EESE LIBRARY UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA Received . Accessions No. '**-< J classify the systems of belief which have reached us from, the past, paying due regard to their succession in time, in certain groups, or types of thought, which are more or less closely identified with the localities or countries in which they have appeared. This seems the most natural method to pursue in writing a description of thought as it has oc- curred in history. But when the object is, as in the case of this work, to examine the whole subject of human knowl- edge, a less elaborate historical method will better serve. Instead of going through the tedious repetitions of detail in all the recognized philosophies, and pointing out their inter- dependencies, classifying them into such schools as the 1 Lewes: " Bio. His. of Phil.," p. 34. THE DAWN OF PHILOSOPHY. 15 Ionian or physical, the Pythagorean or mathematical, the Eleatic, and the Megaric, we will content ourselves with a brief sketch of the most important systems, and a portrayal of the original features in each. The other method has been so exhaustively applied by such writers as Ritter, Ten- nemann, Degerando, Victor Cousin, Hegel, Zeller, and Uebervveg, and its results, after all, are so purely historical, so meagre in a logical and developmental sense, that there is little encouragement for others to follow it. We will confine ourselves, therefore, to the endeavor to show, by selections from the accounts of these philosophies, that there has been one great problem of thought which they have all attempted to solve, and that the nearness of the approach of each to the solution of this problem has little or no connection with their relative positions in history. The organic history of our race is so incom- parably great when measured by the few centuries of progress which make up the sum of recorded history, that in the strict sense of the word we have no ancient philosophy to study. The Greek mind suffers nothing by comparison with the mind of the nineteenth century. With regard to their natural capacity for dealing with the fundamental problems of thought, the Greeks were our peers. If intro- spection, or any purely logical achievement could have sup- plied this coveted knowledge, we should have inherited it from them in the same perfection in which their art has reached us. Neither with the Greeks nor the moderns has there been any want of intellectual acumen. There is a deeper cause for our failure, thus far, to grasp this problem of thought. What is this cause ? It is to be found in the limitations which have hitherto restricted our conceptions of knowl- edge. Human knowledge in the higher sense means human life, and the problem of thought can only be solved by the development of knowledge as a whole. From the time of the ancient Greeks to our day, the nature of man has pro- gressed but very little. Human character appears rather in 1 6 THE SCOPE OF LANGUAGE. the attitude of about ascending to a higher plane than of oc- cupying it. And until this ascent has been actually made, we cannot look upon the struggles of the Greeks to solve the problems of thought as antique or alien. Their meth- ods, their aspirations, and their successes, judged by accepted standards, were in essence like our own ; and with our own they compare very favorably. In describing, therefore, the outlines of the thought of Thales and his immediate succes- sors, and in emphasizing the success of Anaximander in his effort to reach a solution of the great problem before us, strange as it may seem, we have already drawn the logical boundaries of the whole history of philosophy. Notwith- standing that the achievements of Socrates, Plato, and Aris- totle have not yet been mentioned, and that the writings of Descartes, Kant, and their successors, up to the time when contemporaneous writing begins, are yet to be described ; the whole logical compass of these illustrious writers has been anticipated by previous thought, and the farthest reach of their speculations proves to have been familiar ground to prehistoric minds. The corroborations of these state- ments are to be heard on every hand. The futility of thought, the hopeless search of metaphysics, the limits of the knowable, even so recent a movement in philosophy as agnosticism the modern term for the belief in an unknow- able are but expressions of the common verdict, that these early Greeks, and their predecessors in the East, went just as far as we have gone, in an intellectual sense, toward solv- ing the first problem of life. When we say that the growth of knowledge as a whole will alone realize any actual progress in this constant effort of our race to achieve an ultimate analysis, we merely specify that science and religion as well as thought are necessary factors in this growth, and that what is known as specula- tion and unaided introspection are of themselves utterly im- potent to accomplish the desired result. After this state- ment it may seem abrupt to offer the student a key to the ever-recurring enigmas of philosophical systems, as we find THE DA WN OF PHILOSOPHY. I/ them recorded in history. But as the charge, that philoso- phers have reasoned in a circle from the earliest records of human speculation, is not a new one, to emphasize the po- sition here advanced we must demonstrate the possibility of progress. It is the task of this work to show that knowledge is not merely thought, but that it includes conduct ; that truth cannot find a fuller expression in words after all than in ac- tions, and as a consequence, that we shall have to extend the sphere of metaphysics to that of morality, identifying these spheres as but phases of one fact of development in order to accomplish our demonstration. In offering, there- fore, at the very outset, a key to the metaphysical problem, it might appear that I have anticipated our argument, but I do not go beyond that department of truth which is indi- cated by the general title of these chapters. As we ap- proach the climax of Greek Philosophy, in the systems of Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle, if we are to show that the thought of these men has no higher significance than earlier speculations, it will be necessary to have some common measure for the significance of words ; : for all philosophy aims at an ultimate analysis. This needed criterion, then, we will proceed to explain. There is in England a school of geologists who have re- nounced all forms of generalization. They refuse to build up any theories of the organic history of our planet, but devote themselves entirely to the accumulation and classifi- cation of geological data. This resolution is the outgrowth of the many disappointments with which the generalizations or theories of geologists have met. The insuperable difficul- ties of estimating the comparative remoteness of events, when the only record of them is to be found in solidified sand and mud, all the results of physical forces and condi- tions which repeat themselves over and over again, leaving no traces of their chronological interdependence, have dis- couraged these scientists, and they have determined to -hazard no further opinions until they have accumulated 1 8 THE SCOPE OF LANGUAGE. more facts. This is a silent reproof to the less conscientious members of their profession who " have imagined that they could tell us what was going on at all parts of the earth's surface during a given epoch ; and have talked of this de- posit being contemporaneous with that deposit, until, from our little local histories of the changes at limited spots of the earth's surface, they have constructed a universal history of the globe as full of wonders and portents as any other story of antiquity." The only radical distinction between the development of ancient and of modern philosophy is that which arises from the poverty of the ancients in scientific facts. In other words, the only difference between ancient and modern knowledge (leaving out for the present the moral aspect) is the growth of science. This does not deny to philosophy an exclusive sphere relatively independent both of science and religion ; on the contrary, it circumscribes that sphere. It does emphatically deny, however, that there is any other method of mental apprehension used in any of these three spheres of human activity than that now universally ac- knowledged to be the method of science. Mind is a function of the organism, and has a definite and invariable mode of procedure. To identify the principle of this procedure with that of the humbler organic activities is the special task of the succeeding part of this work ; but it is not too soon to make the statement that truth is independent of words, that facts express themselves. If we fail to interpret facts aright, it is a failure of harmony between our minds and our sur- roundings, a maladjustment of inner to outer activities. The classification of facts which constitutes our intelli- gence and accounts for every aspect of it is a classification of changes. These changes express relations which have their terms in other changes, and so on to eternity and in- finity. If we would express these changes in numbers, we should merely reduce them to units of time ; if we would express them in quantities, we should merely reduce them to units of space ; if we would seize these changing phenom- THE DA WN OF PHILOSOPHY. 19 ena and analyze them in order to determine their weights and affinities, we should merely express many relations in terms of simpler relations, for weight and affinity are re- lations having for their terms more or less familiar condi- tions ; if we would comprehend the aggregates of changes viewed in the heavens and on the earth, we should merely enlarge the scale of the very method of investigation which we have applied to lesser groups. If we turn our attention to our race and generalize the principles of its development, we use the same method and our effort expresses the same law ; the analogy never ceases, and it never begins. We discover our lives to be the function of this infinity and eternity of conditions. Philosophy, rebelling against imaginary limits to percep- tion, would turn its face away and peer into the depths beyond. Resolutely it has held this attitude for centuries. Its eye has not dimmed, its hope has not abated, but the misty distances into which it has been peering have gradually been peopled with facts ; for science has patiently plodded on, enlarging the sphere of reality until we find ourselves in a universe of facts grand enough to satisfy our proudest hopes. When we look back at this steadfast unsatisfied gaze of the ancients trying to penetrate phenomena, we regard them with a certain poignant pity, because their horizon of reality was so limited. But to-day where is the mind that has taken full advantage of its opportunities in this newer world of knowledge? Who can afford to look unintelli- gently or contemptuously upon our domain of facts ? Who can complain of the method which has accomplished such rich results ? Not the philosopher who would truly interpret nature. There are phases of nature, however, which seem to evade the scientific method ; they are the phenomena of humanity. The questions which they raise are those of our origin and destiny, of our relations to one another and to the universe. This is a philosophy which would still bid defiance to the slow teachings of experience ; it is impatient of the restraints 20 THE SCOPE OF LANGUAGE. and the discipline of universal order; it claims a higher source of knowledge than that of the classification or com- parison of facts. This philosophy is called religion ; to its study we devote the third division of this work. It is to that philosophy which stands between science and religion, which occupies the territory of mind or language, that we would now give our attention. The word entity is a fiction. There is no such thing as an unrelated fact, an unconditioned existence. The mind rep- resents a principle, but it is the principle of all activity. Both ancient and modern philosophy teem with efforts to reduce diversity to unity, the many to the one. This one is not a place or a time, but a principle. The word principle means first ; the word first means one. Hence to succeed in this effort, to discover that unity which is the natural goal of classification, will be to accomplish the object of philosophy and amalgamate it with the departments of knowledge hitherto distinguished as science and religion. For the discovery of this ultimate fact, so long sought, philosophy wholly depends upon that method of comparing facts which is pursued in the sciences. From the time of Thales to that of Kant, philosophy has consisted of nothing but the grouping of observed facts, and deductions from them. Words have never been more than an attempt to ex- press what has already been expressed in these facts. If mind is a fact, it must be the product of other facts ; if it is .a phenomenon, it must be the function of its conditions ; if it is a relation, it must have its terms in the other relations. To say that it is an entity, is to corrupt our language with hid- den contradictions, to stultify the mind. As we have seen, the only ultimate difference between the philosophies of different ages is to be found in the command of facts enjoyed by each age. Apart from this, the scope of all philosophies has been identical. The question of the ultimate analysis was just as clearly stated in the speculations of Thales, Anaxi- mander, and Pythagoras, as in Descartes, Spinoza, or Kant. The latter writers, especially Kant, had a vast accumulation THE DAWN OF PHILOSOPHY. 21 of empirical data, scientific knowledge, to aid them in their speculations, but they had not successfully applied them to the science of mind. The postulate of Descartes (" I think, therefore I am "), the God of Spinoza, and the idealism of Kant, were no nearer the ultimate generaliza- tion than the speculations of the earliest thinkers. They one and all strove to reduce all imaginable diversities to one principle. The vastly superior scientific knowledge of the modern thinkers only seemed to increase the field of their diversities, it did not bring them to the ultimate simplicity. This ultimate simplicity has many names ; in seeking for it, it has been denominated the ultimate unity, truth, fact, principle, cause, substance, energy, force, existence, or reality. Thales, in the paucity of his scientific experience, thought that it was water ; Anaximenes, that it was air ; Diogenes of Apollonia, that it was living air ; Anaximander of Miletus, that it was the eternal motion of the infinite ; Descartes considered it a dual principle of mind and matter; Spinoza calls it God. Kant attributes this ultimate reality to mind alone, and Herbert Spencer calls it the " persistence of force." Where is the progress of the intervening twenty- five centuries ? Surely it is in scientific knowledge, and not in pure philosophy. Will it be too much to ask the reader to believe that this ultimate reality or principle is plainly and unmistakably confronting us wherever w r e turn, that it alone accounts for every experience, and that the only reason why it has so long escaped us is, that it is an inseparable and primordial quality of our very existence ? It is too near to be seen, too easy to understand ; and for this reason, and only for this reason, it is difficult to explain. If singleness of mind is strength, then indeed it requires the greatest intellectual power to grasp this fact. It would seem, though, that the requisite condition of the mind to appreciate this truth is not that of great tension, or a very high degree of train- ing, but a self-discipline, a submission to the power of facts, a renunciation of mental or verbal conceit ; in a word, the 22 THE SCOPE OF LANGUAGE. very thing in an intellectual sense that religion demands of us in a sentimental sense in order to know God. To present the argument in a scientific form, the whole burden is to prove that matter and space are words which have the same ultimate signification. Matter is clearly a generalization of the statical side of phenomena. Under analysis matter disappears in motion. Space is simply our term for infinity or extension, and therefore the argument turns upon the point whether the universe is a plenum or not. In further support of the fact that it is, I refer the reader to an argument in " Problems of Life and Mind," by G. H. Lewes, as a powerful corroboration of this view, that matter and space are terms which are logically indistinguisha- ble. This argument, entitled " Action at a Distance," is given entire in Chapter XV., Part II., of the present work. Some time after I had made an attempt J to explain the above theory of the identity of matter and space, this essay gave me unexpected assistance. Although it does not state in terms that matter and space are the same thing, this is an irresistible inference from the argument. The question is one of such transcendent importance in philosophy, and this argument by Lewes seems to me so conclusive, that I thus refer to it in advance. The consequences of this reasoning are momentous. Un- less this theory stand, the categories of thought, or ultimate realities, will remain discrete, as we find them in Herbert Spencer's " Psychology," and in all other modern philoso- phies, namely, Space, Time, Matter, Force, and Motion. Some writers add Cause, but it is now generally admitted that Cause stands for merely one aspect of every phenomenon, the obverse side of which is Effect, cause being thus a term denoting a purely logical distinction. Others, again, postu- late Consciousness as an ultimate reality. Spencer, for instance, distinctly declares consciousness to be an irreduci- ble principle, but this error is fully met and set aside by Lewes. 1 An anonymous brochure published in 1881. THE DAWN OF PHILOSOPHY. 2$ The interdependence of the five ultimate terms, above- named, has not as yet been successfully demonstrated ; but if matter and space are admitted to be the same reality, under different aspects, the difficulty at once disappears ; for then motion becomes the ultimate reality and space and time become its obverse aspects. Space and time have no separate existence apart from motion ; their identity is merged in this ultimate fact. As stated above, the amount of mental reorganization or reform necessary to grasp this simplest of all facts is such as to place it practically beyond the reach of minds that have been trained to cherish the distinctions which this theory would destroy. We have met many people of scientific and philosophic training who are logically incapacitated for re- ceiving this truth ; they would no more believe that matter and space were the same thing than a devotee would surren- der his faith. It is, therefore, to the younger class of think- ers that we must appeal, thinkers who have not committed themselves too deeply, who are open to conviction, who are hospitable to new truths when they are clearly stated and amply sustained. If motion is the ultimate reality, and space and time are its obverse aspects, all ultimate terms must be made to take their places in this trinity of realities. The word infinite, for instance, can have no signification beyond that of space; and the terms extension, coexistence, and unlimited, so often found in philosophic writings, all stand for the statical aspect of motion, the most convenient name for which is space. On the other hand, the word absolute has no signification beyond that of time, and the terms sequence, invariable flux- ion, and unconditioned, mean in their deepest sense the same thing as time. With this understanding of the ultimate sig- nificance of the chief philosophic terms, it will be compara- tively easy to continue our review of philosophy, for we have the key to every metaphysical situation. CHAPTER II. THE PRE-SOCRATIC PERIOD. Xenophanes Parmenides Zeno of Elea Heraclitus Anaxagoras Empedo- cles Democritus. ACCORDING to the well-known essay of Victor Cousin, Xenophanes was born in the 4 Paris at the age of twenty and joined the school of William de Champeaux, a renowned teacher of the art of disputation. It was not long before Abelard challenged his teacher and defeated him in argument ; then the character of his am- bition became apparent. He was not primarily a lover of wisdom, but rather of the glories and triumphs of contro- versy. He looked upon the past as a repository of knowl- edge containing more truth than his age possessed, and throughout his teachings this attitude was maintained, which- SCHOLA S TICISM. 93 caused them to lack the inspiration of progress. In our age we are not discouraged by believing in the retrogression of knowledge ; our studies are full of hope, we feel the possi- bility of increasing knowledge, of exalting human life. During the revival of learning in Europe, all study was a retrospect, and thought flowed down from the intellectual heights of ancient Greece to the lower levels of the later civilizations. It is not to be wondered at, therefore, that Abelard con- tented himself with exhibiting to admiring crowds the treas- ures which he found in the literatures of the Greeks and the Romans, and that he felt the hopelessness of any endeavor to add to the achievements of the past. We are reminded by his fate that the deepest reproach that can be made to a teacher, is that of unfaithfulness to his precepts. He was a brilliant orator and a master of the art of disputation ; but in teaching there is no power like that of example ; and as he lacked those sterling virtues which alone could have made his life correspond with the ideals which he held up for others, his career challenged ad- miration but failed to command respect, or to exert any deep influence. Abelard was a representative Scholastic. He has been called by different writers a nominalist, a realist, and a con- ceptualist. Others think that his doctrines contain all these kinds of thought in more or less definite proportions. For our purpose it will be well to avoid these fine distinctions, as they never mean any thing sufficiently definite to repay the trouble of analyzing the terms. There is one broad distinction, however, running through all philosophic thought which can form the sufficient basis of our classification. This distinction begins in the differ- ence between the teachings of Aristotle and those of Plato. Plato gave an objective existence to ideas ; he believed that thoughts came nearer to the source of things than the things themselves ; and as we can only recognize ideas by 94 THE SCOPE OF LANGUAGE. names or words, he mistook symbols for realities, and be- lieved that, by operating on these symbols, deeper truths could be reached than by studying nature directly. This was the dialectics of Plato, and can be best described by the term Idealism. The antithesis of idealism is science, the patient investigation of facts accompanied by verification, and the grouping or classification of these facts into more and more general ideas. The ideas of science are always subordinate to facts, because they are derived from them. This, in general terms, is Aristotle's theory, and is distin- guished from Plato's in that Plato held ideas to be superior to facts. Of course there is a fundamental truth of which both these interpretations are more or less distinct expres- sions, but the difference between the theories is broad and clear ; other and more minute distinctions are unnecessary for the understanding of the general history and principles of philosophy. For instance, Realism is a belief which sup- poses that certain kinds of ideas, known as general terms or abstract ideas, such as animal man truth, have an objec- tive existence. Idealism maintains that all ideas have ob- jective existences, such as both the idea of a given man, and the idea of man in general, or that of a given animal and the order animal. Nominalism is the ultra scientific posi- tion. It holds that names stand for relations which we per- ceive among facts, and that all relations are merely functions of their terms or conditions : that a general name, such as circle, simply stands for the relation of a circumference to its centre ; that this relation can be generalized by apply- ing it to many simpler groups of facts ; but in each case it is strictly the function of these facts and has no separate existence. Realism, on the contrary, holds that the name circle stands for a type of existence independent of all conditions. It is a modified form of that rank Idealism of Plato which believed in divine archetypes from which all concrete em- bodiments were derived ; that an attribute or quality was not simply the expression of certain conditions, but was a SCHOLASTICISM. 95 mystic genus or supernatural order of being, a mysterious . something more real than the conditions expressing it. This Idealism has fallen into such disrepute that the word real has come to signify the exact logical opposite of it. Real, to us, means rational, sensible, true, the antithesis of ideal, fanciful, unreal. Is it surprising, therefore, that com- mon-sense people should be puzzled when they are told that Realism is a species of Idealism, and that it is the theory that general names, such as circle beauty right, have a sep- arate existence from round things beautiful objects right actions ; that, in a word, Idealism believes that all reality is in the mind ; Realism, that about seven-eighths of all reality is in the mind ; whereas Nominalism leaves things as they are, and claims for the mind no monopoly of reality ? But the confusion becomes doubly confounded when we find the Scholastics declaring that Aristotle, who is supposed to stand for the rational or scientific order of perception, was a Real- ist or a semi-Idealist. Aristotle, who honestly endeavored to oppose the Idealism of Plato, became so entangled in its mystical phraseology that his works were interpreted in the Middle Ages as Scholastic Realism, and were identified with religious orthodoxy. The broad distinction which exists between Idealism and Science is the only safe one to use in philosophic classifica- tion. This distinction, as we have before said, can be traced to the difference between Aristotle and Plato ; but as both these great masters were monopolized by the church for many centuries, the interpretations put upon their works are more than confusing. Hence we shall not be surprised to find a long line of logical reformers from Abelard even to Francis Bacon denouncing the teachings of Aristotle as a means of opposing Idealism. Abelard was a strange mixture of Idealism and Nominal- ism. An analysis of his thought in this regard would be as tedious as profitless, for it suggests nothing original and gives no indications of a direct study of nature. His career was neither scientific nor, in the best sense, philosophic. -96 THE SCOPE OF LANGUAGE. We must not forget, however, that he contended long and earnestly for freedom of thought, and practically began the movement which resulted in the separation of philosophy and theology, the severing of that union which had been effected by the Alexandrian school. To glance at another civilization, the Mohammedan cul- ture is not without its position in the history of thought. The Arabians were diligent students of Greek philosophy, and had translated a number of Aristotle's works into their language long before the revival of learning among the Chris- tian nations. An Arabian philosophy grew up which was a combination of Mohammedanism and Greek thought, as Scholasticism was a combination of Greek thought and Christianity. The chief feature of this philosophy was mys- ticism. All Eastern thought has a tinge of mysticism that strange faith which has the doctrine of total depravity for one support, and the principle of ecstatic communication with God for the other. The Mystics had a contempt for human energy. One of their orders symbolized this idea by planting a stick in the desert and carrying water hundreds of miles across the burning sands to water it. They believed that the highest possible existence is absolute inaction, in order to superinduce a reverie, or ecstasy, which is the con- dition necessary to have perfect communion with God. This idea is distinctly visible in Plato's teachings, and it lingers in modern philosophy in the greatly modified form of a belief in a priori ideas. Such an advanced work, even, as Spencer's "Psychology" has a faint trace of it in the notion of irreducible intuitions. We find nothing in the system of Algazzali, the greatest of Arabian philosophers (born in the city of Tours, 1 508 A.D.), which is sufficiently distinct from the thought already re- viewed to merit notice, unless it be this element of mysticism which pervades the school, and which is abundantly repre- sented in Christian culture. Philosophy as well as religion has had its martyrs. In A.D. 1600 Giordano Bruno was burned at the stake in Rome by SCHOLA S TICISM. 97 the Holy Inquisition for teaching independence of thought. It is true that he attacked religious beliefs with great force, but he did it through philosophic writings and lectures. An Italian of great learning, he conceived an intense feeling of rebellion against the narrowness and superstition of his time, and devoted his life to advocating principles of intel- lectual reform. At that time the works of Aristotle were regarded by the learned world with the same superstitious reverence as that in which the Bible is now held ; and as almost all learning was then confined to the church, there was a strange combination of Aristotle's logic and physics, the Ptolemaic system of astronomy, and the Christian dogmas, forming the accepted faith of the church. All those who opposed any part of these beliefs were persecuted as enemies of the Christian religion. The hold which this combination of imperfect science and blind religious belief had upon the public mind, is scarcely conceivable to us. " In 1624 a quarter of a century after Bruno's martyrdom the Parliament of Paris issued a decree banishing all who publicly maintained theses against Aristotle ; and in 1629, at the urgent remonstrance of the Sorbonne, decreed that to contradict the principles of Aristotle was to contra- dict the Church ! There is an anecdote recorded somewhere of a student, who, having detected spots in the sun, commu- nicated his discovery to a worthy priest. ' My son/ replied the priest, ' I have read Aristotle many times, and I assure you there is nothing of the kind mentioned by him. Go, rest in peace ; and be certain that the spots which you have seen are in your eyes, and not in the sun.' ' For ten years previous to Bruno's imprisonment at Venice, where he languished without books or writing materials for six years, he had wandered over the Continent and into England. He was encouraged by Queen Elizabeth, and through her influence lectured at Oxford. Before this he lectured at the Sorbonne in Paris, where he attracted great attention and became very popular. After leaving England he visited Marburg, Wurtemburg, and Prague. In almost 98 THE SCOPE OF LANGUAGE. every place his aggressive nature and principles brought him in conflict with the superior powers, and his visits to the seats of learning were short and stormy. At last, returning to Italy, whence he had fled, he was apprehended, suffered his long imprisonment, and was put to death. Together with the prevailing religious beliefs, Bruno bit- terly and persistently attacked Aristotle and Ptolemy, and in the more hospitable universities, debates of great pomp and ceremony were organized to oppose his teachings. It is to be remembered that these tournaments of learning were a feature of the age. Bruno was a constant satirist of the pedant, whom he held responsible for a great deal of the narrowness of the times, and lost no opportunity to bring him into ridicule. Speaking of him, he says : " If he laughs, he calls himself Democritus ; if he weeps, it is with Her- aclitus ; when he argues, he is Aristotle ; when he com- bines chimeras, he is Plato ; when he stutters, he is Demos- thenes." Bruno was not a scientist, but he had the scientific spirit ; he advocated the study of nature, instead of that unscientific introspection which was the habit of his time. It may seem strange that he was so opposed to Aristotle, and still so thoroughly in sympathy with the Aristotelian method ; this can only be explained by the narrow way in which the writ- ings of the great Stagirite were interpreted by the church. Bruno never could have come into contact with the broad spirit of the Aristotelian method, or he would have recog- nized in it the same hopes and ambitions which he enter- tained himself. Bruno's philosophy had not become eman- cipated from Scholasticism, as indeed but few modern philosophies have. The highest generalization of the an- cients, to which they gave the name of God, or Divine Unity, had become substantialized by constant use in re- ligious thought until its meaning was degraded by undue limitations. This substantialization of the Universal Principle, or the idea of deity, is the great obstacle to an understanding be- THE REVIVAL OF LEARNING. 