Edited by JOHN RICHARD Green
DEMOSTHENES
BY
S. H. BUTCHER, M.A.
hry*0!*'<^ FELLOW AND PRAELECTOR OF UNIVERSITY COLLEGE, OXFORD ;
' FORMERLY FELLOW OF TRINITY COLLEGE, CAMBRIDGE
3Lottt(0n
MACMILLAN & CO.
1881
9^
C O N T E x\ T S.
CHAPTEH PACE
I. The Age of Demosthenes . . . . i
H. Ills Public Life and Speeches. Early
Period 27
III. His Plhlic Life and Speeches. From the
Rise of Macedon to the Fall of
Olynthus (348 B.C.) 50
IV. His Public Life and Speeches. Prom the
Fall of Olynthus to the Peace of
Philocrates (346 B.C.) 77
V. His Public Life and Speeches. From the
Peace of Philocrates (346 b.c.) to
Ch.i:ronfjv (338 B.C.) 91
VI. His Public Life and Speeches. From
CHiCRONEA (338 B.C.) TO HIS DEATH (322 li.C.) II3
VII. His Private Speeches 129
VIII. Demosihenks as a Statesman and an Orator 141
Table of vhe Wokks of Demosthenes . 170
,-1^2
^0..l -,
tj "^^s! ?.'
<^^ ^4^-4^ cos r> ^^^^^^^^-^
^"^ v,.^^
^^ f .
^
5 Rhodes I.
T E C0../C. !
(8^1
DEMOSTHENES.
CHAPTER I.
THE AGE OF DEMOSTHENES.
In the fifth century e.g., when Greece for the first
time had to face a foreign foe, there were silent forces at
work which needed only such a crisis to call them into
active life. At the time of the Persian invasion, the
sentiment of unity took shape under Athenian leader-
ship, and overpowered the instincts of isolation. In
the latter half of the fourth century B.C., when Greek
freedom was again menaced, no such united front could
be offered. The city life, on which Greek civilisation
rested, had proved wanting in vital and expansive
power, nor was its early promise of confederation ful-
filled.
The fall of Athens at the close of the Peloponnesian
Avar had left a void in the Hellenic world which Sparta
could not fill. Sparta's claim was that of a liberator;
her nominal principle was the independence of all
cities, great and small. In effect she knew but one
rule of policy — force in its most undisguised and brutal
form. She had none of that Athenian generosity and
broad culture which had softened, if it had not re-
deemed, the harshness of empire. The thirty four
years of Spartan supremacy, from Aegospotami (405
B.C.) to Leuctra (371 e.g.), were years charged with
mischief Wherever tov/ns or villages were beginning
^ B
2 • • D£MOSTHENES. [chap. i.
to Qnite,- Spafta- stept'in and dissolved each such
nascent society into its barest elements. Indepen-
dence with her meant, what similar professions
afterwards meant in the mouth of Macedon and of
Rome, isolation and dismemberment. The work of
liberation began with vengeance and bloodshed. " The
Spartans," says Isocrates, in a weighty indictment'-
against Spartan misrule, " in three months put to death
without trial greater numbers than Athens had. put on
trial during the whole period of her empire." Between
the promise and the performance of Sparta there was all
the difference between a Brasidas and a Lysander. The
peace of .Antalcidas (3S7 B.C.), negotiated by Sparta
between Persia and Greece, may be taken as an epi-
tome of her policy. The Greeks of Asia were by it
given over to Persia — a deliberate surrender of a
sacred Greek tradition. Some seven or eight years
later, Isocrates, writing of these lonians, says: — "They
suffer worse outrage, even in their persons, than bought
slaves of Athens. No Athenian maltreats his servants
as their masters chastise freemen.'- The same treaty
had guaranteed the independence of the European
Greeks ; and as a coriiment on this Isocrates recalls
how Sparta devastated Mantinea, laid treacherous hands
on Thebes, besieged Olynthus and Phlius, levied
blackmail on the islands, allied herself with Amyntas
of Macedon, Dionysius of Syracuse, and all the
despots who threatened Greek freedom. Not the
least ruinous part of this treaty was the express recog-
nition of the Great King as having the disjio.'^al of
Greek affairs, Sparta being made executor of his com-
mands. Already, at a time when Persian gold was
needed to replenish the f;\iling exchequers of Greece,
he had interfered as paymaster ; he now apj)ears as
arbiter. The day was not far off when a foreigner
yet more dangerous would assume a like office.
* Fane^v. § 113. ' Paru^^'. § 123.
CHAP. I.] THE AGE OF DEMOSTHENES. 3
Another distinctive act of Spartan policy may be
noticed. In 3S4 B.C., Olynthus in Chalcidice was at
the head of a growing league of cities bound together
on Hberal terms of union. There is a special interest
in this, one of the earliest efforts at federal govern-
ment, and we would gladly know more of the details
of organisation than have been told us by Xenophon.
This much, however, is clear, that each city of the
league, while retaining its own constitution, had laws
and franchise in common with the other members,
and mutual rights of marriage and of holding pro-
perty. The neighbouring cities on the coast, and
some towns of Macedon, including Pella, took advan-
tage of the security afforded by the league ; but two
Chalcidic cities. Acanthus and Apollonia, clung to
their independence, and, backed by Amyntas IL, King
of Macedon, applied to Sparta for aid. Sparta, ever
jealous of confederation, sent her armies against Olyn-
thus. In 379 B.C. the city was at last surrendered,
and the league dissolved. Not till about thirty years
later was the fatal meaning of this act discovered. A
power which might have stood a firm barrier for the
Greeks of the North against Macedonian aggression ^
had been broken down.
Thus Sparta everywhere employed the name of
freedom to destroy the reality. Working on illusory
hopes, and fostering a narrow communal spirit, she
undid in the brief period of her rule whatever had
been done for Greece by Athens. The disintegrating
forces, which had been for a while arrested, now pre-
vailed. The genius, indeed, of Epaminondas AVTought
in an opposite direction ; and the nine years from
Leuctra (371 B.C.) to Mantinea (362 b.c.) were
marked by a generous attempt to repair something of
this ruin. But with Epaminondas Theban supremacy
passed away, and Thebes relapsed into her former self.
Meanwhile a new Naval Confederacy had been
4 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. i.
formed at Athens (378 n.c.) on the model of the Con-
federacy of Delos, but with safeguards against the old
abuses. It was joined by Chios, Byzantium, Rhodes,
Mytilene, and embraced in all about seventy maritime
or island cities, whom Spartan harmosts and Persian
despots had driven to seek some organised protection.
Nothing could well have seemed more hopeful than
the league in its beginnings. The internal constitu-
tion of each state was left untouched ; the odious
" tribute " {4>6f)os) with its imperial associations was
exchanged for the " contribution " (o-i'i'Ta^i?) ; and
the amount of each contribution was to be assessed
at a representative council held at Athens. Then
came the difficulty of maintaining the equal rights of
all the members. History began to repeat itself;
contingents had to be raised and payment enforced ;
the Athenian spirit of conquest was revived, and
deficiencies of revenue were made up by acts of
violence and extortion. The allies soon began to fall
away, and in 357 B.C. openly revolted. Once the
federal bonds were snapped by the Social ^^'a^, there
was no effective control over the Aegean waters, which
were overrun by corsair fleets, and preyed on by Persia
or by tyrants of the Asiatic coast. The strength of
Athens was fatally impaired, and the permanent dis-
union of Greece laid bare. Of all this there was one
interested spectator. Philip of Macedon, two years
before the Social War began, had come to the throne
(359 BC.)
AV'hile the Greek states were being detached from
the national life of Greece, the tie between each state
and its members was similarly loosened. \\'ith the
decay of Panhellenic patriotism went also the decay
of the civic virtues. Our main authorities for this
period are the writings of the orators ; and, as some
one has obsen-ed, it would be almost as absurd to
form our estimate of ancient societv solelv from the
CHAr. I.] THE AGE OF DEMOSTHENES. 5
works of orators and poets as it would be to judge
modern society simply by its sermons. Yet, when
writers of such different casts of mind as Isocrates and
Demosthenes agree in discovering the same tendencies,
and denouncing the same evils — widely as they differ
in the cures they prescribe — and when their reflections
are borne out by unquestioned facts of history, we
may safely accept the outlines of their picture.
The one mortal disease, whose workings can be
traced in manifold ways, was the severance of the
individual from the state ; everywhere private needs
were superseding public claims.
A waning interest in political life is seen first in the
Athenian Assembly. Thinned by pestilence, war, and
exile, the civic body was largely recruited from foreign- 1/^
ers; and though the process was a necessary one, it was
passionately lamented by Isocrates. In his pamphlet
On the Peace (355 B.C.) he exclaims: "We who are
so proud of our superior birth care less to keep our
nobility to ourselves against every new-comer, than do
Triballi and Leucani to preserve the doubtful purity of
their blood" (§ 50). He lays the blame down to the
liist of maritime empire to which the old families, that
had survived the days of the tyranny and of the
Persian wars, were sacrificed. " Gradually our rulers
found that they had filled the public tombs with
citizens and the public registers with aliens." Athens
had not in the same degree as Rome the power of
absorbing strangers, and of making its franchise a
privilege to be coveted ; and Demosthenes, like
Isocrates, complains that Athenian citizenship, once
valued, was now degraded. ^ Aristocrats began to y/
look on politics as disreputable ; the wealthy merchants,
too, many of whom were luetics, not citizens, took but
a slight part in public life. A poorer class now pre-
ponderated in the Assembly, which in part consisted
^ Dem Aristocr. § 201.
6 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. i.
of a needy rabble, to whom politics and spectacles were
daily bread. " One comes and another goes, but no
one cares for the public good."^ Important motions
were sometimes carried without any one knowing what
had happened. The difficulty, too, of keeping order
in the Assembly seems to have become so serious that
a special police regulation for the protection of the
chair was passed shortly before 345 B.c The mem-
bers of the tribe to which the Chairman belonged were
ranged round him as a bodyguard. - A certain Aris-
togeiton in particular achieved evil distinction by a
persistent and noisy impudence, " overriding the laws,
the orders of the day {rov TrpoypdfifjiaTos), and public
decency.""* Frequent laws were carried to benefit
indi\-iduals, and these were sometimes made retro-
spective.'* Indeed, the statute book was full of
contradictory enactments, passed for occasional pur-
poses, and without regular formalities.^ Demos-
thenes (Z<'//. § 92) singles it out as one great blot
in Athenian government, that decrees of the people
had acquired more validity than the laws. And
Aristotle i^Polit. vi. 4) sees here the note of a per-
verted democracy, such as was in no sense a con-
stitution. Similar in purport is a saying of his
recorded by Diogenes I^aertius (v. 17), that whereas
wheat and laws were among the discoveries of Athens,
the wlieat was used but the laws were not used.
The growing indifference of the ordinary citizen
towards politics tended to leave the administration in
inferior hands. After Pericles, there had been a rapid
descent to Cleon and Hyperbolus, and the demagogue
of the fourth century is drawn for us as one who
studied the art of flattering the masses. Demosthenes
1 Deni. Embassy, § 136.
5 Cf. Aesch. Timarch. % 33.
' [Dem.] Aristogfit. § 9 ; cf. Exordium 53.
* Dcrn. Timocr. § I16. » Dem. Lept. %% 90, 91.
CHAP. I.] THE AGE OF DEMOSTHENES. 7
describes the people as like some tame animal led about
by his keeper, who ministers to his lower wants ^ (p. 74).
The Great Beast of Plato, humoured and pampered,
occurs to us as the companion picture. Such descrip-
tions do not, indeed, give us the whole truth. A people
who revered personal integrity so far as to elect Pho-
cion forty-five times general ; who, even after defeat,
did not desert Demosthenes ; who at the last were
guided by Hypereides and Lycurgus, cannot have been
as degenerate as has sometimes been supposed. Poli-
tical tact never wholly failed them ; but their moral
fibre was weakened, they had many lapses, and could
not long sustain themselves at the higher level. Signs
were not wanting that the democracy was losing faith
in its own virtue and capacity, and was not far from
a voluntary abdication of its functions. The forms
and vital usages of the constitution were suffered to
fall into disuse. Ordinary law was not enforced.
Never since the Areopagus was divested of its ancient
privileges had that body been so frequently invoked ,
to wield exceptional powers as during the contest
with Macedon. The extravagant rewards, too, and the
homage paid to political leaders indicated a secret
self-contempt 2 on the part of the people — a temper
peculiarly dangerous in a city where personal influ-
ence was supreme.
At Athens, it must be remembered, there was
nothing corresponding exactly to a Ministry in our
modern sense. The Assembly had no responsible
leaders, and those with whom the real power lay were
not necessarily those who held official position. The
ordinary magistrates, appointed by lot and for a single
year, and subject to dismissal at any moment, could
not be expected to carry out any continuous policy or
show special competence. The ten generals, though
their office was elective, and a certain fitness was so far
^ Olynth. ii. § 31. - Dem. Aristocr. § 209.
8 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. i.
guaranteed, exercised powers that were too much sub-
divided to be effective. The one official body that
had any real control over the details of administration
was the Council of Five Hundred. All measures were
submitted to them before they could be proposed in
the Assembly. At the beginning of each year they
examined the accounts of the outgoing magistrates,
and prepared a budget for the ensuing year. Many
also of the functions now vested in a Board of Public
Works or in the Admiralty devolved on them. But
they, too, held office only for a year, and owing to their
unwieldy size had to work through committees
(TrpiTaveis), each of which conducted public business
for so many weeks in its turn. The general principles
of policy were determined, not by the Council, but by
the regular speakers (pi'jTopci) of the Assembly, forming
as a rule a small group of ten or twenty men, who led
the debates, framed measures, and were the true poli-
ticians of Athens. So far as any permanent ^ element
entered into the conduct of affairs, it might be traced
to these unofficial rulers, to their personal influence
and direction. And though ministerial departments
in the strict sense were unknown, a man of sj)ecial
aptitude would devote himself to a single branch of
the administration ; and it was possible to be, as De-
mosthenes virtually was, Minister of Foreign Aflfairs
for a prolonged period without holding any official
appointment beyond an occasional post such as that
of ambassador.
Party government, then, strictly so called, did not
exist ; and party itself was hardly possible where
cohesion and principled union were lacking. The
' The Trcasur)' w.ns the one department where some admini-
strative continuity was secured. The ".Steward of the Public
Revenue" (roju'oy t^s Koivfji irpoffdSov) — the nearest ajipro-ich
to our Chancellor of the Exchequer — was elected for a term of
four years. Lycurg\is held the office for twelve years in all.
CHAP. I.] THE AGE OF DEMOSTHENES. 9
Assembly naturally fell under a shifting clique manage-
ment Demosthenes tells us of a " certain band of
veteran orators"^ who possessed the ear of the house,
and silenced " private members " (ol tStwrat). Of
another similar faction we elsewhere " read : "As
though they were not members of a free common-
wealth, where each and all have therefore a right to
speak, but as if the constitution were an exclusive
priesthood of their own, they are indignant if any man
speaks up honestly in your presence, and they call him
audacious. , . . They bid you crown and not crown
whom they choose, and make their own will supreme
over the resolutions of the house." It was doubtless
to secure the neutrality of the chair, and to prevent
the managing committee of the house from asserting
a corrupt or despotic influence, that the rules for
appointing a Chairman of the Assembly were altered
in the fourth century B.C. ^
A passage in the Second Olynthiac gives us an
insight into the character of a political clique based
on an alliance between generals and orators. The
organisation of this coterie is compared to the legal
organisation for collecting the property-tax (et'o-^opa)
by means of Boards (o-i'/x/xopiai), whose Three Hundred
wealthiest members advanced the money for the other
ratepayers, and so acquired a dominant influence.
Each Board was presided over by a chairman (i^ye/xwv),
^ Androt. § 37.
- Dem.(?) Trier arch. Crown, §§ 19, 22.
^ In the fifth century B.C. the managing committee {vpvTa.vei%),
who, it must be observed, all belonged to the same tribe, appointed
the chairman of the day by lot from their own number. Their
tribe was called the Trpvravevova-a (pvX-rj. In the fourth century B. C
the chairman was one of nine />rocJn' {wpoedpoi), each of whom
represented one of the tribes other than the wpvTavevovaa (pvX-^.
The tribe to which the chairman now belonged was called the
TTpoeopevovaa . § 54. ■' Lysias, Or. xxx. § 22.
* Lysias, Or. xxvii. § i.
" ^.^j;'." L)-sias, Or. xviii. §§ Jj-iJ-
y
CHAP. I.] THE AGE OF DEMOSTHENES. ii
led to the ruin of democracies/ was less frequent in
the second half of the fourth century than at the close
of the Peloponnesian war ; it is mentioned, however,
by Demosthenes, as a method still in vogue among
"dashing" politicians.^ As lawsuits had to begot
up to provide a pittance for the mob, professional
accusers were found to do the work, making lucrative
jobs for themselves, and earning a reputation as good
democrats.^ " It is far more dangerous," says Isocrates, .
"to be suspected of wealth than to be an avowed w^
criminal."^ Timid but opulent citizens would pur-
chase the silence of the informer rather than face the
courts. The praise of poverty in Xenophon's Syj?i-
posium ^ is only half ironical. As a rich man, says
Charmides, he was in constant dread of robbers and
sycophants. There was always some new tax to pay,
and it was impossible to go abroad and escape it.
But ever since he has been ruined and his property
sold up, his case is very different. " Stretched at full
length I sleep comfortably ; I am no longer threat-
ened ; it is I that threaten others. A free man I go
abroad or remain at home. The rich now rise in
my honour and give place to me from their seats
and on the road. To-day I am like a tjTant ; lately
I was unmistakably a slave. I then paid tribute
to the state ; to-day the state pays tribute and sup-
ports me. .... I lose nothing, for I have nothing
to lose, and I have always the hope of getting some-
thing."
Not only was extortion practised by professional
accusers, but the tribunal itself was frequently corrupt. *^
The word denoting the direct bribing of a jury
(S£K-a{'€6i') is first found about the beginning of the
1 Arist. Pol. vi. 3. •* Isocr. Anticl. § 160.
- Dem. Chers. § 69, ° Xenoph. Sympos. § 30 ff.
2 Isocr. de Pace, § 133.
12 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. i.
fourth centur)' c.c. ; and though it is not easy to see how
juries consisting of five hundred members ormore could
be effectively bribed, the fact that they were so is beyond
^ dispute. It was part of the general corruption per-
vading public life, that disorder with which Greece
was "sick even to death." "Envy if a man has
taken a bribe, ridicule if he confesses it, pardon if his
guilt is proved, and every other appendage of corrup-
tion."^ Bribery itself was no new feature in Greek
politics ; what was new was that it had become so
systematic and was little reprobated. Here was one
symptom of the deep disloyalty that was poisoning
the sources of Hellenic life. We read of orators who
were paid to speak and paid to keep silence ; their
/ business was " to earn their pay, not to express views."-
They trafficked in the honours of the state. " Your
privileges and rewards are to them so many trumpery
wares to be sold by public auction. They give them
away at the lowest possible price, and have a fixed
charge for which they draw up any form of decree
that their numerous employers may require."^
Popular morality, however, established a certain
distinction in cases of bribery. To take bribes was
pronounced to be wrong, but only when they were
taken against the interests of the state. This is expli-
citly stated by Hypereides."* The distinction may sound
to us impudent or unmeaning ; but there have been
periods in our own parliamentary history, during the
seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, when the same
idea has prevailed; or, if not the same, the kindred idea,
/ that to give bribes in the interest of the state, in other
words, of party, was justifiable. The saying ascribed
to Walpole, and which at least expresses the theory
' Dcm. Olynth. iii. § 39.
- Dcm. (?) Tricianh. Crmvn, § 19.
' Dem. Aristocr. § 201 ; cf. Triercirch, Crcnvti, § 22 ; and Isocr.
dc Pace, §§121-131. ■• Ilypcrcid. A^t. Dcm. .\xi.
CHAP. I.] THE AGE OF DEMOSTHENES. 13
on which he acted, that " every man had his price,"
was in principle almost equivalent to the more cynical
avowal of Demades, that " he took money and in-
tended to take it."^ Nor must we forget that the
Greek orator, who aspired to be a leading statesman,
occupied a very peculiar position. It was his duty
to be well instructed in the current politics of all the
chief cities, to have trustworthy agents abroad, to
form friendly ties with foreign potentates, to carry on
secret negotiations ; and all this as the unofficial un-
salaried adviser of his country, unaided even by grants
for secret service money. Further, he was expected
to be liberal in his home expenditure and in
voluntary donations to the state. Many sums, of
which it might not be easy to render public account,
passed through his hands and yet left them unsoiled ;
and even the receipt of gifts would not always argue
want of patriotism. A private fortune was becoming
one of the first conditions of political life, and the
Athenians were content that their statesmen, like
their generals, should look outside the city to enrich
themselves, provided that the public interests were
not sacrificed. Yet, whatever might be a statesman's
honesty of purpose, the imputation of venal motives
was a resource too near to hand not to be made the
most of by his opponents. Few escaped suspicion
save those who, like Phocion, contemptuously shunned
contact with affairs, and whose political action was
limited to the bare requirements of duty.
We need not then believe half the charges brought
against one another by rival orators ; but that the
charges should be so lightly bandied is in itself a vicious
sign. Politics which, with the progress of knowledge,
had first been elevated into an art, were now degraded
into a trade. Demosthenes and Isocrates both con-
trast the statesmen of the elder democracy with those
^ Deinarch. Agst. Devi. § 104.
14 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. i.
of their own day. " Politics were not with them a
way of making fortunes." ^ " They regarded govern-
ment not as a mercantile speculation but as a public
service."^ The change was inevitable in a wealthy
democratic society where there was no responsible
Ministry.
The external face of Athens bore evidence of
altered relations existing between the individual and
the state. The grandeur of private houses and of all
that surrounded private life, was in striking contrast
with the meanness of the newly erected public
buildings. The Greeks were more sensitive than we
are to such a contrast Greek art in its best days
stood in intimate connection with national life and
the religious sentiment In the service of the gods it
attached itself to the social activities of man ; it did
not gratify vulgar display or set off personal ambitions.
Once it had issued from the temples its home was in
the thoroughfares of civil life. Till the fourth centun,'
B.c, the highest efforts of architecture had been spent
on the erection of public buildings. But as private
fortunes grew, architecture, an ' after it painting and
sculpture, began to minister to private delights and to
individual culture. At the beginning of the Periclean
age the citizens, from old association, lived chiefly in
the country, and wealthy owners prided themselves on
their country houses, while their town dwellings were
on a much smaller scale.^ Houses and lands, said
Pericles, were merely " the garden of the house, the
superfluous ornament of wealth, "■* possessions to be
lightly resigned in obedience to state interests. Soon,
1 oi) yitp et'j wepiovfflav (irpdrTeTO avTols rd rlys iro\«ws. — Dcm,
0/j'tt//i. iii. § 26.
3 ov yiip iiiiroplav aWa. \(iTovpy[ay ivoixi^ov tXvai. ttjv riv
Koifdv imu^Xeiav. — Isocr. Arcop. § 25.
* Isocr. Arcof> § 52.
* Thucyil. ii. 62, I'rof. Jowctl's translation.
CHAP. I.] THE AGE OF DEMOSTHENES. 15
however, the insecurity of life consequent upon war
brought a large population inside the walls, and
henceforth, as personal luxury grew, the public and
private buildings were seen in painful antithesis.
Upon this topic Demosthenes dwells with emphatic
repetition.^ " Moreover, former times were times of
national prosperity and splendour : no man then stood
out above his fellows. The proof of it is this. — Some
of you may know the style of house of Themistocles
or Miltiades, or of the illustrious men of that day ; you
see it is no grander than the mass of houses. On the
other hand, the public buildings and edifices were of a
magnificence and beauty such that posterity cannot
surpass them — the gateway of the Acropolis yonder,
the docks, the porticoes, and the other permanent
adornments of Athens. To-day your statesmen have
vast private fortunes : some of them have built for
themselves houses grander than many of the public
edifices ; some again have bought up more land than
all of you who are in this court together hold. As
for the public buildings which you erect and whitewash,
I am ashamed to tell ct their meanness and squalor."
{Aristocr. §§ 207, 208).
The festivals were the only national institution
which seemed to retain reality. Demosthenes draws
a comparison- between the punctual precision with
which they were celebrated, and the late and irregular
equipment of the armaments \ and the comparison is
the more pointed because festivals and armaments
alike were provided by the wealthier citizens. In
the one case all details were "prearranged and de-
finite, nothing was left to chance;" in the other "all
was unorganised, unsystematic, and vague " (araKr'
■^ Dem. Aristocr. §§ 206-20S ; Olynth. iii. §§ 25, 26 — a passage
almost verbally repeated by the imitator who wrote the speech
Tfyot o-i^trdlewj (§§ 29, 30) ; cf. also Androt. § 76 ; Timocr. § 184.
2 Dem. Phil. i. §§ 35, 36.
i6 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. i.
dSiopdwT uopurd' aTTavra). A special fund called the
Theoricon had been long ago set past to enable the
citizens to attend the festivals and the theatres. By
means of this bounty the great public solemnities
were brought within the reach of poor as well as rich.
Such an equality of noble enjoyments seemed neces-
sary to complete the democratic idea. Grote has
shown how the Theoricon had in the first instance
a religious aspect ; the public worship of Greece was
embodied in the festivals, which included sacred pro-
cessions, banquets, dramatic entertainments, and
musical contests. The fund thus appropriated ac-
quired something of the sanctity of a Church Fund.
But by degrees the more serious meaning of the
festivals became obscured, and at this time they were
little more than a form of public amusement. Since
the days of Pericles the sums given away as festival
money had been trebled ; the conditions too under
which it was bestowed had been altered. The old
laws provided that in time of war the surj^lus revenue,
after the civil expenditure had been defrayed, should
go to the military iund.*- This provision was con-
stantly neglected ; the surplus was as a rule carried
to the Theoricon in time of war no less than in
peace. Before the end of the Peloponnesian war the
distribution of festival money had been for the time
suspended ; it was revived under the restored demo-
cracy. But hitherto the payment of the bounty had
been dependent on the existence of a surplus in the
revenue. A law of Eubulus, passed in 354 RC,
introduced a totally new principle.-' The festival
^ [Dem.] AVrttVd, § 4.
- The traditional statement that Eubulus .attached the penalty
of death to any ]^ri>]nisal for applying the Theoricon to war pur-
l>oses rests on the late evidence of a Scholiast. The idea was
probably basetl on an over-ftleral acceptance of the word airo\iff6ai
in Olyttth. iii. § 12.
CHAP. I.] THE AGE OF DEMOSTHENES. 17
money was now made a first charge on the revenue.
The superintendents of the Theoricon were given
a permanent control over the entire finances of the
state. If the treasury showed no surplus, an adjust-
ment must be made elsewhere. Some other branch
of the public service had to be starved in order to
provide the guaranteed dividend. Like the distribu-
tion of cheap corn at Rome, this festival dole was
among the most demoralising of all the influences of
a corrupt age. It was called by Demades the cement
(ko AAa) of the democracy (Plut. Mor. p. ion b);
and with still greater aptness it was compared by
Aristotle to the sieve of the Danaids (Arist. Pol.
vii. 5)- _
The Festival Fund stood, as we have seen, in
intimate relation with military affairs, and to these we
must now turn. We are here met by a fact of capital
importance, which shaped the foreign policy of Athens
and reacted powerfully on home affairs. With the
growth of mercenary armies, which belongs to this ,
century, the old military organisation broke down.
The mercenary system has not been confined to
Greece : it has sprung up elsewhere in decadent
societies — in Egypt, Carthage, and ancient Rome, as
well as in medieval and modern Europe. But no-
where was it so disastrous as at Athens, for nowhere
else was the life of thought so closely knit with that
of vigorous action.
Owing to long-continued wars military tactics at
the opening of the fourth century B.C. had made vast
progress : it was found that amateur soldiers could
not compete with professionals, and war became a
trade. The demand for mercenaries came first from
Asia, There the superiority of the trained intelli-
gence of the Greek over the barbarian had been
long discovered, and pay and plunder were most
plentiful in the Persian service. The custom spread
c
l8 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. i.
to the mainland of Greece, and the Corinthian war
(394-390 B.C.) marked its beginning. Even Sparta
sought the aid of this venal courage. The armies
of Greece, like those of Asia, were recruited " from
men without cities, from deserters, and from the dregs
of the criminal classes,"^ who enhsted under the
highest bidder. "The bodies of the Hellenes," says
Lysias, "belong to those who can pay." We have
many pictures of the terrible excesses practised by
these Greeks, "who were barbarians in all save
speech."^ "Common enemies of mankind" is the
title given them by Isocrates, ^ and Demosthenes uses
almost identical language.'* But ruinous as they were
to the countries over which they moved, and especially
to the seaboard of Asia, Greece herself was in the
end the worst sufferer. Of those who thus took service
abroad the greater number never came home. The
drain upon the population went on in increasing
volume. At Issus 40,000 Greek mercenaries fought
for Darius. Finally, Greece perished, says Polybius,
for want of men.
If we turn to Athens we can trace the working of
the change under a double aspect First, the citizen
^ was no longer a soldier. Legally, indeed, he still
continued such ; for in the ancient republics the ques-
tion of compulsory militar)' service was not raised.
From primitive times, when the peo])le was tlie army,
the identity between soldier and citizen had been
tacitly assumed and laid down by law. Ever)- young
man between the age of eighteen and twenty had still
to go through a period of short service on the frontier
preparatory to admission into the regular army. But
here it generally ended. No further militar)' duty was
enforced, and foreign service was in the main left to
4/ mercenaries. This was not due merely to the desire
J Isocr. de Pace, § 44. » De Pace, % 46.
* Isocr. E/i. ix. 9 8. * Aristocr. § 39.
CHAP. I.] THE AGE OF DEMOSTHENES. 19
for repose after an exhausting struggle, or to the exi-
gencies of professional warfare. It was one of the many
symptoms of the decay of civic loyalty. The citizen^/
ceased to be a soldier when he ceased to be a politician.
As the internal government was handed over to a
small knot of orators, so the defence of Athens abroad
was left to mercenaries. The evil at first appeared
under a mitigated form. Chabrias, Iphicrates, and
Timotheus tempered the mercenary element by a
large admixture of citizen troops. Under Chares
and Charidemus the new system was in full develop-
ment.
The case of the fleet differed somewhat from that
of the army. In the time of Pericles foreigners had
been often employed to man the fleet, but the com-
mander of a vessel and the soldiers on board were
citizens. Isocrates says that in his day this practice
was inverted. The needy citizens were forced to row,
while foreigners served as hoplites. Thus when a
descent was made on an enemy's coast, the alien
went ashore under arms, the citizen with a cushion.^
No attempt was made to regulate the abuse by
forming a permanent war fund. The question was a
delicate one, whose discussion was avoided. The
surplus revenue was passed to the Theoricon ; and
even before the law of Eubulus (p. 16) had been
carried, it would have been bold to venture on
questioning the arrangement. The inconsistency of
carrying on wars with an impoverished treasury, and
at the same time of distributing the yearly bonus, was
not honestly faced. The mercenaries had to remu-
nerate themselves as best they could.
When the citizen ceased to be a soldier, the s/
statesman ceased to be a general. Pallas, guardian
of Athens, had the double title of goddess of war and
^ Isocr. de Pace, § 48.
20 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. i.
of civil life ; ^ and the old Homeric ideal of the man
who is great in speech and great in action lingered
on to the days of Miltiades and Themistocles. Even
Pericles united in himself the twofold character, but
in him the statesman predominates over the general.
With Cleon the new era was ushered in, and by the
time of Demosthenes the separation of functions is
pretty fully recognised.- Phocion is noted by Plu-
tarch as the last who resolved to resort to the elder
tradition.^ This divorce between political and
military leadership was the natural outcome of
specialised training. The arts of eloquence and of
war had been highly cultivated, and a division of
labour became not only necessary but desirable.
But the change had also a darker side. The pro-
fessional general was required to lead the professional
soldier. This new type of soldier differed little from
a freebooter ; his leader was almost forced to become
a banditti chief Athenian generals found themselves
obliged to conform to the temper of foreign mercen-
aries, to pay whom was the primary recjuisite.
