PHILOSOPHY 6 SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON, BART,, PEOFESSOE OF LOGIC AND METAPHYSICS IN EDINBUEGH VNIVEESITY ; 0. W. WIGHT, TBANSLATOR OF COUSIN'S " HISTORY OF MODERN PHILOSOPHY.' FOE THE USE OF SCHOOLS AND COLLEGES. NoSs ip?) KOI NoCf aKovei, raAXa %(i)$(l KO.I TV\d. Mind it seeth, Mind it heareth ; all beside is deaf and blind. EPICHAEMOT (?). NEW YORK: D. APPLETON & COMPANY, 200 BROADWAY. M DCCC Lin. Entered according to Act of Congress, in the year 1853, BY D. APPLETON & COMPANY, In the Clerk's Office of the District Court of the United States for the Southern District of New York. 3 TO REV. LAURENS P. HICKOK, D. D., VICE-PRESIDENT OP UNION COLLEGE, LATE PROFESSOR OF CHRISTIAN THEOLOGY IN AUBURN THEOLOGICAL SEMINARY, AUTHOR OF " RATIONAL PSYCHOLOGY," ETC., ETC., THIS COLLECTION OF SIR WM. HAMILTON'S PHILOSOPHICAL DISCUSSIONS AND DISSERTATIONS, %s BeUfcateH; 2 O AS A TOKEN OF TUE EDITOR S ADMIRATION OF ONE OF THE VERY ABLEST METAPHYSICIANS AMERICA HAS PRODUCED; AS A TRIBUTE JUSTLY DUE TO THE FAITHFUL TEACHER, WHO HAS DEVOTED MANY YEARS OF HIS LIFE TO PREPARING YOUNG MEN FOR HIGH PUBLIC DUTIES, O t O THUS FULFILLING TIIE RESPONSIBLE OFFICE OF A "KEEPER OF THE KEEPERS." 43200 S PREFACE. IN this publication we give to the readers and students of philosophy in America all, except part of an unfin- ished Dissertation, that Sir "Wm. Hamilton has pub- lished directly on the subject of metaphysics. The com- pleted supplementary Dissertations on Reid, 1 the foot- notes to Reid that have an enduring interest, and the philosophical portion of the 'Discussions, 2 etc.,' have been used to make up this work. The article on Logic and the Appendix Logical, in the Discussions, might have been added, but these do not properly belong to the metaphysical system of Hamilton, and, moreover, have been reserved for another purpose. The place where each part of this volume may be found in the work from which it is taken, has been designated by a foot-note. In our collection and arrangement of Hamilton's Phi- losophy, we have followed a systematic plan. Any ex- planation or vindication of this plan would be, to those who are unacquainted with Sir Wm.'s system, unintel- 1 The works of Thomas Reid, D. D., now fully collected, with selec- tions from his unpublished letters. Preface, Notes, and Supplementary Dissertations, by Sir Wm. Hamilton, Bart. London and Edinburgh : Third Edition, 1852 : pp. 914 (not completed). 2 Discussions on Philosophy and Literature, Education and University Reform. By Sir Win. Hamilton, Bart. London and Edinburgh, 1852: pp. 758. b PREFACE. ligible ; to those who have mastered its principles, su- perfluous. Our foot-notes are not very numerous, and consist mostly in references to other parts of the work, where some point indicated is more fully treated ; and in explanations of a few, more than usually difficult, pas- sages. In a single instance we have expressed our dis- sent from a position taken by Hamilton, the grounds of which we have briefly designated, without entering upon a systematic discussion. A severer study may convince us that Sir Win. is right and that we are wrong. Hamilton has promised a General Preface to his Reid, and a Sequel of the Dissertations. When these appear, they will be added to this work in a separate volume, in which the Indices will be given to the whole. New York, June, 1853. INTRODUCTION. WE do not propose to give here a resume of Sir Win. Hamilton's philosophy. A correct list, in technical language, of the principles of his system, would not be a clear exposition of his metaphysical doctrines. To attempt to put in a brief introduction the substance of several hundred pages of Hamilton's Philosophical Discussions and Dissertations would be presumptuous and preposterous. A philoso- pher, who thinks like Aristotle ; whose logic is as stern as that of St. Thomas, 'the lawgiver of the Church;' who rivals Muretns as a critic ; whose erudition finds a parallel only in that of the younger Scaliger ; whose subtlety of thought and polemical power remind us of the dauntless prince 1 of Verona ; Avhose penetrating analysis reaches deeper than that of Kant, such a one, it it our pleasure to introduce to the students of philosophy in America ; who, in a style severely elegant, with accuracy of statement, with precision of definition, in sequence and admirable order, will explain a system in many respects new, a system that will provoke thought, that, consequently, carries in itself the germs of beneficial revolutions in literature and educa- tion, in all those things that are produced and regulated by miud in action. True to our plan of making the work as completely Hamilton's as possible, we shall offer, mostly in the language of our author, a few considerations on the utility of the study of phi- losophy. Philosophy is a necessity. Every man philosophizes as he thinks. The worth of his philosophy will depend upon the value of his think- ing. ' If to philosophize be right,' says Aristotle, in his Exhortative, we must philosophize to realize the right; if to philosophize be 1 The elder Scaliger. 8 INTRODUCTION. wrong, we must philosophize to manifest the wrong : on any alterna- tive, therefore, philosophize we must." No philosopher can explore the whole realm of truth. No single mind can compass the aggregate of what is possessed by all. Every system must, then, he incomplete ; it cannot be taken as an equiva- lent for all that can be thought. The most that any system can do for us is to aid us, to stimulate our minds, to infuse higher intellectual energy. ' If the accomplishment of philosophy,' says Hamilton (Db. p. 39, et seq.), 'imply a cessation of discussion if the result of specu- lation be a paralysis of itself, the consummation of knowledge is the condition of intellectual barbarism. Plato has profoundly defined man " the hunter of truth ;" for in this chase as in others, the pursuit is all in all, the success comparatively nothing. " Did the Almighty, 1 ' says Lessing, " holding in his right hand Truth, and in his left, Search after Truth, deign to proffer me the one I might prefer, in all hu- mility, but without hesitation, I should request Search after Truth." 1 We exist only as we energize; pleasure* is the reflex of unimpeded energy ; energy is the mean by which our faculties are developed ; and a higher energy the end which their development proposes. In action is thus contained the existence, happiness, improvement, and perfection of our being ; and knowledge is only previous, as it may afford a stimulus to the exercise of our powers, and the condition of their more complete activity. Speculative truth is, therefore, sub- ordinate to speculation itself; and its value is directly measured by the quantity of energy which it occasions immediately in its dis- covery mediately through its consequences. Life to Endymiou was not preferable to death ; aloof from practice, a waking error is better than a sleeping truth. Neither, in point of fact, is there found any proportion between the possession of truths, and the development of the mind in which they are deposited. Every learner in science is now familiar with more truths than Aristotle or Plato ever dreamt of knowing; yet, compared with the Stagirite or the Athenian, how few among our masters of modern science rank higher than intel- lectual barbarians ! Ancient Greece and modern Europe prove, in- deed, that the " march of intellect" is no inseparable concomitant of ' E/ ftiv t\oooao(pt)Ttov' xal si ft!) i\i,aoif>i}rio vdvriaf Spa i\ooo$ririov. * Aristotle defined happiness, Energizing according to virtue. It results from th healthy, unimpeded activity of every element of eur nature. W. INTfiODUCTION. 9 " the march of science ;" that the cultivation of the individual is not to be rashly confounded with the progress of the species. ' But if the possession of theoretical facts be not convertible with mental improvement, and if the former be important only as subser- vient to the latter, it follows that the comparative utility of a study is not to be principally estimated by the complement of truths which it may communicate, but by the degree in which it determines our higher capacities to action. But though this be the standard by which the different methods, the different branches, and the different masters of philosophy ought to be principally (and it is the only criterion by which they can all be satisfactorily) tried, it is never- theless a standard by which neither methods, nor sciences, nor phi- losophers, have ever yet been even inadequately appreciated. The critical history of philosophy, in this spirit, has still to be written ; and when written, how opposite will be the rank which, on the higher and more certain standard, it will frequently adjudge to the various branches of knowledge, and the various modes of their culti- vation to the different ages, and countries, and individuals, from that which has been hitherto partially awarded, on the vacillating authority of the lower ! ' On this ground (which we have not been able fully to state, far less adequately to illustrate), we rest the pre-eminent utility of meta- physical speculations. That they comprehend all the sublimest ob- jects of our theoretical and moral interest ; that every (natural) con- clusion concerning God, the soul, the present worth and future des- tiny of man, is exclusively metaphysical, will be at once admitted. But we do not found the importance on the paramount dignity ot the pursuit. It is as the best gymnastic of the mind as a mean principally and almost exclusively conducive to the highest education of our noblest powers, that we would vindicate to these speculation the necessity, which has too frequently been denied them. By no other intellectual application (and least of all by physical pursuits) is the soul thus reflected on itself, and its faculties concentrated in such independent, vigorous, unwonted, and continued energy ; by none, therefore, are its best capacities so variously and intensely evolved. " Where there is most life, there is the victory." ' Let it not be believed that the mighty minds who have cultivated these studies,, have toiled in vain. If they have not always realized truth, they have always determined exertion ; and in the genial elo- 1* 10 INTRODUCTION. queuce of the elder Scaliger : u Eio subtilitates, quanquam sint auimi.s otiosis atqiie inutiles, vegetis tniueii ingcniis summain cognoscendi afferunt voloptateui,* sitffl, scilicet in fastigio ejus sapiential, qiuo forum oinniuin principia contemplatur. Et quainvis liannn iudagatio non sit utilis ad machinas farinarias conliciendas ; exuit tamen ani- muin iu.scit'ue rubigine, acuitque ad alia. Eo denique splendoro ailicit, ut pncluceat sibi ad uanciscendum primi opiticis similitudinem. Qui, ut oiunia pleue ac perfects cst, at prroter et supra oinuia ; ita eos, qui scientiarum studios! sunt, suos esse voluit, ipsorumque intellectinn reruiu dominum constituit.'" 'The practical danger which has sometimes been apprehended from metaphysical pursuits, has in reality only been found to follow from their stunted and partial cultivation. The poison has grown up ; the antidote has been repressed. In Britain and in Germany, where speculation lias remained comparatively free, the dominant result has been highly favorable to religion 2 and morals; whilst the evils which arose in France, arose from the benumbing influence of a one effete philosophy ; a and have, in point of fact, mainly been corrected by the awakened spirit of metaphysical inquiry itself.' Hamilton again says (' Discussions-,' p. 696, et seq.) : ' Yet is Philoso- phy (the science of science the theory of what we can know and think and do, in a word, the knowledge of ourselves), the object of liberal education, at once of paramount importance in itself, and the requisite condition of every other liberal science. If men are really 1 Bacon, himself, the great champion of physical pursuits, says: 'Those sciences are not to be regarded as useless, -which, considered in themselves, are valueless, if they sharpen the mind and reduce it to order. Hume, Burke, Knnt, Stewart, &c., might be quoted to the same effect Compare Aristotle, Metapli. I. 2, Eth. Nic. v. 7. 2 The philosophers of Germany, not as it is generally supposed in this country, and even by those who ought to know, have been more orthodox than the divines. Fichte, who was, for his country and his times, a singularly pious Christian, was persecuted by the theologians, on account of his orthodoxy. IK 3 'Since the mctaphysic of Locke,' says M. Cousin, in 1S10, 'crossed the channel on the light and brilliant wings of Voltaire's imagination, sensualism has reigned in France without contradiction, and with an authority of which there is no parallel in the whole history of philosophy. It is a fact, marvellous but incontestable, that from the time of Condillac, there has not appeared among us any philosophical work, at variance with his doctrine, which has produced the smallest impression on the public mind. Condillao thus reigned in peace ; and his domination, prolonged even to our own days, through changes of every kind, pursued its tranquil course, apparently above the reach of dan- ger. Discussion had closed : his disciples had only to develop the words of their master : philosophy seemed accomplished.' (Journal des Savan-s.) During the reign of sen- sualism in France, religion languished, for she was deprived of the aid of her most ef- ficient servant philosophy. W. INTKODUCTION. 11 to know aught else, the human faculties, by which alone this knowl- edge may be realized, must be studied for themselves, in their extent and in their limitations. To know, we must understand our in- strument of knowing. " Know thyself" is, in fact, a heavenly precept, in Christianity as in heathenism. And this knowledge can be com- passed only by reflection, only from within : " Ne te qusesieris extra." It tells us at once of our weakness and our worth ; it is the discipline both of humility and hope. On the other hand, a knowl- edge, drawn too exclusively from without, is not only imperfect in itself, but makes its votaries fatalists, materialists, pantheists if they dare to think ; it is the dogmatism of despair. " Laudabilior," says Augustin, "laudabilior est animus, cui nota est infirmitas propria, quam qui, ea non respecta, mcenia mundi, vias siderum, ftmdamenta terrarum et fastigia coelorum, etiam cogniturus, scrutatur." We can know God only as we know ourselves. " Xoverim me, noverim Te," is St. Austin's prayer ; St. Bernard : " Principale, ad videndum Deum, est animus rationalis intuens seipsum ;" and even Averroes : " Nosce teipsum, et cognosces creatorem tuum." ' ]STor is the omission of philosophy from an academical curriculum equivalent to an arrest on the philosophizing activity of the student. This stupor, however deplorable in itself, might still be a minor evil ; for it is better, assuredly, to be without opinions, than to have them, not only superlatively untrue, but practically corruptive. Yet, even this paralysis, I say, is not accomplished. Eight or wrong, a man must philosophize, for he philosophizes as he thinks ; and the only eifect, in the present day especially, of a University denying to its alumni the invigorating exercise of a right philosophy, is their aban- donment, not only without precaution, but even prepared by debili- tation, to the pernicious influence of a wrong : " Sine vindice prseda." And in what country has a philosophy ever gravitating, as theoretical towards materialism, as practical towards fatalism, been most pecu- liar and pervasive ? 4 Again : Philosophy, the thinking of thought, the recoil of mind upon itself, is the most improving of mental exercises, conducing, above all others, to evolve the highest and rarest of the intellectual powers. By this, the mind is not only trained to philosophy proper, but prepared, in general, for powerful, easy, and successful energy, in whatever department of knowledge it may more peculiarly apply itself. But the want of this superior discipline is but too apparent in 12 INTRODUCTION. English [American] literature, and especially in those very fields of erudition by preference cultivated in England [America]. * Of English [American] scholars as a class, both now and for gen- erations past, the observation of Godfrey Hermann holds good : u They read but do not think ; they would be philologers, and have not learned to philosophize." The philosophy of a philology is shown primarily in its grammars, and its grammars for the use of schools. But in this respect, England [America] remained, till lately, nearly two centuries behind the rest of Christendom. If there were any principle in her pedagogical practice, "Gaudent sudoribus artes," must have been the rule ; and applied it was with a vengeance. The English [American] schoolboy was treated like the Russian pack- horse ; the load in one pannier was balanced by a counter-weight of stones in the other. . . . The unhappy tyro was initiated in Latin, through a Latin book ; while the ten declensions, the thirteen conjugations, which had been reduced to three and two by Weller and Lancelot, still continued, among a mass of other abomina- tions, to complicate, in this country, the elementary instruction of Greek. . . . But all has now been changed except the cause : for the same iuertion of original and independent thought is equally ap- parent. As formerly, from want of thinking, the old sufficed; so now, from want of thinking, the new is borrowed. In fact, openly or occultly, honorably or dishonorably, the far greater part of the higher and lower philology published in this country is an importation, especially from Germany : but so passive is the ignorance of our compilers, that they are often (though affecting, of course, opin- ions), unaware even of what is best worthy of plagiarism or trans- plantation. ' Theology Christian theology is, as a human science, a philology and history applied by philosophy ; and the comparatively ineffectual character of our British [American] theology has, for generations, mainly resulted from the deficiency of its philosophical element. The want of a philosophical training in the Anglican [American] clergy. to be regretted at all times, may soon, indeed, become lamentably apparent, were they called on to resist an invasion, now so likely, of certain foreign philosophico- theological opinions. 1 In fact, this is the 1 This invasion has already come with us. Dr. Hickok and a few others, who alone see the real danger, have faced it manfully and well armed. .The spirit of the Absolute, which has found its way hither through various channels, from the country of Scholling INTRODUCTION. 13 invasion, and this the want of national preparation, for which even at the present juncture, I should be most alarmed. On the Universities, 1 which have illegally dropped philosophy and its training from their course of discipline, will lie the responsibility of this singular and dangerous disarmature.' We commend Hamilton's philosophy to educators, not only for its great excellence as a metaphysical system, for its profound thought and affluent erudition, for its spirit of free inquiry, and, consequently, its power' to quicken the mind; but, above all, we commend it for its accordance with the principles of revealed religion. Sir Wm., though metaphysically the ' most formidable man in Europe,' is an humble Christian ; though the most learned of men, he is ready to bow be- fore the spirit that ' informed' the mind of Paul. Hamilton says that he is confident that his philosophy is founded upon truth. ' To this confidence I have come, not merely through the convictions of my own consciousness, but by finding in this system a centre and con- ciliation for the most opposite of philosophical opinions. Above all, however, I am confirmed in my belief, by the harmony between the doctrines of this philosophy, and those of revealed truth. " Credo equidem, nee von fides." The philosophy of the Conditioned is indeed pre-eminently a discipline of humility ; a " learned ignorance," directly opposed to the false " knowledge which puffeth up." I may say with St. Chrysostom : " The foundation of our philosophy is humility."- (Homil. de Perf. Evang.) For it is professedly a scientific demon- stration of the impossibility of that " wisdom in high matters" which the apostle prohibits us even to attempt ; and it proposes, from the limitations of the human powers, from our impotence to comprehend what, however, we must admit, to show articulately why the " secret things of God" cannot but be to man " past finding out." Humility thus becomes the cardinal virtue, not only of revelation, but of reason. This scheme proves, moreover, that no difficulty emerges in theology, which had not previously emerged in philosophy ; that in fact, if the divine do not transcend what it has pleased the Deity to reveal, and wilfully indentify the doctrine of God's word with some arrogant ex- and Hegel, will not be exorcised by a solemn reading of creeds, and by repeating some stereotyped theological phrases ; it must be brought into the clear white light of thought ; like every other spectre of the night, it will vanish at the real dawn. W. 1 Our American colleges, instead of having 'dropped philosophy and its training from their course of discipline,' have never seriously taken it tip. W. 14: INTRODUCTION. treme of human speculation, philosophy will bo found the most use- ful auxiliary of theology. For a world of false, and pestilent, and presumptuous reasoning, by which philosophy and theology are now equally discredited, would be at once abolished, in the recognition of this rule of prudent nescience; nor could it longer be too justly said of the code of consciousness, as by reformed divines it has been ac- knowledged of the Bible : "This is the book, where each his dogma seeks; And this the book, where each his dogma finds." ' CONTENTS. PART FIRST. THE PHILOSOPHY OP COMMON SENSE ; OR, OUR PRIMARY BE- LIEFS CONSIDERED AS THE ULTIMATE CRITERION OF TRUTH. SECTION I. The Meaning of the Doctrine, and Purport of the Argu- ment, of Common Sense 19 II. The Conditions of the Legitimacy, and legitimate applica- tion, of the argument 86 III. That it is one strictly Philosophical and scientific 41 IV. The Essential Characters by which our primary beliefs, or the principles of Common Sense, are discriminated 47 V. The Nomenclature, that is, the various appellations by which these have been designated 50 VI. The Universality of the philosophy of Common Sense; or its general recognition, in reality and in name, shown by a chronological series of Testimonies from the dawn of speculation to the present day , 85 PART SECOND. PHILOSOPHY OF PERCEPTION. CHAPTER I. ELUCIDATION or REID'S DOCTRINE or PERCEPTION, AND ITS DEFENCE AGAINST SIR THOMAS BROWN 165 CHAPTER II. PRESEXTATIVE AND REPRESENTATIVE KNOWLEDGE. SECTION I. The distinction of Presentative, Intuitive, or Immediate, and of Representative or Mediate cognition ; with the va- rious significations of the term Object, its conjugates and correlatives 233 II. Errors of Reid and other Philosophers, in reference to the preceding distinctions 256 16 CONTENTS. CHAPTER IIL VARIOUS THEORIES OF EXTERNAL PERCEPTION. SECTION I. Systematic Schemes, from different points of view, of the various theories of the relation of External Perception to its Object; and of the various systems of Philosophy founded thereon 265 II. What is the character, in this respect, of Reid's doctrine of Perception ? 272 CHAPTER IV. DOCTRINE OF PERCEPTION MAINTAINED BY THE ABSO- LUTE IDEALISTS. DISCUSSION ON THE SCHEME OF ARTHUR COLLIER.. 285 CHAPTER V. DISTINCTION OF THE PRIMARY AND SECONDARY QUALITIES OF BODY. SECTION I. Historically considered 806 II. Critically considered. Three classes (Primary, Secundo- Primary, and Secondary Qualities) established 852 CHAPTER VI. PERCEPTION PROPER AND SENSATION PROPER. SECTION I. Principal momenta of the Editor's doctrine of Perception, (A) in itself, and (B) in contrast to that of Reid, Stewart, Royer-Collard, and other philosophers of the Scottish School 412 II. Historical notices in regard to the distinction of Perceptio* proper and Sensation proper 482 PART THIRD. PHILOSOPHY OF THE CONDITIONED. CHAPTER I. REFUTATION OF THE VARIOUS DOCTRINES OF THB UNCON- DITIONED, ESPECIALLY OF COUSIN'S DOCTRINE OF THE INFINITO- ABSO- LUTE 441 CHAPTER II. LIMITATION OF THOUGHT AND KNOWLEDGE. SECTION I. A Doctrine of the Relative ; tho Categories of Thought 484 II. Philosophical Testimonies to the Limitation of our Knowl- edge, from the Limitation of our Faculties 517 PAET FIRST. PHILOSOPHY COMMON SENSE. \\ "THERE is nothing that can pretend to judge of Reason but itself: and, therefore, they who suppose that they ran say aught against it, are forced (like jewellers, who beat true diamonds to powder to cut and polish false ones), to make use of it against itself. But in this they cheat themselves as well as others. For if what they say against Reason, be without Reason, they deserve to be neglected ; and if with Reason, they disprove them- selves. For they use it while they disclaim it; and with as much contra- diction, as if a man should tell me that he cannot speak." AUTHOR OF HCDIBRAS (Reflections upon Reason). PHILOSOPHY OF COMMON SENSE, 1 OR, OUR PRIMARY BELIEFS CONSIDERED AS THE ULTIMATE CRITERION OF TRUTH. I. THE MEANING OF THE DOCTRINE, AND PURPORT OF THE ARGUMENT, OF COMMON SENSE. IN the conception and application of the doctrine of Common Sense, the most signal mistakes have been committed ; and much unfounded prejudice has been excited against the argument which it affords, in consequence of the erroneous views which have been held in regard to its purport and conditions. What is the veritable character of this doctrine, it is, therefore, necessary to consider. Our cognitions, it is evident, are not all at second hand. Con- sequents cannot, by an infinite regress, be evolved out of ante- cedents, which are themselves only consequents. Demonstration, if proof be possible, behooves us to repose at last on propositions, which, carrying their own evidence, necessitate their own admis- sion ; and which being, as primary, inexplicable, as inexplicable, incomprehensible, must consequently manifest themselves less in the character of cognitions than of facts, of which consciousness assures us under the simple form of feeling or belief. Without at present attempting to determine the character, number, and relations waiving, in short, all attempt at an artic- 1 The Philosophy of Common Sense properly comes first in Hamilton's System, for he sets out from the ultimate facts of consciousness, or the pri- mary beliefs of mankind. The leading Supplementary Dissertation in his edition of Reid, constitutes the first general division in our arrangement of his philosophy. W, 20 PHILOSOPHY OF COMMON SENSE. ulate analysis and classification of the primary elements of cogni- tion, as carrying us into a discussion beyond our limits, and not of indispensable importance for the end we have in view ;* it is sufficient to have it conceded, in general, that such elements there are ; and this concession of their existence being supposed, I shall proceed to hazard some observations, principally in regard to their authority as warrants and criteria of truth. Nor can this as- sumption of the existence of some original bases of knowledge in the mind itself, be refused by any. For even those philosophers who profess to derive all our knowledge from experience, and who admit no universal truths of intelligence but such as are generalized from individual truths of fact even these philosophers are forced virtually to acknowledge, at the root of the several acts of observa- tion from which their generalization starts, some law or principle * Such an analysis and classification is however in itself certainly one of the most interesting and important problems of philosophy ; and it is one in which much remains to be accomplished. Principles of cognition, which now stand as ultimate, may, I think, be reduced to simpler clemente ; and some which are now viewed as direct and positive, may bo shown to be merely indirect and negative ; their cogency depending, not on the immedi- ate necessity of thinking them for if carried unconditionally out, {hey are themselves incogitable but in the impossibility of thinking something to which they are directly opposed, and from which they are the immediate re- coils. An exposition of the axiom That positive thought lies in the limita- tion or conditioning of one or other of two opposite extremes, neither of which as unconditioned, can be realized to the mind as possible, and yet of which, as contradictories, one or other must, by the fundamental laws of thought, be recognized as necessary : The exposition of this great but unenounced axiom would show that some of the most illustrious principles are only its subordinate modifications as applied to certain primary notions, intuitions, data, forms, or categories of intelligence, as Existence, Quantity (protensive, Time extensive, Space intensive, Degree) Quality, etc. Such modifications, for example, are the principles of, Cause and Effect, 1 Substance and Phenom- enon, etc. I may here also observe, that though the primary truths of facts and the primary truths of intelligence (the contingent and necessary truths of Eeid) form two very distinct classes of the original beliefs or intuitions of conscious- ness ; there appears no sufficient ground to regard their sources as different, and therefore to be distinguished by different names. In this I regret that I am unable to agree with Mr. Stewart. See his Elements, vol. ii. ch. 1, and his account of Reid. See Part Third of thia vol. pawira. W. PHILOSOPHY OF COMMON SENSE. 21 to which they can appeal as guaranteeing the procedure, should the validity of these primordial acts themselves be called in question- This acknowledgment is, among others, made even by Locke ; and on such fundamental guarantee of induction he even bestows the name of Common Sense. (See below, in Testimonies, No. 51.) Limiting, therefore, our consideration to the question of au- thority ; how, it is asked, do these primary propositions these cognitions at first hand these fundamental facts, feelings, beliefs, certify us of their own veracity ? To this the only possible an- swer is that as elements of our mental constitution as the es- sential conditions of our knowledge they must by us be accept- ed as true. To suppose their falsehood, is to suppose that we are created capable of intelligence, in order to be made the victims of delusion ; that God is a deceiver, and the root of our nature a lie.- But such a supposition, if gratuitous, is manifestly illegiti- mate. For, on the contrary, the data of our original conscious- ness must, it is evident, in the first instance, be presumed true. It is only if proved false, that their authority can, in consequence of that proof, be, in the second instance, disallowed. Speaking, there- fore, generally, to argue from common sense, is simply to show, that the denial of a given proposition would involve the denial of some original datum of consciousness.; but as every original da- tum of consciousness is to be presumed true, that the proposition in question, as dependent on such a principle, must be admitted. But that such an argument is competent and conclusive, must be more articulately shown. Here, however, at the outset, it is proper to take a distinction, the neglect of which has been productive of considerable error and confusion. It is the distinction between the data or deliver- ances of consciousness considered simply, in themselves, as appre- hended facts or actual manifestations, and those deliverances considered as testimonies to the truth of facts beyond their own phenomenal reality. Viewed under the former limitation, they are above all skepti- cism. For as doubt is itself only a manifestation of consciousness, 22 PHILOSOPHY OF COMMON SENSE. it is impossible to doubt that, what consciousness manifests, it does manifest, without, in thus doubting, doubting that we actu- ally doubt ; that is, without the doubt contradicting and there- fore annihilating itself. Hence it is that the facts of conscious- ness, as mere phenomena, are by the unanimous confession of all Skeptics and Idealists, ancient and modern, placed high above the reach of question. Thus, Laertius, in Pyrrh., L. ix. seg. 103 ; Seztus Empiricus, Pyrrh. Hypot, L. i. cc. 4, 10, et passim ; Descartes, Mecl., ii. pp. 13, and iii. p. 16, ed. 1058; Hume, Treatise on Human Nature, vol. i. pp. 123, 370, et alibi, orig. ed. ; Schulze, Aenesidemus, p. 24, Kritik, vol. i. p. 51 ; Plai- ner, Aphor., vol. i. 708 ; Reinhold, Theorie, p. 190 ; ScJtad, in Fichte's Philos. Jour., vol. x. p. 270. See also St. Austin, Contra. Academ., L. iii. c. 11 ; De Trin., L. xv. c. 112 ; Scotm, in Sent., L. i. disk 3, qu. 4, 10 ; Buffier, Prem. Verit., 9 11 40; Maynds Essay on Consciousness, p. 177, sq. ; Reid,^. 442, b. et alibi ; Cousin, Cours d'Hist. de la Philosophie Mo- rale, vol. ii. pp. 220, 236. On this ground, St. Austin was warranted in affirming Ni- hil intelligenti tarn notum esse quam se sentire, se cogitare, se velle, se vivere ; and the cogito ergo sum of Descartes is a valid assertion, that in so far as we are conscious of certain modes of existence, in so far we possess an absolute certainty that we really exist. (Aug. De Lib. Arb., ii. 3 ; De Trin., x. 3 ; De Civ. Dei., xi. 26 ; Desc., 11. cc., et passim.) Viewed under the latter limitation, the deliverances of con- sciousness do not thus peremptorily repel even the possibility of doubt. I am conscious for example, in an act of sensible percep- tion, 1, of myself, the subject knowing ; and 2, of something given as different from myself, the object known. To take the second term of this relation : that I am conscious in this act of an object given, as a non-ego' that is, as not a modifica- tion of my mind of this, as a phenomenon, doubt is impossi- 1 Hamilton always uses ego, and non^eyo, instead of me and not-me, which, though convenient and common, involve a grammatical error. W. PHILOSOPHY OF COMMON SENSE. 23 We. For, as has been seen, we cannot doubt the actuality of a fact of consciousness without doubting, that is subvert- ing, our doubt itself. To this extent, therefore, all skepticism is precluded. But though it cannot but be admitted that the object of which we are conscious in this cognition is given, not as a mode of self, but as a mode of something different from self, it is how- ever possible for us to suppose, without our supposition at least being felo de se, that, though given as a non-ego, this object may, in reality, be only a representation of a non-ego, in and by the ego. Let this therefore be maintained : let the fact of the testi- mony be admitted, but the truth of the testimony, to aught be- yond its own ideal existence, be doubted or denied. How in this case are we to proceed ? It is evident that the doubt does not in this, as in the former case refute itself. It is not suicidal by self-contradiction. The Idealist, therefore, in denying the exist- ence of an external world, as more than a subjective phenome- non of the internal, does not advance a doctrine ab initio null, as a skepticism would be which denied the phenomena of the inter- nal world itself. Yet many distinguished philosophers have fall- en into this mistake ; and, among others, both Dr. Reid, proba- bly, and Mr. Stewart, certainly. The latter in his Philosophical Essays (pp. 6, 7), explicitly states, " that the belief which accom- panies consciousness, as to the present existence of its appropriate phenomena, rests on no foundation more solid than our belief of the existence of external objects." Reid does not make any declaration so explicit, but the same doctrine seems involved in various of his criticisms of Hume and of Descartes (Inq. 1 pp. 100 a., 129, 130 ; Int. Pow., pp. 269 a., 442 b). Thus (p. 100 a.) he reprehends the latter for maintaining that consciousness affords a higher assurance of the reality of the internal phenomena, than sense affords' of the reality of the external. He asks Why did Descartes not attempt a proof of the existence of his thought ? and if consciousness be alleged as avouching this, he asks again, 'The reference is to Hamilton's edition of Reid. W. 24 PHILOSOPHY OF COMMON SENSE. Who is to be our voucher that consciousness may not deceive us ? My observations on this point, which were printed above three years ago, in the foot-notes at pp. 129 and 442 b.,' I am 1 The following arc the foot-notes referred to : "There is no skepticism possible touching the facts of consciousness in themselves. We cannot doubt that the phenomena of consciousness are real, in so far as wo are conscious of them. I cannot doubt, for example, that I am actually conscious of a certain feeling of fragrance, and of certain percep- tions of color, figure, etc., when I see and smell a rose. Of the reality of these, as experienced, I cannot doubt, because they are facts of conscious- ness ; and of consciousness I cannot doubt, because such doubt being itself an act of consciousness, would contradict, and, consequently, annihi- late itself. But of all beyond the mere phenomena of which we are con- scious, we may without fear of self-contradiction at least doubt. I may. for instance, doubt whether the rose I see and smell has any existence be- yond a phenomenal existence in my consciousness. I cannot doubt that I am conscious of it as something different from self, but whether it have, in- deed, any reality beyond my mind whether the not-self \>e not in truth only self that I may philosophically question. In like manner, I am conscious of the memory of a certain past event. Of the contents of this memory, ae a phenomenon given in consciousness, skepticism is impossible. But I may by possibility demur to the reality of all beyond these contents and the sphere of present consciousness. " In Eeid's strictures upon Hume, he confounds two opposite things. He reproaches that philosopher with inconsequence, in holding to ' the belief of the existence of his own impressions and ideas.' Now, if, by the existence of impressions and ideas, Eeid meant their existence as mere phenomena of consciousness, his criticism is inept ; for a disbelief of their existence, as such phenomena, would have been a suicidal act in the skeptic. If, again, he meant by impressions and ideas the hypothesis of representative entities dif- ferent from the mind and its modifications ; in that case the objection is equally invalid. Hume was a skeptic ; that is, he accepted the premises af- forded him by the dogmatist, and carried these premises to their legitimate consequences. To blame Hume, therefore, for not having doubted of his borrowed principles, is to blame the skeptic for not performing a part alto- gether inconsistent with his vocation. But, in point of fact, the hypothesis of such entities is of no value to the idealist or skeptic. Impressions and ideas. viewed as mental modes, would have answered Hume's purpose not a whit worse than impressions and ideas viewed as objects, but not as affections of mind. The most consistent scheme of idealism known in the history of phi- losophy is that of Fichte ; and Fichte's idealism is founded on a basis which excludes that crude hypothesis of ideas on which alone Eeid imagined any doctrine of Idealism could possibly be established. And is the acknowl- edged result of the Fichtean dogmatism less a nihilism than the skepticism of Hume? 