99 tween philosophy and religion. These two contrasted interpretations of deity employ the same terms but give to them different meanings ; and so deeply rooted has this misunderstanding become, that it is virtually beyond correction. New generations must grow up with a common knowledge of the meaning of these most important of all words, before a reconciliation can be effected. After the time of the Neo-Platonists and the Alexandrian school, philosophy for fifteen centuries remained subservient to religion and degenerated into a mystic theology. Such men as Bruno rebelled against this low order of thought, and struggled to throw off the concrete meanings imposed upon ultimate terms ; they were only partially successful, and passed away leaving their work incomplete. But from the turmoil of mixed theological and philosophic debate, called Scholasticism, the science of Metaphysics again springs into existence, and the word God becoming purer and purer in its meaning, at last assumes the form of the Ulti- mate Reality, or Universal Principle Motion, the ob- jective and subjective aspects of which are Space and Time. Thus Science and Theology unite in the Synthesis of Knowledge, giving us at once the only true philosophy, the only pure religion. Francis Bacon, about the merit of whose works there has been so much dispute in England, especially during the present century, was born in 1561. He studied at Cam- bridge, and afterward took up the profession of law, in which he became eminent. Under the reign of James the First his fortune advanced rapidly. In 1616 he was sworn a member of the Privy Council, and in the following year was appointed Keeper of the Great Seal, then created Baron of Verulam, and Viscount of St. Albans. Macaulay says : " The moral qualities of Bacon were not of a high order. We do not say that he was a bad man. He was not inhuman or tyrannical. He bore with meekness his high civil honors, and the far higher honors gained by his intellect. He was very seldom, if ever, provoked into treating any person with malignity 100 THE SCOPE OF LANGUAGE. and insolence. * * * No man was more expert at the soft answer which turneth away wrath. He was never ac- cused of intemperance in his pleasures. His even temper, his flowing courtesy, the general respectability of his de- meanor, made a favorable impression on those who saw him in situations which do not severely try the principles. His faults were we write it with pain coldness of heart and meanness of spirit. He seems to have been incapable of feeling strong affection, of facing great dangers, of making great sacrifices. His desires were set on things below." In the zenith of his prosperity a sudden reverse was at hand. Notwithstanding his large income, his habits of extravagance tempted him to accept bribes. He was charged with cor- ruption, and, after an attempt at defence, publicly acknowl- edged his guilt. The sentence was severe : he was condemned to imprisonment during the King's pleasure, and fined forty thousand pounds ; he was declared incapable of holding any office in the State or of sitting in Parliament, and was also banished from Court. This sentence was scarcely pro- nounced when it was mitigated, for he passed only two days in the Tower, when he was liberated. Retiring to Gorham- bury, he devoted himself to literature during the remainder of his life. When the rest of the sentence was finally remit- ted, and he could have resumed his seat in the House of Lords, he did not do so, shame, perhaps, preventing him. On his death-bed, knowing that if he had thought pro- foundly, he had nevertheless acted most unworthily, he said : " For my name and memory, I leave it to men's charitable speeches, and to foreign nations, and to the next age." His confidence was not misplaced ; men have dealt leniently with him, for " turn where we will, the trophies of that mighty intellect are full in view." Bacon is accredited with the honor of establishing the modern scientific method. Although it would be difficult to find an age, since history began, completely without a sci- entific method, a glance at the situation in the time of Bacon 1 Macaulay's " Miscellanies," p. 255. THE REVIVAL OF LEARNING. IOI will convince us that much of our scientific advancement and educational reform are to be traced to his influence. Bacon lived in a time of marked theological and metaphysi- cal activity. The great work of Copernicus had just begun to unsettle the Christian beliefs, and Galileo was in the midst of his controversy with Rome. The paths of science and religion were beginning that redivergence which has since brought these two branches of knowledge into such antag- onism. Lessing's "Fragments" and the acrimonious wars which they engendered were yet unheard of, but theological debates filled the air, and there was a certain freshness and earnestness about these collisions which they are without to- day. Science was so feeble and had so few friends, religion was so generally held as the arbiter of all questions of the understanding, that Bacon's unflinching devotion to the scientific method, his supreme indifference to the war of words around him, showed a deep appreciation of the real needs of his time. Bacon is often called the father of experimental philosophy, but his works attempt no solution of the metaphysical prob- lem ; he carefully avoids throughout the use of ultimate terms. His idea of the nature of perception constitutes the great force of his system. He saw clearly that human knowledge is but an aspect of life, and that it springs from a fact which is more than human and deeper than personality. He saw the futility of trying to express this fact in terms either of human or divine personality, and therefore declared that all knowledge was subordinate to or expressed by facts. Gen- eralizations, he reasoned, are only broad classifications of facts. He overlooked, however, the great truth that all facts must take some part in human life in order to be classified, and that the constant human or subjective term in every perception can be made to disclose a constant objective term ; that in the multiplicity of facts a unity can be dis- cerned, a principle which accounts for universal as well as individual life. One of Bacon's celebrated aphorisms is : " Man, the min- 102 THE SCOPE OF LANGUAGE. ister and interpreter of Nature, can act and understand in as far as he has, either in fact or in thought, observed the order of Nature: more he can neither know nor do." In other words, to understand any thing perfectly, that thing must harmonize with our experiences. If our experiences are not sufficiently extended to receive great truths, we must extend them by the accumulation of more facts, as the only means of increasing knowledge, or, what is the same thing, of enlarging life. If we were to reduce Bacon's method to a single sentence, we would say: do not jump at conclusions ! His power and originality centre in the " systematization of graduated verification as the sole method of research." He shows a great contempt for the conventional meta- physical method of forming generalizations from insufficient facts. " There are two ways," he says, " of searching after and discovering truth ; the one, from sense and particulars, rises directly to the most general axioms, and resting upon these principles and their unshaken truth, finds out intermediate axioms, and this is the method in use ; but the other raises axioms from sense and particulars by a continued and gradual ascent, till at last it arrives at the most general axioms, which is the true way, but hitherto untried. " The understanding, when left to itself, takes the first of these ways ; for the mind delights in springing up to the most general axioms, that it may find rest ; but after a short stay there it disdains experience, and these mischiefs are at length increased by logic for the ostentation of disputes. " The natural human reasoning we, for the sake of clear- ness, call the anticipation of nature, as being a rash and hasty thing ; and the reason only exercised upon objects, we call the interpretation of nature." To interpret nature, therefore, was Bacon's only way to learn. As Bacon paid little or no attention to an ultimate analysis, he never seemed to realize that the greatest need of the race is a point of beginning for perception, so that all the " graduated verifications," upon which he so earnestly THE REVIVAL OF LEARNING 103 insisted, should invariably lead us back to one incontroverti- ble principle. That he, nevertheless, felt the possibility of such an analysis is manifest from the following passage in his " Novum Organum " : "But let none expect any great promotion of the sciences, especially in their effective part, unless natural philosophy be drawn out to particular sciences ; and, again, unless these particular sciences be brought back again to natural philosophy. From this defect it is that astronomy, optics, music, many mechanical arts, and what seems stranger, even moral and civil philosophy and logic, rise but little above their foundations, and only skim over the varieties and surfaces of things, viz. : because after these particular sciences are formed and divided off, they are no longer nourished by natural philosophy, which might give them strength and increase ; and therefore no wonder if the sciences thrive not, when separated from their roots." The roots of all science he thus conceived to be moral or natural laws. To reduce these natural laws or experiences to a single principle never seemed to occur to him as feasible. Bacon said that Aristotle corrupted natural philosophy with logic, which simply means that he reasoned beyond his depth. Aristotle for centuries was regarded as the originator of the inductive method, because he was a scientist and studied nature, carefully accumulating facts and drawing from them general laws. He classified facts through resem- blances of different kinds, and gave to these resemblances names. His attention was largely devoted to the study of comparative anatomy, the resemblances in the structure of animals. These classifications have led to our present divi- sion of the whole animal kingdom into five sub-kingdoms, each of these sub-kingdoms again divisible into provinces, each province into classes, and the classes into successively smaller groups, orders, families, genera, species. Surely thus far Aristotle did not corrupt natural philosophy. But 1 " Novum Organum," I., Aph. 79, 80. 104 THE SCOPE OF LANGUAGE. he did strive to reach an ultimate analysis, and to this end he framed his ten categories of thought. He also indulged in a great deal of metaphysical speculation, which Bacon regarded as a sheer waste of time. It is an interesting fact that Bacon should have differed so much from Aristotle and still have inherited from him his own chief distinction ; for Bacon is now widely known as the apostle of the inductive method of philosophy. This method is supposed by some to constitute a kind of reasoning distinct from that em- ployed in the deductive method ; whereas all that is really meant by the terms induction and deduction is a different manner of investigating facts, the process of reasoning being constant in all methods. Before Aristotle's time the animal kingdom was regarded as a great mass of unrelated phe- nomena. Biology was unknown, and anatomy and physiology were confined to such rude results as could be obtained by untrained observation. The result was that the knowledge of animal life was chaotic. As we have seen, Aristotle studied animal structures, and from comparisons built up classes of resemblances. This is the inductive method of research, because it is said to proceed from particulars to generals. It is contrasted with the deductive method, or the procedure from generals to particulars. The fault which Bacon finds with Aristotle, then, is sim- ply that he did not proceed to the farthest lengths of rea- soning, that he did not define the contrasted nature of individual and general existence, without breaking loose from his careful synthesis of organic life. This objection of Bacon's is well taken ; but it must be remembered that Aristotle was far less fully equipped for such an undertaking than Bacon might well have been, and that the latter lacked the ambition and courage for the attempt. CHAPTER VI. MODERN PHILOSOPHY. Descartes Spinoza Hobbes Locke Hartley Leibnitz Berkeley Hume. IF it is to England that we owe the inauguration, through Francis Bacon, of experimental science, it is to France that we are indebted for the firm establishment of Modern Philosophy. The writings of Rene Descartes Duperron mark the transi- tion from mediaeval to modern thought. To be a great thinker is a higher distinction in France than in any other country. Not that there are as many scholars in France as there are in Germany, or that the logical achievements of England suffer by comparison with those of the continent ; but the French language affords the least opportunity of all tongues for vagueness of expression, and hence a system of philosophy, to command lasting respect in France, must be distinguished for clearness, definiteness, and good sense. Such, allowing for the time in which it was written, is the system of Descartes. Born in 1596, Descartes was contemporaneous with Galileo, and suffered not a little from the spirit of religious intoler- ance which pervaded Europe at that time. Educated by the Jesuits, he had no sooner mastered the religious and philosophic thought of his time than he announced his dis- satisfaction with it. He declared that the only result of his studies had been to enable him to discern his utter ignorance. At the age of twenty-three he conceived the project of re- organizing the philosophic knowledge of the world, and be- gan a series of travels principally in his own country, for the purpose of studying life. These travels, which lasted about ten years, included various periods of service in the army. The 105 106 THE SCOPE OF LANGUAGE. garrison life afforded him opportunities of study, and brought him in contact with many scholars of note. Mathematics was the favorite study of Descartes, and it was not long be- fore he achieved a European reputation in this science. The faculty which he acquired for solving problems was marvel- lous. The discovery of the application of algebra to geome- try, his chief scientific merit, was a crisis in his career. The manner in which he approached this discovery he thus describes: "The long chains of simple and easy reasons which geometers employ in arriving at their most difficult demonstrations made me fancy that all things which are the objects of human knowledge are similarly interdependent ; and that, provided we abstain from assuming any thing false, and observe the correct order in deducing things one from another, there are none so remote that we cannot reach and so hidden that we cannot discover them. I was at no trouble in finding out where to begin ; for, considering that the mathematicians only had attained to some certainty, and this because they occupied themselves about the easiest sub- ject of all, I thought I should examine this first. And then, considering that to know the mathematical sciences, I should sometimes require to consider them each in detail, and sometimes only to retain or understand several of them conjointly, I thought that to consider them better in partic- ular I must consider them in lines, because I could find noth- ing simpler, or more distinctly representable to my imagina- tion and senses ; but to retain them, or to consider several of them together, it was necessary to explain them by the briefest possible symbols, and thus I should borrow all that was best from geometrical analysis and from algebra and correct the defects of each by the other." This puissant method opened up new fields of discovery to Descartes. Not content with applying it to mathematics, he saw its bearing upon the physical sciences, and even enter- tained a vague hope of applying it in some form to the study of mind. " Not that I ventured to examine forth- with all manner of problems, which would have been a vio- MODERN PHILOSOPHY. IO/ lation of my rules; but, knowing that their principles must all be derived from [first] philosophy, in which I could, as yet, find none that were certain, I thought that here, above all, I ought to establish them." Thus we see that the exact deductions of mathematics had a charm for Descartes, and supplied him with a method to which he always afterward adhered. During these ten years of wandering, Descartes resided at times in Paris, where he had the advantage of scientific friends as well as the distraction of Court life into which his good social position introduced him. This scientific association gave him ample exercise in mathemat- ics and developed in him a taste for other investigations, among which is prominently mentioned practical optics ; but he longed for more abstract studies and the retirement which makes them possible. At the age of thirty we find him secluding himself in Hol- land and beginning the work which resulted, eight years afterward, in the publication of the " Discourse on Method," and the celebrated " Meditations." The appearance of these works interested at once the learned world, and their author was almost immediately recognized as an original and pow- erful thinker. Charles the First of England and Christina of Sweden urged him to come to their respective Courts. The civil war in England decided his choice in favor of Stockholm, where he became interested with Christina in the establishment of an academy of sciences. Descartes' delicate health, however, soon succumbed to the rigor of the northern climate. With Scandinavian indifference to comfort, Christina insisted upon taking her lessons in phil- osophy at five o'clock in the morning of an Arctic winter. Descartes was too chivalrous to demur; and scarcely had he begun to teach his royal friend the principles of his phil- osophy, when he was taken with the illness which in a few days caused his death. In the development of the mind of Descartes we find mir- rored the dawn of modern philosophy in Europe. His ap- preciation of the Advantages of a broad culture can be judged 108 THE SCOPE OF LANGUAGE. of from the famous autobiographical passage in the opening of the " Discourse on Method " : " I know that the languages I then learned were necessary for the understanding of ancient authors ; that the grace of myths stimulates the mind ; that the memorable deeds in histories exalt it, and, being read with discretion, and in forming the judgment, that the reading of all good books is like a conversation with the best people of past centuries who have written them, nay, even a studied conversation, in which they disclose to us only their best thoughts ; that eloquence has incomparable strength and beauty; \hakpoetry has enchanting delicacy and sweetness. * * * But I came to think that I had spent enough time at languages, and even in the reading of ancient books and their histories and fables: for it is almost the same thing to converse with men of other ages as it is to travel ; but if one travel too long, one becomes a stranger to one's own home. * * * I highly esteemed eloquence and loved poetry ; but I thought that both one and the other were mental endowments rather than the fruits of study. Those who have the strongest reasoning faculty and digest their ideas most thoroughly, so as to make them clear and intelligible, are always best able to persuade men of what they propose even though they talk bos Breton and have never learned rhetoric ; and those who have the most pleasing fancies, and can express them with best adornment and most sweetness, will still be the best poets, even should the art of poetry be unknown to them." Passing from this delineation of culture to his philo- sophic position, we find that Descartes perceived that a vacuum, or absolutely empty space, was an impossibility. He said that the essence, or first principle of matter, or sub- stance ', is extension, and that wherever there is extension there is matter ; or, which is the same thing, he identifies Matter with Space. " The substance which fills all space must be assumed as divided into equal angular parts. Why must this be assumed ? Because it is the most simple, therefore the most natural supposition. This substance being set ins MODERN PHILOSOPHY. 109 motion, the parts are ground into a spherical form, and the corners thus rubbed off, like filings or sawdust, form a second or more subtle kind of substance. There is, besides, a kind of substance, coarser and less fitted for motion. The first kind makes luminous bodies, such as the sun and fixed stars; the second makes the transparent substance of the skies ; the third kind is the material of opaque bodies, such as earth, planets, etc. We may also assume that the motions of these parts take the form of revolving circular currents, or vortices. By this means the matter will be collected to the centre of each vortex, while the second or subtle matter surrounds it, and by its centrifugal effort constitutes light. The planets are carried round the sun by the motion of this vortex, each planet being at such a distance from the sun as to be in a part of the vortex suitable to its solidity and mobility. The motions are prevented from being exactly circular and reg- ular by various causes. For instance, a vortex may be pressed into an oval shape by contiguous vortices." * With these rather fanciful theories of physics, fanciful from our point of view, but exceedingly penetrating when we consider the state of science in the beginning of the seventeenth century, Descartes makes the most important assertion in the whole range of physical truth, but he seems to have little conception of its vast logical importance. This assertion was the identification of Matter and Space, as con- vertible terms, representing the ultimate statical generaliza- tion. The ultimate fact with Descartes was personal exist- ence, or consciousness. From this he deduced the fact of general existence, or God. His famous dictum, " I think therefore I am,'* is really an identical proposition ; for the kind of existence postulated is Consciousness, or the act of thought. His proposition simply means, Existence being thought, I think therefore I exist, or, I think therefore I think. The method of Descartes is a faithful elaboration of his fundamental tenet of consciousness. His capital axiom is, ll All clear and distinct ideas are true" ; which means 1 Whewell : " Hist, of the Inductive Sciences," vol. II., p. 134. 110 THE SCOPE OF LANGUAGE. that thought justifies itself. This rule, although true in the sense that all facts justify or express themselves, is merely an argument against a superstitious belief in causes. It ad- vocates a careful scrutiny of the relations between cause and effect. The assertion that all clear and distinct ideas are true, does not disclose the nature of perception ; nor does the dictum "I think therefore I am " throw any light upon the purely relative nature of the fact of individuality, or per- sonal existence. Descartes, in deducing the existence of God from personal existence, clearly reversed the order of perception ; for God is the Ultimate Reality, the chief fact from which all individual facts are but derivations. In perception, the individual responds to the universe ; and as the individual is but a part of the universe, the fact of personal existence is subordinate to that of general exist- ence, or God. 1 God cannot, therefore, be deduced from consciousness, but consciousness may be deduced from God. The conception of Deity is an ultimate analysis. Every conception, however humble, employs this fact as an inte- gral part. To reduce the above argument to metaphysical terms, God is Motion thoughts, or individual perceptions, are motions. Here we have Divine Unity contrasted with the variety which is expressed in personal life. With Descartes, who read and admired Bacon, and util- ized many of his valuable suggestions, the beginning of modern science was fairly inaugurated. In the metaphysical reasonings of Descartes I am unable to see more profundity or originality than can be found among the ancient Greek and Alexandrian authors. The dissatisfaction with the an- cients, so commonly felt at the time, was more with their science than with their philosophy, more with the paucity of their facts than with the use made of them. 1 This interpretation of consciousness is fully explained in the review of the systems of Herbert Spencer and G. H. Lewes, Part II., where the mind is studied as the activity of an organism. MODERN PHILOSOPHY. 1 1 1 A full appreciation of the greatness of Descartes can be had only by viewing him in the scientific plane of his age. His ideas on physics were elaborated before the other parts of his system, although the fear which the persecution of Galileo inspired delayed for a long time their publication. Descartes saw that it was impossible to write upon philoso- phy without ultimately declaring himself upon these ques- tions, and therefore his true originality was hidden for a time through fear of a conflict with the church. Had he announced his discoveries concerning the operations of nature as they occurred to his mind, he would have des- troyed his influence and imperiled his liberty. His first phil- osophic production was an elaborate exposition of the true method of investigation. Its title was, " Discourse on the Method of Properly Guiding the Reason in the Research of Truth in the Sciences : also the Dioptric, the Meteors, and the Geometry, which are Essays in this Method." It is seen that, in this work, an effort was made to avoid religious controversy. It was distinctly scientific. Of course, in studying the nature of thought, it is necessary to become metaphysical ; but where this occurs, the argument is couched in conciliatory and devout language, with the mani- fest object of escaping the direct charge of infidelity. In the fourth division of the " Discourse on Method " the nature of God and of the human soul is discussed. By a course of reasoning which ignores one difficulty after an- other, the author arrives at the conclusion that the human soul is absolutely distinct from the body 1 ; that this soul is put into the body by a divine being infinitely perfect, whose existence is proved by the ideas we have of his perfection. These ideas disclose to us our imperfection, as the positive discloses the negative, or as being discloses non-being. 8 No one can read the fourth division of the " Discourse on Method " without seeing in it the identical metaphysical reasonings which are most popular with the orthodox writers . 1 " Discours de la Methode," vol. I., pp. 158, 159. * Ibid., vol. I., p. 60. 112 THE SCOPE OF LANGUAGE. of the present day. The popularity of these metaphysics is due to the fact that they are just enough involved to escape the plain statement that God is not a spirit, but the ultimate reality or fact of the universe. The theologians of the seventeenth century, however, were by no means satisfied with these guarded statements ; and although Descartes declared himself a conservative in faith, although he was a " pet pupil of the Jesuits," and strove earnestly to discuss philosophy apart from religion, and to uphold the moral teachings of the church, the appear- ance of his argument on Method was the occasion of a tem- pest of controversy, in which he was bitterly assailed by the leading theologians of the Universities of northern Europe, both Catholic and Calvinistic. These attacks were made by theological theses against Descartes, in some of which the printed comments were so offensive that they were struck out by order of the magistrates of Utrecht. About four years after the appearance of the " Discourse on Method," the " Meditations " made their appearance. These were more religious in tone, and consequently more meta- physical. Unlike his first work, they were written in Latin, and constitute a labored argument about first principles. Although they are considered by many to be the greatest achievement of Descartes, they are in reality the least valu- able of his writings. The " Meditations " was printed in Paris in 1641, with the King's privilege and the approbation of the Doctors of the Sorbonne. The full title was " Medita- tions concerning the First Philosophy, in which are demon- strated the Existence of God and the Immortality of the Soul." The official sanctions under which this work was published were obtained by the direct prayer of Descartes, who felt keenly the attacks made upon his first work. He also took the precaution of having a dozen copies of the " Medi- tations " submitted to the ablest theologians of the time, so that the criticisms might be obtained and published with the author's replies to them, thus establishing the work in a controversial light from the beginning. One of the chief MODERN PHILOSOPHY. 113 results of these criticisms, which came from such distin- guished men as Arnauld, Gassendi, and Hobbes, was to change the discussion of the immortality to the immateriality of the soul, which latter title was more in accordance with the manner in which Descartes treated the subject. The scientific writings, which form the most interesting part of the " Method," were omitted in the " Meditations," which reduce it to a mere enlargement of the metaphysical argument of the first publication. This argument concern- ing the relative importance of the facts of general and per- sonal existence, or of God and the human soul, has been fully dealt with above. The question of the principles of certitude, or the measure of doubt, also receives much attention in the " Meditations." As has already been ex- plained in a previous chapter, this question belongs to the nature of perception, or the study of mind as the function of the organism, and cannot be successfully discussed in the absence of an ultimate physical analysis, or without full un- derstanding of the relation of body and mind. 1 What con- cerns us most is, not the logical position of the " Medita- tions," for this position has been superseded long ago, but the effect which the work wrought upon the world and the life of the author. In the preface to the " Meditations," Descartes, not feel- ing quite satisfied with his proof of the immortality of the soul, says, that a strict proof of this theory would require a complete development of his whole system of physics. He suggests that the first requisite is to form a " clear and distinct " conception of the soul as distinct from the body, because substances thus clearly conceived to be distinct must really be so ; which is in effect " taking firm hold of one's own sleeve in order to jump over the river." In reply to the objection that Hobbes made to this argument, Des- cartes admits that we only infer the difference between mind and body from the difference in their qualities, or ac- tivities, which as above said, at once remands the whole 'See Part II., chap. i. 114 THE SCOPE OF LANGUAGE. question to the study of mind as the function of an organ- ism, or modern psychology. The Protestant theologians of Utrecht and Leyden, irri- tated by the imprudent enthusiasm of one of Descartes' disciples, Le Roy (Regius), began a systematic opposition to the Cartesian philosophy. This movement developed into a persecution which proved a grievous trial to Descartes. It began with disputations by theses in the Universities, which were followed by the public with intense interest. These disputes were confined for some time to general prin- ciples, but Le Roy, wishing to force a logical issue with his adversaries, boldly announced the principle, under the authority of Descartes, that man was a being composed of the two elements of mind and extension ; that he was not a substance per se, but a substance per accidens, which means, that human existence is not an unconditioned fact, but that man is a natural phenomenon, and is therefore the function of his conditions. This announcement was a direct chal- lenge to the powerful orthodox party. The Protestants, represented by Voe't and Arnauld, the rectors of the Uni- versities of Utrecht and Leyden, immediately resented it. The acumen of these theologians can be judged of from the fact that they were Aristotelian in their faith, bitterly opposing the theory of the earth's motion round the sun, which theory they identified with the philosophy of Des- cartes. From our point of view, it would seem as though all the best thought and intelligence of the seventeenth cen- tury were arrayed against Christian orthodoxy, but this is hardly fair either to the early Protestants or the Catholics ; for religion does not oppose science because it is science, but because new theories of life and mind disturb the authority and dignity of the church. As long as religion attaches her faith to persons instead of to principles, to fixed creeds hav- ing the authority of mysterious books instead of to the great principles of human progress, so long will those discoveries which are the natural movement of life disturb her peace. A religion on the contrary which identifies God with the Uni- MODERN PHILOSOPHY. 