^toow A THE RELIGION OF PLATO THE GREEK TRADITION FROM THE DEATH OF SOCRATES TO THE COUNCIL OF CHALCEDON (399 B. C. TO 451 A. D.) INTRODUCTION : PLATONISM VOLUME I. THE RELIGION OF PLATO THE RELIGION OF PLATO BY PAUL ELMER MORE AUTHOR OF "SHELBURNE ESSAYS" PRINCETON UNIVERSITY PRESS PRINCETON LONDON : HUMPHREY MILFORD OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS 1921 Copyright, 1921, by Princeton University Press Published, 1921 Printed in the United States of America PREFACE In the Preface to my Platonism I said that my purpose in pubhshing that work was to lay the foundation for a series of studies on the or- igins and early environment of Christianity and on various modern revivals of philosophic re- ligion. Four years have passed since those lec- tures were delivered and printed, and the project which then stood rather vaguely before me has taken more definite shape. My plan now is that the series — or better, perhaps, the core of the series — should consist of four volumes. Of these the first is presented herewith; the second will deal with the Hellenistic philosophies, principally Epicureanism, Stoicism, and Neoplatonism; the third will be on Christianity, and the fourth will contain a number of essays on fundamental ques- tions raised in the course of the foregoing studies. As I have already observed, and may have to observe again, my intention is not at all to com- pose a history of Greek philosophy or of Chris- tian dogma ; the work in these fields has been done thoroughly and repeatedly. Nor am I concerned with ultimate origins. No doubt, to take the present volume, an exposition of Plato's sources would be interesting and would throw a clarifying 45G775 vi PREFACE light on some of his religious ideas ; but this field also has been well covered, notably by Erwin Rohde. Somewhere one must start, some re- striction one must accept ; and the inclusions and limitations imposed on the task here begun are determined by the fact that it is undertaken with a very definite thesis in view. Just what that thesis is it may be well to state at the outset in the fewest possible words. My belief then is that Greek literature, philo- sophic and religious, pagan and Christian, from Plato to St. Chrysostom and beyond that to the Council of Chalcedon in 451 a. d.^ is essentially a unit and follows at the centre a straight line. This body of thought I call the Greek Tradition, since the main force in preserving it intact while assimilating large accretions of foreign matter was the extraordinary genius of the Greek speech. The initial impulse to the movement was given by a peculiar form of dualism developed by Plato from the teaching of his master Socrates. The great Hellenistic philosophies — Epicurean, Stoic, and Neoplatonic — were attempts, each on a dif- ferent line, to reconcile the dualistic inconsistency in the nature of things, as we know them, by forcing our experience into the Procrustean bed of reason. And each of these philosophies, it may be said here, by its rationalistic rejection of the paradox in the nature of things only succeeded at PREFACE vii the last in falling into grosser paradoxes of logic and ethics. Christianity, on the contrary, not- withstanding its importation of a powerful for- eign element into the tradition, and despite the disturbance of its metaphysical theology, was the true heir and developer of Platonism, truer than any of the pagan philosophies. And by the side of the orthodox faith, as set forth in the Creed of Nicea and the Definition of Chalcedon, there ran a succession of heresies which endeav- oured, each again on its own line, to reconcile the paradox of the two natures and one person of Christ by methods curiously resembling the mon- istic rationalism of the heretical philosophies, if I may so call them. It is this tradition, Platonic and Christian at the centre, this realization of an immaterial life, once felt by the Greek soul and wrought into the texture of the Greek language, that lies behind all our western philosophy and religion. With- out it, so far as I can see, we should have re- mained barbarians; and, losing it, so far as I can see, we are in peril of sinking back into bar- barism. Unfortunately the direct tradition passed in the East into the keeping of a people who had no strength of heart and mind to main- tain it, and, roughly speaking, with the death of Chrysostom, the virtue had at last gone out of it ; then Greece came to an end. But in the West viii PREFACE the tradition met a different fate. There it was taken up by a people of stronger nerve, who showed in rehgion the same faculty of assimila- tion as they had shown in pure literature, and who passed the inheritance on to the vigorous young races of the North. Yet if the Latin genius assimilated much, it also adapted; and the tradition, as it comes to us through this medium, assumed a new ethos at the first, and in the centuries since the separa- tion of East