before it with the energy of a demon. The truth of this observation is proved in a fearful way by certain phases of the French Revolution. Napoleon was right when he said : ' The Metaphysicians, the Ideologists have, destroyed France.' The ideological acceptation of ' Liberty and Equality ' has filled France with ruins and drenched it with blood. The doctrinaire application of the * monarchical principle,' has repressed the political freedom of Germany and hindered the growth of her power. The carrying out of the abstract principle of nationality has threatened the peace of all Europe. The truest and most fruitful ideas become mischievous if they are taken up by ideologists and then transferred to practice by narrow fanatics. Empiricism. The exclusively empirical method is one-sided in the opposite way ; it holds to the mere outward form, to the letter of the law or to the apparent fact. This method in science is valuable at the most in amassing material in compilations; in actual politics it frequently gains many adherents, especially among the officials of a bureaucracy. Empiricism does not often, like ideology, directly endanger the whole State ; but it makes the bright sword of justice rust, hinders the public welfare in all sorts of ways, causes a quantity of small injuries, weakens the moral vigour and enfeebles the health of the State in such wise that in critical times its salvation is made always difficult and Chap. II.] SCIENTIFIC METHODS. 7 sometimes impossible. While the practical application of mere ideology brings the State into the acute crisis of political fever, this mere empiricism rather produces chronic maladies. The advantage of the historical over the merely empirical The histori- method is that it does not thoughtlessly and servilely honour actual institutions and actual facts, but recognises, explains, and interprets the inner connection between Past and Present, the organic development of national life and the moral idea as revealed in its history. This method cer- tainly starts from the actual phenomena, but regards them as living, not as dead. Akin to the truly historical is the truly philosophical Thephiio- method, which is not one of mere abstract speculation but s of ' concrete thinking ' a (concret denkt\ i. e. it unites together "" Ideas and Facts (Idee und Realitaf). While the historical method is based upon the course of outward events and their evolution, the philosophical starts from the knowledge of the human mind, and from that point of view considers the revelation of the spirit of man in history. Most of those who have attained to a higher scientific These standpoint have through natural temperament gone in either United by the one or the other direction. Only a few have had the wrltfrs ate ' genius to unite both. Among these Aristotle especially deserves our admiration. His ' Politics/ although written in that youthful period of the world's history which preceded the more advanced development of the State, has yet re- mained for two thousand years one of the purest sources of political wisdom. Cicero imitated, in the form of his rea- soning and his mode of exposition, the philosophical manner of the more richly gifted Greeks, but the best part of the material of his work he rightly took from the practical politics of Rome. Among modern writers, Bodin, Vico, and Bacon may be named as early representatives of the philosophic-historical method. Burke, who resembles Cicero a [For an explanation of this phrase of German philosophy see Wallace's Translation of Hegel's Logic, Prolegomena, Ch. x.] 8 INTRODUCTION. [Chap. II. in the grandeur and charm of his eloquence, resembles him also in the way in which he grasped the principles of politi- cal wisdom from the history and life of his country, and ex- pressed them with the dignity of philosophy and the splendour of genius. Machiavelli, who has stored up in his works the abundant and sad experience of a profound and shrewd knowledge of mankind, and Montesquieu who looked on the world with a frank, cheerful glance and abounds in acute remarks and exact observations, some- times adopt one method, sometimes the other. Yet the former is more given to the historical, the latter to the philosophical *. On the other hand, Rousseau and Ben- tham, like most of the Germans, keep rather to the philo- sophical method, but, more often than their great model Plato, they fall into the one-sided error of mere ideology. The his- It is thus clear that the two methods, the historical and philosophical philosophical, do not conflict : they rather supplement and supplement correct one another. He assuredly takes a limited and each < other t narrow view of history who thinks that with him history is at an end and no new legal conception (Rechf) can arise ; and he is a vain and foolish philosopher who thinks that he is the beginning and end of all truth. The genuine his- torian as such is compelled to recognise the value of philo- sophy, and the true philosopher must equally take counsel . of history. ^ Each of the two methods has its peculiar advantages and its peculiar weaknesses and dangers. The chief advantage of the historical method is the abundance and the positive character of its results ; for history is full of the complexity of life and at the same time is thoroughly positive. What- ever the most prolific thinker may think out in his head will always be only a poor fragment compared with the thoughts which are revealed in the history of mankind, and will generally attain only an uncertain and misty shape. But, on the other hand, there is the dangi that, in following the b [So in German (ed. 1875). The French Transl. (2nd edit.) re- verses the remark.] Chap. II.] SCIENTIFIC METHODS. 9 " paths of history, we may forget and lose unity in abundant multiplicity ; we may be oppressed by the weight of the material, overwhelmed by the mass of historical experience, and above all, attracted and enchained by the past, we may lose the fresh outlook on the life of the present and the future. Certainly these are by no means necessary conse- quences of the historical method, but history itself shows us how often men who have given themselves ardently to the study of it go wrong in this way. The advantages of the philosophical method, on the con- trary, are : purity, harmony and unity of system, fuller satis- faction of the universal striving of man towards perfection, ideality. Its results have an especially human character, an especially ideal stamp. And yet, in turn, it has its peculiar dangers : philosophers, in their striving after unity which they often regard as their sole aim, overlook the inner complexity of nature, and the rich content of actual exist- _ence ; following the swift flight of free thought, not infre- quently, instead of discovering real laws, they find barren formulae, empty husks, and take to playing with these ; mis- understanding the natural development, they pluck unripe fruit, plant trees without roots in the ground, and sink into the delusions of ideology. Only a few philosophical spirits have succeeded in avoiding these errors. Note. In what I wrote in 1841 on l The modern schools of Juris- prudence in Germany* (Die neueren Rechtsschulen der deutschen Juristen, 2nd edit. Zurich, 1862), these and similar ideas have been followed out in closer connection with German scientific study. Long ago, however, the English Lord Chancellor, Bacon, censured the errors of the Law of Nature and the positive jurisprudence as studied in his time and expected the necessary reform in the science of law from the combination of history with philosophy. [Cp. De Augm. Scient. viii, c. 3. But see Flint's Vico, p. 151.] CHAPTER III. GENERAL AND SPECIAL POLITICAL SCIENCE. SPECIAL Political Science is limited to a particular nation and a single State, e. g. the ancient Roman Republic, the modern English Constitution, the German Empire of to-day. General Political Science, on the other hand, rests upon a universal conception of THE State. The particular State is based on a particular people, the State in general on mankind \ The general theory of the State, and especially general Public Law, is very often held to be the product of pure speculation, and the attempt is made to deduce it, by mere logical consequences, from a speculative view of the world. Thus there have arisen various systems of Natural or Philosophical ' Public Law,' as distinct from that which is Positive and Historical. I understand the difference other- wise. The State must be philosophically comprehended as well as historically. Neither General nor Special Public Law can dispense with this twofold work. The special theory of the State presupposes the general, as the particular character of a people presupposes the 1 The same idea is at the base of the Roman view. L. 9 (Gains} D. de Justitia et Jure : ' Omnes populi, qui legibus et moribus reguntur, partim suo proprio, partim communi omnium hominum jure utuntur. Nam quod quisque populus ipse sibi jus constituit, id ipsius proprium civitatis est, vocaturque/w^ civile ; quod vero naturalis ratio inter omnes homines constituit, id apud omnes peraeque custoditur, vocatnrque jus gentium, quasi quo jure omnes gentes utuntur.' [Justinian, Inst. Lib. I. Tit. ii. i.] GENERAL POLITICAL SCIENCE. 1 1 common nature of mankind. General Political Science has General to do with the fundamental conceptions, which appear in all science is sorts of ways, in the theories of particular States. The his- j^nfvlrsai tory to which the former pays regard is the history of the Hlstor y- World or universal history, not the history of a particular country, and of a particular State. The speculations of Political Philosophy must be tested and supplemented by the actual history of mankind. Universal history shows us the different stages of development which mankind has lived through since its infancy ; each stage has its ow r n peculiar views of the State, and its own political formations. We learn to understand in what ways the various nations have taken part in the common task of the human race. Not all. periods of universal history, nor all nations, have what periods the same significance for our science. We are specially raceslu-e 1 concerned with the modern State. The ancient and si g" ificant - mediaeval forms of the State need only be considered as preliminary, and in order, by contrast, to bring out more clearly the character of the modern State. The value of different peoples for the formation of the modern State is determined in general by their share in the progress of political civilisation, i. e. of a community of men at once orderly and free. In the history of the world, the Aryan or Indo-Germanic race is as significant for politics as the Semitic race for religion ; but not until they came to Europe did even the Aryans attain a high and conscious political development. Among them the Greeks and Romans took precedence in antiquity, the Teutons (Germanen) in the Middle Ages ; but our modern political civilisation depends chiefly on the mixture of Graeco-Roman and Teutonic elements. The chief share in this modern political develop- ment has been taken by: (i) the English, whose very race is a mixed one, (2) secondly by the French, who combine Old Celtic and Romance with Teutonic elements, and (3) lastly the Prussians, in whom the manly self-confidence and sense of Law (Rechtssinn) of the Teuton is combined with the pliancy and submissiveness of the Slav. The political 12 INTRODUCTION. life of America is derived from that of Europe, but it is only in the United States that it has made progress of its own. General political science has thus to do with the common political consciousness of civilised mankind at the present time, and the fundamental ideas and essentially common institutions which appear in various ways in different States. Even General Public Law is no mere theory it has a positive although indirect influence, as it operates through various particular States, and not through one universal State. Like mankind and his history, it has a real, and not merely an ideal existence. Note. The contrast in Aristotle's Rhetoric (i. 10. 1368 b. 7) between VOJJLOS 'tSios and VO^DS KOIVOS is different from that which we have been considering. The former means the Law which a particular state has worked out for itself, whether written or unwritten, the latter that which is right by nature ((pvafi KOIVOV Sifcaiov) without regard to any political community. BOOK I. THE CONCEPTION OF THE STATE. CHAPTER I. THE CONCEPTION AND IDEA OF THE STATE. 7 HE GENERAL CONCEPTION OF THE STATE. THE conception (Begriff] of the State has to do with the nature and essential characteristics of actual States. The idea or ideal (Idee) of the State presents a picture, in the splendour of imaginary perfection, of the State as not yet realised, but to be striven for. The conception of the State can only be discovered by The concep- history ; the idea of the State is called up by philosophical sSL ar- e speculation. The universal conception of the State is re- SSj^. b t he cognised when the many actual States which have appeared ^osophy in the world's history have been surveyed, and their common characteristics discovered. The highest idea of the State is beheld when the tendency of human nature to political society is considered, and the highest conceivable and possible development of this tendency is regarded as the political end of mankind. If we consider the great number of States which history character- presents to us, we become aware at once of certain common Itatesf ** characteristics of all States ; others are only seen on closer examination. ^ First, it is clear that in every State a number of men are i. a number combined. In particular States the number may be very different, some embracing only a few thousands, others many millions ; but, nevertheless, we cannot talk of a State 1 6 THE CONCEPTION OF THE STATE. [Book I. until we get beyond the circle of a single family, and until a multitude of men (i.e. families, men, women, and chil- dren) are united together. A family, a clan, like the house of the Hebrew patriarch, Jacob, can become the nucleus round which, in time, a greater number gathers, but a real State cannot be formed until that has happened, until the single family has broken up into a series of families, and kindred has become extended to the race. The horde is not yet a tribe (V others chaff}. Without a tribe, or, at a higher stage of civilisation, without a nation ( Volk\ there is no State. There is no normal number for the size of the population of a State rt ; Rousseau's number of 10,000 men would cer- tainly not be sufficient. In the middle ages such small States could exist with security and dignity ; modern times lead to the formation of much greater States, partly because the political duties of the modern State need a greater national force, partly because the increased power of the great States readily becomes a danger and a menace to the independence of the small. 2. afixedf Secondly, a permanent relation of the people to the soil is necessary for the continuance of the State. The State requires its territory : nation and country go together. Nomadic peoples, although they have chiefs to command them and law to govern them, have not yet reached the full condition oY States until they have a fixed abode. The Hebrew people received a political training from Moses, but were not a State until Joshua settled them in Palestine. In the great migrations at the fall of the Roman empire, when peoples left their old habitations and undertook to conquer new ones, they were in an uncertain state of tran- sition. The earlier States which they had formed no longer existed : the new did not yet exist. The personal bond continued for a while the territorial connection was broken. a [For Aristotle's views on this subject, cp. Pol. vii. 4 : in Eth. Ntc. ix. 10. 3, he says there cannot be a State (TTO\IS} of ten men nor of 100,000. Cp. also Pol. Hi. 3. 5.] Chap. I.] WHAT THE STATE IMPLIES. 17 Only if they succeeded in regaining a sure footing were they enabled to establish a new State. The peoples who failed perished. The Athenians under Themistocles saved the State of Athens on their ships, because after the victory they again took possession of their city ; but the Cimbri and Teutones perished, because they left their old home and failed to conquer a new one. Even the Roman State would have perished, if the Romans, after the burning of their city, had migrated to Veii. i Another characteristic of the State is the unity of the 3- unity; whole, the cohesion of the nation. Internally there may indeed be different divisions with considerable indepen- dence of their own. Thus in Rome there was the patrician populus, and alongside of it the plebs. In the older Teutonic states of the middle ages there was the constitution of the people alongside of the feudal constitution. The State may also be composed of several parts which in their turn constitute States : thus from the old German Empire several territorial States have gradually grown up : in the modern federations of North America and Switzerland, and in the new German Empire, a common collective State (Gesammt- staf] and a number of confederated local States exist together. But unless the community forms a coherent whole in its internal organisation, or can appear and act as a unit in external relations, there is no State. In all States we find the distinction (Gegensatz) between 4- distinction between governors and governed, or to adopt an old expression rulers and which has been sometimes misunderstood, sometimes 'mis- S1 used, but which in itself is neither hateful nor slavish between sovereign and subjects. This distinction appears in the most manifold forms, but is always necessary. Even in the most extreme democracy in which it may seem to vanish, it is nevertheless present. The assembly of the Athenian citizens was the sovereign, the individual Athe- nians were its subjects. Where there is no longer any sovereign possessing authority, where the governed have renounced political C 1 8 THE CONCEPTION OF THE STATE. [Book r. obedience, and every one does that which is right in his own eyes, this is anarchy and the State is at an end. Anarchy, like all negations, cannot last, so that out of it there at once arises, perhaps in a rude and often cruel form of despotism, some sort of new sovereignty which compels obedience, and thus reproduces that indispensable distinc- tion. Communists deny this in theory, but in doing so, they deny the State itself. Even they have nowhere been able by annihilating the State to introduce a merely social union, and, if they ever succeed in temporarily winning over the masses to their projects, we may be certain, from the example of the religious communists of the sixteenth century, the Anabaptists, and from the natural consequences of events, that they too would again set up a domination, and that the harshest that has ever been. Amt)IIgme Slavonic peoples we find the old idea that only the unanimity of all the members of a community represents the common will, and that neither the majority nor any higher authority can decide. This principle how- ever can at the most only serve as a principle of local communities, and that only among a people where all easily and quickly agree ; it can never be a political principle, for the State must override the unavoidable opposition of individuals. 5. an organic The State is in no way a lifeless instrument, a dead machine : it is a living and therefore organised being. This organic nature of the State has not always been understood. Political peoples had indeed an image ( Vorstellung) of it, and recognized it consciously in language, but the insight into the political organism remained long concealed from political science, and even at the present day many publi- cists (Statsgelehrte) fail to understand it. It is the especial merit of the German school of historical jurists to have recognized the organic nature of the Nation and the State. This conception refutes both the mathematical and mechanical view of the State, and the atomistic way of treating it, which forgets the whole in the individuals. An Chap. I.] WHAT THE STATE IMPLIES. 19 oil-painting is something other than a mere aggregation of drops of oil and colour, a statue is something other than a combination of marble particles, a man is not a mere quan- tity of cells and blood corpuscles ; and so too the nation is not a mere sum of citizens, and the State is not a mere collection of external regulations. The State indeed is not a product of nature, and there- fore it is not a natural organism ; it is indirectly the work of man. The tendency to political life is to be found in / human nature, and so far the State has a natural basis ; / but the realisation of this political tendency has been left to / human labour a , and human arrangement, and so far the ' State is a product of human activity, and its organism is a copy of a natural organism. In calling the State an organism we are not thinking of in what the activities by which plants and animals seek, consume state is In and assimilate nourishment, and reproduce their species. orgam We are thinking rather of the following characteristics of natural organisms : (a) Every organism is a union of soul and body, i. e. of material elements and vital forces. (b) Although an organism is and remains a whole, yet in its parts it has members, which are animated by special motives and capacities, in order to satisfy in various ways the varying needs of the whole itself. (c) The organism develops itself from within outwards, and has an external growth. In all three respects the organic nature of the State is evident. In the State spirit and body, will and active organs are () The necessarily bound together in one life. The one national spirit and spirit, which is something different from the average sum of y< the contemporary spirit of all citizens, is the spirit of the State; the one national will, which is different from the a [Cp. Arist. Pol. i. 2. 15, 1253 a. 30: &vffi nlv ovv fj opfjirj irdffiv km TT)J/ TOiavTrjv Koivwiav 6 8 irpuros ffvarrjaas fj.eyiarojv curtof,] C 3 20 THE CONCEPTION OF THE STATE. [Book I. average will of the multitude, is the will of the State. The constitution, with its organs for representing the whole and expressing the will of the State in laws, with a head who governs, with all sorts of offices and magistracies for admin- istration, with courts to exercise public justice, with institu- tions of all kinds to provide for the intellectual and material interests of the community, with an army to express the public force this constitution is the body of the State, it is the form in which the nation manifests its common life. Individual States differ like individual men in spirit, character, and form. The progress of mankind depends essentially on the emulation of its component peoples and states. the State, we learn from it at the same time that the State does not stand on the same grade with the lower organisms of plants and animals, but is of a higher kind ; we learn that it is a moral and spiritual organism, a great body which is capable of taking up into itself the feelings and thoughts of the nation, of uttering them in laws, and realising them in acts ; we are informed of moral qualities and of the character of each State. History ascribes to the State a personality which, having spirit and body, possesses and manifests a will of its own. The glory and honour of the State have always elevated the heart of its sons, and animated them to sacrifices. For freedom and independence, for the rights of the State, the noblest and best have in all times and in all nations ex- pended their goods and their lives. To extend the reputa- tion and the power of the State, to further its welfare and its happiness, has universally been regarded as one of the most honourable duties of gifted men. The joys and sorrows of the State have always been shared by all its citizens. The whole great idea of Fatherland and love of country would be inconceivable if the State did not possess this high moral and personal character. The recognition of the personality of the State is thus not less indispensable for Public Law (Sfatsrech?) than for International Law ( Volkerrecht]. A person in the juridical sense is a being to whom we can ascribe a legal will (Rechtswille), who can acquire, create and possess rights. In the realm of public law this conception is as significant as in the realm of private law. The State is par excellence a person in the sense of public law (pffentlich-rechtliche Person). The purpose of the whole constitution is to enable the person of the State to express and realise its will (Statswille\ which is different from the individual wills of all individuals, and different from the sum of them. The personality of the State is ; however, only recognised Chap. I.] WHA T THE ' STA TE IMPLIES. 2 3 by free people, and only in the civilised nation-state has it attained to full efficacy. In the earlier stages of politics only the prince is prominent ; he alone is a person, and the State is merely the realm of his personal rule. The same is true with regard to the masculine character 7 . The of the modern State. This becomes first apparent in con- masclifme. trast with the feminine character of the Church. A religious community may have all the other characteristics of a political community, yet she does not wish to be a State, and is not a State, just because she does not consciously rule herself like a man, and act freely in her external life, but wishes only to serve God and perform her religious duties. To put together the result of this historical con- sideration, the general conception of the State may be determined as follows : the State is a combination or association (Gesammtheif) of men, in the form of govern- ment and governed, on a definite territory, united together into a moral organised masculine personality ; or, more shortly-ythe State is the politically organised national person-^J of a definite country. Notes. i. It is not without interest to observe how different peoples Different have named the State. The Greeks still signified city and state by the ^state* same word, 7ro\ts a sign that their conception of the State was based on the city, and was limited by the city point of view. The Roman expression, civitas, refers likewise to the citizenship of a city as the nucleus of the State, but has more of a personal character than the Greek word, and is better adapted to take up into itself greater masses of people. It speaks too for the high significance of the State, that the expression ' civilisation ' is derived from the name of the State, and practically coincides with the extension and realisation of the State. In a certain way the other Roman name, res publica, stands still higher, in so, far as it contains not merely a reference to the citizenship of a city, but to a people (res populi}, and a regard to the people's welfare. In the sense of the ancients the expression Republic does not exclude Monarchy but does not apply to despotic governments. [Cp. Engl. ' Commonwealth.'] In modern languages the expression ' State ' is the prevailing one, not only in the Romance but in the Teutonic languages (stato, etat> Staf). In itself completely indifferent (it signifies originally any condition, and 24 THE CONCEPTION OF THE STATE. at first the fuller expression status reipublicae was required in order to bring out a more exact reference to the State), this term in course of time has become the most universal denomination of the State, un- ambiguous and needing no qualification. Although ' the established,' * what stands,' is brought into prominence, this connexion is put aside, and the word signifies not the existing arrangement and constitution of the State (iroXireia), but the State which can outlive even a complete transformation of the form of government. All other modern expressions have only limited validity ; e.g. the proud word Reich only applies to great states under a monarchical organisation, and suggests likewise a combination of several relatively independent countries, like the Latin word imperium (Fr. and EngL empire), in which at the same time there is an allusion to the imperial (kaiscrlick) rule. More narrow is the sense of the word ' country ' (Land), which primarily signifies the external territory of the State (and of a state that is not broken up into separate parts), but secondarily is applied to the State itself which has this territory. This expression forms the natural counterpart to the Greek -noXis, since it bases the State primarily on the country (Landschaft), while the other bases it on the city. The fine word ' Fatherland ' is still narrower, by virtue of its relation to the individual ; but at the same time it is elevated and spiritualised by the reference to the personal connexion and transmission of blood relationships in the country : in this word is expressed with clearness and with feeling the whole love and devotion of the individual citizen to the great and living whole to which he belongs with his body, with whose existence his own is bound up, and for which to sacrifice himself is the highest glory of man 1 . 2. In my Pyschological Studies on State and Church (Zurich, 1845) the masculine character of the State has been more exactly worked out. The French expression, L'etat cest I'homme, does not merely signify ' the State is Man in general' (der Mensch im Groszen), but ' the State is the man, the husband (der Mann] in general,' as the Church repre- sents the womanly nature in general, the wife (die Frau\ [It may be as well to note that in German the word Stat is masculine and the word Kirche feminine !] 1 Cp. Eurip. Phoenissae 369-371 : dX HarpiSos tpav airavras. os 5' a\\ojs Aoyoiai xaipei, rbv 8e vovv exetcr' %x fl ' Schiller's William Tell : ' Cleave to thy fatherland, thy country dear, And with thy whole heart cling thou closely to it. For rooted in thy country is thy strength ; Away in yon strange world thou stand 'st alone.' CHAPTER II. THE HUMAN IDEA OF THE STATE. THE UNIVERSAL EMPIRE. CAN we rest satisfied with such a conception of the State as may be arrived at from a consideration of the various actual states which have existed ? The historical school is content to study the State as simply the body of this or that particular nation. Philosophy requires us to go deeper. We find in human The com- , , , , , ,. , . . , mon nature nature the tendency to, and the need for, political existence, of mankind Aristotle long ago uttered the pregnant truth, ' Man is by nedof I* 16 nature a political animal' (avQpuiros (frvo-u iroXiriKov foW. g?ate. rsal Pol. i. 2, 9). It is not any national peculiarity which makes him require the State, and capable of it, but the common nature of mankind. Further, in enquiring into the organism of different States, we discover that the same essential organs are to be found in very different nations. There is everywhere to be recognised a common human character, compared with which the special national forms are only like variations on the same theme. Finally, the conception of the nation is not fixed and determinate in itself : it points with inner necessity to the higher unity of mankind of which the nations are only members. How then could the State be based upon the nation without regard to a higher unity? and if mankind is in truth a whole, if it is animated by a common spirit, how can it avoid striving after the embodiment of its own proper essence, i. e. seeking to become a State ? 26 THE CONCEPTION OF THE STATE. [Book I. Merely national States have thus only a relative truth and significance. The philosopher cannot find in them the fulfilment of the highest idea of the State. To him the State is a human organism, a human person ; but if so, the human spirit which lives in it must also have a human body, for spirit and body belong to one another, and between them make up the person. In a body which is not organised and human the spirit of man cannot truly live. The body politic must therefore imitate the body natural of man. The perfect State is, as it were, the visible body of Humanity. The universal State or universal Empire ( WeltrcicK) is the ideal of human progress. Man as an individual, mankind as a whole, are" the original and permanent antithesis of creation. On this, in the last resort, depends the distinction between Private and Public Law. It is true the common consciousness of mankind is still confusedly dreaming : it has not yet awaked to full clearness, nor advanced to a unity of will. Mankind * has therefore not yet been able to evolve its organic exist- ence. It will take many centuries to realise the Universal State. But the longing for such an organised community of all nations has already revealed itself from time to time in the previous history of the world. Civilised Europe has already fixed her eye more firmly on this high aim. Attempts It is true that all historical attempts to realise the universal this universal State have, in the end, failed. It does not therefore follow past! in ' that the end is unattainable. The Christian Church cherishes the hope of one day including the whole of mankind, and, though this hope has not yet been fulfilled, its fulfilment is not therefore impossible. The Christian Church cannot give up the belief that it will become universal, and human politics cannot give up the effort to organise the whole of humanity. The idea of the universal State (WeltreicK) corresponds to the idea of the universal Church. History itself, if studied without prejudice, points out clearly enough the way which leads to this end, and warns us at the same time against the erroneous paths into which Chap. II.] THE UNIVERSAL STATE. 27 even political genius has strayed in attempting with the rashness of zeal to realise the universal State prematurely. Since first a human consciousness of the State arose in Europe, each age has made the attempt in its own way. First, Alexander the Great. In the marriage festival of i. The Em- a hundred couples at Susa, Alexander gave the world a Alexander symbol of his idea l . He wished to wed the manly spirit of the Great " the Greeks with the feminine quickness and susceptibility of the Asiatics. The East and the West were to be united and mingled together, and from the mingling of both, as in a cup of love, the new mankind was to issue, which should find its satisfaction in the realisation of a great divine and human empire. The culture of the following centuries was at all events determined by Alexander in this way, and the Greek seeds of civilisation grew luxuriantly in the new soil of Asia. But this first brilliant attempt to establish a world- state did not endure, and was hopelessly wrecked with the death of Alexander. This was not merely due to the sad fate which snatched away the founder of the new universal * state in the bloom of his youth, before he had established uniform institutions and taken care for the future. The mingling of diverse elements was unnatural, the leading idea itself was not clear. Political ideas were confused by the mixture : the free human view which the Greeks took of the State could not be united with the religious regard of the Persians for a divine kingdom. The Macedonian monarchy could not at 1 ' Accepto deinde imperio regem se terrarum omnium ac mundi appellari jussit/ Justin, xii. 16. Laurent, Hist, du droit des gens, ii. 5, 262 : [* Une barriere qui paraissait insurmontable separait les Grecs des etrangers. Alexandre s'eleva le premier au-dessus des prejuges de sa nation. Superieur au phi- losophe, son maitre, qui lui conseillait de traiter les Hellenes comme des amis et les Barbares comme des brutes, il concut la pensee de les unir, en abolissant toute difference entre les vainqueurs et les vaincus ... II epousa la fille de Darius et maria ses amis avec les Persanes les plus illustres : la ceremonie se fit a la maniere orientale. On celebra, par une fete magnifique, les noces de tons les Mace'doniens qui avaient epotise des Asiatiques : leurs noms, inscrits sur les registres, se mon- taient a plus de dix mille.'J 28 THE CONCEPTION OF THE STATE. [Book I. the same time be an Asiatic theocracy. The Orientals willingly believed that Alexander was the son of the most high God ; the Europeans were disgusted by his pretensions to divine honours. And races were confused. Hellenic science and culture freed the Oriental world from the limitations of its religious and political bonds ; but their effect was rather to break up the old than to create a new world. The deification of a man drove out reverence for the old gods : European civi- lisation became dissolute luxury, and helped to complete the degeneracy of the East. 2 . The The attempt of the Romans to attain a universal dominion Empire. had a more enduring result. The Roman Empire was a universal empire. The whole Roman people felt itself called to extend its idea of the State over the earth, and to subject all the nations to the Roman supremacy. The manly power and iron force of the Roman character over- came the numerous peoples who dared to oppose Rome's * victorious career, and already the Roman State with its legal institution as strong as rock had been built upon firm foundations in three continents. The greatest of the Romans, Julius Caesar, left to posterity the imperial idea (Kaiseridee) as an inheritance, and in it he has founded an authority which transcends national limits and embraces the world. Even the effort of the Romans has been judged at the bar of universal history. It was not,, like that of Alexander, based upon a mixture of peoples, but upon the higher nature of one people which sought to stamp its national character upon mankind, to Romanise the world. That was its crime. No people is great enough to include mankind, and to stifle other peoples in its embrace. The Roman universal State was wrecked by the resistance of the Teutons in the fresh- ness of their youth. It could not conquer the Germans ; and after centuries of struggle, it succumbed to them. 3. The The idea of the universal State has since then never Holy Roman shone with such splendour on the political horizon, but has never altogether set. The middle ages, with their com- Chap. II.] THE UNIVERSAL STATE. 29 bination of Romance and Teutonic elements, again at- tempted in their way to realise it, first in the Frankish monarchy and secondly in the Roman-German Empire on a more modest scale it -is true, but not without having made important progress in the knowledge of truth. There was no longer to be one supreme and absolute dominion ruling equally the whole life of the community. Christi- anity had in the meantime revealed the great opposition between State and Church, so full of consequences for mankind. The State gave up the claim to rule conscience by its laws ; it recognised that beside it there was a religious community with its own principle of life, and likewise a visible body different from itself, and essentially independent. This was a limit preventing it from exercising omnipotent sway. It was compelled to hand over religious life to the guidance of the Church. It never indeed attained to full clearness with regard to its relation to the Church, but the freedom of religious belief and the reverence for God were saved from the arbitrary will of the temporal ruler. The authority of Christianity depended not on him. Further, the Christian universal empire was no longer to devour and annihilate the various nations, but to assure to all of them peace and justice. The mediaeval Roman emperor was not absolute lord over all nations, but the just protector of their rights and freedom. The imperial idea was thus purified and became the inspiration of a statesman like Frederick II 2 and of a thinker like Dante 3 . The mediaeval empire embraced a great number of essentially independent States, united indeed in a common order and formally subject to the Emperor, but independent in all 2 Frederici Constit. Regni Siculi, i. 30 : ' Oportet Caesarem fore justitiae patrem et nlium, dominum et ministrnm ; patrem et dominum in edendo justitiam et editam conservando : sic et in venerando justitiam sit rilius et in ipsius copiam ministrando minister.' 3 His work, De Monarchia, glorifies the empire ; and . in his Divine Comedy he reverences the Emperor as the head of the divine ordering of the world. Cp. Wegele, Dante's Leben und IVerke, Jena, 1852. 30 THE CONCEPTION OF THE STATE. [Book I. essential matters, and living in their own way. Even the diversity of peoples and races found favour and protection. But what in itself was an advance in the development of the Universal State led to its dissolution, because pursued in a too one-sided manner. The tendency to separation was stronger than the impulse to unity. The difference of nationalities, the opposition of languages separated France and Germany and tore into two parts the Frankish universal monarchy. The slender powers of the German king and Roman emperor could not oppose the rise of princes and local lords. The central institution had no central basis, j and so the centrifugal forces were too strong for it, and the empire went to pieces ; the attempt failed again, but left important lessons to succeeding generations. 4 . The In the present century the Emperor Napoleon I again Napoleon i. attempted to revive the idea which for a time had been neglected. He avoided the error of the middle ages, and took precautions for a strong and active central power, but he did not retain the true advances of the middle ages with sufficient care. He paid too little regard to foreign nationa- lities, and thus went back on the course which the Romans had previously adopted, although acting with more modera- tion than they. He wished to organise Europe as a vast international State, with individual States as its members. The imperial power was to belong to the French nation, which was to take the place of head in the great family of nations. He hoped to attain in one generation what the Romans had taken centuries to do. His plan failed. Not this time because of the resistance of the German people. They submitted reluctantly to the French supremacy ; but despairing of their own old empire, and discontented with the circumstances of their fatherland, they appeared to submit to Napoleon's arrangements. Only the two great German States, aspiring Prussia and Austria with its com- plexity of countries and peoples, the former anxious about its very existence, the latter feeling itself an imperial State, sought in repeated wars to resist the supremacy of France ; Chap. II.] THE UNIVERSAL STATE. 31 but they too were conquered by superior statesmen and generals. But Napoleon failed to overcome the resistance of the English, in whom a great and historical national sen- timent was united with Teutonic ideas of freedom : and the still half barbarian Russians withdrew to their steppes, de- feated but not subdued. The French did not hold out in ^*l .X ff^ misfortune when united Europe turned upon them. Thus y^/ the Napoleonic idea failed of fulfilment like the Roman before it, and for similar reasons. The remaining nations \ felt themselves threatened by the universal monarchy with- out being assured or contented by the new government of the world, and the French nation was not powerful enough to keep them permanently subject. Meanwhile unconquerable time itself works on unceas- Tendencies ,,.... . , towards a mgly, bringing the nations nearer to one another, and common awakening the universal consciousness of the community of ofluTmanity. mankind ; and this is the natural preparation for a common organisation of the world. It is no mere matter of accident that modern discoveries and numerous new means of com- munication altogether serve this end, that the whole science of modern times follows this impulse and belongs in the first place to humanity, and only in a subordinate way to particular peoples, while a number of hindrances and barriers that lay between nations are disappearing. Even at the present day all Europe feels every disturbance in any particular State as an evil in which she has to suffer, and what happens at her extremest limits immediately awakens uni- versal interest. The spirit of Europe already turns its ! regards to the circuit of the globe, and the Aryan race feels itself called to manage the world. We have not yet got so far : at the present day it is not so much will and power that are wanting as spiritual maturity. The members of the European family of nations know their superiority over other nations well enough, but they have not yet come to a clear understanding among themselves and about themselves. A definite result is .not possible until the enlightening word of knowledge has been 32 THE CONCEPTION OF THE STATE. [Book l. uttered about this and about the nature of humanity, and until the nations are ready to hear it. Till then, the universal empire will be an idea after which many strive, which none can fulfil. But as an idea of the future the general theory of the State cannot overlook it. Only in the universal empire will the true human State be revealed, and in it international law will attain a higher form and an assured existence. To the universal empire the particular states are related, as the nations to humanity. Particular states are members of the universal empire and attain in it their completion and their full satisfaction. The purpose of the universal State is not to break up particular states and oppress nations, but better to secure the peace of the former and the freedom of the latter. The highest con- ception of the State which however has not yet been realised is thus : The State is humanity organised, but humanity as masculine, not as feminine : the State is the man. (i) Objec- Notes. T. A man of genius and a lover of truth, the Vaudois V?net Vinet (in L? Individtialisme et le Socialisme} objected to the idea of the Universal State, that it would absorb all the life of humanity, do away with the principle of individual liberty, and exercise an improper temporal rule over conscience and knowledge. This objection compels us to limit this idea more exactly. Answers First of all, it must be recognized, that the State is not the sole t( ? . the ^ e human community, is not the only form in which humanity embodies itself. The Church, as visible and on earth, is also a community and an embodiment of humanity. This however is a recognition that the political rule of the State does not determine the religious life of man, nor endanger the freedom of conscience and the faith of the individual. Secondly, it in no way follows from the human character of the State, that the State has a complete dominion over the individual. In every single man may be distinguished two natures, the one individual, the other common to humanity. The individual with his life does not belong exclusively nor altogether either to the community with other individuals or to the earth, nor therefore to the State as a com- munity of life upon earth. The State is based upon human nature,l not in so far as this is variously manifested in millions of individuals,! but. in so far as the common nature of humanity appears in one being, > and the authority of the State does not therefore extend further than is Chap. II.] THE UNIVERSAL STATE. 33 required by the common interests and the association of mankind. The State itself, when it wrongly trespasses on the domain of Individ;.' ' freedom, is not able to enforce its rule, for it cannot chain the individual spirit, it cannot kill the individual soul. 2. Quite lately Laurent also has declared himself against the idea of (?) Objec- the Universal State (Histoirt du droit des gens , i. p. 39 ff.). His reasons Laurent, are as follows : (a} The world-state would be universal monarchy, and this would be incompatible with the sovereignty of states. (ft) There is a difference between individuals as natural and nations as artificial persons. The former are defective and are moved by bad passions ; the latter are perfect and moral beings. That the former may live together, there is needed the incessant activity of the power of the State ; that the latter may live together, this is not needed, or only exceptionally. (c) The individual is weak, and must submit to the power of the State. States are strong, and therefore will not yield to a higher power. (d) If the Universal State were powerful enough to force the States \ against their will, this superiority would oppress justice and freedom ; for where resistance is impossible, freedom cannot exist. (e) For the development of the individual the national State is necessary, but it is sufficient. The world-state is not required for the welfare of individuals, and would be dangerous to the development of nations. These reasons of my honoured friend have not convinced me : I Answers to should answer them as follows : jections." (a) The Universal State may be thought of with a monarchical head (empire, Kaiserthuni) but also as republic, whether a directory (I am thinking of the European pentarchy) or a confederation or union of States. In no case need we think of the universal government having absolute power, and the continued existence of national States makes a distinction of spheres (Competenzeri) necessary. There is no reason for extending the sphere of the latter beyond the common affairs of the world, e.g. maintaining the peace of the world, protecting its com- merce, and especially what we consider the province of international law. We may find a model in the form of a federal State (fiundesstat}, or a federal empire (Bundesreich\ in which common federal matters are cared for by a common legislature, administration, and judicature, while in matters affecting each country the sovereignty of particular States is still recognised. (b) Nations have their defects and their passions like individuals, and if there were no international law, those which are weak and help- less would be an easy prey to the strong and ambitious. The basis of international law is also the basis of the Universal State. D 34 THE CONCEPTION OF THE STATE. (c) The strength of national States, even as against a universal empire, is the best guarantee that the former will not be oppressed by the latter ; but the greatest national State is not strong enough, if it is in the wrong, to engage alone in a struggle with the world. War will only be possible if groups of States or parties oppose one another. In all other cases war will become the execution of the judicial sentences of the universal tribunals. The best political arrangements cannot completely ensure us against civil war, and we must be content if a stronger organisation of international law makes war between States rarer. Justice never attains its ideal, but in the best cases approximates to it. (d) The universal empire would be in every way less powerful in comparison with national States than a national State in comparison with its citizens. And yet the freedom of the citizens is not threatened but protected by the organisation of the State. (e) The State does not satisfy all individual needs. There are cos- mopolitan interests both spiritual and material (the science, literature, art and trade of the world) which can only find a complete satisfaction in a universal empire. The history of Europe and America shows us how little in our days the rights of entire peoples are secured. Laurent bases international law on the unity of the human race, and no other basis can be found for it ; but he recognises this unity only as an internal one. In my opinion logic and psychology both require that this internal power should manifest itself outwardly. If mankind is internally one being, in its complete development it must reveal itself as one person. The organisation of humanity is the Universal State. I know that the most of my contemporaries regard this idea as a dream; but that cannot keep me from expressing and defending my conviction. Later generations, perhaps centuries hence, will finally decide the question. CHAPTER III. HISTORY OF THE DEVELOPMENT OF IDEA OF THE STATE. I. THE ANCIENT WORLD. A. The Hellenic idea of the State, POLITICAL science does not properly begin till we come to the Greeks. As it was in Greece that the self-conscious- ness of man first unfolded itself in art and philosophy, so it was in politics. Small as was the territory, and limited as was the power The poii- of the Greek State, the principles upon which the Greek ofThe deas political conceptions were based were broad and compre- Greeks - hensive, and the political idea expressed by Greek thinkers is lofty and noble. They base the State upon human nature, and hold that only in the State can man attain his perfection and find true satisfaction. The State is for them ) the moral order of the world in which human nature fulfils ( its end. Plato (Rep. v. p. 462) utters the great saying : 'The best Plato. State is that which approaches most nearly to the condition of the individual. If a part of the body suffers, the whole body feels the hurt and sympathises altogether with 'the part affected.' In this he has already recognised the or- * ganic and even the human-organic nature of the State, although without following out in its consequences this pregnant thought. D*. 36 THE CONCEPTION OF THE STATE. [Book I. The State, according to Plato, is the highest revelation of human virtue, the harmonious manifestation of the powers 1 of the human soul, humanity perfected. As the soul of man consists of a rational, a spirited, and a desiring ele- ment, and as reason and spirit ought to rule the desires, so v in\ the Platonic ideal, the wise ought to rule, the brave warriors should protect the community, and the classes which are occupied with material acquisition and bodily work should obey the two higher orders. In the body politic justice requires that each part should do its own work. (Ref.\v. pp. 428-33.) Aristotle. Aristotle, for whose political philosophy our 'admiration rises, the more we consider the works of his successors, is less guided by imagination than Plato, examines reality more carefully and recognises more acutely the needs of man. Plato cuts off from family lite the ruling classes of the philosophers and the guardians in ord^r that they may live completely for the State, a'nd demands for them a community of wives and property. Aristotle, on tfie con- trary, wishes to maintain the great institutions of marriage, the family and private property. He declares* the State to be ( the association of clans and village-communities in a complete and self-sufficing life V He says that ' man is by nature a political animal ' and he considers the State as a product of human nature. ' The State comes into being for the sake of mere life, but exists (or continues to exist) for the sake of the good life 2 .' In this idea (or ideal) of the State are combined and mingled all the efforts of the Greeks in religion and in law, in morals and social life, in art and science, in the acquisi tion and management of wealth, in trade and industry. The individual requires the State to give him a legal existence : apart from the State he has neither safety nor \ 1 Arist. Pol. iii. 9. 14, I28ob. 40: iruXts 5* 77 yevuv KCLL KCU/J.UV Koivavia 077? rsXtias KOI airapKovs. Cp. iii. I. 12, 1275 b. 20. 2 Arist. Pol. i. 2. 8, r2<;2b. 30: 77 TTU\IS . . . ^ivo^vrj plv ovv rov TIV V(KCV, ovaa 8e rov v ^TJV. Chap. III.] THE ANCIENT WORLD. 37 freedom. The barbarian is a natural enemy, and conquered enemies become slaves, who are excluded from the political community, and are therefore thrust down into a degraded and ignoble position. The Hellenic State, tike the ancient -State in general, Defects of because it was considered all-powerful, actually possessed idea of the too much power. It wa% all in all. The citizen was Too^much nothing, except as a member of the State. His whole S^ed^o existence depended on and was subject to the State. The il - Athenians indeed possessed and exercised intellectual free- dom, but that was only because the Athenian State valued freedom in general highly, not b.ecause it recognised the rights of man. This same freest of states allowed Socrates to be executed, and thought it was justified in doing so. The independence of the family, home-life, education, even conjugal fidelity, were in no way secure from'tate inter- ference ; still less of course the private property of the citizens. The State meddled in everything, and knew neither moral nor legal limits to its power. It disposed of tj^e bodies, and even of the talents of its members. It co'mpelled men to accept office as well as to render military service. The Individual must first be dead in the State before he could, by means f the State, be born again to a free and noble life. 'The absolute power of the State, Limitations apart from the influence of ancient customs, had almost no lute power, other limits than the following : In the first place, the citizens themselves had a share in the exercise of this power, and lest the despotism of the demos might become injurious to themselves also, they avoided the extreme consequences of political communism. In the second place, insignificant matters only supplied small material for their passions to work upon, and they were compelled to pay regard to their neighbours. The Greek States were moreover only composed of fragments of the Hellenic people and sub-races of them. They did not rise much beyond mere city-communes (Stadtgemeinde). The lofty idea had thus only a humble form ; although referring to 38 THE CONCEPTION OF THE STATE. [Book I. mankind, it could only obtain a childish expression in the narrow limits of a mountain valley or a tract of sea-shore. The ideal omnipotence and actual impotence of the State are thus closely connected ; they are the two chief defects of the Hellenic conception of the State, which is in other respects most worthy, true to human nature, and fruitful in results. B. The Roman idea of the State. The Romans had a greater genius for Law and Politics than any other people of classical antiquity, and this more by their moral character than by their intellect. They had therefore a greater influence on the world than the Greeks. influence of At first sight the Roman idea of the State is closely e s ' connected with the Greek. Cicero, in his political writings, has Athenian models constantly before his eyes. The Roman jurists, when explaining law and the State in general, follow the Greek philosophers, especially the Stoics. Cicero declares the State to be the highest product of human power (virtus\ and says that there is nothing in which human excellence comes nearer the will of the gods than in the founding and maintenance of States 3 . Occa- sionally he too compares the State to the individual, and the head of the State to the spirit which rules the body 4 . Differences But in some essential particulars the Roman conception of Greek idea, the State is different from the Greek idea. (i) Law The Romans^ first dijrtinguishedja^ and from n mora- e g ave ^ a definite form, and thus they brought ^outTmore distinctly the legal nature (Rechtsnatur) of the State. Thereby they limited JtheJStat_e, and gave it greater firm- 3 Cicero, de Rep. i. 7 : ' Neque est ulla res, in qua propius ad Deorum numen virtus accedat hum ana, quam civitates aut condere novas aut conservare jam conditas.' * Cicero, de Rep. iii. 25 : ' Sic regum, sic imperatorum, sic magistra- tuum, sic patrum, sic populorum imperia civibus sociisque praesunt, ut corporibus animus.' Chap. III.] THE ANCIENT WORLD. 39 ness and power. It no longer summed up for them the ethical ordering of the world, but was primarily a common legal organisation (gemeinsame Rechtsordnung}. The Romans left very much to social customs and to the religious nature of man. The Roman family was more free as against the State. Private property and private rights were in general better protected against the arbitrary exercise even of public authority. Of course they too made the welfare of the State the highest law (salus populi suprema lex). They arranged even the worship of the gods from a political point of view. No one could resist the State if it uttered its will. But the Roman State limited itself; it restricted the province of its own power and its own action. Further, the Romans recognised the conception of the ( 2 ) The con - ception of People, and brought the constitution into an organic con- the People nexion with the People. They declared the State to be the People organised, and declared the will of the People to be the source of all law 5 . The Roman State was thus not a mere commune (Gemeinde)^ it raised itself to a national State (res publica). Besides, the Roman State was destined to embrace the ( 3 ) Tendency world. Through all Roman , history runs this tendency Empire. 6 "' to universal dominion ; the national jus civile was supple- mented by the jus gentium. The eternal city, the urbs^ became the capital of the world, orbis. The imperium of the Roman magistrate became imperium mundi, the Roman senate became a senate of all peoples and their kings. The majesty of the Roman People culminated in the majesty of the imperial power. The history of Rome, according to the proud expression of Florus", became the history of mankind. This effort gave the Roman idea of the State 5 Cicero, de Rep. i. 25 : c Est igitur, inquit (Scipio) Africanus, res publica res populi ; populus autem non omnis hominum coetus quoquo modo congregatus, sed coetus multitudinis juris consensu et utilitatis communione sociatus.' i. 26 : ' Civitas est constitutio populi? Gaius, Inst. i. i : ' Nam quod quisque populus ipse sibi jus constituit, id ipsius proprium civitatis est, vocaturque jus civile/ a [Florus Prooem. ' Non unius populi sed generis humani facta.'] 40 THE CONCEPTION OF THE STATE. an impetus which left the Greek States far behind, and a greatness before which they were compelled to bow. It was not an illusion but a reality which ruled the ancient world, and which only the Germans in the West and the Persians in the East had the courage and the strength to resist. CHAPTER IV. II. THE MIDDLE AGE. THE two new forces which partly transformed and partly destroyed the universal empire of Rome were Christianity and the Teutonic race. A. Christianity. The Christian religion extended its power over the minds Attitude of of men, denying alike the authority of the Jewish State and church 1 to the Roman Empire. Its founder was not a prince of this th world. The ancient State persecuted him and his disciples to the death. If the first Christians were not directly hos- tile to the State, they cared for other things than political organisation and political interests. When the Christian world made its peace with the old Graeco-Roman State the religious community the ' Church ' was already conscious of her peculiar spiritual existence, and did not regard her- self as a mere State institution. The new idea prevailed that the whole religious life of the community, although not altogether withdrawn from the care and influence of the State, was yet essentially independent. The pro- minently marked dualism of Church and State became an essential limitation of the State, which was now only a community of law and politics, no longer also of religion and worship. When the Church had received in the Pope a visible The Papacy, head independent of the Emperor, and Rome for her 42 THE CONCEPTION OF THE STATE. [Book I. capital, the old Roman idea of universal dominion re- appeared in a spiritual form. Although, even at the height of her mediaeval reputation, the Church did not succeed in abasing the State into a mere ecclesiastical institution, and setting up one universal spiritual dominion of Rome ; yet the idea of the State was for a long time far outshone by her splendour. She could compare herself with the sun, and the State with the moon, and as the ruler over men's souls claimed precedence over the ruler of their bodies. But the dualism of State and Church continued to be recognised, and thus in the main point the independence of Pope and the State was saved. The sword of the Emperor, as well as that of the Pope, was derived from God, the supreme and true ruler of the world 1 . As far as the teaching of the Church prevailed, the idea of the State again, as formerly in the East, received a religious foundation ; the power of the State was derived from God (Gottes!ehen\ but at the same time the spiritual significance of the State was overlooked and misunder- stood ; all spiritual life was to come from the Church, and the State being regarded as merely bodily was put in an inferior position. The elevation of the idea of the State above the narrow limits of nationality was an insufficient compensation. Not humanity, but Christendom was to be organised and governed by it in outward things. The Roman empire was so far renewed in mediaeval forms, but was represented in a superior form by the Roman Church, and in an inferior by the holy Roman Empire of the German people. B. The Teutons. The power of The old Roman universal empire could not permanently ls ' maintain itself against the Teutonic races. These warlike 1 Hincmari de Ordine Palatii, 5 : ' Duo sunt, quibus principaliter mundus hie regitur : auctoritas sacra Pontificum et Regalis potestas.' Sachsenspiegel, i. i : * Tvei svert lit got in ertrike to bescermene de kristenheit. Deme pavese is gesat dat geistlike, deme kaisere dat wert- like ' (God has given two swords for the government of Christendom : to the pope the spiritual, to the emperor the temporal). Chap. IV.] THE MIDDLE AGES. 43 tribes forcibly wrested one province after another from Roman rule; or it happened that the Roman provincials or the emperors themselves called in to their aid the arms of Teutonic princes, who thus in a peaceable manner acquired territorial sovereignty (Landeshoheit]. During the middle ages the Teutons ruled everywhere in the West. They came under the Christian instruction of the Roman Church and the influence of Roman civilisation ; but they maintained themselves upon the thrones of princes, and in the fortresses of the aristocracy. The sceptre and the sword were in their hands. The Teutons are not, like the Romans, an eminently The Teu- political people ; it is with reluctance that the individual acter. submits to the sovereignty of the whole body. Their strong, confident and self-willed individuality interferes with the common consciousness, and checks its power. (Thus the Teuton stood in need of the political discipline of the Roman.) But in spite of this the development of the State in the world's history owes much to them. Above all the Teutons broke the absolutism of the Roman State, and they have won a place in all modern political institu- tions for the freedom of persons, associations, and ' Estates ' (Stdnde). Montesquieu said very truly, that the germs of parliamentary constitutions are to be found in the forests of Germany. In the primitive forms described by Tacitus a , in which the Teutonic kings cooperated with the local princes and other chiefs on the one side, and with the great community of freemen on the other, we recognise clearly the rude beginnings of the free representative govern- ment, which later centuries produced. The Teuton does not derive law, at least not directly, The idea of from the will of the nation : he claims for himself an inborn rights. ua right which the State must protect, but which it does not create, and for which he is ready to fight against the whole world, even against the authority of his own government. He rejects strenuously the old idea that the State is all in [Tac. Germ. c. n.] 44 THE CONCEPT/ON OF THE STATE. [Book I. all. The whole relation is reversed. To the Teuton in- dividual freedom is the supreme thing. He is induced to sacrifice a part of it to the State in order to keep the rest all the more securely. It is a necessary consequence of this character, that the Teutonic idea of the State respects the independence of private rights more decidedly than the Roman. The free- dom of the person, the family, the association is thus more assured and more extended than in the old Roman empire. The rights of the State are thus limited by the rights of the individual as well as by those of the Church. Particu- A further consequence for Public Law is that the Teu- larism 'in . politics. tons in general admit no absolute power of the State, even in matters affecting the community. The Roman concep- tion of imperium is foreign to them. Before obeying they wish to deliberate and vote. Their estates (Stdnde) are a political power with which that of the king must be united in order to make laws. Yet the idea of the State as a collective person is still, as a rule, unintelligible to them. They tend rather to break up the State into actual persons or groups of persons. They understand it primarily as embodied in the king or other princes, who are at the head of the courts of justice, and of the assembly of the people, in the chief of the hundred (Gau), the tithing (Zent\, and the township (Volksgemeinde}. One set of persons some- times strengthens and sometimes limits another ; thus the whole organisation of the community, even in its parts, is filled with the spirit of freedom. Unity is relatively weak, but the independence of the parts is strong. These alterations of the idea of the State in which we recognise considerable advance showed themselves rather in practice than in theory. The Teutons had no political Surviving philosophy of their own. Science in the middle ages was from an- at first in the hands of the Church, and was afterwards determined by the traditions of Roman jurisprudence and Greek philosophy. Even in the old tribal laws are to be found reminiscences of this sort : e. g. in the laws of the Chap. IV.] THE MIDDLE AGES, 45 Visigoths, after the model of classical literature, the body politic is compared with a man, the king with the head, and the people with the members of the body 2 . But this was only a borrowed rhetorical ornament without deeper sig- nificance, and with no definite reference to the actual mediaeval State. In some other respects the idea of the State suffered degradation, and that not merely because it was disparaged by the Church. The mediaeval State might be called a legal State (Rechts- Feudal Ui\v stat\ but in a different sense from that of the Romans. It was not the organisation of Public Law only : all its institutions were interfused with elements of Private Law. Territorial sovereignty was regarded as the hereditary property of a family, and public duties were treated as burdens upon land. The whole feudal law and the patrimonial State in all its aspects suffer from this admixture Roman Public Law only served as a starting-point. The feudal law of the middle ages appeared to be the essential end of the me- diaeval State, and the welfare of the people was neglected for it. The idea of the national State had perished, destroyed by the breaking up of the national and political unity, by the feudal system, by the conflicting claims of territories, estates, and dynasties. What remained of the Roman empire was rather an ideal international, than a political, union of Western Christendom, and this union was held together more by the authority of the Pope and the Roman clergy than by the Empire. On the whole the seeds of a freer and better develop- ment of the State had been sown, but the idea of the State 2 Lex Visigothorum, ii. i. 4 : ' Bene Deus conditor rerum disponens humani corporis formam, in sublime caput erexit, atque ex illo cunctas membrorum fibras exoriri decrevit. Hinc est et peritorum medicorum praecipua cura, ut ante capiti quam membris incipiant adhibere me- delam. Sicque in Statu et negotiis plebium ordinatio dirigenda, ut dum salus competens prospicitur Regum, fida valentibus teneatur salvatio populoium.' 46 THE CONCEPTION OF THE STATE. [Book I. had in the middle ages become less precise and vigorous than among the Romans. C. The influence of the Renaissance. The Roman Even during the middle ages the memory of the ancient aiivethe ep State had never been completely lost. Rome had remained Roman f ** the spiritual capital of the West. The old Roman Empire Empire. j^ j n( j ee( j Deen broken to pieces by the Teutons, but the Teutons who had formed independent kingdoms out of Roman provinces received their civilisation, and, above all, their religion from Rome, and in the place of the fallen city the Roman Church became the ruling power of the middle ages, to which the Teutons themselves in time submitted. In the institutions, method, morals, law and language of the Roman Church, a great, nay the chief, part of the old Roman State was preserved. The old Empire was trans- formed into the new Papacy, the universal State into the universal Church, in order to rule the nations more easily. The old Roman Emperor had exercised his sway by his representatives and officials with the help of Roman law, in the name of the Roman people, and enforced it by the power of his legions ; similarly the Roman Pope com- manded reverence in the name of God and the Church by means of his bishops, and with the help of canon law and ecclesiastical discipline, and enforced his decrees by means of the numerous monastic orders. Roman ly ^ ut a ^ on g s ^e of the Church the memory of the old Empire. Empire still remained. We know nowadays how totally unlike was the Roman Empire of the Frankish kings from Charles the Great and of the German kings from Otto the Great to the old Roman Empire, which had had its seat in Rome and in Constantinople. But the whole middle ages believed that the one was only a continuation of the other, and that the Frankish Emperor, or the Roman Emperor of the German people, was the regular successor of Claudius, Antoninus, and Constantine. In any case the Chap. IV.] THE MIDDLE AGES. 47 renewed dignity of the Emperors implied a reminiscence of the old Roman Empire, and an ideal union of mediaeval ideas and institutions with the ancient world. To this must now be added the rediscovery of the old Roman Law. imperial code, the Corpus Juris Romani, which from the twelfth century had been expounded at the Italian univer- sities, and was revered as a revelation of all human law. From Italy its authority spread victoriously over all Western Europe, from the thirteenth century in France, and with still greater consequences from the fifteenth century in Germany. However the learned jurists were thinking rather of private law, and perhaps of criminal law, than of public law. But many fundamental views about the State, about its legislation, and about its sovereignty which had been expressed by the Romans, became in this way part of the ordinary ideas of the learned class. Recollections of the old Roman republic and its majesty Republican sometimes revived and animated the citizens of towns in their effort to found new city republics. The very names of the civic magistrates in Italy and in Germany implied a dim memory of the consuls of the Roman Republic. Twice over in the middle ages the Roman populace in romantic enthusiasm attempted to reawaken and reanimate the long dead republic ; once in the twelfth century under the leader- ship of Arnold of Brescia, and a second time in the fourteenth century under the tribune Cola Rienzi. Both attempts failed through the political incapacity of the mediaeval Romans, but both testify to the power of the ancient tradi- tion. Even Greek political theories were not quite unknown to Greek the Romance civilisation of the middle ages. The Politics of th Aristotle were studied in many monasteries, and that most famous theologian, Thomas of Aquino, wrote a commentary on the celebrated work of the Greek philosopher. Nevertheless the legal system, and still more the political organisation of the middle ages, were totally different from those of antiquity. The institutions of the time were. 48 THE CONCEPTION OF THE STATE. [Book I. moulded mainly under Teutonic influences, and its ideas dominated by the theology of the Church. The RC- In the second half of the fifteenth century the recollection of the classical period awoke more vigorously, and the classical spirit of the Greeks and the Romans was born again (the ' Renaissance '). The works of ancient art pro- duced a liberating and elevating effect on the Italian artists, in architecture, sculpture, painting, and poetry. The ideas of ancient science were again held in honour, and broke through the bounds set by mediaeval scholasticism and monastic theology. Humanism rose above the ecclesias- tical contempt of the world, and a brighter and more joyous way of looking at life found wide acceptance at courts and in cities. As nearly 2000 years before the Sophists became the teachers of young Greeks of good family, so now the Humanists became the chosen instructors of ambitious youth in Italy, France, and Germany. Educated men were no longer terrified by the reproach that from Christians they were again becoming Pagans. Even the Popes put them- selves at the head of this intellectual movement. Nicolas V (1447-1455), Pius II (Aeneas Sylvius, 1458-1464), Julius II (15031513), Leo X (15 13-152 1 \ protected and encouraged the artistic freedom of the Renaissance. The princely Medici, especially Cosimo (1434-1464) and Lorenzo (1469- 1492), made Florence an Italian Athens. inauence of The ancient conception of the State and ancient political the Classical ...... . . . . _ f . ,. Revival. theories likewise reappeared in part and influenced public affairs, especially in the following ways : (i) A few bold thinkers dared to explain the rise of States and the nature of political authority by human considerations, and thus to oppose theocratic opinions. (2) Secondly, the idea of policy, consciously and calmly considering means and ends for the guidance of the State and the government of nations, became decisive in political practice and theory, and received its clearest expression in the writings of Machiavelli (1469-1527). His Discourses on Livy, in which he glorifies the Roman republic, and his Chap. IV.] THE MIDDLE AGES. 49 Prince^ in which he points out the way to the ambition of rulers, are filled with the political spirit of the Renaissance. (3) Thirdly, we mark the renewal of a political Imperium and a political Sovereignty before whose single authority everything else must bow. In the hands of the prince who ruled the State, this authority, freed from the limitations of feudalism and of the mediaeval ' estates, 7 grew to an absolutism like that of the Roman Emperor. (4) Finally, the Renaissance manifested itself also in an opposite form, to which this growing tyranny incited. With the recollection of the Caesars there awoke also the memory of Brutus ; tyrannicide was praised as republican virtue, and even ' Catilinarian ' conspirators reappear 3 . But all this revival of ancient political ideas and tenden- cies was limited to a comparatively narrow circle of highly educated men. The masses had no understanding and no capacity for it. The whole influence of the Renaissance onfl politics was only partial, and quickly passed by, helping to/ break up the mediaeval, and to prepare the way for the modern State, but bringing -forth no new political organisa- tion of its own. 3 Burckhardt, Die Renaissance , p. 44 ff. [Engl. Tr. I. p. 81.] CHAPTER V. III. THE MODERN IDEA OF THE STATE. A. When does the Modern Epoch commence ? THE historical consciousness of Europeans and Americans at the present day is unanimous in accepting the idea of a period of many centuries in the life of humanity which is called l the middle ages'; and in believing that we are living in a new age. But opinions are still divided as to what point of time separates the modern from the mediaeval period. We have learned that the past is bound up with the future. Presentiments and tendencies of the coming age make themselves felt long before, and countless effects of bygone days continue to operate in changed times. In the depth of the middle ages a few distinguished men gave utterance to ideas which have not been understood until the present century, and even to-day we still find many survivals of mediaeval institutions carefully preserved, and that not merely in monasteries or the castles of the nobility. The old and the new are linked together by the very unity of human life, and it shows a want of sense to sever them sharply from one another. It is the same with the different ages in the life of the individual. Nevertheless it is necessary to determine the different periods of time which, though passing over into one another, may yet on the whole be clearly distinguished. Many date the beginning of the new age as far back as THE MODERN IDEA OF THE STATE. 51 the second half of the fifteenth century. The period of the * Th e Re- . . . naissance? Renaissance appears to them the transition from the middle ages to the modern world. The reawakening of the philoso- phical spirit after the slumber of more than a thousand years, the revival of ancient ideas and memories in opposi- tion to mediaeval beliefs and institutions, the reappearance of a freer and more joyous art under the influence of classi- cal models, above all the rise of the Italian cities which did not shrink from withdrawing themselves as occasion offered from the protection of the Papal hierarchy, the extension of Roman and the disparagement of Canon law, the invention of printing and the diffusion of printed books, the invention of gunpowder and the consequent changes in warfare, the greater enterprise in navigation, and the discovery of un- known countries on the coasts of Africa and in India and of a whole new continent in the West all this certainly marks a transition from the old to the new. But it is not so much the conclusion as the decline of the mediaeval period, and the preparation for the rising tendencies of the new era. The spirit of the age (Zeitgeist} at the Renaissance had rather the character of maturity than of youth or childhood. It was less inclined to create what was new than to revive what was old ; its efforts were directed throughout to the revival of ancient ideas and the imitation of ancient models. It partly reformed and partly destroyed the institutions of the middle ages, but it did not overthrow them nor replace them by creations of its own. The movement, ended by stiffening into the absolutism of princes, great\ and small. Still more often the period of the ecclesiastical Reforma- 2. The Re- .,,,,.. r , , formation ? tion is considered the beginning of the new period not indeed the incomplete attempts at reform in the German Empire at the Diet of Worms of 1495, but the reform of the sixteenth century, which is usually dated from the i3th October, 1517, when Martin Luther nailed his theses to the church door of Wittenberg. As a matter of fact the world-historical breach with the E 2 52 THE CONCEPTION OF THE STATE. [Book I. mediaeval authority of the Roman Church was then complete, and the foundation of Protestant churches was actually a new creation in the ecclesiastical sphere. The liberation of the religious conscience from servitude to Rome undoubtedly gave a powerful impulse to the subsequent liberation of science from all ecclesiastical authority. The moral purifi- cation and elevation of the idea of the State prepared the way for modern politics. Nevertheless the fundamental idea of the German Refor- mation . was not the production of anything new, but the purging of the ancient Church from long-standing abuses, and the restoration of the primitive purity of Christianity. The old historical authority of the Papal Church and its tradition was broken, but the still older and equally historical authority of the Holy Scriptures was retained with greater strictness than before. It was indeed as impossible for the Church reformers to restore primitive Christianity as it was for the Italian masters to reproduce the classical art of Athens and Rome. The world had changed and old ideas could only reappear in new forms. The life of Europe was still advancing, and the Protestant Church, as well as the State which was influenced by Protestantism, were thus relatively new phenomena. But the idea of the State itself remained essentially that of the middle ages. The State was still the kingdom of this world and of the body, the Church was still mainly the spiritual community of the saints preparing for heaven. A decisive proof that the Reformation of the sixteenth century belongs rather to the advancing age of the mediaeval period than to the youthful efforts of the modern era is to be found in the character of the two centuries from 1540 to 1740. This long period gives the impartial observer the impression, not of youth but of old age. Even in the Pro- testant Church a dead and rigid orthodoxy straightway regained the upper hand, allowing no fresh movements, and fettering and repressing the advance of science. In the Catholic Church we mark the growing influence of the Chap. V.] THE MODERN IDEA OF THE STA TE. 53 Jesuits, the most pronounced supporters of the artificially maintained mediaeval hierarchy. The absolute monarchy dominated over the mediaeval nobility and broke up the feudal system, but there was no new blood in the veins of this despotic system which prevailed over the whole continent of Europe, and was repulsed in England alone. It was supported mainly by old ideas, dynastic and Roman, patri- monial and theocratic. The rococo style, which gradually sup- planted that of the Renaissance, is a manifestation of senility. Everywhere there is rather breaking up and decay of the mediaeval period than a fundamentally new era. The young Leibnitz received so vivid an impression of this that he wrote in 1669, ' We may well believe that the world has entered on its old age V The same considerations prevent us from finding the be- 3- The Eng- lish Revolu- ginning of the modern period m the English Revolution, tion? whether that of 1640 or the so-called " glorious " Revolution of 1668. Certainly they brought about something new constitutional monarchy. But the more carefully we compare the English with the French Revolution, the more is our conviction strengthened that the former belongs to the end of the Mediaeval and the latter to the Modern period. The English were struggling mainly for the old Anglo-Saxon liberties and for the traditional rights of Parliament against the absolutism of the king, whereas the French strove to realise a new and rational organisation of the State and a new social freedom. Many therefore see in the French Revolution the first 4- The decided movement of the modern period, and date this from Revolution? 1789, an opinion which flatters French vanity. It is incon- testable that the French Revolution was filled and animated by the modern spirit, but it had begun to work before this. The " age of enlightenment " (Aufk/drung) which preceded had already the unmistakable stamp of the new time. Among many others, Thomas Buckle, the learned historian 5-1740? [The acces- of modern civilisation, has remarked that in the year 1740 a sion of 1 Pichler, Theologie von Leibnitz, i. p. 23. 54 THE CONCEPTION OF THE STATE. [Book I. Frederick change in the current of men's ideas becomes perceptible. the Great * of Prussia. As the sun first lights up the mountain-tops, and only after- wards shines down into the valley, so the new spirit first manifests itself in great men, and only gradually diffuses itself among the multitude. In the second half of the eighteenth century the new spirit animated not only a chosen few, the prophets and forerunners of a coming age : everywhere new ideas rose on the horizon, and the demand for change was universally felt. Men's hearts swelled with the hope of a new life. Art, literature, the state, and society were transformed, the sentiments of the world were turned away decisively from the middle ages towards a new creation. If we compare men and events since 1 740 with those of the preceding centuries, we are struck by the vast change in the character of the times. Not merely are the individuals different, but the conditions of their existence, the ground on which they stand, the air which they breathe. Compare, e. g., Frederick the Great of Prussia, the most significant represen- tative of the modern State and the modern view of life not merely with Louis XIV of France, the clearest representative of the absolute monarchy by the grace of God, which closes the middle ages but even with his own great ancestor, the Elector Frederick William ; or compare the liberation of the Netherlands from Spanish rule with the liberation of North America from English rule ; or compare the French with the English Revolution, or Rousseau with Ulrich von Hutten, or Lessing with Luther, and the vast difference is at once apparent. The newness of the period on which civilized mankind has entered since the middle of last century, appears in the uncer- tain probing and experimenting of political theory and prac- tice, in the daring attempts at a complete new creation, in the momentary despair which succeeds failure, in the oscillations between revolution and reaction. If the modern era has on the whole the character of self-conscious manhood, in a higher degree than any previous period of history, these Chap.V.] THE MODERN IDEA OF THE STATE. 