'The sum total,' says Fichte, 'is this: There is absolutely nothing permanent either without me or within me, but only an unceasing change. I know absolutely nothing of any existence, not even of my own. PHILOSOPHY OF COMMON SENSE. 25 happy'to find confirmed by the authority of M. Cousin. The fol- lowing passage is from his Lectures on the Scottish School, con- stituting the second volume of his " Course on the History of the Moral Philosophy of the Eighteenth Century," delivered in the years 1819, 1820, but only recently published by M. Vacherot. 1 " It is not (he observes in reference to the preceding strictures of Reid upon Descartes) as a fact attested by consciousness, that Descartes declares his personal existence beyond a doubt ; it is because the negation of this fact would involve a contradiction." And after quoting the relative passage from Descartes : " It is thus by a reasoning that Descartes establishes the existence of the thinking subject ; if he admit this existence, it is not because it is guaranteed by consciousness ; it is for this reason, that when he thinks let him deceive himself or not he exists in so far as he thinks." It is therefore manifest that we may throw wholly out of ac- count the phenomena of consciousness, considered merely in them- selves ; seeing that skepticism in regard to them, .under this lim- itation, is confessedly impossible ; and that it is only requisite to consider the argument from common sense, as it enables us to I myself know nothing, and am nothing. Images (Bilder) there are: they constitute all that apparently exists, and what they know of themselves is after the manner of images ; images that pass and vanish without there be- ing aught to witness their transition ; that consist in fact of the images of images, without significance and without an aim. I myself am one of these images ; nay, I am not even thus much, but only a confused image of images. All reality is converted into a marvellous dream, without a life to dream of and without a mind to dream ; into a dream made up only of a dream of itself. Perception is a dream ; thought the source of all the existence and all the reality which I imagine to myself of my existence, of my power, of my destination is the dream of that dream.' " In doubting the fact of his consciousness, the skeptic must at least af- firm his doubt ; but to affirm a doubt is to affirm the consciousness of it ; the doubt Vould therefore be self-contradictory i. e. annihilate itself." W. 'Since the above was written, M. Cousin has himself published the Course of 1819-20, and the Lectures on the Scottish School may now bo found, am- plified, in the fourth volume of his first series. The same thing is stated with precision, clearness, and force, here and there in Cousin's second se- ries, the whole of which we have recently translated and published. W. 2 26 PHILOSOPHY OF COMMON SENSE. vindicate the truth of these phenomena, viewed as attestations of more than their own existence, seeing that they are not, in this respect, placed beyond the possibility of doubt When, for example, consciousness assures us that, in percep- tion, we are immediately cognizant of an external and extended non-ego; or that, in remembrance, through the imagination, of which we are immediately cognizant, we obtain a mediate knowl- edge of a real past ; how shall we repel the doubt in the for- mer case, that what is given as the extended reality itself is not merely a representation of matter by mind in the latter, that what is given as a mediate knowledge of the past, is not a mere present phantasm, containing an illusive reference to an unreal past ? We can do this only in one way. The legitimacy of such gratuitous doubt necessarily supposes that the deliverance of con- sciousness is not to be presumed true. If, therefore, it can be shown, on the one hand, that the deliverances of consciousness must philosophically be accepted, until their certain or probable false- hood has been positively evinced ; and if, on the other hand, it cannot be shown that any attempt to discredit the veracity of consciousness has ever yet succeeded ; it follows that, as philoso- phy now stands, the testimony of consciousness must be viewed as high above suspicion, and its declarations entitled to demand prompt and unconditional assent. In the first place, as has been said, it cannot but be acknowl- edged that the veracity of consciousness must, at least in the first instance, be conceded. " Neganti incumbit probatio." Nature is not gratuitously to be assumed to work, not only in vain, but in counteraction of herself; our faculty of knowledge is not, with- out a ground, to be supposed an instrument of illusion ; man, un- less the melancholy fact be proved, is not to be held organized for the attainment, and actuated by the love of truth, only to become the dupe and victim of a perfidious creator. But, in the second place, though the veracity of the primary convictions of consciousness must, in the outset, be admitted, it still remains competent to lead a proof that they are undeserving PHILOSOPHY OF COMMON SENSE. 27 of credit. But how is this to be done ? As the ultimate grounds of knowledge, these convictions cannot be redargued from any higher knowledge ; and as original beliefs, they are paramount in certainty to every derivative assurance. But they are many; they are, in authority, co-ordinate ; and their testimony is clear and precise. It is therefore competent for us to view them in cor- relation ; to compare their declarations ; and to consider whether they contradict, and, by contradicting, invalidate each other. This mutual contradiction is possible, in two ways. 1, It may be that the primary data themselves are directly or immediately contradictory of each other ; 2, it may be that they are medi- ately or indirectly contradictory, inasmuch as the consequences to which they necessarily lead, and for the truth or falsehood of which they are therefore responsible, are mutually repugnant. By evincing either of these, the veracity of consciousness will be dis- proved ; for, in either case, consciousness is shown to be inconsist- ent with itself, and consequently inconsistent with the unity of truth. But by no other process of demonstration is this possible. For it will argue nothing against the trustworthiness of conscious- ness, that all or any of its deliverances are inexplicable are in- comprehensible ; that is, that we are unable to conceive through a higher notion, how that is possible, which the deliverance avouches actually to be. To make the comprehensibility of a datum of consciousness the criterion of its truth, would be indeed the climax of absurdity. For the primary data of consciousness, as themselves the conditions under which all else is comprehended, are necessarily themselves incomprehensible. We know, and can know, only That they are, not How they can be. To ask how an immediate fact of consciousness is possible, is to ask how con- sciousness is possible ; and to ask how consciousness is possible, is to suppose that we have another consciousness, before and above that human consciousness, concerning whose mode of operation we inquire. Could we answer this, " verily we should be as gods." ' 1 From what has now been stated, it will be seen how far and on what grounds I hold, at once with Dr. Reid and Mr. Stewart, that our original SJO PHILOSOPHY OF COMMON SENSE. To take an example : It would be unreasonable in the Cosmo- thetic or the Absolute Idealist, to require of the Natural Realist 1 a reason, througli which to understand how a self can be conscious of a not-self how an unextended subject can be cognizant of an extended object ; both of which are given us as facts by conscious- ness, and, as such, founded on by the Natural Realist. This is un- reasonable, because it is incompetent to demand the explanation of a datum of consciousness, which, as original and simple, is necessarily beyond analysis and explication. It is still further unreasonable, inasmuch as all philosophy being only a develop- ment of the primary data of consciousness, any philosophy, in not accepting the truth of these, pro tanto surrenders its own pos- sibilityis felo de se. But at the hands of the Cosmothetic Ideal- ists and they constitute the great majority of philosophers the question is peculiarly absurd ; for before proposing it, they are themselves bound to afford a solution of the far more insuperable difficulties which their own hypothesis involves difficulties which, so far from attempting to solve, no Hypothetical Realist has ever yet even articulately stated. 8 This being understood, the following propositions are either self-evident, or admit of easy proof: 1. The end of philosophy is truth; and consciousness is the instrument and criterion of its acquisition. In other words, phi- losophy is the development and application of the constitutive and normal truths which consciousness immediately reveals. 2. Philosophy is thus wholly dependent upon consciousness ; the possibility of the former supposing the trustworthiness of the latter. 3. Consciousness is presumed to be trustworthy, until proved mendacious. 4. The mendacity of consciousness is proved, if its data, imme- beliefs are to be established, but their authority not to be canvassed ; and with M. Jouffroy, that the question of their authority is not to be absolutely withdrawn, as a forbidden problem, from philosophy. 1 On these terms see the third and fourth chapters of the second part of this vol. W. 3 For the illustration of this, see chapter first of the second part. W. PHILOSOPHY OF COMMON SENSE. 29 diately in themselves, or mediately in their necessary conse- quences, be shown to stand in mutual contradiction. 5.*The immediate or mediate repugnance of any two of its data being established, the presumption in favor of the general veracity of consciousness is abolished, or rather reversed. For while, on the one hand, all that is not contradictory is not there- fore true ; on the other, a positive proof of falsehood, in one in- stance, establishes a presumption of probable falsehood in all ; for the maxim, "falsus in uno,falsus in omnibus" must deter- mine the credibility of consciousness, as the credibility of every other witness. 6. No attempt to show that the data of consciousness are (either in themselves, or in their necessary consequences) mutually contradictory, has yet succeeded ; and the presumption in favor of the truth of consciousness and the possibility of philosophy has, therefore, never been redargued. In other words, an ori- ginal, universal, dogmatic subversion of knowledge has hitherto been found impossible. 7. No philosopher has ever formally denied the truth or dis- claimed the authority of consciousness ; but few or none have been content implicitly to accept and consistently to follow out its dictates. Instead of humbly resorting to consciousness, to draw from thence his doctrines and their proof, each dogmatic specula- tor looked only into consciousness, there to discover his pre- adopted opinions. In philosophy, men have abused the code of natural, as in theology, the code of positive, revelation; and the epigraph of a great protestant divine, on the book of scripture, is certainly not less applicable to the book of consciousness : " Hie liber est in quo qucerit sua dogmata quisque ; Invenit, etpariter dogmata quisque *a." J 8. The first and most obtrusive consequence of this proceedure has been, the multiplication of philosophical systems in every conceivable aberration from the unity of truth. 1 " This is the book where each his dogma seeks ; And this the book where each his dogma finds." 30 PHILOSOPHY OF COMMON SENSE. 9. The second, but less obvious, consequence has been, the vir- tual surrender, by each several system, of the possibility of phi- losophy in general. For, as the possibility of philosophy sup- poses the absolute truth of consciousness, every system which proceeded on the hypothesis, that even a single deliverance of consciousness is untrue, did, however it might eschew the overt declaration, thereby invalidate the general credibility of conscious- ness, and supply to the skeptic the premises he required to sub- vert philosophy, in so far as that system represented it. 10. And yet, although the past history of philosophy has, in a great measure, been only a history of variation and error (vari- asse erroris est) ; yet the cause of this variation being known, we obtain a valid ground of hope for the destiny of philosophy in future. Because, since philosophy has hitherto been inconsistent with itself, only in being inconsistent with the dictates of our natural beliefs " For Truth is catholic, and Nature one ;" it follows, that philosophy has simply to return to natural con- sciousness, to return to unity and truth. In doing this we have only to attend to the three following maxims or precautions : 1, That we admit nothing, not either an original datum of consciousness, or the legitimate consequence of such a datum ; 2, That we embrace all the original data of consciousness, and all their legitimate consequences ; and 3, That we exhibit each of these in its individual integrity neither distorted nor mutilated, and in its relative place, whether of pre-eminence or subordination. Nor can it be contended that consciousness has spoken in so feeble or ambiguous a voice, that philosophers have misappre- hended or misunderstood her enouncements. On the contrary, they have been usually agreed about the fact and purport of the deliverance, differing only as to the mode in which they might evade or qualify its acceptance. PHILOSOPHY OF COMMON SENSE. 31 This I shall illustrate by a memorable example by one in ref- erence to the very cardinal point of philosophy. In the act of sensible perception, I am conscious of two things ; of myself as the perceiving subject, and of an external reality, in relation with my sense, as the object perceived. Of the existence of both these things I am convinced : because I am conscious of knowing each of them, not mediately, in something else, as represented, but im- mediately in itself, as existing. Of their mutual independence I am no less convinced ; because each is apprehended equally, and at once, in the same indivisible energy, the one not preceding or determining, the other not following or determined ; and because each is apprehended out of, and in direct contrast to the other. Such is the fact of perception as given in consciousness, and as it affords to mankind in general the conjunct assurance they pos- sess, of their own existence, and of the existence of an external world. Nor are the contents of the deliverance, considered as a phenomenon, denied by those who still hesitate to admit the truth of its testimony. As this point, however, is one of principal im- portance, I shall not content myself with assuming the preceding statement of the fact of perception as a truth attested by the in- ternal experience of all ; but, in order to place it beyond the pos- sibility of doubt, quote in evidence, more than a competent num- ber of authoritative, and yet reluctant testimonies, and give articulate references to others. Descartes, the father of modern idealism, acknowledges, that in perception we suppose the qualities of the external realities to be themselves apprehended, and not merely represented, by the mind, in virtue or on occasion of certain movements of the sen- suous organism which they determine. " Putamus nos videre ipsam tcedam, et audire ipsam campanam : non vero solum sen- tire motus qui ab ipsis proveniunt." De Passionibus art. xxiii. This, be it observed, is meant for a statement applicable to our perception of external objects in general, and not merely to our perception of their secondary qualities. De Raei, a distinguished follower of Descartes, frequently ad- 32 PHILOSOPHY OF COMMON SENSE. mits, that what is commonly rejected by philosophers is univer- sally believed by mankind at large " Res ipsas secundum se in sensum incurrere" De Mentis Humanae Facultatibus, Sectio II. 41, 70, 89. De Cognitione Humana, 15, 39, et alibi. In like manner, Berkeley, contrasting the belief of the vulgar, and the belief of philosophers on this point, says : " The former are of opinion that those things they immediately perceive are the real things ; and the latter, that the things immediately perceived are ideas which exist only in the mind." Three Dialogues, &c., Dial. III. prope finem. His brother idealist, Arthur Collier, might be quoted to the same purport ; though he does not, like Berke- ley, pretend that mankind at large are therefore idealists. Hume frequently states that, in the teeth of all philosophy, ' men are carried by a blind and powerful instinct of nature to suppose the very images presented by the senses to be the external objects, and never entertain any suspicion that the one are nothing but representations of the other." Inquiry concerning Human Understanding, Sect. XII., Essays, ed. 1788, vol. ii. p. 154. Compare also ibid. p. 157 ; and Treatise of Human Nature, vol. i. B. i. P. iv. Sect. 2, pp. 330, 338, 353, 358, 361, 369. Schilling, in many passages of his works, repeats, amplifies, and illustrates the statement, that " the man of common sense be- lieves, and will not but believe, that the object he is conscious of perceiving is the real one." This is from hi. Philosophische Schrif- ten, I. p. 274 ; and it may be found with the context, translated by Coleridge but given as his own in the " Biographia Litera- ria," I. p. 262. See also among other passages, Philos. Schr., I. pp. 217, 238 ; Ideen zu einer Philosophie der Natur, Einleit. pp. xix. xxvi. first edition (translated in Edinb. Rev., vol. lii. p. 202) ; Philosophisches Journal von Fichte und Niethhammer, vol. vii. p. 244. In these passages Schelling allows that it is only on the believed identity of the object known and of the object existing, and in our inability to discriminate in perceptive consciousness the representation from the thing, that mankind at large believe in the reality of an external world. PHILOSOPHY OF COMMON SENSE. 33 But to adduce a more recent writer, and of a different school. " From the natural point of view," says Stiedenroth, " the repre- sentation (Vorstellung) is not in sensible perception distinguished from the object represented ; for it appears as if the sense actu- ally apprehended the things out of itself, and in their proper space." (Psychologic, vol. i. p. 244.) " The things the actual realities are not in our soul. Nevertheless, from the psychologi- cal point of view on which we are originally placed by nature, we do not suspect that our representation of external things and their relations is naught but representation. Before this can become a matter of consideration, the spatial relations are so far developed, that it seems as if the soul apprehended out of itself as if it did not carry the image of things within itself, but perceived the things themselves in their proper space" (p. 26*7). " This belief (that our sensible percepts are the things themselves) is so strong and entire, that a light seems to break upon us when we first learn, or bethink ourselves, that we are absolutely shut in within the circle of our own representations. Nay, it costs so painful an effort, consistently to maintain this acquired view, in opposition to that permanent and unremitted illusion, that we need not mar- vel, if, even to many philosophers, it should have been again lost" (p. 270). But it is needless to accumulate confessions as to a fact which has never, I believe, been openly denied ; I shall only therefore refer in general to the following authorities, who, all in like man- ner, even while denying the truth of the natural belief, acknowl- edge the fact of its existence. Malebranche, Recherche, L. iiL c. 1 ; Tetens, Versuche, vol. i. p. 375 ; Fichte, Bestimmung des Menschen, p. 56, ed. 1825; and in Philos. Journal, VII. p. 35;. Tennemann, Geschichte der Philosophic, vol. ii. p. 294 .{trans- lated in Edinb. Rev., vol. Hi. p. 202) ; Fries, Neue Kritik, Vorr., p. xxviii. sec. ed. ; Herbart, Allgemeine Metaphysik, II. Th., 327 ; Gerlach, Fundamental Philosophic, 33 ; Bencke, Das Ver- haeltniss von Seele und Leib, p. 23 ; and Kant und die Philosc- phische Aufgabe unserer Zeit, p. 70 ; Stoeger, Pruefung, &c., p. 2* 34: PHILOSOPHY OF COMMON SENSE. 504. To these may be added, Jacobi, Werke, vol. i. p. 119 ; and in vol. ii., his " David Hume" passim, of which see a passage quoted infra in Testimonies, No. 87 c. The contents of the fact of perception, as given in conscious- ness, being thus established, what are the consequences to philos- ophy, according as the truth of its testimony (I.) is, or (II.) is not, admitted ? I. On the former alternative, the veracity of consciousness, in the fact of perception, being unconditionally acknowledged, we have established at once, without hypothesis or demonstration, the reality of mind, and the reality of matter ; while no concession is yielded to the skeptic, through which he may subvert philoso- phy in manifesting its self-contradiction. The one legitimate doc- trine, thus possible, may be called Natural Realism or Natural Dualism. II. On the latter alternative, five great variations from truth and nature may be conceived and all of these have actually found their advocates according as the testimony of conscious- ness, in the fact of perception, (A) is wholly, or (B) partially, rejected. A. If wholly rejected, that is, if nothing but the phenomenal reality of the fact itself be allowed, the result is Nihilism. This may be conceived either as a dogmatical or as a skeptical opinion ; and Hume and Fichte have competently shown, that if the truth of consciousness be not unconditionally recognized, Nihilism is the conclusion in which our speculation, if consistent with itself, must end. B. On the other hand, if partially rejected, four schemes emerge, according to the way in which the fact is tampered with. i. If the veracity of consciousness be allowed to the equipoise of the subject and object in the act, but disallowed to the reality of their antithesis, the system of Absolute Identity (whereof Pan- theism is the corollary) arises, which reduces mind and matter to phenomenal modifications of the same common substance. ii., iii. Again, if the testimony of consciousness be refused to PHILOSOPHY OF COMMON SENSE. 35 the equal originality and reciprocal independence of the subject and object in perception, two Unitarian schemes are determined, according as the one or as the other of these correlatives is sup- posed the prior and genetic. Is the object educed from the sub- ject 1 Idealism ; is the subject educed from the object ? Materi- alism, is the result. iv. Finally, if the testimony of consciousness to our knowl- edge of an external world existing be rejected with the Idealist, but with the Eealist the existence of that world be affirmed, we have a scheme which, as it by many various hypotheses, endeav- ors, on the one hand, not to give up the reality of an unknown material universe, and on the other, to explain the ideal illusion of its cognition, may be called the doctrine of Cosmothetic Ideal- ism, Hypothetical Realism, or Hypothetical Dualism. This last, though the most vacillating, inconsequent, and self-contradictory of all systems, is the one which, as less obnoxious in its acknowl- edged consequences (being a kind of compromise between specu- lation and common sense), has found favor with the immense majority of philosophers. 1 From the rejection of the fact of consciousness in this example of perception, we have thus, in the first place, multiplicity, spec- ulative variation, error ; in the second, systems practically danger- ous ; and in the third, what concerns us exclusively at present, the incompetence of an appeal to the common sense of mankind by any of these systems against the conclusions of others. This last will, however, be more appropriately shown in our special consideration of the conditions of the argument of Common Sense, to which we now go on. 1 See, in connection with this more general distribution of philosophical systems from the whole fact of consciousness in perception, other more spe- cial divisions, from the relation of the object to the subject of perception, in the second part, chapter iii. W. 36 PHILOSOPHY OF COMMON SENSE. II. CONDITIONS OF THE LEGITIMACY, AND LEGITIMATE APPLI- CATION, OF THE ARGUMENT FROM COMMON SENSE. From what has been stated, it is manifest that the argument drawn from Common Sense, for the truth or falsehood of any given thesis, proceeds on two suppositions : 1. That the proposition to be proved is either identical with, or necessarily evolved out of, a primary datum of consciousness ; and, 2. That the primary data of consciousness are, one and all of them, admitted, by the proponent of this argument, to be true. From this it follows, that each of these suppositions will con- stitute a condition, under which the legitimate application of this reasoning is exclusively competent. Whether these conditions have been ever previously enounced, I know not. But this I know, that while their necessity is so palpable, that they could never, if explicitly stated, be explicitly denied ; that in the hands of philosophers they have been always, more or less violated, implicitly and in fact, and this often not the least obtrusively by those who have been themselves the loudest in their appeal from the conclusions of an obnoxious speculation to the common convictions of mankind. It is not therefore to be marvelled at, if the argument itself should have sometimes shared in the con- tempt which its abusive application so frequently and so justly merited. 1. That the first condition that of originality is indispens- able, is involved in the very conception of the argument. I should indeed hardly have deemed that it required, an articulate statement, were it not that, in point of fact, many philosophers have attempted to establish, on the principles of common sense, propositions which are not original data of consciousness ; while the original data of consciousness, from which their propositions were derived, and to which, they owed their whole necessity and truth these data the same philosophers were (strange to say !) PHILOSOPHY OF COMMON SENSE. 37 not disposed to admit. Thus, when it is argued by the Cosmo- tlietic Idealists " The external world exists, because we naturally believe it to exist ;" the illation is incompetent, inasmuch as it erroneously assumes that our belief of an external world is a pri- mary datum of consciousness. This is not the case. That an outer world exists is given us, not as a " miraculous revelation," not as a " cast of magic," not as an " instinctive feeling," not as a " blind belief." These expressions, in which the Cosmothetic Idealists shadow forth the difficulty they create, and attempt to solve, are wholly inapplicable to the real fact. Our belief of a material universe is not ultimate ; and that universe is not un- known. This belief is not a supernatural inspiration ; it is not an infused faith. We are not compelled by a blind impulse to be- lieve in the external world, as in an unknown something ; on the contrary, we believe it to exist only because we are immediately cognizant of it as existing. If asked, indeed How we know that we know it how we know that what we apprehend in sen- sible perception is, as consciousness assures us, an object, external, extended, and numerically different from the conscious subject ? how we know that this object is 'not a mere mode of mind, illu- sively presented to us as a mode of matter ? then indeed we must reply, that we do not in propriety know that what we are compelled to perceive as not-self, is not a perception of self, and that we can only on reflection believe such to be the case, in reliance on the original necessity of so believing, imposed on us by our nature, Quas nisi sit veri, ratio quoque falsa fit omnia. That this is a correct statement of the fact has been already shown ; and if such be the undenied and undeniable ground of the natural belief of mankind, in the reality of external things, the incompetence of the argument from common sense in the hands of the Cosmothetic Idealist is manifest, in so far as it does not fulfil the fundamental condition of that argument. This defect of the argument may in the present example in- 4S2COS 38 PHILOSOPHY OF COMMON SENSE. deed, be easily supplied, by interpolating the medium which has been left out. But this cannot consistently be done by the Cos- mothetic Idealist, who is reduced to this dilemma that if he ad- here to his hypothesis, he must renounce the argument ; and if he apply the argument, he must renounce his hypothesis. 2. The second condition, that of absolute truth, requires that he who applies the argument of common sense, by appealing to the veracity of consciousness, should not himself, directly or indi- rectly, admit that consciousness is ever false ; in other words, he is bound, in applying this argument, to apply it thoroughly, im- partially, against himself no less than against others, and not ac- cording to the conveniences of his polemic, to approbate and rep- robate the testimony of our original beliefs. That our immediate consciousness, if competent to prove any thing, must be compe- tent to prove every thing it avouches, is a principle which none have been found, at least openly, to deny. It is proclaimed by Leibnitz : " Si 1'experience interne immediate pouvait nous trom- per, il ne saurait y avoir pour moi aucune verite de fait, j'ajoute, ni de raison. And by Lucretius : Denique nt in fabrica si p*rava 'st Regula prim a, Omnia mendosa fieri atque obstipa necessum 'st ; Sic igitur Ratio tibi rerum prava necesse 'st, Falsaque sit, falsis quaccunquo ab Sensibus orta 'st. Compare Plotinus, En. V. Lib. v. c. 1 ; Buffier, Pr. Ver., 71 ; Reid, Inq., p. 183, b. I. P. p. 260, b. Yet, however notorious the condition, that consciousness unless held trustworthy in all its revelations cannot be held trustworthy in any ; marvellous to say, philosophers have rarely scrupled, on the one hand, quietly to supersede the data of consciousness, so often as these did not fall in with their preadopted opinions ; and on the other, clamorously to appeal to them, as irrecusable truths, so often as they could allege them in corroboration of their own, or in refutation of a hostile doctrine. I shall again take for an example the fact of perception, and the violation of the present condition by the Cosmothetic Ideal- r-r V-, w -*- <^ TvU r-m^ ^ -^ - PHILOSOPHY OF COMMON SENSE. 39 t -7 ' ~ "' k ~ i /l ~' V*~~' & ^--.V 'V^- ~ f- V i ft_i - 7 ists 1, in the constitution of their own doctrine ; 2, in their polemic against more extreme opinions. In the first place, in the constitution of their doctrine, nothing can be imagined more monstrous than the procedure of these philosophers, in attempting to vindicate the reality of a material world, on the ground of a universal belief in its existence; and yet rejecting the universal belief in the knowledge on which the universal belief in the existence is exclusively based. Here the absurdity is twofold. Firstly, in postulating a conclusion though rejecting its premises ; secondly, in founding their doctrine partly on the veracity, and partly on the mendacity, of consciousness. In the second place, with what consistency and effect do the Hypothetical Realists point the argument of common sense against the obnoxious conclusions of the thorough-going Idealist, the Materialist, the Absolutist, the Nihilist ? Take first their vindication of an external world against the Idealist. To prove this, do they, like Dr. Thomas Brown, simply found on the natural belief of mankind in its existence ? But they themselves, as we have seen, admitting the untruth of one natu- ral belief the belief in our immediate knowledge of external things have no right to presume upon the truth of any other ; and the absurdity is carried to its climax, when the natural belief, which they regard as false, is the sole ground of the natural be- lief which they would assume and found upon as true. Again, do they like Descartes, allege that God would be a deceiver, were we constrained by nature to believe in the reality of an unreal world ? But the Deity, on their hypothesis, is a deceiver ; for that hypothesis assumes that our natural consciousness deludes us in the belief, that external objects are immediately, and in them- selves perceived. Either therefore maintaining the veracity of God, they must surrender their hypothesis ; or, maintaining their hypothesis, they must surrender the veracity of God. Against the Materialist, in proof of our Personal Identity, can they maintain that consciousness is able to identify self, at one 40 PHILOSOPHY OF COMMON SENSE. period, with self, at another ; when, in their theory of percep- tion, consciousness, mistaking self for not-self, is unable, they virtually assert, to identify self with self, even at the same mo- ment of existence ? How, again, can they maintain the substantial Individuality and consequent Immateriality of the thinking principle, on the unity of consciousness, when the duality given in consciousness is not allowed substantially to discriminate the object from the subject in perception ? But to take a broader view. It is a maxim in philosophy, Tliat substances are not to be multiplied without necessity ; in other words, That a plurality of principles are not to be assumed, when the phenomena can possibly be explained by one. This regulative principle, which may be called the law or maxim of Parcimony, 1 throws it therefore on the advocates of a scheme of psychological Dualism, to prove the necessity of supposing more than a single substance for the phenomena of mind and matter. Further, we know nothing whatever of mind and mat- ter, considered as substances ; they are only known to us as a twofold series of phenomena : and we can only justify, against the law of parcimony, the postulation of two substances, on the ground, that the two series of phenomena are, reciprocally, so contrary and incompatible, that the one cannot be reduced to the other, nor both be supposed to coinhere in the same common sub- stance. Is this ground shown to be invalid ? the presumption against a dualistic theory at once recurs, and a Unitarian scheme becomes, in the circumstances, philosophically necessary. Now the doctrine of Cosmothetic Idealism, in abolishing the incompatibility of the two series of phenomena, subverts the only ground on which a psychological Dualism can be maintained. This doctrine denies to mind a knowledge of aught beyond its own modifications. The qualities, which we call material Exten- 'The rule of philosophizing, which Hamilton felicitously calls the law of parcimony, was often keenly applied hy the logical Occam ; hence it is sometimes designated as " Occam's razor." W. PHILOSOPHY OF COMMON SENSE 41 sion, Figure, &c., exist for us, only as they are known by us ; and, on this hypothesis, they are known by us only as modes of mind. The two series of phenomena, therefore, so far from being really, as they are apparently, opposed, are, on this doctrine, in fact, admitted to be all only manifestations of the same substance. So far, therefore, from the Hypothetical Dualist being able to resist the conclusion of the Unitarian whether Idealist, Materi- alist, or Absolutist ; the fundamental position of his philosophy that the object immediately known is in every act of cognition identical with the subject knowing in reality, establishes any and every doctrine but his own. On this principle, the Idealist may educe the object from the subject ; the Materialist educe the subject from the object ; the Absolutist carry both up into indif- ference ; nay the Nihilist subvert the substantial reality of either : and the Hypothetical Dualist is doomed to prove, that, while the only salvation against these melancholy results is an appeal to the natural convictions of mankind, that the argument from common sense is in his hands a weapon, either impotent against his opponents, or fatal equally to himself and them. III. THE ARGUMENT FROM COMMON SENSE IS ONE STRICTLY PHILOSOPHICAL AND SCIENTIFIC. We have thus seen, though the argument from common sense be an appeal to the natural convictions of mankind, that it is not an appeal from philosophy to blind feeling. It is only an appeal, from the heretical conclusions of particular philosophies, to the catholic principles of all philosophy. The prejudice, which, on this supposition, has sometimes been excited against the argu- ment, is groundless. Nor is it true, that the argument from common sense denies the decision to the judgment of philosophers, and accords it to the verdict of the vulgar. Nothing can be more erroneous. We admit nay we maintain, as D'Alembert well expresses it, " that the truth in metaphysic, like the truth in matters of taste, is a 42 PHILOSOPHY OF COMMON SENSE. truth of which all minds have the germ within themselves ; to which indeed the greater number pay no attention, but which they recognize the moment it is pointed out to them. . . But if, in this sort, all are able to understand, all are not able to instruct. The merit of conveying easily to others true and simple notions is much greater than is commonly supposed; for experience proves how rarely this is to be met with. Sound metaphysical ideas are common truths, which every one apprehends, but which few have the talent to develop. So difficult is it on any subject to make our own what belongs to every one." (Melanges, t. iv. 6.) Or, to employ the words of the ingenious Lichtenberg "Philosophy, twist the matter as we may, is always a sort of chemistry (Scheidekunst). The peasant employs all the princi- ples of abstract philosophy, only inveloped, latent, engaged, as the men of physical science express it ; the Philosopher exhibits the pure principle." (Hinterlassene Schriften, vol. ii. p. 67.) The first problem of Philosophy and it is one of no easy accomplishment being thus to seek out, purify, and establish, by intellectual analysis and criticism, the elementary feelings or beliefs, in which are given the elementary truths of which all are in possession ; and the argument from common sense being the allegation of these feelings or beliefs as explicated and ascertained, in proof of the relative truths and their neces- sary consequences ; this argument is manifestly dependent on philosophy, as an art, as an acquired dexterity, and cannot, notwithstanding the errors which they have so frequently com- mitted, be taken out of the hands of the philosophers. Common Sense is like Common Law. Each may be laid down as the general rule of decision ; but in the one case it must be left to the jurist, in the other to the philosopher, to ascertain what are the contents of the rule ; and though in both instances the com- mon man may be cited as a witness, for the custom or the fact, in neither can he be allowed to officiate as advocate or as judge. f Kplvttv a&afipovat avipat Idoarn' ao6Te\vos. PHOCYLIDES. PHILOSOPHY OF COMMON SENSE. 