and West it has received accretions which threaten the integrity of its foundation. I do not mean that religion has gained nothing by its transmission through the Latin mind; a cer- tain note of character and worldly wisdom it wanted, and these Rome and her heirs could give. Nor would I belittle the intellectual achievement of the great doctors of the western Church and the western schools in the Middle Ages and since the Renaissance. But withal I am convinced that in certain important matters the Latin, and I may add the Teutonic, mode of thought has perverted the stream of philosophy and religion, and that the need of the modern world becomes daily more urgent to make a return to the purer source of our spiritual life. This does not imply that we should forget all the secular learning of the inter- vening ages, or that we should cease to be our- selves, if that were possible ; but it does recognize PREFACE ix in the Greek Tradition something which we must recover if rehgion is not to disappear and leave our existence dismally impoverished, something without which our wisdom may become vanity and our science a bondage. "We now are turn- ing," says Dr. Foakes Jackson in his History of the Christian Church, "from the great men whose writings made the Christianity of the Middle Ages and of the Reformation, from St. Augus- tine and St. Thomas Aquinas, from Luther and Calvin, to the Greek thinkers, St. Athanasius, St. Gregory of Nyssa, and St. Cyril, to help the religious difficulties of a scientific age." I would broaden Dr. Jackson's statement by regarding this eastward movement as the culmination of a half-conscious tendency of the English Church from the time of the Reformation; and I should like to modify it by including Plato with the masters of eastern theology. The volume now offered, as I have said, is the first of four which are designed to constitute a single connected treatise. The preceding volume, Platonism, may be taken as an introduction to the series, and in the main it fulfills that office suitably enough ; but, owing to the fact that when it was written the larger project of the series was not clearly formed, some things are included in it which belong more properly to the body of the work, and some things are omitted which might X PREFACE naturally be expected in an introduction. That must be my apology if any reader is annoyed by what may seem unnecessary repetitions in these two books on Plato. The narrowing of time and the chances of life are a warning that I should be well content if these four volumes, which I have called the core of the series, are brought to completion. But still "a dream cometh through the multitude of business," and a man's "heart taketh not rest in the night" — which, the Preacher adds, "is also vanity." Already other subjects, on the fringe of the projected circle, are pressing upon my atten- tion. A volume on the tragedians would offer an opportunity to fill out the background to Plato's religious ideas ; a special study of Clement of Alexandria, with translations of passages from his works duly selected and arranged, would elucidate the relations of Platonism and Chris- tianity; essays on the Cambridge Platonists and the Tractarians of Oxford might furnish an in- teresting illustration of the never fully realized trend of Anglican thought. But these things lie on the lap of the gods ; and now I remember the prayer of Marcus Aurehus: "The work of phi- losophy is simple and modest, let me not be drawn away into vain pomp of words." As a control upon the discussion of the various aspects of Plato's religion, it has seemed advisable PREFACE xl that the reader should have actually before him a translation of the passage on which in each case the argument is chiefly based. Thus chapter ii, introducing the topic of philosophy, gives the hypothetical paragraphs of the second book of TJie JReiyuhlic; chapter iv contains the theological excursus that forms the tenth book of the Laws; chapter vii epitomizes the myth of creation from the Timaeus; and chapter x is from the general preamble in the fourth and fifth books of the Laws, dealing with worship and the religious life. If there is a more heart-breaking task than the attempt to convert Plato's Greek into English, I do not know it, and any one who has tried his hand thereat will understand my regret that it was not permissible to print from Jowett or some other of the standard translations. As it is, I have borrowed words and phrases pretty freely from my predecessors. In general my version follows the original closely. The only liberty I have allowed myself is to omit, without indica- tion, the scattered bits of talk that break the con- tinued flow of the argument, or, in a few cases, to incorporate a question or reply into the main discourse. This procedure has involved the oc- casional neglect of a term of address. Omissions of a larger nature are indicated. In conclusion a sentence or two