55 traits, which we have noticed, show that we have only ex- perienced the first stage of this manhood, and that it has still an immature and youthful, sometimes even childish appearance, just as the last centuries of the middle ages have a senile aspect. The organic and psychological law of growth does not only govern the entire life of humanity : it repeats itself in recurring circles in particular periods within the various ages of the world. Thus we date the modern era from the year 1 740. The rise of the Prussian kingdom, Joseph II's reforms in Austria, the foundation of the United States of North America, the changes of the French Revolution and the Napoleonic em- pire, the transplanting of constitutional monarchy to tne continent, the attempted introduction of representative de- mocracy, the foundation of national states, the gradual removal of religious privileges and disabilities in public law, the separation of Church and State, or at least the clear de- marcation between their spheres, the abolition of feudalism and of all privileged orders, the rise of the conception of national unity, the recognition of the freedom of society, all these are the achievements or at least the attempts of the modern State. Note. We are accustomed to consider the history of the human race in its inner connection, and in a regular order. We therefore distinguish the different ages of the world, in the same way that we distinguish the ages of the individual's life. We speak of a childhood and of a youth of mankind, and we consider the latter to end with the classical period of Greek and Roman civilisation. In the same way we separate the middle ages from the youthful and brilliant era of the old Greeks and Romans, and on the other side from the more mature and manly modern world. Whilst the life of the individual is measured by years and decades, the life of humanity has to be reckoned by hundreds or thousands of years. Within particular eras we sometimes discover the same cycle, and the same succession of ages, and find first ascending and then descending stages. Just as great eras of the world's history have a de- finite character and spirit, so it is with the periods and phases which we find within them. Thus, the first and second halves of the eighteenth 56 THE CONCEPTION OF THE STATE. [Book I. century belong to thoroughly different types, and so too the first and second halves of the sixteenth century. The unity This whole manner of contemplating the history of the world is how- ^ hjstory ever Qn ^ va ^j ( j on ^ e presupposition that humanity is not merely a sum unity of of individuals, and its life not a mere sum of individual lives. It depends md ' on the assumption that humanity is a whole, and has a development of its own, which requires for its movement and advance greater periods of time than those of the individual life. In viewing whole periods of hundreds and thousands of years, we cannot but be impressed by this mighty continuity, this fixed order of development, and we infer there- from the unity of the human race, and the destiny of humanity whose great life advances regardless of the little lives of individuals, which consciously or unconsciously contribute to it. The duration If this view is correct, we are led to ask what is the duration of that race 16 humnn humanity whose life is described by universal history. It is not prob- able that the unknown or little known infancy of mankind should stretch back immeasurably, whilst its youth and advancing maturity does not exceed a few thousands of years. There must be some proportion. Yet this presumption seems to be contradicted by the natural science of the present day. The Semitic account of the creation reduces the age of the earth to a few thousands of years. A more profound examination has vastly extended it, and we have learnt to count by millions, or even by milliards of years. The same researches have put the beginnings of the human race further back to a time which it is difficult to determine exactly, and the remoteness of which is immeasurably more vast than any known periods of later history. It is at least very probable, if not certain, that hundreds of thousands of years ago there were beings like men. Natural History has discovered remains of primitive human bones and sculls, which must have belonged to the same unknown pre-historic age as the cavern bears. Even the connection and the transitional stages which link the human body with the older forms of animal life have been pointed out. It has been made probable that the pre-historic man was more nearly related to apes and other animals, than his present repre- sentatives. This at first sight appears to increase our difficulties, but on further examination affords a solution of them. The history of man's creation may go back to far earlier times than the traditional view suspects, but there is no reason for extending the history of civilisation, and what we call universal history, as far back. History be- History could not begin until a higher race showed the capacity of wnTt religious, i. e. it does not make the State depend upon religious belief, but it does not deny that God has made human nature, and that His provi- dence has a part in the govern- ment of the world. Modern political science does not pro- fess to comprehend the ways of God, but endeavours to understand the State as a human institution. 3. All theocracy is repellent Theocracy, to the political consciousness of modern nations. The mod- ern State is a human con- stitutional arrangement. The authority of the State is con- ditioned by public law, and its politics aim at the welfare of the nation (the commonweal), understood by human reason, and carried out by human means. 4. The modern State does Religion. not consider religion a condi- tion of legal status (Recht}. Public and private law are independent of creed. The modern State protects freedom of belief, and unites peacefully different churches and religious 62 THE CONCEPTION OF THE STATE. [Book I. The church. 5 Mediaeval Christendom considered the Church as spiritual, and therefore higher ; the State as bodily, and there- fore lower. Thus the rule, or at least the guardianship, of the priesthood was above that of kings. The clergy stood high above the laity, and en- joyed immunities and privi- leges. Education. 6. In the middle ages the Church guided the education of the young, and exercised authority over science. Public and J. Public and private law Private Law. wefe not distinguished, terri- torial sovereignty was held to resemble property in land, and the royal power a family right. Particu- 8. The middle ages produced Centraiisa- tne feudal system. The power tion. of the State was split up, and there was a gradual descent from God to the king, from him to the princes, then to the knights and the towns. The organisation of law was par- ticularistic. 9. Representation was ac- societies. It abstains from all persecution of dissenters or unbelievers. 5. The modern State regards itself as a person, consisting at once of spirit (the national spirit) and body (the constitu- tion). It feels itself inde- pendent, even as against the Church, which is likewise a collective person, consisting of spirit and body, and maintains its supremacy even over the Church. It recognises no superior status in the clergy, abolishes their privileges and immunities, and extends the authority of law over all classes equally. 6. The modern State leaves only religious education to the Church, the school is a State school, science is free from ecclesiastical authority, and its freedom is protected by the State. 7. Public and private law are distinguished, and public rights imply public duties. 8. The modern State is an organisation of the nation ( VolK) and preserves a central unity in its authority. States are formed on a national (national] basis, and tend to become great in size. Law is national and human, and applies to all equally. 9. The modern State re- Chap. VI.] MEDIAEVAL AND MODERN IDEAS. cording to estates. The aris- tocratic estates of the clergy and the nobility dominated. Law was different in each estate. 10. Great and small lords had the freedom of their dynasties and orders so extensively pro- tected, that the authority of the State was weakened. On the other hand the peasantry were kept in an unfree con- dition. 11. The mediaeval State was merely a legal State (Rechts- stat] ; but the administration of justice was indifferently guarded, and people were often left to maintain their own rights. Government and ad- ministration were weak and little developed. 12. The mediaeval State had little consciousness of its own spirit. It was determined by instincts and tendencies. It gives one the impression of natural growth ; custom was the chief source of its law. quires a uniform representa- tion of the people. The great classes of the people have the chief power : the basis is de- mocratic. Citizenship embraces all classes equally. The law is the same for the whole country and people. 10. The modern State de- Liberties velops the common freedom of citizenship .in all classes, and compels every one to submit to its authority. 11. The modern State, be- Sphere of cause constitutional, is likewise State - actlon - a legal State ; but at the same time it concerns itself with economics and culture, and above all with politics. Govern- ment is strong, and adminis- tration is carefully developed with a view to the welfare of the nation, and of society. 12. The modern State is con- Unconscious scious of itself, it acts accord- consdou~s ing to principles and from le sislation. reason rather than from instinct. Legislation is the principal source of its law. CHAPTER VII. THE DEVELOPMENT OF DIFFERENT THEORIES OF THE STATE. POLITICAL science has had a very important share in altering the actual character of the State and the ideal of what it should be 1 . Modern political theory preceded modern political practice, and has generally accompanied and pointed out the way for change. More rarely, theory has followed facts. The following are the main phases in the scientific develop- ment : i. At the The conception of the State at the time of the Renais- Renaissance. sancCj especially as we find it in the works of Machiavelli, Bodin, and partly also of Hugo Grotius, is the direct outcome of the ancient conception, but begins to deviate from it. Machiavelli. The State is to Machiavelli the highest kind of existence. He reverences it as the noblest production of the human spirit. He loves it passionately, and sacrifices to it without hesitation everything, even religion and virtue. But his State is no longer a legal or constitutional State, such as was that of the ancient Romans. Public law is to him only a means to further the welfare of the State, and to secure the growth of its power. His ideal is exclusively filled and determined by politics. The State is for him neither a moral 1 For more details see Blnntschli's Geschichte des allgemeinen Stats- rechts und der Politik. Miinchen, 1854 : Dritte Auflage, 1881. DIFFERENT THEORIES. 65 nor a legal (Rechtswesen\ but only a political being. Thus, the only standard of all state-acts is utility. What the power and authority of the State demand, that must the statesman do, undisturbed by moral and legal considerations. What is hurtful to the welfare of the State he must avoid. Machiavelli's great service was to make political science independent of theology, and to have discovered the distinc- tion between public law (Sfatsrcckt) and politics (PolitiK). But he has adorned an immoral and unjust policy, has put his prudent advice at the disposal of tyranny, and has thus helped to corrupt the political practice of the last three centuries. . Bodin sees in the State * a right government, with sove- Bodin. reign power, of several households and their common posses- sions V He bases the State especially on the family, common possessions, and sovereignty, and he blames the political ideas of the ancients for having looked too much _ to happiness and success. By his doctrine of the sovereignty of the ruler he gave a scientific support to the absolutism of the French monarchy. Hugo Grotius still inclines to the definitions of Cicero, but Grotius. the transition to modern political ideas may be quite clearly observed. He bases the State, like the ancients, upon human nature, but he is thinking less than they of mankind or of a whole people. He looks, above all, to the individual man. His saying ' hominis proprium sociale ' is a bad trans- lation of the Aristotelian : 6 av6p<*>iros <*ov TroAmKo*/. But it shows in a characteristic way that the modern mind does not begin with the State, but with the individual. The sharp separation of the religious community of the Church from the worldly and political community of the State, and the strong accentuation of personal freedom are two other signs of the modern spirit of the Dutch writer. He declares the State to be ' the complete union of free men, who join themselves together for the purpose of enjoying law, and for 2 Bodin, De la Republique, i.-i. F 66 THE CONCEPTION OF THE STATE. [Book I. the sake of public welfare V The personality of the State was not unknown to him, but it does not dominate his political theory, and in making the consent of men the chief source of public law he suggests a line of thought which was carried out in the later theory of contract. 2 . Theories The idea of contract formed the basis of the modern nature, of theory of the Law of Nature and the speculative political as?ocfat\on nd philosophy which was founded on it in complete indepen- dence of ancient theories of the State. The differences of philosophical schools and of political parties produced a great difference between opinions, hardly any one writer completely agreeing with another. But even into the present century, in the many accounts of the Law of Nature, and of the general conception of the State, there prevailed the fundamental idea that the State was essentially an associa- tion of individuals, and therefore an arbitrary work of individual freedom. The absolutist, Hobbes 4 , who makes the authority of the monarch an all-devouring Leviathan, is in this at one with the radical Rousseau 5 , whose ' sovereignty of the people ' makes the continuance of the whole order of the State an open question. The ingenious Samuel Puffendorf 6 regards the State as a moral person, but its will is, for him too, only composed of the individual wills of all, and he explains the State by the theory of social 3 Hugo Grotius, De jure belli, etc,, i. i. 14: 'Est civitas coetus perfectus liberorum hominum, juris fruendi et communis utilitatis causa sociatus.' i. 3. 7 ; Prolegom. 16. Cp. Leo, Weltgeschichte, iv. p. 149. * Hobbes, De Cive, c. 5. 9. Molesworth's Edit. Vol. II. p. 214: ' Civitas ergo est persona una (?), cujus voluntas ex pacti s plurium homi- num pro voluntate babenda est ipsorum hominum ; ut singulorum viribus et facultatibus uti possit ad pacem et defensionem communem.' 5 Rousseau, Contrat social, I. Ch. 6 : 'Trouver une forme d'associa- tion qui defende et protege de toute la force commune la personne et les biens de chaque associe, et par laquelle chacun, s'unissant a tous, n'obeisse pourtant qu'a lui-meme et reste aussi libre qu'auparavant : tel est le prob- leme fondamental dont le Contrat social donne la solution.* 6 Dejure naturali et gent., vii. 2, 13 : ' Unde civitatis haec commo- dissima videtur definitio, quod sit persona moralis composita, cujus voluntas ex plurium pactis implicita et unita pro voluntate omnium habetur, ut singulorum viribus et facultatibus ad pacem et securitatem communem uti possit.' Chap. VII.] DIFFERENT THEORIES. 67 contract. John Locke zealously defends this theory against the attacks of theological bigots, and finds in it a guarantee of English civic liberty. Even Kant 7 does not get beyond it, although he shows a tendency to do so, and Fichte him- self in his earlier writings still adheres to the same view. The State, according to the whole philosophy of natural rights, is essentially based upon contract and upon associa- tion. If the ancient philosophers did not sufficiently regard the rights of individuals, the modern have committed the opposite error of regarding the individual so much as to ignore the significance of the State as a whole. It was only in the modern period that the theory of 3- System of i i 111 authority. natural law could obtain general acceptance, and lead to attempts to realise it. The absolutist character of the two centuries before 1740 implied a theory of the State, which based it upon the power of a superior. The source of this conception received no further examination. Sometimes people were content with the traditional belief of the Church, that the government had received the sword from God : sometimes they inclined to the patrimonial tradition that the prince was the supreme owner of the country. Mean- while these older doctrines had to undergo a transforma- tion, partly through the accentuation of the ' public law' (offentlich-rechtlicJi) character of sovereignty, partly through the necessary regard to the public weal. The State was thus regarded as being essentially the sphere of the power of a superior, and the government was actually identified with the State (Tetat c*est moi^ as Louis XIV said). This was the fundamental idea of the absolutist theory of the State which, prepared by Bodin and Hobbes, was developed in a theological way, especially by Filmer and Bossuet, and was taught with a hundred variations. In this one-sided view of authority, the rights and liberty of 7 Werke, vii. 197 (Ed. Rosenkranz) : ' A union of many for some end is to be found in all social contracts, but a union which is in itself an end is only to be found in a society, so far as it constitutes a collective being (gemeinsames Weseri)! F 2 68 THE CONCEPTION OF THE STATE. [Book I. the governed were of course altogether left out of sight. Just as the Roman Catholic Church places the essence of its being in the clergy alone, with the Pope at their head, while the laity are regarded as a flock of sheep, who have to be guided and sheared by their spiritual shepherd ; so, according to this theory of the State, only the prince and the government officials had any value, and the subjects were looked on as a mere passive mass, to be managed and governed from above, but with no claim to manage them- selves, or to share the government, or to control the conduct of their rulers. 4 . The State It was with the immediate intention of narrowing the state.' egal sphere assigned to government, alike by the theory of natural law and by the theory of authority, that Kant and Wilhelm von Humboldt declared the State to be a 'legal State ' (Rechtssiat) in the sense that its sole duty was the maintenance of the legal security of each individual. Fichte indeed broke through these narrow limits in describing the State, as at the same time concerned with economics, and in this respect he even exaggerated its power, and towards the end of his life, inspired by the national enthusiasm for i the liberation of Germany, he ascribed to the State still higher spiritual functions. But most German philosophers and jurists of the next generation still adhered to the theory in the narrow Kantian sense. The idea obtained acceptance with many who sought a defence against the mania of the time for over-government, and against the arbitrariness of the police and the military. Legal state But those who opposed the legal State to the police State ' state! ( ce (Polizeist&f), and who declared it to be the work of modern times, to replace the latter by the former, were without a clear consciousness of all that the State implied. The State must not be made a mere legal State, any more than it can be a mere ' police State. 7 In the former case the State would at last become a mere institution for administer- ing justice, in which the legislative power would establish the legal rules, and the judicial power would protect them Chap. VII.] DIFFERENT THEORIES. 69 and apply them to particular cases, and the government would have almost no other activity left it than that of a servant of the law courts, a policeman a . Economic interests, culture, and the development of the national power would be neglected, and there could be no greatness in the policy of the country. On the other hand, a one-sided develop- ment of the ' police State ' would in the end sacrifice all individual rights and freedom to an exclusive regard for that which appears useful to the whole, and would subject free men to an intolerable amount of protection. If then by 'legal State 7 is understood (i) that the State in what is only an institution for protecting the rights of individuals, state is and all public law is clearly turned into a mere means for private < s i"gai a state.' law, and the State sinks to the position of a mere servant of private persons. Further, if by ' legal State' is understood (2) that the State has to organise the rights of the community, and at the same time to care for the recognition of individual rights, this is a quite correct but an insufficient view, since just the most important activity of the statesman, care for the material well-being and the spiritual elevation of the people, is overlooked. Or (3) if it is understood that the State has practically to further the public welfare, but can formally only exercise compulsion in so far as this is required by some definite legal rights, this is true enough, but at the same time it is clear that only one side of political activity is thereby deter- mined, and that no account is taken of public care, e. g. for the needs of food-supply, trade, and civilisation generally, <* [Cpr Book V. ch. iii. below. It will be obvious that Bluntschli's ' legal State ' implies what has in England been called * Administrative Nihilism' (by Professor Huxley, criticising Mr. Herbert Spencer), or ' Anarchy plus the policeman ' the very opposite therefore of what Bluntschli calls * Police State/ which implies what has been nicknamed ' grandmotherly legislation.' It should be observed that some more recent German writers have used the term Rechtsstat simply in the sense of a constitutional government, a government in which the administra- tion does not transgress the law whatever that may be. See Holzendoi ff, Principien der Politik (2nd edit.), pp. 213, 214.] 70 THE CONCEPTION OF THE STATE. [Book I. all of which move freely within those legal limits, and need no formal compulsion. If by legal State is understood (4) the denial of the reli- gious basis of the State, and the affirmation of its human basis and limits; or (5) the resistance to all absolute authority, to the patrimonial State too often allied with arbitrary police interference and the assertion that the citizens must have a share in public affairs, the charac- teristics of the modern State are indeed indicated, but the expression is unfortunate. It is better to call it a ' consti- , tutional State.' The state The State has two aspects : rest and movement, con- regard to tinuance and progress, body and spirit. There are two fa^aV^di political sciences corresponding to this internal distinction, as to Law. p u blic Law and Politics ; and so too there are two great principles which, like two stars, illuminate and fructify the life of the State, conditioning both its form and content : justice (justitia) and the public weal (salus publica). Statesmen have especially the latter before them, jurists the former. The idea of justice determines public law, the idea of welfare guides politics. The care of government relates rather to the public welfare, although within the limits of law. The Romans, the political people par excellence^ assigned to their highest magistrates the care for the public weal as their supreme duty 8 . The activity of the law courts is limited to the maintenance of the law. But if the State is to exist and prosper, it must constantly pay regard to public welfare as well as to law. Now it is just the needs of the common- weal which are more highly regarded by the modern than by the mediaeval State, and therefore the former is less of a mere legal State than the latter. 5 . The The historical school has the merit of having restored the school consciousness of the organic character of the State, of which Seory of indeed a few great statesmen had never lost a vivid compre- the State. 8 Cic. de Legibus, iii. c. 3, of the Consuls : ' Ollis salus populi suprema lex esto/ Chap. VII.] DIFFERENT THEORIES. 71 hension. Frederick the Great of Prussia expressed it clearly in his Anti-Machiavel : ( As men are born, live for a time, and then die from disease or from age, so states come into being, flourish for some centuries, and then perish.' But science had so completely neglected this view that the restoration of it by the historical school had the effect. of a new discovery, and science for the future took a new and more fruitful direction. Meanwhile the historical school was inclined to take up the conception of the State too much as merely national, and to overlook or even to dispute its human significance. Thus, Savigny declared the State to be 'the bodily form of the spiritual community of the nation/ or ' the organic manifestation of the nation V But the brilliant Englishman, Edmund Burke, in contending against the theories of the revolution, brought the historical State into the light of the divine order of the world, in a famous passage of his Reflections on the Revolution in France : ' Society is indeed a contract. Subordinate con- tracts for objects of mere occasional interest may be dis- solved at pleasure ; but the State ought not to be considered as nothing better than a partnership agreement in a trade of pepper and coffee, calico or tobacco, or some other such low concern, to be taken up for a little temporary interest, and to be dissolved by the fancy of the parties. It is to be looked on with other reverence ; because it is not a partner- ship in things subservient only to the gross animal existence of a temporary and perishable nature. It is a partnership in all science, a partnership in all art, a partnership in every virtue and in all perfection. As the ends of such a partner- ship cannot be obtained in many generations, it becomes a partnership not only between those who are living, but between those who are living, those who are dead, and those who are to be born. Each contract of each parti- cular State i$ but a clause in the great primaeval contract of eternal society, linking the lower with the higher natures, 9 Savigny, System des rom. Rechts, i. p. 22. 72 THE CONCEPTION OF THE STATE. [Book I. connecting the visible and invisible world, according to a fixed compact sanctioned by the inviolable oath which holds all physical and all moral natures, each in their appointed place 10 .' Such a conception of the State is far more lofty than was possible according to the mediaeval doctrine that the State was related to the Church, as the body to the soul. The historical school, however, only took up the State as it had come to be. Looking only at the past, it was so powerfully attracted by the scenes of ancient life, that many of its disciples lost understanding for the present, and in- clination to help in improving public conditions. The school of natural law might frequently be reproached with making the State the sport of arbitrary individual will. / Similarly the historical school may be blamed for having its conception of the State fast bound to traditional au- thority and hereditary prejudices u . <;ennan nt Although the works of the historical school are almost ^hiios^h exclusively limited to the legal and political history of 10 Edmund Burke, Reflections on the Revolution in France (Clarendon Press Select Works, edited by Payne, vol. ii. pp. 113, 114). Cp. also Leo (IVeltgeschichte, vi. p. 759), who works out Burke's idea. We are reminded of the noble words of Shakespeare (Troilus and Cressida, Act iii. Scene 3) : ' There is a mystery (with whom relation Durst never meddle) in the soul of state ; Which hath an operation more divine Than breath or pen can give expressure to.' Cp. also King Henry V, Act i. Scene 2 : ' Exeter. For government, though high and low and lower, Put into parts, doth keep in one concent, Congreeing in a full and natural close, Like music. Canterbury. True : therefore doth heaven divide The state of man in divers functions, Setting endeavour in continual motion ; To which is fixed, as an aim or butt, Obedience : for so work the honey-bees, Creatures that by a rule in nature teach The act of order to a peopled kingdom/ 11 The historical tendency becomes a reaction, a return if possible to the middle ages, in the writings of De Maistre and Ludwig nailer. Chap. VII.] DIFFERENT THEORIES. 73 particular states, yet even speculative philosophy gained by the new inquiries. Even Hegel in his theory of Law (Rechtslehre] paid more Hegei. regard to the historical formation of states than the earlier theorists of natural law. He supposed indeed that he found in the history of the world a dialectical process of reason. The ' existing ' appeared to him ' rational.' His theory glorified especially the Prussian state, as it then existed, still absolute although governed in a spirit of public duty. He defended the power of the monarchy, and did not care for the advance of constitutional freedom. But he em- phasised the moral significance of the State, and in opposi- tion to the wretched idea that it was only a necessary evil, he praised it, as the highest and noblest realisation of the, idea of Right. Hegel's State is however only a logical abstraction, not a living organism, a mere logical notion, not a person 12 . Hegel, by founding the State and Law merely upon will, overlooks the fact that in the State not merely is the collec- tive human will operative, but all the powers of human spirit and feeling together. Fr. J. Stahl, who, after Hegel, was the most important Stahi. representative of the philosophical theory of the State in Berlin, argued against the school of natural law and the Hegelian theory with zeal and ability. He undertook to unite the historical tendency with the imaginative specu- lations of Schelling. Stahl has in many ways advanced political science by his dialectical and critical ability in finding new points of view, and by the acuteness with which he lights up many dark, places ; but in other respects his want of thorough historical education, and his somewhat servile sophistry, which made modern formulas subservient to the romantic 12 Hegel, Rechtsphilosophie, 257: 'The State is the realisation of the moral idea. It is the moral spirit as substantial will manifested, and clear to itself, thinking and knowing itself, and accomplishing what it knows, and in so far as it knows it.' Cp. his Philosophy of History, Trans, by Sibree, pp. 40-42. 74 THE CONCEPTION OF THE STATE. [Book I. fancies of great and small despots, have done much harm. Stahl considers the State as 'a moral and intellectual domain,' or as ' the union of the multitude to an ordered common existence, the setting up of a moral authority and power exalted and majestic, to which the subjects must submit.' His idea of the State is more living than Hegel's. He recognises too that the rule of the State ' is limited to common interests,' and in this way he avoids the exaggera- tion of the ancient State, but a trace of the theocracy of the Old Testament runs like a red line through his whole theory of the State, destroying its value for the modern European world. The divine or superhuman majesty of the power of the State can make no peace with human and civil liberty. 7- u "i on of The old strife between the philosophical and historical the philo- sophical and school in Germany has altogether ceased. Peace was made historical methods. as early as 1840. Since then it is recognised on all sides that the experiences and phenomena of history must be illumined with the light of ideas, and that speculation is childish if it does not consider the real conditions of the nation's life. In spite of this union of the two methods, which supplement and correct one another, some authors have more of the philosophical, and others more of the his- torical tendency. Criticism of Another characteristic of modern political science is the the State , ... .... , . from differ- sharper criticism which is exercised not only in examining Snwew!** facts, but in making abstractions from them, and in forming conceptions. This criticism considers the State from the most different points of view. A few of the most notable writers may be named. The works of Robert von Mohl are written mainly from the literary point of view, but they show a sober and intelligent application of the standard of practicability. Alexis de Tocqueville has always in view the movement of political life, whether he is describing the American democracy, or the connexion of the French Revo- lution with the old regime, or the condition of the English aristocracy. The Baron Eotvos is influenced by a distrust of modern ideas. John Stuart Mill criticises public affairs Chap. VII.] DIFFERENT THEORIES. 75 from the radical standpoint of abstract logic, moderated however by his English temperament. Thomas Buckle applies the methods of natural science to the theory of the State, and attempts to explain the life of the State by a consideration of the forces of nature. With other writers criticism has a decidedly historical Historical . ..... _, , . , criticism. character, e. g. Gneist, the chief authority on English con- stitutional history ; Edouard Laboulaye, who writes admir- ingly of the American constitution ; and Heinrich von Treitschke, who first brought out the significance of the Prussian monarchy. Lorenz von Stein follows the same method, but occupies himself chiefly with details of adminis- tration. In the more recent school of Gerber, criticism has taken The juristic especially a juristic character. The writings of many of his pupils show the danger of this method, which tends to re- press progress by formal abstractions. The psychological consideration of the State, on the other The p sy - hand, attempts to explain the life of the State more pro- foundly from the forms and faculties of the human spirit. This method involves an opposite danger, viz. that the movement of Politics may not sufficiently regard the fixed and sure realm of Law, but disturb and transform it. The comparative method which considers the most im- The Com- portant States alongside of one another, is in harmony with pa recent tendencies. Most of the writers who have been named have used it with success. It is indispensable for the general theory of the State. Finally, in an age like ours, in which national States are National formed, the theory of the State accentuates more decidedly thel3tate. than before the national character of the State. Welcker in Freiburg, Franz Lieber in New York, Fr. Laurent in Ghent, Bluntschli in Zurich and Munich, had followed this ten- dency in theory, even before the attempts of Italy and Germany to realise their national unity. The newly- awakened political science of the Italians in its youthful ardour worked out the national basis of the State with 76 THE CONCEPTION OF THE STATE. [Book I. special prominence, and at first not without one-sided passion. Its most distinguished representatives are Man- cini and Padeletti in Rome, and Pierantoni in Naples. The Italians, like the Germans, unite the historical and the philosophical methods in their works. The organic Note. There is still little understanding for the organic or, to use logical a better expression, the psychological and human nature of the State. nature of As there are persons, sometimes educated persons, who have no musical the State. 1^1- t_i j is. i_ r - i ear, or are completely insensible to the beauty of a painting or a draw- ing, so there are many learned men who are complete strangers to organic or psychological thinking. One must not blame them, for nobody can go beyond his natural dispositions, but they would do well to abstain from any judgment about things which they do not under- stand. Otherwise they only exhibit their presumption as well as their deficiency. Schmitt- One of the first to lead the way in the organic method was Fr. Schmitthenner, who declared the State to be ' an ethical organism for the purpose of giving a public expression to external life, law, well- being and culture.' Vollgraff. A remarkable attempt was made by Vollgraff to base the theory of the State on the psychology of peoples. (^ A first attempt at a scientific explanation of general ethnology by anthropology, and of the philosophy of politics and law by the ethnology or national character of peoples? 3 parts, 1851-53.) The work professes to be a first attempt, and as such deserves respect, but is not well adapted to bring the psychological method into repute. Neither the account of the powers of the human mind nor the estimate of the different temperaments is satisfactory, and the considerable amount of collected historical material and the numer- ous observations and notes of travel are so uncritical, and so much mixed up with mere fancy pictures, as not to give the impression of accuracy. Ahrens. Ahrens, a follower of the philosopher Krause, has undertaken to write an organic theory of the State (H. Ahrens, Die organische Statslehre, Bd. I, Vienna, 1850) ; but by the organism of the State, he does not so much understand a living and personal collective being, as an organic arrangement for community in law. VVaitz. Waitz (Politik, 1862, I. 5) says: 'The State is not something arbitra- rily made, it does not arise by a contract between men, nor by the power of one or more individuals. The State grows like an organism, but not according to the laws, nor for the ends of mere natural life : it has its foundation in the higher moral tendencies of man, and is a sphere for the realisation of moral ideas, it is not a natural but a moral organism. The State is the organisation of the people.' The State is Chap. VII.] DIFFERENT THEORIES. 77 not however the realisation of the moral life in general. The moral dis- positions and ideas of man determine also private life, the church, the family, and society. Only if we understand psychologically the collec- tive human nature of peoples, and of mankind, do we get a clear and satisfactory basis for the conception of the State. In my Psycho- Bluntschli. logical Studies on State and Church, Zurich, 1844, I made the first attempt to explain the State from the point of view of the psychology of Fr. Rohmer. I made the mistake of presupposing some understanding for this science which I had made known in my Theory of Parties, but I found out that I was in error, and that all psychological thinking about the State was strange and unknown to the education of the day. My Studies were put aside as ' the incomprehensible nonsense of an otherwise intelligent man.' The fruits of these studies, as they have been matured in the present work, are received with general acceptance. Meanwhile the time has come nearer in which the path on which those studies entered will no longer appear adventurous, and the organic and psycho- logical study of the State will be readily pursued ; then people will be better able to judge, whether these studies have any value or not. Mean- time I find compensation for much misunderstanding and misapprecia- tion in knowing that the two most brilliant of German statesmen, Frederick the Great and Prince Bismarck, have proved by word and deed their understanding for the psychological life of nations and States. BOOK II. THE FUNDAMENTAL CONDITIONS OF THE STATE IN THE NATURE OF MEN AND OF NATIONS. CHAPTER I. MANKIND. THE RACES OF MEN, AND FAMILIES OF NATIONS. MANKIND has not yet found a collective organisation in Mankind : a world-empire. History in times past only knows of single afflference^! 1 empires and states limited to parts of mankind. The general theory of public law (Statsrecht) must therefore begin by observing those parts, and by defining the relation of nations to humanity and the State. A belief in the unity of the family of men is essential to the higher religious sense. Christianity has called all men to be the children of God. The civilised States assume the unity of mankind and recognise a common human nature even in lower races and tribes. But, at the same time, the diversity of races is of the highest importance for the State and for public law : for in the State men appear in an order, and order cannot be imagined without difference.' Science hitherto has failed to discover the mysterious origin of the main races (Hauptrassen) of mankind. Are races due to separate acts of creation ? or have the different races parted gradually from one original parent race ? and if so, what natural forces were at work in the change ? We do not yet know. But at the very outset of the history of human development, as we know it, we find the chief races differing in mental capacity as well as in build and colour, and that diversity has remained essentially the same. It is true that no race has remained quite pure, and large G 82 FUNDAMENTAL CONDITIONS OF THE STATE. [Bk. II. portions of primitive races have been torn away from their kinsfolk, and some of them transformed into new nations. Four main But throughout we can see the distinction between white? black, yellow, and perhaps red races at work in the history of development, especially if we look beyond mere colour, which is often deceptive. There are, indeed, many thinkers who, in theory, deny the mental inequality of these races, but scarcely one who does not constantly recognise it in practical life. The whole history of the world bears witness to the different endow- ment of races, and even to the unequal capacity of the nations which have grown out of them. (0 The It is probable that the dark Ethiopian race, the ' nations Race! 1 "* of the night/ as Cams calls them, once covered not only Africa, their special quarter of the world, but also the southern countries of Asia, and even occupied the southern promontories of the continent of Europe. There can be no doubt of the great age of this, perhaps the earliest of all races. But at no time or place has it, of itself, attained even a moderate degree of legal and political development. It has no real history. In every encounter with white races or men, it has at once given in to them. With a luxuriant fancy and excitable passions it unites a poor understanding and a weak will. Childish by nature, it is meant to be educated and ruled by higher nations. Even in antiquity the black race in India and Egypt were ruled by the white Aryans and Semites. To the present day the old Negro monarchies of Africa are not proper States, but arbitrary and capricious despotisms. These tribes made a distinct advance when they came under the influence of Mohammedan religion and culture, especially in North Africa and the kingdoms of the middle Soudan. The attempts of the negroes of Hayti and Liberia to imitate the governments of the French Empire and the United States are burlesques of the life of political nations. <2) The Red On the other hand, the red races of the American Indians are less childish. But their political capacity is very small. Chap. I.] THE RACES OF MEN. 83 No doubt before the colonisation of America by Europeans there were larger States there, with a considerable and respectable civilisation. But the theocratic monarchies of Peru and Mexico were probably not the work of indigenous races, but were founded by immigrants from Eastern and Southern Asia. The name of ' White Children of the Sun ' given to the Incas in Peru, and the honour paid to white men as c sons of the Gods,' point unmistakably to an Aryan origin. Where the Indians were left to themselves, they again relapsed into the state of wild hunters, and fell into small groups. Their tribal republics with changing chiefs, impetuous orators and assemblies, rest on no firm foundation of law and institutions. They are not States, but societies of hunters. Individuals, perhaps, enjoy a self-willed and fro ward freedom, but the bond uniting the whole is crude and inflexible. They can offer no opposition to the advance of white civilisation, and are crushed out and destroyed by it. The so-called ' yellow ' race has more significance for poll- (3) The tical development. Their home has always been in Asia, and they part into two main tribes, the browner type of the Malays, and the lighter type of the Finns and Mongols. The latter especially has produced great princes, comman- ders, and statesmen. Some, indeed, of these tribes have remained to the present day in the nomad state, as herds- men, hunters, and robbers, chiefly in middle Asia; but other nations of this race have founded great empires. They have retained their roughness in the West, and grown more humane in the East. The race, as a whole, comes nearer to the Caucasian than either the Negroes or the Indians do, and they have from early times, especially in the upper classes, intermarried with whites. The civilised nations (Culturvolker) of China and Japan have reached a higher development than the Huns and Turks. They have pro- \ duced a subtle political philosophy, and the ideas of humanity as opposed to barbarism, and personal merit as opposed to nobility of birth, were recognised by them earlier than by G 2 84 FUNDAMENTAL CONDITIONS OF THE STA TE. [Bk. II. the Aryans of Europe. They have^ione much for agricul- ture, trades, schools, and police. But their ideas of law were always mixed up with moral precepts, and limited by considerations of family life and discipline?) Their govern- ment is a benevolent despotism. They have little sense of honour, and no idea of national freedom. ( 4 ) The Highest in the scale stands the white race of Caucasian or Iranian nations, the l nations of the daylight,' as Carus calls them in opposition to the children of the night and of the twilight, the l children of the sun and of heaven,' as the ancients called them. They are pre-eminently the nations which determine the history of the world. All the higher re- ligions which unite man with God were firstjrevealed among them ; almost all philosophy has issued from the works of their mind. In contact with other races they have always ended by conquering them and making them their subjects. They give the impulse to all higher political development, with its To their intellect and to the energy of their will, we owe, frmiUesf under God, all the highest achievements of the human spirit. Semitic But these ' nations of the day ' part into two great families, (b) the Aryan. t ^ e Semitic and the Aryan nations. The function of the Semites in the world is, above all, a religious one. Judaism, Christianity, Islam, were all first given to the world among Semitic nations, and in the East. But politically they are less important. On the other hand, the Aryan family of nations, whose language is the richest in forms and in thought, holds the first place in the history of States and the develop- ment of rights : they have found their true home in Europe, and it is here that their manly genius for politics has un- folded and matured. On this rests the claim of these Aryan nations of Europe to become, by their ideas and institutions, the political leaders of the other nations of the earth, and so to per- fect the organisation of mankind. These differ- This diversity of races, then, is natural : it is due to nature's Race are creative energy, and is not merely the product of human thTs-Tof' 1 history. On the other hand, the nations into which these Chap. I.] THE RACES OF MEN. 85 races divide, or which have arisen from the fusion of different Nationaiity races, are clearly the product of human history. Nations toricai.' are ' historical ' members of humanity and its races. We do, indeed, know of primitive nations, nations, that is, which meet us in early times, of which we have scanty knowledge, or whose origin is lost in antiquity. But there are a very large number of nations whose origin falls within the domain of our historical knowledge, and we have sufficient ground for believing that the ( primitive nations ' arose in the same way. History, by processes of separation and fusion, as well as by change and development, has in course of time severed nations and produced new ones. Hence the peculiarity of nations appears less in their physical appear- ance than in their spirit and character, their language and their law. Notes. i. Prichard in his Natural History of Man has treated of the differences and affinities of the chief races in physical structure and speech : while A. de Gobineau in his Essai sur Vinegalite des races humaines, Paris, 1852-1855, has tried to bring out political differences. Interesting and stimulating as these works are, there is still much to be done before sure scientific results are attained. The latest and most complete work is Th. Waitz, Anthropologie der Naturvb'lker (Theil vi. bearbeitet von Gerland), 1859-1872 ; cf. also Peschel, Volkerkunde, 5th ed., 1 88 1, pp. 337 ff. 2. Science has too long neglected the important bearing of race on law and politics. Gobineau, who seeks to supply this want, often goes to the opposite extreme of explaining everything by race. He also at- tends too exclusively to race founded on birth and descent (Geburtsrasse), ignoring the fact that a race, as we see both in families and nations, may be produced by education (anerzogene Rasse). Such a 'secondary' race, though more dependent on human freedom, has a powerful influence on the development of rights. The Romish clergy are a striking instance of this. The influence of individuals is distinct from that of race, and demands equal attention : individuals have determined the course of history almost more than races. The treatment of these differences by Fr. Rohmer in his Lehre von den politischen Parteien (dargestellt durch Theodor Rohmer, Zurich, 1844) deserves more attention than it has received. CHAPTER II. THE CONCEPTIONS ' PEOPLE" AND ' NATION? VULGAR usage confuses the expressions ' people ' (Nation] and * nation' (Volk); science must carefully distinguish them. But even scientific language is often confused by the fact that the same words are used in different senses by different civilised nations. impUes P a In En g u ' sh the word ' people,' like the French ' peuple] civilisation, a implies the notion of a civilisation, which the Germans (like Nation is a political idea, the old Romans in the word ' natio ') express by Nation a . The political idea is expressed in English by * Nation,' and in German by Volk. Etymology is in favour of German usage, for the word natio (from nasci) points to birth and race, Volk and populus rather to the public life of a State Thus the Germans in the middle ages were at once a people (Nation) and a nation (Volk), while in the last few centuries they ceased to be a nation, and were rather a people divided into a number of different states, countries, and one may almost say nations. To-day the German nation ( Volk) has come to life again, although in- dividual parts of the German people form parts of non- German nations and states. Although in our time the sense of nationality is stronger than ever before, yet even now the ideas of ' people ' and ' nation ' nowhere fully coincide. a [The English word ' people ' has however very often the political sense of Volk, e.g. Volksvertretung = ' Representation of the people.'] THE CONCEPTIONS ' PEOPLE* AND l NATION! 87 Peoples and Nations are the product of history. A People Origin of a comes into being by a slow psychological process, in which Peop e ' a mass of men gradually develope a type of life and society which differentiates them from others, and becomes the fixed inheritance of their race. A mere arbitrary combination or collection of men has never given rise to a People. Even the voluntary agree- ment and social contract of a number of persons cannot create one. To form a People, the experiences and fortunes of several generations must co-operate, and its permanence is never secured until a succession of families handing down its accumulated culture from generation to generation has made its characteristics hereditary. The rise of a Nation implies merely a political process, Origin of a the creation of a State, and may therefore be brought about quickly by a new constitution, but not with real safety un- less built upon a basis of nationality. In the formation of a People many forces and factors are at work, tending to unite the masses composing it by a common spirit, common interests, and common customs, and to separate them from other masses which have become strange to them. Religious belief acted with such power, especially in me- The influ- diaeval Europe, but also in ancient Asia on the whole iTeiiglon?* thought and life of men, that community of religion was\ made the ground of nationality, and unbelievers were ex-\ eluded as foreigners. Probably the Aryans of India and Persia first parted from one another for religious reasons, and certainly the Brah- manists and Buddhists, in spite of their common habitation, language and descent, fought with one another as foreign peoples, merely on the ground of their faith. And thus the Jewish people maintained their characteristics, not only in their own home, but in the Babylonian Captivity, under the Roman Empire in Alexandria and Rome, and even after the destruction of the Jewish state had dispersed them among strange states and peoples. But now that 88 FUNDAMENTAL CONDITIONS OF THE STA TE. [Bk. II. religious freedom is valued more highly than unity of belief, this influence of religion upon the formation and separation of peoples becomes weaker. Nationality is now a stronger power to unite and to separate than religion. Germans have become conscious of their unity as a nation apart from the question whether they are Catholics or Protestants, Jews or Pantheists, and they maintain their distinction from foreign peoples, although many of these are of the same religion with them. (/>) Language. A stronger influence on the separation of Peoples than that of religion is difference of language. Common lan- guage is the special mark of a People. The populations of different countries gradually give to their language a new form of their own, until a time comes when those who once used the same speech cease to understand one another, because their languages have taken different ways. Henceforward those who still speak and understand the same language recognise one another as members of the same people (' Nationale'\ while the others, whose language they no longer understand, are regarded as strangers. Language is the expression of the common spirit and the instrument of intellectual intercourse. It is carried forward and handed down as a heritage in the family. The national language therefore keeps the sense of nationality awake and living by daily exercise. Even strange races, entering on the heritage of a new language, are gradually transformed in spirit by it until their nationality is changed. Thus the German tribes of the Ostrogoths and Lombards in Italy became Italian ; the Celts, the Franks and Burgundians in France became French ; the Slavs and Wends in Prussia became German. If the feeling of nationality in our day has become more powerful and effective than ever before, it is due in the main to the influence of language, to literature, and above all the periodical press. The ' national ' movement has received its chief impulse from national literature, which is ,the means Chap. II.] THE CONCEPTIONS 'PEOPLE' AND l NATION? 89 to community of thought and feeling, and to the common extension of intellectual possessions. Still, language does not always decide nationality, and therefore the notions of a ' people ' and hereditary com- munity of speech are not exactly coincident. The Bretons and the Basques regard themselves as part of the French people, although they speak French as a foreign language. Here political union in one nation ( Volk\ common fortunes, (c) Habita- interests and culture have awakened and formed the feeling toms, poiiti- of French nationality. On the other hand, English and ca North Americans, although they continue to speak a com- mon language, regard one another as two nationalities, distinct, although closely related. Here it is not language, but the difference of natural circumstances and pursuits, and of historical, social and political conditions which have divided one people into two. These instances show that, apart from (a) religion and (^) language, (c) community (i) of country and habitation, (2) of way of life, occupation and customs, and (3) of political union have their influence in the formation of new peoples. Finally, the mixture of parts of different nationalities may (d) Fusion of give rise to a new type and a new character, and hence to a new nationality. European and American history abound in examples of this. The essence of a People lies in its civilisation ( Cultur) : A People is its inner cohesion and its separation from foreign peoples bed by its spring mainly from development in civilisation, and express splSTand themselves chiefly in influencing its conditions. It can ^iSaSon only be understood from a psychological point of view : its t] l e product i r J ofanuncon- essence is to be seen in the common spirit and common stious pro- character which inspires it. It may be called an organism growth, in so far as its character has received a visible expression in the physique of the race and in language and manners. But it is not, as the Nation is, an organism in the higher sense of a personality. The sense of association and the disposition to unity are there, but there is no unity of legal 90 FUNDAMENTAL CONDITIONS OF THE STA TE. [Bk. II. will and of act, there is no legal personality unless it has become a State and a Nation. Although the human mind and human effort have a very considerable influence in the formation of peoples, yet for the most part the process is an unconscious one. The very fact that the one humanity parts into many peoples, enables it by means of their competition and their manifold energies to unfold all those hidden powers of its. nature which are capable of common development, and to fulfil its destiny more abundantly. The growth and de- velopment of Peoples is a powerful factor in the history of the world, and certainly an essential element in its divine plan. Definition of The conception of a * people ' (Nation) may be thus defined. It is a union of masses of men of different occupations and social strata in a hereditary society of common spirit, feeling and race, bound together, especially by language and customs, in a common civilisation which gives them a sense of unity and distinction from all foreigners, quite apart from the bond of the State. The limits of a People are capable of movement and change. It may grow and spread continuously, by ex- tending its language and manners, its civilisation, among foreign masses, and so assimilating them. It may decrease, collapse, and disappear if a foreign civilisation comes victoriously against it, and absorbs and transforms its members. In this way a great people with a higher civilisa- tion gradually destroys the ruder civilisations of small tribes and replaces them by its own. ^N^don" f ^ a Cation ( Volk) we generally understand a society of all the members of a State as united and organised in the A Nation is State. The Nation comes into being with the creation of guished from the State. It is the consciousness, more or less developed, ?he sense of of political connection and unity which lifts the Nation SSity? al above the People. A Nation which leaves its own country may be imagined as continuing to be a Nation, but only provisionally so, until it succeeds in forming a new State in Chap. II.] THE CONCEPTIONS ( 'PEOPLE' AND ' NATION! 91 a new country. Again, the Nation may precede the State, as the Jewish nation under Moses preceded the Jewish State : but here, again, it is only because the impulse to State-life is strongly developed in it, and its unity of organi- sation paves the way for the foundation of a State. So far the idea of a nation always bears a necessary NO state, no relation to the State, and we may say, ' no State, no Nation.' This genesis of the State we shall consider specially in Book IV. But we do not usually give the name of Nation to a merely passive governed body of people without political rights. And therefore we cannot quite say, * no Nation, no State/ Despotism knows nothing of Nations ; only of subjects. If a whole Nation or the main part of it belongs to one people, it is naturally pervaded by the common spirit, character, language and customs of that people. If, on the other hand, it is composed of parts of different peoples, it has less community of feelings and institutions than a People. On the other hand, the chief point which distinguishes a A Nation is a Nation from a People is that in it community of rights is personality developed in a more marked degree and is raised to the point of participation in the conduct of the State, and its capacity of expressing a common will and maintaining it by acts has acquired the proper organs in the constitution of the State : in a word, it is a collective personality, legal and political. We are justified, then, in speaking of a with a spirit national spirit ( Votksgeist) and a national will ( Volkswille), of its W own ; which is something more than the mere sum of the spirit and will of the individuals composing the Nation. That spirit and will, both by its organs and content, is not individual and isolated and self-contradictory : it has all the unity of a common spirit and a public will. Nations, moreover, are organic beings, and as such are subject to the subject to the natural laws of organic life. In the history organkfiife. of their development the same stages may be distinguished as in the life of individuals. The natural powers and con- 92 FUNDAMENTAL CONDITIONS OF THE STATE. ditions of a Nation, its ideas and needs, are not the same in its old age as in its childhood. For Nations, as for individuals, the middle period of their life is, as a rule, the time of highest development for their spirit and power. Only these periods which are distinguished by decades in indi- vidual lives are to be measured in the life of nations by centuries. But nations no less than men appear to be mortal. Notes. i. Savigny did good service by insisting on the organic character of the nation and the influence of a nation's age on the develop- ment of law in Germany. 2. The family tie by itself does not produce a people or a nation, and Schleiermacher's remark, ' If a number of families are united together and excluded from others by connubium, national unity is the result,' is doubly contradicted by history. Both patricians and plebeians at Rome were united by connubium, but at first they had no connubium with one another, yet together they formed the Roman nation. The Teutonic nations consisted of a union of estates, each of which was united by the tie of connubium. And in modern times we find inter- marriage between different peoples, without giving rise to a new people. 3. Mancini (Delia Nazionalita come fondamento del Diritto delle Genti ; Turin, 1873, p. 37) defines a 'nationality' as and was rather territorial than national. Later centuries saw the growth of the great European peoples (Nationen\ but the State did not as yet gain a basis of nationality nor a national expression : it developed a magis- terial character (obrigkeitliche Stat), finding a centre in the king and his officials. Even the theory of natural rights grounded its claims, not or in poiitl- . . . . cal theory. on a common nationality, but on human nature and its needs, and on the free will of individual men. Rousseau H 98 FUNDAMENTAL CONDITIONS OF THE STATE. [Bk. II. saw the foundation of the State in society, not in a people (Nation). The ' nation ' to which he ascribes the supreme power in the State (souverainete) is not the united people (Nation) but the ' collective body,' or the ' majority of citizens ' who have arbitrarily combined to form the State, whether they form only a small fragment of one people or are composed of a union of several nationalities. The French constitutions of 1791 (Tit. III. Art. i) and 1793 (Arts. 25- 28) and of 1795 (Art. 17) adopted the same principles: the words * peuple ' and ' nation ' were used interchangeably, but both in the same sense of the collective body of citizens (universaliti des citoyens). The government of the State was simply transferred from the centre to the circumference, from the king to the demos. Napoleon When Napoleon, at the beginning of this century, at- natiwisof tempted to revive the empire of Charles the Great, and, resting on the French people as a support, to erect a universal monarchy over Europe, he found a stumbling- block in the other peoples, who regarded the French rule with disgust and hatred. In spite of his genius, national resistance proved too strong for the Emperor who could not appreciate nationality. Even then the sense of nationality was only imperfectly developed. Though the sentiment was at work among the unconscious masses, the spirit of nation- ality was not yet aroused. Even the stubborn and enduring hatred of the English for the French was not so much based on a desire of freeing nationalities (Nationen) from French oppression, as on the hatred of the English aristocracy for the French Revolution, on fear of French preponderance in Europe, and on commercial interests. The English, in spite of the heightened political con- sciousness which springs from their manly pride and sense of law, distrust nationality as a political principle. They know that their island kingdom includes different nationali- ties, and that the national feeling of the Celtic Irish has more than once threatened the unity of the State. Their Indian Empire, too, might be endangered by too strong an Chap. IV.] NATIONALITY AS A PRINCIPLE. 99 insistence on nationality. The Spaniards, in their struggle with the French, felt their own unity as a nation, and hated the French as foreigners : but they regarded it, not so much as a struggle for nationality, as a war for their legitimate prince and the Catholic religion against the fiends of the Revolution. The Germans, owing to the differences of religion and the disintegration of the empire into inde- pendent dynastic kingdoms, had lost all sense of nationality in politics, and only a few educated people listened to the inspiring words of Fichte and songs of Arndt, when they tried to revive it. The Russians went to battle and to death to defend their Czar and his holy empire against the godless West : they had no thought for their claims as a nation. The French Revolution vaguely proclaimed the principle of the independence of nationalities, but it was trodden under foot at the Restoration. The Congress of Vienna, with utter disregard of national rights, distributed fragments of great peoples among the restored dynasties. As Poland had been already divided among Russia, Austria, and Prussia, so now Italy and Germany were cut up into a number of sovereign states, and Belgium and Holland pieced together into one kingdom, in spite of conflicting nationalities. The fact that neither the statesmen of the Revolution nor Nationality those of the Restoration recognised nationality as a political Forties! 6 principle, makes its influence on the political history of to-day more marked and striking. Science, especially in Germany and Italy, had already pointed to the idea of nationality, and hinted at its consequences in politics. But only since about 1840 has the natural right of Peoples to express themselves in the State been appealed to as a prac- tical principle. The impulses to nationality were roused more strongly than ever before, even among the masses, and demanded satisfaction in politics. Peoples desired to give their union a political form and to become Nations. The United dynastic system which European States had inherited from Germany. the middle ages was now threatened by national demands and passions. Austria especially was shaken by the conse- H 2 100 FUNDAMENTAL CONDITIONS OF THE STA TE. [Bk. II. quent striving for independence among its various nationali- ties. The foundation of a united Italy and of the German Empire was inspired by the idea of nationality, which gathered the scattered members of one people and organised them in one State. The power of this national impulse is unquestionable, though its limits are not so certain. Nationality clearly has a closer and stronger connection with the State than with the Church, for it is easier for the Church to be universal. The State is an organised nation, and nations receive their character and spirit mainly from the peoples which live in the State. Hence there is a natural connection and constant interaction between People and Nation. The extreme A People is not a political society ; but if it is really con- state'for scious of its community of spirit and civilisation, it is natural each People.' ^^ ^ g^ouid as ^ to envelope this into a full personality with a common will which can express itself in act ; in fact, to become a State. Modified by This is the basis of nationality as a practical principle in [FnStsof politics ; it is not content with the State protecting national states* and l an g ua g e > custom, and culture, but demands that the State itself should become national. Absolutely stated, it comes to this : ' Every People has a call and a right to form a State. As mankind is divided into a number of Peoples, the world must be divided into the same number of States. One State for every People : nationality the basis of every State.' Is this true ? Let us first compare People and State in regard to limits and extent, and see what differences appear, i. One If the limits of the State are narrower than those of the eludes 6 m people, we find two opposing tendencies : States! If the citizens have a strong and lively sense of their political unity, the State tries to form a new and distinct Tendency to people out of its inhabitants. Thus, in antiquity, the Athe- nians and Spartans became distinct nationalities by virtue of their political education and isolation ; the same was the case with the Venetians and the Genoese in the middle ages, and later still with the Dutch, and partially with the Chap. IV.] NATIONALITY AS A PRINCIPLE. IOI Swiss. But the grandest example of the formation of a new people by the power of the political spirit, aided no doubt by geographical differences, was the separation of the North American States from England. If, on the other hand, national impulses feel themselves (2) Cpm- cramped in a narrow State, they strive to go beyond its limits, and unite with those of the same nationality in other States to form a larger and a national State. Such was the origin in early days of the French State, and in this century of united Italy and united Germany. If the limits of the State are wider than those of the n. One people, that is, if it includes two or more peoples, or por- dudes" tions of peoples p^opfes If the different peoples are settled in masses, side by side s^b^skuL with one another in one country ; the following tendencies then appear : (1) The State, resting on the superior civilisation of one (i) Absorp- people, tends gradually to assimilate the other elements, and so to transform the whole nation into one people. Thus, in the old Roman Empire, the West was Latinised and the East Hellenised. So at the present day the Belgian State, resting on the Walloons and its French capital Brussels, seeks to Gallicise the higher classes of the Flemish popu- lation ; so Russia endeavours to make the Poles Russian by force. This only succeeds where the dominant people is de- cidedly superior to the rest in education, mind, and power. The resistance of the Germans and of the Persians ship- wrecked the Latinising and Hellenising policy of Rome and Constantinople. (2) The different peoples tend towards political separa- ( ? ) Separa- tion. The movement for Repeal in Ireland, the separation of the Lombards and Venetians from Austria, the constitu- tional struggles in Austria generally, the renewed double government of Austria and Hungary, as well as the conflict between Magyars and Slavs, Germans and Czechs, all show the persistent force of this tendency. 102 FUNDAMENTAL CONDITIONS OF THE STATE. [Bk.II. (s) Union of On the other hand, the State may hold the different differences f . by ( rt ) im- peoples together without transforming them in favour of one government, nationality. But in that case it must be impartial, and give up any claim to be specifically national. It will allow each people free course in its inner life and civilisation, and regard them all as possessing equal rights. Its policy will be governed by general and not by special and national considerations. This is how Switzerland has solved the difficult problem of retaining different nationalities side by side, without danger to the unity of the State. Thus in the central mountain region between Germany, France, and Italy, portions of the three great peoples have formed small republican communities, and united in a federation of peace and neutrality. No doubt individual cantons have a national character, either because all their inhabitants belong to one people, as in the German cantons of Northern and Eastern Switzerland, or in the French cantons of Western Switzer- land, or in Italian Ticino, or because one nationality decidedly prevails, e. g. the German in Bern and Grau- biinden, the French in Fribourg and Valais. (/;) Me- A very different way of holding different peoples in poll- force, tical union, without transforming them, was long followed with apparent success by Austrian policy, after the failure of Joseph IPs attempt to Germanise Austria. Each individual state was to be compelled by the forces of the rest l . This mechanical method will only hold the parts in an artificial union, which will last just as long as the compelling force is feared. If its iron hold relaxes, or cannot be brought to bear, the injured nationalities fly violently asunder. Austria has learnt this since 1848. 1 De Parieu, Polit., p. 304, quotes the words of the Emperor Francis II to the French ambassador at Vienna : ' Mes peuples sont etrangers les tins aux autres et c'est tant mieux. Us ne prennent pas les memes maladies en meme temps. En France quand la fievre vient, elle vous prend tons le meme jour. Je mets des Hongrois en Italic et des Italiens en Hongroie. Chacun garde son voisin : ils ne se com- prennent pas et se detest ent. De leurs antipathies nait Tordre et de leur haine reciproque la paix generale.' Chap. IV.] NATIONALITY AS A PRINCIPLE. 103 If the different nationalities are intermixed with one (B) Asshmia- another, there is no danger to the unity of the State, but n< the weaker nationality will probably be suppressed and destroyed by the stronger ; the higher nationality becomes dominant and assimilates by degrees the isolated elements of the rest. Thus it was that the Germans were finally Romanised in what were once Roman provinces, although they were themselves the ruling race. Thus Irish, German, and French in the United States, after two generations, are assimilated by the Anglo-Saxon population. From this general view it appears that the principles of The claims Nationality and of the State interact, but that People and aiity*um-" Nation do not necessarily coincide. We cannot therefore m allow more than a relative claim to the principle of Nation- ality, and on closer consideration we arrive at the following results. Not every people is capable of creating and maintaining (i) Poiiti- a State, and only a people of political capacity can claim to ca become an independent nation. The incapable need the guidance of other and more gifted nations ; the weak must combine with others or submit to the protection of stronger powers. Thus, in the whole of Western Europe, the Celtic peoples have served as passive material in the formation of Romance and Teutonic states ; the diverse nationalities in South-Eastern Europe can only maintain a political exist- ence by resting on one another : the justification of the English rule in India rests on the need of the population for a higher guidance. Strictly speaking, only those peoples in which the manly qualities, understanding and courage, predominate are fully capable of creating and maintaining a national State. Peoples of more feminine characteristics are, in the end, always governed by other and superior forces. As the essence of a people consists in a common civilisa- (2) Diversity tion, not in political unity, a people may be conscious of souTcTo? the former and yet be politically divided. One part of it strength r may be inclined to monarchy, another to a republic, and 104 FUNDAMENTAL CONDITIONS OF THE STA TE. [Bk. II. each may be resolved to realise the ideal it prefers. Such a people may not feel satisfied until it has expressed its character in various forms of constitution. But this diver- sity is sometimes a source of political weakness : it was because the Greeks were broken up into a number of small city states, that they fell a prey, first, to Macedon, and then to Rome. Owing to similar divisions, Italy and Germany have suffered from foreign domination, and have been hampered in their political growth. On the other hand, the development of two or more States from one people sometimes enriches the resources of the people, and is a sign of great vitality : as in the case of the sister States of England with its aristocratic monarchy, and North America with its democratic republic. So, too, the existence of a German Switzerland and a German Austria, outside the German Empire, is a proof of the resources of the German people. ( 3 ) Political A People which is conscious of itself, and of a political vocation, feels a natural need to embody itself in a State. If it has the power to satisfy this impulse, it has a natural right to found a State. In the face of the supreme right of a people to its existence and development, all rights of its individual mem- bers or of its princes fall into insignificance. The destiny of mankind cannot be fulfilled if the peoples of which it is composed are not in a position to fulfil their function in the world. Peoples must, to use Prince Bismarck's words, be able to breathe and move their limbs, if they are to live. This is the basis of the sacred right of peoples to take poli- tical shape and to develope organs for the movement and expression of their common life ; the most sacred of all rights, save that of humanity itself, and the foundation and bond of all others. ( 4 ) The But a ' national ' a State (ein nationaler Stat\ need not national [' national* is here used in the sense of based on nationality' or based on one people/ i. e. as an adjective corresponding to Nation : but sometimes it is used as an adjective to Volk.] Chap. IV.] NATIONALITY AS A PRINCIPLE. 105 include an entire people : only it must embrace a part which is large and strong enough to assert its character and spirit effectively in the State. It is stretching the principle of nationality too far to demand that the limits of the national State should be as wide and as shifting as those of the language of a People : and is incompatible with the permanence of the State-personality (Statsptrscm) and with the general security of rights. France, Italy, and the Ger- man Empire are ' national ' States, although there are parts of the French, Italian and German peoples which do not belong to them. A people (Nation) which has become or is just becoming a nation ( Volk)^ may be justified in drawing to itself such scattered members as it needs for its existence, but has no right, if it can do without them, to tear them away forcibly from a union with another State in which they find satisfaction. But Nationality is not the highest limit of political de- (5) The M J , ideal State. velopment. Ihe development of humanity demands as an essential condition, not merely the free manifestation and competition of peoples, but also the combination of these peoples in a higher unity. Law (das Rechf) rests more upon human nature than upon the peculiarities of Peoples. The developed law of civilised nations is determined more by the requirements of human intercourse than by national custom. The essential institutions of the State are the same in different nations. The highest ideal is of a State which should be based on humanity (die hochste Statsidee ist menschlicJi). And so a national State ( Volksstat] may embrace various nationalities, and even a State which is distinctively based on nationality may gain in breadth and variety by the inclu- sion of foreign elements, which serve to establish and keep open communication with the civilisation of other peoples. Such an admixture may serve as an alloy to give strength and currency to the nobler metal. On the other hand, it is of great advantage to the unity (6) Unity. 106 FUNDAMENTAL CONDITIONS OF THE STATE. [Bk.II. of the State if the nation is based, in the main, on a dis- tinct nationality (Hauptnation\ to which the other elements of the population bear an insignificant proportion, like the Germans in Russia, the Slavonic races in Prussia, the Jews in Germany, and the French in North America. It is much harder to establish and maintain the unity of a nation if it is composed of several peoples vieing with one another in power and importance. England had to overcome this difficulty by the union, first of the Saxons with the Normans, then of the English with the Scotch, and finally of the two last with the Irish ; and it is a difficulty which Austria has not yet overcome. ( 7 ) Equality. If a State consists of different nationalities, which together form one nation, political rights cannot be apportioned by nationality : political community and equality of rights must be shared by all alike 2 . (8) The How far a people is able and worthy to form a State, verdict of ... - ,. . - . , , , history. cannot in the imperfect condition of international law be decided by any human judgment, but only by the judgment of God as revealed in the history of the world. As a rule it is only by great struggles, by its own sufferings and its own acts, that a nation can justify its claim. The state If the State is to fulfil its part as the embodiment of the as the em- . .......... ,... ixxHment of nation, it is plain that its laws and institutions must have regard to the capacities and needs of the nation, in a word, it must be popular (volkstkumlicK). A constitution which disregards the peculiar character of the nation, and which does not correspond with its spirit and thought, is an un- natural and incapable body. If it is forced upon a people by a foreign power, or if, as we have seen before now, in times of great political fever, it has been chosen by the disordered and misguided nation, it collapses again as soon as ever that power slackens or the nation recovers its reason. In either case, however, the damage to the political organism is so serious that it may result in the fall of the nation, and at least cripples its vigour for a long time. 2 Eotvos, Die Nationalitatsf rage, Vienna, 1865. Chap. IV.] NATIONALITY AS A PRINCIPLE. 107 Every great people which is fit to become a nation and a State, has its own political point of view and its own special function as a State, and this cannot be fulfilled unless the nation gives to the State the impress of its own character. This is what is meant by the natural right of a nation to a national constitution (volksthiimliche Verfassung}. Thus the diversity of constitutions corresponds to the diversity of gifts with which nations and peoples are endowed by God. But it may well be that the peculiar character of a nation must gro is not mirrored, once for all, in the State. A nation outlives growth. the changing phases of its development, and although it remains essentially the same, yet its needs and its views alter with the periods of its life. A national and popular State adapts its organism to the continual development of the nation, but without completely losing its identity. The Roman State through all its varied changes reveals the character of the Roman people. The monarchy, the re- public, the empire correspond to the different stages in the life of the people, but in all we see the distinctive impress of Rome. The English monarchy of the Tudors differed from that of the house of Hanover, because the nation developed between the sixteenth and eighteenth centuries. This is what is meant by the natural right of a nation to adapt its constitution to the time. To sum up : a State is natural if its form, at any time, corresponds to the peculiar character and period of develop- ment of the nation embodied in it. Notes. i. Cato in Cic. de Rep. ii. 21 : 'Nee temporis unius nee hominis est constitutio reipublicae.' 2. Frederick the Great, Anti-Machiavel 12: 'Tout est varie dans I'linivers : les temperaments des homines sont differents, et la nature etablit la meme variete, si j'ose m'exprimer ainsi, dans le temperament des Etats. J'entends en general par le temperament d'un Etat sa situation, son etendue, le nombre et le genie de ses peuples, son com- merce, ses coutnmes, ses lois, son fort, son faible, ses richesses et ses ressources.' 3. De Maistre, Considerations sur la France, ch. 6 : ' Mais une con- stitution qui est faite pour toutes les nations, n'est faite pour aucune ; 108 FUNDAMENTAL CONDITIONS OF THE STATE. c'est une pure abstraction, une ceuvre scholastique faite pour exercer 1'esprit d'apres une hypothese ideale, et qu'il faut adresser a Fhomme, clans les espaces imaginaires ou il habite.' 4. Napoleon to the Swiss (1803) : ' Une forme de gouvernement qui n'est pas le resultat d'une longue suite d'evenements, de malheurs, d'efforts et d'entreprises de la part d'un peuple, ne prendra jamais racine.' 5. Sismondi, Etudes sur la Constitution des peuples libres: 'La Con- stitution comprend toutes les habitudes d'une nation, ses affections, ses souvenirs, les besoins de son imagination, tout aussi bien que ses lois. . . . Aussi rien n'indique un esprit plus superficiel et plus faux en meme temps que 1'entreprise de transplanter la Constitution d'un pays dans un autre, ou celle de donner une constitution nouvelle a un peuple, non d'apres son propre genie ou sa propre histoire, mais d'apres quelques regies generales qu'on a decorees du nom de principes. Le dernier demi-siecle, qui a vu naitre tant de ces Constitutions d'emprunt, peut aussi rendre temoignage qu'il n'y en a pas une seule qui a repondu ou aux vues de 1'auteur, ou aux esperances de ceux qui 1'accepterent.' (Introduction, p. 38.) 6. L. Ranke (Zeitschr. i. 91) : ' Our theory is that every nation has a policy of its own. But what is the meaning of this principle of national independence {Nationalunabhangigkeif) which penetrates all spirits? Is it merely that no foreign judge must sit in our cities, and no foreign troops march through our land? Is it not rather this, that we must develope our own mental powers, independently of others, to the full extent of which they are capable ? ' [There is an interesting chapter on ' Nationalities ' in Laveleye, Le Gouvernement dans la democratie^ Livre II. ch. Hi.] CHAPTER V. SOCIETY. FRENCH political theorists, especially since Rousseau, have been inclined to regard the State as a Society, and to identify the conceptions of ' Nation ' (nation) and ' People ' {peuple) with that of Society. Hence the science of the State has been confused, and political practice has also suffered. German political theory distinguishes more sharply between the different conceptions, and so saves many mis- takes. It gives the State a firmer basis and a more secure operation, and protects society against the tyranny of the State. The Nation ( Volk] is a necessarily connected whole, while Relation of Society is a casual association of a number of individuals, (i^T&atioq The Nation as embodied in the State is an organism, with and head and members; Society is an unorganised mass of individuals. The Nation has a legal personality (ist eine Rechtspersori), Society has no collective personality, but only consists of a mass of private persons. The Nation is endowed with unity of will, and the power to make its will actual in the State. Society has no collective will, and no political power of its own. Society can neither legislate nor govern, nor administer justice. It has only a public opinion, and exercises an indirect influence on the organs of the State, according to the views, interests, and demands of many or all of its members. The Nation is a political idea : Society is only the shifting association of private persons within the domain of the State. 1 10 FUNDAMENTAL CONDITIONS OF THE STATE. [Bk. II. No doubt a Nation and a Society, consisting of the same men, interact in many and intimate ways. The State lays down the law for Society : it protects it and furthers its interests in many ways. On the other hand, Society sup- ports the State with its economic and intellectual resources. If the Society suffers, the State suffers with it : while a healthy, beneficent, and cultivated Society strengthens the State, and is the condition of its welfare. But there is not always entire harmony between the State and Society. Sometimes Society, with an eye to its own special interests, or guided by chopping winds of public opinion, makes demands on the State, which it is obliged to reject as unjust or injudicious. Sometimes the State claims of Society services and sacrifices which it is loth to undertake. The permanent security of the State clashes at times with the interests and desires of the moment. From time to time Society suffers from disorders, which can best be relieved by the State, and defects appear in the constitu- tion or administration of the State, the removal of which stirs Society to its depths. One of the main problems of public law and of politics is to reconcile this opposition, justly and judiciously. ( 2 ) to The conceptions of People (Nation) and Society also are related, but not identical. Compared with a hereditary People, Society appears a shifting conglomeration of in- dividuals. A People has created in its language an organic expression of its common spirit, and Society makes use of the national language, so far as it finds it convenient, but has no language peculiar to itself as a Society. A People may branch off into different States : we limit our con- ception of a Society to the inhabitants of one State : or if we speak e. g. of European Society, we include the inhabit- ants of all civilised European States, notwithstanding that they belong to different peoples. Within the State, too, the idea of Society is independent of differences of nation- ality, including all who are living in the State. A People seems to have a natural organisation of its own, at least on Chap. V.] SOCIE TV. 1 1 I the physical side : a Society is only a sum of individual men. Gneist has done a service to political science by accentu- Gneist's ating the difference between ' State ' and ' Society,' and industry.' calling attention to the friction between them. But his designation of modern society as a Society of Industry (Erwerbsgesellschaft} seems too narrow. Certainly the ac- quisition of wealth is one of the strongest and most wide- reaching interests of Society, but still not the only one, nor the most important. Society has regard to the enjoyment of wealth as well as to its acquisition : further, it attaches a high value to family life, apart from all considerations of wealth. It values sociability, and has a lively interest in culture, literature and art. To lay stress on the acquisition of wealth, in defining Society, is to make it too material and selfish, and to ignore its efforts after ideals and a common good. The numerous institutions for the poor and sick, for science and art, voluntarily founded and richly endowed by Society, without any compulsion from the State, are sufficient confirmation of the truth of this position. CHAPTER VI. TRIBES. Tribes ex- As the races of mankind part into different peoples inner dif. (Nationen\ so peoples divide into tribes (Stdmme). The a^eople. careful observer can trace the kinship of peoples in their language, customs, and laws ; but they themselves, though they belong to the same race, have become foreigners to one another, and can no longer understand one another's language. On the other hand, the different tribes of one people feel themselves bound in a common life by common lan- guage and custom. No doubt even among tribes tribal distinctions and peculiarities come to disturb the sense of common nationality. But the national language, to which the ears of all the tribes are open, maintains the sense of national kinship and unity. In dialects we see both ele- ments, national unity and tribal peculiarity. Dialects bear the same relation to a language as particular tribal laws to common national law. Tribes, like peoples, are the product of history, which tends to develope and bring to light internal differences. But they are only fractions of a people : they have no independent national type of their own, but are only expressions, variously coloured or ac- centuated, of the common national spirit. Their in- They thus perpetuate their separate existence, and keep forgood or alive the inner differences which influence the character of the people. While they give a richness and variety to TRIBES. 