115 versal Principle will employ science as a great moral power, enlisting in its services the best efforts of the mind. The Calvinist theologians, headed by Voet, were so bitter in their attacks on Descartes, that an appeal to the Prince of Orange was necessary to put a stop to the persecution. The authority of this prince alone saved the theories of Des- cartes from being formally expelled from the University teachings, and his books from being publicly burned by the hangman of Utrecht. The right of private judgment, which was the fundamental principle of the Cartesian philosophy, first excited the opposition of the church, both Protestant and Catholic ; for Christianity rests its judgments or per- ceptions upon the theory of faith originated by the Alexan- drian mystics. The enduring part of Descartes' system, that which has fairly won for him the name of a great thinker, was his original investigations of natural phenomena and his able criticisms of the sciences. His metaphysics, his reasonings concerning existence, as above indicated, were not in ad- vance of the best Greek thought. Epicurus made a more perfect synthesis of life, Anaximano^er a far keener analysis of first principles; but Descartes gathered together the learning of his age, enriched it with new investigations, and co-ordinated it into a system of knowledge which will ever bear his name and mark an epoch in human history. The science of mathematics is purely a study of motion and its aspects ; that is to say, it expresses all its results in terms of time and space, or of number and quantity, which are but the aspects of motion. Descartes felt that all phenomena could be reduced to terms of time and space, and thus " insisted upon the only true path ever followed by physical science its reduction to the mathematical laws of figure and of motion. " Having first shown," says Prof. MahafTy, " that by the earliest of his discoveries all problems in figure could be reduced to arithmetical formulae, and that these could be generalized by the use of algebraic symbols, he insisted that Il6 THE SCOPE OF LANGUAGE. nothing should be assumed in explaining the laws of nature but the laws of figure and motion. He cast to the winds the whole apparatus of occult qualities, intuitional species, and other assumed secrets by which the scholastic Peri- patetics endeavored to explain, and by which they succeeded in obscuring and confusing, nature." The boldness and novelty of this position of Descartes' can only be appreciated by looking at his scientific sur- roundings. In our day, we are so accustomed to the asser- tion that all phenomena can be expressed in terms of mo- tion, that the importance of this great truth escapes us. How few among those to whom this proposition is familiar are willing to admit its full significance, that all phenomena means all life, and that the term life includes mind. Des- cartes, even, failed to rigorously follow out the meaning of his own induction. He states that all phenomena can be expressed in terms of motion, which distinctly means that motion is the ultimate fact of life ; and yet the fundamental principle of his metaphysics, or his analysis of knowledge, is, that consciousness, or mind, is the ultimate fact of life. His application of algebra to geometry, or his expression of space relationships in algebraic symbols, led to the de- velopment of the fluctional calculus elaborated by Newton and Leibnitz, which constitutes the most exact portrayal science affords of infinitesimal measurements or motions. This discovery of Descartes' raised the science of geometry from a mass of isolated demonstrations of figure and meas- urement, as it came to us from the ancients, to a system of abstract calculations, in which given powers of co-efficients are made to represent constant space relationships. Thus Descartes introduced his philosophy with brilliant discourses in mathematics and physics, which at once commanded the attention of scholars, and gave to his more abstract reason- ings a reputation which they could not have achieved of themselves. " The Principles of Philosophy," the first planned and last published of his capital works, was the most thorough of MODERN PHIL OSOPH Y. 117 them all ; and yet the author admits that this great treatise on physics was incomplete, inasmuch as it was not extended to the treatment of plants, animals, and lastly of man ; so that what is generally supposed to be the greatest logical feat of Descartes his postulate that consciousness is the ultimate fact of the universe is seen to be a direct contra- diction of his best and most original teachings, which tended to subordinate individual to general existence, or conscious- ness to the more general fact of Motion, or God. Benedict Spinoza was born in Amsterdam, in 1632, of a Hebrew family that had moved from Portugal to escape persecution. He studied under the auspices of the Jewish church of his native city ; but his mind soon rebelled against the limits of this religion, and the Rabbins, finding it impos- sible to change his course, visited upon him the then terrible penalty of excommunication. Among the ancients, the word piety seems to have been employed in the sense which we give to the word humanity. It had less to do with formal beliefs and more with charac- ter. A man who sought universal truth, for its own sake, was considered pious. The Greeks knew less of the importance of religious dis- cipline than we do ; being without the past two thousand years of human experience, they were unable to distinguish between intellectual and moral exercise as factors in social advancement. Again : the intellectuality of the Greeks was less taught, more spontaneous, than ours. The great! fact that thought purifies was constantly before them. A man, to be a great thinker in Greece, had to do, for the most part, his own thinking. He had not our facilities for imbibing thought ready-made from others. Those wide sympathies which are the necessary accompaniment of a deep understanding of life, presuppose a certain moral advancement. To discourse of God, or the Universal Prin- ciple, in Greece, was not that semi-mechanical operation which we so often see among religious teachers of more recent times. It was an enthusiasm for the higher or most Il8 THE SCOPE OF LANGUAGE. general truths, at once elevating and purifying to the whole life. This thoughtful and devotional cast of mind the ancients called piety. It demanded a certain capacity, an earnest and sustained effort to bring the mind into harmony with its farthest surroundings ; an effort which is sure in time to compel moral development. It was this kind of piety that was the inspiration of Spinoza's life ; and so completely did it possess him, that the sentence of excommunication with its terrible conse- quences did not even seem to depress him. His life is a singular instance of the resources which we possess in the higher sentiments. It was not considered enough for the ancient Jewish doctors to be scholars ; they were required also to learn some mechanical art by which to support themselves. Spinoza learned the art of polishing glasses for optical instru- ments, in which he attained great proficiency. To escape persecution, he retired to Leyden or Rynsberg, where he passed the life of a recluse, devoting himself to study. A heroic firmness that is truly invigorating to contem- plate shines throughout the life of this man. Our deepest admiration is aroused by his independence of spirit, his cheer- ful nature, his moderate wants and indefatigable industry. In the doctrines of Spinoza we have a worthy study. Many have complained of the abstruseness of his writings, but this is largely due to his persistent effort to reduce all his generalizations to mathematical forms of expression. The language of numbers and quantities is too cold and inflexible to serve as a medium of philosophic thought. To give an idea of the rigidity of Spinoza's style, we cite a few of his celebrated definitions, and place opposite to them the interpretation which the reduction of the cate- gories of thought to a single principle enables one to make. " DEFINITION III. By Substance I Existence is the ultimate reality, or understand that which exists in itself, Motion. Substance, of course, has a and is conceived/^r se ; in other words, place in the conception of Motion, the conception of which does not re- For if matter and space are the same MODERN PHILOSOPHY. quire the conception of any thing else antecedent to it." " DEF. VI. By God I understand the Being absolutely infinite, i. e., the Substance consisting of infinite At- tributes, each of which expresses an infinite and eternal essence. "Explanation. I say absolutely in- finite, but not infinite suo genere j for to whatever is infinite only suo ge- nere we can deny infinite Attributes ; but that which is absolutely infinite includes in its essence every thing which implies essence and involves no negation." " DEF. VIII. By Eternity I under- stand Existence itself, in as far as it is conceived necessarily to follow from the sole definition of an eternal thing." thing, and space is merely an aspect of Motion, our conception of Sub- stance is a part of that of Motion. If absolute means time, and infinite means space, God, or the ultimate generalization or reality, and Motion, are convertible terms ; they mean the same thing, for the aspects of Motion being space and time, and the attri- butes of God the infinite and the ab- solute, they are convertible terms, and must point to the same fact. The "Explanation" of the defini- tion I consider more involved than the definition itself, and therefore not, properly speaking, an explanation. There is but one clear meaning to the word Eternity, and that is Time. Time is an aspect of Motion, and is therefore an aspect of Existence. In No. III. Spinoza says that Substance is Existence itself, and in No. VIII., that eternity is Existence itself. In one case he means Space and in the other Time, and in both his words ex- press the conception of Motion, which includes Space and Time. At the risk of being tedious, we select the seventh and eighth of Spinoza's Propositions with the Scholium attached, in order to show how necessary it is to be definite and clear with regard to the meaning of ultimate terms in forming a final generalization, and also what store Spinoza placed by his ultimate generalization, which he called Substance. " PROPOSITION VII. It pertains to the nature of Substance to exist. " Demonstration. Substance cannot be created by any thing else, and is, therefore, the cause of itself ; its essence necessarily involves existence ; or it pertains to the nature of Substance to exist." " PROP. VIII. All Substance is necessarily infinite. " Dem. There exists but one Substance of the same Attribute ; and it must either exist as infinite or as finite. But not as finite, for as finite it must be 120 THE SCOPE OF LANGUAGE. limited by another Substance of the same nature, and in that case there would be two Substances of the same Attribute, which is absurd. Substance, there- fore, is infinite." " Scholium. I do not doubt that to all who judge confusedly of things, and are not wont to inquire into first causes, it will be difficult to understand the demonstration of Prop. VII., because they do not sufficiently distinguish between the modifications of Substance and Substance itself, and are ignorant of the manner in which things are produced. Here it follows, that seeing natural things have a commencement, they attribute a commencement to Sub- stances ; for he who knows not the true causes of things confounds all things, and sees no reason why trees should not talk like men, or why men should not be formed from stones as well as from seeds, or why all forms cannot be changed into all other forms. So, also, those who confound the divine nature with the human naturally attribute human affections to God, especially as they are ig- norant how these affections are produced in the mind. But if men attended to the nature of Substance, they would not in the least doubt the truth of Prop. VII. ; nay, this proposition would be an axiom to all, and would be numbered among the common notions." This effort of Spinoza at mathematical exactness in thought serves to bring out boldly the nature of the final problem of philosophy. It demonstrates also the impos- sibility of using more than one term to denote the Ultimate Reality, unless the equivalence of meaning between the terms is distinctly laid down. It also shows how necessary it is to determine the exact relationship existing between all the categories, such as time, space, matter or Substance, force, the infinite, the absolute, etc. Time and Eternity are used by Spinoza without any acknowledgment that they mean the same thing. Again : space, matter, extension, infinite, follow in close succession without any effort being made to harmonize or compare their meanings ; whereas in their widest sense they mean precisely the same thing. This important fact is brought out indirectly by Spinoza's own arguments ; for a careful examination of the exhaustive definitions of Substance which he offers shows that it is impossible to establish any ultimate difference between the meaning of the terms he employs to denote space or extension. Again : the words essence, substance, God, and existence, are used repeatedly in a similar sense, and yet no distinct declaration is made of i ft '< MODERN PHILOSOPHY. 121 their equivalence of meaning. Is it any wonder that meta- physics should have been declared a failure by the ancient skeptics, and an effete science by modern agnostics ? And yet how remarkable it is to see throughout the writings of these schools an ever-renewed effort to solve the meta- physical problem ! It is impossible to discuss philosophy in any of its phases without including, directly or indirectly, this problem. In- deed, so fundamental is this great question of the meaning of ultimate terms, that scarcely a thought or feeling can be imagined that is not, in some degree, influenced by it ; and the science of metaphysics, instead of being the farthest removed from practical life, is really the mainspring of all human action, for it identifies and correlates the energies of the mind with those of the universe. When this simple solution of the metaphysical problem shall have become the property of the thinking world, the illogical misgivings which we call skepticism, or agnosticism, will disappear, with all those lower forms of belief in mys- tery known as superstition, and it will be no longer necessary for the mind to become shipwrecked among the meanings of ultimate terms in the outset of the study of human progress. Spinoza was the opposite of a skeptic. Although it has by no means been acknowledged that his system success- fully refutes the doctrines of skepticism, it opposes these doctrines consistently throughout. Here the difference between Spinoza and Lewes appears. Spinoza declares that our knowledge is real, that our impressions of things disclose their real nature. Lewes says that our knowledge is only knowledge of phenomena, and therefore does not disclose the actual nature of things ; which is a gratuitous assertion that the actual is a mystery, or something that cannot be understood. There is perhaps no more direct way of explaining the philosophy of Spinoza than by quoting his argument against the teleological interpretation of nature : this argument 122 THE SCOPE OF LANGUAGE. occurs in the form of an Appendix to the book " De Deo " : " Men do all things for the sake of an end, namely, the good, or useful, which they desire. Hence it comes that they always seek to know only the final causes of things which have taken place, and when they have heard these they are satisfied, not having within themselves any cause for further doubt. But if they are unable to learn these final causes from some one else, nothing remains to them but to turn in upon themselves, and to reflect upon the ends by which they are themselves wont to be determined to similar actions ; and thus they necessarily judge of the mind of another by their own. Further: as within them- selves and out of themselves they discover many means which are highly conducive to the pursuit of their own advantage, for example, eyes to see with, teeth to masticate with, vegetables and animals for food, the sun to give them light, the sea to nourish fish, etc., so they come to consider all natural things as means for their benefit : and because they are aware that these things have been found, and were not prepared by them, they have been led to be- lieve that some one else has adapted these means to their use. For after considering things in the light of means, they could not believe these things to have made themselves, but arguing from their own practice of preparing means for their use, they must conclude that there is some ruler or rulers of nature endowed with human freedom, who have provided all these things for them, and have made them all for the use of men. Moreover, since they have never heard any thing of the mind of those rulers, they must necessarily judge of this mind also by their own ; and hence they have argued that the Gods direct all things for the advantage of man, in order that they may subdue him to themselves, and be held in the highest honor by him. Hence each has devised, according to his character, a different mode of worshipping God, in order that God might love him more than others, and might direct all nature to the advantage of his blind cupidity and insatiable avarice. Thus this preju- MODERN PHILOSOPHY. 123 dice has converted itself into superstition, and has struck deep root into men's minds ; and this has been the cause why men in general have eagerly striven to explain the final causes of all things. But while they have sought to show that Nature does nothing in vain (i. e. which is not fit for the use of men,) they seem to me to have shown nothing else than that Nature and the Gods are as foolish as men. And observe, I pray you, to what a point this opinion has brought them. Together with the many useful things in Nature, they necessarily found not a few injurious things, namely, tempests, earthquakes, diseases, etc. ; these, they supposed, happened because the Gods were angry on account of offences committed against them by men, or because of faults incurred in their worship ; and although experience every day protests, and shows by infinite ex- amples, that benefits and injuries happen indifferently to pious and ungodly persons, they do not therefore renounce their inveterate prejudice." This simple and commanding argument remands humanity to its due place in the universe, and rebukes that inordi- nate conceit which is known in metaphysics as Idealism, and in general philosophy as Anthropomorphism. The former appropriates all reality to the mind, and the latter all nature to the purposes of man. The charge of athe- ism which was so generally brought against Spinoza rests chiefly upon his unfortunate selection of the term Sub- stance to designate the Ultimate Reality ; for it naturally shocks the understanding to designate God by that single aspect of the Universal Principle which we call Substance, Infinity, or Space. In using the word Substance in this widest of its applications, Spinoza meant the substance of existence, or life, the ultimate fact, rather than the statical aspect of the universe which we call Matter or Space. The justice of the claim for Spinoza that he distinctly appreciated the divine unity of nature, and rose above the level of ideal- ism, and all other teleological interpretations of life, none who carefully follow his thought will dispute. The most 124 THE SCOPE OF LANGUAGE. condensed description of his philosophy, and one on the main points of which all the best authorities agree, is given by Lewes. " There is but one infinite Substance, and that is God. Whatever is, is in God ; and without Him, nothing can be conceived. He is the universal Being of which all things are the manifestations. He is the sole Substance ; every thing else is a mode; yet, without Substance, Mode cannot exist. God, viewed under the attributes of Infinite Substance, is the natura naturans, viewed as a manifesta- tion, as the Modes under which his attributes appear, he is the natura naturata. He is the cause of all things, and that immanently, but not transiently. He has two infinite at- tributes Extension and Thought. Extension is visible Thought, and Thought is invisible Extension ; they are the Objective and Subjective of which God is the Identity. Eveiy thing \s a mode of God's attribute of Extension ; every thought, wish, or feeling, a mode of his attribute of Thought. * * * Substance is uncreated, but creates by the internal necessity of its nature. There may be many existing things, but only one existence ; many forms, but only one Substance.. God is the idea immanens the One and All." The obvious fault in this analysis of existence, or life, is, that thought is regarded as an ultimate fact, a fact as simple and general as space or extension an attribute or aspect of God ; whereas thought is a very complex phenomenon re- quiring a vast plexus of conditions. It presupposes the facts of sentiency, of organic life, of individuality, and is therefore far removed in the scale of generality from the subjective aspect or attribute of God, which is the meaning that Spinoza applies to it. Again : Extension is said to be the opposite aspect of God, the antithesis of thought ; while thought, again, is said to be invisible extension. Confusions here are multiplied, for matter is the name commonly given to that space or extension which is sufficiently tangible to be called visible ; and although thought, viewed as the activity of an organism, has a distinct statical aspect, there is surely no necessity for confusing the ideas of thought and matter., MODERN PHILOSOPHY. 125 This is where Spinoza has laid himself opten to the charge of Pantheism, that theory which invests all nature, animate and inanimate, with an inherent faculty of thought, and con- fusing again the ideas of thought and God, disseminates, as it were, a thinking spirit of God throughout the universe, a sort of magnificent fetichism, filling all things with an omnipotent mystery. How different from that simple and pure conception of Deity which demarcates thought as simply an aspect of individuality, recognising in God, or general existence, the divine principle of Life, having eter- nity and infinity respectively for its subjective and objective aspects. Spinoza did not carry his impeachment of the teleological interpretation of nature far enough ; for, although he ex- posed the presumption of the belief that nature moves for the benefit of man, he confused that attribute of man which we call thought with the subjective aspect of God. This confusion was a natural consequence of the Cartesian dualism (in which philosophy Spinoza had thoroughly grounded him- self), and also furnished an excuse for the extravagances of German idealism which were soon to follow. Spinoza's greatest work is " Ethics Demonstrated by a Geometrical Method," from which most of the foregoing quotations are given. It is generally admitted that this work is a masterpiece of metaphysical reasoning, and many writers say that it has never been successfully attacked, such is the rigor and precision of its deductions. Spinoza lived a life of retirement and privation, princi- pally in Holland, where he was, in a measure, protected from the fierce religious persecution of the seventeenth century. For more than a hundred years after his death he was generally stigmatized as an atheist and a monster. The German scholars of Goethe's time, notwithstanding these epithets, promptly recognized his great genius and the touching sublimity of his life and character. Goethe says of him, the man was represented an "Atheist, and his opinions as most abominable ; but immediately after, it is admitted 126 THE SCOPE OF LANGUAGE. that he was a calm, reflective, diligent scholar, a good cit- izen, a sympathizing neighbor, and a peaceable domestic man." Just at the close of Descartes' career, and before the great unity of Spinoza's thought had been given to the world, a mind of singular power and clearness made its appearance in England. Thomas Hobbes, like most of the scientific men of his time, was an eminent mathematician. He studied at Oxford, where the Ptolemaic system of astronomy was still taught, and where the philosophic lectures were chiefly confined to scholastic metaphysics. This was before the law of gravitation or the fluctional calculus had been dis- covered, as Newton and Leibnitz were in their boyhood. The circulation of the blood, which had been known to the Chinese five hundred years before, 1 had just been announced in England by Harvey. The conservation and equivalence of the physical forces was a fact hardly as yet suspected. Galileo had discovered the spots on the sun, the satellites of Jupiter, and Saturn's rings, and was dis- cussing other questions of astronomy with the monks of the Holy Inquisition. Kepler was engaged in working out his laws of the planetary motions. Milton, who had been carefully taught at Christ's College, Cambridge, that the sun turned round the earth, was planning the scene of his great drama of Heaven. The genius of Shakespeare, thirty years after the great poet's death, was not yet recognized. The language of France was just attaining its present state of perfection under the magic sentences of Moliere ; and, as above indicated, Descartes, the first modern who applied to philosophy the rule of scientific investigation, had but a few years before published his " Meditations." It was with these surroundings that Hobbes, by a masterly analysis of the facts of consciousness, laid the foundations of the science of psychology, which has since attained to such development in England. Bacon before him had insisted that facts could alone be * the foundation of knowledge ; that theories, or 1 And to at least one Italian physiologist. MODERN PHILOSOPHY. 12? ideas, must always be subservient to facts. Proceeding upon- this slow but sure method, Hobbes, in a style that is simple, powerful, and clear, analyzed consciousness and thereby in- dicated the solution of the great problems of the scope of language and the nature of perception, which can alone afford an understanding of the relations of life and mind. It : is also interesting to note that at this time the world had not yet heard of the adventures of German thought, as Germany was lying prostrate under the terrible effects of the Thirty Years' War, which had virtually destroyed her civilization. Her great intellectual life had not as yet begun. Hence^ Hobbes had no bad examples of modern idealism to influ- ence him (Berkeley and Kant were yet unborn) ; nor do his writings show that he troubled himself much about the. dialectics of Plato, or the logical difficulties of the Skeptics. The insight which Hobbes had of the all-important question of the scope of language is intimated by his famous aphor- ism : " Words are wise men's counters ; they do but reckon, by them ; but they are the money of fools." This shows that he had studied out the great truth that language springs, from action, and that thought is a part of action inseparable in nature from the simplest organic and even inorganic ac- tivities. Instead of this being materialism, it is the most exalted view of the mind, for it identifies mind with life, explaining the presence of the infinite and the absolute in our conceptions as the obverse aspects of the Universal Principle of life, or Motion. But it must not be assumed that Hobbes made a perfect analysis of the mind, that would have been impossible with the limited scientific advantages of his time ; but his conclusions, as far as they went, are the result of a careful study of facts, and are therefore valuable : he did not attempt those purely theoretical constructions, which have since taken up so much room in philosophy. The connection between thought and sensation is de- scribed by Hobbes with a candor and simplicity which is re- freshing, after reading the tortuous theories of the meta- physicians. It is now a well-established fact that sensation 128 THE SCOPE OF LANGUAGE, and thought are but different phases of the activity of a sen- tient organism. Thoughts are those vastly more complex co-ordinations of impressions which the highly-structured nervous organism, through the condensing process of lan- guage, accomplishes within us ; while sensation is the com- paratively simple external view of isolated impressions. But as there is no absolute dividing line between the muscle and the nerve, or between motorial and psychical phenom- ena, sensation insensibly becomes thought, and thought again sensation. These facts of psychology will be fully ex- plained in the review of Lewes' works on the subject, which occurs under the study of the nature of perception, in Part II. The object in thus mentioning them in advance is to show how clearly Hobbes perceived the true relations be- tween body and mind. Thus, in speaking of the origin of ideas, he says : " When a body is once in motion it moveth, unless something hinder it, eternally ; and whatsoever hinder- eth it, cannot in an instant, but in time and by degrees, quite extinguish it ; and as we see in the water, though the wind cease, the waves give not over rolling for a long time after : so also it happeneth in that motion which is made in the internal parts of man. * * * For after the object is re- moved, or the eye shut, we still retain an image of the thing seen, though more obscure than when we see it. * * * The decay [subsiding] of sense in men waking is not the de- cay of the motion made in sense, but an obscuring of it, in such manner as the light of the sun obscureth the light of the stars ; which stars do no less exercise their virtue, by which they are visible, in the day than in the night. But because amongst many strokes which our eyes, ears, and other organs, receive from external bodies, the predominant only is sensible ; therefore the light of the sun being pre- dominant, we are not affected with the action of the stars." The fault of Hobbes' analysis is not its incorrectness, but its incompleteness. As far as he goes, he has contributed to the science of psychology. It is true that his works lay neglected until James Mill discerned their merits ; that Par- MODERN PHILOSOPHY. 129 liament passed censure upon them on account of the oppo- sition they excited from the church ; but this is due more to the ethical and sociological development of Hobbes' thought than to any thing repulsive in his analysis of mind. The ethics of Hobbes are any thing but attractive, and his ideas of social development were as faulty as the exceeding complexity and difficulty of the subject, and the fact that it had hardly been touched upon before him, excepting in a purely theoretical manner, would lead us to expect. Auguste Comte, who was practically the originator of sociological science, belongs to two centuries later. Such writings as the " Republic " of Plato can hardly be said to belong to a methodical study of the great problems of social life. Hence, when we read of " Hobbes' Theory of Govern- ment," and the " Social Contract," we expect little that is instructive, and we are not disappointed. Hobbes teaches that the natural state of man is war, or mutual opposition, and that society consists in the establish- ment of an authority over him sufficient to overcome this opposition. The end of society, therefore, is to suppress the natural propensities of man, not as we understand it, to develop his better nature. The absurd part of Hobbes' doc- trine is the theory that the cause of the formation of society is the " misery of the natural state of war," and whether the authority exerted to suppress this natural state be founded upon the right of superior strength or cunning, or upon jus- tice, matters not, providing it be strong enough to suppress the state of war. According to Hobbes, the justification of a government is in its strength, and therefore an absolute monarchy is the best form of government, because the strongest. It is easy to understand how his philosophy, loaded down as it was with these imperfect theories, was neglected for two centuries, and is even yet regarded with enmity by many. Not until the elder Mill discriminated Hobbes' valuable analysis of mind from his ethical and sociological theories, was this great English thinker appreciated even by his own countrymen. 130 THE SCOPE OF LANGUAGE. While Spinoza was quietly elaborating his system of philosophy in Holland, and Newton and Leibnitz were uncon- sciously vying with each other in the higher mathematics, the study of mind, as the function of an organism, was taken up where Hobbes had left it and further developed by John Locke (1632-1704). He, too, studied at Oxford and became a mathematician, but principally devoted himself to medi- cine, in which science he attained marked proficiency. His life was cast in those troublous times in England when the principle of the " Divine Right of Kings," which James the First had introduced from Scotland, was being tested by the contending political and religious parties over which his son Charles the First tried to reign. The Scotch Covenanters, so terribly in earnest in resisting that ritual in which they saw but a return to the despotism of Rome ; the discontented Romanists, representing a large part of the culture and rank of the nation ; the English Puritans, who opposed and mistrusted them ; that large class of dissolute nobles, the immoral tlite of England, too selfish to espouse any religion for its own sake, too unintelli- gent to adopt any broad national policy, supporting Royalty but for its emoluments and license, and laying up by their vices and crimes that reaction which Cromwell rose to con- trol ; among these circumstances it was that England ex- hausted, at least for herself, the question of the divine right of kings. And this was the political, social, and moral at- mosphere in which the ideas of Locke were formulated and promulgated. Toleration was a word of vast importance in those days ; hence the conciliatory tone of Locke's writ- ings. Many have mistaken his disposition to avoid too pronounced assertions on ultimate questions for logical weakness or mediocrity : thus Leibnitz calls Locke poor in thought, " paufertina philosophia" This view has been taken up by so many critics, that one who approaches Locke through his general reputation is .surprised to find through- out his writings so much vigor and firmness of thought. His aim seems to have been to create a feeling against Scholasti- MODERN PHILOSOPHY. 131 cism, or purely theoretical philosophy and its interminable disputes, and to study the workings of the mind with a view to discovering what it could do and what it could not do. His philosophy, therefore, was that of experience ; for he examined into what the human mind did after it became a mind more than into the genesis of consciousness. In modern philosophic writings the popular term for that branch of inquiry which begins with the fact of mind, and proceeds to study its assimilation of ideas, is a posteriori (or that which comes after the fact of mind). The term which denotes an inquiry into those principles which are anterior to the fact of mind is a priori. It has been the habit of that school of writers in which Kant is pre-eminent to fix upon arbitrary categories or forms of thought and call them a priori ideas, for natu- rally enough they could not explain the existence of the mind from purely mental experiences. Without any attempt to explain the genesis of these a priori ideas, however, they proceed to build up vast theoretical systems in which the mind is the central mystery, to which all the other mysteries of their theories are made to point. To these a priori phi- losophers, or modern idealists, who have prospered most in the intellectual climate of Germany, we will give attention in the following chapter. Locke, as the successor of Bacon and Hobbes, occupied a hostile position toward this school, which was the beginning of that broad divergence so plainly seen to-day between theoretical and practical philosophy, or the German idealists and the English psychologists. Locke's principal philosophical work was written as early as 1671, although it was not published until 1690. The cause of this long delay was not improbably a very natural reluctance to augment by any possible means the fierce re- ligious disputes which were raging in England, and indeed throughout Europe, during his entire life. This theory becomes all the more probable when we compare his utter- ances on religious subjects with the general clearness and 132 THE SCOPE OF LANGUAGE. depth of his thought. In this regard let us first consider his ethical theories. Although Locke taught a belief in a personal God, whose will was the source of all morality in man, he made the scope of moral conceptions purely human, or organic, by resolving the meaning of good and evil into that of pleasure and pain, making the ultimate test of virtue the degree in which it promotes pleasure and averts pain. This is a logical necessity, to which all writers upon ethics are eventually brought ; for the fundamental fact of individ- ual or organic life is personal existence, and pleasure or happiness, used in its broadest sense, means successful exist- ence, or life ; and pain, used in its broadest sense, means the opposite of this, or death. The question of conduct, therefore, in its simplest form, is a question of life and death ; in its developed form it becomes a study of the most successful or highest life. Al- though Locke says that he believes morality can be reduced to a science, which means that conduct can be reasoned from its origin in the principle of life to all its applications in the details of our existence, he nevertheless makes use of much conventional and theological phraseology which de- prives his system of the purity, breadth, and consistency which is demanded of such writings in our time. For in- stance, after reasoning against the existence of any innate moral rule or idea, he says : " The true ground of morality can only be the will and law of God, who sees in the dark, has in his hands rewards and punishments, and power enough to call to account the proudest of offenders ; for God having by an inseparable connection joined virtue and public happiness together, it is no wonder that every one should not only allow, but recommend and magnify, those rules to others, from whose observance of them he is seen to reap advantage himself. The conveniences of this life make men own an outward profession and approbation of them, whose actions sufficiently prove that they but little con- sider the lawgiver that prescribed these rules, or the hell MODERN PHILOSOPHY. 