Regular pay was not supplied from home, and an
idea was now current that war should be self-support-
ing. To the upright Timotheus this ma.xim meant
that the plunder taken from the enemy should serve
as a bounty for the soldiers. A Chares or a Chari-
demus so interpreted it as to raise indiscriminate
levies upon enemies and allies alike. These exactions
from the allies, as \vc learn from Demosthenes, went
by the euphemism of " benevolences " {evioiai) * — a
phrase which has curious parallels both in English
and German history — and were the chief cause which
brought on the fatal revolt of the allies. Vet pay
must come from somewhere. " Can it come from
' iroXf/tiKrj Kal 7ro\tr«\-fj. Plutarch, Phocion, ch. vii.
- See the complaint of Isocr. de Face, § 54.
' Phocion, ch. vii. * Chcrs. %% 24- 2S.
CHAP. I.] THE AGE OF DEMOSTHENES. 21
the skies ? " says Demosthenes. " No ! the general
must go on with what he scrapes together, begs and
borrows."^ A commander in such a position had
obviously to humour his men to the utmost, to stimu-
late the greed of gain and the love of pleasure, to
give them the opportunity of squandering what they
had, that they might be incited to win more. The
nature of the case forbade him to pursue any large or
even definite plan of operations ; he must live on from
hand to mouth, adopting such means as he could to
prevent his troops from being tempted away by higher
offers. A method of deferred pay was devised by
Iphicrates to ensure this end. It is needless to say
how greatly the treacherous courage, which could thus
be bought, differed from the sustained and disciphned
fortitude of a citizen army.
The abuses in the navy were precisely similar in
kind. Two speeches, which are of the age if not from
the pen of Demosthenes, give us a valuable insight
into this department — the speeches Agahist Polycles
(l.), and On the Trierarchic Crown ^ (li.) The
Trierarchy was an extraordinary public service de-
volving on the wealthiest citizens. At the period to
which both these speeches apparently belong (before
357 B.C.), the office was divided between two trier-
archs (o-wt pi-qpapyoi)^ whose legal duty was to main-
tain and keep in repair a vessel which was provided
and equipped by the state. The office lasted for a
year, at the end of which time the trierarch in com-
mand was bound to hand over the ship in good con-
^ Chers. § 26.
^ Blass argues forcibly for The Tiierarchic Crown being the
work of Demosthenes. If so, it is his earliest speech on a ques-
tion that touched politics (its date being between 361 B.C. and
357 B.C.), and has therefore a peculiar interest. Kirchoff's pam-
phlet on this speech (Berlin, 1865) is an excellent enquiry into
certain points connected with the Trierarchy.
22 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. i.
dition to a successor. The vessel was generally
insufficiently manned at the outset ; and if extra
oarsmen (lavrai) were needed, or skilled hands
(uTTT/pcTai, iTijpea-ia) employed on board, they had to
be paid out of the trierarch's pocket. In the speech
Against Polycles (359 B.c. or 358 B.C.), we read that
Apollodorus, who exceeded the legal requirements in
undertaking the office without a colleague, and in
equipping a ship at his own expense, had his .'term of
service extended by five months, owing to a defaulting
successor, and ultimately received pay for only eight
months out of the seventeen. Even the daily rations
provided were insufficient Many of his crew, who
were picked men, deserted, seduced by high pay and
large bounties. They saw that " my resources were
exhausted, that the state was negligent, the allies im-
poverished, the generals untrustworthy " (§§ 14, 15).
The speech On the Trierarchic Crown reveals another
weakness in the organisation of the fleet A custom
had grown up by which the trierarch contracted with
a deputy, who undertook the office as a speculation.
The terror of this marauding deputy -trierarch was
such that the Athenians, says the speaker (§ 13), were
the only people who were " unable to travel any-
where without a herald's staff," as a pledge of peace-
ful intentions.
The evils of the militarj' system were great when
the general was an Athenian, and responsible to the
peojjle ; they were aggravated when the general, as
well as the soldiers, was a foreigner, and like them
free from civic scruples. In all cases there was the
same tendency to become independent of the state,
and to form treasonable connexions abroad. Thus,
Iphicrates became son-in-law of the Thracian Cotys,
and served him against Athens, Charidemus allied
himself with Cersobleptcs, and Chares with Artobazus.
Yet such men, some of them mere pirates, became
CHAP. I.] TPIE AGE OF DEMOSTHENES. 23
heroes for the time ; and Demosthenes observes that
victories were now ascribed to the general, and not to
the nation. " No one would think of attributing the
victory of Salamis to Themistocles, instead of to
Athens, or the battle of Marathon to INIiltiades instead
of to the country. But now it is often said Timotheus
took Corcyra, and Iphicrates cut to pieces the Spartan
division, and Chabrias won the battle of Naxos. You
seem, Athenians, to waive your claim to these achieve-
ments by the extravagant distinctions with which you
have rewarded each of these generals. "■'■
While success was lavishly rewarded, defeat was
visited with the like severity. Even Timotheus was
made to suffer for results, the causes of which were in-
herent in a vicious system. The relations thus created
between the military and civil leaders were uniquely
mischievous. The people took their estimate of the
generals from the lipj oi the orai.ors,"' whose favour was
therefore studiously sought. Chares spent on this
object some of the contributions of the allies,^ and
Charidemus seems to have kept paid agents at home
to propose honorary votes in his favour.'^ Alliances
so insecure needed little to convert them into enmities.
The people, quick to suspect guilt when there was
failure, looked to the orators to give effect to their
displeasure. Accusption might be made a profitable
task. The document which is known as Failip's
Letter (340 B.C.), now generally supposed to be
genuine, hits the truth with singular exactness. He
points out how it was the interest of the orators, as
distinct from that of the people, to maintain war, and
proceeds thus : " I am told by persons well acquainted
with your government that to them peace is war, and
^ Dem. Aristocr. §§ 198 ff.
2 Dem. Aristocr. § 147 ; cf. Trierarch. Crown, §§ 16-21.
^ Theopompus ap. At/ten. xii. 43.
■* Dem. Aristocr. §§ 185-6.
/
24 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. i.
war is peace ; for they always get something from the
generals either as their tools or their accusers " (§ 1 9).
Thus the division of labour between the civil and
military authorities was ready to expand into an open
breach.
From what has been said it will be seen that a
financial problem was in the age of Demosthenes
that which perhaps most pressed for a practical
answer. The main source of revenue was dried up,
since the tribute of the allies had ceased to flow in ;
and Athens had to fight for her existence at a moment
when she was most impoverished, and when pro-
fessional armies had made war more than ever costly.
The people still insisted on the budget showing a. sur-
plus to be devoted to their amusements ; and even
had it been otherwise, the existing revenue could
hardly have sufficed to keep up a war establishment
In days before the institution of a national debt, two
methods only of meeting extraordinary expenditure
had occurred to the Athenians. One was a direct
tax (eicr)o/)u) upon the property of all citizens except
the poorest — a tax which was regarded with ever-in-
creasing aversion — the other was the imposition of a
special service upon the wealthy classes, and an appeal
to their patriotism to come to the relief of the state.
The latter expedient was that which the people most
favoured, and on which they mainly depended. Even
in 402 B.C. Lysias had said that the surest revenue of
the state was the property of the wealthy.^ But such a
system created bitter class jealousies, and at the same
time was ineffective. The rich, already harassed in
divers ways by the democracy, found ways of cvadin,
the burden. Various attempts at reform were mad^,
but the balance had been merely altered and r.ot
righted, till the Trierarchic Law of Demosthenes (j -,
B.C.) satisfied conflicting claims. But in truth the
^ Lysias, Or. .\xi. §113.
CHAP. I.] THE AGE OF DEMOSTHENES. 25
demands on patriotism had been overstrained at
Athens ; what in its nature could only be exceptional
was expected to be normal ; the state looked for a
sustained and high-WTOught spirit of self-sacrifice, in
times when the individual was daily drifting away from
the current of civic life.
The attitude of thinking men towards politics had
in it no healing influence. Between philosophy and
Greek life there had always existed a latent antagonism,
though in the Periclean age the signs of the future
schism were as yet few. Long ago the philosophers
had attacked the polytheistic religion — one of the two
principles on which Greek society was based ; by
degrees it pronounced also against the other principle,
that of the City itself. It is recorded of Anaxagoras
that when some one saidiio him, " You don't care for
your country," he answered, "I care greatly for my
country," and pointed to the heaven.^ Similarly Soc-
rates, when asked ironically "What is your country?"
replied, " My country is the world. "^ The story about
Socrates, whether true or false, shows the spirit of the
Socratic school, whose nascent instincts of cosmopo-
litanism were hampered by the narrow limits of the
city. The sight too of politics degraded into faction,
and of a public morality which sanctioned what private
morality condemned, was repugnant to thinkers for
whom individual virtue was of the highest moment.
The proved impotence of all known governments, and
of democracy in particular, to restrain excess and foster
habits of virtue, created in the noblest spirits a pro-
found despair. We catch its tones in the well-known
; assage of Plato, describing the man who, reflecting
u'lon the evil times on which he had fallen, " holds
ii;- peace and does his own business;" "who is like
^ ■ 'log. Laert. ii. 7.
■^ Plutarch de Exsilio, ch. 5 ; Cic. Tusc. v. 37. There is a
play on the double meaning of the word Koafj-ios.
26 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. i.
one who retires under the shelter of a wall in the storm
of dust and sleet which the driving wind hurries along ;
and when he sees the rest of mankind full of wicked-
ness, he is content if only he can live his own life and
be pure from evil or unrighteousness, and depart in
peace and good will with bright hopes. " ^
Philosophy did not, however, openly assail existing
systems, or attempt to head a popular and revolutionary
movement. It stood aside in aristocratic seclusion,
slowly moulding an educated opinion whose centre
was in Athens, but whose branches were throughout
Greece. The newly awakened desires for larger
unions were turning dimly towards monarchy. As
the world was not yet prepared to make the philosopher
a king, the next best thing was to turn the king into
a philosopher. Panegyrics on monarchy were written
by students, and that which was at first a vague aspi-
ration was becoming an idea that might touch practical
politics. Some, like Isocrates, sought for a ruler of
Greek blood who should bind together the Hellenes
in some great military enterprise. Others thought of
more peaceful triumphs. Any hope, indeed, with
which Plato may have looked to Syracuse was rudely
disappointed by the younger Dionysius ; Plato's
followers, however, entered into close alliance with
the Macedonian court, which had for many years
given a welcome to Greek philosophers. The new
intellectual intercourse which now sprang up between
Athens and Macedon was one fresh solvent introduced
into civic life, and must have helped to bring about
that final divorce between thought and action which
indicated the ruin of free Greece.
^ Plato, Kc-f>. B. vi. p. 496 ; Prof. Jowett's translation.
CHAPTER II.
HIS PUBLIC LIFE AND SPEECHES. EARLY PERIOD.
Demosthenes was born probably in the year 484
B.C. Like many eminent Athenians he came of a
mixed marriage. His father was a well-to-do manu-
facturer of the deme Paeania, who had two establish-
ments, one for cutlery, the other for upholstery. On
his mother's side he had foreign blood in his veins.
She was the daughter of Gylon, an Athenian citizen
who had settled in the Crimea, and taken a wife from
that region. Hence the reproach afterwards levelled
against Demosthenes that he was a barbarian and a
Scythian. He was seven years old when his father
died leaving property estimated at fourteen talents
(about ;^34oo), in those days a very respectable
fortune. His guardians were Aphobus and Demophon,
nephews of his father, and Therippides, a friend of the
family. During a minority of ten years the property
might well have doubled in value, but between fraud
and mismanagement on the part of the guardians, little
more than one-tenth of the capital bequeathed was
handed over to Demosthenes when he came of age.
Of his early years we know but little ; he seems to
have passed a joyless and companionless boyhood.
A delicate and sickly child, with a studious bent of
mind, he took no part in the ordinary athletic train-
ing of a Greek ; he lived at home with his mother
28 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. ii.
and a younger sister. With his sensitive nature and
precocious intelligence he must soon have become
aware that things were going amiss. Gradually the
resolve to redress the wrongs of his house took definite
shape in his mind, and henceforth, doubtless, he was
an eager listener in the law courts. Tradition records
the deep impression made on him by the orator
Callistratus pleading for his life ; and the wonder
with which he observed the sovereign influence of
speech. To carry out his purpose he had to acquire
a knowledge of law and some rhetorical skill. The
teacher he applied to was Isaeus, the well-known
speech-writer, and a great icgai authority, especially
in cases of inheritance. Demosthenes was now
eighteen years old. The three or four years he
spent under Isaeus were a time of bracing disciple-
ship, a period whose ripe results were seen in the
comprehensive knowledge of law, and the grasp of
legal principles, hereafter characteristic of Demos-
thenes, and in a faculty of rigorous reasoning at close
quarters in which the pupil surpassed the master.
At the age of twenty he commenced the suit against
his guardians, in an action against Aphobus (363 b.c),
in which he pleaded his own case. The full sum claimed
was awarded him, but payment was as far oft" as ever.
Under the Athenian law of debt it was not easy for a
creditor to enforce his rights. Aphobus, who had
already refused to abide by an arbitrator's decision,
and had othenvise shown himself an adept at artifice,
resolved to defeat the judgment of the court. He
succeeded in delaying the issue by creating out of the
present trial two fresh suits. The more important of
these was that of Demosthenes against Onetor, the
wealthy brother-in-law of Aphobus. A pretended
mortgage had been made to him of a farm belonging
to Aphobus, as a means of preventing Demosthenes
from seizing the farm in execution of the judgment.
CHAP. II.] PUBLIC LIFE AND SPEECHES. 29
The amount finally recovered by Demosthenes is
not known ; it can have been but a remnant of his
patrimony, enough to secure him a competence and
no more.
The speeches Against Aphobus, and Against
Onetor, show the marked influence of Isaeus, not
only in certain borrowed commonplaces and similar
turns of expression, but in their general spirit and
structure. It may well be that Isaeus aided in their
composition, but we cannot infer, with some ancient
critics, that the speeches were written by him. The
features in which they recall Isaeus are for the most
part features common to Isaeus and Demosthenes ;
— lucid reasoning, cogent and elaborate proof, narra-
tive and proof interwoven, more emotional warmth, a
more rapid and nervous phrase, than is commonly
found in the earlier forensic oratory. More distinct-
ively Demosthenic are the recapitulations, the frequent
use of the dilemma, the persuasive earnestness of tone.
The perorations claim special notice. The two
speeches Against Onetor end in a peculiarly Isaean
manner, — in an argument powerfully thrust home.
In the two speeches Against Aphobus the deep indig-
nation of the young man kindles him into a final
appeal more pathetic than Attic usage sanctioned.
These years of painful effort were a fit training for
the struggle of after life. It is true they may have
helped to make Demosthenes an ungenial person, to
turn seriousness into sourness, a reserved into a
morose temper. But without the absorbing passion
that occupied his boyhood, and the obstacles that he
had to encounter single-handed, we should perhaps
never have had the gi-eat qualities that marked the
mature man. In the tenacity of purpose, the self-con-
centrated energy with which he pursued his end, there
was the promise of future greatness.
" You have not yet," says Demosthenes, at the end
30 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. ii.
of his second speech against Aphobus, " proved me,
and you cannot know what service I may do you :
but at least you may hope that I shall not be a worse
man than my father." Already, perhaps, the young
man had some stirrings of ambition ; by the time the
suit against his guardians was over he was certainly
becoming conscious of his powers. But he had many
natural defects to remedy. His articulation was
defective, his manner clumsy, his voice weak and ill-
managed. On his first appearance in the assembly
he sat down amid laughter and uproar. With indo-
mitable patience he strove to subdue his rebellious
organs. Demetrius of Phalerum heard from his own
lips how with pebbles in his mouth he had recited
verses, how he had declaimed while running, or as he
walked up hill, and how he had practised his gestures
in front of a mirror. Other more sensational exercises
are not so well attested. He also had recourse to
the lessons of actors, and formed himself on their
model. The grave dignity of the Periclean oratory
had given way to a more dramatic and impassioned
manner. Demosthenes conformed himself to the
prevailing taste, but fastidious critics always found
something overdone in his delivery. His early diffi-
culties left some permanent trace. He never seems
to have attained perfect certainty and self-control in
extempore speech, and for this, among other reasons,
he seldom rose, even in answer to a clamorous
demand, save after careful premedituiioi^ Vet rare
occasions are recorded on which his improvised
eloquence achieved signal success.
His first regular work was speech-writing for the
law courts — at Athens a frequent stepping-stone to
])ublic life, as was the profession of an advocate at
Rome. Even in later years, and at the height of his
political activity, he never wholly gave up this work.
Most, however, of the speeches he wrote for others
CHAP. II.] PUBLIC LIFE AND SPEECHES. 31
belong to the years 362-354 b.c For seven years
after his own lawsuit it does not appear that he again
spoke in court. He was slowly perfecting himself
in private. His spare hours he spent in practice
with the pen, in the study of law and of Athenian
history, and in mastering the practical politics of the
day, especially questions concerning the v.aw and
finance. After hearing a speech he would come
home and resume its main outlines by himself, and
even recall its periods. Passing events and law cases
afforded him matter for solitary discussion ; in his
own chamber he recounted the facts and argued
doubtful points.
His earliest court speeches were in private (or, as we
should say, in civil) cases. But by degrees his forensic,
labours brought him into contact with public life.
The Athenian law courts stood in a peculiar relation
to the legislature. The responsibility for a measure
rested during a year, not with the body that passed it, but
with the author of the measure. Within that time he
might be indicted for an " unconstitutional proposal "
(ypa(j)i] rrapav6fx(j}v), that is, for proposing a measure
inconsistent with existing laws. The tribunal had in
each case to determine the vague phrase " unconstitu-
tional." IMany questions of party politics were thus
fought out in the law courts. The forensic speeches
of Demosthenes in these public causes must be taken
as an exposition of his general policy. Even when
he is writing for others, himself remaining hidden
behind the scenes, the voice is still that of Demos-
thenes. His strong personality, his sincerity of con-
viction, breaks through dramatic disguises. The
speeches composed for political trials from 355
to 352 B.C. — Agaiftst And/vtion, Agaitist Leptities,
Against Twiocrates, Against Aristocrates — all exhibit
the formed purpose of a statesman. They may be
read as the prelude to his political career. Already
32 DEMOSTHENES. [chaf. ii.
he had set himself the task of his life — to assert for
Athens her proper place in the Greek world, to reform
domestic abuses, to rouse again the civic spirit, which
appeared to him to be slumbering, not dead.
The speech Against Androtion (355 b.c),
written for Uiodorus, is a blow aimed by Demosthenes
against the existing administration. Androtion had
proposed that the outgoing Council should receive, as
usual, a golden crown. Diodorus and Euctemon
jointly attacked the measure as illegal. Euctemon had
spoken first. The main issues are supposed to have
been already dealt with, and the second speaker
assumes the right to a freer handling. Of the legal
arguments against the proposal, the first, which is
technical, is passed over lightly. The second is more
seriously urged, that there was a law prohibiting the
bestowal of the crown in cases where the Council in
its year of office had not added new ships to the navy.
Demosthenes appeals, as his manner is, to history to
show that the state of the navy had a decisive influ-
ence for good or evil on Athenian affairs. As a
further objection to the proposal it is argued that
An(^rotion, being a man of infamous character and a
state debtor, was disc|ualified from speaking in the
assembly. These personal imputations, which would
have been relevant only if backed up by legal decisions,
lead up to an account of Androtion's public adminis-
tration. An indignant force animates this ])art of the
speech, and reveals the true voice of Demosthenes
behind that of the speaker. The special charge,
which is narrow and in part technical, broadens out
into an attack upon a mischievous system. Demos-
thenes, it is clear, has ]nit his heart into the case.
He inveighs against Androtion as one of a corrupt
school, whose financial policy was showy and unsound,
and who imagined that they might override the laws
at their will and pleasure. The argumentative subtle-
CKAP. II.] PUBLIC LIFE AND SPEECHES. 33
ties with which the speech abounds rest upon the
thought that- constitutional forms must be jealously
guarded. The concluding passage (§§ 69-78) resembles
in tone the great political speeches that are to come.
Demosthenes has already formed his own conception,
hereafter to be enlarged but not essentially altered, ot
what the spirit of Athens truly is. That spirit Andro-
tion has misread. He did not see that " this people
has never striven to acquire riches, but always to win
renown. Once the wealthiest of the states of Greece,
it spent all in the cause of honour. Hence it has won
treasure imperishable, alike in the memory of noble
deeds and in the splendour of the monuments which
enshrine them (§ 76). The mingled irony and
indignation with which the speech ends are strikingly
unlike the ordinary calm of the Attic peroration.
The verdict was given in favour of Androtion.
The speech Against Leptines marks the first
occasion on which Demosthenes appeared in court
on a political question. Leptines had carried a law
withdrawing the hereditary immunities which had
been bestowed on public benefactors, and attaching
a penal prohibition to the proposal of similar immu-
nities for the future. The descendants of Harmodius
and Aristogiton were alone exempted. A year had
expired since the law had been passed. The author
of it was therefore no longer personally responsible,
but the law itself might still be arraigned as uncon-
stitutional.^ Those whom Demosthenes supported
in this trial proposed in its stead a law which should
regulate but not abolish such honorary grants. There
were, however, plausible arguments on the other side.
The moment was one of financial embarrassment at
the end of the Social War ; the measure of Leptines,
^ Hence the title of this speech, tt/jos AeTrnVTjr, not /card
AeTrrivov,
34 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. ii.
removing privilege and equalising burdens, vas in
apparent harmony with democratic principles ; and
cases existed where the disproportion between reward
and merit was conspicuous. The measure too was
popular, for it secured the people in their amuse-
fnents, the exemptions in question being exemptions
only from the " ordinar)' liturgies," that is from those
state burdens which were connected with the festivals.
The speech of Demosthenes subjects the measure to
a detailed but comprehensive treatment. Various
threads of argument are interwoven. He contends
that the law is dishonourable, impolitic, unjust, and
unconstitutional. But there are no symmetrical divi-
sions corresi)onding to these several lines of thought
He sometimes combines the points of view, some-
times passes by easy transitions from one to the
other. The presiding thought is that the law is a
violation of public faith. It is inconsistent with
the spirit of Athens. Athens had always valued
a good name above riches. Commercial morality
was protected by strict legislation : was the national
credit to be more lightly esteemed ? So nice and
jealous had been the honour of the Athenians
that they had paid debts contracted in their name
even by usurpers such as the Thirty Tyrants. The
saving effected by this law was after all slight ; but
were it far greater, it would be too dearly pur-
chased. Such a jiarsimony was not economy. If
the state was impoverished, all the more ought they
to guard their credit, the one treasure that was their
own. " You must beware," says Demosthenes, " not
to be found guilty as a nation of acts from which
you would shrink as individuals" (§ 136). They
might be tempted in the name of religion to re-
pudiate their promises. The festivals, it might be
said, are religious sen-ices, obligatory upon all. But
the pretext of religion could not justify a dishonesty
CHAP. II.] PUBLIC LIFE AND SPEECHES. 35
which human morality condemned. Besides, nothing
was so abhorrent to Athens as meanness or pettiness
of soul. Let her retain her large generosity, and
still hold forth high inducements to patriotism : who
could say when she might again need a liberator, and
wish to recompense him.'* At the end of the speech
Demosthenes employs an illustration which tradition
had ascribed to Solon, and which the orator himself
works out more fully elsewhere {Timocr. §212): "Those
who debase the coinage you punish with death :
strange indeed will it be if you give ear to those who
debase the whole commonwealth and render it un-
trustworthy" (§ 167). Such are briefly the great
principles which Demosthenes conceived to be at
stake. " My main point," he says, " is not the
question of the immunity. I maintain that the law
introduces a vicious practice, the result of which will
be to create a distrust of all the grants conferred by
the people" (§ 124). The speech must be read in
order to appreciate the variety of argument which he
brings to bear upon this central idea. The style is
that of calm reasoning. It never quite rises into the
language of passion, but a moral elevation of view
does the persuasive work of passion. This and a
certain subtle delicacy of expression are the two
features of the speech which most impressed the
ancients.
On turning to this speech after The Androtion we
recognise here a new feature — a quiet self-mastery and
studied moderation. There is no invective ; at most
there are touches of courteous irony. In general it
may be observed of the early speeches of Demos-
thenes, that those which he delivered himself, whether
forensic or deliberative, differ from the forensic speeches
which he composed for others. The former are on
the whole guarded and temperate, the latter are
more abrupt, impassioned, and personal. It may
36 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. ir.
be that he grew warm and even violent as he put his
thoughts on paper ; that as a speech-writer for others
he yielded to this tendency; but that in his first
public appearances he resolved not recklessly to
prejudice his career by making personal enemies.
In the same year (354 B.c),at the age of thirty, he
came forward and spoke in the Assembly. Tradition
tells us of previous attempts which were failures, but
the speech On the Symmories or Navy Boards
is the first political harangue of which we have a
record. The speech had a double motive. The
question under immediate discussion was war with
Persia. Demosthenes connects it with a measure for
the reform of the Navy, whence the speech derives
its title. Rumours were afloat of an intended inva-
sion of Greece by Artaxerxes Ochus, King of Persia,
and a burst of warlike patriotism was awakened.
The Athenians had recently aided a revolted Satrap,
and were quick to detect a coming vengeance. The
Persian preparations were in truth directed against
rebellious subjects ; but at Athens there were some
who told of the vast armament already on its way, of
the 1200 camels laden with gold which the king was
bringing ; how he would raise a large army of Greek
mercenaries, and how the faithless Thebans would
again join him as of old. Demosthenes had to cool
the misdirected ardour of his countrymen, and he
seized the moment to lay down some broad lines of
foreign policy. He saw, as is evident from various
indications in the speech, that Persia was no longer
a serious menace to Greece. But while restoring
public confidence, he does not seek to remove all
apprehension tor the future. Fear was preferable to
apathy, and was capable of being turned into a
healthy stimulant. The Greeks, he pointed out,
might combine for a defensive war ; they could not,
and ought not, for a war of aggression. Their fear
CHAP. II.] PUBLIC LIFE AiS'D SPEECHES. 37
of Persia was for the time neutralised by mutual
hatred. " Your ambassadors will simply go on a
rhapsodising mission from town to town " (§ i 2). To
force the states into a premature union would be to
drive the weaker among them into the arms of Persia.
Athens was the guardian of Panhellenic interests,
and had exceptional obligations. " Many of the other
Greek states may prosecute private interests of their
own to the neglect of Greece at large : for you it
would be dishonourable even to take vengeance for
your wrongs in such a way as to bring the wrong-
doers under the barbarian yoke " (§ 6). Danger was
not now imminent. Their immediate need was to
husband their resources, and take precautionary
measures against the evil day. This leads him to his
practical proposal, which he introduces with a charac-
teristic preface. " The head and front of your
preparation consists in a frame of mind such that
each man among you shall be willing and eager to do
his duty. Whenever you have been united in your
aims, and each individual has regarded the task of
execution as devolving upon himself, nothing has ever
slipped from your grasp. On the other hand, when-
ever you have formed a determination, and then
looked at one another, each expecting his neigh-
bour to act while he was to remain idle, everything
has failed you" (§§ 14, 15). The key-note of the
Philippics is here struck. He proceeds to explain his
scheme of navy reform. The scheme has, as he
himself says, been laboriously thought out, and it is
precise in every detail. It is based on the existing
organisation of the Sy?iwwries, and aims at ensuring
the better despatch of armaments by bringing the
departments of the navy into a closer and better
defined relation to one another. For this purpose
the larger boards are broken into smaller groups ; to
each group is assigned a corresponding division of
38 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. ii.
the fleet, and its proper share of the funds. Definite
duties are substituted for vague and diff'used respon-
sibility. He did not now ask them to raise money ;
the money would be forthcoming when the danger
was more real (§§ 16-23). The orator then returns
to the main topic, and reinforces his previous argu-
ments. We may refer in passing to his sentiment
about Thebes, which is far removed from narrow
prejudice : " I know it is difficult to say anything to
you about that people. You hate them so that you
would not like to hear anything to their credit, even
if it were true." He then declares his belief that
" so far from them ever being likely to join the
Persian king in an invasion of Greece, they would
give vast sums, if they could, to atone for their past
offences against her" (§ 33). The substance of his
advice is resumed thus : " Do not then expose the
maladies of the Greek world by convoking its members
when they will not listen to you, and going to war
when you will be unable to carry it on. Rather keep
quiet, maintain your courage, and make preparations "
(§ 38).
No previous speaker had urged this course of
action, and throughout the debate Demosthenes was
almost unsupported. The invasion of Persia by a
united Greece had long been a popular theme for rhe-
toricians and declaimers. It had a special charm for
a people who lived, as the Athenians did, almost
wholly on the memories of the past. Isocrates had,
two years before, urged the plan with an almost
pathetic earnestness as the only cure for their mani-
fold ills. And now it seemed to meet the crisis and
to fall in with the temper of the people. Demos-
thenes, with that sense of the possible which is
one of the first requisites of statesmanship, marked
firmly the limits within which such an idea was appli-
cable. And the people, in answer to this convincing
CHAP. II.] PUBLIC LIFE AND SPEECHES. 39
wisdom, gave up a futile enterprise. The positive
side of the orator's counsel did not meet with equal
favour. No alteration was made in the navy till
sixteen years later, when he himself carried a more
simple and thorough reform.
This speech is a remarkable instance of Demos-
thenes' earlier manner. A long study of Thucydides,
whose influence can hardly be traced in the court
speeches of the same period, has here left its manifest
mark. The style may perhaps in part be explained
by the scrupulous premeditation of a young man
before facing the Assembly. Be that as it may, there
is a stiff dignity in the language and an extreme com-
pression of thought differing from his later style.
One fact remains to be noted. Nowhere in this
speech is Philip named. An allusion to him has
been generally supposed in the repeated mention of
existing and acknowledged foes (§§ 11 and 41), as
opposed to contingent enemies such as Persia. JMr.
Mahaffy (Greek Lit., ii. 315) has, I think, shown
from the context itself good reason for doubting this
reference. This much, however, is beyond dispute,
that the gravity of the danger from Macedon was not
as yet apprehended by Demosthenes any more than
by other politicians.
In the course of the next year (353 B.C.) Pelopon-
nesian affairs engaged attention. Epaminondas had
left behind him two creations in the Peloponnese — an
independent Messene, and a new city, Megalopolis,
into which were incorporated the scattered villages of
the Arcadian league. These young communities had
grown up under the shelter of Thebes, but Sparta
bitterly resented her lost dominion, and ever since
the battle of Mantinea had watched her moment for
recovering it. Thebes was now hard pressed in the
Phocian war, and Sparta's opportunity seemed to
have come. But her designs must be decently
40 DEMOSTHENES. [ciiAi-. n.
veiled. She proposed a general restoration of ancient
rights, by which all possessions held by the several
Greek states before the disturbing period of Theban
supremacy should be resumed. Athens among other
states would profit by it. She was allured by the
promise of the border town of Oropus, an old and
coveted possession now in the hands of Thebes. The
gain to Sparta herself was kept in the background,
but it was not far to seek. Messenia was again to
be Sparta's, and Megalopolis was to be dissolved under
the pretext of communal independence. Athens had
already, in 355 B.C., undertaken to help Messene in
the event of a Spartan invasion. Megalopolis, now
threatened by Spartan arms, and unable to look to
her natural protector Thebes, sent an embassy to
Athens. A counter - embassy arrived at the same
time from Sparta,
Each cause found heated advocates, and Demos-
thenes, at the beginning of the speech For the
Megalopolitans, says that one might fancy the
speakers in the debate to be Arcadian and Lacedaemo-
nian delegates, not Athenian advisers. The anti-Theban
feeling was at this time dominant at Athens, and to
plead for Theban allies was to uphold a losing cause.