113 national life, they have often proved a hindrance to the unity of a State. Though Rome grew strong by the internal conflicts of parties, resting originally on tribal differences, it was the violence of tribal antagonisms which prevented the Greeks from forming a durable collective State. The antagonism of tribes has also had a strong influence Tribal an- in modern Europe, especially among the Germans, whose tagonlsm - ancient constitution was nothing but an organisation of tribes. The mediaeval tendency to individualism found in it a strong support, as the modern tendency to unity found a strong hindrance. This appears in the history of Italy and Germany. In both countries, it is true, the old tribes were broken up at an early date, in Italy mainly by the independent development of the towns, in Germany chiefly by the policy of the kings and the separation of territorial lordships. But tribal feeling and individualism still con- tinued to be a power in the cities, and although, when once the older tribal duchies came to an end, the different tribes combined to form large territories, tribal jealousy and enmity still played a considerable part in the downfall of the German Empire, and even now the opponents of German unity make use of tribal prejudices to embarrass, if they cannot prevent, the national development. History teaches us that a tribe may furnish the starting- The tribe point for the formation of a new nation. It is more likely ofanew 6 1 to become a nation and form a new State, however small, n than to form a new people. This last stage of development is only reached when a fusion takes place, and with it an alteration of language, as happened with the Teutonic tribe of the Lombards in Italy, or if the tribe developes its dialect into a new language of its own, as the Dutch have done. CHAPTER VII. CASTES. Divisions WITHIN the geographical limits of people, nation or nation and tribe, appear further differences which correspond to no geographical limits we may call them different platforms, so to speak, in the structure of society, or different ten- dencies of the collective life, or different grades of political importance and development. Such are Castes, Privileged Classes or Estates (Stdnde), and Classes. The system of Castes has been most fully worked out in India, but has not been without influence in Egypt and Persia. It belongs preeminently to the Aryans of Asia, and has never been acclimatised in Europe. But in America it found a new application in the difference be- tween the white and coloured races. The system of Estates (Stande) appears among many nations, both ancient and modern, but was carried to its fullest development in the Europe of the middle ages among the Teutonic' nations. The system of Classes presupposes a rationally organised State, such as those of China, Athens and Rome, and many modern States. Castes are regarded as the work of nature, or the unalterable creation of God ; Estates appear as the product of national history, and differences of occupation ; Classes are an institution of the State. In Castes we see the authority of religious faith : in Estates, the power of social life, of economical and educational conditions ; in Classes, the organising capacity of statesmen. CASTES. 115 Castes are of necessity hereditary and unchangeable, like courses of masonry firmly built one over the other. Estates grow like plants, and have an organic development, like peoples and States. In them free choice of profession comes in to modify or crush hereditary rights. In earlier times Estates are still hereditary and akin to Castes, but as civilisation advances, freedom of occupation comes in, and they approach to Classes. Classes, like works of art, alter with the different aims of the State. The Indian Caste-system, which may be regarded as The Indian typical, is represented in the Laws of Manu as a creation of G Brahma. The belief, which Plato wished to implant in his State by the myth of the metals a , is fully established among the Hindoos. The highest Caste, that of the Brahmans, in which the (0 The ill i i Brahmans. Aryan blood remained purest, though not quite untainted by other elements, came from the mouth of God. They are therefore, as it were, the living word of God, the purest and fullest expression of the Divine. Science, religion and law are their special care. The meanest Brahman, as such, ranks higher than the king. Their nature is preeminently divine, and though they are not forbidden to occupy secular offices, and mix in secular business, their purity is heightened by abstinence from material pleasures l . The man who strikes a Brahman with a blade of grass, incurs the condemnation of hell. The second Caste, the Kshatriyas, from among whom (2) The comes the king, is created of the arm of God. They are the incarnation of force and physical strength, and are a Caste of born warriors and nobles. Though trade is not forbidden them, their proper calling is to bear arms. The third Caste, the Visas or Visayas, proceeds from the (3) The thighs of God. The higher civil professions belong to [Rep. iii. 415.] 1 Laws of Manu, ii. 162 (edited by A. Loiseleur Deslongschamps, Paris, 1833) : ' A Brahman shall shun worldly honour like poison, and thirst for the scorn of men as fcr nectar.' [c. ii. 162 in Sir W. Jones' Transl. edit, by Grady, Lond. 1869, p. 33.] I 2 1 1 6 FUNDAMENTAL CONDITIONS OF THE STA TE. [Bk. II. them : they are called to agriculture, cattle-raising, and commerce. ( 4 ) The The fourth and lowest Caste, the Sudras, springs from the feet of God. They are the servile population : devoted to the material wants of life, and unworthy to read the sacred books. intercourse The higher kind of marriage presupposes equality of Castes. birth : but a man of higher Caste may marry a wife of lower Caste, though a wife may not marry beneath her. But numerous mesalliances have in course of time produced many inconveniences, and have given rise to new hereditary pseudo- castes (Miss kas ten) of rejected outcasts. It is very rarely possible for an individual to pass from one Caste to another : rigid exclusiveness is the general rule. The system of Caste prevails even after death, dominating the future life as well as the present. It is only very rarely, and at the cost of many thousand years of effort, that even a Kshatriya can rise to the divine height of a Brahman. On the other hand, a false step at once thrusts him downward, almost beyond hope of recovery. The origin We know that the Hindoos are mistaken in their belief, and that the Castes are in great measure the product of human history. In the Vedas is preserved the memory of a time when there were privileged classes (Stdndc), but as yet no Castes. in differ- The opposition between the three higher Castes, called iiace collectively Aryans, and the Sudras, can be traced back to original difference of race : the white Aryans conquered the land of the dark-skinned Sudras, and settled there as their lords, just as the white Europeans settled among the primi- tive red population in America. The old name for Caste, * Varna,' meaning ' colour, 7 points to this original opposition between white and dark races. As we go higher in the Castes, we find the white race purer, as we go lower we find more mixture with the original dark race 2 . The two highest a For the history and nature of the Indian Castes, see Lassen, Indische Alterthumskunde, Book II. n ; Gobineau, DC rinegalitt des races Chap. VII.] CASTES. 117 Castes stand out above the third, as in most Aryan peoples we find an aristocracy above the demos. Finally, the elevation of the Brahmans over the Caste of or of knights and nobles, and even over the kings, was the last in time ; and can only be explained, in my opinion, by the rise of the new pantheistic religion of Brahma, which won a spiritual victory over the old polytheistic worship of nature- gods, by the heightened sense of the divine among the Brahman priests, sages and saints, and by the energy and devotion with which they remained loyal to their divine calling amid every danger, and willingly resigned earthly sovereignty to the kings 3 . The system of Castes thus arose gradually out of historical events and struggles. But afterwards it received a religious sanction, and was permanently stereotyped. It was fostered with such care in the whole education of the young, by the prescribed religious duties, by all the institutions of private and public life, that men ceased to consider any deviation from it as possible, and the system was handed on unchanged from generation to generation. The Caste-system is not an institution of the State, nor a A stereo- part of the constitution. It is rather a framework into which donatin the State is fitted, and to which it is subordinated. It is a the State ' universal and perpetual arrangement of the world, domina- ting all relations. For this reason higher development of the State is impossible so long as the State is bound to serve the system of Caste. It cannot develope freely ac- cording to its own principle of life. How can a political ideal become actual in face of rigid unalterable masses, held in separation and bondage by a higher law ? What meaning can the authority of the State have, and how can it exercise its coercive power when its subjects believe that obedience humaineS) ii. p. 135 ; M. Duncketj History of Antiquity ', Book V. ch. iv, Eng. ed. [See art. ' India ' by W. W. Hunter, in Encyclopedia J3ritannica.~] 3 I have treated this view in greater detail in my Die Altasiatischen Gottes- und Weltideen, p. 29 f. 1 1 8 FUNDAMENTAL CONDITIONS OF THE STA TE. [Bk. II. to the government involves misery and suffering for thou- sands of years ? Order and No doubt the hereditary principle (das Erbrecht} is of permanence. . -10 T great importance in the State. It maintains the connection between past and future, it secures the permanence, so to say, of the bodily structure of the State, which survives the life of individuals. But where it dominates public law ab- solutely and exclusively, it fetters and cripples the best forces. The State becomes at last a mummy, in which the embalmer's art vainly tries to conceal the features of death ft . The system of Castes tends to harden and stereotype the differences between the strata of society. The upper aristo- cratic Castes, richly endowed with hereditary privileges, may feel satisfied with it, but it only presses the more hardly on the middle and lower strata. It brands their humiliation with the mark of contempt, and leaves the individual no hope of escaping from the bonds in which he is held fast. It heightens the authority of the upper and destroys the free- dom of the lower classes. But no pro- It is true that comparative perfection in individual pro- frTe S dom. fessions, and even remarkable intellectual activity in the highest circles, is compatible with it. But by making family succession and tradition of race the highest law, it denies utterly the individual freedom which strives to go beyond these limits. It has produced saintly hermits, great philo- sophers, distinguished poets, brave warriors, excellent fathers and sons, clever craftsmen, but it has never produced great statesmen, and nowhere tolerated free nations. All its institutions are directed to the maintenance of order, none of them aim at progress in life. Its ideal is rest : movement is dangerous. Life is an unchanging repe- tition, a wheel revolving for ever in the same way and round the same axle. Where life has so little value, we can under- stand how it was that the Buddhist doctrine of absorption into nothingness appeared as a real relief from the eternal & [For the use and abuse of ' the cake of custom/ see Walter Bagehot's Physics and Politics, p. 2 7, and ch. iii. and iv.] Chap.VIL] CASTES. lip monotony, and found numerous followers. Indian civilisa- tion is the blossom and fruit of the Caste-system. But deeply rooted as this was, it could not permanently save that civilisation from internal decay, or defend Indian inde- pendence against hostile conquest. The India of to-day inherits the relics of the Caste-system Modem as a burden from the past : it no longer bases upon it its conception of the order of the world : under the influence of the English spirit it is building upon another foundation. CHAPTER VIII. PRIVILEGED CLASSES OR ESTATES". Estates or THROUGHOUT the European nations we find Privileged Pprlad in ide ' Classes or Estates (Statute) instead of Castes. Both give Europe. an or g an j c orc i er to the various members of the nation. But Estates differ from Castes in this, that they are influenced by the movement of history, they develope. In Europe especially, Castes have become Estates, and have passed through many and varied changes. Their The earliest form of Estates recalls the Caste-system. 0%!^ They were at first hereditary, and the attributes assigned to them and the myths describing their divine creation point to an original affinity to the Indian Caste-system. The Edda tells how the god Rigr, on his wanderings, begot first the Thral, the ancestor of the servile population ; then, in a better home, the free Karl, the ancestor of free peasants ; and finally, the noble Jarl, whom he taught to throw the dart and poise the lance, and to whom he entrusted the sacred secret of the Runes. These Estates too differed in build and complexion, the Nobles having brilliant white complexion, bright hair and shining cheeks, the servants (Knechteri) ugly face and bony limbs. (i) Priests. The Druids of Gaul may be compared with the Brahmans x . a [It seems simplest, for brevity, to translate Stand here and in ch. xvii. by * Estate ' in its old sense of a social class, as distinct from ' Class' in the political sense which Bluntschli gives to it. The French translation has ordre. Elsewhere * Estates ' is generally used only of the Estates as assembled in Diet or Parliament.] 1 Caesar, de B. G. vi. 13: * Illi rebus divinis intersunt, sacrificia publica ac privata procurant, religiones interpretantur. Ad hos magnus PRIVILEGED CLASSES OR ESTA TES. 1 2 1 They also have the care of religion, science and laws in their charge, although they, and still more the pre-Christian priests of the Germans (whose name Godi is derived from Gott, as Brahman from Brahma), are more closely con- nected with the national nobility. The mediaeval position of the Clergy, as a special order of Christian priests, bears a closer resemblance to the Caste of Brahmans. The old Nobility (Adet) whom we find everywhere in (^ Nobility. Europe in the earliest records, was everywhere a hereditary class, and as a rule, absorbed the chief functions of the two highest castes. Language generally bears witness to its hereditary character : the Athenian Einrarpidai and Roman Patridi are so called from their descent from noble fathers, while the German Adalinge derive their name from the family (Ada!) from which they drew their blood 2 . The Lucumones of Etruria and the knights of the Gauls were a hereditary nobility. Legend loved to derive the highest families, and especially those of princes, by imme- diate descent from gods or heroes, and to honour them as the seed of the gods. To this primitive nobility, as a rule, belongs the priest- hood, and the science of things divine, as well as the know- ledge and practice of law. They are appointed before others to the highest official positions, and they take a high rank in the military system. On the other hand, civil professions are for the most part closed to them. Usually they have dependents (horige Leute] under their protection and in their service ; and are distinguished even in the sphere of private law by their lordship of the soil (Gutsherrschaff). They are fond of living on hills, and in the cities, too, choose the high ground 6 . These characteristic traits are found with slight variations in the early history of the European nations. The further adolescentium numerus disciplinae causa concurrit, magnoque ii sunt apud eos honore. Nam fere de omnibus controversiis publicis privatis- que constituunt.' 2 See Schmitthenner, Statsrecht, pp. 31 and 103. & [Cf. Arist., Pol. vii. n. 5, 13305 19.] 122 FUNDAMENTAL CONDITIONS OF THE STA 7E. [Bk. II. we trace back this institution, half political, half religious, the closer do we find the likeness to be. (3) Freemen. The Freemen (die Gemeinfreien\ among Greeks and Romans and Germans, form the strength of the demos and of the nation. They are in the full enjoyment of national rights : and are the mainstay of the State. The nobility indeed rise above them, but not like the Indian noble as an essentially different creature, but as a distinguished class rising out from their midst, but still united with them, and having their root in the same ground of national rights. The Freemen in early times are as a rule owners and tillers of the soil. As such appear the Teo^opoi in the early Athenian constitution, the ordinary Spartiatae, the Roman Plebeians, the Freemen of all German tribes, among whom free birth and free land enjoy special rights. They also take part in trade, though less readily. They may perhaps so far be compared in their way of life with the Visas, but they are raised above these, in public respect, by their capacity to bear arms they form the main body of the infantry and they further exercise political rights in the community, which vary with its constitution. Though subject to authority (die Obrigkeit\ as freemen they are not dependent on any special lord. They have not perhaps originally the right of patronage (Schutzherr- schaft\ but they can have their l own men ' (JEigene). Their Estate is originally a hereditary one : as a rule the free man is born free (ingenuus), (4) DC- Lastly, we shall find many traces of an Estate which appears from the first to be breaking up, and which there- fore is somewhat doubtful, an Estate of Dependents (horige Leute), occupied like the Indian Sudras with the lower needs of life. Sometimes it consists of conquered inhabitants, always of the same race as the conquerors, sometimes of the poor brought into permanent servitude by oppression and debt. To this class belong the 6fjTfs and TreAdrm of the Greeks, the 'Clients' in Rome, Gaul, and Britain, the Liten of the Germans. Chap. VIII.) PRIVILEGED CLASSES OR ESTATES. 123 They have a lord to guard and protect them (Mund- und Schutzherr), Trpoorar^s or pair onus. They are part of the nation, and are not on the same level as slaves (die Eigene\ but their freedom, their rights, and the value attached to them, are less than those of the freeman proper. Handi- crafts are chiefly carried on by them : and freed servants generally pass into this class. The history of these estates is most closely interwoven Estates the with the history of each several State : changes and revolu- mediaeval tions of constitutions are very often only the result and the p a Tidcs. expression of internal and unnoticed changes in the relations and ideas of Estates. The whole structure of law, in the middle ages, takes its character and colour from the idea of Estates. Every Estate had its own special laws and forms of justice, as it had its own costume. The Clergy lived by canon law, Princes by the law of nobles (Herrenrecht\ Knights had their feudal law (Lehensrechf), Retainers (Dienstleute) their special law (Dienstrecht\ Citizens the law of their city, and Peasants their manorial customs and law (Hofrecht}. The political structure of the nation was conditioned by these differences, and its unity broken up. At first here- But during the middle ages these privileged classes bSome e (Stdnde) tended to become less hereditary, and more pro1 professional (Berufsstdnde). In later centuries there are four main Estates (i) Clergy, (2) Nobles, (3) Citizens or third Estate, (4) Peasants. The two first, aristocratic Estates, won a commanding political position. The third saved civil freedom. The fourth was powerless, and Subject. and finally At the end of the middle ages we find these four Estates have decayed, and in great part dissolved. But isolated remains last on like ruined masonry into the modern world. To understand the modern State aright we must know the meaning of these Estates in the middle ages. It is only by contrast with them that the modern State comes to under- 'stand itself. CHAPTER IX. I. THE CLERGY. The clergy THE Clergy held the first place among the mediaeval order. Estates. According to the strict doctrine of the Church they were not a national estate at all : they were an ordo ecclesiasticus , not an ordo civilis. The State was regarded merely as an organisation of laymen, above whom the priesthood were raised by their consecration. The Christian priests did not, like the Brahmans, rest their claims on divine descent for they did not perpetuate their order by marriage but rather on divine institution. They are filled by the Holy Spirit, and consecrated by the vows of the Church. The basest and most corrupt Clerk, in virtue of his order, stands high above the most eminent and virtuous laymen, as gold above iron, or the spirit above the body. They stand The ideals of the Clergy were near akin to those of the stlte,lid e Brahmans. Only the Christian clergy did not give up the hove ll ' secular rule as the Brahmans did, and were less inclined than they to conform to the ordinance of the State. According to the logical doctrine of the mediaeval Church the laws of the State were not binding on the clergy : it was for them to examine and judge, and then decide how far they would voluntarily obey them. As soon as the privileges of the clergy or the interests of the Church seemed in danger, the clergy refused all obedience, resting on the word of Scrip- ture, ' We ought to obey God rather than man V and on [Acts v. 29.] THE CLERGY. 125 their spiritual superiority. On the other hand, they demanded of the secular authority that it should obey the laws of the Church without contradiction, and lend its power to carry them out. They even withdrew themselves from secular jurisdiction in civil as well as in criminal cases. Their pretensions could not tolerate the supremacy of secular judges, of ' the sheep above the shepherds/ They were not bound to service in war, because weapons of iron did not suit their religious vocation. But they also avoided the obligation to pay taxes, appealing on every occasion to their immunities, in order to shake off every burden the State laid on them. As clergy of Rome they despised the limitations of nationality. They were not citizens of 'any one nation, or of any definite country ; they only recognised the universal bond of Christendom centred in Rpme, the capital of the world, the seat of the Popes. The canon law was the law of their life, and they refused to be accountable except to the mild juris- diction of the Church. However, even in the time of their greatest power the clergy never completely severed themselves from the State, partly owing to the circumstances of their history, partly from considerations of their own interests. The Christian Church, with its clergy, had arisen and become great within the old Roman Empire with its world- wide and far-reaching domination ; and the political powers of Rome did not resign their authority. They demanded of all inhabitants of the Holy Roman Empire obedience to the laws, to the imperial government, and the imperial courts. The clergy could at most secure isolated privileges from the emperors : their subjection was unquestionable. The Frankish monarchy still held fast to the subordination Growth of * i_. i ,. i i i i -11 their political of bishops and priests to the king, and to the imperial laws power, and courts, although now the power of the State had dimin- ished, and the Church had become more independent. Under the German princes the immunities of the Church were extended by slow degrees, at first more by grace and 126 FUNDAMENTAL CONDITIONS OF THE STA TE. [Bk. II. favour of the king than by any recognition of the ecclesias- tical law, which now began to assert its own authority with arrogance. Even when the rights of the Church had gradually won their way against contradiction and resistance, their authority was not everywhere the same. Italy. Interest also united the clergy most closely with the laity and the State. During the middle ages the head of the Church, the Pope of Rome, acquired a political sovereignty over the so-called Patrimonium Petri. Partly by royal grant, partly by the gifts of princes, there arose a Church- State governed by clergy. The highest spiritual authority thus came to be associated in Rome and the Roman terri- tory with secular sovereignty. Not merely were the Popes called upon, as supreme bishops, to represent the interests of the Church, if need were, before the Emperor and the various States, but being among the first of Italian princes they were deeply involved in the interests of Italian policy. This was indeed ' the ruin of Italy.' (Machiavelli, Discorsi, \. 12.) They were strong enough to keep divisions alive in Italy, but not to unite Italy under their sovereignty, nor to defend it from the inroad of hostile armies, though they were always ready to call in foreign powers to their help if their policy required it. They raised Rome again to the position of the first city in Christendom, and adorned it with churches and works of art; but the gifted Romans, under their Church govern- ment and discipline, fell behind the citizens of the Italian republics in civil virtues and achievements, and the Church- State became the warning instead of the pattern of higher political development. The modern world has learnt that ecclesiastical rule is not fitted for the sound government of the State, and the secularisation of the States of the Church has proved a great political gain to the Romans. Germany. Next to Italy, Germany did most to raise the political power of ecclesiastical princes. Even under the Frankish monarchy the bishops held a prominent place in the national assemblies, sometimes associated with the great laymen, Chap. IX.] THE CLERGY. 127 especially the counts of districts (Gaugrafen\ as an assembly of Majores or Seniores, sometimes in separate ecclesiastical assemblies. But their contact with secular (0 The imperial power and dignity comes out most clearly in the constitution constitution of the German Empire. There we find three out of the seven electors are ecclesiastical princes, the Archbishops of Mainz, Koln and Trier ; and the Archbishop of Mainz, as Arch-Chancellor of Germany, votes first. They held the first place in the Electoral College, and at the same time as territorial princes they early acquired an almost sovereign independence. Besides these there was a large number of Archbishops, Bishops, and Abbots, who had acquired rights of territorial sovereignty over definite districts, and who sat and voted at the imperial diets, either giving a vote each (eine Virilstimme] as proper princes of the Empire e. g. the Archbishops of Bremen, Magdeburg and Salzburg, and the Bishops of Augsburg, Wurzburg and Basel ; or taking part in a col- lective vote (Curiatstimme\ and sitting together on the so-called * Prelates-benches ' (Prdlatenbdnke) which corre- sponded to the benches of the Counts. In the heraldic order (Heerschildsordnung) of the law-books, the ecclesias- tical princes ranked next to the king. The secular princes, though equal with them in the constitution of the Empire, were placed third, because they might conceivably become vassals of the ecclesiastical princes, while the converse would be unseemly. In the great contest of Investitures between the Popes and the Saxon emperors, it was proposed that the princes of the Church should give up their secular sovereignty and devote their life to the Church, but in vain. Such a sugges- tion, even when it came from the Pope, was indignantly rejected by the ecclesiastical princes of Germany. The consequence was that in Germany too ecclesiastical offices became involved with political offices and political interests. The same thing happened in the provinces of the Empire. The local prelates bishops, abbots, priors, masters of 1 28 FUNDAMENTAL CONDITIONS OF THE STA TE. [Bk. II. ( 2 ) Provincial religious orders formed a separate estate, with a right to sit constitu- . ... , / -r 7 \ i tions. in the provincial assembly (Landtag), either as a separate Curia (Prdlatencurie) or along with the nobles, and exercised a more or less extensive jurisdiction on their domains. Their rights in the provincial estates (landstandische Rechte] were generally based on their position as territorial lords. Hence, although they might secure their own immunity from taxes and military service, they could not urge the same claims for their servants (Ministerialeri) and peasant dependents (Hintersassen) who were always laymen. The country needed their taxes, and the prince of the country as feudal lord required them to furnish mounted troopers. One advantage which the ecclesiastical aristocracy had over the secular was that it was not hereditary, but rested on personal education and election. The son of an artisan might become pope, the son of a peasant an archbishop \ The Re- But as time went on this predominance of the clergy and formation. . . r ..... the aristocratic powers of the ecclesiastical princes and pre- lates was shaken and destroyed. The German Reformation of the sixteenth century struck a fearful blow at the secu- larised Church. With the spread of Protestantism eccle- siastical princedoms became temporal, sees were abolished, monasteries broken up, and religious orders dissolved. Before the Reformation there sat in the German Reichstag the three ecclesiastical princes, three other archbishops, and thirty-nine bishops. After the peace of Westphalia the number was reduced to three electoral princes, one arch- bishop (Salzburg), and twenty bishops. Only Swabia and the Rhine-provinces now retained their bench of prelates. The whole of the North and a good part of the South had rid itself of ecclesiastical sovereignty. Even in the countries which had remained Catholic the change was only postponed. There was no part of Germany 1 Pope Gregory VII, himself the son of a carpenter, stated this clearly : ' Rome has become great among heathens and Christians quod non tarn generis aut patriae nobilitatem quam animi et carports virtutes perpendendas adjudicaveritC Cf. Laurent, tud. sur VHist. vii. p. 335. Chap. IX.] THE CLERGY. 129 where ecclesiastical sovereignty survived the revolutionary movement at the beginning of this century. Even the electoral princes of the left bank of the Rhine were carried away by the storm, and their domains incorporated with France. The domains of the other ecclesiastical princes were granted by way of compensation to secular dynasties. With the end of the Empire the ecclesiastical lords lost their position as an imperial estate, and maintained an inse- cure position in certain provincial diets (Lands tande). Once again, after many centuries, the episcopate became a purely ecclesiastical office, without political power. Their jurisdic- tion fell with their territorial sovereignty. The Catholic clergy having thus lost their temporal position and power could no longer realise the mediaeval ideal. Modern political feeling could not tolerate any subordination of laymen to clergy : it demanded universal obedience to the laws and the constituted authorities of the State. The time for clerical immunities and privileges was gone by ; all were subject to one law, one jurisdiction. The history of the clergy in England and France was England and somewhat similar. They had never acquired the same territorial sovereignty as in Germany, and in both countries the secular side of the State was more strongly asserted than in Germany. But the clergy were an estate : in England they sat with the lords temporal in the Upper House b ; in France they formed a separate estate, the first in the kingdom. But the Reformation in England and the Revolution in France profoundly affected their position. The mediaeval immunities disappeared before the principle of common and equal obligation to the law (Rechtspflickt). When Louis XVI summoned the States-General in 1789, the clergy voluntarily abandoned their separate position and 6 [The clergy, as a body, declined the position of a parliamentary estate, which was offered to them by Edward I. The Lords spiritual still sit with the temporal peers : but it is probable that in the middle ages they owed their seat rather to their secular position as tenants-in- chief than to their clerical dignity.] K 130 FUNDAMENTAL CONDITIONS OF THE STATE. anticipated the nobles in entering the National Assembly, which represented not the estates of the middle ages, but a body of free citizens. Thus the mediaeval estate of the clergy was everywhere broken up. The great distinction between clergy and laity had lost its practical effect, and was no longer recognised by the State in its system of rights. The great mass of the clergy were merged in the middle classes, the high dignitaries of the Church in the aristocracy. CHAPTER X. II. THE NOBILITY. A. The French Nobility. THE Patricians of ancient Rome formed a hereditary The. old nobility of birth ( Geschlechtsadef) : but internal party birth at struggles early transformed it into a political aristocracy, came a based not on descent, but on the free choice of the people Nobility of to public offices. This political aristocracy of the senatorial %& families lasted through the Republic into the Empire. The old patrician families, which in the time of Augustus had dwindled down to fifty, and very seldom received an addition (the families of the Emperors were in law always patrician "), still perhaps in fact, though no longer in law, formed the nucleus of this aristocracy ; the ancient glory of their name, traditional experience in State affairs, often too their large property and personal connections, won them the respect to which they owed their place in the Senate. But besides these, the aristocracy was constantly renewed and quickened by the addition of eminent men, distinguished as generals, statesmen, orators, or lawyers, who under the Republic entered the Senate by election to public offices, under the Empire by the summons of the Emperor. Thus political merit and public distinction had become the basis of the later Roman nobility, which even at the time of its decadence retained a remnant of its bygone freedom and greatness. [Mommsen, Rom. Statsrecht, ii. p. 765.] K 2 132 FUNDAMENTAL CONDITIONS OF THE STATE. [Bk. II. Maecenas' Maecenas' famous discourse l on the Principate is an ex- cellent expression of the idea which Roman statesmen had of the aristocracy in imperial times. The Emperor's friend advises him to purge the Senate of the incapable members thrust upon it by the confusions of the civil wars, and to fill up the vacancies by careful nominations. He recommends him to reject no one on the score of poverty, but rather to supply poor and capable men with the needful means. In the choice of senators he should look not merely to Italy, but also to the allies, and even to the pro- vincials, and so assemble round him the first men from among all the peoples of the empire, men marked by family, character or wealth, as leaders of the people, and should give them a share in public affairs and in the government of the world. To increase the number of eminent men that assembled in the Senate at Rome, would be to secure a better provision for the needs of the State and the loyalty of the provinces. The Equites, distinguished by their wealth, should form a lower aristocracy of wealth, composed of eminent men of the second rank. Further, that the sons of senators may be fit to succeed to the duties of their fathers, they must be worthily educated in the sciences and in arms. The French The history of the French Nobility is a very chequered Nobility. .... .. / n i 7 t one. We can distinguish the following periods, each with its special characteristics. The Mero- i. The foundation of the French Nobility belongs to the vm: Period, Merovingian period (481-752). Strangely enough the traces of an old Frankish nobility of birth are very uncertain. But this period developed a nobility of personal fealty (ein personlicher Treuadel\ based mainly on the relation of the king to his people. Perhaps even here special regard was paid to the old families of nobles. But besides these, other free Franks and Germans were received by the king among his Antrustiones, and even Romans as guests of the 1 Dio Cass. Hi. 14-40. Chap. X.] THE FRENCH NOBILITY. 133 king (convivae regis) received a similar rank. Sometimes persons of low birth, slaves and dependents, are found rising to the highest offices of the empire, and thus becoming nobles. This Nobility then had grown out of very mixed ma- terials. It was, at least for the most part (as Schaffner has shown in detail 2 ), not a hereditary nobility, but a nobility of personal service, bound by an oath of fealty. The privilege of a higher Wergeld was a sign and a consequence of the higher value attached to its members. Beyond this its privileges in private law were few. But politically it was distinguished partly by the association of the position of an Antrustio with high offices of State, court posts, and eccle- siastical dignities, partly by participation in the King's Council and a prominent place at the national assemblies. In the institution, as in the members who composed it, we find the same mixture of Romance and Teutonic ele- ments. But the Teutonic element tended to gain the mastery. To this belong, (i) the personal tie of fealty to the king (trustis dominicd), which was propagated by family custom and family interest, and was extended beyond to the vassals of other lords (Seniores) ; (2) the grant of royal benefices to the great nobles, mainly in the form of lands. These two relations form the chief source of the later Feudal System. 2. The change in the royal dynasty was in great measure The Caro- the work of a revolution in the nobility. The Carolingian Pefiod, Mayors of the Palace, as representatives of the king, put 752 ~ 987 ' themselves at the head of the powerful military nobility. They helped to confirm the nobles in their domains : and then with their aid they drove out the degenerate kings. This movement, as Guizot has pointed out 3 , found its main and constant support in northern France, in Austra- sia, where the Germans were dominant, and which was hence called Francia Teutonica, as opposed to the Roman 2 Geschichte der Rechtsverfassung Frankreichs , i. p. 2 1 7 ff. 3 Essais sur Vhistoire de France, p. 52 ff. 1 34 FUNDAMENTAL CONDITIONS OF THE STA TE. [Bk. II. France of the South. The result was that the French Nobility received a distinct Teutonic stamp. The Nobility of office and service became more and more a feudal nobility (Lehensadel] of Barons, Seniores, and Vassals, each of whom learnt to feel his independence within his own sphere. Thus the transition was made from the hierarchy of royal officials to the independent sove- reignty of Seigneurs : and the nobility became hereditary with their fiefs. The period 3. The new Feudal Nobility reached its highest develop- 987-1226^ s ' ment and power in the third period, that of the Capets (987 to St. Louis, 1226). Charles the Great had understood how to preserve the unity of the State and strengthen the royal power. But under his successors the universal monarchy of the Franks parted into several independent States, and in the Frankish monarchy itself offices and fiefs became more independent. Charles the Bald was obliged 4 to recognise the hereditary principle for Countships and Fiefs of the empire in favour of the sons of vassals, and even of inferior vassals. Soon after the same right was admitted for col- lateral relatives. Only in the Church the idea of a personal nobility of office was maintained, while in the State it was transformed into a hereditary feudal nobility. Thus the rule of hereditary Seigneurs spread in various degrees and forms over the whole of France. The higher Some of them had supreme authority (obrigkeitliche o i ity. Qewalf) in all essential respects, and only recognised a very limited feudal authority over them on the part of the king (pberlehensherrliche Gewalt\ To this haute noblesse (der hohe Adel) belong Dukes, Counts, Viscounts, and Barons. Most of them were crown vassals, some of them were also vassals of dukes and counts, 4 Convent. Carisiac. of 877, in Man. Germ. Hist. Legg. p. 539. Cf. Waitz, Verfassungsgeschichte, iv. 227: ' Inheritance of fiefs was not generally recognised in France till much later. The kings resisted the principle till the second half of the eleventh century.' Cf. Luchaire, Hist, des Institutions Monarchiques de la France sous les premiers CapJtiens, ii. 1 9 ff. Chap.X.] THE FRENCH NOBILITY. 135 only very few were allodial lords. They possessed haute justice (die hohe Gerichtsbarkeif), and stood at the head of the military constitution, which had now lost its earlier national character and become a feudal and knightly ser- vice. On the other hand, the military services they owed to the king were exactly fixed and defined. The king could not issue laws or levy taxes without their consent. In the same way they issued ordinances and imposed taxes in their domains with the consent of their vassals. Whoever lived on their domain (Herrschaff) had to swear loyalty (fides) to them, and the vassal had to swear fealty and homage (foy et hommage] : he was their subject ( Unterthan). Political sovereignty was thus split up among a loose association of hereditary sovereignties based upon private rights. The higher nobility was no longer a pre-eminent class of the people, nor did its essence lie in the fealty and services which it owed to the king. Its chief characteristic is that its members have become feudal princes and seigneurs. In fact it has attained sovereignty (die Souverdnitdt) 5 . The lower nobility underwent similar changes. It had The lower r Nobility. sprung from two sources, first the profession of knight, and second the offices of the court. At first it was their pro- fession which made the position of the knights or retainers (Dienstleute, Ministeriales\ who were bound in special loyalty to a lord : the knights were generally free, but the retainers were often of servile birth. But the professional nobility in time became hereditary and feudal. The knights acquired feudal estates, which became hereditary in their family, the officials (Dienstleute) received court fiefs. As wealthy men (riches oms) they ' stood apart from the yeomen (roturiers\ and as vassals they were brought near to their lords (seigneurs). As the lord sat at the king's table (conviva regis\ so the knight sat 5 Such is the old expression, Beaumanoir xxxiv. 41 : ' (Jascuns barons est sonvrains en sa baronnie. Voirs est que li rois est sourrains par desor tous? 136 FUNDAMENTAL CONDITIONS OF THE STA TE. [Bk. II. at the table 6 of his lord. Their services in war and at court were attached to their estates, as the sovereign rights of the Seigneurs to their domains. They too had a limited ter- ritorial sovereignty (Grundherrlichkeit\ and generally had an inferior and intermediate jurisdiction (basse justice] over the subjects of their feudal lords. Their class became more and more exclusive, and came to imply knightly birth and knightly education. The new nobility, on the ground of their birth, were called gentils hommes. Certainly birth alone did not make a knight 7 , but one who was not born of a knightly father the condition of the mother did not matter could not, as a rule, become a knight. The king alone could raise a man to the nobility 8 . At the same time the association of this nobility with the possession of a fief was at first so close that the yeoman (roturier) who bought a fief and lived on it became a franc homme in virtue of his estate, and if his grandson succeeded him in it, he became a gentil homme 9 - But .the ' free knighthood ' (freies Ritterthum) without fief, which grew up by the side of the other, held its position in virtue of birth, education, and profession. This lower nobility, too, had many degrees, from the Vavasseurs or Bas Sires up to the Viguiers (vicarii), who were specially numerous in the South, and often had an intermediate jurisdiction ; the Chdtelains^ some of whom came near to the Barons, and the Vicomtes, some of whom belonged to the Barons, while others had an inferior posi- tion in the feudal service of a Count. But throughout this confusing diversity of degrees and privileges the feudal principle is always fundamental. 4. The fourth period witnessed an entire transformation 6 Loysel, Inst. Coutum. i. I. 14 : * Nul ne doit seoir a la table du Baron s'il n'est Chevalier/ 7 Cp. the French legal saying, * Nul ne nait Chevalier.' Loysel, Inst. Coutum. i. i. 8 Loysel, ib. i. i. 12 : 'Nul ne peut anoblir que le Roy.' 13: 'Le moyen d'etre anobli sans Lettres, est d'etre fait Chevalier/ 9 Schaffner, ii. p. 160. Chap.X.] THE FRENCH NOBILITY. 137 of the nobility. First came a struggle for sovereignty be- From St. tween the Monarchy and Nobility. The kings were the Revolution! representatives of the awakening spirit of national unity and I226 ~ I789> the quickened consciousness of the State. In this struggle they were supported by the jurists, who maintained and finally brought into use the principles of Roman law. They found a powerful organ for their doctrines in the royal court of justice, the Parliament (Parlemeni). The nation, and chiefly the people of the towns, though seldom inter- fering, supported them indirectly. A new system of royal officials, independent of the feudal tie, was gradually introduced. Paid troops of the king served the royal power without limit or reserve. The great fiefs of Dukes and Counts were one after another absorbed by the crown, sometimes by succession or contract, often by armed force, and the alienated sovereign rights were once more concentrated in the crown. Thus the independent sovereignty of the nobility was broken. The victory of the King over the Seigneurs was completed by Louis XI (1461-1483). The Nobles only saved remnants of their earlier territorial sovereignty (Landeshoheif) : they became Governors ( Gouver- neurs) in certain provinces, but lost the position of territorial nobles. They had become merely a privileged class of subjects, whose distinctions and privileges more and more appeared to conflict with new ideas and beliefs. The later struggles of the King and the Nobility were of quite a different kind 10 . They were struggles of political and religious parties, sometimes of mere court parties, headed usually by nobles. 10 De Tocqueville, F Ancien Regime, has shown how the abolition of the political rights of the nobility, taken together with the continuance of their economical privileges, stirred up the national hatred against them. As long as they had judicial duties, and were especially occupied with public business, their freedom from taxation and their receipts irom burdens on land and persons were intelligible. But after the royal officials had taken over the whole administrative and judicial business of the State, these economical privileges appeared unjust. 138 FUNDAMENTAL CONDITIONS OF THE STA TE. [Bk. II. If the nobles wished to attain influence and power, they could only do so in the service of the king. They could not play any considerable part in the States-General, for it never took a fixed and regular form. The feudal The old feudal nobility was thus transformed into a mere becomes nobility of the court, based rather on outward rank and noSikv. honours than on political rights. Henri IV had commanded the nobles to live on their estates. Louis XIV brought them to the court to dazzle them into complete subjection 11 . In the first rank stood the Peers of France (Pairs de France), at first twelve in number, six ecclesiastical lords, six secular vassals of the crown ; but they were afterwards increased by the addition of the royal princes and many other secular nobles. The Peerage was hereditary : it had the privilege of free access to the king and to the Parliament of Paris, before which alone it could be brought to trial. At the coronation the Peers carried the insignia of royalty. Next to the Peers came the Dukes, Marquises, Counts, Barons, Viscounts, Chatelains, whose rank appeared in their titles and arms. Last came the lower nobility of Squires and simple Gentle- men (Gentilshommes). The old nobility had depended mainly on birth, though partly determined by the possession of seignorial rights (Grundherrschaff). But now a new nobility appeared by its side, taking its origin chiefly from royal grant. It consisted mainly of those who were nominated to the higher civil and military offices, and above all of the lawyers in the sovereign courts, the noblesse de robe. These posts were no longer hereditary, or attached to the soil, and hence this nobility constantly received new accessions. Connected with it was the nobility of the Doctors of law (milites litter ati, legates), which, unlike all the rest, depended not on the royal favour, but on scientific eminence, ^lessede A lower element in the nobility consisted of the many 11 De Parieu, Polit. icoff. Chap. X.] THE FRENCH NOBILITY. 139 who were raised to it by letters patent, often for the sake of the fee, sometimes as a reward for services, not always the most honourable 12 . 5. The brief and violent catastrophe of the French Revo- The Re- lution destroyed the whole system of nobility. It began v with the fusion of the hitherto separate Estates in a general National Assembly. It went on to abolish the nobility as a distinction opposed to the democratic principle of equality 13 . Finally, it tried to exterminate the nobles with the help of the levelling guillotine. 6. When the passions of the Revolution had glutted them- selves with the blood of eminent men, and its theory of equality had dulled its sharp edge on the iron of facts, attempts were made, even in France, to restore the nobility in a new form on the levelled ruins of the past, but without lasting success. The most interesting was the attempt of Napoleon i. Napoleon, who saw in aristocracy at once an essential support and a limitation to monarchy. In the order of the Legion of Honour he created a sort of modern knighthood, which was open to every one who did eminent service to the State, but was essentially a personal and honorary dis- tinction. He also thought of founding a higher hereditary Aristocracy, in which the surviving families of the old historic nobility should be united with the descendants of the new French marshals, ministers, and other high officials. One can see that Napoleon's idea was to combine the insti- tutions of the early Roman Empire with the traditions of French history. Meanwhile he had hardly taken the first 12 See Schaffner, vol. ii. 13 Law of 25 June, 1790. Art. I : 'La noblesse hereditaire est pour toujours abolie ; en consequence les titres de prince, de due, de comte, etc. ne seront pris par qui que ce soit, ni donnes a personne.' Const, of Sept., 1791 : i. p. 219 ff. Hostis originally means * guest/ 'stranger/ and ' enemy/ 2 1 o FUNDAMENTAL CONDITIONS OF THE STA T. [Bk. II. after the law of his own nation ' {Jeder nach seinem ange- borenen Volksrecht}. Modern law recognises that the foreigner has rights, and protects him accordingly, what makes i. But there are various answers to the question, who is to be regarded as a native, and how a man becomes a member of a nation. Descent and domicile are the deter- mining factors, but they may be combined in different ways. Nationality may be determined by a. Birth- a. Place of birth (Geburtsort\ This is in the main the later mediaeval view, and is still the principle of English law, which distinguishes ' natural-born ' subjects from c aliens.' Birth on an English ship or in an English embassy is equi- valent to birth in England. But the principle has been so far modified that the children of Englishmen, born abroad, become English citizens : and naturalisation has become much easier 2 . The law of the United States goes on the same principles 3 . b. Domicile. b. Domicile. This form of the territorial principle is more in keeping with modern ideas, because it lays stress not on the casual place of birth, but on the permanent domicile of the parents, and subsequently of the man himself. But here differences arise, according as settlement is made easy or difficult. This was the principle partially followed by Austria in earlier times and by individual German states 4 . But there, too, it was modified by the forms of a personal grant of native rights. 2 Blackstone, Comm. i. 10; Stat. 7 and 8 Vic. cap. 66. By the law of 1870, St. 33 Vic. cap. 14, naturalisation has been made still easier. 3 Birth in the territory of the United States constitutes citizenship. But the children of citizens born abroad acquire it by descent. Settle- ment in the United States is the essential condition of naturalisation, which is very frequent. Cf. Story, Commentaries on the Constitution of U. S. A., book iii., ch. 16, and Riittimann, Nordam. Bundesstatsrecht, i. 89. * Austrian Fundamental Law, 29 : * Foreigners acquire Austrian citizenship by entering the public service, by adopting a business which involves regular settlement in the country, by a continuous residence Chap. XXL] NA TIVES AND ALIENS. 2 1 1 (c) Midway between these comes the Swiss principle of c - .Member- membership in the commune, which forms the basis of commune, membership of the Canton (Cantonsburgerrecht], and of the Swiss confederation (Schweizerbiirgerrecht}. The rights in the commune depend not on place of birth or domicile, but on descent from parents who are citizens of the com- mune, even though they live outside it 5 . It is not unlike the old Roman municipal law, which was also based on origo from a particular munidpium a . (d) Modern States, generally, recognise nationality as a [Cf. Wordsworth's Sonnet, Thought of a Briton on the Subjugation of Switzerland : ' Two Voices are there ; one is of the sea, One of the mountains ; each a mighty voice ; In both from age to age thou didst rejoice, They were thy chosen music, Liberty ! '] Chap. II.] NATURAL FEATURES. 231 uniting all parts of the habitable globe in one unbroken and fruitful bond of union. Thomas Buckle called attention to the influence of more temporary and changing phenomena. Here again the scenes of sea and mountain make a deeper and more striking impression than those of the inland plain : but there are other influences besides. In the tropics, nature often appears so overpowering, that, in despair of conquering her, man gives up all effort : and his fancy sees nothing but the awful force of nature ; his heart is filled with fear and superstition. Violent snows, the march of glaciers, and fall of avalanches in mountain regions, the heavy rains and floods, the terrific storms and hurricanes in many hot countries, the rapid change from luxuriant vegetation to parched desert, the desolating swarms of insects and the peril of wild beasts all these influences may depress and confound, instead of stimulating, those who live among them. For this reason, Advantage a temperate country is best adapted for the growth of man's p e * a te m mind. A monotonous climate is not stimulating enough : chmate - a violent one shocks him, He needs a varied and tem- perate climate to excite his thoughts and call out his effort : his mind, which would run riot in the tropics, then de~ velopes with an orderly and rational growth. But we must not exaggerate the importance of natural phenomena. After all, less depends on them than on the moral and intellectual education of man by man. Even in hot countries reason may be educated and fancy curbed by a feeling for the beautiful : and superstition may grow rank and thought be choked under a temperate sky. Man is not the creature of natural forces : he must face nature boldly and independently, making use of her when she is kind, and combating her when she is cruel. CHAPTER III. THE FERTILITY OF THE SOIL. WHERE the soil of a country is fertile it is easier to support life : and population increases in proportion. It might appear that a fruitful soil was the most favourable condition for the welfare of society and of the State. This thought gave birth to the idea of a blissful Paradise, where rich and varied fruits grew ready to man's hand : and even now this is the ideal of the childish and the indolent. But riper years and human effort bring with them a contempt for a condition which has no conception of the true end of life, the development and perfecting of man's nature. Barren soil. Certainly a very barren soil is unfavourable for social life : for man is then obliged to procure his food from a distance, by means of commerce. In such cases commercial cities may rise and flourish, as did Venice, the daughter of the unfruitful sea. But the peoples as a whole in barren coun- tries can only live poorly and painfully ; the population is sparse and has but a meagre growth. A fixed home is hardly possible ; men live a nomadic life in scattered families and hordes. Buckle has pointed out that the Mongols and the Tartars made little progress on their own barren steppes, only developing a civilisation in the richer soil of China and India : and that the Arabs did not become an advanced state till they left Arabia for the fruitful lands of Persia and the coast of the Mediterranean. The slow development of the State in cold climates is not THE FERTILITY OF 7 HE SOIL. 233 merely due to the difficulty of procuring warmth and the severe struggle with nature, but also, and largely, to the barrenness of cold countries. The same effects are to be found in those hot countries, where the apparent fertility is great, but is marred by frequent and sudden catastrophes, e. g. swarms of insects, or floods. For social life is just as much hindered by difficulties in gathering and preserving rich crops as by absolute scarcity of produce. A very fruitful soil, which furnishes sufficient food with- Fruitful . . . , , .. soil tends to out requiring labour, is better than an unproductive soil, produce but it is by no means the best basis for the State, for these reasons : The main motive to human effort is the desire for sub- (i) indo- sistence. If this is removed by the bounty of nature, men work little, or not at all ; and generally sink into indolence and sensuality. Where they do not work, men fail to develope the hidden resources of their nature, and society does not advance. On many tropical islands the people live a happy sensual life, but remain uncivilised. Naples made a great advance when she converted her idle lazzaroni into industrious labourers. Where labour is not needed, labour and labourer are ( 2 ) Degra- dation of despised ; the life of the mass of the people counts for labour, nothing. Nowhere is human life so brutally disregarded as in the negro despotisms of Africa, where the soil is fruitful without tillage, and there is no industry to ennoble labour. Great fertility of soil promotes an unequal distribution (3) in- of property. We find a few rich men, living in superfluity, property. hardly any middle class, and a great mass of poor and servile population. As there is no check on population in such countries, it increases rapidly. But an occasional famine or invasion reduces the careless population to misery. Those few who have had the providence to hoard their fruits, compel the masses to surrender their fruit-trees and their land in return for food. Military leaders, in return for their protection, exact taxes and service : priests, who reconcile the gods and invoke their blessing, receive 234 CONDITIONS OF THE STATE IN NATURE. [Bk. III. large estates from the faithful. Thus there gradually arises a class of rich landlords and princes, of nobles and priests, who own the whole country. They attain to some degree of civilisation and to great material wealth. They exact labour from the subject classes, but hold them cheap, because there are plenty of labourers, and man, as such, has no value. The masses become poor, despised, and completely dependent : they live a dull and brutal life of service, completely cut off from any civilising influence. India. Buckle was the first to lay proper emphasis on these facts, and to establish them historically. But he certainly goes too far when he explains the early Indian civilisation and the system of castes by this cause, and maintains that higher civilisation pre-supposes superfluity. Like all English- men, he lays too much stress on economical conditions. The fact is, that the most eminent Brahmans and Buddhists preferred poverty to wealth, the Kshatriyas loved power and honoured courage more than wealth, while the Visas, who did not belong to the aristocracy, set a high value on the wealth that they amassed by industry, trade, and usury. The Sudras were reduced to a servile condition, not because they were poor, but because they were a conquered popula- tion of inferior race. Still, it is true that the luxuriant rice plantations easily support a large population, so that, as the land gradually became the property or the fiefs of princes and nobles, the contrast of few rich and many poor was developed, and has lasted up to the present day : on the one side, a small and highly civilised body, enjoying great material comfort ; on the other, a despised and oppressed multitude, Egypt. The same was the case in Egypt. There the date-palm yields a large harvest without much attention. The vast buildings of the kings point to an enormous expenditure of strength and human life. The Hebrew records describe the miserable condition of the servile labourers. Joseph's advice might be of service to the treasury of Pharaoh, but it was disastrous to the people. Chap. III.] THE FERTILITY OF THE SOIL. 235 Again, in Mexico and Peru, we find a small body of rich Mexico and and powerful men exploiting the masses, and again the mischief is partly due to the seeming bounty of nature, which produces maize, bananas, and potatoes in abundance. Naked slavery below, arts and tyranny above, external weakness, gigantic buildings and poor hovels, such is the picture of these favoured lands. Can statesmen remedy this evil ? They can if they are seriously devoted to the work of advancing a healthy national life. In spite of a fertile soil, it is possible to protect the lower classes against the upper, and to educate them to be free men, to promote a better division of property, and raise the middle class. The most favourable soil then is one of moderate fertility, Moderately . . J fertile soil which requires the expenditure of serious and persistent the best, labour. There labour and the labourer are properly valued, but they are not overtasked, and there is no destitution. Man's powers are developed, and the conditions of life perfected : families enjoy a secure existence in moderate prosperity, and wealth is so distributed that the middle class is numerous and well to do. One class shades off gradually into another : there is no danger of the lower classes being enslaved, nor of the higher becoming a privileged caste. There is a great diversity of occupations, but the people form a coherent whole, animated by a common spirit. Doubtless history proves that these conditions do not necessarily lead to an equal division of wealth and a healthy national life, and there are many other more powerful factors involved. But if we compare Europe with Western or Southern Asia, or North America with Central and Southern America, or even South Italy with Lombardy and Switzerland, the superiority of such conditions becomes evident. The main business of the State in this sphere will Legislation, be to defend healthy natural conditions against human in- terference, and to maintain an equilibrium of forces, so as to promote mutual aid and advancement. Legislation and 236 CONDITIONS OF THE STATE IN NATURE. economy may help in saving the soil from desolation or ex- haustion, and may prevent the accumulation of land in a few hands, especially in mortmain, and secure a natural distribution of wealth. It may sometimes transform a barren soil into a fertile one, and so increase the production of the country by providing for the drainage of marshes or the irrigation of meadows. CHAPTER IV. THE LAND. As the State has its personal basis in the people, it has its material basis in the land. A people does not become a permanent State till it has acquired a territory. The part of the earth which the nation occupies, or which The State the State governs, is called its land or territory (Statsgebtet). Territory. Its extent, like the development of the nation, is determined by historical events : for the legal existence of the State it is unimportant. There have always been small monarchies and republics, and they have maintained a certain degree of equality by the side of their greater neighbours. It is, there- fore, absurd to try to fix a normal limit for the territory of a State. The Greek city-states looked petty in face of the Roman Empire, but Athens takes her place beside Rome in the history of the world. But still the extent of a State has a great influence on its political character and import- ance, and is closely connected with many grave political questions. Obviously these two necessary elements of the State, the land and the people, react on one another. The land may be too small for the people, inadequate to supply its intel- lectual and material wants. The growth of population may lead to the foundation of colonies to receive the surplus. Or the sense of power or the requirements of its civilisation may demand an extension of territory, and lead to annexa- tion or conquest. In this case it is hard to reconcile the 238 CONDITIONS OF THE STATE IN NATURE. [Bk. III. natural right to growth and self-development with the his- torical rights of other nations. Again, when a State becomes too small to maintain a secure existence, in the face of other growing States, it may either ally itself with other States, or allow itself to be absorbed by a more powerful State. On the other hand, a sparse population may feel its terri- tory too wide, or some particular part of it may desire to be independent. In the first case the State will encourage im- migration, in the second it will adopt a policy of separation or dismemberment. Tendency Here the present age differs entirely from the middle state? 6 ages : then the general tendency was to small States, now it is to large ones. Then Italy, France, Germany, Spain, and at first the British Isles and the Slavonic countries, were all divided among a number of petty monarchies and republics. The unity of the Roman Empire was ideal rather than actual. The tendency to form larger States began with England, and is seen on the Continent after the latter part of the fifteenth century, and has not yet reached its limit. The mediaeval States were innumerable. Almost every lordship, many towns and religious houses, and even villages, maintained an independent political existence. Only a few of these constitutions now remain, and there is small pro- spect of their survival. Many influences co-operated to substitute this infinite partition for the old unity of the Roman ideal : want of roads and posts, and of means of locomotion ; the tendency to special rights (die particulare Rechtsbildung), the defective system of police, the feudal constitution, with its limited military service and defective means of war, the narrow circulation of money, the separa- tion of estates, the fundamental conceptions of dynastic rule and private law, the want of a national consciousness, and the Teutonic tendency to independence and to corporate promoted organisations. On the other hand, the formation of large cwMsation. States has been promoted by the improvement and ex- tension of means of communication, high-roads and rail- Chap. IV.] THE LAND. 239 ways, steamships, postal and telegraphic service, the quickened impetus of trade and commerce, increased military and financial resources ; in a word by the entire development of modern civilisation and the awakened national consciousness and more rational legislation which it has brought with it. The modern State needs a broader basis than can be Limits to found in a mere municipal or judicial district. As privileged a territory, class (Stand) and tribe have had to give place to people and nation, so towns and manors have to merge themselves in the wider unity of the country : only so can the concep- tion of a Nation ( VolK) supersede the conceptions of local citizenship or narrow association. A Country and a Nation are both essential to the modern idea of a State : without a country the State is at best insecure and ineffective ; it may be retained for a while as a curiosity, but being quite cut off from modern life it is exposed to the general hatred of the small-state system (die Kleinstaterei). This principle fixes the lower limit for the size of a State. Its higher limit is determined by the principle that every part must be within reach of the central authority. But this limit of course is an elastic one. Since the invention of steam-locomotion and the telegraph, no country is too remote for communica- tion with its capital. It can no longer be denied that it is possible to unite the whole globe in one political organisa- tion, now that international law, with its hypothesis of the union of many States in one humanity, extends over the greater part of the inhabited earth. Of the total land surface of the globe, estimated at nearly 54,000,000 square miles, Great Britain governs nearly 9,000,000 square miles, Russia about 8,300,000 square miles, China 4,500,000, the United States over 3,000,000 square miles. Here are vast and distant territories, which are still animated by one political spirit. But the power of a State is not to be measured by its Population mere extent. The German Empire has a territory of about ortant than 210,000 square miles, and yet is the most powerful State in area * 240 CONDITIONS OF THE STATE IN NATURE. [Bk. III. Europe. France, with its 204,000 square miles in Europe, is at least as strong as Russia, whose territory in Europe is ten times the size. The European territory of Great Britain only covers 121,235 square miles, but from this it governs colonies and dependencies far larger than itself. Population is a far more important factor in determining the power of a nation than extent of territory, though the latter is not without weight. The further a territory extends, the greater becomes the difficulty of movement, and hence also of government. Its scattered forces can only be slowly collected, and its distant provinces are not under perfect control. Improved means of communication have lessened this difficulty, but not re- moved it. The word of command can be flashed to the farthest limit of the State, but it lacks the emphasis of im- mediate authority : and it may be misunderstood, or, if the subject is unwilling, evaded. Even with railways it takes time to convey men, and food, and stores : and in thinly populated provinces it is not always possible to establish railways : often even highways are wanting. Hence, an extension of territory does not always mean an increase of power. A State may be weakened by its con- quests, if the smaller territory was easier to govern, strength It is easy to annoy a State of wide extent by attacking it ness of large at different points, but it is hard to gain any permanent success against it. The enemy can traverse wide tracts unopposed, but they will find it difficult to maintain them- selves. Their only chance is to attack and defeat the con- centrated power of the State. This assertion is confirmed by the recent wars in Russia and North America. But while great size in a State may make it helpless and cumbrous, it has its advantages. A large State has command of vast resources, which are not exhausted in a moment : hence, in a dangerous crisis it can afford to wait and watch the turn of influence of events : it can seldom be conquered at a blow. The size Constitution, of a State also has an influence on the form of its constitu- tion. Direct democracy is only possible in a small country ^ Chap. IV.] THE LAND. 241 where men can meet frequently in the assembly. Constitu- tional monarchy requires a larger area for its representative system. The vast extent of the Roman Empire was a main reason of the decay of the Republic and the concentration of authority in an absolute Emperor. In Russia too the absolute power of the Czar is partly due to the vast mass of its territory, and even England does not propose to give India parliamentary institutions. Accordingly the constitutional policy (die Verfassungs- politik) of a State must consider the character and extent of its territory, and adapt itself to it. The territorial limits of a State are not eternal or unalter- able. They depend on the growth or decay of national forces. But still they are more fixed and permanent than the limits of its population, and are only altered from time to time by great events. The boundaries of a State may either divide it from Boundaries. a foreign State, or from a part of the earth which belongs to no State. In the first case the boundary is regarded as a fixed line, and is marked by stones, trenches, walls, &e. In the latter case there is no need to draw a strict line : the boundaries may be advanced or withdrawn without compli- cations with other States. To the first class belong : (a) Rivers and streams, although these are not so abso- lutely fixed as land boundaries. The strict frontier between the two governments is fixed either at the middle of the river, or in the bed of the river proper (Thalweg)^ i.e. the channel which it takes at its lowest ; but as the mid-channel is that chiefly used for navigation and commerce, it is con- sidered as common to both States for these purposes. But both these boundaries may be altered by the alluvial or denuding action of the water on the banks, or the alteration of the course of the stream. (b) Mountains : these generally separate distinct tribes and ways of life : communication is rare, and only by single passes. As a rule the highest ridge of the mountain, or the water- shed, is regarded as the natural boundary. 242 CONDITIONS OF THE STATE IN NATURE. To the second class belong : (a) Seas and large lakes, which are naturally subject to no State, and are open to the common use of all the world. (^) Deserts and steppes, and sometimes forests and savage mountains. But these regions are appropriated as civilisa- tion advances. Further definition of boundaries belongs to International law. Union of Sometimes several countries are united to form a new territories, and larger whole, an Empire (ReicTi). This may happen in various ways. (a) The countries united retain their existence, and on a footing of equality : e. g. the United States of America, the German Empire. (I}} The countries exist separately, but on an unequal footing, one being regarded as imperial (Hauptland), the others as dependent (Nebenldnder] : e. g. Great Britain with its colonies and dependencies, France with Algiers. (r) The previous countries become provinces of one Empire : e.g. the spread of Russia. The ideal But as the ideal basis of the perfect State is not the nation, but humanity, so its ideal territory is the whole earth, uniting in one harmonious whole the diverse qualities of different countries, so as to complete and enrich one another. But the practical principle for present politics, which are still far from the goal of the ideal, is this : that a varied territory is the best for a State : one where there are mountains and valleys, rivers and lakes, seaboard and plains ; not that such countries are more fertile, for in some parts the difference of level makes cultivation impossible, but because the various faculties of the inhabitants are thus stimulated and developed to the utmost. On the other hand, the worst is an inland territory of wide and desolate steppes : that is why these regions have always been the home of nomad tribes which fall short of political life. CHAPTER V. TERRITORIAL SOVEREIGNTY. THE sovereign rights of a State over its whole territory state are often called ' State property ' (Statseigentkum). But pr the name, though not inappropriate to the early States of Asia, or to the feudal State, is incompatible with modern political ideas. In the old Jewish State Jehovah, in Egypt the Pharaohs were regarded as sole proprietors of the soil, and private persons only enjoyed a transitory use of it : in the Roman Empire, again, the land of the conquered provinces was regarded formally as the property of the Roman nation or Emperor, and the provincials only enjoyed an inferior though actual property (in bonis) in the land. In some mediaeval States, e. g. in England after the Norman Con- quest, the king was the supreme proprietor and feudal lord of the whole land, and his subjects only occupied their estates as fiefs. In all these cases the idea of State-property naturally arose from the fusion of the idea of private property with that of political sovereignty. But it becomes untenable now that private and public law are entirely distinct. We must distinguish then the sovereign rights of the State State in its territory (Gebietshoheit, imperiuni] from the pro- perty (dominium) of the State. Property is a matter of private law, even when it belongs to the State : sovereignty is essentially political, and can only belong to the State, or the head of the State *. 1 The ancients recognised this distinction. Hugo Grotius, De jure R 2 244 CONDITIONS OF THE STA TE IN NA TURE. [Bk. III. its cons* i. On its positive side this sovereignty means that the State has complete power over all its territory, to enforce its laws, execute its decrees, and exercise its jurisdiction. Its power extends not only over persons but over land and things ; but this power belongs to the State alone, and is outside the sphere of private law. 2. On the negative side, the State has the right of ex- cluding every other State or power from sovereignty in, or interference with, its territory. Hence the modern State does not allow any foreign power to exercise juris- diction or police in its territory. Alienation of the whole or part of a country is incompatible with this political conception of territorial sovereignty. It is no longer possible to do as the mediaeval princes did, who sold, or pawned, or partitioned 2 their domains as pieces of private property. Modern public law adheres to the principle that the territory of a State is inalienable and indivisible 3 . Alienation is only possible (exceptionally) under the forms of public law, in virtue either of a law or of international contracts, including treaties of peace 4 . Grotius further demands as a consequence of natural right, that if part of a country is to be alienated, the consent of the inhabitants of that part must be given, as well as that of the whole State. This demand is a just one, because their whole political existence is at stake, and the legislature cannot be supposed to represent them properly when it is bent on dissolving the union of the State. But belli ac pads, ii. 3. 4, quotes Seneca, De benef. vii. 4, ' Ad reges potestas omnium pertinet, ad singulos proprietor? and Dio Chrysost. Orat, xxxi, 37 X ( ^ } P a T *7 S TroAeo;?, dAA' ouSei/ fJTrov TU>V KCKTyfAevow KO.O~TOS Kvpios tari 70Jv kavrov. 2 Instances in antiquity only occur in cases where the prince had absolute power over land and people. Cf. Hugo Grot. i. 3, 12. 3 French Const, of I79 1 * ii- IJ : ' Le royaume est un et indivi- sible? For German States see Zacharia, Deutsches Stats- und Btmdesr. i. 83. * Prussian Const. ^"1850, Art. 2: 'The limits of this country can only be altered by a law.' Chap.V.] TERRITORIAL SOVEREIGNTY. 245 in most cases necessity will prove too strong for natural rights 5 . Limitations on the sovereignty of the State in favour of and Hmita- other States (statsrechtliche Dienstbarkeiteri) are possible, and uc are analogous to the ' servitudes ' of private law. But they must have their basis in public law, and their purpose must be a public one. For instance, a State may allow a neighbour the use of a military road across its territory, or of its postal system, or may open its ports. But freedom of sovereignty must be guarded against encroachment, even more jealously than freedom of property in private law : for any permanent limitation is a disastrous injury to the unity and harmony of the State, and to the free development of its institutions in the interest of public welfare 6 . Notes. i. The change of the title of the French kings from Roi de France to Roi des Fran^ais, after the Revolution, was a protest against the earlier idea that France was a patrimonium regis, and so far marks an advance in political thought. [The title of Roi des Fran^ais was introduced into the constitution of 1791, and it was given to Louis Philippe by the French Chambers in 1830. But it was not held by Louis XVIII and Charles X, who, like their predecessors, were Rois de France^] But when once the significance of territorial sovereignty is realised, it does not matter which form is used. Stahl (Statslehre, ii. p. 38) goes too far when he calls the national title barbaric. Roman and German Emperors have preferred it : and it is nobler than a territorial title in as much as a nation is greater than a country. 2. Rectification of frontier is not included under alienation, as it merely defines the existing boundaries. But it is not mere rectification when whole tracts of inhabited country are cut off and exchanged by a State to round off its frontiers. [On the conception of territorial sovereignty see Maine, Ancient Law, p. 103 ff.] 5 Hugo Grot. ii. 6. 4 ff. Cf. Final Act of Vienna of 1820, Art. 6 : ' Voluntary resignation of sovereign rights over the territory of a con- federation, except in the interest of a member of the confederation, must have the consent of all members of the confederate State.' For fuller treatment of the question see Bluntschli, Modernes Volkerrecht, 286. 6 Schmitthenner, Statsrecht, p. 409 : ' Private property of a foreign State or sovereign, in the territory of a State, does not limit the authority of that State.' CHAPTER VI. DIVISION OF THE COUNTRY. GENERALLY, the territory of a State is so large that it has to be divided for purposes of government. There are four chief kinds of division : Provinces. i. Provinces. The provinces of the Roman Empire were originally independent States, which had been made subject to Rome. Modern provinces also often represent earlier States, which have been merged in a larger whole : but sometimes they have been created by the State to which they belong : and often, as in the German Empire, the provinces (duchies) have given rise to new countries. The characteristic feature of provinces is their compara- tive independence. Their government is subordinate to the general government, but has comparatively extensive independent powers. Further, in representative constitu- tions they sometimes have a legislative body for the conduct of their own affairs, a provincial parliament. The modern tendency to unity is unfavourable to this division. The separate legislative powers of the provinces have been abolished in France, Spain, and England, and in the { Crown-territories ' (Kronldnder] of Austria limited to the sphere of economics and education. But though thorough unity of organisation is to the advantage of a State, the complete abolition of provincial freedom, ignoring, as it does, the special wants and characteristics of different districts, may injure healthy and fruitful elements in the national life. The Teutonic nations feel the want of pro- DIVISION OF THE COUNTRY. 24-7 vincial independence more keenly than the Romance nations. 2. Circles (Kreise) are large political districts, but have 2. circles. no claim to be considered as separate countries. In the old Frankish and German imperial constitution, the duchies and princedoms corresponded to provinces, the cantons (Gaue) to circles. Under the same head come the counties of Eng- land and the United States, the German Kreise, the French departementS) and the Prussian Regierungsbezirke. This division is founded not on local or tribal differences, but on the necessity of an organised administration. But still the historical associations of the district and its natural means of communication have to be taken into account. Provinces may be compared with the different buildings of a castle, Circles with the storeys of a house. They generally have some central power of administration and superior jurisdiction. Further, there is now a tendency for the population of a Circle to attend to its own special interests, and to organise common institutions, e. g. roads, magazines, hospitals, schools, poor-houses, prisons. This opens up a fruitful field for self-government and representa- tive institutions \ 3. Districts (Bezirke) are generally subdivisions of Circles, 3- Districts, and have a subordinate administration and jurisdiction. These, again, may be recognised as corporate bodies, with property and institutions of their own 2 . Such was the position of the Teutonic hundreds (Centenen, Huntari\ the provincial courts (Landgerichte), and bailiwicks (Oberamteieri) of Germany, the Cantons of France, and the Kreise of Prussia. Mere electoral districts do not belong to this category, as they are only temporary, and form no organic part of the State. Such inorganic divisions have little to recommend them. 1 Cf. Vivien, tud. ordin. ii. 6. 2 Vivien, op. cit. ii. 3. The cantons in France do not form corpora- tions, but only official districts for judicial and electoral purposes. 248 CONDITIONS OF THE STATE IN NATURE. 4 . Com- 4. Communes (Gemetnden) in town and country. These form the simplest division in the State, but they are of vital importance. The personality of the commune (die person- liche Gemeinde) is to its district what the organised nation is to its country. It inspires it with its common life ; not, indeed, a life of political activity, but of common social and economical interests. Large cities are equivalent to districts, great capitals to circles, or even to provinces (e. g. Berlin). principles Alterations in the political divisions of a country are a question of law. In all these grades the State has to guard its common interests and the harmony of its organisation. But in the higher grades the influence of public interests is greater, and the State has more freedom in determining the divisions. The commune, on the other hand, is naturally so intimately bound up with existing corporations, that their wishes have to be considered. The chief considerations which determine the State in these arrangements are : (a) The political purpose of the division. (b] Natural influences, such as the connection of river valleys. (c). The history of the inhabitants. (d) Commercial relations. Mathematical considerations of number or area are sub- ordinate to all these. CHAPTER VII. THE RELATION OF THE STATE TO PRIVATE PROPERTY. PRIVATE property, i. e. the command of man over wealth, The history is as old as man a . When primitive men plucked the fruits for their food, or chose a cave for their home, or even when they clothed themselves with leaves or skins, they were acquiring property. Property is not primarily a product of the State. In its earliest, and incomplete, and insecure form, it is the work of individual life, a sort of extension of the physical exist- ence of individuals. A man gains possession of things which lie around and come into his power, he turns them to his own use and service, appropriates them. When to this he adds a consciousness of his right to possess them, the idea of property is complete. Even the nomad, who has no fixed political bond, has property in his clothes, his arms, his flocks, and his furniture. Even Robinson Crusoe, on his desert island, extended his property. Communism, which denies the justice of private property Communism. and declares it to be robbery l , conflicts with the nature of man as created by God : ' Let them have dominion over the fish of the sea, and over the fowl of the air, and over the cattle, and over all the earth ;' Gen. i. 26. It is also at variance with the whole history of mankind, which recog- [See Emile de Laveleye, Primitive Property.^ 1 Proudhon, ' La propriete c'est le vol.' 250 CONDITIONS OF THE STATE IN NATURE. [Bk. III. nises property among all nations and at all times, and is still engaged in developing it. The abolition of property, which communists propose, would mean the death of individual freedom, the destruction of civilisation, and of the family; in a word, a barbarism worse than that of the rudest society 2 . social (>u. The doctrine of the socialists is more temperate and humane, but equally absurd, and less consistent. Frobel may be taken as representative of this view. Property is a ' fief held from society by the occupant : ' the right of the individual is a ' consequence of a common will (Gesammt- wille] recognised by a number of men who form a sovereign society V This doctrine is no less false than communism to the individual nature and freedom of man : recognising, as it does, only derivative and transitory possession, it pro- poses to replace free property by an exaggerated parody of mediaeval feudalism, i. e. to return to a lower stage of civili- sation : for it is only dressing up in democratic phrases the same theory of servitude which in the dark ages produced an abject flattery of arbitrary despotism. The state The State has no absolute power over private property, propevty. which lies indeed, as such, outside the range of public law. The State does not create or preserve it, and therefore cannot take it away. It simply protects it, as it protects all individual rights, and has the same authority over it as over its inhabitants. The main principles governing the relation of the State to private property are accordingly i. The State guarantees the security and freedom of property 4 . ' J Cf. Thiers, De la propriete, ii, who is excellent as a critic of com- munistic and socialistic systems, but not successful in his philosophical derivation of the idea of property. 3 Frobel, Sociale Politik, ii. pp. 392 and 400. * This principle finds expression in many constitutions. The re-issue of Magna Charta by Henry III, 1225, contains several clauses to this effect. The French republican constitution of 1848, Art. ii, and the Charter of 1814 (Art. 8) contains the clause ' Toutes les proprietes sont inviolables.' Prussian Const, of 1850, Art. 9, 'Property is in- violable.' Chap. VII.] RE LA T10N OF THE STA TE TO PR OPER TV. 251 2. The State has no arbitrary power of disposing of property. 3. The State has a right to tax property for public purposes. This does not exhaust the relations of the State to private property. Its rights are extended by certain limitations on the freedom of private property. 1. Certain things are naturally unfitted to become private Limits of private property, and are reserved for general use. Such res publicae property. are rivers, sea-coasts,, harbours 5 . Under this head come the unproductive regions of snow and glaciers, impassable gorges, and moors, &c. But glacier- ice may become an article of commerce, and hotels have been built on Alpine peaks. In such cases the ownership is derived from the State. By the side of such natural gifts come such works of the civilised State as are devoted to public service, especially public roads and canals, public spaces, &c. All these are res publicae (domaine public), and so long as they remain such, cannot be owned as private property even by the State, though the control of the State over them is sometimes termed property. 2. There are other things, which, though naturally capable of being held as private property, are reserved because they have a close connection with the public welfare, or because their management demands more extensive resources than private owners can usually control. To this class belong mines, salt-works, and other monopolies. 