regarding the footnotes. Some of these, more indeed than I xii PREFACE like, are controversial. They must be excused by the necessity, as I am bound to see it, of clear- ing Platonism of the false metaphysical interpre- tations that have been clustering about it since the days of the so-called Neoplatonists. As for the rest of the notes their aim, when not mere references, is to keep constantly in view the main thesis of this book as a member of the series, viz. that the religion of Plato is not an isolated phe- nomenon but an integral part of the great Tra- dition. It may be that I should have attained my object better if the quotations in the notes also had been turned into English; but some- thing, I felt, ought to be conceded to those readers who cherish the speech of Plato and Paul and Chrysostom, and for other readers the sight of the unfamiliar letters may serve as a provocative reminder that our spiritual and intellectual in- heritance is still intrinsically Greek. P. E. M. Princeton, N. J., May 31, 1921. CONTENTS PAGE Preface v I. The Components of Religion 1 ^ II. Translation from Tlie Be public. Book ii 22 ~^III. Philosophy: Justice and the Soul. . 37 IV. Translation of Laws X 75 V. Theology: The Being of God 107 VI. Theology: Providence and Justice . 137 v/ VII. Translation from the Timaeus. . . . 167 VIII. Mythology: The Creation 198 IX. Mythology: The Problem of Evil. 232 X. Translation from Laws IV and V. 262 XI. Rehgious Life : Worship 278 XII. Religious Life: The Ideal World. 309 Appendix A 340 Appendix B 345 Appendix C 350 1/ THE RELIGION OF PLATO CHAPTER I THE COMPONENTS OF RELIGION The subject of the present volume is the re- ligion of Plato as part of a great spiritual ad- venture of the ancient world from the death of Socrates to the Council of Chalcedon just eight centuries and a half later. This movement, despite large importations from without, was es- sentially a product of the Hellenic mind; but its record comes to us in two languages, Greek and Latin, whose genius was strikingly different. One of the pecuHarities of the Greek tongue is its richness in distinctions where often it lacks terms to gather these distinctions under a com- mon head. And nowhere is this peculiarity more marked than in the subject we have to consider; for, strange as it may seem, Greek has no ex- pression for the general idea conveyed by the word "religion," which we take from the Latin. The nearest approach to it perhaps is euseheia, or theoseheia; but the meaning of these terms is rather "piety," an aspect of religion, than religion in the more comprehensive sense. No word, or 1 2 THE RELIGION OF PLATO combination of words, can be found in the lan- guage of Epicurus, or of Plato and St. Athana- sius, to carry the exact equivalent of "religion" in the tremendous line of the Epicurean poet of Rome: Tantum religio potuit suadere malorum. On the other hand it is equally true that Latin, strong in generalizations but poor in distinctions, had no native resource for discriminating the main components of what is reallj^ a complex phenomenon, and for terms to designate these was obliged to borrow from its sister speech. If "religion" is Latin, "philosophy" and "theology" and "mythology" are Greek. Now this linguistic difference corresponds to a deep-seated divergence in ways of thinking. That is not to say that the Latin mind was totally incapable of analysis; Latin did in fact adopt the Greek terminology for the various com- ponents of religion, and so handed them on to us. Nor does it follow that, because the Greek lan- guage possessed no definite term for religion, therefore the Hellenic mind was completely in- sensible to the generalization lying behind diver- sity. Such an inference would be unwarranted, for an idea may be operative although there be no single word available to express it. But it is true that these traits of the Latin and the Greek languages are indicative of an original bias or emphasis in the mind and temper of the two COMPONENTS OF RELIGION 3 peoples, and that a language tends to preserve such a bias or emphasis among its inheritors. We can see this in the fact that, even apart from other modifications introduced by the temper of Rome, primitive Christianity as it is presented in the Latin Fathers gives the impression of an unana- lysed experience of the whole soul, whereas in the Greek Fathers it is comparatively easy to keep in view the strands of which that experience is com- posed. Undoubtedly, so far as religion is a mat- ter of character and the will, it happens that power has been transmitted with the Latin unity of conception ; but it is at least a question whether such gain in power has not been at the expense of clear thinking.