LIBRARY OF THE UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, Clciss ^ — > ^ / PRINCIPLES OF Political Economy BY CHARLES GIDE, Professor of Political Economy in the University of MoNTPELUER, France. TRANSLATED BY EDWARD PERCY JACOBSEN (Formerly of University College, London). ^itb an Introbtictxon anb 3|[ote3 By JAMES BONAR, MA., LL.D. BOSTON, U.S.A.: D. C. HEATH & CO., PUBLISHERS. 1892. Copyright, 1891, Bt D. C. heath & CO. \ ^^ Typography by J. S. Cushing & Co., Boston, U.S.A. Presswork by Berwick & Smith, Boston, U.S.A. INTRODUCTION. American and English readers will welcome the translation of Professor Gide's book. It is neither a primer for beginners, nor a dissertation for the learned, but a guide-book for serious students 'who have mastered the economical alphabet, and are feeling their way to a judgment of their own on economical subjects. Its place in French economic literature is almost unique. It is helping many a young Frenchman to turn his attention to economic theory, and to study it in the light of the latest discussions. Professor Gide has Adam Smith's faculty of making his readers think for themselves, and accept no conclusion without following out the process that leads to it. He lays a just emphasis on the need of impartiaHty and freedom from prejudice. In a book wTitten for real students of a subject, the truth should be told without reserve or fear of consequences. Economists familiar with recent investigations (Continental, American, and English) of the doctrines of Value, Wages, Foreign Trade, etc., will not always agree with the views presented in this volume. Students will do well to supplement its somewhat scanty references to current economic literature by such a bibliography as that which is given by Professor E. B. Andrews in his Institutes of Economics (Boston, 1889). It will be observed that the schools of modern economists are (in the beginning of the book) so classified that our author re- 107552 in IV INTRODUCTION. mains outside of them. His position, however, is substantially that of the First or " Classical School," if we substitute evolution and social union ("solidarity") for finality and individualism. Like the Classical School, he recognizes the need of Theory and (to that end) of Abstraction ; and the theoretical work of the Classical School is in great part the foundation of his own new building. Political Economy in the hands of Professor Gide is neither dismal in its conclusions, nor dull in its deliberations. Though these may be counted adventitious attractions, they will be keenly appreciated by most of his readers. In point of style, our author has few rivals, even in France. JAMES BONAR. Hampstead, London, X4th March, 1891. AUTHOR'S PREFACE TO THE THH^D [FRENCH] EDITION. -•o*- When the first edition of this work appeared in 1883, 1 refrained from prefixing any prefatory note, for I thought it wiser for the book to introduce itself to the pubHc. In the second edition I somewhat sharply repUed to some severe criticisms which had been directed against the tendency of the treatise. In the preface to this new edition complaints are out of the question ; all that I can do is to thank the public for the favorable manner in which the book has been received both in France and abroad. I have endeavored to acknowledge this kind reception by cor- recting and supplementing, to the best of my powers, the weak points and deficiencies which have been brought before my notice. However, there is a criticism of a general nature which has reached me from various quarters and has proceeded from friends as well as from adversaries ; to this I must devote a few words ot explanation unless I wish to incur the charge of neglecting it. The complaint is, that in treating each question I have set forth the various competing systems without expressing my own opinions in a sufficiently decided manner ; I am, therefore, charged with leaving students to wander in a state of unpleasant uncertainty, and with consequently failing to discharge in full measure the duties of a pro- fessor who is entrusted with the care of the minds of the young. My reply is, that this book is not intended for scholars in pri- mary schools or for use in secondary education. Nor is it addressed exclusively to students of the universities ; its object is also to reach practical men who wish to form for themselves an opinion on economic and social questions ; I repeat, men who wish to V vi author's preface to the third edition. form an opinion " for themselves," and are not content with re- ceiving one ready-made from the teacher's hps. My method may sometimes leave the reader in a state of hesitation and suspended, as it were, in a species of mental balancing which is wont to lull to sleep minds of a sluggish nature ; but I am confident that it will be profitable to those who are eager for the discovery of truth and do not wish to have opinions forced upon them. Further, I have not shrunk from pronouncing an outspoken judgment on all questions in which the truth seems to be beyond contro- versy ; in all cases in which doubt is possible, — a class of ques- tions which unfortunately is far more extensive, — I have striven to maintain an equal balance, but, nevertheless, have not neglected to throw in that grain of sand which, for the keen observer's eye, is enough to turn the scale. Perhaps I may also be allowed to remark, that the excess of impartiality for which I am taken to task has not been the char- acteristic feature of treatises on political economy which have been hitherto published in France. For several generations these books had been in the habit of presenting political economy in only one light, — the point of view of the " Liberal " school. There is, then, no reason to murmur if later treatises should break with a tradi- tion which was beginning to assume the shape of a law, should restore their rightful place to doctrines which have heretofore been proscribed, and should give their due share of justice even to notions which do not command our assent ; for thus can be applied Shakespeare's admirable maxim, — " There is some soul of goodness in things evil, Would men observingly distil it out." — Henry J ', act iv. scene I . CHARLES GIDE. AMERICAN INTRODUCTION. -•o«- SciENCE is international; it suffers when the natural relation between different countries is interrupted, and gains when the connection is resumed. The publication in America of a treatise on Economics written in France, and translated in England, means the re-establishment of an intellectual commerce that has been partly under an embargo. The orthodoxy of many French econ- omists, and the impulse to enlist under new school or historical standards, which lately showed itself in America, had the effect of isolating these two countries from each other ; while between the American school and the English school of a few years ago, a similar though less complete separation had taken place. Between England and America an active interchange of thought has since been established. In addition to the benefit to be derived from a closer scientific relation to France, there are specific gains to be expected from the use of Professor Gide's treatise by American students. Its progressive spirit will make it everywhere welcome, and its appreci- ative attitude toward the older schools of thought will, at the same time, make it everywhere useful. It carefully retains the best fruits of early work ; the " new departure " that it represents is one that does not break with the past. Its conspicuous quality is a wisdom that is not often combined with so much of brilliancy. Mr. Jacobsen has been very successful in preserving in his trans- lation the literary quality of the original work. J. B. CLARK. Northampton, Mass., March 20, 189 1. vu TABLE OF CONTENTS. GENERAL NOTIONS. PAGE I I. The object of political economy II. On method in political economy 4 III. Whether there are natural laws in political economy 9 IV. The four economic schools ^5 Book I. WEALTH AND VALUE. Chapter I. — Wealth. I. The desire for wealth • 3^ II. The wants of man 34 III. The definition of wealth 3^ Chapter II. — Value. I. What is value ? 44 II. What is the cause of value ? 47 III. Critical examination of the various theories of value 54 IV. Variations in value "° V. The effects produced on value by competition ^4 VI. Whether competition is cheapness ^^ Chatter III. — Price. I, How value is measured by exchange 7- II. On the choice of a common measure of values 74 III. What is price? ^^ IV. Whether the measure of value be not an insoluble problem S4 V. Whether money should be reckoned as wealth ^S ix X TABLE OF CONTENTS. Book II. PRODUCTION. Part 1 . — The Conditions of Individual Production. the factors of productiom. Chapter I. — Nature, ,age I . Ihe environment 96 1 1 . The ground 99 in. The raw material loi IV. Motive forces 103 Chakfer II. — Labor. I. On the part played in production b. labor 108 II. How labor produces in III. What kinds of labor should be called productive? 113 IV. On pain as a factor of labor 118 V. On time as a factor of labor 121 Chapter III. — Capital. I. On the part played in production by capital 1 25 II. The meaning of the productivity of capital 127 III. The distinction between wealth which is capital and wealth which is not 1 30 IV. The durability of fixed and of circulating capital 135 V. How capital is formed 1 38 Part II. — Tjik Social Conditions of Production. the social organis.m. Chapter I. — Association. I. The various forms of association 145 II. The advantages and disadvantages of large production 150 III. Whether large production should be extended to agriculture 154 Chapter II. — Division of Labor. I. The different forms of division of labor 158 II. The advantages and the disadvantages of division of labor 161 III. Liberty of labor 1 66 TABLE OF CONTENTS. XI Chapter III. — Exchange. page I. On the part played in production by exchange 169 II. The advantages of exchange 172 III. On the means of facilitating exchange 174 IV. On the part played in production by traders 174 V. The disadvantages of the multiplication of traders 176 VI. Means of transport 1 79 VII. The breaking-up of barter into sale and purchase 182 Chapter IV. — Metallic Money. I. Why the precious metals have been chosen as the instrument of exchange 186 II. The invention of coined money 188 III. The conditions to be fulfilled by all good money 190 IV. Gresham's law 194 THE QUESTION OF MONOMETALLISM AND BIMETALLISM. I. The necessity of taking several metals, and the resulting difficulties 198 II. How it is that bimetallist countries really have but one money. . . 202 III. Whether it is adWsable to adopt the monometallist system 207 IV. Whether the respective value of the two metals could not be fixed by an international understanding 211 Chapter V. — Paper Money. I. Whether metallic money can be replaced by paper money 214 II, Whether the creation of paper money is equivalent to a creation of wealth 219 III. The dangers resulting from the use of paper money and the means of preventing them 224 IV. How even paper money may be dispensed with 228 V. How the improvements in exchange bring us back to barter 233 VI. The decadence of the precious metals 234 Chapter VI. — International Trade. I. Why exaggerated importance is attached to foreign trade 236 II. Why international trade always tends to take the shape of barter 237 III. What is meant bv the Ijalance of trade 241 IV. Wherein lie the advantages of international trade 246 Xll TABLE OF CONTENTS. PAGE V. Why the advantages of international trade should be measured neither by the excess in imports nor by the excess in exports. . 248 V'l. How it happens that international trade necessarily harms certain interests 250 THE QUESTION OF FREE TRADE AND PROTECTION. 1. Why the question of free trade is a question 252 II. The protectionist system 256 III. Whether the dangers feared by the protectionist theory are real . . 260 IV. On the disadvantages of protective duties 264 V. Why the bounty system is preferable 269 VI. On some moderate forms of protection 270 Ch.apter VII. — Credit. I. Credit operations 272 II. Credit papers 275 III. Whether credit can create capital 277 IV. Banks 280 V. Deposits 281 VI. Discount 283 VII. On the issuing of bank notes 286 VIII. The differences between the bank note and paper money 290 IX. The rate of exchange 292 X. The raising of the rate of discount 299 XI. Some special forms of credit 303 the question OF MONOPOLY OR OF LIBEKTY OF BANKING, I. On monopoly or competition in the issuing of notes 309 II. As to liberty or regulation in the issuing of notes 313 Part III. — The Equilibrium between Production and Consumption. Ch.\pter I. — Insufficiency in Production. I. The increase of population; the laws of Malthus 320 II. On the limitation of production in agriculture, and the law of decreasing returns 323 III. On the limitation of production in other industries 328 IV. How limitation of production affects prices 330 TABLE OF CONTENTS. XIU PAGE Chapter II. — Excess in Production. I. How to maintain the equilibrium between production and con- sumption 334 II. Crises 336 III. Is there reason to fear too much' production? 341 Chapter III. — Progress in Production. I. Current illusions as to economic progress 345 II. The disadvantages necessarily involved in all progress in pro- duction 348 III. The question of machinery 351 IV. The future of production 356 Book III. CONSUMPTION. How Wealth can be Employed. Chapter I. — Expenditure. I. What should be our conception of expenditure? .... 361 II. How it happens that expenditure regulates but does not feed production 364 HI. The real aims of expenditure 366 IV. Luxury 369 V. The expenditure of foreigners 373 VI. The means of reducing expenditure 376 Chaiter II. — Saving. I. What should be our conception of saving? 379 II. The conditions necessary for saving 382 HI. Institutions for the facilitation of saving. 386 Chapter HI. — Investing. I. What should be our conception of investing? 390 II. The conditions necessary for investing 395 XIV TABLE OF CONTENTS. Book IV. * DISTRIBUTION. Part I. — The Various Principles of Distribution. Chapter I. — The Social Problem. page I. Is there a social question ? 398 II. The inequality of wealth 401 111. Why the problem of distribution is so hard to solve 406 Chapter II. — The Socialist Solution. I. Communism 410 II. Collectivism 414 III. The different formuLie for the division of wealth 418 IV. Why there is no solution 428 Chapter III. — The Rights of Property. I. The origin of the rights of property 430 II. What are the attributes of the rights of property? 431 III. Over what things should the right of property extend? 438 IV. The historical evolution of landed property 445 V. The legitimacy of landed property 451 VI. The law of ground rent 455 MI. The nationalization of the land 461 VIII. The organization of landed property 464 Part II. — The Various Classes of Sharers. Chapter I. — The Autonomous Producer. I, Why this condition is the most favorable for a fair distribution of wealth 473 Chapter II. — The Master. I. The part played by the master, and the legitimacy of profits 477 II. The laws which regulate profits 482 TIT. Whether tha rate of profits is in inverse ratio to the rate of wages 486 Chapter III.— The Wages-fj^rner. I. The contract of wages 4^9 II. The laws which regulate the rate of wages 49- TABLE OF CONTENTS. XV PAGE III. The rise in wages 503 IV. Whether there are any means of improving the condition of the wages-earners 506 V. Strikes 5^9 VI. State interference 5^2 VII. Co-operation 5^9 Chapter IV. — The Man who Lives on his Income. I. The right to be idle 526 II. The rent of land 529 III. House-rent 532 IV. Interest , 535 V. Does the rate of interest tend to fall? 539 Chapter V, — The Indigent. I. The right to relief .... 543 II. The organization of public relief. 547 III. Is pauperism on the increase? 55^ Appendix. — The Public Fin.a.nces of Fr.\nce. I. Public expenditure 554 II. The public revenue 559 III. The public debt 570 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. -ooXXOO- GENERAL NOTIONS. I. THE OBJECT OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. It may appear strange, at the beginning of a treatise on political economy which is perhaps the hundredth which has been written on the subject, to declare that a precise definition of political economy has still to be found. Such, however, is the truth ; and after all, there is nothing very surprising about it. No science can be clearly defined until it has been finished and till the neighboring sciences are so also. Now, such is not the case with the science which is occupying our attention ; on the contrary, like the other social sciences, it is a science in process of formation. Just as in a still unexplored land, the traveller cannot mark out on the map the exact frontiers of each district, but must confine himself to indicating more or less approximately the great dividing lines which he perceives or guesses at, so here, too, we must be contented with pointing out as accurately as we can the domain of political economy, without venturing to mark it off very clearly from the territory of the other social sciences. Without, then, seeking at present a precision that would be useless, we may say, in harmony with most writers, that political economy is the science of wealth. Although the word " wealth " of itself greatly needs definition, yet it sharply suggests to the mind the essential facts with which our science deals, and there- 2 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. fore frees us from a recourse to long circumlocutions ; still we must not be led astray by the circumstance that political economy deals with wealth, that is to say, with things, res, nor be tempted thereby to class it among the natural sciences which study bodies. Wealth, as we shall see, is created by the needs of men living in society, and consequently the study of wealth is nothing but the study of " man " under one of his most characteristic aspects. Three questions have always occupied the thoughts of men : " How can wealth be produced ? " " What use should be made of it?" " In what manner should it be divided?" The several an- swers to each of these questions constitute one of the great divisions of political economy ; viz., production, consmnption, and distribu- tion. In works on political economy, almost without exception, a fourth division is added, viz., circulation ; but we must confess that we have never been able to understand what the term answered and referred to. For the circulation of wealth, i.e. the transferring of commodities from hand to hand, is, as will be seen, nothing but a consequence and a form of division of labor. It is there- fore irrational to detach this section from the department of pro- duction in order to make it into a distinct branch. The fact that wealth may be transferred from hand to hand is a circumstance which is valueless in itself, and its only worth lies in the measure in which it contributes to social production. It is clear that the three questions which constitute the pith of political economy are essentially practical ones, and it seems to follow that the science whose object it is to supply an answer to these questions should itself be of a practical nature ; in other words, be an art rather than a science. Indeed, it was under this aspect as an art, or say a practical study pursuing a definite aim, namely, national prosperity, that political economy was always regarded by the ancients. This, too, is shown by the etymology of the word (oikos = the house, i^o/xos = government, ttoAis = the city), and Adam Smith, the father of the science, adhered to this definition. But the human mind, which is always curious to learn the GENERAL NOTIONS. 3 reason of things, has gone on to ask a further question : '^ What is Wealth?" But this differs from the three earher questions by possessing a purely speculative character ; its object is to deter- mine the causes which render wealth desirable, to discover the necessary relations between different kinds of wealth ; in other words, to formulate the laws of value and of price. To the answering of this branch of questions we purpose to devote a fourth division ; but to comply with the necessities of logic this must be our first part, and should be regarded as the purely theoretical side of political economy. In most works on political economy, value is merely dealt with as a portion of exchange, but that presents it in a far too narrow light. The notion of value is really the basis of all political economy ; and not only exchange, but distribution, consumption, and production likewise become united, from a strictly scientific as well as from a practical point of view, when questions of value are discussed. It is logical, then, to give value a branch to itself, unless, indeed, we are willing to scatter it through all the other divisions^ In fine, works on pure pohtical economy are in reality nothing but treatises on value. Political economy is not the only science which treats of the relations between men and things or of the relations of men ififer se ; Laiv and Morals share in this study. These three great social sciences have the same object, at least for a part of their work ; though, no doubt, they view it under three differ- ent aspects. The economist is concerned merely with the wants of men, the lawyer with his rights, the moralist with his duties. But on questions of succession, property, credit, on the contract of loans and of wages, the lawyer and the economist are compelled to join hands, just as the economist and the moralist have to meet on the questions of luxury or poverty and many others. This is a happy meeting and is of great benefit to all three sciences. Our virtual separation of them follows less from the necessities of logic than from that weakness of human understanding which debars us from comprehending so vast a domain at one and the same 4 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. glance. Still it is to be hoped that there may be a daily increase in their blending and joint study. Years ago Auguste Comte laid down " that every study isolated from its various social elements was, from the very nature of the science, compelled to be essentially sterile, after the exajnple of political eco7iomy:' For he conceived the idea, which constitutes his chief title to fame, of the regulation of all social phenomena by a separate science which he called sociology. All workers at sociology, whether they be of the school of Comte or of the school of Herbert Spencer, apply their main efforts to the formation of a huge synthesis of all the social sciences ; but the field is so vast that it is easy to miss the right road, II. ON METHOD IN POLITICAL ECONOMY. In scientific language the term " method " is used to mean the road that must be followed for the discovery of truth. Now there are several roads, and the question as to which road should be chosen has in recent years aroused a great controversy. The classical school of economics, of which Ricardo is the most illustrious representative, used to employ the deductive method, — a method which starts from certain general principles that are regarded as indisputable, and proceeds thence by way of logical consequence to deduce an indefinite series of propositions. Geometry (or even theology) may be taken as the type of the sciences that employ the deductive method. Law students will readily recognize that Law itself, particularly Roman Law, employs the deductive method ; for the jurisconsult, starting from a few principles laid down by the Twelve Tables, or found in the jus gentium, proceeded to construct that huge monument of learning that we call the Pandects. In economic science the deductive school started from the principle (named hedonistic) " that man always desires to obtain the maximum of satisfaction with the minimum of pain," and thence deduced a series of propositions which still constitute the framework of economic science. GENERAL NOTIONS. 5 The new school rejects this mode of reasoning ; it asserts that in social science, and in the physical or natural sciences likewise, the inductive ?nethod is the only one to employ : this method starts from the observation of certain particular facts in order to rise to the height of general propositions ; for example, from the fact that all bodies fall, to the law of gravity. In economics this method will be shown in the individual and accumulated obser- vation of all social facts as they are revealed to us, in their present state by means of statistics or by information supplied by travellers, in their past state by history. Thus we shall be able to slowly raise the edifice of economic science, which will then be the true science, not like that artificial science (so says the new school) which the deductive school constructed in cut and dried fashion. Both of these methods are too absolute ; but truth is never reached by so perfectly straight a road. The real method of political economy proceeds by three stages : First. By the observation of facts without any preconceived notion, even those which at first sight appear to be the most trivial. Second. By the imagination of a general explanation which will enable us to establish mutual relations between certain groups of facts ; i.e. by the forming of an hypothesis. Third. By the verification of the validity of this hypothesis, by seeking, by the aid of experiment if possible, at any rate by specially directed observations, to discover whether it exactly cor- responds with the facts. ... Of course it is not necessary for the same men of science to make observations, form hypotheses, and verify them ; for the gifts of observation and of imagination are somewhat rarely combined in the same person. The above has been the procedure adopted in all sciences. All those great laws which constitute the bases of modern sciences, beginning with Newton's Law of Gravity, are only verified hypotheses ; and we must add that the great theories which are the groundwork of scientific research, e.g. the existence of ether in physics, or the theory of evolution in natural science, are merely hypotheses which require verification. Proof of this may be found 6 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. in Claude Bernard's Introdiictioji a V Etude de la Mcdecine Experi- mentdk and in M. Naville's La Logique de VHypothcse. As Stanley Jevons has observed in his Principles of Science, the method employed for obtaining the discovery of truth in the sciences is similar to that unconsciously made use of by those who try to find the meaning of those rebuses or ciphers to be met with on the back page of some illustrated papers. In order to guess what the meaning of this enigma may be, we imagine some mean- ing or other. Then we observe whether this really agrees with the figures or images before us ; if it does not, it is an hypothesis to be rejected. We then conceive another one, and so forth, until we obtain a more successful result, or lose courage altogether. We shall find nothing in facts unless we have previously in our minds an image or a forecast of the truth. The new school, then, is wholly in the right when it blames the classical school for its dogmatic attitude and for its tendency to believe that the principles, at which it has arrived by reasoning, are the exact expression of what is and of what ought to be. But this school, in its turn, commits no less serious an error in believ- ing that the attentive observation of facts is of itself sufiicient to establish the science of economics, and that we may therefore for the future dispense with any resort to abstraction, hypothesis, and the " let us suppose " so dear to the school of Ricardo and so obnoxious to the school now under mention. The facts presented to us by nature are too numerous, too complex, too interlaced ; and in economics especially, they form too inextricable a labyrinth for us ever to be able to discover our whereabouts, unless reason or imagination comes to our aid and throws light upon the darkness and forms order out of the chaos. It is true enough that the generalizations of the classical school to which, too ambitiously, perhaps, has been given the name of "laws" (for instance, those associated with Ricardo and with Mal- thus), are for the most part only hypotheses to be verified or to be rejected. But, such as they are, they have rendered eminent service to the science of economics, and it would be ungrateful GENERAL NOTIONS. 7 to disown them, even though they may come to be regarded not as the framework of poUtical economy, but only as the scaffolding used during the construction of buildings, and destined to be taken down as soon as the work is completed. Latterly, however, a new deductive school has arisen, which, in spite of adhering faithfully to the reasoning method, and even pushing it to the extreme, as is shown by its preferring to employ mathematical language, has been wary enough not to be ensnared by its own speculations, as was the case with the former deductive school. This newer deductive school presents its abstractions purely as what they are ; that is to say, as hypotheses intended to illuminate facts and guide observation. • In his Elements cV Economie politicjue pure, M. Walras of Lau- sanne writes : '' Pure political economy is essentially the theory of the determination of prices under a hypothetical regulation of ab- solutely free competition." To this may be added a dictum of Signor Pantaleoni in his Principii di Economia pura : " Whether the hedonistic and psychological hypothesis (that of the maximum of pleasure with the minimum of effort), whence all economic truths are deduced, coincides or fails to coincide with the motives which actually determine men's actions, is a question which in nowise detracts from the accuracy of truths deduced therefrom." In point of method there is one great difference between the economic and the natural sciences ; in economics it is very diffi- cult and often impossible to employ experime7it, and therefore hypotheses may remain in suspense for an indefinitely long period, for want of any suitable means of v^erification. The chemist, the physicist, and even the biologist, though the last experiences greater difficulties, can always place the fact which they wish to study under certain artificially determined conditions which they can vary at will. For instance, in order to study the respiration of an animal, they can place it under the bell-jar of a pneumatic machine, and alter the pressure of the air according to their requirements. This power is never possible to the economist, even though he be 8 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. joined by a lawgiver or an omnipotent despot. In social matters we are obliged to study facts as they are presented to us, without being able to isolate them from the web of connected facts in which they are implicated. We cannot put a country under a bell-jar; and even if we could, that would not be enough to enable us to draw any certain conclusions. Let us suppose that in order to study the effects produced by free trade, we could take two countries, and subject one to an absolute regime of free trade, the other to a protectionist system ; and find, at the end of ten years, that the former had greatly increased in wealth, whereas the latter had become ruined. No doubt this would be valuable information for us to gain ; but still, even under the extraordinarily favorable, and moreover, altogether imaginary, circumstances that I have supposed, the experiment would not be a decisive one. For the various destinies of different countries can be explained by far other causes than differences in their commercial systems ; to wit : differences in environment, in race, in legislation, in individual energy. Take the two Australian colonies of New South Wales and of Victoria ; though both of them are of the same race and in the same environment, the first is free-trading, the second is protec- tionist. Although this experiment has already lasted for a long time, are we to think that the question of free trade has yet been solved? By no means ! Adhuc sub jiidice lis est. Instead, therefore, of being able to make direct social experi- ments, we are obliged to wait for what chance may supply us with in certain particular circumstances, such as the application of a new method of legislation, the foundation of a socialist com- munity, a pathological crisis in an existing society ; and even then this indirect mode of experimentation would but very rarely lead us to any definite conclusions. We must not then be astonished, as people too often are, if the science of economics takes far longer to construct than was the case with the physical or natural sciences. Nay ! the reverse rather would have caused surprise ; for on the one hand the GENERAL NOTIONS. 9 observation of facts is in this study more difficult than it is else- where ; and, on the other hand, the most powerful means for reading between the lines of facts (the auxiliary that has enabled the other sciences to make such marvellous and so rapid prog- ress), I mean experiment, now deserts us. A further reason this, for not absolutely rejecting the employment of the abstract method. In truth, the observation of economic and social facts is a task which is infinitely above all individual effort. It could only be the collective work of thousands of men putting their observations together, or of governments themselves, using for this purpose the powerful means of investigation which they have at their disposal. If there is one simple and elementary fact among all the facts which have any connection with the social sciences, it is surely that of the number of persons composing a society. Yet it is clear that an isolated observer is absolutely powerless to determine this matter. Governments alone can undertake this task, and even then it is only quite recently that official returns have attained a moderate degree of accuracy. To take another example. In 1879 ^^^ French National Soci- ety of Agriculture wished to make an inquiry into the question whether the division of property had increased or diminished. Can a simpler question be imagined ? Yet the result of this inquiry (as reported by M. Leroy-Beaulieu in his book on La Repartition des richesses) was that out of ZZ correspondents, -i^^ replied that the division of property had increased, 4 that it had diminished, 21 that it had remained unchanged, and 25 made no reply at all, probably because they knew nothing at all about it. III. WHETHER THERE ARE NATURAL LAWS IN POLITICAL ECONOMY. When we grant to any branch of human knowledge the name of science, our object is not the simple bestowal on it of an honorary title ; the assertion we make is, that the facts studied by this 10 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. " science " are naturally connected with one another in a regular order ; in other words, that they are subject to laws. In some domains the order of phenomena is so obvious that such a state of things has compelled remark even from the minds v/hich are least accustomed to scientific speculations. A mere lifting of the eyes skywards is enough to establish the regularity of the nightly progress of the stars, of the monthly succession of the phases of the moon, of the yearly journey of the sun through the constellations. In the most remote days of history, shepherds watching their flocks, sailors steering their vessels, had already recognized the periodical nature of these movements, and herein were laid the foundations of a true science, the oldest of all sciences, — astronomy. The phenomena which are manifested in the constitution of organized bodies and dead matter are not as simple, and the order of their co-existence or succession is not as easy to comprehend. Many centuries, therefore, had to elapse before the human mmd, lost in the labyrinth of things, succeeded in laying hold of the guiding thread, in finding at length order and law in these facts themselves, and in forming out of them the sciences of physics, chemistry, and biology. Little by litde this idea of a constant order among phenomena has penetrated into all domains, even into those which at first sight seemed destined to remain forever closed to it. Even those winds and waves, which poets had from time immemorial made the emblem of inconstancy and caprice, have in their turn come to recognize the empire of this new power. At least the great laws have been established, which direct, through the atmosphere or across the oceans, the aerial or the maritime currents. And meteorology, or the physics of the globe, has in its turn established its foundations. Even the chances of wagers, the combinations of dice — there is none, even of these, which has not been sub- jected to the calculation of probabilities. Hazard, even, hence- forward has its laws. The day, too, was to come when this grand idea of a natural GENERAL NOTIONS. I I order in things, after having step by step, in the giiise of a con- quering power, invaded all the domains of human knowledge, would at length penetrate the region of social facts. To the French school of Physiocrats falls the distinction of having first recognized and proclaimed the existence of this natural govern- ment of things ; thence, in truth, is derived the name of their school, from two Greek words which mean " government of nature." For this reason they might be said to have earned the title of founders of economic science, had they not been too greatly eclipsed by the glory of Adam Smith. " Human society," said Quesnay, " is a necessary fact, governed by providential laws. The mission of government is not to make laws, but to declare and proclaim natural laws, and make their observance sure." In the present century, especially, following in the wake of Auguste Comte and Herbert Spencer, nearly all the great schools, positivist, evolutionist, historical, even socialistic, have teemed with opinions of this character; all of them, in greater or less degree, regard human societies as organisms, which are born and developed according to laws precisely analogous with those bio- logical laws which govern the evolution of all living creatures. Still, it cannot yet be said that this notion of natural laws in economics is unanimously accepted. It conflicts, in fact, with no small difficulty ; economic facts are human acts, and therefore voluntary acts, and as being such can scarcely be conceived as falling under the rule of inevitable laws. However, there is no insurmountable contradiction in the case. If an inevitable contradiction is customarily found (or supposed) to exist between the idea of liberty and the idea of natural law, that arises from our not understanding the latter expression in its real sense : natural law is represented under the shape of civil law or penal law ; that is to say, as a power holding a sword in its hand, which insists on being obeyed, willy nilly. Nothing could be more false than this conception. Natural law is only the expression of a constant relation which has been established between certain phenomena, and in economics it is nothing but 12 PRIN'CIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. the expression of certain constant relations in the acts and pro- ceedings of men. Now statistics have frequendy shown the really surprising regu- larity in the recurrence of the most important acts of human life, such as marriage ; or of the most trivial, such as posting a letter without having addressed it. In economic facts, properly so called, this regularity is no less remarkable. The current of a river, which is usually determined by natural laws, is neither more constant nor more regular than the movement of a great commercial current, such as that of a railway hne, and the variations of traffic of the latter are surely easier to explain and to forecast than the changes of level of the former. For an explanation of this regularity which is so strange at first sight, it would be sufficient, to begin with, to consider how important a part is played in social facts by the involuntary and the unwitting ; for instance, the influence, or rather the tyranny, exercised over our daily conduct by habit^ imitation, and heredity, — those three factors which have the common attribute of being absolutely independent of our will (see M. Tarde's very inter- esting book Les lois de V imitation). But, in truth, it is not even necessary for an explanation of this phenomenon to restrict the field of human liberty. The regularity of economic and social facts is not opposed to liberty ; on the contrary, it is the consequence of this liberty when enlightened and deliberate. Imagine a world in which all men were absolutely free, absolutely wise ; the march of events therein would be cer- tainly far more regular even than it is with us. If, on the other hand, all men were mad, then, but then only, would disorder and chaos be the law of this world, and economic facts would be beyond the pale of all rational prediction. Kant, the metaphysician of free will, fully admits, however, the existence of natural laws in the social sciences. " In whatever way free will may be represented in metaphysics, its manifestations are in human actions determined, like every other phenomenon, by general laws of nature. History, which deals with the recital GENERAL NOTIONS. 13 of these manifestations, however deeply their causes be hidden, does not abandon one hope ; viz., that in observing the play of free will on a large scale it may discover therein a regular movement. . . . Thus marriages, births, and deaths do not seem to be subject to any rule which would admit of the calculation of their number beforehand ; yet the yearly tables drawn up in some great countries testify that in this matter as close obedience is paid to constant laws as is paid by the variations in the atmosphere, the growth of plants, the course of rivers, and the remainder of the economy of nature. Individuals, nay, whole peoples, do not in the least imagine that though following each of them their own bent and often engaging in strife with one another, they are still unconsciously obeying, just as the bees and the beavers, the design of nature which is unknown to them, and are contributing to an evolution, which, even could they be aware of it, would be of little matter to them." — Kant, Idea of an Universal History. Edition Hartenstein, IV, 143. Prediction, in fact, is the criterion by which we recognize the existence of natural laws, and consequently, too, the character of a true science. If, indeed, facts are linked together in a certain order, like a well-managed procession in which each member keeps its place and observes its distances, if there is, to use a current phrase, a "march " of events, it should always be possible, one fact being given, to foresee what should follow or accompany it. In some sciences, on account of their simplicity, this power of prediction is so extensively exercised that it stupefies the vulgar and assumes the shape of actual prophecy ; for instance, the predictions of astronomy. In the physical and natural sciences prediction rarely cleaves the future, but yet in more modest measure it enables the chemist, combining two substances in a crucible, to say what body will result from this combination and what its properties will be ; and by its aid the geologist can state the various strata that will be met with in the piercing of a tunnel or the sinking of a mine -shaft. The naturahst who sees for the first time an unknown animal, even before dissecting, can tell in 14 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. advance, from certain external signs, what organs will meet his scalpel, and their order of presentation. Is the economist capable of availing himself of a similar faculty of prediction, thanks to his scientific pretensions ? He is, undoubtedly. Of two objects of the same quality but of unequal value, he can foretell that the buyer will choose the less dear ; or if that instance be too trivial, he can nowadays, from various signs, such as the rate of exchange, which is neither more nor less certain than the warnings given to the sailor by the barometer, observe and foresee the approach of commercial crises. We shall have occasion to see other instances. If into any country an inferior money be introduced, say paper money, the speedy disappearance of the good money can be safely pre- dicted (see Gresham's Law). By the simple sight of the rate of exchange one can judge of the financial and commercial condi- tion of a country (see Exchange). Stanley Jevons has even es- sayed to prove that there is a ten-yearly cycle in commercial crises parallel to that shown by astronomical phenomena, to which his daring theory strove to relate them (see Crises). We must point out that even those who are the most vehement in refusing to economists the possibility of prediction in economic questions, do not fail, however, to employ it themselves in their ordinary course of life and in the management of their daily busi- ness. The financier who buys a share in the Suez Canal or in a railway foresees the continuity and the progressive increase of a particular traffic in a fixed direction, and his purchase of the share at a high rate testifies, whether he will or no, to his firm confi- dence in the regularity of one economic law. Every one who speculates — and who is there who does not speculate? — resorts to prediction after his own fashion ; this, no doubt, is too often exer- cised in a haphazard manner, but it might be used scientifically : taking it al^ in all, the speculator, as far as he is concerned, con- siders prediction to be perfectly rational. True enough, in this sphere forecasts are, as is sometimes said, only approximate ones, and cannot be expected to reach any GENERAL NOTIONS. 15 mathematical precision. But it would be utterly absurd to con- clude that, because exact prediction is not possible, therefore there are no laws at all ! No one can hold that wind, rain, hail, or storms are the result of chance, much less of human will. They are certainly ruled by natural laws. Yet forecasts are no more exact in this branch than they are in economics, and a commercial crisis can be more safely predicted than can a cyclone. If our predictions in political economy are always uncertain and do not look far in advance, the reason of this must be sought, not at all in the non-existence of economic laws or in a sup- posed want of order in events, but purely in our ignorance of causes, just as m meteorology. Whatever may be one's opinion as to free will, it is not doubtful, as John Stuart Mill says, " That given the motives which are present to an individual's mmd, and likewise the character and disposition of the individual, — if we knew the person thoroughly and knew all the inducements which are acting upon him, — we could foretell his conduct and the man- ner in which he will act." — Logic, VI, ii, sect. 2, page 422. Such motives will never be known to us exactly. Luckily, in the treatment of economic facts, we have not to forecast the con- duct of any one individual considered by himself; all that con- cerns us is the conduct of men viewed en tnasse ; we have only to deal with averages, and therefore have no need of that exactness which is indispensable to the astronomer or the physicist. IV. THE FOUR ECONOMIC SCHOOLS 1 The science of Political Economy is divided into numerous schools (into almost as many as philosophy), which is an incon- testable sign of inferiority. It is no real consolation to say that the science has existed for scarcely more than a century, and that age will remedy this defect. Other sciences which are no older, 1 In an Address given at Geneva in March, 1890, our author classifies the schools as those of Liberty, Authority, Equality, and Solidarity, respectively; and he ranks himself with the last. — J. B. 1 6 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. some, indeed, which are younger, have already succeeded in de- veloping a collection of principles sound enough to gain the unan- imous adhesion of all their students. As this is not the case with economics, many keen intellects refuse to grant it the title of " science," or at any rate declare that such a title is a premature one. Yet it is well to remark that the various schools differ from one another far less about the explanation of economic phenomena than about the mode of studying them, the way of judging them, and the practical consequences that can be deduced. The pos- sibility of a common understanding is not remote when the ques- tion is, for example, the discovery of the causes of the inequality of wealth; but when the subject for discussion is to determine whether this inequality of conditions is a good thing in itself, and especially whether any attempt at modification is necessary, then it is that divergences of opinion become marked. They arise, then, from the moral and political character of this science, and probably will never disappear, though there is reason to hope that on certain essential principles some agreement will be arrived at. Section i. The Liberal School. The first of these schools is what is called classical on account of its having appeared first, and having long reigned without a rival ; or liberal, in virtue of the famous formula which is its motto. But is it really a school ? Its partisans reply to such a question with some hauteur, and claim to represent the science itself; they assume, and for the most part receive, even from their opponents, the name of eco?wmists, and nothing more. The latter, however, sometimes term it, not without a touch of irony, the orthodox, or individualist, school. Its doctrine is very simple, and may be summed up as follows : — Human societies are governed by natural laws which we could not alter one Jot, even if we wished, since they are not of our making. Moreover, we have not the least interest in modifying them, even if we could ; for they are good, or, at any rate, the best possible. (" The laws which govern capital, wages, and the dis- GENERAL NOTIONS, 17 tribution of wealth are as good as they are inevitable. They bring about the gradual elevation of the level of humanity." — Leroy- Be.\ulieu, Precis d'economie politique.) The part of the econo- mist is confined to discovering the action of these natural laws ; and It is for men and governments to strive to regulate their conduct according to them. These laws are in nowise opposed to human Hberty; on the contrary, they are the expression of relations which are spontane- ously established between men living in society, wherever these men are left to themselves, and are free to act according to their interests. Thus, between these individual interests which are apparently antagonistic a harmony is established, which exactly represents the natural order of things, and is far superior to any artificial combination which could be imagined. The part of the legislator, if he wishes to insure social order and progress, is confined, then, to developing these individual initiatives as far as possible, to doing away with whatever might interfere with them, and to prevent individuals from harboring ill will, or being biassed one against the other. Therefore the inter- vention of the powers that be ought to be reduced to that minimum which is indispensable to the security of each and of all ; in a word, to laisser faire. " We assert that these natural laws govern the production and distribution of wealth in the manner which is the most useful ; i.e. the most conformable to the general good of the human species. Observation of them, together with the smoothing away of the natural obstacles which impede their action, and especially the prevention of any artificial obstacles, is suffi- cient to render the condition of man as good as is consistent with the state of advancement of his acquirements and his industries. Our gospel, therefore, is summed up in these four words, * Laisser faire, laisser passer.' " — De Molinari, Les lois naturelles. The whole of Bastiat's famous work, the Harmonies econo- miqiies, is nothing but the development of these ideas. This conception assuredly lacks neither simplicity nor grandeur. Whatever destiny be in store for it, it will at least have the merit l8 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. of having assisted to establish the science of poUtical economy ; and, if some day other doctrines take its place, it will none the less be the foundation upon which they are built. The most serious complaint that can be made against this body of teaching is a very marked tendency to opti7nis??i, which ap- pears to be inspired far less by a truly scientific spirit than by a desire to justify the existing order of things. Undoubtedly, from a consideration of the economic organization of a society and of the institutions which are its groundwork, the conclusion may be drawn that they are beneficial, at any rate in certain aspects ; for the very fact of their existence and duration shows well enough that they have a value which is at least relative; further, that they are natural is a just conclusion to make, for they are evidently determined by the series of previous states which produced them. But in nowise can it be inferred that they are the best possible ; that conclusion is altogether illogical. Auguste Comte, years ago, protested in the name of science against " this systematic tendency to optimism which is clearly theological in origin" {Cours de philosophie positive^ 48^ legon). But this doctrine cannot even offer the excuse that it agrees with theology, as Comte supposes ; for Christian theology is less optimistic than anything else. On the contrary, in its eyes, the actual order of things and all the manifestations of human liberty are irretrievably vitiated by the Fall. Nor is it any more legitimate to conclude that because natural laws are permanent and immutable, the existing economic facts and institutions should also possess this character of permanence and immutability. That, too, is a sophism, not to say word-jug- glery. If, on the other hand, as contemporary science shows a tendency to believe, the natural law, par excellence, is that of evolution, then it would be necessary to say that natural laws, far from excluding the idea of change, always presuppose it. When the Socialists, for instance, maintain that the wages system is bound to disappear, because, just as it has succeeded to serfdom and slavery, so it too will be replaced in turn by co-operation or GENERAL NOTIONS. 