3. Distinct from public property in the narrow sense, are things set apart for particular public uses, especially public 5 Marcianus in Dig. I. Tit. 8, de div. Rer. : ' Flumina paene omnia et portus publica sunt.' Ulpianus in Dig. xliii. Tit. 12: ' Ptiblicum flumen esse Cassius definit, quod perenne sit.' The conception of a public river is narrower according to Code Civ. art. 538 : 'Les chemins, routes et rues a la charge de 1'Etat, les fleuves et rivieres navigables ou flottables, les rivages, lais et relais de la mer, les ports, les havres, les rades, et generalement toutes les portions du territoire fra^ais qui ne sont pas susceptibles d'une propriete privee, sont considered comme des dependances du domaine public.' See also Sachsenspiegel, ii. 28. 4. Prussian Law, ii. 15. 38, 41. Austrian Code, 407. 252 CONDITIONS OF THE STATE IN NATURE. [Bk. III. buildings, official residences, fortresses, arsenals, barracks, S:c. Such things may fitly be spoken of as property, but their employment in the public service removes them from the sphere of private property and exchange. They must remain under control of the State (domaine public relatif) in order to be available for public purposes. 4. The fact that most real property was originally derived from the State, which divided the conquered land among the warriors or families of the tribe, has this consequence in many States that when property in land is extinguished by emigration or death of a family, the land reverts to the State. Even still, English and American law hold that land in new colonies belongs to the State, and must be bought from it by the colonists. This treatment of land, which is not yet, or has ceased to be private property, is justified by the principle of territorial sovereignty, which regulates pri- vate ownership, and exercises full authority in its absence 6 . Vacant inheritances revert in the same way ; here, occupation by the first comer would produce great confusion. But only a false conception of the State could lead to the idea that the State has a natural right to property in every- thing in its territory which is without an owner, to the exclusion of all aliens. Survival Roman law took a truer view : the State had no more of state ea right to * res nullius^ than any private person. Alien or ownership. c ftj zen rnight occupy them, and became owner by this occupation 7 . On the other hand, in the middle ages the notion of feudal sovereignty favoured the extension of State- ownership to objects of private law, and this view has survived in many modern systems. (a) Prussian law gives the State a prior right of occupa- 8 Cf. Pierantoni, Diritto Costitutionale, Napoli, 1873, i. p. 306 ff. La proprieta dello Stato. 7 Justinian, Inst. ii. I, 12 : 'Quod enim ante nullius est, id naturali ratione occupanti conceditur/ Cf. Gaius, ii. 66. Klober, Oeffentl. Recht des deutschen Bundes, 337, has put forward the theory that dSedTrora cannot be occupied by foreigners within the State. But why should not a foreigner who catches a bird that flies into his room have as much right to it as a native ? Chap, vil.] RELA TION OF THE STA TE TO PROPER TV. 253 tion in the case of certain unclaimed or abandoned property, especially land, cattle, &c. ; and no one can occupy without the State's permission. But in other things it allows a free right of occupation 8 . (b) English law makes the king owner of most unclaimed property 9 : but it still recognises a free right of occupancy for certain moveables 10 . (c) French law is like the English. It states the general principle, ' Les biens qui n'ont pas de maitre appartiennent a I'fitat u .' (d) Austrian law adopts the view that things without owner (freistehende Sachen) may be freely appropriated 12 . 5. Limitations arising from the supreme sovereignty of the State over land and people, and its obligation to protect the continuous and successive existence of members of the State. To this belong taxation and all police regulation of private property. 6. Limitations arising from the right of expropriation Expropria- (Enteignung). It is generally assumed that the right of ex- tlon> propriation was not recognised by the Romans, and that, therefore, freedom of property was unconditionally pro- tected even where the public advantage demanded .the cession of property. It is quite certain that they did not admit any universal right of cession (Abtretungsrecht). But still, their great canals, their straight military roads, their aqueducts and fortresses, would be inexplicable if the State had not had the power to enforce cession in individual cases. Probably they did as the English to now passed a special law for the particular case. An Act of Parliament is necessary in England if owners are to be forced to resign their properties for public undertakings 13 . 8 Prussian Law, ii. 16. i ff. 9 Blackstone, i. 8, quotes Bracton : ' Haec quae nullius in bonis stint et olim fuerunt inventoris de iure natural!, iam efficiuntur principis de iure gentium.' 10 Blackstone, ii. 16, 26. 11 Code Civ. Art 713. Cf. Arts. 539, 723, 768. 12 Austrian Code, 381 ff. ^ 3 Cf. Blackstone, i. i, and many recent laws on canals and railways. 254 CONDITIONS OF 7 HE STATE IN NATURE. [Bk. III. Qn the continent the right of expropriation has been generally adopted and regulated. Many modern constitu- tions include the principle that the State has a right to enforce cession of property for purposes of public welfare if it pays full compensation 14 . This principle is completely justified by the consideration that where the private rights of individuals and the general rights of the public conflict with one another, the latter ought to prevail, but only so far as circumstances demand. The opposing interests are reconciled by cession on the one side and compensation on the other. The question whether public interest demands expropria- tion in any particular case belongs to public law, and ought, therefore, to be settled not by a civil court, but by the organs of the government proper, either by the legislature, as in England and the United States, or by the actual executive, as is usual in Germany, or by administrative courts. The latter procedure is fairer, for it is the business of government to settle in each case what the public good demands, and it is best fitted for estimating the means proposed. But the procedure must be such that no arbitrary caprice be allowed to encroach on private rights 15 . For examples see Neuester Expropriationscodex, Niirnberg, 1837, and especially Griintrab, Enteignungsrecht, p. 66, foil. 14 Bavarian Law of 1756, iv. 3. 2. Prussian Law, i. n. 4-11. Introd. 73-75. Code Civil, Art. 545 : * Nul ne peut etre contraint de ceder sa propriete, si ce n'est pour cause d'utilite publique, et moyennant une juste et prealable indemniteV Austrian Code, 365 : 'If the general good demands it, a member of the State must give up his property in return for due compensation.' French Constitution Voluntary ~ .,,... ,, . . separation. larger common State is the division of an empire into Compulsory several States, or the partition of one State among several pa foreign States. The former may occur organically without external compulsion by the different parts affirming their particularism more and more and then separating ; but the latter is commonly the work of foreign force. The partitions of Poland (1772, 1793, 1795) are terrible examples of such 282 THE RISE AND FALL OF THE STATE. unjust force, in an age which prided itself on its enlighten- ment and humanity. 6. with- As the concession of sovereign rights forms new States, renunciation so by the withdrawal or renunciation of sovereign rights, pre- r4hts? reiJ viously independent States may gradually lose their political existence. The history of the German Empire offers ex- amples of this mode of formation, the history of France of this mode of extinction. The centralisation of France, especially since Louis XI, has thus by degrees abolished a number of * sovereign seigniories ' ; but Germany too, since the Revolution, has shown a similar tendency in its mediatisations. CHAPTER VI. SPECULATIVE THEORIES. I. 'THE STATE OF NATURE.' PHILOSOPHICAL speculation is fond of imagining a primitive . The condition in which men lived without government, and then Ag e . en asking how from that condition mankind has arrived at the State. The popular imagination has often decked out this primitive condition with smiling pictures of innocence and abundance of natural enjoyments, and dreamed of a golden age of Paradise, in which there were as yet no evils and no injustice, while all enjoyed themselves in the unlimited freedom and happiness of their peaceful existence. In this primeval condition there was supposed to be no property, since the superabundance of nature gave to every one in sufficiency all that his unsophisticated and uncorrupted tastes could require. As yet there was no difference of ranks, nor even of callings. Every one was like another. Then too there was neither ruler nor subject, nor magistrate, nor judge, nor army, nor taxes l . In comparison with such an ideal the later political con- The state dition of man must appear perversion and decline. Only sa ry evil/ when men encountered previously unknown plagues, when 1 Shakespeare depicts this state of nature ' with brilliant irony in the Tempest, Act ii. Scene i, line 140 ff. 284 THE RISE AND FALL OF THE STATE. [Book iv. passions were aroused in their breasts, and new dangers ap- peared, and guilt destroyed the peace of their souls, was there needed a power to terrify and to punish the wicked, and to secure the enjoyments of all against disturbance. Thus the State was thought of as a necessary evil, or at least as an institution of compulsion and constraint to avoid greater evils. 2. The state In opposition to this childish and cheerful idea of Para- of Nature as . . a state of disc, other and sometimes morose philosophers imagined the non-political condition of man as much worse than the political, as a condition of ceaseless hate and war of all against all : and if even they thought the State an evil, yet this evil was more endurable and less than the original ' state of nature ' in which men were like wild beasts a . This philosophical idea found a welcome confirmation in the theological speculation which regarded the State not as the organisation of Paradise, but of fallen humanity. Both views Both these views overlook the political nature of man, overlook k^ jg nore tne t ru th 2 w hich Aristotle expressed so well, nature* 1 tnat man ^ s ' a political animal.' We may imagine a condi- a [According to Hobbes, Leviathan, Part i. chs. xiii, xiv, the natural condition of man, i. e. his condition ' out of civil states,' is ' a condition of war of every one against every one.' Cp. Spinoza, Tract. Pol. c. ii. 14 : * Homines ex natura hostes.' c. v. 2 : ' Homines civiles non nascuntur sed fiunt.' But these expressions of Hobbes and Spinoza are to be understood rather as a logical statement of what would be the con- dition of man apart from civil society, than as distinctly implying a historical theory. They err from ignoring history rather than from as- serting false history. The word ' natural ' is used merely in the negative sense of ' non-civil ' or * non-political,' and thus is the very reverse of Aristotle's tyvais, which, as he tells us, is to be found in the end (reAos) or completest development of anything. Pol. i. 2, 8, I252b. 32. In 16, 1253 a. 31 he says almost the same thing as Spinoza, op. cit. c. ii. 140 2 Rousseau (Disc, sur Vinegahte des conditions parmi les homines) : 1 L'homme, dans 1'etat de nature, repugne a la societe.' Mirabeau an- swered him excellently : ' Non settlement 1'homme semble fait pour la societe, mais on petit dire qu'il n'est vraiment homme, c'est-a-dire un etre reflechissant et capable de vertu, que lorsqu'elle commence a s'or- ganiser. Les hommes n'ont rien voulu ni du sacrifier en se reunissant en societe : ils ont voulu et du etendre leurs jouissances et V usage de la liberte^ par les secours et la garantie reciproques.' (Essai sur le despo- tisme.} Chap. VI.] THE STATE OF NATURE. 285 tion of man which preceded the rise of the State, but this condition could never have satisfied his higher needs 3 , and it was an immeasurable advance in his development when the germ of political capacity unfolded itself and came to light. 3 Plato (Rep. ii. 369) makes the State come into being, because the in- dividual man is not self-sufficing (ai/rap/cr)?). CHAPTER VII. II. THE STATE AS A DIVINE INSTITUTION. IN antiquity as well as during the middle ages the belief in the divine institution of the State was more extended and more intense than at the present day. But even then this divine foundation of the State was understood in very different senses. 1. The state According to one view, the State was the immediate founded by work of God, the direct revelation upon earth of the divine government. This view lay at the basis of the Jewish theo- cracy, and its logical consequence is always the theocratical form of the State to which alone it is adapted. If God has founded the State directly, it is natural that He should main- tain and govern it directly. 2. AS in- According to another view, the State is only indirectly founded by founded by God, and is only indirectly governed by God 1 . This view was shared by the Greeks and Romans. Their States were by no means theocratic but thoroughly human, yet no public business of any importance was undertaken in antiquity without prayer and sacrifice preceding, and the care of the auspices, by which the will of the gods was dis- covered, occupied a great place in the public law of the Romans. They united a consciousness of human freedom 1 It is only in this sense that Niebuhr (Gesch. d. Zeit der RevoL i. 214) calls the State ' an institution ordained by God, and belonging to the essential nature of mankind, like marriage and the paternal relation. But it is an institution which cannot become perfect in this world. The State, as it actually exists, is only a shadow of the divine idea of the State.' THE STATE AS A DIVINE INSTITUTION. 287 and self-determination with the belief in a divine direction of human affairs ; and if even in the destiny of the indi- vidual the power of the gods was felt, it appeared to them still clearer that the destiny of that great moral community, which we call the State, could not be separated from the will and working of deity 2 . Were they mistaken ? It is self-evident that Christianity cannot regard the State as outside the divine ordering and government of the world. It is significant for the Christian conception that the apostle Paul, at a time when the Emperor Nero was persecuting the Christians, addressed these famous words to the Romans (xiii. i): 'Let every soul be in subjection to the higher powers : for there is no power but of God ; and the powers that be are ordained of God.' Thus it is natural enough that during the whole middle ages, in all Christian States, the sovereign authority was derived from God, and the highest authority, that of the Emperor, immediately and directly 3 . 2 Haller (Restaur. i. p. 427) cites a fine passage of Plutarch, in which he says : ' A city might more easily be founded without territory, than a State without belief in God.' Cp. Washington's Inaugural Speech to Congress in 1789: ' It would be peculiarly improper to omit, in this first official act, my fervent supplication to that Almighty Being, who rules over the universe, who presides in the councils of nations, and whose providential aids can supply every human defect, that His benediction may consecrate to the liberties and happiness of the people of the United States a government instituted by themselves for these essential purposes, and may enable every instrument employed in its administration to exe- cute with success the functions allotted to his charge. In tendering this homage to the great Author of every public and private good, I assure myself that it expresses your sentiments not less than my own, nor those of my fellow-citizens at large less than either. No people can be bound to acknowledge and adore the invisible hand which conducts the affairs of men more than the people of the United States. Every step, by which they have advanced to the character of an independent nation, seems to have been distinguished by some token of providential agency.' [The Speeches are given in Sparks, Life of Washington, vol. ii.l 8 This is also the meaning of the Constitutio Ludovici Bavarici of the year 1338 : * Declaramus quod imperialis dignitas et potestas est imme- diate a solo Deo (i. e. not indirectly, mediate, through the Pope) statim ex sola electione (by the Electors Kurfursten] est Rex verus et im- perator Romanorum censendus,' The Augsburg Confession (1530) teaches in its i6th Art.: 'That all authority, government, law and order in the world have been created and established by God Himself.' 288 THE RISE AND PALL OF THE STATE. [Book IV. Erroneous Grand as is the view which connects the rise and fall of the^divfne States with the divine government of the world, and high as "hTsTau. its moral significance is always to be accounted, we must not overlook that this is essentially religious, and not political ; and thus this idea, if made a political and legal principle, causes and palliates errors and abuses. Thus : Monarchical i. God has indeed made man a political being, but at the llce ' same time has made him free to realise the implanted idea of the State by his own exertions and according to his own judgment, and in the forms which seem suited to him. It is a profound error to reject particular forms of the State, for instance the republican, because God rules the world as a king. The prince as 2. Authority is indeed in principle and in fact dependent se tative* 6 on God, but not in the sense that God has exalted particular privileged persons above the limitations of human nature, set them nearer to Himself and made them demigods, nor in the sense that God has named human rulers as His per- sonal representatives, identical with Himself so far as their authority extends 4 . Such theocratical ideas contradict the human nature of those to whom the government of the State is entrusted. The proud words of Louis XIV, * We princes are the living images of Him who is all holy and all power- ful V are a blasphemy towards God, and an insult towards his subjects men as much as he. Authority as 3. Many understand the authority, distinct from the per- such divine. , . . ....... sons who exercise it, as superhuman and politico-divine. Stahl says 6 , ' The authority of the State is of God, not only * Cp. Stahl, Statslehre, ii. 48 : ' According to the theocratic con- ception of the middle ages, the chiefs of Christendom are the representa- tives of God Himself. Rulers (Pope, Emperor, and Kings) have thus in their own persons the fulness of His authority/ 5 (Etwres de Louis XIV, ii. p. 317, where the following passage occurs: 'Celui qui a donne des rois au monde a voulu qu'ils fussent honores comme ses representants, en se reservant, a lui seul, le droit de juger leurs actions. Celui qui est ne sujet doit obeir sans murmurer : telle est sa volonteV 6 Statslthre, ii. 43. On the other side cp. Macaulay in the passage quoted infra, Bk. vi. ch. xiv : footnote 2. Chap. VIL] THE STATE AS A DIVINE INSTITUTION. 289 in the sense that all rights are of God, property, marriage, paternal authority, but in the quite specific sense, that it is the work of God which He regulates. The State rules, not merely in virtue of the rights which God has given it, as a father does over his children, but it rules in the name of God, therefore it is that the State is clothed with majesty/ But this is to come back to an objective theo- cracy, which would practically lead to the ruler being considered the personal representative of God a view which Stahl himself rejects and would introduce again all the assumptions and abuses bound up with it. Christ himself by his saying, ' Render unto Caesar the things that are Caesar's,, and unto God the things that are God's,' has clearly and decidedly pointed out the human character of the State, and rejected every identification of political authority with specifically divine rule. Therefore political science does well in considering the existence and institutions of the State from the human point of view. 4. Not infrequently the immutability of the existing con- Divine right. stitution, and especially of the person of the ruler or of his dynasty, has been defended by the principle that the ' powers that be are ordained of God.' But that the immutability of the external forms and of personal relations is no necessary part of the divine government of the world, is shown by the whole of history ; and Paul's very advice, to obey * the powers that be,' recognises indirectly the mutability of poli- tical institutions. In the seventeenth century, indeed, that precept might cause many pious Englishmen to have sincere scruples whether it was right to resist the tyranny of James II, and to deprive him of his throne ; but after William of Orange was recognised as king by the nation and the parlia- ment, even the most scrupulous and conscientious religious Tory could honour in him 'the power ordained of God V [The non-juring Tories were by no means in such a hurry to recog- nise William III. They maintained that the de facto king was not king de jure. Bluntschli seems to have taken his idea of the scrupulous religious Tory from the * Vicar of Bray.'] U 290 THE RISE AND FALL OF THE STATE. [Book IV. irresponsi- 5. It is the same with the question of responsibility. That statesmen to whom much is entrusted, and that princes who have power conferred on them, are responsible to God for what they do or omit, follows from the previous principle ; but that does not decide on the further question, whether and how far they are also responsible to a human judge. Irresponsibility to human judges is claimed for the highest authority in the State, not because it is specially divine, but simply because it is the highest. The statesman must not, in the belief that God deter- mines the destiny of nations and States, and in the con- fidence that God will govern well, tempt God and shirk his own responsibility. Rather, he is not freed from his own responsibility, until he has conscientiously fulfilled the task entrusted to him to the best of his power 7 . History of Note. The history of the expression c by the grace of God/ which is sioV^b^the added to the title of kin g s > deserves attention. At different periods it grace of has had different senses. (a} The expression was especially used in the middle ages. The old Frankish kings used indifferently the forms, 'gratia Dei,' ' divina ordi- nante providential ' divina favente gratia? l divina favente dementia] i per Dei miser ic or diam? At that time the expression signified merely the humble reverence and religious gratitude of the king towards God, to whom he ascribed his personal elevation ; but it was used by elected as well as hereditary princes. King Pipin, who owed his elevation to a revolution, used the formula as readily as his son Charles the Great. In the Frankish period it expressed no sovereign power. Bishops and abbots, although legally chosen or appointed by kings, and temporal counts, although royal officials, added this formula to their titles. (b) In the German-Roman Empire the expression at first continued in the same way. Not only elected kings, but dukes, counts who held offices under the king, and bishops and abbots recognised in the same way the grace of God. Sometimes temporal magnates add to the grace of God the grace of the emperor, and spiritual princes the grace of the pope ' Dei et imperiali gratia? ' Dei et apostolicae sedis gratia! 7 Lamartine, Revolut. de 1848, i. p. 47, says 'of himself: 'II tentait Dieu et le peuple. Lamartine se reprocha depuis severement cette faute. C'est un tort grave de renvoyer a Dieu ce que Uieu a laisse a rhomme d'Etat, la responsabilite ; il y avait la un defi a la Providence.' Chap. VII.] THE STATE AS A DIVINE INSTITUTION. 291 Gradually, however, the exclusive use of the phrase ' Grace of God ' comes to signify immediate or direct authority ; as opposed to the derived authority of a vassal. The expression corresponded above all to the mediaeval tendency to derive all power from God. (c ) After the Reformation the Lutheran theologians began to proclaim the saying of Paul, 'the powers that be, are ordained of God,' as a Christian dogma, and to declare those in authority the anointed repre- sentatives of God. Luther himself was less narrow ; he once wrote to King Henry VIII of England : ' I, Martin Luther, by the grace of God ecclesiastes, to Henry, by the ungrace of God King of England.' . . . The theologians who held by the letter did not consider that the apostle Paul expressly applied that saying to the Roman Emperor Nero, who had received his power from the Roman people, and meant to oppose the theocratically minded Jewish Christians who contemned the heathen emperor. They overlooked the fact that the apostle Peter had quite the same intention, when he recommended to the Christians obedience to human government (i Peter ii. 13). They gloried in being the defenders of the divine right of temporal princes. (0 Still more decidedly Louis XIV of France and James II of Eng- land attempted to make ' the grace of God ' a new political dogma, and thereby to obtain a higher sanction for the absolutism of the king. Unlike all the other human rights of property, family, parliament, the right of the king was to be specifically divine, that is to say, absolute. He was to be raised above the sphere of human law. Meantime the French estates refused to sanction the king's divinity, and the English Parliament resisted still more vigorously. The English Revolution of 1688 and the French Revolution of 1789 definitely rejected this theo- cratical principle. (e] The most decided adversaries of this principle were the German publicists, PufTendorff and Thomasius, but above all, Frederick the Great, who saw in it the fundamental error of European politics. (/") Stahl has recently attempted to give a new acceptance to the false idea, and to smuggle it anew into the theory of the State in the form of an objective divine right of authority, as distinct from the per- sonal deification of the absolute king. In vain : the modern world cannot be bewitched by this abortive product of a diseased imagination. U 2 CHAPTER VIII. III. THE THEORY OF FORCE. Might is THE State is the work of violent domination, it is based on the right of the stronger.' Thus we are assured by certain philosophers, but still oftener by despots 1 . This doctrine is favourable to despotism, for it justifies every act of violence ; but it may also serve the purpose of revolutionaries as soon as they are strong enough to exercise force openly. It is ordinarily invoked by the brutal might which violates right. It is a sophism attractive only for the strong, more likely to crush than to deceive the weak : it may deceive the man who holds it, but not others. It has been said that history proves the truth of this opinion. Certainly, force shows itself more often in the foundation of States than contract, but only very seldom has brute force alone arbitrarily produced States, and never great and lasting States. As a rule, if force, especially in the form of war, has had its share in the foundation of new States, the force was still only the servant of real claims of right. It was not the source of right, but only broke through the obstacles which prevented it flowing in its proper chan- nels. Might did not create right, but supported it, and compelled recognition for it. Wherever in history force appears in its nakedness, there it is not an instrument of creation, but of destruction and death. 1 Plutarch (Life of Camillus. c. 17) puts this theory into the mouth of the Gallic king Brennus : ' The most ancient of all laws, which ex- tends from God to the beasts, gives to the stronger rule over the weaker.' THE THEORY OF FORCE. 293 This doctrine is a most flagrant contradiction of the con- ception of personal freedom. It recognises only masters and slaves. By free men (liberi] it understands freed men (libertini\ It equally contradicts the idea of Right or Law, which manifestly has a spiritual and moral significance : mere physical force ought to serve right and, if it pretends to be right, it has risen against its proper master 2 . However, even the errors 01" this doctrine contain a re- Element of siduum of truth. It makes prominent one element which doctrine. is indispensable to the State, namely force (Macht\ and has a certain justification as against the opposed theory which bases the State upon the arbitrary will of individuals, and leads logically to political impotence. It lays emphasis on realities and on facts, and warns us against vain attempts at realising the dreams of mere speculation, where natural forces resist. Without force a State can neither come into being nor continue. Force is required within, as well as without ; where force has produced firm and enduring results, it seeks and commonly obtains a connection with right, that is a recognition and purification by means of right. Without right the might of the stronger is brutal, it is the wolf that devours the lamb. United with right, it becomes worthy of the moral nature of man. 2 ' Le plus fort n'est jamais assez fort pour etre toujours le maitre, s'il ne transforme sa force en droit, et 1'obeissance en devoir.' Rousseau, Contr. Soc. i. ch. 3 ; quoted by Schmitthenner, Statswissenschaft, i. P- IS- CHAPTER IX. IV. THE THEORY OF CONTRACT. influence of ESPECIALLY since the time of Rousseau-, the doctrine the theory of , i /- r the social that the State is a free work of contract, of convention between its citizens, has enjoyed great and wide-spread popularity. It flattered men's self-complacency ; for every one might fancy himself a founder of the State : and it appeared to suit the wishes of all ; for every one might in- terpret the terms of the contract as he chose. This theory obtained a fatal authority at the time of the French Revo- lution. By the help of it the old political forms were torn down, and manifold but unsuccessful attempts were made to erect on the ruins a new edifice which should please everybody. But, although this theory found especial ac- ceptance as the justification of revolution, it had served before to defend the legitimacy of absolute rule". [It should be noted that the Theory of Contract is applied in dif- ferent ways by Hobbes, Locke, and Rousseau. According to Hobbes (Leviathan, ch. 17) men only pass from the 'state of nature' to the social state by surrendering their rights to a sovereign (one, few, or many). Locke (Treatises on Government, Book ii. ch. ii. 6) supposes rights, e.g. of liberty and property, to exist in the state of nature : by the 'original compact' (Locke uses the term 'compact,' not ' contract') a form of government is instituted to secure these rights (c. viii). Ac- cording to Rousseau men pass from the state of nature to the social state by the social contract (as on Hobbes's theory), but the sovereign to whom each surrenders his rights is 'the people,' so that each is sovereign as well as subject (Contr. Soc. i. c. 6). This sovereignty is inalienable (ii. c. i) : a government is not instituted by a contract (iii. c. 16) ; the government is only the minister of the General Will. Thus, according to Hobbes, a revolution against the de facto government, which he identifies with the sovereign, implies a return to the state of nature, THE THEORY OF CONTRACT. 295 What was said of the theory of force applies conversely in this case. The theory of force, as a rule, favours despotism, but may, exceptionally, excuse the results of revolution. The theory of contract is especially favourable to anarchy, but exceptionally defends the oppression of minorities by arbitrary majorities, or the tyranny of a conqueror over those who have surrendered to him. This theory claims universal validity. It makes the rise, The theory and in a certain sense also the continuance, of all States U1 depend on contract. But history does not afford a single instance in which a State has really been brought about by contract between individuals. There are indeed particular cases of contracts between two or more States which have produced a new State : there are also some cases in which princes and chiefs have, by a contract with particular classes or estates of the people, produced new constitutions : but there is no instance in which a State has been formed like a trading or an insurance company by its * equal ' citizens. The opinion that the continuance of States depends upon a perpetual renewal of contract between individuals, receives, as little support from history. Rather do we find that the individual is born as a member of the State, and is begotten, born and educated with the particular characteristics of his nation and his country before he is in a position to have and to express a will of his own. The evidence of history is thus absolutely opposed to this theory. Even at the time when the doctrine of social con- tract was most widely accepted and exercised most influence, it was contradicted by manifest facts. The people was broken up into ' free and equal citizens, 7 but even in the primary assemblies the minorities did not contract with the anarchy, and is quite unjustifiable. According to Locke, a revolution might be justifiable, where the government had ceased to fulfil the trust reposed in it, i.e. to protect personal rights. According to JRousseau, a revolution would be only a change of ministry. Contrary to what is very commonly supposed, Locke does not speak of any contract between government and people. His theory is almost identical with that of Rousseau. Cp. T. H. Green, Works, ii. pp. 366-396.] 296 THE RISE AND FALL OF THE STATE. [Book IV. majorities, who carried out their will as if it had a superiority and validity of its own. The Constituent Assembly was indeed regarded as a selection and a representation of all the citizens, and had as its appointed task to agree upon a constitution ; but even here the form of procedure was that of a decision of one united body, rather than of a contract between a number of individuals. People adopted a fiction of contract, and deceived themselves and others by speaking of the consent of individuals, where the majority, as organ of the whole, was exercising an authority which was often an intolerable tyranny \ The theory This theory may be disproved not only by history but by illogical. ..,../ T , , , ,. logical criticism. It assumes the freedom and the equality of the individuals who conclude the contract ; but political freedom, which is here presupposed, is only conceivable in the State, and not outside it. Man has indeed the aptitude for this freedom, just as he has the impulse to, and the need for, the State, but this freedom can never be realised, except in the organic freedom of the State. Further, if individuals were only equal, a State could never come into being, for it implies as a necessary condition political inequality, without which there is neither ruler nor ruled 2 . The main error lies in representing individuals as con- tracting. If individuals make contracts, private rights are created, but not public rights. What belongs to the in- dividual as such, is his private property, his individual pos- sessions. With that he can deal, one like another can make contracts about it. But contracts cannot have a political character unless there is already a community above the individuals ; for a contract, if political, does not deal with the private good of individuals, but with the public good of the community. 1 Rousseau (i. c. 5) feigns an original unanimity which creates the subsequent law of majorities: 'La loi de la pluralite des suffrages est elle-meme un etablissement de convention et suppose, au moins une fois, I'unanimiteV 2 Arist. Pol. ii. 2, 3, 1 261 a. 24: ov yap ytverat TTO\IS l opo'tow' Tpov yap ffvupaxia (an alliance) teal iro\is. Chap. IX.] THE THEORY OF CONTRACT. 297 Thus, neither a nation nor a State can arise out of con- tract between individuals. A sum of individual wills does not produce a common will. The renunciation of any number of private rights does not produce any public right. For practical politics this doctrine is in the highest degree Practically dangerous, since it makes the State and its institutions the produce of individual caprice, and declares it to be change- able according to the will of the individuals then living. It destroys the conception of public law, instigates the citizens to unconstitutional movements, and exposes the State to the uttermost insecurity and confusion. It is to be con- sidered, therefore, a theory of anarchy rather than a political doctrine. Nevertheless, it contains an element of truth. In oppo- Yet contains . . an element sition to the theory which sees in the State a mere product of truth. of nature, it accentuates the truth that the human will can determine and influence the formation of the State; and in contradiction to a thoughtless empiricism, it vindicates the rights of human freedom and the rationality of the State. Notes. i. The 'famous sentence of Aristotle (Pol. i. 2, 12), that the State is prior to the individual citizen as the whole is prior to the part, contradicts the idea that the State can be made out of individuals. The political individual, the citizen, is only a member in the body of the State, and can have no separate existence apart from his connection with it. 2. The error of founding the State upon individual will is connected with the more widely accepted error of supposing that Right or Law (Rechf] is the product of Will. Certainly the free will of man is able to affect and alter in many ways what is right and just, but the greatest part of this has been fixed from everlasting by the order of the world and the nature of men and circumstances, and is altogether independent of the will of men. Most Right is not invented, but discovered and re- cognised, found not formed. ' Thou shalt ' has greater influence in the production of law than 'we will.' Even Hegel, who derives Right, not from ' the particular individual will,' but from ' the true will,' which is ' in and for itself,' has not properly comprehended the nature of Right, although he has completely seen the error of the theory of contract. Compare Philosophic des Rechts, 258. 3. The Genevese citizen J. J. Rousseau by his brilliant dialectic ob- tained the victory for the theory of contract in public opinion. Another 298 THE RISE AND FALL OF THE STATE. [Book iv. Mailer's Swiss, the Bernese patrician, Ludwig von Haller, attacked the prevalent the^tate. doctrine of the law of nature with great energy, and thoroughly refuted the theory of contract. He was less successful in the positive part of his system, which he called * Restoration.' His doctrine ought not to be confounded with the theory of force : but he is the teacher of reaction, as Rousseau was of revolution. Haller founds the State upon ' the natural law that the stronger rules.' In the superiority of the one, and in the need of the other, he recognises the basis of all rule, and of all dependence. He calls it an external, un- alterable ordinance of God, but this shows that by might he does not mean the same thing as force, and he carries out the opposition between them. l Power is limited by duty, by the moral law which God has written on the hearts of men, which reveals itself in the conscience of children, and in all times among all peoples : * Shun evil and do good/ and * Injure no one and leave to every one his own.' The law of justice and the law of love guard against power (potentia) degenerating into violence (vis). These two laws are implanted by God in man, they are innate, they are universal and necessary, eternal and unalterable, they are intelligible to every one, and the highest and mightiest, to whom all other human laws must submit, cannot be dispensed from the observance of them by any one. They are also the mildest and most loving, their yoke is easy and their burden is light. Not the will of the whole people, not the common good, not even the fear of man's violence, but the will of God alone is the basis of this law of duty. Thus it is valid even for the powerful, every transgression of it is a forbidden misuse of force, whether com- mitted by the meanest head of a house or the greatest potentate a want of justice or a want of love. Justice must be demanded from the strong as from the weak. Love and benevolence must be expected from the better part of the human heart. Against the possible misuse of the highest power there is no help to be found in human arrangements. There is no human judge over the sovereign. There is no help except in God. * The belief in God,' as Plutarch says, l is the bond and cement of all human society, and the support of justice.' Religion alone can keep power in its limits, and strengthen the weak. We have reproduced the chief points in Haller's doctrines in his own words. It is obvious that he derives Right and the State, not from justice but from power, and regards the former only as a limit of the latter. Might and might alone produces right. The greater the might, the higher the right. Whereas, in truth, might alone is only de facto and not dejure. This train of thought pervades the whole system. Rever- ence for actual power often prevents him seeing the ideal moral character of Law ; the desire to secure the highest power, and the right of the sovereign against every infringement sometimes becomes contempt and hatred towards every endeavour to secure the rights of subjects against Chap. IX.] THE THEORY OF CONTRACT. 299 misuse of supreme power, and to limit its exercise as if it were a crime to protect the divine law of duty by human arrangements against human violation. He is therefore a declared opponent of the whole consti- tutional system, and he works out in an extreme manner the mediaeval idea that sovereignty is a property. [For a criticism of this chapter of Bluntschli's see A. Fouillee, La Science Sociale Contemporaine, ch. i. M. Fouillee defends the theory of Social Contract as an expression of the ideal of the State.] CHAPTER X. V. THE NATURAL SOCIABILITY AND POLITICAL CONSCIOUSNESS OF MAN. The state IT is not enough to refute the current speculative theories. thetodai" We have still to discover the one common cause of the hanuw rise of States, as distinct from the manifold forms in which they appear. This we find in human nature, which besides its individual diversity has in it the tendencies of community and unity. These tendencies are developed, and peoples feel themselves to be nations, and seek a corresponding out- ward form. Thus the inward impulse to Society (Statstrieb*) produces external organisation of common life in the form of manly self-government, that is, in the form of the State. This social This social tendency works at first instinctively and un- passes'from consciously. The many look up, half with trust and half scfous to n the with f ear > t a leader by whose courage and genius they are Sage! " impressed, and whom they honour as the supreme expression of their community. They arrange themselves under him, and obey his commands. Gradually, however, with advanc- ing civilisation and experience, the hidden impulse reveals itself, and there is formed a consciousness and a will of the State, first of all, as is natural, in the leaders and chiefs of the people : in them it becomes an active consciousness and an ordering and effective will of the State, while the mass of the governed does not as yet advance beyond a passive a [Compare Aristotle's phrase : vffft 77 op^ \v -ndaiv lirl TT)J/ oivuviav, Pol. i. 2. 15, 1253 a. 30.] NATURAL SOCIABILITY OF MAN. 301 consciousness of the State. Gradually this consciousness extends itself among the higher, and at last also among the lower classes and orders of Society, and becomes even among them active and effective. This assumption of a political tendency in human nature at first unconscious, but afterwards conscious, does not contradict the historical origin of States, but explains them. Among the powerful it rises to the passion of domination, among the weak it becomes servile submission, but among the free it is enlightened by understanding and filled by that moral self-consciousness which is in harmony with the moral common consciousness. Only the free State is a true State, for only in it is there a common political spirit (Statsgeisf) permeating all classes of the people. This view, which had already been expressed by the This view . ! contains the ancients , contains all that is true in the false speculative truth in the ,.., . rri oi. various false theories, without the accompanying errors. The State is theories. indirectly divine, since God has implanted the social impulse in human nature, and has, in this way, willed the realisation of the State. Sound religious feeling is thus not injured by our declaring the State to be, in the first place, the appointed work of man. Again, our view recognises the significance of the real force which is indispensable for the formation of the State ; for the essential power depends upon the common impulses of human nature. Finally, the element of free will has its rights accorded to it ; but instead of scattered individual wills, we recognise the common will of the nation or the State. This general will exists in germ among a people as naturally as the tendency to union and organisation, which we call the political tendency. This common will, in manifesting itself, becomes the will of the State, whereas mere individual will remains individual even if two individuals make a contract between them. Thus the proper expression of the common 1 Cp. supra, p. 297. Cp. also Cic. de Rep. i. 25 : < Ejus (populi) prima causa coeundi est non tarn imbecillitas, quam naturalis quaedam hominum quasi congregatio.' 302 THE RISE AND FALL OF THE STATE. will is not a Contract, but a Law (Gesetz) in the case of permanent regulations, an Order (Befeht) in the case of administrative police, a Judgment (Urtheit) in the adminis- tration of justice. The State has in itself organs which enable the common will to become conscious of itself, to resolve, and to carry out its resolutions. The State a The State is thus not an arrangement only for the purpose necessary ., . _ . ., . good. of taming evil passions. It is not a necessary evil, but a necessary good. Only by the realisation of the State can peoples and humanity, taken collectively, manifest their real inward unity and attain to a free corporate existence. The State is the fulfilment of common order, and the organisa- tion for the perfection of common life in all public matters. Thus understood, the State is in the first place a human and terrestrial formation ; but nothing prevents us from placing alongside of the religious ideal of an invisible Church, which is a community of spirits united by religion, the political ideal of an invisible State which is a community of spirits united politically. Theologians speak of a more perfect Church in heaven, and so the statesman may con- sider the earthly State as only a preparation for the heavenly. But the actual State is that in which we live and work. Political science has to do with it alone, and such a State is to be completely explained and understood from a consider- ation of human nature. BOOK V. THE END OF THE STATE. CHAPTER I. THE STATE AN END OR A MEANS? HOW FAR IS IT END OR MEANS ? THE question is often raised whether the State is an end or a means ? i. e. whether the State has an end in itself (Selbstzweck\ or simply serves as a means to enable indi- viduals to attain their ends ? The ancient theory of the State, especially that of the Ancient Greeks, regarded the State as the highest aim of human thestate as life, as perfect humanity, and was therefore inclined to regard an ' the State as an end in itself. As compared with the State, individual men appeared only as parts, not as beings with separate personal rights. The State did not serve the indi- vidual, but the individual the State, as the member serves the body. The welfare of private men was therefore unhesi- tatingly sacrificed to that of the State, and in fact the former was only so far justified and valuable as it was serviceable to the welfare of the State. In the same way individual freedom was only regarded as a part of national freedom, and met with neither encouragement nor protection when it sought to go its own way in opposition to the general welfare of the nation and the State. In complete opposition to this fundamental theory of the Modem ancients is the opinion, which has been often maintained by thesSte as English and American writers, that the State is not an end a ' in itself, but is simply a means to secure the welfare of indi^ viduals. Macaulay repeatedly throughout his works a main- [See Essay on Machiavelli, in Essays (Popular Edition), p. 47.] X 306 THE END OF THE STATE. [Book V. tains that the chief defect of ancient politicians and of Machiavelli lies in the fact that they do not, like the moderns, recognise the great principle that ' societies and laws exist only for the object of increasing the sum of private happiness.' This modern school regards the State simply as an institution or machine which gives to indi- viduals security for their life, their property, and their per- sonal freedom, or at most as an artificial creation designed to raise and promote the welfare and happiness of all indi- viduals, or at any rate of the greater number. Since the time of Bacon this opinion has been zealously defended by many politicians, and even by theorists. No one can really deny it who sees in the State only a collection of indi- viduals. Macaulay believes that the improvement in the conduct of public affairs in recent times is chiefly due to the influence of this theory. Robert von Mohl considers it preposterous to attribute equal importance to men and to a mere institution for their welfare, one-sided- It seems to me that both the ancient and the modern ness of both . . . . theories. view contain a germ of truth ; but both commit the error of regarding only one side of the matter and of overlooking or denying the other side. The form of the question itself, whether the State is a means or an end, leads to this one-sidedness and therefore to error. From one point of view a thing may be regarded as a means for obtaining other ends, from another as con- taining its end in itself. A picture is often a means of obtaining a livelihood for the artist or a profit for the picture-dealer. Yet a true work of art is to the artist the aim of his highest effort ; he sees in it the expression of his most vivid feelings, the embodiment of his ideal. In this way it has its end in itself. So, too, marriage serves un- doubtedly as a means for husband and wife to satisfy their individual needs, and to open to both a more happy exist- ence. But marriage is also the union of two sexes separated by nature, and on this union is founded the family, i. e. a higher collective unit, to which the individual existence of Chap. I.] HO W FAR IS IT END OR MEANS? 307 all its members is subordinate. Each member of the family is willing to sacrifice a part of his personal interests and will to the higher end which is involved in marriage and the family. The same is true of the State. On the one hand it is a means for the advantage of the individuals who compose it. From another point of view it has an end in itself , and for its sake the individuals are subordinate, and bound to serve it. The one-sided view of the ancients, which overlooked the Danger of individual in the nation, seriously endangered his liberty theory? 6 " and his welfare, and led up directly to the conception of the omnipotence, which easily degenerated into the tyranny, of the State. The equally one-sided view of the moderns, which is of the unable to see the wood for the trees, fails to recognise the theory" majesty of the State, and thus tends to dissolve it into a confused mob of individuals and to encourage anarchy. The ancients failed to give sufficient attention to an im- Modem portant task of the State, viz. the protection of personal of the freedom and the promotion of the personal welfare of the mdlvldual - majority. Modern politics can claim the merit of having recognised this function of the State, and of having brought it into more general practice than the ancients did. In the present day a policy is justly regarded as contemptible and hateful which treats the welfare of individuals as a ball to be tossed about at the caprice of rulers, or dropped altogether at the dictation of circumstances. It is acknowledged now that law and its administrators do not merely exercise rule over individuals, but render very essential and important services to them. A large number of useful and beneficent public institutions in the present day owe their origin to this view. It is to it that we must trace the modern develop- ment of personal freedom, and especially of freedom of opinion. It has been applied by Christianity to the re- ligious life, and by the Teutonic sense of law to the whole legal existence of the individual. X 2 308 THE END OF THE STATE. [Book V: The state a But in spite of this it is a logical and political error to maintain that the State exists only for the sake of private individuals, and that the administration has no object but to care for their welfare. Such a contention would destroy the very essence of the State, and would reduce Public Law (Statsrechf) into a mere preliminary condition of Private Law (Privatrecht}. In all nations of a manly spirit there are thousands of men who, when the State is in danger or need, will undertake heavy burdens, and will endanger both the peace of their families and their own lives. This spirit of self-sacrifice can only be explained on the supposition that these men prefer the safety and welfare of their State and nation to their own. The deeds of ancient heroes would be the folly of idle fanaticism if the State were only a means of serving individual interests, if the collective life of the nation had not a higher value than the life of many in- dividuals. In the great dangers and crises of the national life it becomes clear to men that the State is something better and higher than a mutual assurance society. When the love of fatherland is kindled, it melts the selfish ambition of the individual, and when once the sense of duty towards the State is awakened in the masses it inspires and elevates them. Their welfare Just as the nation is something more than the sum of persons belonging to it, so the national welfare is not the same as the sum of individual welfare. It is true that a close relationship exists between the two, and that they usually rise and fall together. If the individual welfare of the majority is diminished, that of the State is usually suffering from serious evils. But the lines and direction of the two are not always parallel. Sometimes they cross each other, and sometimes they are altogether separate. Every now and then the State is compelled, either for its own preservation, or in the interest of future generations, to make heavy demands from its present members, and to impose weighty burdens upon them. It sometimes happens, also, that the needs of individual welfare call for extra- Chap. I.] HOW FAR IS IT END OR MEANS? 309 ordinary aid and support from the State, which thus incurs serious obligations. It follows from this that we must examine more closely under what conditions the State is a means for individual interests, and under what conditions and within what limits the State, as an end in itself, is justified in demanding the subordination of its individual members. [Cp. Fouillee, Science Sociale Contemporaine, p. 253 : ' En un sens, la societe humaine n'est qu'un moyen ; en un autre, elle est line fin, parce qu'en derniere analyse elle se resout en line multiplicite innom- brable d'individus qui travaillent chacun pour le bien de tous et tous pour le bien de chacun.'] CHAPTER II. FALSE VIEWS OF THE END OF THE STATE. i. That it is IT has often been asserted in theory, and still more often the ruHng m in practice, that the real end of the State is the rule of the supreme power ^ especially of princes over their subjects, If the maintenance of this rule were the end of the State, the logical conclusion must be that the ideal State should be as absolute and as extensive as possible, so that the final aim of political effort would be absolute universal monarchy, or rather universal despotism. This would make it im- possible to reconcile national freedom with the development of human powers. The whole conception has its origin, not in human nature, nor in the social impulses which nature has implanted in mankind, but in the ambition of rulers and their haughty desire to exalt themselves. Aristotle long ago condemned this opinion in the famous dictum 1 , 'All constitutions which regard only the private good of the rulers are corruptions or perversions of the normal constitutions.' It is forgotten that a nation exists within the State ; that the subjects are men like their rulers, and possess the same human capacities, feelings and powers ; that it is therefore preposterous to regard the one class as the 1 Politics, iii. 6. 12 79 a, 19. FALSE VIEWS OF THE END OF THE STATE. 311 sole possessors of political rights, and the others as simple objects of their rule, as things. All the arguments against slavery are equally valid against this sort of despotism. Rule is unquestionably an attribute of the power of the State, but it is not the end of the State ; on the contrary it is a means to realise the end of the State. It is rather a duty towards the nation than a right to be enjoyed by the ruler. Rule therefore requires to be limited and defined by the constitution. The ideal of a State which approaches as nearly as possible to perfection does not consist in absolute, but in constitutional, i. e. relative rule. It often happens that some form of government, originally founded with good intentions, ceases in time to suit the altered conditions of a nation. In such a case it cannot be the duty of a healthy policy to leave this system unaltered just as it was inherited from previous generations : on the contrary, one's aim should be to improve the now useless system, and to restore harmony with the other conditions of the national life. According to the theocratic theory, the end of the State 2. That it is is the realisation of God's kingdom upon earth. Stahl 2 says : the divine" The duty of the State depends upon the service of God. w It should establish the rule of God, and maintain justice, discipline, and morality, which are God's commands for social life.' In the middle ages this conception was generally believed both by Christians and Mohammedans. But the modern world, while granting the religious importance of this view, and fully comprehending how the whole machinery of the world was revealed to the pious spirit by the light of the divine administration, utterly rejects the erroneous and fatal way in which divine rule was applied to direct the conduct of human affairs. The comparison on which the idea of theocracy rests, that the prince rules over a nation as God rules over the world, is obviously false. God's rule over the world is the rule of 2 Rechtsphilosophie, ii. 2. 312 . THE END OF THE STATE. [Book v. an absolute over relative beings, of the creator over his creatures : we cannot discover his origin, nor can we define its methods or its objects. The rule of a prince over a nation is the rule of a man over men, i. e. similar beings ; the prince's life is guided and his qualities limited just as those of his subjects, and the latter are fully capable of criticising him from a human standpoint. The comparison of a prince with God is therefore false from every point of view, and, as it leads to pride and excessive self-esteem, it is also harmful. The end of the State must be recognisable by men, it must be determined by human nature, and it must be at any rate nearly attain- able by human effort. 3 . That it It is altogether erroneous to place the end of the State someexter- re outside the people and country which form it, so that it object. b ecomes merely a means to secure external objects. The clerical party has been accustomed to prove the necessity of the States of the Church by pointing out that the independence and authority of the Roman Catholic Church require a Pope who shall be at the same time sovereign ruler in Rome. They fail to perceive that this argument clearly tells against the temporal power. For by it they deny the independence of the Papal States, and with it their character as a State, because no State can exist as the slave, wanting both will and legal rights, of some external power, even though this latter be the Roman Catholic Church. They presume that the Roman people who compose this State have submitted to a political serfdom in the interests of a religious and non-political community, a presumption which is equally opposed to the character of the people and to the religious nature of the Church. History has declared its judgment upon this enormity. Rome now belongs, not to Catholic Christendom, which is divided into many States, but to the Roman, or rather to the Italian, nation, of which the Romans are members. But even in the present day there are several examples of the same error. The principality of Lichtenstein obviously Chap. II.] FALSE VIE WS OF END OF THE STA TE. 313 does not exist for the sake of the small village of Liechtenstein and its scanty population. It serves only for an external object, viz. to support the rank and dignity of the princely dynasty which lives outside the country at the imperial court of Austria. This is obviously a State which has not its end in itself. CHAPTER III. INSUFFICIENT OR EXAGGERATED VIEWS OF THE END OF THE STATE. i. That its AFTER Kant and Fichte the opinion long prevailed in 15 Uhe Germany that the true end of the State was merely the assurance of rights, and especially those of person and property. p rope rty. Kant (Rechtskhre, 47-49) expressly declared that ' the safety (i.e. the end) of the State does not consist in the welfare or happiness of the citizens, but in the agreement of the constitution with the principles of law.' Fichte (Natur- recht, in his Works, iii. 152) maintains that l the assurance of the rights of all men is the only general will ' (i. e. the will of the State). Starting from this view of Kant, Wilhelm von Humboldt assigns very narrow limits to the activity of the State, and defines its end as ' the maintenance of security against both external enemies and internal dissensions V Even in our own century, when the idea of nationality is so strong, Eotvos (Moderne Ideen, ii. 91) maintains that 'the end of the State is the security of the individual.' This opinion arose in the latter half of the eighteenth century d . In those days men sought to find some funda- a [Humboldt's Sphere and Duties of Government supplies the motto to Mill's Liberty. For Mill's views cp. also his Pol. Econ. Book V. In practice however Mill allows the State very extensive functions. Much more extreme is the view of H. Spencer, The Man v. the State. ~] 6 [It is as old as the Greek sophists. Cp. Arist. Pol. iii. 9, 8, 128ob, 10, where Lycophron the Sophist is said to have held that ' Law (6 VIEWS OF THE END OF THE STATE. 315 mental limitation to the over-government of that enlightened despotism which, benevolent as it was, proved oppressive and destructive of personal freedom, and which was accus- tomed to justify every interference with family life, with the free choice of a career, and with the administration of private revenues, by a professed regard for the general welfare. The definition of the end of the State as the maintenance of legal security seemed to offer a convenient weapon for opposing this over-government successfully, and the State thus limited was termed a Rechtsstat (Legal State), in opposition to the detested Polizeistat (Police State) c . This narrowing of public life by restricting the end of the State failed to satisfy either the instincts or the necessities of modern nations. No one doubted that the maintenance of legal security is one of the duties of the State, but no modern nation or government could allow its political activity to be limited to so narrow a domain. Even the champions of the opinion were compelled by their personal experience to break through these limits, and to direct their policy to higher ends. Fichte began by asserting that the ' protection of property ' was the chief end of the State, but in the great struggle against the universal despotism of Napoleon, which was willing enough to protect property, he rose to the conception of a national State, which should serve as the organ of the national spirit. As a Prussian minister, Wilhelm von Humboldt strove to effect the in- tellectual advancement of the Prussian nation by means of State-schools, though in his theory he had condemned them, and to extend the power of the Prussian State, though it was already amply sufficient to enforce civil and criminal law. vo/ios} is only concerned with the securing of mutual rights and is not able to make the citizen good and just (cyyvr^s d\\rj\ois ruv jkicaioav, dAA' ovx olos Troitiv dyaOovs KOLL diKaiovs TOVS TroA/ras).' See Oncken, Staatslehre des Aristoteles, i. p. 217. Locke, Treatise on Government ', Book II. ch. ix, holds that the end of political society and government, or, as he expresses it, the reason why men enter into society, is that every one may the better preserve himself, his liberty, and property.] [See above, Book I. ch. vii. p. 68.] 316 . THE END OF THE STATE. [Book v. Defects of In fact this formula about legal security does not exhaust the end of the State, and especially of the civilised State of modern times : it would correspond much more to the views of the middle ages, which did not advance far beyond the conception of private law. The sense of law (Rechtssinn) is not the only active force in a nation. It has also a number of economic necessities, which have nothing to do with legal security, such as roads, canals, railways, posts and telegraphs. The State alone can satisfy these needs, and it would not venture to do so if its sole end was the assurance of rights. Again, the nation has important intellectual interests, national schools, schools of science and art, technical schools. For these the care of the State is indispensable ; it is impossible to leave them to the chance of private caprice or to the calculating authority of the Church, which is always seeking to bring the State under its own control. The middle ages neglected these interests because they adopted this narrow view of the State as an institution for maintaining legal security. Moreover, the nation is a political being, which is con- cerned not only with the making and administration of laws for the security of private rights, but in a far higher degree with political government and the development of its liberties. its results. This insufficient definition of the end of the State, when practically applied, has the following results : (a) The neglect of economic interests. (b) The neglect of common intellectual interests. (c) The paralysis and death of public spirit in the nation, and thus the weakening of the power of the State. (d) The encouragement of a petty and pedantic system of law, the result of which is a litigious temper fatal to the authority of the State. 2 . That its Another equally prevalent view, that the genera! happiness secure is the true end of the State, is as much too wide as the harness, former is too narrow. The happiness of men is for the most part independent of the State. Even most of the material goods on which human welfare is dependent, e. g. Chap. III.] VIEWS OF THE END OF THE STATE. 317 dwelling, food, clothing and income, are acquired, not through the State, but by the labour and saving of individuals. Still more is this true of the spiritual goods, on which the ideal wealth and happiness of mankind are founded. It is not the State which endows men with their talents and capacities; these are the gift of nature, and they differ in individual cases instead of being common to all. The State can confer on no one the delights of friendship and love, the charm of scientific study or of poetical and artistic creation, the consolations of religion, or the purity and sanctification of the soul united with God. Men are not citizens in their whole life and being ; they have their own natural endowments and their special duties. The State rests upon the community of the nation, not upon the differences of individuals ; its end therefore cannot em- brace all the ends of private life. This error, like the other, has serious and harmful results Harmful . ... results of when practically applied : this view. (a) The State is led to encroach upon departments which do not belong to its rule, and to exercise tyranny when it ought to restrict itself to the protection of private freedom. (b) The State being really incapable of managing these departments of private life, will by unskilful handling do harm and obstruct the natural development, in spite of its desire to increase the sum total of private happiness. (c) As the State strives after unattainable objects and squanders its forces in a false direction, it will be led away from its true aims, and will lose part of its power to ac- complish those duties that lie to its hand. This error proved a source of serious evil to the political life of antiquity; but the party of enlightenment in the eighteenth century went astray in the same manner. The end of the State in modern politics must be more accurately defined and limited. CHAPTER IV. THE TRUE EA T D OF THE SJ'ATE. only one THERE is only one conception of the State, although it is general end . . of the state, realised in very various ways among different nations and in different lands and periods. Logic, therefore, compels us to accept also one general view of the end of the State, in spite of the fact that in history the different nations who form States strive after very various objects. The unity of the common end admits of these special differences, but it combines and harmonises them. Robert von Mohl (En- cyclopadie, p. 73) was right in asserting that each nation has to pursue various objects according to its special character and needs ; but his theory wanted that unity of conception which is necessary to prevent hopeless diversity and devia- tions in the conduct of the State. On the other hand, von Holtzendorff (Politik, B. iii), who has treated this subject with special attention, gives the name of ' harmony of the ends of the State ' to what we call the unity of the end. ' justice is The question now arises, how is this single and supreme end of the State to be formulated? Many say that it is justice, the realisation of law. This definition seems to us too narrow, and it is erroneous if law is held to include both public and international law, and is not limited to the legal security of individuals (comp. Chapter III). Law is rather a condition of politics than its end : justitia fundamentum regni. And the life of nations is not only a judicial life ; there is also the economical and intellectual life, and the life of the national power. Even the legal-minded Romans did not consider jus to be the supreme end of the State. THE TRUE END OF THE STATE. 319 Hegel, as Plato long before him, says that the end of the | Morality State is morality {Sittlichkcit) and the realisation of the moral law. But the two powers which determine and con- dition the moral life, viz. the spirit of God and the spirit of the individual man, are both outside the control of the State. The domain of morality is far more comprehensive than the domain of politics ; and if the State attempts its control it oversteps its proper limits, and exerts a harmful influence upon morality. The Romans saw the real function of the State in the The securing public welfare. Their two expressions, res publica and salus welfare 3 " publica, are logically as well as verbally connected ; they are, in fact, as substance and quality, as potentiality and realisation. This formula of the end of the State has been frequently misunderstood, mainly because attention has been given, not to the community (the res publica), but to the crowd of individuals, or to the wiles of rulers. It has been used too often to excuse the arbitrary despotism either of princes or of majorities, and it has been completely discredited by the horrors of the Parisian Committee of Public Safety (1793-5). But the expression is really above criticism, if one regards is not in- the natural limits of the State, and especially the judicial order and administration, and if one avoids trespassing upon matters outside those limits, such as the free life of the in- dividual and of religious communities. To every statesman the welfare of his nation has been the first object to strive for, and every patriotic citizen is enthusiastic for the safety of his fatherland. The public welfare is therefore an indis- pensable object of policy, and its promotion is undoubtedly the chief duty of the State. This definition of the end of the State includes also the development and perfecting of law, and generally the improvement of all common relations and conditions of life. It includes also the administration of law, which is necessary to secure the peaceful course of the common life, and which prevents or punishes wrongs by which the community is harmed. This political principle 326 TIfE END OF THE STATE. [Book V. of the Romans, salus populi suprema lex esto, does not err in being too narrow, but rather in straining the power of the State, and extending it to alien matters. but is in- - Still, from one point of view, the expression is insufficient. sufficient in ... ,. . . times of Although in ordinary times policy aims at securing the national welfare, yet there are moments in a nation's life when it has to face extraordinary duties. There are cir- cumstances in which the State, like an individual, must risk its existence, and with it the national welfare. At such a time it may be a patriotic duty to resign a life which cannot be prolonged with honour. Suppose that an enemy of overwhelming power offers to a small nation many external advantages, such as decreased taxation, the security of peace, or a better administration. A simple regard for the public welfare would dictate the acceptance of the offer, while its rejection might bring disaster or even ruin upon the State. Nevertheless it might be a fatal duty to prefer death with honour rather than voluntary submission to the foreigner ; and it is possible that a heroic and desperate struggle may secure a subsequent revival of the State. A splendid ex- ample of this was given by the Athenians in the time of Themistocles. Sometimes ruin is the necessary and worthy termination of an existence that is no longer possible. The tragic fate of Carthage or of Jerusalem may be deplored, but in both cases it was inevitable. Sometimes, too, a small State must perish because its people are no longer capable of maintaining their independence, and because it is called upon to enter into the higher collective life of a nation. No unprejudiced German or Italian would deplore the destruction of those petty States which had become useless and impotent, but would rather glory in their fusion into a larger and more important whole. In such cases our formula about the public welfare is insufficient, unless it is applied to the new community. defin'tlon ~^ ut a ^ ^cse objections are avoided if we formulate the proper and direct end of the State as the development of the national capacities^ the perfecting of the national life^ and, Chap. IV.] THE TRUE END OF THE STATE. 321 finally, its completion ; provided, of course, that the process of moral and political development shall not be opposed to the destiny of humanity. This formula includes everything that can be regarded as a proper function of the State, and excludes everything that lies outside the State's range. It regards the idiosyncracies and the special needs of different nations, and thus, while it firmly maintains the unity of the end of the State, it secures the variety of its development. The life- task of every individual is to develope his capacities and to manifest his essence. So, too, the duty of the State- person is to develope the latent powers of the nation, and to manifest its capacities. Thus the State has a double function. Firstly, the maintenance of the national powers ; and, secondly, their development. It must secure the con- quests of the past, and it must extend them in the future. Within this common end are included certain special ten- This general dencies. Very often these are pursued singly, and justifica- fndSdeT tion is sought in the peculiar character of some given nation, tendencies, but this conduct is fraught with danger to the State as a whole. As illustrations may be mentioned : (i) The development of the national power (Macht). The E.g. the de- State must have power in order to maintain its independence SiSSf* and to enforce its decrees. It is only as possessing power power ; that a State can exist and live. But States vary very much according to the kind and degree of this power. (a) World-powers ( Weltmdchte) are States whose import- ance and activity extend far beyond their own domain : they play a decisive part in the politics of two continents or of the whole world, and therefore they are specially bound to care for the peace and order of the world (i.e. international law). () Great powers (Grossmdchte) are not necessarily world- powers, though every world-power is of course a great power. The world-power must be a maritime power, because it cannot exert its influence on the destinies of the world without the connexion given by the sea. But a great power may be simply a land-power, e. g. Prussia before Y 322 THE END OF THE STATE. [Book V. the formation of the German Empire. So, too, both then and now, Austro-Hungary is rather a great than a world- power. A great power also exerts an extensive influence far beyond the limits of its own country : it cannot be over- looked, nor can its voice be disregarded without danger when the relations of its own continent undergo important alterations. If at any time either of these powers abuses its strength to oppress other rightful States, the other powers are justified in resisting. Even a man of great genius, like Napoleon I, was unable to raise the great power of the French nation into a European supremacy, and the failure of this attempt led to his overthrow. So, too, Russia was not strong enough to subdue Turkey. Austria could not maintain its rule over Italy. The maritime supremacy of England has been at last compelled to admit the rivalry of other nations. (c) Intermediate and peaceful powers (neutral States) are not strong enough to play a great part in foreign politics, and are mostly absorbed in domestic affairs. The policy of these States, modest as it is, has very great importance, not only for their own inhabitants, but also because it limits and moderates the dangerous currents of la grande politique . (d) Real petty States have only a very dubious and in- secure existence in our epoch, which prefers the formation of greater and stronger States. They can only secure themselves by seeking the protection of the great powers, or by attaching themselves to some stronger State. But in the middle ages the opposite tendency prevailed, and the peoples of Europe, especially the Germans and Italians, were inclined to favour the very smallest political units. A State has two chief means for increasing its power in relation to foreign States, (i) diplomacy, and (2) the army and navy. A State which regards as its chief function the maintenance of its military strength, of the warlike courage of its members, and its armament, is called a military State. Examples of such a State are Sparta among the Greeks, and the kingdom of Prussia before the foundation of the Chap. IV.] THE TRUE END OF THE STATE. 323 German Empire. When a State is threatened from with- out, or is growing to its necessary limits, this extraordinary strain of its military forces is inevitable. But in a normal State which has reached its full development, it must never be forgotten that military power is only a means, and not an end of policy, and that undue straining of this power will be harmful to the true ends of the State. (2) Sometimes also it is economic interests which are or of specially prominent. Thus we speak of pastoral, agricul- fntTre^ts ; tural, industrial, and mercantile States. It is true that these interests are mainly those of private individuals, and only in a lesser degree interests of the whole nation. But on this very account, an exclusive or undue devotion to them leads to the neglect of the other functions of the State, and damages all other interests. Moreover, the public spirit of such nations is never fully developed, but is corrupted by the selfish and narrow devotion to private interests. In a pastoral State the nation will remain poor and ignorant ; in an agricultural State men look with mistrust and disfavour upon the higher culture, because rude manners are the natural accompaniment of their primitive pursuits. To an industrial State the chief dangers lie in disturbances among the artisans and the exclusion of foreign commodities, while a mercantile State may be easily led astray by a shop-keeping spirit. (3) The life of a nation may also be chiefly directed by orofin- . v , i . 11 tellectual intellectual interests, and thus arises what we may call an interests ; intellectual State (Culturstaf). The military State of Sparta was opposed, in the time of Pericles, by the intellectual State of Athens, which has bequeathed to posterity undying proofs of its love of art and of the capacity of the Athenians for acquiring knowledge. Florence, Venice, and Antwerp have had periods in which intellectual interests have sur- passed all others. The Chinese State in the present day is another example, although its culture is stationary rather than progressive ; and both Zurich and Geneva pride them- selves on giving special attention to their public schools. Y 2 324 THE END OF THE STATE. [Book V. Noble as these objects are, their excessive promotion, to the detriment of the other powers of the nation, is the sign of an unhealthy policy. or of legal (4) In some States the chief function is considered to be fo l r a freed e om : the development of the legal guarantees for national and individual freedom, and thus arise free legal States (freie Rechtsstateri}) as notably the Swiss Cantons and the States of North America. This formula of the end of the State lies, even more than those discussed above, at the heart of the general conception of that end. or of (5) Finally, when the consciousness of nationality gives unity"* the chief impulse to public life, when the manifestation of national unity seems to be the chief end of the State, we have national States. Such was France in former times, and such are in our own day the kingdom of Italy and the German Empire. indirect Besides the proper and direct end of the State, which functions of . . the state, relates to the nation itself, we must consider all the indirect functions of the State, which relate merely to private life. Here it is especially important to find some accurate definition of the limits of State action. The duties of an individual may be formulated, like those of the State, as the development and manifestation of his individual character and capacity ; but again, this must be in harmony with the ends of the family, of the nation, and of humanity. To fulfil these duties, private freedom is essential. It is, in the first place, the duty of the State to protect this private freedom against unjust attack, and especially to avoid any attempt on its own part to restrict or oppress it. Limitations A preliminary necessity is to form a clear conception of acdon. the way in which the State is limited by its own nature. (i) The State is an external organisation of the common life. It has organs, therefore, only for things which are externally perceptible, and not for the inner spiritual life which has never manifested itself in words or deeds. It is therefore impossible for the State to embrace all the ends Chap. IV.] THE TRUE END OF THE STATE. 325 of individual life, because many, and those the most im- portant, sides of that life are concealed from its view and inaccessible to its power. The natural gifts of individuals are wholly independent of the State, which can give neither intelligence to the fool, nor courage to the coward, nor sight to the blind. The State has no share in kindling love within the heart; it cannot follow the thought of the student, nor correct the errors of tradition. As soon as questions arise about the life, and especially the spiritual life, of individuals, the State finds both its insight and its power hemmed in by limits which it cannot pass. (2) The State is wholly based upon the common nature of men, and especially of its own people. Therefore it cannot control private life in what is essentially individual, but only so far as that life is affected by the common nature of all men and by common necessities. For example, the State can secure to all men equally the possession of a corporeal thing, which we call property, but it must leave to the individual the disposal and management of this property. The property of Paganini in his violin, of Liszt in his pianoforte, or of Kaulbach in his crayons, is a wholly different thing from the property of an unskilled person in those instruments. With this more subtle form of owner- ship the State has nothing to do, because it is individual and not common. So, too, the State can regulate in a rough and general way the conditions of marriage and the rights of married persons : in fact, it is bound to do so, because upon these depends the security of the family and the moral health of the nation. But the manner in which any parti- cular marriage is completed, and the more delicate forms of family life, lie outside the control of the State. Wilhelm von Humboldt saw this, and was led astray into a desire to with- draw the institution of marriage from legal regulation, and to leave it altogether to private freedom. The Canon Law fell into the opposite error, and endeavoured to impose legal regulations upon matters which pertained to private freedom. When the State punished heresy as a crime, it overstepped 326 THE END OF THE STATE. its natural limits and encroached unduly upon personal freedom. (3) The rule of the State extends no further than that of law, because every rule which has the power of compulsion rests upon the foundation of law. But law in its turn is limited, (a) By the necessity of the peaceful co-existence of indi- viduals, or by the recognition of the necessary conditions of common life (private law, criminal law) ; and () By the existence and development of the nation, to which the private life of individuals is subordinated so far as the security and welfare of the former demand (taxation, military obligations, constitutional and administrative law). So far as law is in question, the State is the supreme authority, because the making and administering of law belong by their very essence to the State. (4) The State can extend its administrative care, and therefore its influence, beyond the domain of judicial organ- isation, but it has then no power of compulsion, and its functions are limited to the support and encouragement of important social objects for which State help is needed (economical and educational measures of the State). The care of the State for the national welfare is here expanded into a care for the welfare of society, but only because the latter is in need of assistance. [Note. Besides the works of Mill and Spencer already referred to above, ch. iii. note a, the following books in English may be mentioned as dealing, from different points of view, with the limits of State action : Burgess, Political Science, Part I. Book II. ch. iv ; Cunningham, Politics and Economics ; Donisthorpe, Individualism-, Green, Lectures On Political Obligation in Works, ii, and Lecture on Liberal Legislation and Freedom of Contract in Works, iii ; Goschen, Address to the Edinburgh Philosophical Institution on Laissez-Faire and Government Interference ; Farrer, The State in relation to Trade ; Jevons, The State in relation to Labour (these two last both in ( The English Citizen ' series); Mackay (editor), A Plea for Liberty (with introduction by H. Spencer) ; Montague, Limits of Individual Liberty ; Ritchie, Principles of State Interference', Sidgwick, Political Economy, Book III ; Elements of Politics, Part I ; J. F. Stephen, Liberty, Equality, Fraternity ; Woolsey, Political Science, Part II. ch. v.] BOOK VI. THE FORMS OF THE STATE. CHAPTER I. THE DIVISION OF ARISTOTLE. MORE than two thousand years ago Aristotle laid down Aristotle's a division of the forms of the State which must be regarded as the accepted view even in the present day. In making this division he started from the conception of sovereignty, or rather of governmental authority. In every State there is a supreme organ *, in which power is concentrated and to which all other organs are subordinate. The form of this organ stamps a peculiar mark upon the State, and it is natural therefore to make it the basis of a division of States. Aristotle calls all those States which regard the good of Normal the community normal (6p6ai), while those which regard only the good of the rulers he calls perversions ( of the normal State 2 . Starting from this conception, he finds three normal forms, each of which is accompanied by its corresponding perversion. ' The supreme power,' he says, * must be vested either in an individual, or in a few (the minority), or in the many (the majority).' From this he derives the following normal forms : 1. Kingship (/3ao-tXem), as Aristotle calls it, or Monarchy, the more common name now the rule of an individual. 2. Aristocracy, the rule of a minority consisting of the best citizens (or exercised for the best interests of the State). 3. The rule of the majority, of the masses, is called by Aristotle ' Polity V In his day the democracy of the Greek 1 Aristot. Pol. iii. 6. i, 2, 1278 b, 6. 2 Ib. iii. 6. n, 1 279 a, 17. 3 Pol. iii. 7. 1-3, 1279 a J 22 sec l- [Cp- Eth. Nic. viii. c, io.j 330 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. [Book VI. cities, especially of Athens, had degenerated, and therefore he avoids the term Democracy for the rule of the majority exercised for the common interests, and restricts it to the perversion of that rule. But in later times Democracy has become again the usual term for this third form of the State, and we shall employ it in that sense. Perversions. The three perversions are thus designated by Aristotle : 1. Tyranny or Despotism, the rule of an individual exer- cised primarily in his own interests. 2. Oligarchy, the rule of the rich for their own ad- vantage. 3. Democracy 4 , in Aristotle's phrase, or, as we prefer to call it, Ochlocracy *, the arbitrary rule of the poor (and. we may add, the uneducated) masses. Quality more i n ma king this division, Aristotle seems to have laid the important thanQuan- chief stress upon the number of persons who share the supreme authority, just as in the Linnean system the num- ber of stamens determines the genus of a plant. But this runs counter to his own fundamental principle, that the form of a State depends upon the quality, and not the quantity, of the ruling organ. Aristotle himself 5 saw the risk of this misconception, and therefore pointed out that 4 Aristot. Pol. iii. 7. 5-8. 