Demosthenes adopted a line of professed neutrality,
but in effect he supported the application of Megalo-
polis. His primary thought is that the balance of
power must be maintained (an idea which recurs in
the speecli A^s^ainsl Aristocratcs, § 102). Athens could
not .afford to allow cither Thebes or Sparta to become
menacing to herself His opponents had laid stress
on the inconsistency of which Athens would be guilty,
if, after deliberately siding with Sparta at Mantinea
against Thebes and her Arcadian allies, she were now
to dissolve this friendship. To this objection Demos-
thenes opposes first the threatening ambition of Sparta,
who has violated the compact (§§ 6-10), and then the
CHAP. II.] rUBLIC LIFE AND SPEECHES. 41
constant tradition of Athens to protect the oppressed
(§§ 14, 1 5). " Circumstances will be found to shift with
changing ambitions, but the policy of Athens is the
same" (§ 15). He discerns in the specious proposals
of Sparta a revival of old methods. It was " too late
in the day for her to become generous." That " each
state should possess its own " was a phrase with a well-
known historical meaning. Rather than help Sparta
to regain her former ascendency, Athens should, if
necessary, renounce the hope of Oropus. It would
be a grave mistake to reject now, as was once done
before, the suit of the Arcadians, and again to drive
them to seek other aid.
War between Sparta and Megalopolis followed.
The Athenians, whatever vote they may have
passed (of that we have no record), stood aloof
from the contest. Some years later, when the
Arcadians were again in distress, they looked not
to Athens but to Philip. In him they found a willing
protector, and they became among the trustiest of his
allies.
The speech For the Liberty of the Rhodians
is another utterance upon foreign policy, and may be
taken in this connection. It is akin to the speech
On the Synunories as touching the attitude of Athens
to Persia \ to that For the ATegalopolitaju, as being
the answer to another appeal against oppression. At
the end of the Social War (355 B.C.) Rhodes was
subjected to Mausolus, prince of Caria, a vassal of
Persia, and an oligarchy dependent on him was
established. On the death of Mausolus, ^#lo was
succeeded by his widow Artemisia, the democratic
exiles besought Athens to aid them in freeing their
country from the Carian yoke. There was a strong
popular feeling against Rhodes, which had led the
revolt of the allies against Athens (357 B.C.), and her
humiliation was hailed as a well-earned chastisement.
42 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. ii.
Demosthenes had to take account of this feeling, and
to treat it with deHcacy and management. He
pointedly disclaims being the official patron of the
Rhodians (ovre yap 7rpo^€i'(u riov dvSpwv, § 1 5). In order
to put himself en rapport with his hearers, he even
assumes a tone of rejoicing over Rhodian misfortunes.
Yet in Athenian interest, and that only, he bids them
forget old grudges (p) [xinja-LKaKeli', §§ 15, 16). Then
he unfolds to them the larger aspects of the question.
The cause was that of democracy against oligarchy,
of freedom against oppression. A contest with oli-
garchy was a contest with an armed doctrine, one
in which no quarter was given (§§ 17-21). Having
carried his hearers with him through the political
argument, he is able to go one step farther, and to
venture now upon a touch of human sympathy.
" Though it may be said that the Rhodians are justly
punished, the occasion is not one for exultation. The
prosperous should always show an unselfish concern for
the distressed, seeing that the future is dark to all
men" (§ 21). But definite objections had also to be
met. It was said that interference with Rhodes would
probably entangle Athens in war with Artemisia, and
perhaps with Persia. Demosthenes deals twice with
this point (§§ 11-13 and §§ 22-24). He gives reason
for thinking that Artemisia would remain neutral.
As for the Persian king, his hostility, judging by recent
history, was not formidable, but in any case it ought
to be braved. This advice the orator shows (§§ 7-10)
not to be inconsistent with the position taken up in
the speech O/i the Sytnmorics. But a question of
right was also raised. Treaty engagements were urged
which bound Athens to non-intervention. Demos-
thenes denies that there would be here any infraction
of right ; but maintains that, even wore it otherwise,
Athens coultl not alone support treaty rights which all
other powers had agreed to violate. " When every other
CHAP. II.] PUBLIC LIFE AND SPEECHES. 43
state is only seeking the means of wrong-doing, for us
alone to allege pleas of justice, in order to avoid serious
effort, I count not justice but cowardice" (§ 28).
Towards the close of the speech a lively attack is made
on an anti-democratic party in the state. It is an
anticipation of later and more scathing onslaughts
upon the leading politicians. The people are them-
selves in part to blame ; they keep in their confidence
proved partisans of the enemy. " You should have
regarded a man's post in poHtics exactly as you do his
post in war. You hold that the man who deserts the
post assigned him by his general, ought to be degraded
and to forfeit his pubUc privileges. Similarly those
who desert the political post inherited from their
ancestors, and who support an oligarchical policy,
ought to be disqualified from acting as your coun-
sellors."
Once again Demosthenes failed. From various
passages in the speech (§ i, § 3°, §§ 34, 35) it appears
that he had good hopes that the resolution would
pass ; he doubted whether it would be executed.
From a later speech {On the Peace, § 25) we learn
incidentally that Rhodes was in 344 B.C. still under
Carian rule.
The speech For the Rhodians has been tradition-
ally assigned, on the authority of Dionysius of Hali-
carnassus, to the same year as the First Pliilippic
(351 B.C.), and to a later period in that year. I
have never understood how the statesman who spoke
the First Philippic could within a few months re-
vert to an earlier point of view. Philip is indeed
mentioned once, but it is only a passing reference.
" Some of you, I see, constantly disparage Philip
as of no account, and dread the Persian king as a
powerful foe, when he chooses to be such. If we are
to despise the one too much to repel him, and are to
fear the other so far as to yield him everything, against
44 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. ii.
whom, Athenians, shall we take the field?" (§ 24).
This is an advance upon some earlier speeches, but
its tone is ver)' different from that of the First Phi-
lippic. Dionysius is not always accurate as a his-
torian, and I am disposed to think, with Mr. Mahaffy,
that the speech ought to be brought forward either
into the same year as the speech For the Megalopo-
litans (353 B.c) or at latest into the year following.^
As an independent argument it may be added' that
the manner in which the orator, appealing to the
recollection of his audience (§ 6), repeats the very
phrases he had used in the speech On the Symmories
seems to imply less of an interval between the
speeches than is commonly supposed At any rate,
the received chronology breaks the orderly develop-
ment of Demosthenes' thought, and offers nothing to
account for the retrograde view taken in the speech
For the Rhodians.
We must here turn back from the Assembly to the
law-courts, and observe again the activity of Demos-
thenes during this period in purifying home affairs.
In 353 B.C. he is once more in conflict with Andro-
tion, who had escaped condemnation in the former
trial. Androtion and certain of his fellows had been
called on to refund public moneys which they had
embezzled ; in default of payment they were liable to
imprisonment as state-debtors. Timocrates brought
forward in their interest a measure essentially altering
the existing law, by extending the time after which
state-debtors became liable to arrest This measure
was to be retrospective. It was pushed through the
* In this case we may accept the date given by Diodorus for
the death of Mausolus (353 B.C.) — .in event which from the
speech itself we infer to have recently happened — as .against
IMiny's d.ate (351 li.c.) The chronology of other e.astern events
alluded to is uncertain, but there is nothing, I believe, in it fatal
to the view put forward above.
CHAP. II.] PUBLIC LIFE AND SPEECHES. 45
Assembly, but within a year after it passed Diodorus
and Euctemon indicted the proposer. Under these
circumstances Demosthenes composed the speech
Against Timocrates for Diodorus. Several pass-
ages of it are verbally repeated from the Androtion ;
the speech is a long one, and raises many curious
points of law. Demosthenes contends that the law
of Timocrates was carried informally, that it was in
substance unconstitutional, and would be mischievous
in its working. The arguments are by no means all of
equal value. Some seem to depend on oversights in
the drafting (§§ 79-81, and perhaps §§ 82, 83), others
are downright captious (§§ 85-87, and still more ob-
viously §§ 88, 89), while others remain that are pow-
erful and subtle. But from § 91 onwards he leaves
mere technicalities and verbal criticisms, and grapples
with the question in its wider issues. He shows
how the public services will suffer if the state has no
prompt method of enforcing its claims (§§ 91-95).
At the best of times it is no easy matter to keep pace
with the sudden calls of war, but under this new
statute "will the enemy, think you, wait the subter-
fuges and artifices of rogues at home ? " The system
of internal finance will also be deranged, for no
adequate provision is made for current expenditure
(§§ 96-101). He exposes the evils of retrospective
legislation, devised to shield political associates. "To
frame statutes about the past is not to legislate but
to protect criminals " (§ 116 ; cf. § 123). Towards the
end of the speech he uses a vivid illustration :
" Suppose that at this very moment you were to hear
a cry raised close to the court, and that you were
told ' The prison is opened, the prisoners are
escaping,' there is not one of you, however old or
indifferent, but would lend what help he could.
Suppose, further, that some one came up and said,
' It is Timocrates who has set them free,' at that
46 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. ii.
instant and without a hearing Timocrates would be
arrested and put to death. Well, Athenians, this
man you have now in your hands : not by stealth
has he done this deed, but in broad day by cheating
and cajoling you he has passed a law, which does
not open the prison-house but demolishes it, and
with the prison, the tribunals" (§§ 20S, 209). The
peroration is a dignified statement of the duty of
Athens above all states to guard her laws and espe-
cially her penal code.
The last forensic speech belonging to this early
period is the speech Against Aristocrates (352 b.c.)
Apart from its intrinsic excellence it has a special and
twofold interest. It is our chief authority on the law
of homicide at Athens ; it also presents a detailed
picture of coidotticri life in tliis century (p. 20).
Aristocrates had carried a resolution in the Council
declaring the person of Charidemus to be inviolable,
and any one who attempted his Ufe to be an outlaw
from the dominions of Athens and her allies. Chari-
demus was a soldier of fortune, a native of Oreus in
Euboea, who at this stage of his chequered career
was established as minister, commander-in-chief, and
brother-in-law to the Thracian prince Cersobleptes.
The Athenians, still grieving for the loss of Amphi-
polis, were impressed by the assurance that Charide-
mus would recover it for them (§ 14), though it was
by his faithlessness that it had once already slipped
from their grasp (§ 149). The proposal was checked
before it reached the Assembly, being impeached as
illegal by Euthycles, for whom Demosthenes composed
this speech.
The structure of the speech is unusually symmetri-
cal for Demosthenes. There is a formal threefold
division, according to which it will be shown, first,
that the proix)sal is illegal ; secondly, that it is against
the public interest ; thirdly, that Charidemus does not
CHAP. II.] PUBLIC LIFE AND SPEECHES. 47
deserve such a distinction (§ 18). The arguments,
however, under the second and third head overlap
and interlace in the Demosthenic manner. The legal
case is stated from §§ 23-99. The Draconian law of
homicide is quoted and lucidly interpreted. The law
itself is a remarkable survival of a primitive period.
It forms the earliest of the strata out of which Athenian
criminal law was composed, and came down from a
time when private vengeance still existed, and expiatory-
rites were blended with punishment. The orator
proves, apparently with overwhelming force, that the
proposal of Aristocrates contravenes all the principles
of this code. Not having the text of the proposal,
we cannot be sure that such was the intention of its
author ; but the quotations reveal, at least, serious
ambiguities of phrase, and of these Demosthenes
avails himself to the uttermost. Under the second
head (§§ 100-143) the main contention is that the
Chersonese is endangered by the proposal. Here, as
had been said at the outset (§ i), lay the vital point
for deliberation. The jealousy of the Thracian princes
was the safeguard of the Chersonese; a strong monarchy
in that quarter might be fatal to Athenian interests,
and the decree of Aristocrates, being virtually in favour
of Cersobleptes, would give him a preponderant power
over his rivals. Cersobleptes was perhaps friendly at
present, but bitter experience had shown the value of
friendships with semi -barbarian potentates. Others,
moreover, with as good a claim as Charidemus, would
apply for a like honour. Was the state to become
the bodj'guard of every such adventurer? The pro-
posed decree tended as little to the honour of Athens
as to her interest. European Greeks were by it made
over to Cersobleptes in the same way as the Asiatic
Greeks were, by the peace of Antalcidas, surrendered
to Persia. Throughout this division of the speech the
argument is enforced by an apposite use of historical
48 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. ii.
examples — an instrument which no one wields with
more effect than Demosthenes. The third topic is
the past life of Charidemus — how he had been in
Athenian, Olynthiac, Asiatic, and Thracian service,
and had played false to pretty nearly each employer
in turn.
In the epilogue Demosthenes broadly reviews
different principles of reward and punishment. He
contrasts the wise economy observed by the ■ elder
democracy in the distribution of honours with the
lavishness of later days. Nor were previous deserts
then allowed to atone for subsequent disloyalty,
whereas the chastisement of offenders was " an idea
now extinct in Athens " (§ 204). Amongst the visible
signs of this decline was the private magnificence that
stood beside public indigence. " Now our adminis-
trators have risen from beggary to wealth, and are
abundantly provided for years to come, while you
have not in the treasury sustenance even for one day's
march ; but the moment for action comes, and the
means are wanting. For in old days the people was
the master of its statesmen ; now it is their servant.
The fault is theirs who draw up resolutions like these,
and accustom you to despise yourselves, and to look
up to one or two individuals. I'hen they enter into
the heritage of your glory and your wealth. As for
you, you have no enjoyment of them ; you witness the
blessings of others, while your only part is that of
dupes. Oh ! how greatly would they groan, those
men of old, who died for freedom and for glory, who
left behind them memorials of many a noble deed,
could they but know that Athens has attained to the
style and rank of a dependant, and is taking counsel
whether she is to guard the person of Charidemus 1
Charidemus! woe the day!" (§§ 209, 210). The
spirit of Athenian elo(]uence forbatle the orator to end
here. 'I'he reason of the jury must be won, tiieir
CHAP. II.] PUBLIC LIFE AND SPEECHES. 49
feelings must not seem to be stormed. So the key is
altered. The peroration of the speech is a calm
summary of the legal arguments (§§ 215-219).
It would appear that the proposal of Aristocrates
was confirmed in spite of Demosthenes. In the next
year Charidemus was in the Athenian service, and
was sent on a mission to aid Cersobleptes. Amadocus,
a rival prince, had meantime sought the protection of
Philip, who, entering Thrace, soon imposed his will
on him and Cersobleptes alike. Henceforth it was
against Macedon that Athens had to defend the
Chersonese.
CHAPTER III.
HIS PUBLIC LIFE AND SPEECHES. FROM THE RISE
OF MACEDON TO THE FALL OF OLYNTHUS (34S B.C.)
The power of Macedon had now been growing for
seven years, but had excited little observation. The
first mention of Philip in Demosthenes is in the
s^Q&c\i Against Lepdnes (354 B.C.); it is little more
than a sigh over lost possessions, Pydna and Potidasa.
In the speech On the Sy?nmorii's (354 B.C.) the allu-
sion to Philip is, at best, very doubtful (p. 39) ; in
the speech For the Megalopolitans there is none. The
speech On the Rhodians makes cursor}* mention of
Philip. In the speech Against Aristocratcs (353 B.C.)
he emerges more distinctly as the enemy of Athens
(§§ III, 112, § 1 16, § 121), but it is difficult not to
read something of contempt in the words Im. Suprov
^'tAiTTTTov ToiTovt Tov MuKeSova (§ III), "I need not
ask whether you know of that Macedonian Philip."
He is then cited as an instance of restless but short-
sighted ambition, and that only by way of comment
on the Thracian prince Cersobleptes. Nor does a
later passage (§§ 11 8-1 21), in which he is made to
point a warning against faithless friendships, betray
any serious alarm.
The blindness of the Greek world to the rise of
the Macedonian power may be puzzling to us who
know the setiuel. But we must take into account
CHAP. III.] PUBLIC LIFE AND SPEECHES. 51
first the contempt of the Greek for the barbarian,
which tended to obscure events. Macedon was out-
side the Hellenic pale. Thessaly might at a stretch
be included within it, but Mount Olympus was the
farthest limit. The Macedonian language was indeed
allied to the Greek, but a mixture of foreign elements
had almost effaced its Hellenic kinship. Far more
important than differences of language was the differ-
ent mode of life. The basis of Macedonian life was
not the city (ttoAcs), but the tribe (e^vos). The
people, instead of being self-governed, were under the
rule of a king ; and though their monarchy was prob-
ably a relic of the heroic age, and differed widely
from Asiatic despotism, yet civilised Greece con-
sidered it essentially barbarous. It was useless to
point to the true blood which ran in the veins of the
kings, who were descended from Heracles and the
Temenids of Argos, and one of whom, Alexander I.,
so long ago as the time of the Persian invasion, had
run in the foot-race at Olympia, and as victor had
been celebrated by Pindar.
The first civilising efforts were made by Archelaus
I. (413-399 B.C.), the Peter the Great of this Russia of
the ancient world. He organised the army, fortified
towns, and opened up the country with roads ; but
the elements of civil life, and the industries of peace,
remained foreign to the people. Still less could the
higher culture of Greece make its way among them.
Archelaus gathered to his court Greek artists like
Zeuxis, dramatists like Euripides and Agathon, musi-
cians like Timotheus; he even sought to attract
thither Socrates. But whatever the court circle may
have acquired of refined tastes, the heart of the
people was untouched. Upon Archelaus' death
there followed anarchy and civil war for forty years.
Macedon was still an outlying district of barbarism.
Moreover, Macedon had not hitherto been strong
52 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. hi.
enough to take an independent course of action.
Surrounded by enemies, it had waited upon the turns
of Greek pohtics, attaching itself now to Athens, now
to Sparta, as passing needs required. A tradition of
astute diplomacy had been created, but no great
statesman had yet appeared. Macedon had come to
be regarded as a makeweight which might turn the
doubtful scale of Greek ambitions, but not as an
independent force. It was by the aid of Sparta that
Amyntas, Philip's father, had been able to keep his
crown. ^Macedonian towns had till quite recently
been tributary to Athens. Philip himself and his
brother had been brought (369 b.c) by the dethroned
Eurydice as suppliants to the knees of the Athenian
general Iphicrates.
In 368 B.c, Philip, at the age of fifteen, was taken
by Pelopidas as a hostage to Thebes. There, during
three years of e.xile, he acquired all that Greek
culture could give. He observed closely the shifting
scenes of Greek politics, and the forces moving
behind them ; and above all, he learned military
tactics from the great Epaminondas. In 360 b.c he
became regent for his nephew, and presently took the
sovereignty for himself (359 b.c) Within less than
two years from his regency he had overcome enor-
mous difficulties. He had cheered the spirit of a
people broken by defeat, he had curbed a proud
nobility, he had set aside rival claimants to the
throne, and had thrust back his enemies from two
frontiers. He now set himself to reconstitute the army,
drawing closer the ties of military fellowship, and
turning to account the lessons of Ej^aminondas in the
organisation of the Macedonian phalanx, which re-
mained unconquered till it met the Roman legion.
But if Macedon was ever to become more than a
petty state, it was necessar)' for her, as it was for
Russia in later history, to push her borders to the
CHAP. III.] PUBLIC LIFE AND SPEECHES. 53
sea. At present Greek colonies barred the way.
Three powers commanded the northern waters of the
^gean, — Athens, Amphipolis, and the revived Olyn-
thus. A coahtion between any two of these might
have been fatal to Philip's projects. From the first
he pursued one consistent policy, that of isolating his
enemies, and playing off the jealousies of state against
state. Not until the arts of intrigue and diplomacy
were exhausted, would he resort to force.
Amphipolis first engaged his attention. This town
was strongly situated near the mouth of the Strymon.
It held the main road from east to west, and gave
access to the gold mines and the timber of Thrace.
It was a colony planted by Pericles in 437 B.C., as an
outpost of Athenian influence in that quarter. It had
been taken by Brasidas in the Peloponnesian war
(424 B.C.), and repeated efforts to recover it had
failed. Philip, on his accession, anxious to conciliate
the Athenians, withdrew the garrison placed there
by his predecessor, and renounced his claim. But
Athens neglected to occupy the town. Meanwhile
Philip, relieved from pressing dangers at home, seized
a pretext for attacking it. Envoys were sent to Athens
beseeching aid ; but secret negotiations had been in
progress between Philip and Athens, the purport of
which was that Athens should restore Pydna, which
had been wrested from Macedon, and in return receive
Amphipolis. With the embassy from Amphipolis
came a letter from Philip, and renewed assurances of
good will. He was besieging Amphipolis, he said,
in the Athenian interest, and intended to restore it
to them as rightful owners. The Athenians agreed
to the treacherous bargain, and were duped. Philip
took and kept Amphipolis (357 b.c.)
The Olynthians, now alarmed at the course of
events, made overtures to Athens. Philip's deputies
were also at hand to counterwork the petition. The
54 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. hi.
king, they said, was still minded to restore Amphi-
polis, but the Athenians had not yet fulfilled their
part of the compact, the transfer of Pydna. At this
moment Athens was almost destitute of resources and
of aUies, for the Social War had lately broken out.
The Athenians were the less inclined to alienate
Philip and to renounce the hope of AmphipoHs, and
therefore rejected the Olynthian overtures. Olynthus,
estranged from Athens, welcomed Philip's advances.
He entered into alliance with them, and ceded Anthe-
mus, a disputed possession lying between Olynthus
and Macedon. Then he boldly laid hands on Pydna
(357 R-c), and besieged Potidaea, an Athenian town
which held the isthmus of Pallene. Succour was sent
from Athens, but too late to be of any avail. After a
protracted siege Potid^ea surrendered, and Philip
made it over to Olynthus as a further pledge of their
new friendship. The Athenian garrison he dismissed
home, with a declaration of peaceable intentions
towards Athens.
Thus Philip had robbed Athens of all her seaports
save one on the Thermaic Gulf, and had opened a
wide breach between his two most formidable opponents.
Amphipohs, his greatest prize, he now turned to good
account In the neighbourhood he founded a new
city, Philippi. among the mines of Mount Pangsus,
from which the yield of gold was a thousand talents a
year, sufficient to maintain his wars and pay his agents.
Timber for the construction of a fleet was supplied
from the mountains. The year 356 b.c was signalised
by three events of good omen for Philip, following one
upon another — the defeat of the Illyrians by Parmenio,
an Olympic victory in the chariot race, and the birth
of a son, Alexander.
For the next three years Philip was consolidating
his victories in the north. His apparent inaction
seems to have disarmed suspicion, and even to have
CHAP. III.] PUBLIC LIFE AND SPEECHES. 55
lulled the vigilance of Demosthenes. But in 356 B.C.
the Athenians lost Methone, their last town on the
Macedonian coast, and Philip was brought within
reach of Thessaly, which was to be his stepping-stone
into Greece. Fortune gave him an opportunity such
as he loved, the Sacred War, which broke out in 355
B.C., being his pretext. The Amphictyonic Council,
at the instigation of Thebes, had imposed a fine on
the Phocians for sacrilege. The Phocians seized the
temple of Delphi, and soon applied the treasures of
the god to support their mercenaries. They then
allied themselves with the tyrants of Pherae. PhiHp
was thus able to appear as the champion at once of
freedom and of religion. A great victory in 352 B.C.
made him master of Thessaly. From the port of
Pagasae he dominated Euboea and menaced Athens.
Corsair ships issued hence, harassing the allies, pil-
laging Lemnos and Imbros, and capturing Athenian
merchantmen. A sacred trireme was on one occasion
carried off from the bay of Marathon.
Philip now conceived a more daring project, to
penetrate into Greece itself, and chastise the Phocians
in the heart of their own country. The news of his
march to Thermopylae roused the Athenians for once
to vigorous action. A citizen force was despatched,
and Philip found the gates of Greece closed against
him. For years to come this prompt deliverance was
a theme for orators, and a memory on which the
people complacently reposed.
In the latter half of the same year (352 B.C.), Philip,
seeing that events were not yet ripe for him in Greece,
fell back upon Thrace. He received the submission
of the Thracian princes, and advanced towards the
Thracian Chersonese, which Athens had not long since
recovered (357 b.c.) The news that he was besieging
Heraeon Teichos, a fort on the Propontis, arrived in
Athens in November 352 b.c. There was a panic in
/
$6 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. hi.
the city. At all hazards they must keep their hold
on the Chersonese, and secure their corn supplies from
the Euxine. An armament was voted, to be manned
with Athenian citizens. Reports then came that
Philip was ill — some said he was dead. The expedi-
tion was given up, and the old torpor returned. But
rumour was soon again busy with Philip and his
movements. He was meditating, it was said, the
overthrow of Thebes in combination with Sparta — he
had sent an embassy to Persia — he was fortifying
towns in Illyria {Phil. i. § 48). Splendid resolutions
were carried, but no action was taken. At length,
after a series of idle debates, Demosthenes, in the
second half of 351 b.c, surprised the Assembly by
coming forward before the recognised leaders of the
house, calling on the people to break once and for
all with the old system.
The First Philippic marked the beginning of a
long struggle between opposing principles. Hither-
to Demosthenes had attacked the existing adminis-
tration indirectly in the law courts ; now he placed
himself in open and personal antagonism to it He
felt the delicacy of his position, as we see from some
apologetic tones in the speech (§§ i, 15, 51). He
begins with a reference to the futile guidance of his
opponents as his own excuse for speaking, but per-
sonal bitterness there is none. The events of the
past year had revealed to Demosthenes, with tenible
distinctness, that the danger was great and imminent.
But he alone had eyes to see. The peace policy,
instituted after the Social War, was still cherished by
the people. The chief spokesman of this party was
Eubulus, who in 354 B.C. had become Steward of
the Treasury. An able financier, he had adajited his
whole system to one end, — the renunciation of foreign
politics, the encouragement of home industr)-, and
the comfort and amusement of the citizens. Upright
CHAP. III.] PUBLIC LIFE AND SPEECHES. 57
and patriotic himself, he lent his influence to foster
the selfisjg and pleasure - seeking instincts of the
Athenians. His programme not only made no pro-
vision for war, but almost consciously excluded it.
Among his followers was found _Phocion, who, with
his stronger character and greater attainments, might
have been expected to leave his mark on the age.
Of all men in Athens he was most respected for a
stern virtue. But a philosophic training had left
him clear-sighted and despairing. Half-heartedly he
mixed in pubHc life, and accepted with an undis-
guised contempt the honours thrust on him by his
countrymen. The leader of aristocrats and men of
intellect, he allied himself also with Eubulus and
baser associates, and upheld abuses which he had
not the courage to mend. Isocrates, too, the elegant
but unstatesmanlike pamphleteer, was one of the
peace party. Four years ago he had put forth his
views on home and foreign policy. He probed the
Sjores of Athenian life with a sure touch, but his
proposed remedies were almost childish, and the
nerveless rhetoric in which he expounded these
remedies failed to make a single convert. The First
Philippic draws a picture of Athenian character in ^'
many respects identical with that of Isocrates. The
improvident city is portrayed with its make-shift policy,
..devoid of all intelligence and scope, its bursts of
barren emotion with relapses into indifference, its
blows that are struck too late. The s peech is a
stirring callj^np^ l onger " l-n Ac \)^'^\\(^ hy rpgnlntinns —
and _despatches "^ \ 31), but to act__ vigorously and witli_-
a plan. Its object is to provide for the, future, not to
meet a passing danger. Nowhere else are the short-
comings of the people so unsparingly handled, but
correction is tempered with consolation, and the
eff"ect of the whole is to stimulate, not to benumb.
In style the First Philippic is in Demosthenes' most
SS DEMOSTHENES. [chap. hi.
distinctive manner ; rapid, clear, incisive ; vigorously
reasoned, but instinct with passion ; with one central
>^and recurring thought led up to by converging lines
of argument.
The orator starts with the plain truth that the
Athenians must follow other counsels than those which
had prevailed. All had indeed gone ill with them,
but there was one element of hope for the future,
that they themselves were to blame for the past ; and
that they had not yet put forth their strength. He
reminds them how not so long ago they had risen
successfully against Spartan domination ; he sets
before them the examp le of their enemy, Philip, who
out of weakness had waxed great by vigilance and
energy. " He saw well that all the places he seized
are the open prizes of war, that those who are present
are the natural owners of the goods of the absent,
those who are willing to venture and to toil, of the
possessions of the careless" (§ 5). But there was
no divinity about his greatness. Even now at
the eleventh hour they might retrieve the past if
only they would one and all shake off their apathy.
*' Philip is not a man to rest satisfied with conquests
won, he is ever enlarging his circle, and whilst we wait
and fold our hands, he envelopes us on all sides with
his t5)ils. When then, Athenians, when will you do
your duty ? What are you waiting for ? For necessity ?
Then what are we to think of present events ? To
my mind, the strongest necessity a free man knows is
shame for his cause. Or tell me, do you prefer to
stroll about and ask one another, Is there any news?
^^■hy, what newer thing could there be than a
Macedonian subjugating Athenians, and ordering
the affairs of Cireece? Is Philip dead? No, he is
only ill. Dead or ill, what difference to you? If
anything should befall him you will soon raise up
another Philip for yourselves " (§§ 7-1 1).
CHAP. III.] PUBLIC LIFE AND SPEECHES. 59
Demosthenes then proceeds to explain his own
scheme, which is composed of two parts. First a
' fleet of fifty triremes must he equipped, which shall be
Kept in reserve, always ready to sail at short notice,
and forestall Philip's descents on the coast. Citizens
must serve on board the fleet (§§ 16-18). This part
of the plan stands in somewhat loose connection with
the rest. It is mentioned briefly, and is hardly an
essential point, for it does not enter into the financial
statement which follows. The orator passes rapidly to
the second part, which contains the pith_pf the speech. \/^
(§§ i9"3°)- -A- smfJl standinof nrmy must be kqDt up
" for offensive o p(:iations, c unaiotiag ui part of citizens .
"Talk not of your 10,000 or 20,000 mercenaries,
mere forces on paper" {hria-ToXiiialovi Suva/iets, lit.
" forces that exist in despatches," § 1 9). His pro-
posal, he is aware, was a modest one compared to
more ambitious but unexecuted projects ; it was,
however, as much as their present resources could,
bear, and it was capable of expansion. All he asks
for is 2000 infantry and 200 cavalry, but he insists
that one-fourth of each arm shall be Athenian citizens.
He shows from experience how necessary this was. ■ '^'
The oflftcers too should be Athenians, and chosen not
for show but for service. " Putting aside some one
general whom you send to the field, your generals all
parade in the processions with the masters of the
ceremonies. Like modellers of wax figures, you
^ choose your infantry and cavalry officers for the
market and not for war " (§ 26). (A financial state-
ment follows. A scheme finding ways and means /
was here read out, but not being an integral part oT
the speech, it has not been preserved.)
In the third division of the speech (§§ 31-50) he
reverts again to his central topic — a permanent force
and personal exertions — and approaches it from
another side. The Athenians could not at any
6o DEMOSTHENES. [chap. hi.
moment send succours northward, owing to the north-
erly winds of summer and the storms of winter.
They must therefore station their armament through-
out the year at Lemnos, Imbros, or some adjoining
island, from which they could annoy Philip and
protect the allies. Thus they would no longer lose
place after place by arriving too late. " It is the part
of skilled strategists not to follow upon events, but to
direct them" (§ 39). Athenian warfare is," however,
l ike barbarian bo.xing. " When a barbarian is struck,
he always feels for the blow ; strike him elsewhere,
and there go his hands ; parry the blow and look his
adversary in the face he cannot and will not " (§ 40).
Philip's restlessness seemed to be providentially
ordained as a spur to quicken their slow intent ; it
could not but rouse them unless they had fallen into
a last despair. A war that had been begun to chastise
Philip had become a war of self-defence. It was time
for them once more to fight their own battles (here
again he strikes the dominant note), to do more
than send out empty galleys and idle hopes from the
platform — armaments which excited the laughter of
the enemy and the deadly apprehension of the allies.
They need only go forth, and " the war itself would
discover the weak places of Philip's power" (§ 44).
" Citizens of Athens should be at once soldiers in the
field, witnesses of the conduct of the war, and judges
of the general on his return" (§ 47). They might
then hope for a better stamp of general, not one that
" braved death two or three times over in the law-
courts, but never once dared to face death on the
battlefield " (§ 47). They had had enough of accusa-
tion and ncws-mongering : "Away with such talk!
Sure we arc of this, that Philip is our enemy, that he
robs us of our own, that he has long insulted us,
that all we have tnisted to others to do for us has
turned out to have been done against us, that what
a:
CHAP. III.] PUBLIC LIFE AND SPEECHES. 6i
remains depends upon ourselves, that unless we are ^
now willing to fight him abroad, we may be compelled-^
to fight him here " (§ 50).