1 9 some other at present not named state, their line of argument can no doubt be criticised ; but it cannot be stigmatized as con- tradicting natural laws, since these very laws cause the same plant to produce in succession, first seed, then flower, then fruit. Not only can economic facts and institutions suff"er change, but also our will is by no means powerless in bringing about these alterations. Indeed, this will is every day and in the most effica- cious manner exercised on physical facts for their modification according to our needs, and this reasoned human action on natural phenomena is not in the slightest incompatible with the idea of natural law ; on the contrary, it is closely bound up with it. As M. Espinas wittily remarks in his Societes animales, " If human activity was incompatible with the order of things, the act of boiling an &g% would have to be regarded as a miracle." If, in truth, the idea of law were non-existent, if there were no bond between phenomena, if a cause might produce a certain effect, or might not ; in a word, if chance were the ruler of the world, man would be powerless to do aught, or to attain any end what- ever ; for while modifying such and such a fact he would never know what the result was to be, and his acts would be those of a blind man. Man erects lightning conductors to protect his build- ings because he believes in a natural law, viz. that metallic points exert a certain influence on electricity ; but, if electricity followed at random any track, it is clear that Franklin's invention would be useless. Besides, the mere opening of the eyes enables us to perceive at once man's marvellous power of modifying natural phenomena. Some, no doubt, from their immensity or their distance, obtain immunity from all acts of ours, — say, astronomical, or geological, or even meteorological phenomena : then we have but to submit to them in silence, and our power of prediction does not enable us to escape from a shock from a comet or from an earthquake ; but how many other domains are there in which our knowledge is almost supreme ! Most of the compounds of inorganic chemistr}' (the most important ones, by the way) have been made by the 20 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. man of science in his laboratory. On seeing the cattle-breeder in his stalls, the horticulturist in his gardens, ceaselessly modifying animal or vegetable forms and creating new races, it seems as if animate Nature herself submitted to a process of kneading like inert matter. Even atmospheric phenomena do not entirely escape from the power of human industry ; the latter, indeed, makes bold to assert that by fitting clearances, or by new plantations, it will modify the government of the winds and the waters, and, repeating the miracle of the prophet Elisha, will, whenever it wishes, bring down from heaven the rain and the dew. In much greater measure, our activity can be exercised on eco- nomic facts, precisely because they are acts done by man, and we have immediate hold over them. Even the teachings of the deter- minist school, those who deny free will (and surely the liberal school are not among such) recognize that man has the power of modifying the order of things in which he lives. They only make this reservation : that every act of man is itself predeter7nined by certain causes; but that is a question in pure metaphysics into which we have not to enter in this place. Without doubt, here as in the sphere of physical phenomena, this action of ours is restricted within certain limits, which science tries to mark out, and which all men, whether acting individually by means of private enterprise, or acting collectively under legislative regulation, should make it in- cumbent upon themselves to respect. Here we might quote Bacon's old adage, " Naturae non imperatur nisi parendo " ; for the modifi- cation of economic facts, economic laws must be known and con- formed to. Alchemy strove to turn lead into gold ; chemistry has abandoned that useless quest, having found that these two bodies are simple elements, or at least irreducible ones ; but it has not renounced the attempt of converting charcoal into diamond, for in this case it has established the presence of one single body in two different states. The Utopian uselessly tortures nature to ask and obtain what it cannot give him ; the man of science asks only for what he knows to be possible. But the sphere of this term " possible " is far wider than the classical school imagines. GENERAL NOTIONS. 21 Section 2. The Socialist School. The socialist school is as old as the classical school ; older, we may even say, for there were socialists long before there was any political economy. As the doctrines of this school are especially critical in nature, they are far harder to formulate than those of the preceding school. Still they may be summed up as follows, at any rate, in their essential features. The various socialist schools hold that the organization of modern societies is tainted by certain essential vices, and is there- fore destined to disappear at a more or less near future. In their eyes, this organization is not in the least a natural product of liberty, but is the result of a long series of acts of injustice and spoliation which have been in a measure hallowed by written laws. Their special objects of attack are private property and free competition, and their aim is to prove that the action of these two great springs, which set in motion the whole social organism, tends to sacrifice social to private interest, and to enable a few privi- leged persons to live at the expense of the huge body of the disinherited. They wait, then, for a new order of things, in which private property, if not completely abolished, will at any rate be reduced to the minimum which is compatible with the just requirements of hum.an personality, and- in which personal interest will no longer be the sole motor power, and will be subordinated to the collec- tive welfare. As to the manner in which this future society is to be brought about, the various schools have numerous divergent theories. Some, who might be called idealists^ but who are most usually termed Utopians^ and whose doctrines are nowadays some- what, perhaps too much, discredited, strive to build up this future society like a new house, with certain a priori principles of justice as foundation and as scale. Others, who proudly assume the title of scientific socialism, assert that this future society will sua sp07ite issue forth from present society, like a butterfly from its chrysalis. In the most interesting and original portion of their thesis they i2 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. labor to prove that this society of the future is now reposing, in the state of an embryo, in the womb of our present-day societies, which are already ripe for such a birth. It is sometimes care- lessly said that this school contests the existence of natural laws ; that is perfectly incorrect. On the contrary, it is irreconcilably determinist ; only, while for the liberal school the term " natural law " implies the idea of stability and immutabiUty, to the socialist school it presents the idea of unlimited change and transformation. Instead of regarding human societies as Bastiat regarded the solar system, as turning round a fixed point and suspended in an eternal and changeless equilibrium, it pictures them in the shape of a plant or an animal, which from birth to death is undergoing cease- less transformations. We must confess that this is exactly the standpoint of contemporary science. Even the solar systems undergo change and transformation. In general, save for a few exceptions, it considers the Revolution to be indispensable for the substitution of the new order in place of the present. Coming from evolutionists, this manner of looking at things is at first sight rather astounding ; they attempt to justify it by noting that the process of evolution is often accomplished by means of crises ; i.e. by the brusque and even violent passage from one state to another. They instance the chrysalis, which, before becoming butterfly, must tear away its cocoon ; or the chicken, which, to leave the egg, must break the shell with its beak. All these schools (save one alone, the anarchist school, which, on the contrary, is violently individualist) are naturally disposed to extend as far as possible the functions of the collective powers, represented by the State or by the municipalities, since their aim is to transform into public agencies all that which to-day springs from private enterprise. It is only, however, as a transition step that socialism asks for the extension of the functions of the State. For it professes the greatest contempt for the State as it is to-day, the bourgeois State, as it terms it, which looks after its interests and carries on its enterprises by the same methods as are used by GENERAL NOTIONS. 23 individuals. In its plans for reorganizing future society, this school avoids even pronouncing the word "state," and prefers to use the term "society." The State, in the socialist plan, is to lose all political character, so as to become purely economic ; it is to become something analogous to the administrative council of a huge co-operative society, embracing the entire country. It is on this point that true socialism can be distinguished from State socialism. At this stage we cannot gauge the value of the criticisms directed by the sociaUst school against the existing order of things ; we shall come across them once more in the course of our further exposition. Suffice it to say here that they appear to contain a somewhat large portion of truth. It is especially from the critical point of view that contemporary socialism has produced some remarkable works ; notably, those of Proudhon in France, and those of Karl Marx in Germany. But it is from the positive, or, if it is preferred, the constructive point of view, that the weak side of this school is discoverable ; and we must observe that its most distinguished leaders, especially those whose names have been just mentioned, have prudently avoided any entrance into that field. The detailed exposition of the socialist ideal may, however, be seen in Schaffle's Quintes- senz des Socialistnus (a German book, which has been trans- lated into French and into English), in Gronlund's Co-operative Commoriwealth, and in Bellamy's very successful novel. Looking Backward. In fact, whatever be the imperfections, or even dan- gers, of personal interest, and the desire to grow rich, as the motor power of the economic mechanism, it is not easy to see by what other means men can be made to stir. There are only two possible means, — compulsion and love. Now love, or altruism, as it is called in opposition to egoism, would indeed be the true solution, and we must hope for its realization in the future. But the so- cialists, who are relying on such a motor force at this time of day, are certainly showing their possession of an optimism which is as stubborn in its own way as that for which we were just now 24 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. blaming the economists. Before man makes up his mind to work purely out of love for his neighbor, a more radical transformation would be necessary than could be brought about by any social revolution. Man would have to procure a new heart. There is, therefore, reason to fear that, the motor spring of love failing them, the socialists will be obliged to fall back upon com- pulsion ; now, besides the circumstance that the loss of liberty would be too high a price to pay for the general welfare, even at this price it is doubtful whether the desired result could be attained. For, in order that the production of wealth shall be abundant, the employment of individual energy is always requi- site, and experience shows that a regime of compulsion forbids the full exercise of such energies. Further, many socialists be- lieve that they will be able to dispense with individual initiative, and have recourse, instead, to the action of collective bodies, the State, municipalities, powerfully organized corporations, and so forth ; but this hope is based on no sounder foundation than that mentioned above. For every-day experience teaches us that asso- ciations, great or small, are worth not a jot more than the indi- viduals of whom they are composed. Consequently, every system which will tend to reduce i?idividual energy will not stand a great chance of gaining anything especially advantageous from collec- tive enterprises, how-ever ingeniously they may otherwise be organ- ized. Section 3. The Catholic or Christian School. Although the very epithet which is used as the distinguishing mark of this school appears to put it outside the pale of scientific classification, yet in some countries it has obtained too great a development, and even from the purely economic standpoint (our only object of study here) it presents too characteristic features for us to pass it by in silence. The Catholic school, like the classical school, firmly believes in the existence of natural laws, called by it providential laws, which govern social as well as physical facts. But it believes that GENERAL NOTIONS. 25 the working of these providential laws may be seriously deranged by the action of human liberty, and that this indeed has actually come to pass by man's own fault ; the world is not what it was destined to be, what God would have wished it to be. We must obser\'e that Fourier's theory^ also consisted of the asseveration that for man there is " a plan of God " the secret of which has been lost through man's own fault, but which he must try and rediscover. The Catholic school differs from the liberal school in not being in the least optimistic ; it regards the social order of things neither as good, nor even as naturally tending towards the best ; above all, it does not trust to latsserfaire for the re- estab- lishment of harmony and the confirmation of progress ; for it is in this very liberty, or rather in liberaHsm, that it discovers the real cause of social disorganization. To take its programme : it hopes to re-establish social concord by the influence of a triple authority, that of the father in the family, of the employer in the workshop, and of the Church in the State, these several "social authorities," of course, being boundto carry out reciprocal duties. It is not hostile to the interference of the State, which, to quote ,the words of Pope Leo XIII., " is, after the Church, God's minister for good." The vehemence of the criticisms made against the present organization of society by the Catholic school, together with its appeal to State interference in certain cases, has caused economists of the liberal school to call it Christian socialism. Against this imputation it vigorously protests, and in truth, except for certain points of view which are common to them, it differs from the socialist school toto orhe. Firstly, in that it has no intention of abolishing the fundamental institutions of social affairs as they are, such as property, inheri- tance, the wages system, etc. ; but proposes, on the contrary, to restore, that is to say, to strengthen them. iThe features of Fourier's system are described in detail by Professor Gide in his introduction to the volume Charles Fourier, (Euvres Choisies {Peiite Bibliotheque Economique, Guillaumin, 1890). — J. 13. 26 PRINXIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. Secondly, in that it disbelieves in evolution and in the indefi- nite progress of the human species, and seeks its ideal far less in the future than in a return to some of the institutions of the past, for instance, to the family stock, to rural life, and to pro- fessional corporations of employers and workmen acting together. The term '' family stock " {/ami7/e souche) is used by the school of Le Play to designate the family strongly bound together and stable as in older days, so as to form a small permanent society existing within society at large. This is in opposition to the un- stable and constantly scattered family which is the characteristic feature of modern societies. Le Play's school is a branch of the CathoHc school,^ which, how- ever, is differentiated from the latter, and therefore becomes more approximated to the liberal school, by a stronger tendency to lay action as opposed to Church interference, and by a narrower limi- tation of the sphere of State interference. Brushing aside all controversy that might trench on political or religious ground, the strongest objection that could be made to this body of doctrine taught by the Catholic school was long ago formulated by John Stuart Mill, when he asserted that there was no example of any class whatever, when in possession of power, having exercised that power for the benefit of the other classes of the community. It is greatly to be feared that, if ever the task of solving the social problem were entrusted solely to the ruling classes as employers, the mournful fact animadverted on by Jolin Stuart Mill would receive but one confirmation the more. There is also a Christian (but not Catholic) socialism which is taking a more prominent place in Protestant countries, both in England and in the United States.- Though denouncing the 1 See the article of Mr. II. Iliggs "Frederic Le Play" in ihc Harvard Quarterly yournal of Economics, July, 1890. — J. B. 2 A sign of its presence in England is the formation of the " Christian Social Union " and the publication of its organ, the Economic Revie-v. The leading members and writers are adherents of the High Church party in the English Church. — J. B. GENERAL NOTIONS. 2/ iniquities of the existing social order with no less severity than the Cathohc school, and likewise waiting for "a. land in which justice dwells," it is deeply divided from the Catholic school by its programme. For the conservation of social peace or concord it relies less on the authority of a few " classes " than in the increas- ing solidarity of all classes, and co-operative institutions appear to it to be the best means for bringing about such a solidarity. Thus, though it does not in a general way refuse all State inter- ference, still it is jealous to preserve all individual energy. Sectiox 4. The Historical or Realist School. The school which was at first called " historical," or that of the " socialists of the chair " {Katheder socialisteti), but which more readily receives the name of the realist school, sprang from a reaction against the classical school, as regards both its method and its tendency. It first saw the light in Germany about forty years ago, and professors of the German universities are still among the number of its leaders. By now, however, it has drawn into its fold many professors of political economy of all countries save France. (Reference may be made to the author's article " The Economical Schools in Prance " in the New York Political Science Quarterly, December, 1890.) The commencement of this school is usually dated by the publication, in 1854, of Roscher's Treatise of Political Economy. It was in Germany, too, that the historical school of Law first arose under the guidance of Savigny. As to its method, the realist school absolutely rejects the deduc- tive method, which is based on a priori reasoning, on abstractions, and on hypotheses, and asserts that the only way of arriving at truth is by the patient observation of facts. It is to history that the realist school turns for the study of social and economic facts ; for history alone, by teaching us how economic and social institutions have been formed and are being transformed, can enlighten us as to their real character. Now social institutions, when studied from 'this hisfdricat stand- 28 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. point, are seen to be exceedingly changeable, varying, indeed, from nation to nation, and ceaselessly undergoing mutations in the very midst of any one individual people. In this manner the historical school claims to blow to the winds that double character of universality and of permanence which the classical school used to attribute to economic phenomena and used to gild with the name of natural laws. We must therefore cease to look for any general laws which regulate man as an abstract being, but must rather seek for the historical laws that govern the relations of men living in a specified society. Hence the name sometimes bestowed on this school, that of the "national-politico-economical" school. Whilst the classical school regards landed property and the wages system as definitive institutions which arise from necessary and general causes, the historical school merely looks on them as simple "historical categories," which spring from diverse causes and assume very variable forms according to the country and to the age. As regards its tendencies, this realistic school altogether rejects the principle of laisser faire ; in its opinion economic science has a practical aim to reach ; when a social science is in question, it thinks that the old distinctions between an "art" and a "science" are out of duty, and in this manner resorts to the conception enter- tained by the earliest economists (see page 2). It holds that we can only hope to modify economic institutions in the direction pointed to us by history, and that therefore the science includes the art in the same manner as the past contains the future. " What is, what will be, what ought to be," are to this school inseparable terms. Precisely because of the little weight it allows to the notion of natural law, it attaches a proportionately greater importance to the positive laws emanating from the legislator, and beholds in them one of the most important factors of social evolution. To quote M. De T>aveleye {Elements d'econo7?iie politique^ page 17), "The laws with which political economy is concerned are not the laws of nature ; they are those laid down by the legislator. The former elude the will of man ; the latter proceed from it." Hence it is led to considerably extend the functions of the State, GENERAL NOTIONS. 29 and on this point does not in the least share the antipathy or the distrust felt by the Uberal school. This tendency has earned for the new school, or at least a section of it, the name of State Socialists. This school has of late greatly influenced not only men's thoughts, but likewise legislation. Most of the laws promulgated during the last twenty years, which are known as "labor legislation," as well as the powerful movement in favor of the international regulation of labor, are in large measure its work. It has certainly rendered great service to the science by broad- ening the narrow, factitious, studiedly simple, and vexatiously optimistic point of view at which the classical school has always remained stationed. It has conferred on it a new life by reju- venating its somewhat empty theories with new materials drawn from history, the comparison of laws, and statistics. This school has caused poHtical economy to quit that systematic abstention in which it was wont to enclose itself; and to the question men have so long been propounding, "What is to be done?" it has sought another reply than a sterile laisser faire. As regards the delicate matter of State interference, we thor- oughly agree with the new school in recognizing an historical fact in the incessant development of State functions, which, perhaps, is precisely one of those natural laws whose very existence is disputed by the school in question. Like it, too, we believe that the State's mission is to develop more and more the social solidarity (or the cohesion of society) of which it is the living image, even though for the accompHshment of this end it may have to exercise its authority and impose according to its discretion sacrifices on some for the benefit of others. Too often, alas, the State has shown itself unfit for the right exercise of this high social function ; for in the past it has only served as an instrument in the interest of one class, and indeed, in the democratic governments of to-day, for the benefit of one party. Such a procedure has thus given some weight to the arguments of the hberal school. However, the education of States is gradually progressing ; more rapidly, indeed, than that of individuals, who are ceaselessly carried off by death. 30 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. There is, therefore, reason to hope that when the State has been founded on more scientific bases, when poHtical economy aids it in marking out its road, and when practical questions take the place of sterile political questions, on that day the State will be able to exercise in economics a more rational and efficacious influence than it has hitherto done. It is with regard to its method that this new school is the most vulnerable and open to criticism. The result of its desire to be realistic and descriptive is, that it appears to have lost sight of the true character of the science, which, in spite of all endeavors, must remain in the nature of an abstraction, Chevreul, the French scientist, who recently died, having passed the age of a hundred years, used to say, " Every fact is an abstrac- tion." ^ Though this dictum seems a strange one at the first glance, yet it is easily understood if we only consider that what we call a fact is previously something which has had to be separated out of a host of other connected facts, and for the observation of which abstraction has had to be made of many other things. Thus, in scoffing at the procedure and' the methods of the de- ductive school, the new school exhibits much affectation and some ingratitude ; for, in fine, it still lives and moves in the categories which were laid down by the old school. It has not exactly re- made the science ; it has merely informed it with a new spirit. By applying its attention to the observation of facts and the varia- tions shown in various nations and at various times, its tendency is to fall into erudition, and to lose sight of the general conditions which everywhere determine economic phenomena. If it were necessary to renounce any attempt at discovering permanent re- lations and laws under the changing manifestations of phenomena, we should be obliged definitely to abandon our attempts to form a science of political economy ; however dangerous to the science rash hypotheses might be, they would be infinitely less serious than such a confession of weakness. ^ Or, as has been said by Professor Edward Caird, ' There is only One Fact, and every part of it taken separately is an abstraction.' — J. B. BOOK I. WEALTH AND VALUE. -•O^ CHAPTER I. WEALTH. I. The Desire for Wealth. To be rich, in the popular sense of the term, is for a man to have the means of obtaining for himself good food, good clothes, good housing, and careful nursing if he falls ill ; to be able to keep sufficiently warm in winter and agreeably cool in summer, to have easy means of access and of transit to wherever he wishes to go, and to partake of all the pleasures offered by civilized Hfe to those who can profit by them. It is, too, to be exempt from the necessity of working for a livelihood, to be free to do as he pleases, and to follow his tastes and his fancy. Finally, it is to be released from all anxiety as to his future or that of his children. Wealth considered from this point of view depends on the quan- tity of goods that a man possesses, and is synonymous with abun- dance. But the word "wealth" presupposes something more than this ; it indicates a state of superiority, and consequently implies ine- quality of conditions. It points out the privileged position of a man by which he is enabled to command the labor of a multitude of his fellow-creatures, or what comes to the same thing, to dis- pose of the products of their labor. ''Riches is power," said Hobbes, and such, in truth, is the etymological meaning of the 31 32 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. word {Reich, empire, power). Considered from this point of "view wealth is a purely relative state, and depends far less on the quantity of goods possessed by a man than on that possessed by his felloius. If they have less than he has, he is rich ; if they have as much as he has, he is not rich. It is clear that if every one was rich, there would be no more rich men. It is not surprising, then, that from time immemorial wealth has always been ardently coveted by men ; although the opinion is permissible that this desire, now raised to the rank of a passion, is beginning to assume a somewhat excessive development in certain societies, especially in those in which we live ; although it may be salutary for a more austere system of morality to strive, hitherto without much success, to moderate so exaggerated a passion, yet we have no hesitation in declaring that this desire is natural and even legitimate. To proceed : a distinction must be drawn between the motives which incite man to seek wealth ; they are of two different kinds, and correspond to the two aspects under which the idea of wealth is presented. Men seek wealth, both to satisfy their wants and to mark themselves off from their fellows ; they are urged in the former direction by the desire for well-being, in the latter by the desire for inequality. The legitimacy of the first of these motives can be the more easily established. Man has the right, and even is bound by the duty of trying, to satisfy all those wants which lead to the preser- vation and development of his being in the broadest sense of these words. What may be blamable in the matter is not so much the desire for wealth as the means employed for its obtainal, and especially the use that is made of it. If wealth in this world were always the result of personal labor, if it were always directed towards the greatest good of man, physical, intellectual, and moral, its effects would be ever beneficial, never baneful ; there would never be too much of it ; nay, there would never be enough. Unhappily, it is far too certain that in the whole world, and even in our modern societies, which are so proud of their knowledge WEALTH AND VALUE. 33 and so vain of their luxury, the vast majority of men do not pos- sess even that minimum of wealth which constitutes daily bread, far less that amount of comfort the absence of which always lowers human dignity. The unequal distribution of wealth may deceive us on this point ; but if a division could be made, the mis- erable share which would fall to each would dismay the obser\'er. We should then be thankful that we are rather richer than our fathers, and make bold to hope that our children may be much richer than we are. If the day comes, as we must hope, when wealth will be so increased as to amply provide for the material wants of all, then it will be time to call a halt, and humanity at large will henceforward be able to devote its strength and its time to the pursuit of goods of a more noble kind. The legitimacy of the second motive seems to be more dis- putable, and it is fair to hold that the desire for inequality is not a beneficent feeling. Yet it hardly appears that it could be sup- pressed or even much reduced without gravely injuring civilization ; probably without it the source of wealth would soon be dried up. Indeed, for the multiplication of wealth we must not trust only to the former of these two motives, the desire for well-being ; this feeling is not innate in man's breast, as we are too apt to suppose — witness those primitive societies which live in eternal poverty without ever seeking to emerge therefrom. It is the desire for inequality, or, if you will, what comes exacdy to the same thing, the desire to rise above the common level, which is the cease- less goad of man's natural idleness. Mr. Mallock, an English author, has devoted a whole volume, Social Equality, to the development of this idea, which he de- fines, perhaps not without some exaggeration, in the following for- mula : " All productive labor that rises above the lowest, is always motived by the desire for social inequality." — Social Equality, pages 35, 36. 34 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. II. The Wants of Man. There is no Hving being that has not certain wants, were it only that of food, which must be satisfied for the creature to hve and attain its ends. The higher we go in the scale of life, the more complicated and sensitive is the organism, and the more complex and multiple do the wants become ; for the being which occupies the summit of the hierarchy, for man, they are legion. Could we come to know a being superior to man, we should certainly dis- cover that he possessed an infinitude of wants of which we in this world can form no idea whatever. If the progression of wants is so marked on turning from lower to higher beings, it is no less striking on passing up from savage to civilized man. Had we to point out the most characteristic feature of that social state which is denoted by the somewhat in- definite term, civilization, the most noteworthy, perhaps, would be the multiplicity of wants. The art of civilizing a people consists in implanting in it new wants ; this is proved by the example of savage communities. The wants of humanity are like those of a child. The child, at birth, needs nothing except a litde milk and a warm covering ; but little by little he comes to require more varied food, more com- plicated garments, and, moreover, toys ; each year arises some new want, some new desire. We, to-day, are sensible of a thousand wants which were unknown to our grandfathers, relating to com- fort, hygiene, cleanliness, education, travel, social intercourse; and it is certain that our grandchildren will have further needs. The more we see, the more we learn, the more our curiosity awakens, and the more, too, do our desires increase and multiply. Each in- vention, each idea that is born into the world, engenders a whole generation of new wants. Doubtless, some of the number do not continue, and after having lasted for a few generations, or perhaps only for a few days, sink like dead leaves falling from the tree ; maybe the very caprice that gave them birth abandons them, as with the ephemeral creations of fashion ; maybe a new and con- WEALTH AND VALUE. 35 flicting want dethrones its predecessor. But in a general way, the number of wants which disappear far from balances the tale of those which arise, and just as with the generations of men we have a crowd which goes on multiplying from age to age. A school of moralists which dates from a very high antiquity, reckoning among its founders Diogenes with his tub, regards this progressive and indefinite multiplication of wants as a great evil, which political economy should apply itself to stop. But, for our part, we can see in the development of these wants nothing more than the normal development of human beings ; we think that an attempt to restrict the former would be to rob the latter, and that for the suppression of wants we should first of all have to suppress ideas. Without doubt, among these wants, which are ceaselessly spring- ing up among the generations of man, there are many which are frivolous or even harmful, and which far from favoring man's development only serve to retard it ; e.g. the taste for alcoholic liquors. But we must observe that for the efficacious eradication of any want whatever, the best means is to substitute another one. Indeed, to combat this very alcohoHsm, temperance societies have found that the best mode is to open establishments in which an attempt is made to accustom consumers to drink tea or coffee. There is reason to hope that in the future, when man's aims are more enhghtened and his desires are conformable only to his true nature, he will be able to follow them without arriere-pensee, and to strive to satisfy them without experiencing remorse. Even admitting that in certain cases contetitus sua sorte may be the motto of a philosopher, it should never be the watchword of a people. Woe to the races which are too easily satisfied, whose desires do not stretch beyond the narrow circle of the bounding horizon, and whose only requisites are a handful of ripe fruit for food and a nook in a wall where they may sleep shaded from the sun ! They will not be long in vanishing from an earth the capa- bilities of which they have not turned to advantage. The school of moralists, of which we have just spoken, starts 36 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. from the idea that the fewer wants a people has, the more time will it devote to intellectual speculations. But experience shows that in reality, the inverse order of things comes to pass, and that the fewer wants that races have, they are, in general, the more idle, ignorant, and swayed by the grossest appetites. It is easy to understand in virtue of what law the wants of man tend to develop in this wise. A want, still timid and ill-defined, arises first of all in the bosom of one single man, or in the hearts of a small group of men ; in those, only, who from their privileged position have already been able to amply satisfy the primary necessities of life, and who then turn their desires to a new hori- zon. But man, before all, is an imitative being ; by iviitaiion the want is immediately propagated. Like an epidemic it speeds from neighbor to neighbor. Every one feels it, or fancies he does, and applies himself to find some means for satisfying it. In pro- portion as the progress of industry allows the gratification of this satisfaction with greater ease and at less expense, the imitators continuously increase in numbers, and what was at first merely a caprice of luxury, reserved for those favored by fortune, soon penetrates the lowest strata of society. This subject is treated in an interesting way in M. Tarde's book Les Lois dc Vimita- tion, to which we have previously referred. From another side, in addition to having surface extension, the want also gains in depth. Man is not only an imitative being, he is also a being with habits ; desire, once felt and regularly satis- fied, gradually becomes fixed, takes root, and can no longer be torn away without a painful shock. As is so well expressed in popular language, it becomes second nature. At one time work- men wore neither linen nor foot-gear, had neither coffee nor tobacco, and ate neither meat nor wheaten bread; nowadays these wants have become so inveterate, that the workman who was unable to satisfy them and was suddenly reduced to the condition of his fellows in the times of Saint Louis or Good King Henry would certainly die. If we add that a habit which has been transmitted through a WEALTH AND VALUE. 3/ long series of generations is not slow in becoming fixed by means of heredity, and that the senses grow more subtle and more exact- ing, we shall be able to appreciate the despotic power acquired in the long run by a want which at its origin appeared to be the most futile or the most insignificant. It would be impossible to give a complete classification of the wants of man, but most of them can be ranked under these four heads: food, housing (including furniture, heating, and lighting), clothing, and orjiament. The first two are shared by man with the animals ; the last two are peculiar to him. The last of all, whatever may be said as to it, is as natural to man as the preceding are ; in fact, it might even be placed before clothing. As Theophile Gauthier has remarked, the Papuans, who go about stark naked and eat earthworms, hang colored berries from their necks and ears, and cover their bodies with tattoo-m.arks. Very nearly all the wealth to be found in all countries exists only to satisfy these material wants, particularly the first one, food ; and this holds even in societies which have reached a high pitch of prosperity and might be thoug^ht to have done with these first necessities of existence. [Let the quantity of nourishment necessary for each Frenchman be on the average ten pence a day — by no means an exaggerated amount ; this represents, for the whole of the French population, a yearly consumption of ;£"5 60,000,000 sterling, or probably more than half the entire production of France !] Yet education, the taste for the beautiful, the need of social intercourse or of travel- ling from place to place, the desire for always knowing the latest news, or for amusement, nay, for fighting, which is more fashion- able than ever, — all these call into existence a number of impor- tant articles of wealth in the shape of libraries, telegraphs, and telephones, carriages, tramways, omnibuses, newspapers, theatres, pictures, music, cannon,* and ironclads. 38 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMV. III. The Definition of Wealth. In the vocabulary of political economy, the word " wealth " has not altogether the same meaning as it has in popular speech. It does not exactly denote a ce?-tain state, a certain fortune, the fact of being rich, but it points out ce?-tain things, all those things the possession of which can obtain for us any satisfaction whatever, independently of any idea of quantity or of opulence. In this sense, a bit of bread, a pin, a farthing-piece, is from the economist's point of view as much wealth as is an estate, a diamond necklace, or a certificate of government stock. The first condition necessary for a thing to be termed wealth is that it should serve to satisfy some want or desire, in other words, that we should Judge it to be useful ; for utility is nothing but the correlation we establish between certain things and our wants. The judgment that we thus pass on the utility of things may chance to be gravely erroneous.^ Relics of more or less authentic- ity have been for many centuries, and to-day even in some coun- tries are still regarded as incomparable wealth, on account of certain virtues which are attributed to them. Many mineral waters and pharmaceutical preparations are much in request, though their healing properties are far from being proved. No matter ; whether useful or not, the mere fact of our judging them to be such con- stitutes them wealth. Generally, however, our judgment is not altogether blind, and our holding a thing to be useful arises from our having reason to believe that it really is so, from our discovery of some relation between its physical properties and some one of our wants. Bread is useful, partly because we have need of nourishment and partly because corn contains just those elements which are specially fit- ting for our food. The diamond is so higWy prized because it is in the nature of man, as well as in that of some animals, to expe- rience pleasure on looking at shining objects, and the diamond, in virtue of its powers of refraction, which excel those of any other ^ i.e, from the point of view of a riper wisdom. — J. B. WEALTH AND VALUE. 39 known substance, has just this property of shedding incomparable beams. It is for science to enUghten our judgments by instructing us as to the properties of bodies and the laws of nature. In this way, thanks to discovery and invention, the patrimony of humanity is increased every day by some new conquest : at one time, out of the clay which constitutes the mud of our streets, human industry makes the sparkling, solid, and at the same time light metal, which we call aluminium ; at another, it converts the foul waste of coal into colors which are more splendid than Tyrian purple. Yet the list of the things that we make use of is still exceedingly small, when compared with the immense number of those that we turn to no account. Of the 140,000 known species of the vegetable kingdom, less than 300 are used in farming ; of the millions of species reck- oned in the animal kingdom, there are scarcely 200 that we have turned to any service ; and with inorganic bodies the proportion is not more favorable (De Candolle, Origitie des pla7ites cultiveeSj page 366). But the list of our riches is lengthened every day, and there is every reason to believe that, were our knowledge per- fect, this vast world would not contain one blade of grass, one grain of sand, in which we had not been able to discover some measure of utility. However, to be able to reckon a thing in the number of our riches, it is not enough to know that it is useful ; it is also neces- sary that we should be able to utilize it. Knowledge is power, as the saying goes, but that is not always true ; our knowledge may remain in the purely speculative stage and not supply us with any practical means of reaching our ends. We know that the dia- mond is a crystal of carbon, but we have not yet succeeded in making diamonds out of coal ; we know that in China or in Ton- quin there are very rich coal mines, that on the African plateaux there are fertile and healthful tracts and probably gold mines, but for various reasons neither the ones nor the others are within our reach, and we cannot work them. They are, therefore, not wealth, at least for the present, any more than are the fertile tracts or 40 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. precious metals which the astronomer, by aid of telescope or spec- trum analysis, might discover on Mars or on Venus. Those primary conditions indicated above are beyond the reach of discussion ; but there are two others which have for long excited famous controversies among the learned, though fortunately they are merely questions as to words. The first question is, Does the definition of wealth necessarily imply the idea of materiality ? In the eyes of all the older econo- mists, and of the greater portion even now, this further condition appeared to be as indispensable as the two primary ones ; and it is certain that in current speech the word '' wealth " necessarily awakens the idea of a "thing*' {res) which is perceptible by our senses, can be touched, can be counted, can be weighed. We may certainly say that virtue, talent, and savoir /aire are wealth, but we shall be thought to speak in metaphor. However, it is our opinion, though not formed without some hesitation, that this condition is not indispensable, and that the metaphor is in fact the reality. Everything that is of a nature to answer to any desire felt by man and to obtain for him certain advantages, everything that in his eyes is worth the trouble of being paid for, either at the price of a personal effort or by the sacrifice of a sum of money, necessarily falls within the sphere of political economy and constitutes '' wealth." The opinion given by the physician is wealth by absolutely the same right as the morphia he administers to his patient ; the instruction that a professor gives his pupils is wealth in exactly the same way as the book he publishes and exhibits for sale at the bookseller's. If the barber's pole or shaving-dish which is exposed as his sign outside his door is regarded as wealth, surely we should consider as wealth of a like nature the name and the social standing of a business firm or a banking house. Besides, if this terminology be found to clash too violently with our inherited habits of speech, nothing prevents us from restrict- ing the term "wealth " to " things" properly so called, and to give the name of '' sennces " to every act of man which is able to pro- WEALTH AND VALUE. 4I cure any satisfaction for his fellows, in a direct manner and without intermediate incorporation in a material object. However, some very recent writers — e.g. Clark, Pantaleoni, and Mazzola — have remarked, not without considerable subtlety, that to give a man any gratification, he must be acted on by means of his senses, and consequently by the intermediation of some material object, — the sound-vibrations of the air in motion, the luminous vibrations of the ether. Thus the words of the lecturing professor would not reach us in a vacuum, nor would the facial expressions of the actor be visible in an unlit night. From this point of view, then, we may say that there cannot be any "non-material " wealth.^ We now come to the second question, Does the definition of wealth necessarily imply the idea of value? This condition is no more indispensable than the other. The idea of value is not necessarily bound up with the idea of wealth ; for surely a fertile soil, a m-ild climate, a fine network of navigable rivers, and safe and deep roadsteads are the earnest of wealth for a country ; and yet they have no exchange-value. It is even possible to establish an antithesis between these two terms; ''wealth" corresponding to the idea of abundance, "value" answering to the idea of scarcity. Let us suppose, for example, that by a lucky miracle worked by human industry all products were to be so multiplied as to become as abundant as spring water or the sand of the shore ; should we not have to regard this marvellous multipli- cation as an increase of wealth, nay, as the climax of wealth? Yet according to the above hypothesis, all things, precisely on account of their superabundance, would have lost all value ; they would have neither more nor less value than that very spring water or those grains of sand with which we just compared them. This, however, is the question which J. B. Say thought to be the 1 This argument alone would drive us back to the position which the author, perhaps too hastily, abandoned. The arguments against regarding good-will of a business, etc., as wealth, over and above the particular things and services to which they relate, are given by Dr. Bcihm-Bawerk, in his Rechte und Verhaltnisse (1881). — J. B. 42 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. most difficult in political economy, and which he set forth thus : " Wealth being made up of the value of things which are pos- sessed, how can it come about that a nation will be the richer by lowering the price that is asked for those things?" — Coiirs d'eco- )wmic politique, Part III, Chap. V. Proudhon in his Contradic- tions eco7iomiqiies raised again the same questions and defied "■ any serious economist " to answer it. This contradiction is only arbi- trary, and arises solely from a certain double meaning of the term " wealth," of which we have already warned our readers {vide page 31 seq.). As far as the word "wealth " means satiety, comfort, it is connected only with the idea of abundance, and is completely independent of the idea of value in exchange. It is considered under this aspect when we treat of a country, or better still, of humanity at large. But when " wealth " signifies inequality, the relation of superiority of one individual to another, in this sense the idea of wealth is inseparable from the idea of value. A vine- yard proprietor, for instance, is rich not in proportion to the greater or less abundance of the vintage, but in proportion to its greater or less degree of value. If he were the only person who had grown wine that year, his wealth would be at its maximum ; but if wine was as plentiful as spring water, he would be ruined. Madame de Sdvign6 expressed this most picturesquely when she wrote from Grignan (October, 1673) : ''This whole place is bursting with corn, and I have not a farthing. Seated on a heap of corn I shriek, * I am starving.' " ^ If we repeat our previous supposition, that all products became superabundant, in that land of plenty there would clearly be no more rich persons ; for henceforward all men would be equal before the valuelessness of things, just as Rothschild and the beggar are equal under the light of the sun. We might get clear of our difficulty by being careful to use the word " goods " {bond) instead of " wealth " whenever the term is used in an absolute sense to denote abundance, welfare, and to 1 See the article " Abundance " in Palgrave's Dictionary of Political Economy. — J. B. WEALTH AND VALUE. 43 reserve the word " wealth " for the cases in which it is taken in its relative sense, as denoting a certain social situation. Yet it happens that, as in practice wealth is only regarded from the point of view of the relations of individuals with individuals, the second acceptation of the term is by far the more widespread ; hence in ordinary speech the idea of wealth is always associated with the idea of value. This latter, however, is a distinct idea, and now requires our separate study. CHAPTER II. VALUE. I. What is Value ? ' When we know that a thing is suitable -to procure for us any satisfaction whatever, it thereupon becomes the object of our desires. But even of the things which are of a nature to obtain for us certain satisfactions, all are not equally desired or equally desirable. We do not place them casually on the same footing, but we arrange them in a sort of hierarchy. Some we prize very highly, others we think of little worth ; in a word, we have preferences. Now, the order of these preferences, this unequal place in our esteem which we attribute to them, is precisely what is expressed by the word " value." To say that gold has more value than silver, or, more generally, that gold has a great value, simply states the fact that for one reason or another (which reason we shall try and find by and by) we judge that gold is more desirable than silver, or more desirable than any other object. Value, then, which is the dominating idea in all political economy, denotes nothing mor e than a fact whic h in itsdlLis very simple, the fact that a thing__is mor eor.less desir ed. Were theword French^we should only have to say, " Value is desirability ^ It is much to be wished that this word, though a trifle barbarous, may be allowed to be added to the vocabulary of political economy, which up to the present is by no means rich. ^ This section would perhaps have been clearer, if the author had seen his way to adopt the distinction between Subjective and Objective Value drawn by the Austrian Economists and corresponding roughly to the old-fashioned distinction between Value in Use, and Value in Exchange. — J. B. 44 WEALTH AND VALUE. 