^ The driving force of religion would seem to be connected with something un- analysable at its heart; its surest defence against critical attack, on the contrary, may be found in a more intellectual comprehension of its struc- ture. And so, in an age of sceptical criticism, if we care to recover our inheritance of faith, it may 1 An illustration of the danger inherent in this tendency to generalize without regard to distinctions may be found in the authorized version of James i, 27: "Pure religion and undefiled before God and the Father is this, To visit the fatherless and widows in their affliction, and to keep himself unspotted from the world." St. James is defining threskeia, "religious worship or usage," which is not coterminous with the Latin religio; and to take his words as a defi.nition of religion in toto, as they are often taken today, leads to a deplorable impoverishment of the spiritual life. 4 THE RELIGION OF PLATO be advisable to look beyond the Latin sources, on which our western world has mainly depended, to the Hellenistic Fathers of the Church, and be- yond them to the earlier thinkers of Athens, to Plato first of all. By this process we may be able to get a clearer understanding of what is univer- sally valid in religious experience, and to separate the deciduous overgrowth from what is still of vital importance for us in the Greek Tradition. In the following chapters I propose to study the religion of Plato first under the three aspects of philosophy and theology and mythology, and then as a composite whole; but as a preliminary it may be well to take a hasty survey of the changing fortune of these terms in the course of their ancient history. It is natural that philosophy, as standing for what was most presumptuously Hellenic and pagan, should have had the most diversified career. Among classical writers, from the begin- ning or from a very early period, the word ac- quired a double sense, practical and theoretic. At one time it might denote merely an unreasoned discipline or way of life, as, for example, in the speech composed by Lysias to be spoken by an uneducated cripple before the Senate of Athens : "For this, I think, is the aim and philosophy of all the afflicted, that they may live under their misfortune with as little discomfort as possible."^ 2 For the Cripple 10. 61lE COMPONENTS OF RELIGION 6 Between this ethical use of the word and its higher, more theoretical sense the interval is bridged over by such a thought as the following from Marcus Aurelius: "What then can help us on our way? One thing, and one alone, phi- losophy; which is to keep the spirit within us (ton endon daimona) inviolate and free from scathe."^ From this it is an easy step to Plato's consummation of wisdom in self-knowledge, and to that "philosophy of the soul" which is a recog- RepubUc nition of its diviner potentiality. The mediator between classical and Christian writers was Philo the Jew, a contemporary of Jesus, who made it the business of his life to reinterpret the Mosaic scriptures in the terms of Platonic Idealism, yet would not hesitate on oc- casion to speak slightingly, even contemptuously, of Plato in his desire to establish religion on a basis other than merely human wisdom.* To Philo, the Hebrew mystics of his own day were in possession of a higher truth than the wisest of the gentiles had been able to reach by means of their uninspired philosophy. As secular studies con- 3 Meditations ii, 17. 4 See particularly, in his De Vita Contemplativa (which with Conybeare I hold to be authentic), the account of the life of study and fasting led by the sect of Therapeutae in Egypt, and the contrast he draws between their modest Sabbathday pannychides and the banquets of the Greeks as described in the Symposia of Plato and Xenophon. 6 THE RELIGION OF PLATO tribute to the acquisition of philosophy, whose servants they are, so, he says, philosophy is but the contributary and handmaid of that divine wisdom (sophia) with which religion really be- gins. Philosophy, for purely human reasons, may teach the control of the passions and the gov- ernance of the tongue, and these indeed are de- sirable in themselves, but they become a more solemn and holy matter when practised for the honour and good pleasure of God/ To the earliest Christian writers, the so-called Apostolic Fathers, philosophy was virtually non- existent. Their immediate successors, upon whom first fell the task of justifying the faith intellectually, were in too precarious a position to make concessions to their most dangerous rivals, and among the Apologists of the middle decades of the second century the prevailing note is hatred and abuse of Greek philosophy .° Justin is more generous than the others; but the real change comes with Clement of Alexandria, whose life-work in the Christian field was much like that of Philo in the Jewish, an effort to enrich religion with the spoils of Platonic Idealism 5 De Congressu Eruditionis Gratia 79. — Yet elsewhere, notably in the De Vita Cotitemplativa, t] ttcit/jio? (f>iXoao(f)t,a is for him the purest wisdom of religion. All these words are used now loosely, and now strictly. 