The First Philippic is one of a series of Philippics
on which we now enter. The series naturally falls
into two groups. The first includes the speeches
delivered while Philip was still a foreign power seek-
ing admission into Greece — the First Philippic (351
B.C.), and the three Olynthiacs (349 B.C.) The
second group belongs'to the period subsequent to the
peace of Philocrates (346 B.c), and comprises the
speech On the Peace (346 B.C.), the Second Philippic
(344 B.C.), the speech On the Embassy (343 b.c),
On the Chersonese (341 B.C.), and the Thii-d Philippic
(341 B.C.) Philip had by that_ time _securgd _ 3. font-
hold in Gxeece, and been received into the Amphi c -
tyonic Council.
During the earlier period (351 to 346 B.C.) De-
mosthenes stood almost alone in Athens. Ranged
against him were all easy-going citizens, Avith their
leaders, the philosophers and men of letters, the
commercial classes, the short-sighted patriots, and as
the years went on an increasing band of Philip's
hirelings. In the speeches of this period he is_a.t '
once combating Philip, and a more insidious foe, the .'
Athenian people. His voice has many tones — in- '
dignation, scorn, warning, encouragement — but the
theme is always one. He appeals to the ar-oc; i
€Ka(rro9, to the indiv idual man, to the will and to the ■
conscience ; and strives to kindle a spirit capable of
sustained effort. But he sees that he is pursuing a
fugitive object. The people, once assembled, seem
to be alive with generous sentiments ; they love to /
hear of the past and of great deeds which they may [''
jsmulate. Decrees are carried and there is an
Il lusory sense__of.jiuty done. No sooner has the
intoxication passed off than each man seeks how to
62 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. in.
shirk his own part. The emotion which is spent
upon itself weakens the capacity for ggaiiijie action.
Demosthenes attempts to shame his hearers by pointing
yjto FhiH p. He is the embodiment of action, they
^ / §xceT in barren talk. He possesses the verj- qualities
) for which they once were famed. In the mouth of
an adversary we read this description of Athenian
character in Thucydides (i. 70): " They are equally
quick in the conception and execution of every hew
plan. . . . They are bold beyond their strength ; they
run risks which prudence would condemn ; and in
the midst of misfortune they are full of hope. . . .
Their bodies they devote to their country, as though
they belonged to other men ; their true self is their
mind, which is most truly their own when employed
in her service. ... To do their duty is their only
holiday, and they deem the quiet of inaction to be
as disagreeable as the most tiresome business."
Personal service is now the one thing they grudge
to their country.
Of Philip's movements for the next two years we
know little. He was working darkly, though doubt-
less with an aim ; and his apparent inaction may have
been partly meant to qj'^t suspicion. When next he
comes into view he is engaged in a design which must
have been long premeditated. He had already estab-
lished three main points of contact with the sea, — at
/ Amphipplij^ on the Strymonic Gulf (Gulf of Con-
\/ tessa), at Methone on the Thermaic Gulf (Gulf of
Salonica), and at Pa;\asa; (Volo) in Thessaly. But
between the two gulfs mentioned there lay the un-
subdued promontory of Chalcidice, separating his
kingdom from Thrace and the Euxine, and studded
with Greek colonics. We have already seen how
the Olynthian confederacy was broken up by Sparta,
(p. 3). At the accession of Philip the league was
partially restored, though Athens as well as Macedon
CHAP. III.] PUBLIC LIFE AND SPEECHES. 63
had done her best to crush its growth (364 b.c.)
We have also seen how Athens in 357 B.C. rejected
the suit of Olynthus, and the bribes by which PhiUp
bought her friendship. But the Olynthians now saw
themselves hemmed in by the encroachments of
Macedon ; Thrace was being subjugated, Thessaly
had succumbed, and their turn must come next.
In 352 B.C. they made peace with Athens and an
alliance was discussed (Aristoc?: § 109), at which
Philip marked his displeasure by making a demon-
stration against Olynthus. The alliance fell through,
and Philip, contenting himself with this, retired for
a while into Illyria and Epirus. Though capable, as
{q\v men have been, of swift decisive movements, he
also knew how to wait. He had many agents in the
Chalcidic towns working upon the discordant in-
terests of the league, and in Olynthus itself he had
gained influential citizens. It was probably midsum-
mer 349 B.C. when he entered Chalcidice with an
army, and besieged some of the confederate towns.
Up to the last professions of peace were on his lips
( Chcrs. §59; Phil. iii. §11). Olynthus now sent an
embas sy to A^e ns, proposing al liance and beseech-
mg help^_ Events had of la-*^e /^larched rapidly, and
the blindness which had led the people to reject the
prayer of Amphipolis in 357 B.C. was no longer
possible. On this occasion the First Olynthiac
was spoken.
The chronology and sequence of the Olynthiac
orations cannot be determined with certainty. The
discussion is too minute for this place, but it is prob-
able that all three speeches belong to 349 b.c, and
that the traditional order of the speeches is right. It
is strange that in the case of a speaker so free
from vagueness as Demosthenes, the speeches them-
selves should not throw more light upon the order in
which they come. But the main situation is the same
64 DEMOSTHENES. chap. hi.
throughout, and the interval between them is brief.
Philip's attack is directed not yet against Olynthus,
but against the confederate cities. Demosthenes,
moreover, is in a sense tongue-tied ; he is leading up
to a measure on which he dares not bring a regular
motion. By the law of Eubulus, the Festival Fund
/ (p. 1 6) could not be appropriated to war purposes,
yand the proposer of such a measure was liable
to an indictment. It is this that hampers Demos-
thenes all through the Olynthiacs. He is aware that
no substantial good can be done till the financial
system is reformed, and, therefore, while pleading for
Olynthus and proclaiming the urgency of the crisis,
he also impresses on his hearers that a change of
administration is the primary requisite. But the pre-
vailing faction was strong, and the subject had to be
warily approached. In the First Olynthiac he states
the two alternative methods of raising funds, with a
feigned acquiescence in whichever method the people
approves. In the Third Olynthiac he boldly pro-
nounces that the Festival Fund must be applied to
war. This marked advance would alone be almost
decisive in favour of keeping the Third Olynthiac in
its present place. The relation of the other two
speeches to one another is a far more doubtful point
To return to the First Olynthiac. Tlie petition of
Olynthus seems to have met with little opposition.
Before Demosthenes spoke, it had probably been re-
solved to conclude the treaty, and to send help.^ What
Demosthenes demands is ^;onipt action, and the
simultaneous despatch of two citizen forces, one to
^■^ defend Olynthus, the other to harass Macedon.
The crisis itself, he says, is an elo(]ucnt call to
^action. The succour you send to Olynthus must
consist of Athenian troops, and be sent promptly;
^ The tone of the speech points to this conchision ; and the
use of the article r^v po^Otiav (§ 2) is also significant.
CHAP. III.] PUBLIC LIFE AND SPEECHES. , 65
with it must go an embassy to announce its coming,
and to defeat Philip's intrigues in the city. The
King's absolutism, helpful as it is in war, happily
creates a mistrust in free communities. The Olyn-
thians see by the fate of other cities that they have
now to fight, not for glory or for a strip of territory,
but to save themselves from ruin and slavery. A
longed for opportunity has presented itself to you.
Olynthus, by no intervention of yours, has fallen out
with Philip, and may be made a fast friend. Seize
the moment, and beware of repeating former errors.
Think of Amphipolis, Pydna, Potidaea, Methone, •/
Pagasce, all lost through our neglect. "Always letting
slip the present, and Jancying that the future will take_ .
care of itself, we have ourselves raised Philip to a
height of power greater than that of any previous
king of Macedon " (§ 9). By the grace of the gods
we can to-day repair something of the past, and wipe
out the shame. But if now we abandon Olynthus,
the highway is opened for Philip to go whither he will.
Judge what he will do by what he has done. Con - '
trast " th at activity which is part of his habit and very, /
'Semg " with your indolence] '~'lf it is to be his firm
principle ever to outdo the past, and yours to take
nothing heartily in hand, what, think you, can we
hope to be the end? In the gods' name, is there
one among you so simple as not to know that, Jf we
are so careless, the war yonder will soon be here "i ' ^
And in that case, Athenians, I fear jt will be with us^-j /
as with men who borrow lightly at a high interest. __J ^
They have a brief spell of prosperity, and then they
lose their capital itself. So, I fear that we may turn
out to have paid dearly for our indolence, that our
pleasure-seeking ways may force us in the end into
many a hard and unwelcome task, and that even our
home jiossessions maybe at stake" (§§ 14, 15).
The second part of the speech (§§ 16-20) contains
F
66 ^ DEMOSTHENES. [chap. hi.
his positive advice. The assistance sent to Olynthus
must be t\vofold, in order to be effective. One force
/ / must be^ despatched to save the Chalcidic town s,
\/\' another to harass JNlacedon. As for the money, there
was a fund ready to hand (so cautiously does he in-
dicate the Festival Fund), if it were thought well to
use it Failing that, nothing was left but extraordi-
nary taxation — i n one way or other supplies mus t
~=^ b e forthcoming. Demosthenes expressly declines to
frame a motion concerning the Festival Fund ; he
merely expresses his view that the receipt of a salary
from the treasury ought to be conditional on service.
The third division of the speech (§§ 21-27) is in its
main thought similar to the first ; under another aspect
he shows how favourable the moment was for action.
Philip's position, he says, has weaknesses in it not
visible at first sight. He has been disappointed at
the resistance he has met with. His allies, the Thes-
salians, true to their character, are showing signs of
wavering, and the Illyrians would gladly throw off the
yoke. ^In_Philip's necessities behold your opportuni-
ties. Turn them to account, as he would do were
lie in your case. Above all, remember that now you
have to choose between war abroad and war at your
own door. Once Olynthus has fallen, who is to pre-
vent him from marching on Attica ? Thebans ? Whv
— though it is a harsh thing to say — they will aid him.
Or Phocians? They cannot help themselves. And
an invasion, if it comes, will mean rjuin and sham e.
The peroration is a brief appeal to the rich, to the
.young, and to the people's advisers, each to take his
share in a cause in which all have an equal interest.
The speech missed its chief aim. A Hi n ace was
indeed made ; but if any succour was sent it was
merely the mercenary force under Chares, which from
other sources we know to have been despatched in
349 B.C. From certain passages {Olynth. L §§ 16, 17;
CHAP. III.] PUBLIC LIFE AND SrEECIIES. 67
Olynili. ii. § 11) it might seem that the First and
Second Olyiithiac were both deUvered before assistance
was sent. But the tone of the Second Olynthiac im-
plies that it is designed to meet a mood of despond-
ency, due probably to some miscarriage in the war.
In this light we can see the special force of §§ 27-29.
From these paragraphs the inference is natural that
complaints were raised by a clique of politicians against
the general who was out on service. We may con-
jecture that Chares, being short of proper supplies
from home, had been indulging his predatory tastes.
Though the Second Olynthiac would, on this suppo-
sition, follow the First Olynthiac^ there is a close re-
semblance between the point of view taken in each.
The introductions to the two speeches are very similar
{piyntli. i. §§ 5-10; ii. §§ 1-4); and Philip's relations
towards Thessaly are described in almost identical
language. Only it must be observed that the leading
idea of the Second Olynthiac — that Ph ilip's power is
less formida ble than it seems — is merely sketched in
the First {Olynth. i. § 21 ff.) In the Second Olyn-
thiac the thought is developed under various aspects,
always as an incentive to increased energy on the part
of the Athenians. Philip's external weakness is por-
trayed in his relations with his allies (§§ 5-10), his
inn er we akn_e_ss in his relations with his own subjects
and friends (§§ i/).-2i). These are the central divi-
sions round which the rest is grouped. There is a
subtle symmetry in the structure, which only yields
before a close analysis. After the exposition of the
first idea, an objection is answered (§§ 9, 10), and
practical exhortation follows (§§ 11-13). A corre-
sponding method is observed in dealing with the
second idea.
Philip's power, says Demosthenes, is based on per-
jury and wrong; by bribes and promises, he has
cheated in succession Athens, Olynthus, and Thessaly.
68 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. hi.
His artifices are now exhausted, and his allies, whose
eyes are opened, will fall away. Forts and havens do
not in themselves constitute power : on justice alone
can a durable structure be reared Bear aid then, and
that instantly, to the Olynthians ; enter into negotia-
tions with the Thessalians, but be sure that you back
/up your words with actions, for Athens has a name
for facile speech, and her promises are distrusted.
Macedon in itself, and apart from allies, js not for-
"midable. The people have little sympathy with the
ambition of their prince, and with a glor}' of which
they do not reap the fruits; they are weary of incessant
wars, which cut them off from home life, and shut
the ports upon the hard-won products of their industry.
Philip's famous bodyguard is of little worth ; his jeal-
ous dislike of excellence banishes men of ability, and
none are left as his companions but brigands and
buffoons. " At present, no doubt, prosperity casts
these blemishes into the shade : success has a wonder-
ful power of hiding such base elements from view.
But the first check to his arms will bring all to light.
And I think we shall not have long to wait, if it be
the gods' will and your resolve. In the human body
while a man is in good health he is not aware of local
ailments, but on the first touch of illness, all starts
into life, rupture or sprain, or any other unsoundness
in the system. So too with states and sovereigns ;
so long as they carry on war abroad, their defects
escape the general eye ; but once they come to
grapple with a frontier war, everything is revealed "
(§§ 20, 2 0.1
Philip, you say, is favoured by fortune. Yes, but
* The idea of tliis passage is possibly Ixirrowed from Plat.
Rep. viii. p. 566 E. It is remarkable that the same ill'.istralion
is almost verbally repeated in 'JVit- Crown (^ 19S). There, by a
boltier application, /Eschincs is the latent unsoundness which
disturbs the body politic.
CHAP, m.] PUBLIC LIFE AND SPEECHES. 69
Athens is more highly favoured, if only she would do
her duty. " But here we are sitting still, and doing
nothing; and the sluggard cannot command the
services even of his friends, much less those of the
gods. No wonder indeed that he, marching and ■ \
toiling in person, present at every point, never letting
an opportunity slip or a season go by, prevails over ^
us who are p utting off , p assing vote s, and asking v
questions . This does not surprise me. . . . What I "
am surprised at is, that you, Athenians, who ip-ioxmer
days fought the cause of Greece against the Lacedae-
monians, who, rejecting many opportunities of selfish
aggrandisement, spent your own substance in contri-
butions, and bore the brunt of danger in the field, —
and all to protect the common rights, — that you now
s hrink from service, and are slow to con tribnt^p in
defence of your own possessions " (§§ 23, 24).
Hitherto you have been accusing one another, trusting
to others rather than to yourselves, and letting time go
by. Your fortune can never mend until your conduct
is changed. Nothing is now left for us to keep — we
have to recover all. The work is ours, and must be
done immediately ; ourselves and our property must
be put at the disposal of the state. Not until we do
our part, can we call our generals to account. Ill-
supplied by you, they embark on enterprises of their
own ; they are recalled, and brought to trial for mis-
conduct. While you are wrangling and governing by»/
a clique of orators and generals, the public interest
suffers ; one class bears the burdens, the others pass
votes of censure. When will you become your own
masters, and cease to follow the blind bidding of
leaders ? The sum and substance of my advice is j
this, that you should aU_con tribu te y_o_ur shar£jp_JtJ:ie j
war, ail serve in turn, and^^iyeJiLJlli-an_equaLiieariiig
m~youFcounsels7 judging each proposal on its-meEttSy
and apart from personal influence. ""
t/f
70 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. hi.
No reinforcements, it would seem, were despatched
between the time of the Second and Third Olynthiacs.
The three main expeditions which we know to have
been sent during the war, are each connected with an
embassy from Olynthus, and of such repeated embas-
sies there is no hint in the speeches. In the Third,
no less than in the preceding Olynthiacs, the outbreak
of the war is treated as quite recent {Olvrith. iii. § 6 :
cf. i. § 7 ; ii. § i). Demosthenes still speaks as if all
had yet to be done ; for the first expedition of relief
under Chares he probably regarded as too ineffectual
to deserve the name. Olynthus itself, as distinct from
the Chalcidic towns, is not represented as in more
pressing danger than before. Yet the Third Olyn-
thiac is separated from the other two by a marked
difference of character. The buoyant confidence with
which, in the two first speeches, the orator had wel-
comed the opportunity, has given way to a tone of
anxiety :\r\d pnssi nnntp wnrnfii^ Touches of light
irony no longer find place. ^V ith indignant remon-
strance he strives to dispel illusions ; he rebukes and
cliastens an undue exultation, caused doubtless by
trivial successes of mercenaries. In this mood it was
to be feared that the people would forget the lessons
of the past, and content themselves with being spec-
tators of the war instead of actors in it. So Demos-
thenes abandons his attitude of reserve, and speaks
out some hard truths for which the ears of his audi-
ence had been gradually prepared. In attacking the
administration of Eubulus he strikes at the heart of
the mischief F or the first time he openly dor]r;r p«;
t hat the fund nnw npprojirint.'d tn tli. - festivals nuis^
b e devoted to war. A war ta.\, which he had before
put forward as the only alternative, was a progressive
tax upon property, and fell on all the citizens, except
the poorest (p. 24). It was unpojiular and difficult
to raise, and fit only to be a supplementary or occa-
CHAP. III.] PUBLIC LIFE AND SPEECHES. 71
sional expedient Demosthenes demands that the
law by which the surplus revenue was passed to the
Festival Fund shall first be formally repealed. At
Athens a statute could not, as in Roman law, be
implicitly abrogated. A body called the Nomothetse
were appointed every year to revise the laws ; they
were, in fact, a jury invested with the functions of a
legislative committee. Demosthenes asks that such a
commission should deal with the Theoricon ; the
repeal of the existing law would clear the way for a
definite motion. The question of the Theoricon runs
through every division of the speech ; each line of
argument converges upon this point (§§ 10-13, i9>
31, 2,^ ff.) The epilogue (§ t,^ ff) sketches rapidly
the working of a scheme by which the distribution
of the Festival Fund might be regulated without being
abolished, A skeleton of the speech is here added.
The speakers, says Demosthenes, who talk to you
of punishing Philip have taken no reckoning of facts.
The time is past when this language might have been
used ; our first concern now is how to save our allies.
I feel some difficulty, however, in advising you, for
hitherto you have failed from want of will, not of
knowledge. I must ask you, therefore, to bear with
me if I speak to you with some plainness.
You remember three years ago how you resolved
to send an expedition against PhiHp — how reports
came that he was ill, and the expedition was aban-
doned. There is another such crisis to-day; do not
repeat the old mistake. It has long been your wish
that Olynthus should be at war with Philip ; events
have worked out your wish. Let us then aid Olyn-
thus vigorously, and with all our heart. When Olyn-
thus has fallen, Athens will be endangered. From
hostile Thebans or impoverished Phocians there is
nothing to hope. We shall be constrained, instead
of aiding others, to seek aid ourselves.
72 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. hi.
We are resolved, you say, to help Olynthus ; but
how is it to be done? Do not be startled at my
answer. Appoint a legislative commission, not to
frame new laws (you have enough already), but to
repeal such existing laws as are mischievous — those,
I mean, by which the fund s whiclT_ om^jQ-be-ftf>plted
to war are distributed among lestival-seers at hom e,
as well as those which permit evasions of military
duty. U ntil these laws are formally abrogated, you
cannot expect any one to bring ruin on himself by
venturing on a salutary' proposal.
Resolutions by themselves are useless ; had it de-
pended on resolutions, Philip would have been chas-
tised long ago. Let us now act, and in good earnest;
let us not throw the blame of past failure upon others,
when all are equally in fault. The only practical
method of attaining our end is to deal with the Fes-
tival Fund ; show me any other means, and I will
gladly accept it. " But I wonder if it ever has been,
or ever will be, that when a man has spent his all
on what is bad, he should have what he has lost
to spend aright " (§ 1 9). Let us face hard realities,
and not be misled by our wishes. It would be as
mean as it would be foolish to suffer Philip to enslave
Greek states, and all for want of supplies.
I do not wantonly court unpopularity. I would but
imitate the candour of the statesmen of early times,
who did not humour their audience when great inter-
ests were at stake. The subservience of later -day
politicians has exalted them, and at your expense.
Look on the two picture s. — Athens of old^ and Athen s
as sTie is. """
" FoF~lTve and forty years our fathers ruled over
a willing Greece; more than 10,000 talents they
brought into the Acropolis ; the king of Macedon
jjaid them that submission which a barbarian owes
to Greeks ; many glorious trophies they erected in
CHAP. III.] PUBLIC LIFE AND SPEECHES. 73
memory of their own prowess by land and sea ;
alone of all men they have left an inheritance of
renown which envy cannot touch" (§§ 24, 25). Such
were they in their relations to Greece. In their
own city the public edifices were of incomparable
beauty and grandeur, private houses were of a modest
simplicity (see p. 15). Turn now to the present.
At a time when the field was free, and there was none
to contest the prize with us, — for Sparta had fallen,
and Thebes had her hands full, — " when we might
have held our own securely, and been umpires of the
claims of others, we have been robbed of our territory,
we have spent more than 1500 talents to no purpose;
the allies whom we gained in war have been lost to
us in peace through yonder leaders ; we have trained
into greatness our enemy and rival. If not, I would
ask any one to come forward and tell me whence, but
from the heart of Athens, has Philip drawn his strength.
But, I am told, things abroad may be bad, our home
affairs are now better. What are the proofs? The
parapets that we whitewash, the road that we repair,
the fountains, and such like trumpery ? Look now at
the men of whose administration these are the fruits.
They have exchanged beggary for wealth, obscurity
for eminence ; some have erected private houses
more magnificent than the public buildings ; and as
Athens has been abased, so have they been exalted "
(§§ 27-29).
What is the cause of the change ? It is this.
Formerly the people had the courage to fight its own
battles, and was master of its statesmen. " Now
political leaders have the disposal of emoluments ;
all business passes through their hands. You, the
body of the people, emasculated, stripped of treasures
and of allies, are reduced to the rank of menials and
supernumeraries, only too happy if your friends dole
you out festival moneys, and get up special processions,
74 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. hi.
and, to crown your manly conduct, you feel grateful
for being offered what is your own. Meanwhile,
they coop you up within the very walls of the city,
and lead you to your pleasures ; they make you
tame and obedient to the touch. To my mind it is
impossible that lofty and generous sentiments can be
inspired by mean and paltry actions. The sentiments
of men must bear the exact impress of their habits "
(§§31,32).
If you will retu rn to the ancient ways, — if you will
serve and work and give of your abundance, you may
yet achieve some solid good. You may free your-
selves from these pittances which are like the diet
physicians prescribe to their patients. ' As the sick
man's diet neither imparts strength nor allows him
(juietly to die, so these doles of yours are not enough
to be of substantial benefit, nor do they allow you to
pass to something better in despair" (§ 33). In time
of peace let the citizens still enjoy the bounty of the
state ; in time of war let the state exact service from
all, — service in the field from the young, service in
organising and supervising from the old. What is
bounty in the one case will be salary in the other.
It is not enough for us to sit idle, listening to reported
victories of this or that man's mercenaries ; we must
work ourselves in our own cause, and not desert the
post of virtue bequeathed us by our ancestors.
" I have said, I think, all that I deem expedient ;
I pray that you may take whatever course is likely
to conduce to the good both of the country and of
yourselves." V I •
No immediate action, as far as we know, followed
this speech. I'.ut early in 348 B.c new troubles
arose. Through Macedonian intrigue, and against
I )emosthenes' advice, Athens engaged in a costly and
futile enterprise on behalf of Plutarchus in Eubrea ;
and at a moment when her undivided energies were
CHAP. III.] PUBLIC LIFE AND SPEECHES. 75
needed to save Olynthus, she had a double war on
her hands. ^ The prospect was alarming, and Demos-
thenes' policy concerning the Theoricon was for the
moment accepted by the people. On the motion of
ApoUodorus it was resolved that the surplus revenue
should go to war purposes ; but the measure was
presently reversed, and its author prosecuted and
found guilty.
In the spring of 348 B.C., Philip, who had been
temporarily called away to quell a rising in Thessaly,
was opening a second campaign against Chalcidice.
One by one the allied cities fell before him ; some
yielded to his arms, the gates of others opened to
his gold. He advanced within a few miles of Olyn-
thus, curtly telling the inhabitants that either they
must quit Olynthus, or he Macedon. Already a small
body of Athenian cavalry had been sent on from
Euboea to Olynthus. A last and pressing appeal for
aid now came. The Athenians despatched a con-
siderable force of citizens, not of mercenaries ; but
the north wind was contrary, and before the succou r
could arriv e, O lynthus, afte r n gallnpt r\pff?-nrp^ InH
. fallen. Philip determined to leave here a signal
record of his vengeance. Olynthus and her thirty-
two confederate towns were levelled to the ground ;
her 10,000 inhabitants were sold into slavery. A
traveller in those regions, says Demosthenes seven
years later, could not even have traced the site of
cities (/%//. hi. § 26). No act of Philip's life gave
a greater shock to Greek feeling- Whether from policy
or from temperament, Philip was, as a .rule, a mag-
nanimous enemy; even the prejudices of Greeks he
was careful not to wound. It is true that Olynthus
was a revolted ally, and that Greek history afforded
cruel precedents in such cases, yet these precedents
hardly applied to a prince who was still a foreigner
and outside the Hellenic world. The terror, how-
76 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. hi.
ever, inspired by the act mastered all other feelings.
The moment was a decisive one for Greece. Men's
imaginations were overawed, and the perspective of
events was fatally disturbed. Philip followed up his
conquest by the use of arts in which he was skilled.
Amid great rejoicings he held the Olympic festival,
instituted in Macedon upon the Greek model Here
he made himself of easy access to all. Some thought
it their wisdom to come to a timely understanding
with the conqueror, and were soon captivated by his
gracious advances. They brought back with them
to their several homes a taint, which became a spread-
ing corruption throughout Greece. Others watched
events at a distance with a wavering loyalty and
enfeebled courage.
CHAPTER IV.
HIS PUBLIC LIFE AND SPEECHES. FROM THE FALL OF
OLYNTHIIS-TO THE PEACE OF PHILOCRATES (346 B.C.)
The Euboean war of 3 48 b.c. gave rise to an unpleasant
incident in Demosthenes' life. A certain Midias, of
whose insolent and vulgar opulence we have a vivid
picture, had an old feud with Demosthenes, dating
from the time of the suit against Aphobus. An award
had then gone against him. He had already taken
vengeance on the arbitrator by procuring his disen-
franchisement, and had watched his opportunity against
Demosthenes. The Eubcean war, which was strenu-
ously opposed by Demosthenes, was supported by
Eubulus and his adherents, including Midias. Thus
party differences came in to inflame personal dislike.
It so happened that Demosthenes had undertaken to
furnish the chorus for his tribe at the Great Dionysia
in 348 B.C. jMidias, with malignant pertinacity, took
every means to spoil the performance ; he even tried
to tamper beforehand with the judicial award. On
the day of the performance he struck Demosthenes
in the face before the whole theatre. Demosthenes
laid a Probole, or preliminary complaint, before the
people, and a vote was passed declaring Midias to be
guilty of contempt of the festival {ddcKdv Trepl rrjv
eopri^v). The vote by itself carried no legal sanction ;
78 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. iv.
it remained to be confirmed by a tribunal. Demos-
thenes, rejecting all offers of compromise, carried to
its last stage the procedure of the Probole, under
which the extreme penalty of the law, extending to
death or confiscation, might be enforced. The peculiar
features of the outrage were that it was committed
against an official personage, and at a religious solem-
nity ; and these are the points that Demosthenes
presses home.
The speech Against Midias has received both
in ancient and modern times an admiration which it
is difficult fully to share. Lord Brougham goes so
far as to say that it " excels in spirit and vehemence
perhaps all his other efforts." There is, no doubt, in
it a genuine and fiery indignation ; both in its strength
and in its weakness, it is an admirable example of
ancient invective. The pathos, which in Demosthenes
is commonly disguised or subdued, is here prominent.
All the figures of rhetoric can be illustrated from tlie
speech ; the diction itself has often a poetic cast, be-
traying strong emotion. Demosthenes has invested
the subject with such dignity as it admits of Each
of the main divisions of the speech is wrought up
into a kind of peroration, in which the wider aspects
of the outrage are presented. But a " box on the
ear" cannot even by genius be elevated into the
higher order of ideas ; the very solemnity of the
scene at which it occurred makes the effect a tritle
ludicrous. A stinging sense too of personal wrong
is often dominant in the speech, and class jealousies,
which in his public life Demosthenes strove to allay,
are appealed to in a tone which recalls a tribunician
harangue in early Roman history. But lighter touches
are not wanting. The description, for instance, of
Midias himself is amusing. Elected to a cavalry com-
mand on the strength of his riches, so stingy was he
that he paraded on a borrowed horse, which, however,
CHAP. IV.] PUBLIC LIFE AND SPEECHES. 79
he could hardly sit in a procession through the market-
place (§§ 1 71-174). The one public burden he in-
curred was a trierarchy ; or rather it was a desertion
and a speculation disguised as a trierarchy (§§ 166-
7). "Where then are his brilliant doings? Where
are his official services, his splendid outlays ? For
myself I cannot see, unless it be in this — that he has
built a mansion at Eleusis large enough to darken
all the neighbourhood — that he keeps a pair of white
horses from Sicyon, with which he conducts his wife
to the mysteries or anywhere else he fancies — that he
sweeps through the market-place with three or four
lackeys all to himself, and talks about his bowls, and
drinking horns, and saucers, loud enough to be heard
by the passers-by" (§ 158). But there are also pass-
ages of calm and grave eloquence. There is one
such in the peroration : " Just ask yourselves and seek
what it is that makes you who are jurors for the time
being the supreme power in the state, whether the
number empanelled be two hundred, a thousand, or
what not. It is not, you will find, that you, un-
like the rest of the community, are marshalled in arms,
that yours is the best bone and muscle, that you
are in the first bloom of youth. Nothing of the kind.
It is owing to the strength of the laws. And what is
the strength of the laws ? If any one of you is injured
and cries for aid, will they run up and lend help ?
No ; they are dead letters and nothing more. This
they cannot do. Where then lies their power? In
their being enforced by you, in their being made always
valid for all who need them. Thus the laws are strong
through you, and you through the laws. You are
bound, therefore, to defend them as you would your-
selves against wrong, to regard all injuries done to
the laws, whosoever the author prove to be, as injuries
to the community. No public services, no pathetic
appeals, no personal influence, no device of art, must
So DEMOSTHENES. [chap. iv.
avail to shield the transgressor of the laws from paying
the penalty" (§§ 223-225)
Apart from the blemishes inherent in the subject
matter of the speech, there remain marks of incomplete
revision. These are explained by a statement occur-
ring first in Aeschines {Ciesi/'/ton, § 52), which is left
uncontradicted by Demosthenes, and is repeated by
Plutarch and others, that Demosthenes in the end
compromised the suit for half a talent It was not
the half-talent, we may be sure, that tempted him to
forego his revenge. Such was not the temper he
showed in the long suit with his guardians, or in the
earher stages of this very aftair. It has been plausibly
suggested that he dropped the case in obedience to
political motives. At the end of the year in which
this speech was written (347 B.C.), he is found acting
in conjunction with the party of Eubulus, as one of
the embassy sent to negotiate peace with Philip. To
this new connection he may have sacrified some per-
sonal feelings. But this leads us back, to the main
thread of the history.
The fall of Olynthus in 3 48 n.c produced a sudden
change of front in the policy of Eubulus. Embassies
were sent in all quarters to unite the Greeks in a
national war. This is the first occasion on which
Aeschines comes much into notice. He had been in
turn an usher in his father's school, a tragic actor,
and a clerk in the Assembly. His brilliant and versa-
tile gifts opened for him a way into public life, and
here he became a follower of Eubulus. He now
undertook a mission to Arcadia. At a meeting in
Megalopolis he inveighed against the traitors who had
sold their countn,-, and denounced Philip as " a blood-
guilty barbarian " {liapfiapov t( Kal akda-ropa, Dem.
£//i!>. § 305). It was not long since that Megalopolis
had received a cold rebuff from Athens (352 B.C. p. 41),
and the summons to arms naturally met here with
CHAP. IV.] PUBLIC LIFE AND SPEECHES. 8i
no response. But other states paid as little heed.
Intent on their local quarrels they looked to the
mediation of Philip with hope rather than fear.