45 But from this idea, however simple it be, some very important consequences spring. Section i. Since value arises from desire, it proceeds from us rather than from things ; as we say nowadays, it is subjective far more than objective. It is not attached to objects as a quality which can be perceived ; it is born at the moment when desire awakes, and vanishes when it dies out. Like a butterfly, desire flutters from thing to thing, and value abides only where desire rests. Doubtless if an article of wealth is one of those which answer to the permanent wants of the human race, say corn or iron, it will be able to maintain its value throughout the ages ; but if it is one of those which only correspond to those changing wants that are daily turned topsy-turvy by the caprices of fashion or the dis- coveries of science, then its value is as ephemeral and fugitive as the want which created it. Dresses that are no longer worn, books that are no longer read, pictures that have ceased to be looked at, remedies that no longer cure, — how long the list would be of those riches which have lost their value ! But yet, if by chance the desire of the collector, perhaps the most intense of all desires, happens to settle on these dead riches, they will receive a new lease of life and will immediately obtain perhaps a far higher value than they had in the course of their previous exis- tence. But value varies not only at different times, but also from country to country and even from individual to individual. We all know the proverb de gustibus non disputanduvi : let us add " and values " ; for they too depend on each man's tastes. Nor is this all : value may vary in each individual according to circumstances. A starving man will rank food as the first in the order of his preferences, and like Esau will sacrifice a fortune in exchange for a mess of pottage ; but when once filled he will give not a farthing for it. Yet an objection presents itself. If value has thus a purely subjective, individual character, does it not appear that each thing ought to have as many different values as there are individuals? But such is not the case ; in the market corn is sold at the same 46 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. price for every one : the starving man will pay neither more nor less than he who is filled to repletion. We are so accustomed to this fact that it seems perfectly natural ; yet it is somewhat surpris- ing. It is explained by the competition which takes place in the same market between the sellers and buyers, and which brings it about that no one, however strong his desire may be for a thing, will consent, usually speaking, to pay more for it than his neighbor. The value of the sack of corn does not precisely depend on the desire any person may have for this particular sack, but on the general desire all the persons in the market may have for the sacks of corn there on sale. See for this matter " The Effects produced on Value by Competition." However, if we satisfy ourselves with averages and neglect indi- vidual cases, it would not be difficult to conceive a classification of articles of wealth, arranged according to men's preferences in a fixed time and country ; on this all articles of wealth would appear in their order of value, from the diamond which is worth about p{^20oo a grain down to water which is worth a fraction of a penny a ton. It is under this form that the idea of values should be represented, and assuredly such tables would be very instructive and suitable for informing us as to the manners and ideas of different races and different times. Section II. It results, then, from our definition that the notion of value is purely relative, consisting as it does in a preference given to one thing over another. It therefore necessarily pre- supposes a compa7-ison between the two things. It is a notion of the same class as size or weight. To say that a thing is 7vorth would be unintelligible if we did not add "is worth more or less than other things " ; and when we use, without any addition, the current phrase that some object, say diamond, has " a great value," the term of comparison, though understood, exists none the less. We mean to say, either that it has a great value relatively to the unit of money, in which case it is compared with that specific object which we call pieces of money ; or that it takes a high place in the scale of wealth, in WEALTH AND VALUE. 4/ which case it is compared with all other wealth considered col- lectively. Similarly, when we say that a body, e.g. platinum, is very heavy, without expressing any comparison, we mean either that it represents a considerable number of kilogrammes, — that is to say, we compare it with the weight of a litre of water, — or that on making out the list of all bodies known to us, it would take the first place from the point of view of weight. Section III. It follows, then, from our definition that we ought never to speak of a rise or fall of all values : such a proposition would be meaningless. For if value is nothing more than an order or classification established between articles of wealth, how is it conceivable that all values can at one and the same time rise or descend? In order that some may rise in the scale, they must take the place of others, which consequently must fall. It is just as if the candidates who are admitted to the Ecole Polytechnique or the Ecole Normale, and classed according to order of merit, were to ask if they could not all at the same time have obtained a higher place. However, as we shall see presently, a general rise or fall of prices is a perfectly intelligible and indeed very frequent phenomenon. II. What is the Cause of Value ? We have just stated that things have greater or less value according as we desire them more or less ; in fact, that the order of values is none other than the order of our preferences. But that is not enough : we should like to penetrate deeper and discover the rationale of these desires and preferences. Why do we prefer one thing to another? If we can answer this question, we shall have lighted on the cause, the essential element of value. Unfortunately this is the most difficult inquiry to be met with in all political economy. If we are dealing with two objects which answer to the same want, then we have not much trouble in find- ing our reply; we shall certainly prefer the one which by virtue of its qualities appears the better fitting to satisfy our want ; i.e. which is the more useful : of two fruits of the same species we shall choose 48 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. the more luscious, of two sheep the fatter, of two pictures the better painted, of two rooms the more comfortable, of two pieces of land the more fertile ; in fact, of any two commodities whatever we shall choose that which is of the better quality. If the two objects satisfy the same want equally well, then they must have the same value. On this hypothesis, then, utility seems to be the raisori d'etre of our preferences, and therefore the true foundation of value. But now let us consider two objects which answer to different wants, say a loaf of bread and a hat. How shall we find the reason for our preferences? The guiding thread escapes our grasp. Here, indeed, we have no longer to compare two objects, but two wants ; but our wants have no common measure. Are we, then, to say that our wants can be accurately classified from the point of view of reason, morals, or hygiene ? that thence we prefer, or ought to prefer, the objects which correspond to the most essential wants? in fact, just what is expressed in popular parlance every time anything is said to fall under the category of necessary, or useful, or agreeable, or superfluous objects? Then utility would still stand as the reason for our preferences and the foundation of value, but only on condition that we use this word "utility " in its common sense ; i.e. that we interpret it as meaning an object's property of answering to some more or less rational and more or less legitimate want. We should then have to say that our loaf has more value than our hat, because it is more essential for man to obtain nourishment than to cover his head. But this conclusion suffices of itself to prove the futility of such a train of reasoning ; we know well enough that a loaf is not worth more than a hat, but that the opposite is the case. The merest, nay, the most perfunctory, glance at all the things which make up our valuables will sufficiently show us that their value is most often not in direct, but far rather in inverse ratio to their rational utility. For what are the objects which fill the lowest places in the scale of values? Corn, coal, iron, water (if the last named, indeed, can WEALTH AND VALUE. 49 receive any value), the very objects which answer to men's most essential wants and for lack of which they would be bound to perish ! What, then, are those which occupy the most exalted stations in this hierarchy of values ? Gold, diamonds, lace, perhaps a broken piece oi faience in some collection, or an edition of some old book which no one has ever read, or will ever read ; that is to say, the objects which serve only to satisfy our curiosity or to flatter our vanity. However, it might be rejoined that if instead of comparing a diamond and a bushel of corn as particular bodies, we were to draw a comparison between diamonds and corn as kinds, our conclusions would be different. It is evident that though an individual would not hesitate to prefer a diamond to a bushel of corn, yet the human race, or indeed any people, were they compelled to choose, would not hesitate to prefer corn to diamonds; and as a matter of fact, the total value of the corn cir- culating in the world is far higher than the total value of the dia- monds. That simply shows that for value, just as for wealth, there is a social or general point of view which differs from the indi- vidual point of view. But it is this individual point of view which alone concerns each one of us ; we have never to buy or sell any but concrete objects. The total value of corn or of any other commodity in the world interests no one but the statistician. Let it not be said that matters take this course because men are senseless, and that if they were wise their preferences would be dictated by reason, and the scale of values would coincide with the scale of utilities. Firstly, it is no use inquiring into what men's preferences should be in this matter ; the value of things is deter- mined by what men actually desire, and not at all by what they ought to desire. Moreover, the objection is groundless. It may be correct to say that men are wrong in attributing too high a value to trifles, but no one could assert that they err in ascribing no value at all to a glass of water ; were the whole earth peopled by none but wise men, the value of water would certainly be not a farthing the more. Let us put our question again, and try to find another answer. 50 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. Here are a loaf and a garment ; what makes us prefer one to the other? However Httle we may reflect, we shall not hesitate in replying, " It depends upon circumstances." Man's wants cannot be placed in an invariable order like the seven prismatic colors ; they are incessantly changeable, and sometimes one, sometimes another, comes to the front. If we are hungry, we shall prefer the loaf; if we are well filled, but feel cold, we shall choose the gar- ment. If we are neither hungry nor cold, we shall think of future rather than of present wants, and shall decide our action by the following considerations. If our larder is well provisioned, we shall choose the garment ; if our wardrobe is amply supplied, our choice will fall on the loaf. In fine, other things being equal, we shall always prefer that one of the two objects with which we are the less well provided. Why do we argue in this fashion? for the very simple reason that no one of our wants is unlimited, and when we have enough wealth to satisfy it, we have no motive for . desiring any more of the commodity. Of what use would a surplus be? We should not know what to do with it. Perhaps it may be said that we should always be able to dispose of it, and, as a matter of fact, people are not often seen to refuse any article of wealth because they have got enough of it. On the contrary, we consider it a wise plan always to accept. True enough ; but only when others have ?ieed of that commodity of which we have too much, and when we therefore know that we shall be able to dispose of it profitably. The circumstance that certain men are not sufficiently provided with this commodity establishes that it is desired by them, and that it therefore acquires some value. But if it exists in such a quantity that each man is sufficiently provided with it, it is clear that no one will want more of it, either for himself, for he would not know what to do with it ; or to dispose of it to others, for he would no longer find any purchasers. If, as we have shown, value has desire as its foundation, it can- not exist where there is satiety ; for desire, then, is also absent. Each of man's wants requires a certain quantity of wealth, but not WEALTH AND VALUE. 51 ail unbounded quantity ; there is a limit to it. As long as the limit is not reached, the desire subsists, though the nearer it is approached, the weaker does the desire become, and value sub- sists and decreases together with it. As soon as the limit is reached, the desire is extinguished and the value vanishes at the same moment. It is even possible, as Jevons very subtly remarks, that when once this limit has been passed, the desire we have for the thing is converted into repulsion. It is just like those series, so well kno\vn to mathematicians, which diminish as far as zero, and then begin to increase below zero, but with a negative value. Limitation in quantity, or scarcity, comes then after utility and along with it as the decisive reason for our preferences. If scarcity holds such a place in our decisions, we ought not to wonder at it or regard it as the effect of some caprice similar to that of a col- lector-maniac, who seeks for a rare article purely that he may be able to say that he is its only possessor. By no means ; if limi- tation in quantity constitutes the reason for value, — that is, because it is itself a consequence of the physical and moral nature of man, — its foundation rests on that physiological and psychological law according to which every want is limited. This doctrine was first taught by Condillac in his fine work Le Comtfierce et le Gou- verjiement (lyTO) ;^ but it has been taken up again and most ingeniously developed by Stanley Jevons in his Theory of Political Economy (1871). But limitation in quantity is not itself an absolute fact. There is not a thing in the world, even among products of nature, and in still larger measure, among the products of human industry, the quantity of which is so rigorously fixed that it cannot be increased by the expenditure of some effort. When we say that diamonds are rare, we do not mean that nature has put into circulation only a fixed number of specimens and has then destroyed the mould ; 1 e.g. ch. I. " Abundance, superabundance, and scarcity dwell rather in our opinion about quantities than in the quantities themselves; but they dweli in the opinion, only because they are supposed to dwell in the quantities." — J.B. ^2 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. we merely mean that it requires much trouble or much luck to find more of them, and that therefore the existing quantity can be increased but with difficulty. When chronometers are said to be rare, it is not meant that between the ends of the earth there only exists a fixed amount of numbered samples : an unbounded num- ber can be produced. But, as the construction of a good chro- nometer requires considerable time and special skill, the quantity is limited by the available time and labor. It is not probable that in France there are fewer trousers than waistcoats ; yet trousers may be said to be rarer than waistcoats. For as they require more material and more time for their making, the former of these gar- ments are not so easy to multiply as the latter, and for this very reason are generally dearer. The limitation in quantity or the scarcity of any commodity depends, then, solely on the greater or less difficulty experienced in obtaining it. It is easy now to explain why air and water have no value. Yet are they not especially useful articles? Undoubtedly, in the sense that they answer to the most imperious of wants ; but, however useful they may be, they are not desired; for their abundance is such that we have always enough of them, and to renew our sup- ply, if we need air, we have but to open our mouths and draw in a breath ; if water, to bend over the brook and drink. Then who troubles about a glass of water in such countries as ours? We have always enough and to spare, as is capitally said. For one lost, we can find ten to replace it. It is true that if we were in the desert, in " the land of thirst," or in a place where a glass of water was not easily procurable, it might become a highly desirable article ; but then, too, it would be capable of acquiring a value which might be said to be unbounded, and higher than that of any other object in the world. And why so? precisely because on such an hypothesis the supply of water would be found to be insufficient. If in our part of the earth water has generally no value, it is as drinking-water, with regard to its use for quenching the thirst ; for from that point of view it is superabundant. But when it is required for purposes of irrigation or for pleasure, or as WEALTH AND VALUE. 53 a motor force, it usually has some value, and even a considerable one. Why? Because for such uses it does not exist in large enough quantities to satisfy the wants of proprietors ; hence it is rendered desirable and receives a value. In the same way we can explain why diamonds or fine pearls, which answer to such futile wants, take so high a place in the scale of values. It is because their quantity is so very small that the immense majority of mankind possess none of them, though they desire them keenly (I speak at least of the feminine half of the species), and that even the favored owners are not usually so well provided with them as not to be able to desire more. That Kmit- ing point where satiety begins and desire dies is never reached with this kind of wealth. But if chemistry ever succeeds, as it reckons on doing, in converting carbon into diamonds, then as each man would be able to obtain as many of them as he wished, the desire would fall to zero and drag down the value in its fall. Even if the existing quantity was not destined to be considerably modified, yet the mere possibility of increasing that quantity at will would serve to chill desire and keep down value. To recapitulate : we can answer, in the following manner, the question, **What is the cause of value?" Things have ?Jio?-e or less of value accordijig as we desire them more or less keenly. We desire them more or less keejily according as their quantity is 77ioi'e or less insufficient for our wants. Their quantity is more or less insufficient according as it is in our power to multiply them more or less easily. We may add that an excellent criterion for measuring the utility of a thing may be derived from a consideration of the degree of suffering or of annoyance that we should receive from the priva- tion of a small portio7i of this thi?ig. According as this suffering is ?iil or slight or intense, the utility of the thing in question will be ;/// or slight or very great. Take the utility of water. Does the reader reply that is great, nay, incalculable? By no means; for consider the suff'ering that will be entailed by the privation of 54 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. a glass of water ; it is absolutely nothing. The value of water, therefore, is likewise nought. Similarly, the value of bread can be shown to be very slight. This theory, which has recently become celebrated under the name of final utility or limited utility, and which is taught by most economists, e.g. Jevons, Walras, and Menger, seems to have been discovered in 1854 by Gossen, a German writer, whose book on the subject was long utterly unknown, or perhaps even before him by Dupuit, a French engineer.^ III. Critical Examination of the Various Theories of Value. Economists have always sought for the causes of value, and each school, according to its respective tendencies, has fastened on to one or other of them. Utility, scarcity, difficulty of attain- ment, and labor are the principal ones which have been specially pointed out as the real cause or causes. Utility has often been put forward as sufficient in itself to ex- plain value, and therefore rendering unnecessary an attempt to find other causes. The chief exponents of this have been Condillac, J. B. Say, and Stanley Jevons. To the obvious objection that many very useful things have no value, this school replies that utility cannot be conceived apart from a certain limitation in quantity, and that to speak mathematically, it is necessarily a " function " of quantity. If a thing is in excess, e.g. water, no por- tion of it (say a glass of water) can be said to be useful ; it is not useful, for no one thinks aught of it. What is superabundant is necessarily superfluous, and what is superfluous is necessarily useless. This doctrine comes very near the truth, and, indeed, closely resembles the opinion we have set forth. Yet we must observe that by employing the word "utility" in a somewhat dif- ferent sense from its ordinary acceptation, and by attributing to it 1 Gossen was only one out of a number. See Jevons' Political Economy, Preface and Supplement to second and later editions. For the relation of Jevons to the Austrian Economists (who avoid the use of Mathematics), see the Harvard Quarterly Journal of Economics, October, 1 888. — J. B. WEALTH AND VALUE. 55 many things it does not mean, this doctrine forces language and seems to turn on the point of a verbal ambiguity. The mathematical school — for instance, M. Walras — gives the preference to scarcity ; for here this school finds that especial advantage for those who wish to introduce mathematical methods into economic science, the being able to base the theory of value on the mathematical idea par excellence, the idea of quantity. Scarcity is limitation in quantity, but, they add, it also implies utihty; for does not calling a thing scarce mean that it is^ sought for and consequently is useful ? If it served no purpose, no one would want it ; and, if no one wanted it, it could not be said to be scarce were it otherwise unique ; as, for instance, a letter written by a peasant who had never written but one in his whole life. We must reply, however, that the idea of scarcity is not strong enough to stand alone unless we read into this word many things it does not say ; for, to use a well-known example, cherries are no less scarce in July than in May, but as they are not then early fruit, i.e. are no longer desired, their value is gone. The classical school' in England preferred to choose difficulty of- attainment ; certainly the amount of difficulty that we experience in procuring a thing is a cojidition of its value, but it is by no means the cause. Corn draws its value, not from the circumstance that it requires long labor and exhausting work, but from the fact that we suffer hunger and that this grain is especially fitting for our nourishment. The amount of difficulty that we experience in producing corn only acts upon its value in the proportion in which it affects our satisfying of our hunger. Finally, another school teaches that labor is the real cause of value. This theory, which has been set forth in rather varied forms, has now some position in the science ; first expounded by Ricardo, it has gathered round its standard economists of the most opposite schools from Bastiat to Karl ]Marx. In reality, this theory does not deny that utility — that is to say^ the property of satisfying any human want or desire — is the primor- dial condition of all value. Of course we should have to have lost 56 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. our senses before entertaining the idea that a thing which is of no use can have any value, whatever amount of labor it may have entailed. But according to this school, if utility is the condition of value, it is not its cause or its measure. The basis of value, according to Ricardo, its substance, according to Karl Marx, is man's labor, and each thing has more or less worth according as it has required more or less labor. The cause of this theory attracting so many generous minds is, that difering from the preceding group, which rests value on a purely natural fact, utility or scarcity, it grounds value upon a moral act, — labor. Could it be proved that the value of all our possessions, e.g. land, is in proportion to the labor they have cost us, we might be justified in concluding that every man's property or fortune is in direct ratio to his labor, and thus the social organi- zation would be firmly seated on a principle of justice. Yet this doctrine, like Joseph Prudhomme's legendary sword, may be used to combat existing institutions as well as to defend them. While the school of Bastiat employs it to show that each man's fortune is proportional to his labor, Karl Marx's followers, on the other hand, seek to prove by its aid that the values possessed by the wealthy classes are due entirely to the labor of the workmen who have been basely robbed of them ; thence the conclusion is drawn that these values must be returned to those who have created them. The theory certainly contains a portion of the truth. No one disputes that the labor necessary for the production of things has a considerable influence on their value, and this follows from the very circumstance we sought to explain in our analysis of value. We agreed that value ultimately depends on the greater or less facility we experience in multiplying things ; now, as labor is the principal factor of production, it is clear that the degree of facility we have in multiplying things will in the ultimate analysis depend on the amount of labor they require for their production. But it follows from this very train of reasoning that labor can act on the value of things only indirectly, and purely as regards WEALTH AND VALUE. 57 quantity. Of itself it has no influence on value, and this is shown clearly enough by facts that can be noticed every day. 1. If the value of a thing had for its cause or substance the labor expended in its production, this value would necessarily have to be immutable ; for, as Bastiat himself grants, " Past labor is not susceptible of increase or decrease." Now we know, on the con- trary, that the value of an object varies constantly and ceaselessly ; it is evident, then, that these variations are absolutely independent of the labor of production. For a priori reasons, moreover, it is absurd to think that the value of a thing can thus depend on a fact which is over and done. The matter is finished, there is no harking back to it, and we must say, like Lady Macbeth, " What is done cannot be undone " ; let us speak no more of it. 2. If labor were the cause of value, equal values would always correspond to equal labors, and unequal to unequal. Now every moment we see objects which have cost the same amount of labor selling at very different prices {e.g. a fillet of beef and the tongue or the tail of the same ox) ; and inversely, objects which have required far different amounts of labor selling at the same price {e.g. one gallon of wine produced on an estate which yielded i8o gallons per acre, and one gallon of wine of the same quality pro- duced on an estate which yields 1800 gallons per acre). Ricardo did not deny this fact, for on it he based his famous theory of Rent (see below, "Distribution") ; but the explanation he gives merely establishes the incontestable fact that two objects of the same quality, i.e. of the same utility, have necessarily the same value, however unequal be the respective amounts of labor they have cost. 3. If labor were the cause of value, where there had been no labor there would be no value. Now there are innumerable things which possess a value, and often a very high one, without having required any labor ; such as a spring of mineral water or petro- leum, guano deposited by sea-birds, a sandy beach in the south of France which has been ploughed only by the wind from the open sea and which is sold at a very high price for the plantation 58 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. of vines, a few yards of ground in the Champs-Elysees, etc. Nor do Ricardo and his school deny (for the fact is not capable of denial) that there are certain objects " whose value depends only on scarcity, since no labor can increase their quantity." Yet he considers these to be insignificant, and only gives as examples valuable ^^ictures, statues, etc. In reality, these objects form an enormous body of exceptions and nuUify the rule. 4. Lastly, if labor is the cause of value, what is to be the cause of the value of the labor itself? For labor has certainly a value ; it is bought and sold, or, if the term is preferred, is hired every day at a certain price. It is easy to explain the value of labor by the value of its products, just as the value of a piece of land is determined by the value of the crops it can yield. But if we explain the value- of products by the value of the labor which has formed them, we but argue in a circle whence there is no exit.^ Ingenious attempts have been made to fit in this theory with the various difficulties of fact which we have just pointed out. Carey says that the value of any object depends, not precisely on the amount of labor expended in its production, but on the labor necessary to produce a similar object; i.e. the labor of reprodiiclion. Bastiat says that the matter to be considered is not the labor done by the person who has produced the object, but the labor spared the would-be acquirer. As, according to Bastiat, the sparing a person of a certain amount of labor is to render him a service, the author of the Harmonies proceeds then to define value as the relation between two services exchanged, and to declare that a service rendered is the cause and the measure of value. This for- mula, in spite of its popularity for some time, is a pure tautology. To the question, "Why has a diamond a greater value than a pebl)le?" it answers, "Because when I am handed a diamond, a greater service is done me than when I am handed a pebble." 1 There is a full discussion of the " Labour theories of Value " in Dr. Bohm- Bawerk's book on Capital and Interest, Vol. L (English translation by W. Smart, 1890), pp. 297 seq. — J. B. WEALTH AND VALUE. 59 No one disputes so puerile a proposition, but it is enough to reply, that if the service rendered by the transfer of a diamond is greater than that rendered by the transfer of a mere pebble, it follows simply from the diamond possessing a greater value than the pebble. So we have only reversed our position. In reality, it is not the service rendered by the person who yields me the object that determines its value ; but it is the value of the object yielded which determines and measures the importance of the service rendered. See in the Revue iVeconomie politique, May-June, 1887, an examination we have made of this theory. Karl Marx declares that we have no concern with the individual labor which may have been expended in producing any object, but must deal with the social labor, or, rather, the average labor necessary for the production of this commodity in general. These various theories cannot be discussed here ; we shall con- fine ourselves to remarking that all these theories derived from the idea of labor conflict more or less with the same difficulties as the fundamental theory, and that they lack the merit which it pos- sessed of satisfying the idea of justice. We have agreed that there would be harmony if it could be proved that the value of an object is proportional to the amount of effort that must be expended for its production ; but this harmony vanishes or becomes very doubtful if we content ourselves with showing that the value of an object is only proportional to the labor necessary for reproducing a similar object (as Carey says) ; or to the efforts that must be made to procure a like object (as Bastiat says) ; or to the average amount of labor required for the industrial production of this class of objects (as Karl Marx says). To recapitulate : the numberless theories which have been pro- pounded for the explanation of the phenomena of value may be divided into two distinct groups or tendencies. The one is bound up with the idea of utility, and rests value on man's wants ; the other is bound up with the idea of labor, and rests value on man's efforts. The first is, in our opinion, the expression of what is ; in fact. 60 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. the value of things is proportional to our wants or desires. The second is the expression of what should he ; in point of equity it is to be wished that value might be proportional to our efforts or labor. It would prove us to possess an unscientific mind if we were to think that the natural law of vahies can ever be changed ; l)ut we are not debarred from hoping that in spite of or by means of this law we may succeed some day in making fact more conform- able with equity ; that is to say, in rendering value more and more proportional to labor. IV. Variations in Value. That imaginary list on which we supposed all articles of wealth to be ranged in order of preference has, we are aware, no stability about it. The value of each thing — I mean its place relatively to the others — constantly varies. The reason for this is evi- dent ; for value springs from our desires, and what could be more changeable than they are? Even granting that we are dealing with some physiological want, such as the need of food, yet, since there is an infinite variety of objects capable of satisfying that want, our desire can turn from one to another, and can make all of them in turn ascend or descend on the scale of values. Can we trace any general ])rinciples or laws which regulate these movements ? We can ; and such an investigation is of the greatest interest. If, as we have previously said, utility and limitation in quantity are the two elements of value, the moving springs of our desires, it follows that, if both or one of these elements happen to vary, value will necessarily vary. Firstly, If the utility of a thing constantly increases, its value will increase in like manner. This is the case with land, whether a building site in town, or cultivable ground in country, the utility of which increases regularly in proportion as a growing society has need of more room and more food. Therefore the value of ground, except in temporary crises, is in a state of constant progression. WEALTH AND VALUE. 6 1 Secondly, When, on the contrary, the iitiUty diminishes, other things being equal, value must fall. This is the case with the precious metals, and especially with silver, which daily loses in value, not only because the more refined taste of the present day does not require it so much in the shape of plate or jewelry, but mainly because the improvement in instruments of credit gradually impairs its utility as money. Thirdly, When the quantity increases, other things being equal, value must diminish. This is the case with manufactured products, which machinery enables us to multiply daily with growing ease. Fourthly, When the quantity diminishes, other things being equal, value must increase. This is the case with game, which, after having formed the usual food of man when societies were in their infancy, has so diminished in quantity, in consequence of the opening up and the putting into cultivation of land, that in all civilized countries it is nowadays merely an article of luxury reserved for the table of the rich. The same, perhaps, will happen some day with butchers' meat ; for in every civilized country the same causes are tending to restrict more and more the amount of land devoted to the pasturage and the breeding of cattle, and con- sequently, the quantity of cattle in proportion to the population. Of all commodities, it is meat which rises the most rapidly in price. But besides these variations that we might call secular, because in the course of ages they slowly and uniformly displace articles of wealth in the scale of values, and which will be more easy to understand after we have studied the laws of production, there is another class of variations to which every value is subject : these might better be styled oscillations, for they recur after short intervals, sometimes in one direction, sometimes in another. Ex- pressed in terms of money, they can be read in the variations of the market rates of commodities as they are daily quoted in the newspapers. These variations, though perhaps less interesting for the economist, are of far more consequence to the business man and the manufacturer, for on these depend their profits or their loss. 62 PRINCIPLES OF POLPriCAL ECONOMY. For instance, fish has what may be called a normal value, re- sultinir on the one hand from the utility of this food, that is to say, from the degree of taste that consumers have for this kind of nourishment ; and on the other hand from the limitation in its quantity, according as the country has a larger or smaller coast- line, according as its seas are better or worse stocked with fish, and according as a larger or smaller number of its inhabitants devote themselves to this particular fishery. But, over and above this normal value, itself a variable one, yet varying but slowly and then generally in the direction of a rise, the value of fish when in the market is liable to a host of temporary variations. Thus on fast days in Catholic countries fish rises in value, acquiring on such days a new utility on account of the decrees of the Church, which permit no other animal food. Inversely, its value will hW if the haul has been especially abundant. These oscillations are usually said to be regulated by //le law of supply and dcjnand. This celebrated formula was for long regarded as the fundamental law of political economy, and was employed to explain any sort of phenomenon. Since then, how- ever, it has been much criticised and has incurred some discredit. In its most simple sense this formula means : the price of every commodity in a market depends on the relation which exists between the quantity offered by the sellers and the quantity de- manded by the buyers. If the demand is greater than the supply, the price rises ; if the supply is greater than the demand, the price falls. In this sense the proposition is evident. But, really, this formula contains nothing more than the two elements of value we are already acquainted with, viz., utility and scarcity, regarded as acting at a fixed time and place. It is clear, then, that the larger or smaller quantity of goods that the sellers may offer in the market constitutes what we have called scarcity, whilst the larger or smaller quantity demanded by the consumers depends on the degree of intensity of their wants or desires ; in other words, on the degree of utility that the particular commodity may possess for them. This proposition does not throw any great light WEALTH AND VALUE. 63 on the explanation of phenomena, but it has the advantage of including some rather complex ideas in a short and simple for- mula. Nothing more than this must be sought from it. People have discredited it just through ascribing to it a precision it does not admit of. For example, it has been erroneously expressed in the following mathematical formula : " Value varies in direct ratio of the quan- tities demanded, and in inverse ratio of the quantities offered." This means to say, that if the demand is doubled, then, the supply remaining the same, the value will be doubled ; and that, inversely, if the supply is doubled, then, the demand remaining the same, the value will be reduced by half. In such terms as these, the proposition is absolutely false, as was long ago proved by John Stuart Mill and by Cournot. People forget that though supply and demand act on value, yet value, in its turn, reacts on supply and demand, and tends to re-establish that equilibrium between them which had been momentarily disturbed. When demand exceeds supply, value certainly rises ; but the very result of this rise in value is to reduce demand from the side of the buyers, and to increase supply from the sellers ; so that the quantities supplied and demanded are not long in regaining their equality. The simplest observation is enough to prove this. Let us take some stock on the Bourse, — say the three per cents, — and let it be at 95. Continually a cer- tain quantity of government stock is offered, and a certain quantity demanded. At the opening of the Bourse, suppose the stock demanded to be double the figure offered. Who would be so foolish as to imagine that the price of the stock ought consequently to be doubled, and rise to 190? Yet that is precisely what ought to occur if the above formula was correct ; but in reality the price of the stock may not rise in the least, and that for the very simple reason that by far the larger number of the would-be purchasers at 95 withdraw when the price rises. It is clear that if the amount of stock demanded diminishes in proportion to the rise in price, at the same time, and for the same reason, the amount offered 64 PRINXIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. increases. A moment, then, will necessarily come when the de- creasing demand and the growing supply will become equalized ; and at that moment equilibrium will be re-estabUshed. A rise of a few pence is generally sufficient to bring about this result. Inversely, it is not impossible, in certain exceptional cases, for supply and demand to entail far more than proportional variations in value. Gregory Kin^s Law, established two centuries ago by numerous observations on the price of corn in England, showed that the slightest variation in quantity caused more than propor- tional variations in price. Thus, if the crop was diminished by half, the price per bushel was multiplied almost by five. However, this law has now lost almost all its importance, in consequence of international trade in cereals. We have to remark, indeed, that, thanks to that system of exchange which brings together in one market the produce of countries situated on all the zones, not only is the bad harvest of one land compensated for by the good harvest of another, but also the production of corn, instead of being intermittent, becomes continuous ; for there is not a day in the year, so to speak, on which harvesting is not going on in some portion of the globe. V. The Effects produced on Value by Competition. When each individual in a country is at liberty to take the action he considers the most advantageous for himself, whether as regards the choice of an employment or the disposal of his goods, we are said to live under the regime of competition. This regime, under which at the present day nearly all civilized societies live, exercises a decisive influence on all economic phe- nomena, and especially on value. As far as regards value, competition has the following effects : — Firstly, It tends to equalize the values of all similar products. Desires and wants being different in the case of each man, it would follow that the same object ought to have a particular value for each individual; that, for instance, in a corn market there WEALTH AND VALUE. 65 ought to be as many different prices as there are buyers. But competition prevents the accomphshment of such a result ; in reahty, in our corn market there will be only one price for all the sacks of com. Why? Because if a particular one of the buyers chanced to offer for a particular sack a price higher than that current in the market, all the sellers would hasten to offer him their sacks at a lower price, and would compete with one another till the price had fallen down again to the general level. Inversely, if a seller agreed to dispose of his sack below the market price, all the buyers would press round him and outbid one another, till the price had been forced up again to the general level. Stanley Jevons calls this law, which states that there is never but one price for objects of the same quality, the law of indifference. By this he means that all the objects being, according to the hypothesis, of the same quahty, buyers have no motive for preferring some to others, and that in this state of indifference the slightest variation in value is enough to provoke outbiddings in one direction or the other, which would restore the equilibrium. Secondly, It tends to restore the value of all products to a minimum level, determined by the cost of production. When we come to production, we shall see, that to produce any article of wealth a certain quantity of wealth must necessarily be consumed. The value of the wealth produced is as a general rule higher than that of the wealth consumed ; for, if it were otherwise, the producer would incur a loss. Unless, then, the unexpected comes to pass, there will always be a difference, or a margin, between the two values ; and it is this very difference which constitutes the profits of the enterprise. It is clearly to the interest of the producer to extend this margin as much as possible, by trying either to lower the value of the wealth consumed (raw material, wages, etc.), or to raise the value of the wealth produced. But the competition of the producers acts in just the inverse direction ; the buyers, vying with one another, each producer strives to attract them to him by reducing as much as possible the margin between the cost price and the 66 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. selling price, until that minimum limit is reached beneath which it would be no longer worth while to produce. There is a wide- spread notion that the cost of production and value stand to one another in the relation of cause and effect ; in other words, that things possess a value on account of their particular cost of pro- duction, and that this value is always determined by this cost of production. This is altogether a sophism. True enough, under the action of that external cause which is called competition, value and cost of production bear a constant relation one to the other ; but it is not correct to say that cost of production determines the value of the product. On the contrary, it would be more correct to say that // is the value of the product which deterfnines the cost of production. Before incurring any expenses in the production of a thing, every producer first asks himself, " What will be the value of the product?" If he con- siders that this value will be enough to cover the expenses and leave him a margin of profit besides, he ventures on the enterprise. In the opposite case, he refrains. If he happens to err in his predictions, it will be so much the worse for him ; and all the expenses he may have incurred will not be able to raise the value of the product a farthing above the value determined by the law of supply and demand. Moreover, it is a petitio principii to say that the cost of produc- tion is the cause of the value of things. For, as the cost of pro- duction is, as we have seen, nothing but the value of the wealth consumed in the course of production, such a train of argument would merely explain value by value. The cost of production may greatly vary, not only, as is obvious, for different prodiicts, but also for products of the same sort. From the latter circumstance arises an economic problem which is sufficiently remarkable, and the solution of which is extremely important. Let us consider some hundreds of sacks of corn offered for sale in a market. It is evident that they have not all been pro- duced under identical conditions. Some have been raised by WEALTH AND VALUE. 6/ means of manuring and labor ; others have grown ahnost sponta- neously on fertile soil. These hail from San Francisco, and have doubled Cape Horn on their way ; those come from the next farm. If, then, each sack was to have fixed on a ticket its own peculiar cost price, there would, perhaps, not be two on which the same price could be read. Let us suppose, for instance, that these cost prices ranged from 10 to 20 shillings. Under these conditions what will be the market price ? will it be equal to the cost price of the sack which cost the most, or of that which cost the least, or of some intermediate sack ? Will it be fixed at 20 or 10 or 15 shillings? In other words, will the value, on this hypothesis, be regulated by the maximum cost of produc- tion, or by the minitnum, or by the average ? Here we must draw distinctions. If we are speaking of products w^hich cannot be multiplied at will, or only in a very restricted measure, — and this is just w^hat occurs with corn, — the market price will have to be regulated by the cost price of the sack which has been the most expensive to produce, 20 shillings in our example ; that is to say, the value is regulated by the maximum cost of production. For if we suppose, as we are bound to do, that all the sacks in the market are abso- lutely necessary for the food- supply, and that none of them can be dispensed with, we shall certainly have to make up our minds to pay a price high enough for none of these sacks to have been produced at a loss ; for if any one of them was so circumstanced, its production would be discontinued, and thence there would be a deficit in the supply of corn. If, on the other hand, we are speaking of products which can be actually or virtually multiplied at will, — e.g. yards of cotton- stuff, or hundreds of nails, — the market price would probably fall, if not all at once, at any rate after a short time, to the level of the lowest cost price ; that is to say, the value tends to be regu- lated by the minimum cost of production. In fact, it \\\\\ be to the interest of the producer whose cost price is the lowest to profit 68 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. by his privileged position to lower his prices to a limit very near to his cost price, in order to undersell his competitors and extend his sale as much as possible. If he happens to be of sufficient weight to supply the market by himself alone, his less-favored rivals will have nothing to do but disappear : there is no further need of them. To recapitulate: Whenever we are dealing with a product which cannot be multiplied at will, it is the maximum cost of production which determines the market value. Whenever we are deaUng with a product which can be multiplied at will, it is the minimum cost of production which determines the market value.^ VI. Whether Competition is Cheapness. There is a very wide-spread notion that competition always pro- duces cheapness, and monopoly dearness. Thus, competition is considered by the public to be a power which is beneficent, demo- cratic, and always conducing to the general welfare, whereas monop- oly is regarded as a public scourge. Many people even think that all political economy 'can be reduced to this axiom. Yet it is not an absolute truth. Undoubtedly the ordinary effect of competition, as we have seen in the preceding chapter, is to lower the value of products to the level of the cost of production, which is advantageous for the public. But competition, after passing a certain limit, may produce a precisely inverse effect. If it raises up a number of producers or middlemen out of proportion to men's wants, — 6:g. two or three railway lines where one would have sufficed, or a hundred bakers in a town which was previously content with ten, — then the gen- eral expenses increase in considerable proportions ; that is to say, 1 i.e. if (after what our author has said on page 66) it is right to say that cost determines value at all. — J. B, WEALTH AND VALUE. 69 each single article produced requires for its production a larger consumption of wealth (in the shape of wages, raw material, imple- ments, sites, etc.), and, the cost of production rising, the value of the product rises in a parallel manner.^ This does not mean that competition does not bring about here, too, its usual effect of maintaining the value of the product at the level of the cost of production, by reducing profits. On our pres- ent hypothesis, producers are only too well aware that their profits are reduced to the minimum ; but the reduction of profits, instead of resulting from a fall in the selling price, which would be advan- tageous for the public, comes from a rise in the cost price which is detrimental to all concerned. (For the inconveniences of a multiplicity of middlemen, see below, "Traders," page 176). If competition does not necessarily lead to cheapness, it follows, a contra7'io, that monopoly does not necessarily produce dearness. It has the disadvantage, it is true, of allowing the producer who is invested with this particular monopoly to realize exceptional profits, but it may enable him, also, to reduce his prices, through economy in his general expenses ; thus a trifling disadvantage would be compensated by a great advantage. The equalization of incomes is certainly a good thing to aim at, but economy in production is better. Observe, too, that it is altogether erroneous to imagine that a producer who possesses a monopoly has the power of fixing prices according to his own will, and that the public must submit to his good pleasure. In reality, the value of his products is determined by the same laws as every other value, i.e. by the demand of the public. As this demand, in obedience to a constant economic law, grows in direct ratio to the lowering of prices, it is for the most part the monopolist's interest to fix his prices at a very low figure, and as near as possible to the cost price, in order to attain the greatest possible sale. Such a course is usually pursued by ^ Even with the explanation which follows, this position seems paradoxical, and the views of Value not quite consistent with that of Sect. IV. and V. — J. B. yO PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. intelligent producers who hold a monopoly either de Jure or de facto. To sell cheaply in order to sell largely, and thus recoup yourself from the quantity sold, has become the favorite motto of present-day commerce. (For this question of monopoly read Cournot's remarkable chapters, either in his Pmicipes mathhna- tiques de la theo?