6 See, for instance, Tatian §§2, 25, 32; Athenagoras 11; Theo- philus of Antioch iii, 3-8. COMPONENTS OF RELIGION 7 while still maintaining that revelation had brought a higher kind of wisdom to mankind. In his use of the word philosophy Clement is not consistent. Sometimes it designates for him a merely negative training in logic which will en- able the believer to expose the errors of a hostile sophistry ; at other times it is a moral discipline, chastening the will and preparing the heart for the reception of truth; while again it is adopted boldly as a synonym for the revealed truth.^ But in the main Clement follows the Philonic scheme of a progress from secular studies to philosophy and from this to divine wisdom,^ although his Sophia has acquired a more definite content than the Jew's, being now the perfect and self-suf- ficient doctrine of the Word, the power and wis- dom of God displayed in the economy of salva- tion.^ Later, when their rivals have been beaten from the field and are no longer a serious menace, the Doctors of the Church can afford to forget the appropriation of the word philosophy to pagan T Strtmata I, xx, 100; xvi, 80; xxviii, 177; xxix, 182; et passim. 8 See, for example, Stromata I, v, 30, where he simply para- phrases the passage of Philo's De Cong. Er. noted above. Origen has expressed the same notion, Philocalia xii, 1: 'Iv,' orrcp a(n (fn.Xocr6(^wv iraiSts TTcpt yeto/iCTptas Koi fiovaiKr/^, ypa/u./iuiTiK^S re Kol pr)T0piK7JiXo(TO<^ta, roxid ■^fitU eiTTOJ/icv Koi irepl avT^s iXo(ro^«is Trpos xP'O'TiavKT/xov. 9 Stromata I, xx, 100. 8 THE RELIGION OF PLATO wisdom, and do not hesitate to usurp it for their special vocabulary. Thus, for instance, a popular moralist like Chrysostom can appeal to the phi- losophy of a mixed congregation almost in the manner of a Lysias addressing the Senate of Athens, while a theorist such as Gregory of Nyssa feels no need to apologize or explain when he re- fers to the whole Christian ethos as a "high phi- losophy.'"*" The word, in its progress among Christian writers from neglect to hostility, from hostility to condescension, and from condescen- sion to lordly appropriation, has come a complete circle. Philosophy is no longer a humble prepara- tion for a higher form of wisdom, as it was in Philo and, at times, in Clement, but is itself the norm of conduct and the supreme wisdom; it is not contrary to religion, but a part or aspect of religion. Yet still with this difference which clings to it from its long history, that in Chris- tianity the perception of truth has become secon- dary to and dependent upon theological and mythological dogma, whereas to the pagan it was primary and free. This similarity and distinction will grow clearer, I trust, as we proceed. Meanwhile, before passing to the other con- stituents of religion, it is important to observe a 10 For examples of this sliding use of the word see Chrysostom, In Mat. 186d, 187d, 190c, 235b, 238e, 252d, 273c, 328a, In Phil. 21 Id; Gregory, Cat. Or. 18 (with Srawley's note). COMPONENTS OF RELIGION 9 further distinction. In both the classical and the late Christian writers the word philosophy, as we have seen, had a double application. At one time it was taken ethically, or practically, to designate a certain self-mastery in conduct, while at another time its sense is intellectual and seems to rise into the region of pure intuition. The point I would make is that no real inconsistency exists in this double aspect of the word, and that even when most theoretical philosophy still retains, in proper usage, something of its simpler, practical value; it implies always theory as concerned with actual life and as resting on a definite experience of the soul. In this way philosophy, as a study of the deeper and more inward facts of consciousness, was rightly contrasted with those encyclical, or secular, studies (grammar, rhetoric, mathematics, music, etc. ) which are its handmaids ; and, as still pragmatic in its method, it was distinguished with equal propriety, though perhaps not with equal regularity, from those bastard overgrowths of eristic, or metaphysics, which are its most inveter- ate enemies for the very reason that they so subtly resemble it. In close connexion with the passage in which Philo sets forth the friendly place of philosophy between secular studies and the wisdom (sophia) that looks to the honour of God, he states in strong language the irreconcilable difference be- 10 THE RELIGION OF PLATO tween true philosophy and the abuse of reason to which the name metaphysics may be restricted: "As among physicians the so-called word-cure offers no help for the sick — for diseases are cured by medicine and surgery and diet, but not by words — so in philosophy there are mere word- dealers and word-catchers, who have no will or skill to heal the life filled with ailments, but from early youth to extreme old age are not ashamed to squabble over opinions and syllables, as if