43 It must be recollected, also, that in appealing to the conscious- ness of mankind in general, we only appeal to the consciousness of those not disqualified to pronounce a decision. " In saying" (to use the words of Aristotle), " simply and without qualifica- tion, that this or that is a known truth, we do not mean that it is in fact recognized by all, but only by such as are of sound understanding; just as in saying absolutely that a thing is wholesome, we must be held to mean, to such as are of a hale constitution." (Top. L. vi. c. 4. 7.) We may, in short, say of the true philosopher what Erasmus, in an epistle to Hutten, said of Sir Thomas Moore : " Nemo minus ducitur vulgi judi- cio ; sed rursus nemo minus abest a sensu communi" When rightly understood, therefore, no valid objection can be taken to the argument of common sense, considered in itself. But it must be allowed that the way it has been sometimes applied was calculated to bring it into not unreasonable disfavor with the learned. (See C. L. Reinhold's Beytrsege zur leichtern Uebersicht des Zustandes der Philosophic, i. p. 61 ; and Nieth- hammer in his Journal, i. p. 43 sq.) In this country in particu- lar, some of those who opposed it to the skeptical conclusions of Hume did not sufficiently counteract the notion which the name might naturally suggest ; they did not emphatically proclaim that it was no appeal to the undeveloped beliefs of the unreflect- ive many ; and they did not inculcate that it presupposed a critical analysis of these beliefs by the philosophers themselves. On the contrary, their language and procedure might even, some- times, warrant an opposite conclusion. This must be admitted without reserve of the writings of Beattie, and more especially of Oswald. But even Reid, in his earlier work, was not so explicit as to prevent his being occasionally classed in the same category. That the strictures on the " Scottish Philosophy of Common Sense" by Feder, Lambert, Tetens, Eberhard, Kant, Ulrich, Jacob, &c., were inapplicable to Reid, is sufficiently proved by the more articulate exposition of his doctrine, afterwards given in his Essays on the Intellectual and Active Powers. But these 44 PHILOSOPHY OF COMMON SENSE. criticisms having been once recorded, we need not wonder at their subsequent repetition, without qualification or exception, by philosophers, and historians of philosophy. To take, as an example, the judgment of the most celebrated of these critics. " It is not" (says Kant, in the preface to his Prolegomena) " without a certain painful feeling, that we behold how completely Hume's opponents, Reid, Oswald, Beattie, and, at last, Priestley, missed the point of his problem ; and whilst they, on the one hand, constantly assumed the very positions which he did not allow, and on the other, demonstrated warmly, and often with great intemperance, what he had never dreamt of calling into question, they so little profited by the hint which he had given towards better things, that all remained in the same position as if the matter had never been agitated at all. The question mooted, was not Whether the notion of Cause were right, applicable, and, in relation to all natural knowledge, indispensable ; for of this Hume had never insinuated a doubt ; but Whether this notion were to the mind excogitated a priori, whether it thus possessed an intrinsic truth, independent of all experience, and consequently a more extensive applicability, one not limited merely to objects of experience ; on this Hume awaited a disclosure. In fact, the whole dispute regarded the origin of this notion, and not its indispensability in use. If the former be made out, all that respects the conditions of its use, and the sphere within which it can be validly applied, follow as corolla- ries, of themselves. In order satisfactorily to solve the problem, it behooved the opponents of this illustrious man to have pene- trated deeply into the nature of the mind, considered as exclu- sively occupied in pure thinking : but this did not suit them. They, therefore, discovered a more convenient method, in an appeal to the common understanding of mankind (gemeiner Menschenverstand) " and so forth ; showing that Kant un- derstood by the common sense of the Scottish philosophers, only good sense, sound understanding, ody ' (Select Discourses) ; and his friend Dr. Henry More designates the same by the name of intel- lectual sense. (Test. n. 45.) Jacobi defines Vernunft, his facul- ty of ' intellectual intuitions ' as ' the sense of the supersensible.' (Test. n. 87.) De la Mennais could not find a more suitable ex- pression whereby to designate his theological system of univer- sal consent, or general reason, than that of Common Sense ; and Borger in his classical work ' De Mysticismo ' prefers sensus as the least exceptionable word by which to discriminate those notions, of which, while we are conscious of the existence, we are ignorant of the reason and origin. ' Cum igitur, qui has notiones sequitur, ilium sensum sequi dicimus, hoc dicimus, illas notiones non esse ratione [ratiocinatione] quaesitas,sedomni argumentatione antiquiores. Eo autem majori jure eos sensus vocabulo complecti- mur, quod, adeo obscurae sunt, ut eorum ne distincte quidem no- bis conscii simus, sed eas esse, ex efficacia earuin intelligamus, i. e. ex vi qua animum afficiunt.' (P. 259, ed. 2.) See also of Testi- monies the numbers already specified. c. In the third signification, Common Sense may be used with emphasis on the adjective or on the substantive. In the former case, it denotes such an ordinary complement of intelligence, that, if a person be deficient therein, he is accounted mad or foolish. Sensus communis is thus used in Phaedrus, L. i. 7 ; but Hor- 'tcenty-one times ; which last, by the by, Xylauder always renders by ' Sen- sus communis.' Now how many timea does Plutarch use as a synonym, icoiviv vovvl Not once. He does, indeed, once employ it and Kenya; Qpi- vaf (p. 1077 of the folio editions); but in the sense of an agreement in thought with others the sense which it obtains also in the only other ex- ample of the expression to be found in his writings. (P. 529 D). I see Forcellini (voce Sensus) has fallen into the same inaccuracy as Harris. I may here notice that Aristotle does not apply the epithet common to in- tellect at all; for roB KOIVOU (De An. i. S. 5) does not, as Thcrnistius sup- poses, mean ' of the common [intellect]' but ' of the composite,' made up of soul and body. PHILOSOPHY OF COMMON SENSE. 57 ace, Serai i. iii. 66, and Juvenal, Sat. viii. 73, are erroneously, though usually, interpreted in this signification. In modern La- tinity (as in Milton contra Salmasium, c. 8) and in most of the vulgar languages, the expression in this meaning is so familiar that it would be idle to adduce examples. Sir James Mackintosh (Dissertations, &c., p. 387 of collected edition) indeed, imagines that this is the only meaning of common sense ; and on this ground censures Reid for the adoption of the term ; and even Mr. Stewart's objections to it seem to proceed on the supposition, that this is its proper or more accredited signification. See Ele- ments ii. ch. 1, sec. 2. This is wrong ; but Reid himself, it must be acknowledged, does not sufficiently distinguish between the second and third acceptations ; as may be seen from the tenor of the second chapter of the sixth Essay on the Intellectual Powers, but especially from the concluding chapter of the Inquiry. In the latter case, it expresses native, practical intelligence, natural prudence, mother wit, tact in behavior, acuteness in the observation of character, &c., in contrast to habits of acquired learning, or of speculation away from the affairs of life. I recol- lect no unambiguous example of the phrase, in this precise ac- ceptation, in any ancient author. In the modern languages, and rc,ore particularly in French and English, it is of ordinary occur- rence. Thus, Voltaire's saying, ' Le sens commun n'est pas si commun ;' which, I may notice, was stolen from Buffier (Meta- physique, 69). With either emphasis it corresponds to the xoivo'f XoyirffAoj of the Greeks, and among them to the ot)o X6yo of the Stoics, to the gesunde Menschenverstand of the Germans, to the Bons Sens of the French, and to the Good Sense of the English. The two emphases enable us to reconcile the following contradictions: ' Le bon sens (says Descartes) est la chose du monde la mieux partagee ;' ' Good sense (says Gibbon) is a quality of mind hardly less rare than genius.' d. In the fourth and last signification, Common Sense is no longer a natural quality ; it denotes an acquired perception or 3* 58 PHILOSOPHY OF COMMON SENSE. feeling of the common duties and proprieties expected from each member of society, a gravitation of opinion a sense of conven- tional decorum coramunional sympathy general bienstance public spirit, ;v. In this sense au-oir"nxo, iifoirrixog are rare. The term Intuition is not unambiguous. Besides its original and proper meaning (as a visual perception), it has been em- PHILOSOPHY OF COMMON SENSE. 59 ployed to denote a kiud of apprehension, and a kind of judg- ment. Under the former head, Intuition, or intuitive knowledge, has been used in the six following significations : a. To denote a perception of the actual and present, in oppo- sition to the ' abstractive' knowledge which we have of the possi- ble in imagination, and of the past in memory. b. To denote an immediate apprehension of a thing in itself, in contrast to a representative, vicarious, or mediate, apprehension of it, in or through something else. (Hence by Fichte, Schelling, and others, Intuition is employed to designate the cognition, as opposed to the conception, of the Absolute.) c. To denote the knowledge which we can adequately repre- sent in imagination, in contradistinction to the 'symbolical' knowledge which we cannot image, but only think or conceive, through and under a sign or word. (Hence probably Kant's application of the term to the forms of the Sensibility the imaginations of Space and Time in contrast to the forms or categories of the Understanding.) d. To denote perception proper (the objective), in contrast to sensation proper (the subjective), in our sensitive conscious- ness. e. To denote the simple apprehension of a notion, in contra- distinction to the complex apprehension of the terms of a propo- sition. Under the latter head, it has only a single signification ; viz. : f. To denote the immediate affirmation by the intellect, that the predicate does or does not pertain to the subject, in what are called self-evident propositions. All these meanings, however, with the exception of the fourth, have this in common, that they express the condition of an immediate, in opposition to a mediate, knowledge. It is there- fore easy to see how the term was suggested in its application to our original cognitions ; and how far it marks out their distinc- tive character. It has been employed in this relation by Des- 60 PHILOSOPHY OF COMMON SENSE. cartes, Leibnitz, Locke, Hemsterhuis, Beattie, Jacobi, Ancillon, Degerando, Thurot, and many others. II. The second condition, which, along with their Immediacy, seems to have determined a class of names, is the Incomprehensi- bility or Inexplicability of our original cognitions. Under this head there are two appellations which first present themselves Feeling and Belief ; and these must be considered in correlation. A thing mediately known is conceived under a representation or notion, and therefore only known as possibly existing ; a thing immediately known is apprehended in itself, and therefore known as actually existing. This being understood, let us suppose an act of immediate knowledge. By external or internal perception, I apprehend a phenomenon, of mind or matter, as existing ; I therefore affirm it to be. Now if asked how I know, or am assured, that what I apprehend as a mode of mind may not be, in reality, a mode of matter, or that what I apprehend as a mode of matter may not, in reality, be a mode of mind, I can only say, using the simplest language, ' I know it to be true, because I feel and cannot but feel,' or ' because I believe and cannot but believe it so to be.' And if farther interrogated how I know or am assured that I thus feel or thus believe, I can make no better answer than, in the one case, 'because I believe that I/ee,' in the other, 'because I feel that I believe? It thus appears, that when pushed to our last refuge, we must retire either upon Feeling or upon Belief, or upon both indifferently. And accordingly, among philosophers, we find that a great many employ one or other of these terms by which to indicate the nature of the ultimate ground to which our cognitions are reducible; while some employ both, even though they may accord a preference to one. 1. FEELING, in English (as Sentiment in French, Gefuehl in German, &c.), is ambiguous : And in its present application (to say nothing of its original meaning in relation to Touch) we must discharge that signification of the word by which we denote PHILOSOPHY OF COMMON SENSE. 61 the phenomena of pain and pleasure. Feeling is a term prefera- ble to Consciousness, in so far as the latter does not mark so well the simplicity, ultimacy, and incomprehensibility of our original apprehensions, suggesting, as it does, always something of thought and reflection. In other respects, Consciousness at least with a determining epithet may be the preferable expression. In the sense now in question, Feeling is employed by Aristotle, Theo- phrastus, Pascal, Malebranche, Bossuet, Leibnitz, Burner, D'Aguesseau, Berkeley, Hume, Kames, Hemsterhuis, Jacobi, Schulze, Bouterweck, Fries, Koppen, Ancillon, Gerlach, Franke, and a hundred others. In this meaning it has been said, and truly, that ' Reason is only a developed Feeling.' 2. BELIEF or FAITH (IIioVis, Fides, Croyance, Foi, Crlaube, &c.). Simply, or with one or other of the epithets natural, pri- mary, instinctive, &c., and some other expressions of a similar import as Conviction, Assent, Trust, Adhesion, Holding for true or real, jf/-ajvj,ei, notiones, conceptiones, conceptus, &c.), some- times simply, but more usually limited by the same attributes ; though these terms were frequently extended to complex cogni- tions likewise. If viewed as complex cognitions they have been designated, either by the general name of 4. JUDGMENTS, PROPOSITIONS (judicia, cwrocpavo'eif, ^piTao'iif, effata, pronunciata, enunciata, , firmcp. sententice, j7//>j &' oviroTt Tfaftirav dmftXurat rjv nva iroXXol Aaoi tfuinl^ovaC Olds vv rif tirri Kal air^. ' The Word proclaimed by the concordant voice Of mankind fails not ; for in man speaks God.' Hence the adage ? Vox Populi, vox Dei. 2. HERACLITUS. The doctrine held by this philosopher of a Common Reason (uvo Xoyoj), the source and the criterion of truth, in opposition to individual wisdom (Wia iriotv- riov' KOI rots Xoyoif, lav bno\oyovpcva luxvvuri rots' tyaivopivots. Id. 'H aiaQwiS ( fttvafttv. Id 90 PHILOSOPHY OF COMMON SENSE. c. Anal. Post. L. i. c. 2, 16. ' But it is not only necessary that we should be endowed with an antecedent knowledge of first principles all or some but that this knowledge should, likewise, be of paramount certainty. For whatever communicates a quality to other things must itself possess that quality in a still higher degree; as that on account of which we love all objects that partake of it, cannot but be itself, pre-eminently, an object of our love. Hence if we know and believe through cer- tain first principles, we must know and believe these themselves in a superlative degree, for the very reason that we know and believe [all] secondary truths through them.' In connection herewith, compare the passages quoted above, p. 70 b. d. Rhet. L. i. c. 1. 'By nature man is competently organ- ized for truth ; and truth, in general, is not beyond his reach.' e. Metaph. L. ii. (A minor) c. 1. ' The theory of Truth is in one respect difficult, in another easy ; as shown indeed by this that while enough has been denied to any, some has been conceded to all.' f. Elh. Nic. L. x. c. 2. Arguing against a paradox of certain Platonists, in regard to the Pleasurable, he says ' But they who oppose themselves to Eudoxus, as if what all nature desiderates were not a good, talk idly. For what appears to all, that we affirm to be ; and he who would subvert this belief, will himself assuredly advance nothing more deserving of credit. Compare also L. vii. c. 13 (14 Zuing.). In his paraphrase on the above passage, the Pseudo-Androni- cus (Heliodorus Prusensis) in one place uses the expression com- mon opinion, and in another all but uses (what indeed he could hardly do in this meaning as an Aristotelian, if indeed in Greek at all) the expression common sense, which D. Heinsius in his Latin version actually employs. ' But, that what all beings de- sire is a good, this is manifest to every one endowed with sense' - (ifoitfi TOI tv al//^iy, of the Stoics, far less of the Epicureans (however, as in the present instance, styled innate or implanted), were more than generalizations a posteriori. Yet this is a mistake, into which, among many others, even Lipsius and Leibnitz have fallen, in regard to the former. See Manud. ad Stoic. Philos. L. ii. diss. 11 ; and Nouv. Ess. Pref. t This gloss of Aero is not to be found in any of the editions of the two Horatian scholiasts. But I am in possession of extracts made by the cele- uated William Canter, from a more complete MS. of these commentators, than any to which Fabricius and their other editors had access. This codex belonged to Canter himself; and he gives its character, and a few specimens of its anecdota, in his Novaz Lectioneg. The copy of Horace (one of the first editions of Lambinus) in which these extracts are found, contains also the full collation of Canter's 'Manuscript! Codices Antiquissimi' of the poet (two PHILOSOPHY OF COMMON SENSE. 95 8. SENECA. a. Epist. 117. 'Multum dare solemus prae- sumptioni omnium hominum. Apud nos veritatis argumentum est, aliquid omnibus videri.' b. Ep. 9. ' Ut scias autem hos sensus communes esse, natura scilicet dictante, apud poetam comicum invenies, " Non est beatus, esse se qui non putet." ' c. Ep. 120. 'Natura semina nobis scientiae dedit, scientiam non dedit.' 9. PLINY the Younger. Paneg., c. 64. 'Melius omnibus quam singulis creditur. Singuli enim decipere et decipi possunt : nemo omnes, neminem omnes fefellerunt.' 9* QUINTILIAN. Inst., L. v. c. 10, 12. 'Pro certis habe- mus ea, in quse communi opinione consensum est.' 10. ALEXANDER OF APHRODISIAS, the oldest and ablest of the interpreters of Aristotle whose writings have come down to us, follows his master, in resting truth and philosophy on the natural convictions of mankind. a. On Fate, 2, edd. Lond. et Orell. Ou xevov ou

- rsgw TVS yvutfTixys gve^si'og), he says that it is not only to be dis- tinguished from our belief, or rather error, in regard to things sen- sible ; but likewise from the belief we have of what are called Common Notions, with which it, however agrees, in that these common notions command assent, prior to all reflection or reason- ing: (xcti ya rats xoivafc svvoiaj *o tfavrog Xo'you iritfrew/xsv). See below, Hermes, No. 99. Among other Platonists the same doc- trine is advanced by the pseudo Hermes Trismegistus, L. xvi. sub fine, p. 436, ed. Patricii, 1593. 17. AMMONIUS HERMIT (as extracted and interpolated by Philoponus) in his Commentary on Aristotle ' On the Soul,' In- troduction, p. 1-3, ed. Trincavelli, 1535. ' The function of Intel- tect (voiJf) is by immediate application [or intuition, a#Xa7j r/], to reach or compass reality, and this end it accom- PHILOSOPHY OF COMMON SENSE. 99 plishes more certainly than through the medium of demonstra- tion. For as Sense, by applying itself at once to a colored or figured object, obtains a knowledge of it better than through demonstration for there needs no syllogism to prove that this or the other thing is white, such being perceived by the simple ap- pliance of the sense ; so also the Intellect apprehends its appro- priate object by a simple appliance [a simple intuitive jet, cwrX*) sVjSoXT)], better than could be done through any process of demon- stration.' . . . ' I say that the rational soul has in, and co-essential with it, the reasons (Xoyouj) of things ; but, in consequence of being clothed in matter, they are, as it were, oppressed and smothered, like the spark which lies hid under the ashes. And as, when the ashes are slightly dug into, the spark forthwith gleams out, the digger not however making the spark, but only removing an im- pediment; in like manner, Opinion, excited by the senses, elicits the reasons of existences from latency into manifestation. Hence they [the Platonists] affirm that teachers do not infuse into us knowledge, but only call out into the light that which previously existed in us, as it were, concealed. ... It is, however, more correct to say that these are Common Notions or adumbrations of the Intellect ; for whatever we know more certainly than through demonstration, that we know in a common notion.' .... Such common notions are ' Things that are equal to the same are equal to one another,' ' If equals be taken from equals the remainders are equal,' ' Every thing must be either affirmed or denied.' 18. ST. ANSELM professes the maxim 'Crede ut intelligas; which became celebrated in the schools, as opposed to the ' In- tellige ut credas' of Abelard. 19. ALGAZEL of Bagdad, 'the Imaum of the world,' some- where (in his Destruction of the Philosophers, if I recollect aright) says, as the Latin version gives it ' Radix cognitionis fides.' 20. ST. THOMAS AQUINAS. a. De veritate ficlei catholic* contra Gentiles, L. i. c. 7, 1. 'Ea quse naturaliter rationi insi- 100 PHILOSOPHY OF COMMON SENSE. ta, verissima esse constut ; intantum, ut nee ea falsa esse possibile cogitare Principiorum naturaliter notorum cognitio nobis divinitus est indita, cum ipse Deus sit auctor nostne natu- rae. Haec ergo principia etiam divina sapientia continet. Quic- quid igitur principiis liujusmodi contrarium est, est divinae sapi- entiae contrarium : non igitur a Deo esse potest. Ea igitur qua; ex revelatione divina per fidem tenentur, non possunt natural! cognitioni esse contraria.' b. Expositio in Libb. Metaph. Aristot. Lect. v. ' Et quia talis cognitio principiorum (those of Contradiction and of Ex- cluded Middle) inest nobis statim a natura, concludit,' &c. c. Sumraa Theologiae, P. i. Partis ii. Qu. 51, art. 1. ' Intel- lectus principiorum dicitur esse habitus naturalis. Ex ipsa enim natura animae intellectualis convenit homini, quod, statim cogni- to quid est totum et quid est pars, cognoscat quod omne totum est inajus sua parte, et simile in cseteris. Sed quid sit totum et quid sit pars cognoscere non potest, nisi per species intelligibiles a pbantasmatibus acceptas, et propter hoc Philosophus, in fine Poste- riorum, ostendit quod cognitio principiorum provenit ex sensu.' d. De Veritate, Qu. xi. De Magistro, conclusio. ' Dicendum est similiter de scientiae acquisitione, quod pneexistunt in nobis principia quae statim lumine intellectus agentis cognoscuntur, per species a sensibilibus abstractas, sive sint complexa ut diynitates, sive incomplexa, sicut entis et unius et hujusmodi qiue statim intellectus apprehendit. Ex istis autem principiis universalibus omnia principia sequuntur, sicut ex quibusdam rationibus semi- nalibus,' p. 45. 'Non certe quod putaret Aristoteles, summos illos viros (Parmenidem et 6* 130 PHILOSOPHY OF COMMON SENSE. Melissum) tarn longe a communi sensu abhorruisse, ut opinarentur nullam esse omnino rerum dissimilitudinem,' speaking of Grotius, says : 'De jure gentium eleganter scripsit, et auctor classicus est. Imprimis, quod repre- hendunt imperiti, laudandum in eo libro est hoc, quod omnia veterum auctorum locis ac testimoniis probat. Nam ita provoca- tur quasi ad totum genus humanum. Nam si videmus, illos viros laudari, et afferri eorum testimonia, qui dicuntur sensum communem omnium hominum habuisse ; si posteri dicant, se ita sentire,. ut illi olim scripserint : est hoc citare genus humanum. Proferontur enim illi in medium, quos omnes pro sapientibus PHILOSOPHY OF COMMON SENSE. 133 habuerunt. Verum est, potest unusquisque stultus dicere ; ' Ego habeo sens-urn communem ;' sed sensus communis est, quod con- sensu humano dictum sit per omnia specula. Ita etiam in reli- gione naturali videndum est, quid olim homines communi con- sensu dixerint: nee ea ad religionem et theologiam naturalem referenda sunt, quae aliunde accepimus. Sic egit Grotius in opere praastantissimo. Ostendit, hoc Romanorum, hoc Gallorum, lega- tos dixisse ; hoc ab omni tempore fuisse jus gentium, hoc est, illtid jus, ex quo totse gentes judicari, et agi secum, voluerint. Sermo est de eo jure quod toti populi et illi sapientissimi scrip- tores nomine et consensu populorum totorum, pro jure gentium habuere ; de eo, quo gentes inter se teneantur ; non de jure put- tivo, quod unusquisque sibi excogitavit. Haec enim est labes, hoc est vitium sseculi nostri, quod unusquisque ponit principium, ex quo deducit deinde conclusiones. Bene est, et laudandi sunt, quod in hoc cavent sibi, ut in fine conveniant in conclusionibus ; quod ex diversis principiis efficiunt easdem conclusiones : Sed Grotius provocat simpliciter ad consensum generis humani et sensum communem} 78. PRICE, in his Review of the principal Questions on Mor- als, 1 ed. 1758, speaking of the necessity of supposing a cause for every event, and having stated examples, says ' I know nothing that can be said or done to a person who professes to deny these things, besides referring him to common sense and reason] p. 35. And again : ' Were the question whether our ideas of number, diversity, causation, proportion, r so sheer an ignorant as he would really demonstrate. Estimated by 1 The hopes of Sir William, like those of every mortal, have not all been fulfilled. W. 170 PHILOSOPHY OF PERCEPTION. aught above a very vulgar standard, Reid's knowledge of Philo- sophical opinions was neither extensive nor exact ; and Mr. Stew- art was himself too competent and candid a judge, not fully to acknowledge the deficiency.* But Reid's merits as a thinker are too high, and too securely established, to make it necessary to claim for his reputation an erudition to which he himself advances no pretension. And be his learning what it may, his critic, at least, has not been able to convict him of a single error ; while Dr. Brown himself rarely opens his mouth upon the older authors, without betraying his absolute unacquaintance with the*natters on which he so intrepidly discourses. Nor, as a speculator, does Reid's superiority admit, we conceive, of doubt. With all admi- ration of Brown's general talent, we do not hesitate to assert, that, in the points at issue between the two philosophers, to say nothing of others, he has completely misapprehended Reid's phi- losophy, even in its fundamental position, the import of the skeptical reasoning, and the significance of the only argument by which that reasoning is resisted. But, on the other hand, as Reid can only be defended on the ground of misconception, the very fact, that his great doctrine of perception could actually be reversed by so acute an intellect as Brown's, would prove that there must exist some confusion and obscurity in his own devel- opment of that doctrine, to render such a misinterpretation pos- sible. Nor is this presumption wrong. In truth, Reid did not generalize to himself an adequate notion of the various possible theories of perception, some of which he has accordingly con- founded: while his error of commission in discriminating con- sciousness as a special faculty, and his error of omission in not dis- criminating intuitive from representative knowledge, a distinction without which his peculiar philosophy is naught, have contrib- uted to render his doctrine of the intellectual faculties prolix, vacillating, perplexed, and sometimes even contradictory. Before proceeding to consider the doctrine of perception in * (Dissertation, &c., Part ii. p. 107.) [In my foot-notes to Eeid will be found abundant evidence of this deficiency.] PHILOSOPHY OF PEKCEFflON. 171 relation to the points at issue between Reid and his antagonist, it is therefore necessary to disintricate the question, by relieving it of these two errors, bad in themselves, but worse in the confu- sion which they occasion ; for, as Bacon truly observes, ' citius emergit veritas ex errore quam ex confusione.' And, first, of consciousness. Aristotle, Descartes, Locke, and philosophers in general, have regarded Consciousness, not as a particular faculty, but as the universal condition of intelligence. Reid, on the contrary, fol- lowing, probably, Hutcheson, and followed by Stewart, Royer- Collard, and others, has classed consciousness as a co-ordinate faculty with the other intellectual powers; distinguished from them, not as the species from the individual, but as the individual from the individual. And as the particular faculties have each their peculiar object, so the peculiar object of consciousness is, the operations of the other faculties themselves, to the exclusion of the objects about which these operations are conversant. This analysis we regard as false. For it is impossible : in the first place, to discriminate consciousness from all the other cogni- tive faculties, or to discriminate any one of these from conscious- ness ; and, in the second, to conceive a faculty cognizant of the various mental operations, without being also cognizant of their several objects. We know ; and We knoio that ice know : these propgsitions, logically distinct, are really identical ; each implies the other. We know (i. e. feel, perceive, imagine, remember, &c.) only as we know that we thus know ; and we know that we knoio, only as we know in some particular manner (i. Q.feel, perceive, Cartesian universality. Hobbcs employs it, and that historically, only once or twice ; Henry More and Cudworth are very chary of it, even when treat- ing of the Cartesian philosophy ; "Willis rarely uses it ; while Lord Herbert, Reynolds, and the English philosophers in general, between Descartes and Locke, do not apply it psychologically at all. When in common language, employed by Milton and Dryden, after Descartes, as before him by Sidney, Spenser, Shakspeare, Hooker, &c., the meaning is Plutonic. Our Lexi- vographere are ignorant of the difference. The fortune of this word is curious. Employed by Plato to express the PHILOSOPHY OF PERCEPTION. 201 cies) were not ' in all the dark ages of the scholastic followers of Aristotle' regarded as ' little images derived from without ;' for a numerous party of the most illustrious schoolmen rejected spe- real forms * of the intelligible world, in lofty contrast to the unreal images of the sensible ; it was lowered by Descartes, who extended it to the objects of our consciousness in general. When, after Gassendi, the school of Condillac had analyzed our highest faculties into our lowest, the idea was still more deeply degraded from its high original. Like a fallen angel, it was relegated from the sphere of Divine intelligence to the atmosphere of human sense, till at last Ideologic (more correctly Idealogu), a word which could orAy prop- erly suggest an a priori scheme, deducing our knowledge from the intellect, has in France become the name peculiarly distinctive of that philosophy of mind which exclusively derives our knowledge from the senses. Word and thing, ideas have been the crux philosopJiorwn, since Aristotle sent them packing (xatptTiaaav IStai) to the present day. A few notes, which we transfer from Hamilton's Reid, will complete the history and definition of the word idea. W. Whether Plato viewed Ideas as existences independent of the divine mind, is a contested point ; though, upon the whole, it appears more proba- ble that he did not. It is, however, admitted on all hands, to be his doc- trine, that Ideas were the patterns according to which the Deity fashioned the phenomenal or ectypal world. It should be carefully observed that the term Idea, previous to the time of Descartes, was used exclusively, or all but exclusively, in its Plutonic sig- nification. By Descartes, and other contemporary philosophers, it was first extended to denote our representations in general. Many curious blunders have arisen in consequence of an ignorance of this. I may notice, by the way, that a confusion of ideas in the Platonic with ideas in the Cartesian sense has led Reid into the error of assimilating the hypothesis of Plato and the hypothesis of Malebranche in regard to our vision in the divine mind. The Platonic theory of Perception, in fact, bears a closer analogy to the Car tesian and Leibnitzian doctrines than to that of Malebranche. Reid, in common with our philosophers in general, had no knowledge of the Platonic theory of sensible perception; and yet the gnostic forms, the cognitive reasons of the Platonis\p, held a far more proximate relation to ideas in the modern acceptation than the Platonic ideas themselves. This interpretation 2 of the meaning of Plato's comparison of the cave exhibits a curious mistake, in which Reid is followed by Mr. Stewart and many others, 3 and which, it is remarkable, has never yet been detected. In the similitude in question (which will be found in the seventh book of the Republic), Plato is supposed to intend an illustration of the mode in which 1 Whether, in the Platonic system, Ideas are or are not independent of the Deity, is, and always has been, a vexata quiestio.$ee Hamilton's Reid, p. 370. W. 1 The interpretation given in the text of Reid W. 1 Hamilton has shown in another place that Bacon has also wrested Plato's similitude of the cave from its genuine signification /(". 9* 202 PHILOSOPHY OF PERCEPTION. cies, not only in the intellect, but in the sense. In the fifth, 'phantasm? in 'the old philosophy,' was not the 'external cause of perception? but the internal object of imagination. In the shadows or vicarious images of external things are admitted into the mind to typify, in short, an hypothesis of sensitive perception. On his snji position, the identity of the Platonic, Pythagorean, and Peripatetic theories of this process is inferred. Nothing can, however, ho more groundless than the supposition ; nothing more erroneous than the inference. By his cave, images, and shadows, Plato meant simply to illustrate the grand principle of his philoso- phy that the Sensible or Ectypal world (phenomenal, transitory, yiyv6ntvov, 3v xal nit 8c) stands to the Noetic or Archetypal (substantial, permanent, SVTM 8c) in the same relation of comparative unreality in which the shadowx of the images of sensible existences themselves, stand to the things of which they are the dim and distant adumbrations. In the language of an illus- trious poet ' An nescis, qutecunque haec sunt, qua) hac nocte teguntur, Omnia res prorsus veras non esse, sed umbras, Aut specula, undo ad nos aliena elucet imago? Terra quidem, et maria alta, atque his circumfluus aor, Et quse consistunt ex iis, hac omnia tenueis Sunt umbrae, humanos quse tanquam somnia qusedam Pcrtingunt animos, fallaci et imagine ludunt, Nunquam eadem, fluxu semper variata pcrenni. Sol autem, Lunseque glohus, fulgentiaque astra Csetera, sint quamvis meliori praedita vita, Et donata sevo immortnli, hsec ipsa tamen sunt uEterni specula, in quae animus, qui est inde profectus, Inspiciens, patriss quodam quasi tactus amore, Ardescit. Verum quoniam licic non perstat et ultra Nescio quid sequitur secum, tacitusquc rcquirit, Nosse licet circum hsec ipsum consistere verum, Non finem: sed enim esse aliud quid, cujus imago Splendet in iis, quod per se ipsum cst, et principinm esse Omnibus seternum, ante omnein numerumque diemque ; In quo alium Solem atque uliam splendescere Lunam Adspicias, aliosquc orbes, alia astra manere, Terramquc, fluviosque alios, atque uora, et ignem, Et nemora, atque aliis errare animalia silvis.' And as the comparison is misunderstood, so nothing can be conceived more adverse to the doctrine of Plato than the theory it is supposed to elu- cidate. Plotiuus, indeed, formally refutes, as contrary to the Platonic, the very hypothesis thus attributed to his master. (Enn. IV., 1. vi. cc. 1. 8.) The doctrine of the Platonists on this point has been almost wholly neglect- ed; and the author among them whose work contains its most articulate PHILOSOPHY OF PERCEPTION. 203 the sixth, the term ' shadowy film] which here and elsewhere he constantly uses, shows that Dr. Brown confounds the matterless development has been so completely overlooked, both by scholars and phi- losophers, that his work is of the rarest ; while even his name is mentioned in no history of philosophy. It is here sufficient to state, that the t"Sa>\a, the Myoi YVUS-IKOI, the forms representative of external things, and corresponding to the species sensiles expresses of the schoolmen, were not held by the Plato- nists to be derived from without. Prior to the act of perception, they have a latent but real existence in the soul ; and, by the impassive energy of the mind itself, are elicited into consciousness, on occasion of the impression (rivals, xdBos, eiKpatris) made on the external organ, and of the vital form ((,v elSos), in consequence thereof, sublimated in the animal life. The verses of Boethius, which have been so frequently misunderstood, contain an accurate statement of the Platonic theory of perception. After refuting the Stoical doctrine of the passivity of mind in this process, he proceeds: ' Mens est efficiens magis 1 Longe causa potentior, Quam quaB materias modo Impressas patitur notas. PrcKcedit tamen excitans Ac vires animi movens Vivo in corpore passio, Cum vel lux oculos ferit, Vel vox auribus instrepit: Turn mentis vigor extitus tyuas intus species tenet, Ad motus similes vocans, Notis applicat exteris, Introrsumque reconditis Formis miscet imagines.' I cannot now do more than indicate the contrast of this doctrine to the Peripatetic (I do not say Aristotelian) theory, and its approximation to the Cartesian and Leibnitzian hypotheses ; which, however, both attempt to explain, what the Platonic did not how the mind, ex liypothesi, above all physical influence, is determined, on the presence of the unknown reality within the sphere of sense, to call into consciousness the representation through which that reality is made known to us. I may add, that not merely the Platonists, but some of the older Peripatetics held that the soul virtually contained within itself representative forms, which were only excited by the external reality; a* Theophrastus and Themistius, to say nothing of the Platonizing Porphyry, Simplicius and Ammonius Hermiae ; and the same opinion, adopted, probably from the latter, by his pupil, the Arabian Adelandus, subsequently became even the common doctrine of the Moorish Aristotelians. 