-ie des richesses or in his Revue Soinmaire des doctrines economiques, 1877.) Finally, it must not be forgotten that in certain special cases, — notably, every time a monopoly is established by law, — the law can fix tariffs ; and thus are obtained the advantages of large pro- duction, while the disadvantages of excessive profits are avoided. This is done when the working of railway lines is granted to one or more privileged companies ; and the results of such a system are often far superior to those afforded by competition. Thus it is very clear that the tendency of modern industry is not towards competition, but towards monopoly, a real monopoly which is exercised by powerful companies, which may either work on their own lines, or form part of a syndicate. Trade, transport, manufacture, mines, are becoming concentrated in the hands of large associations, which are in their turn showing a tendency to federate as associations of the second degree. Of late years these have become well known as Cartels, "Trusts," "Rings," and so forth. As a rule they are not favorably regarded by the public or by respective governments, and they are often stigmatized as mo- nopolists. This severe judgment is well merited when their only object is avowed speculation, but as a new form of industrial organi- zation they may be of great use by preventing a waste of produc- tive power, by making production more regular, by keeping up prices, and thus warding off crises and enforced lack of work. Still their action will render even more necessary a certain amount of State interference. We may refer to Professor P'oxwell's article on Monopolies in \}c\^ Revue d"" economic politique for 1889.^ There 1 ' Growth of Monopoly,' a paper read to the Economic Section of the British Association, 7th Sept., 1888, and translated in the September number of the Revile d'cconomie politique (1889), of which Professor Gide is an editor. -J.B. WEALTH AND VALUE. 7 1 is also a tendency to monopolies exercised directly by the State, as in the case of the post-office, telegraphs, railways, banks of issue, and by municipalities in the matters of gas and the electric light, omnibuses, and tramways. CHAPTER III. PRICE. I. How Value is measured by Exchange. Manv economists hold it to be an indisputable principle that the idea of value cannot be conceived apart from exchange (Stanley Jevons even proposes to suppress the term "value," and to replace it by " ratio of exchange "). Our analysis, on the contrary, proves that the idea of value pre- cedes exchange, both in order of time and in order of importance. The idea of value means nothing more than a preference granted one thing over another, a comparison, the weighing of two desires. The idea, then, is not necessarily bound up with exchange. Rob- inson Crusoe had his preferences, but I confess that they were in the latent state, and that the conditions of his isolated existence were not suitable to reveal them to others, or even to himself. If he had been asked to point them out, and to class the articles of wealth composing his modest property according to the values he ascribed to them, he would have found the task embarrassing. At the most, he would have been able to class them roughly in two or three groups, according as they corresponded to more or less essential wants. Yet we can imagine some occasion which might cause this confused and indistinct notion of value to rise suddenly out of his inner consciousness, and compel it to take a definite shape. Such an occasion, for instance, arose even in the first few days after his landing. When he had to rescue each article of wealth singly from the ship, which was on the point of sinking (for the storm did not leave him time to save all, but only enough to rescue some of them), he must have been obliged to make a choice and determine which one he preferred to save first. The order in 72 WEALTH AND VALUE. 73 which he successively brought them to land, perfectly showed the order of his preferences, and consequently, too, the respective values he ascribed to them. Let us confess that in reality it is almost solely exchange which causes the idea of value to rise from the inner consciousness in which, so to speak, it was slumbering, which determines it and measures it. In every exchange, and in present-day societies ex- changes are innumerable, two articles of wealth are laid side by side, and each exchanger weighs in his mind the article he must give up and the article he desires to acquire. Though this is not the place for us to discuss exchange, — for we shall find it later on in dealing with the organization of production of which it is one of the principal springs, — yet we ought to show in what way exchange determines and measures value. As we know, the value of a thing is nothing but the more or less keen desire with which it inspires us. But it may be asked, How are desires to be measured ? Just like any other force, — by their effects. Now we know that each party to an exchange is called upon to make some sacrifice for the satisfaction of his desire ; he must give up a certain quantity of the wealth he possesses in order to attain what he covets. Clearly, the extent of the sacrifice he is disposed to make can serve to measure the intensity of his desire. The exchange of ten sheep for one ox proves that men, for one reason or another, consider an ox to be ten times more desirable than a sheep. The keener the desire with which an object inspires us, the more distant will be the limit at which we shall consent to part with it. The higher the place it holds in the order of our preferences, the greater will be the quantity of any other article that must be offered us in order to arouse in our minds a desire opposite in direction and equal in intensity, and to make the scale turn to the side of the latter desire. The expression, then, is perfectly correct, that " the value of a thing is determined by the quantity of other things for which it can be exchanged " ; or, more briefly, that the value of a thing is determined by its purchasing power. But we must not say, as is too often done, that it is the purchas- 74 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. ing power which constitutes value. Vahie is constituted by our preferences alone. The purchasing power is only an effect of value, just as. the power of attraction of an electro-magnet is merely the effect of the current which penetrates it. If, then, in exchange for an ox I can have 8, lo, or 12 sheep, I can say that the value of an ox is 8, 10, or 12 times greater than that of a sheep ; or, inversely, that the value of a sheep is 8, 10, or 12 times smaller than that of an ox. This can be expressed thus : " The respective values of any two commodities are in inverse ratio to the quantities exchanged." The more of a thing that has to be given up, the less is it worth ; the less of it that has to be given in exchange for another thing, the more is it worth. It is just as in weighing. When the balance is in equi- librium, the weights of the objects can be said to be in inverse ratio to the quantities weighed. If we have to put ten sheep into one scale to balance one ox in the other, that is because the weight of a sheep is only the tenth of the weight of an ox. II. On the Choice of a Common Measure of Values. To obtain a clear idea of size, weight, value, and all other quantitative notions, it is not enough to compare objects two at a time, as we have just done ; we must compare all things with one specific object, which shall always be the same; we need one single term of comparison; in a word, we require a conwion vieasure. For measuring lengths, the term of comparison chosen has been some part of the human body, such as a foot, a thumb (inch), or a forearm's length (cubit), or a specific fraction of the circumference of the globe. For measuring weights, the term of comparison chosen in the metric system has been a fixed weight of distilled water. For measuring value we must certainly take as our term of comparison the value of some object or other ; but which are we to choose ? It is a remarkable fact that nations have almost unanimously agreed in choosing as their measure of values, as their standard. WEALTH AND VALUE. 75 the value of the precious metals, gold, silver, copper, but especially those of the first two. They have all made use of a little ingot of gold or silver, to which they have given the name of franc, pound sterling, mark, dollar, rouble, etc. For measuring the value of any object it is compared with the value of that small weight of gold or silver which serves as the unit of money ; that is to say, we try to find how many of these tiny ingots must be given up for us to acquire the commodity in question. If, for instance, ten are needed, we say that the commodity is worth ten francs, or ten dollars, etc. Why have the precious metals been taken as the common measure of values? Because, as they had already been chosen, on account of some remarkable properties, to act as instruments of exchange (for the reasons which have caused the precious metals to be chosen as instruments of exchange, see pages 186-187), and as exchange is, as we have shown, the very transaction which serves to measure values, the precious metals were naturally marked out to fulfil this high function. Yet these two functions, although always confounded in practice, are theo- retically quite distinct, and could, indeed, if we wished, be per- fectly well separated (see Stanley Jevons on Money), For instance, the collectivists, in the social organization which they are sketching out, propose to suppress exchange and consequently the instrument of exchange, but they never dream of suppressing the measure of values ; on the contrary, they propose a certain measure of values which would consist of labor notes. Inasmuch as these two functions of money are perfectly distinct, we have thought it right to discuss them in two different parts of this work, and, though we have been blamed for this separation, we have thought it right to retain it as a perfecdy logical one. However, it is right to recognize that though the precious metals are far better suited, by their natural properties, to serve as instruments of exchange than as a measure of values, yet they possess two special properties which enable them to fulfil this ']6 PRIN'CIPLES OF POLITICAL ECOxXOMY. second function in a manner which, if not perfect, is at least superior to the use of any other imaginable measure of value. These two properties are, firstly, their very great facility of transport; secondly, their almost indefinite durability. Thanks to the first of these two properties, the value of ..the precious metals is, of all values, that which fluctuates least from place to place ; thanks to the second, that which fluctuates least from year to year. It is this double invariability (relatively speaking) in space and in time which is the essential condition of every common measure. If the difficulty of transport could be altogether overcome in the case of any one commodity, and if the gift of ubiquity could be granted if, the result would be that its value would be practi- cally the same in all places. Let its value be supposed to be less high in one part of the world than in another ; then men would soon come to seek it at this first place in order to transport it to the second ; and, as by our hypothesis, the carriage would present no difficulty and require no expense, the slightest difference in value would be enough to make the enterprise a profitable one. The equilibrium, if we suppose it to have been broken, would then be instantaneously re-established, just as the level is instantly restored in the case of a liquid whose molecules are perfectly fluid. Now, the precious metals being of all commodities, except precious stones, those which have the greatest value in the small- est volume, they are also those whose carriage is the easiest, and whose value, therefore, will the most rapidly recover its normal level. For one per cent of its value, freight and insurance in- cluded, a mass of gold or of silver can be conveyed from one end of the world to the other, whilst the same weight of corn would have to pay, according to circumstances, 20, 30, or even 50 per cent of its value. It might seem to follow from this, that save for this one per cent, the value of the precious metals would be the same in all parts of the world : yet such a conclusion would be considerably too broad ; for it is certain that the value WEALTH AND VALUE. JJ of the precious metals is not the same everywhere, and that in particular it is more depreciated in the places where they are found and worked, i.e, in' mining countries (a fact that explains the very high prices prevalent in those districts) ; nevertheless we may say that the value of these metals satisfies well enough the first condition, viz., invariability in space. It complies far less satisfactorily with the second condition, in- variability in time ; yet even from this point of view the precious metals are superior to most other commodities for the second reason we have given, namely, their very great durability. The principal cause of the value of an object fluctuating from one epoch to another is the variation in its quantity. If we imagine a product to be of such a" nature that its quantity is liable to vary from zero up to a very considerable figure, the variations ^ in it^ value will be extreme. This is the case with corn. Before harvest the granaries may be absolutely empty ; after harvest, they will be full, and the difference between a good and a bad year may be immense. Hence, too, there are enormous variations in the value of this article, and they would be still greater, were it not that facility of carriage and international trade brought about a sort of equilibrium in production (see above, page 64). But because of their durabihty, which enables the same particles of metal, coined and recoined over and over again, to pass down the ages, the precious metals possess quite other characteristics. They accumulate htde by httle into a huge mass, into which the annual production pours as if into a reservoir which is continu- ously growing, and in which, therefore, accidental fluctuations become of smaller and smaller proportionate amount and impor- tance. In a headlong torrent the slightest increases in volume are manifested by enormous changes of level, but the level of Lake Geneva is only raised in imperceptible proportions even by the greatest swellings of the Rhone. The same holds with values. Let the corn crop for one particular year be doubled throughout the whole world. Then, as the stock is likewise doubled, the 78 PRINXIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. depr- ciation in prices will be terrible. But let the ontpi*t of gold or silver mines happen to double during one year; then, as this output does not, at the most, represent more than two or three per cent of the existing stock, the effect produced will be but trifling. Yet these variations end by being very perceptible in the long run ; for at the rate of two or three per cent per annum, the stock would become doubled in twenty-four or thirty-six years. If, then, the value of the precious metals offers substantial enough guarantees of stability in time, when short periods only are under consideration, it altogether fails in this respect when long periods of time are included, say twenty or twenty-five years, not to speak of several centuries. In this regard, then, our proposed measure of value is extremely defective. Could a better one be found ? Well, several have been pro- posed as such. Here are a few of the most noteworthy : the value of corn, or the wages for a day's hibor ; again, in quite another order of thought, it has been proposed to measure the value of things by the Jiumher of hours of labor necessary for their production. Let us discuss the respective merits of each of these. Firstly, the value of corn. On first thoughts this is a most astonishing choice ; for if we consider the value of this commodity in different places or at different times, we find not only that it is not invariable, but also that there are few values whose fluctuations are more marked. At the same moment a bushel of corn may be sold for ^3 \os. in France, and for £\ or 30 shillings in some of the Western States of America. According as the year is good or bad, the value of corn may also vary in enormous proportions, though these variations may have been diminished by the facility, of exchange. But it is replied that, though the value of corn is incompar- ably more variable than that of the precious metals, when only short spaces of time are considered, yet is far more stable when we extend our observation to long periods. Throughout its sharp and numerous oscillations the value of corn would appear WEALTH AND VALUE. 79 to tend always to remain equal to itself; and these would seem to be the reasons for such a curious property. I. Say its supporters, the utility of corn may be regarded as constant ; for, on the average, does not a man always require the same quantity of corn as food, to-day as yesterday, to-morrow as to-day? Corn, then, answers to a want which is constant and always equal to itself, provided that man's physical constitution does not undergo radical modifications. Again, its scarcity, that is to say, the relation between the quantity produced and the quan- tity demanded, should equally be regarded as constant from one century to another. That quantity of com is and will always be pro- duced which is necessary to support the inhabitants of a country ; for beneath that limit they would die of hunger : but no greater quantity will be produced, for above that hmit it would be super- fluous, and superabundance would entail an immense depreciation. No doubt this equilibrium may be disturbed by the vicissitudes of the seasons, but the more violent the displacement, the stronger is its tendency to recovery. Now if utility and scarcity, the two essential elements of the value of corn, as of every other value, can be regarded as con- stants, the value of corn itself might be regarded as a fixed point whence we might measure all other values. Unfortunately, these are mere abstractions. It is not a fact that men nowadays eat the same quantity of corn as their forefathers did, at least, if we speak of wheat ; nay, they eat far more ; for in the last century they mainly lived on cereals of inferior quality. On the other hand, it is possible that in the future, if the consumption of meat or vegetables increases, the consumption of corn may decrease. Even admitting that the utility of corn might remain constant, there would still be an element in its value which would continue to be variable ; namely, the greater or less ease with which we obtain it, whether directly by means of agriculture, or indirectly through international trade. Nevertheless, from the point of view of its fluctuations in value, corn certainly possesses quaUties and defects which are exactly / So PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. inverse to those characteristic of the precious metals. For this reason it may be used, side by side with them, as a vakiable enough means of checking them. 2. The value of a day's labor, choosing the least reinune^-a- tive labor. This theory rests on a double idea : on the one hand, that the essential and indispensable wants of human exist- ence are the same for each man ; on the other, that in every society there is a certain class of men who from their wages can only just provide for these primal necessaries of life (see Book IV, "The Law of Brass"). If these elementary wants represent a " constant," the least amount of wages required to satisfy them should also represent a constant value. But this hypothesis is even more chimerical than the preceding one. In the first place, it is not absolutely proved that in every society there is inevitably a part of the population which is reduced to the bare necessaries of life ; in any case it is clear that these bare necessaries are not the same for the serf of the twelfth cen- tury as for the French peasant of to-day, the same for the Ameri- can laborer as for the Chinese coolie. The one would live and have enough to spare on what would but leave the other to die of hunger. 3. The qua7jtity of labor. This doctrine, which was set forth by Adam Smith and Ricardo, has been powerfully developed by Karl Marx. We must not confound this theory with the preceding one, as too many economists have done, with Adam Smith, perhaps, at their head. It is one thing to take as the measure of the value of objects the value of labor, the price of manual labor, wages, in a word, the proposal we were discussing just above. It is quite another thing to take as the measure of their value the quantity of labor, the pains taken in producing them, as is the proposal now before us. The orii^inality of this theory lies in its attempting to measure values not by another value, but by a quantity of quite a different order; this method, then, is radically different from those we WEALTH AND VALUE. 8 1 have heretofore considered. Its principle is, that between the value of any object and the quantity of labor devoted to its pro- duction there is a constant relation, so that the one can be meas- ured by the other. If, then, we ask how are we to measure the quantity of labor itself, the reply is : By its duration, by the number of days or hours devoted on an average to this particular labor. Thus we light on a very simple common measure. This theory is naturally connected with the doctrine which regards labor as the cause of value, a doctrine we have already rejected. But still the present theory is not, as is generally believed, a necessary consequence of the former doctrine. While rejecting the idea that labor is the cause of value, we might still allow that it can serve as its measure. The theory requires the following modifications. It can correctly be asserted that men take the more pains in producing an object they desire the more ; in other words, that they attribute to it a higher value. Just as up to the present we have measured the value of things by the sacrifice a person is willing to make for their obtainal, i.e. by the amount of money given up by the buyer ; so, too, we can measure it (value) by the sacrifice of their time and trouble men are willing to make for their production. In this sense Adam Smith's fine saying can be accepted, — " Labor was the first price, the original purchase- money, that was paid for all things." — Wealth of Nations, I, v, 14. On this theory, then, labor appears to us no longer as the cause, but, on the contrary, as the effect of value, or rather of that desire which constitutes value. Now, once admitting that labor is an effect of value, nothing could be more scientific than the measur- ing of a cause by its effects. Heat is measured by the expansion of bodies, starting from the principle that each increase in length of the thermoraetric column must be proportional to each increase in temperature. Why not grant likewise that the amounts of labor are proportional to the respective natures of the articles ? Yet this theor will always encounter two difficulties : firsdy, that the amo' . of labor, the amount of trouble taken, is but 82 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. very imperfectly measured by the time occupied ; secondly, that even granting that the amount of labor might be gauged by its duration, we should still be without any practical means of calcu- lating the average amount of time necessary for the production of any one article of wealth. (For the development of this objection, see in Book IV the chapter "The Different Formulae for the Divis- ion of Wealth.") III. What is Price ? The value of a thing can be expressed in a thousand different ways. Homer says that Diomede's armor was worth a hundred oxen. A Japanese would have said, a few years ago, that it was worth so many hundredweight of rice ; an African negro, so many yards of cotton stuffs ; a Canadian trapper, so many fox or otter skins ; a Frenchman or an American of the nineteenth century will say it is worth so many francs or dollars. Each of these expressions indicates in its way a measure of value ; but the last only, which measures the value of a thing by the value of a certain quantity of pieces of gold or silver, bears the name of price. The price of an object, then, is the expression of the relation which exists between the value of that object and the value of a certain weight of gold or silver, or more briefly, its value expressed in te?'ms of money ; and as in every civilized country money is the only measure of values, the word "price" has become synony- mous with the word " value." Indeed, it is the only expression for value that we actually employ, though theoretically we may use a host of others. In the same way, for measuring lengths we never speak except of yards, etc., although we may just as well express a particular length by comparing it with a man's size, the height of a tree, or any other length. Nevertheless, we must not altogether confound price and value, as is popularly done, and believe, for instance, that because the price of a thing is the same in two different places its value must necessarily be the same ; or, inversely, beheve that because the WEALTH AND VALUE. S^ price of a thing has varied, its value must necessarily have varied in the same proportion. That might be a gross blunder. If we suppose that the value of the precious metals has not remained the same from yesterday up to to-day, it is clear that the value of every object measured by means of these precious metals will be found to have altered ; that is to say, its price will have varied, and that in inverse .ratio to the fluctuations in value of the precious metals. If the length of a metre, or rather the length of the earth's cir- cumference of which the metre is but a subdivision, were through some startling phenomenon reduced by a tenth, is it not clear that all objects measured by us henceforward would appear to be one- tenth longer or higher? Yet no such change would have occurred ; it would be merely an illusion produced by the shorten- ing of the unit of measure. Similarly, if money, or, rather, the precious metals which constitute it, happened to lose about a tenth of their value in consequence of some far less extraordi- nary phenomenon, say their superabundance, it is clear that the price of all objects, that is to say, their value expressed in money, would seem to us to have risen by a tenth. We can therefore lay down the following formula : " every variation in the value of money involves an inversely proportional variation in prices." Would the reciprocal be equally true, and might we say that every variation in prices presupposes an inverse variation in the value of money? Our answer is, "Yes, if the variation in prices is absolutely general ; no, if it is not so." In the latter case the variation in the prices of certain objects evidently depends on causes peculiar to these objects. Now as the prin- cipal factor which influences the value of money is the greater or less quantity of money in the shape of coin, a second formula can be laid down, which, however, is not so absolutely true as the first one, — " every variation in the quantity of money involves a directly proportional variation in prices." Thus if the quantity of money in a country happens to double, it is probable that, other things being equal, prices will rise considerably, though it would 84 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. be rash to say that they will double. We admit that this second formula is not absolutely true, for quantity is not the only factor which influences the value of money. The development of com- merce, the increase in population, the substitution of instruments of credit for metallic money, may act in different ways on the utility of money, and consequently on its value, irrespective of any vari- ation in its quantity. (See M. Milet's article " un aphorisme or- thodoxe, mais inexact sur la monnaie " in the Revue d' Eco7iomie politique y March-April, 1890.) IV. Whether the Measure of Value be not an Insoluble Problem. The function of a common measure is to enable us to compare objects situated in different places, and therefore incapable of a direct comparison, or to compare the same object at different points of time and ascertain whether it has varied, and, if so, in what proportions. By the use of the yard-measure I am able to compare the stature of Lapps with that of Patagonians, and to measure exactly how much taller the latter are than the former. If the yard-measure is in use, or even known, some million years hence, it would enable me to compare man of that date with man as he is to-day, and to ascertain whether he has degenerated in stature. But it is clear that our conclusions will be accurate only so long as we are certain that the length of the yard-measure used as our standard is exactly the same in Lapland and in Patagonia, and that a thousand years hence it will be just what it is to-day. Inva- riability of the magnitude chosen as a common measure, invaria- bility in space and in time, appears then to be an indispensable condition ; or, at any rate, if this magnitude varies, we must be able to determine, and consequently to correct, these variations. We require the same utility from a common measure of values ; that is to say, from money. By its aid we wish to be able to com- pare the values of commodities situated in different places, or to WEALTH AND VALUE. 85 compare the value of one particular commodity at different times. Is it not of great interest to a corn-merchant to know whether corn has a higher value in France than in Russia, if he has more this year than he had last year? But of what use would our calcu- lations be, if the value of the commodity we take as our unit {i.e. the value of money) was not the same in Russia as in France, not the same this year as last year? Is it not, then, necessary for the value of money, also, to satisfy the condition indispensable for every common measure, — namely, invariability in space and in time ? Now we know from our previous explanation that the value of each thing varies, and that of the precious metals likewise, although in smaller proportions than in the case with the others. Thus the attempt to discover a measure of values would seem to be an insoluble, nay, contradictory problem, a very squaring of the circle for political economy ; this, in truth, is the almost unanimous opinion of economists. Yet we cannot join them. It is true that we must abandon the hope of finding an invariable unit of measure, but this condition is not absolutely indispensable. In no sphere of work, in fact, have men been able to discover a rigorously invariable standard. Even the metre [3.280 feet] of platinum and iridium, which was cast with great trouble and at great expense at the Conservatoire des Ayts et Metiers to serve as standard for all countries which have adopted the metric system, even this varies in length for each degree of temperature. But the coefficient of expansion is known and the necessary rectifica- tions are made. The htre [1.760 pints] of distilled water, which serves as unit of measure for weight, under the name of kilogramme [2.204 pounds avoirdupois], has really a weight which varies for each degree of latitude or each yard of altitude. But we know the law of these variations and can reckon for them. In the same way we should care little for our type of value varying, if only we could discover and determine those variations : that once accomplished, nothing would be easier than the making of the necessarv corrections. 86 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. The whole question, then, resolves itself into this : can we dis- cover and determine these fluctuations? Let us suppose that to-day a hst was to be carefully prepared of the price of all commodities, not one being omitted. Ten or a hundred years hence let a new list of prices be compiled ; if on comparing this with the former one it be found that all prices, without exception, have increased fifty per cent, on such an hypothesis we can affirm that the value of money has actually fallen thirty-three per cent. For henceforward everything that used to cost two shillings costs three ; that is to say, three shillings are only worth what two used to be, and therefore money as coin has lost a third of its value. But it may be asked, what authorizes us to draw such a con- clusion ? The following line of argument : Such a phenomenon as a general and uniform rise of prices permits of but two possible explanations : we can admit — either that things are what they seem to be, i.e. that all commodities have undergone an upward move- ment, which is both universal and identical ; — or that the value of one thing only, say money, has been subjected to a downward movement, no change whatsoever having occurred in the value of all other commodities. Which of these explanations are we to choose? Common sense does not allow a moment's hesitation. In proportion to the simplicity and ease of the second explana- tion is the improbability of the first, in consequence of the mar- vellous combination of circumstances which it requires. How are we to conceive a cause capable of acting simultaneously and equally on the value of the most dissimilar objects, as regards their utility, their quantity, and their mode of production? How imagine a cause able to raise at exactly the same time and in pre- cisely identical proportions, the value of silk and of coal, of corn and of diamonds, of lace and of wines, of land and of manual labor, and of all other things which are not bound up with one another, and in fact are absolutely independent ? The choice of such an explanation would be just as irrational as to hold that the WEALTH AND VALUE. 8/ motion of the stars is better explained by the system of Ptolemy than by that of Copernicus. This movement may be interpreted in two ways, either by the displacement of the entire heavenly vault from east to west ; or, perfectly easily, by the displacement of our earth in the contrary direction. Now, in spite of the lack of any direct proof, we do not doubt for a moment which is the prefer- able and real explanation. It is absurd to imagine that heavenly bodies, so different in nature, and so enormously distant from one another as the sun, moon, planets, bright stars, and nebulous stars, could execute such a movement, preserving their respective places and mutual distances as if they were soldiers on parade. An identical line of argiuiient must be used to account for the upward movement of prices ; it can be rationally understood only as a sort of optical illusion ; it is an apparent movement caused by the actual and inverse movement of money, which discloses it to us and measures it at one and the same time (see Cournot, op. ciL). In reality, the circumstances are not so simple as we have sup- posed them to be for the sake of argument. An absolutely gen- eral and uniform rise of prices will never be shown to occur ; as the value of each individual object depends on its particular causes of variation, we shall only find that certain prices have risen, but in very different proportions ; that others have remained stationary, and that some have even fallen. Yet if skilfully managed calculations could strike a general aver- age, say a rise of ten per cent, this could only be explained, for the reasons given above, by an equal (and inverse) fall in the value of money. This may be paralleled by another analogy borrowed from as- tronomy. The stars, which are inaccurately termed fixed stars, have been discovered, in reality, to change their positions in very divergent directions. Yet astronomers believe they have discov- ered a mean alteration of all these movements towards a specific point in the sky. No other way of accounting for this general movement has been found, than that it should be regarded as an optical illusion, produced by a slipping movement of our solar 88 PRINXIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. system towards an exactly opposite point. An attempt has even been made to measure this latter movement. We can now easily understand how variations of the standard could be calculated from variations in prices, and how tables of these fluctuations could be published at fixed times, to serve as an official guide for the correction of the errors which arise from the use of money as the measure of values ; thus debtors who had borrowed a hundred pounds might be discharged from their obli- gations on the payment of only ninety, or inversely might be com- pelled to pay one hundred and ten, according as the computation showed a rise or a fall of ten per cent in the value of money. Similar tables of reference have been previously proposed in 1822 by Lowe, in 1833 by Scrope. (See Jevons on Money, page 328.) V. Whether Money should be reckoned as Wealth. Popular opinion would give a ready answer to this question. Always — we might almost add everywhere — men have given money a quite exceptional place in their thoughts and desires. They have regarded it, if not as the only wealth, as at any rate by far the most important, and, truth to tell, they appear to esteem all other wealth only in proportion to the quantity of money that can be acquired for it. The value a tradesman places on his goods in taking stock of his wealth means nothing, so long as they are not realized (as he would express it) ; that is to say, are not sold. Thus, in his oi)inion, wealth goes for nothing except when it exists in the shape of coin. For a man to be rich, he must possess either money or the means of obtaining it. It would be interesting to trace through history the various shapes taken by this idea which confounds gold with wealth. There were the attemjjts of the mediaeval alchemists to transmute all metals into gold and thereby accomplish what they termed the f?iagnum opus, which would have been far less a chemical discovery than an economic revolution. 'I'here was the enthu- siasm kindled in the Old World on the arrival of the first galleons WEALTH AND VALUE. 89 from America, convincing men that in fabled Eldorado an end would be found for all miseries. The same idea was manifested in the efforts made by governments to establish that ingenious " Mercantile System " that was to cause money to flow into the countries that had it not, and to prevent it quitting those lands which were possessed of it. Even to-day this old confusion is still extant ; it is visible in the anxious care with which statesmen and financiers watch the goings-out and the comings-in of coin, as they appear to result from the balance between exports and imports. But on turning to economists we shall receive quite another answer ; for it was by a protest against this very idea, which it termed a prejudice, that political economy first manifested its existence. PoUtical economy was but new born and was still stam- mering with Boisguillebert when it sent forth from his lips this utterance : " It is quite certain that money is not a good of itself, and its quantity does not create the opulence of a country." — Econo7nistes du XVII P steck. Edit. Guillaumin, Tome I, page 209. Since Boisguillebert's days every economist has regarded coin with absolute contempt, and has stated it to be a mere com- modity like everything else, and even much inferior to any other article ; for by itself it is incapable of satisfying any want or of affording us any enjoyment, and, indeed, is the only thing whose abundance and scarcity can be said to be matters of perfect indif- ference. If there are few pieces of money in a country, each one will have a greater purchasing power ; if there are many, the pur- chasing power of each coin will be less. What does it matter to us? These two opinions can be easily reconciled, however contra- dictory they may appear to be. The public, as usual, only takes the individual point of view, and is correct according to its own lights ; the economists are right from the general point of view. Every piece of money must be regarded as an " order " or ticket which is valid as regards the sum-total of existing wealth, and gives its holder the right of claiming as his own, and at his own choice, 90 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. any portion of this wealth, until the value of the coin has been reached, Moreover, as may be seen in iSlacLeod's works, this " order " possesses an advantage over credit papers, in that it carries its own security with it ; for it is guaranteed by the value of the metal that composes the coin. Naturally each one of us desires to have the greatest possible number of these orders, and the more we have, the richer we are. We know well enough that, in themselves, these orders can neither stay our hunger nor slake our thirst. We are not so stupid as to think that ; and ages before economists had lighted on this truth, legend had taught it in its tale of King Midas dying of hunger while surrounded by wealth which his own folly had turned into gold. Yet even the contemplation of such a fate has not prevented us from regarding these "orders" as far more convenient than any other kind of wealth, and we are quite right in thinking so. For, in society as it is, every one who desires to obtain an ob- ject he has not produced himself (and the immense majority of people are thus situated) can only obtain it by a double process : firstly, by exchanging the products of his labor, or his labor itself, for money — this is called ** to sell " ; secondly, by exchanging this money for the objects he desires — i.e. " to buy." The second of these processes, purchase, is very simple ; by means of money a wished-for object is always easily obtained. The first process, sale, is infinitely more difficult ; money is not always readily procurable for any article. Thus the possessor of money is in a fir better position than the possessor of any other commodity : for the satis- faction of his wants the former has but one stage to clear, and that an easy one ; the latter has two, and one of them, an awkward bit of ground, presents considerable difficulty. It has been well said that any article of wealth corresponds only to a special and deier- viinate luant, while money corresponds to a ge?ieral and tmiversal luant. The owner of some commodity may not know what to do with it. The possessor of money will have no trouble of that kind ; he will always find some one to take it from him. If by chance he is not able to make use of it at the moment, he has the handy WEALTH AMD VALUE. 9 1 expedient of keeping it for a more favorable opportunity. Few other goods can be kept in that fashion. But the possession of money carries with it what is perhaps an even greater adv^antage ; for he who has money can make sure of being able to fulfil his engagements : no other wealth enjoys this remarkable quality ; for in the eyes of the law, just as in the un- written law of custom, money is regarded as the only means of discharging liabilities. There is no business man or manufacturer who does not always owe more or less considerable amounts. Now his having in stock goods worth more than the sum-total of his debts might be useless (and in cases of failures it sometimes happens, when all reckonings have been made, that the assets exceed the liabilities) ;^ unless at the desired time he is able to get his signature honored by that particular form of wealth which we call " hard money," he is declared bankrupt. Is it surprising, then, that so great importance is attached to a commodity on the possession of which our credit and our honor may at any moment be dependent ? If we turn from the position of the individual man, and con- sider the whole mass of individuals who constitute society, the point of view changes, and there is more correctness in the econo- mists' thesis that the amount of money in a country is a matter of indifference. It would be no use to me to have the amount that I hold multiplied by ten, if the sa^ne thing happened for all the other members of society. On that hypothesis I should be no richer ; for wealth is purely relative, and I should not be able to obtain a larger measure of satisfaction than I previously had. For as there is no increase in the sum-total of wealth from which these " orders " are payable, each order will entitle me to a share, which is ten times less. In other words, the purchasing power of each coin will be ten times less ; or again, all prices will be multiplied by ten, — and my position will be as it was. However, in their 7nutual triations, countries, like individuals, ^ In the crisis in the London Money Market, November, 1S90, the great House most seriously affected is said at the time of its stoppage to have had assets exceeding its Habilities b) no less than ^^4,000,000 sterling. — J. B. 92 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. gain by being well provided with money, but rather less, however. As exchange relations and credit transactions between countries are not so numerous as they are between individuals, money, whether as the instrument of purchase or of payment, is not so important a f:ictor in such relations. Still, the increasing solidarity of the nations will tend to proportionally enhance the power of money in this field. If we were to multiply by ten the amount of money in France, there would be no change in the respective position of Frenchman as against Frenchman (the increase being premised to be propor- tional for all) ; but France would not be on the same terms as regards foreign countries, and so obvious a fact is erroneously denied by economists in their struggle against the mercantile sys- tem. Their very abundance would cause pieces of money to be depreciated in France, but not elsewhere ; they would retain intact their purchasing power in foreign markets, and France might thus obtain an increase of satisfaction which would be in proportion to her increase of money. However, as we shall show when dealing with international trade, this privileged position could not last long. The economists' dogma, that the quantity of money is a matter of indifference, does not become perfectly true till we not only extend our view over all individual men, and over all countries, but embrace in our observations the human race at large. We might then assert with absolute accuracy that the discovery of gold mines, a hundred times more valuable than those we are now cognizant of, would not benefit man in the least. Nay, we should rather be inconvenienced ; for, as gold would be worth no more than copper, we should be compelled to load our pockets with as cumbrous a form of money as that which Lycurgus sought to force upon the Lacedaemonians. BOOK II. PRODUCTION -»<>♦- Part I. — The Conditions of Individual Production. THE FACTORS OF PRODUCTION. Our first study will be the conditions of individual production, that is to say, such conditions as every man is subject to, even though he be alone in the world, like Robinson Crusoe on his island. After that we shall study the conditions of social pro- duction, the conditions experienced by men living in society, which only arise, or at any rate develop, with the progress of civilization. Thanks to a tradition which has nowadays become altogether classical, production has three agents attributed to it, — land, labor, and capital. This threefold division possesses the advantages of simplicity and ease ; its demerit is that it does not state what should be stated, and does state what should not be stated. To begin with, it errs in placing on a footing of equality ele- ments of production which are extremely unequal in importance, and are very different in their mode of action ; it ranks together labor, which is actually the age7it of production, and capital, which is oijly an instrument ; it puts on the same grade labor and nature, which are the original factors of all production, and capital, which is merely a factor of the second order, being a derivative product of the two first. 93 94 PRIN'CIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY, Again, it is incomplete ; for it omits certain conditions of pro- duction which are as important as those it enunciates, e.g, time, the environment, and so forth. The process of individual production should be represented as follows : — Man is the sole agent of production, understanding the word " agent " to mean that it is he alone who can take the initiative in every productive enterprise. This activity of man, in so far as it is employed for the production of wealth, is called labor. But this energy cannot work in the void ; it does not emanate from a creative fiat ; for its fertility it requires certain external conditions which we shall now enumerate. Thev are five in number. 1. Raw material. Man, as we have just said, cannot make anything out of nothing. This is then a sine qua non — as it is, indeed, for the wealth that is wrongly called non-material, or services rendered. Human speech is only air in motion. 2. A certain extent of groimd. For the production of anything some place is required, were it only sufficient to hold a work-bench or a loom. 3. A certain duration of time. Man's activity is limited by time as much as by space. No act of production can be instan- taneous. We shall see that this condition, like the preceding one, far from being purely metaphysical, has consequences which are of serious economic importance and of great practical interest. 4. Certain tools. In production man cannot dispense with those implements which, as has been well said, play for him the part of supplementary organs. Of the numerous definitions which have been proposed for distinguishing man from animals, " maker of tools " is certainly one of those which fit him best. 5. A favorable environment, which is composed of climatic, geographical, and geological conditions. Man's activity, like that of every other living being, is subordinated to the environment in which he lives and should evolve. Such is the order in which the conditions of individual pro- duction should be analyzed. Still, although persisting in regarding PRODUCTION. 95 the old tripartite division as a vexatious one, we have been obliged to adhere to it at least in form. Indeed, for us, in a book like this, to break with a classification which has been unan- imously adopted in all books and in courses of instruction,^ would be to confuse our readers. All that we can do is to try and fit these conditions into the classical frame as well as is possible, though some, indeed, do not easily lend themselves to such an attempt. We will now take in succession land, or rather nature, labor, and capital, and seek under each of these three heads for the various conditions just enumerated. 1 Dr. Bohm-Bawerk, /Capital- Zifts, Vol. II, 2>2, (English translation by Smart, p. 79), recognizes only two productive forces — Nature and Man. See Hai-vard Quarterly Journal of Economics^ April, 1889, p. 337. — J. B. CHAPTER I. NATURE. By the word " nature " we must not understand a fixed factor of production, for that would be meaningless, but rather the whole body of the pre-existing elements supplied to us by the environ- ment in which we live. The term "land" was formerly employed instead of "nature." The expression, indeed, is equivalent in extent, if we are to under- stand by it not simply cultivable ground, bu*- the terrestrial globe. No doubt, our planet, and merely the superficial crust of that, is the only portion of the universe 'vvhich can serve as the field for our economic activity. Still, as savage tribes have been known to make use of the crude iron they have discovered in fallen aerolites, and as we directly borrow the sun's light for our photographic pro- cesses and its her*- for " Mouchot " machines, taking all in all, the term " nature " is tiie more accurate. Now, for man to produce aught, nature, as shown in the previ- ous section, must provide him with a favorable environment, a large enough extent of ground, and raw material which can be utilized. Ground might be said to be included in our term, " environment." It is so philosophically, but not so, economically : for ground is an object of property, whereas the environment is not : thus ground is a separate element. She also supplies him with the natural forces which work his machines. We will say a few words on each of these four ways in which nature collaborates with man. I. The Environment. It is possible that some historians or philosophers, like Mon- tesquieu may have exaggerated the influence of the geographical environment on the social and political development of peoples, 96 PRODUCTION. 97 but it would be difficult to exaggerate this influence so far as it concerns economic development and productive power. Air, water, and land have all had a decisive influence on the evolution of human societies. Le Play's school builds up the whole of social science from this question as to the environment. It distinguishes three kinds of ground which give rise to the three types of primitive societies : the steppe to the pastoral races, the seashore to the fisher tribes, the/^r^i-/to the hunter peoples. These are the fundamental types of simple societies, i.e. those which subsist purely on the spontane- ous products of the soil ; but Le Play's school goes further and derives from them by relation of necessary affiliation, all the complex, or, in other words, civilized societies. Thus from the primitive state of the soil it accounts for the origin of the establish- ment of property, of the family, etc. This system has been treated in a very interesting manner by M. Demolins in the Revue de la science so dale, iS86. I. Tlie climatic situation. Tropicallands may have witnessed the growth of brilliant civilizations, but they have never been favored with laborious and industrially fertile races. For there Nature seems to discourage productive activity both by her gener- osity and by her outbursts of violence. In those blissful climates where " bread grows like a fruit," and clothing and even housing are scarcely required in consequence of the warm temperature, man comes to rely upon nature and spares himself all effort. On the other hand, in those regions physical forces are so exceed- ingly violent, their various manifestations, torrential rains, floods, earthquakes, cyclones, are so irresistible, that man is cowed and does not even conceive the audacious idea of conquering them and turning them to his own ends : he scarcely dreams of meas- ures of self-defence. In our temperate lands Nature is niggard and severe enough to compel man to rely in great measure upon his own efforts ; but the forces she displays are not so awe-inspir- .ing as not to allow human industry to tame her. In this way she may be said to favor productive activity both by what she refuses and by what she gives. ^8 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. 