hap- piness la}^ in the endless and idle pursuit of terms, and not in improving character as the source of human life."" The same condemnation of the logomachy of metaphysics, as a caricature of genuine philoso- phy, is one of the constant topics of the later Christian philosophers. Clement of Alexandi-ia returns to it again and again. ^" Gregory of Nazi- anzus puts the case bluntly in the introduction to his Theological Orations: "On what subjects and how far should we philosophize? On those subjects that are within our reach, and as far as the mental state and faculty of the hearer can follow." The whole trend of his argument shows how clearly he saw that the dead hand of 11 De Cong. Er. 53. "Word-cure," Xoyiarpda. I do not know- to what particular sect of faith-healers the title is applied. But the term is not quite clearly defined by Liddell and Scott as associated with Galen's Aoyiarpo?, "a physician only in words." See Galen III, 145; VIII, 670. 12 i;. g. Stromata V, i, 5-7. COMPONENTS OF RELIGION 11 metaphysics takes hold of the mind only when the soul has lost its birthright of self-knowledge and is driven to chase shadows in place of sub- stances. He would have subscribed heartily to the saying of a modern divine who, like Milton, had "some not insignificant taste for the sweet- ness of philosophy," and was also well versed in the long vexations of metaphysical debate : "The genuine ground of all communion with the infin- ite having sunk away within us, all sorts of logical proofs, and logical disproofs, will quarrel to- gether about primitive certainties that shroud themselves from both."" There is no serious difficulty in keeping the sphere of philosophy separate in our mind from the other two components of religion, and, so far as it is a matter of mere terminology, there would be no harm in emphasizing this separation by limiting the word religion to designate the sphere of theology and mythology taken together as distinct from philosophy. That indeed was the actual usage of many Greek writers, and we too may find it convenient at times to employ philosophy and religion, after the manner of Philo, in this contrasted sense. It is a fact to be remembered also that philosophy, so understood, may be even antagonistic to religion. But gen- erally, in the present volume at least, I propose 13 James Martineau, Essays I, 268. — See Appendix A. 12 THE RELIGION OF PLATO to take religion in its broader scope as embracing philosophy as well as theology and mythology. These terms have a way now of gliding one into the other, and now of standing apart, as do the subjects they connote. By theology I mean, as its etymology implies, the science of God, the consideration of His na- ture in itself. Here again we have to face the fact that the terminology at our command is a part of the popular language, and as such is commonly used without technical precision. Theology is often extended to include a contem- plative, even a metaphysical, study of the whole field of the divine activity, and the poverty and fluidity of our vocabulary may justify on occa- sion this more general use of the word. But for the purpose in hand we have a right to limit its meaning to that j)art of religious theory which Gregory of Nazianzus had in mind when he gave to his orations against the Eunomians the dis- tinctive title of Theological. His subject matter, with insignificant deviations, is strictly that to which I have limited theology in my definition, that is, the bekig and nature of God, here re- garded, as would be inevitable with a Christian, in relation to the question of the Trinity as one Deity subsisting in three persons. And it is note- worthy that in his effort to unravel the perplex- ities of this paradox, Gregory, while never for a COMPONENTS OF RELIGION 13 moment obliterating the boundaries between phi- losophy and theology, does not disdain to fall back upon the procedure and theorems of philoso- phy to elucidate his theology. So in his most eloquent passage on the divine vision, admitting that all we can see of God is only as it were the back parts, as beheld by Moses on Mount Sinai — only the indications of Himself which He has left behind Him in the wonder and majesty of the created world — confessing that the reve- lation of God as Father, Son, and Spirit is no more than a clumsy translation into human speech of truths that surpass human understand- ing, Gregory compares the theologian who would approach Deity to the philosopher in Plato's al- legory of the cave, who, brought from darkness face to face with the celestial world of Ideas, cannot endure to raise his eyes forthright to their ineffable glory, but must lower his gaze to their shadowy images and reflections/* The ascent of philosophy and theolog\^ are thus, in Gregory's mind, parallel and may be taken one to illustrate the other; but their goal and object are not the same: one ends in the vision of the eternal Ideas, the other looks to the knowledge of God. Re- ligion should embrace both. Theology and mythology, especially in the Christian scheme, are never far apart, and in their 14 Or. Theol. ii, 3. 