133 he has ordained for the punishment of those that transgress them." * Thus we see that, although Locke rebelled against the theory of innate or supernatural ideas, he had a very me- chanical way of looking upon the relations between the di- vine and the human. He seemed to think that the divine meant a God fashioned after man, dealing out rewards and punishments in a distinctively human manner, and even employing a mechanical hell to enforce his will. All this seems unworthy of the breadth of Locke's mind ; but we must remember the times in which he lived and the condi- tion of religious knowledge in England during the seven- teenth century. After the above quotation, however, it is not without wonder that we read the following ethical com- parisons : " Yet, if we ask a Christian who has the views of happiness and misery in another life, why a man must keep his word, he will give this as a reason : Because God, who has the power of eternal life and de^ath, requires it of us. But if a Hobbist be asked why, he will answer: Because the public requires it, and the Leviathan will punish you if you do not. And if one of the old philosophers had been asked, he would have answered : Because it was dishonest, below the dignity of a man, and opposite to virtue, the highest perfection of human nature, to do otherwise." 2 This shows a complete independence of superstition ; and we are compelled to believe that Locke, like Descartes, knew better than he thought it advisable to write on re- ligious matters ; or else, that he had not harmonized his thoughts on the existence and nature of God with the results of his other investigations. This opinion is confirmed by such passages as the following, which, although they do not deny, are surely intended to undermine the belief in a supernatural revelation. " So God might by revelation discover the truth of any proposition in Euclid, as well as men by the natural use of their faculties come to make the discovery themselves. In all things of this kind there is J " Essay Concerning Human Understanding," vol. I., p. 62. * Ibid., p. 61. 134 THE SCOPE OF LANGUAGE. little need or use of revelation, God having furnished us with natural and surer means to arrive at the knowledge of them. For whatsoever truth we come to the clear discovery of, from the knowledge and contemplation of our own ideas, will always be certainer to us than those which are con- veyed to us by traditional revelation. For the knowledge we have that this revelation came at first from God can never be so sure as the knowledge we have from the clear and distinct perception of the agreement or disagreement of our own ideas. * * * The history of the deluge is conveyed to us by writings which had their original from revelation ; and yet nobody, I think, will say he has as certain and clear a knowledge of the flood as Noah, that saw it ; or that he himself would have had, had he then been alive and seen it. For he has no greater assurance than that of his senses that it is writ in the book supposed writ by Moses inspired ; but he has not so great an assurance that Moses writ that book as if he had seen Moses write it." 1 The extreme timidity of this criticism of the authorship of the Pentateuch is to be contrasted with the confidence with which Professor Max Miiller now speaks upon the sub- ject to the English public ; but it should be remembered that Mr. Miiller now places the latest known revelation of God to man as far back as Abraham, 2 which renders all the historical surroundings of Moses perfectly natural. The task which Locke set himself in writing the " Essay on Human Understanding" was, " to inquire into the original certainty and extent of human knowledge, together with the grounds and degrees of belief, opinion and assent " ; or, as we would express it to-day, to examine into the objects of perception, and the principles of certitude, as distinguished from the nature of perception. Thus he confined 1 "Works of John Locke," vol. III., pp. 140, 141. 3 ' ' And if we are asked how this one Abraham possessed not only the primitive intuition of God as He had revealed Himself to all mankind, but passed through the denial of all other gods to the knowledge of the one God, we are content to answer that it was by a special Divine Revelation." Max Miiller, "Chips from a German Workshop," vol. I., p. 367. MODERN PHILOSOPHY. 135 himself to that branch of psychology which begins with the fact of mind. Locke, employing the ancient simile, viewed the mind as a tablet upon which experience records its impressions ; a very inadequate way of looking upon mental phenomena, as it leaves out of view many prominent conditions. What resemblance is there, for instance, between a white tablet, which certainly has no reactionary power of its own, and a complex organism of definite structure, and therefore predetermined functions or activities, existing in a medium of language or intelligence which also has a definite structure, and hence the power of reacting in a prede- termined manner ? The study of language as the social factor in mental phe- nomena, by such men as Comte, Spencer, and Lewes, has yielded rich results for psychology ; but this view of lan- guage was scarcely entertained in the time of Locke. The nearest approach to this great subject which he made was his dim foreshadowing of the " association of ideas," afterward developed by Hartley and Mill. But Locke had enough to do to combat the doctrine of innate ideas, which was so generally accepted in his time. It was acknowledged that there are predispositions of the mind which give to in- dividuals, through the accumulated modifications of heredity, understandings of things, or conceptions, which are practi- cally before experience ; but these inherited mental ten- dencies were regarded as ultimate psychological facts defy- ing analysis, and taking the form of arbitrary, irreducible categories of thought. This is the theory which Locke op- posed, and well he might, for its influence has been so per- sistent as to have governed the metaphysical opinions of even such recent thinkers as Mill and Spencer, both of whom, as will be abundantly shown hereafter, devoutly believe in a priori, unknowable conceptions which they postulate as irre- ducible and mysterious figments of the mind, whence all thought springs. The strange part of this modern a priori philosophy is that 136 THE SCOPE OF LANGUAGE. its advocates include among the mental mysteries the fact of Consciousness itself, 1 which really throws all these specula- tions about the ultimate principles of mind into hopeless confusion. Locke taught that the source of all our ideas is sensation ; and that thought, or reflection, is the apprehension and gen- eralization of facts. This is strictly in accordance with the best conceptions of modern psychology, if the consideration be not omitted that the organ of thought, which is now called the sensorium, is only developed by experience, and, therefore, that its structures contain a potentiality which is a factor in the formation of ideas ; in a word, without this definite structure ideas would be impossible, and experience, as an educator of ideas, would be in vain. It is interesting to see how Locke approaches the prob- lem of the categories of thought. Our idea of Space, he says, is derived from sight and touch. These experiences are co-ordinated and generalized until we form a symbol or general idea of all externals, co-existences, or Space. This idea of Locke shows how much deeper down in the scale of reality is Motion than its aspects, Space and Time ; for what myriads of motions, both subjective and objective, are im- plied in the phenomena of sight and touch, and the co-ordina- tions of their results in thought ! In the review of Herbert Spencer's works, this theory, that the origin of our conception of Space is the " sense of resistance," will be found clearly and fully developed, giving us one of many points of resemblance between the writings of Locke and Spencer. To those who have made themselves conversant with mod- ern philosophy, the writings of Locke are an unfailing source of interest, as they show that the psychology for which Eng- land has become so famous is but a generic development of his thought. Improving upon the psychology of Locke, David Hartley (1705-1757), an eminent English physician, propounded the 1 See Spencer's " First Principles," and Mill's " Logic." MODERN PHILOSOPHY. 137 " vibration theory " as an explanation of the association of ideas. In his celebrated work, " Observations on Man," upon which he labored from 1730 to 1746 (first published in 1749), he tells us that his idea of a physical basis to mind, or that there is a physical explanation possible of sensation and thought connecting the two as muscular action and sensa- tion, was first suggested to him by the Principia of Newton. The theory of "the association of ideas " can, in a simpler form, be traced as far back as Aristotle. Hobbes noticed the principle under the name of " mental discourse," but Locke gave it its present familiar name. Hartley acknowledges his obligation to a dissertation by the Rev. Mr. Gay prefixed to the translation of Archbishop King's " Origin of Evil," in which the principle of " the association of ideas " is applied to moral phenomena ; but Hartley was the first to definitely formulate this principle, which is now " applied to the different practical fields of language, law, morals, politics, education, religion, and soci- ology," 1 into a philosophic system, and to make its enunci- ation the study of a lifetime. It is to be seen from the fact that this principle was first advocated by men of acknowl- edged religious spirit, that the ideas of evolution are the natural fruit of the most devout minds. Hartley endeavored to prove that the primal fact of con- sciousness had its physical expression in changes in the nerve centres of the thinking being, and that the structures of the nervous system centring in the brain were the physi- cal counterpart of all mental phenomena ; " that our ideas spring up, or exist, in the order in which the sensations ex- isted of which they are copies." The order of occurrence of ideas, therefore, is determined by the past activities of the mind as we find them registered in the structures of the brain. The happiness of this thought is manifest to those who have traced its development in the psychological studies of Herbert Spencer and George H. Lewes, where the inter- actions of function and structure explain all organic life. 'See "David Hartley and James Mill," by G. S. Bower. 138 THE SCOPE OF LANGUAGE. The particular development which Hartley gave the vibra- tion theory is known as his theory of "neural tremors," which, it must be admitted, has many special features that the advance of Science has proved incorrect. Newton's hints as to the relation between sensation and motion con- tributed to the neural hypothesis. The difficulty of the subject Hartley describes as follows : " If that species of motion which we term vibrations can be shown by probable arguments to attend on all sensations, ideas, and motions, and to be proportioned to them, then we are at liberty either to make vibrations the exponent of sensations, ideas, and motions, or these the exponents of vibrations, as best suits the inquiry, however impossible it may be to discover in what way vibrations cause, or are connected with, sensa- tions or ideas." 1 As the term vibration is so indefinite as to mean much the same thing as motion the ultimate fact in all phenomena of mind as well as of body, in tracing con- sciousness to neural tremors or vibrations we have reached the theoretical end of the analysis of mind. To state these neural tremors in terms of time and space, or numbers and quantities, is the task of the psychology of the future, but it cannot afford us a deeper or more general principle than we have already discovered in that of Motion employed as an explanation of mind. Gottfried Wilhelm von Leibnitz (1646-1716) was a Ger- man mathematician and philosopher of great merit. He was the Newton of Germany ; but, unlike Newton, he in- dulged in metaphysics, and has therefore been considered more of a philosopher than his great English contemporary, whose theory of universal gravitation still holds the highest place among our generalizations of motion. At the age of twenty Leibnitz endeavored to harmonize the systems of Plato and Aristotle, and produced a treatise on the " Com- binations of Numbers and Ideas." At twenty-three he ac- cepted the office of Councillor of State at Frankfort, and in the year following, 1668, published his " New Method of 1 "Observ. on Man," vol. I., p. 32. MODERN PHILOSOPHY. 139 Learning and Teaching Jurisprudence." In 1670 he ad- vanced new and bold theories of Motion (" Theory of Con- crete Motion " and " Theory of Abstract Motion "), which, when compared with the great discovery of Newton in the same direction, show how inevitably the mind reverts, in science as well as in religion, to the problem of the Univer- sal Principle. About this time Leibnitz visited Paris, where he met Cassini and Huyghens, and soon after made the ac- quaintance of Newton and Boyle in London. Here he was made a member of the Royal Academy, and announced his discovery of the Infinitesimal Calculus, nearly identical with Newton's Method of Fluctions. The ambitions of Leibnitz were not satisfied with the vast command of the physical sciences which he enjoyed, and which made him famous throughout France, England, and Germany, for in the prime of his life he interested himself in a beneficent effort to harmonize the Protestant and the Catholic churches. Toward the end of his career (1710) he produced his great work entitled " Essay of Theodicea, on the Goodness of God, the Liberty of Man, and the Origin of Evil " ; in which he advanced the celebrated theory of Optimism. Leibnitz confined himself in writing almost entirely to French and Latin ; for at his time, as will aftenvard appear, there was comparatively little culture in Germany, and the Greek language was employed scarcely at all in science or philosophy; his audience, therefore, was principally in France and in England ; for it was only toward the close of his life that Germany began to show signs of the marvellous intellectual development which she has since achieved. Among the philosophical writings of Leibnitz his criti- cisms of Locke are the most interesting, as Leibnitz was a Cartesian, believing in a dual principle in nature, or an abso- lute difference between body and mind. His opinions are clearly based upon the teachings of Plato and Democri- tus ; and it is a fact of no small interest that as Bacon, Hobbes, and Locke laid the foundations of English thought, 140 THE SCOPE OF LANGUAGE. Leibnitz gave the first impetus to the Idealism of Germany. The difference between Leibnitz and Locke is thus stated by the former : " The question between us is whether the soul in itself is entirely empty, like tablets upon which noth- ing has been written (tabula rasa), according to Aristotle and the author of the ' Essay,' and whether all that is there traced comes wholly from the senses and experience ; or whether the soul originally contains the principles of several notions and doctrines, which the external objects only awaken on occasions, as I believe with Plato." Leibnitz here at- tempts to prove the existence of innate ideas in order to oppose the theory that knowledge springs wholly from the exercise of the senses and reflection. The factor of reflec- tion, however, which was insisted upon by Locke, is so sug- gestive as to discover to the close observer a remote agree- ment between the two great schools of thought which Leibnitz and Locke respectively represented. It is to a clear knowledge of the nature of perception that we must look for a reconciliation of these conflicting theories. Bishop Berkeley (1684-1753) and Hume (1711-1776) were the historical successors of Hobbes, Locke, and Hartley as English writers on philosophy ; but as they respectively re- produced those eccentricities of Greek thought known as Idealism and Skepticism, they retarded, if any thing, the scientific study of mind which their immediate predecessors had inaugurated. They were both erudites learned in Aris- totle, Plato, and the Greek Skeptics. But these ancient theories, deeply interesting as they are when studied as parts of the civilization which produced them, appear very faded when compared with modern thought. Hence we find the metaphysical speculations of Berkeley and Hume tame and uninstructive. George Berkeley was born and educated in Ireland, and was always distinguished for the best qualities of his race generosity, morality, and religious fervor ; in fact, the sat- irist Pope expresses the common verdict of his time in ascribing " To Berkeley every virtue under heaven." He MODERN PHILOSOPHY. published, in 1709, "An Essay Toward a New Theory of Vision," and in the year following, " The Principles of Human Knowledge," in which he advanced his celebrated theory of Idealism, that there is no proof of the existence of matter anywhere but in our own perceptions, as though the words proof and perception did not both imply mind, which can never be more than one of the two terms of the relation expressed in thought. If mind implies an external relation it implies space or matter. This theory of Idealism has been examined as it first appeared in Plato, and we again study it in its subsequent unparalleled development in Kant's a priori philosophy. Suffice it to say that Berkeley has been more or less faithfully reproduced in the Subjective Idealism of Schelling and the Absolute Idealism of Hegel, both generic developments of Kant and remote develop- ments of the Dialectics of Plato, and the Skepticism of the New Academy ; for, strange to say, the unnatural exaltation of the fact of perception which we find in Idealism leads directly to the distrust of mind exemplified in Skepticism. Berkeley gave evidences of being influenced by Locke and Hartley. He followed Locke in regarding the proposition, that a material world really exists, as not strictly demonstra- ble, but went beyond him by declaring the proposition false. He followed Hartley in asserting that there was a necessary succession or association of ideas, but he went beyond him by declaring that the order of nature was not reflected by mind, but was caused by mind. " That which we call the law of nature," he says, " is in fact only the order of the suc- cession of our ideas." This is manifestly reversing the order of perception, or assuming individuality to be the ultimate fact, and general existence to be a subordinate fact derived from individuality ; the absurdity of which, when followed to its logical consequences, is beyond expression. Berkeley published, in 1725, "A Proposal for Converting the Savage Americans to Christianity." To promote this idea he undertook to found a college in this country. The English government promised to aid the enterprise, and he 142 THE SCOPE OF LANGUAGE. sailed for Rhode Island in 1728. During the voyage he wrote a poem on the subject of his mission. While in this country he preached for about two years at Newport, R. I., but the British ministry failing to keep their promise concerning the projected college, he returned home. The Skepticism of David Hume was so marked and so ably reasoned that it awakened a number of Scottish philos- ophers, headed by Thomas Reid, to a vigorous polemic against it, and in Germany incited Immanuel Kant to the construction of his Critical Philosophy. At the age of twenty-six, Hume published in London (1738) his "Treatise on Human Nature," in which the principles of his Skep- ticism are declared, and of which work Mackintosh says: " It was the first systematic attack on all the principles of knowledge and belief, and the most formidable, if universal Skepticism could ever be more than a mere exercise of ingenuity." In 1742, his " Essays, Moral, Political and Lit- erary," appeared ; in 1752, " Political Discourses," and soon after, the famous " History of England." Hume traces our idea of Cause to what he calls habit, our habit of observing the causes of events ; and from this he argues that it is impossible for us to form any idea of the real nature of cause, because our idea is derived entirely from particular experiences. He forgets that the firmest ground of certainty is our inability to disbelieve. Hence an experience which is without exception is universal to us. If we are able to reduce every conceivable phenomenon, or experience, to an ultimate fact, which remains constant in every experience, that fact, to us, is our highest generaliza- tion of cause, and constitutes the general existence of which individuality is but the consequence. Infinity, to man, is that which he is unable to limit ; the Absolute, that to which he is unable to supply conditions. The former effort has manifestly more to do with externals, or objects, than the latter, and is therefore the objective as distinguished from the subjective, aspect of the irreducible fact, cause, or MODERN PHILOSOPHY. 143 Motion. Hence Hume, in denying the possibility of our knowing the nature of the objective connection between cause and effect, merely stated, in other words, the old theory of Carneades, that we cannot know phenomena as they really are. This theory we have fully dealt with in chapter IV. As a natural consequence of Hume's theory of the unreal nature of knowledge, he denied that we could form a con- ception of God, or the immortality of the soul, two widely different propositions, as God is the ultimate fact, and Immortality is the endless perpetuation of a relative fact, which gives us a contradiction in terms. Hume's political writings brought him into prominence, and after his return from Paris, accompanied by his friend Rousseau, he was intrusted with the diplomatic correspond- ence of England (in 1767). Soon after this he retired to Edinburgh, the scene of his best literary efforts, and lived in retirement until his death in 1776. CHAPTER VII. GERMAN PHILOSOPHY. Kant Fichte Schelling Hegel Schleiermacher Schopenhauer. FOR those who have ceased to regard the mind as a mys- tery, a critical review of the German a priori philosophy is unnecessary, for they will easily identify this new growth of Idealism with its kindred errors of the past. They will regard such events as the Centennial translation of Kant's ''Critique of Pure Reason/' by Professor Max Miil- ler, and other like publications, as the last guns which ob- stinate artillerymen fire after the tide of battle has turned against them and their cause has been rendered hopeless. The vast majority of people, however polite may be their culture, are accustomed to view history through its external events, and to judge thought by its official position. To them, reformations are invisible until their effects become crystallized in structural changes, and logical movements are unappreciated until they appear in text-books and encyclo- paedias. To such as these the a priori philosophy will be a reality as long as animate professors expound it to living stu- dents. But to the earnest thinker who is in full sympathy with the progress of his times, whether he be able or not to state categorically his belief, there are abundant evidences that Idealism has been permanently superseded by a higher and a better faith. The proof of this is the increasing contempt with which scientific men, whatever may be their religion, re- gard metaphysics, and the importance which the teaching of morality has gained over the mere defence of dogma through- out the Christian world. An understanding of the scope of language has insensibly dawned upon our era, as a result 144 GERMAN PHILOSOPHY. 145 of which ideas are subordinated to actions ; beliefs are be- ginning to be estimated by the lives of the believers; and although the organization of religion and learning remains apparently the same, theology and metaphysics, considered as distinct sciences, are almost universally regarded as merely formal acquirements of little or no practical value. When in addition to these facts it is remembered that almost every surviving system of theology or of metaphysics is idealistic in its tendency, we perceive that there is in effect a popular uprising against the empty idioms of the a priori school, which extends far and wide beyond the limits of philosophic culture. We have no idea, however, of depending upon a sympathy so general and indefinite for the refutation of Idealism. There are too many instances in history of the re-establish- ment of false doctrines long after they have been to all appearances destroyed, to trust to what is, after all, but a harbinger of victory. As Germany slowly arose from the almost indescribable desolation of the Thirty Years' War, she entered upon a century of her history during which she had no national existence or memories, no literature or language, no social, religious, or moral life. The nation had expired when peace was concluded in 1648. This war not only destroyed an old civilization which was fairly abreast with that of the rest of Europe ; it so completely destroyed it that the nation has been two hundred years in regaining her natural status in the world. Commercial statistics show that the general pros- perity of Germany in 1850 had but just reached the level of that which she enjoyed at the beginning of the war of 1618. " The highly cultivated language of Luther was forgotten, together with the whole literature of his time. Many schools and churches stood abandoned, for public instruc- tion and public worship had nearly perished. * * * There was no middle class nor gentry left; the higher noble- men had become petty despotic princes, with no hand over them, since the Emperor was but a name ; the lower went 146 THE SCOPE OF LANGUAGE. to their court to do lackey's service. A whole generation- had grown up during the war, and considered its savage bar- barism as a normal state of society. * * * For all habits of self-government, even in the cities, had gone ; the gentle- men had become courtiers instead of magistrates. An un- precedented coarseness of manners had invaded not only courts and cities, but also the universities and the clergy." A century later, when Frederick II. realized the desires of Prussia in a reign memorable for its impartial devotion to the whole nation, firmly establishing the Prussian State, the intellectual life of Germany was not only awakened but im- mediately burst into a luxuriant growth. Universities were established and regenerated, great scholars, great poets, and great thinkers immediately appeared. Leibnitz, Kant, Goethe, Schiller, Herder, and the rest, came to glorify the new national life. The beauties of the ancient classics were rediscovered, history was read by fresh minds and its organic nature disclosed, sciences were created to deal with the new problems of life ; for a nation had arisen and taken a new interest in humanity. In the midst of this intellectual exal- tation German philosophy was born. Is it any wonder that its whole existence has been marked by a kind of subjective intoxication ? Each national language formulates its philosophy with an unfeigned satisfaction and pride. The old, old problems of life^ which Greece absorbed from the East and expressed so vivid- ly, were new in Germany ; but a careful examination of their structure discloses them to be of the same logical species as their progenitors. The German type of these problems, however, has marked modifications due to a greater and a higher environment. German philosophy is more Greek than the Grecian ; it is a refined leaven of the Greek thought, so powerful that it has fermented the mind of Europe ever since its appearance. It has produced idealists beside whose theories Plato's Idealism is rational ; it has produced materi- alists whom Aristotle would not have recognized ; it has 1 See " German Thought," by Karl Hillebrand. GERMAN PHILOSOPHY. 147 generated skeptics whom Carneades would have wondered at. But of all these schools Idealism has taken the deepest root, its fancies have most pleased the multitude, and what was in the beginning the innocent recreation of a few literati has become a national vice. How different has it been with France and England ! These nations have had their wars and revolutions, but they have never suffered destruction ; their development has had no great gap in it ; it has been more gradual, and conse- quently more rational. During the time that Germany was slowly regaining life, France was leading the civilization of Europe under Louis XIV. England was in advance in political institutions and religious liberty, and, as well as Spain and Holland, was superior in commerce and conquest; but in all those graces of life and mind which tend to develop and refine the individual, and in the unity and strength of her national life, France of the eighteenth century was pre- eminent. " The French," says Taine, " became civilized by conversation. Their phrases, still formal, under Balzac are looser and lightened ; they launch out, flow speedily, and under Voltaire they find their wings. Pedantic sciences, political economy, theology, the sullen denizens of the Academy and the Sorbonne, speak but in epigrams. * * * What a flight was this of the eighteenth century! Was society ever more anxious for lofty truths, more bold in their search, more quick to discover, more ardent in embracing them ? The perfumed marquises, all these pretty, well- dressed, gallant, frivolous people, crowd to philosophy as to the opera ; the origin of animated beings, the question of free judgment, the principles of political economy, all is to them a matter for paradoxes and discoveries." Just previous to this time we find Leibnitz complaining of the sensuality and ignorance of the German gentry as com- pared with the love of science in England, and the intelli- gence and culture of the French. Count Mannteufel writes to Wolff, as late as 1738, " The German princes, who might be compared to your lords, think it beneath their dignity to cultivate their mind." 148 THE SCOPE OF LANGUAGE. Thus we have England, in the first half of the eighteenth century, enriched by Shakespeare, Dryden, Pope, Addison, and Swift, and learning from Locke and Newton ; France in possession of Pascal, Descartes, Moliere, Malebranche, Ra- cine, and Boileau ; England earnest and studious ; France brilliant and refined, and Germany as yet intellectually un- born. Looking at Germany from the closing years of the nine- teenth century, with an unequalled army of trained scientists animated by the true spirit of original investigation, and almost universal culture, with intellectual and religious free- dom, one might easily expect great things of her. But her originality, her genius, which attained such a marvellous life during the century which closed with 1850, has seeming- ly passed away, and it is in her abnormal Idealism, the natu- ral consequence of a sudden intellectual development, that we are to find the cause. There is a lesson to be learned from the process which underlies the survival of great names in history. It is that the most indestructible lives are not necessarily those which have most interested their contemporaries, but those which have instigated the most needed re- forms. As these lives recede in history, they fade out or become brighter according to the degree in which they have actually served the needs of their time. We find, therefore, that the reputation of Kant, the first of the great German thinkers, depends upon the intrinsic value of his philosophy, although his philosophy is really the least im- pressive feature of his life. What Germany most needed, what every nation most needs, is a true philosophy. Kant endeavored to supply this need, and if he failed, his great learning, his broad humanity, his moral acumen, may insure for him the lasting love and esteem of his countrymen, but they cannot sustain his greatness as a logical reformer. The " Critique of Pure Reason " is acknowledged to be the representative work of Kant. Let us carefully examine it with a view to forming an estimate of its value. GERMAN PHILOSOPHY. 149 The first words of the preface are : " Our reason ( Vernunff) has this peculiar fate, that, with reference to one class of its knowledge, it is always troubled with questions which cannot be ignored, because they spring from the very nature of rea- son, and which cannot be answered, because they transcend the powers of human reason." This simply means that the ultimate nature of reason is incomprehensible, which is rather a discouraging admission to make at the very outset of a work, the object of which is to examine into the nature of reason. Kant must have believed, however, that the nature of reason was comprehensible in some degree, otherwise he would never have attempted an exhaustive criticism of " Pure Reason/' Let it be our object, then, to discover what degree of com- prehensibility Kant believed in, or hoped for, with regard to the nature of reason. The preface continues as follows : " Nor is human reason to be blamed for [being incompre- hensible]. It begins with principles which, in the course of experience, it must follow, and which seem sufficiently con- firmed by experience. With these, again, according to the necessities of its nature, it rises higher and higher to more remote conditions. But when it perceives that in this way its work remains forever incomplete, because the questions never cease, it finds itself constrained to take refuge in prin- ciples which exceed every possible experimental application, and nevertheless seem so unobjectionable that even ordinary common-sense agrees with them." This clearly states a well known fact, that the reason springs from particular experiences and rises to general truths. But among these general truths, Kant tells us, the Reason can find no end, no resting-place, and is " constrained to take refuge in principles which [transcend experience'] ex- ceed every possible experimental application." The point to be marked here is, that it is impossible for Reason to act at all without putting in motion or expressing its deepest principles. If reason springs from experience, as Kant admits, we can find in experience the expression of its 150 THE SCOPE OF LANGUAGE. first principles. These categories, or most general principles, Kant declares, transcend all experience, and yet he clearly admits that the reason, of which these principles are simply the aspects, begins in experience. This contradiction we find still more emphatic further on. In the introduction Kant tells us, " If we remove from experience every thing that belongs to the senses, there remain, nevertheless, cer- tain original concepts, and certain judgments derived from them, which must have had their origin entirely a priori, and independent of all experience, because it is owing to them that we are able, or imagine we are able, to predicate more of the objects of our senses than can be learned from mere experience, and that our propositions contain real generality and strict necessity, such as mere empirical knowl- edge can never supply." Here is an assertion which, in our time, sounds indeed pre- posterous, that there is an absolute dividing line, or differ- ence of nature, between sensuous apprehensions and the co- ordination of those apprehensions which gives us the highest achievements of reason. By the term " a priori" which really means nothing but before, Kant wishes to designate certain mysterious conceptions which cannot be accounted for by the natural activities of the sentient organism. But these principles, notwithstanding their mysterious nature, are supposed to reside somewhere in the organism. On the same page we are told that there is a certain kind of " knowledge which transcends the world of the senses, and where experience can neither guide nor correct us : here rea- son prosecutes investigations, which by their importance we consider far more excellent, and by their tendency far more elevated, than any thing the understanding can find in the sphere of phenomena." This looks rather ominous. If Kant is to take us into a region of knowledge where our investigations cannot be verified by any possible experiences, a region of investiga- tion which is far more " excellent " and " elevated than any thing the understanding can find in the sphere of phenom- GERMAN PHILOSOPH Y. 1 5 1 ena," no one will blame us if we feel alarmed at the thought of the intellectual apparitions which we are to meet there. But any reluctance which we may have to accompany our author is dissipated when he continues, " Nay, we risk rather any thing, even at the peril of error, than that we should surrender such investigations, either on the ground of their uncertainty or from any feeling of indifference or contempt. * * * Besides, once beyond the precincts of experience, we are certain that experience can never contradict us, while the charm of enlarging our knowledge is so great that nothing will stop our progress until we encounter a clear contradiction." ] From this it is evident that the only defence we are to have, in the region of knowledge to be traversed by the " Critique of Pure Reason," against the delusions of the imagination, is the sense of " clear contradiction." This is a certain relief ; for it assures us that we are not expected to leave all sense behind. But the question arises : How, in a sphere of " knowledge which transcends the world of the senses," are we to retain enough sense to appreciate a clear contradiction ? The modern psychologist has no faith in the existence of " Pure Reason " ; the very name implies a belief in the actual separation of what are but aspects of one fact of sen- tiency. To show how firmly Kant believed in this actual separation, we give his definition of Pure Reason : " Every kind of knowledge is called pure if not mixed with any thing heterogeneous. But more particularly is that knowledge called absolutely pure which is not mixed up with any expe- rience or sensation, and is therefore possible entirely a priori. Reason is the faculty which supplies the principles of knowl- edge a priori. Pure Reason, therefore, is that faculty which supplies the principles of knowing any thing entirely a priori. An Organum of pure reason ought to comprehend all the principles by which pure knowledge a priori can be acquired and fully established. A complete application of such an 1 Kant's "Critique of Pure Reason," vol. II., pp. 2, 3. 