204 PHILOSOPHY OF PKRCEPFION. species of the Peripatetics with the corporeal effluxions of Democ- ritus and Epicurus : ' Qua 1 , quasi membrantr, Miiuino do cortice rerum Dcreptas, volitant ultro citroque per auras.' Dr. Brown, in short, only fails in victoriously establishing ugainst Reid the various meanings in which ' the old writers' employed the term idea, by the petty fact that the old writers did not employ the term idea at all. Nor does the progress of the attack belie the omen of its out- set. We shall consider the philosophers quoted by Brown in chronological order. Of three of these only (Descartes, Arnauld, Locke) were the opinions particularly noticed by Reid ; the others (Hobbes, Le Clerc, Crousaz) Brown adduces as examples of Reid's general misrepresentation. Of the greater number of the philosophers specially criticised by Reid, Brown prudently says nothing. Of these, the first is DESCARTES ; and in regard to him, Dr. Brown, not content with accusing Reid of simple ignorance, con- tends ' that the opinions of Descartes are precisely opposite to the representations which he has given of them.' (Lect. xxvii. p. 172.) Now Reid states, in regard to Descartes, that this philos- opher appears to place the idea or representative object in per- ception, sometimes in the mind, and sometimes in the brain ; and he acknowledges that while these opinions seem to him con- tradictory, he is not prepared to pronounce which of them their author held, if he did not indeed hold both together. 'Des- cartes,' he says, ' seems to have hesitated between the two opin- ions, or to have passed from one to the other.' On any alternative, however, Reid attributes to Descartes, either the first or the second form of representation. Now here we must recol- lect, that the question is not whether Reid be rigorously right, !>ut whether he be inexcusably wrong. Dr. Brown accuses him of the most ignorant misrepresentation, of interpreting an author, whose perspicuity he himself admits, in a sense 'exactly the PHILOSOPHY OF PERCEPTION. 205 reverse 1 of truth. To determine what Descartes' doctrine of per- ception actually is, would be difficult, perhaps even impossible ; but in reference to the question at issue, certainly superfluous. It here suffices to show, that his opinion on this point is one mooted among his disciples ; and that Brown, wholly unac- quainted with the difficulties of the question, dogmatizes on the basis of a single passage nay, of a passage in itself irrele- vant. Reid is justified against Brown, if the Cartesian Idea be proved either a material image in the brain, or an immaterial representation in the mind, distinct from the precipient act. By those not possessed of the key to the Cartesian theory, there are many passages* in the writings of its author, which, taken by themselves, might naturally be construed to import, that Des- cartes supposed the mind to be conscious of certain motions in the brain, to which, as well as to the modifications of the intellect itself, he applies the terms image and idea. Reid, who did not understand the Cartesian philosophy as a system, was puzzled by these superficial ambiguities. Not aware that the cardinal point of that system is that mind and body, as essentially opposed, are naturally to each other as zero, and that their mutual intercourse can only be supernaturally maintained by the concourse of the Deity ; f Reid attributed to Descartes the possible opinion, that * Ex. gr. De Pass. 35 a passage stronger than any of those noticed by De la Forge. t That the theory of Occasional Causes is necessarily involved in Des- cartes' doctrine of Assistance, and that his explanation of the connection of mind and body reposes on that theory, it is impossible to doubt. For while he rejects all physical influence in the communication and conservation of motion between bodies, which he refers exclusively to the ordinary concourse of God (Prime. P. II. Art. 36, etc.} ; consequently he deprives conflicting bodies of all proper efficiency, and reduces them to the mere occasional causes of this phenomenon. But a fortiori, he must postulate the hypothe- sis, which he found necessary in explaining the intercourse of things substan- tially the same, to account for the reciprocal action of two substances, to Mm, of so incompatible a nature as mind and body. De la Forge, Geulinx, Male- branche, Cordemoi, and other disciples of Descartes, only explicitly evolve what the writings of their master implicitly contain. We may observe, 206 PHILOSOPHY OF PERCEPTION. the soul is immediately cognizant of material images in the brain, But in the Cartesian theory, mind is only conscious of itself; the affections of body may, by the law of union, be the proximate occasions, but can never constitute the immediate objects of knowl- edge. Reid, however, supposing that nothing could obtain the name of image which did not represent a prototype, or the name of idea which was not an object of thought, thus misinterpreted Descartes ; who applies, abusively, indeed, these terms to the occasion of perception (i. e. the motion in the sensorium, unknown in itself and resembling nothing), as well as to the object of thought (i. e. the representation of which we are conscious in the mind itself). In the Leibnitio-Wolfian system, two elements, both also denominated ideas, are in like manner accurately to be contradistinguished in the process of perception. The idea in the brain, and the idea in the mind, are, to Descartes, precisely what the ' material idea 1 and the 'sensual idea 1 are to the Wolfians. In both philosophies, the two ideas are harmonic modi- fications, correlative and coexistent ; but in neither is the organic affection or material idea an object of consciousness. It is merely the unknown and arbitrary condition of the mental representa- tion ; and in the hypotheses both of Assistance and of Pre-estab- lished Harmony, the presence of the one idea implies the con- comitance of the other, only by virtue of the hyperphysical deter- mination. Had Reid, in fact, not limited his study of the Car- tesian system to the writings of its founder, the twofold applica- tion of the term idea, by Descartes, could never have seduced him into the belief that so monstrous a solecism had been com- mitted by that illustrious thinker. By De la Forge, the personal friend of Descartes, the verbal ambiguity is, indeed, not only noticed, but removed ; and that admirable expositor applies the term ' corporeal species' to the affection in the brain, and the though we cannot stop to prove, that Tennemann is wrong in denying De la Forge to be even an advocate, far less the first articulate expositor of the doctrine of Occasional Causes. PHILOSOPHY OF PERCEPTION. 207 terms ' idea] ' intellectual notion] to the spiritual representation in the conscious mind. De rJSsprit, c. 10. But if Reid be wrong in his supposition, that Descartes admit- ted a consciousness of ideas in the brain ;* is he on the other alternative wrong, and inexcusably wrong, in holding that Des- cartes supposed ideas in the mind not identical with their percep- tions? Malebranche, the most illustrious name in the school after its founder (and who, not certainly with less ability, may be supposed to have studied the writings of his master with far greater attention than either Reid or Brown), ridicules as ' con- trary to common sense and justice' the supposition that Descartes had rejected ideas in ' the ordinary acceptation.'' and adopted the hypothesis of their being representations, not really distinct from their perception. And while ' he is as certain as he possibly can be in such matters,' that Descartes had not dissented from the general opinion, he taunts Arnauld with resting his paradoxical interpretation of that philosopher's doctrine, ' not on any passages of his Metaphysic contrary to the common opinion' but on his own arbitrary limitation of ' the ambiguous term perception.' (Rep. au Livre des Idtes, passim ; ARNAULD, CEuv. xxxviii. pp. 388, 389.) That ideas are ' found in the mind, not formed by it] and consequently, that in the act of knowledge the represen- tation is really distinct from the cognition proper, is strenuously asserted as the doctrine of his master by the Cartesian Roell, in the controversy he maintained with the Anti-Cartesian De Vries. (ROELLI Dispp. ; DE VRIES De Ideis innatis.} But it is idle to multiply proofs. Brown's charge of ignorance falls back upon himself; and Reid may lightly bear the reproach of ' exactly reversing 1 the notorious doctrine of Descartes, when thus borne, along with him, by the profoundest of that philosopher's disciples. Had Brown been aware, that the point at issue between him * Reid's error on this point is, however, surpassed by that of M. Royer- Collard, who represents the idea in the Cartesian doctrine of perception as txdusivfly situate in the brain. (CEuvres de Jieid, III. p. 384.) 208 PHILOSOPHY OF PERCEPTION. and Reid was one agitated among the followers of Descartes themselves, he could hardly have dreamt of summarily determin- ing the question by the production of one vulgar passage from the writings of that philosopher. But we are sorely puzzled to account for his hallucination in considering this passage perti- nent. Its substance is fully given by Reid in his exposition of the Cartesian doctrine. Every iota it contains of any relevancy- is adopted by Malebranche ; constitutes, less precisely indeed, his famous distinction of perception (ide) from sensation (sentiment) : and Malebranche is one of the two modern philosophers, admit- ted by Brown to have held the hypothesis of representation in its first, and, as he says, its most ' erroneous'' form. But princi- ples that coalesce, even with the hypothesis of ideas distinct from mind, are not, a fortiori, incompatible with the hypothesis of ideas distinct only from the perceptive act. We cannot, however, enter on an articulate exposition of its irrelevancy. To adduce HOBBES, as an instance of Reid's misrepresentation of the ' common doctrine of ideas,' betrays on the part of Brown a total misapprehension of the conditions of the question ; or he forgets that Hobbes was a materialist. The doctrine of represen- tation, under all its modifications, is properly subordinate to the doctrine of a spiritual principle of thought ; and on the supposi- tion, all but universally admitted among philosophers, that the relation of knowledge implied the analogy of existence, it was mainly devised to explain the possibility of a knowledge by an immaterial subject, of an existence so disproportioned to its nature, as the qualities of a material object. Contending, that an imme- diate cognition of the accidents of matter, infers an essential iden- tity of matter and mind, Brown himself admits, that the hypothe- sis of representation belongs exclusively to the doctrine of dual- ism (Lect. xxv. pp. 150, 160) ; whilst Reid, assailing the hypoth- esis of ideas, only as subverting the reality of matter, could hardly regard it as parcel of that scheme, which acknowledges the real- ity of nothing else. But though Hobbes cannot be adduced as a competent witness against Reid, he is however valid evidence PHILOSOPHY OF PERCEPTION. 209 against Brown. Hobbes, though a materialist, admitted no knowledge of an external world. Like his friend Sorbiere, he was a kind of material idealist. According to him, we know nothing of the qualities or existence of any outward reality. All that we know is the ' seeming] the ' apparition] the ' aspect] the 'phenomenon] the 'phantasm] within ourselves ; and this subjective object of which we are conscious, and which is con- sciousness itself, is nothing more than the ' agitation 1 of our internal organism, determined by the unknown ' motions,' which are supposed, in like manner, to constitute the world without. Perception he reduces to sensation. Memory and imagination are faculties specifically identical with sense, differing from it simply in the degree of their vivacity ; and this difference of in- tensity, with Hobbes as with Hume, is the only discrimination between our dreaming and our waking thoughts. A doctrine of perception identical with Reid's ! In regard to ARNAULD, the question is not, as in relation to the others, whether Reid conceived him to maintain a form of the ideal theory which he rejects, but whether Reid admits ArnaulcTs opinion on perception and his own to be identical. ' To these authors,' says Dr. Brown, ' whose opinions on the subject of perception, Dr. Reid has misconceived, I may add one, whom even he himself allows to have shaken off the ideal system, and to have considered the idea and the perception as not distinct, but the same, a modification of the mind, and nothing more. I allude to the celebrated Jansenist writer, Arnauld, who main- tains this doctrine as expressly as Dr. Reid himself, and makes it the foundation of his argument in his controversy with Malo branche.' (Lecture xxvii. p. 173.) If this statement be not untrue, then is Dr. Brown's interpretation of Reid himself correct. A representative perception, under its third and simplest modifi- cation, is held by Arnauld as by Brown ; and his exposition it- so clear and articulate, that all essential misconception of his doctrine is precluded. In these circumstances, if Reid avow the identity of Arnauld's opinion and his own, this avowal is tanta- 210 PHILOSOPHY OF PERCEPTION. mount to a declaration that his peculiar doctrine of perception is a scheme of representation ; whereas, on the contrary, if he sig- nalize the contrast of their two opinions, he clearly evinces the radical antithesis, and his sense of the radical antithesis, of the doctrine of intuition, to every, even the simplest form of the hypothesis of representation. And this last lie does. It cannot be maintained that Reid admits a philosopher to hold an opinion convertible with his, whom he states 'to profess the doctrine, universally received, that we perceive not material things immediately, that it is their ideas, which are the immediate objects of our thoughts, and that it is in the idea of every thing tliat we perceive its prvpertie&l This fundamental contrast being established, we may safely allow, that the radical misconception, which caused Reid to overlook the difference of our presentative and representative faculties, caused him likewise to believe that Arnauld had attempted to unite two contradictory theories of perception. Not aware, that it was possibly to main- tain a doctrine of perception, in which the idea was not really distinguished from its cognition, and yet to hold that the mind had no immediate knowledge of external things : Reid supposes, in the first place, that Arnauld, in rejecting the hypothesis of ideas, as representative entities, really distinct from the contem- plative act of perception, coincided with himself in viewing the material reality as the immediate object of that act ; and in the second, that Arnauld again deserted this opinion, when, with the philosophers, he maintained that the idea, or act of the mind representing the external reality, and not the external reality itself, was the immediate object of perception. But Arnauld's theory is one and indivisible ; and, as such, no part of it is iden- tical with Reid's. Reid's confusion, here as elsewhere, is explained by the circumstance, that he had never speculatively conceived the possibility of the simplest modification of the representative hypothesis. He saw no medium between rejecting ideas as something different from thought, and the doctrine of an immedi- ate knowledge of the material object. Neither does Arnauld, as PHILOSOPHY OF PERCEPTION. 211 Reid supposes, ever assert against Malebranche, 'that we per- ceive external things immediately,' that is, in themselves.* Maintaining that all our perceptions are modifications essentially representative, Arnauld everywhere avows, that he denies ideas, only as existences distinct from the act itself of perception.f * This is perfectly clear from Arnauld's own uniform statements ; and it is justly observed by Malebrancbe, in his Reply to the Treatise on True and False Ideas, (p. 123, orig. edit.) that, 'in reality, according to M. Arnauld, 1 ice do not perceive bodies, -we perceive only ourselves. 1 t (Euvres, t. xxxviii. pp. 187, 198, 199, 389. et passim. It is to be recol- lected that Descartes, Malebranche, Arrumld, Locke, and philosophers in general "before Reid, employed the term Perception as coextensive with Con- sciousness. By Leibnitz, Wolf, and their followers, it was used in a peculiar sense, as equivalent to Representation or Idea proper, and as contradistin- guished from Apperception, or consciousness. Reid's limitation of the term, though the grounds on which it is defended are not of the strongest, is con- venient, and has been very generally admitted. 1 On this point may be added the following (Reid, p. 296) : ' Arnauld did not allow that perception and ideas are really or numerically distinguished i. e. as one thing from another thing; not even that they arc modally distinguished i. e. as a thing from its mode. He maintained that they are really identical, and only rationally dis- criminated as viewed in different relations ; the indivisible mental modification being called A perception, by Reference to the mind or thinking subject an idea, by refer- ence to the mediate object or thing thought Arnauld everywhere avows that he denies ideas only as existences distinct from the act itself of perception. See (Euwea, t. xxxviii pp. 187, 198, 199, 389.' ' The opinion of Arnauld in regard to the nature of ideas was by no means over- looked by subsequent philosophers. It is found fully detailed in almost every systema- tic course or compend of philosophy, which appeared for a long time after its first pro- mulgation, and in many of these it is the doctrine recommended as the true. Arnauld's was indeed the opinion which latterly prevailed in the Cartesian school. From this it passed into other schools. Leibnitz, like Arnanld, regarded Ideas, Notions, Represen- tations, as mere modifications of the mind (what by his disciples were called material ideas, like the cerebral ideas of Descartes, are out of the question), and no cruder opinion than this has ever subsequently found a footing in any of the German systems. ' " I don't know," says Mr. Stewart, " of any author who, prior to Dr. Reid, has ex- pressed himself on the subject with so much justness and precision as Father Buffier. in the following passage of his Treatise on ' First Truths :' '"If we confine ourselves to what is intelligible in our observations on ideas, we will say they are nothing but mere modifications of the mind as a thinking being. They are called ideas with regard to the object represented; and perceptions with regard to tire faculty representing. It is manifest that our ideas, considered in this sense, are not more distinguished than motion is from abody moved.' (P. 311, English Translation.)" Idem. iii. Add. to vol. i. p. 10. ' In this passage, Buffier only repeats the doctrine of Arnauld, in Arnauld's own words. Dr. Thomas Brown, on the other hand, has endeavored to show that this doctrine 212 PHILOSOPHY OF PERCEPTION. Reid was therefore wrong, and did Arimuld less than justice, in viewing his theory 'as a weak attempt to reconcile two incon- sistent doctrines:' he was wrong, and did Arnauld more than justice, in supposing that one of these doctrines is not incompat- ible with his own. The detection, however, of this error only tends to manifest more clearly, how just, even when under its influence, was Reid's appreciation of the contrast subsisting be- tween his own and Arnauld's opinion, considered as a whole ; and exposes more glaringly Brown's general misconception of Reid's philosophy, and Jiis present gross misrepresentation, in affirming that the doctrines of the two philosophers were identi- cal, and by Reid admitted to be the same. Nor is Dr. Brown more successful in his defence of LOCKE. Supposing always, that ideas were held to be something distinct from their cognition, Reid states it, as that philosopher's opinion, ' that images of external objects were conveyed to the brain ; but whether he thought with Descartes [erratum for Dr. Clarke ?] and Newton, that the images in the brain are perceived by the mind, there present, or that they are imprinted on the mind itself, is not so evident.' This Dr. Brown, nor is he origi- nal in the assertion, pronounces a flagrant misrepresentation. Not only does he maintain, that Locke never conceived the idea to be substantially different from the mind, as a material image in the brain ; but, that he never supposed it to have an existence apart from the mental energy of which it is the object. Locke, he asserts, like Arnauld, considered the idea perceived and the percipient act, to constitute the same indivisible modification of the conscious mind. We shall see. In his lan.guo.ge, Locke is, of all philosophers, the most figura- tive, ambiguous, vascillating, various, and even contradictory; (which he Identifies with Reid's) had been long the catholic opinion ; nnd that Reid, in his attack on the Ideal system, only refuted what had heen already almost universally exploded. In this attempt he is. however, singularly unfortunate ; for, with the ex- ception of Crousaz, all the examples he adduces to evince the prevalence of Arnauld's doctrine are only so many mistakes, so many instances, in fact, which might be alleged in confirmation of the very opposite conclusion. 1 W. PHILOSOPHY OF PERCEPTION. 213 as has been noticed by Reid, and Stewart, and Brown himself, indeed, we believe by every author who has had occasion to com- ment on this philosopher. The opinions of such a writer are not, therefore, to be assumed from isolated and casual expressions, which themselves require to be interpreted on the general analo- gy of his system ; and yet this is the only ground on which Dr. Brown attempts to establish his conclusions. Thus, on the mat- ter under discussion, though really distinguishing, Locke verbally confounds, the objects of sense and of intellect, the operation and its object, the objects immediate and mediate, the object and its relations, the images of fancy and the notions of the understanding. Consciousness is converted with Perception, Perception with Idea, Idea with Ideatum, and with Notion, Conception, Phantasm, Representation, Sense, Meaning, &c. Now, his language identifying ideas and perceptions, appears conform- able to a disciple of Arnauld ; and now it proclaims him a fol- lower of Digby, explaining ideas by mechanical impulse, and the propagation of material particles from the external reality to the brain. The idea would seem, in one passage, an organic affection, the mere occasion of a spiritual representation ; in another, a representative image, in the brain itself. In employ- ing thus indifferently the language of every hypothesis, may we not suspect, that he was anxious to be made responsible for none ? One, however, he has formally rejected ; and that is the very opinion attributed to him by Dr. Brown, that the idea, or object of consciousness in perception, is only a modification of the mind itself. We do not deny, that Locke occasionally employs expressions, which, in a writer of more considerate language, would imply the identity of ideas with the act of knowledge ; and, under the cir- cumstances, we should have considered suspense more rational than a dogmatic confidence in any conclusion, did not the follow- ing passage, which has never, we believe, been noticed, appear a positive and explicit contradiction of Dr. Brown's interpretation. It is from Locke's Examination of Malebranche's Opinion, which 214 PHILOSOPHY OF PERCEPTION. as subsequent to the publication of the Essay, must be held au- thentic, in relation to the doctrines of that work. At the same time, the statement is articulate and precise, and possesses all the authority of one cautiously made in the course of a polemical discussion. Malebranche coincided with Arnauld, and conse- quently with Locke, as interpreted by Brown, to the extent of supposing, that sensation proper is nothing but a state or modifi- cation of the mind itself ; and Locke had thus the opportunity of expressing, in regard to this opinion, his agreement or dissent. An acquiescence in the doctrine, that the secondary qualities, ot which we are conscious in sensation, are merely mental states, by no means involves an admission that the primary qualities of which we are conscious in perception, are nothing more. Male- branche, for example, affirms the one and denies the other. But if Locke be found to ridicule, as he does, even the opinion which merely reduces the secondary qualities to mental states, a for tiori, and this on the principle of his own philosophy, he nnist be held to reject the doctrine, which would reduce not only the non- resembling sensations of the secondary, but even the resembling, and consequently extended, ideas of the primary qualities of matter, to modifications of the immaterial unextended mind. In these circumstances, the following passage is superfluously con- clusive against Brown, and equally so, whether we coincide or not in all the principles it involves : ' But to examine their doc- trine of modification a little further. Different sentiments (sensa- tions) are different modifications of the mind. The mind, or soul, that perceives, is one immaterial indivisible substance. Now I see the white and black on this paper, I hear one singing in the next room, I feel the warmth of the fire I sit by, and I taste an apple I am eating, and all this at the same time. Now, I ask, take modification for what you please, can the same unextended, indivisible substance have different, nay, inconsistent and opposite (as these of white and black must be) modifications at the same time ? Or must we suppose distinct parts in an indivisible sub- stance, one for black, another for white, and another for red ideas, PHILOSOPHY OF PERCEPTION. 215 and so of the rest of those infinite sensations, which we have in sorts and degrees ; all which we can distinctly perceive, and so are distinct ideas, some whereof are opposite, as heat and cold, which yet a man may feel at the same time ? I was ignorant before how sensation was performed in us : this they call an explanation of it ! Must I say now I understand it better ? If this be to cure one's ignorance, it is a very slight disease, and the charm of two or three insignificant words will at any time remove it ; pro- batum est? (Sec. 39.) This passage, as we shall see, is corre- spondent to the doctrine held on this point by Locke's personal friend and philosophical follower, Le Clerc. (But, what is curi- ous, the suppositions which Locke here rejects, as incompatible with the spirituality of mind, are the very facts on which Ammo- nius Hermiae, Philoponus, and Condillac, among many others, found their proof of the immateriality of the thinking subject.) But if it be thus evident that Locke held neither the third form of representation, that lent to him by Brown, nor even the second ; it follows that Reid did him any thing but injustice, in supposing him to maintain that ideas are objects, either in the brain, or in the mind itself. Even the more material of these alternatives has been the one generally attributed to him by his critics,* and the one adopted from him by his disciples.f Nor is this to be deemed an opinion too monstrous to be entertained by so enlightened a philosopher. It was, as we shall see, the com- mon opinion of the age ; the opinion, in particular, held by the most illustrious of his countrymen and contemporaries by New- ton, Clarke, Willis, Hook, &c.J The English psychologists have indeed been generally very mechanical. * To refer only to the first and last of his regular critics : see Solid Phi- losophy assarted against the Fancies of the Jdelsts, by J. S. [JonN SERGEANT.] Lond. 1697, p. 161, a very curious book, absolutely, we may say, unknown; and COUSIN, Cours de Philosophic, t. ii. 1829 ; pp. 330, 357, 325, 365 the most important work on Locke since the Nouveaux Essais of Leibnitz. t TUCKER'S Light of Nature, i. pp. 15, 18, ed. 2. + On the opinion of Newton and Clarke, see Des Maizcaux's Eecueil, i. pp. 7, 8, 9, 15, 22, 75, 127, 169, &e. Genovesi notices the crudity of New- PHILOSOPHY OF PERCEPTION. Dr. Brown at length proceeds to consummate his imagined victory by ' that most decisive evidence, found not in treatises read only by a few, but in the popular elementary works of science of the time, the general text-books of schools and colleges.' He quotes, however, only two : the Pneumatology of Le Clerc, and the Logic of Crousaz. ' LE CLERC,' says Dr. Brown, ' in his chapter on the nature of ideas, gives the history of the opinions of philosophers on this subject, and states among them the very doctrine which is most forcibly and accurately opposed to the ideal system of perception. " Alii putant ideas et perccptiones idearum easdem esse, licet rela- tionibus differant. Idea, uti censent, proprie ad objectum refer- tur, quod mens considerat; perceptio, vere ad mentem ipsam quae percipit : sed duplex ilia relatio ad unam modificationem mentis pertinet. Itaque, secundum hosce philosophos, nullac sunt, proprie, loquendo, ideas a mente nostra distinctae." What is it, I may ask, which Dr. Reid considers himself as having added to this very philosophical view of perception ? and if he added noth- ing, it is surely too much to ascribe to him the merit of detect- ing errors, the counter statement of ichich had long formed a. part of the elementary works of the schools} In the first place, Dr. Reid certainly ' added' nothing 'to this ton's doctrine, ' Mentem in certbro prjesidcrc atquc in eo, suo scilicet senso- rio, rerum imagines cemereS On Willis, BOO his work De Anima Jjrvtorum, p. 64, alibi, cd. 1072. On Hook, sec his Lect. on Light, 7. We know not whether it has been remarked that Locke's doctrine of particles and impulse, is precisely that of Sir Kenelm Dighy ; and if Locke adopts one part of so jfross an hypothesis, what is there improbable in his adoption of the other f that the object of perception is, a ' material participation of the bodies that work on the outward organs of the senses' (Digby, Treatise of Bodies, c. 82). As a specimen of the mechanical explanations of mental phenomena then considered satisfactory, we quote Sir Kenelm's theory of memory. ' Out of which it followeth, that the little similitudes which are in the caves of the brain, wheeling and swimming about, almost in such sort -as you see in the washing of currants or rice by the winding about and circular turning of the cook's hand, divers sorts of bodies do go their course for a pretty while ; so that the most ordinary objects cannot but present themselves quickly,' &c., - lished the speculative absurdity of our belief in the existence of an external world. In the passage, on the contrary, which Dr. Brown partially extracts, he is showing that this idealism, which in theory must be admitted, is in application impossible. Specu- lation and practice, nature and philosophy, sense and reason, be- lief and knowledge, thus placed in mutual antithesis, give, as their result, the uncertainty of every principle ; and the assertion of this uncertainty is Skepticism. This result is declared even in the sentence, with the preliminary clause of which, Dr. Brown abruptly terminates his quotation. PHILOSOPHY OF PERCEPTION. 233 But allowing Dr. Brown to be correct in transmuting the skep- tical nihilist into a dogmatic realist ; he would still be wrong (on the supposition that Hume admitted the truth of a belief to be convertible with its invincibility) in conceiving, on the one hand, that Hume could ever acquiesce in the same inconsequent con- clusion with himself; or, on the other, that he himself could, without an abandonment of his system, acquiesce in the legitimate conclusion. On this supposition, Hume could only have arrived at a similar result with Reid ; there is no tenable medium between the natural realism of the one and the skeptical nihilism of the other. ' Do you follow,' says Hume in the same essay, ' the in- stincts and propensities of nature in assenting to the veracity of sense?' I do, says Dr. Brown. (Lect. xxviii. p. 176, alibi.) ' But these,' continues Hume, ' lead you to believe that the very perception or sensible image is the external object. Do you dis- claim this principle in order to embrace a more rational opinion, that the perceptions are only representations of something exter- nal ? It is the vital principle of my system, says Brown, that the mind knows nothing beyond its own states (Lect. passim) ; philosophical suicide is not my choice ; I must recall my admis- sion, and give the lie to this natural belief. 'You here,' pro- ceeds Hume, ' depart from your natural propensities and more obvious sentiments ; and yet are not able to satisfy your reason, which can never find any convincing argument from experience to prove, that the perceptions are connected with any external objects.' I allow, says Brown, that the existence of an external world cannot be proved by reasoning, and that the skeptical argu- ment admits of no logical reply. (Lect. xxviii. p. 175.) 'But' (we may suppose Hume to conclude) ' as you truly maintain that the confutation of skepticism can be attempted only in two ways (ibid.), either by showing that its arguments are inconclusive, or by opposing to them, as paramount, the evidence of our nat- ural beliefs, and as you now, voluntarily or by compulsion, aban- don both ; you are confessedly reduced to the dilemma, either of acquiescing in the conclusion of the skeptic, or of refusing your 234 PHILOSOPHY OF PERCEPTION. assent upon no ground whatever. Pyrrhonism or absurdity? choose your horn.' Were the skepticism into which Dr. Brown's philosophy is thus analyzed, confined to the negation of matter, the result would be comparatively unimportant The transcendent reality of an outer world, considered absolutely, is to us a matter of supreme indifference. It is not the idealism itself that we must deplore ; but the mendacity of consciousness which it involves. Conscious- ness, once convicted of falsehood, an unconditional skepticism, in regard to the character of our intellectual being, is the melan- choly, but only rational, result. Any conclusion may now with impunity be drawn against the hopes and dignity of human na- ture. Our Personality, our Immateriality, our Moral Liberty, have no longer an argument for their defence. 'Man is the dream of a shadow ;' God is the dream of that dream. Dr. Brown, after the best philosophers, rests the proof of our personal identity, and of our mental individuality, on the ground of beliefs, which, as ' intuitive, universal, immediate, and irresisti- ble,' he not unjustly regards as ' the internal and never-ceasing voice of our Creator, revelations from on high, omnipotent [and veracious] as their author.' To him this argument is however incompetent, as contradictory. What we know of self or person, we know, only as given in consciousness. In our perceptive consciousness there is revealed asan ultimate fact a self and a not -self ; each given as independ- ent each known only in antithesis to the other. No belief is more ' intuitive, universal, immediate, or irresistible,' than that this antithesis is real and known to be real ; no belief is therefore more true. If the antithesis be illusive, self and not-self, subject and object, I and Thou are distinctions without a difference ; and consciousness, so far from being ' the internal voice of our Crea- tor,' is shown to be, like Satan, ' a liar from the beginning.' The reality of this antithesis, in different 2*irts of his philosophy Dr. Brown affirms and denies. In establishing his theory of percep- tion, he articulately denies, that mind is conscious of aught be- PHILOSOPHY OF PERCEPTION. 235 yond itself; virtually asserts that what is there given in con- sciousness as not-self, is only a phenomenal illusion, a modifica- tion of self, which our consciousness determines us to believe the quality of something numerically and substantially different. Like Narcissus again, he must lament, ' Me ego sum sensi, sed me mea fallit imago.' 1 After this implication in one part of his system that our belief in the distinction of self and not-self is nothing more than the deception of a lying consciousness ; it is startling to find him, in others, appealing to the beliefs of this same consciousness as to ' revelations from on high ;' nay, in an especial manner alleg- ing ' as the voice of our Creator,' this very faith in the distinction of self and not-self, through the fallacy of which, and of which alone, he had elsewhere argued consciousness of falsehood. On the veracity of this mendacious belief, Dr. Brown establishes his proof of our PERSONAL IDENTITY. (Lect. xii.