3, 1279!), 4-26. Cicero, de RepubL i. 26, expresses the idea of Aristotle as follows : ' Quum penes unum est omnium summa rerum, regem ilium unum vocamus, et regnum ejus reipublicae statum. Quum autem est penes delectos, turn ilia civitas optimatium arbitrio regi dicitur. Ilia autem est Qivits&popularis, in qua in populo sunt omnia.' The three perversions arise when ' ex rege dominus (fit), ex optimatibus/#^V0, ex populo turba et confusio ; ' i. 45. [The term ox^oKparia is first used for the lowest form of democracy by Polybius, vi. 4.] 5 Aristot. Pol. iii. 8. 6, 1279 b, 34 seq. [Cp. iv. c. 4.] Misled by several modern accounts of the matter, I had previously overlooked this, and had thus unfairly criticised the great political philosopher. Sparta was a monarchy, although two kings ruled together. [Not according to Aristotle. He calls it an ' aristocracy,' in the lower sense of the term, according to which it applies to a form of mixed govern- ment ; Pol. iv. 7. 4, 1293 b, 16; v. 7. 10, 1307 a, 35. The Spartan kingship he considers only ' a hereditary generalship for life ' an office compatible with any form of government; iii. 15. 2, 1286 a, 2.] Venice was an aristocracy, although there was a doge at the head of the State. Chap. I.] THE DIVISION OF ARISTOTLE. 331 the difference of number is naturally connected with a difference of character in the ruling power, and that it is the latter which is the ultimate criterion. Nevertheless, he has not expressed himself definitely enough about the principles of quality. There is another point in which Aristotle's division re- Aristotle's quires correction. It is incomplete, because history shows complete. us a number of States which do not come under any of his three normal forms. In all of them the supreme power belongs to men, whether it is to one man, or to the best, or to the people. But there have been States in which no human authority has been recognised, in which the supreme power has been attributed either to God, or to a god, or some other superhuman being, or to an Idea. The men who exercised rule were not regarded as its possessors, but as the servants and vicegerents of an unseen ruler, free from the weakness of human nature. This fourth form of State, when directed to the welfare ideocracy. of the subjects, may be designated by the general term of Ideocracy (Theocracy) ; and its perversion may be called Idolocracy. Note. Schleiermacher (Abhandlungen der Berl. Akademie der Wissensch. 1814, Ueber die Begriffe der verschiedenen Statsformeri) has maintained that the three ancient divisions, monarchy, aristocracy, and democracy, ' are always running into each other.' For example, in a democracy the leading men may resemble an aristocracy ; and some- times an individual, e. g. Pericles, may rule like a monarch. The same truth applies to a monarchy, and Mirabeau was right in saying (Speech of 1790 in his Works, viii. 139), ' In a certain sense republics are monarchical, and again in a certain sense monarchies are republics.' Nevertheless, the old division is by no means an empty one, and it is perfectly true that the form of the supreme power does give a definite stamp to the whole constitution of the State, and that the most important political principles stand in the closest relations to it. CHAPTER II. THE SO-CALLED MIXED STATE. The Roman EVEN in ancient times the attempt was made to add to Aristotle's division a fourth form, called the Mixed State a . Cicero especially declared the Roman State to be a model of this fourth form, a mixture of monarchy, aristo- cracy, and democracy, and maintained this form to be the best of the four \ what is By a Mixed State may be understood one in which Mixed * monarchy, aristocracy, or democracy are moderated or limited by other political factors, e.g. a monarchy may be limited by the formation of an aristocratic Senate or Upper House, and of a primary or representative Assembly of the people. In that case it is true that such a divided con- stitution is better than when an individual, or a few, or the majority rule absolutely and without restraint. But such a mixture as this does not create a new form of State, for the supreme governing power is still concentrated in the hands of the monarch, or of the aristocracy, or of the people. On the other hand, if it is understood that the supreme a [Aristotle himself recognised mixed constitutions : e. g. Pol. iv. c. 7.] 1 Cicero, de Republ. i. 29 : ( Quartum quoddam genus reipublicae maxime probandum esse censeo, quod est ex his, quae prima dixi, moderatum et permixtum tribus : ' and i. 45 ; ' Placet enim, esse quiddam in republica praestans et regale, esse aliud auctoritati principtim partitum ac tributum, esse quasdam res servatas judicio voluntatique multitudinis.' [Polybius (vi. n) had previously described the Roman constitution as mixed. Plato (Laws, i. 712) treated Sparta as a mixed government, but without using the phrase. On the whole question, see Cornewall Lewis, Use and Abuse of Political Terms, pp. 72-90.] THE SO-CALLED MIXED STATE. 333 governing power is itself divided between the monarch, the aristocracy, and the people, so that two supreme govern- ments exist side by side, each independent of the other, then Tacitus is right in rejecting the idea of a Mixed State, and in maintaining that its existence, or at any rate, its continuance, is impossible 2 . In later times men have considered England to be a The English Mixed State of this kind, in which rule is divided between three supreme powers, King, Lords, and Commons, and they have asserted that the English Constitution is perfect, just because it is the ideal realisation of this mixed form. But it is an error to suppose that the English Constitution has arisen * from a division of the supreme governing power. It was the monarchy which, in old times, gave to the State its special form, and the monarchy has been gra- dually limited, first by a powerful aristocracy, and later by the admission of democratic elements. The external form of the State has always been monarchical, and to the sove- reign is attributed not only the supreme governing power (the executive), but also the highest place in the legislative bodies or parliament c . Moreover, it is generally forgotten that the principle of The govem- Aristotle's division does not rest on the nature and com- EgTsi'ature, e position of the legislative power ; for in any advanced State s?dered n " this is usually representative of the chief elements of the whole nation. On the contrary, it depends on the anti- thesis between the government and the governed, and upon the question to whom the supreme administrative power belongs. This latter cannot be divided, not even between 2 Tacitus, Ann. iv. 33 : ' Cunctas nationes et urbes populns aut primores aut singuli regunt : delecta ex iis et consociata reipublicae forma laudari facilius quam evenire, vel si evenit, baud diuturna esse potest.' *> [It is not the same question, whether a government is mixed, and whether it has arisen from a mixture. Cp. Aristotle's remarks about the Solonian constitution at Athens ; Pol. ii. 12. 2, 3, 1273 b, 35 seq.] c [Throughout the book Bluntschli has been misled by exaggerating the power of the monarchy in the English constitution. For a more correct view, see Bagehot, English Constitution^ 334 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. a king and his ministers, for this would create a dyarchy or triarchy, and would be opposed to the essential character of a State, which, as a living organism, requires unity. In all living beings there is a variety of powers and organs, but in this variety there is unity. Some organs are superior and others inferior, but there is always one supreme organ, in which the directing power is concentrated. The head and the body have no separate and independent life, but they are not equal. So also for the State, a supreme organ is a necessary condition of its existence, and this cannot be split into parts, if the State itself is to retain its unity. There is not, therefore, any such fourth form of State as has been called a Mixed State ; and so far as mixture is possible, it is amply treated in a consideration of the three simple States enumerated above. Note. In our days there has been much talk of ' democratic monarchy,' and the formation of such States has been designated as the work of the age. If the expression implies that monarchy must now-a-days base itself upon the masses (the demos}, and must stand in close connexion with them, it is correct, but such a State is a pure monarchy, and not in any sense mixed. If, again, it implies a monarchy limited by demo- cratic institutions or, like the July-monarchy of 1830 in France, ' surrounded by republican institutions/ it has also a certain meaning ; but in this case, as history shows, there is a danger that the principles of the two institutions may come into conflict, and that monarchy may be overthrown by the rising democracy or republic. But if it implies a mixing or division of the supreme executive power, so that it is half monarchical and half democratic, then it has no reasonable meaning, and a State so constituted could not possibly endure. The French Con- stituent Assembly of 1789 believed, with Rousseau, in the possibility of such a division of the sovereignty between two equal powers, one of which should belong to the nation, and the other to the king. But as soon as it was practically tried, the system showed itself inconsistent and unmanageable. Pinheiro-Ferreira (Principes du droit public, 475) declares that monarchy to be democratic in which there are no privileges ; but he includes under privileges any aristocratic distinction. To him, therefore, the expression merely implies a monarchy in which there are democratic but no aristocratic organisms, i. e. an incomplete state in which the aristocratic elements are disregarded or suppressed. Compare below, Chapter XVII, on Constitutional Monarchy. CHAPTER III. LATER DEVELOPMENTS OF ARISTOTLE'S THEORY, MONTESQUIEU, while following in essentials the division Monies- of Aristotle, made a distinct scientific advance in seeking qt for each of the three forms monarchy, aristocracy, and democracy a spiritual or moral principle, apart from the number of the ruling power. Whether he succeeded is another matter. In his view virtue is the principle of democracy, moderation of aristocracy, honour of monarchy, and fear of despotism. He thus made despotism a fourth kind of State, but it is better treated by Aristotle as a per- version of the normal polity. Schleiermacher 1 made a notable attempt to classify the Schieier- various States according to different stages in the develop- " ment of political consciousness. A State originates when the people acquire the consciousness of the l necessary dis- tinction (Gegensatz) between the government and the subject.' The first step is when a small people or tribe acquires this consciousness, and the new sentiment usually seizes ' equally upon the whole mass which is ripe for political life. 7 Then the sense of this distinction developes among all ; they unite to form the government, and then separate again to become subjects. This is democracy, in which the opposition between public spirit and private 1 Schleiermacher, Ueber die Begnffe der verschiedenen Statsformen, in the Abhandlungen der Berliner Academic, 1814. 336 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. [Book VI. interests is only slightly apparent. Or it may happen that, although the whole mass is ripe for political life, the impulse to form a State may affect it unequally : the political consciousness may develope first in an individual or a few. This creates inequality, which leads either to monarchy or aristocracy. In this stage, while the State is still small, the three forms are very similar, and are readily inter- changed; but the natural inclination is always towards democracy, because the masses speedily overtake the individual or the few who were the first to acquire political consciousness, In the second stage, which unites several of these small tribes, one exercises rule over others. This form of State is essentially aristocratic, as in the earlier stage it is essentially democratic. It cannot be democratic, because the majority of the tribes are subject to the ruling one, and therefore unequal. Externally it may assume the form of monarchy, but the king must belong to the ruling tribe, and is therefore only an aristocratic king. The third and final stage, to which the latter is an inter- mediate step, is reached when a great people becomes fully conscious of national unity. The democratic character of the first stage could not fully develope the political distinc- tion of government and subjects, nor could it reach the dimensions of a great nation. In the aristocracy of the second stage the ruling tribe had always its separate interests, and national unity was not the principle of the State. It is in the third stage that true Monarchy is fully developed, and the monarch represents the unity of the State, and government in its full power. This view of Schleiermacher gives an intellectual basis to the three recognised forms of States, and connects them with the stages in the development of the political idea. Democracy appears as the lowest, and monarchy as the highest, stage. Although no new principle of division is introduced, yet a deeper insight is obtained into the spirit of the different forms. Chap, ill.] DEVELOPMENTS OF ARISTOTLE'S THEORY. 337 But the course of history by no means corresponds with this logical development of Schleiermacher ; in fact, the historical order is often the reverse monarchy, aristocracy, and democracy. This is really the more natural order, because the active political consciousness is usually de- veloped first in the upper classes of society, who live under more favourable conditions, and then is gradually extended to wider and lower circles. CHAPTER IV. THE PRINCIPLE OF THE FOUR FUNDAMENTAL FORMS OF THE STATE. Four forms THE different forms of State are specifically divided, as Aristotle recognised, by the different conceptions of the distinction between government and subjects, especially by the quality (not the quantity) of the ruler (Herrscher). 1. The first form is Ideocracy, of which the highest type is Theocracy. Here the people regard their ruler as a superhuman being, who is raised above them by nature : God Himself is regarded as the true governor of the State. 2. In direct opposition to Ideocracy is Democracy. In the former the people are subjected to an external power outside and above themselves ; in the latter the people govern themselves, i. e. collectively they form the govern- ment, but as individuals they are subjects. 3. In Aristocracy the distinction between government and subject is human, and within the limits of the nation : an upper class or tribe becomes the government, while the other classes and tribes are subjects. But while the latter have nothing to do with the government, the individual members of the ruling class are also subjects. 4. In Monarchy the distinction between government and subjects is complete, but it is again human. The government is concentrated in an individual, who is merely a ruler, and not at the same time a subject, but who belongs altogether to the State, and personifies the unity of the nation. Their origi- In each of these four fundamental forms an original type (Urtypus) is reflected : PRINCIPLE OF THE FUNDAMENTAL FORMS. 339 Theocracy represents the rule of God over the world, but a rule which is exerted directly, and in a way harshly and despotically. Monarchy glorifies the unity of humanity in * Man ' as an individual : the ruler represents the collective State, the national unity is personified in its prince. Democracy expresses the idea of the community of the nation, or of all individuals, and presents to us the State as a parish or commune (Gemeinde). Aristocracy embodies the distinction between the noble and the lower elements of the nation, and gives the rule to the former. Its type is the nobility of higher race and quality, just as the commune is the type of Democracy. From one point of view Theocracy and Monarchy stand Consider- in contrast to Aristocracy and Democracy. In the two these forms, former, the supreme power and majesty of government are so concentrated that the ruler is not also a subject, and that he represents no private interests, but only the interest of the State. In Theocracy, this elevation of the govern- ment is divine, and therefore absolute ; in Monarchy it is human, and therefore relative. On the other hand, in Aristocracy and Democracy the distinction between govern- ment and subject is not so clearly marked : the same men at one moment rule and at another obey ; they have both public and private interests. Hence it is that both are often classed under the common name of Republic. In Democracy this mixture of functions extends to the whole people : in Aristocracy it is limited to the ruling class. The latter, in relation to the other members of the nation, are merely rulers, but among themselves they are usually organised democratically, and thus both govern and are governed at the same time. Thus Aristocracy appears to be an intermediate stage between Democracy and Monarchy. But, from another point of view, it is Monarchy and Aristocracy which 'are connected, and stand in contrast to the other two forms. In them the distinction between government and subject is humanly organised in such a way Z 2 340 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. [Book VI. that the rulers feel and know themselves to be independent ; they are so regarded by the people ; they govern in their own name and by independent right, though of course this is more completely the case in monarchy than in aristocracy. On the other hand, whether God or the people be regarded as ruler, their authority must be exercised by some inter- mediate persons, either priests or magistrates. These latter belong personally to the class of subjects, and they exercise only delegated authority as the servants of God or of the people. They cannot therefore be regarded as real rulers ; they only administer the government for the real rulers, who are unable to act in person. They are constantly forced to refer to a superior power, which itself rules them, and which confers upon them an authority that they do not possess in themselves. The distinction of States according to the forms of government is the foundation of constitutional law, and belongs to the domain of public law (Statsrecht). The same distinction is to be found in the tendencies of their political life, even in opposition to the form of their constitution. A State may be ruled in a spirit tending to theocracy (theokratisirender Geist\ although it recognises some human ruler, e. g. an ecclesiastical prince or a priestly caste. So too a State may tend to aristocracy, although its public law recognises no aristocracy, e. g. the English State, where the monarchical form is modified by an aristocratic spirit. There are also States tending to democracy, though they are not democracies, e. g. Norway ; and others tending to monarchy which have no real monarch, e. g. the French Republic. Note. F. Rohmer {Lehre von den politischen Parteien, 219 sq.) divides States according to the four ages of human life, and in making this division he regards, not the form of the State, but its political spirit, i. e. its party-character. His four divisions are : Idolstat, in which the political spirit is Radical. Individualstat ,, ,, Liberal. Rassestat (race-state) Conservative. Formenstat ,, ,, ,, Absolutist. A monarchy, for example, may pass through all these phases of the Chap. IV.] PRINCIPLE OF THE FUNDAMENTAL political spirit in order. R. v. Mohl's objection (Stats^vissenschaft, I. p. 262), that a nation can be neither young nor old because children and old men live in it side by side, rests upon a misconception of the theory which he opposes. The ancients perceived clearly that nations, as organic units, pass through successive ages analogous to the youth and age of individuals, and Savigny has made the idea familiar to the legal circles of Germany. But in addition to this succession of periods in a nation's history, one must also consider that a nation has an innate character of its own. Just as some individuals are by nature childlike or even childish, and remain so in the prime of life, while others have an elderly and staid character even in youth, so there are nations which are childish and elderly by nature. This is most evident in the great race-divisions. The Negroes are children several thousand years old, the Red Indians have for centuries displayed the characteristics of age. In Europe, the continent of manly nations, the Spaniards quite apart from the period they have reached represent the elderly, as the Germans the youthful, spirit. Whether young or old, and whether this youth or age is due to natural character or to the period of its history, the people transfer their spirit to the State in which they live. The manly forms of constitutional monarchy become a simple farce among the childish people of Haiti. CHAPTER V. THE PRINCIPLE OF THE SECOND AR Y FORMS OF THE STATE. Division of THE quality of the head of the State determines the form fccording to of the whole body. But it is necessary to consider in the EhesL g bjectl second place the rights of the subjects, in order to fully determine the legal character of the constitution, and to complete the Aristotelian division. As in considering the government one looks at the ruling organ, so in considering the subjects, i. e. the nation in its narrow sense, one looks at their control over the govern- ment and their share in legislation. By following this method of classification we arrive at the following three secondary forms of States. Unfree; i. The subjects are treated merely as a passive mass, bound to unconditional obedience to the governing power. They have no right of control nor any share in legislation. Such a State is absolutely governed, and we may call it the unfree form. And it is not only unfree when it is exposed to the arbitrary caprice of a despot (Despotism), but in a political sense it is equally unfree when the ruler recognises the restraints of law and protects personal property and freedom (Absolute Government). Half-free.- 2. Some of the subjects, i. e. the upper classes, have the right of control and a share in public business, and thus limit the government. But the rest of the people, and especially the lower classes, have no political rights or PRINCIPLE OF THE SECONDARY FORMS. 343 freedom. These States are half free ; and may be illustrated by the mediaeval States which were organised upon feudal principles or upon class privileges (Lehens- und Stdndestateri). 3. All classes have political rights. The whole country or Free states. nation controls the government and takes part in legislation. These are free States, or republics in the widest sense of the word (or national States, Volksstaten). This control or share in the government is exercised either (a) directly through the assembly of citizens, as was usual in ancient times (Ancient Republics), or (b) indirectly through committees and representatives, the system of the present day (Modern Representative States). If we now bring together the fundamental and the second- ^ f p g|j cation ary divisions, we obtain the following results : division to 1. Theocracy tends, by its principle, to the class of unfree fundamental States. But it is not necessarily despotic, for the ruling God, or the priesthood inspired by Him, may recognise and re- spect a law of the community. It may therefore approach to the second or to the third class, so far as the exercise of the divine rule is influenced by the co-operation of aristo cratic classes or of a national assembly. In this sense the Jewish theocracy was republican. 2. Aristocracy gravitates towards the second class, the half-free States. But it may be regarded as unfree when the demos is wholly without political rights ; or it may rise to be a free national State ( Volksstat] if the demos is allowed, as in Rome, to have a real representation. 3. Democracy naturally belongs to the third class, the free States. But it may become a despotism to the minority, or an absolute government as regards individual citizens : and again, in relation to a servile class (e. g. the slaves and helots of antiquity or the negroes in America), it may appear as a half-free State. 4. Monarchy, the most various of all kinds of State, forms numerous combinations with these three classes. The des- potisms of the East and the absolute governments of the West are obviously unfree ; the kingdoms and principalities 344 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. of the middle ages, restricted by the clergy and the secular nobles, were half-free; the Roman kingdom as organised by Servius Tullius, the kingdom of the old Franks and the modern Norwegians, all of which have given to the national assembly a distinct share in the government, may serve as examples of free monarchies : and finally, the constitutional monarchy of the present day is the nearest approach which monarchy has yet made to a free State with a representative constitution. When Aristotle's division, which rightly starts from the summit, is thus completed by a consideration of the base, the chief objections to it are removed. It is no longer possible to maintain that it wants precision, or that it fails in explaining such points as the close connexion between modern representative democracy and constitutional mon- archy, or the essential difference between absolute monarchy and mediaeval monarchy limited by class privileges (stdndisch beschrdnkte Monarchic). Note. This analysis of the secondary forms of States was suggested by the very interesting study by Georg Waitz of the difference of State forms (Politik, p. 107 sq.). Waitz gives the name of Republic to a state in which the government rests either with the nation or its delegated representatives. On the other hand a Kingdom exists when an indi- vidual governs by his own power and in complete independence of the people. In his view the Aristotelian division is secondary, and his own is primary. According to him the Roman Empire becomes a Republic and the German Empire a Kingdom : the old Roman Patriciate is a Kingdom, the Napoleonic Empire a Republic. But this method brings confusion rather than order into the two divisions. The arrangement given above and based both upon the quality of the ruler and the rights of the subjects, is logically clear and necessary to complete the division of Aristotle. It also explains satisfactorily why it is that constitutional monarchy is more closely related to representative democracy than it is to absolute monarchy. CHAPTER VI. THEOCRACY OR IDEOCRACY. THEOCRACY is a form of state which belongs to the Theocracy infancy of the human race. The earliest political develop- "arTyd"?. ment took place in Asia and Northern Africa, and here the first states are theocratic. In the early youth of humanity the sense of dependence upon the divine being and upon the mysterious forces of nature was extremely vivid, and the influence of God or nature upon the life and education of men was more direct and powerful than it has since been. All ancient sagas and myths represent one or more gods as holding personal intercourse with mankind. Plato's account of the original condition of the Hellenic race agrees with the belief of all early peoples. He tells how Kronos, reflecting on the weakness and incapacity of the men of that time ' placed as kings and princes not men but demons (6V/uoi>f?), beings of superior and divine origin.' Plato was himself in favour of this theocratic conception, and in his theory of the State he employs artifices to allure men back to the old belief in divine rule a . In this belief in gods and demons 1 as the true heads of it involves the State was inevitably involved the preponderant influence p^fest^ oi a [See Plato, Laws, iv. 713.] 1 An extraordinary demonocratic state of the present day is described by A. H. Layard {Nineveh and its Remains ', vol. i. pp. 269, &c ). The Jezidi, a tribe of the mountains of Mesopotamia, are subject to a priestly ruler, the great Scheik, and worship Satan, who they believe will one day be restored to his high estate in the celestial hierarchy. 346 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. [Book VI, of the priests, the chosen mortals who were vowed to the service of the gods and who alone could understand their will and their utterances. Among such peoples therefore the priests have supreme rank. In some the priests rule directly in the name of one or more gods. In others kings are at the head of the State, but they rule only as repre- sentatives and organs of the gods, and either are themselves high-priests or are under the influence and control of the priesthood. The former may be called pure, the latter limited, Priest-states (reine and gebrochene Priesterstateri}. The latter form the stage of transition from Theocracy to Monarchy. Meroe. A pure Priest-state was that of the Ethiopians in Meroe. The priestly caste was supreme : from their own body they nominated some of the best, and of these God chose one in a solemn ceremony : the people immediately did obeisance to the divine nominee and revered in him the representative of God. But the power of this chief was restricted on every side by the divine laws and by the continued manifestations of God's will in the oracles communicated through the priests. A strict ceremonial ordered all his movements and left no room for free decision ; everywhere the priests ac- companied him and co-operated with him. Even his life was not secure : if he displeased God, this was revealed to the priests, they announced to him the message of divine wrath, and nothing remained for him but to appease the offended deity by a voluntary death 2 . Egypt- Of the mixed priest-state we see an example in Egypt. According to popular tradition the gods originally ruled directly. Some centuries later human kings are found, but they were regarded either as gods or as the descendants of gods, and their power was limited by the divine law, by a strict etiquette, and by the influence of the supreme priestly caste. The divine precepts regulated such minute details that the king could not even choose his own food, but his 2 Diodorus Sic. Hist. iii. 5, 6. Cp. Leo, Weltgeschichte, i. p. 79. Chap. VI.] THEOCRACY OR IDEOCRACY. 347 frugal meals were fixed for all time 3 . It is true that the priests did not dare to bring him to trial during his lifetime, but after his death they formed a solemn public tribunal and issued a judgment on which depended his honour among posterity, the reception of his soul in the lower world, and even his resurrection. The Egyptians believed so strongly in the life after death that they took the greatest pains to preserve the body from corruption, to adorn it with extravagance, and to build for its reception palaces which suggested all the needs of life. It is obvious therefore what hopes and fears must have been based on this judgment and what tremendous power it placed in the hands of the priests. The old Indian state resembled the Egyptian, and was India. also mainly Ideocratic. In the order of castes the king stood below the Brahmins. A Brahmin would consider himself and his daughter degraded if he gave her in mar- riage to the king. Yet the royal dignity was so highly esteemed that a certain divinity was considered to pertain to it. According to the laws of Manu the king's body is pure and holy, being composed of elements which have their origin in the eight divine guardians of the world. ' As the sun blinds he the eyes and the heart, and no one on earth dare look him in the face. God has created him for the preservation of all beings. No one may scorn him even in infancy and say "he is a simple mortal," for a great divine force dwells within him V The Indian king was also surrounded by priests. He must be consecrated by them on his accession. The seven or eight ministers, whose advice he must take on all matters, were mostly Brahmins. He could take no important step without first consulting a council of conscience composed of Brahmins. He was bound by the strictest ceremonial, and 3 Diodorus Sic. Hist. i. 71, 72. Cp. Duncker, History of Antiquity (trans, by Abbott), i. p. 188. * Manava Dharma Sastra. Laws of Manu (trans, by Sir W. Jones), v. 96, 97 ; vii. 3-8. 348 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. [Book VI. the laws of Manu reminded him in the gravest terms of his responsibility, though they did not define it very precisely. 1 The foolish monarch who oppresses his subjects with in- justice will speedily lose both kingdom and life, he and his whole family V The Indian state, being of Aryan origin, was freer than the preceding : the royal dignity and power were more fully developed than in the more sombre states of Meroe and Egypt. But in all we find a rigid system of caste and great privileges in the hands of the priests, who had absolute mastery over the intellectual life of the nation, and were richly endowed with earthly goods. In Egypt they held a third of the land 6 , and according to the Indian law ' a king, even though he be dying of want, may not levy a tax on a Brahmin well-read in the sacred books, nor allow such a Brahmin to starve V The lower classes were oppressed and despised, and there was no prospect of individual advance- ment to brighten their hard lot. The Egyptian peasants were simple serfs who cultivated the property of the priests, the kings, or the warriors. The shepherds and artisans were bound by birth to their occupation, were subject to arbitrary taxation, and had no active part in political insti- tutions. Compulsory labour of all kinds was common in these countries. For centuries this theocratic character has prevailed in the states of Asia, and it is still visible in the eastern em- pires. It is true that as the secular ruler has increased his power by the conquest of vast territories, the authority of the priesthood has been obscured and driven into the back- ground. But the rulers themselves have become gods, and thus the theocratic character of the state has been main- tained, though not in the old form. First the ruler was God in person, and kings and priests were His instruments ; then the rule passed more and more into the hands of the priest- hood, headed by a priestly, or later by a military, king ; 5 Laws of Manu, vii. 54, etc. 6 Diodorus Sic. i. 73. 7 Laws of Mami, vii. 1 33. Chap. VI.] THEOCRACY OR IDEOCRACY. 349 finally the king himself was venerated as a god, and a super- human despotism arose. This was the case in the Persian empire, as in the later rule of Mohammedan Sultans and the Emperors of China. Vitagpa, the king of Iran about the year 1000 B. c., in Persia, whose time Zarathustra (Zoroaster, Serduscht) appeared as a prophet, called himself priest-king, and in the Persian sacred books (the Zend-Avesta) the king is placed, not in the caste of warriors as in India, but in that of priests (the ' learned in law and in god 8 '). The whole political system was re- ligious, there was no distinction between law and morality, the invisible world of good and evil spirits was regarded as in constant connection with the visible world of humanity. But when kings arose in Persia outside the priestly class, the state became more and more a despotism, and the in- fluence of the Magi, though still considerable, was far less than in earlier times. The king became as all-powerful as the god who had raised him to rule ; his court was the earthly copy of the heavenly court of Ahuramasda, the good spirit. Divine honours were paid to him : he sat upon his lofty throne of gold, adorned with purple robe, tiara on his head, the golden staff in his hand, the sword by his side, ' glittering like the sun in the shining firmament/ and before him foreign envoys prostrated themselves in the dust, like slaves before their lord, or worshippers before their god. Gifts were offered to him like sacrifices to a god, and when he died he was carried to the gorgeous mausoleum in Per- sepolis, there to continue the life of the blest. He was honoured with a solemn ceremonial and symbolic rites 9 . In reality this ceremonial enclosed him like a golden net, deprived him of all freedom of will, and mocked his boasted omnipotence. Nevertheless, this change from priestly rule to despotism 8 Vuller, Fragmente iiber die Religion des Zoroaster (Bonn, 1831), PP- 33> 69. Cp. Spiegel, Avesta (Leipzig, 1852-63), vol. iii ; also Duncker, History of Antiquity, v. p. 132. 9 See Leo, Weltgesch, i. 120 sq. ; Duncker, vi. 389 seq. 350 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. [Book VI. marks a distinct step in advance. It overthrew the rigid rule of a revelation which the priests read in the stars and which was deemed divine, and it broke through the innumerable forms which were imposed upon the whole political life by the observance of fixed supernatural laws. A free human will, despotic though it was, began to express itself in public affairs, and could give attention to changes of political conditions and to the new needs of the people. Thus the iron system of caste was early broken up in Persia. The Jewish The most notable of ancient theocracies was that of the Jews in the Mosaic dispensation. It was based on the firm foundation of a pure religion, and of a vivid belief in a single God, the creator and preserver of the world. Among the Jews the king was God himself, Jahve or Jehovah. He was the immortal lord of a mortal but chosen people. He was both legislator and ruler. The whole system of law, which we call Mosaic, was regarded as the revelation of God, with whom Moses spoke in the solitude of the mountain-top, whose will he received with fear and trembling and announced to the people with loyal truth. Thunder and lightning manifested the presence of God upon Mount Sinai. The whole people was elevated by His divine rule. In Egypt they had been despised and regarded as outcasts with whom intercourse was degrading. Now they were filled with the lofty thought that they were the nation chosen and preferred by God. Although they were divided into hereditary tribes, and had one special priestly tribe (that of Levi), yet all were descendants of Abraham, Isaac, and Jacob, they formed as it were a ' nation of priests.' Thus their ruling principle was not that of rigid caste distinctions but the brotherhood of the tribes. The divine law was preserved in an Ark overlaid with gold, over which rose the golden mercy-seat, guarded by two cherubim and revered as the seat of divine revelation. The ark and the mercy-seat were both concealed behind a curtain in the Holy of Holies within the tabernacle which was God's Chap. VI.] THEOCRACY OR IDEOCRACY. 351 residence, and was carefully guarded by the priests. There the High Priest received the commands of Jehovah and an- nounced them to the people. The High Priest, descended from Moses' brother Aaron, was the natural organ of the divine will, and also the representative of the people before their Lord. In exceptional and critical times Jehovah sent inspired individuals, or prophets, to restore His neglected authority, to awaken the conscience of kings or people, to punish backsliding, to urge repentance and amendment, and to reveal the future destiny of the nation. The judges who were placed at the head of the tribes to administer the law, did so in the name of Jehovah, ' for the judgment is God's.' Therefore they shall 'not respect persons in judg- ment, but shall hear the small as well as the great, and not be afraid of the face of man.' If any cause was too hard for them, they were to demand God's judgment through the Levites, and this judgment they must carry out or die 10 . The whole soil of the Promised Land was the property of Jehovah, and the various families only held it as tenants. In recognition of the divine ownership a tenth of the produce of land and flocks had to be given to the taber- nacle for the maintenance of the priests. Every seventh year was a year of rest, even for the land which was not tilled, just as the seventh day of the week was a day of rest for men ; and after seven times seven years came the year of jubilee, in which the original division of the soil was renewed, so that impoverished families recovered their lands, while those who had grown rich had to resign their surplus. A Jew could never be a slave; if poverty compelled him to sell himself he was treated as 'a hired servant and a sojourner,' and was released in the year of jubilee. A slave among the Jews was always of foreign blood 11 . When the Jews afterwards demanded a king, that they 10 Deuteronomy i. 17, and xvii. 8, &c. Cp. Duncker, ii. 201 sq. 11 Numbers xxv. ; Deuteronomy iv. and v. Cp. Duncker, ii. 219. 352 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. [Book VI. might be ' like other nations,' Jehovah granted their wish through the mouth of their judge, Samuel, but He consoled the latter by saying, ' Hearken unto the voice of the people in all that they say unto thee : for they have not rejected thee, but they have rejected me, that I should not reign over them ] V So the state passed from pure theocracy to monarchy, but the monarchy was always partly theocratic, and influenced by the religious character and mission of the Jewish people. . Theocracy In Europe we find only isolated and feeble echoes of the old theocracy. Caligula appearing in public as Jupiter with golden beard and lightning ; Heliogabalus sacrificing as a priest to the sun ; Gessler in the Swiss legend bidding the free mountaineers to revere the emperor's hat : all these are only caricatures of a form of state which had perished, and which had no claim to permanence. But there are a few relics of theocracy in the Roman empire, e.g., in the statues and temples to living emperors, the name of Divus given to them after death, and the ceremonial of the later Byzantine court. In the middle ages the influence of the clergy, always de- voted to the theory of theocracy, gave to the Christian states a theocratic colouring. This is apparent in secular as well as in ecclesiastical principalities, though naturally more so in the latter. Thus the Emperor has to receive priestly consecration *. But however fond men were in the middle ages of deriving all right and power from God, they never regarded their rulers as anything but men, and they im- posed manifold human restraints upon their power. The only real theocracy in Europe is the Christian Church, the hierarchy of the clergy. Secular princes and govern- 12 1 Samuel viii. 7. b [The prince chosen by the seven Electors assumed the title of King of the Romans : he was not formally Emperor until his coronation by the Pope, which was often delayed for some time. Charles V was the last Emperor who received this papal coronation : his successors assumed the imperial title on election. The Holy Roman Empire ended with the abdication of Francis II in 1806.] Chap. VI.] THEOCRACY OR IDEOCRACY. 353 ments are always being reminded of their human origin by the Church. The fundamental forms of the mediaeval state are rather aristocracy or monarchy than theocracy. On the other hand, the Mohammedan states which arose The Moham- . i , 1 . medans. in the middle ages must be regarded as theocratic in character. It is true that the Mohammedans did not, like the Jews, believe in a direct and regular government by God ; Mohammed did not restore the theocracy of Moses. But the Koran teaches that God confers rule upon whom He will, and treats the human head of the State as the representative vicegerent and vassal of God. In the Caliphate, the ideal of the political system of Islam, are combined the functions of high-priest and of king. The Caliph is Emperor and Pope in one. There is no valid distinction between religion and law, theology and juris- prudence; theologians are also lawyers. Islam has much more in common with theocracy than Christendom has 13 . The modern world is obviously hostile to the theocratic form of State, and to everything that suggests it : witness the disappearance of ecclesiastical principalities, and the abolition of the Pope's temporal power in iSyo 14 . The following are the ordinary characteristics of theocratic General char- ~ acteristics of States : Theocracy. 1. There is a close intermixture of religion and law, of ecclesiastical and political institutions and maxims, with a preponderance in favour of the religious elements. The prospect of the life after death so dominates over the earthly life that it obstructs its free development. 2. The principle of authority is exalted to a superhuman height, and becomes by its nature absolute. All civil and political life is dependent upon it. The subjects do not 13 For other states with a theocratic tendency, see Bluntschli, article Ideokratie in the Deutsches Statsworterbuch, v ; also v. Mohl, Encyclo- pddie der Statswissenschaft, 41. 14 Even the constitution of Montenegro, which a few years ago possessed a priestly-military chief in the Vladika, has approximated to the other states of Europe by separating the priestly dignity from the sovereignty. A a 354 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. [Book VI. stand in any human relation to their chief, they are not con- nected with him by common patriotism, common nationality, or common race. The ruler is raised to an inaccessible height and becomes omnipotent. 3. So far as this divine authority is based upon a revela- tion made long ago and no longer continued, as among the Jews upon the Mosaic dispensation, and among the Moham- medans upon the Koran, it founds a firm but unchangeable organisation. If, on the other hand, the deity is supposed to issue new decrees to suit changing circumstances and momentary needs, then there are only two ways in which its human representatives can learn the divine will. Either there are definite external forms for its manifestation, or it must be known by internal inspiration. The first method was employed by the Chaldeans who read the stars, by the Jews who watched the aspect of the rising sun, by the Roman augurs and haruspices who scrutinised the entrails of the sacrifices and the flight of birds, by the Greeks who questioned the oracles, and by the Germans who cast the dice. It leads always to superstition and fraud. A belief in inspiration, on the other hand, leads to a passive sur- render of the intellectual powers that were given for active use, and to a passionate confidence in the expected impulse from above. Thus in a theocracy the human organs which are indis- pensable for deciding matters of legislation and government, are very imperfectly developed and can never be relied upon. 4. The secular magistrates are subordinate to the priests, who regard themselves as nearer to God. If they rule directly, the State is obviously a priest-state, while if a secular sovereignty co-exists with them, their supremacy still remains beneath the surface, and it is a latent priest- state. In every priesthood there is something effeminate, so that in a priest-state the manly qualities are subordinate to the Chap. VI.] THEOCRACY OR IDEOCRACY. 355 feminine, and self-confidence and freedom never reach full development. Under clerical rule laymen must always be obstructed and kept in the background. 5. There is a harsh criminal jurisdiction and cruel punish- ments 15 . Human justice represents the wrath of God, the free movement of the individual intellect is condemned as impious, and a slight offence is treated as an insult to the divine majesty. 6. The education of the people falls wholly into the hands of the priests. Schools become instruments for the attain- ment of clerical objects. Science, art, and all kinds of skill are only encouraged so far as they serve these objects ; as a rule they are distrusted and neglected, and if they seem to threaten any danger to religious authority they are suppressed and persecuted. They are regarded, not as having any value in themselves, not as free creations of the human intellect, but merely as slaves of the Church. 15 See Duncker's remarks in \hzHistory of Antiquity, iv. 398. A a 2 CHAPTER VII. THE CHIEF KINDS OF MONARCHY. MONARCHY is the most widely recognised form of State in the world. It is found in all continents, in Asia and Europe it is almost universal, and it has been so from the beginning of history to the present day. But monarchies differ so much both in idea and in form that it is difficult to classify their main divisions. Despotism. i. The transition from theocracy to human kingship forms Despotism, of the kind which mainly prevailed in Asia. The distinguishing mark of Despotism is the concentration of all rights in the monarch, so that no one has any right apart from or in opposition to him. He may recognise the re- strictions of religious or moral duty, or of his responsibility to God, but his power is not limited by the rights of his subjects, who are mere slaves and dependent upon his arbitrary grace and favour. Such a despotism must seek some justification for itself by appealing to the divine omnipotence. The despot must be revered as the vicegerent of God, his power is unlimited because it comes from above. Thus despotism is closely allied to theocracy, and shares its defects, in spite of the human character of the ruler. The Mohammedan States of the middle ages had this tendency towards despotism, and it is only in our own day that they have approximated more nearly to the human monarchy of the rest of Europe. Civilised 2. Despotism may be regarded as the barbarous form of onarchy. mo narchy. The peoples of Aryan origin rejected it long ago as degrading, and recognised the rights of classes and THE CHIEF KINDS OF MONARCHY. 357 individuals apart from those of kings and princes. The subjects have regarded themselves as freemen, not as slaves. Whenever the monarchical power has been strained so as to verge upon despotism, they have regarded it as an injustice, and have seized the first opportunity to compel the ruler to respect their rights. Civilised monarchy, therefore, is always conditioned and limited by a judicial organisation to secure common rights. The position and power of the monarch is raised rather than lowered by this, for it is a nobler task to guide the political forces of a free people, than to direct the stupid obedience of a servile mass. The more a State can combine the unity and energy of the whole with the freest development of the members, the more perfect is its organisation. This is possible in a civilised monarchy, in a despotism it is impossible. The human intellect has made many attempts in different periods and among different nations to find the exact measure of the limitations that should be imposed upon monarchy. One of the earliest forms is the Kingship of the Family, Patriarchal or Patriarchy (Geschlechtskonigthum^ Patriarchie]. The king ings ' is regarded as the head of the chief family, as the elder and father of the race. This early and artless institution, which is found in the Vizpati of the Indian races and the Kuning of the German tribes, is regulated by the relations and spirit of the family. Equally bound up with the institutions of personal pro- Feudal perty and security is the patrimonial principality of the middle ages, whether in the form of the feudal State (Lehensstaf) or of a simple territorial lordship (Landesherr- schaft, dominium terrae}. This, too, is influenced by family rights and dynastic conceptions, but it also confounds the State with the ownership of the soil, and treats the function of the ruler as a right over property. These two forms, in which political consciousness is as yet undeveloped, may be termed immature phases of monarchy. 358 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. [Book VI. Military and 3. When the political consciousness is only partially cipSr in ~ awakened, and is directed only to a single function of the ruling power, we have one-sided (einseitige) forms of mon- archy. Such are military principalities in which the military function is primarily regarded, or judicial principalities (Gerichtsherrschafi] in which the judge is the ruler. The former is more absolute and energetic, the latter more limited and peaceful. Absolute 4. When the political consciousness is excessively de- veloped in the prince, the central power obtains decisive preponderance in his hands, and the people have no political rights. This absolute monarchy is the civilised form corre- sponding to the barbarous form of despotism, but it differs from it in that the monarch recognises a judicial organisa- tion, and is willing, at any rate as a rule, to respect it. In the Roman Empire this power was more absolute than in modern states, in which it has been restricted even in the middle ages by Christianity and by the development of freedom. Limited e Limited monarchy is at once more noble and better Monarchy. * J proportioned. It retains the unity and supremacy of the central power, and seeks to combine with these the liberty of all classes and individuals of the nation. In the middle ages such a monarchy was restricted by the privileges of nobles or of estates, as in modern times by representative and constitutional forms. Kingship 6. In treating of monarchy it is necessary to notice the distinction between Kingship and Empire (Kaiserthum), a distinction which is found in all stages of development, in the rude despotisms of Asia, and in the civilised states of Europe. The idea of Kingship refers to the nation, that of Empire to humanity. Kingship is the supreme institution of the single national State, Empire is the crown of the world. The emperor is raised above kings as humanity above the sepa- rate nations. The rulers of Oriental empires are always kings of kings. Julius Caesar conceived the thought of the Chap. VII.] THE CHIEF KINDS OF MONARCHY. 359 universal rule of Rome, and history has given his name to this lofty conception of the State. But this idea can never be fully realised until the world has advanced to a universal organisation of humanity. Till that time all attempts to restore the Empire must be, like those in the past, partial and imperfect 1 . 1 On the idea and the history of the Empire, see the article on Kaiser- thum in the Deutsches Statsworterbuch. CHAPTER VIII. I. FAMILY KINGSHIP AMONG THE GREEKS AND GERMANS. character- THE conception of kingship among the tribes and states Gr'ee^amT y of early Greece and Germany is remarkably similar, while Monarchy. ^at which prevailed among the ancient Romans, who come between them in point of time, differed in important re- spects from both. The kingship of the Greeks and Germans is the transition from the ideocratic form of single rule in the east to a human and political institution. The kings were believed by the people to derive their descent from the gods, from Zeus or Woden *, but they were not themselves regarded as gods, and they were subject to human restraints. Therefore, the honours paid to the king were greater than his power. He represented the nation in its relations with 1 Hence the expressions of Homer, K 8e Aibs 5torp($is. Cp. Iliad) ii. 204-6 : OVK ayaOov TroXvicoipavir]' els Koipavos eff "Eh @affi\vs, o5 !5o>tf Kpovov i ^KrJTTTpov T ^5e 0e/itoray, iva Cp. Hermann, Griech. Statsalterth. 56 ; also Sophocles, Philoct. 138-140: T\va yap T\vas trtpas real yvwfia trap' orca TO Oetov Cp. the praise of kingship in the Indian epic, Rama, in Holtzmann, Indische Sagen, ii. p. 316 : ' As for the body the eye always To all sides carefully looks, So for the realm the prince of men, Root of virtue and law. GREEK AND GERMAN FAMILY KINGSHIP. 361 the gods, and officiated as intermediary between the two in sacrifice and prayer 2 , when these were not performed by a special priesthood. Thus in Athens, after the monarchy had been abolished, the sacrificing archon retained the title of king. Their pecuniary estimation was much higher than that of the other members of the State. The ivergild of the king in Germany was usually many times as great as that of the noble. They were also very superior to their subjects in wealth, the greater part of the land was their domain, and they received the largest share of conquered territory 3 . Their residence, or palace, was larger and more richly adorned than the other houses 4 . Their treasuries, or hoards, were rich in ornaments and precious stones. They had ex- ternal ensigns of their royal rank, the sceptre 5 , the throne, and the announcement of their approach by heralds. Their dress was always conspicuously brilliant. The ancient kings Wrapped in blind darkness Waste and confused is the world Unless the king keeps order And shows what is just and unjust.' According to Jornandes, c. 14, the Amals spring from the race of the Asa. Hengist and Horsa are believed to be descended from Woden. On the gradual development and extension of monarchy among the German tribes, even among those which originally had no kings, see Dahn, Die Konige der Germanen (Miinchen, 1861-71), and Gierke, Deutsches Genossenschaftsrecht, i. p. 48, &c. 2 Aristor. Pol. iii. 14. 12, 1285 b. 10. In the Scandinavian countries this characteristic of the kings is more prominent than in the known history of any German state. Comp. Grimm, Deutsche Rechtsalt. p. 243. King Hakon of Norway, though inclined to Christianity, was compelled by the still heathen peasants to sacrifice in ancient fashion at the Thing, to drink from the sacred goblet, and to eat horseflesh. Konrad Maurer, Die Bekehrung des nonvegischen Stammes zum Christenthum y i. p. 160 if. 3 Tacitus, Germ. c. 14 : ' Materia munificentise per bella et raptus ' ; c. 26 : ' Agros inter se secundum dignationem partiuntur.' In spite of incessant alienations, the kings and princes of Germany retained extensive territories throughout the middle ages. 4 Homer, Od. iv. 45-46 : "Hs re yap r]\iov a'tyXrj ire\v Comp. vi. 301, and the ' Hallen ' of the German princes. 5 Homer, //. ii. 100-8. Cp. Grimm, Rechtsalt. p. 241. 362 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. [Book VI. of India and China always appeared in a long robe worked in gold thread, and with a yellow umbrella 6 . The existence of royal families and their supposed descent from the gods prove that ancient monarchy was hereditary. Yet there were no fixed rules of succession. Among the Greeks regard was paid to personal courage and capacity. Women and children were almost always excluded, and as acknowledgment by the nobles and people was necessary, it sometimes happened that the hereditary succession was broken through 7 . Among the Germans the practice pre- vailed of election by the nobles and recognition by the people, but as a rule the succession was hereditary, and children obtained the crown more often than in Greece. There was nothing, however, to prevent the free community from preferring a more distant member of the royal family if he seemed more likely to be a capable ruler 8 . Limits to The political power of these kings was considerable, but royal power. , . . ..... was subject to important limitations. i. The king presided over and directed both the council of princes and the national assembly 9 . But in both, ac cording to Tacitus, his authority depended rather on his persuasive influence than on his right of command 10 . 6 Grimm, Rechtsalt. p. 239 ; Thierry, Recits des Temps Merovingiens, ii. 82 ; Rama, 1. 782 (in Holtzmann, Indische Sagen, vol. ii). 7 Comp. the history of CEdipus. Among the Indians we find a similar combination of hereditary right (by primogeniture) with election by the princes ; v. Holtzmann, Indische Sagen, ii. 184. 8 Tacitus, Germania, c. 7 : ' reges ex nobilitate sumunt.' The German name for king, Chuningcn: Kun-ing, comes from chun or chuni, family. Childebert II became king of Austrasia at the age of five (Thierry, Temps Meroving. ii. 43). Instances of departure from hereditary succession are more common in the history of the Visigoths and Lombards. F. Dahn (Die Konige der Germanen, i. 32) lays more stress upon hereditary right, Thudichum (Der altdeutsche Stat, p. 60) upon election, but both recognise the combination of the two principles. A similar combination is to be found among the Indians ; v. Holtzmann, Indische Sagen, ii. 184 (Rama, 1. 22). 9 The @ov\rj or ytpovres of the Greek kings corresponds to the concilium principum which Tacitus describes among the Germans ( Germ. cc. n, 12). 10 Tac. Germ. c. n : 'auctoritas suadendi potius quam jubendi.' Chap. VIII.] GREEK AND GERMAN FAMILY KINGSHIP. 363 2. He was the chief judge, and though he did not pro- nounce the decision, he defended and maintained the law 11 . His power was not at all arbitrary, as he was bound to respect the decision of the court. 3. He was the head of the military organisation, and usually the leader of the army 12 . It was by war that his power increased 13 . But the Germans, just because they respected hereditary right more than the Greeks, were often compelled by the minority of the king to appoint heretogan (duces, dukes) to take the actual command, though the king was still regarded as the supreme head of the national force (ffeerbann). 4. Real government was very little developed among the early Greeks and Romans, though its germs were concealed under the attributes of the king which have just been enumerated. 5. In both races the king's existence and rights were hemmed in by the rights of gods and men. The Greeks laid special stress upon the obligation of their kings to re- spect the divine ordinances and the national laws and customs, and they pointed to this as distinguishing them from oriental despots u . The king was within the judicial organisation, not above it ; he was not outside the nation, but at its head. The German kings were still more limited by the rights of the whole body of freemen 15 . But there was one peculiarity of the German kingship The German r Camitatns. 11 Hence Homer calls the kings SiKaa-noXoi (II. i. 238) and 0fjuffTo-rr6\oi. The Indian name for king, rag, comes from rag (right, richten), as rex from regere. Comp. Lassen, Ind. Alterth. i. 808 ; also Holtzmann, Ind. Sagen, ii. 184 (J?ama, 1. 23) : 'The burden of justice which the King's majesty bears.' 12 Arist. Pol. iii. 14. 12, 1285 b. 9 : fcvpioi S' rjaav TTJS TC Kara ir6\fAoi> rjycfjiovias. In many of the German tribes a successful heretoga founded a royal dynasty. 13 Cp. Caesar, de B. G. vi. 23. 14 Dionys. Hal. v. 74; Arist. Pol. iii. 14. 12 and 14. Cp. Sophocl. Oed. Rex, 1. 850 sq. ; Antig. 1. 451, and Oed. Col. 1. 1372 sq. 15 Tac. Germ. c. 7, ' nee regibus infinita aut libera potestas ; ' and c. u, * penes plebem arbitrium.' 364 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. which led to a great increase in its power. This was the comitatuS) a body of men bound by oath to personal fidelity, whose constant aim was to defend the king's honour and power against all opponents. This institution is the germ from which sprang the later feudal organisation, which was destined to break through and to a great extent to transform the old constitution. CHAPTER IX. II. NATIONAL MONARCHY IN ANCIENT ROME. IN some points the kingship of ancient Rome seems Conception closely akin to that of the Greeks and Germans, but in Monarchy, others it displays such important differences that we must regard it as a new and more developed form. In the very appointment of the kings there are two notable points of difference hereditary succession is less prominent than nomination or election, and popular belief does not attri- bute divine descent to the kings. It is true that the founders of Rome were believed to have divine blood in their veins, and Romulus was placed among the gods after death. But from his time the gods exerted their influence in the choice of kings, and in all other matters, only by the signs of the auspices, by the in- visible impulse of the soul, and by the irresistible might of destiny. Thus, though the idea of divine influence re- mained, the Roman kingship was purely human ; the insight and will of the individual were more regarded than descent and the family 1 . The Roman king was chosen either by his predecessor or by the interrex with the help of the senate and the ap- proval of the gods. The choice was for life only, so that no hereditary dynasty was created, and it depended more 1 In the same way inheritance among the Romans was based not so much upon family relationship as upon the individual will of the testator, who was free to name his own heir. 366 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. [Book VI. upon individual character than upon descent. The elected king himself proposed the lex curialis by which the royal authority and the auspices were given to him 2 , just as the imperium was conferred upon the magistrates of the sub- sequent republic. Thus the Roman kingship was from the first an individual magistracy. This conception is obviously quite different from that of the Greeks and Germans. The character of the kingly power shows an equally important divergence. In many points it is similar : the king is the high-priest who sacrifices for the nation ; he assembles and guides the Senate and the Comitia ; he is the supreme judge, though in certain cases there is an appeal from him to the people ; he is the rightful head and leader of the army; he is rich in lands and revenues 3 . Administra- But his power is stronger and more complete than that of the Greek kings, though the latter are the hereditary descendants of the gods. The strong political sense of the Romans is obvious from the first in the extent of the ad- ministrative power which they confer upon their magistrates, in order that they may take energetic measures in defence of the public welfare. The imperium is distinctly Roman in origin, and it is this which distinguishes their kingship from the previous forms. External The external ensigns of the Roman are quite as imposing as those of the Greek and German kings, but they also manifest their greater power. The fasces which the twelve lictors carry before them are not mere symbols, but real instruments of punishment for the disobedient. The im- perium and the lictor's axe are always connected in fact and thought by the Romans 4 . 2 This is the so-called lex regia, which was renewed under the Empire. Ulpian, L. \. pr. de constit. Princip. ; Cicero, dfc lege agrar. ii. n. Cp. Mommsen, Rb'misches Statsrecht, i. 588. 3 Cp. Niebuhr, Rom. Gesch. i. 356 ; Rubino, Untersuch. iiber rbm. Verf. i. Abschn. 2 ; Mommsen, ibid. ii. 9. * Cic. pro Flacco, c. 8 : ' Opifices et tabernarios atque illam omnem faecem civitatum, quid estnegotii concitare in eum praesertim qui nuper summo cum imperio fuerit, summo autem amore esse propter nomen ipsum imperil non potuerit. Mirandum vero est homines eos, quibus Chap. IX.] NATIONAL MONARCHY IN ANCIENT ROME. 367 The imperium, which was transferred to the king with the Legislative auspices, gave him the right both of issuing edicts and of P laying down the principles of law. It must never be for- gotten that the Roman State was founded by a king, and that it was his power which passed by tradition to his suc- cessors. Permanent laws needed the consent of the Senate, and from the time of Servius Tullius 5 the sanction of the people (jussu populi\ but at the same time the royal will was essential and usually decisive. The king alone could propose a law, and he could prevent any law from being discussed or voted upon 6 . Besides these laws the king could in his edict lay down, without the counsel and con- sent of any assembly, the legal maxims which he intended to follow. This jus edicendi was unquestionably a right of the kings, though seldom exercised by them : it was not created for the later magistrates, but was handed on to them from their predecessors. Thus the judicial power of the Roman kings was far Judicial greater than that of the German. Both presided, at first in p person, over the law-courts, but the rex was not bound by the decision of the assessors. He not only directed the course of the trial, but also laid down the principle (jus dicit) which was to apply to the particular case. In early times he often gave judgment himself. On him depended almost the whole administration of civil and criminal kw 7 . odio sunt nostrae secures ' &c. Cp. ibid. c. 34, * non imperium non secures ; ' also Livy, xxiv. 9. Hal. iv. 36. 6 Rubino (Untersuch. p. 18) has thrown great light on many points of the public law of ancient Rome, but he has gone too far in attributing the legislative power exclusively to the king. It is true that the terms constituere, instituere, dare jus, are used instead of the more modest expression, rogare legem, but the former do not imply that the senate and people had no right in the matter. 7 Cic. de Rep., ' omnia conficiebantur judiciis regiis ; ' ibid. ii. 31. Zonaras, Annal. vii. 13. 368 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. [Book VI. Military The military power of the Roman kings was very exten- sive. In the field he had absolute power of life and death over both officers and soldiers. Even in republican times we see not only dictators, whose power was that of the kings undiminished, but also consuls, putting to death officers against the petition of the army, and even decimat- ing whole legions 8 . officials. The king was the source of all other political and priestly offices. He nominated the tribunus celerum, the leader of the knights, and the praefectus urbi, who governed the city in his absence. From him the augurs and pontiffs derived their powers of divination and their knowledge of the sacred law 9 . important The essence of the imperium is a strong administrative position of . . . , . . . the Roman power which can act decisively whenever and wherever poli- tical needs or momentary circumstances require, and which can enforce measures for the public welfare. Such a power was only exercised by the Greek kings to a very slight extent, and among the Germans was unknown ; but in the Roman state it assumed the greatest importance from the first. As the Romans loved absolute rule over their family and their property, so their political imperium was also absolute. Their kings were not only judges in time of peace, their chief functions, as the name indicates, was that of governors (rex, regere). In this way it becomes intelligible that the whole policy of the Roman state in the kingly period should be directed by the royal will, that all institutions should be referred to the kings, and that they should have been able to undertake and complete works which appear gigantic even in the present day. The king had to look after the supply of food and the cultivation of the soil, to watch over the morals of the citizens, and to exercise extensive police powers. All the functions which were afterwards divided among consuls, 8 Livy, ii. 59 ; v iii. 7 ; ix. 16. Brisson, De FormuL, p. 455, etc. * Rubino, Untersuch. pp. 114 and 298. Chap. IX.] NATIONAL MONARCHY IN ANCIENT ROME. 369 praetors, censors, and aediles, were originally combined in the single hand of the king 10 . To sum up : Rome was the first state in history to produce a human and national monarchy with complete concentra- tion of political authority and with almost absolute ad- ministrative power. . 136. Bb CHAPTER X. III. THE ROMAN EMPIRE. The Umpire THE Roman Empire, which was founded by Julius Caesar coHectbTof and established by Augustus, and which has exercised so 5fil! lican great an influence upon the political development of all later times, was not formed, as has been sometimes maintained, out of a simple accumulation of republican magistracies. It was really a revival of the old monarchical power on a far vaster scale and in harmony with the intervening changes a . It is true that the Emperors assumed a number of functions which had belonged to republican magistrates : the tribunicia potestas secured their personal inviolability, gave them the right of veto, and enabled them to pose as champions of the lower classes : the censorial power b gave them the supervision of morals and the function of revising at will the lists of senators and knights : the dignity of pontifex maximus made them supreme arbiters of the sacred law. From time to time they took the office of consul. a [Mommsen (Rom. Statsr. II. Abth. ii.) rightly describes the Princi- pate, as instituted by Augustus, rather as a restoration than an abolition of the Republican constitution. Comp. Mon. Ancyr. 6. 12 : 'in con- sulatu sexto et septimo . . . rem publicam ex mea potestate in sena- t[us populique Romani a]rbitrium transtuli.' Nominally the position of the Princeps was that of a magistrate raised above the rest by his superior dignitas, though in fact the possession of the proconsular imperium made him supreme. But this itself was only an extension of republican precedent, and did not put the Princeps above the laws.] & [Augustus held the census in virtue of the consular e imperium. But the censorship still existed as a separate office, and was held by later emperors, e. g. Claudius, Vitellius, Vespasian, and Titus. It was abolished by Domitian, and its duties were merged in the indefinite powers of the emperor. See Mommsen, Rom. Statsr. ii. 3. 6.] THE ROMAN EMPIRE. 3-71 But the conception of their power did not rest upon this cumulation of offices, but upon the creation of a new centralised government, of a real monarchy. Republican forms might conceal the change for a time, but it was obvious to clear-sighted men even in the days of Augustus. At the accession of Tiberius the principle of monarchy was clearly expressed in the Senate by Asinius Gallus when he asserted that * it was impossible to divide the indivisible, that the body of the state was one, and could therefore only be ruled by the mind of one man V The Emperors assumed only the modest title of Princfys (Senatus) la , but their power was so great that few could resist its temptations, and most of them were ruined either in intellect or in morals. The Empire was not hereditary but Election to ii r> i it f the Empire. elective : its first holders were chosen, nominally for ten years, really for life. They were not regarded as of divine origin, and they recognised the supremacy of the people. Their authority was conferred upon them by a law of the people 2 . But though descent and family connexion were not in principle regarded in the choice of an emperor, they usually had great practical influence, and the chosen prince received in full personal right a power as extensive as that of the Roman people itself had been under the Republic. And when once that power had been conferred it could neither be diminished nor withdrawn. 1 Tac. Ann. i. 12. In i. I, he says of Augustus : 'cuncta discordiis civilihus fessa nomine principis sub imperium accepit.' Comp. the con- ferences of Maecenas and Agrippa with Augustus in Dio Cass. 52. la According toMommsen {Rom. Statsr. ii. 733), the name of Princeps has no reference to the Princeps Senatus^ but is used in the sense of Princeps omnium or civium. [See also art. on Princeps by Prof. H. F. Pclham in Journal of 'Philology ', viii. 323.] 2 Ulpianus, L. i. pr.de constit princip. \ ' Quod principi placuit, legis habet vigorem, utpote, cum lege regia, quae de imperio ejus lata est, populus ei et in eum omne suum imperium et potestatem conferat. Gaius, i. 5. 6. de jure nat. [The proconsular e imperium was not conferred by a lex popzdi. The Princeps was recognised as Imperator by the salutation of the senate or of the army. On the other hand, he received the tribunicia potestas by a law of the comitia (the comitia tribuniciae potestatis) following on a decree of the senate. See Mommsen, Rom. Statsr. ii. pp. 812-3, 8 3^-9-] B b 2 372 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. [Book VI. Analysis of The imperial power, in addition to the special magistracies ,"ow e e r la which the Emperor usually held, may be thus analysed : 1. The disposal and command of the whole military forces of the state, and of the praetorian guard in the city. The introduction of standing armies, which became neces- sary as the boundaries were extended, secured the existence of the empire and enforced obedience 3 . It was this function which gave to the emperors the title of imperatores, which had a different meaning in earlier times. 2. The absolute government of. the richest and most important provinces [?], from which the Emperors derived enormous wealth and power. On the whole, the provinces gained considerably by the change of constitution. Their great men were admitted to the senate and to office by the Emperors, while the oppressions and exactions of the imperial legati were far less than those of the ever-changing proconsuls and propraetors of the Republic. The more permanent interests of the Emperors enjoined a more merciful and orderly administration. 3. The decision of all questions of foreign policy, the right of peace and war, and of concluding treaties 4 . 4. The right of convening the senate, of proposing matters for discussion, and of giving legal force to its decisions 5 . It is well known how obsequious and sub- missive the senate was to the Emperors. 5. A decisive voice in the appointment to magistracies and all important offices. Both the comitia (which retained for a time a formal existence) and the senate were bound 3 Maecenas urged Augustus strongly to form a standing army (ffTpcLTiwras aOavaTovs}, and to leave the mass of the people to their peaceful occupations. Dio Cass. 52. * Lex de Imp. Vespasiani, in Bruns, Fontes Juris Romani, p. 118 : ' foedusve cum quibus volet facere liceat' 5 Ibid. : ' utique ei senatum habere, relationem facere, remittere senatus consulta per relationem discessionemque facere liceat . . . utique cum ex voluntate auctoritateve jnssu mandatove ejus praesenteve eo senatus habebitur omnium rerum jus perinde habeatur servetur ac si e lege senatus edictus esset habereturque.' [See also Mommsen. Rom. Statsr. ii. 860 ff.] Chap.X.] THE ROMAN EMPIRE. 373 by law to respect the Emperor's recommendation of candi- dates 6 . 6. The absolute power of acting for the welfare and honour of the state, which forms the real essence of the imperial authority 7 . It was by virtue of this power that not only the edicts, but also the decrees and rescripts of the Emperor obtained the full force of laws, so that he was able to cover the whole field of legislation 8 . To prevent any hostile criticism or resistance, the lex de imperio definitely announced that it overrode all other laws, whether of the senate, \hzpopulus, or the// Waitz, Hi. 499 ff. 10 Capit. Car. Magni, a. 802 (Pertz, i. 97-99), and a. 810 (Ib. i. 163-4) ' Guizot, ssaiSj pp. 191 ff. ; Waitz, iv. 411-488. 380 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. [Book VI. The counts of districts or shires ( Gaugrafen) had supreme judicial power, while that of the counts of hundreds (Zent- grafeti) was limited. Both derived their jurisdiction, the one directly and the other indirectly, from the king, as the supreme judge upon earth. Their military powers sprang from the same source. In the early period of the Frankish monarchy the position of count was not hereditary, but was a real office, to which the king had the right of appointment. Under Charles the Great's successors, however, the natural tendency to hereditary succession soon began to obscure this official character and to create a hereditary right to the dignity. Gradually the missi dominid became obsolete, the duchies were restored, and the offices of the kingdom sank into family property. Thus the power of the Romano -German monarchy perished, and the aristocracy of princes and lords took its place. close con- 4. There is one other notable point about the Frankish nexion with ,,... . . j Empire and monarchy, and this is its close connexion with the Western Empire a connexion established by Charles the Great and of both with the extension of Christianity and with the Christian Church. The state had become Christian, and the monarchy had received consecration at the hands of a priest u . The king felt himself bound to maintain and extend the pure Christian belief in his territories, while his duty as emperor was to destroy heathenism and heresy as far as his power reached. This duty was fulfilled by Charles the Great on a large scale and with great severity 12 . Christendom itself was repre- sented as a single body with two organisations, one sacer- dotal and the other monarchical, Church and State 13 . But 11 Hincmar, de Ord. Pal. c. 5 : ' principes sacerdotum sacra unctione reges in regnum sacrabant.' 13 Even before he received the imperial dignity, Charles the Great bore the title 'devotus sanctae Dei ecclesiae defensor humilisque adjutor.' 13 See Hincmar, c. 5. for the reported saying of Pope Gelasius to the Emperor Anastasius : ' duo sunt (potestates) quibus principaliter, una Chap. XI.] THE PRANKISH MONARCHY. 381 though the king was the head only of the latter, he enforced among the clergy also the recognised Christian discipline. He summoned synods, superintended the conduct of bishops and monasteries, and issued many laws and ordinances on ecclesiastical matters. So too the spirit of the hierarchy exercised a marked influence upon political institutions and upon the legal principles of the secular organization u . cum specialiter cujusque curae subjectis, mvmdus hie regitur : auctoritas sacra pontificum et regalis potestas.' [See Migne, Patrologia t lix. col. 41 ; also Bryce, Holy Roman Empire, chap, vii.] H Comp. Eichhorn, i. 158. CHAPTER XII. V. FEUDAL MONARCHY AND MONARCHY LIMITED BY CLASS PRIVILEGES. A. Feudal Monarchy. Decline of THE Frankish monarchy contained all the essential con- Carohngian . , r ...... Monarchy, ditions of a true monarchy, and so far it is the beginning of a new development of the modern state. But the opposing powers and passions were so strong in the nation, and the traditions of German nobles and freemen were so hostile to a strong central administration, that it was only possible for exceptionally powerful rulers to exert to the full their kingly authority and to bring out the real character of the state. Weak kings were powerless, and under their rule the ten- dency was obvious to dissolve the unity of the state, to limit and discredit the central power, and to give independence to local governments. Feudal With the decline and extinction of the Carolines the Monarchy, \ royal authority :sank into obscurity, and the princes and lords seized the administration of isolated peoples and terri- tories. The Romano-Germanic universal monarchy was replaced by the feudal monarchy, which gives to the middle ages their special political character, itscharac- The following are the most notable characteristics of tenstics. feudal monarchy : it is based i. Every previous monarchy had been based upon a tribe; upon Classes. . * or a nation or a united people, and might therefore be called a national or popular (volksthumlicK) institution. But the FEUDAL MONARCHY. 383 feudal monarchy, although connected with a special nation of which the king is the head, had its essential basis in the personal bond of fealty between the king, the supreme lord of the land, and his vassals, who derived from him their power, rank, and property. The mass of the people, as not being bound by this feudal tie, were only regarded in a sub- ordinate and indirect way. Thus the monarchy was rather the institution of a class or estate than of the nation : it was founded not so much upon the people as upon the feudal vassals (Gefolgeschafi}. 2. Personal fidelity, ennobled and strengthened by the Fealty and .-,/-, i ^^ ^ Homage. idea of honour, became now an important political concep- tion \ All vassals, on receiving their fiefs from a lord, swore to him the oaths of fealty and homage 2 . These oaths and the whole feudal system may be most clearly traced in the mixed Saxon and Norman law of the English kingdom. The tenants in chief took the oath of homage (Mannschaftseid] 3 to the king upon their knees, while they stood to swear the oath of fealty 4 with their hand upon the gospels. Bishops and abbots were exceptions, as they took the latter oath only. The oath of homage was the more 1 In Tacitus' account of the German comitatus, he points to these moral qualities as the basis of the institution; v. Germ. 13, 14 : ' Magnaque comitum aemulatio, quibus primus apud principem suum locus ; et principum, cui plurimi et acerrimi comites. Haec dignitas, hae vires ; magno semper electorum juvenum globo circumdari in pace decus, in bello praesidium .... Quum ventum in aciem, turpe principi virtu te vinci, turpe comitatui virtutem principis non adaequare. Jam vero infame in omnem vitam ac probrosum superstitem principi suo ex acie recessisse. Ilium defendere tueri, sua quoque fortia facta gloriae ejus assignare praecipuum sacramentum est. Principes pio victoria pugnant, comites pro principe.' a In French legal phrase, foi et homage^ 3 The formula of this oath shows the importance attached to personal fidelity. Bracton {Rolls Series], i. p. 632 : * Devenio homo vester, de tenemento quod de vobis teneo, et fidem vobis portabo de vita et membris et terreno honore contra omnes gentes.' Comp. Du Cange, s. v. homagium. * Bracton, i. 632, gives the formula of the oath of fealty; ' Hoc audis, domine, quod fidem vobis portabo de vita et membris, corpore, et catallis, et terreno honore, sic me Deus adjuvet et haec sancta Dei evangelia.' Comp. Du Cange, s. v.fidelitas. 384 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. [Book VI. specially and directly connected with the possession of the fief. The oath of fealty was more general, and could there- fore be exacted from other subjects who were not bound by the feudal tie. Instances of this are to be found in the Carolingian times, doubtless under the influence of feudal conceptions 5 . The fealty thus sworn was mutual. The lord was equally bound with the vassal, but the latter alone was bound to homage 6 . Tenure of 3. The endeavour on the part of the feudal monarchy to bring all subjects into the relation of vassalage had a ma- terial influence upon the tenure of land. The Norman kings of England strove to obtain supreme possession (Obereigen- thum) of the whole land, so that not only all fiefs, but also allodial estates, were regarded as being derived from the king. Thus the national right of free property in the soil was transformed into the feudal right of dependent occupa- tion or tenure 7 . This is a general characteristic of feudalism, but it is especially clear in the history of English law 8 . Authority 4. By parallel steps all political power came to be re- the King, garded as derived from the king. The king received his authority as a grant from God 9 . The lords received their 5 Capit. Car. Magni, a. 811, c. 13 (Pertz, i. 175) : ' Ut missi nostri populum nostrum itemm nobis fidelitatem promittere faciant secundum . consuetudinem.' 6 This is expressed in the English maxim, ' quantum homo debet domino ex homagio, tantum illi debet dominus ex dominio.' Reeves, Hist, of English Law (ed. by Finlason, 1869), i. 175. Assises de Jerusalem, Haute Cour, 322 (Kausler, p. 372) : L'assise et la lei de Jerusalem juge et dit que, autant doit li rois de fei a son home lige, come Thome lige doit a luy, et ains est tenu li rois de guarantir et de sauver et de desfendre ses homes liges vers toutes gens qui tort leur vorreent faire, come ses homes liges sont tenus a lui de guarantir le et de sauver vers toutes gens. Et, por ce, ne peut il mie mettre la main sur son home lige sans esgart de ces pers.' 7 See above, Bk. ii. chap, n, note. 8 In France the cognate principle, nulle terre sans seigneur, was accepted as early as the thirteenth century; Loysel, ii. 2. i. The feudal system was never so widely extended in Germany or Italy. 9 According to the Sachsenspiegel (i. i), God gave the temporal sword to the emperor alone ; whence it followed that kings only received their power through the emperor. This theory, however, was not Chap. XII.] FEUDAL MONARCHY. 385 right to rule from the supreme feudal lord, the king, just as the planets derive their light from the sun 10 . But they ruled, not as mere officials of the state or organs of the government, but by their own right and for their own ends,, in the same way as they held their fiefs. This combination of political rule with personal independence, and the hereditary connexion of the various grades of authority with certain families and estates, are specially characteristic of the feudal system. The king cannot re- fuse to grant authority to his vassals who have a here- ditary right to it, nor can he interfere with the exercise of that authority, nor define or limit its scope. Every circle of the administration is essentially distinct and in- dependent. Thus the unity of the State existed only in form. Any Power of the attempt to act with decision was met by insuperable diffi- culties. The greater and lesser vassals thwarted and re- stricted the central power, instead of acting as its agents. The national life was split into a variety of individual forms, and the single state was dissolved into a number of petty sovereignties. Free scope was given to the will and the inclination of individuals, especially of the magnates, but no common political action of the whole body was possible. The aristocracy alone was powerful and free : the monarchy had dignity without strength : the people found the natural development of its powers obstructed on all sides. The further the lower classes were removed from the centre, from the feudal suzerain, the more oppressive was the arbitrary authority of the intermediate lords. The two elements of the monarchical power among the Germans, the military and the judicial ban^ were now divided among the numerous lords and vassals. The executive generally accepted, and the kings, while respecting the superior dignity of the emperor, professed to derive their power immediately from God. As an old French maxim put it, 'Le roi ne tient que de Dieu et de Tepee/ Loysel, i. 2. 10 Sachsenspiegel, iii. 58. C C 386 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. [Book VI. government was far weaker and more limited than that of the Frankish kings. The whole constitution had become aristocratic, although monarchy was retained as an ornament. The kings of the Capet line had little to distinguish them from the great lords n : even the German kings were often foiled in internal affairs by the action of the princes. It was only exceptionally, when circumstances were specially favourable or dangers specially threatening, that the kings were enabled to exercise a strong central power. That this was the case in England after the Norman Conquest was due, partly to the fact that the Norman nobles saw their own security in a close alliance with the crown, and partly to the necessity of an energetic government to maintain the new dynasty on the throne. 5. Guizot has propounded the question why it is that feudalism was always hateful to the people, not only at the time of its decay, but when it was at the zenith of its power. The chief reason for this is thus stated by him : ' Feudalism was a confederation of petty sovereigns, of petty despots, unequal among themselves and bound by duties and rights to each other, but invested with arbitrary and absolute powers in their own domains, over their direct and personal subjects. ... Of all tyrannies the worst is that which' can thus count its subjects and can see from its seat the boundaries of its rule. The caprices of human will were there manifested in their intolerable variety and with irresistible promptitude. It was a system in which the in- equality of conditions was most rudely visible : wealth, power, independence, all the advantages and rights stood in imme- diate and visible contrast with misery, weakness, and servi- tude. . . . Despotism was as great as in a pure monarchy, privilege was as much developed as in an organised 11 Hugo Capet wrote to the Archbishop of Sens : ' Regali potentia in nullo abuti volentes, omnia negotia reipublicae c'onsultatione et sententia fidelium nostrornm disponimus.' Mirabeau, Essai sur le despotisme ; GEuvres, ii. p. 390. Comp. Luchaire, Histoire des Institutions Monarchiques, i. 243 ff. Chap. XII.] FEUDAL MONARCHY. 