152 THE SCOPE OF LANGUAGE. Organum would give us a System of Pure Reason. But as that would be a difficult task, and as at present it is still doubtful whether such an expansion of our knowledge is here possible, we may look on a mere criticism of pure reason, its sources and limits, as a kind of preparation for a complete system of pure reason. It should be called a critique, not a doctrine, of pure reason. Its usefulness would be negative only, serving for a purging rather than for an expansion of our reason." ] Any meaning which this defini- tion has certainly hinges upon the term a priori. The further service which this term is made to do in Kant's ideas can be judged of from the following : " I call all knowledge transcendental which is occupied not so much with objects as with our a priori concepts of objects. A system of such concepts might be called Transcendental Philosophy. But for the present this is again too great an undertaking. We should have to treat therein completely both of analytical knowledge and of synthetical knowledge a priori, which is more than we intend to do, being satisfied to carry on the analysis so far only as is indispensably necessary in order to understand in their whole extent the principles of synthesis a priori, which alone concern us. This investigation, which should be called a transcendental critique, but not a sys- tematic doctrine, is all we are occupied with at present. It is not meant to extend our knowledge, but only to rectify it, and to become the test of the value of all a priori knowl- edge." Thus we have the privilege of reviewing a transcendental criticism of a priori knowledge, or, knowledge which acknowl- edges no connection with experience. Kant describes the scope of his great work in these words : " All that constitutes transcendental philosophy belongs to the Critique of Pure Reason. * * * Transcendental phi- losophy is the Wisdom of pure speculative reason. Every thing practical, so far as it contains motives, has reference to 1 Kant's " Critique," pp. 9, 10. a Ibid., pp. 10, n. GERMAN PHILOSOPHY. 153 sentiments, and these belong to empirical sources of knowl- edge.'" The " Critique of Pure Reason " opens with a discourse on what Kant calls " Transcendental ^Esthetic," and from that proceeds to " Transcendental Logic," "Transcendental An- alytic," " Transcendental Dialectic," and closes with the Method of Transcendentalism, under the respective heads of " Discipline of Pure Reason " and " Canons of Pure Rea- son." These titles have a magnificent sound, but there is too much that is transcendental (above the earth) about them. The careful or conscientious thinker, being earthly, likes to keep his feet upon the solid ground of good sense ; he feels that this is the only position which secures logical strength and repose, and that no thoughts are too high, too pure, or too excellent to rest upon so human a base. Correct reason- ing is logical integrity, intellectual morality ; but we have no right to impeach the logical integrity of the " Critique of Pure Reason " by assuming any connection between moral and intellectual procedures ; for its author tells us plainly, in the last page of the introduction, that " although the highest principles of morality and their fundamental concepts are a priori knowledge, they do not belong to transcendental phi- losophy, because the concepts of pleasure and pain, desire, inclination, free-will, etc., which are all of empirical origin, must here be presupposed." This leaves us in an uncom- fortable state of uncertainty whether he means that trans- cendental philosophy has nothing to do with morality, or whether a priori knowledge has nothing to do with transcen- dental philosophy. At all events, the assertion is definite that in transcendental philosophy the moral sentiments, so far as they represent a motive, have no place. Hence the author of the " Critique of Pure Reason," in describing the scope of his work, deliberately takes leave of all that is estimable and useful in philosophy, namely, the study of life as a means of illuminating conduct, and applies himself to the creation of that system of " a priori knowl- edge " now widely known as German Idealism. 1 Kant's " Critique," pp. 12, 13. -154 THE SCOPE OF LANGUAGE. Herder, the Pindar of Germany, a pupil of Kant, a pro. found scholar and moral teacher, earnestly denounced the Kantian philosophy. James Sully, in the Fortnightly Review of October, 1882, thus describes the antagonism of teacher and pupil : " Herder's conception of history as but an extension of nature's processes was diametrically opposed to Kant's dualism of human freedom rising above and opposing na- ture. * * * He had no liking for Kant's critical philoso- phy, with its cumbrous apparatus of ' intellectual forms.' To his concrete mind ever impressed with the organic unity of man, it seemed to resolve the human intellect into a num- ber of unreal abstractions. It was a distinct retrogression from the experience philosophy of his predecessors, and along with the French Revolution threatened ' to send back the world a hundred years.' Herder's chief dislike of the Kantian philosophy, however, arose out of his view of its hurtful consequences in literature, art, and theology. ' Criti- cism ' was the fashion of thought of the hour. ' In every journal ' (writes Herder) * these dogs and curs bark and yelp the critical canons without canon, without feeling, law, and rule. God help us!' The sharp separation of art and mo- rality and the worship of pure form in art which Schiller and Goethe were preaching, were professedly based on Kant's teaching. And then there was the young generation of theologians who had come under the spell of Fichte's elo- quence at Jena, and who were blatant with somewhat vague ideas about liberty and the supremacy of reason. One can hardly wonder that the soul of the General Superintendent should have been excited to wrath by the appearance of youthful candidates for clerical appointments who thought to conceal by loose talk of this sort the depth of their igno- rance on all theological matters, candidates of whom one even had the audacity to write an essay against marriage. " So it came to pass that Herder's spirit was inflamed against Kant, and delivered itself of a solemn denunciation. In the year 1799-1800, there appeared from his pen two GERMAN PHILOSOPHY. 155 works which were intended to give the coup de grace to Kant's influence. These were the ' Metakritik,' which was directed against the 'Critic of the Pure Reason/ and the ' Kalligone,' which was to be a refutation of the theory of taste and art put forth in the ' Critic of the Practical Reason.' The mode of attack may be seen by a reference to the intro- duction to the ' Metakritik.' It is an appeal from chair phi- losophers to the sensible laity. He dwells on the mischief wrought by the Kantian teaching. * For twelve years the critical philosophy has been playing its part, and we see its fruits. What father (let him ask himself) wishes his son to become an autonomous being of the critical sort, a metaphy- sician of nature and virtue, a dialectical or revolutionary pettifogger, according to the critical stamp? Now look round and read ! What recent book, what science is not covered with flaws of this kind, and how many noble talents are (we hope for a time only) ruined ! Foreign nations scorn us : " Are you there, you Germans, you who were so far on in many things? Are you speculating about the question how it is possible for your understanding to have come into existence ? * * * Unformed nation ! how differ- ent the things you ought to be thinking about ! " " The remedy for the evil lies in the hands of every intel- ligent reader. Ordinary men are fully capable of destroying the ' misty woof of words.' Everybody has a mind which he can interrogate in order to know whether it behaves in the fashion set forth in the ' Critic.' ' Ask thyself, thy senses, thy understanding, thy reason ; they have imprescriptible rights. Are the senses willing to be transubstantiated into empty forms, the understanding into a senseless process of spelling, and the reason into a chaos ? ' ' But this brave attack and timely warning fell to the earth ; it passed unheeded. And thus Herder, " the humanizer of theology, the reviver of pristine life in literature, injured himself only by his rash venture into the thorny enclosure of metaphysics. He called into existence a whole army of enemies only too ready to enlist under the banner of the 156 THE SCOPE OF LANGUAGE. Konigsberg philosopher, and he alienated some of his best friends." The mind of Germany has indeed been put back a hundred years in its growth by the Kantian philosophy. Idealism hangs like a fog over her intellectual life ; her art, her litera- ture, and even her science, are dwarfed by it. In Germany the religious world is either superstitious or materialistic; thought being separated from morality or real life, the religion of philosophy does not exist ; even her political life seems to be retarded by this unnatural divorce. The warm- est friends, the ablest critics of this great nation compare her to a mind without a body. From this can it not be in- ferred that her body in the highest sense is without a mind ? The fluent and methodical manner in which Kant pro- ceeds to analyze perception is calculated to throw one off his guard. The propositions which embrace his description of mental phenomena are stated with such precision and ap- parent candor that one is apt to take their logical integrity for granted. For instance, at the outset he affirms that " sensibility alone supplies us with intuitions (Anschauungen). These intuitions become thought through the understanding (Verstand), and hence arise conceptions (Begriffe). All thought, therefore, must, directly or indirectly, go back to intuitions (Anschauungen), i. e. to our sensibility, because in no other way can objects be given to us." 1 Thus we have sensation and thought duly recognized as different aspects, of mental phenomena, their separation being purely artificial. Then follows the very fair assertion: " The effect produced by an object upon the faculty of representation (Vorstel- lungsfdhigkeif), so far as we are affected by it, is called sensation (Einpfindung). An intuition [Anschauung] of an object, by means of sensation, is called empirical. The un- defined object of such empirical intuition is called phenome- non (Erscheinung)" But suddenly we have a leap into obscurity which is amazing, and which of course we cannot follow. Witness these words : " I call all representations 1 Kant's "Critique," p. 17. GERMAN PHILOSOPHY. 157 in which there is nothing that belongs to sensation, pure (in a transcendental sense). The pure form, therefore, of all sensuous intuitions, that form in which the manifold elements of the phenomena are seen in a certain order, must be found in the mind a priori. And this pure form of sensibility may be called the pure intuition (Anschauung)" A moment ago we were told that " sensibility alone sup- plies us with intuitions"; that "all thought must, directly or indirectly, go back to intuitions, i. e. sensations " ; that " sensation is the effect produced upon the faculty of repre- sentation by an object " ; thus completing the chain of cause and effect between the many forms of mental activity which Kant names as sensuous apprehensions, representations, in- tuitions, and thoughts. In the face of this we are told that he " calls all representations in which there is nothing that belongs to sensation,/#r^ (in a transcendental sense)." Truly this transcendental sense seems to be the source of Kant's lasting error ; lasting because, as we shall see, he has artic- ulated his system so ingeniously and covered up its logical defects so dexterously with such a wealth of tautology, that nothing but the most persistent vigilance can disclose the unconscious deceit which permeates the whole "Critique of Pure Reason." Speaking of space, Kant says : " No determinations of ob- jects, whether belonging to them absolutely or in relation to others, can enter into our intuition before the actual exist- ence of the objects themselves ; that is to say, they can never be intuitions a priori. * * * Space is nothing but the form of the phenomena of all external senses ; it is a subjective condition of our sensibility, without which no ex- ternal intuition is possible for us." Such language as this is simply an outrage upon good sense. If it came from a less illustrious pen than that of Kant, we might well pass it by with contempt. It involves a mass of contradictions and is loose and incoherent, logically, to the last degree. The determinations of objects, or the properties by which 1 Kant's " Critique," p. 23. 158 THE SCOPE OF LANGUAGE. objects are perceived, imply a relation between the perceiv- ing subject and the object ; the determinations of objects, therefore, cannot belong to them absolutely, for they imply a relation. When Kant says that the " determinations of objects cannot enter into our intuition before the existence of the objects themselves," it is to be remembered that, as the determinations are qualities or functions of the objects, they imply or presuppose the existence of the object, and hence there can be no question of priority. As for the determina- tions never becoming " intuitions a priori" we have been dis- tinctly told that intuitions come alone through sensibility. We therefore deny that there is any meaning in the term "intuitions a priori." The difference between sensuous in- tuitions and intuitions a priori is based upon an arbitrary separation, by Kant, of the matter and form of phenomena ; 1 a distinction which has no foundation in fact, for the form of objects is clearly the expression of certain statical or space aspects ; and the word matter is merely a generalization of the statical aspects of all phenomena. When Kant says, therefore, that space is a subjective condition of our sensi- bility without which no intuition of externals (objects) is possible, it is clear that he does violence to facts, first by insisting that space means form and does not mean matter, and then that form is absolutely distinct from matter or external phenomena. In a word, Kant abstracts from that aspect of motion or general existence, which we call space, a so-called transcendental principle which he calls form, and leaves behind a mutilated conception which he calls matter. Form, he says, belongs to the mind and transcends all sensi- bility or experience ; but matter does not belong to the mind, and cannot get into it, because it is not form. Surely 1 " The matter only of all phenomena is given us a posteriori ; but their form must be ready for them in the mind (Gemuth] a priori, and must therefore be capable of being considered as separate from all sensations. * * * The pure form, therefore, of all sensuous intuitions, that form in which the mani- fold elements of the phenomena are seen in a certain order, must be found in the mind a priori. And this pure form of sensibility may be called the pure intuition (Anschauung)" "Critique of Pure Reason," p. 18. GERMAN PHILOSOPHY. 159 the difficulty begins and ends with what Kant says, for he offers no proof whatever that form is transcendental, or that it is separable from the statical aspect of phenomena. The reader will no doubt be edified by the following defini- tion of time and space offered by Kant : " Time is the formal condition, a priori, of all phenomena whatsoever. Space, as, the pure form of all external intuition, is a condition, a pri- ori, of external phenomena only. But as all representations,, whether they have for their objects external things or not, belong by themselves, as determinations of the mind, to our inner state ; and as this inner state falls under the formal conditions of internal intuition, and therefore of time, time is a condition, a priori, of all phenomena whatsoever, and is. so directly as a condition of internal phenomena (of our mind), and thereby indirectly of external phenomena also." 1 As a specimen of a priori or transcendental reasoning, this is a masterpiece; but it would not be in keeping with the spirit of the " Critique " to try and reduce these conceptions to " sense," or to assimilate them with " experiences." We suppose that " the formal condition, a priori, of all phe- nomena whatsoever " means the idea of all phenomena ; there- fore we have the assertion that time is the idea of all phenomena ; but we are told that space is a condition, a priori, of external phenomena. Now, by external, Kant means external to the mind, or phenomenal, so that exter- nal phenomena means all phenomena. Hence the differ- ence between these definitions of space and time results in nothing, and we have the simple statement, if a simple state- ment can be drawn from such language, that time and space are the ideas of all phenomena. " But," Kant con- tends, " as all representations, whether they have for their objects external things or not, belong by themselves, as de- terminations of the mind, to our inner state; and as this inner state falls under the formal conditions of the internal intuition, and therefore of time, time is a condition, a priori, of all phenomena whatsoever, and is so directly as a condition 1 Kant's " Critique," pp. 29, 30. l6o THE SCOPE OF LANGUAGE. of internal phenomena (of our mind), and thereby indirectly of external phenomena also." Is not this simply an asser- tion, that time is the idea of external phenomena, and also that it is the condition of internal phenomena (or mind)? In a word, Kant tries to occupy both sides of an imaginary boundary line, which he would draw between two aspects of a single fact of existence, and thereby, without perceiving it, obliterates the line. It will be remembered that phenomena are rigidly ex- cluded by Kant from the subjective or a priori world ; that man is not a natural but a supernatural being, using natural and phenomenal as convertible terms. But sensibility is of course natural and must belong to the world of phenomena. This difficulty he avoids by creating for himself an a priori man (in a transcendental sense), who is put into an a priori world ; and if by any chance the a priori man manifests any thing phenomenal, or natural, or sensible, he is ordered by the irate philosopher of Konigsberg to resume his apriori character. Then the good Kant looks about him and per- ceives that space is an inconveniently real and universal principle, and also that his a priori man has space relation- ships which cannot be destroyed ; so he avoids the difficulty by saying that all space is a priori and is in the a priori man. Whatever of space is not in the a priori man, is only matter and has no reality, for all reality is in the a priori man. This beautiful truth he expresses in the following familiar language: " Space, as the pure form of all external intuition, is a condition, a priori, of external phenomena only. But all representations, whether they have for their objects external things or not, belong by themselves, as de- terminations of the mind to our inner state." This defini- tion brings him in collision with time, which he finds to be also an inconveniently absolute principle that had not been well considered in the first creation of the a priori man. So he boldly attempts to make time a priori; but all his efforts prove fruitless ; he struggles hard, but time resists. Kant, however, would not have been the GERMAN PHILOSOPHY. l6l greatest of German philosophers had he allowed himself to be vanquished by time, so after a long and labored argu- ment 1 which attempts to prove the ideality of time, he makes the unprecedented point that time has an empirical existence, but that empirical not being a priori is not really any existence at all. The following argument is added under the head of an EXPLANATION. " Against this theory, which claims empirical but denies absolute and transcendental reality to time, even intelligent men have protested so unanimously, that I suppose that every reader who is unaccustomed to these considerations may naturally be of the same opinion. What they object to is this: Changes, they say, are real (this is proved by the change of our own representations, even if all external phe- nomena and their changes be denied). Changes, however, are possible in time only, and therefore time must be some- thing real. The answer is easy enough. I grant the whole argument. Time certainly is something real, namely, the real form of our internal intuition. Time, therefore, has subjective reality with regard to internal experience ; that is, I really have representation of time and of my determina- tions in it. Time, therefore, is really to be considered, not as an object, but as the representation of myself as an object. If either I myself or any other being could see me without this condition of sensibility, then these self-same determina- tions which we now represent to ourselves as changes would give us a kind of knowledge in which the representation of 1 " Time is therefore simply a subjective condition of our (human) intuition (which is always sensuous, that is, so far as we are affected by objects), but by itself, apart from the subject, nothing. Nevertheless, with respect to all phenomena, that is, all things which can come within our experience, time is necessarily objective. We cannot say that all things are in time, because, if we speak of things in general, nothing is said about the manner of intuition, which is the real condition under which time enters into our representation of things. If, therefore, this condition is added to the concept, and if we say that all things as phenomena (as objects of sensuous intuition) are in time, then such a proposition has its full objective validity and a priori universality." " Critique of Pure Reason," pp. 30, 31. 1 62 THE SCOPE OF LANGUAGE. time, and therefore of change also, would have no place. There remains, therefore, the empirical reality of time only, as the condition of all our experience, while absolute reality cannot, according to what has just been shown, be conceded to it. Time is nothing but the form of our own internal intuition. 1 " Take away the peculiar condition of our sensibility, and the idea of time vanishes, because it is not inherent in the objects, but in the subject only that perceives them/' a Take away the a priori man, and time is annihilated. I do not give these quotations for the purpose of proving any thing concerning time or space, but to show how in- coherent and contradictory were Kant's explanations of these ultimates. It is impossible to read the above quota- tions without seeing that both the objective and subjective existence of space and time are admitted in one breath,, and that the effort to limit the aspects of motion to an im- aginary subjective world absolutely separated from the world of sense, was as futile as it is, in the light of our day r absurd. After laying such a foundation of error, one can imagine the dreary waste of reasoning which follows in the subse- quent chapters of the " Critique." The a priori man is driven from pillar to post in the storm of facts which trans- cendental reasoning stirs up, and the extraordinary vitality which he displays is a lasting proof of the power of organiza- tion, whether it be for good or for evil ; for this a priori man is wonderfully articulated with facts where they are to be had, and an abundant supply of words where facts are wanting. We have reason to be grateful that philosophy is not so- rare a thing in the world that one is obliged to delve among the intricacies of " Kant's Transcendental Dialectics " for I 1 can say, indeed, that my representations follow one another, but this means no more than that we are conscious of them as in a temporal succession, that is, according to the form of our own internal sense. Time, therefore, i& nothing by itself, nor is it a determination inherent objectively in things. 9 Kant's " Critique," pp. 32, 33. GERMAN PHILOSOPHY. 163 the facts of consciousness. There is no denying that a great many of these facts are given by Kant, and that one can glean from his writings much that is valuable concerning the procedure of the mind ; but it is the opinion of all competent authorities that the fundamental principles of Kant's philos- ophy declare against the possibility of a unification of knowledge. Strange as it may seem, the philosophy of Kant strongly resembles the Skepticism of Hume. Hume openly declared philosophy to be impossible, upon the grounds that the operations of the mind are transcendental, or unknowable, while Kant acknowledged reality only in the subjective sphere, placing limits upon the intellect which are fatal to an understanding of the divine unity of nature ; or, to that con- ception of God which can alone harmonize life and mind. Kant's theory of the limitations of knowledge is thor- oughly anthropomorphic. It finds in knowledge certain principles of certitude which appear to him to be universal ; but because he discovers these principles through the agency of his own thought, he concludes that at all events they can- not extend beyond the range of human consciousness. The inevitable relations of consciousness to sentiency, and of sen- tiency to the general activities of nature, never seem to break upon his mind. But having measured the human understanding and described its absolute (?) limits, he is obliged to admit that it is only an island in a sea of mystery. This is the very position of the ancient skeptics, who saw no real harmony or identity of procedure between mind and the general activities of nature. Thus we find that the old theories of Skepticism, which were so highly developed by the Greeks in the New Academy, are reproduced in the Kantian dialectics with scarcely a variation ; while the novelty of their appearance in the German language under the elaborate forms of the " Critique of Pure Reason " was enough in itself to account for the reputation they at once achieved. The Skepticism of Kant is thus but a reproduction of ancient Skepticism, 164 THE SCOPE OF LANGUAGE* which held that we cannot know things per se absolutely or as they really are in themselves. This can hardly be a correct theory of perception, since human knowledge is the relation between a sentient organism and its surroundings, and must be the expression of conditions, whereas absolute means independent of conditions. Absolute or a priori knowledge, therefore, is a contradiction in terms. Hence a system which rests its fundamental principles upon the assumption of an absolute knowledge becomes an absurdity. Lewes, who made a profound study of Kant, says : " In his ' Critique ' we are only to look for the exposition of a priori principles. He does not trouble himself with investi- gating the nature of perception ; he contents himself with the fact that we have sensations, and with the fact that we have ideas whose origin is not sensuous. * * * He did not deny the existence of an external world ; on the con- trary, he affirmed it, but he denied that we can know it ; he affirmed that it was essentially unknowable." The corner-stone of Kant's philosophy, as expressed in the " Critique of Pure Reason," is that there is no reality exactly corresponding to the notions of men, and that what constitutes reality for us is simply our own mental represen- tations. Let us examine this proposition. In perception there are two factors, the subject and the object ; or of the phenomenon of perception there are two aspects, the sub- jective and the objective. Kant says that there is no exter- nal reality corresponding to the subjective side of percep- tion, and that, therefore, as there is no disputing the reality of the subjective side or thought, all reality must be thought. This logical snarl is wholly due to a false limitation of the meaning of words. All those forms of mental activity known as notions, mental representations, or thoughts, im- ply an object as well as a subject. The separation of sub- ject from object in the consideration of thought is purely artificial. When we look upon thought as the activity of a sentient being, we cannot exclude from view the infinite conditions of this activity which relate it to universal life ; GERMAN PHILOSOPHY. 165 we cannot isolate the subjective phenomenon of thought by appropriating to it all reality. Thought is distinctly a rela- tion, the function of subjective and objective conditions. Kant's assertion, therefore, that all reality is subjective, is a one-sided view of the fact of thought. If the many names for mental or psychical activity, such as perception, thought, mental representation, etc., were recognized as relatively equivalent terms, and if mental phenomena were acknowl- edged as the activity of an organism, whether that organism be an individual or a race, there would be no difficulty in accounting for the subjective and objective sides of thought. It is our failure to identify these contrasted sides as aspects of a single fact which alone impels us to attribute exclusive reality to either the one or the other. To this latter asser- tion all Kantians would at once demur, for they are contin- ually speaking of absolute mind, or intelligence. The term absolute simply means time, or the unconditioned, and therefore cannot be applied to any individual phenomenon, such as thought or mind. This explanation might dispose of all the difficulties of the Kantian system, if there were not a distinct contradiction of this theory of the absolute nature of mind developed in Kant's psychology : for there is no de- nying that he also teaches that there is no absolute dividing line between subject and object in the act of perception that the mind does not think in itself, but is acted upon and reacts upon its surroundings in producing thought. His creation, however, of an a priori sphere of thought, which is absolutely separated from sensibility and external phenom- ena, so confuses the theory of the union of subject and ob- ject, that it is difficult to understand how he could have retained two such conflicting opinions at once. The teacher of philosophy is bound to express himself with simplicity and clearness ; and when he does not, it is fair to conclude that he himself is not clear upon the subject. The serious contradictions which occur in the two edi- tions of the " Critique of Pure Reason " are admitted by the most pronounced Kantians. In speaking of these two 1 66 THE SCOPE OF LANGUAGE. editions, Prof. Miiller says : " That the unity of thought which pervades the first edition is broken now and then in the second edition, no attentive reader can fail to see. That Kant shows rather too much anxiety to prove the harmless- ness of his * Critique ' is equally true, and it would have been better if, while refuting what he calls Empirical Idealism, he had declared more strongly his unchanged ad- herence to the principles of Transcendental Idealism. * * * I must confess that I have always used myself the first edition of Kant's ' Critique,' and that when I came to read the second edition, I never could feel so at home in it as in the first. The first edition seems to me cut out of one block, the second always leaves on my mind the impression of patch-work." 1 These contradictions are slight, however, when compared with those already pointed out in the main argu- ment of the " Critique " with regard to the nature of per- ception. Hence, since it is well known that the Nature of Perception is the foundation of every philosophy, we think we are justified in accepting what, outside of Germany, is becoming a very general opinion that Kant's " Critique of Pure Reason " is a monument of logical subtlety and at the same time an incor- rect and hopelessly confused analysis of Mind. That this view is not generally shared by those who have studied in Germany under the influence of the Kantian system is only too manifest. Professor Noire, in the introductory review to Max Miiller' s translation of the " Critique," after giving evidence of a very high order of philosophic culture, closes his examination of the pre-Kantian systems as follows: " Kant alone succeeded in solving all the contradictions and paradoxes in which the reason was entangled, and in ex- plaining them completely in accordance with their own nature, as he dropped the sounding-line into depths which as yet no mortal mind had dared to fathom, and brought up from thence to the light of day news of the primary condi- tions and eternal postulates of reason. It is therefore not 1 Kant's " Critique," Translator's Preface. GERMAN PHILOSOPHY. 