-xv.) Touching the object of perception, when its evidence is inconvenient, this belief is quietly passed over as incompetent to distinguish not-self from self ; in the question regarding our personal identity, where its testimony is convenient, it is clamorously cited as an inspired witness, exclusively competent to distinguish self from not-self. Yet, why, if in the one case, it mistook self for not-self, it may not, in the other, mistake not-self for self, would appear a problem not of the easiest solution. The same belief, with the same inconsistency, is again called in to prove the INDIVIDUALITY OF MIND. (Lect. xcvi.) But if we are fallaciously determined, in perception, to believe what is sup- posed indivisible, identical, and one, to be plural and different and incompatible (self self + not-self) ; how, on the authority of the same treacherous conviction, dare we maintain, that the phenomenal unity of consciousness affords a guarantee of the real simplicity of the thinking principle ? The materialist may now contend, without fear of contradiction, that self is only an illusive phenomenon ; that our consecutive identity is that of the Delphic 236 PHILOSOPHY OF 1'KRCEPTION. ship, and our present unity merely that of a system of co-ordinate activities. To explain the phenomenon, he has only to suppose, as certain theorists have lately done, an organ to tell the lie of our personality ; and to quote as authority for the lie itself, the I*erfidy of consciousness, on which the theory of a representative perception is founded. On the hypothesis of a representative perception, there is, in fact, no salvation from materialism, on the one side, short of idealism skepticism nihilism, on the other. Our knowledge of mind and matter, as substances, is merely relative ; they 'are known to us only in their qualities ; and we can justify the pos- tulation of two different substances, exclusively on the supposition of the incompatibility of the double series of phenomena to coin- here in one. Is this supposition disproved ? the presumption against dualism is again decisive. ' Entities are not to be multi- plied without necessity* ' A plurality of principles is not to be assumed where the phenomena can be explained by one.' 1 In Brown's theory of perception he abolishes the incompatibility of the two series ; and yet his argument, as a dualist, for an immaterial prin- ciple of thought, proceeds on the ground, that this incompatibility subsists. (Lect. xcvi. pp. 646, 647.) This philosopher denies us an immediate knowledge of aught beyond the accidents of mind. The accidents which we refer to body, as known to us, are only states or modifications of the percipient subject itself ; in other words, the qualities we call material, are known by us to exist, only as they are known by us to inhere in the same substance an t}te qualities we denominate mental. There is an apparent anti- thesis, but a real identity. On this doctrine, the hypothesis of a double principle losing its necessity, becomes philosophically ab- surd ; and on the law of parsimony, a psychological unitarianism, at best, is established. To the argument, that the qualities of the object are so repugnant to the qualities of the sub- ject of perception, that they cannot be supposed the accidents of the same substance ; the Unitarian whether materialist, ideal- ist, or absolutist has only to reply : that so far from the attri- PHILOSOPHY OF PERCEPTION. 237 butes of the object being exclusive of the attributes of the subject in this act ; the hypothetical dualist himself establishes, as the fundamental axiom of his philosophy of mind, that the object known is universally identical with the subject knowing. The ma- terialist may now derive the subject from the object, the idealist derive the object from the subject, the absolutist sublimate both into indifference, nay, the nihilist subvert the substantial reality of either ; the hypothetical realist so far from being able to re- sist the conclusion of any, in fact accords their assumptive premi- ses to all. The same contradiction would, in like manner, invalidate every presumption in favor of our LIBERTY OF WILL. But as Dr. Brown throughout his scheme of Ethics advances no argument in support of this condition of our moral being, which his philos- ophy otherwise tends to render impossible, we shall say nothing of this consequence of hypothetical realism. So much for the system, which its author fondly imagines, ' al- lows to the skeptic no resting-place for his foot, no fulcrum for the instrument he uses ;' so much for the doctrine which Brown would substitute for Reid's ; nay, which he even supposes Reid himself to have maintained. ' SCILICET, HOC TOTUM FALSA RATIONS RECEPTUM EST !'* * [In this criticism I have spoken only of Dr. Brown's mistakes, and of those only with reference to his attack on Keid. On his appropriating to himself the observations of others, and in particular those of Destutt Tracy, I have said nothing, though an enumeration of these would be necessary to place Brown upon his proper level. That, however, would require a separate discussion.] CHAPTER II. EEPRESENTATIVE AND PRESENTATIVE KNOWLEDGE. 1 I. THE DISTINCTION OP PRESENTATIVE, INTUITIVE OR IMME- DIATE, AND OF REPRESENTATIVE OR MEDIATE COGNITION ; WITH THE VARIOUS SIGNIFICATIONS OF THE TERM OBJECT, ITS CONJUGATES AND CORRELATIVES. THE correlative terms, Immediate and Mediate, as attributes of knowledge and its modifications, are employed in more than a sin- gle relation. In order, therefore, to obviate misapprehension, it is necessary, in the first place, to determine in what signification it is, that we are at present to employ them. In apprehending an individual thing, either itself through sense, or its representation in the phantasy, we have, in a certain sort, an absolute or irrespective cognition, which is justly denom- inated immediate, by constrast to the more relative and mediate knowledge, which, subsequently, we compass of the same object, when, by a comparative act of the understanding we refer it to a class, that is, think or recognize it, by relation to other things under a certain notion or general term. With this distinction we have nothing now to do. The discrimination of immediate and mediate knowledge, with which we are at present concerned, lies within and subdivides what constitutes, in the foregoing division, the branch of immediate cognition ; for we are only here to deal with the knowledge of individual objects absolutely considered, and not viewed in relation to aught beyond themselves. This distinction of immediate and mediate cognition it is of the 1 Hamilton's second Supplementary Dissertation on Reid constitutes this chapter. W. PHILOSOPHY OF PERCEPTION. 239 highest importance to establish ; for it is one without which the whole philosophy of knowledge must remain involved in ambi- guities. What, for example, can be more various, vacillating, and contradictory, than the employment of the all-important terms object and objective, in contrast to subject and subjective, in the writings of Kant ? though the same is true of those of other re- cent philosophers. This arose from the want of a preliminary determination of the various, and even opposite meanings, of which these terms are susceptible, a selection of the one proper meaning, ; and a rigorous adherence to the meaning thus pre- ferred. But, in particular, the doctrine of Natural Realism can- not, without this distinction, be adequately understood, developed, and discriminated. Reid, accordingly, in consequence of the want of it, has not only failed in giving to his philosophy its precise and appropriate expression, he has failed even in withdrawing it from equivocation and confusion, insomuch, that it even re- mains a question, whether his Doctrine be one of Natural Realism at all. The following is a more articulate development of this important distinction than that which I gave some ten years ago ;' and since, by more than one philosopher adopted. For the sake of distinctness, I shall state the different momenta of the distinction in separate Propositions ; and these for more convenient reference I shall number. 1. A thing is known immediately or proximately, when we cognize it in itself ; mediately or remotely, when we cognize it in or through something numerically different from itself. Imme- diate cognition, thus the knowledge of a thing in itself, involves the/acf of its existence ; mediate cognition, thus the knowledge of a thing in or through something not itself, involves only the possibility of its existence. 2. An immediate cognition, inasmuch as the thing known is itself presented to observation, may be called a presentative ; and inasmuch as the thing presented is, as it were, viewed by 1 See previous chapter, p. 178. W. 240 PHILOSOPHY OF PERCEPTION. the mind face to face, may be called an intuitive* cognition. A mediate cognition, inasmuch as the thing known is held up or mirrored to the mind in a vicarious representation, may be called a representative f cognition. 3. A thing known is called an object of knowledge. 4. In a presentative or immediate cognition there is one sole object ; the thing (immediately) known and the thing existing being one and the same. In a representative or mediate cogni- tion there may be discriminated two objects ; the thing (imme- diately) known, and the thing existing being numerically different. 5. A thing known in itself is the (sole) presentative or intui- tive object of knowledge, or the (sole) object of a presentative or intuitive knowledge. A thing known in and through something else is the primary, mediate, remote,^ real, existent, or represent- * On the application of the term Litutiive, in this sense, see in the sequel of this Excursus, p. 256, a. b. t The term Representation I employ always strictly, as in contrast to Pre- sentation, and, therefore, with exclusive reference to individual objects, and not in the vague generality of Eepresentatlo or Vorstettung in the Leibnitz- ian and subsequent philosophies of Germany, where it is used for any cogni- tive act, considered, not in relation to what knows, but to what is known ; that is, as the genus including under it Intuitions, Perceptions, Sensations, Conceptions, Notions, Thoughts proper, &c., as species. \ The distinction of proximate and remote object is sometimes applied to perception in a different manner. Thus Color (the White of the "Wall for instance), is said to be the proximate, object of vision, because it is seen im- mediately ; the colored thing (the Wall itself for instance) is said to be the remote object of vision, because it is seen only through the mediation of the color. This however is inaccurate. For the Wall, that in which the color inheres, however mediately known, is never mediately seen. It is not indeed an object of perception at all ; it is only the subject of such an otyect. and is reached by a cognitive process, different from the merely percep- tive. On the term Heal. The term Real (realis), though always importing the existent, is used in various significations and oppositions. The following occur to me : 1. As denoting existence, in contrast to the nomenclature of existence, the thing, as contradistinguished from its name. Thus we have definitions and divisions real, and definitions and divisions nominal or verbal. 2. As expressing the existent opposed to the non-existent, a something iu PHILOSOPHY OF PERCEPTION. 24:1 cd, object of (mediate) knowledge, objectum quod ; and a thing tnrough which something else is known is the secondary, imme- contrast to a nothing. In this sense the diminutions of existence, to which reality, in the allowing significations, is counterposed, are all real. 8. As denoting material or external, in contrast to mental, spiritual, or inter- nal, existence. This meaning is improper; so, therefore, is the term Realism, as equivalent to Materialism, in the nomenclature of sorne recent philoso- phers. 4. As synonymous with actual / and this (a. as opposed to potential, b.) as opposed to possible existence. 5. As denoting absolute or irrespective, in opposition to phenomenal or rela- tive, existence ; in other words, as denoting things in themselves and out of relation to all else, in contrast to things in relation to, and as known by, in- telligences, like men, who know only under the conditions of plurality and difference. In this sense, which is rarely employed and may be neglected, the Keal is only another term for the Unconditioned or Absolute, T& Syria; tv. 6. As indicating existence considered as a subsistence in nature (ens extra unimam, ens natures'), it stands counter to an existence considered as a representation in thought. In this sense, reale, in the language of the older philosophy (Scholastic, Cartesian, Gassendian), as applied to esse or ens, is opposed to intentionale, notionale, conceptibile, imaginarvum, rationis,cognitionis, . in anima, in intellectu, prout cognitum, ideale, &c. ; and corresponds with a parte rei, as opposed to aparte intellect/us, with subjectivum, as opposed to oojec- tivum (see p. 240 b. sq. note), with proprium, priiicipale, and fundamentale, as opposed to vkarium, with materiale, as opposed to formale, and with/or- male in seipso, and entitativum, as opposed to representativum, &c. Under this head, in the vascillating language of our more recent philosophy, real approximates to, but is hardly convertible with objective, in contrast to sub- jective in the signification there prevalent. 7. In close connection with the sixth meaning, real, in the last place, de- dotes an identity or difference founded on the conditions of the existence of a thing in itself, in contrast to an identity or difference founded only on the relation or point of view in which the thing may be regarded by the think- ing subject. In this sense it is opposed to logical or rational, the terms being here employed in a peculiar meaning. Tims a thing which really (re) or in itself is one and indivisible may logically (ratione) by the mind be considered as diverse and plural, and vice versa, what are really diverse and plural may logically be viewed, as one and indivisible. As an example of the former ; the sides and angles of a triangle (or trilateral), as mutually correlative as together making up the same simple figure and as, without destruction of that figure, actually inseparable from it, and from each other, are really one ; but inasmuch as they have peculiar relations which may, in thought be con- sidered severally and for themselves, they are logically twofold. In like man- ner take apprehension and judgment. These are really one, as each involves the other (for we apprehend only as we judge something to be, and we judge only, as we apprehend the existence of the terms compared), and as together 11 242 PHILOSOPHY OF PERCEPTION. (Hate, proximate, ideal,* vicarious or representative, object of (mediate) knowledge, objectum quo, or per quod. The former may likewise be styled objectum entitativum. 6. The Ego as the subject of thought and knowledge is now commonly styled by philosophers simply The Subject ; and Sub- jective is a familiar expression for what pertains to the mind or thinking principle. In contrast and correlation to these, the terms Object and Objective are, in like manner now in general use to denote the Non-ego, its affections and properties, and in general the Really existent as opposed to the Ideally known. These expressions, more especially Object and Objective, are ambiguous ; for though the Non-ego may be the more frequent and obtrusive object of cognition, still a mode of mind constitutes an object of thought and knowledge, no less than a mode of matter. Without, therefore, disturbing the preceding nomenclature, which is not only ratified but convenient, I would propose that, when we wish to be precise, or where any ambiguity is to be dreaded, we should employ on the one hand, either the terms subject-object or subject- ive object (and this we could again distinguish as absolute or as relative) on the other, either object-object, or objective object.\ they constitute a single indivisible act of cognition ; but they are logically double, inasmuch as, by mental abstraction, they may be viewed each for itself, and as a distinguishable element of thought. As an example of the latter; individual things, as John, James, Richard, &c., are really (numer- ically) different, as coexisting in nature only under the condition of plu- rality ; but, as resembling objects constituting a single class or notion (man) they are logically considered (generically or specifically) identical and one. * I eschew, in general, the employment of the words Idea and Ideal they are BO vague and various in meaning. But they cannot always be avoided, as the conjugates of the indispensable term Idealism. Nor is there, as I use them, any danger from tlieir ambiguity ; for I always manifestly employ them simply for subjective (what is in or of the mind), in contrast to objec- tive (what is out of, or external to, the mind). t The terms Subject and Subjective, Object and Objective. I have already had occasion to show, that, in the hands of recent philosophers, the principal terms of philosophy have not only been frequently changed from their orig- inal meanings and correlations, but those meanings and correlations some- times even simply reversed. I have again to do this in reference to the cor- PHILOSOPHY OF PERCEPTION. 243 7. If the representative object be supposed (according to one theory) a mode of the conscious mind or self, it may be distin- relatives subjective and objective, as employed to denote what Aristotle vaguely expressed by the terifis ra fiplv and rd avTaoT6v,vorjT6v, yviacrrov, firioT^nSv, SoiAi/rdy, ipcKrdv, 6ov\evrdv, TUOT&V, &c., &c.), so the Greek philosophers alone found little want of a term precisely to express the abstract notion of objectivity in its indeterminate universality, which they could apply, as they required it, in any determinate relation. The schoolmen distinguished the subjectum occupationis, from the subjectum inhcKsionis, pr&dicationis, &c., limiting the term objectum (which in classical Latinity had never been naturalized as an absolute term, even by the philosophers) to the former ; and it would have been well had the term subjectum, in that sense, been, at the same time, wholly renounced. This was not, however, done. Even to the present day, the word subject is employed, in most of the vernacular languages, for the materia circa quam, in which signification the term object ought to be exclu- sively applied. But a still more intolerable abuse has recently crept in ; ob- ject has, in French and English, been for above a century vulgarly employed for end, motive, final cause. But to speak of these terms more in detail. The term object (objectum, id quod objicitur cognitioni, &c.) involves a two-fold element of meaning. 1, it expresses something absolute, some- thing in itself that is ; for before a thing can be presented to cognition, it must be supposed to exist. 2, It expresses something relative ; for in so far as it is presented to cognition, it is supposed to be only as it is known to exist. Now if the equipoise be not preserved, if either of these elements be allowed Jo preponderate, the word will assume a meaning precisely opposite to that which it would obtain from the preponderance of the other. If the first element prevail, object and objective will denote that which exists of its own nature, in contrast to that which exists only under the conditions of our faculties ; the real in opposition to the ideal. If the second element prevail, object and objective will denote what exists only as it exists in thought ; the ideal in contrast to the real. Now both of these counter meanings of the terms object and objective have obtained in the nomenclature of different times and different philosophies, 244 PHILOSOPHY OF PERCEPTION. guished as Egoistical ; if it be supposed (according to another) something numerically different from the conscious mind or self, uay in the nomenclature of the same time und even t^ie same philosophy. Hence great confusion and ambiguity. In the scholastic philosophy in which, us already said, object and objective, subject and subjective, were first employed in their high abstraction, and as absolute terms, and, among the systems immediately subsequent, in the Car- tesian and Gassendian schools, the latter meaning was the one exclusively prevalent. In these older philosophies, objectivum, as applied to ens or ease, was opposed loformale and subjectivum ; and corresponded with intentionale, vicarium, representativum, rationale or rations, intellectuale or in inteUectu, proitt cognitum, ideale, &c., as opposed to reale, proprium, principale, funda- mental?, prout in seipso, &c. In these schools the esse subjecticum, in contrast to the ease objectivum, de- noted a thing considered as inhering in its subject, whether that subject were mind or matter, as contradistinguished from a thing considered an present to the mind only as an accidental object of thought. Thus the faculty of im- agination, for example, and its acts, were said to have a suJijective existence in the mind ; while its several images or representations had, qua images or objects of consciousness, only an objective. Again, a material thing, say a horse, qua existing, was said to have a subjective being out of the mind ; qua conceived or known, it was said to have an objective being in the mind. Every thought has thus a subjective and an objective phasis ; of which more particularly as follows : 1. The esse subjectivum, formaU, or proprium of a notion, concept, species, idea, <&c., denoted it as considered absolutely for itself, and as distinguished from the thing, the real object, of which it is the notion, species, &c. ; that is, simply as a mode inherent in the mind as a subject, or as an operation exert- ed by the mind as a cause. In this relation, the esse rtale of a notion, species, &c., was opposed to the following. 2. The esse objectivum, vicarium, intentionale, ideale, representativum of a notion, concept, specits, idea, &c., denoted it, not as considered absolutely for itself, and as distinguished from its object, but simply as vicarious or repre- sentative of the thing thought. In this relation the esse reale of a notion, &c., was opposed to the mere negation of existence only distinguished it from a simple nothing. Hitherto we have seen the application of the term objective determined by the preponderance of the second of the two counter elements of meaning ; we have now to regard it in its subsequent change of sense as determined by the first. The cause of this change I trace to the more modern Schoolmen, in the distinction they took of conceptus (as also of notio and intentio) into formalis and objectivus, a distinction both in itself and in its nomenclature, incoiisist- ent and untenable. A. formal concept or notion they defined ' the immedi- ate and actual representation of the thing thought ;' an objective concept or notion they defined' the thing itself which is represented or thought.' PHILOSOPHY OF PERCEPTION. 245 it may be distinguished as Non-Egoistical. 1 The former theory supposes two things numerically different : 1, the object repre- Now, in the first place, the second of these, is, either not a concept or notion at all, or it is indistinguishable from the first. (A similar absurdity is commit- ted by Locke in his employment of Idea for its object the reality represent- ed by it the Ideatum.) In the second place, the terms formal and objective are here used in senses precisely opposite to what they were when the same philosophers spoke of the esse formale and esse dbjectivum of a notion. This distinction and the terms in which it was expressed came however to be universally admitted. Hence, though proceeding from an error, I would account in part, but in part only, for the general commutation latterly effected in the application of the term objective. This change began, I am inclined to think, about the middle of the seventeenth century and in the German schools. Thus Calovius 'Quicquid objective fundamentaliter in natura existit,' &c. (ScriptaPhilosophica, 1651, p. 72.) In the same sense it is used by Leibnitz; e.g. N. Essais, p. 187 ; and subsequently to him by the Leibnitio-Wolfians and other German philosophers in general. This appli- cation of the term, it is therefore seen, became prevalent among his country- men long before the time of Kant ; in the ' Logica ' of whose master Knutzen, I may notice, objective and subjective, in their modern meaning are em- ployed in almost every page. The English philosophers, at the commence- ment of the last century, are found sometimes using the term objective in the old sense, as Berkeley in his ' Siris,' 292 ; sometimes in the new, as Nor- risinhis 'Keason and Faith' (ch. 1), and Oldfield in his 'Essay towards the improvement of Eeason' (Part ii. c. 19), who both likewise oppose it to sub- jective, taken also in its present acceptation. But the cause, why the general terms subject and subjective, object and ob- jective, came, in philosophy, to be simply applied to a certain special distinc- tion ; and why, in that distinction, they came to be opposed as contraries this is not to be traced alone to the inconsistencies which I have noticed ; for that inconsistency itself must be accounted for. It lies deeper. It is to be found in the constituent elements of all knowledge itself; and the nomen- clature in question is only an elliptical abbreviation, and restricted applica- tion of the scholastic expressions by which these elements have for many ages been expressed. All knowledge is a relation a relation between that which knows (in scho- lastic language, the subject in which knowledge inheres), and that which is known (in scholastic language, the object about which knowledge is conver- sant) ; and the contents of every act of knowledge are made up of elements, and regulated by laws, proceeding partly from its object and partly from its subject. Now philosophy proper is principally and primarily the science of knowledge ; its first and most important problem being to determine What can, we know ? that is, what are the conditions of our knowing, whether 1 See the next chapter. W. 246 PHILOSOPHY OF PERCEPTION. sented, 2, the representing and cognizant mind : the latter, three; 1, the object represented, 2, the object representing, 3, the cognizant mind. Compared merely with each other, the former, as simpler, may, by contrast to the latter, be considered, these lie in the nature of the object, or in the nature of the subject, of knowl- edge? But Philosophy being the Science of Knowledge ; and the science of knowl- edge supposing, in its most fundamental and thorough-going analysis, the distinction of the subject and object of knowledge; it is evident, that, to philos- ophy the subject of knowledge would be, by pre-eminence, The Subject, and the object of knowledge by pre-eminence, The Object. It was therefore natu- ral that the object and the objective, the subject and the subjective should be employed by philosophers as simple terms, compendiously to denote the grand discrimination, about which philosophy was constantly employed, and which no others could be found so precisely and promptly to express. In fact, had it not been for the special meaning given to objective in the Schools, their employment in this their natural relation would probably have been of 'a much earlier date ; not however that they are void of ambiguity, and have not been often abusively employed. This arises from the following circum- stance : The subject of knowledge is exclusively the Ego or conscious mind. Subject and subjective, considered in themselves, are therefore little liable to equis-ocation. But, on the other hand, the object of knowledge is not neces- sarily a phenomenon of the Non-ego ; for the phenomena of the Ego itself constitute as veritable, though not so various and prominent, objects of cog- nition, as the phenomena of the Non-ego. Subjective and objective do not, therefore, thoroughly and adequately dis- criminate that which belongs to mind, and even that which belongs to matter; they do not even competently distinguish what is dependent, from what is independent, on the conditions of the mental self. But in these significations they are and must be frequently employed. Without therefore discarding this nomenclature, which, as fur as it goes, expresses, in general, a distinction of the highest importance, in the most apposite terms ; these terms may by qualification easily be rendered adequate to those subordinate discrimina- tions, which it is often requisite to signalize, but which they cannot simply and of themselves denote. Subject and subjective, without any qualifying attribute, I would therefore employ, as has hitherto been done, to mark out what inheres in, pertains to, or depends on, the knowing mind whether of man in general, or of this or that individual man in particular; and this in contrast to object and ob- jective, as expressing what does not so inhere, pertain, and depend. Thus, for example, an art or science is said to be objective, when considered simply as a system of speculative truths or practical rules, but without respect of any actual possessor ; subjective when considered as a habit of knowledge or a dexterity, inherent in the mind, either vaguely of any, or precisely of this or that, possessor. But, as has been stated, an object of knowledge imiy be a mode ofmind, or PHILOSOPHY OF PERCEPTION. 247 but still inaccurately, as an immediate cognition. 1 The latter of these as limited in its application to certain faculties, and now in fact wholly exploded, may be thrown out of account. 8. External Perception or Perception simply, is the faculty presentative or intuitive of the phenomena of the Non-Ego or Matter if there be any intuitive apprehension allowed of the Non- Ego at all. Internal Perception or Self -Consciousness is the fac- ulty presentative or intuitive of the phenomena of the Ego or mind. 9. Imagination or Phantasy? in its most extensive meaning, is the faculty representative of the phenomena both of the exter- nal and internal worlds. 10. A representation considered as an object is logically, not really, different from a representation considered as an act. Here object and act are merely the same indivisible mode of mind viewed in two different relations. Considered by reference to a (mediate) object represented, it is a representative object ; con- it may be something different from mind ; and it is frequently of import- ance to indicate precisely iinder which of these classes that object comes. In this case by an internal development of the nomenclature itself, we might employ, on the former alternative, the term subject-object ; on the latter, the term object-object. But the subject-object may be either a mode of mind, of which we are con- scious as absolute and for itself alone, as, for example, a pain or pleasure ; or a mode of mind, of which we are conscious, as relative to, and represen- tative of something else, as, for instance, the imagination of something; past or possible. Of these we might distinguish, when necessary, the one, as the absolute or the real subject-object, the other, as the relative or the ideal or the representative subject-object. Finally, it may be required to mark whether the object-object and the svl- ject-object be immediately known as present, or only as represented. In this case we must resort, on the former alternative, to the epithet prefsentatin? or intuitine; on the latter, to those of represented, mediate, remote, primary, principal, &c. 'This observation has reference to Eeid. See sequel of this chapter, ii. and the following chapter, ii. A, 4. W. 2 ' The Latin Imayinatio, witli its modifications in the vulgar languages, was employed both in ancient and modern times to express what the Greeks denominated ^avraola. Phantasy, of which Phansy or Fancy is a corruption, and now employed in a more limited sense, was a common name for Imagi- nation with the old English writers.' Reid, p. 379. II'. 248 PHILOSOPHY OF PERCEPTION. sidered by reference to the mind representing and contemplating the representation, it is a representative act. A representative object being viewed as posterior in the order of nature, but not of time, to the representative act, is viewed as a product ; and the representative act being viewed as prior in the order of nature, though not of time, to the representative object, is viewed as a producing process. The same may be said of Image and Imagi- nation. (Prop. 21, and p. 259, a b, and note.) 1 1 . A thing to be known in itself must be known as actually existing (Pr. 1), and it cannot be known as actually existing unless it be known as existing in its When and its Where. But the When and Where of an object are immediately cognizable by the subject, only if the When be now (i. e. at the same moment 1 with the cognitive act), and the Where be here (i. e. within the sphere of the cognitive faculty) ; therefore a presenta- tive or intuitive knowledge is only competent of an object present to the mind, both in time and in space. 12. E converse whatever is known, but not as actually existing now and here, is known not in itself, as the presentative 1 Time is cognizable and conceivable only as an indefinite past, present, or future. An absolute minimum we cannot fix an infinite division we can- not carry out. We can conceive Time only as a relative. The Present, so far as construable to thought, has no reality. (See p. 488.) Will Sir William then explain to us what he means by the phrase at tht, same moment with? In Extensive Quantity he wisely docs not demand an absolute ' present,' for in that case the Eleatic Zeno's demonstration would hold him motionless. He does seem to demand an absolute present in Extensive Quantity. Abso- lute present, has no place in thought. Perception must take place in time, /. . in an indefinite present. Add that Memory, as Hobbcs, Descartes, and Aristotle call Imagination, is a dying sense ; and what hinders us from say- ing, with Reid, that Memory is an immediate (=non-mediate) knowledge of the past? It seems to us that Hamilton is here crossing a shadow of the Absolute, and that the question may in part be redargued from his own ground of Relativity. We do not mean that Sir William is wrong in making a distinction between Presentative and Representative knowledge, but that the line of demarkation might be shifted. We here speak briefly, and only to the initiated ; and regret that these sheets are passing so rapidly through the press that we cannot discuss the question at some length, for it is one of the most important in philosophy. W. PHILOSOPHY OF PERCEPTION. 249 object of an intuitive, but only as the remote object of a repre- sentative cognition. 13. A representative object, considered irrespectively of what it represents, and simply as a mode of the conscious subject, is an intuitive or presentative object. For it is known in itself, as a mental mode, actually existing now and here.* * Propositions 10-13 may illustrate a passage in Aristotle's treatise on Memory and Reminiscence (c. 1), which has been often curiously misunder- stood by his expositors ; and as it, in return, serves to illustrate the doctrin* here stated, I translate it : ' Of what part of the soul memory is a function, is manifest ; of that, to wit, of which imagination or phantasy is a function. [And imagination had been already shown to be a function of the common sense.] ' And here a doubt may be started Whether the affection [or mental modification] being present, the reality absent, that what is not present can be remembered [or, in general, known]. For it is manifest that we must conceive the aifection, determined in the soul or its proximate bodily organ, through sense, to be, as it were, a sort of portrait, of which we say that memory is the habit [or retention]. For the movement excited [to employ the simile of Plato] stamps, as it were, a kind of impression of the total pro- cess of perception! [on the soul or its organ], after the manner of one who applies a signet to wax. . . . ' But if such be the circumstances of memory Is remembrance [a cogni- tion] of this affection, or of that from which it is produced? For, if of the latter, we can have no remembrance [or cognition] of things absent ; if of the former, how, as percipient [or conscious of this present affection], can we have a remembrance [or cognition] of that of which we are not percipient [or conscious] the absent [reality] ? Again,! supposing there to be a resem- bling something, such as an impression or picture, in the mind ; the percep- tion [or consciousness] of this Why should it be the remembrance [or cog- nition] of another thing, and not of this something itself? for in the act of remembrance we contemplate this mental affection, and of this [alone] are we percipient [or conscious]. In these circumstances, how is a remembrance [or cognition] possible of what is not present ? For if so, it would seem that what is not present might, in like manner, be seen and heard. ' Or is this possible, and what actually occurs ? And thus : As in a por- trait the thing painted is an animal, and a representation (tMv) [of an ani- mal], one and the same being, at once, both (for, though in reality both are not the same, in thought we can view the painting, either [absolutely] as animal, or [relatively] as representation [of an animal]) ; in like manner, the phantasm in us, we must consider, both absolutely, as a phenomenon (Oeu- t AitrOtipaTos : this comprehends both the objective presentation atVOi/rdv, 8eep.m W. 282 PHILOSOPHY OF PERCEPTION. And he does this, emphatically too. Speaking of the Perception of the external world: 'We have here a remarkable conflict between two contradictory opinions, wherein all mankind are engaged. On the one side stand all the vulgar, who are unprac- tised in philosophical researches, and guided by the uncorrupted primary instincts of nature. On the other side, stand all the philosophers, ancient and modern ; every man, without excep- tion, who reflects. In this division, to my great humiliation, I find myself classed with the vulgar? (I. P. 302 b.) 4. All philosophers agree that self-consciousness is an imme- diate knowledge, and therefore affords an absolute and direct cer- tainty of the existence of its objects. Reid (with whom conscious- ness is equivalent to self-consciousness) of course maintains this ; but he also maintains, not only that perception affords a sufficient proof, but as valid an assurance of the reality of material phe- nomena, as consciousness does of the reality of mental. (I. P. 263 b, 269 a, 373, et alibi.) In this last assertion I have shown that Reid (and Stewart along with him) is wrong ; for the phe- nomena of self-consciousness cannot possibly be doubted or denied ;' but the statement at least tends to prove that his per- ception is truly immediate is, under a different name, a con- sciousness of the non-ego. 5. Arnauld's doctrine of external perception is a purely ego- istical representationism ; and he has stated its conditions and consequences with the utmost accuracy and precision. (I. P. 295-298.) Reid expresses both his content and discontent with Arnauld's theory of perception, which he erroneously views as inconsistent with itself (297 a b). This plainly shows that he had not realized to himself a clear conception of the two doctrines of Presentationism and Egoistical Representationism, in them- seives and in their contrasts. But it also proves that when the conditions and consequences of the latter scheme, even in its purest form, were explicitly enounced, that he was then suffi- 1 See Part First. W. PHILOSOPHY OF PERCEPTION. 283 ciently aware of their incompatibility with the doctrine which he himself maintained a doctrine, therefore, it may be fairly con- tended (though not in his hands clearly understood, far less articulately developed), substantially one of Natural Realism.