This failure to bring Greece into union with Athens
left only one course open. Demosthenes and all
other thoughtful men saw that after a war of unbroken
disaster some breathing-space was needed. Even
before the taking of Olynthus, Philip had indirectly
informed the Athenians that he was prepared to treat
with them. The subsequent capture of Athenian
citizens in Olynthus produced a profound impression,
and informal negotiations were set on foot for their
release. About the same time (347 B.C.), Thebes
had appealed to Philip against the Phocians, and
envoys from Phocis reached Athens urgently beseech-
ing aid in holding Thermopyls. The Athenians, as
in 352 B.C., sent prompt succour. Phalsecus, the
Phocian general at the pass, refused, from suspicion or
jealousy, to admit the Athenian troops. To the Athe-
nians this conduct suggested painful doubts whether
Phalsecus might not have a secret understanding with
Philip. If so, it was one more argument in favour of
peace. Philip, on his side, was well disposed to listen
to overtures. It was an essential part of his scheme
to make an unopposed entrj'- into Greece. He meant
to march through Thermopylae as the champion of
the god. All the subsequent negotiations, all the
delusive assurances with which he entertained the
Athenians, were directed to this end, though he him-
self must have been surprised at the docility with
which the Athenian ambassadors lent themselves to
his plan.
The first official overtures came from Athens.
Philocrates proposed, and Eubulus seconded the
proposal, that ten ambassadors should be appointed
to treat for peace with Fhiltp (end or347 B.cf) The
envoys chosen included Philocrates, Demosthenes,
G
82 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. iv.
and Aeschines. The passage of history on which we
now enter is in many respects exceedingly obscure.
We are almost wholly dependent on assertions made
by Demosthenes and Aeschines, and these assertions
often are not merely inconsistent with one another,
but self-contradictory. Our main sources of informa-
tion are the speeches delivered, three years after the
events, by Demosthenes and Aeschines, On the
Embassy^ and those delivered by the same orators,
sixteen years after the events, in the trial On the
Crcnvn. The speech of Demosthenes On the Peace
(346 B.C.), and that of Aeschines A^^ainst Timarchus
(345 B.c), are incidentally valuable. It may be
observed that the further the speeches are removed
from the events, the more reckless are their statements ;
and it is peculiarly unfortunate that we derive almost
all our knowledge from forensic speeches, which by a
recognised Greek practice abound in misrepresenta-
tion. Further, it appears that Aeschines is more
hopelessly at variance with himself than Demosthenes.
But both orators are anxious to disclaim, as much as
possible, their part in a peace, which, with its author,
soon became greatly discredited. Only where their
testimony concurs or does not conflict can we feel
ourselves on any sure ground.
A detailed account of the first embassy is found
only in Aeschines, and has rather the value of anec-
dote than of political historj'. He tells of the surly
and suspicious manners of Demosthenes on the
journey ; of his insolent belief in his own eloquence,
how he boasted that he had " exhaustless sjirings of
argument" ready, and would "stop Philips mouth
with a good sound cart-rope" (Aesch. Einb. § 21).
Then how in the audience-chamber at Pella he
completely lost his presence of mind, and after an
obscure preamble broke down. In pointed contrast
with this failure, Aeschines complacently records his
CHAP. IV.] PUBLIC LIFE AND SPEECHES. 83
own speech, enforced by proofs drawn from mythical
no less than from recent history, and clearly establish-
ing the title of Athens to Amphipolis. As a states-
man, Aeschines is more damaged by this speech, on
which he prided himself, than he would have been by
a failure, such as that which he ascribes (and probably
with truth) to his rival. Philip must have smiled at
the cogency of his argument as addressed to a
victorious belligerent. On the way home — if we
may believe Aeschines — Demosthenes occupied him-
self partly in binding his colleagues to keep silence
about the fiasco at Pella, partly in laying traps for
them by means of puerile challenges to repeat before
the Assembly their praises of Philip. The_ envoys
brought ba ck a letter f r om Philip ( March 346 B.a),
wl-nrh l-hpy present ed tothe rniinri1._ The letter was
distinctive of its author. " He intended to do them
great services, which he would have stated more
explicitly had he been sure of obtaining alliance as
well as peace" (Dem. E^nb. § 40). The actual terms,
however, were merely a recognition of the status quo,
that each side should keep what at the time they
possessed.
The matter was debated at Assemblies held on
the 1 8th and 19th of Elaphebolion (March). Two
main points had to be determined. The first related
to Philip's conquests — was he to keep them all?
Here there could be little doubt ; the very basis of
the peace was the status quo, and, indeed, after a war
of nine years, in which all the losses had been on one
side, no other terms could have been looked for.
The second point was the vital one. Who were to
be included in the peace ? The motion proposed by
Philocrates, who had, doubtless, received his instruc-
tions from Philip, was that peace and alliance should
be concluded between Philip and his allies on the
one part, and Athens and her allies on the other;
84 DEMOSTHENES. [chap, iv
but two allies of Athens were expressly excluded, the
Phocians and the town of Halus in Thessaly. This
proposal seems to have been supported in its entirety
by Aeschines ; Demosthenes supported it, with the
exception of the disastrous clause excluding the
Phocians and Halus. The Assembly resolved to
strike out this clause, thus implicitly including Phocis
and Halus in the list of allies. But, as it turned out,
this availed nothing.-' At the Assembly held si.x days
later, for the purpose of administering the oaths
to the Athenians and their allies, the Macedonian
plenipotentiaries refused to admit the Phocians as
Athenian allies. To have yielded here would have
been to surrender the cardinal point on which Philip's
calculations turned. If peace were made with the
Phocians, the plea for his armed inter\-ention in
Phocis would be gone. On the other hand, the
Athenians were no less deeply interested in maintain-
ing alliance with those who held Thermopyloe, the
key of Northern Greece. It was a hard dilemma
for the Assembly. Philocrates and Aeschines now
became the interpreters of Philip's intentions, and
took on them to reassure the people. The king's
enigmatical letter received from them a definite con-
struction. He was unable, they said, at present to
regard the Phocians as allies owing to his relations
with Thebes. But once the treaty was concluded he
would be the friend of Athens, he would protect the
Phocians, humble Thebes, and restore to Athens
Euboea and Oropus. These audacious promises,
made by envoys who had had direct dealings with
Philip, fell on credulous ears. Worse instincts were
also satisfied, for hatred of Thebes was still among
the governing motives of Athenian policy. The
oaths of ratification were accordingly taken, and
the name of the Phocians was omitted. Though
Demosthenes had opposed the original exclusion
CHAP. IV.] FUBLIC LIFE AND SPEECHES. 85
of the Phocians from the treaty, we do not learn that
he here entered a patriotic protest. On a later
occasion when he exposed these same delusions, he
could not get a hearing ; probably he could not have
got one now. Yet his silence is to be regretted.
The idle hopes now excited continued to be worked
upon till Philip was inside Thermopylce.
It remained t o receive the oaths of ratification from
Phili p a] id ^'^ oiiip<^, A second embassy, compose d
of t he same members as'TEe first , w as appointed fe r
the purpose . The peace was to date from the ratifi-
cation of the treaty. It was to be feared that Philip
would reckon not from the day that the oaths were
administered at Athens, but from the day that they
were administered to himself. All that he could
secure in the interval he would look on as the fair
prize of war. Demosthenes, therefore, did what he
could to hasten the departure of the ambassadors.
They lingered ten days in Athens, and then journeyed
forward leisurely to Macedon. At Pella they
awaited Philip's return from Thrace, in spite of in-
structions to repair to wherever Philip happened to be.
It was now fifty days since they had left Athens, and
meantime Philip had pushed his conquests in Thrace,
and reduced to submission Cerspbleptes, an Athenian
ally. Precious time had been wasted, and the Cherso-
nese had been daily more imperilled. On his arrival
at .Pella, Phili p took the oaths himself, but nothmg
was yet done about his allies. Ambassadors from
the chief states of Greece were now at Philip's court,
each seeking to forestall his favour. Philip was per-
fectly affable to all, but wrapped his designs in pro-
found mystery. While making no definite promises,
he allowed vague and contradictory reports to circu-
late. The hopes of all were kept alive to the last,
and joint action was precluded. In his progress
southwards at the head of an army, he was still ac-
86 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. iv.
companied by a crew of bickering envoys. He
specially invited the Athenian ambassadors to mediate
between Halus and Pharsalus — a new pretext for
bringing him nearer to his goal without raising an
alarm. Demosthenes became more and more uneasy
at tlie position of affairs. He wrote a despatch home,
he says, but his colleagues objected to it, and sent
their own version in its place. He resolved to take
news in person, but here again he was hindered; At
Pheroe in Thessaly the oaths were at last administered
to Philip's allies, and the Phocians at the same time
were expressly excluded from the treaty. The Athe-
nian envoys arrived at Athens on the 13th of Sciro-
])horion (June), after an absence of seventy days.
When they left Philip he was three days' march from
Thermopylae.
Demosthenes, on his return, instantly laid his re-
port before the Council. He exposed the impostures
practised during the past months, and accused
Aeschines and others of traitorous concert with
Philip. He implored them still to save Phocis and
Thermopylae. Moved by his earnestness, the Council
withheld the usual vote of thanks from the ambassa-
dors. But in the Assembly held a few days later,
another spirit prevailed. Aeschines assured the
people that they need only keep quiet, and in a few
days everything would turn out as they wished.
Thebes, not Phocis, was Philip's real enemy, as would
be seen by the event. Eubcea was to be given up to
Athens in compensation for Amphipolis, and there
was more in rcsen'e — a hint at the restoration of
Oropus. It was the old mystification again. A letter
from Philip was also read, in which he apologised for
the delay of the embassy, and took the blame upon
himself. He conveyed general assurances of his good
will, but that was all. Demosthenes rose, and declared
that he knew nothing of the promises held out by
CHAP. IV.] PUBLIC LIFE AND SPEECHES. 87
Aeschines, and did not believe in them ; but he was
hooted down. Philocrates observed that it was no
wonder that he and Demosthenes were not of the
same mind ; Demosthenes was a water-drinker, and
he hked his wine ; and the people laughed. The
vagueness of Philip's letter was made up for by the
lucid commentary of Aeschines, who explained that
the king's diplomacy was necessarily secret, and re-
quired confidential interpreters. On the motion of
Philocrates, it was carried that, unless the Phocians
surrendered the temple to the Amphictyons, Athens
would compel them by force of arms. There were
Phocians present at this act of betrayal. Up to this
moment the Phocians had probably shared the pre-
valent illusions. They, too, had been led to believe
that Philip's menacing attitude tow^ards them was
designed to veil hostile purposes against Thebes. In
any case, they thought Athens could not but stand
by them at the last. The present decree, however,
was unambiguous, and disarmed resistance. On the
23d of Scirophorion, seven days from the passing of
the decree, Phalsecus made his own terms with Philip,
who thus, without striking a blow, became master of
Thermopylse.
The Athenians had despatched a third embassy to
present the decree of Philocrates to Philip. This time
Demosthenes solemnly declined to act Aeschines
also remained at home on the score of illness. But
before the embassy had executed their commission,
they were met by the news of the convention with
Phalsecus. In the first transport of grief and disap-
pointment, the Athenians carried resolutions for the
defence of the city. Philip forthwith summoned the
Amphictyonic Council to pass judgment on the
guilty Phocians. The machinery was somewhat anti-
quated, and the states now represented in the Council
were bitter enemies of Phocis ; still it was venerable
88 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. iv.
from old association, and might give a colour to high-
handed usurpation. The doom inflicted on Phocis
was that it should cease to be a state. Twenty-two
Phocian towns were dismantled; the inhabitants were
dispersed into villages, deprived of their arms and
horses, and subjected to a crushing tribute. The
seat and votes of the Phocians in the Amphictyonic
Council were forfeited to Philip, and the right of
precedence in consulting the oracle was transferred
from Athens to him. He was further chosen to pre-
side at the celebration of the Pythian games (Aug.
346), to which, however, the Athenians refused to
send their representative. Such was the end of the
Sacred War, carried on now for ten years. Philip
had attained the object which he had long pursued,
by patience and diplomacy no less than by the active
energies of genius. He had received admission into
the Greek commonwealth at the religious centre of
Greece.
But Athens still held aloof, and he could not dis-
pense with her recognition. An embassy came to
demand it. Popular indignation was roused, and the
patriot party urged an unconditional refusal. Demos-
thenes, as once before at a less critical moment
(p. 36), brought the counsels of prudence to bear
on a heated assembly. The speech he delivered
toward the end of 346 B.c, is known as the Speech
On the Peace. He rebukes the Athenian habit of
reflecting after the event. He reminds his hearers
of three distinct occasions on which it would have
been well had they taken his advice — at the time of
the last Eubcean war, at the opening of the peace
negotiations, and in the recent debates after the return
of the second embassy. He claims no special pre-
science, but merely a pure and unbiassed judgment.
He then proceeds to the subject in hand. The peace
was, indeed, unworthy of Athens, but having been
CHAP. IV.] PUBLIC LIFE AND SPEECHES. 89
made, it must not be broken. Everything must be
avoided Avhich would give the self-styled Amphictyons
a pretext for combining against Athens. Many
states of Greece had grudges against her of their own,
and in the name of Amphictyonic union might push
their hostility to more desperate conclusions than if
they were acting singly. The Social War had proved
how discordant ambitions might unite to produce
unforeseen results. Without sacrificing honour, the
Athenians must avoid imprudent action. Already
they had acquiesced in the loss of Oropus, Amphi-
polis, Cardia, Chios, Cos, and Rhodes, in order to
ensure a balance of advantage ; would it not be sheer
folly to go to war with a whole confederacy for " the
shadow of Delphi ?"
This speech is the first of the second group (p. 61)
of Philippic orations. It is brief and unimpassioned,
containing merely a sober view of a difificult situation ;
and the expression remains on a level with the
thought. The advice contained is sternly practical,
and bitter alike to the speaker and the hearers. It
has in it none of the higher inspirations of genius.
By a strange exception to the Attic practice, the
language of emotion hardly appears except in the
concluding words. The cautious wisdom of Demos-
thenes in avoiding an occasion for an Amphictyonic
war was fully justified by subsequent history \ for the
present, however, the danger was averted. It is to
be regretted that three years later, in his speech
On the Embassy (§§ 111-113), Demosthenes, in his
anxiety to sever himself completely from Aeschines
and his policy, is led to deny his own share in these
transactions. But, widely unlike as were the two men's
motives, the substance of their advice on this question
cannot have differed sensibly. Each of them recom-
mended the recognition of Philip's Amphictyonic
title. Demosthenes grounds his advice on the par-
90 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. iv.
amount needs of the moment, and he throws out
hints to show that he has no sympathy with the
Philippising party. In peace upon such terms he
saw an armistice rather than a durable settlement,
and the next few years were a time of preparation
for the decisive stru^crle.
CHAPTER V.
HIS PUBLIC LIFE AND SPEECHES. FROM THE PEACE
OF PHILOCRATES (346 B.C.) TO CH^ERONEA (338 B.C.)
During the years of nominal peace from 346 B.C. to
340 B.C., Philip carried on a diplomatic warfare,
without ever coming to an open rupture. Larger
horizons had, doubtless, already opened up to him
outside Greece. He aspired to the leadership of the
Hellenes in a war against Persia, but the temper of
Athens stood in his way. Philip was not one who
regarded moral forces as material obstacles which
might rudely be set aside. Any attempt to treat
Athens hke Olynthus, and to violate the home and
centre of Greek life, might arm against him a con-
federation of all the powers. He must if possible
bring Athens to act with them, or at least not to act
against him. Hence the terms of studied courtesy
in which he addresses the Athenian people, his
laboured apologies, his indignant disavowals of the
very purpose on which he is engaged (all reminding
us forcibly of the methods of Napoleon I.), his hints
at enigmatic services which he has no intention of
performing. Of those who gave credence and cur-
rency to these friendly professions, some were honest
dupes. Isocrates, in 346 B.C., in the interval between
the conclusion of the peace and the end of the Sacred
War, speaks of ill-natured persons who pretended that
92 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. v.
Philip had designs against the freedom of Greece,
and he is almost ashamed to notice the groundless
suspicion {Phili/>p. § 73). The destruction of Phocis
was Philip's practical comment on these remarks.
But the faith of Isocrates remained unshaken, and a
letter he wrote to Philip, probably in 342 rc, is con-
ceived in the old strain. Philip continued to work
out his ends by arts of his owa He kept the peace,
but sought to isolate Athens by forming fresh alliances
in every quarter. Demosthenes followed and thwarted
each movement His influence steadily grew ; he
was no longer an opposition speaker, he had become
a recognised adviser and a leader of opinion. Round
him gathered a patriot party, embracing in its ranks
Hegesippus, Lycurgus, and Hyperides. But each
step in advance was sharply contested and painfully
won ; and Eubulus, though his power was on the
wane, still retained the control of finance. From
such hands Demosthenes determined to wrest the
administratioa Conscious that a decisive struggle
was imminent, he strove to impress his own convic-
tion on others, and to prepare a national resistance.
His leading thought during this period was to organise
an Hellenic league against the usurper, to bring
Greece into co-operation with Athens. The speeches
beginning with the speech On the Peace (346 b.c.)
down to the Third Philippic {-^^i n.c), form a gradu-
ated series in which this idea is developed with
increasing clearness and emphasis.
To the Peloponnesian states the first call was ad-
dressed. Philip, who had retired for a time from the
scene of Greek politics to consolidate his power at
home, reappeared in 344 B.C., and established an olig-
archical regime in Thessaly. In the same year he
interfered in the Peloponnese, where he aspired to play
the part of Epaminondas in supporting the independ-
ence of Mcssene and Argos against Sparta. The reality
CHAP, v.] PUBLIC LIFE AND SPEECHES. 93
of his friendship was proved by subsidies of men and
money. On the proposal of Demosthenes an em-
bassy was sent, of which he himself was the chief
member, to counteract these intrigues. He visited
Messene and Argos ; he pointed to Olynthus and
Thessaly as warning instances of states which Philip
by presents and promises had lured to their ruin.
They had known, he said, Philip the benefactor ; let
them pray that they might never know Philip the
deceiver. " Manifold are the contrivances of art for
the defence and security of cities — battlements, walls,
trenches, and the like — all made by human hands and
costly to maintain. But there is one universal safe-
guard, planted deep in the hearts of thinking men,
a safeguard which is good and salutary for all, and
especially for free communities against despots. What
is this ? Mistrust. Guard this, hold it fast ; if you
keep it, you may rest assured no harm will come to
you. What is the object you seek ? Liberty. And
do you not see that Philip's very titles are irrecon-
cilable with liberty ? Every monarch and despot is a
foe of freedom, and hostile to law. Beware then, lest
in seeking deliverance from war, you find a master !"
{Phil. ii. §§ 23-25).
This mission to the Peloponnese was the origin,
apparently, of an embassy sent to Athens in ;'44 B.C.,
on which occasion Demosthenes spoke the Second
Philippic. The draft of a reply to the envoys was
embodied in the speech, but the loss of this document
leaves us to conjecture the precise situation. The
speech taken alone would seem to be primarily an
answer to Philip's remonstrances against the miscon-
struction put upon his conduct by the Athenians.
But in any case its scope is far wider than the diplo-
matic issue of the moment. Demosthenes exhibits
here the true relation of Philip to Athens and to
Greece. The introduction reads like a preface to a
94 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. v.
warlike proposal, but no such proposal follows. The
speech is preparatory to action, not a summons to
act ; its aim is to enlighten and convince rather than
to exhort The style, though animated, is not marked
by any passionate vehemence ; only towards the end
(§ 33) ^ clearer vision of his countr)''s danger is borne in
upon the orator, and his language reflects his emotion.
He begins by a sarcastic remark on the means
taken to check Philip's progress ; the Athenians talk
while Philip acts, and each side succeeds best in their
own line. Unless, then, the people are satisfied with
such empty triumphs, they must alter their whole
method (§§ 1-5). He then combats the easy faith
with which the assurances of Macedonian partizans
are accepted. Against Athens, he says, all Philip's
efforts are aimed. His friendship for Thebes, for
Argos, for Messene, betrays his motives. He is ac-
quainted with the inglorious past of those cities, and
with the traditions of your history. He does not
tempt you into his alliance. " This is the noblest of
all tributes to your character. You are thus pro-
nounced to be the only people who could never be
bribed to abandon the common rights of Greece, who
never for favour or profit would barter away your
Hellenic loyalty" {§§ 7-12). He next refutes the
apologies offered for Philip. He points to the incon-
sistency between his promised policy in the Pelopon-
nese and his actual policy in Bceotia — he who sub-
jected the Boeotian cities to Thebes, will he free the
Peloponnesian cities from Sparta ? He shows how
Philip, by a necessity of his position, was pursuing a
settled plan of hostility to Athens (§§ 13-19). This
he enforces by a summary of the arguments he had
used in his mission to the Peloponnese. Argives and
Messenians, it appeared, still remained deaf to wise
counsel ; Athenians had a clearer insight, and neglect
on their part would be without e.\cuse (§§ 20-27).
CHAP, v.] PUBLIC LIFE AND SPEECHES. 95
Having submitted his proposed reply to the en-
voys, he points in the epilogue (§§ 28-37), riot by
name, but still unmistakably, to Philocrates and
Aeschines as the guilty causes of the present troubles.
Their promises had deceived the people ; let not the
innocent hereafter suffer in their stead. " Believe me
the day will come when Philip's doings will pain you
more than they do now. I see things marching to
their end ; and though I have no wish to be a true
prophet, yet I fear the evil is but too nigh already.
When, then, it shall no longer be in your power to dis-
regard events, when you shall no longer hear from me
or from another that it is you who are menaced, but
when you all see it with your own eyes, and know it for
yourselves, you will probably yield to angry and bitter
feelings. And as your ambassadors have kept from
you the guilty secret of their own bribed services,
those who endeavour to repair what through them
has been lost may become, I fear, the victims of your
displeasure. . . . While the storm then is still coming,
still gathering, while we still hear one another's voices,
I would remind each of you of what you know full
well — who it was persuaded you to abandon Phocis,
and made you to give up Thermopylse (and ever since
Philip commands these places he commands the road
to Attica and to the Peloponnese) — who has caused
you to take counsel, not about your rights or your
foreign policy, but about your home possessions, and
about war upon Attica, a war whose smart each one
will feel only when it comes, but whose beginning dates
back to that day. . . . Enough has now been said to
waken recollection. That my words should be fully
verified, grant, all ye gods, that it may never come to
this ! For myself, I could wish no man to suffer even
a merited doom at the cost of danger and damage to
the community" (§§ 32-37).
The anti-Macedonian party were soon emboldened
96 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. v.
to begin the judicial proceedings hinted at in the
Second Philippic. In 343 B.C. Hyperides impeached
Philocrates, who retired into exile, and in his absence
was condemned to death. About the same time
Demosthenes resumed an accusation, which three
years before he had laid against Aeschines, for mis-
conduct on the second embassy. The charge was a
delicate one for him to maintain, for it was only a
narrow line that had separated his own advice from
that of Aeschines at one period of the nc^'otiations
(p. 84). Hence in the speech On the Embassy he
carefully limits the charge ; Aeschines, he says, is not
accused of having concluded peace, but of having
concluded a shameful and ruinous peace. Techni-
cally the prosecution related only to the second
embassy, but the previous part taken by Aeschines
in framing the terms of the treaty is incidentally
attacked. Demosthenes, however, in attempting to
disclaim all responsibility for a peace which was now
discredited, becomes fiercely polemical, and is led
into many disingenuous, and some false, statements.
His case is, moreover, complicated by the nature of
the evidence available. He can bring no direct
proof of Aeschines' guilt. The presumption of guilt
rested on an inference derived from the conduct of
Aeschines at different moments. The facts had,
therefore, to be so marshalled as most forcibly to
suggest the inference. Hence the peculiar disposi-
tion of the speech. While Aeschines follows the
historical order of events, Demosthenes inverts that
order. Each aims at producing an impression of
honest artlessness, Aeschines by a straightforward
and continuous narrative, Demosthenes by a would-
be haphazard arrangement. Aeschines manages to
ignore or evade the real issues by lingering over
transactions which were not impugned, and by repelling
at leuLith collateral charges. The seeming artless-
ciiAr. v.] PUBLIC LIFE AND SPEECHES. 97
ness of Demosthenes is one of the artifices he often
employs to mask the weak points of a case. Some
arxient as well as modern critics have seen in the
absence of regular order a want of plan. But the
orator in truth shows an exact appreciation of the
materials at his command, and of their value as evi-
dence. He has one capital and indisputable fact to
start from, that the pledges and promises of Aeschines
on his return from the second embassy mystified and
deceived the people, and that the result was the seizure
of Thermopylae and the destruction of Phocis. This is
the groundwork of his reasoning, and forms the chief
article of accusation. The point is developed at length
in §§ 29-97, and is elsewhere reiterated. But so far
Aeschines is not proved corrupt. Demosthenes marks
the possible alternative. Aeschines, he argues, must
either have been honestly deluded or have been in
guilty collusion with Philip. If the former, would he
not, after the event had falsified his hopes, have ab-
horred the man by whom he had been deceived? But
nothing of the kind ; he shared in Philip's rejoicings
at Delphi over the work of ruin, and since that time
he has aspired to the friendship and advocated the
cause of the conqueror. Such conduct can only be
accounted for by corruption. This is the topic
handled from §§ 98-149. The argument is not easy
to meet, and Aeschines certainly fails to "rebut it.
I'he same conclusion had been previously arrived at
from another side. The abrupt conversion of Aes-
chines from an ardent patriot, rousing Greece to a
war against the foreigner, into a servile partisan, was
capable only of one explanation (§§ 9-28).
Having established this strong presumption against
Aeschines, he goes back upon the events of the second
embassy itself. He exposes the fatal delay of the
ambassadors, and their neglect of instructions (§§
150-178). By relating the events in this connection
H
98 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. v.
he is making up for the want of direct evidence ; a
treasonable colour is given to proceedings which might
have been more leniently interpreted.
Here the first great division of the speech ends.
The main position has now been made good ; the rest
is supplementary and corroborative, and may roughly
be called the Epilogue (§§ 179-343). The first divi-
sion of the speech is more distinctively forensic in
character ; the charges are formally stated, and the
proofs adduced. The second half is rather in the
deliberative manner. The range of topics is enlarged,
principles are set forth, and a wider political outlook
is taken. The special case of Aeschines is, in a pass-
age of indignant eloquence, merged in a general view
of the increase of traitors in Greece, and of the im-
punity accorded them (§§ 259-2S7). A powerful re-
capitulation (§§ 315-336) recalls to the jury the prime
indictment.
With all its force and ingenuity the speech is of an
unwieldy length, and sufiers from excessive repeti-
tions. Other intrinsic weaknesses have been indicated
above. But the large and statesmanlike utterances
which are scattered through it, and which abound in
the latter half, atone for much that is ignobly personal
or disingenuous. The bold disregard of technical
rules of rhetoric claims some notice. Nowhere, un-
less in The Crown, are outward laws of symmetry so
completely set aside in favour of a more subtle but
still a presiding order. Narrative and proof are
blended ; the events, displaced from their proper se-
quence, are so disposed, that in telling their own story
they suggest the desired inference. Refutation is not
kept distinct from proof or narrative. The exact point
at which tlie Epilogue begins may be variously fixed.
Erom the reply of Aeschines we can infer some-
thing as to the relation between the present form of
Demosthenes' speech and the form in which it was
CH.vr. v.] PUBLIC LIFE AND SPEECHES. 99
delivered. The general structure must have been the
same, for Aeschines criticises its artificial order (Aesch.
Emb. § 96). And Aeschines' answers have, on the
whole, a minute correspondence with the objections
as we read them in Demosthenes. The discrepancies
are comparatively few, and of two kinds. Some con-
sist in slight variations of detail, such as are almost
always found between a speech quoted from memory
and the same speech as delivered. Others are more
important, and seem to imply that the version cited
by Aeschines was, in some respects at least, fuller
than ours. To take one instance, Aeschines quotes
(§ 10) a story and a comparison which are totally
absent from the extant speech. Whether the speech,
as we have it, was abbreviated by Demosthenes for
publication, or is an unrevised draft which was ex-
panded in delivery, is not so easy to determine.
The result of the trial was, as we learn on good
authority, that Aeschines was acquitted by thirty votes
— a doubtful victory, and probably due to the influ-
ence of Eubulus, whose dominion in the law courts is
in this very speech denounced.
In the years between 344 B.C. and 341 e.g., the
tide of events turned partially against Philip. He
sought to ally himself with other religious centres of
the Greek world besides Delphi. In Elis he found a
footing, which seemed to promise influence in Olyni-
pia. Another design, however, of supplanting Athens
as guardian of the sanctuary of Delos was frustrated.
His most important success was in Euboea ; there he
established his despots at Oreus and Eretria. But
both on the east and west he was foiled in the attempt
to gain access to the Peloponnese. First, Megara
was rescued by prompt succour from Athens. Bafiied
on this side, he turned his arms towards Epirus, and
intrigued in Aetolia. He marched upon the impor-
tant town of Ambracia, the possession of which would
loo DEMOSTHENES. [chap, v
have opened up Acarnania and the Corinthian Gulf.
Here again the Athenians were beforehand ; they had
thrown a body of troops into Ambracia, and the way
to the south was closed. An embassy to Acarnania,
led by Demosthenes and backed up by Athenian arms,
was successful in forming a league in that quarter.
The danger of an invasion of Attica had for the pre-
sent receded. Philip, in 342 b.c, entered on a new
campaign against Thrace, and pushed further east-
wards ; a permanent conquest of the countr)- between
the Hellespont and the Euxine would serve him at
once as a base of operations against Asia and would
deal a vital blow to Athens.
In 341 B.C. Athens found herself menaced in her
most vulnerable point abroad. The Thracian Cher-
sonese had for about two centuries been regarded as
an integral part of Athenian territory, and was the
bulwark of her maritime empire in the north. If
Thermopylae held one gate of Greece, the Chersonese
might be said to hold the other. It commanded the
passage of the Dardanelles and the corn trade of the
Black Sex On its safety depended the very subsist-
ence of Athens, for from the Black Sea came almost
all the grain imported into Attica, amounting to about
one-third of the total consumption.
Diopeithes, an Athenian mercenary, had in 343
R.c. attempted to force some settlers upon Cardia, in
the Chersonese. Situated at the head of the isthmus
not far from the modern Gallipoli, Cardia held a posi-
tion of somewhat the same importance that Gallipoli
holds now. The city had in 357 rc. been recognised
as independent, and in the late treaty had been en-
rolled among the allies of Philip. But the Athenians
from long possession had not ceased to look on it as
their own. Philip sent aid to Cardia, and Diopeithes
retaliated by plundering districts of Thrace that were
subject to Macedon. This led to a letter of menace
CHAP, v.] PUBLIC LIFE AND SPEECHES. loi
and remonstrance from Philip to the Athenian people.
His partisans in Athens pressed for the recall of
Diopeithes ; Demosthenes saw the necessity of keep-
ing a firm grasp on the Chersonese at a moment when
war was imminent, and resisted the demand. Tech-
nical right was on the side of Philip, for armed
violence towards Macedonian subjects or allies was
a violation of the peace.
In his speech On the Chersonese, Demosthenes
(341 B.C.) refuses to treat the question on a narrow
technical issue (cf his contemptuous phrase, § 57,
avTi] i) SiaSuiacria). He takes it out of the juridical
sphere into that of politics. His argument, morally
and politically valid, maintained that Athens, appa-
rently aggressive, was in a very real sense acting on the
defensive — that the peace existed only in name, and
that Philip had long been at war, though war had not
been declared. A permanent force, consisting in part
of the troops of Diopeithes, must, he said, be kept in
the neighbourhood of the Hellespont — a recommend-
ation which he had in substance urged already in the
Mrsf Philippic (351 B.C.)
Such is the essential and recurrent thought of the
speech On the Chersonese^ the most perfect, perhaps,
of all the deliberative harangues of Demosthenes.
It has in it almost every variety of tone. From a
subdued sarcasm it rises into fiery scorn and passion-
ate invective. He abases his audience by the picture
of their lower selves, but presently reanimates them
by the image of austere devotion which the ideal
Athens presents. Three main topics find place in the
speech ; but they pass imperceptibly into one another,
in the Demosthenic manner, without the marks of a
rigid division. First, the situation is set forth in its
true aspect (§§ 1-29) ; next, the orator, passing, as his
custom is, to the moral side, combats the deep-seated
apathy of the people (§§ 30-51) ; and finally, breaks
102 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. v.
forth against the venal politicians who flatter the base
appetites of the people, and deaden the public honour
(§§ 52-75)-
The passage of eloquent self-justification in §§ 67-
7 2 contains the orator's conception of a statesman ;
the manner in which the personal element is here
almost effaced in the desire to assert a great principle,
is profoundly characteristic of Demosthenes.