387 aristocracy, and both displayed themselves in the crudest and most offensive form. Despotism was not mitigated by the distance and elevation of a throne ; privilege was not disguised under the majesty of a great corporation. Both belonged to an individual who was always present, always alone, and always in close neighbourhood to his subjects. 12 ' This description contains some truth, but in its entirety it The system applies to France alone among mediaeval states. The feudal wholly op- system was not everywhere detested, and the attachment pref even of peasants to their lord was not rare. Also it was not essential to the system that the lords should have ' arbitrary and absolute power ' over their vassals. Where such power was exercised as was the case in France and too often in other countries it was in direct opposition to the system which established, from the summit to the base, circles of administration in which the powers were derived from above and independent. Even the serfs had fixed hereditary rights ; their duties could not be increased at the lord's will^ and their persons could only be disposed of according to. tradition and customs. The manorial law (Hofrechf) had the same fixity and sanction for the lower, as the feudal law for the higher classes 13 . But apart from the cases in which the lords exceeded their rights, there can be no doubt that the small size of the lord- ships and the difficulty of escaping from oppression, which was so close at hand, were among the worst characteristics of feudalism. 6. The Feudal State was pre-eminently a legal state (Rechts- Existence of stat\ Although the principle of the public welfare was ob- rights. scured, the various political rights were clearly limited and defined. Like private and personal rights, they could be 12 Guizot, Essais (No. v. Du caractere politique du regime fcodal], pp. 33-5- 13 This is proved by numerous local customs and judicial decisions ( Weisthiimer}. Many of these point to a defiant attitude on the part of the peasants towards their lords. C C 2 388 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. [Book VI. disposed of at will by the ordinary legal processes of sale, exchange, donation, inheritance, etc. They were protected either by judicial process or by the admitted right of private war. On the one hand, there was a definite legal organisa- tion which secured freedom to individuals and to separate corporations, but not to the nation as a whole : on the other hand, there was a continuous internal war, an ever-recurring anarchy. These, like the double face of Janus, are the two inconsistent appearances presented by the feudal state in the middle ages. B. Monarchy limited by Estates or Class Privileges. Limits on Before the close of the middle ages feudal monarchy powerf a gradually gave way to a monarchy limited by class privileges (stdndisch beschrdnkte Monarchic) which is the mediaeval pre- decessor of the modern representative monarchy. From about the year 1250 this form prevailed in most of the European states, and it lasted for three centuries until in the sixteenth it was transformed into absolute monarchy. The king or prince still derived his power from God or from his suzerain, and regarded this power as the property of himself and his dynasty. Within the range of his princely authority he felt himself to be master and endured no opposition to his will. But the range was now very limited : everywhere the prince was confronted by the rights of classes, of corporations, and of individuals, which he was bound to respect as he would have his own rights respected. The possessor of these rights was prepared to defend them, if necessary, with arms or with the more peaceful weapons of law. Legislation. The king had no legislative power by himself. The counsel and consent of the national estates (Reichsstdnde) were necessary for the edicts of the king, the approval of the provincial estates (Landstdnde) for those of the prince. Administra- The administrative power was still very slightly developed and very limited. There was no body of officials to carry Chap. XII.] MONARCHY LIMITED BY ESTATES. 389 out the will of the central government. The tenants in chief, to whom the royal rights were entrusted, exercised them within their domains as their own. The court offices were held, mostly in hereditary succession, by vassals and ministers who served their lord according to traditional forms with more show than reality. Usage and etiquette, the traditions of classes, and family spirit were far more influential than the sentiment of duty to the law and public spirit. The provincial estates, in which the nobles pre- ponderated, exercised an often oppressive control over the princely government by their complaints and remonstrances. Not infrequently they attacked the prince's ministers and called for their dismissal or their punishment. Sometimes they demanded the guardianship of the prince's person, or that their commissioners should be entrusted with a share in the government. The king was still regarded as the supreme judge, and jurisdiction, occasionally sat in person to administer justice. But the judgment was pronounced by the assessors (Sckoffen\ and the king had only to carry it out. He himself was bound by the law and could be called to account for wrong-doing. It was an old German custom that every lord possessing judicial rights should, if accused, be tried before his own representative. Thus the German king, though at the same time he was Roman Emperor and the secular head of Christendom, could, under certain circumstances, be com- pelled to appear before the Count Palatine of the Rhine, and to submit himself to the judgment of the princes. So, too, the count (Graf) might be judged by his acting magis- trate (Schultheiss). The police administration was undeveloped and usually Police, combined with the functions of the judge. There were as yet no gens d'armes, and the modern police system was non- existent. Even the military power of the prince was restricted by Military powers. the feudal laws and customs. The vassals owed only a fixed and very limited service, and this they regarded as a burden 390 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. on their land and were eager to prevent any energetic use of it. The German kings frequently experienced how difficult it was to check the defiant independence of the great dukes, and how little the fealty of the princes of the empire towards their head could be relied upon. It was possible for kings and princes to obtain a more sub- missive and useful army by employing mercenaries, and this was often done. But mercenaries had to be paid, and if the estates refused to grant any taxes for the purpose, their pay had to come out of the king's personal revenue, and this often involved him in debt and difficulties. Moreover, as these mercenaries were often foreigners, they made the prince hate- ful to the country which they held in servitude. Taxation. The king had no right to raise taxes except when the estates had first recognised their necessity and approved their levy, which an aristocratic body was by no means inclined to do. Many of the taxes were gradually made into charges upon real property, the burden of which fell mostly on the lands of the peasants, and they thus became fixed and in- variable. In this, as in the other points, it is obvious that both estates and individuals were wanting in a sense of com- mon duties to the State. CHAPTER XIII. VI. MODERN ABSOLUTE MONARCHY. THE mediaeval monarchy, , limited by privileged classes, Rise of was directly followed, not by the modern representative monarchy, but by absolute monarchy, which obtained strength from the struggle with the estates. Both the mixed German and Romance and the pure German nations of Europe had to pass through this stage before they could realise the modern form of state. Absolutism appeared first and most conspicuously in in the France and Spain. Where the German element prepon- countri derated in a nation, it was difficult for the kings to establish despotism, which conflicted with the legal principles and traditions of the Germans. Roman traditions, on the other hand, which were now revived both in theory and in practice, were altogether favourable to monarchy J . Ever since the twelfth century, when feudalism was at its zenith, the French lawyers had been striving with united energies to establish the monarchy upon the old foundations of the imperial law of Rome. The maxim of their school was that the government must be one, indivisible, and absolute, qualities which they combined under the expres- sion of a sovereign power. Starting from this point, they treated the rights of jurisdiction and government enjoyed by the feudal nobles as encroachments and abuses, inconsis- tent with the interests of king and people, and either to be swept away or to be limited as much as possible. They 1 Thierry, Recits des Temps Meroving. i. 16. 392 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. [Book VI. represented the French kings as the successors of the Roman emperors, Roman law as the one true law, the legal usages of feudalism they treated with disdain. Centuries elapsed before these theories were carried out in practice and the rule of the nobles was really broken. But the internal struggle never ceased until the feudal system with its variety of forms had been annihilated, and absolute monarchy, which had been growing stronger and stronger, arose upon its ruin. The maxim of the Roman law, quod prindpi placuit legis habet vigorem, was revived as a principle of politics in the French form, Qui veut le roi, si veut la lot*. When once unrestricted power of legislation was conceded to the king, it was easy for him to remove the obstacles which feudalism and the rights of the estates had opposed to the develop- ment of the central power, of the national spirit, and the public welfare. The judicial tribunals, inspired by the study of Roman law, and especially the Parliaments of Paris and the provinces, helped to give the victory to this tendency. Public opinion, especially in the towns, which had preserved Roman traditions and had been to some extent free from feudal influences, was favourable to the new conception. The citizens hated the lesser nobles more than they feared the king, and hoped, by weakening the former, to secure the progress of their trade and manufacture. The peasants also gained rather than lost by the increase of the royal power over their aggressors. Monarchy triumphed over feudalism, in France under Louis XI (1461-1483) 3 , in Spain under Philip II (1556- 2 Beaumanoir, ii. 57 : g ut a u confidence in it was shattered, and it gradually advanced towards ruin. Its principles were rejected by the liberal philosophy of the eighteenth century. In the person of Frederick II, this philosophy ascended the throne of a rising State, and thence proclaimed the maxim that the king is not the proprietor of the land, nor the lord of the people or State, but ' the first servant of the State V The principle of absolute monarchy was fatally weakened before the French Revolution, and was in no condition to withstand the storm. In spite of numerous fluctuations it finally perished in all the civilised states of Europe as the people became conscious of their freedom. Russia. It is only in Russia that absolute monarchy survives to our own day 8 . Religious sentiments are stronger in the East than in the West, and the immense size of the country and its comparative want of civilisation require a strong central government. The greatest reforms, such as the enfranchisement of the serfs by Alexander II, in 1858, could never have been accomplished except by the decisive will of the emperor. They would hardly have been called for by the aristocracy, and a free and cultivated burgher class does not exist as a political or social power. The lower classes are not wanting in ability to manage their own affairs in their villages and business associations, but are incapable of taking any important part in politics or legislation. a [Hegel (Geschichte der Phil. ii. 195) calls Frederick the 'philosopher- king ' (in the sense of Plato's Republic} not because, as a private person, he dabbled in Wolffian metaphysics and French philosophy, but because he made the welfare of his State a principle in his government against particular rights, &c. Cp. Hegel's Philosophy of History, Eng. trans. p. 460.] 8 The Russian laws call the Czar an ' independent and absolute sovereign/ and base his power expressly upon divine command : ' God Himself orders men to submit to his supreme authority, not only from fear of punishment, but as a religious duty.' Legislation belongs ex- clusively to the Czar, though he usually takes the advice of his Council. Sammlung der russischen Reichsgesetze (Swod), Bd. i. Sect. i. Art. I. Foelix, Revue Etrangere, iii. 700. CHAPTER XIV. VII. CONSTITUTIONAL MONARCHY. A. Its Origin and Progress. CONSTITUTIONAL monarchy is the fruit of modern times Rise of Con- but its germ is to be found, as was pointed out by Montes- Monarchy, quieu, in ' the forests of ancient Germany.' The first great but immature step towards the creation of that form of state which we now call constitutional, was taken when German princes established themselves upon Roman soil, when Roman political ideas were brought into contact with German rights. Then followed the period of feudal monarchy and of the limitation of the royal power by a strong aristocracy. The unity of the State was lost, the welfare of the people was neglected, and the king had no power proportionate to his dignity. Then the national tendency to unity revived, and the German feudal State was again illuminated and fertilised by the political principles of Rome. The people began to move at the same time, but the princes anticipated them, and seized the iron sceptre of absolute power. Classes began to struggle with each other and with the princes. As the middle ages came to an end the modern constitution of the State was close at hand. It is the end of a history of more than a thousand years, the completion of the Romano- Germanic political life, the true political civilisation of Europe. This form of State was first developed in England, where i. in Eng- land, 398 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. [Book VI. it had long been slowly but surely ripening. In no Euro- pean country did the monarchy retain so much power in the middle ages as in England, but nowhere were the rights and liberties of the nobles and the people so courageously defended and so securely founded. Kn.^iisi, B u t the English were not spared the fevers of political 1! " strife. Two great revolutions threatened the whole edifice of the State with ruin. The first, in the middle of the thirteenth century, was the attempt of the barons to take the government from the king into their own hands. This was the object of the Provisions of Oxford in 1258, which were forced upon Henry III by Simon de Montfort 1 . In the second, which arose in the seventeenth century from Charles Fs struggle with the Long Parliament, both monarchy and aristocracy were for a time swept away by the fanatical party of democratic Puritans. But on both occasions the disease did not last long enough to permanently weaken the body politic, and though the external symptoms were bad enough, it had not sufficient internal strength to give an alien direction to the national life. Both times England quickly recovered from the shock, the connexion with the past was never broken, and the national development remained organic and normal. Both revolutions resulted in distinct progress. From the first is to be dated the summoning of town representatives to par- liament, the origin of the later House of Commons. The second was completed by the foundation of the new con- stitutional monarchy in 1689, which is henceforth a national institution 2 . 1 Guizot, Essais, p. 388. [The Provisions of Oxford, which estab- lished a very temporary system of government and which had nothing directly to do with the origin of town representation, have hardly the importance which Bluntschli attributes to them. A far greater date in the history of constitutional government is the year 1399 when a revolu- tion placed the House of Lancaster upon the throne to which he makes no allusion.] 2 For a general view of the results of the Revolution of 1688, see Macaulay, History of England (Popular Edition), ii. p. 240 ; Gneist, Engl. Verf.- Gesch . 6 2 8-7 2 4. CH.XIV.] PROGRESS OF CONSTITUTIONAL MONARCHY. 399 Constitutional monarchy is a combination of all other Character- . istics of Con- forms of State. It preserves the greatest variety without stitutionai sacrificing the harmony and unity of the whole. While giving free room to the aristocracy to exercise its powers, it imposes no restraint upon the democratic tendencies of the people. In its reverence for the law we can even see an ideocratic element. But all these various tendencies are held together in their due relations by the monarchy, the living head of the State organisation. Constitutional monarchy in England has its stages of Results of development. The following belong to the time of William tion of 1688. of Orange : 1. Absolute monarchy was rejected as an unconstitutional encroachment, to which resistance was justifiable. 2. In opposition to the mystical conceptions of orthodox theologians who revered the royal rights as divine, these rights were declared to be human and limited by the con- stitution 3 , just as much as the rights of the Lords and Commons in Parliament, or the personal liberties of every Englishman. 3. The Declaration of Rights (1689) authoritatively formulated and secured the rights of Parliament and the liberties of the nation. The union of this declaration with the settlement of the succession made it impossible for the monarchy in the future to sever itself from these rights and liberties. 4. The irresponsibility of the king was declared to be a rule of the constitution, but the expulsion of the Stuarts proved clearly that exceptions could be made to the rule, if king and people came into irreconcileable collision. 5. Ministers were made responsible to Parliament, the 3 Act of Settlement, 1700, art. iv. Stattttes of the Realm, vii. 638 [quoted in Stubbs, Select Charters, 528-31]: ' Whereas the Laws of England are the birthright of the people thereof, and all the Kings and Queens, who shall ascend the Throne of this realm, ought to administer the government of the same according to the said laws, and all their officers and ministers ought to serve them respectively according to the same/ etc. 400 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. [Book VI. Commons having the right of accusing, the Lords of trying them. Other rights of Parliament were recognised, viz. : (6) to share in legislation, (7) to grant taxes and to regulate the royal household, (8) to control the executive government. (9) The judicial administration, based upon the sworn juries selected from the people, was made completely inde- pendent and its powers extended. (10) Freedom of the press and of political meetings was granted, so that public opinion could criticise and control the government. The Hanoverian kings found it difficult to understand these principles and their consequences, but circumstances were too strong for them to refuse their recognition of the free constitution. In our own day the influence of Prince Albert induced the royal family to become unreservedly constitutional, and thus the monarchy has lost neither respect nor power, while it has thrown off the prejudices of dynastic tradition, and has become a truly national monarchy ( Volkskonigthuni). The English king has realised that he does not represent his own will, but that of the State. Thus the ministers and since the English ministers are kept in power by the con- fidence of Parliament, or rather of the House of Commons the popular representatives have more influence over the government than in continental states. So far the English monarchy may be called parliamentary or republican. But the reverence for the crown is nowhere stronger than in England ; and however strong the aristocratic elements and the Parliament may be, the English constitution has re- mained a monarchy 4 . * [Bluntschli here quotes passages from Burke and Sir Robert Peel to prove the importance of the royal power. It is hardly necessary to remind English readers that our constitution is a monarchy only in the popular, and not in a scientific sense. For the real functions of the crown in England, see Bagehot, English Const, pp. 33-88.] CH.XIV.] PROGRESS OF CONSTITUTIONAL MONARCHY. 401 The second grand effort to introduce a constitutional n. France. monarchy was made by the French. The constitution of S^i? 1 " 1791 was intended by its authors to be a masterpiece directly deduced from modern political principles. But the principles of the Constituent Assembly were rather repub- lican and democratic than monarchical. Its members were influenced, not so much by the English constitution, as by Rousseau's theories of the sovereignty of the people and of the two powers, and by the constitutional democracy of America with its three powers, each independent, but held together by the unity of the sovereign people. The con- stitution of 1791 was essentially democratic: its monarchy was alien to the system, a survival from the past with which on all other points the Revolution had completely broken. Napoleon revived the monarchical power and raised the The First nation from the mire into which it had sunk. The central authority was once more concentrated in his strong hand. The Revolution was still recent, and the country required a strong dictatorship to carry it through the European war. But he was too energetic a ruler to give France a new con- stitutional monarchy, and the times were not suited to such an experiment. Yet he allowed some rude approaches to it. He recognised the people as the source of his power, and he opened to all Frenchmen the way to honour and ad- vancement. He sought to create in the Senate a new aris- tocracy which, as he said, ' should protect the sovereignty, while the democracy elevates to the sovereignty 5 .' If his dynasty had been peaceably prolonged, a national consti- tutional monarchy might in time have been founded upon these beginnings. But to Napoleon himself the political rights of the other corporations were displeasing as limita- tions upon his absolute will, and his fall involved all his institutions in the same ruin. 5 Las Casas, Mtm. iii. 32. Compare above, Book ii. ch. 10. The best description of the ideal Napoleonic state, an ideal which was never practically realised, is to be found in the Idles Napoleoniennes, written by Louis Napoleon in 1839. Dd 402 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. [Book VI. The charter The Charter of Louis XVIII (4 June, 1814) was in its essence a compromise between the old dynasty which re- turned from exile and the French people which had witnessed the Revolution and the rule of Napoleon, a compromise between the claims of the old monarchy and the new prin- ciples of government, between legitimacy and the revolution. In form it was a free gift of the king, and emanated from his exclusive authority 6 . It contained other contradictions besides this, but at the same time it was better than the previous attempts to realise a constitutional monarchy in France. While the forms of the English constitution had been apparently copied, the spirit was altogether different. Greater power was allowed to the French than to the English king, or rather, as the Charter professed to be issued by the abso- lute authority of the monarch 7 , his power was less limited. But the French monarchy was much less secure than the English, not only because the character of the people was more unstable and prone to change, but because the Revo- lution had destroyed the aristocracy and had trained the whole people in democratic opinions and tendencies. The peers (pairie\ who shared the right of legislation with the crown and formed a supreme court for political offences, were to be ' a truly national institution, uniting the recol- lections of the past with the hopes of the future, the old regime with the new/ But in reality the new nobles of Napoleon's time were put too much in the background, and the old decaying aristocracy was too generously treated. The hereditary peers were very inferior to the English House of Lords, and could never be regarded as a permanent or ' truly national institution. 7 The Chamber of Deputies was to replace 'the old assemblies of the Champs de Mars as well 6 See the preamble : ' Nous avons volontairement et par le libre exercice de notre autorite royale accorde et accordons, fait concession et octroi a nos sujets . . . de la Charte constitutionnelle qui suit.' 7 ' Bien que 1'autorite toute entiere residat en France dans la personne du Roi.' Ch.XIV.j PROGRESS OF CONSTITUTIONAL MONARCHY. 403 as the third estate of the States General.' But it was really a pure plutocracy, and was employed for the profit of the official class. The mass of the citizens, who were wealthy and civilised and had played an important part in the re- volutionary period, could neither elect nor be elected. The peasants, to whom the Revolution had given free property and even political rights, were equally excluded, while the lower classes were wholly disregarded. The demos, now a great political power in France, was not likely to support a constitution which left it entirely unrepresented. The Revolution had strengthened two conflicting ten- dencies, that towards centralisation and that towards the extension of democracy. If carried to extremes, the one led back to absolute monarchy, the other to revolutionary anarchy. The Charter sought to strengthen and control the former, and thus to restrain the latter tendency 8 . The Charter survived the first popular storm, which was Revolution roused by the absolutism of Charles X and by the revo- lutionary press. The party cry of Louis Philippe and of the July Revolution of 1830 was that ' the Charter should be a reality.' But the hereditary was replaced by a life peerage, and the basis of the Chamber of Deputies was enlarged, though it retained its plutocratic character a . Then came a second storm, of which no one had foreseen Revolution the violence, and in February, 1848, the whole constitution, though better than what followed, and though containing in itself the capability of improvement, was overthrown in 8 De Tocqueville, Democracy in America (trans, by Reeve), i. 93 : ' In the French Revolution there were two impulses in opposite directions, which must never be confounded the one was favourable to liberty, the other to despotism. . . . The Revolution declared itself the enemy of royalty and of provincial institutions at the same time ; it confounded all that had preceded it despotic power and the checks to its abuses in indiscriminate hatred, and its tendency was at once to overthrow and to centralise. This double character of the French Revolution is a fact which has been adroitly handled by the friends of absolute power.' a [The qualification for a vote was lowered from 300 to 200 francs of direct taxes. Even after this the number of electors was less than half a million, and this limited franchise was a prominent cause of the failure of the Orleanist monarchy.] D d 2 404 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. [Book VI. one day, the majority being too surprised and stupefied to resist a desperate minority. For the second time the demos sought to rule France. The representative democracy of the first Revolution was restored with a President of the Republic ; but his authority was seriously checked and limited by the National Assembly, which was divided by bitter party passions, and wasted its strength in endless debates. The popular instinct, however, turned again to monarchy, and a second Napoleon became the conqueror and the heir of the democracy. Louis Napo- leon seized upon the administration, and justified his action by the consent of the vast majority of Frenchmen. The Second The constitution of the new Empire (1852) recalled rather the Roman than the English state. In fact, the Napoleonic ideas had a distinctly Roman character, and thus commended themselves to the Romance element of the French 9 . Homage was paid to the majesty of the people as the source of all political power; the constitution was subject to its consent; the Legislative Body depended upon its approval ; even the imperial power was derived from its will 10 , and the Emperor was responsible to the popular voice. Democratic equality, so dear to the masses, was unreservedly recognised in the right of universal suffrage. Upon this broad basis the im- perial power was raised to majestic dignity. The initiative in legislation, the supreme control of politics, diplomacy, the army and the official body, were placed in the Emperor's hands. Even the members of the council of state could be dismissed at his pleasure. The constitution recognised only two great powers the majority of the people and the Em- peror. All that stood between them had the merest shadow of independence. Ministers were responsible only to the head of the State, but some of them were merely orators 9 The constitution of 1852 bore an external resemblance to the Napoleonic constitution of the year VIII (1801), but the differences were really considerable. De Parieu, Pol. p. 201. 10 Napoleon Ill's title ran : ' par la grace de Dieu et la volonte nationale Empereur des Ch.xiv.] PROGRESS OF CONSTITUTIONAL MONARCH Y. 405 employed to defend the government in the Chamber, and these men sometimes obtained an influence dangerous not only to the representatives but also to the Emperor n . The power of the Legislative Body was negative rather than positive ; it might reject but it could not improve a harmful or unjust law ; it had no initiative, and could only confer with the Council of State about proposed changes by means of commissions. The Senate was professedly created to defend popular liberties, to maintain the constitution, and in exceptional cases to take the initiative in proposing re- forms. But it was by its nature aristocratic, and its members were compelled to adhere to the Emperor, partly by the fact that they owed their dignity to him, and partly by the social and party relations of France. The chief object of the govern- ment was to maintain harmony between the Emperor and the masses, and therefore very scanty liberty was allowed to opposition either in the chambers or in the press 12 . This autocratic constitution failed to satisfy the revived desire for popular liberty. Napoleon III was compelled to make concessions in the direction of constitutional mon- archy I2a . A senatorial decree (Sept. 1869) granted to both Houses the right of initiation, allowed ministers to become members of them, and made the latter responsible to the Senate. These changes were submitted to the people, and approved in \^Q plebiscite of 1870 (20 April) by 7,350,142 votes to 1,538,825. But these concessions failed to save the constitution in Revolution the crisis which was brought about by the collapse of x 7 * Napoleon's policy and of the French army in the war with Germany. A new revolution in Paris (4 Sept. 1870) 11 De Paiieu, Pol. p. 204, who alludes to M. Rouher, but without mentioning his name. 12 In the Reveries Politiques of Louis Napoleon, which were written as early as 1832, is to be found a sketch of a French constitution, which bears the same relation to the constitution of 1852 as the ideals of youth to the ripe judgment of manhood. l2a These concessions commenced with the decrees of Jan. 19, Feb. 5, March 14 and 23, 1867. 406 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. [Book VI. abolished the Empire and again tried the experiment of a Republic *. in. RO- The changes experienced by France in the revolutionary Countries, period and afterwards exercised an important influence upon other, and especially upon the Romance, countries. In Italy the victorious arms of the French established republics on the model of their own ; and afterwards Napoleon I erected vassal kingdoms both in Italy and Spain which were copies of the French empire. It seemed as if the constitu- tion of modern Europe was to be dictated from Paris, but the fall of Napoleon's supremacy was immediately fatal to his ephemeral creations. More important in the development of constitutional monarchy, though also of only short duration, were the constitutions proclaimed in 1812 in Sicily and Spain, i. siciiy. The constitution of Sicily, which was mainly the work of Lord William Bentinck, was naturally modelled upon that of England. At the same time the aristocratic traditions of the Norman period were made use of, and the modern theory of the division of powers was more clearly recognised than in England. The legislative power was given to the Parliament, which, however, included only the two Houses without the king. The king had to confirm laws, not as a part of Parlia- ment but as a separate and external power 13 . The Chamber of Peers consisted of the Sicilian barons and prelates. The secular peers were hereditary, but the king could create new peers among nobles who possessed a net revenue of 6000 francs. The Lower House consisted of representatives, and a very small income was sufficient qualification for the suffrage or a seat. The executive power rested with the king, but his minis- ters and privy councillors were responsible to Parliament for its exercise. In all important matters the king was b [The existing French constitution was drawn up by a National Assembly in 1875 (25 Feb.). For an analysis of it see Demombynes, Les Constitutions Enropeennes (Paris, 1883), ii. pp. 1-166.] 13 Articles i, 2, and 14. A German translation of the constitution appeared in the Portfolio for 1848. CH.XIVJ PROGRESS OF CONSTITUTIONAL MONARCHY. 407 bound to consult his Privy Council, and in some, e.g. the bringing of troops into Sicily, the appointment of foreign officers, the creation of new magistracies, or the granting of pensions for political services, he had to obtain the consent of Parliament. The judicial power was exercised in the king's name, but 1 only by the officials fixed by the law.' Each Sicilian was allowed to resist any illegal restraint ; the censorship, except for theological works, was abolished \ feudal rights were suppressed, etc. It is obvious that this constitution was an imitation of English forms, with a certain admixture of the theories put forth in the French constitution of 1791. The republican element preponderated in both, but in Sicily the contrast with monarchical tradition was the more marked because the absolutist court of the Bourbons could not endure the constitution, and the quarrel between the clericals and the Jacobins was fought out with all the heat and frenzy of the southern character. When Naples was restored to the king, he felt himself strong enough to revoke the constitution which he had sworn to observe, and to restore absolute government. But this first effort to combine the political forms of England with the theories of the French Re- volution, and thus to form a new constitutional system, remained a model for many subsequent attempts in the same direction. Similar theories about the constitutional State and the 2 . Spain. division of the three powers inspired the very complete con- stitution which was issued by the Spanish Regency (March 19, 1812) at a time when the king was a prisoner, and great ' part of the country was in the hands of the French. It took as its model the French constitution of 1791, and proclaimed the principle that the people is sovereign (Art. 3), but at the same time it allowed very extensive rights to the king. Legislative power was entrusted to the ' Cortes combined with the king' (Art. 15), and the latter was also charged with the 'supervision of justice ' (Art. 171). But reiterated 408 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. [Book VI. votes on the part of the Cortes could compel the king to sanction a law. The Spanish constitution differed very essentially from the English, because it did not admit an intermediate Chamber of Peers, but placed the king face to face with one assembly of national representatives, the Cortes 14 . In spite of its defects and the want of enthusiasm with which it was received, this constitution became popular after its arbitrary abrogation by the restored king, Ferdinand VII (May 4, 1814), and several attempts were made (in 1820 and 1836) to restore it by force. The Estatuto Real vi 1834, which gave Spain a representative government, was in- sufficient to satisfy the people. In 1836 the Queen-Regent, Christina, was compelled to recognise the constitution of 1812, and in the next year the influence of the progressist party obtained the formal sanction of a new constitution based upon that of 1812, with partial modifications taken from the Estatuto Real. This recognised the king's right to sanction laws without limitation, and established two houses, a senate and a chamber of deputies 15 . A revision of the constitution in 1845 (May 23) by the moderate party (moderados) brought it nearer to the French Charter of 1830 16 . Even this did not terminate the constitutional struggles, and the country continued to be tossed alternately by clerical reaction and radical anarchy, by court intrigues and military dictatorships. The misrule of the bigoted Queen Isabella brought about a new revolution in 1868, which expelled both the Bourbons and the Jesuits. For a long time the monarchical party looked round in vain for a king, until in 1870 the duke of Aosta, second son of the Italian king Victor Emmanuel, accepted the offered crown as Amadeo I. 14 A German translation of the constitution is to be found in Politz, ii. 263 ff. ; and in Schubert, Verf. ii. 44 ff. Comp. Gervinus, Geschichte des XlX.Jahrhunderts, ii. 135 if. 15 Biilau, Europ. Verf. seit 1828, p. 221. 16 Schubert, Verf. ii. 105 ff. and 116 ff. [See also Laferriere et Batbie, Constitutions d' Europe et d'Amerique, p. 474.] Ch.XIV.] PROGRESS OF CONSTITUTIONAL MONARCHY. \^ For a time there seemed a favourable prospect for consti- tutional government, but before long the king was disgusted by the ceaseless conspiracies, and abdicated of his own accord (February n, 1873). Soon afterwards the military party seized the government, and prepared the way for the re- storation of constitutional monarchy with the young Alfonso XII, who was proclaimed king on the ist of January, 1875. Meanwhile the Bourbon claimant, Don Carlos, supported by the priests and the legitimists, had been striving to assert his hereditary rights in the northern and Basque provinces, with no result except to increase the misery of the people. In 1876 a Cortes was summoned to draw up a new con- stitution, which was approved by King Alfonso on the 3oth of June. According to this the nation was to be re- presented by a Senate, of which the members were partly senators by right, partly nominated by the king, and partly elected (Electoral Law of February 8, 1877), and by a Chamber of Deputies (Electoral Law of December 28, The Spanish constitution of 1812 was imitated in the 3- Portugal. Portuguese constitution of 1822, which, however, was never fully recognised. In 1826 Don Pedro, to strengthen the position of his daughter Donna Maria da Gloria, drew up a new constitution, which better preserved the monarchical principle, and also, following England and the French Charter, added to the Chamber of Deputies a house of hereditary and life peers. This constitution recognised four powers : (i) the legislative power, belonging to the Cortes under the sanction of the king; (2) the mediating power (moderador\ held by the king, ' as the supreme head of the nation, to maintain the balance and harmony of the other political powers ; ' (3) the executive power, in the hands of king and ministers; (4) the judicial power, entrusted to independent courts 17 . c [For an analysis of this constitution, see Demombynes, i. 398 ff.] 17 Articles u, 13, 71, 75, 118 of the Constitution of 1826. Both constitutions are given in Politz, ii. 299 ff. ; the latter in Schubert, Verf. ii. 148. [See also Laferriere et Batbie, p. 488.] 410 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. [Book VI. Even after the victory of Don Miguel and the absolutists who would have nothing to do with either constitution, two parties continued to strive with varying success, the democrats for the constitution of 1822, and the 'chartists' for the charter of 1826. In 1838 the latter constitution was revised, and hereditary peerages and the council of state were abolished 18 . The mass of the people took little part in these changes of institutions. Nevertheless, under the influence of the modern Coburg dynasty, political conditions have developed more successfully and peaceably in Portugal than in Spaing 4 . Brazil. Constitutional monarchy made its way from Portugal to Brazil, which became independent of the mother-country in 1822, and there underwent the same struggles and the same alternations of fortune, but also made the same progress, as in Europe. [The monarchy was overthrown in 1889.] 5 . Italy. It took a long struggle to free Italy from the degrading yoke of absolute rule. Although the Napoleonic kingdoms of Italy and Naples had been nothing more than limited autocracies, the absolutism of the restored Bourbon and Hapsburg princes was endured with impatience by the people. Secret conspiracies and open revolts struggled against the cruel reaction, and were only put down with the help of foreign arms. When the king of Naples agreed in 1820 to grant his subjects the Spanish constitution of 1812, Austrian troops at once stepped in to restore the old despotism. The movements between 1830 and 1840 were equally futile, as the massive power of Austria, on which the dynasties leaned for support, was always ready to suppress any attempt at constitutional government. It was only after 1840 that the spirit of reform obtained greater strength by allying itself with the national desire for freedom from foreign rule. In 1847 all Italy was roused, and the movement seemed to have the support of the new 18 Schubert, Verf.ii. 173. d [For the contemporary constitution of Portugal, see Demombynes, i. 487-] Ch.XIV.] PROGRESS OF CONSTITUTIONAL MONARCHY. 4 1 1 Pope, Pius IX. Even before the outbreak of the Revolu- tion in Paris, Ferdinand II in Naples, and Charles Albert in Piedmont, were compelled to establish constitutions. But the former hastened to destroy the work as soon as he could do so with safety, although he had sworn to maintain it ' in the name of the Holy Trinity l9 .' The result of his treachery was that, when his son Francis II was urged by necessity to restore constitutional government in 1860, the people re- fused to trust him, and the dynasty was expelled. In Piedmont matters went better. The House of Savoy adhered with rare determination to the constitution of the 4th of March, 1 848, which Charles Albert had accepted on the model of the French Charter of 1830. It is true that Charles Albert failed in his design to form a kingdom of Italy under his sceptre. The victories of Radetzky checked his ambition, and perhaps preserved the peninsula from the flood of a premature democracy. But even in this period of reaction Victor Emmanuel remained loyal to the promise of his father. His wonderful successes in 1859 and 1860 were to a great extent due to the confidence which the Italians felt in his loyalty to the constitution and the nation, and in the great statesman, Cavour, whom he appointed to manage his affairs. French assistance drove the Austrians from Lombardy, the new national kingdom extended itself over the principalities of central Italy, and the bold campaign of Garibaldi added to it Naples and Sicily. With the help of Prussia Venice was annexed in 1866, and finally, in 1870, the Franco-German war compelled the French troops to evacuate Rome, and enabled the Italians to occupy their old capital. The German victories destroyed the last eccle- siastical State of Europe. The new Italian monarchy has remained firmly constitutional, and even the republican party followed the example of Garibaldi in recognising this form of government as best suited for existing conditions. Belgium forms the transition from the Romance to the 6. Belgium. 19 Proclamation of 8 Feb. 1848, in the Portfolio, i. 64. 412 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. [Book VI. German States. The Belgian constitution of 1831 was copied from the French Charter of 1830, but makes greater concessions to the burgher democracy. This is seen in the assertion that 'all powers are derived from the people' (Art. 25 : one must remember that Belgium had no native dynasty, and was compelled to call in a foreign king), in the rejection of class distinctions (Art. 6), and in the wider suffrage. The system of two chambers is retained, but the Senate is elected only for a period of eight years, and the electors are the same as for the Chamber of Deputies, the only distinction being that a higher qualification of age and property is required for senators (the original plan was to give the nomination of senators to the king). Under the wise and statesmanlike rule of Leopold of Coburg, Belgium was very little affected by the crisis of 1848, and has since continued to increase in prosperity in spite of the passionate contests between the ultramontane and liberal parties' 20 . iv. Teutonic In Scandinavia the constitutional system has had a pe- oiusSde* culiar history. In Sweden, the Diet was composed in the f ^Sweden s i xteentn century of four estates, each with a separate vote, viz. the nobles and knights, the clergy, the citizens, and the peasants. The kings were often compelled to rely upon the two lower orders for support against the great power of the nobles, whose influence was chiefly exerted outside the Diet in the Council (comprising both the Council of State and the ministers). Gustavus III was the first to break through this preponderance of the nobles, which threatened both the existence of the crown and the security of the country, by opening (1789) political offices, except 'the highest offices of the State and the Court,' to non-nobles. The Swedish constitution of the 7th of June, i8o9 21 , is a development from the earlier constitution of 1772 22 . The 20 Theodor Juste, Gesch. der Griindung der constitutionellen Monarchic in Belgien, 1850, 2 Bde. [For fuller details of the Belgian constitution, see Demombynes, i. 236 ff., and for the complete text, Laferriere et Batbie, p. 66.] 21 Schubert, Verf. ii. 368. [Laferriere et Batbie, p. 321.] 22 Schubert, ii. 349. Ch.XIV.] PROGRESS OF CONSTITUTIONAL MONARCHY.^ functions of the Council of State and the four secretaries of State are regulated with much greater care and precision than in other modern constitutions, and the exclusive pretensions of the nobles to fill these posts are restricted. The estates remained until recent times four in number, and without their consent the king could neither change the constitution, issue laws, nor levy new taxes. As a rule a majority of three estates bound the fourth, but in the case of constitutional laws all the estates and the king must be unanimous. In many points this constitution recalls the mediaeval organisation of Germany. Although presenting many ad- vantages it has found, outside Sweden, little attention and no imitators, mainly because the division of estates made it difficult to obtain a decisive expression of the national will. In 1866 the ordinary system of two chambers superseded the four estates '. Far more democratic is the Norwegian constitution of the 2. Norway. 4th of November, 1814. The Swedish king (Charles XIII), whom the peace made king of Norway also, was compelled by circumstances to accept the constitution which the Nor- wegians themselves had drawn up in the spring of 1814, to secure their personal freedom and independence. Legisla- tion is the function of the people and exercised by the Storthing (Art. 49). The king has the right of sanction, but cannot reject a law which has been passed three times by the Assembly. The Storthing is chosen by the people (mostly landed proprietors), and then divides itself into two chambers, the Lagthing and the Odelsthing. The executive power belongs to the king, his ministers being responsible. Subsequent efforts to extend the royal power and to create a political aristocracy have all failed. The opposition of the free peasants and citizens to both changes has been the more vigorous because of the jealousy with which Norway has maintained its independence of Sweden 23 . e [Rigdagsordnung u. Riddarhusordnungvon 22 June, 1866.] 23 Schubert, Verf. ii. 404 ff. Comp. art. Norwegen in the Deutsches Statsworterbuch. [The constitution is to be found in Laferriere et Batbie, p. 372.] 414 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. [Book vi. s. Denmark. In Denmark the revolution of 1660 was directed against the nobles, and the assistance of the citizens made the monarchy absolute. It was not till the present century that constitutional government was introduced, at first in the in- complete form of provincial estates (law of 28th May, 1831), but made more democratic by the fundamental law of the 5th of June, 1849. The struggles of Danes and Germans have turned upon the difference of nationality rather than of constitution. In 1866 (28th July) a revision of v the con- stitution was made by the king and the Rigsdag (composed of two chambers, Landsthing and Folkething) f . 4 . Holland. In the modern kingdom of the Netherlands, which re- placed the old republic of the United Provinces and the later Napoleonic kingdom of Holland, constitutional mon- archy was at once introduced (28th March, 1814, and after the union of Belgium by a new law of 24th August, 1815). The new constitution of the i4th of October, 1848, was an advance in the same direction, and the constitutional spirit has been lately strengthened in Holland. v. German The old ' Roman Empire of the German people ' had be- States. The Empire. come a powerless dignity in the last century of its nominal existence. All real power was in the hands of the princes, amongst whom the emperor only retained an influential position as Archduke of Austria and King of Hungary and Bohemia. But in their own separate territories most of the princes had broken through the restraints imposed by their estates and had established absolute government. Their power, derived from imperial offices which had become hereditary, was, after mediaeval fashion, half theocratic, half patriarchal. It was extended by the Roman conception of sovereignty, and acknowledged no restraints except the slight bond of obedience to the empire and the obligation to appear before the Imperial Chamber (Reichskammergericht] and the Aulic Council (ReichshofratK). /[For the Danish Constitution, which was voted on Nov. 7, 1865, and sanctioned July 28, 1866, see Laferriere et Batbie, p. 399.] Ch.XIV.] PROGRESS OF CONSTITUTIONAL MONARCHY. 4 1 5 The first State to establish this independent absolutism Rise of was Prussia. While Austria grew into a great European power almost outside the Empire, and became the rival of France, a new State arose in the north, and rapidly acquired strength in a contest with the mediaeval empire, which was waged however in the spirit of German nationality. The Austrian and Catholic houses of rfapsburg and Lorraine rested for support upon the imperial dignity, traditional rights, the nobles, the clergy, and an army composed of various races ; while the Protestant house of Hohenzollern became the representative and the champion of the national liberty and spirit of Germany. Frederick the Great (i 740-1 786) deserves to be reverenced as the father of constitutional monarchy upon the continent. If he had been better understood by the peoples and more imitated by the princes, the transition from the absolute to the constitutional form of State would have been much easier to accomplish. No one has more energetically con- tended against the doctrine that the king is the lord and master of his State ; no one has more definitely maintained that monarchy is an office and the king only the chief servant of the State. The whole mediaeval theory of divine right and proprietary rule he unhesitatingly rejected. That he neither revived the old constitution of the estates, nor created new representative institutions, is easily explicable by the fact that he was too far ahead of his subjects, who were not yet ripe for a share in the government. But he prepared the way for constitutional monarchy : (i) by car- rying out the principle that the royal rights are duties to the State, (2) by his legislation (the Preussische Landrecht}^ and (3) by compelling all officials to discharge their political duties with zeal and fidelity. The French Revolution led Germany astray from the path marked out by Frederick, as it made the princes timid and the people radical. The constitutions which Napoleon's influence established The Con- in the States of the Confederation of the Rhine may to the Rhine. 41 6 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. [Book VI. some extent be regarded as marking the transition to con- stitutional monarchy. They cleared away the last remnants of the old estates, collected the fundamental laws into a single act, and gave a sort of representation, though despic- able and powerless, to property, industry, and education. The Con- The desperate effort of the War of Liberation freed 1815'" D Germany from the foreign yoke, and offered a favourable opportunity for introducing the modern organisation in a national and liberal spirit. The few great statesmen that the country possessed, Stein, Humboldt, and at first Har- denberg, wished for such a change, and Frederick William III had publicly expressed himself favourable to it. But the absolutist sentiments of the German dynasties and of the noble and official classes were too strong, the Revolu- tion had inspired an overwhelming mistrust of all modern ideas, and the political education of the people was still very immature. Both the German confederation and the sovereign states which composed it retained absolute government, only slightly limited by recollections of the provincial estates. The i3th article of the Act which con- stituted the confederation, declared that ' in all States of the Confederation there shall be a constitution of local estates ' (landstandische Verfassung), but the Austrian statesmen expressly provided against any interpretation of this phrase to imply a ' representative or constitutional monarchy. 7 Constitu- It was quite exceptional when a few states established 18x5. a kind of constitutional monarchy in imitation of the French monarchy, but modified by survivals of the old provincial estates. The lead was taken by the Duchy of Nassau (2 Sept. 1814), where the constitution was very short-lived, by Luxemburg (24 August, 1815), and notably by Saxe-Weimar-Eisenach, which presented the rare spec- tacle of a prince, Karl August, personally inclined to free institutions. More important was the action of the Southern States Bavaria (26 May, 1818), Baden (22 August, 1818), and Ch.xi V.] PR GRESS OF CONS TITUTIONAL MONAR CH Y. 4 1 7 Wtirtemberg (25 September, 1819) where the far-sighted government had first to put down the opposition of the old estates. These States adopted constitutional government from politic motives, in order to strengthen themselves against the greater States which were despotically ruled. Their example was followed by the Kingdom of Hanover (17 Dec. 1819), the Grand Duchy of Hesse (17 Dec. 1820), and Saxe-Meiningen (23 August, 1829). All these constitutions gave ample powers and rights to the king. Tn fact, monarchy was more secure among the conservative Germans than in France, and as long as it understood and followed the advance of liberal ideas, was allowed the management of public affairs with more con- fidence than was felt elsewhere. The arrangement of the chambers was copied from the English and French models. But the upper chambers, composed for the most part of the landed nobility (Grund- adel), whose claims and ideas belonged to the past, with the addition of a few officials dependent upon the court, could never acquire sufficient respect and authority. The lower chambers were less plutocratic than in France, but as they followed the lines of the old estates, they were often declared to be ' class rather than representative ' institu- tions. This, however, is unfair. The distinction between the mediaeval organisation of estates and the modern repre- sentative government is not that the latter does not recognise the difference of estates among the people, but that it is national, and lays stress rather upon the unity of the nation and the State than upon the special interests of the classes that compose the nation. Now this modern principle is expressly recognised, for example, in the Bavarian Consti- tution, which calls upon the deputies to swear that they will ' consult for the general welfare of the whole land with- out regard to separate estates or classes.' The development of constitutional monarchy was hin- dered for many decades by the distrust and hostility of the governments of the two great States of Germany. In E e 4i8 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. [Book VI. Prussia all efforts at reform failed, and instead of the pro- mised representation of the people, only provincial estates were granted. The Austrian Government believed that absolute government was the only means of maintaining the unity of its various provinces. The German Con- federation directed all its activity to maintain the so-called * monarchical principle,' and to establish a police supervision over the people. New move- The French Revolution of 1830 led to new movements ^830.* a in Germany, and impelled a number of States to introduce the constitutional system. The electorate of Hesse received a constitution (5 Jan. 1831) which was devised to protect popular liberties against the despotism of the prince. In Saxony a constitution was modelled upon that of Bavaria (4 Sept. 1831); and Hanover obtained a new fundamental law (26 Sept. 1833), which was, however, rejected by the next king, Ernst August, and only restored in 1840 in a modified form. Thus, in spite of the hostility of the two great States, constitutional government steadily advanced in Germany, although it was often more formal than real, and suffered much from an officious bureaucracy and from the conflicts of parties both within and without the assemblies. Prussia. At last, on the 3rd of February, 1847, Frederick William IV issued a patent creating a common Landtag for Prussia on the basis of the old provincial estates. This assembly received the right of advice in legislation, of consent to new taxes, and of petitioning about internal affairs. Thus Prussia stepped from the class of absolute to that of limited monarchies, and began to draw nearer to the representative states of Germany. The impulse had been given to the introduction of the modern system, and the constitution was the stronger for preserving the connexion with existing relations instead of simply copying the ordinary forms of constitutional government Although the rights of the Landtag were miserably insufficient, progress had become possible, and the defects of the constitution might be Ch.XIV.j PROGRESS OFCONSTITUTIONALMONARCHY. 419 removed as the people advanced in political education. Unfortunately the government was so hostile to the legiti- mate wishes of the Landtag that it lost the confidence even of the moderate parties. When Europe was shaken by the political earthquake of 1848, the new edifice collapsed. On the 5th of October, 1848, a new constitution was drawn up, which was mainly the work of the democratic and revolu- tionary party. Six months later the king issued an electoral law (30 May, 1849), which led to the drawing up of the revised constitution of the 3ist of January, 1850 24 . Since that date many important changes have been made, mostly in the direction of strengthening the central authority. Although the constitution had many and serious defects, it has furnished a legal basis for political life in Prussia. The events of the next few years proved that the spirit of the constitution had not been so generally accepted as the form. Dissatisfaction was shown by the upper house (Herrenhaus), which was composed of the representatives of absolutism and of mediaeval chivalry. The monarchy, accustomed to unchecked power, found it hard to accept its altered position. It was only gradually that the popular representatives (Haus der Abgeordneteri) became conscious of the limits of their power and of the great gulf which separated the Prussian government from the parliamentary system of England. But during the obstinate and bitter struggles between reform and reaction, between authority and liberty, the constitution took deeper and deeper root, and hostilities gradually gave way to the sense of duty towards the State. In the fire of the war of 1866 with Austria all the elements of opposition were fused into unity. Austria was also taken unawares by the Revolution of Austria. 1848. The various peoples, who had hitherto been held together by the Hapsburg dynasty, now struggled for separa- tion, and Vienna was for a moment in the hands of youthful 24 The text is to be found in Zacharia, Die detitschen Verfassungsgesetze der Gegenwart, p. 74 if. [See also Laferriere et Batbie, p. 138.] E e 2 420 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. [Book VI. and inexperienced enthusiasts. Unity disappeared every- where except in the army, the last bulwark of the monarchy. The victories of the army enabled the Austrian statesmen to recover the reins of government, and under the pressure of internal and external dangers, they undertook to recon- struct a new and more united State. The constitution which was granted on the 4th of March, 1849, was the first attempt to organise the Austrian empire upon the principles of constitutional monarchy. But the experiment was never put into practice. It seemed impossible to unite in a single assembly peoples which varied so completely both in race and in civilisation ; and the revolt of Hungary made it more essential than ever to retain a dictatorial and united govern- ment. As the ruling dynasty had always been the connect- ing link between the Austrian provinces, it was thought best to concentrate all powers over the State in the hands of the emperor. An imperial patent (20 August, 1851) declared ministers to be responsible to the sovereign alone ; by a cabinet decree of the same day the imperial council (ReichsratH) was transformed into a crown council ; and by another patent (31 Dec.) the constitution of 1849 was sup- pressed. A decree of the cabinet (31 Dec.) promised the erection in the crown lands of deliberative committees composed of the nobles, lesser landowners, and industrial classes 28 . But in reality absolute monarchy was restored with a machine-like body of officials to carry out its will, with a moral support in the Catholic clergy, and a material support in the strong army. After 1858 absolutism suffered a series of defeats in Prussia, Bavaria, Baden, Wiirtemberg, the electorate of Hesse, &c., and in the Italian war of 1859 Austria dis- covered the powerlessness of her three props, the bureau- cracy, the army, and the clergy. Again the imperial government saw no way of escaping from its financial and political difficulties except in granting a representative con- stitution. In an imperial diploma of the 2oth of October, 25 Zacharia, p. 62 ff. CkXIV. PROGRESS OFCONST1TUTIONALMONARCHY. 421 1860, this resolve was announced, and an attempt was made to carry it out in the Fundamental Law of the 26th of February, 1861. According to the diploma the powers of the monarchy were to be brought into harmony with * the consciousness of historic rights in the various kingdoms and provinces.' Each people was to have its own Landtag with partial autonomy, and at the same time all were to co-operate in the general Reichstag both in legislation and in controlling the imperial government. There were to be two Reichstags, one for the whole monarchy, the other for the western pro- vinces. This constitution, however, had only a tentative existence, as the Hungarians refused to send deputies to the Reichstag. An imperial declaration (20 Sept. 1865) suspended the action of the Reichstag and again freed the government from its control. But the disasters of 1866 brought about a new change. After the defeat of Koniggratz [or Sadowa] and the treaty of Prague with Prussia, earnest negotiations were carried on with Hungary, which steadily refused to give up its ancient rights, or to exchange them for a Con- stitution that was merely a gift from the emperor. At last they agreed to make peace on condition that the legal continuity of the Hungarian Constitution should be ac- knowledged, that the laws of 1848 and the independence of their kingdom should be preserved, and that all the encroachments that had been attempted should be declared null. This was virtually the restoration of dualism. Hence- forth there is a Reichstag and a ministry for Hungary, and another Reichstag and ministry for the Austrian provinces on this side of the Leitha. A series of laws from 1867 onwards organised the responsibility of ministers, the method of representation, the judicial and civil administra- tion. The suspended constitution, so far as it was ap- plicable, had to be revived. The two Diets appointed a joint assembly (' delegations ') which was to act with the three common ministers, viz. those of finance, war, and 422 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. [BookVi: foreign affairs, in arranging a general policy for the whole empire. It is doubtful whether this compromise will be permanent, but it is certain that neither Austria, Hungary, nor Bohemia would tolerate a return to absolutism, and that, though they may differ as to forms, they are un- animous in the desire for a constitutional monarchy which shall secure influence and control to the national repre- sentatives. Proposed The attempt to extend constitutional forms from the in- Consdtution dividual states to the German Confederation led to the drawing up of a constitution (28 March, 1849) which was to embrace all the German states except Austria. The Prussian kings were to be hereditary emperors ; each state was to be represented in a federal senate (Statenhaus), and the German people were to send deputies to a national assembly ( Volkshaus\ But the scheme was never carried out. Austria prepared for war rather than accept such a solution of the German question; the king of Prussia would not accept the imperial crown from the hands of the national assembly ; Bavaria refused its adhesion ; and the nation itself was not sufficiently decided. Dynastic and separatist influences were stronger than the sense of na- tional unity, and were able to foil all later efforts, especially those of Prussia, to unite Germany more closely under a constitutional monarchy. The war of 1866 was necessary to overcome the obstacles interposed by Austria and the ruling dynasties. North Ger- The North German Confederation (i 6 April, 1867) can federatk^n, only be called a constitutional monarchy with considerable reservations. The direction of a common policy was en- trusted to the Prussian king as hereditary President and General of the Confederation. He was aided by a Federal Chancellor, named by himself but responsible, who was the head of a Chancery for carrying out the administration. The executive power, therefore, resembles that in a con- stitutional monarchy. On the other hand, the President was checked, not only by the Reichstag, containing repre- Ch.XIV.] PROGRESS OFCONSTITUTIONALMONARCHY. 423 sentatives of the German nation, but also by the Federal Council (BundesratJi), in which the governments of the allied States had seats and votes. These two bodies exercised the legislative power and controlled the federal administration. The constitution of the German Empire (i6th April, 1871) German strengthened the monarchical element by the addition of the ^7^' imperial title. But even in the present day the Emperor has only a limited right of veto in the case of certain military and financial measures ; he has no independent and direct share in legislation ; and the Federal Council (Bundesrath) is not merely a legislative senate, but a joint ruler of the empire. To some extent, therefore, there is a collective government of the various princes and local rulers, and this is more like an aristocracy than a monarchy. The mixture of principles in the Empire, which Puffendorf declared to be monstrous two centuries ago, has not yet been fully cleared up. But in spite of peculiarities and inconsistencies the constitution of Germany has shown both force and vitality, and if monarchical power and unity, with 'the re- cognition of national rights and liberties, forms the essence of constitutional monarchy, must certainly be regarded as belonging to this class of States. Looking back over the whole subject we see that the Resume, system of representative or constitutional monarchy has obtained a most decisive predominance in Western Europe. Almost every civilised European State has recognised not only personal rights but the political rights of the nation and of the classes composing it, and has admitted national representatives to a share in legislation. Monarchy is no longer absolute and unlimited, but has become a supreme legal power (pberste Rechtsmacht) limited by the rights of the subjects. But in other points the constitutional forms are very varied. In England the monarchy is surrounded by ?, powerful aristocracy, and the actual conduct of affairs is 424 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. [Book VL dependent rather upon the majority in Parliament and the ministers who are responsible to it, than upon the in- dividual will of the sovereign. On the continent there is no aristocracy which enjoys such power and respect. There the democratic element is the most prominent after the monarchy : aristocracy has only a moderating and mediating influence. The constitutional struggles on the continent are between monarchy and democracy, which are always striving to find their proper relations to each other and to the whole State. Each contends for exclusive rule and the suppression of its rival, but the momentary defeat of either has always been followed by a sudden revival. Constitutional monarchy on the continent avowedly strives to assume an organic form which shall give its proper rights to each part of the body politic, to the monarchy its full power and majesty, to the aristocracy dignity and influence, and to the demos peace and liberty. On the continent generally, and especially in France [i. e. before 1870] and Germany, monarchy is the active head of the State, not only in form but by the whole character of the constitution. Only when it comes into conflict with national instincts, and with the great current of history, is it checked by the incalculable force of public opinion which, as a rule, is passive and stationary. Except in such a case as this, it is far stronger than aristocracy, which in Germany is willing to serve the crown for its own ends, and in France murmurs in impotence ; it is stronger even than the national represen- tatives, who can control the Government but cannot them- selves govern. In France the Bourbon monarchy relied mainly upon the wealthy burghers, Napoleon III upon the lower classes. In the separate German States monarchy looks for support partly to the army and partly to the officials, who in their turn act as the chief restraint upon the crown, while in the Empire it relies upon the support of the masses and the governments of the different States, Nowhere has an organisation been founded which shall satisfy the claims of the demos ; though numerous efforts Ch.xiv.] PROGRESS OF CONSTITUTIONAL MONARCHY. 425 have been made in this direction. When this has been accomplished, when the ruling dynasties have laid aside their mediaeval prejudices and conformed to the modern ideas, the long struggle will be over, and full security will have been given to that limited monarchy which is destined to combine the unity of the whole with the liberty of every part, and to bring into harmony the political spirit of Rome and the German sentiment of freedom. Note. The above subject, has been treated by Gustav Zimmermann in a pamphlet, which attracted great attention at the time it appeared, entitled Die Vortrefflichkeit der constitutionellen Monarchic fur England und die Unbrauchbarkeit der constitutionellen Monarchic fur die Lander des Europdischen Continents, Hannover, 1852. (The excellence of con- stitutional monarchy for England and the impossibility of its application in continental countries.) This pamphlet is the absolutist rejoinder to the more fertile radical literature on the subject. Zimmermann, like most of his opponents, derives his notion of constitutional monarchy solely from the external forms and maxims of the English constitution. He is probably quite right in maintaining that the English system is not applicable to the continent, because its contradictions and its defects, which at home are corrected and softened down by tradition and by the interests of the ruling aristocracy, would be made far worse if it were carried out in a democratic spirit. But the English system is not identical with constitutional monarchy ; it may be the greatest and, in spite of logical errors, the most successful effort to realise it, but it is not the sole perfect realisation. To say that conditions on the continent are unsuited for the English system, is not to say that they are also unsuited for constitutional monarchy, i. e. for a monarchy which recognises that its own political rights, like those of the subject classes, are fixed and limited by the constitution and that for legislation especially all parts of the body politic must work together. An organic monarchy is necessarily constitutional, because the organism itself is the constitution. Zimmermann's perpetual designation of the chief authority as the property of the prince shows that, in spite of his keen eye for details, he has no real comprehension of the modern conception of the state. The choice of this mediaeval standpoint brings him into collision with the whole current of modern life. For a time he may contrive to dam the flood, but as the waves rise he must be swept away with his frail edifice. (I leave this passage as it was written in 1857. It has been confirmed in 1866.) If there is one principle which is clearly grasped in the present day, it is that political power is a public duty as well as a public right, that it belongs to the political existence and life of the whole nation, and that it can never be regarded as the property or personal right of an individual. \ CHAPTER XV. B. False Ideas of Constitutional Monarchy. Errors : ALMOST all the civilised States of Europe have adopted the system of constitutional monarchy, hoping to find in it a means of reconciling, not only the contradiction bequeathed by the middle ages, between absolute rule on the one hand, and a weak and divided State on the other ; but also the various currents of contemporary politics, and especially those of monarchy and democracy. It is therefore of direct practical importance to discuss the foundations of this system. But it is first necessary to clear away some errors and mis- conceptions that have prevailed on the subject. i. That the The French Revolution set itself in the early years to executive realise the idea of Rousseau, that the State contains two r only> powers, the will or legislative power, and physical force or the executive power. 'The people wills, the king executes,' was considered in France to be the essential formula of con- stitutional monarchy \ 1 Rousseau, Contr. Soc. iii. I : ' Toute action libre a deux causes, qui concourent a la produire, Tune morale, savoir la volonte qui determine 1'acte, 1'autre physique, savoir la puissance qui 1'execute. . . . Le corps politique a les memes mobiles, on y distingue de meme la force et la volonte ; celle-ci sous le nom de puissance legislative, 1'autre sous le nom de puissance executive.' Mirabeau, Speech of i Sept. 1 789 : ' Deux pouvoirs sont necessaires a 1'existence et aux ibnctions du corps politique ; celui de vouloir et celui d'agir. Par le premier la societe etablit les regies qui doivent la conduire au but qu'elle se propose, et qui est in- contestablement le bien de tons. Par le second ces regies s'executent, et la force publique sert a faire triompher la societe des obstacles que cette execution pourrait rericontrer dans Topposition des volontes indi- viduelles. Chez une grande nation ces deux pouvoirs ne peuvent etre IDEAS OF CONSTITUTIONAL MONARCHY. 427 This idea sets the people in opposition to the king, and in fact suppresses monarchy altogether, as it makes the king a mere servant of the popular will, which is external to him, and formed without his having any part in it. The fall of Louis XVI, and the proclamation of a Republic by the Jacobins, were doubtless the result of historical circum- stances, but they were also the natural consequence of this principle of the constitution. If, on the other hand, the king is regarded as the equal of the legislative power, instead of being excluded from it as a subordinate, the necessary unity of the State organism is destroyed, and an impossible dyarchy 2 , a monster with two heads, is created. This must split up the State, or else must speedily give way to either the monarchical or the democratic principle. To avoid this absurdity Sieyes wishes to make the head 2. That the of the State purely passive, and regarded this as the basis of pS-liy the constitutional system. Napoleon, a born monarch if ever pas! man was, branded this proposal with indelible contempt : 4 How can you expect a man of talent and honour to resign himself to play the part of a hog which is to be fattened upon two millions? 37 A more common expression is that ' the king has the 3. That the exerces par elle-meme ; de la la necessite des representants du peuple pour Texercice de la faculte de vouloir, ou de la puissance legislative ; de la encore la necessite d'une autre espece de representants pour 1'exercice de la faculte d'agir ou de la puissance executive.' Thiers, Hist. de la Revol. Prang, i. 97 : ' "La nation veut, le roi fait," les esprits ne sortaient pas de ces elemens simples, et ils croyaient vouloir la monarchic, parce qu'ils laissaient un roi comme executeur des volontes nationales. La monarchic reelle, telle qu'elle existe meme dans les Etats libres, est la domination d'un seul, a laquelle on met des bornes au moyen du concours national. . . . Mais des 1'instant que la nation peut ordonner tout ce qu'elle veut, sans que le roi puisse s'y opposer par le veto, le roi n'est plus qu'un magistrat. C'est alors la republique avec un seul consul au lieu de plusieurs. Le gouvernement de Pologne, quoiqu'il y cut un roi, ne fut jamais (?) nomme une monarchic.' 2 The discord which is produced by this dyarchy was well understood by the democratic-republican party in France, and they took advantage of it to get rid of the monarchy altogether. a Las Casas, Mem. iv. 428 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. [Book VI. royal power right to rule and govern, but the exercise of this right by C mini$tert, belongs not to him, but to his ministers.' This relation has practically existed at certain times in several countries, and may still do so. But if it is recognised as a permanent political principle, it must lead to the abandonment of monarchy and the introduction of a republic. For if the person to whom a right is ascribed is permanently deprived of its exercise, he loses the real substance of the right, and is certain before long to lose also the empty title, which will pass to whoever has the exercise of the right. In the middle ages the vassals and tenants first exercised proprietary rights over the soil, then they obtained the use or possession, and" finally they wrested the complete and formal proprietorship from the former lords. When the Caroling Mayors of the Palace had usurped the royal power from the Merovings, they were not long in seizing the royal title as well. When once the real power of government passes from the king to his ministers, the authority of the latter becomes republican, and the monarchy is an empty form 4 . To keep a mere symbol at the head of the State, instead of a living and active individual, may be Ideocracy, but it is not Monarchy. 4. That the It is therefore absurd to maintain that in constitutional soniuSarac- monarchy the personal character of the king is a matter of important, indifference, that it does not matter whether he is dis- tinguished or a nullity, whether he is intelligent or feeble- minded, whether he is of noble character or a scamp. Constitutional monarchy tends to provide that the king shall be able not only to do as little harm, but also to do as much good as possible. It is only in this sense that his power is limited ; he is no mere puppet in the hands of his ministers. It would be a monstrous system which denied the dignity and qualities of manhood to the holder of the * The radical-democratic party in the Frankfurt Parliament of 1848 was not altogether wrong in designating ' constitutional monarchy ' as a ' sinecure ' and a ' hat without a head,' with no function except to * appoint a premier' (who will usually be opposed) and to 'rear a Chap. XV.] IDEAS OF CONSTITUTIONAL MONARCHY. 429 supreme position in the State, or which granted the smallest measure of political liberty to the possessor of the highest political rights. How would loyalty or affection towards the monarch be possible, if it was a matter of indifference whether he was worthy of such sentiments, or whether he was even capable of understanding and returning them? This principle would lead to the logical conclusion, that the most imbecile prince, as having the least insight and will of his own, would be the most constitutional monarch 5 . Could such a form of State satisfy the longing of nations for a well- adjusted and intelligent organisation ? It is customary to justify this conception by appealing to the English constitution, but in England the personality of the sovereign is not at all a matter of indifference, but the reverse 6 . The famous formula of M. Thiers, le rot regne et ne s : That the gouverne pas, is equally incorrect as a description of consti- but does not tutional monarchy. The skilful minister failed in his own & attempt to put it into practice. Louis Philippe certainly did not fall because he attempted to govern as well as to reign, and his successor, Napoleon III, won the favour of the masses precisely by undertaking the government himself. The expression reign implies the formal rights of majesty and dignity, while the word govern refers to the practical direction of the policy of the State. Both rights belong equally to the head of the State, and to refuse him the latter or (which is the same thing) to give him the form without 5 Hegel, RechtsphiL 280, went too far in maintaining that 'a monarch has nothing to do but to say yes, and to dot the i's.' He has to say no as well as yes, and to give not only the ' formal decision ' but also the really decisive word. And besides deciding, he ought to take an active initiative when necessary. J. H. Fichte, Beitrag zur Statslehre, 1 the most empty-headed regent would be in that case the ideal.* 6 Any one may be convinced by reading Brougham's Statesmen of the time of George III, that the individuality of the king has a great influ- ence upon his ministers, and that it is a mistake to suppose that the royal will is a matter of no importance. [Bluntschli forgets that George Ill's reign was an exceptional period in English history, in which the king strove, and for a time successfully, to make himself more of a real ruler than his immediate predecessors had been.] 430 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. the reality, is to destroy the monarchical power : rex est qui regit. Government (regieren) is not to be confounded with ad- ministration (uerwalteri). It is not the king's function to apply himself wholly to the petty details of the latter, nor would such conduct be for the advantage of the State. 6. That the Others, starting from the idea of the sovereignty of the king must , r ... obey the people, have asserted as the principle of constitutional monarchy that ' the king is bound to govern according to the will and the opinion of the majority of the people.' This sacrifices the monarchy to democratic ideas. The rule of the majority is democracy. But one of the great merits of monarchy lies in the fact that the king is bound to defend the rights and liberties of the minority against the encroach- ments of the majority. Monarchy would cease to exist if the king were simply a delegate and servant of the majority which really ruled the State. The democracy thus con- stituted might keep a phantom and powerless king at its head, but he would remain there only as long as his masters found it more convenient to disguise their real power 7 . 7 This was exactly what the French National Assembly of 1789 tried to do. Thiers rightly describes the assembly as ' democratique par ses idees et monarchique par ses sentiments.' History has shown how im- possible it is for such a condition to last. In France the powerless monarchy was destroyed by the omnipotent democracy (1792). CHAPTER XVI. C. The Monarchical Principle and the Conception of Constitutional Monarchy. CONSTITUTIONAL monarchy must be a real and not a phantom monarchy. The essence of Monarchy is the personification of the The essential r , ~ . .... 11T characteris- majesty and sovereignty of the State in an individual. It tics of differs from Theocracy because it attributes the right of rule to the monarch himself instead of regarding him as the representative of God who is the real ruler. It differs from Republics with a doge or president at their head, in the fact that the latter are compelled to regard themselves as the servants or delegates either of the aristocratic minority, or of the democratic majority, whereas the monarch is not the subject of these powers, but the independent holder of the Government. In a republic, political authority has a collective, in monarchy an individual, expression. The monarch is, in the supreme sense, the personality of the State (Statsperson). In this conception there are two sides, both of which must be present, if the name of monarchy is to be pre- served : I. The personal elevation of the head of the State, as the individual representative and organ of the supreme power. II. The substantial concentration in the monarch of the highest dignity and power of the State. The two poles of the prince's activity are the initiative and the sanction. I. With the first principle may be combined they allow 432 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. [Book VI. legislative (i) the checking of the monarch in legislation by the mtohrteria? representation of the other elements of the nation, and oo operation; ^ the o kijg at i O n on the part of the king to exercise his rights and duties in conjunction with his ministers. For however high the position of the other members of the body politic, the monarchy stands still higher, and by providing that the king's will shall be the will of the State and not his own personal will, the constitution only lightens his task and preserves his authority from misconception or disaster, but not But this principle is inconsistent with the idea subordinate ( x ) tnat tne rnonarch is a mere idol or form, and not a monarchy. liying be j n g . Qr (2) that the monarch is subordinate to the national repre- sentatives or to his ministers, and that he may be compelled by them to express a will other than his own, or to act in opposition to his own will. Necessary Since the supreme power belongs to his person, he must t f hTm OTarch. preserve the freedom and the rights of his personality 1 . His person does not belong to the State entirely and in all rela- tions, but it does so belong in a special degree, and more than any other person. He may be also a husband or father, the member of a Church, or perhaps a scholar or poet. But in all public affairs the will of the State ought to find expression in his individual will. In a monarchical State great value is placed upon the individual care and energy of the monarch, and it would be monstrous to ascribe to him the highest rights and then on that very ground to place him under the guardianship of others. It is not the chambers which create a law, public respect for a law is based upon the free sanction given to it by the king. The ministers do not give their authority to the king's decrees ; on the contrary, they them- selves receive their authority from the king, and serve him as the organs, though it may be the indispensable organs, 1 Guizot, Mem. ii. 237 : 'Dieu seul est souverain et personne ici-bas n'est Dieu, pas plus les peuples que les rois. Et la volonte des peuples ne suffit pas a faire des rois ; il faut que celui qui devient roi porte en lui-meme et apporte en dot, au pays qui 1'epouse, quelques-uns des caracteres naturels et independants de la royaute.' Chap. XVI.] CONSTITUTIONAL MONARCHY. 