* To Reid's inadequate discrimination common to him with other philosophers of the different theories of Perception, either as possible in theory, or as actually held, is, as I have already noticed, to be ascribed the ambiguities and virtual contradictions which we have now been considering. In the first place (what was of little importance to the Hypo- thetical, but indispensably necessary for the Natural Realist), he did not establish the fact of the two cognitions, the presentative and representative ; signalize their contents ; evolve their sev- eral conditions ; consider what faculties in general were to be referred to each ; and, in particular, which of these was the kind of condition competent, in our Perception of the external world. In the second place, he did not take note, that representation is possible under two forms the egoistical and non-egoistical ; each, if Perception be reduced to a representative faculty, afford- ing premises of equal cogency to the absolute idealist and skep- tic. On the contrary, he seems to have overlooked the egoistical form of representationism altogether (compare Inq. 106 a, 128 a b, 130 b, 210 a, I. P. 226 a b, 256 a b, 257 a b, 269 a, 274 a, * It will be observed that I do not found any argument on Reid's frequent assertion, that perception affords an immediate knowledge and immediate belief of external things (e. g. I. P. 259 b, 260 a b, 267 a, 809 b, 326 b). For if h'c call memory an immediate knowledge of the past meaning thereby, in ref- erence to it, only a negation of the doctrine of non-egoistical representation, he may also call Perception an immediate knowledge of the outward reality, and still not deny that it is representative cognition, in and by the mind itself. 284 PHILOSOPHY OF PERCEPTION. 277 b, 278 a b, 293 b, 299 a, 318 b, 427 a b) ; and confounded it either with the non-egoistical form, or with the counter doc- trine of real presentatiomsm. In consequence of this, he has been betrayed into sundry errors, of less or greater account. On the one hand ; to the confusion of Presentationism and Non-ego- istical representationism, we must attribute the inconsistencies we have just signalized, in the exposition of his own doctrine. These are of principal account. On the other hand ; to the confusion of Egoistical and Non-egoistical representationism, we must refer the less important errors; 1, of viewing many philosophers who held the former doctrine, as holding the latter ; and 2, of considering the refutation of the non-egoistical form of represen- tation, as a subversion of the only ground on which the skeptic and absolute idealist established, or could establish their conclu- sions. CHAPTER IV. 1 DOCTRINE OF PERCEPTION MAINTAINED BY THE ABSOLUTE IDEALISTS. DISCUSSION ON THE SCHEME OF ARTHUR COL- LIER. WE deem it our duty to call attention to these publications : s for in themselves they are eminently deserving of the notice of the few who in this country take an interest in those higher spec- ulations to which, in other countries, the name of Philosophy is exclusively conceded ; and, at the same time, they have not been ushered into the world with those adventitious recommendations which might secure their intrinsic merit against neglect. The fortune of the first is curious. It is known to those who have made an active study of philosophy and its histoiy, that there are many philosophical treatises written by English authors in whole or in part of great value, but, at the same time, of extreme rarity. Of these, the rarest are, in fact, frequently the most original : for precisely in proportion as an author is in ad- vance of his age, is it likely that his works will be neglected ; and the neglect of contemporaries in general consigns a book, espe- cially a small book; if not protected by accidental concomitants, 1 This was first published in the Edinburgh Review, for April, 1839, and has recently been published in the ' Discussions,' under the title of Idealism. That portion of it which shows that Catholicism is inconsistent with Ideal- ism is a new, and very important, contribution to the history of philosophy. It also does justice to the name of an almost forgotten idealist, who was scarcely inferior to Berkeley himself. W. a The following are the titles of the books reviewed : 1. Metaphysical Tracts by English Philosophers of the Eighteenth Century. Prepared for the Press by the late Rev. Sam. Parr, D. D. 8vo. London. 1837. 2. Memoirs of the Life and Writings of the Rev. Arthur Collier, M. A., Rector of Langford MagrM, in the County of Wilts. From A. D. 1704 to A. D. 1732. With some Account of his Family. By Robert Benson, M. A. 8vo. London. 1887. W. 286 PHILOSOPHY OF PERCEPTION. at once to the tobacconist or tallow-chandler. This is more par- ticularly the case with pamphlets, philosophical, and at the same time polemical. Of these we are acquainted with some, extant perhaps only in one or two copies, which display a metaphysical talent unappreciated in a former age, but which would command the admiration of the present. Nay, even of English philoso- phers of the very highest note (strange to say !) there are now actually lying unknown to their editors, biographers, and fellow- metaphysicians, published treatises, of the highest interest and importance : [as of Cudworth, Berkeley, Collins, e more properly ideas accompanying the sensations of Sight and Touch than the sensations of either of these senses' only, mediately or immediately, repeats Aristotle ; to whom is therefore due all the praise which has been lavished on the originality and importance of the observation. [I might have added, however, that Hutcheson does not claim it as his own. 1 For in his System of Moral Philosophy (which is to be That certain motions raised in our bodies are, by a general law, constituted the occasion of perceptions in the mind. (2) These perceptions never come entirely alone, but have some other perception joined with them. Thus every sensation is accompanied with the idea of Duration, and yet duration is not a sensible idea, since it also accompanies ideas of internal consciousness or reflection: so the idea of Number may accompany any sensible ideas, and yet may also accompany any other ideas, as well as external sensations. Brutes, when several objects are before them, have probably all the proper ideas of sight which we have, without the idea of number. (S ) Some ideas are found accompanying the most different sensations, which yet are not to be perceived separately from some sensible quality. Such are Extension, Figure, Motion and Rest, which accompany the ideas of Sight or Colors, and yet may be perceived without them, as in the ideas of Touch, at least if we move our organs along the part* of the body touched. Extension, Figure, Motion, or Rest, seem, therefore to be more properly called ideas accompanying the sen-nations of Sight and Touch, than the sensations of either of these senses; since they can be received sometimes without the ideas of Color, and sometimes without those of Touching, though never without the one or the other. The perceptions which are purely sensible, received each by its proper sense, are Tastes, Smells, Colors, Sound, Cold, Heat, fcc. The universal concomitant ideas which may attend any idea whatsoever, are Duration and Number. The ideas which accompany the most different sensations, are Extension, Figure, Motion, and Rest, These all arise without any previous ideas assembled or compared the concomitant ideas are reputed images o/ something external.'' Sect I., Art 1. The reader may, likewise consult the same author's 'Synopsis Metaphysicte,' Part II., cap. I., 8. W. ' Hamilton says, refering to the passage from Hutcheson: 'But here I may observe, in the first place, that the statement made in the preceding quotation (and still more articulately in the "Synopsis"), that Duration or Time is the inseparable concomitant both of sense and reflection, had been also made by Aristotle and many other philoso- phers; and it is indeed curious how long philosophers were on the verge of enunciating the great doctrine first proclaimed by Kant that Time is a fundamental condition, form, or category of thought In the second place, I may notice that Hutcheson is not entitled to the praise accorded him by Stewart and Royer-Collard for his originality in " the fine and important observation that Extension, Figure, Motion, and Rest, arc- rather ideas accompanying the perceptions of touch and vision, than perceptions of these senses, properly so called." In this, he seems only to have, with others, repeated Aris- totle, who, in his treatise on the Soul (Book II., Ch. 6, Text 64, and Book III., Ch. 1. Text 186), calls Motion and Rest, Magnitude (Extension), Figure, and Number (Hutcheson's very list), the common concomitants ( gives a full and formal list ot the Tactile qualities. In his treatise De Homine, under the special doctrine of Touch ( 29, 30) wo, have Pain, Titillation, Smoothness, Roughness, Heat, Cold, Humidity, Dryness, Weight, ' and the like. 1 He probably acquiesced in the Aristotelic list, the one in general acceptation, viz., the Hot and Cold, Dry and Moist, Heavy and Light, Hard and Soft, Viscid and Friable, Rough and Smooth, Thick and Thin. De Gen. et Corr. ii. 2. PHILOSOPHY OF PERCEPTION. 323 they are considered as residing in the objects themselves of our sensations, Descartes, like Democritus and Galileo, held to be only modifications of those contained under the former. ' Exceptis Magnitudine, Figura et Motu, quse qualia sint in unoquoque cor- pore explicui, nihil extra nos positum sentitur nisi Lumen, Color, Odor, Sapor, Sonus, et Tactiles qualitates ; quse nihil aliud esse in objectis, quam dispositions quasdam in Magnitudine, Figura et Motu consistentes, hactenus est demonstratum. (Princ. P. iv. 199. Med. Resp. vi. p. 194.) This distinction, by their mas- ter, of the two classes of quality, was, as we shall see, associated by the Cartesians with another, taken by themselves, between Idea and Sensation. I have previously shown, that Aristotle expressly recognizes the coincidence of his own distinction of the proper and common sen- sibles with the Democritean distinction of the apparent and real properties of body. I have now to state that Descartes was also manifestly aware of the conformity of his distinction with those of Aristotle and Democritus. Sufficient evidence, I think, will be found of the former, in the Principia, P. iv. 200, and De Ho- mine, 42 ; of the latter, in the Principia, P. iv. 200- 203. All this enhances the marvel, that the identity of these famous classifications should have hitherto been entirely over- looked. 10. The doctrine of DERODON an acute and independent thinker, who died in 1664 coincides with that of Aristotle and his genuine school ; it is very distinctly and correctly expressed. Sensible qualities, he says, may be considered in two aspects ; as they are in the sensible object, and as they are in the sentient ani- mal. As in the latter, they exist actually and formally, consti- tuting certain affections agreeable or disagreeable, in a word, sen- sations of such or such a character. The feeling of Heat is an example. As in the former, they exist only virtually or poten- tially ; for, correctly speaking, the fire does not contain heat, and is, therefore, not hot, but only capable of heating. ' Ignis itaque, proprie loquendo, non habere calorem, atque adeo non esse calidum 324 PHILOSOPHY OF PERCEPTION. sed calorificum ;* nisi vocabalum caloris sumatur pro virtute pro- ducendi calorem in animali. Scd pliilosophi (he refers to the scho- lastic Aristotelians with their substantial Forms, and Intention- al Species, though among them were exceptions) sed pliilosophi sunt prorsus inexcusabiles, qui volunt calorem, sumptum pro vir- tute calefaciendi, quse est in igne, aut potius identificatur cum ipso igne, et calorem productum in animali, esse ejusdem speciei, na- turae et essentisD ; nam calor moderatus productus in animali con- sistit iu aliqua passione et quasi titillatione grata quse sentitur ab animali, qua3 passio non potest esse in igne.' And so forth in re- gard to the other senses. (Philos. Coutr. Phys., p. 190.) 11. I may adduce to the same purport GLANVILLE, who, in his 'Vanity of Dogmatizing' (1661, p. 88 sq.), and in his 'Scepsis Scientifica' (1665, p. 65 sq.), though a professed, and not over- scrupulous antagonist of Aristotle, acknowledges, in reference to the present question, that ' the Peripatetic philosophy teaches us, that Heat is not in the body of the sun, as formally considered, but only virtually, and as in its cause.' I do not know whether Glanville had Aquinas specially in view ; but the same general statement and particular example are to be found in the Summa contra Gentes, L. i. cc. 29, 31, of the Angelic Doctor. 12. It is remarkable that Mr. BOYLE'S speculations in regard to the classification of corporeal Qualities should have been wholly overlooked in reference to the present subject ; and this not only on account of their intrinsic importance, but because they proba- bly suggested to Locke the nomenclature which he has adopted, but, in adopting, has deformed. In his treatise entitled ' The origin of Forms and Qualities,' published at Oxford in 1666, Boyle denominates 'Matter and Mo- tion' ' the most Catholic Principles of bodies.' (P. 8.) ' Magni- tude (Size, Bulk, or Bigness), Shape (Figure), Motion or Rest,' to * The chemists have called Caloric what they ought to have called Calo- rific. The Lavoiserian nomenclature, whatever it merits in other respects, is a system of philological monstrosities, in which it is fortunate when the analogies of language are only violated, and not reversed. PHILOSOPHY OF PERCEPTION. 325 which he afterwards adds ' Texture,' he styles ' the Primitive Moods or Primary Affections of bodies, to distinguish them from those less simple Qualities (as Colors, Tastes, Odors, and the like) that belong to bodies upon their account' (p. 10). The former of these, he likewise designates ' the Primitive or more Catholic Affections of Matter 1 (pp. 43, 44) ; and in another work (Tracts 1671, p. 18), l the Primary and most Simple Affections of Mat- ter.' 1 To the latter he gives the name of ' Secondary Qualities, if (he says) I may so call them' (p. 44). In reference to the difficulty, ' That whereas we explicate colors, odors, and the like sensible qualities, by a relation to our senses, it seems evident that they have an absolute being irrelative to us ; for snow (for instance) would be white, and a glowing coal would be hot, though there were no man or any other animal in the world' (p. 42). And again (p. 49) : ' So if there were no sen- sitive Beings, those bodies that are now the objects of our senses, would be so dispositively, if I may so speak, endowed with Colors, Tastes, and the like, but actually only with those more catholic affections of bodies, Figure, Motion, Texture, &c.' Is this intend- ed for an Aristotelic qualification of the Democritean paradox of Galileo ? In his Tracts, published at Oxford, 1671 in that entitled ' His- tory of particular Qualities,' he says : ' I shall not inquire into the several significations of the word Quality, which is used in such various senses, as to make it ambiguous enough. But thus much I think it not amiss to intimate, that there are some things that have been looked upon as Qualities, which ought rather to be looked on as States of Matter or complexions of particular Qualities ; as animal, inanimal, ' four<3. Locke is therefore wrong, really and verbally. Really he is wrong, in dis- tinguishing trinal extension and impenetrability (or ultimate incompressibil- ity) as two primary and separate attributes, instead of regarding them only as one-sided aspects of the same primary and total attribute the occu- pying of space. Each supposes the other. The notion of a thing trinally extended, eo ipso, excludes the negation of such extension. It therefore includes the negation of that negation. Bat this is just the assertion of its ultimate incompressibility. Again, the notion of a thing as ultimately incompressible, is only possible under the notion of its trinal extension. For body being, ex hypothesi, conceived or conceivable only as that which occupies space ; the final compression of it into what occupies no space, goes to reduce it, either from an entity to a non-entity, or from an extended to an unextended entity. But neither alternative can be realized in thought. Not the former ; i'or annihilation, not as a mere change in an effect, not as a mere resumption of creative power in a cause, but as a taking out from the sum total of existence, is positively and in itself incogitable. Not the latter; for the conception of matter, as an unextended entity, is both in itself inconceiv- able, and ex hypothesi absurd. Verbally, Locke is wrong, in bestowing the name of solidity, without a qualification, exclusively on the latter of these two phases ; each being equally entitled to it with the other, and neither so well entitled to it, without a difference, as the total attribute of which they are the partial expressions. But these inaccuracies of Locke are not so important as the errors of subsequent philosophers, to which, however, they 1 See below, p. 356. W. 336 PHILOSOPHY OF PEKOEPTION. a separate class, is that the mind finds it impossible to think any particle of matter, as divested of such attributes. Remark. In this criterion Locke was preceded by Galileo. seem to have afforded the occasion. For under the term Solidity, and on the authority of Locke, there have been introduced as primary, certain qualities of body to which in common language the epithet Solid is applied, but which have no title whatever to the rank in question. Against this abuse, it must be acknowledged, Locke not only guarded himself, but even to a certain extent, cautioned others ; for he articulately states that Solidity, in his sense, is not to be confounded with Hardness. (B. ii. c. 4, 4.) It must, however, also be confessed, that in other passages he seems to iden- tify Solidity and Cohesion ; while on Solidity he, at the same time, makes ' the mutual impulse, resistance and protrusion of bodies to depend.' (Ibid. 5.) But I am anticipating. In a psychological point of view and this is that of Locke and metaphysicians in general no attribute of body is primary which is not necessary in thought; that is, which is not necessarily evolved out of, as necessarily implied in, the very notion of body. And such is Solidity in the one total and the two partial significations heretofore enu- merated. But in its physical application, this term is not always limited to denote the ultimate incompressibility of matter. Besides that necessary attribute, it is extended, in common language, to express other powers of resistance in bodies of a character merely contingent in reference to thought. (See ii.) These may be reduced to the five following : Fourth Meaning. The term Solid is very commonly employed to denote not merely the absolutely, but also the relatively incompressible, the Dense, in contrast to the relatively compressible, the Eare, or Hollow. (In Latin, moreover, Solldus was not only employed, in this sense, to denote that a thing fully occupied the space comprehended within its circumference ; but likewise to indicate, 1, its entireness in quantity that it was whole or com- plete ; and, 2, its entireness in quality that it was pure, uniform, homoge- neous. This arose from the original identity of the Latin Kolidum with the Oscan sollum or solam, and the Greek oW. See Festus or Verrius Floccns, vv. Solitavrilia and Sotto ; also J. C. Scaliger, De Subtilitate, ex. 76.) Fifth Meaning. Under the Vis Inertia, a body is said to be Solid, i. e. Inert, Stable, Immovable, in proportion as it, whether in motion or at rest, resists, in general, a removal from the place it would otherwise occupy in space. Sixth Meaning. Under Gravity, & body is said to be Solid, i. e. Heavy, in proportion as it resists, in particular, a displacement by being lifted up. The two following meanings fall under Cohesion, the force with which matter resists the distraction of its parts ; for a body is said in a Seventh Meaning, to be Solid, i. e. Hard, in contrast to Soft ; and in &n Eighth Meaning, to be Solid, i. e. Concrete, in opposition to Fluid. The term Solidity thus denotes besides the absolute and necessary prop- erty of occupying space, simply and in its two phases of Extension and Im- penetrability, also the relative and contingent qualities of the Dense, the PHILOSOPHY OF PERCEPTION. 337 Bat it does not, alone, suffice to discriminate the primary from the secondary qualities. For, as already noticed, of two contra- dictory qualities, one or other must, on the logical principle of ex- cluded 1 middle, be attributed to every object. Thus, odorous or inodorous, sapid or tasteless, &c., though not primary qualities, cannot both be abstracted in thought from any material object ; and, to take a stronger example, color, which, psychologically speaking, contains within itself such contradictions (for light and darkness, white and black, are, in this relation, all equally colors) is thus a necessary concomitant of every perception, and even every imagination, of extended substance ; as has been observed by the Pythagoreans, Aristotle, Themistius, and many others. e. These attributes really exist in the objects, as they are ideally represented to our minds. Remark, In this statement Locke followed Descartes ; but without the important qualification, necessary to its accuracy, under which Descartes advances it. On the doctrine of both phi- losophers, we know nothing of material existence in itself; we know it only as represented or in idea. When Locke, therefore, is asked, how he became aware that the known idea truly repre- sents the unknown reality ; he can make no answer. On the first principles of his philosophy, he is wholly and necessarily ignorant, whether the idea does, or does not, represent to his mind the attributes of matter, as they exist in nature. His as- sertion is, therefore, confessedly without a warrant ; it transcends, Inert, the Heavy, the Hard, the Concrete ; and the introduction of these lat- ter, with their correlative opposite^, into the list of Primary Qualities was facilitated, if not prepared, by Locke's vacillating employment of the vague expression Solid; in partial designation of the former. By Kaines, accord- ingly, Gravity and Inertia were elevated to this rank ; while Cohesion, in its various modifications and degrees, was, by Kames, Eeid, Fergusson, Stew- art, Royer-Collard, and many others, not only recognized as Primary, but expressly so recognized as in conformity with the doctrine of Locke. See the sequel of this and ii. 1 It is an axiom in Logic, that of two contradictory propositions, if one be false, the other must be true. This is called the principle of Excluded Mid- dle; i. e. between two contradictories. W. 15 333 PHILOSOPHY OF PERCEPTION. ex hypothesi, the sphere of possible knowledge. Descartes is more cautious. He only says, that our ideas of the qualities in question represent those qualities as they are, or as they may ex- ist ; ' ut suut, vel saltern esse possunt.' The Cosmothetic Ideal- ist can only assert to them a problematical reality. f. To the second class belong those qualities which, as in ob- jects themselves, are nothing but various occult modifications of the qualities of the former class ; these modifications possessing, however, the power of determining certain manifest sensations or ideas in us. Such, for example, are colors, sounds, tastes, smells, &c., all, in a word, commonly known by the name of Sensible Qualities. These qualities, as in the reality, are properly only powers ; powers to produce certain sensations in us. As in us, they are only sensations, and cannot, therefore, be considered as attributes of external things. Remark. All this had, long before Locke, become mere philo- sophical commonplace. With the exception of the dogmatical assertion of the hypothetical fact, that the subjective sensations of the secondary depend exclusively on the objective modifica- tions of the primary qualities, this whole doctrine is maintained by Aristotle ; while that hypothetical assertion itself had been ad- vanced by the ancient Atomists and their followers the Epicure- ans, by Galileo, by Descartes and his school, by Boyle, and by modern philosophers in general. That the secondary qualities, as in objects, are only powers of producing sensations in us this, as we have seen, has been explicitly stated, after Aristotle, by al- most every theorist on the subject. But it was probably borrow- ed by Locke from the Cartesians. It is not to be forgotten, that Locke did not observe the pro- priety of language introduced by the Cartesians, of employing the term Idea, in relation to the primary, the term Sensation, in relation to the secondary, qualities. Indeed Locke's whole philo- sophical language is beyond measure vague, vacillating, and am- biguous ; in this respect, he has afforded the worst of precedents, and has found only too many among us to follow his example. PHILOSOPHY OF PERCEPTION. 339 20. PURCHOT'S doctrine on this subject deserves to be no- ticed which it never has been. It struck me from its corres- pondence, in certain respects, with that which I had myself pre- viously thought out. The first edition of his Institutiones Philo- sophicae did not appear at Paris until a year or two after the pub- lication of Locke's Essay, the second was in 1698; but the French cursualist does not appear to have been aware of the spec- ulations of the English philosopher, nor does he refer to Boyle. His doctrine which is not fully stated in any single place of his work is as follows : a. The one Primary Affection or Attribute of Body is Exten- sion. Without this, matter cannot be conceived. But in the notion of Extension as an attribute is immediately involved that of Solidity or Impenetrability, i. e. the capacity of filling space to the exclusion of another body. b. But extended substance (eo ipso, solid or impenetrable) 1", Necessarily exists under some particular mode of Extension, in other words, it has a certain magnitude ; and is Divisible into parts ; 2, Is necessarily thought as capable of Motion and Rest ; 3, Necessarily supposes a certain Figure ; and in relation to other bodies a certain Position ; These five, 1, Magnitude or measure of extension, involving Divisibility ; 2, Motion ; 3, Rest ; 4, Figure ; 5, Position or Situation,^ styles the simple and secondary attributes, affections, or qualities which flow immediately from the nature of Body, i. e. Extension. c. Out of these Primary Affections of Body there are educed, and as it were compounded, other affections to which the name of Quality in a more emphatic and appropriate sense belongs ; such among others are Light, Colors, Sounds, Odors, Tastes, and the Tactile qualities, Heat, Cold, Moisture, Dryness, &c. These he denominates the secondary and composite qualities or affections of Body. (Instit. Philos. t ii. Phys. Sectt. i. iv. v. pp. 87, 205, 396, ed. 4.) 340 PHILOSOPHY OF PERCEPTION. 21. LE CLERC does not borrow his doctrine on this head from his friend Locke ; and his point of view is not purely pschycologi- cal. The five properties common to all bodies Extension Di- visibility Solidity (Impenetrability) Figure Mobility he very properly does not denominate Qualities, but reserves that name for what serves to distinguish bodies from each other. Un- der this restriction, he divides Qualities into Primitive and Deriv- ative. By Primitive he designates those occult qualities in body which are known to us only in their effects ; as, for example, the cause of Solidity. The Derivative, he says, are those which flow from the Primitive and affect our senses, as color, savor, odor, &c. His doctrine is, however, neither fully evolved nor unambig- uously expressed. (Clerici Opera Philos. Phys., L. v. cc. 1, 6.) 22. LORD KAMES, in the first edition of his ' Essays on the principles of Morality and Natural Religion,' (1751), touches only incidentally on the present subject. He enumerates Softness, Hardness, Smoothness, Roughness, among the Primary Qualities (p. 248) ; and he was, I am confident, the only philosopher be- fore Reid, by whom this amplification was sanctioned, although Mr. Stewart has asserted that herein Reid only followed the clas- sification of most of his immediate predecessors.* (Essays, p. 91.) The second edition I have not at hand. In the third and last (1779), there is introduced a chapter expressly on the distinction, which is treated of 'in detail. He does not here repeat his previous enumeration ; but to Size, Figure, Solidity (which he does not define), and Divisibility, he adds, as primary qualities, Gravity, the Vis Inertice, and the Vis Incita ; the two last being the Vis Incita or Vis Inertine of Kepler and Newton divided into a double power. See Reid's Correspondence, pp. 55, 56. Eames unwittingly mixes the psychological and physical * Mr. Stewart also says that Berkeley ' employs the word Soliditity as synonymous with Hardness and Resistance.' This is not correct. Berkeley does not consider hardness and resistance as convertible; and these he mentions as two only out of three significations in which, he thinks, the term Solidity is used. PHILOSOPHY OF PERCEPTION. 341 points of view ; and otherwise, his classification in so far as origi- nal, is open to manifold objections. See the foot-note * at p. 334 c. and ii. 23. REID. We have seen that Descartes and Locke, to say nothing of other metaphysicians, admitted a fundamental differ- ence between the primary and the secondary qualities: the one problematically, the other assertorily, maintaining, that the pri- mary qualities, as known, correspond with the primary qualities, as existent : whereas that the secondary qualities, as sensations in us, bear no analogy to these qualities as inherent in matter. On the general doctrine, however, of these philosophers, both classes of qualities, as known, are confessedly only states of our own minds ; and, while we have no right from a subjective affection to infer the existence, far less the corresponding character of the existence, of any objective reality, it is evident that their doctrine, if fairly evolved, would result in a dogmatic, or in a skeptical, negation of the primary, no less than of the secondary qualities of body, as more than appearances in and for us. This evolution was ac- cordingly soon accomplished ; and Leibnitz, Berkeley, Hume, Condillac, Kant, Fichte, and others, found no difficulty in demon- strating, on the principles of Descartes, and Locke, and modern Representation] sts in general, that our notions of Space or Exten- sion, with its subordinate forms of Figure, Motion, &c., has no higher title to be recognized as objectively valid, than our sensa- tions of Color, of Savor, of Odor ; and were thus enabled tri- umphantly to establish their several schemes of formal or virtual idealism. Hence may we explain the fact that this celebrated distinction is overlooked or superseded in the speculation, not of some merely, but of all the more modern German Schools. It is therefore manifest that the fundamental position of a con- sistent theory of dualistic realism is that our cognitions of Ex- tension and its modes are not wholly ideal ; that although Space be a native, necessary, a priori, form of imagination, and so far, therefore, a mere subjective state, that there is, at the same time, competent to us, in an immediate perception of external things, 342 PHILOSOPHY OF PERCEPTION. the consciousness of a really existent, of a really objective ex- tended world. To demonstrate this was therefore prescribed, as its primary problem to a philosophy which, like that of Reid, proposed to re-establish the philosophy of natural realism of common sense, on a refutation of every idealism overt or implied. Such is the problem. It remains for us to see how it was dealt with. Reid's doctrine, in regard to the Primary and Secondary Qual- ities, is to be found in the Inquiry, ch. 5, sect. 46, p. 123-126, and in the Intellectual Powers, Essay ii. ch. 17, p. 313-318. In his enumeration of the Primary qualities Reid is not invari- able; for the list in the Inquiry is not identical with that in the Essays. In the former, without professing to furnish an exhaust- ive catalogue, he enumerates Extension, Figure, Motion, Hard- ness and Softness, Roughness and Smoothness. The four last are, as we have seen, to be found, for the first time, in the earliest edi- tion of Lord Kames's Essays on Morality, which preceded Reid's Inquiry by thirteen years. In the latter he gives another list, which he does not state to be an altered edition of his own, but which he apparently proposes as an enumeration identical with Locke's. ' Every one,' he says, ' knows that Extension, Divisibil- ity, Figure, Motion, Solidity, Hardness, Softness, and Fluidity, were by Locke called primary qualities of body.' In reference to himself this second catalogue omits Roughness and Smoothness, which were contained in his first : and introduces, what were omitted in the first, Divisibility (which Kames had also latterly added), Solidity, and Fluidity. In reference to Locke this and the former list are both very different from his. For, allowing Divisibility to replace Number, and say nothing in regard, either to the verbal inaccuracy of making Motion stand for Mobility, or to the real inaccuracy of omitting Rest as the alternative of Mo- tion ; we find in both lists a series of qualities unrecognized as primary by Locke ; or, as far as I know, by any other philosopher previous to Lord Kames and himself. These are Roughness and Smoothness in the Inquiry ; Fluidity in the Essays ; and Hard- PHILOSOPHY OF PERCEPTION. 343 ness and Softness in both. But these five qualities are not only not to be ascribed to the list of primary qualities by Locke ; they ought not to be viewed as co-ordinate with Extension, Solidity (which Reid more rigorously than Locke limits to the ultimate in- compressibility of matter), Figure, Mobility, and Divisibility, i. e. not as primary qualities at all. Of these five qualities, the last three, as he himself states (p. 314 a), are only different degrees of Cohesion ; and the first two are only modifications of Figure and Cohesion combined. But Cohesion, as will be shown ( ii.), is not a character necessarily involved in our notion of body ; for though Cohesion (and we may say the same of Inertia), in all its modes, necessarily supposes the occupation of space, the occupa- tion of space while it implies a continuity does not necessarily imply a cohesion of the elements (whatever they may be) of that which occupies space. At the same time, the various resistances of cohesion and of inertia cannot be reduced to the class of Sec- ondary qualities. It behooves us therefore, neither with Locke and others, to overlook them ; nor to throw them in without qualification or remark, either with Descartes among the Second- ary, or with Reid among the Primary, qualities. But of this again. Independently of these minor differences, and laying also out of account Reid's strictures on the cruder forms of the represen- tative hypothesis, as held by Descartes and Locke, but which there is no sufficient ground to suppose that Descartes, at least, adopted ; Reid's doctrine touching the present distinction cor- responds, in all essential respects, with that maintained by these two philosophers. He does not adopt, and even omits to notice, the erroneous criterion of inseparability in thought, by which Locke attempts to discriminate the primary qualities from the secondary. Like Descartes, he holds that our notions of the pri- mary qualities are clear and distinct ; of the secondary, obscure and confused ; and, like both philosophers, he considers that the former afford us a knowledge of what the corresponding qualities are (or, as Descartes cautiously interpolates, may be) in themselves, 344 PHILOSOPHY OF PERCEPTION. while the latter only point to the unknown cause or occasion of sensations of which we are conscious ourselves. Reid therefore calls the notion we have of the primary qualities, direct ; of the secondary, relative. (I. P. 313 b.) On this subject there is, thus, no important difference of opinion between the three philoso- phers. For if we modify the obnoxious language of Descartes and Locke ; and, instead of saying that the ideas or notions of the primary qualities resemble, raerely assert that they truly rep- resent, their objects, that is, afford us such a knowledge of their nature as we should have were an immediate intuition of the ex- tended reality in itself competent to man, and this is certainly all that one, probably all that either philosopher, intended, Reid's doctrine and theirs would be found in perfect unison. The whole difficulty and dispute on this point is solved on the old distinction of similarity in existences and similarity in representation, which Reid and our more modern philosophers have overlooked. Touch- ing this, see, as stated above, the doctrine of those Schoolmen who held the hypothesis of species (p. 257 a b) ; and of those others who, equally with Reid, rejected all representative entities different from the act itself of cognition (p. 257 b. note). But much more than this was called for at Reid's hands. His philosophy, if that of Natural Realism, founded in the common sense of mankind, made it incumbent on him to show, that we have not merely a notion, a conception, an imagination, a sub- jective representation of Extension, for example, 'called up or suggested? in some incomprehensible manner to the mind, on oc- casion of an extended object being presented to the sense ; but that in the perception of such an object, we really have, as by nature we believe we have, an immediate knowledge or conscious- ness of that external object, as extended. In a word, that in sen- sitive perception the extension, as known, and the extension, as existing, are convertible ; known, because existing, and existing, since known. Reid, however, unfortunately, did not accomplish did not at- tempt this. He makes no articulate statement, even, that in per- PHILOSOPHY OF PERCEPTION. 