1 67 too much to say that Kant is the greatest philosophical genius that has ever dwelt upon earth, and the ' Critique of Pure Reason ' the highest achievement of human wisdom." 1 And Max Miiller makes more conspicuous this flagrant ex- ample of ethnic conceit by declaring that the thought of Kant fills up the entire logical perspectives of humanity. The only exception to be taken to this view of Professor Miiller is, that he has manifestly confused his own logical perspectives with those of humanity. The " Critique of Practical Reason," which appeared in 1790, is generally admitted to be a retraction of the prin- ciples of the first edition of the " Critique of Pure Reason." But Kantians of the present day, for the most part, deny to their master the privilege of changing his mind, for they are almost unanimously of the opinion that the first edition of the " Critique of Pure Reason " really represents the teach- ings of Kant, while the second edition and the " Critique of Practical Reason " they seem to entirely ignore. We will not, however, be influenced by these eccentrici- ties of the followers of Kant ; for the least we can accord to the great master is, that his mental development was con- tinuous, and suffered no serious mishap during the heyday of his literary activity. The " Critique of Practical Reason " deals with the sub- ject of Morality. Its estimation of human duty is exalted, but its effort to trace duty to an ultimate principle has been widely criticised. Kant's original theory of justice was, that it is an entity, an innate principle of the human mind, present alike in all races and individuals, and indepen- dent of social progress. This theory he afterward modified, but still held to the belief that justice was universal. The strongest objection made to this belief was, that certain tribes of savages killed their old men when they became feeble. The mode of determining the degree of feebleness which merited death was, to require the most venerable men of the tribe to cling to the branch of a tree, 1 Kant's " Critique," vol. I., p. 359. 1 68 THE SCOPE OF LANGUAGE. which was violently shaken, and those who failed to retain their hold were put to death. Kant's reply to this argu- ment was, that the fact that these old men were allowed a chance for life proved the presence of the idea of justice in the tribe. Was there ever an injustice which did not prove as much? In our day, it is well known that the conception of jus- tice (which, it is to be remembered, is a purely relative term) has grown up from the simplest mechanical experiences ; such, for instance, as the balancing of weights. The idea of justice or duty becomes clearer and more general with social advancement. Kant's theory, therefore, that justice is a priori, a mysterious presence in the mind which cannot be explained by natural experience, reduces the source of mo- rality to the level of a superstition which is the opposite of philosophical. Morality is rightly reasoned conduct ; but all reasoning cannot be represented in abstract symbols. There is a logic of feeling as well as of signs, an unspoken movement of the emotions which enters into every human determination. Since morality is the highest exercise of the judgment, the most complete harmony between practical and intellectual life, false methods of philosophizing, erroneous explanations of the procedures of the mind, are demoralizing in their effects upon society. The direct influence of idealism upon morality is seen in the tendency toward the idealization of human attributes, such as love, virtue, or reason. The en- thronement of these qualities as a priori or absolute princi- ples in life leads directly to the greatest extravagances of conduct. The theory that love is a God-inspired feeling, and that when a feeling can be clearly demonstrated to be love it becomes holy, or justifies itself, is a natural conse- quence of idealism ; and it is one of the most pernicious beliefs that it is possible to entertain. What rivers of blood have been shed, what homes destroyed, what hearts broken, in learning the nature of love ! Although love expresses the deepest feelings of which we are capable, it is but the func- GERMAN PHILOSOPHY. 169 tion of a vast plexus of conditions, and depends upon these conditions for its justification. However exalted and pure we may imagine a passion to be, whether life and happiness depend upon its gratification or not, the question whether the feeling is right or wrong is governed by the conditions which surround it, and has nothing whatever to do with its intensity or imagined purity. Again : the idealization of virtue, or self- abnegation the theory that virtue is an absolute principle moving in a foreign universe of sin an a priori, God-inspired intuition instead of the natural development of a well-or- dered life, the result of pure examples and good habits, leads to all those extravagances of conduct which vary from asceticism and other forms of moral austerity to the more general and lower grades of hypocrisy. Lastly : the ideali- zation of the faculty of reasoning (mind) gives rise to the greatest logical extravagances, from the Dialectics of Plato and the absolute Skepticism of the Academicians to those forms of Idealism known as the a priori philosophy of Kant and his followers, the influence of which still remains in modern agnosticism. Thus the success of morality, the ad- vancement of the chief science of life, depends directly upon a just appreciation of the limits of language and the nature of perception, which alone can make possible the Unification of Knowledge. All recognized German philosophy subsequent to Kant is but a development of either the practical or the ethical side of the Kantian system, with a more or less marked subser- vience to the Idealism with which Kant so deeply imbued the German mind. The cast of thought, therefore, which we find in Fichte, Schelling, Hegel, Schopenhauer, Herbart, and the other post-Kantian writers, seems predetermined to an extent which it would be difficult to understand without first becoming acquainted with what may be called the solidarity of German philosophic culture, the almost servile imitation which marks the development of the German conception of Mind. There are instances, however, in the writings of all the above-named authors where they have risen above the arbi- 170 THE SCOPE OF LANGUAGE. .trary influence of their great predecessor, and delight us with their originality and genius. This was especially the .case with Fichte, who seems to have had the faculty of making all who came within his influence respect and love him. An example of the highest type of German character, he was a moral and intellectual enthusiast. Johann Gottlieb Fichte was born at Rammenau, a village .in Upper Lusatia, in May, 1762. His first serious effort in philosophy was the study of Kant's " Critique of Practical Reason," in which he tells us that he discovered, for the first time, the absolute freedom of the will. The theological training which he received in preparation for the ministry had given him the belief in a supernatural source of morality ; and as ethics was the subject nearest to his heart, a deep and natural sentiment, he was both surprised and overjoyed to find what he regarded as a successful attempt to trace the inspiration of virtue to the natural operations of the mind. He prepared a hurried treatise called " A Critique of Every Possible Revelation," and making a pilgrimage to Konigs- berg, presented it to Kant, who, recognizing in it a high order of ability, was instrumental in securing its publication. By an accident, the author's preface, in which he acknowl- edged himself a beginner in philosophy, was omitted from the first edition, nor did his name appear on the title-page. Some of the German newspapers jumped at the conclusion that it was a production of Kant, especially as it seemed to be a development of the ethical teaching of that writer, and accorded to it unbounded praise. When the mistake came to light, Fichte's reputation was instantaneously made, and the result was an invitation to fill the chair of Philosophy at Jena (1793). Here, according to one of the favorite criti- cal methods of his age, he was assailed for atheism, and re- fusing to make any retractions he resigned (1799). After many changes of place he was made professor of philosophy in the New University at Berlin, where his career was short but dramatic. His eloquence and ability secured him im- mediate and wide attention ; his lectures on Ethics were GERMAN PHILOSOPHY. 1 71 stirring, and made a visible impression upon his times ; but the national enthusiasm which marked the opening of the memorable campaign of 1813 carried him from the close of one of his lectures into the ranks of the assembling army, and within a year he was taken with a fever and died. The Fichtean philosophy was elaborated during the few years of stormy activity which its author passed at the Uni- versity of Jena. He endeavored to develop the practical or ethical side of Kant's philosophy ; for it was to expound the Kantian system that he had been invited to the chair. But a revolution in Kant's own views had taken place ; his " Critique of Pure Reason" had been virtually retracted by his " Cri- tique of Practical Reason"; and as these works appeared but six years apart, the latter shortly before Fichte began lectur- ing at Jena, it will readily be seen that the first great disciple of Kant had a somewhat difficult and confusing task in ex- pounding the views of his master. The object in reciting these details is to show how closely woven all that is known as German philosophy is, and how much it consists in the arbitrary creations of a few men, all living at about the same time, and most of them having personal intercourse and sympathy ; Kant being the senior of the group and the in- stigator of the whole movement. We can find no fault with Germany, therefore, when she, even at this time, looks to Kant as her greatest philosopher, for all German philosophy is acknowledged to be but branches or side developments of the Kantian theories. But when Germany says that Kant is her greatest mind, she under- estimates the value of her other geniuses, such as Herder, Goethe, Schiller, and Lessing, who have contributed so much to the knowledge of the world. Kant's philosophy, with all its branches, has, it is true, been written in German, but not in the universal language of good sense. Fichte exaggerated the idealism of Kant, which we have already described, by advocating what is known as Subjective Idealism. This means that objects of thought or percep- tion do not exist externally, but only subjectively, or in the 172 THE SCOPE OF LANGUAGE. mind. This belief, absurd as it seems, we are bound to believe was sincere, although it commits the fatal error of confusing thoughts with things : the very thing that Plato and the Skeptics did, but in a less grotesque manner. The reasoning by which this belief is brought about has been analyzed in our description of Greek thought. The fallacy which this reasoning so successfully conceals arises entirely from giving certain words different meanings, and afterward employing these words as having the same meaning. For instance, Fichte tries to establish the identity of being and thought, or general existence and personal existence. If we allow him to do this in the beginning, of course he can make whatever use he pleases of facts ; for if we admit that facts exist only in the mind, and if the mind is expressed only through language, he can form any hypothesis he wishes and we are powerless to resist ; for with an intel- lectual appetite which is hardly conceivable he devours fact itself, and consequently has on his own side all the facts in any argument he chooses to moot. But Fichte was too moral a man to make any dishonest use of the great logical advantage thus claimed. He amused himself in building up theories, which in turn served to amuse others. These theories have been called by his commentators " Theoretical Philosophy," to distinguish them from practical philosophy a not unsuggestive distinction. We must not forget, however, that Fichte's incomparable character, his enthusi- asm for intellectual and moral reform, his brilliant talents and scholarship, won for him vast numbers of admirers. Shortly after he began his lectures at Jena, Forberg writes : " Fichte is believed as Rheinhold never was. The students understand him even less than his predecessor, but they be- lieve all the more earnestly on that account." Leaving the metaphysics of Fichte to their fate, we turn with pleasure to his Moral Philosophy, which has a freshness and reality about it that enable it to survive the mystifying influences of his logic. What, he asks, is the revelation which consciousness gives ? It consists in the fact that GERMAN PHILOSOPHY. 173 41 1 am free ; and it is not merely my action, but the free de- termination of my will to obey the voice of conscience, that decides all my worth. More brightly does the everlasting world now rise before me ; and the fundamental laws of its order are more clearly revealed to my mental sight. My will alone, lying hid in the obscure depths of my soul, is the first link in a chain of consequences stretching through the invisible realms of spirit, as in this terrestrial world the ac- tion itself, a certain movement communicated to matter, is the first link in a material chain of cause and effect, en- circling the whole system. The will is the efficient cause, the living principle of the world of spirit, as motion is of the world of sense. I stand between two worlds, the one visible, in which the act alone avails, and the intention matters not at all ; the other invisible and incomprehensible, acted on only by the will. In both these worlds I am an effective force. The Divine life, as alone the finite mind can conceive it, is self-forming, self-representing will, clothed, to the mor- tal eye, with multitudinous sensuous forms, flowing through me and through the whole immeasurable universe, here streaming through my veins and muscles, there pouring its abundance into the tree, the flower, the grass. The dead, heavy mass of inert matter, which did but fill up nature, has disappeared, and, in its stead, there rushes by the bright, everlasting flood of life and power from its Infinite Source." This kind of eloquence, which was a new thing in the German language, must have moved the hearts, excited the minds, and transcended the understanding of Fichte's stu- dents. When it is carefully analyzed, however, it is found to be a sort of summer-night's dream in philosophy, which is fascinating though enervating to the mind. Frederick William Joseph Schelling was born in Wiirtem- berg, January, 1775, and was therefore thirteen years younger than Fichte. He afterward became Fichte's pupil and chief expositor, succeeding to his chair at Jena. Schelling made the acquaintance of Hegel at the University of Tubingen, where a warm and lasting friendship was formed between 174 THE SCOPE OF LANGUAGE. them. He remained in Bavaria until 1842 (where he was "honored, rewarded, and ennobled," when the King of Prussia persuaded him to come to Berlin to fill the chair once held by Hegel. Lewes tells us that in 1845 ^ e " had the gratification not only of hearing him lecture on Mythol- ogy to large audiences, but also of hearing him, in the ex- pansiveness of private conversation, pour forth his stores of varied knowledge." He continued an active, intellectual life to the last, and died August 20, 1854. Schelling taught that the Reason was incapable of solv- ing the problems of philosophy, a very old doubt, but certainly an inconsistent one ; for does not philosophy, which is an effort to solve the problem of existence, pre- suppose a belief in our ability to succeed? But this incon- sistency was a mere trifle to some of the difficulties which Schelling attempted to overcome. He saw that it was necessary to have some faculty which he could believe was able to solve the problem of life, so he decided to call this faculty the " Intellectual Intuition," a name so apt and pleasing that it has continued in use ever since, and is de- voutly believed in as a mental principle distinct from the natural coordinations of reason, even by advanced psycho- logical writers, who are supposed to belong to an opposite school. Schelling inaugurated what may be called an aristocracy of intuition, to which only a privileged few could gain ad- mittance. The line which circumscribed this elite, however, seems to have been drawn against all those who could not understand Schelling's philosophy. " Really," he exclaims, " one sees not wherefore Philosophy should pay any atten- tion whatever to Incapacity. It is better rather that we should isolate Philosophy from all the ordinary routes, and keep it so separate from ordinary knowledge that none of these routes should lead to it. Philosophy commences where ordinary knowledge terminates." Here we see some of the first fruits of that unnatural transcendentalism which Kant so successfully established in Germany. GERMAN PHILOSOPHY. 175 The foundation of Schelling's philosophy was the lumi- nous principle that " Nature is Spirit visible ; Spirit is invis- ible Nature: the absolute Ideal is, at the same time, the absolute Real." If this proposition were as harmless as it is meaningless, we could well afford to pass it by without further comment. Let us, however, examine this saying, which depends so largely upon the meaning of the word absolute. The salient points in Schelling's philosophy are best brought out by comparing his system with that of Fichte. Fichte said that the Non-Ego was created by the Ego; Schelling said that the two were equally real, and that both were identified in the Absolute. " In what, then, does Schelling differ from Fichte, since both assert that the pro- duct (Object) is but the arrested activity of the Ego ? In this: the Ego in Fichte's system is a finite Ego, it is the human soul. The Ego in Schelling's system is the Abso- lute the Infinite the All, which Spinoza called Substance \ and this Absolute manifests itself in two forms in the form of the Ego, and in the form of the Non-Ego as Na- ture and as Mind." 1 When we remember that the word' absolute has no deeper meaning than Time, and that Time is not an ultimate but a relative fact an aspect of Motion ; when we think that the Ego means nothing but the indi- vidual ; that the Infinite means that other aspect of Motion which we call Space ; and that Substance, also, when used in its widest sense, means Space ; we can see how all these efforts to transcend the limits of language, to place words before things, ideas before facts in the order of reality, serve but to emphasize the great truth that a true con- ception of knowledge can be obtained alone by reducing the number of the categorical terms until the meaning of all possible combinations of words converges in that of a single term or universal principle. How long will the higher ingenuities of man be exerted to resist this all-powerful truth, and, by so doing, postpone the success 1 Lewes: "Hist, of Phil.," p. 709. 176 THE SCOPE OF LANGUAGE. of philosophy, which is simply an ultimate analysis bringing the mind, or individual life, into harmony with general ex- istence ? But notwithstanding its intricacies and absurdities, there is an underlying strength in Schelling's thought which makes it evident that if Germany could only throw off this curse of Idealism, her genius would again assert itself and accomplish great things in the world of speculation. Schelling's writings display great knowledge and research, fine intuitions, but so many changes of opinion occur that, although some posi- tions are adhered to throughout, it is impossible to construct from them any coherent method. In this particular Hegel differs from Schelling ; for in Hegel we have a new and coherent method of dealing with the problems of philosophy. George Frederick William Hegel was born at Stuttgart .in 1770, and studied philosophy and theology at Tubingen. He was a private tutor in Switzerland and Frankfort until the death of his father in 1801, when a small inheritance enabled him to remove to Jena and to publish his first work, a dissertation directed against the Newtonian sys- tem of Astronomy, in which he pitted the transcendental theories of Schelling against the scientific method of in- duction. In any other country this proceeding would have helped the fame of Newton ; but in Germany it obtained for Hegel the reputation of an original thinker. Soon after this he joined Schelling in editing the " Critical Journal of Phi- losophy/' in which appeared his celebrated essay entitled " Faith and Knowledge," a criticism on Kant, Jacobi, and Fichte. It was at Jena also that he wrote his " Phanom- enologie des Geistes," the writing of which was not even interrupted by the battle which gave that place into the hands of the French. On the nigfyt of this battle he is said to have finished the work, oblivious of the pain and terror with which he was surrounded. We shall not be disap- pointed in the production of a mind capable of withdrawing itself so completely from the world. In 1816 he was called GERMAN PHILOSOPHY. 177 to the chair in Heidelberg, and two years later to that of Berlin, the first in Germany. Here he formed a school which included many illustrious members, and lectured until his death in 1831. What has made the fame of Hegel is the invention of his new method of philosophy. The world hitherto had been unable to discover the procedures of the mind ; Hegel fixed upon a mental procedure of his own and discovered it to the world. This method was none other than the fa- mous identity of contraries, which teaches that objects or ideas which are different are, in a sense, not different ; that contradiction implies an innate identity ; that subject and object are one, or that internal and external are equivalent terms in a transcendental sense. This, of course, was a great discovery, because, at least in the form in which Hegel ex- pressed it, it had never been made before ; and Hegel at once became a German prophet. Some hardy critics pronounced the principle absurd, because it led to contradictions, but Hegel replied that this was the very reason why it was true ; for, he said, the conditions of all truth consist in the identity of contraries or contradictions. This, it cannot be denied, was logical, providing his first assertion be admitted. The ground for this assertion, it is true, is a question of fact, but Hegel held himself superior to facts, and the intellectual portion of Germany applauded his brave position. Hegel established "Absolute Idealism." Kant was con- tent with plain idealism, Fichte with subjective, and Schell- ing with objective idealism. Hegel wanted absolute ideal- ism, and he therefore established it. " It may be thus illustrated : I see a tree. Psychologists tell me that there are three things implied in this one fact of vision, namely, a tree, an image of that tree, and a mind which apprehends that image. Fichte tells me that it is I alone who exist ; the tree and the image of the tree are but one thing, and that is a modification of my mind. This is Subjective Idealism. Schelling tells me that both the tree and my Ego are existences equally real or ideal, but they are 1 78 THE SCOPE OF LANGUAGE. nothing less than manifestations of the Absolute. This is Objective Idealism. But according to Hegel, all these expla- nations are false. The only thing really existing (in this one fact of vision) is the Idea the relation. The Ego and the Tree are but two terms of the relation, and owe their reality to it. This is Absolute Idealism." Some say that this idealism of Hegel is but the skepticism of Hume in a dogmatic form ; others, that it is a refinement of the Spinozistic notion of Substance. It is, in my opinion, a great truth badly expressed. The twelve octavo volumes of Hegel's Philosophy and Logic were not written in vain ; they constitute the most tortuous and fantastical expression that the world has ever produced of the simple truth that the ultimate fact or re- lation is Motion, and that Time and Space are its subjective and objective aspects. The harmonies of this truth can be traced throughout his dexterous paradoxes and his ingenious word-puzzles, but with an effort that is out of all proportion to the benefit derived. In fact Hegel, instead of helping the world to find the ultimate reality, seems to have done all he could to render it forever incomprehensible. And had we no other means of studying philosophy than Germany thus af- fords us, it is a question whether our civilization would last long enough to bring this truth to light. The difficulty, therefore, is not in understanding German thought, but in establishing, by any reasonable mental effort, an agreement between its assertions and the facts of consciousness and life. The warning of Herder against the idealism of Kant and his followers, however, was not entirely lost. There has been a distinct opposition in Germany, which has, in a measure, represented Herder and repeated his protests, but with little or no effect. Chief among this opposition we find the name of Schleiermacher (1768-1834), preceded by Christian Gottlieb Selle, Adam Weishaupt, Feder, Tittel, and Tiedemann. These men have defended the doctrine of the objective and real validity of knowledge, but their voices have been practi- cally unheeded by both philosophic and scientific Germany. 1 Lewes : " Hist, of Phil.," pp. 723, 724. GERMAN PHILOSOPHY. 179 Again: Schopenhauer, the pessimist (1788-1860), tried to reconcile idealism and realism, and postulated the Will (used in a wider sense than as a human faculty) as the ultimate reality. The success of these efforts can be best judged of from the writings of such prominent modern scientists as Du Bois-Reymond, and his pupil Professor Rosenthal, who distinguished themselves by brilliant discoveries in nervous phenomena, the very citadel of thought, and yet regard the mind with superstition, plainly showing the influence of the a priori philosophy. We also have the recent assertion of Karl Hillebrand, that " almost all the really great men of science in Germany are neither materialists nor spiritualists, nor skeptics, but critics of the Kantian school." 1 But again it is to be remembered that Germany has prac- tically repudiated, little by little, all the post-Kantian phil- osophy of Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel, whom Schopenhauer courteously calls the three great impostors, and rests her case upon what Kant himself lived to refute and recall, the anal- ysis of mind to be found in the " Critique of Pure Reason." We are told that Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel endeavored to be true Kantians, but by resting one foot on the " Cri- tique of Pure Reason," and the other on the " Critique of Practical Reason," they were obliged to perform all sorts of logical contortions to preserve their equilibrium. When all these things are considered are we not, upon the whole, entitled to say that the transcendental production known as German philosophy assumes, to the disinterested student, the appearance of a huge family quarrel rather than a worthy attempt to solve the problems of life ; and that, as far as the progress of thought is concerned, the world can well afford to dispense with it ? Hence it is with a feeling of unfeigned relief that we turn to the more mature and gradually developed culture of France and England, in which soil the idiosyncrasies of thought that achieved such rank development in Germany, although frequently making their appearance, have never been able to gain a substantial hold. 1 " German Thought," p. 203. CHAPTER VIII. THE ECLECTICISM AND POSITIVE PHILOSOPHY OF FRANCE AND THE SCOTCH SCHOOL. Gassendi Malebranche Condillac Cabanis Gall Royer-Collard Cousin Comte Reid Hamilton. AFTER the religious fervor of Europe had expended itself in the Crusades, there remained the three famous orders of chivalry known as the Teutonic Knights, the Templars, and the Knights of St. John. The latter maintained their or- ganization by a long and valiant defence of Southern Europe against the Turks. The Templars were disbanded about fifty years after the last Crusade, while the Teutonic Knights turned their attention to Christianizing what was then known as pagan Prussia. This they did by almost exterminating a brave and hardy people, who loved their rude mythology and bitterly opposed the forms of Christian worship and the rule of the Empire. While this was going on, Paris had become the first great seat of learning in Christendom ; its University was then a congeries of schools connected with monasteries and churches, but without that corporate unity which afterward made it the model of almost all the Uni- versities of Europe. As an example of its early importance, Henry II. of Eng- land, in 1196, offered to refer his dispute with Becket to the arbitration of the Peers of France, the Gallican Church, or -the Nations of the University of Paris. Toward the end of the thirteenth century Pope Nicholas IV. conferred privi- leges upon the doctors and students which virtually gave the University a government of its own ; and in the middle vof the fifteenth century it was attended by over twenty-five 1 80 THE ECLECTICISM OF FRANCE. i8l thousand students, which at that time was nearly half the population of Paris. It was in Paris that the chief battles of Scholasticism were fought. William de Champeaux, Abelard, Thomas Aquinas, and Duns Scotus, all lectured there. When the great Luther sounded the alarm of inde- pendent thought, which resulted in the emancipation of learned Europe from the papal authority of Plato and Aris- totle, Loyola opposed the movement by establishing the Society of Jesus, with its invincible organization and re- nowned culture. His object was to preserve the Catholic faith in its entirety, including its ancient philosophy. But it was the favorite pupil of the Jesuits, Descartes, who soon afterward dealt the death-blow to Scholasticism, emanci- pating thought from the tyranny of the church. Thus it was in the turmoil of the theological war which raged throughout England, France and Germany, and culmi- nated in the establishment of Protestantism, that modern philosophy was born. It was born in the writings of Des- cartes and Spinoza, and was therefore an avowed attempt to define, not motion, but the nature of God. Thus in severing its connection with theology philosophy exalted its religious character, instead of debasing it. It proceeded, untrammelled by obsolete faiths, to form a true conception of the unity of God, to bring all thought into harmony with this highest of thoughts, to establish an ultimate gen- eralization. But what great influence has been urging the claim of Motion to its position as the highest or most general con- ception ? Is it not the voice of Science, trying to persuade us that God is a principle, not a person ? Its method is patiently to classify and arrange all experience into one vast organon of truth. As Science progresses, it becomes more and more conscious that there is but one fact or principle, in which all analysis ends and all synthesis begins. Bacon, in England, took the sure path of science, feeling that although he might not reach a complete analysis of knowledge, such progress as he made would be in the right 1 82 THE SCOPE OF LANGUAGE. direction. There was but feeble resistance offered to this reform in France ; the age felt the need of throwing off the delusions of arbitrary dialectics and reaching out for actual facts. Such, however, is the fascination in seeking the ulti- mate analysis of life, that the superb scientific achievements of Descartes were neglected for his complicated and unsatis- factory metaphysics, which led to a dual principle, and there- fore did not even pretend to unify knowledge. To the philosophy of Descartes was opposed that of Gas- sendi, who inaugurated the eclectic philosophy, a school which subsequently attained to such eminence in France through Royer-Collard, Jouffroy, and Cousin. Pierre Gassendi was born in Provence, France, in 1592, and became a distinguished astronomer and mathematician, as well as a theologian. At the age of twenty-four he was appointed Professor of Theology at Aix, where he had studied. His first work was a polemic entitled " Paradox- ical Essay Against Aristotle " (1624), in which he opposed the Aristotelian Astronomy, but announced his fidelity to the church, maintaining that Christianity was in nowise dependent upon the then Christian philosophy. In 1647, through the influence of the Archbishop of Lyons, brother of Cardinal Richelieu, he was appointed Professor of Math- ematics in the College-Royal of France, where his lectures attracted great attention, and were attended by the Mite of Paris. "A System of Epicurean Philosophy " and " The Philo- sophical System of Gassendi " were his principal works. The latter was a combination of the various systems of antiquity, with a view to showing by their juxtaposition the correct method ; which is the plan of Eclecticism. Gassendi also wrote a criticism of the " Meditations " of Descartes, opposing the innovations of that writer in meta- physics. But his chief power was in the field of scientific investigation, where he had such friends as Kepler, Galileo, and Descartes. His reasonings with regard to the atomic theory are especially interesting and show a great boldness of thought. THE ECLECTICISM OF FRANCE. 