433 of his will. So far as the king is not bound by the con- stitution to the consent and co-operation of other members of the State organism, so far he is completely free to express his own personal will and to act in accordance with it. The peculiarity of constitutional as contrasted with other His relations r f i ... . with legisla- torms or monarchy, consists in the monarch being unable tureand either to legislate or, as a rule, to exercise the functions of m government by himself alone. For legislation the consent of the chambers is necessary, while in the work of government he must admit the co-operation of ministers. But constitu- tional monarchy does not transfer the centre of gravity in the government either to the chambers or to the ministers. A system in which the majority in the chambers or among the ministers could formally and necessarily determine the action of the prince, would be in contradiction with the monarchical principle, and would really be a Government of Parliament and ministers 2 . Doubtless the constitutional monarch will in practice often conform to the decisions of the chambers, or the advice of his ministers, because he will see in them the expression of the will of the State. But if he wishes to discharge his duties as king he must reserve to himself the free right of examining them from the stand- point of the national welfare. Within these limits the constitutional monarch can move with perfect freedom. It is preposterous to think of pre- venting him from expressing his own opinion. Every capable man must utter his real sentiments 3 , and though political considerations may often restrain the monarch, no 2 For the system of government by Parliament and ministers, see below, Book vii. 3 Guizot, Mem. xii. 184: ' Un trone n'est pas un fauteuil vide, auquel on a mis une clef pour que nul ne puisse etre tente de s'y asseoir. Une personne intelligente et libre, qui a ses idees, ses sentiments, ses desirs, ses volontes comme tous les autres reels et vivants, siege dans ce fauteuil. Le devoir de cette personne, car il y a des devoirs pour tous, egalement sacres pour tous, son devoir, dis-je, et la necessite de sa situation, c'est de ne gouverner que d'accord avec les grands pouvoirs publics institues par la Charte, avec leur aveu, leur adhesion, leur appui.' Ff 434 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. [Book VI. one has the right to deny him freedom of speech or to impose the necessity of falsehood upon him 4 . The monarch ought also to examine into the state of the country with his own eyes and ears ; he should inform him- self of the needs of the people, watch all the manifestations of public life, and when the general interests and welfare demand it, he should promptly take the initiative in preparing the necessary laws or measures. This is the way in which the great monarchs of former times have distinguished them- selves 5 . Constitutional monarchy also opens a great career in such matters to princes of ability, and it should be very careful not to close it. Power and II. The second principle is that the monarch must have th^Consti- the highest dignity and full power in the State. This monarch. principle is accepted even in the English constitution, which imposes more limitations upon the royal rights than have been found tolerable by most of the continental monarchies. The following conclusions are involved in this principle : i. Constitutional monarchy is not an aggregate of isolated rights, but the unity and fulness of all rights of sovereignty fi . Absolute monarchy goes further than this, in that it grants 4 See the noteworthy remarks in Stahl, Das monarchische Princip. p. 9. Luther, Tischreden (Table- Talk) : 'There is nothing more graceful or praiseworthy in a prince than to speak freely his opinion, and to do and say without fear whatever he has at heart.' How could he respect the free speech of others, if his own freedom is subject to restraint ? 5 Frederick the Great, Essai sur les Formes du Gouvernement : 'Le souverain represente 1'Etat : lui et ses peuples ne forment qu'un corps, qui ne peut etre heureux qu'autant la concorde les unit. Le prince est a la societe qu'il gouverne ce que la tete est au corps : il doit voir, penser et agir pour toute la communaute, afin de lui procurer tous les avantages dont elle est susceptible. Si Ton veut que le gouverne- ment monarchique 1'emporte sur le republicain, 1'arret du souverain est prononce : il doit etre active et integre et rassembler toutes ses forces pour fournir la carriere qui lui est ouverte. Le souverain est attache par des liens indissolubles au corps de TEtat ; par consequent il ressent par repercussion tous les maux qui affligent ses sujets, et la societe souffre egaleinent des malheurs qui touchent son souverain.' 6 Article 57 of the Final Act of Vienna (1820) correctly expressed the monarchical principle in its first paragraph, but it included all three kinds of monarchy, absolute, limited by class privileges (standisch\ and constitutional monarchy. The second paragraph was hostile to the Chap. XVI.] CONSTITUTIONAL MONARCHY. 435 to the other political corporations neither independent rights nor any necessary share in the exercise of the royal rights : it claims all rights for itself, and allows to others only grace 7 . Constitutional monarchy, on the other hand, is limited in that it recognises the rights of other corporations and the liberty of its subjects. 2. The monarch has a share in legislation which is usually decisive as regards the substance of a law, and always so as regards its form. He has the initiative and the sanction of all laws, and they are promulgated in his name. If this fundamental rule be denied, the monarchical principle is encroached upon by republican influences, the supreme authority is given to the chambers, and the king, so far as legislation is concerned, becomes their subject. In a monarchy the rights of the chambers can only be con- current and not exclusive. 3. The whole Government is concentrated in the monarch: it belongs to him as of independent right, and is exercised in his name. In a constitutional monarchy the ministers or other officials cannot govern in their own name, although at the same time the king cannot govern without their co-operation and agree- development of constitutional forms : ' The whole sovereign power must be concentrated in the head of the State, and it is only in the exercise of certain definite rights that the sovereign can be bound by the co- operation of the estates.' The subsequent growth of constitutional monarchy has made this article out of date. 7 One can see that this idea does not follow from the conception of monarchy, by comparing the expressions of Frederick the Great, him- self a somewhat absolute ruler. Antimachiavel , i : ' Le Souverain, bien loin d'etre le maitre absolu des peuples qui sont sous sa domination, n'en est que le premier magistrat.' (Elsewhere he uses the expressions, ' le premier serviteur,' or < domestique de 1'Etat.') Mirabeau, on the other hand, abandons monarchy and sets up the Republican rule of the people, when he says to princes : ' vous etes les salaries de vos sujets, et vous devez subir les conditions auxquelles vous est accorde ce salaire sous peine de le perdre' (Essai sur le Despotisme, (Euvres, ii. 279). Still more definite were the expressions about the true position of the monarch used by Frederick II, in his first audience with his ministers (i June, 1741) : ' I think that the interest of the country is also my own, that I can have no interest except that of the country. If ever the two should not agree, the welfare of the country must have the preference.' Ff 2 436 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. [Book VI. ment. All their rights and functions are derived from the royal power, and they cannot employ these rights, as in the feudal monarchy of the middle ages, for their own ends, but must use them for the State, and so as to preserve its organic unity. In relation to the ministers, as in legislation, the king has the initiative and the sanction : and while the former can and must be exercised by the ministers as well, the latter belongs to the king alone, and the ministers have only the right of free consent to the royal commands 8 . Constitutional monarchy recognises the mediaeval principle that all authority starts from above and descends to the various lower stages, that government proceeds from the centre to the circumference, and not in the reverse direction. But the mediaeval splitting-up of the Government into in- dependent fractions has been avoided in the present day. All individual organs of the State are subordinate to the monarch, not only those whose action is entirely dependent upon his will, but also the ministers whose consent is necessary before he can express the will of the State, the judges whose range of action is entirely free from his in- fluence, and even the chambers which share the legislative power with him as independent forces in the State. As the head is superior to all other members of the body, so the monarch occupies the highest place in the body politic. Constitutional monarchy is relative and not absolute ; it suits itself to different relations and needs, and varies accord- ing to national character and history. It is therefore mis- leading to derive the conception of it from the English constitution alone. The following characteristics are common to all forms of constitutional monarchy : persona power c shall be independent of both the" national representatives and of the ministers. This theory opens a comfortable back-door to the absolutism of princes, but it is fatal to the whole constitutional organisation. (In his second edition (i. 136 ff.) von Stein has completely altered his views on this point.) Chap. XVI.] CONSTITUTIONAL MONARCHY. 437 (1) The dignity and power of the monarch are regulated General charactens- by the constitution. The constitutional prince does not tics of Con- . . . stitutional stand outside or above but in the constitution. It is the Monarchy, regard for the legal organisation fixed by the constitution and binding upon the monarch which gives its name to this form of government. Whether the constitution should be written or not, is by no means a matter of indifference, but it is not essential for the conception 9 . In England, the mother-country of constitutional monarchy, there are single constitutional laws and written declarations of the national liberties, but there is no complete and systematic code of the political organisation, such as is pre- ferred in modern times and usually known as a constitution. The English laws have arisen gradually as the result of political struggles and of special needs at different periods of the history of the nation. Modern constitutions have mostly been elaborated all at once as complete and connected legal systems under the influence of some general theory of the State. Constitutional monarchy is possible in both forms. But, without contesting the importance of unwritten law, the greatest value has always been placed upon written charters and confirmations of political rights. This is in harmony with the conditions of modern life : in later times the consciousness of right has not grown up in direct connexion with custom, and it can only find the necessary security and clearness in the fixity which is given by a written document. (2) The constitutional monarch is bound to respect not only the letter of the constitution, but also the laws of the State. He can only expect and demand obedience as regulated by the constitution and the laws 10 . 9 There are some * paper constitutions,' as Frederick William IV called them in a speech from the throne, which are easily destroyed because they are merely built upon theory, without any real roots in the nation. But a^ constitution does not become a ' paper constitution ' by being formulated in writing ; on the contrary this gives greater strength and security to its provisions. 10 Compare the article Monarchic in the Deutsches Statsworterbuch. 438 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. (3) Legislative power only belongs to the king in com- bination with the representative chambers. He needs their consent as well as their counsel in order to promulgate a law. (4) The financial arrangements and the granting of taxes are also dependent upon the co-operation and consent of the representative bodies. (5) In government and administration the co-operation of the ministers is necessary. The king's ordinances, decrees, and commands are not legally binding upon a third person until the royal signature has been countersigned by a minister. (6) The responsibility of the ministers and of all other officials is indispensable. (7) The independence of jurisdiction and the exclusion of the cabinet from judicial functions is a necessary check upon the government and an important guarantee for the rights of subjects. (8) Classes and individuals must be regarded as possessing not only personal and private, but also public rights, and these are no less inviolable than the rights of the monarch. Constitutional monarchy must be understood to be the national kingship of a free nation. CHAPTER XVII. ARISTOCRACY. I. THE GREEK FORM. SPARTA. As Athens was the highest expression of ancient demo- cracy, so Sparta was among the Greeks the most marked example of aristocracy. In general the Greek character was more inclined to democratic than to aristocratic forms, and it was only in relation to foreign barbarians that they liked to consider themselves a born aristocracy. But the Dorian race, to which the Spartans belonged, preferred aristocratic forms and tendencies for their domestic institutions as well. The ideal principle of aristocracy is the rule of the nobler Origin of the . , ,. Spartan elements of the nation over the subordinate masses. The aristocracy. way in which these nobler elements are estimated and exalted varies in different states. In Laconia the ruling race was that of the Spartans, who had conquered the land with arms and had subjected the old inhabitants, the Periceci or Lacedaemonians. Rulers and subjects were divided by birth. The first conquerors organised the government so as to transmit it to successive generations of their descend- ants. Thus hereditary political rights, a characteristic of all ancient aristocracies, had a natural origin in this en- deavour to maintain acquired power, and became a funda- mental principle of the whole State. This hereditary rule of the Spartans was not modified by its exciusive- any intermixture of races. The distinction between Spartans 440 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. [Book VI. and aliens remained as strict and absolute as a difference of caste, and intermarriage was forbidden. Only very rarely and exceptionally was an alien admitted to the full rights of citizenship. The ruling race was never invigorated by the admission of new families, and the subjects were not consoled by the prospect that the best of their descendants might rise by merit to be leaders of the State. This exclusiveness appears the more strange and oppressive as the Spartans were not very careful in other points to maintain the purity of their blood. Spartan wives, whose husbands had fallen in war, were given to the embrace of Helots, that they might give birth to Spartan children. Education. But education was all the more carefully organised, and this completed the advantages of birth. The two together were intended to preserve the supremacy of the Spartans. The State was so careful to give a political and military education to its youth, that it did not scruple to sacrifice for this end the unity and the freedom of the family. No- where was individual life so subordinate to public life; nowhere was the omnipotence of the State carried to such an extreme as in Sparta. Man was regarded as existing only for the State. internal Among themselves the Spartans were possessed of equal equahty. r jgh ts . anc [ democratic equality within the aristocracy was carried so far that Lycurgus made it a basis of his constitu- tion that all Spartan families should possess equal property a . Each family had an equal lot (K\rjpos) in the division of the land, and was forbidden to alienate it. To prevent the accumulation of personal property, which might create a distinction between rich and poor, the use of gold and silver was prohibited. The Helots, who cultivated the lands of the Spartans, were not the property of individuals, but belonged, like the lands themselves, to the State ; and their payments in kind were by law equally divided. Even the a [The equality of property in Sparta is denied by Grote, History of Greece, Part ii. ch. 6. But Plato, Laws, iii. 684, certainly points to a tradition of an original equality at the time of the Dorian conquest.] Chap. XVII.] THE GREEK ARISTOCRACY. 441 Syssitia, or public meals, at which the citizens were divided into separate tables, were common and equal for all. Thus equality was much more complete and secure among the aristocratic Spartans than among the democratic Athenians. But the Spartan rule was by no means exercised in a de- institu- mocratic form, to which in fact the character both of the tlc State and of the nation was opposed. A popular assembly TheEcciesia, (KK\r)o-ia or a\ia) existed in Sparta, but the real power was in the hands of the Senate (ye/jovo-m), which usually decided all public business 1 . Their decisions were in important matters submitted to the ecdesia, but merely for acceptance or re- jection. In the latter no one could speak except the kings, the ephors and senators, and no one could vote except men of at least thirty years of age. The composition of the State was regulated by aristocratic The Senate, considerations. The 9000 heads of Spartan families were divided into 30 Oboe, which may be compared with the Roman Curice. The two royal Oboe nominated the two kings, and each of the other 28 Oboe nominated one senator, who was to some extent the peer of the kings 2 . Thus the senate was composed of thirty members, and this arrange- ment prevented the exclusive preponderance of single fami- lies, while it served the dignity and rights of the different families as a whole. The Spartans paid the greatest respect to old age, as the essential condition of wisdom. All sena- tors, except the king, must be at least sixty years old. This excessive regard for age seems to be a blot on the constitu- tion. Years bring weakness as well as wisdom : and the conduct of the state requires not only the experience of age, but also the full productive power and fresh vigour of man- hood. The election was made by the acclamations of the popular assembly, which had been previously canvassed by the candidates. By canvassing for this high dignity the old 1 The ecdesia of the Spartans had the same power and importance as the national assemblies of ancient Greece in the time of Homer. See C. Trieber, Forschungen zur spartanischen Verfassungsgeschichte, Berlin, 1871, p. 114. a Homer gives the name of acnA.es to these councillors of the king. 442 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. [Book VI. Kings and Ephors. Artificial character of the con- stitution. Its dura- bility. men expressed their conviction that they could still render good service to the State and their willingness to devote the rest of their life to its service : the acclamation of the as- sembly expressed the confidence of the people. The dura- tion of the office, which was for life, was a security against the capricious changes of popular favour, but involved the danger that it might be retained in spite of growing weak- ness and incompetence. The Spartan aristocracy was limited, partly by the king- ship, which represented in a more lofty manner the unity and dignity of the State, and partly by the democratic in- stitution of the ephors, the changing organs of the people, who controlled the official activity both of the kings and of the senate, and also exercised an extended jurisdiction in affairs of State. The Spartan constitution impresses one as a work of art. Like Plato's Republic, it gratifies the sense of external beauty and harmony, but its interior is so unnatural 3 that on the whole it repels rather than attracts. Its architecture may inspire admiration, but it offers no temptation to dwell within it. If the Athenians deserve to be blamed for having preferred the rule of the masses to a well-ordered State, the Spartans may also be accused of having sacrificed human freedom to political organisation. Their system is more distinguished, but it affords less pleasure and comfort than the Athenian : the one maintains an even balance of politi- cal capacity, the other offers at once more light and more shade : the one is too stationary, the other too mobile. In durability, the Spartan constitution had an immense advantage. Solon witnessed, without being able to prevent, the victory of tyranny over the democracy which he had established with its mixture of the aristocratic elements of birth and wealth. After the fall of the tyrants, pure demo- cracy was introduced at Athens, but it fell into obvious and 3 The Greeks did not realise this as we do, because the freedom of the individual life did not appear especially natural to them, and the Spartan constitution agreed with their ideal. Comp. Trieber, /. c. Chap. XVII.] THE GREEK ARISTOCRACY. 443 hopeless collapse before it had existed a century. On the other hand, the constitution of Lycurgus maintained the greatness of Sparta for five centuries. When Sparta did fall it was because that constitution had been violated by the accumulation of wealth, by the corruption which was thus introduced, and by the demagogic intrigues of the ephors 4 . The durable power of the constitution itself is the more astonishing when we consider that its provisions were op- posed both to human nature and to the current of events, but it may have been partly due to the ideocratic belief of the people that its founder was the favourite of Zeus, and himself a demi-god. The similar constitution of Crete, and the equally aristo- cratic constitution of Carthage, can boast of equal durability 6 . In fact, history proves that aristocracies, by making stability the essential principle of their organisation, can maintain themselves and the State much longer than democracies can preserve the rule of the demos. 4 Laurent (ii. 290) points out that the immutability of the constitution was a cause of the depopulation of Sparta. b [The constitution of Sparta is criticised by Aristotle in Pol. ii. c. 9: that of Crete in c. 10 : and that of Carthage in c. 11.] CHAPTER XVIII. II. THE ROMAN ARISTOCRACY. Comparison IN its essential character, the Roman Republic was as and Roman much an aristocracy as Sparta, but of a higher kind. The tks. Romans drew a sharp distinction between the public rights of the State and the freedom of individuals and families. They had also a conspicuous sense of the grandeur and power of the State which they were eager to increase, but they never assumed the right of shaping the individual life to suit the State. Thus they avoided that artificial and narrow exclusion of every foreign element which may have preserved the purity of national virtue among the Spartans, but at the same time made them incapable of maintaining that prominent position in the outside world to which des- tiny had called them. From the beginning the Romans were free from that rigidity of class distinctions which is found in Sparta. Classes in Rome did not stand immov- ably face to face, each paralysing the action of the other, but contributed by their struggles and varying influences to a higher development of political life. The Roman con- stitution is a work of art like the Spartan, but on the one hand it is more in conformity with human nature and the general conditions of the world, and on the other hand it is more distinguished by its wealth of forms and the grandeur of its relations. The Roman State impresses one very no- tably as an organism. Aristocratic If we consider the principal aspects of the Roman character of *,,. ^11 i i Republic we find the aristocratic character everywhere pre- THE ROMAN ARISTOCRACY. 445 vailing, although modified by monarchical and democratic the latter . J obvious in institutions. This is manifest in (i) the relations of classes; (2) the national assemblies ; (3) the senate ; (4) the magis- tracies. The Roman patricians did not. like the Spartans, derive * The - , lationsof their origin from a single race, but from the Latins and classes ; Sabines, and partially from the Etruscans, just as the English nobles combine Saxon and Norman blood. From the first this fact must have acted to prevent rigidity and despotism on the part of the patriciate. And afterwards, though all political power was for a long time in their hands, it was moderated by the organisation of the plebs with its own magistrates, and by the necessity of giving an increasing share in the government to the new plebeian aristocracy. Ultimately from the union of the old with the new aristo- cracy arose the class of optimates *, a class which was never exclusive, but which was of supreme importance in the Roman State. As long as the Republic lasted, the aristocracy retained the traditions of government and the familiarity with public affairs. It was distinguished by birth, education, wealth, power, religious and political knowledge. At the same time it never ceased to draw to itself new forces from the plebs. While it advanced to the highest power, and became first the equal and then the superior of kings, it never ceased to be in complete accord with the people from whom it had sprung. The Romans were as careful about political education as the Spartans, but they treated it as the business of the family, and not of the State. Hence came the variety and the hereditary character of political tendencies, while in Sparta everything was uniform within the aristocracy. Most of the great Roman families were, and remained, conservative; but some, for example the patrician Valerii and the plebeian Publilii and Sicinii, were inclined to liberal principles. The 1 Compare above, Book II. ch, x. p. 131, 446 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. [Book VI. Claudii, with rare exceptions, may be. compared with the English Tories. 2 . the na- Of the three Roman assemblies only the youngest, the tional assem- , , . . rr,, biies ; comitia tnbuta a , had a democratic organisation. They were ^frlbuta not originally destined to take any part in the government, but only to act as an organ of the wishes and opinions of the plebeians, and as a limit upon the excessive power of the patriciate. Later, however, they not only became a fac- tor in legislation, but usurped the whole legislative power. But even in the later years of the Republic, when the aris- tocracy was rapidly declining and monarchy was close at hand, it was only in very exceptional cases, and under the influence of some ambitious tribune, that the comitia of the tribes exercised a really decisive power. As a rule the en croachments of democracy were hindered, partly by regard for the immense authority of the senate, and partly by the tribunes themselves, as they alone could make proposals and each of them could control and obstruct the action of the other b . The ordinary function of the comitia tributa was to act as a check upon the obstinacy and excessive power of the aristocracy. Comitia The comitia curiata, which lost all their original import- ance and sank into a mere form in the later times of the Republic, were thoroughly aristocratic. They formed the assembly of the old patrician aristocracy of birth, arranged by families and curia, and the senate was originally only a committee of the heads of these families. If the plebeians [For the relation of the Tribe-assembly of the plebs (Concilium plebis tributunt] to the assemblies of the populus (comitia proper), see Mommsen, Forschungen. He distinguishes (i) the assembly of the corporation of the plebs, whose plebiscites finally acquired the force of leges by the lex Hortensia of 287 B.C. ; and (2) the assembly of the whole people (populus) by tribes (comitia tributa) , which in the fourth century B.C. began to absorb much of the business of the comitia centuriata. But as the numbers of the patricians diminished, the differ- ence between an assembly of ft& populus and of the /Mr became almost purely formal.] & [The Tribunate, which was originally merely the organ of the cor- poration of the plebs, thus became practically an instrument of senatorial government, until the Gracchi turned it to other uses.] Chap.XVUL] THE ROMAN ARISTOCRACY. 447 were ever admitted to the comitia curiata it was only in a very subordinate position. The most important of the assemblies, the comitia cen- Comitia turiata, in which the whole nation met together, was so organised as to give the most decisive preponderance to the upper classes. (a) Great weight was attached to property. The first class alone, consisting of those who paid the highest rating, contained eighty centuries, and if the eighteen centuries of the knights voted with them, they had an absolute majority of votes. The same relation of voting power to property prevailed also in the four other classes : four persons in the second class were equal to six in the third, twelve in the fourth, and twenty-four in the fifth class. The numerous proktarii and the still more numerous capite censi were all crowded into one of the 193 centuries, and had thus a very slight influence in an assembly where the aristocracy of wealth was so powerful la . (fr) Birth and nobility of profession were also considered. Thus the eighteen centuries of the knights, which were formed on these principles, were placed, as the most noble, at the head of the assembly. (c) Age too had a greater voting power than youth, for the centuries of the seniores contained by the natural laws of mortality only half as many members as those of ihejuniores, though both counted as the same. (d) If we put the classes out of sight, it is obvious that the whole external appearance of the assembly was the reverse of democratic. The taking of the auspices, the fixed military organisation of the whole body, the presidency of great magistrates, and the rule that they alone had the right of addressing and treating with the people (jus agendi cum populo\ all gave the assembly a dignified and moderate character. It was not unnatural that a Roman should look la On the constitution of the comitia centuriata compare Madvig, Verfassungund Venvaltung des romischen Stats, i. 109 ff. ; and on its later development, Ib. i. 117 ff. 448 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. [Book VI. with a certain lofty contempt upon the chaos and turbulence of a Greek ecclesia 2 . This aristocratic organisation of the nation was entrusted with the making of the real laws and with the election of the higher magistrates. 3 . The Se- The Senate was also a very important institution of the Roman state by its composition and its functions. Origin- ally consisting of the heads of the patrician families, of the prinripeS) and representing mainly the aristocracy of birth, it became later an assembly of statesmen who had proved their capacity by holding high office. The history of the senate shows us the transformation of the patrician nobility, which continued to be respected as the source of the auspices and the guardian of sacred traditions, into the later nobility of office. The great magistrates of Rome might be compared with kings, and the ancients themselves called the senate, which consisted of men who had held these magistracies, c an assembly of kings ' ; so high was the position of this political aristocracy. The censors, as the guardians of morals were entrusted with the honourable task of forming the list of senators from among the ex-magistrates and of excluding unworthy individuals. The senators sat and voted according to the rank of the office they had held, as having been consuls, censors, praetors, aediles, or quaestors. Their business was conducted with the strict formality that characterised Roman rule. It was opened with prayer and sacrifice, all its pro- ceedings were conducted by the ruling magistrates, who also 2 Cicero, pro Flacco, c. 7 : ' Nullam illi nostri sapientissimi viri vim concionis esse voluerunt ; quae scisceret plebes aut quae populus juberet, summota concione, distributis partibus, tributim et centuriatim descriptis ordinibus, classibus, setatibus, auditis auctoribus, re multos dies pro- mulgata et cognita, juberi vetarique voluerunt. Graecorum autem totae res publicae sedentis concionis temeritate administrantur. Itaque ut hanc Graeciam, quae jamdiu suis consiliis perculsa et afflicta est, omittam : ilia vetus, quae quondam opibus imperio gloria floruit, hoc uno malo concidit, libertate immoderata ac licentia concionum. Quum in theatro imperiti homines, rerum omnium rudes ignarique, con- sederant, turn bella inutilia suscipiebant ; turn seditiosos homines reipublicae praeficiebant ; turn optime meritos cives e civitate eji- ciebant.' Chap. XVIII.] THE ROMAN ARISTOCRACY. 449 brought forward proposals and took the votes ; and the deli- berations were preserved from digression or encroachment by the intervention of the tribunes or magistrates. All important state business was either prepared or decided in the senate. It provided for the worship of the gods and their festivals and sacrifices. It conducted the negotiations with foreign states and envoys, and managed all the important diplomacy of Rome. Its criticism of laws and its approval were usually decisive. In the sphere of administration its own decrees (senatusconsulta) took the place of laws. It managed all the finances, granted taxes, and determined the objects and the amount of expenditure. The levying and arrangement of troops were in its hands, as were also the granting of powers and instructions to the proconsuls and propraetors who had received provinces, and the control of the whole provincial administration. In serious crises the senate could grant to the consuls that unlimited power which seemed necessary to save the republic from harm. It may be doubted whether the Roman magistracies were 4. the magi; ...... . tracies. monarchical or aristocratic institutions, but it is certain that they were not democratic. This is obvious in the external forms that surrounded them, the purple border of the toga, the raised curule chair, the voluntary band of assessors and friends, the procession of lictors, and the connexion with the gods which is expressed in the auspices taken on appoint- ment and kept up by frequent consultations afterwards. The extensive and in itself absolute power which lay in the imperium of the magistrates was essentially royal 3 . The re- publican side of their character was visible only in the short duration of their office, and in the division of their power between two or more magistrates of equal rank. An aristo- cratic principle, which is peculiar to the Roman constitution and is very notable, is seen in the power of every magistrate to obstruct by his veto any official action of a magistrate of 3 Cicero, de Legibus, iii. 3 : ' regio imperio duo sunto.' Polyb. vi. 1 1 , 7 : ruv VITCLTOW ovaiav, TtAcuys iiovap\ucov e^atVcr' ivai Kai 450 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. equal or inferior rank 4 . This principle moderated the omni- potence of the imperium, without weakening its activity when the necessity or the advantage of the State called for its exercise. The magistrates were chosen by the whole people, but the election to the higher offices was reserved to the comitia centuriata^ in which the aristocracy of wealth preponderated, and which were managed by the magistrates and limited by the auspices. Moreover such election was as a rule open only to those who belonged to the national aristocracy, either because they belonged to a distinguished family, which gave them a famous name, a large body of clients, and popular favour, or because they had great wealth which enabled them to gain over the masses by public games at their expense, or because they had acquired reputation and influence as suc- cessful generals, or eloquent orators. After the higher magis- tracies had been opened to the plebeians, they were no longer limited to the nobles by birth ; but in all but very exceptional cases they were practically confined to that great political and social aristocracy into which the patriciate was trans- formed. Also those who had held these offices formed the senate. It must be admitted, therefore, that the Roman republic, in spite of the influence of monarchical and democratic ele- ments, was essentially an aristocracy. And it was not an aristocracy of a family, or of a class, like the numerous forms of the middle ages, but the most magnificent and powerful national aristocracy that the world has ever seen. 4 Hence the formula in Cicero, de Leg. iii. 3 : ' ni par majorve potestas prphibuisset.' It is the same principle which prevailed in the Roman private law among co-proprietors: 'neganti major potestas.' Comp. Gellius, Nodes Atticae, xiii. 12, 15. CHAPTER XIX. III. REMARKS UPON ARISTOCRACY. MONTESQUIEU a has declared moderation to be the prin- The essential ciple of aristocracy, and it is true that moderation is needed aristocracy. for its security as it is suggested by the consideration that the subject masses are superior in number and physical force. The feeling that its power has no external limits may impel a democracy to an immoderate use of that power. But aristocracy cannot easily free itself from the fear of opposi- tion and revolt, and is thus induced as a rule to keep its pre- ponderance from being too oppressive. It knows that its position is insecure without moderation, and therefore its policy is usually conservative. But this fails to express the essential principle of aristo- cracy, which is rather to be found in the moral and intel- lectual superiority of the ruling class. It is no true aristocracy unless the best (ol apio-rot) really rule \ Aristocracy loses all real vitality when the ruling class degenerates from the quali- ties which raised it to power, when its character decays, and it becomes weak and vain. It perishes equally, even though a [e L? Esprit des Lois, iii. ch. 4.] 1 Montesquieu's assertion that virtue is the principle of democracy [ibid. iii. ch. 3] is not nearly so correct as Aristotle's dictum (Pol. iv. 8, 7. 1294 a. 10) : ' The characteristic of aristocracy is virtue, that of democracy freedom.' But historical reality has little in common with the ideal of philosophers. De Parieu, Polit. p. 36 : ' L'aristocratie a toujours en fait designe le gouvernement des plus puissants plutot que celui des plus vertueux.' This work of De Parieu contains many excellent remarks upon aristocracy. G g 2 452 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. [Book VI. its great qualities remain, when the subject classes attain to equal distinction, and the old aristocracy is too negligent or too disdainful to complete and strengthen its own forces by their admission. The Roman aristocracy obtained its great- ness, and the English aristocracy has preserved its influence and respect, because both remained in living union with the life of the people, and constantly derived new vigour by re- cruiting themselves from the classes below them, its exclusive- Exclusiveness is the cardinal fault of every aristocracy. ness is often . ' fatal. The privileges of the ruling class are founded upon its qualities, but in the endeavour to secure the former by the strong defence of hereditary succession, it has often lost sight of the latter altogether. Such a limited aristocracy may maintain itself upon a small scale, but when its relations are extended it becomes unequal to the task. Sparta and Venice became weak when they had made great conquests. Neither the Spartans proper nor the Venetian nobili were numerous or strong enough to rule extensive territories, and the rest of the people, excluded from political life and in- fluence, could give but feeble assistance 2 . So, too, the aristocracy of Berne was ruined, not so much by the internal degeneration of the patriciate, as because it failed to recruit itself from the distinguished men of the city and country, various All aristocracy is based upon the distinction of quality, aristocracy, but the particular quality chosen depends upon the peculiar character and condition of the people. If it is birth, as in so many of the mediaeval aristocracies, we have an aristo- cracy of family, a noblesse ( Geschlecter- oder Adelsaristokratie\ in which the rights of families or of classes have a great influence upon the constitution. The preference of culture and education forms an aristocracy of priests or of scholars. If age is regarded as the qualification for rule, we have an aristocracy of elders (Aldermdnner) or senators ; if military distinction, an aristocracy of knights ; if property, either in land or moveables, an aristocracy of landowners or capitalists, 2 See Machiavelli, Discorsi> i. 6. Chap. XIX.] REMARKS UPON ARISTOCRACY. 453 or in other words a plutocracy, which Cicero declares to be the most hateful of all forms of state 3 . The aristocracy of optimates has a party character, because it combines a num- ber of families and persons. An aristocracy of office may be regarded as founded upon political motives, especially while it remains an elective aristocracy, but less so when, as happened in the middle ages, it gradually becomes here- ditary, and thus turns into an aristocracy of birth, or noblesse. Not infrequently several qualities are combined to form an aristocracy, and this is stronger than one which is based upon a single quality, because the latter has to face the hostility of all classes and persons who have other natural claims to aris- tocratic position. Aristocracy is eager to make its advantages conspicuous, General and therefore to display the external grandeur and dignity of tics? ct< the State. It may dispense with the affection, but never (^External with the respect of its subjects, and it seeks to impress them by an imposing display of external pomp, which gives dis- tinction to political forms and also strengthens authority. This is a marked advantage of aristocracy over democracy, because the latter may too easily degrade both their magis- trates and the State itself to the level of common life. But the advantage also involves a danger that the ruling (2) Harsh- classes may over-estimate themselves and may pay too little ne care and attention to their subjects. Aristocracies have often displayed towards the lower classes a harshness and cruelty which have been the more intolerable because accompanied by contempt. Convincing evidence of this is to be seen in the treatment of the Helots by the Spartans, the oppression of plebeian debtors by the Roman patricians, the sufferings of Irish cottiers at the hands of English landlords, and the greedy despotism exercised by English governors over the Hindus of India and the negroes of Jamaica 4 . 3 Cicero, de Rep. i. 34 : ' nee ulla deformior species est civitatis quam ilia in qua opulentissimi optimi putantur.' Comp. Leo, Naturlehre des Stats, p. 89 ff. 4 Comp. De Tocqueville on the English aristocracy, (Euvres, t. viii. 454 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. [Book VI. (^Excessive As democracy as a rule is too fickle and changeable, so aristocracy rushes into the opposite fault of excessive fixity and obstinacy. Democracy, conscious that its power is un^ limited, easily forgets the conditions of its maintenance. Aristocracy, full of anxiety to maintain itself, often falls into the error of thinking that the best way to accomplish this is to hold fast to the old system and to rigidly exclude every change. As a matter of fact aristocracies have shown more capacity for a policy of conservatism than democracies, and their existence has always been longer. They avoid rash political experiments, they advance by cautious and measured steps, and it is only when threatened by real danger that they display decisive energy and copy for a time the charac- teristics of monarchy. Within limits this is a good quality and springs from the natural instinct of self-preservation ; but if carried beyond those limits it becomes a fatal error. ( 4 ) Excessive This conservative spirit shows itself also in the natural ^wditary tendency to make heredity the fundamental principle of its institutions. In the middle ages, when the whole of Europe was impressed with an aristocratic character, this tendency was especially conspicuous. Even the Empire, although originally founded upon the idea of monarchy, became essentially an aristocracy after the fall of the Hohenstaufen 5 . 5 This was well known to the Frenchman Bodin, but since then many German historians have found it convenient to forget it. Bodin, de Rep. ii : ' Et quoniam plerique imperium Germanorum monarchiam es?e et sentiunt et affirmant, eripiendus est hie error. . . . Neminem autem esse arbitror, qui cum animadverterit, trecentos circiter principes Ger- manorum ac legatos civitatum ad conventus coire, qui ea, qnae disci- mus, jura majestatis habeant, aristocratiam esse dubitet. Leges enim turn imperatori, turn singulis principibus ac civitatibus, cum etiam de bello ac pace decernendi, vectigalia ac tributa imperandi, denique judices imperialis curiae dandi jus habent. . . . Sceptra quidem, regale solium, pretiosissimae vestes, coronae, antecessio, subsequentibus Chiis- tianis regibus, imaginem regiae majestatis habent, rem non habent. Et certe quodam modo jure omnibus ornamentis ac honoribus cumulari mereatur : sed ea est aristocratiae bene constitutae ratio, ut quo plus honoris eo minus imperil tribuatur ; et qui plus imperio possunt, minus honoris adipiscantur, ut omnium optime Veneti in republica constituenda decreverunt. Quae cum ita stnt, quis dubitet, rempublicam Germanorum aristocratiam esse?' Philipp Chemnitz (Dissert, de ratione status in imperio nostro Rom. Germ., 1640) based his schemes of reform upon Chap. XIX.] REMARKS UPON ARISTOCRACY. 455 The imperial dignity itself did not become hereditary, but was filled up by the choice of the hereditary electors. But the Emperor, in spite of his dignified position, had very little power. Before deciding any important matters he had to consult the Diet. The electoral college prepared all laws and had the first vote in the Diet. The second vote belonged to the other princes, who had contrived to trans- form what were originally offices of State into hereditary sovereignties. After the princes came the college of the imperial cities, but in these the government was usually held by a patrician oligarchy, so that their representation was really aristocratic. The government was exercised by the Emperor and Diet conjointly : the central authority was everywhere hindered and obstructed by the feudal independence of the landowning nobles. In all the politi- cal and legal relations of the middle ages, the aristocratic inclination to hereditary succession is visible. It regulated everything ; fiefs, imperial offices and dignities ; all grades of jurisdiction, whether of counts, bailiffs, territorial lords, or even the local assessors ; knighthood and court service ; rank and office in towns and villages, and the manorial holdings of the peasants. Modern times, on the other hand, have shown a decided aversion to heredity as a political principle. Both tendencies contain an element of truth, but both are wrong if carried to excess. In our own day it is right to struggle against the restraints which rigid heredity imposes upon modern development and the satisfaction of new needs ; it is right to claim the free recognition of individual worth, and to insist that political offices, which demand personal ability and subordination to the whole, shall not be subject to the idea that Germany was an aristocracy. Comp. Perthes, Das deutsche Statsleben vor der Revolution, 1845, 246. Puffendorf called the Empire a mongrel compound of monarchy and aristocracy, but recog- nised the prevailing tendency to aristocracy. [Nobody now denies that the Empire after the fall of the Hohenstaufen was an aristocracy with an ornamental monarch. The same arguments might have convinced Bluntschli that the English monarchy is equally ornamental.] 456 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. [Book VI. hereditary rules or treated as the property of particular families. But it is wrong to break off the connexion which hereditary succession maintains between the present and the past : it is wrong to introduce loose and frequent change where the stability of tradition is needed, or to alter, without need, conditions which may serve as strong pillars of the State, and which may transmit to the future great moral interests and forces. To do this is to build upon the sand : it involves a breach of the organic nature both of nation and State, for their life does not vary with each generation, but is prolonged in unbroken course from century to century 6 . (s) Devotion Aristocracy sets itself to preserve external order as the to law. 6 In aristocratic England the importance of political heredity is still fully comprehended. See the expressions of Burke in his Reflections on the Revolution in France (Clarendon Press Series, p. 38): 'You will observe, that from Magna Charta to the Declaration of Right, it has been the uniform policy of our constitution to claim and assert our liberties, as an entailed inheritance derived to us from our forefathers, and to be transmitted to our posterity; as an estate especially belonging to the people of this kingdom without any reference whatever to any other more general or prior right. . . . We have an inheritable crown ; an inheritable peerage ; and an house of commons and a people in- heriting privileges, franchises, and liberties, from a long line of an- cestors. ... A spirit of innovation is generally the result of a selfish temper and confined views. People will not look forward to posterity, who never look backward to their ancestors. Besides, the people of England well know, that the idea of an inheritance furnishes a sure principle of conservation, and a sure principle of transmission ; without at all excluding a principle of improvement. It leaves acquisition free ; but it secures what it acquires. . . . Our political system is placed in a just correspondence and symmetry with the order of the world, and with the mode of existence decreed to a permanent body composed of transitory parts ; wherein, by the disposition of a stupendous wisdom, moulding together the great mysterious incorporation of the human race, the whole, at one time, is never old, or middle-aged, or young, but in a condition of perpetual decay, fall, renovation, and progression. Thus, by preserving the method of nature in the conduct of the state, in what we improve, we are never wholly new ; in what we retain, we are never wholly obsolete. ... In this choice of inheritance we have given to our frame of polity the image of a relation in blood ; binding up the constitution of our country with our dearest domestic ties ; adopting our fundamental laws into the bosom of our family affections ; keeping inseparable, and cherishing with the warmth of all their combined and mutually reflected charities, our state, our hearths, our sepulchres, and our altars.' Chap. XIX.] REMARKS UPON ARISTOCRACY. 457 security for its own maintenance. The same motive urges upon it the protection of law and the careful observance of legal forms. Except when its passions have been aroused by danger to its existence, aristocracy is entitled to boast that it has shown more justice than democracy in its treat- ment both of its subjects and of its own members. It is no accidental circumstance that the greatest development of the science of law was the work of an eminently aristocratic nation, the Romans. Equal recognition has been given to the strict but impartial justice of the Venetians, to the wise law of Berne, and to the strong sense of law which charac- terises the aristocratic English. In the middle ages policy itself took the external form of a legal judgment and its execution. Contemporary opinion is so unfavourable to aristocracy Decline of as a form of State, that no example has survived the middle ar of the nineteenth century. The aristocracy of ancient Rome was first broken by the rise of democracy and then crushed by the Empire. The mediaeval aristocracies of Italy and Germany were humbled by the growing power of the princes, and ultimately destroyed by the hostility of the burgher class. In the modern State, therefore, the aristo- cratic classes, as a distinct part of the nation, assume an intermediate and not a sovereign position. Everywhere they are subordinate either to monarchy or democracy, and though they may moderate the one and ennoble or restrain the other, they can no longer claim as their right the government of the State. CHAPTER XX. DEMOCRATIC FORMS OF THE STATE. I. DIRECT DEMOCRACY (ANCIENT). Difference THERE is a great difference between the ancient idea of wicieirtand democracy (^//wwfporwj, the rule of the demos, of the free and democracy, equal citizens) and that of modern times. Among the ancients men started from the State and sought to secure the liberty of all by dividing political rule equally among all. Now they start from individual liberty, and strive to give away as little of it as they can to the State, to obey as little as possible. The old democracy, whether absolute or modified in form, was always direct ; modern democracy is as a rule representative. It is obvious that the former can only exist in a small state, while the latter is also applicable to a great nation with extended territories. Democracy Th e Greeks, split up into a number of little states, sought in Greece. and found in democracy the satisfaction of their political tastes. It is undeniable that something democratic is to be found even in the old monarchies and so-called aristocracies of Greece, which distinguishes them from modern monarchy or from the Roman aristocracy. It is also notable that the greatest Greek philosophers, while unfavourable in their judgment of the absolute democracy of Athens 1 , took a 1 On this point Xenophon, Plato, and Aristotle are all agreed. DIRECT DEMOCRACY. 459 moderate democracy as their ideal, and gave to it the name of polity or constitutional government (TroAire/a) in a special sense a . Democracy found its most logical expression in Athens, The Athe- i 11 1-11 -i nian consti and its nature can nowhere be better studied than in the tution. Athenian constitution. In no other state was the rule of the people so extensive ; almost all important business was brought before the ecdesia^ which met so frequently, often once a week, that it would be inconceivable if we did not remember that ordinary and professional labour was carried on not by the free citizens but by the numerous slaves. The ecdesia was the visible representation of the many- The **// headed demos. It contained all citizens over twenty years of age, unless they had become liable to any loss of civic rights. In it the Athenians felt themselves to be the lords of the state, each individual to be a part of the sovereign whole. The characteristic mark of democracy is that the majority shall rule and that every citizen shall have a share in the governing power, and this was here fully developed. Every citizen had a free right of speech, and the privileges of age, which existed in the times of Solon, were soon swept away with all other restrictions as burden- some. An orator had free scope for his eloquence, and a [Only Aristotle uses iro\iTia in this sense. Cp. Eth. Nic. viii. 10, i ; Pol. iii. 7) 3 ; iv. c. 7 and 8. But this iroXtrcia is not his ideal state, but only the 'best average state.' See Pol. iv. c. I and 2. Plato in the Republic places democracy below oligarchy, but in the Politicus, 302, 303, he reverses their positions and distinguishes two kinds of democracy, a good and a bad. It is to this ' good ' kind that Aristotle gives the name of Polity. In discussing the Solon ian constitution (Pol. ii. 12) Aristotle distinguished 77 Trdrpios drjfjLOKparia, which may be con- sidered ' a good mixed constitution,' from the extreme democracy of later times. Plato, in the Politicus, 293, separates the ideal State from all the five or six ordinary forms of government. Whether one, few, or many rule is unimportant in comparison with the question, whether those who rule have the science of ruling or not. But since he thinks this science of ruling is more likely to be found in one or the few than in the many, he generally speaks of the ideal State as kingship or aris- tocracy (as in the Rep?). Aristotle on the other hand vindicates the political capacity of the many (Pol. iii. 15, 7, 8).] 460 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. [Book VI. could often exercise a magical influence over the crowd, It was fortunate when great statesmen, like Pericles, could support their opinions by oratory. More often men's minds were carried away by adroit and ambitious demagogues, who ruled the mob by exciting its passions. There is nothing in the modern state which at all corresponds to this influence of oratory, which moved its assembled hearers far more strongly than the press can move its scattered readers. The orator's voice and gestures added meaning and em- phasis to his words, and the approval of the crowd as it listened in the consciousness of power gave a mighty impulse to the debate. In our own day parliamentary speeches have much less influence, partly because our assemblies are smaller and more select, and partly because their power is more limited. its powers ; The powers of the ecdesia embraced the whole life of the State. Solon had limited them to the election of magis- trates, the control of the government, and advice about laws, but the demos, led by its orators, soon overstepped these limits. The decisions of the people (^i^iVpora) were as decisive as those of an absolute despot ; like him the demos could command what it pleased, even though con- trary to the law 2 . Legislation properly belonged to the nomotheta, but their decisions were practically determined by the debates and votes of the ecdesia, of which they were only a numerous committee elected in each particular case. The assembly itself decided all the important affairs of government. It appointed ambassadors and determined their instructions ; it heard the envoys of foreign states, decided on peace or war, chose the generals, and fixed both the pay of the soldiers and the conduct of military opera- tions. In its hands lay the fate of conquered towns and countries, the acceptance of new gods, the regulation of religious festivals and new priesthoods, the granting of the rights and privileges of citizenship. It received once 2 Comp. Aristot. Pol. iv. 4, 25, 29, 1292 a. 6, 24. Chap. XX.] DIRECT DEMOCRA CY. 461 in each prytany (35 or 36 days) a financial report of the State revenue and expenditure ; it levied taxes, fixed the tax paid by aliens (/UT'- of Athens. It is still visible in some of the mountain cantons of Switzerland, where every year the Landsgemeinde meets, and by the raising of hands distributes the offices and dignities of the little republic, usually to the most respected families, and gives its sanction to the laws which have been prepared by the councils. These simple demo- cracies, little touched by the stream of European life, deserve our respect for their five hundred years of a history that is rich in manly episodes and rarely stained by acts of violence, for the simplicity of their customs and the peace- ful and happy existence of their inhabitants. But in recent times they have been affected by the tendency to introduce the representative forms which prevail in the other Swiss cantons and in the United States of America. The French movements of 1793 and 1848 aimed at a representative constitution, and in the present day it is the ideal of demo- cratic parties everywhere. The modern form of democracy may be declared to be representative democracy. As constitutional monarchy originated in England, so re- x. Repre- presentative democracy, or the modern form of Republic, as democracy the Americans prefer to call it, was developed in North America! 8 " America. It is noteworthy that the two chief forms 9f the 470 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. [Book vi. modern State owe their origin to the political genius of the Anglo-Saxon race. Causes of its Several causes combined to start and develope a new democratic constitution in America. It was only partially due to the extension of a territory which required hard toil . before it could be made fit for cultivation. Earlier history had shown that extensive territories were not favourable to democracy; they had usually been colonised by great monarchies, and the colonists were kept in strict subjec- tion. In South America new settlements had been founded and huge tracts of land had been occupied and made pro- ductive by a numerous population, but it was long before that part of the continent possessed a democracy. The real cause is to be found, not in the soil, but in the char- acter of the men ; but at the same time it may be allowed that the extent of territory gave freedom and security for development, while the hard struggle with nature created a spirit of manly courage and self-reliance. New Eng- The English colonists brought from their old home the love of self-government, liberty, and legality. In the new world they also found freedom from the oppression of feudal and aristocratic institutions. From the first com- plete equality prevailed among the planters. The Puritans, who settled in New England, belonged to the English middle class. Their religious belief was opposed to any ecclesiastical hierarchy ; they wished to share in the com- mon priesthood of Christians, and regarded each other as brothers. They sought the other side of the Atlantic to escape the persecutions of the episcopal Church and of the State which maintained it, to preserve their religious and their political freedom. Their ideas were at once theocratic and democratic. They did not rebel against the monarchical and parliamentary constitution of England, but they wanted to free themselves from the immediate oppression of the Government. The first agreement of the ' Pilgrim Fathers/ which all signed on their landing at Plymouth, throws light on the origin of North American democracy. ' In the Chap. XXII.] REPRESENTATIVE DEMOCRACY. 471 name of God, amen ; we, whose names are underwritten, the loyal subjects of our dread sovereign King James, having undertaken, for the glory of God, and the advancement of the Christian faith, and honour of our king and country, a voyage to plant the first colony in the northern parts of Virginia, do, by these presents, solemnly and mutually, in the presence of God and of one another, covenant and combine ourselves together into a civil body politic, for our better ordering and preservation, and furtherance of the ends aforesaid ; and by virtue hereof to enact, constitute, and frame, such just and equal laws, ordinances, acts, con- stitutions, and offices, from time to time, as shall be thought most convenient for the general good of the colony. Unto which we promise all due submission and obedience/ Similar proceedings were taken by the first emigrants to Rhode Island, Newhaven, Connecticut and Providence. Thus these communities, which formed the New England group of colonies, with Massachusetts at their head, adopted a form of government which appeared as the joint work of free men. Wholly different from this were the conditions of the Virginia, southern group, which was at first called Virginia, until the name was afterwards confined to the most important of the colonies. There the episcopal Church, with its aristocratic constitution, found ready recognition. Although most of the planters belonged to the middle class, the settlement was directed rather by economic than by religious interests, and moreover several members of the aristocracy held large estates there. Later the population was recruited by the arrival of numerous adventurers, and of the criminals and vagabonds who were transported by the London police. Still, even in Virginia, it was found impossible to trans- Carolina, plant the aristocratic constitution of England, and the notable attempt which was made by Locke at Shaftesbury's request to draw 7 up a similar constitution for Carolina (1669) was a complete failure. The colonists had no wish to become tenants of the proprietaries, landgraves and caciques 472 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. [Book VI. (barons), when they might be free proprietors elsewhere, and in 1693 Locke's constitution was abolished. Both in the northern and southern colonies the planters, prevented by the great distances from meeting in person, instituted representative assemblies composed of freely elected depu- ties, which exercised the autonomy of the colony and controlled the administration. The germs of the institu- tion may be traced as far back as 1619, and it was soon adopted in all the colonies. New York There was a stronger intermixture of foreign elements syivania. in the central group, of which New York, originally New Amsterdam, and Pennsylvania were the most prominent. But there too, the influence of the English race led to the adoption of the same constitution in essentials. The points in which all the colonies were alike, may be thus enumerated : Common (a) English law without either landlords or feudal elements of r ' i_ i i i r i the colonial tenure : free property in the soil was the basis of the constitu- tions, economic system. (b) Essential equality of position and rights, and the absence of any aristocracy like that which still held power in England. This equality was, however, broken by marked differences of race. The Red Indians, the original inha- bitants of the country, were not placed on a level with the white men, nor admitted to share in the government of the community ; but they had special rights and laws of their own. Far lower was the position of the Negroes, the descendants of imported slaves from Africa. They were usually the property of the white planters, but in the excep- tional cases when they obtained freedom they were never admitted to the political rights of citizens. (f) The constant habit of self-reliance in contrast to State-aid. This is visible at the time of the first settle- ment, when the neighbours helped each other to build block-houses. (d) The general education of the people by means of national schools. These were founded very early by the Chap.XXIL] REPRESENTATIVE DEMOCRACY. 473 villages for their own youth, and in many colonies at- tendance was made compulsory. (e) A free constitution of the villages, and independent administration of the counties. (/) The small number of officials. Of these the most important was the governor of a whole colony, who was elected by the planters in the chartered colonies, nominated by the proprietors in the proprietary, and by the English Government in the crown colonies. Next to him came the presiding judges. Both had to act in co-operation with representatives of the citizens, the governor with his coun- cillors, the judge with the jurors. The justices of the peace, who were nominated in England by the king from among the gentry, were in America always free tillers of the soil. (g) Hardly any standing troops, their place being taken by the militia. (h) The existence of a House of Representatives, elected in each colony by the free men, which acted with the Senate in making laws, but by itself granted taxes and controlled the administration. (/") The custom of short tenure of offices, so as to provide for frequent changes. (k) Lastly, the gradual development of a free press and freedom of combination. On these foundations an independent representative con- stitution, at first encouraged by the Crown, was built up in each colony long before the separation from England. When the declaration of independence (1776) broke off the con- nection with the English king and Parliament, the new republics were at once complete. The Federal constitution of the Union (1787) was only The Union. the logical application of these provincial institutions on a grand scale to the collective State then formed. The new form of State was imitated by the French in 2 . France. the constitutions of 1793 and 1795, and again in 1848 and 1870, but without permanent success. The political ideas of 'liberty, equality, fraternity,' were adopted with pas- 474 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. [Book VI. sionate devotion by the French ; but their traditions were monarchical, and their customs very slightly republican. They have always been inclined to call in State aid rather than to help themselves, to prefer the glory and power of the State to legality or the unassuming labour of consti- tutional life. The French tendency to centralisation has always been more in favour of monarchy than of a re- public a . *, switzer- On the other hand, the representative democracy of America found a soil ready prepared for it in Switzerland, to which it was transplanted by French intervention. In Switzerland the greater cantons were aristocratically governed ; some, as Bern, Fribourg, Soleure, and Luzern, by a hereditary class of patricians, others, as Zurich, Basel, and Schaffhausen, by the exclusive corporation of burghers. But communal liberty had been retained as the basis of the cantonal organisation, and the Republic, the political ideal of the people, had a deep root in the popular character and customs. There were no standing troops and no per- manent officials. The independence of Switzerland had been won in a struggle with princes and nobles. It was therefore nothing unnatural when, in harmony with modern theories, civil liberties were extended to all classes and to the whole country, and the aristocratic privileges of the patricians and burghers were abolished. This completed the change from an aristocratic to a representative re- public \ The attempt of 1798 to form the whole of Switzerland into a united representative democracy was not permanent. The traditions of independence in the older cantons and the elements of internal opposition were too strong to admit a [A Republic has been established in France ever since 1870, and the prospect of a royalist restoration seems now to be almost hopeless.] 1 Act of Mediation, 1 803, xx. 3 : * II n'y a plus en Suisse ni pays sujets, ni privileges de lieux, de naissance, de personnes ou de families.' See Bluntschli, Schweizerisches Bundesrecht, i. 474. Federal Const, of 1848 and 1874, art - 4'- ' I n Switzerland there are no subjects, and no privileges of place, of birth, of family, or of person.' Chap. XXII.] REPRESENTATIVE DEMOCRACY. 475 of submission to the Helvetic Republic, which was soon dissolved. But in many cantons, and especially in the towns and the new cantons, representative forms were retained, in spite of the partial reaction in favour of aris- tocratic privileges which followed 1814. The reforming movements after 1830 gave freer expression to the repre- sentative form, and in 1848 it was applied to the Con- federation *. Modern democracy is essentially different from the old 4- Differ- Greek form. The Persian Otanes (in Herodotus, III. 82) ancient and enumerates five characteristics of ancient democracy: (i) democracy. the equality of all rights (la-ovo^ia) ; (2) the rejection of arbitrary power like that exercised by the oriental despots ; (3) the appointment to offices by lot ; (4) the responsibility of officials ; (5) common deliberation and decision in the popular assembly. Three of these are admitted in the modern State, in constitutional monarchy as well as in the republics ; but the other two, appointment by lot and the popular assembly, are rejected. The ancient democracy admitted all citizens equally to a share in the government; the modern democracy intro- duces an aristocratic distinction in the election of the best men as representatives, and is thus a nobler form of demo- cracy. The right of sovereignty is ascribed to the whole body of citizens, to the people, but the exercise of that right is entrusted to the most eminent men, to the repre- sentatives of the people. The citizens still take a direct part in public affairs in the following points : (a) In the voting on constitutional laws. In Switzerland the principle has been generally recognised since 1830, that constitutional laws require the consent of a majority of the citizens, not reckoning those who abstain from voting 2 . In b [For the Swiss Constitution of 1848, see Laferriere et Batbie, des Constitutions d" Europe et d Amerique (Paris, 1869), pp. 84-102.] 2 Const, of Zurich, 1831, 93: ' If the proposal (of a constitutional change which has been twice discussed by the Grand Council) is 476 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. [Book VI. the United States, on the other hand, the vote is entrusted, not to the whole people, but to a numerous assembly of representatives specially selected for the purpose (Con- vention). (b) Sometimes in the voting on other laws. In this case the popular decision takes either the positive form of sanc- tion (referendum] so that the acceptance of the citizens gives validity to a law, or the negative form of a veto which en- ables the citizens to reject a law after it has been carried by the representative chambers. In the latter case the number of those voting against the law must exceed half of the whole body of citizens ; while in the former case a simple majority of those voting is decisive. Both forms are bor- rowed from pure democracy, and as they may easily give rise to agitation among the masses, they involve danger to the interests of civilisation and culture. They were first adopted by some of the separate democracies of Switzer- land, and in 1874 were introduced into the Confederation 3 . (c) In the election of members of the legislative body. These elections are usually based upon the mathematical principle of equal electoral districts and the counting of heads, but occasionally upon organic divisions, e. g. the communes. The representation is therefore usually incom- plete, and is determined too much by party tendencies. This defect is by no means inherent in or confined to representative democracy; it is equally manifest in con- stitutional monarchy. The so\e- The regular exercise of the supreme power is usually en- reignty in representa- trusted to large assemblies, which are chosen as the most tive demo- r . crades. perfect and complete representation of the sovereign people. accepted, it must be submitted to the whole body of citizens for their acceptance or rejection.' Federal Const, of 1848 and 1874, art. 6 : ' The Federation undertakes to guarantee the cantonal constitutions, provided that they have been accepted by the people and can be revised if an absolute majority of the citizens demands it.' 3 Federal Const, of 1874, art - 89: ' Federal laws or decisions binding the whole Confederation, which are not of urgent importance, are to be submitted for the acceptance or rejection of the people, if this is de- manded by 30,000 qualified Swiss citizens or by eight cantons. 5 Chap. XXII.] REPRESENTA TIVE DEMOCRA CY. 477 In Switzerland during the middle ages, the Grand Coun- cils of the towns, and the Landrdthe of the rural cantons, were only extensions of the real Councils, in which authority was concentrated, by the addition of committees of other members of the canton for important business, and in the towns for legislation as well. In the present day the Grand Councils are separated from the government, raised above it, and exalted to be the authorised holders of the sove- reignty 4 . The federal assembly (Bundesversammlung), which consists of two councils, occupies a similar position with regard to the federal government 5 . In North America both the National Congress and the legislative bodies of the separate States are composed of two chambers, and are still more distinctly separated from the government. In government 'the people have no longer any direct share, Theadminis- even in those states which have kept pure democracy for power, legislative purposes. Everywhere the work of government is entrusted to authorised representatives who carry it on in the people's name. In some states the choice of the head of the government is made directly by the people. For in- stance, the governors of most of the American states and the town councillors of Geneva are elected by the whole body of citizens 6 . The President of the United States is chosen 4 Const, of Zurich, 1831, 38 : ' The exercise of the supreme power in accordance with the constitution is entrusted to a Grand Council. It has in its hands the making of laws and the superintendence of the local administration. It represents the canton in its external relations/ Cherbuliez, De la Democratic en Suisse, ii. pp. 35 ff. 5 Federal Const, of 1848, 60 : ' The supreme power in the Con- federation is to be exercised by the Federal Assembly, which consists of two parts, the National Council (NationalratJi] and the Council of Estates (Standeratti}? Federal Const, of 1874, art. 71 : ' With reserva- tion of the rights of the people and of the cantons, the supreme power in the Confederation is to be exercised by the Federal Assembly.' 6 So in the French Constitution of 1848, art. 43 : ' Le peuple Frangais delegue le pouvoir executif a un citoyen qui re9oit le titre de President de la Republique/ [Bluntschli apparently meant to refer to art. 46 of the constitution : ' Le President est nomine, au scrutin secret et a la majorite absolue des votants, par le suffrage direct de tous les electeurs des departements Fran9ais et d'Algerie/ Laferriere et Batbie, p. cxxxviii.] 478 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. Book VI. by electors, who in their turn have been chosen by the pri- mary electors. In others, on the other hand, the choice is in the hands of the legislative body, which thus represents the people in appointing to the chief offices. The latter system prevails in most of the Swiss republics, where the Grand Council appoints both the government and the chief judges, in France, and in a few of the American states. Under the first system the government is obviously more independent and powerful, especially in relation to the chambers, because it can claim to be equally representative of the people, and to have received still greater proofs of the public confidence. Under the latter the government is more dependent on the legislature to which it owes its existence \ and therefore there is less possibility of making each power limit and restrain the other c . jurisdiction. Jurisdiction is also exercised in the name of the people, but the judges, who require special qualities and training, are usually nominated either by the government, as in the United States and republican France, or by the legislature, as in Switzerland. But a direct share in jurisdiction is given to the people by the jury system, as the jurors are selected by lot from among the whole body of citizens. Local admi- In every representative democracy the communal con- stitution is of especial importance, and forms the solid foundation of the whole organisation. In the communes the burghers are trained in public affairs, in self-government, and civil freedom. In them, at least in the smaller and rural communes, it is still possible for all the citizens to meet in the communal assembly, though in the towns this is also formed by representation. The republics of Switzer- land and North America can both trace their foundation c [The important difference between these two ways of electing the head of the executive government is well illustrated in the French Con- stitution of 1848. M. Grevy proposed that the President should be elected by the National Assembly, but it was decided that he should be chosen by universal suffrage. The result was to create two equal powers, the President and the Assembly, without any means of settling a dispute between them. This state of things enabled Napoleon III to establish the Second Empire.] Chap. XXII.] REPRESENTATIVE DEMOCRACY. 479 historically to a free communal constitution ; and if this is not true of France, it only furnishes another proof that the French have no natural tendency to a republican government. Leaving on one side the very slight direct share of the people in their own sovereignty, we see that in representa- tive democracy the rule is that the people governs through its officials, while it legislates and controls the administration through its representatives. On this point the modern con- stitution shows a marked resemblance to those states which draw a distinction between the rulers and the ruled. CHAPTER XXIII. IV. CONSIDERATION OF REPRESENTATIVE DEMOCRACY. MONTESQUIEU declared the principle of democracy to be virtue. But virtue, as a political principle, presupposes, not the equality of all, but a respect for the moral worth of the rulers, which is not to be found in pure democracy. All that we can say is that a certain measure of virtue in the mass of the people is an indispensable practical necessity for a good democracy, and that the want of it must involve speedy ruin. It may rather be maintained that virtue has been made the political principle of representative demo- cracy, which is not only a more moderate but also a nobler form of democracy, because in the system of election it borrows some of the advantages of aristocracy. Difficulty of Its principle is that the best men of the nation govern in bes^re^-e- * the name and by the commission of the nation. But the ves ' great difficulty lies in organising the elections so as to secure that the best men both in intellect and character shall be chosen. The democratic tendencies of the present day are in favour of regulating elections simply by the number of electors. Democracy, placing, as it does, great value upon equality, readily adopts mathematical rules for its institu- tions ; it counts the citizens, and assigns equal rights to an equal number. Danger of But this system is better suited to direct democracy, quantity 2 which extends the exercise of power to all citizens alike, quality. tnan to representative democracy, which distinguishes citi- zens according to their worth, and only entrusts the ad- REPRESENTATIVE DEMOCRACY. 481 ministration of public affairs to the better among them. Thus the latter form regards the quality of the elected, and it is unnatural that it should regulate the electoral divisions simply by quantity. Moreover the defects of the system are far more harmful in the representative state. The popular assembly of a direct democracy is not merely a mass of individuals with equal rights ; it is readily in- fluenced by the magistrates, by the great orators, and the most respected citizens ; the decision of the majority will probably correspond to the true character of the whole nation. But in a representative democracy the nation is not thus united ; on the contrary, it is divided into a number of scattered units, which may be equal in number, but which in regard to quality stand in a wholly different relation to the whole, and are therefore very unequal parts of the nation. Is it possible to maintain that the rural dis- tricts of Brittany or the manufacturing districts of Lyons at all resemble the electoral divisions of Paris, where one finds mixed together without real union the wealthiest and most educated members of the community, the numerous grades of simple burghers and artisans, and a low rabble such as cannot be paralleled elsewhere in France ? This difference in the electoral districts demands logically that a different value shall be placed upon their votes. True representation can only be secured by arranging the elections so that every element and every interest in the nation shall be represented in proportion to its relation to the whole. Number has a cer- tain value, but it is not sufficient by itself. Other qualities, such as property, education, occupation, and mode of life, must also be regarded ; and it is best to do this in con- nexion with organic parts of the nation rather than with merely arbitrary subdivisions. We may thus lay down two fundamental principles for Practical representative democracy. (i) Whenever the whole body of citizens act together, or when a vote is given by the whole nation, it is enough to reckon merely the number of votes, as in a direct democracy. i i 482 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. [Book VI. (2) On the other hand, the mere counting of votes is insufficient when parts of the nation are electing repre- sentatives for the whole. The parts must be arranged according to quality, so as to guarantee the election of the best men, and to give due proportion to the intel- lectual, moral, and material elements of the nation. Advantages The peculiarity of representative democracy is that it van\age ad of ascribes the right of sovereignty to the majority, but tiTede- ta ~ entrusts its exercise to the minority. To secure that the mocracy. minority shall rule according to the wishes of the majority, the latter reserves to itself the choice of those who are to act in its name, and new elections are held at short intervals of time. This constitution recognises that the majority has neither the leisure nor the ability actually to exercise the self- government which it claims as its natural right. But it credits the majority with sufficient intelligence and interest in the State to take part in the elections, and to find the ablest men for its representatives. It demands less from the citizens than direct democracy, but more from the representatives. It relies upon the self- confidence of free and equal citizens, but at the same time it trusts that they will be modest enough to elect their best men, and to submit willingly to the rule of their representa- tives as long as these retain the confidence of the majority. weakness of The frequent elections make the rulers dependent upon the ruled, and yet the latter have to obey during the in- terval. The freedom of the subjects is more securely founded than the authority of the government. The chief magistrates are regarded rather as the servants than as the heads of the republic. Although, according to Guizot, a state can only be ruled from above and not from below, representative democracy tries to maintain as much as possible the appearance of being ruled from below. Thus the government comes to resemble a mere administration , and the State is like a commune on a grand scale or a great economic institution ( Wirthschaft}. Chap. XXIII.] REPRESENTATIVE DEMOCRACY. 483 The weakness of authority shows itself least in the legis- lative bodies; in fact there is a danger that the represen- tatives may identify themselves altogether with the nation and may be carried away by the illusions of omnipotence. The government, on the other hand, has great difficulty in making its authority really strong and vigorous. The frequency of elections makes its position insecure and dependent upon the changeable opinions of the people. It is only powerful as long as it is supported by the majority, and it can only carry out extensive and far-reaching plans, when these are in accordance with the instincts or tra- ditions of the nation, and thus contain a security for their permanence. The organs of government have an unassuming and civic Want of appearance. There is none of the pomp and majesty with ?pSentra- which monarchy and aristocracy are surrounded ; the soil is tl( too natural for the artificial forms of court diplomacy ; de- mocracy prefers to be represented by simple charges d'affaires or consuls. A great standing army would be a constant menace to its security and its freedom, and it has to main- tain a large militia and Landwehr. The concentration of all forces is less developed than the independent decision and free movement of every part. The institutions for the public service are usually good, Excellence and sometimes excellent. In a democracy one expects to Institutions. find numerous establishments for useful and charitable purposes, good roads and means of communication, numer- ous national schools, cheerful festivals, etc., and moreover one is less plagued with bureaucracy and red-tape. On the other hand, there is more difficulty than in other Neglect of constitutions to induce the State to attend to the loftier cu interests of art and science. A democratic nation must have reached a very high stage of civilisation when it seeks to satisfy needs of which the ordinary intelligence cannot appreciate the value or the importance to the national welfare. The manly consciousness of freedom, which creates and Elevation I i 2 484 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. of public finds expression in the constitution, elevates the middle classes who form its chief support; while the direct or indirect contact with public affairs developes the intelli- gence and strengthens the character of the citizens. There is a wide foundation and free play for patriotism, and in times of crisis the citizens are willing to make great sacri- fices for their country. To aristocratic dispositions the constitution offers less opportunity for development, and the people often display mistrust or hostility towards them. But even they can earn respect, if they will refrain from wounding the feeling of equality by haughty pretensions, and if they enter into rivalry with the best of the democrats in zeal and devotion for the public good. Note. Robert v. Mohl {Encydopadie, p. 346) has contested the assertion made above, that in a representative democracy the principle of number ought not to be absolutely decisive. He says : ' However true it may be in general that the right of taking part in an election ought not to be regarded as a personal right of the individual, but rather as a delegated function or office, yet this does not apply to the exercise of the sovereignty of the people by representation. The sovereignty of the people is based upon the innate right of the indi- vidual to a share in the government.' I allow that this is the view of the modern democratic theory, especially as it was formulated by Rousseau. But the result is that it has never emerged from the con- fusion of personal with public rights, and its so-called social state is only the patrimonial state reversed. The error is obvious to every one who has grasped the distinction between the unity of the nation and the aggregate of the citizens. An elector derives his right to vote, not from nature, but from the State. Every system of election is an insti- tution of the State for public ends. [On the subject of this chapter, see Mill, Representative Government^ CHAPTER XXIV. COMPOSITE FORMS OF STATE. HITHERTO we have considered only simple States. But Various States are also composite^ when they consist of parts which composite are also States or are organised like States. In them the States - differences between the simple forms are repeated, and so far there is nothing specially notable about them. For example, both the collective and the separate States, or the chief State and its dependencies, may be organised as monarchies or as representative democracies. But it may happen that the collective and the separate States have different constitutions. The German Con- federation of 1815 remained an oligarchy of sovereign princes, without popular representation, while constitutional monarchy was gradually introduced in the individual States composing it. Some of the Swiss Cantons are still direct democracies, whereas the Federation is a representative democracy. England possesses a constitutional monarchy, but the English dependencies in Asia are absolutely ruled, and some of the colonies elsewhere are half-sovereign republics under British suzerainty and protection. Where there are great differences in nationality, civili- zation, and historical conditions, a difference of constitution is natural and justifiable; but where these conditions are the same, as in the German Confederation, such a differ- ence is contrary both to nature and harmony. 486 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. [Book VI. In all composite States we meet with a new distinction (Gegensatz\ viz. that between the power of the collective or chief State, and the independence of the separate States or dependencies. With regard to this point we may make the following subdivisions : i. Theabso- i. A chief State ruling absolutely over subject depen- dencies. To this class belong many possessions of the one state over others. urO p ean powers, especially in Asia and Africa. The chief State alone has a free organisation, the dependencies are unfree and subject to foreign rule. The opposition between the States is very marked, and all the energy of the ruling State is needed to avoid a conflict 1 . 