The real subject of debate, says Demosthenes, is
not the conduct or intentions of Diopeithes, but the
safety of the Chersonese, which once lost cannot be
recovered (§§ 1-3). We ought, we are told, to choose
between peace and war. But Philip leaves us no
choice in the matter; we are driven to act in self-
defence, unless it be maintained that Philip may
attack us anywhere except on Attic soil, but that we
may not attack him even in Thrace (§§ 4-S). Again it
is said, Diopeithes has been behaving as a freebooter,
and his forces ought to be disbanded. Excellent ad-
vice, if Philip is also prepared to disband his forces.
Otherwise it is the old story over again — Philip at the
head of a permanent army, executing swift surprises,
we hastening to the rescue when the mischief is done
(§§ 9-12). The hidden purpose of such counsel is to
paralyze us, while Philip is left free to march to By-
zantium, to the Chersonese, or even to the borders of
Attica. Our clear duty is to send funds and rein-
forcements to Diopeithes, not to lend ourselves to
carry out the dearest wishes of Philij) (§§ 13-20). " I
desire, therefore, to question you ^ freely about our
present situation, and to consider what we ourselves
are now doing, and how we are conducting our aftairs.
We do not choose to raise money, nor do we dare to
serve in person, nor can we keep our hands off the
public funds, nor do we make over to Diopeithes the
contributions of the allies, nor do we sanction the sup-
' Reading with S. Vfj-aa not irpot vfjias.
CHAP, v.] rUBLIC LIFE AND SPEECHES. 103
plies he finds for himself; but we eye him maliciously,
and question the source of these supplies, and pry into
his plans, and keep up a jealous scrutiny. Nor yet,
being in this frame of mind, are we inclined to attend to
our own concerns, but, while with our lips we applaud
those who hold language worthy of Athens, in act we
co-operate with their opponents. It is your practice,
when a speaker comes forward, to ask him, 'What then
are we to do ?' I should like to ask you, ' What then
are we to say?' For if you will neither raise money,
nor serve in person, nor keep your hands off the public
funds, nor make over to Diopeithes the contributions
of the allies, nor leave him to supply himself, nor
resolve to attend to your own concerns, I know not
what to say" (§§ 21-23). Diopeithes is obliged to
provide for his troops as all Athenian commanders
have done before him ; he levies contributions under
the name of" benevolences " (p. 20). There are some
who, caring more for the Greeks of Asia than they do
for the Greeks of their own country, accuse Diopeithes
before the people. This can have but one result, to
impair his authority abroad, and 'cut off his last re-
source. The proposal to send an army to watch and
control him is an extreme of folly. If he must be
recalled and brought to trial, a despatch will suffice
(§§ 24-29)-
The people conspire with their counsellors to shift
the blame of their misfortunes upon some helpless
victim ; they fear to recognise the true culprit, who,
they know, cannot be chastised save by force of arms.
Pampered into timid inaction by their leaders, they
find at last that their existence is at stake. What
answer could you make to the reproaches of the
Greek states, if they addressed you thus? — "Athenians,
you send us constant embassies, you warn us against
Philip ; what have you done yourselves, while Philip
was absent and ill ? You have not so much as de-
I04 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. v.
livered two cities in Euboea, hostile outposts planted
against Attica ; you have proved that, were Philip to
die ten times over, you would not bestir yourselves "
(§§ 30-37)- If you ask my positive advice, I would
say : " first convince yourselves that Philip is at war
with Athens, that he has broken the peace, that he is
the deadly enemy of the whole city, of the verj' ground
on which it stands, nay, of every human being within
its walls. . . . But with nothing is he so much at war
as with our constitution, against nothing are his designs
equally directed, on no single aim is he so much bent
as on its destruction." Be assured that Philip's
activity in Thrace is with a view to mastery in Attica.
He does not rough it in that slough of despond for
the sake of the millet and barley in the Thracian pits.
In the face of this restless enemy you must maintain
the existing force at the seat of war as a permanent
army of reserve. All this demands heavy sacrifices,
but these must not deter us. " Suppose you have the
word of a god for what it is beyond mortal power to
promise — that, if you continue quiet and make sur-
render of all, Philip will not finally turn his arms
against you ; still, by Zeus and all the gods, it is a
disgraceful act, unworthy of yourselves and of your
country's past, and of your fothers' achievements, to
abandon all the rest of Greece to bondage for the
sake of selfish ease. For myself, I would rather be
dead than have offered such advice." ^^'e will act,
you say, when there is necessity. The necessity most
imperious to freemen has come, or rather gone — the
necessity of honour. A slave's necessity is chastise-
ment and the lash (§§ 3S-51).
Some orators dwell largely on the advantages of
peace, and on the waste and misappropriation of public
money entailed by war. Their pacific counsels are
superfluous ; more fitly would they be addressed to
Philip than to you. Such men grieve over the risk of
CHAP, v.] PUBLIC LIFE AND SPEECHES. 105
petty peculation ; they look on with indifference
while Philip" is making all Greece his prey. They
attempt to cast on us the odium of kindling war, as
if war was not long since kindled. And war upon us
means a war of extermination. " Philip well knows
that you will not be his slaves ; that you could not if
you would, for you are used to empire" (§§ 52-60).
Now you cannot vanquish your enemy outside
until you have punished the enemy within the
walls; for Philip, who elsewhere has been forced to
lavish kindness on a people in order to overcome
them, has been able to inflict on you loss after loss
without equivalent, and all because of the license
granted to his advocates in Athens. "Thanks to this,
some of them have exchanged penury for sudden
wealth, a nameless obscurity for eminence and renown ;
while you from honour have sunk into obscurity, from
affluence to destitution — for the wealth of a state
consists, to my mind at least, in allies, credit, esteem,
of all which you are destitute. It is because you dis-
regard Philip's progress, and suffer events to drift as
they will, that he has become prosperous and power-
ful, a terror to all men, Greeks or barbarians ; you
stand alone and degraded ; splendid in the profu-
sion of the market, but in every needful provision
contemptible. . . . Then some chance speaker rises
and says : ' What ! you make no proposal, you do
not hazard a motion, you are timid and spiritless.'
Brazen, offensive, and impudent, I am not, and hope
I never may be ; yet I count myself more truly
courageous than your dashing politicians. To im-
peach, confiscate, reward, and accuse, without regard
to the public interest, — all this demands no exercise of
courage. When a man's own safety is guaranteed
him by speeches and measures which court your
favour, he is bold without much risk. But he, who
for your good often thwarts your wishes, who never
io6 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. v.
speaks to win your favour, but always to promote
your interest ; who, while pursuing a policy in which
fortune prevails more commonly than forethought,
makes himself responsible before you alike for the
plan and for the issue — he is truly courageous, such
an one does genuine service ; not those who for an
ephemeral popularity have sacrificed the country's
highest welfare — men whom I am so far from wishing
to emulate or from regarding as citizens worthy of
Athens, that if the question were put to me, ' And
you, what services, pray, have you done our country?'
I would pass by the duties I have discharged as
trierarch and choirmaster, the sums I have contri-
buted, the captives I have ransomed, and other like
acts of benevolence ; I would merely say that my
policy has nothing in common with such as theirs.
Able I may be, as well as others, to accuse, to bribe,
to confiscate, in a word, to act as they do ; yet never
have I chosen any such part, never have I been be-
trayed into it by avarice or ambition. My language
has consistently been such as to place me below many
in your eyes, but such as would exalt you, if you would
but listen to me. Thus much I may be allowed to
say without offence. Nor do I take it to be my part,
as an honest citizen, to devise a policy which would
speedily make me pre-eminent in Athens, and you
last among the nations. The country ought to grow
in greatness as the measures of patriots unfold ; it is
the duty of all to recommend always what is most
salutary, not what is easiest. Nature herself will take
the road to what is easy ; it needs the lessons of a
l)atriotic elo(iuence to conduct the hearers to what is
salutary "' (§§ 61-72). I am reproached with speaking
merely and not acting, liut I hold that speech is
action in a statesman; his word is his work; his
province is to counsel, it is for you to e.xecute (§§
73-75)-
CHAP, v.] PUBLIC LIFE AND SPEECHES. 107
Demosthenes then sums up his advice. If the
vigorous action he urges is taken, he expresses a hope
(though in a tone of abated confidence) of a return
to better days. But, without such action, all the
eloquence in the world could not save the country
(§§ 76, 7 7)-
The Third Philippic followed after an interval of a
few months, the situation being still unchanged. It
has been pronounced by many ancient and modern
critics to be the greatest of the popular speeches of
Demosthenes. In one respect at least it rises above
the speech Oti the Chersonese. The orator's vision is
enlarged and yet intensified. He speaks as a
Hellenic patriot rather than as an Athenian citizen.
Every thought is here subordinated to the danger of
Greece. He had not hitherto ventured to bring a
formal motion, but the ground was cleared by the last
speech, and the minds of the Athenians were ready to
receive the plainest counsels. He now proposes that
Athens should arm herself and head a Hellenic
league. The despatch of envoys to the various states,
incidentally recommended in The Chersonese, here
rises into prominence. Though the tone of the speech
marks a sense of danger more pressing than before,
it is very far removed from despair. The hopeful ex-
pressions, both in the beginning and the end (§§ 4
and 76), are strikingly bold.
It is here more than usually difficult to convey by
extracts any impression of the eloquence of Demos-
thenes. The force of the speech lies largely in rapid
enumerations of recent facts (§§ 11, 12, 15-17, 26, 27,
32-35, 65-67), and in contrasts drawn from the past.
Impassioned and compressed narrative takes the
place of close argument. INIany of the same facts
appear in repeated allusions, but each time in a fresh
setting and under new lights. Stroke follows upon
stroke in swift succession. Each familiar name calls
loS DEMOSTHENES. [chap. v.
up an eventful history and associations of its own,
and the retrospect is charged with bitter memories.
Such a historical review, cumulative in its effect, must
be read continuously; the parts hardly bear to be
separated from the contexture of the whole.
A critical question of much interest, as touching
the method of Demosthenes' composition, attaches
itself to the Third Fhilippic. The best manuscript,
the Parisian S (as well as the Laurentian L which is
of the same family), differs remarkably from the
ordinary text by the omission of phrases and of
whole passages. The variation seems due to a double
recension ; both texts probably proceed from Demos-
thenes himself Good reasons have been brought for
supposing the shorter text of S to represent the
maturer correction of the orator.
Early in the speech (§§ 6-20) the question is raised,
which had formed the groundwork of the speech On
the Chersonese, Is it still possible to choose between
jieace and war? The treatment, however, is here
broader and leads to more comprehensive conclusions.
If the choice, says Demosthenes, were still open, he
would be in favour of peace ; but Philip speaks peace
and acts war ;^ it was to procure such a one-sided
])eace as the present that he had dealt his bribes. If
the Athenians were waiting for a declaration of war,
they might learn by the examples of Olyntlnis, Phocis,
Pherre, and Oreus, that it was not Philip's practice
to declare war till he was at the gates. Nor would
he make an exception in favour of Athens ; if she
shut her eyes, it was not for him to enlighten her. If
they looked, however, not at words but at deeds, they
might convince themselves that from the day that
Phocis was destroyed, Philip had been at war ; unless
it were maintained that to bring up siege-batteries
did not mean war, till the batteries were planted
* A maxim recommended and carried out by Napoleon I.
CHAP, v.] PUBLIC LIFE AND SPEECHES. 109
against the walls. They were bound then to defend
the Chersonese and Byzantium, but that was not
enough ; larger issues were now involved, for all Greece
stood in imminent peril.
In the second division of the speech (§§ 21-35) he
gives the grounds of this conviction. A new fact was
visible in Greek history. Athens, Sparta, and Thebes,
when in turn they were supreme, had been jealously
watched by the other states and their excesses checked ;
but Philip was allowed full power to do as he would
— " to fleece, to pillage, and to enslave " state after
state. Rapidly he enumerates the violent deeds of
him, whose " ambition neither Hellas nor the land of
the barbarians can contain." The Greeks, " self-
blockaded in their cities " (Siopcopvyfieda Kara TToAets),
saw and heard all, without one effort to combine and
save Greece, each one resolved to make the most of
his own brief respite, while his neighbour was perish-
ing ; though there was none so far off, but that Philip
came to him at last with the certainty of a fever's
access. The sufferings that Greeks had formerly
undergone at the hands of Sparta and Athens were
sufferings inflicted by true-born Greeks. Phihp's
domination was so far worse than theirs, as the waste
and ruin of an estate by a slave was worse than mis-
management by the lawful heir ; for Philip was no
Greek, nor even a barbarian of respectable origin.
And to fill the measure of his insolence, the destroyer
of Greek cities presided at the Pythian games, and
issued his mandates to all. The Greeks looked on
as they might at a hailstorm, praying that they them-
selves might be spared, but without an effort to pre-
vent it. Even their own private -swongs they took
quietly — so far were they from redressing the wrongs
of Greece. They faced one another in a torpor of
mistrust.
Next he asks the cause of this change (§§ 36-69),
no DEMOSTHENES. [chap. v.
and he finds it not in any accident of individual life.
"Something there once was in the heart of the masses
which there is not now, something which prevailed
over the wealth of Persia, which kept Greece in free-
dom, which was unvanquished in battle by land or
sea." This secret force was a hatred of bribery.
"New principles are now imported, wherewith Greece
is sick even to death. And what are these? Envy,
if a man has taken a bribe ; ridicule, if he confesses
it ; pardon, if the guilt is proved ; hatred of those
who censure him ; and ever)' other appendage of
corruption." Wealth, population, all the material
elements of strength, were by this pervading vice
rendered impotent and unavailing. The sense of
Panhellenic interests, which their forefathers mani-
fested in stern decrees, had died out. Bribed coun-
sellors possessed the ear of the Assembly ; and yet
Olynthus, Euboea, and Oreus were so many standing
warnings of cities which had met their fate by listen-
ing to the counsels of treason.
Lastly, Demosthenes introduces his own substantive
proposal (§§ 70-76), with the prefatory words, that if
the rest of the world consented to be slaves, Athens,
at least, must do battle for freedom. Let them, while
their strength was unspent and while honour survived,
first arm themselves, and show Greece that they were
in earnest ; next, send envoys everywhere to organise
a national league. But he insists and repeats that to
their own efforts they must primarily trust, that Athens
was now the last stay of Greece. " If you think that
Chalcidians or Megarians will save Greece, while you
shirk the contest, you are mistaken. . . . The task is
yours : this is the privilege won and bequeathed to
you by your ancestors at the cost of many and great
dangers.
" This," he concludes. " is what I have to say, these
arc the measures I propose. Adopt these measures, and
CHAP, v.] PUBLIC LIFE AND SPEECHES. in
it is my belief that even yet our affairs may be retrieved.
If any man has better advice to offer, let him speak
forth and declare his counsel. And, be your decision
what it may, grant, all ye gods, that it may be for our
good !"
The years 340 B.C. to 338 B.C. were a period of
great awakening for Athens. Demosthenes was now
supreme director of the state, and by these years he
himself (in The Crown) claims to be judged. The
literary record of his eloquence fails us just at the
point where it achieved its highest successes. None
of the speeches of this period are preserved. The
earlier harangues were committed to writing by the
orator, in the hope that their influence might outlive
the moment of delivery. But speech now passed
into instant action, and attained its end ; and the
only memorial of these orations is contained in a few
ppieaclid pages of history. First Eubcea was wrested
flora Phihp. Athens became the centre of a Hel-
lenic league comprising Eubcea, Acarnania, Corinth,
Achsea, Corcyra, Megara. By the force of his
eloquence Demosthenes won back to Athens the
estranged Byzantines, whose city, soon afterwards
besieged by Philip, was relieved by Athenian arms.
From west to east, wherever a patriotic resistance was
organised, Demosthenes was the soul of the move-
ment. At the same time he combated internal abuses.
He had begun his public life with a proposed measure
of navy reform, and now in the teeth of intrigue and
opposition he carried a measure at once more simple
and more complete. Under the existing system all
who were liable to the charge of the Trierarchy con-
tributed an equal share. By the Trierarchic Law of
Demosthenes the share of each was in proportion to
his rated property, and the burden equitably adjusted
between rich and poor. A social grievance was thus
removed. The measure was justified by its practical
112 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. v.
working. Evasions and delays were now almost
unknown, and among the most striking features of
the war was the increased efficiency of the marine.
Another of his measures was a still greater triumph.
In the First Olynthiac (349 B.C.) he had delicately
approached the question of the Festival Fund ; not
until 339 B.C. could he carry his long wished for
reform, by which the surplus of the yearly expendi-
ture went not to the Theoricon, but to war purposes.
Thus, at the final crisis, the Athenian populace learnt
to renounce some cherished pleasures.
For a brief space it seemed as if all mi^ht yet be
retrieved. But another Sacred War, opportunely
kindled, brought Philip once more within Greece to
e.xercise " the protectorate of religion " (Aesch. Ctcs.
§ 129). The precise point at which intrigue began
cannot be determined ; but events so followed one
another as to bear all the marks of a studied plot;
and in this plot Aeschines would seem to have been
a chief accomplice. Once inside Thermopylre, Philip
forgot his mission against the guilty Locrians, and
seizing Elatea, commanded the passes into Bceotia.
The sequel is well known from the famous narra-
tive in The Croni/i ; — the evening tidings brought to
Athens — the consternation in the city — the hastily
convened Assembly — the long silence and pause of
expectation till Demosthenes arose and gave his
counsel — his embassy to Thebes, resulting in alliance
between Thebes and Athens. Here was the crowning
achievement of his eloquence. Old jealousies were
silenced, and the rival cities stood loyally together till
Cha:ronea, where " the liberties of Greece were buried
in the graves of the fallen" (Lycurg. Lcocrat. § 50).
CHAPTER VI.
HIS PUBLIC LIFE AND SPEECHES. FROM CH/ERONEA
(338 B.C.) TO HIS DEATH {322 B.C.)
The part that Demosthenes had henceforth to play
was reduced to narrower Hmits. Athens, indeed,
still retained municipal independence ; unlike Thebes,
she had not yet received a Macedonian garrison, and
Demosthenes, recognising the altered situation, devoted
himself to internal affairs. He still looked forward
to Philip's death as a possible moment for the enfran-
chisement of Greece ; but the doom inflicted on the
rebellious Thebes by Alexander (335 B.C.) threw back
such hopes into a more distant future. With the
marv^ellous conquests of Alexander in Asia, Macedonian
influence became dominant at Athens ; yet popular
sympathy did not desert the patriots. The year 330
B.C. afforded a decisive test of feeling. To this year
belongs the speech on The Croivii, the last speech of
Demosthenes, and the noblest monument of ancient
eloquence. The case had its origin in these circum-
stances. — In 338 B.C., after the battle of Chseronea,
Demosthenes had held a double office ; he had been
placed on the Commission for the fortification of
Athens, and had been made treasurer of the Theori-
con. Early in 336 B.C. Ctesiphon proposed that he
should receive a golden crown for his services, and
that the proclamation of the crown should be made
I
114 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. vi.
in the Theatre at the Great Dionysia ; that is, in the
presence of all the strangers assembled at Athens for
the festival The measure was passed by the Council,
and thus became a TrpofSovkevixa (bill). It still needed
the ratification of the Assembly to become a \l.-i'i(f)icrfia
(decree). Aeschines at this point stopped the progresr
of the bill by a notice that he would bring a Graphe
Paronomon (p. 31) against Ctesiphon. The grounds
of his indictment were three : ( i ) that it was not true
that Demosthenes had done good service to the state,
and the laws forbade the insertion of a falsehood in
the public records ; (2) that he had not yet passed his
audit, and that it was illegal to crown an official in
such a position ; (3) that the proclamation of the
crown in the Theatre was unlawful.
That charges so different as those contained under
the first and the other two heads of the indictment
should be capable of being combined shows a curious
state of legal procedure, and illustrates the misappli-
cation and abuse of the Graphe Paronomon. The so-
called falsehood under the first head was not a cjuestion
of fact, but a question of opinion upon pohtics. It
could only have found a place in this accusation by
a loose extension of the phrase unconstitutional to
denote all that was inexpedient to the state. The
manoeuvTC was a skilful one, by which Aeschines here
contrived to associate the policy of Demosthenes with
an irrelevant technicality. That the real issue, how-
ever, lay in the first article of indictment was, in spite
of disguises, recognised by Aeschines no less than by
Demosthenes. The question was whether the policy
of Demosthenes had been condemned by the event.
Of the other points of the charge the second was
legally sound. The rule of law was clear, though it
had been often violated in custom. The third was
more doubtful. Aeschines admitted that there wa.<;
one exceptional case in which the crown might be
CHAP. VI.] PUBLIC LIFE AND SPEECHES. 115
bestowed in the Theatre ; but it applied, according to
him, only to crowns bestowed by foreign states. The
letter of the law seems to have been here in favour of
Demosthenes, but in the absence of more complete
documentary evidence some uncertainty must remain.
For six years Aeschines did not venture to bring the
case into court. Even after Cha^ronea, Demosthenes
received marks of unabated confidence from the people.
It was not till the complete triumph of the Macedonian
power that Aeschines saw his opportunity. Philip had
died in 336 B.C., Alexander had crossed into Asia in
334 B.C., and in 331 b.c. had won his great victory at
Arbela. The next year witnessed the failure of Agis'
attempted rising in the Peloponnese. The patriot
party seemed silenced, and Aeschines now brought his
long-delayed action in presence of all Greece.
It was no ordinary criminal case. It marked the
last moment in a personal duel carried on for sixteen
years between famous antagonists. It was, moreover,
the closing scene of a conflict between parties — a con-
flict which had broadened into a national struggle.
Judgment had to be passed on two rival policies,
between which it was not possible to be neutral.
The speech of Aeschines is as usual clear and lucid
in arrangement. He proceeds at once to the technical
points, and states them so as to set off the legal strength
of his position. At the end of the speech he enforces
them once more. In the body of the speech he
reviews the career of Demosthenes in four periods :
I. From the beginning of the war with Philip about
Amphipolis to the peace of Philocrates (357-346
B.C.); 11. From that peace to the renewal of the
war (346-340 B.C.); III. From the renewal of the
war to Chseronea (340—338 b.c); IV. From 338
B.C. up to the present time. There is one remark-
able note of weakness in the speech. Aeschines,
intent apparently on catching votes on both sides,
ii6 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. vi.
himself halts between two opinions. He never
definitely either approves or condemns the general
policy of resistance to Macedon. Though the dominant
tone seems to betray Macedonian sympathy, an opposite
sentiment is in parts visible. The treatment of periods
I. and IV. is designed to discredit Demosthenes with
the patriot party. The charges against him in the
first period, and in part of the second, almost retort
those of Demosthenes against Aeschines in the speech
On the Embassy. And in the fourth period he is
accused of having neglected three occasions of rising
against Alexander. This puzzling ambiguity of view
is hardly explicable, e.xcept on the supposition that
Aeschines, secure of the Macedonian support, thought
to better his case by proving that, judged even as
an anti- Macedonian and a patriot, Demosthenes was
insincere.
Demosthenes in his reply deals rapidly with Period
I. During that period he had held no accepted
position at Athens, and he speaks of it as strictly
irrelevant to the main charge. He confines himself
almost entirely to the peace negotiations of 346 b.c,
which had been impugned by Aeschines. His version
of these negotiations is marked rather by boldness of
outline than by faithfulness to fact. Had he com-
mented on the earlier years of this period, within which
fell the First Philippic and the Olynthiac orations, he
would have occupied a strong vantage-ground But
he had no wish to waken exasperating memories of
warnings despised. Throughout the speech he is at
pains to estabhsh a solidarity between himself and
the Athenian people. The periods, therefore, on
which he expatiates, and on which he rests his claim
to honour, are the second, and still more, the third —
years in which he had become supreme, in which
Athens, at one with him, had taken up the struggle
and failed. The stress of the accusation had been
CHAP. VI.] PUBLIC LIFE AND SPEECHES. 117
laid upon the final war (340-338 B.C.), and Demos-
thenes is content to accept the challenge. He points
triumphantly to those days when doom was gathering
for measures and actions conceived in the spirit of
the imperial city. The fourth period he passes over
in silence, but for the brief allusions in §§ 320-323.
Events of that period, subsequent to the decree of
Ctesiphon, were in truth outside the scope of an
oration in defence of that decree. Moreover it was
a time in which speech and action were alike fettered ;
and the cautious reserve of The Crozun in its references
to Alexander does but foreshadow the new epoch
which commenced after Chaeronea.
Demosthenes, in reviewing his own life, follows in
the main the divisions into periods marked out by
Aeschines. But the narrative with him is by no
means continuous. Period I. of Aeschines is covered
by §§ 18-52 of The Civivn; Period IL by §§ 60-109;
Period III. by §§ 160-187 and §§ 211-251. The
motive w^hich governed this arrangement will become
clearer by exhibiting the structure of the whole.
Roughly speaking, the design is to keep the technical
points of law in the background — they are inserted
between Periods II. and III. — to begin and end with
public policy, so adjusting the emphasis that a pre-
ponderating weight may fall upon Period III.
In form an apology the speech is in reality a
glowing eulogy, not so much on the orator himself as
on Athens that trusted him. Such a skeleton of the
speech as I can here add is no more than a guide to
studying the multiform and intricate structure of the
whole.
The Exordium (§§ 1-8) is distinguished by a solemn
invocation of the gods, an exceptional beginning in
Greek oratory. In §§ 9-53 Demosthenes refutes
certain charges, which he says are in fact alien to the
case. These chiefly concern the events of 346 B.C.,
Ii8 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. vi.
and attach themselves to Aeschines' first period. He
describes the state of Greece before the negotiations
of 346 B.C. (§§ 18-24); he tells of the delay in the
ratification of the treaty (§§ 25-30), of the ruin of
Phocis (§§ 31-41), and of the immediate effects upon
the Greek world (§§ 42-51).
His formal reply to the indictment is contained in
§§ 53-125. His answer to the first charge consists
in a review of his own policy, foreign (§§ 60-101) and
domestic (§§ 102-109), i^ ^he years of peace from
346—340 B.C. (Period H. of Aeschines). Among
the achievements of his foreign or Hellenic policy he
singles out the liberation of Eubcea, and the deliver-
ance of Byzantium and of the Chersonese. The one
measure of home policy which he records is the reform
of the trierarchy. Early in this division of the speech
he thrice raises a question which runs through the
very tissue of The Crozcm, a question which Aeschines
never fairly faces. I quote one of these passages :
" What course ought Athens to have adopted when
she beheld Philip intriguing for empire and do-
minion over Greece ? \Vhat language ought I f>/i. § 69).
The sum of twenty talents may seem but a small nucleus
for a war -fund, yet it may have been accepted as a
pledge of future bounties. If such were his projects,
secrecy was essential ; he must at all hazards disclaim
the gift. On this view he stands acquitted of per-
sonal cupidity ; and though his conduct will not bear
to be tried by a high standard, yet the morality of
the day would not have condemned it.
Demosthenes escaped from prison and went into
exile. " On the shores of Troezen and Aegina," says
Plutarch, " he might often be seen sitting, and gazing
with tearful eyes towards Attica." But in 323 rc.
Alexander died, and Greece made one more effort,
worthy of her best days, to shake off the yoke.
Under Leosthenes, a skilful general, the Lamian war
opened brilliantly. Demosthenes, now reconciled to
CHAP. VI.] PUBLIC LIFE AND SPEECHES. 127
Hypereides, joined the envoys to the Peloponnese,
and aided the movement with all his eloquence. A
motion for his recal was soon carried at Athens.
His return was a triumph. A galley was sent to
Aegina to fetch him ; from the Piraeus a procession,
headed by archons and priests, escorted him to
the city.
The joy was of short duration. The battle of
Crannon (322 B.C.) crushed the hopes of Greece.
The Athenians had to admit a Macedonian garrison,
to remodel their constitution, and to give up their
leading orators. Demades carried in the Assembly a
decree condemning Demosthenes and Hypereides to
death.
Demosthenes had already quitted Athens ; his pur-
suers found him seeking refuge in the temple of
Poseidon in Calauria. Archias, who had once been
an actor, was the agent hired by Antipater to hunt
down the fugitives. At first he tried with soft per-
suasions to tempt forth Demosthenes from his asylum.
Demosthenes, who was seated near the door, looked
up and said, " Archias, you never won me by your
acting, nor will you now win me by your promises."
Angry threats now took the place of promises.
" Now," said Demosthenes, " you speak like the
Macedonian oracle : before you were only acting.
Wait a moment till I AVTite a word to my friends at
home." He then went into the inner part of the
temple, took out a roll, and putting the pen to his
mouth bit it, as was his manner when writing. Soon
he felt the poison he had sucked beginning to work ;
and throwing back the covering he had wrapped
about his head, fixed his eyes on Archias, and said,
" The sooner now you play the part of Creon in
the tragedy and cast forth this body unburied, the
better. But I, gracious Poseidon, quit thy temple
while yet I livej as for Antipater and the Mace-
128 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. vr.
donians, they have not spared even thy sanctuary
from defilement." He tottered forward, and, as he
had just passed the altar, fell with a groan and yielded
up his life (Plutarch Dem. ch. 30).
Demosthenes died at the age of sixty-two (322 B.C.)
" It was on the sixteenth day," adds Plutarch, " of the
month Pyanepsion, the saddest day of the feast of the
Thesmophoria, which the women celebrate with fast-
ing in the temple of the goddess." Forty years later
the Athenians set up a bronze statue of the orator, and
decreed that the eldest of his family should have
public maintenance for ever in the Prytaneum.
CHAPTER VII.
HIS PRIVATE SPEECHES.
Aristotle notes among the differences between the
forensic and deUberative types of eloquence, that the
deUberative style gives less scope for chicanery, and
admits fewer digressions and personalities, less of in-
vective and emotional appeal. So, too, Dionysius
says that the audience of a law-court require gUtter
and entrancement, while for the Assembly there is
need of exposition and help. These distinctions
might be fully illustrated from Demosthenes. No-
where in the speeches he addressed to the Assembly
does he, when denouncing a corrupt system, even
mention an opponent by name. But his court
speeches descend to scurrilous personalities. Espe-
cially in public causes his invective is intemperate ;
political animosities, that had been suppressed in
serious debate, here find free expression. " I hate
these men," is the passionate avowal of Demosthenes
{E>nbass. § 223). Speeches such as those O/i the
Civivn and On the Embassy^ where there is a blending
of the deliberative and the judicial element, show the
most abrupt contrasts — grave statesmanlike counsel
alternating with low abuse. Demosthenes spoke, no
doubt, in bitter earnest ; yet we must not measure
his feelings by the violence of his language. Cari-
K
I30 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. vii.
cature was an understood part of judicial eloquence,
as it was of the old Attic comedy. To attack
a man's private life, his origin, his family, or his
friends, was an accepted form. If it were omitted,
the jury would probably feel themselves defrauded.
In private causes invective was kept within bounds,
but ample room was still left for falsehood and e.xag-
geration. Yet we have not any reason to think that
the scandals, which were welcomed as a seasoning to
discourse, appreciably affected the verdict.
But the Athenians were also connoisseurs in fine
language, and their artistic sense had to be satisfied.
It was urged against one of Demosthenes' clients
that he was an objectionable fellow, who walked fast
and talked loud. He pleads guilty, but offers an
apology ; " it is nature's doing," he says, " and it can-
not be undone ; if it could, there would be nothing to
distinguish between man and man " {Ai^ainst Pantcen.
§§ 52-56). If the jury were not disposed to be
lenient to clumsiness and ugliness, still less could
they tolerate ungraceful speech. Demosthenes saw
that these fastidious critics must be charmed in order
to be won. So he concedes much to them ; he goes
beyond his practice in the Assembly ; for though the
deliberative speeches, too, cost him minute artistic
toil, yet in them there is no phrase, no word, that is
not pertinent to the subject ; no ornament for its own
sake ; all is subordinated to a serious practical end.
But in the forensic speeches there are occasionally
lively digressions, racy fictions, and displays of power,
whose main object is to please.