183 Gassendi combined the idea of material substance as taught by Descartes, with the idea of atoms. The weight of the atom he identified with its motion or energy ; thus refuting the theory of the imponderability of atoms which we find current among some physicists even of the present day. Motion, which is the fundamental fact in all phenom- ena, was selected by Gassendi in lieu of Descartes' erroneous theory of an ultimate substance or matter. " The atoms (created and set in motion by God) are the seed of all things : from them, by generation and destruction, every thing has been formed, and fashioned, and still continues so to be." It is also interesting to observe that Gassendi explained the fall of bodies by the earth's attraction, and yet, like Newton himself, held action at a distance to be impos- sible. A reference to the teachings of Democritus and Epicurus will distinctly show the source of Gassendi's speculations, as both these men offer a very refined and, considering their time, a wonderfully advanced theory of the universe, in which all phenomena are reduced to the principle of the related activities of atoms, or the finest imaginable subdi- vision of matter, the first step in the direction of an ulti- mate analysis. Gassendi also wrote a history of the science of Astronomy, including an account of the lives of Copernicus and other great astronomers, an excellent description of the state of that science in his day. The seventeenth century in France was as conspicuous for its theological activity as the eighteenth century was for its general and absorbing interest in philosophy. Nicholas Malebranche (1638-1715) was the last and great- est of those Oratorian priests and writers who contributed so largely to the religious literature of France. The philosophy of Malebranche was entirely subservient to the doctrines of the Catholic Church, and developed the ideal or mystical side of Descartes' teachings. It is so full of beauty and high moral purpose, however, that no philosophic 1 84 THE SCOPE OF LANGUAGE. writer has been more read and admired in France, not even Descartes. His chief work, " Recherche de la Ve- rit " (1674), was immediately recognized for its literary and philosophic merit. As a metaphysician, Malebranche interests us but little, for his reasonings are so mystical, or ideal, that he has been called the Kant of his country. He was essentially a Christian philosopher, and deduced his theory of knowledge from communication with a personal Deity, something after the method of St. Augustine or Moses, but with a less concrete conception of God. Malebranche taught that the soul and the body are enti- ties, absolutely distinct, and, as a natural consequence, that the senses cannot supply us with truth. As God embodies all truth, the soul must receive this truth directly from God, and endeavor to preserve it untainted by the sinful body. All of this sounds more like theology than philosophy. Male- branche was nevertheless far too good a writer and thinker to be neglected in a review of philosophy. He had an intu- ition of divine unity, and endeavored to express it by har- monizing the philosophy of Descartes with Christian beliefs. This gives us a succession of essays on duty which nothing but a most delicate and profound understanding of life could produce. These thoughts on ethics are interspersed with Platonic metaphysics, rendered in the terminology of Des- cartes. Next in the history of French thought, and really the di- rect logical successor of Gassendi and Descartes, we have Etienne De Condillac, who was born at Grenoble in 1/15. The attention which Locke's philosophy had attracted in France was signalized by this writer. Locke had en- deavored to prove that all thought springs from sensation and reflection. Condillac offered a simplification of this theory by saying that thought and sensation are but different views of the same thing, that sensation presupposes a sen- sorium, and that every activity of a sensorium is in some degree a thought. This opinion is vehemently opposed by modern psychologists, upon the ground that thought is THE ECLECTICISM OF FRANCE. 185 exclusively the function of a special thinking organ called the brain ; and that the fact that some animals evince highly complex sensations after the brain has been removed proves that sensation is independent of thought. Condillac and his pupils gave to the word thought a wider meaning than perhaps properly belongs to it, but this is ex- cusable when we remember that it is only by calling atten- tion to the elasticity of the meaning of words that their hidden interdependencies are brought to view. The aphorism " to think is to feel " (pensercest sentir) is called an absurdity of the Sensational school, to which Condillac belonged ; but there is no denying that this dictum has a logical value, for the simple reason that no psychologist is able to point out exactly where sensation ceases and thought begins, although these faculties are distinct enough when viewed separately. Thought is a coordination, an activity, which takes place in the nervous system. That its operation is not entirely confined to the brain there are many means of proving. The effects upon thought which disturbances in the system, remote from the brain, occasion, to say nothing of the organic diseases which wholly incapacitate the mind, are familiar instances of the obscure cooperation of the whole sensorium in the act of thinking. The muscle .and the nerve are nowhere absolutely disjoined. But there is no need of confusing their functions. Condillac had no difficulty in distinguishing between thought and sensation, as the words are commonly used ; he simply wished to point out the fact that there is no absolute dividing line between thought and sensation ; and in so doing he rendered a service to philos- ophy ; although it is easy, from the better understanding which we now have of the subject, to find fault with his phraseology. Condillac, in his criticism of Locke, says : " Locke dis- tinguishes two sources of ideas, sense and reflection. It would be more exact to recognize but one ; first, because reflection is, in its principle, nothing but sensation itself; 1 86 THE SCOPE OF LANGUAGE. secondly, because it is less a source of ideas than a canal through which they flow from sense. This inexactitude, slight as it may seem, has thrown much obscurity over his system. He contents himself with recognizing that the soul perceives, thinks, doubts, believes, reasons, wills, reflects ; that we are convinced of the existence of these operations, because we find them in ourselves, and they contribute to the progress of our knowledge ; but he did not perceive the necessity of discovering their origin and the principle of their generation, he did not suspect that they might only be acquired habits ; he seems to have regarded them as innate, and he says only that they may be perfected by ex- ercise." x This seems unjust to Locke, when we remember how he strove to prove that we have no innate idea ; and yet Condillac's exception is well taken, for Locke does speak of many faculties as belonging to the mind, without offering any clear explanation of their origin. Condillac's psychology can hardly be called scientific, if we compare it with such recent works as those of Bain, Spencer, and Lewes. At the age of thirty-one he published his first work, an " Essay on the Origin of Human Knowl- edge " (1746). This was followed, in 1754, by his "Treatise on Sensation," which spread his reputation throughout Europe : soon after this he was appointed preceptor to the Prince of Parma, for whose use he wrote his "Cours d'Etudes." Among his literary friends we find the names of J. J. Rousseau, Grimm, and Diderot. In 1768 he was elected a member of the French Academy, but never after- ward attended any of its sittings. The chief merit of Condillac was his discovery of the im- portance of language as a factor in intelligence. He taught that we owe the development of our faculties to the use of signs, and that the power of thinking is directly depend- ent upon the exercise of speech. When we think how important these inductions are, and how little progress 1 " Extrait raisonne du Traite des Sensations." " CEuvres de Condillac" -(1803), IV., 13. ; THE ECLECTICISM OF FRANCE. has since been made beyond them, we realize the signal im- portance of Condillac's services to thought. As Comparative Physiology originated with Goethe, so did Comparative Psychology, notwithstanding its present un- developed state, originate with Cabanis, a French physician and philosopher, born at Conac, in 1/57. Cabanis admitted that all mental phenomena were reducible to activities akin with sensation, but he asked, What, after all, is sensation ? Is it feeling the name we give to sensations of which we are conscious ; and if so, what degree of consciousness does the word sensation imply ? What are we to call those myriad changes constantly going on within us of which we are entirely unconscious ? Is it not clearly only those activities which are sufficiently obtrusive to attract attention that we call feeling ; and are not all internal activities, in the broad- est sense, sensations ? These inquiries of Cabanis fairly opened the problems of Comparative Psychology, for they cited, as the field of psychological research, the whole vast empire of organic life in which the psychical states are but the evidences of a higher complexity of action. In the ascending complexity of organisms we have more and more sensitiveness to remote influences, more and more perfect coordinations of these impressions ; and as function and .structure are but different views of a single fact of develop- ment, we have potentialities which we severally call instincts, faculties, and innate ideas, awakened into activity, not created, by the experiences of life. Without certain inherited structures certain degrees of development are impossible, but the structure is not wholly in the individual, it resides also in the physical and intellectual environment, i. e. in civilization and language. Thus Cabanis not only demar- cated the scope of psychology, but he actually began the science by "connecting the operations of intelligence and volition with the origin of all vital movements." Auguste Comte later built upon this great plan, and in the systems of Herbert Spencer and George H. Lewes we shall find it .further developed. In 1802 Cabanis produced his principal 1 88 THE SCOPE OF LANGUAGE. work, " Relations Between the Physical System and the Mental Faculties of Man." He warns his readers that they will find no discussions of ultimate principles in his works. He contented himself with studying mind as the function of an organism ; and although some of his conclusions were crude, such as that " the brain secretes thought as the liver secretes bile," the worst that can be said of them is, that they are unhappy metaphors imperfectly expressing impor- tant truths. Cabanis was a personal and political friend of Mirabeau, the undisciplined genius of the French Revolution, whom he assisted with his pen during the great struggle. Diderot,, Condorcet, and Franklin are also numbered among the friends of Cabanis, who seems to have been in full sympathy with the great political and social movement of his time, a period in which a calm and complete philosophy was surely not to be thought of. We have now to note the appearance of an innovation in the study of the mind which was principally due to the Ger- man physician Francis Joseph Gall (1757-1828), the founder of the system of Phrenology. He graduated at Vienna, and practised medicine there for many years. He made a spe- cial study of the brain, and formed elaborate theories concerning the external signs connected with the different faculties of the mind. About 1805, with his coadjutor, Dr. Spurzheim, he began to propagate his views on Phrenology by lecturing in Paris, Berlin, and other cities. In 1808: he presented to the French Institute his " Researches into the Nervous System in General and the Brain in Particular," which was reported upon adversely by the committee to which it was given. Soon after this he began the publication of his principal work, " The Anatomy and Physiology of the Nervous System in General and the Brain in Particular." During the last twenty years of his life he was a resident of Paris. The bold theory that certain portions of the brain corre- sponded with certain mental faculties stimulated a more THE ECLECTICISM OF FRANCE. 189 thorough research into nervous phenomena. The chief ob- jection made to the generalizations of phrenologists is, that the exceptions to their rules are so many and serious that the rules are virtually destroyed by them, leaving but iso- lated observations which give little prospect of ever becom- ing a science. The correspondence, for instance, between certain cranial shapes and certain mental peculiarities is scarcely ever to be relied upon. Who would be willing, upon seeing the shape of the skull, without hearing the voice, observing the actions, or weighing the words of a person, to make even a guess at his mental capacity or characteristics ? We must remember that the cranioscopist has the advantage of all these other means of judging before making his guess. Even the simplest of all phrenological generalizations " the size of the brain is a measure of power, other things being equal/' has so many exceptions that it is practically value- less. Of this rule, Lewes, who is so much at home on the subject, says : " Phrenologists forget that here the * other things ' never are equal ; and consequently their dictum, ' Size is a measure of power,' is without application. There" never is equality in the things compared, because two brains exactly similar in size and external configuration will never- theless differ in elementary composition. * * * Nerve tis- sue, for example, contains both phosphorus and water as constituent elements, but the quantity of these elements varies within certain limits : some nerve-tissues have more phosphorus, some more water ; and according to these variations in the composition will be the variations in the nervous force evolved. This is the reason why brains differ so enormously even when their volumes are equal. The brain differs at different ages, and in different individuals. Sometimes water constitutes three fourths of the whole weight, sometimes four fifths, and sometimes even seven eighths. The phosphorus varies from 0.80 to 1.65, and 1.80; the cerebral fat varies from 3.45 to 5.30, and even 6.10. These facts will help to explain many of the striking excep- tions to phrenological observations (such, for example, as the THE SCOPE OF LANGUAGE. manifest superiority of some small brains over some large brains)." As far as Gall's efforts tended to place psychology on a physiological basis, they were in the right direction ; but it is to be observed that his chief followers have neglected the physiological side of phrenology for what is called cranios- copy, which on account of the uncertainty of its conclusions cannot be ranked as a science. Philosophy did not escape the reactions which followed the French Revolution. The reign of terror extended into thought. The horrors resulting from the brief and unnatural rule of ignorance and passion made the people return to the old belief that true intelligence is superhuman, so that the mys- tic philosophy of Christianity regained its ascendancy in the mind of the nation. The mistake made was that of suppos- ing the highest intelligence to be a mystery with which the church is in some way entrusted. Theories of life which attempt to do away with the element of mystery, which would make our highest concep- tions the natural or logical development of our most famil- iar experiences, have come in conflict with organized religion, and are therefore supposed to neglect the higher aspects of life. Until it is understood that the highest aspect of life means the most general or intelligent view of existence, un- til the idea of mystery is discovered to be but some degree of delusion, the endless recriminations which occur between the adherents of those schools of thought known respectively as the " natural " and the " supernatural " will continue to postpone the advent of a true religion, or the Unification of Knowledge. The effect of the Revolution upon the thought of France was to make it dread every thing anti-religious or anti- spiritual, and to bring the old-fashioned mystic philosophy again into favor. The best minds which France has since produced show an almost pathetic reverence for the spiritual. Had any one been bold enough to affirm that there is no fun- damental mystery in life, he would have been at once classed THE ECLECTICISM OF FRANCE. 191 with the demons of the Revolution. Not French Philosophy alone, but even French criticism, has been warped by this reactionary tendency ; and we find the most superb intellects cringing before this spectre of the mind, variously denomi- nated as the unknowable, the infinite, or the absolute, or, worse than all, the spiritual. Even in the recent speech of Renan, before the French Academy, we find him burning incense to this ancient God by numerous mysterious references to the " Infinite " ; while in all the eclectic philosophers, such as Royer-Collard, Cousin, and Jouffroy, this mystical element is clearly present. When the University of France was established by the Imperial Government, centralizing the whole educational system of the nation, Royer-Collard was called to the chair of philosophy (1809), but only accepted the invitation after long hesitation, and then immediately began a course of study to fit himself for the position. He had studied at the College of Saint-Omer, which was under the management of his uncle, the Abb Collard, had adopted the legal pro- fession, and taken an active interest in the stormy politics succeeding the Revolution. At the time of his appointment to the chair of philosophy he was regarded as a man of wide culture and fine abilities, but he had not identified himself with any particular school of philosophy. Our interest in him comes from the fact that he founded what is known as the Eclectic System of Philosophy, which afterward gained such a reputation in France. It was at first simply a comparative study of the chief systems of thought, but un- der Victor Cousin it assumed the character of a distinctive method, which we will duly examine. The attempt of Royer-Collard was to effect a compromise between what he regarded as the opposite extremes, Sensa- tionalism and Idealism. He rejected Condillac's analysis of consciousness, and endeavored to introduce the mystical ele- ment of Idealism in the modified form in which it occurs in the writings of Reid and Stewart. The influence which he exerted on the thought of France has been chiefly THE SCOPE OF LANGUAGE. through his pupils, among whom were Guizot, Ampere de Remusat, and Cousin. Victor Cousin is one of the chief philosophic writers of modern times. He was the king-maker of the French phi- losophy during the first half of this century, for he first crowned Reid and Stewart, making the Scotch school popu- lar in France ; then studying Kant, he imposed upon his obedient countrymen the autocracy of Konigsberg. Weary- ing of this, he raised to power Proclus of Alexandria, editing his works and advocating his cause ; and after this he gave his inconstant allegiance to the transcendental Hegel, weav- ing his theories into the celebrated doctrine of Eclecticism. To the prodigious amount of study which such changes of heart must have cost, Cousin added the arduous task of editing the complete works of Descartes in eleven octavo volumes, and producing his works on Abelard and Pascal, the celebrated translation of Plato in thirteen volumes, his " History of Philosophy," well known in this country, and several original treatises, besides contributing largely to the literary and philosophic reviews of France. It would be difficult to find a more agreeable and eloquent writer than Cousin. In him we have a striking instance of the difference between the highest order of erudition and real logical acumen. His style is clear and graceful, his pages are laden with interesting references and pleasing generaliza- tions ; but one looks in vain for the development of any great theme or deep-laid philosophic purpose. There is every thing to beguile, but nothing to establish, the mind. His method, briefly described, is, that "All systems are in- complete views of the reality, set up for complete images of the reality. All systems containing a mixture of truth and error have only to be brought together, and then the error would be eliminated by the mere juxtaposition of system with system. The truth, or portion of the truth, which is in one system would be assimilated with the portions of the truth which are in other systems ; and thus the work would be easy enough." AUGUSTE COMTE. 193 The extraordinary success which attended the lectures of Cousin in Paris from the year 1828 can only be accounted for by the beauty and lucidity of his expositions, and his en- thusiasm and eloquence. The interest which his lectures aroused has not been equalled since the days of William de Champeaux and Abelard. At the same time that Cousin and Jouffroy lived and taught, a mind of singular force and originality appeared in France as the founder of the so-called Positive philosophy. The name of Auguste Comte is familiar to the reading world, but the name of his philosophy is even more widely known. There is, however, nothing in his teachings which gives them an exclusive right to the name Positive, for we are unable to find that the author had a firmer grasp of the principles of certitude than many another philosopher. As the basis of his theory of knowledge, Comte postulates an unknowable existence, which he says we can never know. This mysterious existence, using the language of Plato and the Greek skeptics, he calls noumena. It is to be observed that he gives us no hint as to what the term noumena means, excepting that it is utterly unknowable. The reason which Comte gives for filling in the perspectives of human knowl- edge with noumena is, that our knowledge is only relative but noumena are absolute. Now, as absolute means without con- ditions, is it conscientious in Comte to impose upon noumena the condition of existence ? As for our knowledge being relative, it could hardly be any thing else, as relative means related, and we are certainly intimately related to the rest of the universe. The principles of certitude, therefore, which Comte fondly hoped to centre in his Positive philosophy are transgressed at the outset of his exposition of knowledge by intruding upon our perceptions the presence of an inde- finable mystery. After creating for himself these difficulties, Comte displays wonderful resources in avoiding them. His grasp of scientific facts is marvellous ; he marshals in review his battalions of data until one is overcome with the extent of his learning ; but as the succeeding columns disappear in 194 THE SCOPE OF LANGUAGE. the distance he offers no explanation as to whence this vast army comes or whither it is going. In a word, with regard to those ultimate problems of knowledge, such as the limits of language, and the nature of perception, Comte is incom- plete and unsatisfactory. The influence of Comte's writings in England was almost immediate. The English mind leans toward the positive, and was tempted by the name of the system to investigate it. Dr. Thomas Brown, J. S. Mill, Spencer, Lewes, and Harriet Martineau, all expound the Cours de Philosophic Positive. Comte had but a limited number of disciples in France ; the nation was too well entertained by the brilliant Cousin to give him their attention. The example of England, however, and the writings of Littre, the most eminent of Comte's disciples, at last brought the Positive school into such prominence in France that it is now commonly re- garded as the philosophic faith of the nation. The manner in which Comte abandons, in the outset of his system, the great problem of perception is thus aptly described by Mill : " The fundamental doctrine of a true philosophy, according to M. Comte, and the character by which he defines Positive Philosophy, is the following : We have no knowledge of any thing but phenomena ; and our knowledge of phenomena is relative, not absolute. We know not the essence, nor the real mode of production, of any fact, but only its relations to other facts in the way of succession or of similitude. These relations are constant that is, always the same in the same circumstances. The constant resemblances which link phenomena together, and the constant sequences which unite them as antecedent and consequent, are termed their laws. The laws of phenomena are all we know respecting them. Their essential nature and their ultimate causes, either efficient or final, are un- known and inscrutable to us." The metaphysical errors in this analysis of knowledge are now too familiar to need comment. They are the old, old errors of agnosticism, of skepticism, of the belief in an un- AUGUSTE COMTE. 195 knowable. These errors give us but another instance of the perverse habit in introspective analysis of creating a mystery and then worshipping it as a " final cause." The assump- tion made is that there is an absolute knowledge (which is an absurdity), that this absolute knowledge is beyond our knowledge, for " we have no knowledge of any thing but phe- nomena," and yet this absolute knowledge is defined as the " essence," the " real mode of production," the " final causes of phenomena." " The essential nature, the ultimate causes of phenomena are unknown and inscrutable to us," and yet it is insisted that we know of these things which are un- knowable. How much more simple would it be to deny the existence of these precious mysteries. Would we run any serious risk in denying the existence of things which have never troubled any one excepting those who affirm over and over again that they know nothing of them? If the com- pensation for the risk is to be a rational theory of knowledge, let us at least try it. Let some other race of philosophers take up and cherish these mysteries ; we have nursed them long enough. The chief merit of Comte's system is to be found in his sociological inductions, by which he indicates the organic nature of all human development, thus opposing the theory advanced by Rousseau and others, that society with all its complex processes is an artificial structure, a divergence from nature. Notwithstanding the contradictions above enumer- ated, Comte suggested, through his classification of the sciences, principles of mental evolution which have contrib- uted greatly to our conception of knowledge. Perhaps no writer ever aimed so high, ever attempted to do more. His propositions are splendid. "A social doctrine," he says, " is the aim of Positivism, a scientific doctrine its means." "The aim of Positivism is to create a philosophy of the sciences as a basis for a new social faith," hence his celebrated "Organon of the Sciences" and his "Religion of Hu- manity " ; add to this " the predominance of the moral point of view," "the rigorous subordination of the intellect to the 196 THE SCOPE OF LANGUAGE. heart," and we have the figure of the great emotional sys- tem of Comte. There is scarcely an idea which the most advanced biology, psychology, and even sociology establish which cannot be found latent in the writings of Comte, ideas of course derived in part from such writers as Cabanis, Gall, Condillac, and their predecessors. But criticism has no right to give to imper- fectly elaborated theories the more perfect form of later and higher developments. Thought, like science, must pass for what it is, not for what it could be, or might have been. The idea that law rules in the moral and social as well as the physical world is clearly emphasized by Comte, but the fur- ther development of this idea, which we find in Spencer and Lewes, constitutes the distinction of these latter writers from Comte. Hence, to say that Spencer owes all his philosophy to Comte, an assertion which has attracted some attention in England recently, is as untrue as it is ungenerous. It is a significant fact that the profundities of Comte's system were but poorly appreciated until Spencer actually established great inductions which are scarcely more than germinal thoughts in the positive philosophy. No one can doubt this who will carefully compare Comte's scheme of the sciences with Spencer's synthetic philosophy; and yet Comte's scheme of the sciences is his best work, that which has challenged the widest admiration. The theory of knowledge which runs thoughout this scheme, however, as already pointed out, cannot bear close analysis. Comte taught that all true methods of investigation are fundamentally alike ; that philosophy is but the union of all positive knowledge into a harmonious whole. These are good generalizations ; but the moment he particularizes he becomes arbitrary, and contradicts himself. He says that the progress of humanity has three stages, the theological, the metaphysical, and the positive ; for speculation always begins with supernatural, advances to metaphysical, and finally reposes in positive, explanations ; which is equivalent to saying that all conceptions of God, or all efforts to arrive AUGUSTE COMTE. 197 at an ultimate fact or principle, which, in all cultures, have taken the form of metaphysical and theological speculations, are to be cast aside as primitive methods tending but to un- certainty, and that positive philosophy alone complies with the canons of a true investigation. When we consider how faulty is the analysis of knowledge which this "positive philosophy " offers, and how true are the theological and metaphysical intuitions of the race when viewed as a whole, we fail to perceive that positivism has risen to the higher plane of thought and feeling which its author claims for it. This assumption of Comte is all the more strange when we remember how liberally he acknowledges the debt of human- ity to all who have contributed to the sum of knowledge either through religion or thought. The explanation is to be found in the fact that he was influenced by the belief in a fundamental mystery, and hence stigmatizes all efforts to find God, or an ultimate principle, as not only hopeless, but as belonging to stages of human development which are primitive in comparison to the unerring procedures of Posi- tivism. When we think that philosophy can only succeed by harmonizing religion with the search for divine unity known as metaphysics, and that the classifications of science can be but subsidiary to this achievement, we are unable to accept Comte's analysis of human progress or his definition of philosophy. And yet it is easy to see that notwithstanding his imperfect conception of the true nature of theology and metaphysics, he was keenly alive to the fact of a divine unity in life and mind ; for in describing the stages of human development he says that the highest condition of the theo- logical stage is " when one being is substituted for many, as the cause of all phenomena " ; of the metaphysical stage, "when all forces are brought under one general force called nature" ; and of the Positive stage, "when all phenomena are represented as particulars of one general view." This is certainly good evidence that notwithstanding his arbitrary subdivisions of progress he was conscious that the search for 198 THE SCOPE OF LANGUAGE. the Ultimate Fact, the First Cause, or God, first system- atically attempted in ancient Greece, still unremittingly prosecuted in our times, and which has been more or less distinctly voiced in all the concerted thought and feeling of the world, is the true philosophy, and that it must pursue the same methods to the end. Thus it is that in reviewing the writings of Comte we are forced into alternate con- demnation and praise, for with the highest merit the gravest inconsistencies are found. The subdivisions of philosophic thought have been largely determined by the ethnic sentiment, the ties of country and race. In ancient philosophy this is not so apparent, as Greece had little or no competition in the thought of other nations. In the Christian civilization, however, we not only find a rendering of philosophy in each of its languages, but there are further subdivisions corresponding with the geo- graphical boundaries of different peoples speaking the same language. It is natural enough that each different language of Europe should have a philosophy of its own, though these systems may much resemble each other. But when Scot- land and England are accredited each with a different school of thought, the merely geographical or national element in the division becomes obtrusive ; the classification lacks the dignity which should belong to the highest order of thought. As Auguste Comte taught a Positive philosophy, so did Thomas Reid promulgate a system of Common-Sense ; and as the qualities designated by these names are essential to every well-regulated mind, whether its surroundings be those of Athens, Paris, or Edinburgh, we must not be disappointed if we fail to find any very distinct logical characteristics in these systems corresponding with their names. The chief writers of what is called the Scotch School were, first, Thomas Reid (1710-1796), then Dugald Stewart, Thomas Brown, and Sir William Hamilton. They all lectured in Scotland. Stewart wrote upon the system of Reid, Brown lectured and wrote of both his predecessors, and Hamilton published complete editions of the works of Reid and THE SCOTCH SCHOOL. 199 Stewart ; so we have in the thought of these four men an organon of truth which, whatever may be its other excel- lencies, can at all events be clearly identified with Scotland. Bishop Berkeley was the first to formulate in English the doctrine of Absolute Idealism. Hume deduced from Berke- ley's arguments a skepticism which, as we have already pointed out, is virtually the same thing as Idealism. Thomas Reid rejected the skepticism of Hume. But by admitting the possibility of an unknowable existence, he really agreed with Hume in all essential particulars. Dr. Thomas Brown, upon being asked whether the difference between Reid and Hume was not chiefly one of words, replied: "Yes, Reid bawled out we must believe in an outward world ; but added, in a whisper, we can give no reason for our belief. Hume cries out, we can give no reason for such a notion ; and whispers, I own we cannot get rid of it." Thus we have a confession from one of the chief Scotch metaphysicians that Reid, although he claimed to have refuted both idealism and skepticism, was really an agnostic, which is the most popular name for the modern skeptic. Dugald Stewart comes very near the truth when he says that the belief in the external world, or space, is one of the " Fundamental Laws of Human Belief," or, as we would ex- press it, one of the conditions of perception. Reid sought to prove that our instincts account for our be- lief in an external world, but he insisted that it is impossible to account for our instincts ; which is hardly an acceptable solution of the problem of perception. " To talk of Dr. Reid," said the Quarterly, in its review of Stewart's Second Dissertation, " as if his writings had op- posed a barrier to the prevalence of Skeptical Philosophy, is an evident mistake. Dr. Reid successfully refuted the prin- ciples by which Berkeley and Hume endeavored to establish their conclusions ; but the conclusions themselves he himself adopted as the very premises from which he reasons. The impossibility of proving the existence of a material world from ' reason, or experience, or instruction, or habit, or any 2OO THE SCOPE OF LANGUAGE. other principle hitherto known to philosophers/ is the argu- ment, and the only argument, by which he endeavors to force upon us his theory of instinctive principles." Sir William Hamilton was one of the clearest and most advanced writers upon metaphysics, of modern times. His philosophy is principally devoted to the consideration of three questions, (i) the perception of the external world ; (2) the nature of necessary truths, or the principles of certitude ; and (3) the law of causation. The discussion of such ques- tions as these can lead to no definite results unless we first agree upon the signification of those general terms known as the Ultimate Realities, or the categories of thought. Such words as the Infinite and the Absolute, called by Hamilton the " two inconceivables," are employed so often that we feel convinced they stood for very important facts in his mind. Again : Space, Time, Matter, Force, and Motion, are con- tinually employed in conflicting senses. For instance, Hamilton affirms that Space and Extension mean the same thing, but, if there is any difference at all in them, Space is a priori and Extension a posteriori ; or, the idea of Space is given in the fact of mind and the idea of Extension grows up with experience. He also distinctly teaches that, whereas mind and matter both appear in Time, matter alone appears in Space : From which it is fair to conclude that space appears in mind, but mind does not appear in space. Now, as no mind has ever yet appeared out of space, we are unable to appreciate this distinction, however clear it may be to the admirers of the Scotch School. Again : Hamilton, it is well known, employs the word Matter frequently in the Kantian sense of Force, as a necessary element of consciousness, which makes it all the more difficult to understand how an element of consciousness, called matter, which we are told never appears out of space, can be an element of conscious- ness, if consciousness, or mind, appears only in Time and not in Space. It is generally admitted that matter always occu- pies space, but if mind cannot appear in space, the question arises, what becomes of the space which matter ought to oc- THE SCOTCH SCHOOL. 