14 THE RELIGION OF PLATO confines actually merge together. The ground on which they meet is the question of Providence. In its more general aspect, however, Providence, as an expression of the power and wisdom and justice of God Himself, would properly come under the range of theology ; and so, as we shall see, it was treated by Plato. In Christianity the classification is complicated by the double role of one of the persons of the Trinity. Considered in relation to the Logos as creator and governor of the world, Providence remains fairly within the competence of theology ; but as carried out in the plan of salvation by the condescension of the Logos to human nature and His reassumption of human nature into deity it falls more specifically under the head of mythology. For mythology is just that part of religion which is concerned with the intermingling of the divine and the human spheres of being, whether made manifest by the appearance of the gods among men, or looked for in the extension of man's life into the world of the gods. As for the word mythology, we must admit that it is totally rejected by the Christians, and this for the obvious reason that it would seem to place the Incarnation on the same level with such myths of Greece as the amorous exploits of Zeus among the daughters of men and the scarcely less decorous adventures of Apollo, and COMPONENTS OF RELIGION 15 would assimilate the terrors of the judgment day to the pains of Sisyphus in Hades and the pleasures of the heroes in the islands of the Hes- perides." Instead therefore of regarding the In- carnation as a myth they preferred to speak of it as the "economy," that is as God's particular management of the human race so as to raise it from its fallen estate; while to the judgment of mankind at the divine tribunal and its conse- quences they gave the name of "eschatology," the science of the last things. If in our handling of this department of religion we recur to the clas- sical usage, it is because we have no better term than myth to include the intermingling of the two worlds whether exemplified in the doings of the pagan gods, or in Plato's allegory of creation and future judgment, or in the Christian econo- my and eschatology. But we would adopt the word without prejudice. Because the unsavoury escapades of a pagan god are called m\i;hs, it does not follow that any disrespect is intended to the incarnation of Christ by treating it also under the head of mythology. A myth may be false and silly; it may be the veil, more or less trans- parent, of sublime truth. For the connexion of theology with mythology and the distinction between them in Christian literature one may refer to the Catechetical Ora- 15 Justin Martyr, Apology I, liv. 16 THE RELIGION OF PLATO Hon of Gregory of Nyssa, which is virtually con- temporaneous with the Theological Orations of the other Gregory/*' Of the forty chapters com- posing the work of the Nyssean the first four are theological, discussing in briefest terms the being and nature of God as displayed in the Trinity. The next four chapters deal with the more gen- eral question of Providence as involved in the creation of man and the origin of evil ; they serve as a transition from the theological introduction to the mythological argument (chapters ix-xl) which occupies the remainder of the book. To the narrowly orthodox this part of the work has not been entirely acceptable, as showing traces of the suspected doctrines of Origen. To the less sensitive reader it may appeal as one of the greater products of the Greek religious imagina- tion, confused perhaps here and there in its logic ( some groping is almost inherent in the nature of the subject matter), yet on the whole presenting the act of God's self-abasement to humanity and the consequent restoration of humanity to its di- vine perfection in the form of a stirring spiritual drama. It is the sublimation of mythology; for mythology, in the end, cannot be defined better than as the drama of religion. 16 Another illustration may be found in the Contra Gentiles and the De Incarnatione of Athanasius. The first is theology, the second mythology. COMPONENTS OF RELIGION 17 Enough has been said, I trust, to show how the analytical view of religion, as composed of philosophy and theology and ,mythology, was common to the Greek writers, both pagan and Christian, from Plato to St. Chrysostom. The elements remain the same ; but it is true also that as we pass from pagan to Christian the order of assurance and of temporal acquisition among these elements undergoes a complete reversion, and that the lesson we take to ourselves will de- pend on our attitude towards what is no less than a revolution within the circle of the Greek Tradi- tion. To the pagan, particularly the