The Athenian theory of citizenship required each
man to si)eak in his own cause. His public duties,
whether in the army, in the Assembly, or in the law-
courts, were exercised by himself, and not through
another. The custom had a remarkable eflect on
Greek forensic orator)', and made it widely different
CHAP, vii.] PRIVATE SPEECHES. 131
both from the Roman and from the English type.
The unlettered peasant or the busy tradesman, in
going to law, would originally apply to some more
learned friend, who would advise him and probably
give him the sketch of a speech. Gradually, as elo-
quence became an art, a class of professional speech-
writers grew up towards the end of the fifth century.
They were called " logographers," and in their hands
Attic oratory was moulded. They seldom appeared
in court ; when they did speak for a client, it was by
grace of the court they spoke, not as advocates proper,
but as friends of the litigant. The litigant himself was
bound first to say something on his own behalf He
might then, after a few w^ords, beg leave to call on
some more capable person to put his case ; he him-
self was too inexperienced, he had weak health or
some other defect. As a rule, however, the logo-
grapher's work was limited to giving legal advice and
to writing a speech for the client to deliver ; and he
was employed chiefly in civil cases. Part of his art
w^as to remain undetected, to assume the character
and catch the tone of each client in turn, to feign the
embarrassment of one who finds himself unexpectedly
in a law-court, to seem to be improvising as he goes
on. He must hide the compass of his own resources,
and not let the jury suspect the presence of a paid
expert. If a minute knowledge of law is shown, it
must appear to have been merely got up for the
occasion. Such a speech will be brief, for it has to
be learnt by heart by one who is not a trained
speaker ; its idiom will be that of daily life ; it will
be simple in structure and free from artifice. Its
persuasive force will be due to clear and vivid narra-
tive rather than to ingenious argument. The more
impetuous movements of oratory will be avoided, as
likely to put the jury on their guard and so destroy the
illusion. The feelings will be moved not so much
132 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. vii.
by express appeals as by an air of truthfulness and
candour.
This form of dramatised speech-writing was brought
to perfection by Lysias. But the legal fiction that
the si^eaker was his own advocate was daily becoming
more transparent. Isa^us at times threw off the dis-
guise and wTOte openly as a master. Demosthenes
proceeded farther in the direction of Isjeus, We
have already seen (p. 31) that the speeches he com-
posed for others to deliver in public causes are in
truth political orations, enforcing his own views and
expressed in his own language. He wTites without
fear and without reser\-e, the more so that he wTites
as an anonymous author. His tone is that of the
statesman, not of the logographer. How a client
managed to learn a speech so elaborate as, for instance,
the speech Against An'sfocrates, is a matter for wonder;
and we may suspect that there were large omissions
in delivery. But the greater number of the court
speeches, being of a purely private character, are
brief and comparatively straight for\vard. It is true
that here also he made little effort to sustain the
character of the speaker. These speeches, all but
two, are written for plaintiffs, not for defendants ; and
the militant energy of Demosthenes' genius inclined
him to put forth all his strength and skill in attack.
He comes into the combat as an athlete armed at all
points ; guileless simplicity is in him a forced attitude.
He knows the laws intimately and disengages their
principles ; he examines and discusses evidence in a
searching manner which makes it impossible to mis-
take him for the " plain man " ; he grapples with an
opponent in strenuous argument, he forestalls objec-
tions and leaves no escape. The sober colouring of
Lysias has been warmed into a more glowing tint ;
there is a quickened life, a more resonant tone, greater
variety and passion. The latest private speeches,
CHAr. VII.] PRIVATE SPEECHES. 133
in their phrase and in the structure of their periods,
approach nearly to the dehberative harangues.
In a few instances, however, Demosthenes is care-
ful to observe dramatic proprieties, and his skilful
portraiture then falls little, if at all, below that of
Lysias. Such is the speech Against Conon, where
the action is one for assault and battery, the plaintiff
Ariston being Demosthenes' client. It opens with a
vivid picture of camp life on the Attic frontier.
Ariston was there on garrison duty together with the
defendant's sons, who spent the afternoon in drinking
and the evening in playing drunken pranks. Ariston,
whose tent happened to be pitched near theirs, was
the chief sufferer. He and his messmates at last laid
a complaint before the general. A severe reprimand
was administered, but on that very evening the young
men made an outrageous attack on Ariston, almost
ending in bloodshed. The quarrel bred in the camp
was carried to the city. One evening as Ariston was
taking his usual walk in the Agora with a friend,
Ctesias, son of Conon, caught sight of him, raised a
shout, and instantly disappeared into a house where
a drinking -party was going on. The guests issued
forth, and presently encountered Ariston in the street;
and, while some of them held the friend, Conon and
his son tripped up Ariston, plunged him in the mud,
jumped on him and kicked him so violently that his
lip was cut through and his eyes closed up. Conon
then crowed over his prostrate foe, in imitation of a
victorious fighting cock, while his comrades bade him
do the flapping of the wings with his elbows. The
bruises brought on a long illness in which Ariston
was at the point of death. The defendant tried to
laugh it off as a practical joke. " Ah," says Ariston
to the jury, " but you would have found it no laughing
matter if you had been present when I was dragged,
and stripped, and kicked, and after leaving my house
134 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. vii.
quite well was borne home on a litter ; when my
mother rushed out, and the women cried and wailed
as if there had been a death in the house, so that
some of the neighbours sent to ask what had hap-
pened " (§ 20). Conon himself in his younger days
had belonged to a kind of " Mohawk Club," called
after a Thracian tribe, "The Triballi." His sons
were members of a similar society, which is graphic-
ally described (§§ 34, 35).
The whole story is told and commented on with
exquisite grace. The tone is that of a middle-aged
man of i:)recise habits, who knows little law, and
would have known less had it not been for the
defendant ; anxious to seem calm, but not quite able
to smother his indignation ; a little wanting in a sense
of the ludicrous, and so keenly alive to his own re-
spectability — which is a recurring topic — that he
must ai)ologise for being aware that such rowdyism
even exists — an admirable butt, we may imagine, for
members of a Mohawk Club out on a campaign.
A\'c now pass to another speech (In reply to Cal-
licles), less perfect in form than the last, but almost
as dramatic, and marked by touches of naive humour.
The opening words are these : " Well, Athenians,
there really is no greater nuisance than a bad and
grasi)ing neighbour, as I myself have had the luck to
find out." This somewhat j^ettish, impatient tone,
quite in keeping with the young defendant's character,
is sustained throughout. The plaintiff, Callicles, and
the defendant held adjacent mountain farms, sepa-
rated only by the road. The present action is one for
damages, caused by the stopjiage of a watercourse,
which used, Callicles alleges, to pass through the
defendant's land. The defendant's fiither, however,
had built a wall and diverted the water into the road;
hence there was an overflow, and Callicles' farm was
flooded. On the other hand, the defendant contends
CHAP. VII.] PRIVATE SPEECHES. 135
that tlie wall was built more than fifteen years before
his father died, and no objection had been raised at
the time, " though, of course, there was often rain
then as well as now " (§ 4) ; that the enclosed land
was not part of a watercourse, but private property
long ago planted with vines and figs and other trees,
and containing a family burial-ground. " Who would
plant trees in a watercourse ? Or who would bury his
ancestors there?" (§13). The stream, too, did not come
down from a neighbour's land and pass out into the
next neighbour's land ; it flowed down the road both
above and below him. Why then divert it ? Who ever
heard of a watercourse by the side of a road ? The
public road is its proper channel. (This quite seri-
ously, for a road in Greece was and is often the bed of
a torrent.) Nor would his next neighbour below thank
him if he were to turn the water into his land. " If
then," he says, " I may not drain it off either into the
road or into private ground, in heaven's name, gentle-
men, tell me what am I to do ? Callicles, surely, won't
compel me to drink it up" (§ 13). If all who suffered
from excess of water in those parts were to go to law
with him about it, his fortune would need to be many
times greater than it was in order to stand it. But,
as the plaintiff's mother had let out, there was little
harm done, though there was much lamentation ; a
few bushels of barley had got wet, and an oil-jar had
been upset without being damaged. The truth was,
Callicles coveted his neighbour's farm ; that was the
secret of his litigation. " In going to law with me,"
says the defendant, " I hold him to be a thoroughly
abandoned and benighted man" (§ 13).
Among the most powerful and persuasive of the
private speeches is the speech For Phormio, who was
at this time head of the chief banking house at Athens,
He had been first foreman to Pasion, the founder of
the firm, and afterwards his successor. ApoUodorus,
136 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. vii.
Pasion's elder son, who distinguished himself by a
spendthrift and ambitious generosity, and was now
in a financially desperate case, put in a claim against
Phormio for a certain sum of banking stock supposed
to be due to him under Pasion's will. On Phormio's
behalf it is pleaded that several years ago a com-
promise had t een made extinguishing all claims, and
that this compromise was a legal bar to the present
action. Further, ApoUodorus' whole story is shoAvn to
be without foundation. The jury were so completely
convinced of the justice of Phormio's case, that they
would hardly give ApoUodorus a hearing in reply.
Apart from the great merit of the speech, it ought
to be read for a certain painful interest it has acquired.
U'aken in conjunction with the first speech Against
StepJianus, it is supposed to reflect gravely on the
character of Demosthenes. The latter speech, whose
genuineness could hardly have been doubted but for
the desire to vindicate the orator's morality, is written
for ApoUodorus in a suit he brought against Stephanus
for giving false witness in the Phormio case. Thus
Demosthenes, as is thought, acted dishonourably in
pleading on opposite sides.
The charge, however, against him appears in some-
what different shapes. Aeschines accuses him of
having communicated beforehand to ApoUodorus a
speech he had been paid to write for Phormio (Aesch.
£»il}. § 165). Plutarch merely says that he wrote
speeches for and against ApoUodorus in his quarrel
with Phormio ; that it was like selling two swords
from the same workshop to be used on opposite sides
{Life pf Dem. ch. 15). Aeschines no doubt, as usual,
sets his rival's conduct in the darkest light, while
Plutarch's version of the stor}' is borne out by the
speeches as they have come down to us, and has a
better claim to accci)tance. The morality of Demos-
thenes' conduct may in this case perhaps be dubious.
CHAP. VII.] PRIVATE SPEECHES. 137
but it is not so palpably bad as has been supposed.
The " logographer " must be kept distinct from the
modern advocate. He entered into a far less binding
relation with his client ; he did not appear for him
and in his stead ; he held no responsible office and
took no public part in the proceedings. Nor did he
belong to any corporate society, among whom there
existed a clear code of etiquette and of honour. He
was an anonymous wTiter, making his livelihood by
his pen. Moreover, the actual charge against Demos-
thenes is not that he wrote speeches on opposite sides
in the same suit, but in successive suits, one of which
arose out of the other. Even an English barrister,
under such circumstances, could not well refuse to
take a brief against a former client, supposing that the
client had not retained his services in the second suit.
Yet the outside public would probably be a little
shocked at "lawyers' morality." The case was an
exceptional one at Athens, as it is now, and attracted
the more attention since it involved a well-known
name. But there was an uglier side to the matter.
In the second trial Demosthenes maintains that
Stephanus, who was called as a witness for his client
in the first trial, was guilty of perjury. Also, he
attacks his late client's character with a coarse violence
and a wantonness which goes beyond the conventional
invective of the law-courts. He writes for Apollodorus
as Apollodorus would have written himself, not sparing
even the speaker's own mother. And it is precisely
here rather than in the change of sides that we feel
the real discredit lies.
It has been ingeniously suggested that political
causes brought about a union at this time between
Demosthenes and Apollodorus. The date of the first
speech Against Stephanus is the end of 349 B.C. or
the beginning of 348 b.c. It was early in 348 B.C.
that Apollodorus, at a critical moment, aided Demos-
138 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. vii.
thenes' policy by making a tentative proposal, at the
risk of his civic rights, in relation to the Festival Fund
(P- 75)- Ori such terms, perhaps, did Demosthenes
consent to support him in his lawsuit.
One argument of some weight may be alleged against
the genuineness of the first speech A}:;ainst Stcp/ianus.
Seven speeches delivered by Apollodorus have come
down to us among the works of Demosthenes. Two
of these (Aga/f/sf Callippus and Against Nicostratus)
would seem, on internal chronological evidence, to
have been spoken before Demosthenes' suit with his
guardians had even begun, and one of them (Against
Timot/ieus) before it was concluded. This, then,
would be a decisive reason for rejecting them. A
certain presumption, it may be said, is thus raised
against the remaining speeches for Apollodorus ; the
author of the three speeches just mentioned was prob-
ably the author of all. And, it is urged, we can further
account for the reception of these spurious speeches
among the collected works of Demosthenes ; for this
collection (made at Alexandria by Callimachus) was
based on no critical recension ; it embraced such
anonymous wTitings as had any obvious bearing upon
Demosthenic speeches, and was not intended to pre-
judge the question of genuineness. Thus, it is said,
the speeches for Apollodorus came to be inserted as
the companion speeches to that written For Phormio
against Apollodorus.
But another view is also possible. We may assume
the first speech Against Stephanus to be the work of
Demosthenes — a speech with marked Demosthenic
qualities, and about which no doubt was raised in
antiquity — and yet not accept all or any of the other
speeches written for Apollodorus ; for, reasoning as
before, we may urge that the admission of a single
genuine speech would naturally bring with it into the
collection other doubtful or spurious speeches written
CHAP, vii.] PRIVATE SPEECHES. 139
in the same client's behalf. And in fact such would
seem to have been the view of those ancient critics
who rejected some, but not all, of the speeches for
Apollodorus.
Much of the literary criticism which in recent times
has undertaken to discriminate between genuine and
spurious works of Demosthenes rests on no solid basis.
The evidence of style alone is most uncertain, and
authorities here differ as much as in the detection of
Homeric interpolations. We may grant in certain
speeches that there are rhythmical irregularities, and
a want of finish in the phrase, without on that account
rejecting the speeches themselves. Demosthenes did
not always put forth his whole strength in unimpor-
tant court speeches, or add the last touch to what he
^^TOle. The very carelessness which is thought suspi-
cious may sometimes be dramatically appropriate to
the speaker. The safest course for moderns is not
to reject, on purely stylistic grounds, such speeches as
were pronounced genuine by Dionysius, whose delicate
perception of Greek idiom we can never hope to equal.
Some few speeches, however, may on other grounds
be pronounced rhetorical forgeries, being vague and
declamatory, wanting in coherence and historical pre-
cision ; and in such cases modern historical criticism
has generally borne out the literary doubts of Dionysius.
But by far the greater number of the private speeches
which go by the name of Demosthenes are written, if
not by him, by some of his contemporaries,^ and are
authentic records of the period to which they profess
to belong. Their actual authorship matters but little.
Their chief value lies in this — that they contain de-
^ The speeches written by a logographer seem to have become
the property of the cHent for whom they were written ; and such
floating compositions were easily attached to famous names.
This is one reason why the court speeches are more doubtful than
the rest.
140 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. vii.
tailed information on Attic law, and reflect every phase
of social and mercantile life in the fourth century b.c
It would be interesting to know whether Demos-
thenes pursued the work of a logographer throughout
his life. It is clear that during the years of his
political leadership, and when his influence was at its
height, he took very little part in private lawsuits.
The latest of his undoubtedly genuine private speeches
{Against Pantcenctus) falls between the speech On the
Peace (346 B.C.) and the Second Philippic (344 B.C.)
But if the speeches Against Phcenippus, Against
Phormio, and Against Dionysodorus^ are also his, it
would seem that, after the accession of Alexander,
and the more definite triumph of Macedon, he took
refuge from an enforced political inaction in the
employment of his younger days. But the point is
one which must remain uncertain unless these ve.xed
questions of authorship can be finally solved
^y
i
CHAPTER VIII.
DEMOSTHENES AS A STATESMAN AND AN ORATOR.
We may now form some general estimate of Demos-
thenes. Unlike Cicero, he is known to us only as a
citizen, not as a man. His speeches, great in their
self-forgetfulness, reveal next to nothing of his private
life, and the few letters which have come down under
his name, even if we admit them to be genuine — a
most doubtful supposition — are, with one exception,
public documents addressed to the Council and people
of Athens. Even his private correspondence, if it
existed, would not, we may be sure, be marked by the
candid confidences and genial humour which in Cicero
are so fascinating. In that grave and unbending
nature, to which politics were an absorbing passion,
there was little room for domestic affections or for the
play of the social instincts. Yet it is a mistake to
think of him solely as the author of Philippics, or to
allow the main episode to obscure the life. It was
not the struggle with Macedon that gave a bent and a
purpose to his thoughts. From the outset it was his
aim to revive public spirit in Athens, to purify the
home administration, to bring vigour into the conduct
of foreign affairs. Before Philip was seen to be a
dangerous antagonist the organic lines of his policy
had been traced.
142 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. viii.
But while his career is stamped by an essential
unity, a gradual enlargement of view is visible. From
the first we find Athens standing out before him as a
living personality with a well-defined character (to tt}?
TToAews ?jBos, Lepf. § 13, Timocr. § 171). Certain
features disengaged themselves at once, generous qualities
such as were the birthright of a noble well-bred people,
disinterestedness, magnanimity, pity for the oppressed,
a delicate and scrupulous honour. He had studied
the history of Athens and gathered from it all that
was noblest in her past, uniting the elements in an
ideal portrait which became to him henceforth a
power that moved his imagination and controlled his
reason. This portrait of national character he set
( before his countrymen as an object of loving imitation.
Athens must identify herself with her best moments,
and be made to feel that she was never more
truly herself than when at her grandest. The dor-
mant feelings of patriotism and self-respect must be
elicited. Instinct must be developed into virtue.
Demosthenes was always free from the narrow pre-
judices of an Athenian. In his later life he was
J accused by Aeschines of Boeotian sympathies ; and in
his first popular harangue {On the Synunories, ^ Z2))
I his tone towards Thebes, then an object of bitter
hatred, is strikingly temperate. In the same speech
(§ 6) he declares the exceptional obligations of Athens
towards Greece at large, and marks the limit thus
imposed upon her private vengeance. The part of
/^ Athens in the speech For ihc Mc<:;alopoUtans (p. 40)
is to deliver the oppressed (§§ 14, 15): "Circum-
stances may change with changing ambitions, but
the policy of Athens is the same." But generous
instincts are not as yet perfectly harmonised with
other motives. The principle most insisted on in
/ the speech For the JMei^alopoHtans is that of the
balance of power (cf. Aristocr. §§ 102 {{.), and in
CHAP. VIII.] STATESMAN AND ORATOR. 143
the speech For the Rhodians the claims of democracy
against oligarchy are the decisive consideration.
1' In the early Philippics and OlyiitJiiacs the sense of
' Athenian interests is still dominant. But after the
taking of Olynthus the Hellenic character of the
struggle became daily more manifest, and Demos-
thenes' view was enlarged with the growing dimensions
of the danger. The Athenian was sunk in the Hellene.
Starting from appeals to self-interest, he passed into
another region ; insensibly he led up from the men-
aced independence of Athens to the vision of a death-
struggle between barbarism and Hellenism, between
lawless aggression on the one side and dignified
freedom on the other. Athens was bound to take
up the championship of Greece, apart from her own
safety or selfish advantage. The tone of The Croioti
is not adopted by Demosthenes to vindicate a policy
which had failed. It is anticipated by a statement
scarcely less empathic in the speech On the Cher-
sonese (§ 49 ; quoted p. 104) : it is the settled convic-
tion of the Third Philippic. We have seen how in
the next two years he was able to elevate his hearers,
both in Athens and outside it, to a similar height
of national devotion. It was his part to overcome
( petty jealousies, to blot out old scores by acts of con-
\ ciliation towards Euboeans, Thebans, and Byzantines ;
' to deprecate the insistance on strict rights. In each
state he appealed to what there was of best in the
local traditions. " He reminded," says Plutarch, " the
Thebans of Epaminondas, and the Athenians of
Pericles." The triumph of this high-minded policy
was attained in the famous embassy to Thebes and
the union of the cities before Chaeronea. The gener-
ous spirit of Demosthenes was censured by his rival.
It was alien to the practical politicians of the day,
and it hardly finds expression elsewhere within the
range of Attic oratory.
144 DEMOSTHENES. [ciiap. viii.
Thus had his character developed as doom closed
round the city. He had learned to look on the
/ cause of Athens as one with the cause of Greece.
His eari^ and instinctive admiration of all that was
generous in conduct meets us again in T/ie Crown, in
a reasoned defence of Athenian magnanimity (§§ 95-
100, § 238 fT.) The first of these passages is pre-
liaced with the words : " Communities, like individuals,
^ should ever strive to mould their future by the noblest
chapters of their past." These "noblest chapters,"
of Athenian history, as he interpreted them, were
moments inspired by a high enthusiasm that disre-
garded vulgar expediency. The level of Panhel-
lenic patriotism attained by Demosthenes was higher
than was reached by Pericles, and was equalled, if
at all, by Epaminondas alone.
<( On the study of Thucydides Demosthenes had
been nourished. Apart from such legendary anec-
dotes as that he copied out Thucydides eight times,
there is ample evidence, in spite of few direct imita-
tions or verbal reminiscences, that he was penetrated
by the thought of the historain. He had learnt from
i' Thucydides that events are the outcome of character;
that they are not startling or dramatic incidents, the
work of an arbitrary will, but phenomena whose reason
lies deep in the moral disposition of nations and indi-
viduals, and the law of whose succession can be dis-
covered. Such a view, akin to that which Sophocles
embodied in poetry, was applied in his own field by
Thucydides with such a penetrating analysis of mo-
tives as to make of history a new science. To observe
I character, and especially the broad lines of national
I character, under such a master, became a great train-
ing in politics. A searching inquiry into real causes
is as distinctive of the orator as it is of the historian.
] )emoslhenes will not be jnit off with illusions or
superficial explanations, he nuist trace back external
cilAr. viii.] STATESMAN AND ORATOR. 145
events to their hidden source. Character with him is
all in all. His first political speech exhibits this
thought already formed {On the Synnnorics, §§ 14, 15,
p. 37) ; every Philippic is instinct with it. " Is Philip
dead % No, he is only ill. Dead or ill, what differ-
ence to you? If anything befalls him, you will
instantly raise up another Philip for yourselves"
{Phil. i. § 17). Again, it was the speeches of Thucy-
dides that first taught him what a luminous force is
padded to debate by attaching facts to their principles,
and by combining particular with general ideas ; al-
though, in the application of the discovery, he followed
his own method. From Thucydides he learnt that
X mastery is assured to calm intelligence backed up by
sustained and vigorous effort ; and that speech is of
1 value only so far as it contains in it the promise and
potency of action. Before undertaking to interpret
Athenian history, and to read Athenian character,
he had trained his political reason in the most fortify-
ing study that ancient literature afforded.
The influence, however, upon him of his elder con-
temporaries was not insignificant. Subsequent tradi-
tion loved to tell how he had been the pupil of Plato
and of Isocrates, a tradition w^iolly unsupported by
evidence, and an instance of the perpetual attempt to
affiliate great men together as master and pupil. At
first sight we may see nothing but contrast between
the strenuous and robust eloquence of Demosthenes,
wath its face set towards action — an eloquence in which
reason was vivified by contact with passion — and the
dreamy splendour of Isocrates, who wrote from his
study, spending ten years in publishing a pamphlet,
while events had outstripped his pen ; who w^as neither
philosopher nor politician, but had an unsteady foot
in either world. Or again, Plato drawing up the con-
stitution of his ideal city, what had he to do with
Demosthenes, whose thoughts were centred in Athens,
L
146 DEMOSTHENES. [cii.u>. viii.
who, in no wise blind to her faults and failures, found
in her a city with a great part to play, and with noble
traditions to be reanimated?
Yet these men, differing widely in opinions, held
f certain principles in common. Demosthenes owed to
Plato and to Isocrates the idea that ethical motives
ought to be introduced into the life of states, that
political morality has a serious meaning. Isocrates
sought to raise the dignity of eloquence by applying
it, not to trivial themes, but to serious political discus-
sion, and by giving it a moral content The rules of
Iprivate conduct were, he held, applicable to states ;
justice was for the interest of nations as well as of
individuals, and was even more binding on nations "by
reason of their immortality" {Peace, § 120). Shortly
before the birth of Demosthenes he began to set forth
these views ; but his passionless homilies fell on inat-
tentive ears. It needed a stronger thought and a
living voice to convert such abstract principles into
truths which could shape action. Demosthenes was
able, as Isocrates was not, to draw on the ideal world
without ever losing sight of the real. The fusion he
effected between morals and politics admits of many
illustrations ; a few instances may here be given.
In the political organism he saw a moral institution.
i\ To him, as to Plato, democracy reflected character,
and was among the influences by which character was
moulded. But they estimated its worth very differ-
ently. To Plato it denoted, first, a form of govern-
ment under which each man did what was right in his
own eyes ; next, a state of the soul in which there was
no eciuilibrium of forces, no sovereign and controlling
power. Now, Demosthenes is aware that democracy
is in a peculiar sense liable to fall under the sway of
passion, and he therefore insists on individual virtue
as a condition of its existence. Plato thought virtue
r and democracy an impossible union, for democracy
CHAP. VIII.] STATESMAN AND ORATOR. 147
implied lawlessness. Demosthenes, on the other
r^ hand, held democracy to be the reign of law as op-
posed to oligarchy, the reign of caprice {Ti>nocr, §§ 75,
76). The idea is not confined to hirn ; but while it
occurs elsewhere as a rhetorical commonplace, it is to
him a vital and fruitful conception.
As the state was in his view a moral institution, so
the statesman had corresponding functions. This was
a doctrine which Plato had made familiar ; but Plato,
observing the poor success of statesmen in regenerat-
ing mankind, despaired of the commonwealths of
earth, and condemned as failures Pericles and all others
who had been " bad tamers of wild animals." Demos-
thenes, too, demands from the statesmen other quali-
Jties besides the intellectual; not only to "see events
in their beginnings, to forecast the future, to forewarn
others," but also "to limit to the utmost the range of
those vices which are inherent in the very idea of a
J state, . . . and to promote harmony, kindly feeling,
and the impulse towards duty" [Croivn, § 246). The
statesman is no mere administrator ; nor, on the other
hand, is he a sage or a moraUst, though it is his duty
to guide and to enlighten the public conscience. Two
conditions are here indispensable. First, he must
J( s how a f earless^since^ity. The duty of speaking out
the truth at all costs, of not ignoring facts, is laid
down in the earliest of his political speeches proper.
He conformed faithfully to his own ideal. Plutarch
{Life of D €711. ch. xiv.) describes his courage in utter-
ing rude truths and withstanding the passions of the
people in language which recalls Thucydides' descrip-
tion of Pericles (ii. 65, 8). Like Pericles, he was
able, as we have seen, to abate an extravagant con-
fidence no less than to brighten moments of despair.
Constitutionally timid as he probably was, his whole
life eloquently refutes Aeschines' charge of cowardice
before a crowd. As years go on the figure of the
X
148 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. viii.
statesman stands out in his speeches in bold rehef
against that of the sycophant. The two portraits are
first drawn in The Chersonese (§§ 68-72), and are com-
pleted in The Croum (§§ 189 i\.)
The second requisite in a statesman is a profound
sense of responsibility'. Demosihenes frequently
applies the words x—cvOwos and evUvvai, which denote
the official responsibility of the magistrate, to the
moral responsibility of the statesman. Good inten-
tions, "of no mean force," as Burke .says, "in the
government of mankind," are not enough. A man
must form a proper estimate of his own powers. He
is not compelled to conduct public business, but
having once undertaken it, he may not set up honest
incapacity as a plea f(jr failure. Such a plea would
be small consolation to ruined allies, and to their
wives and children. This is forcibly urged in the
speech On the Embassy m 99 ff.) The Croum con-
tains the matured expression of the orator's opinion
on this head. The responsibility he there accepts is
greater even than before : he consents to be judged in
the light of the event. Now, however, schooled in
hard experience, he recognises more fully the limits
of human control over circumstance. If the states-
man fails, it must not be through want of foresight,
of moral purpose, or of sustained energy.
The Stoic Panaetius, we are told by Plutarch,
declared that " the principle which ajipears in the
greater number of the speeches of Demosthenes is,
that the honourable (to? ko-Xov) alone is to be chosen
for its own sake. This is the principle of The Cnnvn,
of the speeches Aa^ainst Aris/ocrahs, Ai^ainst Ltf tines,
and of the Philippics. In all of these he seeks to lead
his countr)'men not towards that which is most plea-
sant, most easy, or most profitable ; he often calls on
them to set safely and wellbeing below honour and
duty" i^Life of JDiiii., ch. xiii.) Demosthenes, as we
CHAP. VIII.] STATESMAN AND ORATOR, 149
have seen, maintained that this was the embodiment
of the spirit of Athens {e.g. Lept. § 13), and Philip's
recognition of the fact was the noblest homage that
he could have paid their city {Phil. ii. § 10). The
moral elevation of view which distinguishes him is
not found in an equal degree in any other orator, so
far as I know, except in Burke. It establishes a pro-
found inner resemblance between the two men, and
produces a unity of thought underlying obvious
differences of style. The large and enhghtened
wisdom impressed upon their works, running counter
to the prejudices of the day, is in a great measure
due to this cause. The sentence that sums up the
speech on Conciliation with America is conceived in
the very spirit of Demosthenes : — " Magnanimity in
politics is not seldom the truest wisdom ; and great
X empires and little minds go ill together." For them
no one department of politics stood isolated; each
derived its meaning from its relation to the whole.
A pervading moral purpose bound together even their
occasional utterances. Home and foreign policy were
r^ to Demosthenes inseparable. He protests against
repairing failure abroad by measures which left un-
touched the heart of the evil at home. His method
was remedial, not palliative. He took in the social,
economic, and military bearings of a measure in one
view. His trierarchic law (340 B.C.), whose various
aspects he himself indicates {Crown, §§ 102-109),
achieved at once a reform of the navy, corrected a
social grievance, and equalised the burdens upon
capital. His scheme for applying the Theoricon to
war purposes, carried after a struggle of eleven years
(339 B.C.), was another measure of comprehensive
scope (cf. pp. 16 ff., 1 1 2). In reviewing his early court
speeches {Against Androtion, Against Timocrates),
we have seen how out of technicalities of law and
details of finance he rises to efforts for purifying
I50 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. viii.
the administration and reducing corrupt influence.
Economic reform was to him, as to Burke, a matter
of constitutional and social import (Burke's speech
on Economic Reform). One case, primarily economic,
is enlarged by him into a matter which touched the
very foundations of public morality and expediency.
The discussion, raised on the law of Leptines, was
whether certain hereditary exemptions granted by the
people for distinguished public services should be
revoked (p. 33). One part of the argument of
Demosthenes is recapitulated in these sentences from
the Letter to a Noble Lord on the subject of Burke's
pension. " I ever held a scant and penurious justice
to partake of the nature of a \sTong. I held it to
be in its consequences the worst economy in the
world. In saving money I soon can count up all
the good I do ; but when by a cold penur)- I blast
the abilities of a nation, and stunt the growth of its
active energies, the ill I may do is beyond all calcula-
tion." Another point still more insisted on by
Demosthenes is thus expressed by Burke in an earlier
speech in which he is himself advocating retrench-
ment : "A critical retrospective examination of the
pension list, upon the principle of merit, can never
serve for my basis " {On Economic Reform). The
views of the two orators on ever)' question of public
policy will be found to depend on some principle,
and that principle has its root in morals.
The instability of unrighteous power is thus
described by Demosthenes : — " It is not possible,
Athenians, it is not possible to found a solid ])ower
upon op]ircssion, perjury, and fiilsehood. Such an
empire may endure for the moment or for the hour ;
nay, it may perhaj:)s blossom with the rich promise of
hope ; but time finds it out, and it drops away of
itself. As in a house, a vessel, or any similar
structure, the foundations should above all be strong.
/
^
CHAP. VIII.] STATESMAN AND ORATOR. 151
SO should the principles and groundwork of conduct
rest upon truth and justice" {Olynth. ii. § 10). No
bolder assertion of a moral title as the only endur-
ing claim to empire is to be found among Burke's
denunciations of our rule in India. Similarly in the
Leptines (§ 136) the broad command is laid down :
" Beware not to exhibit as a nation conduct which
you would shrink from as individuals." But Demos-
thenes in another passage of the same speech admits
that the analogy between the state and the individual
is incomplete. The state, for instance, cannot always
form friendships on precisely the same grounds as an
individual (§ 50). Like Aristotle, he holds that the
state may and ought to employ a bad man if he
is useful.