345 ception we have an immediate knowledge an objective conscious- ness, of an extended non-ego, actually existing ; as in imagina- tion we have a subjective consciousness of a mode of the ego, rep- resenting such an extended non-ego, and thereby affording us a mediate knowledge of it as possibly existing. On the contrary were we to interpret his expressions rigidly, and not in liberal con- formity with the general analogy of his philosophy, we might, as repeatedly noticed, found on the terms in which he states his doc- trine of the primary qualities, and, in particular, his doctrine con- cerning our cognition of extension, a plausible argument that his own theory of perception is as purely subjective, and therefore as easily reducible to an absolute Idealism, as that of any of the philosophers whom he controverts. Thus when Reid, for example (Inq. 123 b), states 'that Exten- sion ' is a quality suggested to us by certain sensations,' i. e. by certain merely subjective affections ; and when (324 b) he says that Space [Extension] whether tangible or visible, is not so properly an object of sense as a necessary concomitant * of the objects both of sight and touch ;' he apparently denies us all im- mediate perception of any extended reality. But if we are not percipient of any extended reality, we are not percipient of body as existing ; for body exists, and can only be known immediately and in itself, as extended. The material world, on this supposi- tion, sinks into something unknown and problematical ; and its existence, if not denied, can, at best, be only precariously affirmed, as the occult cause, or incomprehensible occasion, of certain sub- jective affections we experience in the form, either of a sensation of the secondary quality, or of a perception of the primary. 1 'According to Eeid, Extension (Space) ia a notion a posteriori, the result of experience. According to Kant, it is a priori; experience only affording the occasions required by the mind to exert the facts, of which the intuition of space is a condition. To the former it is thus a contingent: to the latter, a necessary mental possession.' W. * ' It seemingly requires but little to rise to Kant's view of the conception of space as an a, priori, or native form of thought.' W. 15* 34:6 PHILOSOPHY OF PERCEPTION. Thus interpreted, what is there to distinguish the doctrine of Reid from the undeveloped idealism of Descartes or of Kant ? ' Having noticed the manifest incongruity of Reid's doctrine on this point with the grand aim of his philosophy, an incongruity which I am surprised has not been long ago adverted to either by friend or foe, I may take this opportunity of modifying a former statement (p. 123 b, note*), 8 that, according to Reid, Space is a notion a posteriori, the result of experience. On re- considering more carefully his different statements on this subject (Inq. 123 sq. I. P. 324 sq.), I am now inclined to think that his language implies no more than the chronological posteriority of this notion ; and that he really held it to be a native, necessary, a priori form of thought, requiring only certain prerequisite condi- tions to call it from virtual into manifest existence. I am con- firmed in this view by finding it is also that of M. Royer-Collard. Mr. Stewart is however less defensible, when he says, in opposi- tion to Kant's doctrine of Space 'I rather lean to the common theory which supposes our first ideas of Space or Extension to be formed by oilier qualities of matter.' (Dissertation, See chapter iii. i. 4, S, 11. W. 18* 418 PHILOSOPHY OF PERCEPTION. 13. All Perception is a sensitive cognition : it, therefore, appre- hends the existence of no object out of its organism, or not in immediate correlation to its organism ; for thus only can an ob- ject exist, now and here, to sense. is the oldest testimony for such a usage ; and long after Aristotle, after, in- deed, the line had been already fathered on Epicharmus, wo have Pliny (II. N. xi. 87), Cassius Felix (Pr. 22), St. Jerome (Adv. Jovin. ii. 9), the manu- scripts of Stobaeus (iv. 42), and the Scholiast of Aristophanes (PI. 48), all ad- ducing it only as an adage. It is not, however, till nearly six centuries after Epicharmus, and considerably more than four centuries after Aristotle, that we find the saying either fully cited as a verse, or the verse ascribed to the Syracusan. But from the time of Plutarch, who himself thrice alleges it, its quotation in either fashion becomes frequent ; as by Tertullian, Clement of Alexandria, Maximus Tyrius, Julian, Theodoret, Olympiodorus (twice), and Tzetzes (four times). Porphyry (thrice) records it but as a saying of Py- thagoras ; and lamblichus, as a dictum of the Pythagorean School. These authors both had learning, though neither, certainly, was ever critical in its application. Their statements can only, therefore, be held to favor the opin- ion that they were unaware of any decisive evidence to vindicate the verse to Epicharmus. 4. But if improbable, even at first sight, that such a verse of such an au- thor, should not, if authentic, have been adduced by any writer now extant, during the long period of six hundred years, the improbability is enhanced when we come to find, that during that whole period it is never quoted, even under circumstances when, had it been current as aline of Epicharmus, it could not but have been eagerly appealed to. Plato, as observed by Alci- raus and Laertius, was notoriously fond of quoting Epicharmus ; and there were at least two occasions in the Thewtetus ( 102, sq.), and in the Phsedo ( 25 [11 Wytt.]) when this gnome of his favorite poet would have confirmed and briefly embodied the doctrine he was anxiously inculcating. Could he fail to employ it ? In fact, it comes to this ; these passages must either be held to follow, or to found, the philosopheme in question. In like manner Cicero, in his exposition of the first passage (Tusc. i. 20), couldhardly have avoided as- sociating Epicharmus with Plato, as Tertullian and Olympiodorus have done in their expositions of the second had the line been recognized in the age of the former, as it was in the age of the two latter. Nor could such an apothegm of such a poet have been unknown to Cicero, to Cicero, so generally conver- sant with Hellenic literature, and who, among other sayings of Epicharmus himself, adduces in Greek, as his brother Quintus paraphrases in Latin, the no less celebrated maxim Be softer, and to doubt incUn'd : . These are the very joints of mind ; or on the other reading Be cool, and eke to doubt prepense : These are the sinews of good seme. PHILOSOPHY OF PERCEPTION. 419 ii. Sensation proper and Perception proper, in correlation. 14. In perception proper there is a higher energy of intelli- gence, than in Sensation proper. For though the latter be the apprehension of an affection of the Ego, and therefore, in a certain sort, the apprehension of an immaterial quality ; still it is only the apprehension of the fact of an organic passion ; whereas the former, though supposing Sensation as its condition, and though only the apprehension of the attributes of a material Non-ego, is, however, itself without corporeal passion, and, at the same time, the recognition not merely of a fact, but of relations. (See 22, 29, and p. 379 notef.) 15. Sensation proper is the conditio sine qua non of a Percep- tion proper of the Primary qualities. For we are only aware of the existence of our organism, in being sentient of it, as thus or thus affected ; and are only aware of it being the subject of exten- sion, figure, division, motion, and when touched on almost always misrepresented (even Mr. Harris, for instance, has wholly misconceived the nature of the gnostic reasons) ; nor on this can I now enter, though, as recently noticed, it bears a striking analogy to one phasis of the doctrine of Reid. In special reference to the present distinction I may, however, refer the reader to a passage of Plotinus. (Enn. in. vi. 2.) In the Cartesian philosophy, the distinction was virtually taken by Descartes, but first discriminated in terms by his followers. In general, Perception proper, and the Primary qualities as per- ceived, they denoted by Idea ; Sensation proper, and the Second- ary qualities as felt by Sensation (sensatio, sentiment). See De Raei (Clavis, &c., p. 299, alibi, ed. 1677) ; De la Forge (De 1'Esprit, ch. 10, p. 109 sq., ch. 17, p. 276, ed. Amst. et supra 328 a) ; Geulinx (Dicfe~~ Principia, pp. 45, 48, alibi, et supra ,328 a) ; Rohault (Physique, passim) ; Malebranche (Recherche, L. iii. P. ii. ch. 6 and 7, with Ecclairc. on last, et supra 330 b) ; Silvain Regis (Cours, t. i. pp. 60, 61, 72, 145); Bossuet (Con- naisance de Dieu, ch. iii. art. 8); while Huffier, S" 1 Gravesande, Crousaz, Sinsert, Keranflech, Genovesi, with a hundred others, might be adduced as showing that the same distinction had been very generally recognized before Reid ; who, far from arrogating to himself the credit of its introduction, remarks that it had been first accurately established by Malebranche. As already noticed (330 b), it is passing strange that Locke, but truly marvellous that Leibnitz, should have been ignorant of the Cartesian distinction of Sensation and Idea (Sentiment, Idee). Locke's unacquaintance is shown in his ' Essay,' besides other places, in B. ii. ch. 13, 25, but, above all, in his 'Examination of P. Malebranche's Opinion ;' and that of Leibnitz, elsewhere, and in L. ii. ch. 8 of his ' Nouveaux Essais,' but more particularly 436 PHILOSOPHY OF PERCEPTION. in the ' Examen du Sentiment clu P. Malebranche,' both of which works he wrote in opposition to the relative treatises of Locke. As for Locke, he seems wholly unaware that any difference sub- sisted in the Cartesian school, between Idea and Sensation ; while Leibnitz actually thinks that Malebranche ' entend par sen- timent une perception d'imagination !' In his own philosophy, Leibnitz virtually supersedes the discrimination. I am, therefore, doubly surprised at the observation of M. Royer-Collard, that ' Malebranche is the first among modem philosophers, and, with Leibnitz, perhaps the only one before Reid, who accurately dis- tinguished perception from the sensation which is its forerunner and sign.' (Jouffroy's Reid, iii. 329.) In the Kantian school, and generally in the recent philosophy of Germany, the distinction is adopted, and marked out by the terms Anschauung or Intuitio for the one apprehension, and Empfindung or Sensatio for the other. In France and Italy, on the other hand, where the distinction has been no less universally recognized, Reid's expressions, Perception and Sensation, have become the prevalent; but their ambiguity, I think, ought to have been avoided, by the addition of some such epithet as proper. Since generalizing the Law of the coexistence, but the coexist- ence in an inverse ratio, of Sensation and Perception, of the sub- jective and objective, and, in general, of feeling and cognition ; I have noticed, besides those adduced above from Aristotle and Galen, other partial observations tending to the same result, by sundry modern philosophers. Sulzer, in a paper published in 1759 (Vermischte Schriften, vol. i. p. 113), makes the remark, that ' a representation manifests itself more clearly in proportion as it has less the power of exciting in us emotion ;' and confirms it by the analogy observed in the gradation of the agreeable and disagreeable sensations. Kant in his Anthropologie (1798, 14), in treating of the determinate or organic senses (Seusus fixi), says : ' Three of these are rather objective than subjective i. e. as empirical intuitions, they conduce more to the cognition of the PHILOSOPHY OF PERCEPTION. 437 external object, than they excite the consciousness of the affected organ ; but two are rather subjective than objective i. e. the representation they mediate is more that of enjoyment [or suffer- ing] than of the cognition of the external object. . . . The senses of the former class are those 1) of Touch (tactus), 2) of Sight (visus), 3) of Hearing (auditus) ; of the latter, those a) of Taste (gustus), b) of Smell (olfactus).' This and the Galenic arrangement will appear less connective, if we recollect, that under Touch Galen comprehends Feeling proper, whereas Feeling proper is by Kant relegated to his vital sense or sensus vagus, the coenaesthesis or common sense of others. See also Meiners, Untersuchungen, i. p. 64 ; Wetzel, Psychologic, i. 225 ; Fries, N. Kritik, i. 14-19 ; Anthropologie, i. 27, 28, &c., &c. M. Ravaisson, in an article of great ability and learning on the 4 Fragments de Philosophic' which M. Peisse did me the honor to translate, when speaking of the reform of philosophy in France, originating in Maine de Hira^s recoil against the Sensualistic doctrine, has the following passage : ' Maine de Biran commence par separer profondement de la passion I'activite, que Condillac avait confondue avec elle sous le titre commun de Sensation. La sensation proprement dite est une affection tout passive; 1'etre qui y serait reduit irait se perdre, s' absorber dans toutes ses modifications ; il deviendrait successivement chacune d'elles, il ne se trouverait pas, il ne se distinguerait pas, et jamais ne se connaitrait lui-mfime. Bien loin que la connaissance soit la sen- sation seule, la sensation, en se melant a elle, la trouble et 1'ob- scurcit, et elle eclipse a son tour la sensation. De la, la loi que M. Hamilton a signalee dans son remarquable article sur la theo- rie de la perception : la sensation et la perception, quoique instpa- rables, sont en raison inverse Vune de Tautre. Cette loi fonda- mentale, Maine de Biran 1'avait decouverte pres de trente ans auparavant, et en avait suivi toutes les applications ; il en avait surtout approfondi le principe, savoir, que la sensation resulte de la passion, et que la perception resulte de 1'action.' (Revue des Deux Mondes, Nov. 1840.) It is perhaps needless for me to say, 438 PHILOSOPHY OF PERCEPTION. that when I enounced the law in question (in 1830), I had never seen the printed memoir by De Biran, which, indeed, from the circumstances of its publication, was, I believe, inaccessible through the ordinary channels of the trade, and to be found in no library in this country ; and now I regret to find that, through procrastination, I must send this chapter to press before having obtained the collective edition of his earlier works, which has recently appeared in Paris. All that I know of De Biran is comprised in the volume edited in 1834 by M. Cousin, from whose kindness I received it. In this, the ' Nouvelles Conside- rations sur les Rapports du Physique et du Moral de 1'Homme,' the treatise in which, as his editor informs us, the full and final development of his doctrine is contained, was for the first time published. But neither in that, nor in any other of the accom- panying pieces, can I discover any passage besides the following, that may be viewed as anticipating the law of coexistence and inversion : ' Souvent une impression perdue a tel degre cesse de l'6tre a un degr6 plus eleve ou lorsqu'elle s'avive au point d'ab- sorber la conscience ou le moi lui-meme qui la devient. Ainsi plus la sensation serait 6minemment animale, moins elle aurait le caractere vrai d'une perception humaine.' PART THIRD. PHILOSOPHY OF THE CONDITIONED, "Laudabilior est animus, cui nota est infirmitas propria, quam qui, eu non respecta, racenia mundi, vias siderum, fundamenta terrarum et fastigia coelorum, etiam cogniturns, scrutatur." ST. AUGUSTINE, (De Uhitate, proem to the fourth book.) CHAPTER I. 1 EEFUTATION OF THE VAEIOUS DOCTRINES OF THE UNCONDI- TIONED, ESPECIALLY OF COUSIN'S DOCTEINE OF THE INFI- NITO-ABSOLUTE.* THE delivery of these Lectures 2 excited an unparalleled sensa- tion in Paris. Condemned to silence during the reign of Jesuit ascendency, M. Cousin, after eight years of honorable retirement, 1 This was originally published in the Edinburgh Review, for October, 1829. It has since been republished in the Discussions, pp. 1-37. W. s Hamilton is reviewing a work entitled, ' Cours de Philosophic, par M. Victor Cousin, Professeur de Philosophie a la Faculte" des Lettres de Paris. Introduction d. VHistoire de la Philosophie, 8vo. Paris, 1823.' See our trans- lation of ' Cousin's History of Philosophy,' vol. i. W. * [Translated into French, by M. Peisse ; into Italian, by S. Lo Gatto : also in Cross's Selections from the Edinburgh Review. This article did not originate with myself. I was requested to write it by my friend, the late accomplished Editor of the Review, Professor Napier. Personally I felt averse from the task. I was not unaware, that a discussion of the leading doctrine of the book would prove unintelligible, not only to ' the general reader,' but, with few exceptions, to our British metaphysi- cians at large. But, moreover, I was still farther disinclined to the undertak- ing, because it would behoove me to come forward in overt opposition to a certain theory, which, however powerfully advocated, I felt altogether una- ble to admit ; whilst its author, M. Cousin, was a philosopher for whose genius and character I already had the wannest admiration, an admiration which every succeeding year has only augmented, justified, and confirmed. Nor, in saying this, need I make any reservation. For I admire, even where I dissent ; and were M. Cousin's speculations on the Absolute utterly abol- ished, to him would still remain the honor, of doing more himself, and of contributing more to what has been done by others, in the furtherance of an enlightened philosophy, than any other living individual in France I might say in Europe. Mr. Napier, however, was resolute ; it was the first number of the Review under his direction ; and the criticism was hastily written. In this country the reasonings were of course not understood, and naturally, for a season, declared incomprehensible. Abroad, in France, Germany, Italy, and latterly in America, the article has been rated higher than it de- serves. The illustrious thinker, against one of whose doctrines its argument 19* 442 PHILOSOPHY OF THE CONDITIONED. not exempt from persecution, had again ascended the chair of Philosophy ; and the splendor with which he recommenced his academical career, more than justified the expectation which his recent celebrity as a writer, and the memory of his earlier prelec- tions, had inspired. Two thousand auditors listened, all with ad- miration, many with enthusiasm, to the eloquent exposition of doctrines intelligible only to the few ; and the oral discussion of philosophy awakened in Paris, and in France, an interest unex- ampled since the days of Abelard. The daily journals found it necessary to gratify, by their earlier summaries, the impatient cu- riosity of the public ; and the lectures themselves, taken in short- hand, and corrected by the Professor, propagated weekly the influence of his instruction to the remotest provinces of the king- dom. Nor are the pretensions of this doctrine disproportioned to the attention which it has engaged. It professes nothing less than to be the complement and conciliation of all philosophical opinion ; and its author claims the glory of placing the key-stone in the arch of science, by the discovery of elements hitherto unobserved among the facts of consciousness. Before proceeding to consider the claims of M. Cousin to ori- ginality, and of his doctrine to truth, it is necessary to say a few words touching the state and relations of philosophy in France. After the philosophy of Descartes and Malebranche had sunk is directed, was the first to speak of it in terms which, though I feel their generosity, I am ashamed to quote. I may, however, state, that maintaining always his opinion, M. Cousin (what is rare, especially in metaphysical dis- cussions) declared, that it was neither unfairly combated nor imperfectly understood. In connection with this criticism, the reader should compare what M. Cousin has subsequently stated in defence and illustration of his system, in his Preface to the new edition of the Introduction a PHistoire de la Philosophie, and Appendix to the fifth lecture ((Euvres, Serie II. Tome i. pp. vii. ix., and pp. 112-129) ; in his Preface to the second edition, and his Advertisement to the third edition of the Fragments PhilosopMques ((Euvres 8. III. T. iv.) and in his Prefatory Notice to the Pensies de Pascal ((Euvres, 8". IV. T. i.) On the other hand, M. Peisse has ably advocated the counter- view, in his Preface and Appendix to the Fragments de Philosophic, &c.] PHILOSOPHY OF THE CONDITIONED. 443 into oblivion, and from the time that Condillac, exaggerating the too partial principles of Locke, had analyzed all knowledge into sensation, Sensualism (or, more correctly, Sensuism), as a psycho- logical theory of the origin of our cognitions, became, in France, not only the dominant, but almost the one exclusive opinion. It was believed that reality and truth were limited to experience, and experience was limited to the sphere of sense ; while the very highest faculties of mind were deemed adequately explained when recalled to perceptions, elaborated, purified, sublimated, and transformed. From the mechanical relations of sense with its object, it was attempted to solve the mysteries of will and intelligence ; the philosophy of mind was soon viewed as, cor- relative to the physiology of organization. The moral nature of man was at last formally abolished, in its identification with his physical : mind became a reflex of matter ; thought a secre- tion of the brain. A doctrine so melancholy in its consequences, and founded on principles thus partial and exaggerated, could not be perma- nent : a reaction was inevitable. The recoil which began about twenty years ago, has been gradually increasing ; and now it is perhaps even to be apprehended, that its intensity may become excessive. As the poison was of foreign growth, so also has been the antidote. The doctrine of Condillac was, if not a corruption, a development of the doctrine of Locke ; and in returning to a better philosophy, the French are still obeying an impulse com- municated from without. This impulsion may be traced to two different sources, to the philosophy of Scotland, and to the philosophy of Germany. In Scotland, a philosophy had sprung up, which, though pro- fessing, equally with the doctrine of Condillac, to build only on experience, did not, like that doctrine, limit experience to the relations of sense and its objects. Without vindicating to man more than a relative knowledge of existence, and restricting the science of mind to an observation of the fact of consciousness, it, however, analyzed that fact into a greater number of more im- 444 PHILOSOPHY OF THE CONDITIONED. portent elements than had been recognized in the school of Con- dillac. It showed that phenomena were revealed in thought which could not be resolved into any modifications of sense, external or internal. It proved that intelligence supposed prin- ciples, which, as the conditions of its activity, cannot be the results of its operation ; that the mind contained knowledges, which, as primitive, universal, necessary, are not to be explained as generalizations from the contingent and individual, about which alone all experience is conversant. The phenomena of mind were thus distinguished from the phenomena of matter ; and if the impossibility of materialism were not demonstrated, there was, at least, demonstrated the impossibility of its proof. This philosophy, and still more the spirit of this philosophy was calculated to exert a salutary influence on the French. And such an influence it did exert. For a time, indeed, the truth operated in silence, and Reid and Stewart had already modified the philosophy of France, before the French were content to acknowledge themselves their disciples. In the works of Dege- rando and Laromiguiere, may be traced the influence of Scottish speculation ; but it is to Royer-Collard, and, more recently, to Jouffroy, that our countrymen are indebted for a full acknowl- edgment of their merits, and for the high and increasing estima- tion in which their doctrines are now held in France. M. Royer- Collard, whose authority has, in every relation, been exerted only for the benefit of his country, and who, once great as a professor, is now not less illustrious as a statesman, in his lectures, advo- cated with distinguished ability the principles of the Scottish school ; modestly content to follow, while no one was more entitled to lead. M. Jouffroy, by his recent translation of the works of Dr. Reid, and by the excellent preface to his version of Mr. Dugald Stewart's ' Outlines of Moral Philosophy,' has like- wise powerfully co-operated to the establishment, in France, of a philosophy equally opposed to the exclusive Sensualism of Con- dillac, and to the exclusive Rationalism of the new German school. PHILOSOPHY OF THE CONDITIONED. 445 Germany may be regarded, latterly at least, as the metaphysi- cal antipodes of France. The comprehensive and original genius of Leibnitz, itself the ideal abstract of the Teutonic character, had reacted powerfully on the minds of his countrymen ; and Ra- tionalism (more properly Intellectualism*}, has, from his time, always remained the favorite philosophy of the Germans. On the principle of this doctrine, it is in Reason alone that truth and reality are to be found. Experience affords only the occasions on which intelligence reveals to us the necessary and universal notions of which it is the complement ; and these notions con- stitute at once the foundation of all reasoning, and the guaran- tee of our whole knowledge of reality. Kant, indeed, pro- nounced the philosophy of Rationalism a mere fabric of delusion. He declared that a science of existence was beyond the compass of our faculties ; that pure reason, as purely subjective,! and con- * [On the modern commutation of Intellect or Intelligence (Nous, Mens, In- teUectvs, Verstand), and Reason (A.6yos, Ratio, Vernunft), see Dissertations on Eeid, pp. 668, 669, 693. (This has nothing to do with the confusion of Rea- son and Reasoning. ) Protesting, therefore, against the abuse, I historically employ the terms as they were employed by the philosophers here commem- orated. This unfortunate reversal has been propagated to the French philos- ophy, and also adopted in England by Coleridge and his followers. I may here notice that I use the term Understanding, not for the noetic faculty, intellect proper, or place of principles, but for the dianoetic or discursive fac- ulty, in its widest signification, for the faculty of relations or comparison ; and thus in the meaning in which Verstand is now employed by the Ger- mans. In this sense I have been able to be uniformly consistent.] t In the philosophy of mind, subjective denotes what is to be referred to the thinking subject, the Ego; objective what belongs to the object of thought, the Non-Ego. It may ba safe, perhaps, to say a few words in vindication of our employment of these terms. By the Greeks the word kroKttitcvov was equivocally employed to express either the object of knowledge (the materia circa quam), or the subject of existence (the materia in qua). The exact distinction of subject and object was first made by the schoolmen ; and to the schoolmen the vulgar languages are principally indebted for what precision and analytic subtilty they possess. These correlative terms cor- respond to the first and most important distinction in philosophy ; they em- body the original antithesis in consciousness of self and not-self, a distinc- tion which, in fact, involves the whole science of mind ; for psychology is nothing more than a determination of the subjective and the objective, in themselves, and in their reciprocal relations. Thus significant of the prima- ry and most extensive analysis in philosophy, these terms, in their substan- 446 PHILOSOPHY OF THE CONDITIONED. scious of nothing but itself, was therefore unable to evince the reality of aught beyond the phenomena of its personal modifica- tions. But scarcely had the critical philosopher accomplished the recognition of this important principle, the result of which was, to circumscribe the field of speculation by narrow bounds ; than from the very disciples of his school there arose philoso- phers, who, despising the contracted limits and humble results of a philosophy of observation, re-established, as the predomi- nant opinion, a bolder and more uncompromising Rationalism than any that had ever previously obtained for their countrymen the character of philosophic visionaries ' Gens ratione ferox, et mentem pasta chimseris.'* (' Minds fierce for reason, and on fancies fed.') live and adjective forms, passed from the schools into the scientific language of Telesius, Campanella, Berigardus, Gassendi, Descartes, Spinosa, Leib- nitz, Wolf, &c. Deprived of these terms, the Critical philosophy, indeed the whole philosophy of Germany, would be a blank. In this country, though familiarly employed in scientific language, even subsequently to the time of Locke, the adjective forms seem at length to have dropt out of the English tongue. That these words waxed obsolete was perhaps caused by the ambiguity which had gradually crept into the signification of the sub- stantives. Object, besides its proper, signification, came to be abusively applied to denote motive, end, final cause (a meaning not recognized by John- son). This innovation was probably borrowed from the French, in whose language the word had been similarly corrupted after the commencement of the last century (Diet, de Trevoux, voce olget). Subject in English, as sujet in French, had been also perverted into a synonym for object, taken in its proper meaning, and had thus returned to the original ambiguity of the cor- responding term in Greek. It is probable that the logical application of the word (subject of attribution or predication) facilitated or occasioned this con- fusion. In using the terms, therefor!, we think that an explanation, but no apology, is required. The distinction is of paramount importance, and of infinite application, not only hi philosophy proper, but in grammar, rheto- ric, criticism, ethics, politics, jurisprudence, theology. It is adequately expressed by no other terms ; and if these did not already enjoy a prescrip- tive right, as denizens of the language, it cannot be denied, that, as strictly analogical, they would be well entitled to sue out their naturalization. [Not that these terms were formerly always employed in the same signification and contrast which they now obtain. For a history of these variations, see Part II. chapter ii. p. 243 sq. Since this article was written, the words have in this country re-entered on their ancient rights ; they are now in common use.] * [This line, which was quoted from memory, has, I find, in the origiixal, PHILOSOPHY OF THE CONDITIONED. 447 Founded by Fichte, but evolved by Schelling, this doctrine re- gards experience as unworthy of the name of science ; because, as only of the phenomenal, the transitory, the dependent, it is only of that which, having no reality in itself, cannot be established as a valid basis of certainty and knowledge. Philosophy must, therefore, either be abandoned, or we must be able to seize the One, the Absolute, the Unconditioned, immediately and in itself. And this they profess to do by a kind of intellectual vision.* In this act, reason, soaring above the world of sense, but beyond the sphere of personal consciousness, boldly places itself at the very centre of absolute being, with which it claims to be, in fact, identified ; and thence surveying existence in itself, and in its re- lations, unveils to us the nature of the Deity, and explains, from first to last, the derivation of all created things. M. Cousin is the apostle of Rationalism in France, and we are willing to admit that the doctrine could not have obtained a more eloquent or devoted advocate. For philosophy he has suffered ; ' furens;' therefore translated 'Minds mad with reasoning and fancy-fed.' The author certainly had in his eye the ' ratione insanias ' of Terence. It is from a satire by Abraham Eemi, who in the former half of the seventeenth century, was professor Eoyal of Eloquence in the University of Paris ; and it referred to the disputants of the Irish College in that illustrious school. The ' Hibernian Logicians' were, indeed, long famed over the continent of Europe, for their acuteness, pugnacity, and barbarism ; as is recorded by Patin, Bayle, Le Sage, and many others. The learned Menage was so de- lighted with the verse, as to declare that he would give his best benefice (and he enjoyed some fat ones) to have written it. It applies, not only with real, but with verbal accuracy, to the German Rationalists ; who in Philosophy (as Aristotle has it), ' in making reason omnipotent, show their own impotence of reason,' and in Theology (as Charles II. said of Isaac Vossius), ' believe every tiling but the Bible.'] * [' InteUectuelle Anschauung." 1 This is doubly wrong. 1, In grammatical rigor, the word in German ought to have been ' intellectual.' 2, In phi- losophical consistency the intuition ought to have been called by its authors (Fichte and Schelling), intellectual. For, though this be, in fact, absolutely more correct, yet relatively it is a blunder ; for the intuition, as intended by them, is of their higher faculty, the Reason (Vernunft), and not of their lower, the Understanding or Intellect (Verstand). In modern German Philosophy, Verstand is always translated by Intettecfaa ; and this again cor- responds to NoBj.] 448 PHILOSOPHY OF THE CONDITIONED. to her ministry he has consecrated himself devoted without reserve his life and labors. Neither has he approached the sanctuary with unwashed hands. The editor of Proclus and Descartes, the translator and interpreter of Plato, and the prom- ised expositor of Kant, will not be accused of partiality in the choice of his pursuits ; while his two works, under the title of Philosophical Fragments, bear ample evidence to the learning, elegance, and distinguished ability of their author. Taking him all in all, in France M. Cousin stands alone : nor can we contem- plate his character and accomplishments, without the sincerest admiration, even while we dissent from the most prominent prin- ciple of his philosophy. The development of his system, in all its points, betrays the influence of German speculation on his opin- ions. His theory is not, however, a scheme of exclusive Ra- tionalism ; on the contrary, the peculiarity of his doctrine con- sists 1n the attempt to combine the philosophy of experience, and the philosophy of pure reason, into one. The following is a con- cise statement of the fundamental positions of his system. Reason, or intelligence, has three integrant elements, affording three regulative principles, which at once constitute its nature, and govern its manifestations. These three ideas severally sup- pose each other, and, as inseparable, are equally essential and equally primitive. They are recognized by Aristotle and by Kant, in their several attempts to analyze intelligence into its principles ; but though the categories of both philosophers com prise all the elements of thought, in neither list are these elements naturally co-arranged, or reduced to an ultimate simplicity. The first of these ideas, elements, or laws, though funda- mentally one, our author variously expresses, by the terms unity, identity, substance, absolute cause, the infinite, pure thought, &c. ; (we would briefly call it the unconditioned.) The second, he denominates plurality, difference, phenomenon, relative cause, the finite, determined thought, ach other, the positive alone is real ; the negative is only an abstraction of the other, and in the highest generality, even an abstraction of thought itself. It therefore behooved M. Cousin, instead of assuming the objective correality of his two elements on the fact of their subjective correlation, to have suspected, on this very ground, that the reality of the one was inconsistent with the reality of the other. In truth, upon examination, it will be found that his two primitive ideas are nothing more than contradictory relatives. These, consequently, of their very nature, imply each other in thought ; but they imply each other only as affirmation and negation of the same. We have already shown, that though the Conditioned (condi- tionally limited) be one, what is opposed to it as the Uncondition- ed, is plural : that the unconditional negation of limitation gives one unconditioned, the Infinite ; as the unconditional affirmation of limitation affords another, the Absolute. This, while it coin- cides with the opinion, that the Unconditioned in either phasis is inconceivable, is repugnant to the doctrine, that the uncondition- ed (absoluto-infinite) can be positively construed to the mind. For those who, with M. Cousin, regard the notion of the uncondi- tioned as a positive and real knowledge of existence in its all-com- prehensive unity, and who consequently employ the terms Abso- lute, Infinite, Unconditioned, as only various expressions for the same identity, are imperatively bound to prove that their idea of the One corresponds either with that Unconditioned we have dis- tinguished as the Absolute or with tliat Unconditioned ice have distinguished as the Infinite or that it includes both, or that it excludes both. This they have not done, and, we suspect, have never attempted to do. Our author maintains, that the unconditioned is known under the laws of consciousness ; and does not, like Schelling, pretend to an intuition of existence beyond the bounds of space and time. Indeed, he himself expressly predicates the absolute and infinite of these forms. Time is only the image or the concept of a certain correlation PHILOSOPHY OF THE CONDITIONED. 473 of existences of existence therefore, pro tanto, as conditioned. It is thus itself only a form of the conditioned. But let that pass. Is, then, the Absolute conceivable of time ? Can we conceive time as unconditionally limited ? We can easily represent to ourselves time under any relative limitation of commencement and termina- tion ; but we are conscious to ourselves of nothing more clearly, than that it would be equally possible to think without thought, as to construe to the mind an absolute commencement, or an ab- solute termination, of time ; that is, a beginning and an end, beyond which, time is conceived as non-existent. Goad imagina- tion to the utmost, it still sinks paralyzed within the bounds of time ; and time survives as the condition of the thought itself in which we annihilate the universe : ' Sur les mondes detruits le Temps dprt immobile.' But if the Absolute be inconceivable of this form, is the Infinite more comprehensible ? Can we imagine time as unconditionally unlimited ? We cannot conceive the Infinite regress of time ; for such a notion could only be realized by the infinite addition in thought of finite times, and such an addition would, itself, require nn eternity for its accomplishment. If we dream of affecting this, we only deceive ourselves by substituting the indefinite for the in- finite, than which no two notions can be more opposed. The ne- gation of the commencement of time involves likewise the affir- mation, that an infinite time has at every moment already run ; that is, it implies the contradiction, that an infinite has been com- pleted. For the same reasons we are unable to conceive an infi- nite progress of time ; while the infinite regress and the infinite progress, taken together, involve the triple contradiction of an in- finite concluded, of an infinite commencing, and of two infinites, not exclusive of each other. Sp&ce, like time, is only the intuition or the concept of a cer- tain correlation of existence of existence, therefore, pro tanto, as conditioned. It is thus itself only a form of the conditioned. But apart from this, thought is equally powerless in realizing a 4T4 PHILOSOPHY OF THE CONDITIONED. notion either of the absolute totality, or of the infinite immensity, of space. And while time and space, as wholes, can thus neither be conceived as absolutely limited, nor as infinitely unlimited ; s*. their parts can be represented to the mind neither as absolutely individual, nor as divisible to infinity. The universe cannot be imagined as a whole, which may not also be imagined as a part ; nor an atom be imagined as a part, which may not also be im- agined as a whole. The same analysis, with a similar result, can be applied to cause and effect, and to substance and phenomenon. These, how- ever, may both be reduced to the law itself of the conditioned. 