Platonist, philosophy was the dominating element ; here was the starting point of religion and the sphere of whatever certainty is attainable by man; here he thought he was dealing with facts and was stand- ing on a foundation of proved knowledge. In theology he beheved he was still close to ascer- tainable truth, yet removed a step from the re- gion of immediate experience. Mythology car- ried him further afield from positive assurance, though it might be indispensable as the ex- pression, more or less symbolical, of necessary truths. The enlightened pagan might repudiate as vigorously as the Christian the popular tales of the gods, but, if he was humble as well as en- lightened, he would continue to admit that only through myth, purified of its extravagance, could 18 THE RELIGION OF PLATO he lay hold of that enigmatical intercourse be- tween the human and the divine on which the vigour of the religious life is largely dependent. Perhaps no pagan understood this function of the imagination better than Maximus of Tyre, a preacher of Platonism in the days of Commodus. "All things," he says, "are full of mystery {ainigmaton) , both in the poets and in the [an- cient] philosophers. And for my part I like rather their spirit of reverence towards the truth than the boldness of the moderns. For of mat- ters dimly perceived by human weakness the more becoming interpreter is mythology."" The mind of the Christian moved in the oppo- site direction. With him, so long at least as he remained orthodox, what the pagan called myth- ology was the starting point of religion and the field of certainty. The incarnation, with the whole economy of salvation, he regarded as a verifiable historical event, in which the imagina- tion had no part; unless this fact were nakedly and objectively true his faith was vain and his preaching a lie. Symbolism for him entered with theology ; and though he might be ready to perish for his conception of the Trinity, he would not deny that his terms for the relation of the three persons one to another were an inadequate trans- lation into human speech of truths that surpassed 17 Philoso'phoumena iv, 5a. COMPONENTS OF RELIGION 19 mortal comprehension. In a way his theological definitions were admittedly more symbolical than the Platonist's. The divergence becomes again complete when we pass to philosophy. Here, where the Platonist thought he could move se- curely if anywhere, the Christian, so far as he distinguished philosophy from revelation, saw only the blind groping of a ruined intelligence, which, unaided by divine Grace, might catch a glimpse, afar off and shrouded in clouds and thick darkness, of its true home, but in the end must sink into doubt and despair. The full significance of this revolution of direc- tion within what is essentially the same circle of religious experience will be better understood after we have completed our examination of Pla- tonism and Christianity. For the present some intimation of its nature may be conveyed by set- ting side by side certain words of Socrates and a passage from one of the Fathers. "A Hfe with- out criticism, or reflection on its meaning, is un- worthy of a man," says Socrates in the Apology; 38a and more than once he declares that the only thing worth while is to pass one's days conversing about the great problems of conduct and dis- cussing the definitions of good and evil. This is the approach to rehgion by way of philosophy ; it was Plato's way. With it may be compared a characteristic saying of St. Basil in one of his let- W THE RELIGION OF PLATO ters: "For if to live for us is Christ, it follows that our conversation ought to be about Christ, our thought and our conduct should hang upon his commands and our soul should be formed in his likeness. "^^ That is the mythological ap- proach to religion, the way of the Christian. How conscious the ancient writers themselves were of the diversity of the two ways, we may learn from the common accusation brought against the Christians that their rule was, "Do not investigate, only believe." Origen, who quotes the charge and comments on it,^^ could indeed show by way of retort that the pagan philosopher also was impelled to his initial choice of philoso- phy by something resembling an unreasoning act of faith. His reply would have been more ef- fective here, if, as in many other passages of his works, he had insisted that at least the Platonist among pagans and the Christian, though starting from opposite poles and moving in contrary di- rections, were still traversing the same road through the same broad land of rehgious faith. Our present purpose is to examine the attitude of Plato to the three components of religion. It ^^Epistola clix (Migne). 19 Philocalia xviii, 1 (Contra Celsum i, 9) : M^ €$€Ta^€, aWa TTio-Tevaov. See Greg. Thaum., In Orig. 14, for the application of this to Origen's method of teaching. Socrates had said, Apology 38a: 'O Se dvclcTaoros /?to? ov /3i