2. Geographical configuration. Were it not for her insular position, who would ever dream that England would have become the first maritime and commercial power in the world? If a proof were necessary of the dominant part this factor has played in the destinies of England, it would be supplied by the curious feeling of terror which possessed her lately at the mere prospect of being united to the Continent by a submarine tunnel. Why has the continent of Africa, known to man from the remotest antiquity and the seat of the earliest of all civilizations, that of Egypt, remained to this very day out of the sphere of all economic movements? why, on the other hand, are the two Americas, the dis- coveries of a mere yesterday, cut in all directions by the currents of commerce ? The chief reason is to be found in the difference of their river inter-communication. The rivers of the New World flow into the ocean by huge estuaries, and are joined together by such an intricate network, that we can pass from the tributaries of the River Plata into those of the Amazon and thence to those of the Orinoco, and in the northern continent from the basin of the Mississippi to the Great Lakes, almost without leaving the water- way ; but all the African rivers, though no less large, greet the explorer at the lower parts of their course with a barrier of impass- able cataracts or of pestilential swamps. 3. The geological co7istitution of the soil and sub-soil exerts no less influence ; for it is this which creates agricultural and metallurgical wealth. The dread with which England calculates the time when her coal mines may begin to fail her, shows well enough how much she owes them for her industrial development. China has her "yellow" earth, and Russia is no less a debtor for her rich "black earths" — r/V/i literally, not merely figuratively ; for according to statisticians they contain nitrogen to the value of 640,000,000 pounds sterling. It would appear at first sight that man is unable to modify the environment with which nature has surrounded him, that his only resource is to adapt himself to it as best he can. Yet he does succeed in exercising some modifying influence on this very envi- PRODUCTION. 99 ronment, though it, perforce, is extremely Hmited. As regards geology, he cannot create mines where there are none, but by judicious agricultural improvements he can remake the cultivable soil in detail, and make arable tracts of the sites once occupied by marshes, stagnant ponds, and even gulfs of the sea. As regards geography, he cannot alter the great marking lines drawn by Nature, but with a little favor on her part he can succeed in modi- fying them. Thus he can complete a network of inland water- communications, can overcome the barriers raised by mountains and arms of the sea, by constructing roads either above or, bet- ter still, beneath them ; and greatest of all, can separate Africa from the Old World continent, and South America from the New World, thus turning these two peninsulas into two islands. Cli- mate certainly cannot be changed ; but by plantations on a large scale, by fitting cultivation, perhaps, too, by other means, the secret of which we hav^e not yet guessed, human industry will be able to advantageously modify the sway of rain and even of the winds. Thus some scientific men have proposed to alter the course of the great maritime currents, such as the Gulf Stream, for the purpose of distributing heat or coolness among the conti- nents, just as water and gas are distributed in towns. II. The Ground.' Man needs a certain amount of space on land, were it only to stand on. He requires rather more to sleep on, still more to build his house on, and far larger room for the sowing of his corn or the pasturing of his flocks and herds. Now this question of room becomes very serious as soon as the population of a country has grown sufficiently dense. When human beings, in obedience to 1 The word "land," which is ordinarily used, is a very complex combination of ideas ; first comes a superficial extension, which we represent by the word '■'ground'" ; then there are raw materials exemplified by the elements which compose the soil and the subsoil; finally come a number of physical and chemical agencies which are ever at work in cultivated ground in the form of light, heat, humidity, electricity, and so forth. lOO PRIN'CIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. their 'sociable instincts, group together in one of those huge ant- hills called London or Paris, New York or Hankow, the necessary space for housing them ends by becoming deficient ; then plots of land acquire a higher value than that of the buildings which cover them, even were they palaces made of marble ; and as we shall see when dealing with house-rent, the resulting social conse- quences are most deplorable for the working-classes. However, we need not fear that one day there may not be room enough on the earth for men to live on ; yet it is not unreasonable to ask whether there will always be enough space for men to obtain food from. For the portion of ground necessary to supply food for one man is of considerable size, and this portion is always being diminished by the progress of civilization and agricultural methods. For hunter peoples several square leagues are needed per head ; for pastoral races some square miles ; for agricultural nations a few acres are enough ; and the Hmit falls as men pass from cultivating the land far and wide to cultivating it thoroughly and deeply ; i.e. from extensive to intensive cultivation. In China this latter mode of cultivation, which has almost become kitchen-gardening, enables several men to subsist on the produce of two and one-half acres. Yet this defect, though considerably lessened, still con- tinues, and tends to make the human race somewhat anxious as to its future. No doubt, when the required space begins to fail him, man will be able to seek it elsewhere. The discovery of the New World, of South Africa, and of Australia has enormously extended his territory and renders certain enough room for many generations still to come. Yet these reserves stored up for the future will be exhausted some day. Now if we are already somewhat anxiously estimating the amount of coal we still have to burn, we can reckon far more easily the amount of earth that remains over for us to lay hands on. There is no hope of discovering any new lands. Though the surface of the globe is- not yet entirely occu- pied nor even known to us, still it is all measured out. Before another century has passed away the last vacant spot will have PRODUCTION. IQI been filled up, the last landmark will have been planted, and henceforward the human race will have to content itself with its fifty-two million square miles, without the hope of increasing it by new conquests. Its only consolation then will be to repeat the fine that Regnard inscribed, with a presumption the future has falsified, upon a rock in Lapland, '' Et stetimus tandem ubi defuit orbisT III. The Raw Material. The inorganic substances which compose the earth's crust to the slight depth to which we have been able to penetrate, and the organic bodies which proceed from the vegetable or animal living creatures which people its surface, supply industry with the raw material that is indispensable to it, and form the original elements of all wealth. Some of these materials Nature has spread about with lavish profusion ; of others she has been excessively sparing. Among the former may be mentioned some of the constituents of the earth's crust, — granite, chalky matters, clay, and the fresh or salt water which covers three-quarters of the earth's surface. But those carbon-crystals we call diamonds, and even some metals, such as gold or mercury, are found in exceedingly small quantities. Even the substances that exist in large quantities may be scarce if some one particular region be considered. No doubt there are enough stone-quarries in the world to build thousands of capitals like Paris, but all the same they may be absent from the required site of some city, say Nineveh of old time, or London to-day. Sea-salt is unbounded in amount, but is scarce enough in Central Africa to be used for money. Fresh water is the typical example of wealth which is unlimited in supply, yet we need not go as far as the Sahara to find places where water is scarce, and can only be obtained with much engineering toil. In fact, there is only one body which is ubiquitous and immeasurable ; to wit, the atmospheric air which surrounds and envelops the entire globe 102 ^ PRINXIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. with a uniform layer. But even this air is not within the reach of every one, if special conditions of salubrity, coolness, or heat are required. An arid plot at Cannes or Nice sells for ^4 a yard. Why? Because what is paid for is not merely the right to the ground, but the 'right to an atmosphere and a sun that are not found elsewhere. As regards the materials which are superabundant but unequally distributed, human ingenuity can remedy such a disadvantage by removing the substances and transporting them to spots where they are lacking. Hence, as we shall see later on, transportation is really an act of production. But since matter, owing to its weight and inertia, opposes a powerful resistance to any attempt at removal, and since the labor and expense necessary for the overcoming of this resistance increase in proportion to the dis- tance to be covered, industry is not all-powerful, and can only relatively harmonize the inequalities of nature. Nevertheless, men are now so well furnished with implements for this kind of labor, that the effect produced is by no means small. It is clear that man cannot increase in amount substances which are really restricted in quantity. It is not for him to create one atom of matter. Yet, by the aid of chemical combinations or decompositions, he can build up the bodies he requires. If the stock of diamonds ever runs short, he may be able to manufacture more by crystallizing coal ; or if coal, in its turn, ever becomes exhausted, he may succeed in extracting it from the carbonates of lime which are so very common in the earth's crust. In other cases, human industry will have to restrict itself to discovering some substitute ; i.e. some substance possessed of properties analo- gous to those of the missing body. This search is usually more or less successful ; for there is such an infinite variety of organic substances and lifeless matter, that some can be found which possess common characters, and can therefore, to a certain extent, supply one another's place. Animal ivory is threatening to become extinct in consequence of the wasteful and destructive mode of elephant-hunting ; but in the forests by the Amazon a substitute has been found in a vegetable ivory. PRODUCTION. 103 IV. Motive Forces. The work of production consists purely of changing the place or the form of matter. We have seen that, because of its vis iney-tice, matter resists this treatment, and man's muscular strength is not very great. Nevertheless, by the invention of tools, man has been able to create artificial organs which have wonderfully added to his strength and dexterity. Thus, by means of a hydraulic press, a child can exert unlimited pressure ; and Archimedes justly boasted that with a lever and a fulcrum he could raise the earth. Yet some mathematicians have taken the trouble to calculate, that, even if he had found his missing fulcrum, he could have raised the world only to an infinitesimally small height, even by work- ing for some million years. For it is a law of mechanics that when using tools man loses in time what he gains in strength. By them he can lift a weight a thousand times heavier than he could by his arms alone, but he will have to take a thousand times as long over the process. Now, time being a very precious element, which we should be chary about wasting, the practical advantage of the use of tools is comparatively limited. On the other hand, the employment of machines multiplies strength indefinitely. In all times, therefore, and especially since the abolition of slavery has denied him the gratuitous employment of the strength of his fellows, man has striven to fortify his weakness by the aid of certain motive forces supplied to him by nature. There are not very many of them, though too favorable reckonings have been made. In truth, there are only four which man has been able to use in production : the muscular strcjigth of animals ; the motive fo7'ce of winds and of water ; and, best of all, the expa?i- sive power of vapors, especially of steam. It should be observed that in proportion to the powerfulness of these natural forces have been the time and trouble necessary for man to expend before succeeding in utilizing them and turning them to his ends. This is natural ; for resistance increases in 104 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. direct ratio to the force. These results have been effected by the aid of viachities. A machine is but a tool or implement, which instead of being moved by the hand of man, is worked by a natural force (water power, steam, etc.). Now a difficult problem in mechanics is involved in this handling of a natural force which is sometimes irresistible, sometimes unseizable, so as to compel it to turn a wheel, push a plane, or work a shuttle. The domestication of various animals, such as the horse, camel, elephant, reindeer, and Esquimau dog, supplied mankind with the first natural force they used for carrying, draught, and tillage. That of itself was a valuable conquest ; for an animal is propor- tionally stronger than man. A horse's strength is estimated as seven times greater than a man's, and the food he requires is by no means of greater cost. But the number of. such animals in a country is restricted in proportion to the increase of population, for they require much space whence to obtain food ; thus the motive force they afford is, relatively speaking, not of any great account. The motive force of the wind and of rivers has always been used for carriage, and at a later date, though still at a high an- tiquity, for turning mills. These, indeed, are most powerful agen- cies. The motive power of streams in France alone, which is uselessly expended in wearing out pebbles, has been calculated to amount to thirty millions horse-power ; that is to say, to a force equal to the strength of all the men of an age fit for work, who are to be found on earth at the present moment. One single waterfall, such as Niagara, would feed all the factories in England. In the few hours of its devastating existence, a cyclone develops enough motive force to keep going all the workshops in the world for a thousand years, if we only knew how to use it. The waves into which the wind furrows the bosom of the sea, the tides which twice a day break on thousands of leagues of coast-line, form literally inexhaustible reservoirs of force. Unfortunately up to the present man has found no mode of turning them to account. They are still in a savage or untamed state, sometimes too power- PRODUCTION. 105 ful or too weak, too irregular or too intermittent. Thus the forces which might raise the world are even now scarcely used but to turn a few wTetched mills. The expansive power of vapors, or rather the heat generated by combustion, of which this force is only a transformation, grants man the priceless advantage of being able to develop it whej-e, when, ami as he will. It is mobile, portable, continuous, large or small according to demand. We raise it from one up to ten atmospheres, and theoretically, at- least, there is no limit. If water was heated to 516 degrees Centigrade, a not exceedingly high temperature, we should develop a pressure of 1,700,000 atmos- pheres, which is more than sufficient to raise the Himalayas. The only difficulty would be the discovery of a strong enough envelope. In fact, this force is artificial, being created not by nature, but by man : he has made it for his own use and works it as he wishes. No more obedient slave has ever bowed under a master's yoke. The prehistoric inventor, whose name will forever remain un- known, but whom the gratitude of mankind has deified as Pro- metheus, he who first caused a spark to spring from the friction of two pebbles, never suspected when he looked on this flame, which was certainly due far more to chance than to his genius, what mar\'ellous power he was granting to human industry. First of all, no doubt, fire ministered only to the humblest wants of domestic life. Later on it was used for the extraction, the found- ing, and the working of metals. Its utilization as a motive force dates from the time that men discovered the explosive power a spark could communicate to some substances, i.e. gunpowder, and in this form it is still employed, not only to propel projectiles for a mile or two, but also to bore tunnels. But it was not till New- comen, in 1705, and James Watt, in 1769, had used it for dilating steam confined in a chamber, and had thus created the wonderful instrument of modern industry which we call the steam-engine, that fire, or rather heat, became the guiding spirit of industry. I say that the steam-engine is a "wonderful" instrument, for the sake of the services it has rendered us. In reality it is very I06 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. defective ; for it utilizes only a small part, at most a tenth, of the heat generated by the combustion of the coal. There is great waste from the furnace to the boiler, and further, though smaller, waste between the boiler and the engine proper. Hence the remark of M. Le Bon, an engineer, " I hope that before twenty years have passed, the last specimen of this rude machine will have taken its proper place in museums, side by side with the stone hatchets of our primitive ancestors." It will be seen from the following that anxious speculations may justifiably be made as what would happen to human industry if, the supply of coal ever failing, furnaces had to be extinguished, and it could no longer generate at will that heat which is indis- pensable to it as the source of motive power. People sometimes try to set their minds at ease by such foolish proposals as that of replacing heat by electricity, though the only practical means we have of producing electricity on a large scale is precisely the steam-engine. Men are already beginning to ask whether it is not possible to utihze the immense forces whose activity is displayed in those movements of the atmosphere and of the waters, to which we referred just now, or if it will be necessary to draw the heat which we require from the source of all force, the sun itself. There, in truth, is a really incalculable fount of force, which is estimated to be equal to 9^ millions of horse-power per square mile. This is already used by the Mouchot machine, but in a practically insuffi- cient manner. Even admitting the success of such an attempt, this force borrowed from the sun will have the disadvantage com- mon to it with the other natural forces, of not possessing the property of being generated where, when, and as we wish. It will not be manageable. The sun does not shine always or every- where. If on that orb is to fall the task of keeping our workshops going, England will be doomed as a manufacturing and industrial power ; the fogs of the North Sea will become her winding-sheet, and men will henceforward have to journey into the heart of the Sahara to build their industrial capitals ! PRODUCTION. 107 Still, to be able to avail ourselves of these natural forces, we only require to find the secret, on the one hand, of transportijig them for long distances, so as to apply them to the point where they can be utilized, and, on the other hand, of storing up those forces which are developed only intermittently, so as to employ them at the moment when they are required. Electricity seems capable of rendering us this double service. The fact is already established that force can be transported, just as a despatch, by a simple telegraphic wire, but one made of copper and somewhat larger than the ordinary wires. Moreover, electricity can be stored up in accumulators that are already used to propel steamers, tramways, and balloons. In that quarter, perhaps, lies the germ of a beneficent revolution in industry. If some day motive force could be distributed from house to house, Hke water or gas, and could be obtained by the mere turning of a tap,^ we should see no more of those huge work- shops, which to the laboring classes are as unhealthy quarters, from the hygienic as they are from the moral point of view, and which, together with other disadvantages, render family life impossible. 1 This is being clone even now, to some extent, in Germany, where the small concerns still employ more hands than the large (in 1882, four millions as against three millions). See an article by Dr. Albrccht of Berlin in Schmoller's Jahrbuch fur Geseizgebiing (1889), 13th series, Part II. — J. B. CHAPTER 11. LABOR. I. On the Part played in Production by Labor. To achieve its ends, and principally to satisfy the necessities of existence, every living thing is obliged to do a certain amount of work. The seed has to toil to raise its covering, the hardened crust of the earth, and then breathe the air and feel the light. While clinging to its bed, the oyster opens and closes its shell in order to draw from the surrounding water the first elements of nourishment. The spider spins its web, the fox and wolf labor while they hunt their prey. Man is not exempt from this univer- sal law ; he, too, has to persevere and toil in order to supply his wants. As Xenophon says, "The gods sell us all good things at the price of our labor." Among plants this striving is unconscious, among animals instinctive ; with man it becomes a voluntary and conscious act, and its name is labor. But is there not some wealth that man can obtain without work, such wealth as nature lavishly bestows on him? It must first of all be observed that there is not a single product which does not in some measure presuppose the intervention of labor. That follows from the meaning of the word "product," productum, " drawn from somewhere." Rut what could have performed this drawing or extraction except the hand of man? For the application of fruits to the satisfying of our wants, even those fruits which nature has given us, such as the bread-tree fruit, the banana, dates, or. those shellfish which in southern lands are called sea-fruit, man must have given himself the trouble of gathering them. Now, this gathering is clearly labor, and under certain circumstances work of an exceedingly laborious nature. 1 08 PRODUCTION. 109 It should further be remarked that a just conception is not usu- ally made of the important part played by labor, even in the for- mation of those products which are often very inaccurately termed " natural." We are too ready to believe that everything which grows on the earth — cereals, vegetables, fruit — all are due to the generosify of that alma parens renitn. As a matter of fact, most of the plants which supply man with food have been, if not created, at any rate so modified by the cultivation and the labor of hun- dreds of generations, that botanists cannot discover their original t\^es. Wheat, maize, lentils, beans, have been found nowhere in the wild state. Even such species as are met with in a state of nature are wonderfullv different from their cultivated congeners. Between the acid berries of the wild vine and our grapes, between the edible vegetables and succulent fruits of our kitchen-gardens and orchards and the tough roots and the bitter or even poison- ous berries of wild varieties, there is a vast difference ; so great, indeed, that these fruits and vegetables may be regarded as arti- ficial products ; that is to say, as actual creations of human indus- try. Here is the proof. If the constant labor of cultivation be relaxed for a few years, these products speedily degenerate ; i.e. they revert to a state of nature, losing all those virtues with which human industry had endowed them. It is true, however, that some wealth is not the product of labor, precisely because it is not a product ; i.e. it pre-exists before any act of production. I refer to the earth and all the organic matter or inorganic substances wath which it supplies us, — the bubbling spring of water or petroleum, the growing forest, the natural prairie, the stone-quarry, the coal or metal mine, the waterfall suitable to turn a mill-wheel, the guano-bed deposited by sea- birds, the fishery banks teeming with fish, shellfish or coral ; in a word, the original source of the elements of all our wealth. These, surely, constitute wealth, and of the first rank in order of importance, but they clearly exist independently of any labor done bv man. Still for a just conception of the part played by labor in pro- duction, we must add two further points. I lO PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. 1. Such wealth does not exist, qua wealth, i.e. as useful and valuable objects, until human intelligence has been able, firstly, to discover their existence, and furthermore to perceive that they possess qualities which render them fit to satisfy any of our wants. Let us take, for example, any piece of land, say a corn-land in America. Why is this wealth? Because some explorer or pioneer, following th-e course Christopher Columbus first opened out, has discovered the existence of this particular spot. Now the fact of discovery, whether it be applied to a New World or to mushrooms in a wood, always presupposes a certain amount of labor. 2. Again, such wealth cannot be utilized, i.e. employed for the satisfaction of man's wants, until they have been subjected to more or less labor : in the case of virgin soil, till it has been cleared and opened out ; with a mineral spring, till it has been secured and bottled ; with mushrooms or shells, till they have been gathered. Thus even with wealth w.hich is termed natural, labor is seen to be a real agent of production ; for without it, such objects would be virtually non-existent for us, inasmuch as they would serve no purpose for us. In a word, it is labor which discovers and utilizes them. Of course, we do not imply by this that natural wealth obtains all its value from labor; we have already rejected that theory. According to Bastiat, all natural wealth is gratuitous, i.e. valueless, because such objects are the free gift of nature, and may be held to preser\'e that character in all the successive transactions through which they may pass. But the most ordinary observation suffices to give the lie to that theory, which, indeed, was merely conceived to defend landed property from the reproach the socialists bring against it, of monopolizing the gifts of nature which should be the common property of all men. As value is based on utility, all natural wealth, such as virgin soil, gold-bearing strata, guano, etc., possesses a value which exists before any act of labor. For a long time the government of Peru has had no other income but the sale of its guano. PRODUCTION. I I I II. How Labor produces. When we survey the infinite variety of products which rise from under the fairy fingers of human industry, we are apt to imagine that labor is a power which is infinitely complex in its methods, and which defies all analysis. Yet it is nothing of the sort. Labor is merely a muscular force directed by some superintending intelligence : it can have no effects but those of a motive force, and that, a very weak one ; viz., a movement, a change of place. This displacement may be a change of place of the object itself, or of its component parts. In the latter case, we say that there is a change of form, but every transformation amounts to a displacement. The exquisite shapes assumed by clay under the hand of the potter or the statuary, the rich and ingenious patterns wrought on lace by the fingers of the lace-maker, have no other cause than the arrangements, or rather, the displacements, of the molecules of clay or the threads of the tissue. All that man's labor can do is to stir, separate, reunite, insert, superpose, and arrange effects which are only different modes of motion. Take the production of bread, and pass in review the various acts of this production, — ploughing, sowing, reaping, winnowing, grind- ing, sifting, kneading, putting in the oven, — they are nothing but movements and changes of place effected upon matter. Analyze any other industry, and no other factor will be found ; for this is the only part man plays in the work of production, this is the limit of his power. All the profound transformations which are effected in the constitutions of bodies and which by modifying their physical or chemical properties conduce to production, — the mysterious evolution of a plant from its seed, the fermentation which turns a sugary syrup into alcohol, the chemical combination which turns out steel from the furnace iron, — these are not man's work. His part has been limited to placing the materials in the required order : the corn in the earth, the vintage in the vat, the ore in the furnace ; nature has done the rest. Yet, however feeble this motive force may be, it is strong 112 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. enough to transform the world ; for it is exerted by an intelligence which knows how to turn it to the best possible use. Man's strength is relatively feeble when compared with that of animals. For instance, it is one-seventh of a horse's, though a horse is not seven times heavier, and is certainly not seven times larger. Still, we must say, that though man has less muscular force than the animals, he has generally more dexterity, and this he especially owes (as the very name shows) to that marvellous organ we call the hand. Every physical labor, properly so-called, must be preceded by a purely intellectual labor which we term ''invention" ; this consists in discovering the practical means of turning to our ends the forces we have power over, and the objects to which they can be applied. Invention is not, as might be believed, a rare gift which can only be displayed by a few learned men ; on the contrary, it is intimately bound up with every act of production. The Paris knick-knack maker who fabricates for the shops some fresh New Year's Day toy at a farthing apiece, the joiner who tries to make the best use of a plank, are also inventors in the accurate sense of the word. There is no movement of a workman's arms or fingers, there is no combination or organization of labor, which has not been originally invented by some artisan. From this point of view we can say that human intelligence is the first, nay, the only agent of production. However, when once made, invention has the power of ser\'ing as the basis of an unlimited number of acts of production, or, rather, of re-production ; hence the difficulty which the legislator experiences in regulating and protecting the inventor's right of property. The words " invention " and '* discovery " should not be confounded, and, indeed, popular speech has well distinguished between them. It is correct enough to say that Christopher Columbus discovered America, but we should laugh if we were told that he had invented it. Discovery is the revealing of the existence of an object which was previously unknown (such as a PRODUCTION. 113 land, a substance, a star, or a new property of some already dis- covered body). Invention is the conceiving of some new mode of turning to account elements of which we are cognizant and over which we have power. Thus discovery may be regarded as the initial act in the process of production, the first link of the chain from which all the others are hung. Every land now under cultivation, all the wealth that we use, each force that we employ, must at some time or other have undergone this process of discovery. III. What Kinds of Labor should be called Productive ? Economic doctrines on this question of productive labor possess a very curious history. The title of " productive," which was primarily reserved for a single class of labor, has gradually been extended in its application, and has ended in being indiscrimi- nately bestowed on all species of work. The school of the physiocrats conjEined the epithet "produc- tive " to agricultural labor (including therein, hunting, fishing, and mining), and denied it to every class of labor, even to manu- facture. The reason assigned was, that it is the first-named industries alone that furnish the materials for all wealth, and that all other labor is merely engaged in the working of these materials. This definition of the physiocrats was clearly too narrow. Raw material, as it is handed over to us by agricultural labor or extrac- tive industry, is usually altogether unfit for consumption ; it has to undergo numerous modifications which are effected by matiu- factiiri7ig industry. Manufacture is the indispensable complement of the former labors, and without it the process of production is as incomplete as a play with the last acts suppressed.' Of what use would the ore be at the pit's mouth, if it were not to go thence to the forge or the foundry? Of what use would corn be, if it had not to pass through the hands of the miller and the baker? Were it not for the weaver's labor, flax would be no more useful than the nettle. How, then, can we refuse to these labors the / 114 PRINXIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. title of " productive " ? for without them all these kinds of wealth would be useless to us ; in other words, would not be wealth at all. It is altogether a mistake to think that agricultural and extrac- tive industries create wealth, whilst manufacture only transforms it. As we have already shown, the agriculturist himself merely transforms the simple elements he has borrowed from the soil and from the air. He makes corn from water, potassium, silicon, phosphates, and nitrogen, just as the soap-maker fabricates his soap from soda and fatty bodies. Hence, from Adam Smith onwards no one has hesitated to include manufacture in productive labor. There has b^een a longer hesitation as to the labor of transport^ for the act of transport does not appear to effect any modification in the object. The bale of goods is the same at the station where it arrives as at the station whence it came. That, it is said, is a characteristic distinction from manufacturing industry. The drawing of such a distinction is scarcely philosophical, for every act of displacement effects an essential modification in- bodies ; indeed, as we have just seen, is the only modification we can cause in matter. \\\\2X we call transformation in manufac- ture is nothing but an arrangement ; in other words, a change of place of the component parts of substances. If we were to deem a displacement not to be a sufficient modification to be termed productive, we should have to refuse that appellation to extractive industries ; for what is the miner's work save the transporting of ore or coal from the bottom of the shaft to the surfcice of the ground ? Now what distinction can be established between such labor and the wagoner's work in taking this ore or coal from the pit's mouth and carrying it to the works, — unless we assert that displacement is productive when it is exercised vertically, but is no longer so when horizontal ? Besides, it is scarcely necessary to add, that just as manufacture is the indispensable complement of the agricultural and extractive industries, so, too, the labor of transporting is the requisite complement of its predecessors. What would be the use of stripping bark trees in Brazilian forests, PRODUCTION. 115 of extracting guano from the Peruvian islands, of hunting elephants for their tusks in South Africa, if we had no sailors and carriers to convey these products to the places where they are to be used ? What profits it a landowner to have the finest crop in the world, if the lack of a road prevents him transporting it? It is just as if he had no crop at all. With regard to covimcrcial industry the hesitation has been even longer. For it may be noted, that the process of trade reduced to its lowest terms, i.e. to the act of buying for the purpose of selling again (for that is its legal meaning), does not imply any creation of wealth. No 'doubt those who engage in it may make. much money, but that does not add to the general wealth ; in truth, we shall see that the multiplication of business men and middlemen may become a veritable scourge for modern societies. Thus, if commerce can be classed among productive labor, that can only be done with great reservations. On the other hand, we must observe that men of business are most usually occupied with the transport of goods, as is the case with shipowners who carry on the export or the' import trade. In a certain measure, too, merchants may be regarded as the actual directors of transport all the world over : the carrying industry only executes their orders. Moreover, they preserve goods in the shape of stock in hand. They even subject them to certain modifications : the cloth merchant cuts his strips, the grocer roasts his coffee, etc. It is through them that the commodity comes into the hands of the consumer, and thus the cycle of pro- duction is closed. Finally, discussion has been keenest with regard to services rendered, such as those afforded by the liberal professions ; for it may seem strange to call "productive" the labor of the surgeon who amputates a leg, or of the executioner who cuts off a head. However, this last step has also been taken, and now without halting at antiquated and pedantic distinctions, we have come to place under the heading of productive labor all labor that in any wav whatever contributes to the satisfaction of the wants of man. Il6 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. It is a logical consequence of the theory we have expounded, that services rendered, as well as material objects, should be placed in the list of articles of wealth. However, it is of Uttle importance whether this new departure be accepted or not, and if material objects alone are allowed to rank as wealth. The term " produc- tive " should be taken in the widest possible sense. In the social organism, thanks to the law of the division of labor, there is such a solidarity between the labors of men, and they are so closely related, that it is impossible to separate them. Take the production of bread. We need not hesitate about classing as productive labor the respective toil of ploughmen, sowers, reapers, wagoners, millers, and bakers, beginning with Triptolemus, the legendary inventor of corn, and all his successors who have discovered the varieties of cereals and have invented the rotation of crops, or the methods of intensive agriculture. But we cannot restrict ourselves to pure manual labor. It is clear that the labor of the farmer or of the lord of the manor, though he may not himself have put his hand to the plough, is very useful for the production of corn, just as the shepherd joins in the production of wool though he does not shear the sheep himself. Neither can we ignore the work of the engineer who has prepared the plan of a system of irrigation, or of the architect who has constructed the farm-buildings and the barns. Must we stop here ? We might ; but have not the following also contributed to the production of corn, and should not their work, too, be termed productive ? I refer to the county police- man who has frightened away robbers, to the public prosecutor who has prosecuted them, and to the judge who has sentenced them ; nor should I forget the soldier who has protected the year's crop from even worse ravagers ; viz., foreign armies. What shall we say of the labor of those who have moulded the agriculturist and his men, of. the instructor who has taught them their ideas of agriculture or has put them in the way of obtaining such knowl- edge, of the doctor who has kept them in good health ? Is it a matter of indifference for the production of corn or any other PRODUCTION. 117 wealth, that the workers be well taught and of sound constitution ? Are we to disregard the question as to whether they are well ad- ministered and governed, are in possession of order and security, and enjoy the benefits of a good government and good laws? Are we justified in putting aside the kinds of labor which are the most alien from agricultural pursuits, those of writers, poets, and artists? Are we to think that the taste for agricultural labors, and conse- quently the production of corn, cannot be usefully developed in a society by novelists who depict scenes of country Ufe, or by poets who celebrate the pleasures of rural occupations and teach us to repeat, after the author of the Georgics, — " Fortunatos nimium sua si bona norint Agricolae"? Where, then, are we to stop? We see the circle of productive labor extending to infinity, to the farthest bounds of society, like those concentric circles which spread on the surface of the water round the centre we have agitated, and which are lost in the dis- tance, vv'ithout the eye being able to perceive the limit where they stop. No doubt the various kinds of labor we have just passed under review have not contributed to the production of corn in the same way ; some have acted directly, some only indirectly ; but none of them, beginning with the ploughman's toil and reach- ing to the occupation of the President of the Repubhc, could be suppressed without the cultivation of corn suffering therefrom. Still, though we cannot make definite distinctions between these various kinds of labor, yet, proceeding from the centre to the cir- cumference, we can establish a sort of hierarchy arranged, not in order of dignity, but according to their economic utility. The most important for the wealth of a country are labors of discovery and invention ; then come agricultural pursuits, next manufacture, after that the labor of transport, and last of all com- merce and official employments. The fewer the people engaged in these last two kinds of labor, the better it will be. However elementary this classification may appear to be, its Il8 PRINXIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. exposition is not a needless one ; for every day it is utterly misun- derstood by customs and by laws. Thus governments spend mil- lions on developing means of transport without first finding out whether there is anything to transport ; and thus, too, the number of people engaged in retail trade or in official employment in- creases every day, while agricultural pursuits are more and more abandoned. IV. On Pain as a Factor of Labor. All productive labor presupposes a certain amount of toil, and this is a law of supreme importance in political economy. Indeed, if labor was not a toil, pain or difficulty, all economic phenomena would be other than they now are. For instance, if men worked for pleasure, there would no longer be any raison d'etre for individ- ual property so far as it may be regarded as the just recompense for labor and the necessary stimulus to human activity, which indeed is its principal basis. In that case the most serious objec- tion that can be brought against communism would fall to the ground. ■ Fourier, the socialist, perfectly understood this : thus the pivot he gave to the future society that he proposed to organize was attractive labor. He asserted that labor was painful solely on account of a flaw in the organization of our modern societies, and he boasted in his phalanstery that he would make labor attractive for all men by free choice of avocations, variety of occupations, shortness of tasks, esprit de corps, emulation, and a hundred other combinations, some of them ingenious, some fantastic. Why not ? it may be said. Labor, taken as a whole, is only a form of human activity ; now activity has nothing painful about it. To act is to live ; it is absolute inaction which is a torture, and so cruel an one that when it is too prolonged in solitary confinement, it will kill the sufferer or turn him mad. There is no essential difference between labor and a number of exercises which are regarded as pleasures, though they often require an expenditure of PRODUCTION. 119 Strength higher than that needed by labor ; e.g. mountaineering, boating, gardening, even dancing. If Candide took his pleasure in cultivating his garden, and Louis XVI his in making locks, why cannot all men reach this stage of working for the love of it? The answer is, that man only takes pleasure in action in so far as he can obtain satisfaction from the mere exercise of this activity, in so far as this exercise is a natural function. But when this activity is seen in the light of the condition of an ulterior enjoyment, as the effort which he must make to achieve an aim fixed before- hand, — and that is the very essence of labor, — then it becomes painful. Between a boating man who rows for pleasure and a boatman who rows to earn his Hving, between a tourist who climbs a mountain and the guide who accompanies him, between a girl who spends her evening at a ball and the dancer who appears in a ballet, I see only one difference : the first in each pair row, climb, or dance solely to row, climb, or dance ; the others do so to earn their living. This difference, though a purely subjective one, causes the same modes of activity to be regarded as a pleasure by the former, as a toil by the latter. The man who follows a road only for a walk may take pleasure in it, if it presents any attractions, but he who passes over it night and morning only to reach a fixed point always finds it long and wearisome. Now for almost all mankind labor is a path upon which they enter for the necessity of living, and therefore, in accordance with the old curse in Genesis, they have labored " in the sweat of their fece." Doubtless even the humblest labor has its joys, the joys of duty fulfilled and of a natural law voluntarily accepted ; but these austere pleasures will never be felt except by a few chosen spirits, and we should fall into the most chimerical optimism if we flattered ourselves with the hope of one day seeing all men labor solely for pleasure ; i.e. without requiring the stimulus of self- interest or the orders of compulsion. In order, then, to induce man to work and to counterbalance the feeling of pain which is occasioned by all labor, a higher force 120 PRLXCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. is needed : for the slave this is the scourge, for the free laborer it is the desire of satisfying his Vvants. Thus every man who labors is the prey to two conflicting feelings : on the one hand, the desire to satisfy some want or to obtain some enjoyment ; on the other, the wish to escape the pain caused by his work. According as one or other of these desires turns the scale, he wdll continue or will abandon his labor. As Stanley Jevons ingeniously observes, the pain endured by the worker incessantly increases in proportion to the prolongation of the labor, while the pleasure he derives from it constantly di- minishes in proportion as his most pressing wants begin to be satisfied. Thus out of the two desires, the one requiring him to work, the other inviting him to stop, it is clear that the latter will sooner or later gain the day. Take a laborer drawing buckets of water from a well. Fatigue increases with each fresh bucket he has to draw ; on the other hand, the utility of each bucket decreases ; for if the first was necessary for drinking and cooking purposes, the second will only serve for watering cattle, the third for cleaning purposes, the fourth for watering the garden, the fifth for sprinkling the road, etc. At what number is he to stop ? That depends partly on his power of supporting fatigue, but chiefly on the scale of his wants. The Esquimau, who only uses water to quench his thirst, will stop at the first or second pail ; the Dutch- man, who cleanses his house right up to the roof, may have to draw fifty buckets before he thinks he is sufficiently provided with water. Productive activity can be greatly increased if the stimulus of future requirements is added to that of present and actual needs ; if, for example, in a land where water is scarce, the worker thinks of filling a cistern in readiness for the days of drought. But this faculty of weighing together an immediate pain and a distant satisfaction — a faculty which is really called foresight — belongs only to civilized races. It is characteristic of the French peasants, a stock which is laborious though frugal ; a fact which shows that they labor less to satisfy their present needs, which are very few, PRODUCTION. 121 than to provide for future wants, whether those of old age or of their famihes. V. On Time as a Factor of Labor. If all labor involves a certain amount of pain, it also requires a: certain expenditure of time. We have already seen that this is one of the essential conditions of all production, a condition which is absolutely universal ; for Nature herself, as far as she is associated with man in the labor of production, is equally subject to it ; there must be long months of waiting before the seed, slumbering in the furrow, can become the ear, and long years before the acorn develops into the oak. Between the moment when labor begins and the date when it gives the expected results, there is a more or less long lapse of time ; but we may hold it to be a general law, that the longer this period is, the more productive the work should be. It may be short (a few hours are enough) for labors which enable man to live from day to day, from hand to mouth, such as hunting, fishing, or the plucking of wild fruits ; but for agricultural works, large industrial enterprises, or those engineering achievements which do honor to our time, such as mines, artesian wells, railways, tun- nels, canals, — for such as these the requisite time becomes enormous and proportionate to the hugeness of the results.^ How many years will go by between the first stroke of the pickaxe on the Isthmus of Panama and the passage of the first ship through the proposed canal? This condition of all productive undertakings is, as we shall see, one of the very chief causes of the importance of capital and of the privileged position of the holders of capital. Indeed, as he must live while he is waiting for the result of his work, the laborer can attempt nothing without the aid of certain advances, and these are supplied by the capitalist. 1 This point is worked out in full detail by Dr. Bohm-Bawerk in his Kapital- Zins, Vol. II (1889); English translation by William Smart, 1891. — J. B. 122 PRINXIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. It is not enough to state that time is an indispensable factor of all production ; we must add, further, that man has only a limited amount of time to dispose of, not only because his life is short, but because numerous deductions have to be made from that. We must take into consideration the following : Firstly. Man cannot work every hour in the day. We must certainly deduct time for sleep and for meals, and experience has proved that nothing is gained from the point of view of production by extending the duration of the working-day. Custom and even law fix this at ten or twelve hours, and the famous formula of the " Three Eights " now tends to a general reduction to eight hours, which would give only a third of the day for labor. Compare with this the refrain of the old English song, — " Eight hours to work, eight hours to play, Eight hours to sleep, eight shillings a day," which has been brought into fashion again by the recent dis- cussions as to the limitation of the hours of labor. As a matter of fact, if we assign a third of the day for sleep, a third for labor, that is to say, for the requirements of economics, and the remain- ing third for the satisfaction of wants of another kind, but which are no less important for man's development, viz. the duties de- manded by family life, social intercourse, education, physical and intellectual recreation, — if such a portioning out of time is to be the normal one, there will obviously be no more space left for labor. Seco7idly. Man cannot work every day in the year, and there is no country in which there are not a certain number of holidays. England and America rigorously obey the order to observe the Sabbath; the English, moreover, take Saturday afternoon; all this, with some other holidays thrown in, amounts to rather more than eighty days a year. Russia, with its numerous saints' days, has even more. Countries which, like France, pride themselves in being above the sabbatical superstition, gain nothing by that ; for if they do not keep Sunday as a day of rest, they compensate for PRODUCTION. 123 that by taking Monday, which is observed as a hohday in many French trades.' It is rare for even the most industrious of Parisian workmen to reach an average of 300 days' labor a year. Moreover, days of iUness must be reckoned for. Here, again, we must remark that to increase the number of working-days and restrict the days of rest, would only result in a useless expenditure of man's productive strength. Thirdly. Man cannot work/?;- all the years of his life ; we have in all cases to deduct the years of infancy, and also those of old age wherever that state is reached. Let us suppose that the normal length of life is 70 years ; let us suppose, again, that the period of productive labor begins at 18 and ends at 60, — both estimates being certainly exaggerated ; then, even granting such conditions, we should have to subtract 28 years out of the 70, or 40 per cent. It is clear that the power of productive labor of any individual depends on the relation between the two periods of his life : on the one hand, the unproductive period, with its two sections, childhood and old age ; on the other hand, the productive period. While really young or really old, an individual not only does not produce, but also consumes. From a purely economical point of view, it would be by far the best for each man to die just at the end of his productive, and before entering on his unproductive, period. If he dies before this, so much is stolen from his years of production ; if he dies after this, his unproductive years are added to. It is in accordance with this line of argument that some peo- ples slay their graybeards. In all countries, without exception, the average length of man's life is far from reaching the above- mentioned figure, viz. seventy. It usually varies between forty and fifty years as the maximum. Thus the time during which the productive powers are exercised represents a half or at tlie most three-fifths of a man's hfe. 1 This practice, which the French term " f£'ter le luncli," is represented by the "St, Monday" of EngUsh compositors, — Translator's Note. 124 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. From this point of view, the most favored country is that which can show the largest number of men between the ages of eighteen and sixty, or in the period of " useful life," as the saying is. Thus regarded, France is not unsatisfactorily situated. This distribu- tion of ages depends in particular on the average duration of life in any society. The longer that is, the greater the chance of a large number of adults. Yet highly erroneous conclusions might be reached from following too closely this line of argument. If in one country half the children died unweaned, and in another country the same number of children died at the age of fifteen, the latter country would certainly possess a higher average of duration of life, but still would be far worse off from a productive standpoint. In it the proportion of useless mouths would be much greater. Both on economical and even sentimental grounds, it would be better that every child lost at the age of fifteen had ceased to live when six months old.