1 The Conditioned is, therefore, that only which can be positive- ly conceived ; the Absolute and Infinite are conceived only as ne- gations of the conditioned in its opposite poles. Now, as we observed, M. Cousin, and those who confound the absolute and infinite, and regard the unconditioned as a positive and indivisible notion, must show that this notion coincides either, 1, with the notion of the Absolute, to the exclusion of the infinite ; or 2, with the notion of the Infinite, to the exclusion ot the absolute ; or 3, that it includes both as true, carrying their, up to indifference ; or 4, that it excludes both as false. The last two alternatives are impossible, as either would be subversive ot the highest principle of intelligence, which asserts, that of two contradictories, both cannot, but one must, be true. It only, therefore, remains to identify the unity of the Unconditioned with the Infinite, or with the Absolute with either, to the exclusion of the other. But while every one must be intimately conscious of the impossibility of this, the very fact that our author and other philosophers a priori have constantly found it necessary to confound these contradictions, sufficiently proves that neither term has a right to represent the unity of the unconditioned, to the prejudice of the other. The Unconditioned is, therefore, not a positive concept ; nor 1 Bee the next chapter, I. for the applications of that doctrine. W. PHILOSOPHY OF THE CONDITIONED. 475 has it even a real or intrinsic unity ; for it only combines the Ab- solute and the Infinite, in themselves contradictory of each other, into a unity relative to us by the negative bond of their incon- ceivability. It is on this mistake, of the relative for the irre- spective, of the negative for the positive, that M. Cousin's theory is founded : And it is not difficult to understand how the mistake originated. This reduction of M. Cousin's two ideas of the Infinite and Fi- nite to one positive conception and its negative, implicitly anni- hilates also the third idea, devised by him as a connection be- tween his two substantive ideas ; and which he marvellously iden- tifies with the relation of cause and effect. Yet before leaving this part of our subject, we may observe, that the very simplicity of our analysis is a strong presumption in favor of its truth. A plurality of causes is not to be postula- ted, where one is sufficient to account for the phenomena (Entia non sunt multiplicanda prceter necessitatetn) ; and M. Cousin, in supposing three positive ideas, where only one is necessary, brings the rule of parsimony against his hypothesis, even before its un- soundness may be definitely brought to light. In the third place, the restrictions to which our author subjects intelligence, divine and human, implicitly deny a knowledge even a concept of the absolute, both to God and man. ' The condition of intelligence,' says M. Cousin, l is difference ; and an act of knowledge is only possible where there exists a plurality of terms. Unity does not suffice for conception ; variety is ne- cessary ; nay more, not only is variety necessary, there must like- wise subsist an intimate relation between the principles of unity and variety; without which, the variety not being perceived by the unity, the one is as if it could not perceive, and the other as if it could not be perceived. Look back for a moment into your- selves, and you will find, that what constitutes intelligence in our feeble consciousness, is, that there are there several terms, of which the one perceives the other, of which the other is perceived by the first : in this consists self-knowledge, in this consists self- 476 PHILOSOPHY OF THE CONDITIONED. comprehension, in this consists intelligence : intelligence with- out consciousness is the abstract possibility of intelligence, not in- telligence in the act ; and consciousness implies diversity and dif- ference. Transfer all this from human to absolute intelligence ; that is to say, refer the ideas to the only intelligence to which they can belong. You have thus, if I may so express myself, the life of absolute intelligence ; you have this intelligence with the complete development of the elements which are necessary for it to be a true intelligence ; you have all the momenta whose rela- tion and motion constitute the reality of knowledge.' In all this, so far as human intelligence is concerned, we cordially agree ; for a more complete admission could not be imagined, not only that a knowledge, and even a notion, of the absolute is impossible for man, but that we are unable to conceive the possibility of such a knowledge, even in the Deity, without contradicting our human conceptions of the possibility of intelligence itself. Our author, however, recognizes no contradiction ; and, without argument or explanation, accords a knowledge of that which can only be known under the negation of all difference and plurality, to that which can only know under the affirmation of both. If a knowledge of the absolute were possible under these con- ditions, it may excite our wonder that other philosophers should have viewed this supposition as utterly impossible ; and that Schelling, whose acuteness was never questioned, should have exposed himself gratuitously to the reproach of mysticism, by his postulating for a few, and through a faculty above the reach of consciousness, a knowledge already given to all in the fact of con- sciousness itself. Monstrous as is the postulate of the Intellectual Intuition, we freely confess that it is only through such a faculty that we can imagine the possibility of a science of the absolute ; and have no hesitation in acknowledging, that if Schilling's hypothesis appear to us incogitable, that of Cousin is seen to be self-contradictory. Our author admits, and must admit, that the Absolute, as ab- solutely universal, is absolutely one ; absolute unity is convertible PHILOSOPHY OF THE CONDITIONED. 477 with the absolute negation of plurality and difference ; the abso- lute, and the knowledge of the absolute, are therefore identical. But knowledge, or intelligence, it is asserted by M. Cousin, sup- poses a plurality of terms the plurality of subject and object. Intelligence, whose essence is plurality, cannot therefore be iden- tified with the absolute, whose essence is unity ; and if known, the absolute, as known, must be different from the absolute as existing ; that is, there must be two absolutes an absolute in knowledge, and an absolute in existence, which is contradictory. But waiving this contradiction, and allowing the non-identity of knowledge and existence, the absolute as known must be known under the conditions of the absolute as existing, that is, as absolute unity. But, on the other hand, it is asserted, that the condition of intelligence, as knowing, is plurality and difference ; consequently the condition of the absolute, as existing, and under which it must be known, and the condition of intelligence, as ca- pable of knowing, are incompatible. For, if we suppose the ab- solute cognizable : it must be identified either, 1, with the subject knowing ; or, 2, with the object known ; or, 3, with the indifference of both. The first hypothesis, and the second, are contradictory of the absolute. For in these the absolute is sup- posed to be known, either as contradistinguished from the know- ing subject, or as contradistinguished from the object known ; in other words, the absolute is asserted to be known as absolute unity, i. e. as the negation of all plurality, while the very act by which it is known, affirms plurality as the condition of its own possibility. The third hypothesis, on the other hand, is contra- dictory of the plurality of intelligence ; for if the subject and the object of consciousness be known as one, a plurality of terms is not the necessary condition of intelligence. The alternative is therefore necessary : Either the absolute cannot be known or conceived at all ; or our author is wrong in subjecting thought to the conditions of plurality and difference. It was the iron neces- sity of the alternative that constrained Schelling to resort to the hypothesis of a knowledge in identity through the intellectual 478 PHILOSOPHY OF THE CONDITIONED. intuition ; and it could only be from an oversight of the main difficulties of the problem that M. Cousin, in abandoning the in- tellectual intuition, did not abandon the absolute itself. For how that, whose essence is all-comprehensive unity, can be known by the negation of that unity under the condition of plurality ; how that, which exists only as the identity of all difference, can be known under the negation of that identity, in the antithesis of subject and object, of knowledge and existence : these are con- tradictions which M. Cousin has not attempted to solve, contra- dictions which he does not seem to have contemplated. In the fourth place. The objection of the inconceivable nature of Schelling's intellectual intuition, and of a knowledge of the absolute in identity, apparently determined our author to adopt the opposite, but suicidal alternative, of a knowledge of the absolute in consciousness, and by difference. The equally insu- perable objection, that from the absolute defined as absolute, Schelling had not been able, without inconsequence, to deduce the conditioned, seems, in like manner, to have influenced M. Cousin to define the absolute by a relative ; not observant, it would appear, that though he thus facilitated the derivation of the conditioned, he annihilated in reality the absolute itself. By the former proceeding, our author virtually denies the possibility of the absolute in thought ; by the latter, the possibility of the absolute in existence. The absolute is defined by our author, ' an absolute cause, a cause which cannot but pass into act.'' Now, it is sufficiently manifest that a thing existing absolutely (i.e. not under relation), and a thing existing absolutely as a cause, are contradictory. The former is the absolute negation of all relation, the latter is the absolute affirmation of a- particular relation. A cause is a relative, and what exists absolutely as a cause, exists absolutely under relation. Schelling has justly observed, that ' he would deviate wide as the poles from the idea of the absolute, who would think of defining its nature by the. notion of activity.'' * * Bruno, p. 171. PHILOSOPHY OF THE CONDITIONED. 479 But he who would define the absolute by the notion of a cause, would deviate still more widely from its nature ; inasmuch as the notion of a cause involves not only the notion of a determi- nation to activity, but of a determination to a particular, nay a dependent kind of activity, an activity not immanent, but transeunt. What exists merely as a cause, exists merely for the sake of something else, is not final in itself, but simply a mean towards an end ; and in the accomplishment of that end, it con- summates its own perfection. Abstractly considered, the effect is therefore superior to the cause. A cause, as cause, may indeed be better than one or two or any given number of its effects. But the total complement of the effects of what exists only as a cause, is better than that which, ex hypothesi, exists merely for the sake of their production. Further, not only is an absolute cause dependent on the effect for its perfection, it is dependent on it even for its reality. For to what extent a thing exists necessarily as a cause, to that extent it is not all-sufficient to itself ; since to that extent it is dependent on the effect, as on the condition through which alone it realizes its existence ; and what exists absolutely as a cause, exists, therefore, in absolute dependence on the effect for the reality of its existence. An absolute cause, in truth, only exists in its effects : it never is, it always becomes ; for it is an existence in potentia, and not an existence in actu, except through and in its effects. The absolute is thus, at best, a being merely inchoative and imperfect. The definition of the absolute by absolute cause, is, therefore, tantamount to a negation of itself; for it defines by relation and conditions that which is conceived only as exclusive of both. The same is true of the definition of the absolute by substance. But of this we do not speak. The vice of M. Cousin's definition of the absolute by absolute cause, is manifested likewise in its applications. He maintains that his theory can alone explain the nature and relations of the Deity ; and on its absolute incompetency to fulfil the conditions 480 PHILOSOPHY OF THE CONDITIONED. of a rational theism, we are willing to rest our demonstration of its radical unsoundness. ' God,' says our author, ' creates ; he creates in virtue of his creative power, and he draws the universe, not from nonentity, but from himself, who is absolute existence. His distinguishing characteristic being an absolute creative force, which cannot but pass into activity, it follows, not that the creation is possible, but that it is necessary? We must be very brief. The subjection of the Deity to a necessity a necessity of self-manifestation identical with the creation of the universe, is contradictory of the fundamental pos- tulates of a divine nature. On this theory, God is not distinct from the world ; the creature is a modification of the creator. Now, without objecting that the simple subordination of the Deity to necessity, is in itself tantamount to his dethronement, let us see to what consequences this necessity, on the hypothesis of M. Cousin, inevitably leads. On this hypothesis, one of two alternatives must be admitted. God, as necessarily determined to pass from absolute essence to relative manifestation, is deter- mined to pass either from the better to the worse, or from the worse to the better. A third possibility, that both states are equal, as contradictory in itself, and as contradicted by our author, it is not necessary to consider. The first supposition must be rejected. The necessity in this case determines God to pass from the better to the worse ; that is, operates to his partial annihilation. The power which com- pels this must be external and hostile, for nothing operates wil- lingly to its own deterioration ; and, as superior to the pretended God, is either itself the real deity, if an intelligent and free cause, or a negation of all deity, if a blind force or fate. The second is equally inadmissible : that God, passing into the universe, passes from a state of comparative imperfection, into a state of comparative perfection. The divine nature is identical with the most -perfect nature, and is also identical with the first cause. If the first cause be not identical with the most PHILOSOPHY OF THE CONDITIONED. 481 perfect nature, there is no God, for the two essential conditions of his existence are not in combination. Now, on the present supposition, the most perfect nature is the derived ; nay the uni- verse, the creation, the yivo'fisvov, is, in relation to its cause, the real, the actual, the ovrws ov. It would also be the divine, but that divinity supposes also the notion of cause, while the uni- verse, ex hypethesi, is only an effect. It is no answer to these difficulties for M. Cousin to say, that the Deity, though a cause which cannot choose but create, is not however exhausted in the act ; and though passing with all the elements of his being into the universe, that he remains entire in his essence, and with all the superiority of the cause over the effect. The dilemma is unavoidable : Either the Deity is in- dependent of the universe for his being or perfection ; on which alternative our author must abandon his theory of God, and the necessity of creation : Or the Deity is dependent on his manifes- tation in the universe for his being or perfection ; on which alter- native, his doctrine is assailed by the difficulties previously stated. The length to which the preceding observations have extended, prevents us from adverting to sundry other opinions of our author, which we conceive to be equally unfounded. For exam- ple (to say nothing of his proof of the impersonality of intelligence, because, forsooth, truth is not subject to our will), what can be conceived more self-contradictory than his theory of moral liber- ty ? Divorcing liberty from intelligence, but connecting it with personality, he defines it to be a cause which is determined to act by its proper energy alone. But (to say nothing of remoter difficulties) how liberty can be conceived, supposing always a plurality of modes of activity, without a knowledge of that plu- rality ; how a faculty can resolve to act by preference in a par- ticular manner, and not determine itself by final causes ; how intelligence can influence a blind power, without operating as an efficient cause ; or how. in fine, morality can be founded on a liberty which, at best, only escapes necessity by taking refuge 21 482 PHILOSOPHY OF THE CONDITIONED. with chance : these are problems which M. Cousin, in none of his works, has stated, and which we are confident he is unable to solve. After the tenor of our previous observations, it is needless to say that we regard M. Cousin's attempt to establish a general peace among philosophers, by the promulgation of his Eclectic theory, as a failure. But though no converts to his Uncondi- tioned, and viewing with regret what we must regard as the mis- application of his distinguished talents, we cannot disown a strong feeling of interest and admiration for those qualities, even in their excess, which have betrayed him, with so many other aspiring philosophers, into a pursuit which could only end in disappoint- ment : we mean his love of truth, and his reliance on the pow- ers of man. Not to despair of philosophy is ' a last infirmity of noble minds.' The stronger the intellect, the stronger the confi- dence in its force ; the more ardent the appetite for knowledge, the less are we prepared to canvass the uncertainty of the frui- tion. ' The wish is parent to the thought.' Loth to admit that our science is at best the reflection of a reality we cannot know, we strive to penetrate to existence in itself; and what we have labored intensely to attain, we at last fondly believe we have accomplished. But, like Ixion, we embrace a cloud for a divinity. Conscious only of, conscious only in and through, lim- itation, we think to comprehend the infinite ; and dream even of establishing the science the nescience of man, on an identity with the omniscience of God. It is this powerful tendency of the most vigorous minds to transcend the sphere of our faculties, which makes a ' learned ignorance' the most difficult acquire- ment, perhaps, indeed, the consummation of knowledge. In the words of a forgotten, but acute philosopher, ' Mayna, immo maxima pars sapicntice est, qucedam cequo animo nescire 1 See the next chapter, 2, for testimonies in regard to the limitation of our knowledge. W. PHILOSOPHY OF THE CONDITIONED. 483 Hie mundus est infinites. Infinitas et totus est, (Nam mente numquam absolveris ;) Infinitas et illius Pars quselibet, partisque pars. Quod tangis est infinitas ; Quod cernis est infinitas ; Quod non vides corpusculum, Sed mente sola concipis, Corpusculi et corpusculum, Huj usque pars corpusculi, Partisque pars, hujusque pars, In hacque parte quicquid est, Infinitatem coutiuet. INJTNITAS! Secare mens at pergito, Numquam secare desine ; In sectione qualibet Infinitates dissecas. Quiesce mens heic denique, Arctosque nosce limites Queis contineris undique ; Quiesce mens, et limites In orbe cessa quserere. Quod quaeris in te repperis: In mente sunt, in mente sunt, Hi, quos requiris, termini ; A rebus absunt limites, In hisce tantum infinitas, INITNITAS ! INHNITAS ! Proh, quantus heic acervus est ! Et quam nihil quod nostra mens Ex hoc acervo intelligit ! At ilia Mens vah, qualis est, Conspecta cui stant omnia ! In singulis quse perspicit Qusecunque sunt in singulis Et singulorum singulis !'] CHAPTER II. LIMITATION OF THOUGHT AND KNOWLEDGE. I. A DOCTRINE OF THE RELATIVE : THE CATEGORIES OF THOUGHT. THINKING (employing that terra as comprehending all our cog- nitive energies') is of two kinds. It is either A) Negative or B) Positive. A.) Thinking is NEGATIVE (in propriety, a negation of thought), when Existence is not attributed to an object. It is of two kinds ; inasmuch as the one or the other of the conditions of positive thinking is violated. In either case, the result is Nothing. I.) If the condition of Non-contradiction be not fulfilled, there emerges The really Impossible, what has been called in the schools, Nihil purum. II.) If the condition of Relativity be not purified, there results The Impossible to thought ; that is, what may exist, but what we are unable to conceive existing. This impossible, the schools have not contemplated ; we are, therefore, compelled, for the sake of symmetry and precision, to give it a scholastic appellation in the Nihil cogitabile. B.) Thinking is POSITIVE (and this in propriety is the only real thought), when Existence is predicated of an object. By ex- istence is not, however, here meant real or objective existence, but 1 ' Thought and thinking are used in a more, and in a less, restricted signi- fication. In the former meaning they are limited to the discursive energies alone ; in the latter, they are co-extensive with consciousness. In the Car- tesian language, the term thought included all of which we are conscious.' Keid, pp. 222, 270. W. PHILOSOPHY OF THE CONDITIONED. 485 only existence subjective or ideal. Thus, imagining a Centaur or a Hippogryph, we do not suppose that the phantasm has any being beyond our imagination ; but still we attribute to it an ac- tual existence in thought. Nay, we attribute to it a possible ex- istence in creation ; for we can represent nothing, which we do not think, as within the limits of Almighty power to realize. Positive thinking can be brought to bear only under two condi- tions ; the condition of I) Non-contradiction, and the condition of II) Relativity. If both are fulfilled, we think Something. I. NON-CONTRADICTION. This condition is insuperable. We think it, not only as a law of thought, but as a law of things ; and while we suppose its violation to determine an absolute im- possibility, we suppose its fulfilment to afford only the Not-im- possible. Thought is, under this condition, merely explicative or analytic ; and the condition itself is brought to bear under three phases, constituting three laws : i.) the law of Identity ; ii.) the law of Contradiction ; iii.) the law of Excluded Middle. The science of these laws is Logic ; and as the laws are only ex- plicative, Logic is only formal. (The principle of Sufficient Rea- son* should be excluded from Logic. For, inasmuch as this prin- ciple is not material (material = non-formal), it is only a deriva- tion of the three formal laws ; and inasmuch as it is material, it coincides with the principle of Causality, and is extra-logical.) Though necessary to state the condition of Non-contradiction, there is no dispute about its effect, no danger of its violation. When I, therefore, speak of the Conditioned, I use the term in 1 Sufficient Reason=Sum of Causes. ' The principle of the Sufficient Rea- son (p. rationis sufficientis). called, likewise, by Leibnitz, that of the Deter- mining Reason (p. rationis determinantis) of Convenience (p. convenientwi) of Perfection (p. perfectionis) and of the Order of Existences (p. existentia- rum) is one of the most extensive, not to say ambiguous, character. For it is employed to denote, conjunctly and severally, the two metaphysical or real principles 1, Why a thing is (principium or ratio essendi) ; 2, Why a thing becomes or is produced (p. or r.Jiendi) ; and, 3, the logical or ideal principle, Why a thing is known or conceived (p. or r. cognoscendi).'' Reid, p. 464. W. 486 PHILOSOPHY OF THE CONDITIONED. special reference to Relativity. By existence conditioned, is meant, emphatically, existence relative, existence thought under relation. Relation may thus be understood to contain all the categories and forms of positive thought. II.) RELATIVITY. This condition (by which, be it observed, is meant the relatively or conditionally ' relative, and, therefore, not even the relative, absolutely or infinitely) this condition is not insuperable. We should not think it as a law of things, but merely as a law of thought ; for we find that there are contradic- tory opposites, one of which, by the rule of Excluded Middle, must be true, but neither of which can by us be positively thought, as possible. Thinking, under this condition, is ampliative or syn- thetic. Its science, Metaphysic (using that term in a comprehen- sive meaning) is therefore material, in the sense of non-formal. The condition of Relativity, in so far as it is necessary, is brought to bear under three principal relations ; the first of which springs from the subject of knowledge the mind thinking (the relation of Knowledge) ; the second and third from the object of knowl- edge the thing thought about (the relations of Existence). (Besides these necessary and original relations, of which alone it is requisite to speak in an alphabet of human thought, there are many relations, contingent and derivative, which we frequently employ in the actual applications of our cognitive energies. Such for example (without arrangement), as True and False, Good and Bad, Perfect and Imperfect, Easy and Difficult, Desire and Aversion, Simple and Complex, Uniform and Various, Singular and Universal, Whole and Part, Similar and Dissimilar, Congru- 1 We can know, we can conceive, only what is relative. Our knowledge of qualities or phenomena is necessarily relative ; for these exist only as they exist in relation to our faculties. The knowledge or even the conception, of a substance in itself, and apart from any qualities in relation to, and therefore cognizable or conceivable by, our minds, involves a contradiction. Of such we can form ordyanegative notion ; that is, we can merely conceive it as incon- ceivable. But to call this negative notion a relative notion, is wrong ; 1, be- cause all our (positive) notions are relative ; and 2, because this is itself a negative notion i. e. no notion at all simply because there is no relation. Reid, p. 828. W. PHILOSOPHY OF THE CONDITIONED. 487 ent and Incongruent, Equal and Unequal, Orderly and Disorderly, Beautiful and Deformed, Material and Immaterial, Natural and Artificial, Organized and Inorganized, Young and Old, Male and Female, Parent and Child, &c., quibus determinants ignari." 1 Chrysippus's Top or Cylinder is the source. Reid, pp. 599, 616, 617. W. 512 PHILOSOPHY OF THE CONDITIONED. ment the doctrine of liberty proceeds ; the fatalist is shown to overlook the equal, but less obtrusive, inconceivability of an in- finite non-commencement, on the assertion of which non-com- mencement his own doctrine of necessity must ultimately rest. As equally unthinkable, the two counter, the two one-sided, schemes are thus theoretically balanced. But practically, our consciousness of the moral law, which, without a moral liberty in man, would be a mendacious imperative, gives a decisive pre- ponderance to the doctrine of freedom over the doctrine of fate. We are free in act, if we are accountable for our actions. Such ((pwvavrct tfuvsrorrfiv) are the hints of an undeveloped phi- losophy, which, I am confident, is founded upon truth. To this confidence I have come, not merely through the convictions of my own consciousness, but by finding in this system a centre and conciliation for the most opposite of philosophical opinions. Above all, however, I am confirmed in my belief, by the harmony be- tween the doctrines of this philosophy, and those of revealed truth. ' Credo equidem, nee vana fides.' The philosophy of the Condi- tioned is indeed pre-eminently a discipline of humility ; a ' learn- ed ignorance,' directly opposed to the false ' knowledge which puf- feth up.' I may indeed say with St. Chrysostom : ' The founda- tion of our philosophy is humility.' (Homil. de Perf. Evang.) For it is professedly a scientific demonstration of the impossibility of that ' wisdom in high matters ' which the Apostle prohibits us even to attempt ; and it proposes, from the limitation of the hu- man powers, from our impotence to comprehend what, however, we must admit, to show articulately why the ' secret things of God' cannot but be to man ' past finding out.' Humility thus becomes the cardinal virtue, not only of revelation but of reason. This scheme proves, moreover, that no difficulty emerges in the- ology which had not previously emerged in philosophy ; that, in fact, if the divine do not transcend what it has pleased the Deity to reveal, and wilfully identify the doctrine of God's word with some airogant extreme of human speculation, philosophy will be PHILOSOPHY OF THE CONDITIONED. 513 found the most useful auxiliary of theology. For a world of false, and pestilent, and presumptuous reasoning, by which philosophy and theology are now equally discredited, would be at once abol- ished, in the recognition of this rule of prudent nescience ; nor could it longer be too justly said of the code of consciousness, as by reformed divines it has been acknowledged of the Bible : ' This is the book, where each his dogma seeks ; And this the book, where each his dogma finds.' Specially ; in its doctrine of causality this philosophy brings us back from the aberrations of modern theology, to the truth and simplicity of the more ancient church. It is here shown to be as irrational as irreligious, on the ground of human understanding, to deny, either, on the one hand, the foreknowledge, predestina- tion, and free grace of God, or, on the other, the free will of man ; that we should believe both, and both in unison, though unable to comprehend either even apart. This philosophy proclaims with St. Augustin, and Augustin in his maturest writings : ' If there be not free grace in God, how can He save the world ; and if there be not free will in man, how can the world by God be judged !' (Ad Valentinum, Epist. 214.) Or, as the same doctrine is per- haps expressed even better by St. Bernard : 'Abolish free will, and there is nothing to be saved ; abolish free grace, and there is nothing wherewithal to save.' (De Gratia et Libero Arbitrio. c. i.) St. Austin repeatedly declares, the conciliation of the fore- knowledge, predestination, and free grace of God with the free will of man, to be ' a most difficult question, intelligible only to a few.' Had he denounced it as a fruitless question, and (to un- derstanding) soluble by none, the world might hare been spared a large library of acrimonious and resultless disputation. This conciliation is of the things to be believed, not understood. The futile attempts to harmonize these antilogies, by human reasoning to human understanding, have originated connective systems of theology, divided the Church, and, as far as possible, dishonored 22* 514 PHILOSOPHY OF THE CONDITIONED. religion. It must however be admitted, that confessions of the total inability of man to conceive the union, of what he should believe united, are to be found ; and they are found, not, per- haps less frequently, and certainly in more explicit terms among Catholic than among Protestant theologians. Of the former, I shall adduce only one testimony, by a prince of the Church ; and it is the conclusion of what, though wholly overlooked, appears to me as the ablest and truest criticism of the many fruitless, if not futile, attempts at conciliating * the ways of God' to the understanding of man, in the great articles of divine foreknowledge and predestination (which are both embarrassed by the self-same difficulties), and human free-will. It is the testimo- ny of Cardinal Cajetan, and from his commentary on the Sum- ma Theologise of Aquinas. The criticism itself I may take another opportunity of illustrating. Thus elevating our mental eye to a loftier range [we may suppose that], God, from an excellence supernally transcending human thought, so foresees events and things, that from his providence something higher follows than evitability or inevitability, and that his passive prevision of the event docs not determine the alternative of either combination. And can we do so, the intellect is quieted ; not by the evidence of the truth known, but by the in- accessible height of the truth concealed. And this to my poor intellect seems satisfactory enough, both for the reason above stated, and because, as Saint Gregory expresses it, " The man has a low opinion of God, who believes of Him only so much as can be measured by human understanding." Not that we should deny aught, that we have by knowledge or by fuith of the immutability, actuality, certainty, universality, and similar attributes of God ; but I suspect (hat there is something here lying hid, either as regards the rela- tion between the Deity and event foreseen, or as regards the connection be- tween the event itself and its prevision. Thus, reflecting that the intelli- gence of man [in such matters] is as the eye of the owl [in the blaze of day (he refers to Aristotle)], I find its repose in ignorance alone. For it is more consistent, both with Catholic faith and with philosophy, to confess our blindness, than to assert, as things evident, what afford no tranquillity to the intellect; for evidence is tranquillizing. Not that I would, therefore, accuse all the doctors" of presumption; because, stammering, as they could, they have all intended to insinuate, with God's immutability, the supreme and eternal efficiency of His intellect, and will, and power, through the infalli- ble relation between the Divine election and whatever comes to pass. Noth- ing of all this is opposed to the foresaid suspicion that something too deep for lies hid herein. And assuredly, if it were thus promulgated, no Chris- tian would err in the matter of Predestination, as no one errs in the doctrine PHILOSOPHY OF THE CONDITIONED. 515 of the Trinity ;* because of the Trinity the truth is declared orally and in writing, that this is a mystery concealed from human intellect, and to which faith alone is competent. Indeed, the best and most wholesome counsel in this matter is : To begin with those things which we certainly know, and have experience of in ourselves ; to wit, that all proceeding from our free- will may or may not be performed by us, and therefore are we amenable to punishment or reward ; but how, this being saved, there shall be saved the providence, predestination, &c., of God, to believe what holy mother Church believes. For it is written, "Altiora te ne qusesieris" ("Be not wise in things above thee") ; there being many things revealed to man above thy human comprehension. And this is one of those.' (Pars. I. q. xxii., art. 4.) Averments to a similar effect, might be adduced from the writ- ings of Calvin ; and, certainly, nothing can be conceived more contrary to the doctrine of that great divine, than what has lat- terly been promulgated as Calvinism (and, in so far as I know, without reclamation), in our Calvinistic Church of Scotland. For it has been here promulgated, as the dogma of this Church, by pious and distinguished theologians, that man has no will, agency, moral personality of his own, God being the only real agent in every apparent act of his creatures ; in short (though quite the opposite was intended), that the theological scheme of the abso- lute decrees implies fatalism, pantheism, the negation of a moral governor, and of a moral world. For the premises, arbitrarily assumed, are atheistic ; the conclusion, illogically drawn, is Chris- tian. Against such a view of Calvin's doctrine, I for one must humbly though solemnly protest, as not only false in philosophy, but heterodox and ignorant in theology. * This was written before 1507 ; consequently long before Servetus and Campanus had introduced their Unitarian heresies. 516 PHILOSOPHY OF THE CONDITIONED. PHILOSOPHY OF THE CONDITIONED. 517 II. PHILOSOPHICAL TESTIMONIES TO THE LIMITATION OF OUR KNOWLEDGE, FROM THE LIMITATION OF OUR FACULTIES. THESE, which might be indefinitely multiplied, I shall arrange under three heads. I omit the Skeptics, adducing only speci- mens from the others. I. Testimonies to the general fact that the highest knowledge is a consciousness of ignorance. There are two sorts of ignorance : we philosophize to escape ignorance, and the consummation of our philosophy is ignorance ; we start from the one, we repose in the other; they are the goals from which, and to which, we tend ; and the pursuit of knowledge is but a course between two ignorances, as human life is itself only a travelling from grave to grave. ' 'T/j |3foj ; 'Eic Tvpfioio Oop&v, i-rrl rvufiov bSc6ccultes. On s'est moque fort longtemps des qualites occultes ; on doit se moquer de ceux qui n'y croient pas. R6p^tons cent fois, que tout principe, tout premier ressort de quelque oeuvre que ce puisse Atre du ^rand Demiourgos, est occulte et cacb^ pour jamais aux mortela.' And so forth. (Physique Particuliere, ch. xxxiii.) ' II y a done certainement des lois eternelles, iuconnues, suivant lesquelles tout s'opere, sans qu'on puisse les expliquer par la matiere et par le mouvement. . . . II y a dans toutes les Academies une chaire vacante pour les ve'rite's inconnuea comme Athenes avait un autel pour les dieux ignores.'* * Besides the few testimonies adduced, I would refer, in general, for sonu- excellent observations on the point, to Fernelius ' De Abditis Rerum Caufis ' and to the ' Hypomnemata' of Scnnertus. FINIS. University of California SOUTHERN REGIONAL LIBRARY FACILITY 405 Hilgard Avenue, Los Angeles, CA 90024-1388 Return this material to the library from which It was borrowed. OCT 1 6 1995 S L 005 492 126 7 * UC SOUTHERN REGIONAL LIBRARY FACILITY A A ' 000011675 6