2. Thesuze- 2. The suzerainty of one State over vassal States, or the protectorate protectorate of a strong State over less powerful dependen- over n others! cies. Here a certain amount of independence is possible for the vassal or protected States. The Holy Roman Empire is a mediaeval, and the Turkish Empire a modern example of a body politic composed of vassal States. In modern times the protectorate is preferred to suzerainty, although the former has no meaning except when there is a great disproportion of power, and can never commend itself to a free nation. Examples of it may be seen in Napoleon's protectorate over the Confederation of the Rhine, in that of England over the Ionian Islands % and that of the European powers over Moldavia and Wallachia*. 3 . The rule 3. Closely related with the above, but modified and mother. ennobled by filial loyalty, are the relations between the country over ., , . , 1-1 i colonies. mother-country and its colonies, which are not yet inde- pendent, but have almost developed into complete States. 1 See Mill, Representative Government, ch. 17. a [This protectorate was voluntarily abandoned by England in 1863 on the accession of Prince George of Denmark to the throne of Greece as George I.] b [This protectorate was established in 1856 by the Treaty of Paris. In 1858 the six powers concluded a Convention with the Porte to settle the government of the two provinces. In the next year the provinces effected their own union by electing the same prince, and have since become the state of Roumania.] Chap. XXIV.] COMPOSITE FORMS OF STATE. 487 Even after the internal administration of the colony has become substantially independent, it continues to need the protection of the mother-country in its external relations, and is therefore willing to acknowledge a relative superi- ority. The first example of this was seen in the relations of Canada with England. 4. In a Confederation (Statenbunf) or Personal Union : the connected States have usually their full dignity and inde- Personal pendence, although these may be restricted in exceptional cases when common interests require it. The separate States have a complete organisation, but the combination is undeveloped and has no personality of its own except in special, and mostly external, relations. It is rather a con- glomeration of States than a real State, as it wants the necessary organs for legislation, government, and jurisdic- tion. It stands halfway between a permanent international alliance and a constituted State, and is therefore an incom- plete and transitional form. In this form there may be a common people, but there is no real united nation, and the collective life and power are developed with great difficulty. This last defect is less con- spicuous in a Personal Union, which at least possesses a single head in the common monarch, than in a Confedera- tion, which has no united organ whatever. Both forms are completely unfitted for action. The German Confeder- ation of 1815 is the best example of such a system in modern times, and the most eloquent witness to its defects. 5. A Federation (Bundesstat), Federal Empire (Bundes- s- Fede- retch) and Real Union 3 , have this in common, that both the Federal collective (Gesammtstat) and the particular States (Einzel- a nd P Reai staten) have a complete organisation. In a Federation the Umon - particular States are more independent, because each has a government exclusively belonging to itself; whereas, in a Real Union, the head of the collective State is also a 2 See above, Book IV. ch. iii. p. 271. 3 See above, Book IV. ch. iii. p. 272. 488 THE FORMS OF THE STATE. [Book VI. territorial prince in his own territories (Kronlander), and these are therefore less sovereign c . In a Federation and a Federal Empire there is an organised nation, and at the same time the peoples of the particular States also possess organic unity. Thus we speak of Americans, and also of Pennsylvanians and Virginians ; of a Swiss nation, and of Bernese and Genevese ; of Germans, and of Prussians, Saxons, Bavarians, etc. The collective State is as free in its movements and as well provided with organs as the simple State. But the separate States are not at all vassals : within their sphere they are as indepen- dent as simple States 4 . Necessary The co-existence of two kinds of States on the same conditions of . , , x ..... composite territory is rendered possible by (i) a precise distinction between the powers of each, and by making provision for the peaceable settlement of disputes ; and (2) by keeping the governments and the representative bodies as separate and as independent as possible. This separation of persons and functions is most complete in the United States ; the distinction of powers is very carefully regulated in the Swiss constitution 5 . In the German Empire the organs of the c [Bluntschli seems here to confuse independence in relation to the head of the collective State, with independence in relation to the collective State itself.] 4 G. Waitz, Grundziige der Politik, p. 44 : ' Both powers, that of the Confederation and that of the separate States, must be independent (sovereign) in their own sphere : neither must receive delegated power from the other.' Since 1871 numerous publications have appeared about the nature of Federations in general, and especially about the legal constitution of the German Empire, but as yet no satisfactory solution of the difficult problem has been offered. The view in the text, which was originated by De Tocqueville and developed by Waitz, is opposed to the essence of sovereignty as the highest power in the State and therefore indivisible both in respect of sphere and objects. See Seydel, Zeitschrift fur Statswissenschaft, xxviii. 185 ff. Laband, Statsrecht, i. 70 (also in Marquardsen, Handbuch des b'ffentlichen Rechts, Part II, p. 15 ff.). Jellinek, Lehre von den Statenverbindungen, pp. i6ff. and 2530. * See Riittimann (Das nordamerikanische Bundesstaatsrecht ver- ghchen m. den fiolitischen Einrichtungen der Schweiz, 2 Thl., Zurich) on the means which the Swiss Federation has at its disposal to enforce the federal laws. Chap. XXIV.] COMPOSITE FORMS OF STATE. 489 Federal Government are closely connected with those of the separate States, although the Prussian king, as Emperor, assumes the position of a single head of the Federation, and although the Diet is completely distinct from the Chambers of the separate States. The respective powers of the Federation and its members are not at all clearly dis- tinguished, in fact they have been purposely left indeter- minate. But there is ample security for the independence of the separate governments, and for the prevention or speedy settlement of disputes, in the regulations, that an imperial law always overrides a provincial law, and that the consent of the Federal Council is necessary for every imperial law. It is usual to consider that the collective State busies itself with external affairs as a rule, and with a few internal matters of common importance as an exception ; while the independence of the separate States applies to internal administration, and only very exceptionally to external relations. BOOK VII. SOVEREIGNTY AND ITS ORGANS. PUBLIC SERVICE AND PUBLIC OFFICES. CHAPTER I. THE CONCEPTION OF SOVEREIGNTY. THE State is the embodiment and personification of the national power. This power, considered in its highest dignity and greatest force, is called Sovereignty. The name Sovereignty arose first in France, and the con- The term ception was first developed by French science. Bodin made reignty.' it a fundamental conception of Public Law. Since then the word and the notion have exercised great influence on the development of modern constitutions and on the whole politics of modern times. In the middle ages the expression Sovereignty (suprema potestas, supremitas] was used in a still wider sense. Every authority which gave a final decision, so that there was no appeal to a higher authority, was called sovereign. The highest courts of justice were called cours souveraines. Thus a State contained a great number of sovereign offices and corporations. Gradually, however, the name ceased to be given to mere branches of administration, and came to be limited to the one highest ruling power in the State, and the conception was applied only to the concentrated power of the State. From the sixteenth century the notion was entirely domi- Conception nated by the centralising tendencies of French politics and reignty in the efforts of the French kings to obtain absolute power, sovereignty 494 SOVEREIGNTY AND ITS ORGANS. [Book VII. as absolute Bodin declared sovereignty to be the absolute and perpetual power of a State (puissance absolue et perpetuelle (Tune re'publique} : and this sense prevailed. Louis XIV and the Jacobins of the Convention of 1793 alike regarded them- selves as omnipotent 1 . Both were wrong. Modern re- presentative government knows nothing of absolute power, and there is no such thing upon earth as absolute inde- pendence. Neither political freedom, nor the right of the other organs and elements of the State, are compatible with such unlimited sovereignty, and wherever men have attempted to exercise it, their presumption has been con- demned by history. Even the State as a whole is not almighty, for it is limited externally by the rights of other States, and internally by its own nature and by the rights of its individual members 2 . German The German language has no completely equivalent sovereignty expression. The word Obergewalt (superior power), or, as the old Swiss expression ran, * die hochste und grosste Geivalt* '(the highest and greatest power), signifies authority only on its inner side, and not independence externally. The word Statshoheit signifies the dignity (majestas) rather than the power of the State. Statsgewalt implies power rather than dignity. We are therefore compelled, in order to express what is implied in Sovereignty, to use both words, Statshoheit und Statsgewalt. At the same time the German expressions have this advantage that they are less liable than the French to be misunderstood as if they implied absolute power. 1 Thiers, Hist, de la Revol. franf. ii. p. 200, says that in the opinion of the Jacobins, * The nation can never renounce the power of doing and willing at all times that which it pleases : this power constitutes its omnipotence (sa toute-puissance], and this is inalienable. Thus the nation could not bind itself to Louis XIV.' The Abbe Sieyes recognised the error in this theory. Cp. Bluntschli, Gesch. d. Statsw. p. 326. 2 Hanoverian Declaration of 1814, in Hormayr, Lebensbilder, i. p. in : ' The rights of sovereignty do not imply any idea of despotism. The King of Great Britain is undeniably just as much sovereign as any prince in Europe, and the liberties of his people establish his throne, instead of overthrowing it.' 3 Blumer, Rechtsgesch. der Schweizer Demokratien, ii. 140, 141. Chap. I.] THE CONCEPTION OF SOVEREIGNTY. 495 Sovereignty implies : Charactem- 1. Independence of the authority of any other State. Yet Sovereignty. this independence must be understood as only relative. International law, which binds all States together, no more contradicts the Sovereignty of States than constitutional law, which limits the exercise of public authority within. Even the separate States (Lander staten) in a composite State may be regarded as sovereign, although dependent in essential matters, e. g. foreign policy and control of the army. 2. Supreme public dignity what the Romans called majestas. 3. Plenitude of public power, as opposed to mere par- ticular powers. Sovereignty is not a sum of particular isolated rights, but is a general or common right : ' it is a ' central conception,' and is as important in Public as that of property is in Private Law. 4. Further, it is the highest in the State. Thus there can be no political power above it. The French Seigneurs of the middle ages ceased to be sovereign when they were compelled to submit in all essential matters to the king as their feudal lord. The German Electors were able to maintain sovereignty in their own dominions from the four- teenth century *, because they exercised supreme authority in them as their proper right 4 . 5. Unity, a necessary condition in every organism 5 . The division of sovereignty paralyses and dissolves a State, and is therefore incompatible with its healthy existence. [The superior authority of the Electors, as compared with that of the other German princes, was based upon the Golden Bull, issued by Charles IV in 1356.] 4 The draft of the Treaty of Westphalia (1648) in saying 'que tous les princes et Estats seront maintenus dans tous les autres droits de souverainetl, qui leur appartiennent,' used an expression which was new to Germany, souverainete instead of Landtshokeit y evidently with the intention of relaxing the bonds of the Empire. But as a matter of fact most of the German princes were already almost ' sovereign.' 5 Imman. Herrm. Fichte, Beitrdge zur Statslehre, 1848, goes too far in declaring that sovereignty is only the 'unity of the government' (Einheit der Regierung}. Complete power and majesty form the essence of sovereignty. 496 SOVEREIGNTY AND ITS ORGANS. Notes. I. Rousseau, whose theories were translated into fact by the French Revolution, based Sovereignty on the ( general will' (la volonte generate}, and thus made the mistake of substituting suprema vohmtas for suprema potestas. He then argued that since 'power may be trans- ferred but not will' (Contr. Soc. ii. i), Sovereignty is inalienable a conclusion belied by history. He understands Law [Bluntschli says das Kecht, but Rousseau, ii. 6, says la toi, holding that 'dans 1'etat civil tons les droits sont fixes par la loi '] as the product and not as the limitation of arbitrary will. In 'Will' he forgets 'Ought'; and this original error is the source of many others. The Will is a manifestation and expression of the human spirit ; but not like Sovereignty a legal institution in the State (eine Rechtsinstitution des States]. Will may animate the exercise of Law and effect changes in it, but is not of itself Law (istfiir sich kein Reckf]. The Will of the Sovereign presupposes Sovereignty, not vice versd. 2. It is illogical to consider Sovereignty as the source of the State and of Law, and to put the Sovereign above the State. The power and majesty of the State presuppose the States. Thus Sovereignty is a con 1 ception of Public Law, and not superior to it (ilberstatsrechtlicK]. 3. Const. Franz (Vorschule d. St. p. 32) declares that after power 1 the self-consciousness of the State ' is the chief attribute of Sovereignty. But Consciousness, though necessary for the exercise of a Right and for the administration of Law, is not an attribute of Right or Law itself. CHAPTER II. SOVEREIGNTY OF THE PEOPLE OR OF THE STATE, AND SOVEREIGNTY OF THE RULER. To whom belongs Sovereignty ? Political parties are in- clined to answer this question in different ways. Even the scientific student has many difficulties and prejudices to remove. An opinion, widely diffused since Rousseau and the French i. Sove- Revolution, assigns sovereignty to the people. Yes ; but tSeopie as who are the people ? According to some, simply the sum Individuals. of individuals united into the State : that is to say, the J^rchy. State is resolved into its atoms, and supreme power is ascribed to the unorganised mass, or to the majority of these individuals. This extreme radical opinion contradicts the very existence of the State, which is the basis of sovereignty. It is not compatible with any constitution, not even with the absolute democracy which k professes to found, for even there it is the ordered national assembly (Lands gemeinde\ not the crowd of atoms, which exercises the authority of the State. Others understand the equal citizens collectively voting 2. Sovc- in one or more assemblies, i. e. they think of the sovereignty t^pe^pie of the demos in Democracy. The principle of the sovereignty ns7n C their of the people thus understood, and limited to this form xhfs^niy 5 " of government, has a meaning and a truth : it is exactly the f^j?de^ n same as Democracy. But in representative Democracy the m Aevd/iez>oi> irep\ T&V KOWCOV). (2) The magisterial (TO ircpl ras ap%ds). (3) The judicial (TO dKafov). He makes the first concerned with the great political questions of general politics, decisions about war or peace, conclusion of treaties, making of laws, punishment of death, exile and confiscation, and the control of finance. Thus very different sorts of things are brought together external politics, legislation, supreme criminal jurisdiction and control of administration ; but all these are distinguished by their great political significance for the whole State, and for the security of the citizens. Aristotle calls all this deliberation, not legislation, perhaps because legislation proper was not exercised by the popular assemblies till later, and only in- directly, whilst their deliberations had a great influence in the most important matters a . The second class of functions corresponds in some measure to what modern constitutions call executive power, a [No^tot are, indeed, named as one of the subjects with which TO 0ov- \v6(jivov is concerned (Pol. iv. 14. 3, 1298 a. 5). But it is clear that Aristotle, like the Greeks generally, thinks of a State as starting with a sufficient code of laws, framed for it by a vopoOiTrjs, and requiring as little alteration as possible (e.g. Pol. ii. 8. 16-25, I268b. 22 seq., n. 15, 1273 b. 21 : iii. 13. 23, 1284^ 17), the individual ruler or assembly being concerned only with particular details, to which the law cannot apply because it is general (/eafloAov) in its character (N. Eth. v. 10 : Pol. iii. 15. 3 seq., 1286 a. 8). Cp. N. Eth. vi. 8, where distinguished from &ov\VTiKTj.~\ Ll 2 516 SOVEREIGNTY AND ITS ORGANS. [Book VII. but it is more correctly described by reference to the ruling offices. The third class corresponds to our judicial power. Different Although the different functions are objectively dis- oS'exer- tinguished [i.e. in respect of their character], they are often same persons subjectively combined [i.e. in respect of the persons who and'Rome. exercise them]. We have already remarked that the Athenian ecclesia deliberated about laws, executed important matters of administration, and exercised judicial functions. The archons were administrative officials, and yet they had judicial powers. The Roman State was more developed and differentiated. The legislative functions of the comitia were more sharply distinguished from the functions of the senate and the magistrates. Yet the comitia treated of important questions of foreign policy, and in early times decided on appeals against sentence of death. The senate did not only exercise administrative functions ; its resolu- tions came to have the character of laws. Finally, the magistrates as a rule combined administrative and judicial functions. He who possessed the imperium possessed in the same measure jurisdictio l : he had, besides, priestly functions (the auspices), and by his edicts he exercised a sort of legislative power. Nevertheless, there is observable in the institutions of the Republic a conscious effort to differentiate the functions of government. Distinction A new distinction arose in the Eastern Roman Empire. cllTund The emperors, indeed, retained in their hands all public JJfficeTm the powers over the whole empire, but in the subordinate grades Empire ine ^ provincial government civil and military offices were carefully distinguished *. This separation which had not been effected earlier in the interest of the subjects, who 1 Cicero, de Leg. iii. 3: 'Omnes magistrates auspicium judiciumque habento.' Ulpianus in L. 2. D, de in jus voc. : ' Magistrates, qui im- perium habent, qui coercere aliquem possunt, et jubere in carcerem duci.' Ulpianus, L. i. pr. D, si quis jus dicenti : ' Omnibus magistrati- bus . . . secundum jus potestatis suae concessum est, jurisdictionem suam defendere poenali judicio.' *> [Cp. Gibbon's Decline and Fall, ch. xvii.] Chap. VI.] ANCIENT DISTINCTION OF FUNCTIONS. 517 were oppressed by the excessive power of the magistrates, was now carried out in order to secure the throne. This involved, however, a step in political progress which has been accepted in the modern State. In the middle ages the power of the State was on all sides in the , . . , r , Middle Ages checked and limited, but internally it united in itself the little differ- most various functions ; not only the king but every count en had at the same time civil and military, administrative and judicial power, and the assemblies (Dinge) were at the same time legislative and judicial. Bodin was the first to point out that the prince at least Bodin urges ought not to administer justice in person, but should leave tioVof the such matters to independent judges. Bodin shows that tionT* J there are many reasons in favour of the old usage : thus it made a good impression that the king should exercise justice in the sight of all people, but he sees that there are stronger reasons for the monarch withholding himself from personally exercising the office of judge. To be at once legislator and judge is to mingle together justice and the prerogative of mercy, adherence to the law, and arbitrary departure from it : if justice is not well administered, the litigating parties are not free enough, they are crushed by the authority of the sovereign. The horrors of punishment are frightfully increased, and if the prince has a cruel disposition, the judgment-seat swims in the blood of citizens, and the hatred of the people is roused against their chief. It is worst of all when the prince decides in his own affairs, and with regard to crimes against himself. It is better that he should reserve only the prerogative of mercy 2 . Bodin could indeed point to precedents in French History. Certain parliaments of peers had pronounced against the presence of the king in trials. Most States gradually adopted the new principle. Kings began to leave to tribunals the ordinary administration of justice, and to reserve to them- selves only the confirmation of sentences, especially sentences of death. 2 Bluntschli, Gesch. des allg. Statsr. p. 42. Cp. as to Puffendorf, p. 1 24. CHAPTER VII. III. THE MODERN PRINCIPLE OF DIVISION OF POWERS. THE idea that the objective difference of political func- tions requires a corresponding subjective separation in the organs to which these functions belong, has been produced by the course of modern politics. Montes- Montesquieu was the first to enounce the modern prin- ciple with emphasis and effect. He demands in the name of civic freedom and security that different public functions should be exercised by different persons. l If legislative and executive powers are united in the same person, or even in the same body of magistrates, there is no liberty, because people are afraid that the monarch or the senate may make tyrannical laws in order to administer them tyrannically. There is no liberty, again, if the judicial power is not sepa- rated from the legislative and executive : if it is joined to the legislative power, the life and death of the citizens may be arbitrarily disposed of, for the judge will be legislator : if it is joined to the executive power, the judge may have the force of an oppressor V The higher Excessive power united in one hand certainly endangers the a mOTedi? personal freedom. If the different branches of power are functions, separated, they are all mutually limited. Nevertheless, the decisive reason for such specialisation is not the practical security of civil liberty, but the organic reason that every 1 Esprit des Lois, xi. 6. [' De la constitution d'Angleterre.'] Bluntschli, Gesch. des allg. Statsr. p. 267. THE DIVISION OF POWERS. 519 function will be better fulfilled if its organ is specially directed to this particular end, than if quite different func- tions are assigned to the same organ. The statesman only follows the example of nature : the eye is adapted for sight, the ear for hearing, the mouth for speaking, the hand for seizing. The body politic should in the same way have a separate organ for each function. The favourite expression ( separation (Trennung) of Distinction, powers ' leads to false applications of a true principle. A tionf ep ' complete separation or sundering of powers would be a dissolution of the unity of the State. Just as in the body natural all the several limbs are connected together, so in the body politic the connection of the organs is not less important than their difference. In the State there must be a unity of power, and so the powers, though distin- guished according to their functions, must not be absolutely separated. Montesquieu makes the three-fold distinction (\}pouvoir The three. ,/ / \ / ,T i \ T fold division, ij, (2) executif, ($) juaiaatre. The same division is adopted by English political theor- ists. This threefold division has been carried out with rigour, but not without exaggeration, in the United States of North America a , and has been sanctioned by a whole series of modern European constitutions. To these three powers some have added, primarily in the Additions interests of the unity of the State : (4) A moderating power (pouvoir moderateur, royal\ This idea of Benjamin Constant's has been adopted in the Portuguese constitution of Don Pedro. Others have added to the executive power : (5) The administrative (pouvoir administratif). (6) The inspective (potestas inspectiva). (7) The representative (pouvoir representatif). There is a mistaken view that these different powers are [For the way in which the actual constitution of the United States followed the then current theory of the English Constitution, cp. Bage- hot's English Constitution, pp. 27, 227 (edit. 1872).] 520 SOVEREIGNTY AND ITS ORGANS. [Book vil. These diffe- equal. This contradicts the organic nature of the State. t^iaf. rs> The members of an organism have each their own power, but in subordination to one another; otherwise the con- nection and the unity of the whole would not be maintained. And so in the State : if the highest powers were really equal, and not merely in outward form, as in the United States of North America, the State would be torn in pieces. 1 The head cannot be separated from the body and made equal to it, without killing the man.' (Bluntschli, Studien, p. 146.) Not the pro- Another error, which is almost childish, is that which positions of a . syllogism, treats the organism of the State as a logical syllogism : the legislative power determining the rule or major premise, the judicial power subsuming a particular case under it (minor premise), while the executive carries out the conclusion 2 . All the functions of the different powers would thus be united in every judicial decision, and government would be only the policeman to execute this judgment. A. The It is first of all necessary to distinguish the legislative legislative \ power. power from all others. All other functions belong to parti- cular organs, but legislation to the whole body politic. The legislative power determines the laws and institutions of the State themselves (Stats- und Rechtsordnung]. All other powers, on the other hand, are exercised within the existing laws and institutions, in particular, concrete and changing cases. Legislation arranges the permanent relations of the whole; the other powers are, as a rule, exercised only in particular directions, and do not affect the whole nation. These other powers cannot be divided until the rights of the legislative body have been determined. The legislative power does not only fix general rules of a Montesquieu, xi. 6, puts the matter differently. He calls the judicial power also ' la puissance executrice des choses qui dependent du droit civil? and thus distinguishes it objectively from the executive power proper, ' puissance executrice des choses, qui dependent du droit des gens? This strange view has been followed among others by Kant (Rechtslehre, 45), and Spittler (Vorlesungen iiber Politik, 15). On the other side cp. Stahl, Lehre vom Stat, ii. 57. Chap. VII.] THE DIVISION OF POWERS. 521 Right (Rechtsregeln) laws (Gesetze) in the narrower sense. It has also to found and alter the institutions of the State. If it concerns itself with general economic arrangements in the budget (lois d^impot^^ if it approves not principles but demands, if it takes account of the actual circumstances of the country, it is because these acts, although not laws in the proper sense, relate to the whole of the State. Rousseau explains the relation of legislation to adminis- y i ews of tration by the psychological distinction of will and power, and Stein Legislation is the expression of the general will, administra- cr tion consists in particular actions of the government. ' La loi veut, le roi fait V Lorenz von Stein recognises the same distinction. But an insight into the necessity of laws and institutions is not less important for legislation than the will to establish them : and, on the other hand, the actions of government, which chooses the end and the means of its policy, are as certainly acts of will. Thus it is better to make the distinction one of general and particular will, of established order and occasional action. As the whole is more than any of its parts or members, so the legislative power is superior to all the other particular powers. These may be divided, in the modern State, into four B. The other groups of essentially different character. The two most ItateT important and highest are, I, Government or Administra- tion ; II, the Judicial power. I. Government or Administration (Regierungsgeivalt\ I. Govern- rri i i T-I / 77 7 7 . i ment or Ad- 1 he usual expression, ' Executive (voliziehende) power, is ministration, unfortunate, and is the source of a number of errors, mis- The terin , / . ' Executive understandings in theory, and mistakes in practice. It criticised, neither expresses the essential character of government, nor its relation to legislation and the judicial power. A person can execute a decision of his own, or the com- mand or mandate of another. But in any case the execu- tion is only secondary, the decision or mandate is primary. b [See references in footnote i, Bk. vi. chap. xv. pp. 426, 427 above.] 522 SOVEREIGNTY AND ITS ORGANS. [Book VI I. But the functions of government are in their nature primary : it decides and resolves, it expresses its will, orders or forbids, and in most cases its orders are carried out without exe- cutive compulsion* If that is necessary, it is undoubtedly the business of the government ; but as it is secondary, it is ordinarily entrusted to subordinate officials, such as the police. Even if the will of others is in question, the expression * executive ' is inaccurate. It is not true that the government has only to execute in particular cases what the legislature has established in general. As a rule a law is not executed (carried out), but observed and applied. The promulgation of a law is not the same as its execution. The rules which the legislator sanctions, the principles which he expresses, are respected by the government as the legal and constitu- tional limits of its conduct, but within these limits it decides freely : treats with other States, appoints commissions of enquiry, adopts measures necessary for the maintenance of order, furthers what tends to the public weal, nominates functionaries, controls the army. The expression ' execu- tive ' is still less applicable to the administrative government in its relations to the courts of justice. The execution of a judgment is essentially an act of the judicial power itself, whose business it is to administer justice, and to restore rights which have been disturbed, and which does not call in the stronger power of government, except when its own is insufficient. The relation of the two powers is not that of servant to master. The essence The essence of government consists rather in the power of Govern- f .. . . . ment. of commanding in particular matters what is just and useful, and in the power of protecting the country and the nation from particular attacks and dangers, of representing it, and guarding against common evils. It consists especially in what the Greeks call upx*} 3 , the Romans imperium^ the Germans of the middle ages Mundschaft and Vogtei (tutelle 3 Arist. Pol. iv. 15. 4, 1299 a. 27 : TO yap kiriraTTfi tffriv. He finds the essence of authority in command. Chap. VII.] THE DIVISION OF POWERS. 523 and baillage]. Of all other powers government is the ruling, and, without doubt, the highest, being related to the others as the head to the limbs of the body. It includes what is called the representative power. It is called political government (politische Regierung) in the general conduct of the State, administration ( Venval- tung) in reference to details. II. The judicial (richterlicke) power is often regarded as n. The the power which judges (urtheilen) a confusion which is power, favoured by the French [and English] expressions (pouvoir judiciaire). But the essence of judicial power consists not in judging (urtheileri), but in laying down the law (richten\ or, according to the Roman expression,, not in judicio, but in jure. c Judging/ in the sense of recognising and declaring the justice in particular cases, is not necessarily a function of government, nor the exercise of a public power. In Rome it was commonly entrusted to private persons as judices, in mediaeval Germany to the assessors (Schoffen\ not the judges (Richter). In modern times it is often en- trusted to popular juries. Maintaining the law, on the other hand, and protecting the rights of individuals and of the community, has always been considered as a magis- terial function. An essential distinction between judicial power and govern- ment is that the former does not, like the latter, exercise rule, but only protects and applies laws already recognised. The functions of government may be compared to the intel- lectual powers of man, the functions of the judicial powers to his conscience. The separation (Ausscheidung) of the judicial power from that of government in the modern State is a very important political advance. In ancient times and in the middle ages the same magistrates exercised both functions. The purity of justice, the liberty of the citizens, have gained by the change, and government has not lost in security *. Experience * Compare the words of Washington, in his wonderful Farewell Speech (1796) : 'It is important, likewise, that the habits of thinking 524 SOVEREIGNTY AND ITS ORGANS. [Book VII. proves that distinguished statesmen, and government officials, are very seldom likewise good judges, and vice versh. The judicial power, though independent of the government, is yet subordinate to it, in some such way as the heart is to the head. other The functions of sovereignty may appear to be exhausted by this three-fold distinction, and we can easily under- stand how recent constitutions have commonly limited them- selves to these. But on closer examination, we find that there are two other groups of organs and functions, both of which are indeed subordinate to that of government, but may still be distinguished from it, having much less the character of authority and command, which in government is essential. These are : in. and iv. III. The superintendence and care of the intellectual Superintend- . -..,.. / , enceofin- elements of civilisation (Statscultur). material ai IV. The administration and care of material interests interests. (Statswirthsckaft] [Political Economy in the original sense]. In these two groups there is no question of governing. The great factors of civilisation, religion, science, art, do not belong to the organism of the State. Thus the relation of the State, even to the external institutions of religion, science and art, to the Church and the school, is fundamentally dif- ferent from the relation between government and subjects in its own proper sphere. Such matters cannot be subjected to the dominion of the State : its functions are therefore in a free country should inspire caution in those entrusted with its administration to confine themselves within their respective constitu- tional spheres ; avoiding in the exercise of the powers of one depart- ment to encroach upon another. The spirit of encroachment tends to consolidate the powers of all the departments in one, and thus -to create, whatever the form of government, a real despotism. A just estimate of that love of power and proneness to abuse it, which pre- dominates in the human heart, is sufficient to satisfy us of the truth of this position. The necessity of reciprocal checks in the exercise of political power, by dividing and distributing it into different depositories, and constituting each the guardian of the public weal against invasions by the others, has been evinced by experiments ancient and modern, some of them in our country and under our own eyes. To preserve them must be as necessary as to institute them.' Chap. VII.] THE DIVISION OF POWERS. 525 limited to superintendence and fostering care (Aufsicht und Pflege). The same applies to the fourth head, Public Economy. In the administration of the income and expenditure of the State, in the maintenance of the economic welfare of the citizens, in the support of commerce, in the management of public works, in the control of local government, there is no exercise of imperium in the strict sense. Economic admin- istration must be based, not so much on the authority of the State, as on technical knowledge and experience. In no other matters does the action of the State approach so nearly to that of the private person. The property of the State may be bought and sold like that of a private person. The material welfare of the community is the broad basis on which the State rests, and thus, although it is a necessary condition of political existence, occupies the lowest place, while govern- ment occupies the highest. This distinction in the functions of the State has only in recent times come to be gradually recognised. We still suffer from the evils of a confusion of commanding and fostering. Sometimes things are commanded or forbidden, which should only be managed or controlled ; sometimes there is a timid assistance or control, where there ought to be energetic and authoritative action. But matters are better than they were a hundred, or even fifty, years ago. Many institutions have been already separated from the direct administration of government, and are managed, without the employment of force, in a spirit of scientific and technical care, and in the interests at once of the welfare and the freedom of the com- munity. sense. CHAPTER VIII. PUBLIC SERVICE AND PUBLIC FUNCTIONS^". Public Ser- i. IN a wide sense every service exacted by the State, or wideband a rendered voluntarily to the State, can be called ' public ser- wer vice.' This would include the service of soldiers, juries, deputies, and electors, whether secondary or primary. Not all these services, however, are public services in the proper sense, which implies a special charge or commission given by the State. The functionaries of parishes, of the church, and of other corporations, are not servants of the State ; their service is public, but it is not laid upon them by the State, and is not immediately related to the State 1 . The head of the State is not a public servant, in so far as he is himself sovereign, and the source of all public services : yet Frederick the Great was right in calling the king ' the first servant of the State,' because even his office is dependent upon the constitution, and exists altogether for the service of the State. Not ail 2. Not all public services in the narrower sense are public functions ; not all public servants are State officials. A State ffi office is a particular organ in the body politic, with special functions of its own. A public function is limited to particular objects. The la Cp. with this chapter esp. Schulze, Lehrbuch des deutschen Stats- rechts, i. 309 ff. : Laband, Statsrecht des deutschen Reichs, i. 382 ff. : Loning, Lehrbuch des Vertvaltungsrechts, 115 ff. 1 Particular public functions may be entrusted to them, but their proper character is not thereby altered. Cp. Welcker's Statslexicon, s. v. Statsdiener. PUBLIC SERVICE AND PUBLIC FUNCTIONS. 52? office is filled by the person of the official. State officials or functionaries, in a wider sense, are those public servants who, although recognising and respecting their subordination to the head of the State, yet exercise their offices according to their own judgment ; in a narrower sense they are those only who have entrusted to them a power of command (im- perium Gt jurisdtctw), as distinct from those who have no authority of this sort. These last we might describe by the good old term of public curators (offentliche Pfleger). Such are professors and teachers in State schools, directors and physicians in public hospitals, government engineers, and many financial officials, such as treasurers and administrators of crown lands 2 . State functionaries proper are those employed either in ad. Difference ministrative or judicial matters. The former exercise the admSSra- imperium ; within their sphere they order at their own dis- jidldaf cretion what they consider for the public interest, but they ariesJ lon ~ depend upon their superiors, and must submit to their in- junctions. Judicial functionaries, on the other hand, cannot exercise their own discretion as to what public interest de- mands : they must lay down the law as it exists, and apply it according to fixed rules (jurisdictio] ; but in doing so they must act according to their own conscience, and are not bound by any special injunctions of the government. In ordinary circumstances the former class of functionaries may be expected to display a liberal, the latter a conservative tendency. 3. From both kinds of State functionaries we must dis- Official i , r i n , rr . , . assistants. tinguish the employes of the State, and official assistants. These are certainly public servants, but they have no special office, no authority or independent sphere : they are merely assistants of the officials under whom they are placed. Such are clerks, inspectors, revenue collectors, etc. They are 2 Schmitthenner, Statsrecht, p. 503. He uses the expression ' technical officials' (in opposition to 'government officials'), and includes the judges among them. The name would apply better to our second class above. 528 SOVEREIGNTY AND ITS ORGANS. [Book VII. public servants, because their activity is employed as an organic part of the life of the State, and in so far as their work is of an intellectual, though not of the highest kind. If even this last element is wanting, and merely mechanical service is the chief thing 3 , they are no longer to be called public servants, although they are used by the State. One might call them ' private servants, or domestics of the State ' (Statsbediente] : such are lacqueys, porters, beadles, policemen, sergeants-at-arms, etc. Their condition is regu- lated by private law, rather than by the essential conditions of public service. Distinction 4. The distinction between civil and military functions, ci^iTand which was first clearly made by the Emperor Constantine o n ffice a sT the Great 4 , is of significance in the modern State. The officers of the army alone can be considered public servants, as they alone have the command : the other soldiers are only fulfilling a general civic duty, or have voluntarily enlisted under the form of private contract. Military officers are chiefly distinguished from civil by the stricter discipline and the military obedience, but partly also by the fact that they possess authority only indirectly, because their functions are executive, and therefore secondary by nature. Distinction 5- A distinction is made between collegiate and individual collegiate offices 5 . The former, composed of several persons who de- vkhii^" liberate together and of whom the majority decides, are offices. better adapted for advice, the latter for action. Sometimes collegiate deliberation and individual decision may be united : thus a minister decides after having taken the advice of his colleagues. Distinction Further, offices are distinguished as higher and lower, and 3 Schmitthenner, Statsrecht, p. 503, rightly calls attention to this distinction. But in calling the employes of the State * subaltern ' functionaries, he uses an unsuitable term, because it only expresses subordination, which is equally to be found among the real officials. ' State-officials ' (Statsbeamte] and * official assistants ' (Amfsgehulferi) would express the distinction better. 4 Cp. above, Bk. vii. chap. vi. p. 516. Gibbon's Decline and Fall, chap. xvii. 9 Cp. Pozl, Deutsches Statsworterbtich, art. * Amt.' Chap.VHI.] PUBLIC SER VICE AND PUBLIC FUNCTIONS. 529 according to the locality of their operation. There are according v / -r \ -i ff . . to locality. central offices (Landesamter}, intermediate offices relating to provinces, departments, districts, etc. ; and, lowest of all, local or parochial (communal) offices. Sometimes, too, there are concurrent offices, where several functionaries exercise the same powers in the same district, but each by himself, e. g. the magistracies of ancient Rome, the English Justices of the Peace. 6. Office generally implies : what office / \ i i i r it' implies : (a) A certain kind and extent of public powers and duties. This is called its competency. (b) A local seat as the proper centre and residence of its action. Even officials who move about have a fixed official place. (c) A territorial sphere of operation. 7. The relations between the State and its servants are Relation not a matter of private law, but essentially political in stat^and its character. The service of the State is not a commission se or mandate, still less merely hired service. The rules of private contract do not explain either the appointment, or the powers, or the dismissal of a public servant. The State nominates to an office by an act of will, the decree of nomination 6 . This act has been called a special law, an expression which it is better to avoid, since, as a rule, the act of nomination is not made by the legislative 6 Conner, Der Statsdienst am dem Gesichtspunkt des Rechts, Lands- hut, 1808 ; Zacharia, D. St. ii. 25 ff. Schmitthenner (Statsrecht, p. 509), while rejecting the ' legistic' conception of many modern jurists who, strangely enough, wish to apply the principles of Roman private law where the Romans themselves never dreamed of applying them, holds nevertheless that public services are based on contract, though it is not obligatory. This contract ' is the causa praecedens of the instal- lation, just as a feudal contract preceded the investiture in a fief.' But this is an error. Antecedent contracts of the sort are only exceptions. The question, whether one will take an office or not, and the answer to it, do not constitute a contract. The contract must be a feigned one, and for that there is no reason. Where, exceptionally, there is a con- tract, it affects only the private and not the public rights of the parties : and thus we have here nothing to do with it. Acceptance and refusal of a nomination are certainly voluntary acts : but that does not affect the authoritative character of the decree. But cp. Lb'ning, ib. p. 119. M m 530 SOVEREIGNTY AND ITS ORGANS. body, but in monarchies by the king ; in republics, some- times by the government, sometimes by popular election. This decree is essentially a unilateral act of authority, even in the exceptional case where it is preceded by an actual contract, as e. g. in acquiring the services of a foreigner. Such a contract could never serve as the basis of a civil action to force the actual appointment, although it may entitle to a demand for damages, as in a private contract, if the nomination of the State is not carried out. The functions of public service are determined by the State, and have a public and organic character. The office exists only for the State, and not for the individual who holds it. It cannot therefore become the property of a private person, nor as such become an object of private trafficking. Where anything of the sort happens, as in the middle ages, and in France even in later times, the State has not escaped from the limits of private law, and has not yet attained a full consciousness of its political existence. Salary. 8. The salary attached to an office belongs to private law, for the salary is essentially intended to assure the material existence of the official and his family. Claims to salary may quite well be decided on by a civil judge. But this element does not affect the essence of public office. At all times there have been unpaid honorary officials, who have the same significance in the body politic as salaried professional officials. The English Justices of the Peace are just as much State officials as the salaried Prussian Landrdthe (prefects). CHAPTER IX, APPOINTMENT OF OFFICIALS. 1. HEREDITARY offices, which were introduced everywhere Hereditary in Europe in the middle ages, are as universally rejected by the spirit of modern politics. Mediaeval history shows that hereditary offices become seigniories, and thus destroy the unity and order of the State. Besides, heredity is no guarantee of personal capacity. There may in modern States be hereditary offices excep- tionally, commonly where they are purely positions of honour without power, e.g. the offices about the court, which have come down from the middle ages. 2. Of more importance is the distinction between pro- Distinction fessional and honorary offices. The former occupy the professfona whole activity of a man, and form his vocation : they offi d c e n rary frequently require technical knowledge, and consequently preparatory education and apprenticeship or probation. Such offices have therefore a claim to a salary. The latter, on the other hand, require only occasional duties, and may therefore be exercised by those who have a private vocation, as landowners, merchants, etc., and support themselves by this calling or by their private fortunes. Serving on juries, or taking part in represen- tative assemblies, are duties which may be fulfilled in this way. Obviously it is only the well-to-do classes of society who can exercise such offices. The mass of the people lacks education, or leisure, or both. In the modern State professional offices are the more important, but in many cases the advantages of both sorts M m 2 532 SOVEREIGNTY AND ITS ORGANS. [Book VI I. may be combined. Representative government and self- government afford ways in which the direction of a pro- fessional official may be combined with the assistance of representative honorary officials. Thus in Prussia the Landrath (prefect) is combined with the members of the departmental committee (Kreisausschuss) ; in Baden the prefect of the district (BezirksamtY with his district coun- sellors, the professional judge with jurymen and assessors. Officials in 3. The German States, although in many respects less politically advanced than England and France, are ahead in the admirable organisation of professional offices. A ca- pable and trustworthy class of officials is assured by the German system, according to which : (a) Offices are open to all who have the qualifications. Numerous exhibitions or bursaries (Stipendieri) assist the poorer students, but the great number belong, as a matter of fact, to the more highly educated families, and bring with them from home a traditional culture, which in its turn helps to elevate the general level. (<) As a rule, the candidates for public service must have a classical education at the Gymnasium and at the Uni- versity. For certain technical offices, e. g. of engineers, architects, etc., the education of the Realschule and the Polytechnic schools is required instead. At the end of the course of study there is a government examination. The scientific spirit of the German universities refuses to limit study to mere practical preparation for a profession, and thus the defects of the Chinese system are avoided. The necessity of examination prevents the influences of party favour and court intrigue. Yet the system must not be applied in a pedantic way. Exceptions must be made for foreigners or other persons whose talents would be useful to the State, but who have not followed the ordinary course of study. Again, there are appointments which cannot be made by examination, [For the meaning of the terms Kreis, Bezirk> &c., cp. Book III. ch. 6, above, p. 247.] Chap. IX.] APPOINTMENT OF OFFICIALS. 533 such as ministers and counsellors, or professors at the uni- versities, where high political or scientific capabilities are required. (c) After the theoretical examination follows the novitiate (Referendar- oder Practicantendienst\ that is to say, the prac- tical exercise as assistants to officials or lawyers. At the close of this novitiate there is commonly a second examina- ' tion before the candidate himself receives an office l . (d) The State itself appoints, according to its require- ments, those who have fulfilled these conditions. Promotion is made gradually according to period of ser- vice and proof of capacity. Advance in title and rank and payment, in regular order, is the rule, but the system must not be applied in a rigid mathematical way. Seniority must not override the more important consideration of capacity, as it is apt to do where the system has degenerated into a bureaucracy. (e) The salary paid by the State assures to the official a means of support corresponding to his position. Certainly most German officials are very scantily paid, if we compare their earnings with those of trade ; but, on the other hand, they are protected against the uncertainties of commercial enterprise. If a certain number of honorary offices were substituted for the too numerous professional offices, the salaries of the latter could be improved. (/) The German official has pragmatic rights, i.e. he has a legal claim to a fixed salary and to a retiring pension in case of age or illness. By this system the German officials may feel that they have an assured and honourable position ; they form a veritable professional order with the consciousness of their solidarity, and they have the importance of a political power. The head of the State and the representatives of 1 R. v. Mohl, in Mittermaier's Zeitschrift fur Rechtswissenschaft des Auslandes, xvi. p. 431 ff. d. Laboulaye, De r enseignement et du noviciat administratif en Allemagne, in Wolowsky, Revue, xviii. Bluntschli, Deutsche Rechtsschulen, 2nd edit., p. 92 ff. Vivien, t. Adm. i. p. 205. v. Mohl, Politik, Bd. ii. 534 SOVEREIGNTY AND ITS ORGANS. [Book VII. the people must reckon with them, and cannot dispense with their co-operation. officials in 4. The English system is totally different. Police ad- ministration and jurisdiction in the counties are entrusted to unpaid functionaries chosen from the aristocracy. Minis- ters are not taken from the class of permanent officials, but from the parliamentary parties. A great number of public offices are filled by party influence, without regard to any previous preparation for them, but by the patronage and recommendation of influential members of Parliament. But even in England the need of examining candidates is felt more than it was. The higher judicial offices require a long legal education, not indeed at the universities, but at the Inns of Court, and practical experience of the pro- fession. Examinations are now also required for a number of technical offices : incapable persons are rejected, and the influence of parties and patronage is diminished. A change of Ministry affects only about sixty posts, partly eminent political offices, partly offices of the court 2 . ' officials in 5. The system of the United States was originally based states 16 on the English, but worked in a republican and democratic spirit. In the presidency of Andrew Jackson was introduced the dangerous practice of complete change [' the spoils system ']. On the election of a new president, that is every four, or at least every eight years, if a different party comes into power, an immense number of posts is vacated and filled by new persons. This leads to a universal office- hunting, and the interests of the State and society are less considered than the wishes of party. Thus the whole official class is kept in an unstable condition and exposed to violent changes, and corruption is difficult to repress. The judges alone have a better guaranteed position, and the habit of selecting them from experienced advocates assures their legal acquirements and abilities. officials in 6, In France there is indeed an official class, but its France. 2 R. Gneist, Englisches Verwaltungsrecht, 3rd edit. (1883), 23off. Chap. IX.] APPOINTMENT OF OFFICIALS. 535 position is less independent than in Germany. The head of the State, i. e. the Ministry for the time being, has greater power of appointing and dismissing officials, and there is less guarantee for scientific education. Special study at polytechnic, military and normal schools, is indeed required for a great number of technical offices ; university education for the judicial functions. But the rule is not so generally carried out as in Germany. The official is more dependent on the government ; fidelity to party is more regarded than fidelity to his office and the State. 7. In the republics of antiquity, and partly also in those in Republics of modern times, as in Switzerland and America, the system ments" is adopted of appointments for a fixed period of time, gene- STfo?a rally a few years, sometimes with, and sometimes without, period 6 the possibility of reappointment. This system does well enough for local offices, which, as a rule, demand no higher education, and rarely use all the powers of a man's life, but it involves great disadvantages when applied to State offices which require a long professional training, such as has be- come necessary in our highly developed conditions. The system involves frequent changes, favours ambition and party intrigue, diminishes the security of functionaries, and prevents the firmness and stability of political action. The advantage of the easy dismissal of incapable officials, or of those who have lost the confidence of the public, does not outweigh these disadvantages. This system is less dangerous in an aristocracy, which is naturally inclined to stability and moderation, than in a democracy which loves change and for that very reason is inclined to the system of short tenures. There is further the danger of the State losing the service of the most capable men, either through the caprice of the people or because they themselves prefer a less uncertain career. 8. The individual should be free to accept or refuse an Liberty of office to which he is appointed, not because the service of the State is to be based on contract, but because direct compulsion cannot properly be applied to intellectual ser- 536 SOVEREIGNTY AND ITS ORGANS. vice and indirect compulsion is difficult and imperfect in its effects. Individual freedom is the normal source of all use- ful activity. No citizen can be compelled to make greater sacrifices to the State than another. This principle is re- cognised in almost all modern States, republics as well as monarchies 8 . Local offices are an exception : their greater number, and the small claims which they make on the individual, make them appear a universal duty of the citizen 4 . when an 9. The question has been debated When an appoint- begins. tm lt ment begins ? If we remember that the appointment is a unilateral act of the State, we can answer without hesitation : At the moment when this act is made public, is registered or signed : the notification of this to the person nominated, and his subsequent investiture, are only the consequences of a perfect nomination 5 . 3 The rule holds even in Switzerland and Norway. Cp. Story, Com- mentaries on Const. U. S. A. iii. 37, 120. For Germany, cp. Zacharia, I). St. 136. 4 E. g. where a city has become a State, as in the case of the Free Cities of the Empire, or where, as in Canton Appenzell, the constitution is as simple as that of a commune or township. 5 Compare on this point the dispute between President Jefferson and the Supreme Court of Justice in the United States (Story, iii. 37, 120). The former maintained that the nomination gave no rights to the official until he had received the decree which nominated him. The latter held that the mere nomination had effect, so that the nominating government had no longer the right of annulling it. Zacharia, D. St. 136, limits the effects of the nomination to the consequences in private law. This limitation however is neither neces- sary nor correct. The nomination has effects, not as a private contract but a? a public act of the State: and, though the actual exercise of official powers may not commence till after investiture, the right to exercise them pre-exists. CHAPTER X. RIGHTS AND DUTIES OF PUBLIC OFFICIALS. 1. FIRST of all, the official has the right of exercising the Exercise of functions of his office. This is called his competence, and is entirely a matter of public interest. It is at the same time his duty to exercise his functions as required, and to do so or not is not dependent on his individual will. The State may change, increase, or diminish the powers of an office. 2. An official has certainly a right to the title and rank Title and belonging to his office, but this right depends on political rd reasons, and may be modified by legislation. On the other hand, rank and title may remain as the private right of an ex-official. 3. The right of being indemnified for expenses incurred indemnity and injury suffered in the interests of the State is a matter of private law, and belongs equally to paid and unpaid officials. 4. There is no similar right to payment for the services Salary, themselves. It depends on the will of the State whether an office shall be paid or unpaid. A paid official has a right at private law to his salary. A distinction may be made, as in many German States, between two elements in the payment of officials: (i) payment of rank (Standesgehalt\ (2) payment of service (Dienstgehalt). It is the duty and interest of the State to maintain, in a suitable way, those officials whose whole 538 SOVEREIGNTY AND ITS ORGANS. [Book vil. professional activity it employs; but there is further the expense which is involved in or connected with the actual exercise of the office (Dienstaufwand und Representations- kosten)*. This distinction is of importance in the case of officials retiring from active service. They retain a claim to the former kind of payment, though none with respect to the latter. The former is in greater degree a matter of private right, the latter is bound up with the exercise of public functions. Where perquisites and fees are attached to particular offices they are to be considered of the latter character, even where they are reckoned along with the regular maintenance of the officials. The State has the right of altering such fees : it is only a matter of equity if a fixed salary is raised in order to compensate a diminution of fees : there is no legal claim to compensation. Pension. 5. The right to a retiring pension arises from the fact that the official has a claim to his salary at private law if he is compelled to give up his office through no fault of his own. The pension should be proportioned to the salary of maintenance (Standcsgehatf) : or, if there is no distinction of this sort formally recognised, the expenses of actual tenure of office must be deducted in fixing the pension. It is expedient that the amount and conditions of pensions should be definitely fixed by law, in order to avoid anything arbitrary in the awarding of them. A general system of pensions constitutes a heavy burden on the treasury, but such a burden cannot well be avoided where the State requires professional officials. The income of a government official is in most cases very small, compared with the earn- ings of commerce and industry, and commonly requires higher intellectual qualifications and more education. It is therefore a duty of the State to assure those who devote their lives to it against want. The public is compensated for the expense by better service, and the temptations to corruption are avoided. 1 Conner, ibid. 144. ' Beilage ' ix. to the Bavarian Constitution, it-19' Chap. X.] RIGHTS AND DUTIES OF PUBLIC OFFICIALS. 539 The widows and orphans of State servants have no legal claim to a pension. The salary is not hereditary. Many States have the good arrangement of a public pension-fund, chiefly maintained by deductions from official salaries. 6. The duties of officials mostly follow from their rights : Duties of they owe, further, obedience to their superiors, fidelity to the head of the State and to the nation, and, if occasion requires, secrecy. The oath of office, which is com- monly demanded, does not create this obligation, but only strengthens it. It is not the condition of the official's duties, nor does it modify their extent. The kind of obedience varies according to the nature of Obedience, the particular function. It is different for administrative and for judicial functionaries. The latter must obviously occupy, on the whole, an independent position, but even the former are not bound to an absolute or servile obedience. Limits are imposed by both law and morality : in particular cases the extent of the obligation to obedience may raise very difficult questions. (a\ An official may examine if the order he receives is regular in form, i. e. if it is one which his superior is by his office entitled to give, and not due to some caprice, and if it is within the sphere of his own office to execute : he may further refuse to carry out an order which is not signed, if a signature is required. He is a public functionary, and not a private servant, and is therefore competent to examine the form of orders as a test of their legality. If the question of competency is doubtful, and the superior affirms his right to give the order, the inferior must obey. His sole right, and at the same time his duty, is to put his scruples before his superior, and to await a repetition of the order. (b] In no case can an official be bound to render obedience which would violate the higher principles of religion and morality, or make him accomplice in a crime. Such acts can never be the duty of his office. The servant of the State cannot be required to do what a man would refuse 540 SOVEREIGNTY AND ITS ORGANS. [Book VII. from humanity, a believer from religion, or a citizen from regard to the criminal law of the land a . (c) The subordinate official cannot refuse to obey an order, the object of which appears to him illegal or unjust. He can only make representations on the subject to his superior. He ought to presume that his superior does not wish to violate the law, and that he has not considered the matter sufficiently, and may be led to alter his decision by respectful and frank expression of opinion. An official should not fail to save his superiors and the State from mistakes, but if the superior abides by his orders obedience is due, and the superior must bear the responsibility. To authorise resistance in such cases would be to destroy the unity of the State, to paralyse its power, and would lead to far worse consequences than single violations of the law 2 . The same is to be said of unconstitutional commands. The subordinate must not, by resisting, himself violate constitu- tional obedience. a [There is surely a confusion here between the moral duty of the in- dividual and his legal duty as an official. As ' a counsel of perfection,' it is the duty of a government to respect morality, but it cannot be the right of an official to resist on other than legal and constitutional grounds. An official certainly cannot be required to break ' the law of the land' criminal or civil but if he receives an order, which he regards as contrary to (his) religion or morality, he cannot claim, on that ground alone, to set it aside and yet retain the position of an official. The next paragraphs [c] and (7) put the case accurately, but they appear to contradict what Bluntschli says here.] 2 Several constitutions formally express this principle, e. g. the Hanoverian Constitution of 1883, 161 : ' An order issued in proper form by a superior official imposes no responsibility on the inferior who receives it, but on the superior who issues it.' So in the Constitution of Meiningen, 104, and of Altenburg, 37 : * The responsibility for every illegal act belongs to him who orders it. The orders of a higher official are only an excuse if they are in proper form, and have been issued by a competent authority, who then becomes responsible for them.' Gonner, ib. 79, appears to understand the gloria obsequii in the same way, but he uses an unfortunate expression when he speaks of the official as a ' machine ' ; for he recognises the duty of remonstrance against unjust commands, and limits the duty of obedience both in form and object, p. 208. Besides, the expression ' machine ' has a monkish flavour. Cp. on this contested point Schulze, Deutsches Statsrecht, i. 325 ff. ; Laband, i. 427 ff. ; Loning, Verivaltungsrecht, p. 122 ff. Chap. X.] RIGHTS AND DUTIES OF PUBLIC OFFICIALS. 541 7. The spirit of fidelity (Treue) goes further than the Fidelity, duty of obedience. The latter is fulfilled when the official carries out the order given him strictly in form and sub- stance. The former binds him in the whole of his conduct. Fidelity or loyalty is not, indeed, as in the feudal system, the main principle of society : the duties of officials are now determined by legislation. It is not so much a personal allegiance to his prince as the requirements of the State which influence his action. Nevertheless, fidelity still forms the basis of the harmony and moral cohesion of the public service. An official who, in important though isolated points, holds, and on occasion expresses, political convictions different from those of his superiors, does not thereby violate the duty of fidelity. But if on permanent and fundamental principles he finds himself in opposition to the government, and hostile to it ; if, e.g. in a monarchy, he is a declared republican, and works for the establishment of a republic, or vice versa, he breaks the bond of fidelity, and ceases to be a harmonious member of the whole. It is the same with a functionary who takes part in systematic and continuous opposition intended to overthrow or impede the govern- ment. This is a breach of fidelity which no government can tolerate without falling into anarchy 3 . Systematic hos- tility to the ministry, although there is no particular act of disobedience, is likewise a breach of fidelity. An official 3 Washington (quoted in Guizot's Pref. to his Life, i. p. xxiii) : ' As long as I shall have the honour to govern the public affairs, I will never knowingly place in any important office any man whose political maxims are contrary to the general measures of the government. This would be in my opinion a kind of political suicide/ [Letter to Timothy Pickering, Writings, vol. xi. p. 74, quoted in Guizot's Essay, Eng. trans, p. 84.] How strongly German statesmen have felt the evils which accrue to the State from unfaithful officials, may be seen from the following passionate utterances of Stein (Pertz's Life of him, ii. p. 501) : 'We cannot overcome the insolence and turbulence in the dis- position of most of the public officials except by rigorous measures, prompt removal, imprisonment or banishment of those who in this way spread dangerous opinions, or undermine the authority of the govern- ment/ 542 SOVEREIGNTY AND ITS ORGANS. [Book VII. may have absolutely divergent, and even hostile convictions, without ceasing to be faithful in his office. But he must not in his official position express such sentiments. If he believes himself conscientiously bound to declare his hos- tility in word and deed, he ought to resign his office. It is obvious that judges are in a more independent position. Their office is not political in character, and not dependent on the will of the government. A further consequence of official fidelity is that no official accept service under a foreign State, or decorations, pen- sions, or other distinctions of the sort without permission of his own government. Secrecy. 8. Official secrecy is not to be understood in an absolute sense, but only so far as specially ordered, or in matters where the revelation of information, officially obtained, would injure the State or individuals. Two extremes have to be avoided, a pedantic maintenance of mystery, or a mischievous concealment of unconstitutional and illegal action on the one side; indiscreet gossiping on the other. Punishment 9. The State can reprimand or punish functionaries who pHne. 1SC neglect or violate their duties. Crimes, which can be prosecuted and punished before the ordinary courts, are to be distinguished from neglect of duties, which renders a person liable to official discipline. The former are judged by the ordinary law of the land, the latter more specially from the point of view of the public interest. This dis- tinction is the same as that between Justice (Gerichf) and Police (Polizei). The former^ as we have said, are pro- ceeded against at criminal law, but the State has in some cases modified this in its own interest : (i) according to the French practice *, the criminal prosecution of an official for an official crime can only take place with the authorisation of the government, or an authority specially empowered, or 6 [Art. 75 of the Constitution of the year VIII, abolished by decree of Sept. 19, 1870 (Fr. trans.).] Chap. X.] RIGHTS AND DUTIES OF PUBLIC OFFICIALS. 543 (2) there are special courts to try officials 4 . The English practice rejects both these exceptional rules, but protects its aristocratic officials by other means against frivolous attacks 5 . Official discipline goes further, and applies in cases where the ordinary law could find no sufficient ground for a charge, and even in cases where it would have acquitted the accused. It extends to all the faults and negligences of the functionary, even to his private life, so far as that may injure the honour and confidence which his office should receive 6 . Disciplinary punishments are either slight, such as warn- ing, reprimand, and limited fine ; or they are severe, such as suspension from office, removal to another place, com- pulsory retirement, or dismissal. The infliction of the slighter punishments is one of the ordinary powers of the superior officials, and requires no special legal proceed- ing. The severer, on the other hand, require a legal proceeding in order to protect the rights of officials against 4 According to the Imperial Law, Uber die Einfiihrung des Gerichts- verfassungsgesetzes, n, those laws of the various particular States (Landesgesetze} remain in force which make the civil or criminal prose- cution of an official, on account of any act committed directly or indirectly in the exercise of his office, depend on a previous decision (Vorentsckeidtmg}. Such previous decision can, however, only deter- mine whether the official has exceeded the powers of his office or has omitted a duty incumbent upon him. In those German States in which there is a Supreme Court of Administration this decision is pronounced by such court, in the other States by the Imperial Court. Federal laws of this sort exist in Prussia, Bavaria, Baden, Hesse, &c. (cp. Loning, Verwaltungsrecht ', p. 126). In France the requirement of a previous decision has been abolished by the decree of Sept. 19, 1870. On the nature of discipline as distinct from punishment of officials very different views are held. Cp. Loning, op. cit. p. 127 ff. 5 Fischel, Verfassung Englands, p. 351 ; Homersham Cox, English Institutions [? pp. 442, 457, edit. 1863. The Attorney-General can stay proceedings.] The history of the Negro revolt in Jamaica shows how difficult it is even in England to carry on a successful prosecution against powerful officials, even for frightful misuse of authority. Cp. Gneist, Engl. Verwaltungsrecht, p. 376 ff. [On the contrast between the French and English practice see Dicey, Law of the Constitution (ed. 3), ch. xii : ' The rule of law contrasted with droit administratif!'] 6 Reichsbeamtengesetz of 1873, 70. 544 SOVEREIGNTY AND ITS ORGANS. an arbitrary use of power. In many States the punishment of dismissal can only be inflicted by the ordinary law courts ; but ordinary justice is apt to judge the fault as if it were only that of a private citizen, to take too much account of the man, and too little of the official. This system places the interest of the official for the time being above the permanent interest of the office and of the State, the rights of the individual above the rights of the community. A court of justice which has to decide on a matter of such public importance must be composed in such a way as to be able to appreciate the interests involved. Failing such a court, the right of dismissal must remain in the hands of the higher government officials 7 . 7 Reichsbeamtengesetz of 1873, 76. CHAPTER XI. TERMINATION OF PUBLIC SERVICE. OFFICE does not exist for the sake of the official, so that i. Suppres- if an office comes to be suppressed, the official can no office, longer remain such. Public interest alone must settle the nature and continuance of an office, but the suppression of an office does not put an end to the claims of the official to his maintenance, which continue as long as they would have done if the office had not been abolished. Since the acceptance or refusal of office is usually a matter of free choice, so also is resignation ; but the two are not quite on the same level. The freedom of under- taking an obligation does not imply the freedom of shaking it off. In a case where the ability and good-will of the individual are so important as in public offices, compulsory continuance of service is inexpedient 3 . On the other hand, where acceptance of office is a compulsory civic duty, its continuance, at least for a definite period, is likewise com- pulsory 2 . Resignation does not of itself bring the duties of an 2. Resigna- tion. 1 Prussian Landrecht^ ii. 10. 95 : 'The resignation of an official shall only be refused if the general welfare should seriously suffer by its being accepted.' Bavarian Edict of 1818, 22: 'Any one in the service of the State may resign when he pleases without assigning any reason : but in such a case he loses all his salary as well as the title and insignia of office.' 2 Thus in England the sheriff (scire-gerefa] who has held the office for a year is free from the obligation of taking it for the next three years. Blackstone's Commentaries , i. 9. I. N n 546 SOVEREIGNTY AND ITS ORGANS. [Book VII. office to an end. An arbitrary abandonment of office would be desertion. Resignation is only a means of mov- ing the State to withdraw the office it has given. Official duties are not at an end before the State has accepted the resignation, and the time when they terminate may be fixed by the authorities according to public convenience. Termination of office in consequence of simple resigna- tion puts an end to the private as well as the political rights attached to it. 3 . Retire- It is otherwise if a public servant has the right of de- manding to be placed on the retired list (Quiesrirung, Inruhestandsetzung). This puts an end to the public powers of the official, but leaves him his rank, title, and a claim to payment. The amount of pension is commonly regulated according to age or length of service. The right to a retiring pension is based partly on advanced age (in Bavaria 70, in Prussia, Wiirtemberg, Saxony, Belgium, 65 years) combined with long service (30 to 40 years), partly on incapacity arising e. g. from ill health. The latter only constitutes a legal claim to a pension if it has been brought on by the service itself, for in such a case the State is bound to compensate the injuries incurred in the exercise of public duties 3 . 4 . Dismissal. Involuntary dismissal is differently regulated in different countries. In the time of the old German Empire [the Holy Roman Empire], through the influence of jurists, the private rights of the officials were brought into great prominence. Office was considered as a right bestowed usually for life, and not to be withdrawn, except for viola- tion of duty, by a judicial decision 4 . There were indeed 3 Zacharia, D. St. 142, collects some rules on this point in German States. Cp. Loning, Venvaltungsrecht, p. 134 f. As to Belgium, cp. the Law of July 31, 1844. 4 This is formally expressed in the electoral capitulation (Wahl- capitulation] of 1792 as to the members of the aulic council of the Empire (Reichshofrath\ 10 : ' No councillor can be dismissed except after judicial examination of the case, and by a sentence based thereon.' Cp. also the decision of the Deputation of the Empire {Reichsdeputa- tions-Hauptschluss} of 1803, 91. Chap. XI.] TERMINATION OF PUBLIC SERVICE. 547 some protests that an honourable dismissal might be justi- fied from grounds of public interest, but towards the end of the last century the first opinion was more and more widely diffused ; and in many modern constitutions this principle was proclaimed as an advance in liberty and an important guarantee against arbitrary government, not only in Ger- many 4a , but more recently even in Switzerland, where most offices are only bestowed for limited periods. In England, on the other hand, party struggles have long kept the political consciousness awake to the fact that office is given chiefly for the sake of the State, and not of the in- dividual : so much so that the principle became established that the head of the State had full right of taking away as of bestowing office. An exception was introduced in the case of the judges,, in order to ensure their independence. Under William III it was decided that the common law judges should not be appointed as before, i durante bene plaritoj but ( quam diu bene gesserintj the King and Parliament remaining the sole judges of good conduct 5 . The United States of North America adopted similar principles 6 . In France administrative officials have always remained liable to dismissal at will, though from the fifteenth century judges have been irremoveable. As a matter of fact, however, even in France, officials enjoy a tolerably secure position, except in revolutionary times 7 . The German system exaggerates the importance of private rights, but if these are not made to override the welfare of the State, it has advantages over the arbitrary practice of other constitutional States. It assures the private interest 4 1 Bavaria is the only German country in which the ordinary Criminal courts alone can dismiss administrative officials : in the other states dismissal is regarded as a disciplinary punishment. So too in the Empire. Cp. Reichsbeamtengesetz of 1873, 84, 86. 5 Statute 13 Will. III. cap. 3. Until the time of George III the office of judge was terminated by the death of the king. Cp. Gneist, EngL Verwaltungsrecht, p. 236 ff. 6 Cp. Story, iii. 38. 228. 7 Vivien, Etud. Administr. i. 260 f. N n 2 548 SOVEREIGNTY AND ITS ORGANS. [Book vil. of the functionary, and secures the State against party agitation and caprice. In any case it is a fundamental principle that the office exists for the State, and therefore the State can in the public interest dismiss and replace an official. These two rights naturally belong to the same person, i. e. in case of doubt, to the head of the State 8 . This must be recognised even in those States in which only the law courts have the power of dismissal, so far as deprivation of office has merely politi- cal (and not also personal) consequences 9 . These rules admit of two restrictions, (i) in behalf of the independence of the judges, (2) in the interest of the func- tionaries themselves. In modern times the principle is commonly recognised that judges can neither be dismissed nor transferred against their will, and cannot be put on the retired list without retaining their full salary. In England judges can only be removed by a decision of Parliament, in Germany by a judicial sentence 10 . With regard to the second restriction, different cases must be distinguished. The reasons for removing an official may be (a) A crime, which shows his moral unfitness for the office. (fr) Proved moral incapacity (negligence, cowardice, &c.) without crime. 8 The President of the United States of North America had, by the Law of 1789, the sole right of removing officials, who could not be appointed without the concurrence of the Senate (Story, iii. 37. 119). This was illogical, but was not altered till 1867. * Zacharia, 144. There are however some States which do not recognise this principle, and even go so far as to make office for a certain time irrevocable on public grounds. 10 Bavarian Constitution, viii. 3 : ' Judges cannot be removed with loss of salary except by a judicial sentence.' Belgian Constitution, Art. 100 : 'Judges are appointed for life. No judge can be deprived of his place or suspended except by a judicial sentence. A judge cannot be transferred except by a new nomination and with his con- sent.' Spanish Const. Art. 10 : Portuguese Const. Art. 120-123: Austrian Fundamental Law (Statsgrundgesetz] of Dec. 21, 1867, Art. 6 : Prussian Const. 87 : Rechtsgesetz uber die Gerichisverfas- sung, 8. Chap. XL] TERMINATION OF PUBLIC SERVICE. 549 (c) Intellectual incapacity, e. g. loss of memory, insanity, &c. (d) External circumstances which injure an official's activity or deprive him of public confidence, a case which may occur, in times of agitation or through foreign compli- cations, to an official who has fulfilled his duty, nay, even just because he has done so. Thus the minister Stein was dismissed to please Napoleon I. In all these cases the State must possess the means of protecting itself against injury by removing officials. It is only in the first of these (a) that the law courts are adapted to decide the matter according to their ordinary procedure. A judicial removal brings with it loss of title, rank, salary, and claim to pension. The second case (<) is more a matter for official discipline than for the ordinary courts, but the official must always have the opportunity of defending himself. According to the greater or less degree of his fault, there will follow dis- missal, with loss of all claim to salary, but without any injury to his remaining political rights, or he will merely be placed on the retired list with a suitable pension. In the latter case the government can obviously act more freely, because the private rights of the official are not affected. The third case (c) justifies compulsory retirement as a rule, but not dismissal, the official not being himself to blame. The fourth case (d] may be met either by compulsory retirement or by transference to a different post of the same character, dignity, and emolument. These two last cases should be referred to the highest authorities in the government, and when the appointment is made by the chief of the State, his assent or command should be required for removal. A purely arbitrary removal without reason assigned, and without opportunity of defence, is still practised in several States, but is not in accordance with a well ordered system. Temporary suspension may be inflicted either as a penalty s : Suspen or as a measure of prudence. In the former case it may be 550 SOVEREIGNTY AND ITS ORGANS. inflicted either by the law courts, or as a measure of disci- pline by a competent authority. It usually implies loss or reduction of salary for the time it lasts. As a provisional measure it may be provided by the law beforehand in certain cases, e.g. because of a criminal charge, but it may also be adopted by the authorities as a means of withdrawing an unpopular official from the storm he has excited. Suspension should not involve loss of private rights, except when it is a punishment : the official should retain that part of his emolument which has a private character, especially his maintenance (Standesgehalt\ If he is suspended on account of a criminal charge he shall retain these private rights, though the court may order the retention of his salary, as a guarantee for the fine and damages to which he may be made liable, but not until he is condemned is his claim for future payment at an end 11 . 11 Cp. Zacharia, 145 against Heffter. THE END. ClarenOon press, SDrforix RECENT HISTORICAL WORKS. THE CONSTITUTIONAL HISTOR Y OF ENGLAND, IN ITS Origin and Development. By WILLIAM STUBBS, D.D., Lord Bishop of Chester. 3 vols. demy 8vo, 2!. Ss. ; or 3 vols. crown 8vo, 12s. each. SELECT CHARTERS AND OTHER ILLUSTRATIONS OF English Constitutional History, from the Earliest Times to the Reign of Edward I. Arranged and Edited by W. STUBBS, D.D. Fourth Edition. Crown 8vo, Ss. 6d. THE HISTORY OF SICILY FROM THE EARLIEST TIMES. By E. A. FREEMAN, D.C.L. Vols. I and II, 8vo, 2!. 2s. Vol. Ill, The Athenian and Carthaginian Invasions, I/. 4$-. A HISTORY OF THE NORMAN CONQUEST OF ENGLAND, its Causes and Results. By the same Author. 6 vols. 8vo, 5/. 9.$-. 6d. THE REIGN OF WILLIAM RUFUS AND THE ACCESSION of Henry the First. By the same Author. 2 vols. 8vo, i/. i6s. ROGER'S HISTORY OF AGRICULTURE AND PRICES IN England, A. D. 1259-1793. Vols. I-IV (1259-1582), 4/. 13.$-. THE GOVERNANCE OF ENGLAND. By Sir John Fortescue, Kt, sometime Lord Chief Justice of the King's Bench. A revised text, edited with Introduction, Critical and Historical Notes, Glossary, &c., by CHARLES PLUMMER, M.A., Fellow and Chaplain of Corpus Christi College, Oxford. 8vo, half-bound^ I2S. 6d. GASCOIGNE'S THEOLOGICAL DICTIONARY ("Liber Veri- tatum ") : Selected Passages, illustrating the condition of Church and State, 1403-1458. With an Introduction by JAMES E. THOROLD ROGERS, MJ*. Small 4to, IQ.J. 6d. [P. T. o. CONSTITUTIONAL DOCUMENTS OF THE PURITAN Revolution, 1628-1660. Selected and Edited by SAMUEL RAWSON GARDINER, M.A. Crown, 8vo, 9^. A HISTORY OF ENGLAND, PRINCIPALLY IN THE SEVEN- teenth Century. By LEOPOLD VON RANKE. Translated by Resident Members of the University of Oxford, under the superintendence of G. W. KITCHIN, D.D., and C. W. BOASE, M.A. 6 vols. 8vo, 3/. y. WELLESLEY DESPATCHES. A SELECTION FROM THE Despatches, Treaties, and other Papers of the Marquess Wellesley, K.G., during his Government of India. Edited by S. J. OWEN, M.A., formerly Professor of History in the Elphinstone College, Bombay. 8vo, i/. 4?. WELLINGTON DESPATCHES. A SELECTION FROM THE Despatches, Treaties, and other Papers relating to India of Field- Marshall the Duke of Wellington, K.G. By the same Editor. 8vo, i/. 4r. A HISTOR Y OF FRANCE. By G. W. KITCHIN, D.D., Dean of Winchester. Second Edition. 3 vols. crown 8vo, i/. us. 6d. GENEALOGICAL TABLES ILLUSTRATIVE OF MODERN History. By H. B. GEORGE, M.A. Second Edition. Small 4to, i2s. A HISTORY OF GREECE, FROM ITS CONQUEST BY THE Romans to the present time, B.C. 146 to A.D. 1864. By GEORGE FINLAY, LL.D. A new Edition, revised throughout, and in part re- written, with considerable additions, by the Author, and edited by H. F. TOZER, M.A., Fellow and Tutor of Exeter College, Oxford. 7 vols. Svo, 3/. icxr. ITALY AND HER INVADERS, A.D. 376-553. By T. HODGKIN, Fellow of University College, London, Hon. D.C.L. of Durham Uni- versity. Illustrated with Plates and Maps. 4 vols. Svo, 3/. 8*. LONDON : HENRY FROWDE OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS WAREHOUSE AMEN CORNER, E.G. UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA LLL -v/kRY BERKELEY Return to desk from which borrowed. This book is DUE on the last date stamped below. FEB 17 1948 4Aug49LR '50PM TlOec 1 ! JUKI i9S2 \t: R UG 9 1953 3 #53 m 3Jun'55HJ JAN 1 & 1956 LU m LD 21-100m-9,'47(A5702sl6)476 HM 3Apr'60CT REC'D LD