^ To recapitulate : Let us take a man who has worked from the age of 1 8 to 60 at the rate of 300 days a year and eight hours a day. When he reaches the age of 70, and looks back on the past, he will surely be able to say that he has spent his life well, yet he will have worked only 100,800 hours out of the 613,200 he has lived, or rather less than a sixth. After these considerations, it is not surprising that man seeks to economize time, and that the most active peoples of our day have taken as their motto, "Time is money." 1 This argument seems to prove too much. There is no reason for stopping at six months, /xri vyai rhy diravTa fiKa \6yoi/. — J. B. CHAPTER III. CAPITAL. I. On the Part played in Production by Capital. It would appear that man's labor, aided by nature, ought to be sufficient for production. Animals, sure enough, have to meet the necessities of their existence by their own activity and the objects supplied to them by nature. Yet observation shows that if man's labor and nature are left alone face to face, they are extremely likely to remain eternally sterile. For human industry something more is needed ; to wit, a certain amount of wealth which has been previously acquired. Numerous authors have told the stories of men of the Robinson Crusoe type, and have striven to show us man grappling, unaided, with the necessities of existence ; but there is not one of them who has neglected to endow his hero with some tools or pro- visions which are usually saved from a shipwreck. These writers know well enough that without this precaution the story would have to stop after its second page, for their hero's life could last no longer. What was it that these Crusoes lacked? Had they not the resources of their labor and the treasures of a fruitful though virgin nature ? Yes ; but there was still something want- ing, and as they could not do without it, the writer had to see to their obtaining it. What was it ? ^^'hy, pre-existing wealth, capi- tal. This is the name given to the third factor of production. But we need not go so far afield as Robinson Crusoe to become convinced of the utility of capital. The heart of our civilized societies presents situations similar to his. In present-day com- munities there is no more difficult problem than the acquisition of anything when the aspirant possesses nothing. Take one of the 125 126 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. proletariat, a man without any means, — what is he to do to produce what is necessary for him to hve on, to earn his Hving, as we say? A httle reflection will show that there is no kind of productive industry that he can adopt, not even the poacher's occupation, for that would need a gun, or at any rate, snares ; nor a ragpicker's, for that would require a hook and a basket. Thus he would be as wretched, as helpless, and as surely destined to die of hunger as a Crusoe who had saved nothing from his shipwreck, were it not that the social organization came to his assistance by supplying him with the means of producing something by the aid of wealth previously acquired by others. This wealth he can obtain in various ways, either by contracting loans (a highly improbable proceeding, for only the rich find lenders), or by contracting for wages, putting himself in the pay of an employer, who on certain conditions supplies him with raw material and the implements necessary for production. Such is the usual position of the pro- letariat. Some socialists appear to think that such a state of things is abnormal, and is due to the defective organization of society. The case is quite otherwise. This quasi-impossibility of acquir- ing new wealth without the aid of pre-existing wealth is a natural law, which is the same for the savage as for the civilized man, the same in prehistoric times as it is now. Yet however great be the importance of this third factor of production, it is only the product of nature and of labor. Though nowadays it has acquired such weight as to rank equally with its fellow-workers, and sometimes even to take precedence over them, still we must not forget that logically, historically, and genetically, capital proceeds from the two prime factors. It is not an agent in production, as is too often said, but an instrument, an auxiliary, whose aid, it is true, man can no longer dispense with. Once upon a time, however, he was obliged to do without it. It is obvious that the first capital of the human race must have been formed without the help of any other capital. Man was once upon this earth as resourceless as Crusoe on his island, and had to solve the difficult problem of producing the first PRODUCTION. 127 wealth unaided by any pre-existing wealth. That no doubt was an anxious moment to go through, analogous to the overcoming of the dead-stop of a locomotive. With his hands alone man had to set a-going the huge wheel of human industry. But, when it was once in motion, the most difficult part of the task was done, and henceforward the slightest impulse has been enough to give it a velocity which is ceaselessly accelerated. Yes ; in the history of mankind there has been a terrible crisis, a long and agonizing parturition; but after that, wealth once engendered and conceived has only had to develop and grow almost of itself. The first, nay the most shapeless of all created wealth, were it but the flint split in the fire of the anthropoid apes, immediately served as a means of making new wealth under slightly more favorable conditions, and these in their turn have served to create others, the facility of production increasing, so to speak, in a geometrical progression, in proportion to the amount of wealth already acquired. But we know that a geometrical progression, though growing with a dazing rapidity after having reached a certain point, increases terribly slowly during its first terms. Our modern societies, then, who, living on the accumulated wealth of a thousand generations, make almost a jest of multiply- ing wealth in all its shapes, ought not to forget how slow and per- ilous was the earliest accumulation of the first wealth ; they should think, too, of the manv centuries throuirh which the first human societies had to pass, through the dim ages of hewn stone and of polished stone, before they could put together their first stock of capital. Many peoples, no doubt, miserably perished while thread- ing that terrible gorge ; it was reserved only for a few picked races to effect a passage successfully and reach the rank of capitalist societies. Of them we may say ad augusta per a?igusfa ! II. The Meaning of the Productivity of Capital. As a general rule the part played by capital in production is not accurately understood. 128 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. People imagine that all capital yields a revenue in the same manner as a tree bears fruit or as a hen lays eggs ; i.d. that the rev- enue is a product made exclusively by capital, and then possessing a separate existence. What largely aids in the propagation of this false notion is the fact that the greater part of capital is seen by us in the shape of government securities, shares, or debentures, from which, according to the customary formula, coupons are de- tached which stand for the revenue. For six months, three months, or a year, according to the nature of the stock, the coupon grows ; when the day -of payment comes, it is ripe and can be detached. Furthermore, just as after a fruit or a seed has been gathered, it can be sown again, and a fresh plant be formed to bear more fruit, just as after an egg has been laid it can be put under a sit- ting hen, and a chick be hatched in its turn to lay more eggs, — so by investing this coupon at interest a new capital can be formed which will yield new dividend coupons for interest ; in this manner men imagine that they see capital growing and reproducing itself in accordance with the same laws as regulate the reproduction of the species of the vegetable and animal kingdoms. But the law of compound interest is wonderful in quite another fashion than the increase of herrings or of mushrooms, which is so often quoted with reference to the theories of Malthus and Darwin. A mere farthing put out at compound interest on the first day of the Christian Era would have yielded by now a value equal to that of some thousand millions of globes of solid gold of the volume of our earth : the example has become classic. We must pack off to limbo all this phantasmagoria which so strongly and so naturally stirs the bile of the socialists. It is all pure moonshine, this attribution to capital of some productive and mysterious power peculiar to itself alone ; this generative faculty is a mere figment. Whatever the popular saying may assert, money bears no children ; ^ no more does capital. Not only has 1 We may compare with this the saying of Carlyle : " Were a pair of breeches ever known to beget a son?" i^Life in London^ I, 193, letter to Sterling, on the Church.) — J. B. PRODUCTION. 129 a bag of gold pieces never produced a gold coin, as Aristotle observed long ago ; but a bale of wool or a ton of iron has never borne a flock of wool or an atom of iron. If sheep do reproduce other sheep, as Bentham said, imagining that he refuted Aristotle by saying so, it is not because sheep are capital, but merely because they are sheep; for nature has endowed living beings with the power, never enjoyed by capital, of reproducing individ- uals similar to themselves. But capital is dead matter, and is absolutely sterile ; it enables labor to produce, but of itself pro- duces not a jot. Therefore all that men call the revenue, or the product of capital, is, in reality, only the product of labor. The illusion is caused by the sight of many people hving on their income without working, and even rapidly increasing their fortune. We ask. Whence does this income spring? It is cer- tainly not the product of their labor, for they are -engaged in no industry or occupation ; nor is it from any natural agency, for on the terms of the hypothesis they are not landowners. Can it not, then, perhaps, proceed from capital itself which would thus spon- taneously produce it? In reality, this income is altogether the product of labor, of labor which is not seen, but can be readily traced if well sought for ; it is the labor of those who have bor- rowed the capital of the fundholders and have employed it pro- ductively. The interest coupons of colliery shares or debentures in coal mines represent the value of tons of coal extracted by the labor of miners, and the coupons of railway shares or debentures stand for the results of the joint labor of all who have co-operated in the transport of commodities. It may come to pass that capi- tal, after reaching the hands of the borrower, has been wasted or unproductively consumed ; yet in that case the interest received by the lender represents the product of some labor, if not that of the borrower, at least that of some third party. For instance, the coupons of government bonds and securities do not betoken wealth produced by the laborer or the industry of the State, for the State does not produce, and is wont to spend unproductively most of the capital lent it ; no ! these coupons stand for the 130 PRIN'CIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. product of the labor of all citizens, which in the shape of taxes has been yearly poured into the treasury chests, and has thence passed into the hands of stockholders. Thus what we wanted to prove stands thus : the receipt of a fixed income is simply the levying of a quota on the product of some one's labor, a levy which may perhaps be justified by the assistance capital has afforded labor. But that is not the point in question. III. The Distinction between Wealth which is Capital and Wealth which is not. The idea of capital is clear enough to us all. In looking over our property we at once perceive that it can be divided into two classes of goods. Those in the first division are destined to ob- tain for us in a direct manner some enjoyment or some satisfac- tion ; e.g. food, clothing, dwelling-houses, ornaments, ridmg-horses, pleasure parks, pocket-money. The second category comprises objects whence we obtain an income ; such as forms, places of business, docketed securities, factories, machines, tools, stock in trade. We make use of the former for our personal ends, or for our family requirements ; from the latter we try to get profit. For this last-named category of wealth we reserve the name '* capital." This distinction between wealth which is capital and wealth which is* not appears to be very simple. But when we look at it closer, we find that it bristles with difficulties, so that the definition of capital presents one of the most arduous problems in political economy. We must begin by remarking that a great number of objects which have different properties, and therefore varied utilities, can figure equally well under either of the two classes, according /o the use to be made of them. Thus the determination whether an object is, or is not, to rank as capital often depends far less on the object's nature than on its destination. A diamond is capital when used by a glazier for cutting panes PRODUCTION. 131 of glass ; it is not capital when set in a ring or an earring. In the first case it is employed on account of its hardness ; in the second because of its brilliancy. An egg is capital when given to a hen to hatch for the reproduction of chickens ; it is not so when put into a frying-pan to make an omelet. In the one case we use the life-giving power which it contains in the germ state ; in the other we only avail ourselves of the nutritious matter it is composed of. Coal is capital when thrown into the furnace of a steam-engine, for the utilization of the motive force it contains in the latent state ; it is not capital when stirred on a hearth-grate merely for the sake of giving us warmth. There is no need to give further instances of these contrasts, which might be indefinitely multi- plied. We might almost say that there is no product which can- not, somehow or other, be apphed for a twofold end. This is particularly the case with a highly important class of products : all those which under the shape of victuals, clothing, shelter, or any sort of provisions, tend to support man's produc- tive strength. These also are of twofold application, and accord- ing to circumstances are or are not capital. For the laboring man, food is surely no less indispensable for the act of production than are tools or raw material ; the nitrogen and the carbon (which he consumes as meat or as bread) play just the same part as the coal which is burned in a steam-engine, and are themselves trans- formed into muscular force. Therefore all food, when regarded as victuals, stored for future use, is placed by most economists under the head of capital. On the other hand, has any one dining at a restaurant or in the bosom of his family ever regarded the dishes appearing during the course of the meal, were they even in the shape of tinned meats, as implements of production and as fuel for his bodily mechanism? No ! he only desires them to appease his hunger or to tickle his palate. Stanley Jevons asserts that stores of food are typical capital, and are its essential and primordial manifestations whence all the other forms have sprung. Indeed, his premise is, that the true fiinction of capital is to support the worker while waiting for the 132 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. moment when his labor can give good results. This definition of the function of capital necessarily requires it to exist under the shape of means of subsistence, of advances. Of these, all tools, machines, railways, etc., would be only derivative forms, for their production takes some time, perhaps a considerable period ; and hence they must have required a previous amount of advances in the shape of stores of food. It is to this primary form, therefore, that we have always to return. The simplicity and elegance of this theory make it attractive. Nevertheless, though we have previously expounded and defended it in \\\^ Journal des Economistes, October, 1881, we now think that it is rather too exclusive. Time certainly forms one of the essential conditions of, or, say, a limit to, every act of production. (We have already dwelt on this fact.) Still, it does not seem correct to draw from this the conclusion that all productive labor necessarily demands a certain advance in the shape of food. Man did not put off entering on agricultural pursuits till he had stored up provisions to last for a year ; he had sown and tilled the ground in the interval between his hunting expeditions. Before attempting to pierce the Isthmus of Panama, the Company did not amuse themselves with heaping together eatables to feed an army of laborers for eight or ten years. They had to live on the supplies {\\n\\%\\tdi pari passu by the labor of the rest of mankind. Nothing, either in primitive or in civilized societies, resembles these vast hoardings of food which Stanley Jevons regards as capital par excellence ; on the contrary, the whole of the provisions of a country is produced day by day. Besides, it is not our opinion that the only function of capital is to maintain the worker till his labor gives actual results. The flint picked up and cut by quaternary man, the ox yoked to the plough by the first agricul- turist, certainly did not fulfil that function, but nevertheless they were decidedly capital.^ ^ See Dr. Bohm-Bawerk, Kapital-Zins, Vol. II, Bks. iii, iv, ii, D, pp. 337 ^^Q' ^Smart, pp. 319 id. Thus there is a saving of a penny on each pound, which, multiplied by 38,000,000 of Frenchmen, con- suming one pound per head each day, and for the 365 days of the year, would make an annual sum of ^23,000,000, — a rather higher sum than the interest on the French national debt, which in 1887 was ^35,000,000. PRODUCTION. 261 There is no reason to fear that we shall be driven to always import without ever exporting, for imports inevitably excite exports. Inversely, there is no reason to expect to be always able to export without ever importing, for exports necessarily cause imports. Besides, if in the process of international trade all countries were resolved to play exclusively the part of seller, and none of them agreed to play the part of buyer, how would trade be possible ? There is no reason to fear that imports, by making us the cus- tomers of foreigners, will put us into dependence on them, for it is not usually the case for customers to be dependent on their tradesmen. On the contrary, it is the tradesmen, rather, who seek to court the good graces of their customers. Finally, there is no reason to fear that imports will entirely do away with the national labor, for people forget that every importa- tion entails an exportation of equal value, and that consequently the national labor will recoup itself in one quarter for what it has lost in another. We need not then take as serious the appalling picture just set before us — that of a nation driven from its territory by foreign competition, and compelled to emigrate to a foreign land. Even admitting that a country might be unlucky enough to be inferior to its neighbors in all branches of production, none the less it would be obliged to produce, in order to pay for the foreign products it might wish to consume, unless we are to suppose that foreigners would be generous enough to supply the country gratui- tously \vith all its necessaries, in which case its position would be a not unenviable one. And if a country did happen to be reduced to this situation of general inferiority, if it was really poorer than all other countries, if for the same or even a larger amount of labor it could only procure a smaller amount of satisfactions — well, it is certainly not prohibition of foreign products that could change such a situation in the least, or could prevent the inhabitants of that country from emigrating en masse, if ever misery gained the day over affection for one's native land. On the contrary, the nations of Europe would be unable to obtain food, and therefore to keep at home their ever-increasing 262 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. population, unless they were to import from abroad larger and larger supplies. Even now, England, in order to sustain on her limited territory her daily increasing population, is obliged to derive from imports 77iore than half oi her consumption of cereals, meat, drink, etc. The home production of these articles was, in 1883, reckoned to be ;£" 169,140,000, and the importation of the same articles at ^174,660,000 (Stephen Bourne, in th.e Journal of the Statistical Society, September, 1883). To return to the dangers feared by protectionists. It is true that free trade, precisely because it enables the same amount of satisfaction to be obtained with less labor, which is the characteristic feature of all progressive production, may diminish the demand for labor in the very proportion of the economy real- ized and the progress accomplished. It is true that free trade almost always involves, especially at its beginning, great displacement of labor, which at certain points may cause the ruin of the capital sunk or the throwing out of work of the laborers employed, and these effects may take the shape of literal catastrophes. It is true that a country may be fearful of seeing sink, under the weight of competition, some one industry which it judges to be essential to its security ; such as the manufacture of arms, of pow- der, and even of locomotives, dockyards for the construction of war-ships, and even, in a certain measure, of merchant shipping, the breeding of horses, perhaps coal mines or iron fields ; or the industries may be such as it considers to be useful for the satis- factory working of its social constitution, such as the agricultural industry in general, or certain domestic industries. It may fear, too, especially if it be a new country, of seeing growing industries nipped in the bud, which, if they had had time to develop, might have borne fine fruit. In new countries, indeed, growing industries have to contend with great disadvantages. It is not easy for them to compete with industries of old standing, which are in possession of vast markets, and which, thanks to the extent of their production, can • PRODUCTIOX, 263 push to their utmost the improvements of division of labor and of production on a large scale. The struggle is the more arduous, because, in new countries, wages are higher and laborers less experienced. We all know that it is not easy to grow young trees in the neighborhood of old ones ; for, as the latter have already appropriated all the light of the heaven and all the sap of the soil, the younger trees have room to spread neither their roots nor their branches. Thus we understand well enough that the Aus- tralian colonies, who supply the whole world with wool, are desirous of turning it into cloth themselves, instead of sending it to England, to have it manufactured there, and then returned to them. In the same way, if the French colony of Algeria were to turn its alfa grass into paper on the spot, instead of exporting it in the raw state into England, or if Senegal could turn its arachides (ground-nuts) into oil, that would be a great gain, not only for them- selves, but for the whole world ; for there is no more sterile labor than that of transporting from one end of the earth to the other •a dead weight and useless material ; that is a true labor of Sisyphus, for every useless act of conveyance is an useless waste of labor. Even if it were necessary for them to bear a certain sacrifice for some time, in order to put their manufactures into a state of stability, to enable them to take root and successfully compete with foreign manufactures, that, in our opinion, would be an ex- pense well incurred, which one day would be repaid them with interest. It must be confessed that this theory seems to be confirmed by the example of the United States, who, guarded by that rampart of protection that they had reared, have so brilHantly effected their economic evolution, and have become one of the chief man- ufacturing countries in the world. Would American industry have gro\\'n so quickly had it had, from its first beginnings, to struggle against English manufactures, and might it not have been nipped in the bud by its powerful rival ? That is at least a question of debate. It is also worthy of note that most of the English colonies, 264 PRINX'IPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. * nearly all the Australian colonies, Canada, and so forth, although reared in the traditions of free trade, have felt the necessity of having recourse to the protectionist system. Within these limits the dangers pointed out by the protection- ists are real, and within these limits we agree with them that the State has the right and the duty to guard against these dangers by the means that it judges to be best fitted to that end. The dogma of inadmissibility urged by the liberal school against every intervention of the State touches us httle, not only because this principle has no absolute scientific value, but especially because the question here rests in the domain of politics rather than in that of economy. The point is to determine, not the best possible mode of commercial or industrial organization, but the best mode of preserving the industrial and commercial power of a particular country. We do not deny that the system of protection is a burden to the country which is obliged to resort to it, and that it entails considerable sacrifices ; in that we fully agree with the free-traders; we only add that a country does not hesitate to lay* on itself equal or even heavier sacrifices, when the question at issue is to preserve its political, military, maritime, or colonial supremacy. Why should it not do the same for the purpose of saving its industrial or commercial supremacy, for that is of at least equal importance both for its national existence and for its destiny? IV. On the Disadvantages of Protective Duties. If we can grant the essential idea of protectionism, viz. that the State has the right to protect in certain particular cases the industries that are useful to a country, still in our opinion the means employed for that end do not appear to be justified, al- though they have been hallowed by a practice of several centuries : we refer to the laying of import duties. Numerous disadvantages are presented by this mode of pro- cedure. PRODUCTION. 265 Firstly. It fails to achieve the proposed end, for it brings about an unequal protection, which is insufficient for the weak and useless for the strong. Take a duty of two shillings on the hundredweight of corn, which raises the price of corn from 8 to 10 shillings. The landowner who cultivates inferior land or who has but scanty resources, who produces merely ten hundredweight the acre, will only reap an increase in his income of 10 shillings, which probably will not be enough to cover his expenses ; whereas the landowner who being already favored by nature or by im- proved methods, grows thirty hundredweight the acre, and conse- quently could very well do without any protection, will find that his income is increased by ^^3 the acre. Secondly. It grievously shackles foreign trade, for by reducing the importation of goods // reduces exports in the same proportion ; it is therefore in most flagrant opposition to the efforts that nations are making to facilitate communication, to pierce through moun- tains, to cut through isthmuses, to furrow the seas with lines of subsidized steamboats and telegraph cables, to open international, exhibitions, to establish monetary conventions, and so forth. Thirdly. It does the greatest harm to industrial production by raising the cost of production, either directly by the increased dearness of raw material, or indirectly by the increased dearness of manual labor. Hence spring permanent and insoluble con- flicts between the various branches of production : if import duties are put on wools or silks to protect the producers of sheep or silkworm cocoons, there arise outcries for the silk-weavers and wool-spinners ; if import duties are put on wool, silk, or cotton threads, the weaving industries are ruined. The complicated mechanism of the treatment of "goods for re-exportation" is an altogether inefficacious palliative. Fourthly. It does still greater harm to the material production by removing the stimulus of foreign competition. In a political speech Prince Bismarck spoke of those pike that are put in carp- ponds to keep the carp active and to prevent them burying themselves in the mud. That simile is especially appropriate 266 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. here. If we desire — and that is the protectionist's desire — a country to maintain its position as a great industrial and commer- cial power, it must be compelled constantly to renew its tools and machinery and its methods of work, ceaselessly to eliminate worn- out or obsolete organs, just as the snake which renews its youth by casting its skin. As this operation is always a disagreeable one, it is doubtful whether producers would submit to it with a good grace, were they not obliged to do so by an exterior power. Fifthh. Finally, and above all, it nurses in the country a fatal illusion, in caitsifig if to regard as a gain wJiat is really a burden. The advocates of protective duties assert, in fact, that as import duties are laid on foreigners, they do not burden the country at all ; nay, that they actually add to the income of the state. This illusion, the benefits of which the protective system has reaped, has made its fortune, but ought really to be enough to condemn it. For the effect of import duties is to add to the price of com- modities, not only of the imported goods, but also of similar articles which are consumed at home, so that the public pays out from its pocket, in the shape of higher prices, ten times the sum that is gained by the State. Let us suppose that 10,000,000 hun- dredweight of foreign corn enter France, worth on their arrival 1 7 shillings the hundredweight. In consequence of the competi- tion of this foreign corn the 80,000,000 hundredweight of corn, which are approximately the production of France, are also sold only at 17 shillings, and this is the precise subject of complaint. Let us then put a duty of four shillings on the importation of foreign corn. From the custom-house receipts the State (pre- mising that this duty does not reduce the t|uantity imported) will gain 10,000,000x4 = ^2,000,000. Now let us see how the public fares ; not only will it pay four shilHngs more for each hun- dredweight of foreign corn, that is to say, ^2,000,000, which is exactly equal to what the State receives, but also it will pay four shillings more for every hundredweight of corn produced in France, the French producers naturally hastening to sell their corn at the same price as the foreign producers ; that is to say, PRODUCTION. 267 80,000,000X4 = ^16,000,000. That is to say, these protective duties will have brought altogether ;^2, 000,000 into the State coffers, and ^16,000,000 into the pockets of home producers, but will have cost consumers ^18,000,000. That is the decisive argument against import duties, and in spite of its efforts, the pro- tectionist system has never succeeded in refuting it. The usual answer is to assure us that import duties are paid by the foreign producers, and that the price of the imported com- modity will not be increased. Allowing for one moment that this reply is a valid one, yet we should have to conclude from it that, since prices will not be changed, the national industry will not be protected one whit, and the criticisms we have just made on the system of protective duties will receive a last and even more clenching argument, " import duties are of no avail." However, though this reply of the protectionists may be a sound one in certain particular cases, it cannot be accepted in a general way. In consequence of a law, which is well known in this matter of imports under the name of the "law of transference," every tax paid by a producer or a merchant is laid by him on his goods, and thus falls upon the consumer. A fortiori this will be the case with the foreign producer. For how can it be reasonably sup- posed that a country has the power of throwing back on the for- eigner all or part of its imports ? Were such a pleasant receipt to exist, it is clear that each country would hasten to have its duties paid by its neighbors, and consequently no one would be a whit better off. Yet this notion is constantly reproduced : people are never tired of saying that the United States, thanks to their protective system, have been skilful enough to make foreigners pay the interest on their national debt, and even the greater part of the principal. It must be confessed that the Americans have espe- cially aided the spreading of this opinion by expressing it them- selves in the most naive manner. It can be judged from the following extract from a speech of Mr. Lawrence, Comptroller of 268 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. the United States Treasury : " By our customs tariff we inform the foreign manufacturer that he may send his products here, but that he must pay for this privilege. He is therefore compelled to reduce his prices and his profits, and to aid in the formation of that revenue which enables us to wipe out our public debt, and to pension off our soldiers who were maimed or wounded during the Civil War. This is distributive justice, since we force England and France to pay their share of the expenses of a rebellion which they maliciously encouraged." (Quoted in the Economiste fran- gais, 1 882, Vol. I, page 441 .) Similarly, when Russia resolved that, to renew her stock of money, customs duties should henceforward be paid only in gold, she evidently imagined that foreigners, when sending her their goods, would at the same time send the quantity of gold necessary for the payment of these duties. That was won- derfully innocent ! It was the Russian buyers who were obliged to obtain the necessary gold, and not a piece more entered the country ! The argument of the protectionists may be sound, however, in one case w^hich has been especially noted by John Stuart Mill. Every rise in price involves a reduction in consumption. The foreign producer will then have to ask himself whether it is not necessary for him to make a sacrifice and lower the price of his articles by a sum equal to the amount of the duty, in order to keep his custom by adhering to his former prices. The duty which falls on his products leaves him, therefore, on the horns of this unpleasant dilemma : either he must restrict the amount of his sales, or he must suffer a sacrifice in prices. It is not impos- sible that, when all is said and done, his interests may lead him to choose the second alternative, i.e. to burden himself with all or part of the duty. However, two conditions are requisite for his resigning himself to this extremity : firstly, his cost price may enable him to do so ; secoiuily, he is unable to send his products to another market. It would be chimerical to base, one's actions on such an eventuality ; in any case, if this was realized by chance, the mark aimed at by the establishment of the protective duty is PRODUCTION. 269 missed. It is impossible to escape from this dilemma. Besides, obsen-ation of facts shows, at least in a general way, that protective duties induce a corresponding rise in price. V. Why the Bounty System is Preferable. If, then, a state judges that, under certain particular circum- stances, it is useful to protect the national industry, it should resort not to the system of import duties, but to the far simpler and more candid system of bounties, whether in the shape of guarantees of interest or of direct subventions. This method presents none of the disadvantages which we have shown to be inherent in the import duty system. Firstly. It can be graduated at will, so as to protect only those who really need protection, and no others. It may be said, " that will be arbitrary'." The system of protective duties is also arbi- trary, the arbitrariness of a blind man ; whereas this may be that of an intelligent one. Secondly. It lays no shackles on foreign trade, and allows the full development both of imports and of exports, since it does not enhance the price of products. Thirdly. It does not interfere with production, for it does not make raw materials dearer and does not raise the cost of produc- tion ; on the contrary, it lowers it. It is true that, by granting a certain measure of security to the national industries, it may favor routine. That is an evil inherent in every possible system of pro- tection ; still, bounties may be established under certain condi- tions calculated to stimulate the progress of the protected industry. Thus the bounties granted by the law of 188 1 to merchant ship- ping are more or less considerable, according as the ship is a sail- ing-vessel or a steamship, made of wood or of steel, and propor- tionate to its speed. Fourthly. Finally, and above all, this system only professes to be what it really is — a sacrifice imposed on the country for a reason of public utility. It allows no illusion as to this, and gives 2/0 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. rise to no ambiguity. The public knows that it pays for this pro- tection, and knows exactly the price that it pays. Thus it may be held to be certain that a State will only resort to such measures in so far as their utility is clearly perceived, and that in all cases they will not be extended beyond foreseen contingencies, nor pro- longed beyond the fixed limit or term. Therein lies the economic and moral superiority of this system. This it is that is little realized by the protectionists, and hence they rarely ask for the application of this system. They would have too much trouble in obtaining it. Yet the bounty system is practised in France in the shape of bounties for merchant ship- ping, both for building and for navigation, and is justly preferred to surcharges on foreign ships. In new countries it happens often enough that the State guarantees a certain interest on capital sunk in various industrial undertakings. Thus Brazil has granted a guaiiantee of six per cent on sugar manufactories, and a bill has been discussed in the Argentine Republic for granting a similar guarantee on '^ frozen meat " works. VI. On Some Moderate Forms of Protection. Some years ago a party was formed, which, demanding protec- tion in a general way, asked for reciprocity in the matter of customs tariffs. This is called in England fair trade, in antithesis to free trade. If the system is employed by way of reprisals to compel a pro- tectionist country to lower its duties, — if, for example, England answered the prohibitive tariffs of the United States by heavily taxing American produce, — in that case it might very well be justified. As a matter of fact, though, such a question is political rather than economical. If we go further, and attempt to discover in it a scientific theory, it is left without a leg to stand on. If the protective system is held to be beneficial, it should be adopted ; if it is regarded as an evil, it should be rejected ; but whether neighboring countries PRODUCTION. 271 adopt it or not is their affair, not ours. No doubt, were England to lay duties on American products, she would injure the United States, but she would hurt herself too ; and the bad turn we are able to do our neighbor cannot be held to compensate for the harm we do ourselves. Another revised system is that of couniervailiiig duties. Its ad- vocates assert that when a country bears a heavier load of taxes than foreign countries, to re-establish equahty in competition it should burden foreign products with duties which are equivalent to the charges borne by its citizens. This argument is entirely based on the notion that customs duties are borne by the foreign producers. If, as we have at- tempted to show, that is a pure illusion, and if these duties really fall upon our own people in the shape of a rise in prices, then we can appreciate the wonderful originality of this so-called compen- sation, which, under pretence of equalizing the struggle, doubles the burdens of the public. Now if it is merely meant that foreign products ought to be laden \vith duties equal to those paid by the same products within the country, no one will contradict that principle of fiscal equality. Yet this equality is not always observed, even in protectionist countries. Thus one of the great grievances at the present moment (1888) of the vineyard proprietors and wine merchants in the South of France is, that Spanish and Italian wines enter the coun- try with four or five litres of alcohol added per hectolitre, and pay only 2/6 (half-a-crown) import duty, whereas in France each litre of alcohol pays 1/4 (one shilling and four pence) as excise. That is an unjust privilege to the profit of foreign producers, and has been well called a sort of protection turned upside down. CHAPTER VII. CREDIT. I. Credit Operations. However ingenious exchange may be, it is an arrangement that cannot answer all needs ; for, in order to obtain anything by ex- change, one must be able to give in exchange an ec^ual value. Now not every one is in a position to supply this value ; if each person who required lodgings was obliged to buy a house, it is easy to understand how extremely awkward such a state of affairs would be. Men have therefore been led to conceive an arrangement which is akin to exchange, but which is nevertheless different, to wit : lending, by means of which I can obtain a thing provisionally and make use of it for a certain space of time, on condition of merely giving to the person who surrenders it to me an anmuty propor- tional to the time I have enjoyed the use of his article. The name given to this annuity varies according to circumstances, such as farm-rent^ house-rent, interest. This is not the place to discuss the legitimacy or illegitimacy of this annuity ; that will be dealt with when we come to speak of the distribution of wealth. In popular speech, however, the word " credit " has a more restricted sense. It is applied not to the loan of anything whatso- ever, say a piece of land or a house, but only to the loan of a sum of money. This is easily explained by the fiict that, as money in modern societies is the form in which all capital is seen, every loan of capital usually takes the shape of a loan of money ; but we ought further to note that the loan of money has a special charac- teristic which radically marks it off from the loan of a piece of land or of a house. 272 PRODUCTION. 273 This special characteristic lies in the circumstance that the thing lent can only be utilized by the borrower on the condition that it is consumed, i.e. annihilated by him. The man who borrows cap- ital in the form of a bag of money must evidently, whatsoever use he may wish to make of it, empty the bag down to the last shilling. Similarly the borrower of a sack of corn, whether he borrows to sow it or to eat it, is compelled to destroy the corn, whether he intends to put it in the ground or grind it under the millstone. This characteristic is not specially confined to money ; it is pos- sessed by all things which in legal language are res fungibiles {vide Hunter, Romaji Law, page 141), i.e. which are consumed at the first time of using. The feature just discussed introduces into the contract now under analysis serious modifications, as much for the borrower as for the lender. Firstly. The lender, to take him first, is exposed to far more considerable risks. The lender of a house or of a piece of land knows that it will be restored to him at the expiration of the lease ; for he, so to speak, does not lose sight of it while it is in the pos- session of the borrower ; but the lender of a res fungibilis, on the contrary, knows that he is irrevocably deprived of it ; he knows that it is about to be destroyed, and that such is its destination. The Roman jurisconsults had excellently remarked that the thing given in miciuum had to be alie7iated, thus differing from the thing given ifi commodatum, which is merely lent. For when the date fell due, the borrower was not bound to return the thing, for it no longer existed, but had to transfer the proprietorship of something equivalent. The lender, true enough, reckons on an equivalent wealth to re- place that which he has lent, but this wealth is still non-existing ; it must be produced for that purpose, and everything that is future is ipso facto uncertain. Legislators, therefore, have exercised their ingenuity to guarantee the lender against all danger ; and the pre- cautions they have thought out to that end constitute one of the most important branches of civil law ; to wit, guaranty, mortgages, 274 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. joint responsibility, etc. Nevertheless, a certain amount of trust is also required on the part of the lender, that is to say, an act of faith, and this is precisely the reason why men have confined to this particular form of loan the name " credit," which, by its ety- mological origin, presupposes an act of faith {^creditum, credere). Secondly. To turn to the borrower : he is not merely bound, like the farm-tenant or the lodger, to preserve the thing lent to him and to keep it in good condition, so as to return it at the expiration of the fixed time ; after having used it, that is to say, destroyed it, he must labor so as to build up from it an equivalent, so as to wipe out his obligation at the appointed date. It is necessary, therefore, that he should be extremely careful to employ this luealth in a productive man?ier. If he is unlucky enough to consume it unproductively, say on personal expenses, or even if for any reason he fails to reproduce a wealth which is at least equivalent to that lent him, he is ruined. In fact, the history of all countries and of all ages is an actual martyrology of borrowers who have been ruined through credit. Credit, therefore, is an infinitely more dangerous instrument of production than those we have heretofore considered, and is a tool that should only be used by very experienced hands. It is sometimes said that credit only differs from exchange in having for its object, not any commodities whatsoever, but merely capital. That is correct, for we know that we must regard as capi- tal all wealth that is employed in the reproduction of new wealth. Now, as the operation just analyzed demands the productive employment of lent effects, it is right to say that the wealth which is the object of lending is or should be regarded as capital. So much the worse, then, for the borrower, if he is foolish enough to treat it as an income. He misunderstands the meaning of the contract, and for that reason the contract becomes for him a snare. It is also said sometimes that credit differs from exchange in that it consists not in the exchange of two existing wealths, but in the exchange of a present for a future wealth. That, too, is a PRODUCTION. 2/5 correct statement, for we have just seen that the lender surrenders his article, in order to receive in exchange for it, at the date when his loan expires, an article which is at present non-existent, and which must be created during the interval. Later on we shall find in this the explanation of interest and dis- count. There is another credit operation which holds an important place in commercial transactions, and is known under the name of " sale for a payment at a future date," or deferred payment. At first sight we might be led to think that sale for payment at a future date is nothing but a sale, and ought therefore to fall within our chapter on exchange. Yet it is nothing of the sort, for the buyer, in exchange for the article handed over to him, gives nothing, prob- ably because he has no money ; he merely acknowledges himself to be a debtor for the value received, just as if he had borrowed it. He is bound to apply himself to reproduce this value before the appointed date, if he desires to be able to pay it back. This clearly shows the feature alluded to above — the exchange of present wealth for future wealth. Still, one might say the bor- rower pays interest, whilst the buyer for deferred payment pays nothing of the kind. That is erroneous. The price of an article sold for deferred payment is also higher than the price of ready money sales. The difference, which is called discount, exactly represents the interest on the capital lent to the buyer. The above are the fundamental credit operations. II. Credit Papers. Yet these operations required a further improvement. If it was very advantageous for the borrower, whether in the case of a loan, or of sale for deferred payment, to have capital at his disposal for a certain time, on the other hand it was exceedingly disadvan- tageous for the lender to be obliged to do without that capital for the same period of time. A manufacturer has daily to make pur- chases and pay wages. He renews day by day the capital which he requires by the sale of his goods, but if he sells these goods for 2/6 PRINXIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. deferred payment, it certainly appears that he must abandon the hope of obtaining his cash, and that he will find it impossible to carry on his business. What is to be done? Could it perhaps be brought about that the same capital should at one and the same time be at the dis- posal of two different persons, the man who has lent it and the man who has borrowed it ? Yes, that can be managed. It is by means of credit that this apparently insoluble problem is solved. In exchange for the capital surrendered by him, the lender or the seller for deferred payment receives a document, i.e. a piece of paper in various forms, a note to order, a bill of exchange, etc., and this document represents a value which, like all other values, can be sold. If, then, the lender wishes to re-obtain his capital, nothing is simpler. It is enough for him to sell, or, as the phrase goes, to negotiate his paper. The following are the two principal forms of credit docu- ments : — Firstly, the note to order, which is drawn up in this fashion : '* On ninety days from date I will pay to Brown, or to his order, the sum of ^{^400, the value received in goods. April i, 1888. (Signed) Jones." Secondly, the bill of exchange, after this fashion : " On ninety days from date pay to Robinson, or to his order, the sum of ^400, value received in goods. April i, 1888. (Signed) Jones." The note to order, then, is simply a promise to pay, made by the debtor to his creditor. The bill of exchange is a little more complicated. It is an order to pay, addressed by the creditor to his debtor, an order to pay not to himself, the creditor, but to a third party. It is thanks to this form that the bill of exchange is especially employed to settle transactions between one place and another, or between different countries. Each credit operation, then, gives birth to a credit paper. Since in every busy society these credit operations are exceedingly numerous, in consequence of the fact that each commodity is PRODUCTIOX. lyj often sold three or four times (each sale being for deferred pay- ment, and therefore giving rise each time to a new credit paper), the credit papers which exist in a country like France or England represent an enormous mass of value, perhaps ;2^400,ooo,ooo higher in any case than the value of any class of goods whatsoever. III. Whether Credit can create Capital. Credit has attained such importance in our modern societies that we are tempted to attribute to it powers that are miraculous. By speaking every moment of great fortunes that are founded on credit, by stating that the largest enterprises of modern industry have credit for their base, we are persuaded into the belief that credit is an agent of production, which, just like land or labor, can create wealth. Yet that is a phantasmagoric construction. Credit is not an agent of production ; what is a far different thing, it is a special 7node of production, just like exchange, just like division of labor. As we have seen, it consists of the transferring of wealth, of capi- tal, from one hand to another, but to transfer is not to create. Credit creates capital not a whit more than exchange creates commodities. This illusion has been fostered by the existence of credit papers. We have seen that each loan of capital is represented in the lender's hands by a negotiable paper of equal value. Hence it seems that the act of lending has the marvellous power of making two capitals out of one. The former capital of £\oq which has passed into your hands, and the new capital which is represented in my hands by a bill for ^loo, do not they make two? From the subjective point of view that paper is capital. It is so for me, but it is not so for the country ; for it is obvious that it can only be negotiable while another person is willing to surrender to me in exchange capital which he possesses in the shape of money or of goods. This paper, then, is not capital per se, but it simply affords me the possibility of procuring other capital in lieu of that 278 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. which I have give ?i up. Besides, it is evident that whatever use I wish to make of this bill that I keep in my safe, whether I wish to devote it to the payment of my expenses or to productive pur- poses, I shall only be able to do this by converting this paper into objects of consumption or instruments of production which are already in the market. It is then with this wealth afforded by nature, not with these bits of paper, that I shall produce new wealth or merely obtain nutrition. Mr. MacLeod has earned special distinction as advocate of this thesis, that credit papers constitute real wealth and actual capital. He is logical enough in his conclusions, for he defines wealth as " everything which has an exchangeable value." Now as credit papers have incontestably an exchangeable value, they must certainly be reckoned as wealth. But it is the definition that cannot be admitted. If every credit paper, i.e. if every claim, were actually wealth, were each Frenchman to lend his fortune to his neighbor, by this one act the wealth of France would be simultane- ously and instantly doubled ; i.e. would rise from ^£8,000,000,000 to ^16,000,000,000 sterling. Mr. MacLeod insists on the state- ment that these papers at least represent future ivealih. No doubt ; but it is precisely because they are future that they can serve for nothing, and should not be reckoned as existing wealth. They will be reckoned as soon as they have begun to exist. Till that time there will always be this difference between present and future wealth : the former exists, the latter does not exist. We produce and live by means of existing ; we could neither live nor produce with wealth in nubibus. It would be as sensible as, when making the census of the population of France, to add, as an earnest of the future members of society, all those who will be born twenty years hence ! Yet, though credit cannot be termed productive, in the sense that it does not create capital, nevertheless it renders eminent services to production in the following manner : — Firstly, by utilizing existing capital to the best possible advan- tage. For if capital could not pass from one person to another. PRODUCTION. 