He also sees that there are certain limits which
determine the application of moral maxims to inter-
national relations. Some reciprocity of ideas is
necessary, otherwise the nobler morality may lead to
extermination. The rule of force, he points out in the
speech For the RJiodians (§§ 29, 30, p. 42), is the exist-
ing basis of international law; and Athens cannot take
up an isolated and unaccepted standard of morality in
the face of unscrupulous enemies. This would be
"not justice, but cowardice." Nowhere, however,
does he lay down precise rules for the conduct of a
state in cases where justice and self-interest are in
apparent conflict ; in general he assumes their identity.
Yet he recognises that there may be a duty higher
than even that of self-preservation ; he holds it to be
the proud distinction of Athens that there were
moments in her history when, for the sake of Greece
and at the imperious call — the dvayKt] — of honour,
existence itself was staked. He rebels against the
fallacious verdict of outward events. When in T/ie
C?vwn he asserts his calm conviction that defeat in a
cause so noble was better than victory otherwise
152 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. viii.
attained, the true discipleship of Plato is revealed.
The language is the echo of the Gorgias and the
Republic. It may seem near to Stoicism, but the
temperate allowance made for human weakness has
in it a tenderness that is not stoical
Demosthenes was naturally averse to a metaphysical
' treatment of politics. There is nothing in him of
open revolt against the political philosophy of Plato,
as there is in Burke against that of Rousseau. Rarely
does he delay, as he does for a moment in the Leptines
(§ iio), to protest against theorising on a constitu-
tional question. Yet his cast of mind was as pro-
foundly opposed as that of Burke to all deductive
methods, metaphysical or geometric. Burke constantly
maintains that political reason computes not by
mathematical but on moral principles. To the Duke
of Bedford, who took on himself to appraise Burke's
political services, and his claim to a pension, he
writes thus : " I have no doubt of his Grace's readi-
ness, in all the calculations of vulgar arithmetic ; but
I shrewdly suspect that he is little studied in the
theory of moral proportions, and has never learned
y the rule of three in the arithmetic of policy and
state." We are reminded of Demosthenes' reply to
Aeschines, who would estimate his rival's worth in
the spirit of a vulgar bookkeeper. The illustration
employed by Aeschines seemed to imply that the ser-
vices of Demosthenes might be totted up, and his
failures set off against them in the ledger, item against
item, no regard being had to the quality of the facts
compared or the moral value of the results. The
reply of Demosthenes amounts to this, that jiolitical
calculations cannot be reduced to simple addition.
"That Aeschines, however, is not warranted in re-
quiring you to alter your estimate, I shall easily show,
not by casting up figures — political arithmetic is
of a different order — but by a brief enumeration of
CHAP. VIII.] STATESMAN AND ORATOR. 153
events, while I call on you my hearers at once to
audit the account and to attest the facts." Then, after
a summary of events, he proceeds : "A striking re-
semblance, is there not, between the arithmetic of
figures and of facts?" {Crown, §§ 227-231). This
may be called Demosthenes' protest against the mathe-
^ matical method. Another passage in the same speech
is a virtual protest against it priori principles of any
kind being applied to politics. Aeschines had enu-
merated the qualifications of a statesman, and trying
Demosthenes by this standard had found him wanting.
L Demosthenes indignantly refuses to be tried by the
arbitrary ideal of an opponent. "You draw youlT"
ideal," he says, " of the patriotic statesman, just as if
^ you had given a statue to be made by contract, and it
was then delivered to you without the points specified
in the contract. Or as if statesmen were known by
definitions, not by acts and measures " ( Cro2v?z,
§ 122).
The method pursued by Demosthenes as by.^giu^e
was the historical method. Montesquieu, as its
modern founder, won a warm, perhaps an exagger-
ated, admiration from Burke ; Thucydides, the philo-
sophic historian of antiquity, moulded the mind of
Demosthenes. The latter is no doubt guilty of several
historical inaccuracies, yet in spite of these he shows
a more minute knowledge of history than any other
ancient orator, and an infinitely deeper insight into its
meaning. Compared to the brilliant and ill-read
Aeschines, he may be called a genuine historical
student. With this ampler knowledge goes the power
^ of summoning up telling illustrations, which are with
him among the most powerful instruments of proof.
The examples he takes are often from well-known or
recent events, and depend for their force chiefly on
the setting (see the Third Philippic). At times he
X recalls some slighted chapter of history, and with a few
X
154 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. viil.
bold strokes lights up the page. " The time of those
events has indeed gone by, but the time for reading
the lessons of the past is ever present to the wise "
(Crcncn, § 48). Whatever be the allusion, it is free
from antiquarian pedantry and has a direct bearing
upon the subject in hand. He does not, like Aeschines,
support an argument by a reference to a mythical or
V semi-mythical past. He is always practical and pre-
cise, with a strong grasp of the actual. The mastery
of fiicts and precedents which he and Burjce display,
may have been due in no slight degree to the legal as
well as the historical training of the two orators.
But here comes the notable point, that which dis-
tinguishes these two from all other orators and states-
men — the close alliance between facts and principles.
Not that their method of bringing out principles is
^ the same. Burke often expounds them in the manner
of a philosopher — the secret of many of his failures in
Parliament In Demosthenes the principle gradually
(k emerges from the facts. It is not supplied as a thing
ready made. The orator stimulates and provokes
his hearers to reflection ; they and he must reason
together till the truth seems to spring from the contact
of their minds. As the facts are presented first on
one side then on another, the illuminating principle
breaks in. It may be stated briefly and even cursorily,
but this it is which has vivified the whole. Among
the causes which give to the eloquence of Demos-
thenes and Burke an enduring value beyond any other
clocjuence, ancient or modern, none is to be ranked
above this, that a close grappling with detail is found
combined with large generalisations from experience
and the broad assertion of moral truths.
Even the personal element in these orators is largely
redeemed by being attached to principles. Self-praise
rarely in Burke, never, I think, in Demosthenes, be-
comes vainglorious. In IVie Cro'wn it is elevated
t.
CHAr. VIII.] STATESMAN AND ORATOR. 155
into something resembling a noble profession of faith.
The lofty self-assertion of the passage already quoted
(p. 106) from the speech On the Chersonese (see
especially the later sections), deserves to be placed
beside Burke's declaration : " I know the map of
England as well as the noble lord or as any other
person ; and I know that the way I take is not the
way to preferment." Or again, the saying attributed
to Demosthenes, when he was called on to undertake
an unjust prosecution : " Your counsellor I will always
be, even if you wish it not ; a sycophant you shall
never find me, even if you wish it " (Plutarch, Deni.
ch. xiv.) — this surpasses the utterance of Burke when
elected member for Bristol : " Your faithful friend,
your devoted servant, I shall be to the end of my life ;
a flatterer you do not wish for."
The invective both of Burke and of Demosthenes
X. is furious and unmeasured. But Demosthenes has
I this that is peculiar to him : his deliberative eloquence
' is free from personal attacks. Intent on great poli-
tical issues, he never once even names an opponent
before the Assembly — at least, in any speech un-
doubtedly genuine.^ In the law]-courts, and more
especially in criminal cases, there was a tradition of
invective (p. 130). At times, however, an intensity
of hatred finds the stereotyped phrases of abuse in-
adequate, and vents itself in those passages which so
greatly disfigure the speeches of Demosthenes and
Aeschines On the Embassy, and the speech on The
Croiun. But while the speech of Aeschines On the
Embassy never rises above a mean and personal dis-
cussion, that of Demosthenes deals also with great
questions, such as the responsibility of a statesman.
The contrast is still greater between the speech Against
Ctesiphon and the speech On the Crown. What is
1 This is one among many arguments against the genuineness
of the Fourth Philippic in its present form.
156 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. viii.
true in this respect of Demosthenes is, though less
perfectly, true also of Burke. Neither of them lingers
long in the region of the personal. The air is soon
cleared, and we are again upon the heights.
, An apparent want of plan is the most salient
' characteristic of structure in almost all the speeches
of Demosthenes, if we except the private orations.
Modem oratory seems to demand a business-like
perspicuity of arrangement Such, too, was the
practice of Aeschines. But Demosthenes is studi-
ously irregular. He transgresses all the ancient rules
of technical rhetoric He seldom makes any formal
partition into heads. Narrative, refutation, and proof,
are blended or displaced according to the requirements
of the case. The exordium alone stands clear and
sharp ; the epilogue is not always strictly defined
Yet there is nothing accidental in the disposition.
Certain architectonic ideas of order preside over the
whole. There is in each case a given effect to pro-
duce, and all is subordinated to this object There is
therefore no uniform type of structure. The grander
the scale of the design, the less rigorous the laws
of outward symmetry. Thus the longest speeches of
Demosthenes, those On the Embassy and On the Crozcn,
are the most intricate in arrangement (pp. 96 tf., 116
ff.) Genuine works of art, they cannot be dissected
or analysed by the listener, who has to yield for the
time to the generous deception ; at the end an im-
pression of organic unity remains. From his master,
IsKus, Demosthenes learnt these structural effects.
But what tends to become artificiality in Isreus is art
in Demosthenes. Isa^us often betrays his purpose.
Demosthenes seems natural, simple, and unperplexed.
He starts a thought and sets it aside to return to it
later and expand it He announces a scheme which
he does not follow {e.g. Embassy, § 4). He antici-
pates, digresses, recapitulates, and appears to be im-
CHAP. VIII.] STATESMAN AND ORATOR. 157
pelled by a spirit of improvisation. Yet in every
speech there is some persistent central thought ; all
the details are grouped and massed round it ; with
each movement it rises into fresh prominence. It
was a remark of Pitt's that in addressing a popular
assembly you must either be copious on the points
you wish to emphasise or repeat them, and that he
preferred copiousness to repetition. Demosthenes
X. preferred repetition to copiousness ; but in this sense,
that he frequently came back upon the dominant
idea, and enforced it, not with verbal repetition, but
with fresh illustration. This is a capital feature in
his eloquence. He is resolved to secure one of the
high places of the field. From different quarters his
forces converge upon this point ; each avenue of
escape is blocked beforehand. Feints and diver-
sions are resorted to merely to conceal the premedi-
tated plan. No petty skirmishes prevent him from
striking at the heart of the enemy's strength.
Aristotle with admirable truth laid it down that logi-
cal proof is the first essential of rhetorical persuasion.
There is an idea now prevalent, derived rather from
the study of Roman than of Greek literature, that
ancient oratory appeals chiefly to feeling, and modern
oratory to reason. But in fact all the greatest orators,
ancient as well as modern, have been great reasoners.
It may be more plausibly maintained that there are
"X in Demosthenes few of those long chains of argument
for which Fox, for instance, was remarkable. But
even this statement is subject to some deduction.
There are many of the forensic speeches to which it
does not apply ; an interpretation of a complex law,
such as is found in The Aristocrates, is a sustained
argumentative process. His deliberative eloquence
is more popular and more varied in its method :
proof is less formally developed ; but a continuous
thread of thought is maintained, and whatever tends
158 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. viu.
to provoke reflection, to quicken the reasoning faculty,
is welcomed and pressed into the sendee. To stifle
a free intelligence, and to win by mo\ing appeals, is a
short-lived triumph which Demosthenes rejects. He
would set his audience thinking. All he asks of
/ them is to reason with him — Xoyi^ecrde 8i] tt/jo?
Vv 6(U)v. Among his most constraining instruments
of persuasion are lystorical examples, and chiefly
those which are drawn from recent and familiar
events. Each fact, each name, sets some emotion
vibrating. There is stroke upon stroke with little
breathing space between — " creber utraque manu
pulsat " — and each blow is forging a hnk in the
chain. The method is not demonstrative, but it is
essentially argumentative. The inference, if not ex-
plicitly drawn, is immediately suggested.
Another logical weapon which Demosthenes loves
y^ to wield is the dilemma ; and rarely has it been possible
to use it with such telling effect as is done in the
speech On the Embassy (§§ 102 fi"., see p. 97). His
natural strength and dexterity in argument are shown
in many forms ; above all in a certain combative
quality of his genius which he developed into
a commanding faculty of attack. Like Pitt he was
not content with defending himself, he presently
turned the tables and assumed the aggressive. The
speech On the Crown is a memorable case in point ;
minor instances occur in 2he Embassy (e.g. §§ 134-
146, ?§ 89, 90) where objections are met by unex-
pected retorts.
But the form of reasoning most distinctive of him
is when he closes with his adversary' and grips him
in strict and cogent argument. Then comes out the
pliant strength of the athlete, and his daring swiftness
of movement. Among the marks of such passages
arc a dramatic animation of manner, a quick inter-
change of question and answer, a pressing vehemence, .
X
CHAP. VIII.] STATESMAN AND ORATOR. 159
sudden surprises and novel turns of thought or
phrase, an . incisive irony. Alternative possibilities
are stated and disposed of, or a principle is tested in
its detailed application. The method is peculiarly
effective in recapitulation, in securing, inch by inch,
ground which has been disputed and partially won.
This was the second great lesson he learnt from
Isffius ; and from the forensic sphere he imported it
into the deliberative. This " agonistic " virtue is
perhaps the severest test of popular eloquence. Cicero
has little of it ; Burke is totally without it ; Fox had
it; Gladstone has it, though in a less conspicuous
degree than other quaUties ; but Demosthenes here
stands supreme.
It is not possible with Demosthenes, as it is with
lesser orators, to map out a speech into parts and say :
here is an appeal to feeling ; here is pure reasoning ;
for thought is everywhere interpenetrated with feeling,
reason is itself passionate. That which fuses all into
unity is the force of an intense personality, which
cannot convince the intellect without kindHng the emo-
tions. The breath of passion may give life for the
time to the orator's word, but alone it cannot give
permanence. A great speaker of our day would,
with the addition of one quality, take rank among
the highest. John Bright has almost every Demos-
thenic gift except that of strong and persistent reason-
ing. He is easily led away into an emotional digression;
some of his noblest passages are loosely connected
with the subject, they are not wrought into the texture
of the thought. The two most perfect types in which
the eloquence of impassioned reason has hitherto
expressed itself are found in Demosthenes and Burke.
When warmth circulates through the whole speech
it is the less necessary to concentrate it on the perora-
tion. Demosthenes in this respect obeyed an Attic
rule. The Athenians, distrusting their own sensibility.
i6o DEMOSTHENES. [chap. viii.
resented emotional pressure, and the orator, especially
towards the close of his speech, avoided all semblance
of doing moral violence to his audience, and addressed
himself mainly to their reason. In early Attic orator)'
the law of a final calm was scarcely ever violated. By
degrees more colour and animation made their way
, into the epilogue; but pathetic outbursts in the Roman
^/>^manner were still excluded, and the last sentences
were studiously unimpassioned.
The close of an Attic speech recalls the close of an
Attic tragedy in its sedate harmony, and in the place
it gives to artistic convention and euphemistic phrase.
Most of Demosthenes' deliberative speeches end in a
solemn wish or prayer, and the last word of all is
frequently one of lucky import Take, for instance,
the end of the Third Philippic (p. i lo) : " This is what
I have to say, these are the measures I propose.
Adopt these measures, and it is my beUef that even
yet our affairs may be retrieved. If any man has better
advice to offer, let him speak forth and declare his
counsel. And, be your decision what it may, grant,
f all ye gods, that it may be for our good " (o n 8' vfj-iv So^ti
I tout', di 7ravT€s dtou, ori'trcyKoi) ; Or again, the last
/ sentence of the Pi/ si Philippic : " May that prevail
/ which is for the common good of all " (j-ik-wtj S' o ti Totrwr
I v/iii' fxeXXet a-x'voicreiv) ; or of the Pirsl Olyttihiac.
\ " On all accounts may it turn out well " (xpija-ra 8' ttif
'TraiTos ei'veKa). Four of his court speeches end thus:
' " I ."^ee no reason to add anything ; you fully appre-
hend, I think, what has been said " — a formula also
found twice in Isosus. The peroration of Thf CroTvn
has been already noted as a signal exception (p. 123);
there a passionate imprecation precedes the blessing.
'I'he generation that succeeded Demosthenes admitted
pathetic perorations with less reserve. Lycurgus his
younger contemporary, ends a speech in the following
words, where the pathos and the personification arc some-
CHAP. VIII.] STATESMAN AND ORATOR. i6i
what modern in character : " Deem then, Athenians,
that a prayer goes up to you from the very land and
all its groves, from the harbours, from the arsenals,
from tlie walls of the city ; deem that the shrines and
holy places are summoning you to protect them ; and,
remembering the charges against him, make Leocrates
a proof that compassion and tears do not prevail with
you over solicitude for the laws and for the common-
weal." ^
"One might," says the author of the treatise On
the Sublime^ " as soon face with steady eyes a descend-
ing thunderbolt, as oppose a calm front to the storm
of passions which Demosthenes can arouse." Some
feelings, however, he seldom wakens. His highly-
wrought sensibility, due partly to the wrongs of child-
hood, was very different from a natural and healthy
pathos, in which, as in humour, he is deficient —
again in this respect resembling Burke. In this field
of the emotions he wisely puts himself under severe
self-control. While the pathos of Cicero is tender
and effusive, and adapted to stir a jury, the pathos of
Demosthenes is austere and Thucydidean in its reserve,
and unquestionably better suited to political discussion.
The desolation of Phocis, as told of in The Embassy
(§§ 65, 66), is no moving picture of ruin, but an out-
line of fact, where pity for suffering is merged in a
fiery scorn and indignation against its authors. The
instance is a typical one. It is hardly necessary to
contrast with this the melodramatic pathos of Aeschines.
Quintilian claims a superiority for his countrymen
over the Greeks in wit as well as in pathos. So far
as the wit of Demosthenes is concerned, the claim may
readily be conceded. Here he bears no comparison
with Cicero. His pleasantries were ponderous and
sometimes coarse. The writer above quoted says
1 Lycurg. Lcocr., translated by Prof. Jebb, Attic Orators, ii.
3S0.
M
i62 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. viii.
that " where Demosthenes strives to be jocose or
witty he makes us laugh at him rather than with him ;"
and we find in one of the letters ascribed to Aeschines
that " no one ever laughed at Demosthenes' jokes
except Ctesiphon " (Aesch. Ep. v.) It is only in a
few court speeches, where he is writing in the character
of his client, that he has any of the charm peculiar to
Lysias. The naive and innocent humour of the
speeches Against Collides and Against Cotton has
already been referred to (i>p. 133-135). In his political
orations he is bitterly in earnest ; the people preferred
smart sayings to hard duty, and he will not indulge
them. His eloquence, like his character, has in it a
biting and pungent flavour. Humour on his lips is
frozen into sarcasm ; scorn takes the place of railler}',
irony of wit. Touches, however, of grim humour,
reminding us of Aristotle, do occur, chiefly in illustra-
tions ; as in T/ie Crown, where Aeschines, giving his
counsel after the event, is compared to the jihysician
who prescribes for his patient after the funeral. The
speech On the Chersonese has a subdued sarcasm and
subtle irony running through the first half {e.g. §§ 5,
10, 27, 36); more often the irony is disdainful and
indignant, as in a f;imous passage of the Third Philippic
(§§ 65, 66).
The style of Demosthenes is now accepted as the
tj'pe of all that is simjile, direct, and forcible. Yet to
read him with ease is one of the latest fruits of Greek
scholarship. His vigorous compression of thought,
and inversions of the natural order of words for the
sake of emphasis and of rhythm, require continuous
attention on the part of the reader. An intimate study
of Thucydides has left its visible stamp on the early
deliberative speeches. It is doubtless with special
reference to these speeches that Dionysius, the best of
the ancient critics, ob«erves that, " in the style of
Thucydides and Demosthenes, there is much that is
CHAP. VIII.] STATESMAN AND ORATOR. 163
y^ obscure and needs a commentary" (Ljs. ch. 4). De-
mosthenes, at the opening of his career, seems to have
regarded a stately and archaic dignity as appropriate
to political debate. Plutarch says that the people
could not bear his first attempts as being over-elabo-
rate ; and, indeed, parts of the speech Ou the Sym-
■inories'^ (354 B.C.) might have been written by Thucy-
dides himself. There is the same pregnancy and
involution of thought, and a similar love of strained
antithesis. The early forensic speeches have traces of
over-elaboration of a somewhat different kind — an
exact balancing of clauses, a jingling of final syllables,
an almost pedantic avoidance of a hiatus between
vowels, and some exaggerated ornament. The great
organ of speech, afterwards perfected by the orator,
was not yet flexible to his use.
1/ From about 352 B.C. onwards, his eloquence, in all
'its branches, becomes more varied, more abundant,
and gives out fuller tones. The deliberative speeches
gain warmth and colour. The conversational vivacity
now introduced into them is one of many points of
contact which they have with modern parliamentary
oratory. Henceforth Demosthenes moves in ampler
periods ; these he blends with compact sentences.
While drawing largely on the popular idiom, he adapts
it to artistic expression. Words and phrases of everj'-
day life, which hardly find a place in other orators,
are moulded into new combinations so as to seem
natural without being commonplace. His similes, spar-
ingly used, and seldom developed in detail, derive much
of their force from their apposite homeliness (pp. 59,
60, 68, 74, 109). The metaphors are more daring;
but here too there is little expansion, the image being,
^ The different manner adopted by the orator at this period in
the Assembly and the law-courts is well shown by a comparison
of this speech with the Leptines, which belongs to the same
year, but is easy, fluent, and lively.
i64 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. viii.
for the most part, gathered up into a single word or
phrase which is struck off in the heat of passion. Yet,
though the dominant impression left on us by Demos-
thenes is that of severe and disciplined strength, he
appeared to a Greek taste to be at times so elaborately
ornate that Aeschines criticised him on this score, and
Dionysius admits the fact while he offers a justifica-
tion. It is in allusion to this manifold and versatile
faculty of Demosthenes that Dionysius calls him a very
Proteus {Dem. ch. 8). Elements which are elsewhere
found scattered are fused and wTought into one by his
genius.
The union of consummate artistic skill with a direct-
ness of aim that is seemingly unconscious of literary
effort, is a capital feature in his eloquence. Ornament
V for its own sake he disdained ; no orator has so few
showy passages, or is less adapted for a book of e.\-
tracts. To use his own phrase {Chers. § 73), to speak
was, in a sense, to act. His genius, severely prac-
tical, rejects all that is not strictly pertinent to the
subject in hand. Finish of workmanship is not lost,
however, on any popular assembly, and the audience
in his case was a nation of artists, who enjoyed a poli-
tical debate as they did a dramatic or a fnusical
festival. He was resolved to make his eloquence
something more than a spectacle ; but to do so he
must first satisfy every artistic requirement. Those
very speeches which are alive with the fire of passion
^have been laboriously prepared in the closet. The
evidence of the speeches themselves here falls in with
tradition. Demosthenes avows and justifies his own
scrupulous premeditation in a special case {Midias,
§ 191). Sometimes he repeats himself almost ver-
bally in difTerent speeches ; for a Greek, with an artist's
love for ])crfect form, when he had once expressed
his thought in the best way possible, saw no reason
for afterwards expressing it in the second best way.
CHAP, viii.] STATESMAN AND ORATOR. 165
His general avoidance of a hiatus between vowels — a
practice derived from Isocrates — is highly significant.
Modern criticism has discovered the limitations of this
rule, and distinguished the larger freedom of the
later speeches from the strict usage of the earlier
period. The most important result of the inquiry is
this : that the chief anomalies in respect of the hiatus
occur in precisely those passages or speeches which,
on other grounds, we believe to have been imperfectly
revised. We naturally infer that it was only by slow
processes of correction that the hiatus was subjected
to the laws which now govern it. The rhythm is such
as to warrant the same general inference. Its com-
plex and subtle harmonies, resembling those of a Pin-
daric ode, are pronounced by Dionysius {de Compos.
pp. 189-206) to be due to no instinctive process. More
recent investigations fully bear out this view. The
rhythm of Demosthenes, though modelled on that of
Isocrates, is even more unique in ancient oratory than
that of Burke is among the moderns.
The exact relation between the written and spoken
speeches of Demosthenes can never be definitely
settled. We know that he seldom extemporised, and
that when he did so he was liable to be carried away
by transports akin to madness.^ His careful and
anxious preparation was probably in part a safeguard
against his own impetuosity. We know, too, that in
the speech On the Embassy there must have been a
general, though not a detailed, correspondence be-
tween the spoken and the written form. So much
may be inferred from the reply of Aeschines. But
these considerations do not carry us far. The main
difficulty in the way of believing that we have the
^ The vulgarisms of phrase imputed to him by Aeschines, and
nowhere found in the extant speeches, were as unknown to
Dionysius as to us, but may perhaps have escaped from him in
some of these sudden outbursts.
i66 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. viii.
idcliberative speeches in the form in which they were
^(delivered, lies in their remarkable brevity and com-
pression. We must be careful not to exaggerate this
difficulty under the influence of modern notions. It
is only in recent times that we have come to think
that a great speech must necessarily be a long one ;
till the close of the last century, when Burke set a
new example, speeches of two or three hours' length
seem to have been almost unknown in our own Par-
liament And at Athens there were special causes
which helped to keep debate within moderate limits.
To Athenian perception it was plainer than it is to ours,
that the highest strength lies in clearness combined with
terseness, and that the first requisite of speech is that
it should be apt. The questions debated, moreover,
were more familiar and invoked less complex issues ;
the Assembly was generally held in the open air, and
the audience on great occasions might number, per-
haps, 6000 or 7000 people. The last fact alone
would tend to shorten the deliberative as compared
with the forensic speeches. The longest deliberative
speech of Demosthenes could not in its present form
have taken much more than an hour to deliver.
Yet, making every allowance on this head, we shall
be inclined, I think, to hold that occasional ampli-
Hcation must have been necessary in order that the
political speeches, whose full force we begin to feel
only on repeated reading, should tell with full effect
, even on an Athenian audience.
^ In our final judgment on Demosthenes we cannot
ilI) separate the orator from the statesman. If we regard
, his whole policy as a grand mistake, our estimate of
"^ his elocjuence must be affected by this view. It has
been sometimes said that he did not appreciate the
forces opposed to him, that he showed a want of
political penetration. The weaknesses, however,
which he exposed in the Macedonian power, were
CHAP, viii.] STATESMAN AND ORATOR. 1G7
not imaginar}'. That power, he said, had been
reared on frauds and broken promises ; there was a
corrupt court, a discontented people, suspicious alHes
{Olynth. ii.); behind the prince there was no per-
manent state organisation {Phil. iii. § 72). He
expected that the Macedonian, Hke other mihtary
monarchies, would crumble away at the death of the
despot. A phenomenon unique in history defeated
these calculations. Philip was succeeded by a son
greater than himself.
But never at any moment in the contest with
Philip did Demosthenes shut his eyes to the danger,
or lull his countrymen into a false security. To con-
vince and to enlighten was his constant aim. He
saw the conditions of ultimate victory with a terrible
prescience. He knew the utmost that Attic oratory
could do when pitted against an absolute monarch,
v.-ielding all the resources of war and of diplomacy.
A reflective reason controls his most impassioned
speeches, and his measures are marked by a business-
like precision. Gifted with a sense of the opportune,
which is an element of genius, though it is often
misconstrued into inconsistency, he could stand
forth to counsel peace when the interests of the state
required it. By virtue of a commanding eloquence
he carried on the struggle for thirteen years almost
single-handed. There were moments up to the last
when the turn of the scale was doubtful. A few
years before Chseronea the national life awoke from
its long slumber before his potent breath ; had the
awakening come a little earlier, the issue might have
been, if not reversed, postponed for another generation.
Isocrates invited Philip to extend to Athens the
beneficent interference he had shown in Thessaly.
There have been those, both in ancient and in modern
times, who have censured Demosthenes for ranging
himself on an opposite side. Polybius (xvii. 14)
l68 DEMOSTHENES. [chap. viii.
maintains that those whom he branded as traitors in
Arcadia, Messene, Argos, Thessaly, Bceotia, were in
truth benefactors to their respective cities ; that the
Peloponnesian states in particular enjoyed under
Macedon a freedom before unknown ; and that
Athens, as shown by the event, was unwise in re-
sisting. Polybius, writing under the shadow of
Roman greatness, views the struggle of free Greece
against Macedon as he would the rebellion of subject
Achaea against Rome ; and he is not in a position to
value aright political independence. But even if he
is taken on his own narrow ground, his statement may
be disputed. Demosthenes denies it by anticipation,
and history confirms him when he says that the dis-
loyal states of Greece came off worse than Athens at
the hands of the conqueror {Cro'dni, § 65).
Modern objections have generally been couched in
a somewhat different form. The victory of Demos-
thenes, it is said, would have retarded the progress of
the world. Demosthenes, says Cousin, "represented
the past of Greece; he failed disgracefully." "Our
symi)athics should be on the victorious side, for it is
always that of the better cause, that of civilisation
and humanity." But surely there is a limit to the
foresight we may demand from statesmen. Demos-
thenes was, doubtless, mistaken in speaking of Philip
himself as "a barbarian," as "the enemy of Athens
and of the very ground on which she stood." Philip
had genuine Greek sympathies, of which Demosthenes
was not aware. Yet, as we have seen, there was a
very rcAl sense in which Philip, as head of his nation,
was the rej^rcsentative barbarian (p. 51). It was only by
effacing what was Macedonian and absorbing what was
Greek, that the triumph of Philip became the triumph
of civilisation. Demosthenes could not have fore-
seen the Ares of Macedon being transformed, as on
his coins, into the Athenian Apollo, or forecast the
CHAP. VIII.] STATESMAN AND ORATOR. 169
intellectual empire which out of defeat was to be
built up for Greece. Nor even, had he obtained a
vision of all this, is it so clear that he ought to have
counselled his countrymen otherwise than he did.
It may well be doubted whether the bequest of a
weakened sense of national dignity and independence
would not have been a loss to the world greater than
the gain of hastening forward events by a few years.
In any case it is perilous work w^hen a statesman sits
in the seat of the prophet, and substitutes his own
surmises on the tendency of things for the " salutary
prejudice called our country."
The swift decline and death of the Hellenic spirit
within Greece proper, following upon the Macedonian
supremacy, may be gathered from the hymn in which,
fifteen years after the death of Demosthenes, Athens
welcomed Demetrius within her walls. A few lines
of it may here be quoted : — " Hail, son of mightiest
Neptune, and of Aphrodite, for the other gods are far
hence ; they hear not, or they are not, or they heed
us not. But as for thee, we see thee in presence,
not in wood or in stone, but in very truth; our
prayers are unto thee."
"Such," says Athenseus (vi. 63, 64), " was the song
of the warriors of Marathon not only in public but in
their oato homes, those who had punished with death
prostration before the King of Persia, and had slain
the myriad hosts of the barbarians." We may still
feel grateful to one who, though it was in a losing
cause, strove to arrest so sad a decadence. „
V O
M 2
TABLE OF THE WORKS OF
DEMOSTHENES.
The following is a list of the writings handed down among tl.e
works of Demosthenes. On questions concerning genuineness
there is little approach to unanimity of view (see p. 139) ; but the
tendency of recent critics (e.,c- of Blass as compared with A-
Schaefer) is to be more conser\-ative. The results here given
are those to which critical opinion now seems on the whole to
incline. The writings marked with f were doubted in antiquity,
those marked with * not till modern times.
I. DELIBERATIVE SPEECHES {(jvix^ov\€vtikoI \6yoi).
Cc'/nii/w
On the S>'Tnmorics (xiv.)
ly(.«
ll/U.
354 nc.
For the Megalopolitans {xvi.
)
353 B.C.
First Philippic (iv.)
351 B.c.
For the Rnodians(Tv.) .
351 B.C. (but see p.
43)
First Olynthiac (i.)
349 B-c.
Second Olynthiac (ii.) .
349 B.c.
ThirJ Olynthiac (iii.) .
349 B c.
On the Pe.ice (y.) .
346 B.C.
Second Philippic (vi.)
344 BC-
On the Chersonese (viii.)
341 B.C.
Third Philippic (ix.)
341 B.C.
(Philip's Letter (xiL) is probably genuine.)
Spurious.
U.C. BERKELEY LIBRARIES
llilllilllll
CD2iatlD73=l
THE UNIVERSITY OF CAUFORNIA LIBRARY