279 and if each man were reduced to making a direct use of those he possessed, an enormous amount of capital would lie idle. In fact, in all civilized societies there are a number of people who cannot work their own capital : To wit, those who have too much ; for as soon as a fortune ex- ceeds a certain figure it is not easy for its owner to obtain the full profit from it by his unaided strength, without taking into consideration the circumstance that usually, in such cases, the possessor has no inclination to make such an effort : Those 7vho have not enough ; for workmen, peasants, domestic servants, who make small savings, cannot of themselves produc- tively employ such tiny capital. Still, when once these savings are combined, they may make hundreds of thousands of pounds : Those who, by reason of their age, their sex, or their profession, cannot themselves employ their capital in industrial enterprises. This is the case with minors, women, persons who have devoted themselves to a liberal profession, such as lawyers, doctors, mili- tary men, clergymen, public servants, and ejnployes of all classes. To reverse the picture : there are people in the world, such as promoters, inventors, agriculturists, nay, even workmen, who could easily make a good use of capital, if they only had it. Unfortu- nately they have not. But if, by means of credit, capital can pass from the hands of those who cannot or will not put it to account to the hands of those who are capable of employing it productively, that will be of great profit to each one of them, and to the whole country. Now, in every country, we can count by millions of pounds the value of capital withdrawn in this manner, either from sterile hoarding or from unproductive consumption, thus ' fertilized by credit. Secondly, by causing the formation of new capital. For if peo- ple were unable to look forward to the employment of their sav- ings in loans, many persons, especially those just enumerated, would no longer be anxious to save, no possible future use being open to them. As to this point, see further on, '' The Conditions 280 PRINXIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. Necessary for Saving." In fact, credit is to capital what exchange is to wealth. We have previously seen that by transferring wealth from one possessor to another, exchange certainly does not create wealth, but none the less utilizes it and incites to its production. Thirdly, by allowing the saving of a certain atnount of metallic 7noney. This function of credit has already been discussed by us at length. We need not repeat the discussion here. IV. Banks. We saw above that exchange of commodities was scarcely pos- sible without the aid of certain middlemen whom we call traders. In the same way trade in capital would be impossible without the assistance of certain intermediaries who are termed bankers. Bankers are just like other business men. Business men as a class deal with commodities; bankers deal with capital, in the shape either of credit papers or of coin. The former buy in order to sell again, and make their profits by buying as cheaply as pos- sible to sell as dearly as possible. The latter borrow in order to lend, and make their profits by borrowing as cheaply as possible in order to lend as dearly as possible. Here, then, are the two fundamental operations of all banking business, borrowing and lend- ing ; and as these borrowings are usually effected in the form of deposits and these loans in the form of discoimts, they are gen- erally called deposit and discount banks. However, there is a third operation which is very different from the other two, though fundamentally it, too, is a mode of borrow- ing. We refer to the issuing of bank notes. But this operation is not essential to banks ; nay, in most countries it is an exceptional and privileged function which belongs only to certain banks which are called batiks of issue. The history of banks is closely connected with the history of commerce ever since the Middle Ages. The creation of each great bank marks a new stage of commercial development. The first banks were those of the Italian Republics, Venice (? 1156) PRODUCTION. 281 and Genoa (1407). Commercial pre-eminence then passed to Holland, and we come to the great and celebrated Bank of Am- sterdam (1609), speedily followed by those of Hamburg and Rot- terdam. Finally, the creation of the Bank of England in 1694 teaches us that that nation is about to succeed to the commercial supremacy of the world. The Bank of France did not rise till much later, only at the beginning of the present century. Never- theless, in 1 716, Law had founded a famous bank, the sad termi- nation of which is well known to all the world.^ Let us now examine in succession these three different opera- tions — Deposits, Discount, and the Issuing of Notes. V. Deposits. The banker's first task is to obtain capital. No doubt he can make use of his own capital or of those more considerable sums which may be furnished by association, and which in our great loan-societies may rise to some thousand millions pounds sterling. But if the banker carried on his operations only with his own pri- vate capital or that of the association, he would make but small profits and even would render little service to society : we shall soon see the reason for this. He is obliged, then, to carry on his operations by means of the money of the general public, and for that reason has to borrow it from them. (Many large banks never use their own capital in their business ; they invest it, either in real property or in stock, as a reserve or a guarantee to their clients. This is done by the Bank of France.) But how does the banker borrow this money from the pubhc? Not after the fashion of a government or a corporation, or even an industrial society, which borrows for a long date, in the shape of stocks, debentures, or shares, the capital which its owners seek to invest. No ; such a mode of borrowing demands too high a rate of interest for the banker to find any profit on such transactions. What the banker 1 See Dictionary of Political Economy, edited by R. H. Inglis Palgrave, article " Banks " (1891). — J. B. 282 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. asks from the public is that circulating, floating capital which exists in the shape of coin in our trousers-pockets or in the drawers of our safes. In every country there is to be found in this form a considerable amount of capital, which is in nowise fixed, does noth- ing, produces nothing, and waits for the moment of employment. The banker says to the public, " Entrust it to me till you have found some employment for it. I will keep it for you, and will return it you when you require, at the first demand. While you thus wait I will give you a low interest on it, say i|- or 2 per cent. This will be always more than it produces for you : for whilst it is in your strong-box it yields you no returns, and in any case you will avoid the trouble and anxiety of keeping it. Nay, if you wish it, I will do you the service of being your banker, of collecting your yearly income, cashing your coupons, and of paying your creditors, according to the instructions you give us, all which will be very convenient to you." Where this language is heard and understood by the public, bankers can obtain in this way, on very easy terms, a large amount of capital, by draining, so to speak, from circulation, the coin which is scattered about the country. The Journal of the Statistical Society of London for September, 1884, reckons that the sum total of the deposits thus received by the banks of the whole world amounted to ^2,508,000,000, ;^965, 000,000 of which were for England and her colonies com- bined. Sometimes, however, bankers pay no interest on deposits. Cer- tain banks, such as the Bank of England or the Bank of France, refuse to give any interest, for they consider that they render a sufficient service to the depositors whose money they receive ; and no doubt they are right, for they obtain enormous sums on deposit. A step further, too ; in former days, the deposit banks, those time- honored banks, for instance, whose names we gave a page or two back, actually demanded interest to be paid them by the depositors as recompense for keeping safely, as remuneration for services rendered. But most modern banks are accustomed to give their depositors PRODUCTION. 283 a small interest, in order to attract, by means of that bounty, the largest possible amount of deposits. Naturally enough, the in- terest is a httle higher if the depositor agrees not to demand back his money for a certain period, say six months, a year, five years, etc. We have already obsen-ed more than once that in England, for example, it is customary for wealthy people to keep no money in their own houses, but to deposit it all with their bankers. If they have a payment to make to a tradesman or any other creditor, they simply send this creditor to receive payment at their banker's, by giving him an order of payment drawn up on a sheet detached from a note-book with perforations, which is called a check. This custom is beginning to become universal in all countries. But we should note that the check is not, properly speaking, a credit paper ; it is an order to pay from funds which the banker should have in hand for his customer's account. VI. Discount. Once that this floating capital has been borrowed by the bank at a cheap rate, it is the banker's business to turn it to account by lending it to the public. But how ? The banker cannot lend it for a long date, say, by way of mortgage or of advancing funds for a sleeping-partnership in industrial enterprises. He is obliged not to forget that he only holds this capital on deposit ; that is to say, he may be obliged to reimburse it at a moment's notice ; he con- sequently can only let it out of his sight for short-dated transac- tions, which merely deprive him of the disposal of this capital for a short time, and which therefore in some measure allow it to remain within his grasp and beneath his eyes. What loan operation can fulfil these conditions ? There is one which complies with them admirably. When a merchant has sold his goods for deferred payment, according to the usage of commerce, if he happens to have need of money before the expiration of the time, he turns to the banker. The latter then advances the merchant the sum which is 284 PRIN'CIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. due to him for the sale of his goods, making a deduction of a small sum which constitutes his profits, and receives in exchange the claim of the merchant upon his purchaser, i.e. his bill of exchange. The banker keeps this bill of exchange in his safe, and on the day fixed for the expiration of the bill he sends it to the debtor to be exchanged for cash ; in this way he recoups himself for the capital he had advanced. The above process is what is called discount. It is, we may say, a form of loan ; for it is clear that the banker who, in return for a bill of exchange for ^50, payable in three months, advances to the merchant £^df^ ^s, to receive from the' debtor at the expir- ation of the bill the full sum of ^50, has in fact lent his money for a period of three months at an interest of six per cent or rather more. Moreover, it is always a short-dated loan ; for not only are the bills of exchange negotiated by the bank payable within a time which rarely exceeds three months, but this is a maximum which, in average cases, is never reached. The nego- tiators are not always able to negotiate their bills of exchange on the day after they have been sold ; they may have to keep them docketed for some time : it is even possible that they may not be called upon to negotiate them till the eve of the expiration of the bill. At the Bank of France the average period during which bills of exchange are kept is from forty to forty-live days. It is therefore only for a very short space that the banker deprives himself of the money he has received on deposit, for in the short period of six weeks on the average every shilling which has left returns to his safe. It would be difficult to find a loan operation which better com- plies with the exigencies of deposit. Let the demands for re- imbursement of deposits be grouped together during a period of above six weeks, and the banker, thanks to his own cash receipts, will always be able to cope with the demands. Now it is scarcely probable that these demands will be so frequent, at any rate during normal times. Still we must not conceal the fact that the banker has certain risks to run. If all the depositors were to arrange to come and PRODUCTION. 285 ask for their money on one and the same day, the bank would obviously be unable to satisfy them, for their money is at that moment here, there, and everywhere. True enough, it will speedily return to the banker's keeping, but there is always this difference between capital borrowed by the bank as deposits and capital lent by it as discount : The former can always be demanded back from the bank at a moment's notice, whereas it can only ask for the latter to be returned at the end of a fixed period ; and that difference is enough, at any particular time, to cause bankruptcy. But is this problematical danger a sufficient reason to deter banks from making use of the capital they receive on deposit, and to oblige them to keep such moneys as actual deposits, after the fashion of the old banks of Venice or of Amsterdam ? Certainly not. Every one would be discontented. Firstly. The depositors themselves ; for it is clear that if the bank was compelled to keep their money in its vaults without employing it, instead of being able to give them a bonus in the form of interest, it would be the bank that would have to require the payment of interest, to compensate for the cost of keeping. It is better, then, for the depositors to run the risk of having to wait a few days for reimbursement, than to hoard their money at home unproductively, or to be obliged to pay for its safe keeping elsewhere. Secondly. Society, too ; for the social utility of banks consists in combining scattered and unproductive capital in the form of coin, so as to make out of it active and productive capital. This social function would evidently disappear from the moment that banks were unable to make use of their deposits. Banks, then, do not hesitate to use the sums confided to their charge ; but in order to face any possible demands or runs, they are always careful to keep a certain reserve. It is impossible to prescribe a priori any proportion between the amount of the reserve and the sum total of the deposits. A bank's reserve should always be the larger, the slighter its credit and the more numerous its large deposits. It should, in particular, 286 PRLNXIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. Strengthen its reserve during commercial crises, on the advent of the issues of government stock, or of debentures, — in a word, under all circumstances when it can foresee that the depositors will require their money. Contrary to the usual belief, the amount of the reserve of the Bank of France is not fixed by law. It might be 7iil, but it is usually excessive. However, discount is not the only way in which banks can make use of their capital. They lend them also — Firstly. In the shape of advances on bills ; i.e. by taking in pledge movable property, and being careful that the sum lent shall be sufficiently lower than the value of the goods or stock- exchange securities. This process is one of the most important lines of business of the Bank of France. Secondly. In the shape of credit that they open for their cus- tomers. When they have a running account with it, the bank can allow them to withdraw more than they have deposited ; in other words, it practically gives them a loan. Still, as this method of loan (lying uncovered, as the term goes) is exceedingly dangerous, and presents no guarantees, some banks refuse to practise it. It is absolutely forbidden by the regulations of the Bank of France. Vn. On the Issuing of Bank Notes. As with all other business men, it is to the banker's interest to extend his operations as much as possible. By doubling them, he doubles his profits. How is this effected ? The banker does not generally find it difficult to find a use for the capital he holds. There are always plenty of people who desire to borrow. By lowering the rate of discount he can nego- tiate as much paper as he wishes. But, before being able to lend capital, a prior condition is necessary ; namely, to possess capital. There's the rub ! In fact, it is not so easy to find lenders as it is to meet with borrowers. It is necessary that the public should bring their money to deposit, and it may happen that they are not very eager to do so. PRODUCTION. 287 Now if the banker could create capital de novo in the form of coin, instead of having to wait patiendy till the public is willing to bring it to him, nothing would prevent him from extending his operations indefinitely. Some bankers, then, conceived the ingenious idea of thus creating the capital they needed by the issue of simple promises to pay, i.e. bank notes, and experience has proved the excellence of the device by its perfect success. This ingenious invention is attributed to Palmstruch, who founded the Bank of Stockholm in 1656. It is true that the Italian and Amsterdam banks issued many notes, but these merely represented the money the bankers had in their safes ; in other words, were only receipts for deposits. In return for commercial bills which are presented to them to discount, the banks, instead of paying in money, give notes. But it may be asked, How is the public brought to accept this combination ? In return for a bill of exchange which he comes to have discounted, the business man receives merely another credit paper ; that is to say, a bank note. What use is it to him? He wants money, not credit papers ; for as regards paper he might just as well have kept that which has passed into his own hands. It is enough to remark that, though the bank note is really only a credit paper, just like the bill of exchange, yet it is far more convenient paper. The following characteristics differentiate it from credit papers, and particularly from bills of exchange : — Firstly, it yields no interest, not a whit more than a coin. Its value, therefore, is always the same and is not liable to vary according to the distance from the day when it falls due. Secondly, it is transferable to bearer, just like a coin, and is not subjected to the formahties and responsibilities of endorsement. We are all aware that the transference of credits, and especially the question of knowing when this transfer was possible, was one of the most delicate questions in Roman Law. In the French Civil Law such a transference is still subjected to somewhat com- 288 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. plicated formalities. Even in Commercial Law, though these for- maHties have been simplified as much as possible, it is still neces- sary for the transference of a commercial bill to John Smith that the lender should write on the back, " Pay to the order of John Smith," together with his signature and the date, and thus himself becomes liable in case of non-payment. This is what is known as endorseinent. Thirdly, it is payable at sight, i.e. at any time whatsoever, whereas a commercial bill is payable only at a specific date. Fourthly, it is ahvays payable 07i de7?iand, whereas credit papers are payable only on maturity. Fifthly, it is for a round sum, thus harmonizing with the current money systems, ten pounds or one thousand francs or fifty dollars, whereas other credit papers, which represent commercial transac- tions, usually involve fractional amounts. Sixthly. Lastly, // is issued and signed by a well-known batik, the name of which is usually familiar to every one, even to those of the public who are not versed in commercial matters ; for in- stance, the Bank of France or the Bank of England ; whilst the names of the signatories of bills of exchange are scarcely known except by those persons who deal with them. Observe, however, that when the particular promise to pay is destined to circulate lik:e a bank note, the solvency of the debtor is not so keenly scrutinized as when it is a bill intended to be docketed, such as a certificate of stock, a share, or a debenture. Indeed, this holder for a day has no need to trouble as to future solvency : his affair is merely present solvency. All the above considerations cause the bank note to be really accepted by the public as ready money and to become pure paper money. In France and England, too, the bank note is also legal tender, just as gold pieces and the five-franc silver piece ; but we must not fall into the common error of comparing legal tender with forced currency.^ A bill is legal tender when creditors or ' It is impossible to reproduce the play upon words of the original, " cours legal et cours yor'^o or ^£400, he will be unable to turn it to account in any industrial or commercial business without resorting to other people's labor. So far the situation seems to be a perfectly normal one. It is quite legitimate that a man who has too much wealth should em- ploy it to supply work for those who have not enough. Nay, if we consider the matter farther, we can easily discern a fitting harmony in the fact that the capitalist can no more dispense with the laborer for the profitable employment of his capital than the laborer can do without the capitalist for the utilization of his aims. But we are going rather too fast. The landowner or the capi- talist, who employs workmen to labor on his land or with his . capital, regards the product of the business, whatever it may be, whether it takes the shape of agricultural produce or of manu- 477 4/8 rRLN'CIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. factured goods, as his property ; and the selling-price of these products, when the cost of production has been deducted, forms his income or his profits. Here we reach dangerous ground ; for we may ask, in virtue of what right does the master appropriate for himself a value which is the product of the labor of his workmen ? The master replies, through the medium of the economists, that the article produced is altogether his work, for without his initia- tive it would not exist at all ; if he has not made it, at any rate he has had it made. He first conceived the idea of it, and that is the primordial and essential act of all production ; he, too, has sup- plied the means of executing it. Who, then, should have more right to the article than he has? The workmen? But they have merely executed the orders they have received ; they have only been the implements in the hand of the employer. Here is a proof: if we take two businesses that employ an equal number of workmen, we constantly see one succeed and the other fail miser- ably. Industry may be compared to warfare. For who wins the batUe ? The general. No doubt, good soldiers, and good arms like- wise, contribute to the happy issue, but they are the conditions of success and not the efficient cause ; this is shown by the fact that the same troops with the same material of war will be beaten if they are under a bad commander. In business matters, too, generalship is everything. The employer is the " captain of in- dustry " ; victory or defeat depends on him. If he succeeds, he alone reaps the fruits of victory; if he fails, on him alone fall the consequences of defeat, and he is punished by ruin. The socialists shrug their shoulders at this picture, and say that the master is only a parasite, or, if the term be preferred, a specu- lator, whose sole business is to buy to sell again. What does he buy? The power exerted in the workman's toil in the shape of manual labor. What does he sell again ? The same power of labor in the concrete form of goods. He buys it cheap in the labor market where the proletariat are obliged to sell themselves in order to live, and where the supply is always in excess. He sells it again at DISTRIBUTION. 479 a good price because he is able to make this power of labor yield all it can, by lengthening the hours of the working-day as flir as possible, by enticing his men with the deceitful bait of piece- work, and by wearing out women and little children by means of machinery which turns their weak arms to account. To pay labor as little as possible and to make it yield as much as possible, that is the whole secret of the master's profits ; that is the " mystery of iniquity." The first of these two portraits is excessively flattering; the second is a distorted caricature, but both of them bear some sort of resemblance to reality. Given the economic organization of society, it is certain that we must have the master to play his part. The elements of produc- tion are dispersed amongst a multitude of persons : on the one side, the masses who have only their arms, and possess neither land nor capital ; on the other, those w^ho have capital and land, but have no desire or intention to take to manual labor. Now to produce wealth at all, especially on a large scale, it is absolutely necessary to combine these various factors of production in one and the same productive operation. But who is to unite these scattered elements and cause them to converge to a common end ? To whom is to fall the task of foreseeing men's wants, of harmon- izing production with consumption, of determining the path on which the labor and capital of a country should be employed? Obviously not to the proletariat ; it must, then, fall to the capitalist, and it is clear that he who establishes the business will keep the profits for himself. Although the social function of the employer is partly forced upon us by the necessities of the economic situation, it is none the less of evil consequences ; for it makes the problem of distri- bution almost a hopeless one, keeps up the acute state of conflict between capital and labor, and marks off society into two hostile classes. We cannot prevent workmen from thinking that they have rights over the wealth that has proceeded from their hands ; we cannot prevent them from bitterly watching generations of 480 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECOx\OMY. masters or shareholders succeeding one another in turn, and growing rich from factories or mines in which they, the workers, have also labored from fother to son, and have still remained poor. True enough, as was urged by the employers' advocates, they have only been tools ; but the misfortune of present society lies in that very fact that one man can be another's tool. Far differ- ent is this from the first precept of morality as formulated by Kant : always to remember that we must regard our neighbor's personality as an end and not as a means. Are there any ways of escaping from our difficulty? There are only two. We might return to the system of isolated production described in the last chapter ; but such an attempt would be utterly vain. All we can do is to strive to preserve such relics of that order as still remain. Our other course would be to organize production on a basis of association, but not the association practised nowadays, in the form of joint stock companies, capitalists employing whole armies of wages-earners, companies which possess all the disadvantages of the employer system without its advantages ; for that form of association has the most serious defect of accentuating the divorce between capital and labor, by forming two distinct classes in the same undertaking — on the one hand, the workmen, who labor in a business the profits of which they do not receive — and, on the other hand, the shareholders, who receive the profits of a business in which they do not labor, and of the very nature of which they are often ignorant. When the ownership and direction of a con- cern are in the hands of a company, i.e. a fictitious and invisible person, that ownership and authority fall greatly in the estimation of the workmen. Even from a productive point of view these collective undertakings share some of the disadvantages which are shown by great public administrations, and which would be mani- fested on the application of the collectivist system ; namely, an absence of individual initiative, bureaucratic measures, and some waste of labor and of capital. We should strive rather to form co-operative associations of DISTRIBUTION. 48 1 laborers, who would work on their own account, and use instru- ments of production which belong to themselves. Thus they would be able to receive the whole product of their labor. That would be a return to what should be the normal order of things, in which capital would be the instrument of labor ; not as now, when labor is the instrument of capital. In that direction we must hope that the solution to be effected by the future will he, for we ourselves can conceive no other ; but when we deal with co-operation we shall see the difficulties in the way of the success of such associations. The principal difficulty is how to do without the master. We must not forget the solution proposed by the collectivist school, with which we are well acquainted. They would put an end to the classes of capitalists and masters, by abolishing private property in capital and in instruments of production, which would then be handed over to society. Society henceforward would be the only master or employer. As it would not try to make any profits, or, what is the same thing, would pour the profits into the common treasury in the form of public revenue, the people would be freed from the enormous tribute which is now levied annually by landowners and capitalists, as profits, gains, interest, dividend, and land-rent, and which (in France) cannot be less than ;3^3 20,000,000 or ^400,000,000 a year. So large a saving would certainly be worth -the trouble of making, if it could be proved that these employers and capitalists are of no use, and are merely parasites. But if, as our previous explanations seem to show, these employers do play an important part, and would be extremely difficult to replace, and if, unfortu- nately, the forcible appropriation by the State of all agricultural, industrial, and commercial businesses, and the abolition of all individual enterprise, were to reduce the production of wealth perhaps by half, in that case we might find that we had made a very bad bargain, and the saving would cost us dear. 482 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. II. The Laws which regulate Profits. When once we have admitted the social function of the master, whether wilHngly or against our incUnations, the legitimacy of profits naturally follows. We only have to determine the laws which regulate them. As we are aware, the production of wealth requires the con- sumption of other wealth, in the shape of raw materials, imple- ments, and wages {i.e. articles of subsistence consumed by the workmen). If the operation has been performed well, the value of the wealth produced will be higher than the value of the wealth destroyed ; if the work has been done badly, the value of the wealth produced will be less than that of the wealth destroyed. This is, then, a very delicate process, which requires a nice appre- ciation of the wants of consumption, and demands predictions which often take long to fulfil, and in which mistakes may be easily made. The employer has to carry out this operation. If he conducts it successfully, his recompense is the excess of the values produced over the values consumed ; if he has erred in his forecasts, he has to bear the difference between the values pro- duced and the values destroyed. In that case he will lose. The values destroyed in the process of production are what the employer calls the cost of production ; the excess of the values pro- duced over the values consumed forms his net product or profits. Profits are limited by no necessary law. If the employer is skilful enough to produce goods to a high value, and spends but little on them, his profits will be very great. That will be so much the better for society, for this difference of values exactly shows that relatively useless things have been sacrificed for the production of an article, which, relatively speaking, is exceedingly useful, or at any rate answers to a very intense desire. We must not conclude from this that the employer and society take identically the same standpoint. Society measures the cost of production by the quantity of raw material destroyed and the amount of labor employed. The employer estimates it according DISTRIBUTION. ^ 483 to the sums he has to pay out to his workmen as wages and to capitaHsts as interest. Now, as we are here deaHng, not with a destruction, but only with a transference of wealth, — for the expenditure of the employer goes towards the income of other classes, — it matters Httle to society whether the expenses are increased or reduced. Take a piece of land which yields a gross produce of ^^2000. The owner says, "I must deduct ;£i6oo from that for what I pay for manual labor, so that my returns only come to ^400. Not a large sum, to be sure ! " Very likely not ; but these ^1600 which are distributed among the workmen form part of the income of society as a whole. Hence it is sometimes said that, socially speaking, there is no difference between net produce and gross produce ; but that statement is a little too wide. As we are aware, under the action of competition the value of things always tends to approach the cost of production, and we have already more than once explained this mechanism. If, then, there is perfect freedom in industry, — if the producer is not pro- tected by a legal monopoly, or letters patent, or protective duties, — the employer will not often make very high profits, and, in any case, not for long. Now what is the minimum to which competition can reduce profits ? Clearly we cannot suppose that it may reduce profits to zero, by lowering the price of articles to the level of the cost of production, for in that case the employer would make no gains, and would cease to produce. The English school teaches ^ that profits are included in the cost of production. Though such a statement is somewhat start- ling at first, it may be justified, if we consider that profits, under the action of competition, are resolved into wages, interest, redemption, and insurance. But these are the ordinary elements of the cost of production. Between the cost of production and the selling price there must always be a certain margin, which represents the minimum profits. ^ Or rather, " taught." J. S. Mill is probably meant. — J. B. 484 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. We must now determine this minimum, which is composed of three elements. Firstly, the interest and redemption of the capital employed, calculated according to the normal rate of interest in the market for capital. In every society where such a market exists — i.e, wherever there are people who can obtain interest for their capital, while they stay peacefully at home and do nothing — it is clear that no one will amuse himself by sinking capital in industry or trade, unless he is absolutely certain that it will yield him an interest equal to that which he would obtain from the same capital invested in securities which he has in his desk. Still, a close glance at the numerous businesses which are carried on in any society would certainly show us some which are not suffi- ciently productive to remunerate at the current rate the capital which is engaged in them. How is it, then, that such a business continues to go on? We can easily explain this contradiction by looking at the nature of the capital employed. If it be fixed capital, even if we wished, we could not give it any other destina- tion than that for which it was formed. The choice lies between abandoning it altogether, or being content witlr however small a return it may yield. Obviously, the latter course is taken, for it is better to lose part than to lose all. Railway and tram lines often give instances of this. Secondly. The second element is the premium of the insurance against the various risks which the employer has to bear in their entirety. The object of this is not to realize gains, but to avoid loss. If, in some branch of industry, on the average one business out of ten goes bankrupt, the premium must be high enough to com- pensate for bad luck ; for unless the chances of profit were at least to balance the chances of loss, no one would be rash enough to enter on that line of business. Nor is this all. Grant that the business is among the successful ones. It will be lucky if it has not one bad year out of every ten. Let us suppose that this bad year swallows up half the employer's DISTRIBUTION. 485 capital ; then the other nine will have to give him a surplus which will be enough to reimburse him for that loss. We can thus see that there is considerable risk, and that therefore the insurance premium ought to be of some height. Thirdly. The wages of the etnp/oye?-'s labor, which is a com- plex labor, comprising initiative, direction, and control. This ele- ment does not figure in the profits received by shareholders in joint stock companies under the name of dividends ; for such persons do nothing, and pay a manager to conduct the business. Dividends, strictly speaking, should only include interest and the premium on insurance.^ Now the wages of the employer's labor clearly cannot be appraised in definite figures ; they depend on such matters as customs, habits, and the degree of general com- fort. But we may fix our ideas of the subject by saying that the sum ought to be equal to the salary that the employer would have to pay to obtain an engineer or a manager who would super- intend the factory in his stead. Some manufacturers in making out their books put such a sum to their own credit under the head of salary. Obviously, if the business did not reward him for his labor in a fitting manner, the manufacturer would choose another kind of occupation in which he could better utilize his capacity or aptitude. Such are the elements into which profits might be resolved on the purely theoretical hypothesis of a system of absolutely free competition. Naturally, as things actually go, the rate of profits will be usually above but sometimes below our limit. Generally speaking, there is a great tendency to exaggerate the rate of profits. The circumstance that in any business the profits are accumulated in one man's hands, whilst the wages are scattered amongst hundreds or thousands of sharers, throws a false light on the respective importance of the receivers. If mastership were to be abolished and profits were distributed among all the work- ^ In this case the shareholders over any considerable period of time would have gained only by the interest; it would therefore have been equally profit- able for them to have been simply holders of debentures. — J. B. 486 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. men in the factory, in many cases each man's share would be increased only in very small measure. One instance will be enough. In iSSi the coal-miners in the whole of the Department of the Nord distributed a total sum of ^821,176 in wages and ;£i 10,476 in profits {i.e. dividends). Thus the profits were 13 per cent of the wages ; in other words, had the demands of the sociaHsts been complied with, and all shareholders been sup- pressed and their dividends divided among the workmen, each man's daily wages would have risen on the average from 3i-. 2d. to 3^. 7^. Further, each of these elements is itself variable, and the usual doctrine is that each of them tends to fall progressively, whence it is concluded, by a perfectly logical deduction, that the rate of profits itself tends to fall. The rate of interest, we are told, falls in proportion to the increase of capital ; the premium of insurance against risk diminishes in accordance with the reduction of such risks, and finally the wages of superintendence grow lower in proportion as the spread of education makes such labor of man- agement accessible to all. To our mind these assertions are very hypothetical. When we speak of the fall of the rate of interest we shall discuss this topic again. III. Whether the Rate of Profits is in Inverse Ratio to the Rate of Wages. According to Ricardo, the rate of profits always varies in inverse ratio to the rate of wages.' This statement gravely offends the economists of the optimistic school, for it supposes a permanent and necessary antagonism between the interests of masters and of workmen. However, it is perfectly substantiated if we only add, 1 It is to be remembered that, to Ricardo, high or low wages meant a large or small proportion of the product as compared with profits. If the price doubled without any alteration in the said proportion, he would not have said that the rates had altered at all. See Ricardo's Pol. Econ. of Tax., Chap. VII. — J. B. DISTRIBUTION. 48/ as we should do in enunciating all scientific propositions, the words ceteris paribus, "other things being equal." For, if the products of the business become greater, it is clear that the rate of wages and the rate of profits will be able to increase simultaneously without there being any contradiction. Take a piece of cloth which is sold for two shillings ; let one shilling go to the master and the other shilling to the workman. Now if in this factory, the number of hands and the capital engaged remaining the same, but the methods being improved or the labor being executed more intelligently, four pieces of cloth are produced which are worth eight shillings, then the master's share and the workman's share, profits and wages, might also be quadrupled, i.e. rise simul- taneously to four shillings. No doubt it is somewhat absurd to imagine that the production of any manufacture can be made fourfold whilst the old prices are kept up. But, even if we grant that the price of each piece of cloth is reduced by half and falls to one shilling, the total value of the four pieces will still be double the former value of the produce, i.e. be four shillings ; thus profits and waofes can even now be simultaneously doubled. This explains how it is that in new countries, such as the United States and Australia, we see at one and the same time very high wages of 8, 10, or 12 shillings a day, and profits which amount to 15, 20, or sometimes 100 per cent of the capital employed. For in such societies, which combine the methods of the most advanced civilization with the resources of a still virgin land, productive power is at its acme, and, as the gross produce of each productive operation is far greater than it usually is in Europe, the portion that falls to each of the sharers may also be much larger. It is a remarkable fact that these high profits and high wages by no means prevent the industries in such countries from fre- quently producing at a cheaper rate than is the case in other lands where wages and profits are lower, say in India, where manual labor may be had for the asking. We can easily account for this paradoxical result by showing that the greater height of the wages is more than compensated for by the productive superiority of the 488 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. laborers. The labor of an English workman who is paid eight shillings a day may be much cheaper than the labor of an Indian coolie who receives only sixpence a day. That would clearly follow if the former made thirty or forty yards of cotton stuff per diem, whilst the latter only made one. The argument often urged by protectionists is therefore as devoid of a logical basis as it is contrary to facts — their dictum being that, as free trade establishes competition between all coun- tries, its result must be to drive down wages by conferring the superiority on the country which can pay its workmen least. In reality international competition gives the upper hand, not to the land where wages are lowest, but to the one where productive power is the greatest. CHAPTER III. THE WAGES-EARNER. I. The Contract of Wages. The following preliminary observations are necessary : The classical school uses the term wages-earner {salarie) in a very wide sense. Some, indeed, in imitation of Mirabeau, who used to say that the landowner himself was only a wages-earner, indis- criminately put all classes of society into this category. Most include, at least, all those who exchange their services for money, e.g. barristers, doctors, public officials, and even artisans who work to order. We must not be deceived by this abuse of the word "wages- earner," for its sole object is to represent wages as the most general and the most legitimate mode of remuneration.^ Scien- tifically, the word "wages-earner" can only be applied to men who labor for another inaji. Those who work for the public are not " wages earners " ; and popular speech is correct in this respect, for it uses the term "wages" only for the former class. Other men may have salaries, honoraria, fees* etc., but not wages. The wages-earner and the master are a pair of characters whose lot is altogether different, but whom fate has inseparably bound together ; there is litde love lost between them, but they cannot obtain a divorce. The man who possesses nothing but his arms can produce nothing whatsoever, unless he receives an instrument of production ; but, under the present economic organization, no one can supply him with this instrument save the landowner or ^ A chief offender is Max Wirth, who regards conquest as an achievement of skilled labor getting its due wages. See Lange, Arbeiterfrai^e, page 139. -J. B. 489 490 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. the capitalist. Similarly, however large be the instrument of pro- duction that he owns, neither landlord nor capitalist can reap any returns from it without using the arms of other men. Now, since the force of events has thus associated labor and capital, the easiest thing to do would seem to be to make a real contract of partnership. The laborer might say, " I have con- tributed my bodily strength ; you have contributed your capital ; let us share the proceeds." In such a course alone must we endeavor to find a solution of the problem. But the simplest solutions are often those for which we have to wait the longest ; and though this solution is not an impossible one, as some economists assert, still it is certainly not on the eve of realization. For partnership requires that the partners shall have a certain equality of position and a certain community in their aims. Such conditions are wanting when we put together the poor man and the rich man, the proletariat and capitalists. The latter seeks to make his fortune, the former strives to earn his living ; the one speculates on more or less distant results, the other has to think of his daily bread ; the motto of the one is " Risk nothing, nothing gain " ; the other can risk nothing, for there is naught that he can lose. Hence the failure of partnership between capitalist and laborer, and the substitution in its stead of the wages-system. This system is a bargain, by the terms of which the workman surrenders all rights to the product of his labor, in consideration of a fixed sum which is payable either weekly or monthly. This contract contains a double advantage. The employer is left with the definitive ownership of the produce, and the entire control of, and responsibility for, the business ; the workman is guaranteed a sure reward, which is immediate, and is independent of all risks that may attend the business. There is nothing intrinsically unjust in such a contract, for we see it resorted to by other classes of sharers. Thus the capitalist, if he has transactions with the employees, usually prefers the bargain for a fixed sum, which is called loan at interest, to the DISTRIBUTION. 49^ contract of partnership termed a sleeping partnership. Similarly, the landowner, when dealing with that species of employer whom we term the farmer, commonly prefers the form of bargaining called rent to the contract of partnership known as the metayage system. In both cases all rights Over the produce are voluntarily surrendered in exchange for a fixed annuity. However, for a contract of this kind to be equitable, the con- tracting parties should be on an equal footing. That is the case in the instances given above. The lender and the landowner are certainly on an equal footing with the borrower and the farmer ; nay, they possess a superior position, in virtue of which they will not abandon their eventual rights to the produce, unless they are equitably compensated. Thus the balance is usually on their side, and that is evidenced in the terms of the contract. But in the contract of w^ages the positions are reversed. It is the master who holds the whip-hand over the laborer ; and there is great fear that the latter, pressed by want, will do as the hungry Esau did, who sold his birthright for a mess of pottage. Further, leaving the high ground of justice, and using the criterion of social utility, the contract of wages is seen to have a vice which absolutely condemns it. As soon as the laborer sur- renders his interest in the product of his labor, he loses all stimulus to production ; nay, it is obviously to his advantage to do as little work as possible in return for the price the master pays him for his labor. He can only be made to act otherwise by the sentiment of duty or the sentiment of fear ; fear, not of the whip, as the slave feels, but of dismissal, and of the loss of his livelihood. The first of these motives can only influence minds of a higher stamp, and, moreover, grows weaker as the antagonism between masters and workmen becomes more pronounced. The second motive — and human nature may boast of the fact — has never wrung any good results from man. Further, the interests of masters and workmen inevitably clash, and the wages-system does not become more bearable for its fatal offspring, the strike. No one denies that the contract of wages is 492 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. advantageous in certain special cases ; but what is contrary to nature is that this form of contract should become the general law of present society, so that, of their own free will or not, the laboring masses are dispossessed of all rights over the produce of their labor, and are deprived of all interest in the work of pro- duction. Such a state of things can scarcely be regarded as final. We must add that the classical school will not admit this conclusion ; in its opinion, the wages-system constitutes a contract which, besides being legitimate and salutary, is also definitive. II. The Laws which regulate the Rate of Wages. Are there really any natural laws that regulate the rate of wages? The search might almost seem to be an idle one ; for wages vary in amount from one trade to another, and from one place to another, and in each individual instance are determined by a conflict between master and man. But the price of a thi-ng also varies according to the nature of the article, the time, and the place ; it is the result of a free strug- gle between buyer and seller ; yet that does not hinder us from investigating the laws which govern prices. There is no contradiction in this. No doubt, prices and wages are determined by agreements entered on by men ; but these very agreements are fixed by general causes which it is our busi- ness to discover. Our belief in the existence of natural laws in political economy must lead us to hold that men, when making contracts or agreements, are influenced by psychological motiv^es or exterior circumstances which have a general nature and can be disentangled from the confused mass of particular instances. Be- sides, it is not accurate to say that wages, any more than prices, are fixed by individual agreements ; on the contrary, just as there is a general price for commodities, which is only slightly affected by individual bargainings, so, too, there is a general rate of wages for every kind of labor which is as binding on employers as it is on their workmen. DISTRIBUTION. 493 An inquiry into the laws which govern the rate of wages is, therefore, an investigation of the general causes which have made wages higher at the present day than they were half a century ago, and better in the United States than they are in Europe : it is also an attempt to forecast whether the general tendency of wages is to rise or to fall. The problem might be set in a purely abstract way, viz. What ought to be the rate of wages in an ideal state ? In other words, Given the capital and labor engaged in any business, what share ought to fall to each? ^ Say that Robinson Crusoe furnishes Man Friday with a canoe and nets. As the result of his day's work Friday brings home ten bushels of fish. How many are to go to Crusoe (capital) ? How many to Friday (labor) ? In these terms the problem is insol- uble, but many economists have sought to find an answer. Von Thiinen, a German economist, tried to solve it mathematically in his striking book, Natural Wages. His view is that the natural wage is the geometrical mean between two factors. The first is the value consumed in the maintenance of the laborers ; the second is the value produced by their labor. Let a = necessaries and / = product ; then Wages = Va/>. (See Roscher, A'at. Ok. Deutschland, p. 895.) In his P7'incipii d' Economia pura, M. Pantaleoni has tried his hand at the problem. Less ambitious than Von Thiinen, he confines himself to an attempt to determine two fixed Hmits between which the amount of wages falls. His method is to find out the advantage which each of the parties (taken as isolated^ might have obtained. Say that Friday by himself could have filled 3 baskets of fish ; that figure, 3, is the lower limit of his claims. Say that Crusoe by himself could have procured 3 from his capital. Then under no circumstances will he give Friday more than 7, for in that case his collaboration with Friday would do him no good. Friday's wages, then, will be somewhere be- tween 3 and 7. But, if we make the feasible supposition that neither Crusoe nor Friday has obtained aught by his unaided 494 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. efforts, that the value of the isolated capital, and the value of the isolated labor, is in each case zero, then the solution of the prob- lem is perfectly indeterminate. Under the present organization of economics labor is but a commodity which, under the name of manual labor, is bought and sold in the markets like any other article. More properly it is " hired " or " let " ; but the distinction has not that importance in economics which it possesses from a legal point of view. The price of manual labor, then, must be absolutely determined by the same laws as regulate the prices of other commodities. The complex laws which we discussed when considering value are summed up in the formula of supply and demand ; in brief, the value of things is determined by their utility and by their quantity. The price of manual labor, then, must depend both on its utility and on its rarity. Its utility means the productive power of manual labor in a given country at a given time, and the need felt for its assistance ; its quantity signifies the number of laborers who have only their arms to depend on, and who offer them in the market. This is the expression of what is, not of what ought to be ; we shall see that a reaction has set in against this natural law, and that the workers are beginning to escape from it. Various economists have expounded three great theories, each of which, respectively, has endeavored to express the law of wages by a single formula which connects it with one only cause. That, in our opinion, constitutes the incompleteness of all of the theories. As was the case with profits, we shall be confronted by the bat- tling theories of the socialist school and of the optimists. Section i. The Theory of the Law of Brass. The socialist school declares that, with the present organization of economics, wages can never rise above the minimum explained above ; and that this minimum is also the maximum that wages can attain. The following is the line of argument. Manual labor, or the power of labor {Arbeitskraff) , is under present conditions merely a commodity which is sold and bought DISTRIBUTION. 495 in the market in the same way and according to the same laws as every other commodity : workmen are the sellers ; masters are the buyers. Now all commodities are subject to the law that, wherever competition can be freely exercised, their value is determined by their cost of production. This is what economists call natural price or normal value. The commodity, manual labor, cannot escape this rule. Its price, therefore, that is to say, wages, is determined by its cost of production. To quote Las- salle, Bastiat-Schulze-Delitzsch (Chap. IV), "Just as the price of all other commodities, is the price of labor determined by the relations between supply and demand. But what is it that deter- mines the market price of each commodity, or the average rela- tion between the supply and demand of any article? The expenses necessary for their production." We must now learn the meaning of the words " cost of produc- tion " when applied to the laborer considered as a material object. In the case of any piece of machinery, the expenses of production consist (^) in the value of the coal it consumes, {p) in the sum that must be yearly put by to redeem it; i.e. to replace it by another one when it is worn out. Similarly, the cost of production of labor is composed (^) of the value of the food and other articles that the workman must con- sume in order to keep in good health, i.e. to be in a fit state to produce ; {fi) of the redemption premium that is requisite to replace the laborer when he can no longer work, i.e. to rear a child till it is grown up. In brief, wages must be regulated by the value that is abso- lutely necessary for the support of the laborer and his family, or, more generally, for the subsistence and propagation of the laboring population. Such is the theory usually known as the Law of Brass. Enor- mous success has attended this sonorous term which was invented by Lassalle, and since then it has rung forth in all the manifestoes of the labor party as if it were a refrain of a Marseillaise of socialism. We must observe that though this theory was baptized and 496 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. brought into public notice by the collectivist school, it was first formulated by the classical school. Turgot was the earliest author of the statement that '' in every kind of labor the workman's wages must fall to a level solely determined by the necessities of existence." {Distributio7i des Richesses^ § VI.) Almost identical words were used by J. B. Say and Ricardo, and greatly have they been blamed for them. Whoever originated the idea, the name is an excellent one if the theory is believed to be correct ; for it burdens the working classes with the hardest yoke that could be conceived, and reduces them to a truly hopeless position. For in what way can the workman improve his condition? Can he hope to gain more by working harder and better? By no means. As his wages are independent of the productivity of his labor, his power of labor will produce only for the master who has bought it, and to whom alone its fruits will fall. Let him beware, then, of falling into the snares that will be set to induce him to make his labor more pro- ductive, — say the offer of work " by the job," or even a share in the profits. If he is victimized by these artifices, which are purely baits to wring from him the maximum of production, he will be simply playing the master's game without benefiting himself. But can he not trust that he will improve his position by keeping down his expenses and living soberly ? Again, let him beware, for that would make his lot the harder. Since the rate of wages is always on the level of the bare means of existence, as soon as the laborer learns to reduce them, wages will fall in like proportion. If the modern workman were simple enough to accustom himself to subsist on potatoes like the Irishman, or on a handful of rice like the Chinese coolie, his wages would soon be merely the sum that is absolutely necessary for the purchase of a few sacks of potatoes or bushels of rice. His frugality and his thrift would be turned against him, and he would be ensnared by the very virtues which he is exhorted to practise. Can he not, at least, expect something from the progress made in production and the increase of wealth ? No ! that would be DISTRIBUTION. 497 the very worst of all for him. If scientific discoveries were to improve machinery, and thus lower the value of food and other necessary articles, his wages, which are regulated by them, would be decreased in the same degree. Were such progress to be made that an hour's labor would produce enough for one man's daily wants, the workman would still have to labor for twelve hours : in the first hour he would earn his wages, the other eleven would go to his employer's gain. This theory, which is impressive in appearance, is really a play upon words. If we take it literally as meaning that the workman's wages can never rise above what he absolutely requires to live on, it is obviously contradicted by facts. The purely material wants of animal hfe are, on the whole, of no very great importance for man. Irish peasants and French peasants, when far from towns, live on practically nothing. If, then, this indispensable minimum for the support of physical existence were to determine the normal rate of wages, wages would be far lower than what they actually are in all countries. A literal interpretation of the theory would not explain why the rate of wages should be higher in one employment than in another. Engravers and mechanical engineers receive twice or thrice as much as navvies. Do they require a greater quantity of nitrogen or carbon? Why are the wages of agricultural laborers lower in winter, when they are obliged to spend more on fires and clothing, and higher in summer, the very time of the year which renders life so much easier for the poor that poets have been justified in calling it " the poor man's season"? It does not explain why wages are higher in France than they are in Germany, or higher in the United States than in England ; for there is no reason why a Frenchman should eat more than a German, or an American more than an Englishman. Nor does it account for the undeniable fact that wages to-day are higher than they were a century ago. Do we eat more than our forefathers did? If we discard this literal interpretation, we are told that the law refers not only to the minimum which is requisite for the support 498 PRINXIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. of man's physical existence, and is almost as unchangeable as his physical constitution, but also to the minimum which is necessary for the satisfaction of the complex wants of man living in a civil- ized environment, a minimum which varies according to the par- ticular degree of civilization. In this broader sense, the theory becomes far more probable ; but at the same time it grows far less appalling ; indeed, it appears to be almost too reassuring. Does the theory merely mean that the workman's wages are regulated by the habits and standard of life of the laboring classes, by the whole body of physical and social, natural and artificial wants which characterize the environment in which he has to live ? Is it further granted that instead of being " brazen," this minimum is elastic, mobile, and variable according to the race, the climate, and to the age, and that it ceaselessly and inevitably tends to rise in proportion to the increase in number and kind of the wants, the desires, and the requirements of civilized man ? If so, we will not gainsay the theory ; and with all our hearts we hope that it is a true one, for in that case it should be called not th^ Law of Brass, but the Golden Law of wages. But the hope is too great a one. If we ask the disciples of Lassalle why the wages of French day- laborers in rural districts, which formerly only allowed them to eat black bread and wear wooden clogs, have not now risen so as to enable them to take to white bread and use shoes as foot-gear, we are told, " It is the new wants and the new habits which have caused the rise in wages." So be it ; but if they take to eating meat with their bread and to wearing flannel shirts under their waistcoats, are we to assume that their wages will rise so as to enable them to satisfy these new wants? If so, what a happy prospect they have ! Henceforth the workman's fare need not be adjusted to his wages ; his wages will be fixed according to what he eats and how he lives. Under this rosy light the Law of Brass has been set forth in Wealth and Progress, a book by Mr. Gun- ton, an American. As we have previously rejected the doctrine which bases the value of things upon their cost of production, we should be incon- sistent in admitting its application to the case of manual labor. DISTRIBUTION. 499 Section 2. The Theory of the Productivity of Labor. The optimistic school upholds the reverse principle that wages are regulated by the productivity of the workman's labor. The theory is quite a recent one. It was first set forth by General Francis Walker, the American economist, in his book on The Wages Question, and was adopted by Stanley Jevons. It also obtained the support of three of the author's colleagues, MM. Beauregard, Chevallier, and Villey, in three works on wages, which they simul- taneously published, and all of which were crowned by the Insti- tute of France. The workman is never tired of demanding " the whole of the product of his labor," the phrase which forms part of the platform of the labor party. Such a claim would only be justified if the laborer himself had supplied all the elements of production, not manual labor alone, but also the raw material and the implements which the autonomous producer does provide. Under the wages system these conditions are not fulfilled. Once at a public meet- ing a workman shouted out the vulgar but vivid phrase, *' The man who makes the soup should eat it ! " Quite correct ; but is it the. workman who has made the soup ? No ! it is the employer who has provided the kettle, i.e. the instrument ; and the ox which gives the beef, i.e. the raw material ; and none but he sets the pot boiling. Thus the workman's claim to have all the soup for him- self, to obtain the whole of the produce of his labor, is utterly unreasonable under present economic conditions. The present theory, however, does not assert that wages will be equal to the entire value produced by the workman's labor ; for in that case the employer would gain nothing, would doubtless lose, and would therefore abstain from business. It merely holds that the workman receives in the form of wages all that remains of the entire product after a deduction has been made of all the shares which are due to the other collaborators, e.g. after a deduc- tion of the interest on the capital which he does not supply, and of the insurance premium against the risks which he does not bear. 500 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. According to this theory, the value of labor cannot be likened to the value of a commodity, which is subjected solely lo the law of supply and demand as regulated by competition. It is granted that the laborer is an instrument of production, but it is added that the value of an instrument of production depends on its productivity. When a capitalist hires a piece of land, is not the rent which he has to pay calculated according to the productivity of the land ? ^Mlen he hires labor, then, why should not the rate of wages be in proportion to the production of that labor? • If this theory is a sound one, it should be as encouraging as the Brazen Law is discouraging. For if the rate of wages depends on the productivity of the workman's wages, his destiny can be carved by his own hands. The more he produces, the more he will gain; his wages will infallibly be increased by everything that tends to increase and improve his productive activity ; viz. physi- cal development, moral virtues, technical education, inventions, and machinery. In fine, the results of the contract of wages would be even more advantageous than those of actual partnership or profit-sharing, for the workman, and none but he, would profit by ^ the entire increase of the productivity of labor ; he would literally receive the whole of the produce of his labor, after the natural subtraction of interest on the capital which he does not supply, and of the insurance premium against the risks for which he is not liable. This harmonizes with Stanley Jevons's statement, that the laborer's wages always ultimately coincide with the product of his labor, after a deduction has been made of rent, taxes, and interest. The bare enumeration of these consequences shows us in what measure the theory is in opposition to actual facts. We have already granted that the productivity of labor influences the rate of wages ; for by increasing the general wealth of a country it swells the whole mass which is to be divided, and thus comes to augment the respective portion due to each of the sharers, in whom workmen are included. It further affects the rate of wages ; for as soon as labor is more productive, the demand for it should DISTRIBUTION. 5OI increase. But one of the most essential elements is left out of account, — the abundance or scarcity of manual labor, the effect of which is usually the most powerful of all. It is not probable that the productivity of labor in the United States is smaller now than it was twenty years ago ; but in that country the rate of wages has perceptibly fallen, for the proletariat class has been largely added to, both by the immigration of foreign laborers and by the appropriation of the available land. Section 3. The Theory of the Wages-Fund. For many years this was the classical theory, especially in the opinion of English economists ; but it is now beginning to be abandoned. Like the Brazen Law, it starts from the principle that the price of manual labor, that is to say, wages, is determined by the law of supply and demand, and these two factors it defines in the following terms. The supply is furnished by the workmen, the poorer classes, who seek for work whereby to earn their living, and offer the use of their arms for that purpose. The demand is composed of capitalists who need investments ; for the only mode of employing capital productively is to devote it to the supplying of work to workmen. The ratio between these two elements will determine the rate of wages. In Cobden's picturesque and often quoted formula the law means that " whenever two workmen run after one master, wages fall ; whenever two masters run after one workman, wages rise." When couched in these terms the theory may be regarded as irrefutable, and virtually differs little from our own account of the matter. But the theory has been damaged by an attempt to ascribe to it an exactness which it does not possess, and to convert the law of wages into an arithmetical process. Take the circulating capital of a country, or the wages-fund, as the English term it, because they hold that its purpose is to sup- port the laborers during the course of their labor. Then take the number of laborers. Divide the first figure by the second, and 502 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. the quotient will instantly give the sum total of wages. Let ;^400,ooo,ooo be the circulating capital, and 10,000,000 be the number of the laborers, say in France, and the yearly average wages will be ;£40. This theory clearly demands that wages can vary only as one of the two factors varies. Therefore a rise in wages is possible only in the two following cases : — Firstly. If the wages-fund — i.e. the mass to be distributed, the dividend — happens to increase, and nothing but saving can increase it. Seco)idly. If the laboring population, i.e. the divisor, diminishes. Now it can only diminish in proportion as the workmen apply the principles of Malthus, and either abstain from marriage or have few children. The conclusion drawn by John Stuart j\Iill, the ablest exponent of the doctrine of the wages-fund, was that the only safeguard for wages-earners was a restriction of the increase in population. In this shape the theory is hardly more encouraging for the working classes than was the Law of Brass, and it practically amounts to the same result. In its opinion, the divisor (the num- ber of the working classes) must increase far more rapidly than the dividend (the amount of capital available) ; whence it follows that the quotient (wages) must tend to diminish, till it has fallen to the minimum, beneath which it cannot descend. The reason for this is, that the production of children is a far easier matter than the production of capital. The latter presupposes abstinence ; the former implies the reverse. Population is multiplied sponta- neously ; capital is not. This doctrine of the wages-fund is bound up with a conception of capital, with which we have previously disagreed. Every human society is supposed to possess a species of provision store, from which we can draw at will for the support of the laborers ; hence it is inferred that wages can be paid only out of the produce oi past labor, and never out of the produce q{ future labor. As a matter of fact, what labor produces daily is enough to support labor. DISTRIBUTION. 503 We must also note that the professed exactness of the theory is altogether deceptive. In this arithmetical sum which we are asked to solve, the three terms of the problem are three un- knowns ; in the division we have to perform, the dividend, as well as the divisor, is represented by .v. How, then, can we find the quotient ? The following is the real statement of the case : the dividend is not the amount of capital in the country, which could be calcu- lated, if need be ; but it is merely that portion of their capital which employers wish to spend in manual labor. The divisor is not represented by the total population of the country ; it is com- posed of those laborers who have to hire out the use of their arms, and from these we have to deduct all autonomous producers, who may be very numerous. Thus, on a nearer view, the theory is resolved into this : the rate of wages can be obtained by dividing the whole sum distributed in wages by the number of those who receive wages. There was no necessity to prove that. III. The Rise in Wages. The gradual rise in wages, especially for the last half-century, is an indisputable fact. Millions of statistical observations, which have been collected in all European countries, justify the conclu- sion that in this space of time agricultural wages have about doubled, and that wages paid in manufactures have increased by two-thirds, or thereabouts. For this conclusion to have any real value it should be corrobo- rated by a mass of figures, inasmuch as nothing is proved by a few separate figures, which may have been arbitrarily chosen. The requisite tables cannot be given here, but in La Main-d'auvre et S071 p?'ix, a book from the pen of M. Beauregard, Professor in the Faculty of Law of the University of Paris, they may be found, together with a mass of substantiating evidence. A general view of the subject will be obtained from the table prepared by M. de Foville, which we here subjoin. The income of a family of French 504 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. agricultural laborers for a century past is thus set forth by M. de Foville : — 1788 £S 1852 jC22 1813 16 1862 2816^. 1840 20 1872 32 The rise has been much greater in the rural districts than in the tou-ns, and in the provinces than in the capital ; this is explained by the constant emigration from the country into the towns, and from the provinces to the capital. Now, what are we to infer from this rise? According to the optimistic school, the improvement in the condition of the work- ing classes is certain, considerable, and indefinite ; further, it is spontaneously effected, and therefore, in the interests of the work- men themselves, the only policy is one of laisser /aire. This view of the matter is not shared by the socialists, their leading principle being that under the present economic organiza- tion the rich always become richer, and the poor never cease to grow poorer. They cannot deny the material fact of the rise in wages, for it is incapable of denial ; but they assert that it proves nothing as regards the improvement of the lot of the working classes, and rest their case on the following reasons : Firstly. The rise in wages is nominal, and not actual; it is merely an optical illusion occasioned by the depreciation of the value of money. If, during the last half century, money has lost half its value, how does the laborer gain by receiving as his wages a florin instead of a shiUing? He is no better off for that. There is some truth in this assertion. It is a fact that money has lost a portion of its value, especially since the discovery of the Australian and Californian gold-fields, in the year 1850 and there- , abouts ; this full in value of the monetary standard has caused a general rise in prices, and consequently an income of ^80 at the present day does not give double the ease and comfort which ^40 yielded in 1850. We must now see whether this deprecia- tion of the value of the money, or, what is the same thing, the general rise in prices, has been equal to the general rise in wages. DISTRIBUTION. 505 Now it is perfectly certain that prices have not doubled ; their average increase has not even been two-thirds ; the depreciation of money is usually calculated to be a third at the very outside. Therefore the workman who now receives ;^8o, or only ^67, instead of the £^0 he was paid forty years ago, enjoys an income which is not only larger in terms of money, but is also a more powerful instrument of purchase and of consumption. The rise in wages, though partly nominal, is also partly real. For a more accurate estimate of the improvement in general welfare that this increase in wages represents, we ought to .analyze the workman's expenses, and examine what rise in price has been sustained by each of the principal articles in his budget. ]\Iore than once already this task has been carefully performed, and the result shows a clear rise. Food, such as meat, vegeta- bles, wine, butter, and so forth, has largely increased in price, indeed, has more than doubled; house rent has grown in even higher proportions ; and these two are very important items. But bread, which is the principal article in the budget, is not percepti- bly dearer ; manufactured goods, such as clothes, are considerably cheaper ; and there is a further decrease under the headings of transport, intercommunication, and education. Secondly. The socialists add : Even admitting that the rise in wages is partly real, in any case it is not in proportion to the development of the general wealth, and to the increase of the incomes of the other classes of society. Let us suppose that fifty years ago the whole sum to be divided between the propertied classes and the proletariat was ^400,000,000 sterling, or ^200,000,000 for each. Yet the total, now, has risen to ^^800,000,000, — the proleta- riat receiving ^2 80,000,000, and the monied classes, £^ 20,000,000. Then the rise in wages, though real, would not mean an actual rise in condition ; for though the wages-earners' share would have increased by 40 per cent, the share of the other classes would have risen 160 per cent, or four times more. The wages-earners would be better off, but they would not feel richer ; for it must not be forgotten that wealth is purely relative, and such is man's 506 PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL FXONOMY. nature that comfort itself is regarded as misery, if it is contrasted with the opulence of one's neighbors. This argument against the present social order is perhaps one of the strongest that the socialists keep in their armory; for, from the standpoint of social justice, the workers have a right not only to some improvement of their condition, but also to an increase of income at least equal to that gained by the other classes of society. As a matter of fact, this equal increase has not been made. If we look at the official list of the property transmitted in France by inheritance or donation, we find that the figures which were 2,509,000,000 francs in 1835, ^^'^^ 3jI33>c>oo,ooo francs in 1856, rose, in 1885, to 6,429,000,000, though in 1888 there was a slight fall to 6,330,000,000. As the yearly income was clearly in proportion to the entire sum, we may lay down that the total of all private fortunes has been more than trebled in fifty years, and more than doubled in thirty years. This increase is certainly far higher than the increase of wages ; for that, to take the most optimistic calculations, does not exceed 66 or 100 per cent. IV. Whether there are any Means of improving the Condition of the Wages-Earners. There are three ways by which an attempt can be made to improve the condition of the wages-earners, and each of them has been extolled by its particular school. There is the s/n'ke, or the conflict between workmen and employers. There is the /a7C', or State interference. There is co-operation, either between the master and his men, or between the workmen themselves. Before we examine these modes, we should ask whether their efficacy can be depended on. The more rigid members of the Liberal school disbelieve in the efficacy of any of them. As in their opinion the rate of wages is determined by natural laws, it cannot be influenced by any DISTRIBUTION. 5^7 artificial cause. To hold that wages can be made to rise by a combination of workmen, by a chapter of law, or by any form of association, is as absurd as to believe that fine weather can be caused by pushing forward the needle of the barometer with one's fintrer. If washes ever rise after a strike, that is because they were bound to rise in any case. The strike has only been the light tap on the glass of the barometer that stirs the always slug- gish needle to follow the movement of the mercury, and to assume more quickly its position of equilibrium. In fact, if the rate of wages is to rise at all, it will do so spontaneously ; if it has no inclination to rise, it cannot be forced up. In all normal societies the tendency is to rise. All that can be done is to aid this evolu- tion by giving freer play to the forces which have acted hitherto ; viz. competition and freedom of contract. This might be effected by the formation of the Labor Exchanges proposed by M. de Molinari, in which the supply of and demand for manual labor from all parts might be brought into touch, and from which labor might obtain a mobility equal to that possessed by capital. This tranquil mode of philosophizing has discredited the Liberal school more than anything else has, and it is justified neither by observation of facts nor by scientific reasoning. In reality, it is beyond question that the workman's condition has been greatly improved by strikes, or fears of strikes, or the formation of powerful bodies tending towards that end : this is decisively proved by the history of the laboring classes in Eng- land for the last fifty years. Further, it is beyond dispute that State interference has brought about the same result in all coun- tries, in Germany in particular. Although profit-sharing and co- operation have not yet borne much fruit, still the progress made allows us to count on their efficacy. As far as theory goes, we freely acknowledge that the rate of wages is determined by natural laws, — in a word, by the law of supply and demand ; but that does not negative its possible modi- fication by the will of man as excited by combination, co-opera- tion, or State interference. To return to the figure used above, 50', C. F., on coins, 189 note. King, Gregory, his law, 64. Kitchen-gardening, 100, 156, 327. Knights of Labor, 511. Labor, as cause of value, 55-60, 426; as meas- ure of value, 80-82 ; as agent of production, 93, 94; its part in production, 108-110; its i method, in; productive, 113-118; relation to pain, 118-121; "attractive," 118; rela- tion to time, 121-124; one factor of capital, 126, 439; compulsory association for, 146; liberty of, 166; amount of, diminished by progress in production, 348-350; relation to distribution, 423-427; with regard to private property, 439, 441-444; conflict with capital, 479; manual, 494, 495, 508; productivity of, 499-501 ; relation to wages- fund, 501-503; knights of, 511; unskilled, 511; the right to, 516, 517, 544; limitation of hours of, 517-519; field, 550. Labor bureaus, 509, 558. Labor exchanges, 507. Labor legislation, 29, 5i3-5i9' Labor notes, 75. Labor party, 499, 512, 513. Laisser /aire, 17, 28, 253, 316, 504. Land, 93; formerly used for "nature," 96; not identical with " ground," 99; as regards agriculture (see Agriculture /aj^/w) ; equal division of, 419, 420; distinguished from products, 441-445; historical evolution of property in, 445-450; periodical divisions of, 446, 447; mobilization of, 449; legiti- macy of property in, 451-455; "living," 454; "dead," 454; rent of (see Rent); un- earned increment of (see Unearned Incre- ment) ; temporary concessions of, 461-463 ; nationalization of, 461-464, 534, 535, 561; divisibility of, 466; transmissibility of, 466; free trade in, 467,468. Land banks, 303-305 (see Credit Fancier). Land laws, 454, 461-469. " Landlord," the, 532. Landowners, number of, in France, 466; not a distinct class, 471, 472, 530, 531. Land tax, 569. Large businesses, 150, 152. Large farming, 154-157. Large production, advantages and disadvan- tages of, 150-154; economy resulting from, 151, 152; in agriculture, 154-157, 453: as regards isolated production, 474, 475. Large property, 157, 465, 468. Laroche Joubert, profit-sharing in his manu- factory, 520, note. Lassalle, Ferdinand, as collectivist, 415; on the law of brass, 495, 498; on producers' co-operative societies, 523. Latifundia, 467, 468. Latin union, on the currency question, 204, 206, 207. Laveleye, Emile de, quoted on positive laws in political economy, 28; on advantages of exchange, 173, 174; on crises^ 336, 337, 341 ; on luxury, 370, 371 ; on communistic societies, 411, 412; on distinction between land and products, 442; on the Russian mir, 447; on the Bulgarian Zadrugas, 447. 448- Law, his paper money, 219; his bank, 281. Lawrence, on United States' customs tar- iff, 267-268. Leases, of land in farms, 529-532. Legal tender, defined, 190; 199, 205; distin- guished from forced currency, 288, 289. Le Claire, founder of profit-sharing, 520. Le Play, his school, 26 and note; on " family stock," 26; on environment, 97; on home- stead laws, 306 note ; on division of landed property in France, 466. Le Trosne, on exchange, 171. Leroy-Beaulieu, Paul, on division of prop- erty, 9; doctrines of liberal school, 16, 17; on double uses of machinery, 346; on lux- ury) 371; o" poverty and disease, 405; on millionnaires in France, 407 ; on collectivism, 416; on profit-sharing, 520; on landowners and farmers, 530; on fall of rate of interest, 542; on functions of the State, 556; on French public debt, 572; on conversion of French public debt, 580. Letting, the right of, 431. Liberal school, the (or classical), principles of, 16-20; on the social problem, 398, 399; on laws of inheritance, 437, 438; on free trade in land, 467; on State interference, 517, 555» 556; on profit-sharing, 521; on co- operation, 525; on legal relief, 545-547. Liberal professions, the, 115, 470. Liberty of banking, 313, 316. " Liberty of coinage," 193, 194- Liberty of labor, 166-168. Loans, as regards credit, 272-278, 305; with regard to interest, 535-538; public, 57a- 575- Lock-out, 509, 543, 544. Loua, on mortality of classes in Paris, 405. Luxury, 369-373 ; public, 373. 588 INDEX. Machinery, 105-107; a factor of progress of productions and its drawbacks, 345-356. Macleod, H. D., on money, 90; on Gresham's law, 194 note; on credit papers as wealth, 278. Mallock, W. H., quoted on social inequality, 33- Malthus, his laws, 6, 320-323; his theories referred to, 128, 451 note ; anticipates Ricardo in teaching theory of rent, 455 note; his principles, with regard to the wages-fund, 502. Mancipatio, 188, 445. Manufactured products, 330-333. Manufacturing industries, 113, 329. Markets, law of, 342-344. Marshall, Professor, on distribution of labor, i63 note. Marx, Karl, his works on socialism, 23; on theories of value, 55, 56, 59; on measures of values, 80, 81 ; his definition of capital, 138; collectivism, 415, 416; his formula for distribution of wealth, 426, 427 ; on capital and labor, 439; on autonomous producers, 474- Master, the (or Employer), 148, 470,477-481. Mathematical method in economics, 7, 54, 55. Maximum of issue of bank-notes, 315, 318, 319. Maximum of landed estates, 468. Maximum price, 513. Maximum wage, 513. Mazzola, on " non-material " wealth, 41 ; on taxation, 560. Menger, on final utility, 54. Mercantile system, 89, 235. Merchandise, 168. Metayage, 491, 530, 531. Middlemen, 174, 176-178, 389. Mill, James, on unearned increment, 463. Mill, John Stuart, quoted on prediction in political economy, 15; on government by classes, 26; on supply and demand, 63; on one argument of protectionists, 268; on future of production, 357; on spendthrifts, 364; quoted on abstention from consuming, 394; on inequality of wealth, 406; on un- earned increment, 463; on profits and cost of production, 483 note; on wages-fund and population, 502; on an "idle" class, 527. 528. Minimum of landed estates, 468. Minimum wage, 512. Mining concessions, to be temporary, 463. Mints, 193, 203-206. Mir, the Russian, 419, 447. Mobilization of landed property, 304, 449. Molinari, De, on laisser /aire, 17; on joint- stock companies, 149; on autonomous pro- duction, 474; proposes labor exchanges, 507- Money, relation to value, 46; as measure of values, 75; relation to price, 82; variations in value of, 83-88; as wealth, 88-92; powers of, 90-92; "hard," 91, 237, 379; sterility of, 128; as capital, 135; relation to forma- tion of capital, 139, 140; hoarding of, 140, 195; as "a common third," 174, 182-185; coined, development of, 188-190; legal, 190, 198; right, 191; heavy, 191; light, 192; clipping of, 192; token, 193, 194, 199, 204, 224; payment abroad of, 196; sale by weight of, 196; relation to monometallism and bimetallism, 198-213; metallic, com- pared with paper money, 215-222; siege, 219; metallic, amount of in circulation, 221 and note; replacement of by credit methods, 228-233; its part in international trade, 238-242; artificial scarcity of, 303; depreciation of, 332, 504; excess or dearth of, as cause of crises, 340, 341 ; relation to expenditure, 362; relation to expenditure of foreigners, 373-376; relation to saving, 379-581 ; relation to investing, 390-394. Monometallism, 198, 199; discussion of, 207- 211. Monopoly, in production, 68-71 ; of banking, 309-313, 318, 319; of landed property, 455, 464; as yielding State revenues, 561-563. Mont-de-Piete, 516. Moral restraint, 321. Mortgage, 273, 304, 305. Mortmain, 466. Motive forces, 96, 103-107, Movable goods, 441, 445, 453. Mutual loan societies, 307. National workshops, 517. Nationalization of the land, various systems of, 461-464; 534, 535, 561. Natural laws in political economy, 9-16; views of liberal school on, 16-20; views of socialist school on, 22; views of Catholic school on, 24, 25; views of historical school on, 28-30. Natural price, 495. Natural selection, 403, 546. Natural wages, 493. Natural wealth, 109, no. Nature, 95; defined, 96; its mode of collabo- rating with man for production, 96 et seq. Net product, 482, 483. Nijni-Novgorod, fair of, 178. INDEX. 589 Nordhoff, on communistic societies, 412, 413. Note to order, 276. Novatio, 228. Occupation, as origin of rights of property, 430. 431- Octrois, 570. Optimism, 18, 351-355. 442, 443, 459, 486, 499, 552=- Owen, Robert, his Malthusian practices, 321 note; his works and projects, 410, 411; on size of communistic societies, 413. Paepe, Cesar de, inventor of name Collectiv- ism, 414 note. Pain, a factor of labor, 118-121; necessary for saving, 383, 384. Palgrave, R. H. Inglis, article on "Abun- dance" in his Dictionary of Political Economy, 42 note; article on " Banking" in his Dictionary of Political Economy, 281 note; his paper on " Note-circulation " referred to, 300 note. Palmstruch, inventor of bank-notes, 287. Pantaleoni, on hypothesis in political econ- omy, 7; on " non-material" wealth, 41; on distribution of wealth in Italy, 407; on the determination of the rate of wages, 493, 494. Paper money, in relation to Gresham's law, 197; representative, 214; fiduciary, 215; conventional, 215; differences of value of, from value of metallic money, 216-219; antiquity of, 219; relation to wealth, 219- 224; advantages of, to a country, 222; advantages of, to a government, 223 ; dan- gers of, 224; signs of excess of, 225-227; replacement of, by credit methods, 228-232; compared with bank-notes, 290-292; reason of trade in, 295; depreciation of, 297-298. Par, rate of exchange at, 294; government loans at, 573. Partnership, for production and not for dis- tribution, 147; various forms of, 490, 491, 519, 530. 531- Partners, sleeping, 523. Passy, Hippolyte, on small farming, 155. Pauperism, 403-405, 471, 472, 543-553- Peasant proprietors, 464, 465, 473, 475, 476, 530. Pecqueur, a collectivist, 415. People's banks, 307-309. Periodicity of crises, 14, 336, 337. Perpetuity of property, 434, 435. Phalanstery, 164, 351, 377, 411, 413. Physiocrats, on natural laws in political econ- omy, 11; on productive labors, 113; on exchange and wealth, 170, 171; on laisser faire, 253. Political economy, object of, 1-4; definition of, i; etymology of, 2; relation to other sciences, 3; method in, 4-9; natural laws in, 9-15; various schools of, 15-30. Poor laws, 549. Poor rate, 546-549. Precious metals, decadence of, 61, 234, 235; as measure of value, 75-78; as instrument of exchange, 186; advantages of, 187, 188; choice of, as legal money, 198 ; legal ratio (155) between, in France, 200; relation to monometallism and bimetallism, 198-213; legal ratio between, in United States, 207; variations in quantity of, 210; industrial use of, 212, 238; annual production of, 222. Prediction, 12-16. Premium on gold, 225; on foreign paper, 293. Prescription, as regards rights of property, 431. Price and prices, as regards value, 46, 47; as regards competition, 64-69, 72; definition and discussion of, 82-84, 86-88; rise in, consequent on excess of paper money, 226, 227; in international trade, 239, 240; in- fluenced by protection, 265-269; affected by law of decreasing returns, 330-332; dur- ing crises, 338, 339; natural, 495; general rise in, 504, 505, 509. Primogeniture, 437, 465. Producers' co-operative societies (see Co-op- erative Societies of Producers). Production, 93-358 passim; individual, 93- 95; social, 141; insufficiency in, 320; ex- cess in, 334; progress in, 345; future of, 356; large (see Large Production); cost of (see Cost of Production). Professional beggars, 553. Professional risk, theory of, 515. Profits, as regards competition, 69, 470; legiti- macy of, 477-481; laws of and relation to •wages, 482-488; as regards profit-sharing, 520, 521 ; rate of (see Rate of Profits). Profit-sharing, 147; methods and discussion of, 519-522, 524. " Progress of cultivation," 456-458. Property, private, 350, 351; rights of, 430- 438; extent of, 438-445; in land, 442-469; large (see Large Property) ; small (see Small Property). Protection, 248-250, 252-271; history of, 253, 254; system of, 256-260; dangers feared by supporters of, 260-264; disadvantages of, 264-269; moderate forms of, 270, 271. Proudhon, his works on socialism, 23; on wealth and value, 42; quoted on time as 590 INDEX. measure of value of labor, 426; on le- gitimacy of interest, 539; on " gratuitous" credit, 542. Public debt, 570-581; registered, 571. Public expenditure, 554-559. Public health, 559. Public kitchens, 378. Public loans, 397, 572-575 '. " classing " of, 574. Public luxury, 373. Public revenue, 559-570. Public relief, 547-552. 559- Public servants, 471. Public services, 153. Quesnay, on natural laws, 11; on exchange, 171. Raiffeisen banks, 307. Railways, as means of transport, 181, 182; their costliness as regards life, 351 ; owned by the State, 453-455, 562, 563. Rate of discount, 299-303; reasons for the raising of, 299, 300; results of the raising of, 302, 303; 311. Rate of exchange, rise in, resulting from excess of paper money, 226, 227; explana- tion and discussion of, 292-298. Rate of interest, 340, 486; theory of progres- sive fall of, discussed, 539-542. Rate of profits, 482-486; its relation to the rate of wages, 486-488. Rate of wages, its relation to the rate of prof- its, 486-488; the laws regulating, 492-494; theories with regard to, 494-503; discussion of rise in, 503-510. Ratio of exchange, 72. Ratio, legal, between precious metals in France, 200; in United States, 207. Raw material, 94, loi, 102, 113. Realist (or historical) school, 27-30. Reciprocity, 270. Redemption of public debt, 576-578. Registered debt in France, 571. Registration duties, 564. Relief, the right to, 543-547; public, the prin- ciples and practice of the organization of, 547-552; outdoor, 548, 551, 552. Rent of land, discussion of theories of, 455- 461; 471; in relation to various systems of landowning and tenure, 529-532. Rent of houses, 471, 532-535. Resfungibiles, 273. Returns, decreasing or non-proportionate, Liw of, as applied to agriculture, 323-328; rela- tion to other industries, 328-333; relation to Ricardo's theory of rent, 457. Ricardo, his use of deductive method, 4-6; on labor and value, 57, 58; his theory of rent, 455-458; on rate of profits and of wages, 486 and note ; relation to law of brass, 496; on English sinking fund, 577 note. Rich, the, 403, 407, 408. Roads, as means of transport, 181, 182. Robin, on the modes of administering relief, 550- Rochdale pioneers, 388, 524 note. Roschcr, his treatise on political economy, 37; on sumptuary laws, 370. Running account, 286. Saint Simon, his system of distribution of wealth, 421-423; on abolition of inheritance, 435- Sale, the right of, 431, 432. Sale and purchase, 174, 182-185. Sale for cash on delivery, 228. Sale for cash or payment at a future date, 228, , 275- Saving, discussed, 139, 140, 379-389; causing glut of capital, 339; 360; 367; distinguished from investing, 379, 380; conditions neces- sary for, 382-386; institutions for, 386-389; automatic, 388. Savings banks, 386-388. Say, J. B., on wealth and value, 41, 42; on utility as cause of value, 54; on his law of markets, 342, 343; on harmful expenditure, 368; on law of brass, 496. Scarcity, as a cause of value, 55. Schaffle, on socialist ideal, 23; on analogies between social and biological laws, 144. Schmbller, on division of labor, 159 and note, 165; on traders, 175. Schulze Delitzsch, people's banks in Ger- many, 308. Sea-carriage, 181. Services, as regards non-material wealth, 40, 41 : as regards distribution, 399-401, 403. Shakers, society of, 413. Shopkeeper, 175, 473-476- Silver Rill, in United States, 208, Sinking fund, 577 and note. Small farming, its present and future, 154-157, 474, 475- Small industry, 107 note, 154, 474-476. Small property, 157, 466-468. Smith, Adam, on definition of political econ- omy, 2; eclipses physiocrats, 11; on labor and value, 80; quoted on labor and value, 81: on productive labor, 114; on fixed and circulating capital, 135, 136; on division of INDEX. 591 labor, 159, 163 note; on exchange, 173; on paper money and wealth, 220-222; men- tioned with regard to laisser /aire, 253. Socialist school, 21-24; on inheritance, 434, 435. 437 • on co-operation, 525; on progres- sive taxation, 567. Socialism, Christian, 25 (also see Catholic School). Socialism, Christian and not Catholic, 26 and note. Socialism of the Chair (also see Historical School), 27; on State interference, 517. Socialism, scientific, 21. Socialism, State (also see Historical School), 29, 516, 556, 561. Social question, 398 et seq. ; various solutions of, 410-429. Social solidarity, 27, 29, 165, 424. Special trade, 236, 241, Specific duties, 260. Spencer, Herbert, as sociologist, 4; on natural laws in political economy, 11; quoted for analogies between sociological and biologi- cal laws, 143, 144; quoted on interdepen- dence of trades and manufactures, 165; referred to on law of population, 323 ; quoted on inequality, 402; on distinction between land and products, 442; quoted on evolu- tion of landed property, 445; on conquest and landed property, 448; on future of landed property, 450. Stamp duties, 564. State functions, 22, 23, 555-559. State interference, 28-30, 429, 506, 507, 512- 519. 556-558- State lands, 560, 561. State monopolies and industries, 71, 561-563. State properly, 453, 454. State railways, 453, 562. State socialiim (see Socialism, State). Statistics, in economics, 9, 12. Steam-engine, the, 105-107, 356, 475. Strikes, 506; discussed, 509, 510. Succession ab intestato, 435-438. Succession duties, 469, 564. Sumner, fJraham, on occupation, 430, 431. Sumptuary laws, 370. Superannuation fund, 514, 516, 524. Superannuation office, 516. Supply and demand, law of, stated and ex- plained, 62-64; as regards division of labor in society, 166, 167; 335; as regards wages, 507, 508. Surplus value (see Unearned Increment). Taxation, 562-570. Taxes, at a fixed rate, 570; at a proportional rate, 570; direct, 564-570; indirect, 563; on doors and windows, 569; on income, 566- 568; on land, 569; on personal and movable property, 569; on trade licenses, 569; on stocks, 569. Tenure, 448. "Third commodity" (common third), 174, 186, 187. "Three-Eights," the, 122. Thiinen, Von, on natural wages, 493. Time, a factor of labor, 121-124; relation to remuneration of labor, 426. Tools, 94, 103. Torrens act, 304, 449, 450, 468. Trade, 174, 179; general, 236; international (see International Trade) ; special, 236-241. Trade unions, 510-512. Traders, 174; history of, 175; advantages of, 176; disadvantages of, 176-178; in social evolution, 233. Trades, 158-161; distribution of, 166, 167. Transference, law of, 267. Transfers of items, 232. Transport, 102, 114, 174, 178-182, 187, 843. Treasury bills, 572, 577. Treaties of commerce, 254. Trusts, 70, 329. TulTerd, on distribution of labor, 168. Turgot, removes restrictions on labor, 167; states terms of law of brass, 496; on interest, 536; on fall of rate of interest, 541. "Uncovered" (lying), 286. Unearned increment, 444, 459, 460-463, 539. "Union," the, 551. Union, Latin (see Latin Union). Urban population, growth of, 533. Usury, 535. Utility, as cause of value, 54, 59. LTtopia, 410, 411. Utopians, 20, 21. Vagrants and vagabonds, 544, 550, 553; French law on, 550, 551. Value, basis of political economy, 3; relation to wealth, 41-43; discussion of, 44-47; sub- jective and objective, 44 note, 45; causes and theories of, 47-60; variations and oscil- lations in, 60-64 ; influenced by competition, 64-71 ; relation to cost of production, 65-68; relation to exchange, 72-74; measure of, 74-88; tables of variations in, 88; normal, 495- Values, commission on, 245. Vico, his circles, 333. 592 INDEX. Victuals, 131. Vidal, a collectivist, 415. Wages, 471, 489; of employer's labor, 485; of superintendence, 486; Rate of (see Rate of Wages); contract of, 489-492; minimum of, 494, 497. 498; theories of, 494-503; rise in, 503-506; fixed minimum of, 512; fixed max- imum of, 513. Wages-earners, 471, 472, 489, 506, 513-525. Wages fund, 354, 355, 501, 503. Wages system, 147, 490, 492. Walker, General Francis A., denies depreci- ation of government securities in United States in times of crisis, 315 note; his theory of the productivity of labor, 499. Wallace, A. R., on distinction between land and products, 442. Walras, on hypotheses in political economy, 7; on final utility, 54; on scarcity as cause of value, 55; on capital, 133; on distinction between land and products, 442. Wants of man, the, 3, 34-37. 47-54. 357-358, 497. 498. Wars, present or prospective, a cause of in- creased public expenditure, 555. Wealth, as object of political economy, 1-3; double meaning of, 31, 32; motives for seeking, 32, 33; definition of, 38; question of materiality of, 40, 41; relation to value, 41-43; relation to metallic money, 88-92; natural, 109, no; gratuitous, no; the first, 127; distinguished from capital, 130-135; relation to exchange, 169, 170; relation to paper money, 220; relation to credit, 273- 275, 278; relation to increase of population, 320; insufficiency of, 357, 406, 408; employ- ments of, 359, 360; inequality of, 401-406; active, 415; formulse for division of, 418 et seq. Wirth, Max, on crises, 337 note; on con- quest and wages, 489 note. Women, limitation of hours of labor of, 517, 519- Workhouse, the, 550. Wuarin, on taxation, 555. Zadrugas, the, of Bulgaria, 447. 592 INDEX. Victuals, 131. Vidal, a collectivist, 415. Wages, 471, 489; of employer's labor, 485; of superintendence, 486; Rate of (see Rate of Wages); contract of, 489-492; minimum of, 494, 497, 498; theories of, 494-503; rise in, 503-506; fixed minimum of, 512; fixed max- imum of, 513. Wages-earners, 471, 472, 489, 506, 513-525. Wages fund, 354, 355, 501, 503. Wages system, 147, 490, 492. Walker, General Francis A., denies depreci- ation of government securities in United States in limes of crisis, 315 note; his theory of the productivity of labor, 499. Wallace, A. R., on distinction between land and products, 442. Walras, on hypotheses in political economy, 7; on final utility, 54; on scarcity as cause of value, 55; on capital, 133; on distinction between land and products, 442. Wants of man, the, 3, 34-37, 47-541 357-358, 497. 498. Wars, present or prospective, a cause of in- creased public expenditure, 555. Wealth, as object of political economy, 1-3; double meaning of, 31, 32; motives for seeking, 32, 33; definition of, 38; question of materiality of, 40, 41; relation to value, 41-43; relation to metallic money, 88-92; natural, 109, no; gratuitous, no; the first, 127; distinguished from capital, 130-135; relation to exchange, 169, 170; relation to paper money, 220; relation to credit, 273- 275, 278; relation to increase of population, 320; insufficiency of, 357, 406, 408; employ- ments of, 359, 360; inequality of, 401-406: active, 415; formulae for division of, 418 et seq. Wirth, Max, on crises, 337 note; on con- quest and wages, 489 note. Women, limitation of hours of labor of, 517, 519- Workhouse, the, 550. Wuarin, on taxation, 555. Zadrugas, the, of Bulgaria, 447. UNIVERSITY "*^^j.LEY J V from which borrowed. This hook IS L>iJ^ NOV 21 ^947 FEB 1^ t948 14Dec'48W^' 22Jt!l'5Slt JUL 9 1953 LI IN STACKS MAR 24 1960 REC'D l_D JUN8 1960 i>C Jtt;.. C r I Dec o.d7(A5702sl6)476 10755:> YB 60857 ^-^ mm. mm >:> •;?>:i:>^;»;>;sss*;t>M ''•''^•>i>i>:?:>'>J»f;Jtf ? >.v > >•► sr> :>:">?; :^«?Jl}j5i :;fJ5;?{»;BJ%?{i ►j'^; ;>>>»ji?i;> i >'M >'.r,>;'iiit>^>' '-►-'i't'ijijfjJj? JS '''i'i>i>Sgl>f>if^ > >c> >;?; i^j^jiilill '>'><>i»W^J