2OI cupy when it appears as an element of mind in Time alone ? It is evident from this that the Scotch School places matter in a very unfair position, for we are left to conclude that the matter which appears as an element of mind does not occupy the space that it should. Hamilton, as we have said, is one of the clearest and best writers upon metaphysics, of modern times ; but it cannot be denied that there are occasional infelicities in his manipula- tion of the Ultimate Realities, or the categories of thought, which none but the most indulgent readers of his system could overlook. How can we hope to determine such general questions as the " Perceptions of externals," " Necessary truths," " The law of causation," while such confusion reigns with regard to the meaning of the most general terms employed ? To Bacon can be traced the English love of the real as distinguished from the ideal in thought. The great work of Newton was a natural consequence of Bacon's scientific method, but Newton avoided all metaphysical discussions, not because he was not able to reason as well as any of his contemporaries, but because he was conscious of the need of a common understanding of the significance of general terms. The mind that could affirm that " all philosophy consists in the study of Motion " was incapable of enter- taining such a belief as the absolute separation of mind and matter : the mind that saw the impossibility of " action at a distance," or unrelated phenomena, could not consent to an absolute distinction between matter and space, or be- tween force and time. Science, in England, has steadily progressed upon the plan suggested and developed by Newton. In the mean- time the scientific study of mind as the function of an organ- ism, founded by Hobbes and Locke, and developed by Dr. Hartley, the elder Darwin, and the elder Mill, has led to such works as J. S. Mill's " System of Logic," the psycho- logical studies of Professor Bain, and the complete philo- sophic systems of Herbert Spencer and George H. Lewes. 202 THE SCOPE OF LANGUAGE. As these latter systems embody the highest results of English, and in fact of modern, science and thought, our argument can best be furthered by a careful review of them, especially as they constitute the most thorough study in ex- istence of that aspect of knowledge which we call perception. In closing this portion of the work, which has been in large part devoted to the explanation of the scope of lan- guage, let us bear in mind that language can only represent motion, that it is impossible to frame a sentence or express an idea which does not imply as a fundamental fact some movement or activity. The most abstract mathematical sym- bols, such as numbers, letters, a dot, a straight line, or a curve, represent respectively the operation of counting, the grouping of the results of counting, the separation of wholes into parts, the shortest movement between two points, or the movement of a point around a centre. It is well known that the most abstract metaphysical symbols, such as space and time, can only be represented by motions, and are but aspects of the universal fact of Motion. But there are few who are willing to acknowledge the full significance of this truth, that motion is the universal fact ; for it means that all compre- hension, perception, mind, will, are functions or consequences of this fact. This great truth, which is the simplest state- ment of the scope of language, can only be apprehended by studying the genesis of language ; and although this study is scarcely begun in the world, our argument would be in- complete if we were not to give some idea of it. The fundamental form of communication is by gesture. Gesture-language, therefore, is the genetic beginning of all language. Even in these days of developed and apparently arbitrary speech it constitutes a universal medium of ex- pression. Animals comprehend movements or gestures more easily than sounds ; but when we think that sound, or any other activity which appeals to the senses, is but movement, we begin to appreciate how utterly dependent the mind is upon activity or motion. It is a well-authenticated fact that deaf-mutes and savages converse readily through gestures, CLOSE OF THE ARGUMENT. 203 "because in the former, speech, or communication by words, is wholly undeveloped, and in the latter but imperfectly. Even when speech is highly developed, gestures are used as a further emphasis of meaning. The interaction of expres- sion and ideas, or language and thought, the fact that they develop each other, is aptly illustrated by the description which Kruse (himself a deaf-mute and a well-known teacher of deaf-mutes) offers of the formation of gesture-language : " Thus the deaf and dumb must have a language, without which no thought can be brought to pass. But here nature soon comes to his help. What strikes him most, or what makes a distinction to him between one thing and another, such distinctive signs of objects are at once signs by which he knows these objects, and knows them again ; they become tokens of things. And whilst he silently elaborates the signs he has found for single objects that is, whilst he describes their forms for himself in the air, or imitates them in thought with hands, fingers, and gestures, he develops for himself suitable signs to represent ideas, which serve him as a means of fixing ideas of different kinds in his mind and recalling them to his memory. And thus he makes himself a language, the so-called gesture-language ; and with these few scanty and imperfect signs a way for thought is already broken, and, with his thought as it now opens out, the language cultivates and forms itself further and further." It is well understood among those who have studied gesture-language that deaf- mutes and savages are far better able to master it and ex- press themselves than educated people who enjoy the full use of their faculties. Said the director of an Institute : " None of my teachers here who can speak are very strong in the gesture-language. It is difficult for an educated, speaking man to get the proficiency in it which a deaf-and- dumb child attains to almost without an effort." It is evident that all language not only springs from ges- ture-language, but is essentially of the same nature. Not only the means of expression, but the objects of expression, are found upon analysis to be motion. All sentences de- 204 THE SCOPE OF LANGUAGE. pend upon some verb (expressed action or being) for their meaning. Now, when being or existence is identified with life or universal activity through the aid of a metaphysical analysis, we see how from the grammatical side of language also we are irresistibly led to this ultimate fact. All parts of speech are but modifications or inflections of motion. Thus " the deaf-mute borrows the signs of space, as we do similar words, to express notions of time : * * * the present tense [of the verb can be expressed] by indicating ' here ' with the two hands held out, palm downward ; the past tense, by the hand thrown back over the shoulder, * behind ' ; the future, by putting the hand out, ' forward.' But when he takes on his conjugation to such tenses as ' I should have carried,' he is merely translating words into more or less appropriate signs." 1 Quoting from Quintilian, Mr. Tylor says : " As for the hands indeed, without which action would be maimed and feeble, one can hardly say how many movements they have, when they almost follow the whole stock of words ; for the other members help the speaker, but they, I may almost say, themselves speak. * * * Do they not, in pointing out places and persons, fulfil the purpose of adverbs and pro- nouns ? So that in so great a diversity of tongues among all people and nations this seems to me the common language of all mankind." " The best evidence," continues Mr. Tylor, " of the unity of the gesture-language is the ease and certainty with which any savage from any country can understand and be under- stood in a deaf-and-dumb school. A native of Hawaii is taken to an American Institution, and begins at once to talk in signs with the children, and to tell about his voyage and the country he came from. A Chinese, who had fallen into a state of melancholy from long want of society, is quite revived by being taken to the same place, where he can talk in gestures to his heart's content. * * * Macrobius says it was a well-known fact that Cicero used to try with Roscius, the 1 E. B. Tylor : " Early Hist, of Man." CLOSE OF THE ARGUMENT. 2O5 actor, which of them could express a sentiment in the greater variety of ways, the player by mimicry or the orator by speech, and that these experiments gave Roscius such con- fidence in his art, that he wrote a book comparing oratory with acting. Lucian tells a story of a certain barbarian prince of Pontus, who was at Nero's court, and saw a panto- mime perform so well, that though he could not understand the songs which the player was accompanying with his gestures, he could follow the performance from the acting alone. * * * Religious service is performed in signs in many deaf-and-dumb schools. In the Berlin Institution, the simple Lutheran service a prayer, the gospel for the day, and a sermon is acted every Sunday morning for the children in the school and the deaf-and-dumb inhabitants of the city, and it is a very remarkable sight. No one could see the parable of the man who left the ninety and nine sheep in the wilderness, and went after that which was lost, or of the woman who lost the one piece of silver, performed in ex- pressive pantomime by a master in the art, without ac- knowledging that for telling a simple story, and making simple comments on it, spoken language stands far behind acting. The spoken narrative must lose the sudden anxiety of the shepherd when he counts his flock and finds a sheep wanting, his hurried penning up of the rest, his running up hill and down dale, and spying backwards and forwards, his face lighting up when he catches sight of the missing sheep in the distance, his carrying it home in his arms, hugging it as he goes. We hear these stories read as though they were lists of generations of antediluvian patriarchs. The deaf-and- dumb pantomime calls to mind the ' action, action, action ! ' of Demosthenes." The connection between thought and language constitutes the best possible lesson in psychology. In ancient Greece, deaf-mutes were thought to be speechless on account of a deficiency of intellect : we, who take the opposite view, namely, that their deficiency of intellect is due to inability to speak and thus to develop the mind, are still apt to 2O6 THE SCOPE OF LANGUAGE. neglect the fact that there are all degrees of intellectual inca- pacity expressed in imperfections of speech. Thought and the power of uttering thoughts are not only interdependent activities, but they are different views of the same activity. " Thinking is talking to one's self" ; " Language shapes itself in mind, and mind in language." In the gesture-language, we are told, it is impossible to dis- tinguish between the verb and the noun, or the adjective and the adverb. This is because a noun represents the activity or appearance produced by an object, and this appearance is represented by actions or gestures corresponding to it, which really makes every noun a certain kind of action or a verb. " To say, for instance, * The pear is green,' the deaf-and- dumb child first eats an imaginary pear, and then, using the back of the flat left hand as a ground, he makes the fingers of the right hand grow up on the edge of it like blades of grass. We might translate the signs as ' pear-grass,' but they have quite as good a right to be classed as verbs, for they are signs of eating in a peculiar way, and growing." Again : since substantives and verbs are thus indistinguish- able, the adjectives and adverbs which qualify them are equally so ; for gestures bear the same relation to phonetic symbols or spoken words that picture-writing bears to alpha- betical writing. In gestures or pictures, the action expressed is conveyed to the mind directly, in its original or concrete form ; in spoken or written words, it passes through a meta- morphosis of sound and form, a sort of digestion, or reduc- tion to its simpler elements, which adjusts the action to the special senses, or the conditions of perception. Developed language is susceptible of a vastly greater ex- tension and definiteness, because what might be called the atoms of thought are so much more subdivided, and there- fore capable of higher complexities in their redistribution. We cannot make a mould with gravel ; we must use the finest clay, so that every detail of the model may be reproduced by the particles employed. To reproduce our thoughts, we must dissolve them into minute particles of sound and form, CLOSE OF THE ARGUMENT. called letters ; and with this simple medium we reconstruct the most delicate mental delineations. Behind this picture we can clearly see the irreducible fact of Motion, which in a complex form constitutes both the object and subject of thought, approached in its simpler conditions of form and sound through the medium of language. Hence language is an activity which extends the range of sentiency, relating for us the particular and the general, the complex and the simple, or the human and the divine. PART II. THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. 209 PART II. THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. CHAPTER IX. HERBERT SPENCER. The Relation of Perception to Universal Activity The Definitions of Evolu- tion and of Life The " Unknowable." HUMAN knowledge consists of the elaboration of per- ceptions, the organization of facts. The principle of per- ception, therefore, underlies and must explain the whole fabric of ontological science. Notwithstanding the vast pro- portions to which the writings upon this science have grown, there is probably no department of knowledge which, in the future, will require less space to record its truths than the science of Metaphysics. The imposing number of works upon ontology have not, however, appeared in vain. It was necessary that every pos- sible construction of the questions involved should be made before the mind could choose between them. Hence bodies of co-ordinated beliefs have sprung up in all directions ; these have coalesced into orders or schools named after the char- acteristics of each, such as ideal, spiritual, rational, natural, and positive. These schools have been subdivided into varieties which bear the names of their principal advocates, forming a long list and representing practically every possible shade of opinion. This is not only the history of metaphysi- cal science, but of all sciences ; it is, in fact, the only way in which opinion grows into settled belief. The test of truth in the majority of the sciences, although precisely the same 211 212 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. in nature, is much simpler than in philosophy, because the means of verification are so much nearer at hand. There is a horizon, however, to every science which eludes the special methods of each, and requires the combined logic of all to survey it. It is this outlying region of experience which constitutes the field of philosophy. Zeller tells us that " the term Philosophy, as in use among the Greeks, varied greatly in its meaning. Originally it denoted all mental culture, and all effort in the direction of culture. The word aocpia from which it is derived was applied to every art and every kind of knowledge. A more restricted significance seems first to have been given to it in the time of the Sophists, when it became usual to seek after a wider knowledge by means of more special and adequate instruction than ordinary educa- tion and the unmethodical routine of practical life could of themselves afford." Since the time of Plato this word has assumed a more and more special meaning, until to-day it is widely understood to designate not merely a development of knowledge, but a different kind of knowledge from that to which the particular sciences belong. The term mental science, again, has had, if any thing, a more restricted mean- ing than the more general term philosophy. The activities of the mind have been regarded as of another source and kind than other activities. This idea has grown until the different mental faculties, such as memory, will, reason, and perception, have come to be considered as separate princi- ples, the interdependencies of which are inscrutable. The confusion which these superstitions have engendered is only just beginning to give way before the new science of psy- chology, which studies the mind as an organ and its activity as part of organic life. Perception has always been conceded to be the chief men- tal faculty, partaking in its nature of all the others. The -theories concerning the nature of this faculty, which we find in the different systems of mental science, form the truest index to their comparative logical merit. A careful analysis, therefore, of the theory of perception which is presented in HERBERT SPENCER. 213 any system of philosophy, will serve to bring us by the shortest route to a comprehension of its scope, and the position it holds in the great hierarchy of Knowledge. The philosophy of Herbert Spencer has made an impres- sion in America : it is a system which has especially com- mended itself to the inquiring minds of our people. The Americans resemble the Greeks in their intellectual economy ; they have not buried themselves in the karning of the past, and are therefore keenly alive to the progress, and propor- tionately less attentive to the history, of thought. This fact has given Spencer's system, as a whole, an importance which it could not have attained in an older country. In England, and on the continent, Spencer's writings are esti- mated according to their individual merit, philosophical culture there being too general to admit of the concrete conception which we have formed of them. In reviewing a great and new system, such as the Syn- thetic Philosophy of Herbert Spencer, it is a certain dis- advantage to have studied it only at first hand. The enormous reach of its investigations, and the vast co-ordinat- ing power which has made this system one of the greatest achievements of modern thought, are such as to place all who study it, deeply in the author's debt. A new system, scarcely completed, has no subsequent expository l to illu- minate it, to help us to distinguish between what is really original with the author and what is imbibed from contem- poraneous thought. In a mind like Spencer's the rays of contemporaneous thought converge, and it is necessary to view it from a distance in time, in order to separate the re- flected from the individual light. Mr. Fiske says: " When Von Baer discovered that the evolution of a living organism from the germ-cell is a progressive change from homogeneity of structure to heterogeneity of structure, he discovered a scientific truth. But when Herbert Spencer applied Von Baer's formula to the evolution of the solar system, of the 1 1 am not unmindful of the excellent works of John Fiske and Malcolm Guthrie. 214 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. earth, of the totality of life upon its surface, of society, of conscious intelligence, and the products of conscious intelli- gence, then he discovered a truth in philosophy, a truth applicable not merely to one order of phenomena, but to all orders." * If this claim for originality in Mr. Spencer's be- half could be sustained, we should indeed have in him a Columbus of philosophy, for this vast discovery could be compared to a new continent of thought. That this new continent of thought, known as evolution, has been dis- covered, no one will deny ; but we should hesitate to give the credit to any individual, or even to any century. While we plume ourselves upon the discoveries of our century, we are continually forgetting that we are, in the strictest sense, but a consequence of the past ; that by reason of this ines- timable debt knowledge is, for the most part, but erudition, and philosophy but Eclecticism. In distributing the honors, therefore, to the originators of this great theory of Evo- lution, which our race is but beginning to appreciate, our encomiums become a hymn of praise to the thinkers of all ages. Spencer's philosophic system is an application of the principle of evolution to every conceivable aspect of life and of the universe. It begins with a work entitled " First Principles," which is in effect an epitome of the whole. The immediate purpose of this volume is to demonstrate the interdependence of all phenomena, and thereby to define the term evolution. Little by little as his argument progresses Mr. Spencer adds to the meaning of this word evolution, or rather he re- moves one restriction after another to its meaning until its generality alarms the metaphysician, and the inquiry arises, Is it not a universal term ? The position here taken with regard to the meaning of ultimate terms is already familiar to the reader. There can be but one ultimate fact, give it what name or names we please ; for ultimate means final, and a final fact is only distinguished from other facts by its 1 John Fiske : " Outlines of Cosmic Philosophy," vol. I., p. 40. HERBERT SPENCER. 21$ simplicity. If it were complex, it could be separated into more general facts. If it is simple, resisting all further analy- sis, if it is a common property of every fact, if it remains after every analysis has been pushed to its farthest limits, and if it is the foundation of every inference or synthesis, it is unity itself. That Mr. Spencer employs the term evolu- tion as an ultimate fact will be manifest to any one who will patiently examine his treatment of the subject in " First Principles." In closing the second chapter on the Law of Evolution, Spencer says : " As we now understand it, Evolution is de- finable as a change from an incoherent homogeneity to a co- herent heterogeneity, accompanying the dissipation of motion and integration of matter." * In a chapter entitled " The Interpretation of Evolution," and referring to the above described law of evolution, we find the following : "Is this law ultimate or derivative ? Must we rest satisfied with the conclusion that throughout all classes of concrete phenomena such is the course of transformation ? Or is it possible for us to ascertain why such is the course of transformation ? May we seek for some all-pervading principle that underlies this all-pervading process ? * * * It may be that this mode of manifestation is reducible to a simpler mode, from which these many complex effects follow. * * * Unless we suc- ceed in finding a rationale of this universal metamorphosis, we obviously fall short of that completely unified knowledge constituting Philosophy. As they at present stand, the several conclusions we have lately reached appear to be independent, there is no demonstrated connection between increasing definiteness and increasing heterogeneity, or be- tween both and increasing integration. Still less evidence is there that these laws of the redistribution of matter and motion are necessarily correlated with those laws of the direc- tion of motion and the rhythm of motion previously set forth. But until we see these now separate truths to be implications of one truth, our knowledge remains imperfectly 2 coherent. * * * 1 Spencer's " First Principles," p. 360. The italics are the author's. 1 The italics are the author's. 2l6 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. It has to be shown that the redistribution of matter and motion must everywhere take place in those ways, and produce those traits, which celestial bodies, organisms, societies, alike display. And it has to be shown that this universality of pro- cess results from the same necessity which determines eacJi sim- plest movement around us, down to the accelerated fall of a stone or the recurrent beat of a harp-string. In other words, the phenomena of Evolution have to be deduced from the Persistence of Force. As before said, f to this an ultimate analysis brings us down, and on this a rational syn- thesis must build up.' This being the ultimate truth which transcends experience by underlying it, so furnishing a com- mon basis on which the widest generalizations stand, these widest generalizations are to be unified by referring them to this common basis." If the widest generalizations result in the conception of evolution, and if the only common basis for these generalizations, as is admitted by Mr. Spencer, is the universal principle which he calls the " persistence of force," surely evolution in its widest sense is a universal principle. Nothing could simplify philosophy more than this identifi- cation of evolution as a universal principle. So serious are the consequences, however, so grand are the results, and withal so simple is the explanation, that the conventional thinker, entrenched behind his dogmatic dis- tinctions without differences, will make many objections. From this conventional reasoner the first objection would be that evolution is a process, not a principle. But a prin- ciple is merely a prominent or general fact, and it is clear that the fact or process of evolution is the most general in life. Where under the new light of biology and organic chemistry are we to find the limits of life? Is not the most prominent fact in " all phenomena " a universal fact ? Again it will be objected that the correlative or anti- thetical term of evolution is dissolution, and that all phe- nomena have these contrasted aspects, which remands the 1 " First Principles," pp. 397, 398. HERBERT SPENCER. 21 J term evolution to a more subordinate position in the scale of generality than "the persistence of force." This is an objec- tion which needs careful scrutiny, as it seems to mean more than it does. It is impossible to conceive of evolution in the philosophical sense in which the word is used without including the idea of dissolution, in the same way that it is impossible to conceive of the universal principle which we call life without including the idea of death. Again, the senses in which the word evolution is employed in mathematics and dynamics are entirely distinct from the broad philosophical sense, where it is the equivalent of the serial development of all things, " the evolution of ages." To say that evolution is not used by Spencer as a universal principle because its reverse process is involution, would be as sensible as to make the same assertion because dissolution, in a certain restricted sense, is the antithesis or correlative of evolution. Mr. Spencer may not be conscious of the fact that he has defined evolution as a universal principle, but when he builds up a system of philosophy in order to apply the process to all phenomena, that it is in its widest sense a universal fact is an irresistible inference from his words; and the distinc- tion between process and principle when both are facts of universal application becomes invidious. If, as Mr. Spencer says, " evolution is the redistribution of matter and motion," what event in time and space is independent of this cause ? A candid study of the manner in which Mr. Spencer em- ploys and defines the word will convince us that it stands in his mind for the highest generalization of life or existence, and that, as there are no absolute demarcations to life in the universe, evolution is a universal generalization or principle. And here we come to the theory of perception, which we hold to be the chief feature of every system of philosophy, determining its merit as an original production, its impor- tance as a contribution to knowledge ; for it is in the respect of learning the true nature of perception that real progress in philosophy has been made. We see from the above that 218 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. the formula of Evolution suggested by Mr. Spencer, which in its simplest expression is " the redistribution of matter and motion" is acknowledged by him to be but a derived law, or, in other words, a complex expression of a simple law or ulti- mate fact, which he denominates " the persistence of force" and which we submit can find a still more simple expression in the word Motion. Motion is the ultimate term in all the sciences, as well as in philosophy. When we remember the great principle that facts express themselves, it is apparent that the attempts to form such ab- stract generalizations as "concentration of matter" and "dis- sipation of motion" or " Evolution is an integration of matter and concomitant dissipation of motion, during which the matter passes from an indefinite, incoherent homogeneity to a definite, coherent heterogeneity ; and during which the retained motion undergoes a parallel transformation" 1 are useless, for the ultimate fact of motion is so obtrusive throughout that nothing is gained by the definition. As will be evident to any one who follows out Spencer's whole system, these involved formulas of the ultimate pro- cess of evolution are, for the most part, but vain attempts to define motion. These definitions depend for the terms in which they are expressed upon the aspects of the ultimate fact, Motion, or upon different names for the fact itself; such as co-existence and sequence, the equivalent terms space and time, or the frequently recurring motion and matter, which is the fact itself and one of its aspects (matter, the equivalent of space). To speak, therefore, of the redis- tribution of matter and motion as an ultimate law is simply to define motion in terms of its aspects, for the word motion gives us at once the idea of redistribution. I submit that it leads to no advance in knowledge to say that motion redis- tributes itself and one of its aspects. To familiarize ourselves with the procedures of nature is the province of science, but scientific analysis, so far as it is successful, stops with the ultimate fact, or divine unity. 1 " First Principles," p. 396. HERBERT SPENCER. In so far as Mathematics has tried to analyze this ultimate principle, it has failed, for there are no laws of motion which are not expressed by the term itself. 1 Where Physics has tried to analyze motion, it has failed. The cabalistics, which purport to convey a deeper knowledge of this fact than is given in the simple conception itself, are vanities and deceptions. All knowledge is expressed in terms of the 'aspects of motion, i. e. places and times. All knowledge consists in expressions of motion. The only way in which we can enlarge our horizon of facts is by assimilating new experiences with old ones ; the only way in which we can reveal to others these newly discovered facts is by ex- pressing them in terms of more familiar ones. This Spencer has done throughout his system. We are indebted to his powerful and effective method for some of the clearest and most commanding views of the interde- pendences of phenomena which the age affords ; but this very power which he has exerted so happily in revealing hidden truths has carried him to the excess, not of attempting impossibilities, for we admit no impossibilities to knowledge, but of creating impossibilities where none exist. This is 1 Solidity, in the sense in which it is attributed to the atom, is not a fact, but the hypostasis of an abstraction. As M. Cournot observes, an absolutely solid body is unknown to experience. The consistency of the bodies which present themselves to the experimental physicist depends upon the preponderance or bal- ance of forces, such as the forces of cohesion, crystallization, and heat ; and the assumption of the absolute solidity of matter results from that superficial and imperfect apprehension of the data of sense (in conjunction with the disregard of the essential relativity of all the properties of things; which is reflected in all the early notions of mankind. * * * Euler states that without the assumption of absolute space and motion there could be no laws of motion, so that all the phenomena of physical action would become uncertain and indeterminable. If this argument were well founded, the same consequence would follow a fortiori, from his repeated admissions in the first chapter of his book, to the effect that we have no actual knowledge of rest and motion, except that derived from bodies at rest or in motion in reference to other bodies. Euler's proposition can have no other meaning than this, that the laws of motion cannot be established or verified unless we know its absolute direction and its absolute rate. But such knowledge is by his own showing unattainable. It follows, therefore, that the establishment and verification of the laws of motion are impossible. Stallo : "Modern Physics," pp. 180, 202. 220 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. what all thinkers do who divide when they should multiply, who subtract when they should add, who, having found unity, are not content with it, but turn in quest of other uni- ties, or seek in unity itself variety. These futile attempts, which will never cease until the world at large learns to recognize them as useless, are the outgrowth of a misappre- hension of the nature of perception. This we hope duly to demonstrate. The celebrated definition of life which Spencer offers is without doubt a masterpiece of classification, but by reason of its unnecessary complexity it accomplishes less than it purports to do. It is as follows : " Life is the definite combination of heterogeneous changes, both simultaneous and successive, in correspondence with external co-existences and sequences'' Now if the terms employed in this definition are examined, it will be found that the equation which it constitutes can be greatly simplified. To express the conditions of life is to tell the story of the universe ; to study different kinds of life is to pursue certain branches of science. The principle of life is activity. All definitions of life, therefore, other than the mere citing of its principle, must be more or less special or limited ; they must denote the principle and connote cer- tain manifestations. The above definition denotes the prin- ciple of activity, or universal life, and connotes the char- acteristics of organic life. But the terms in which the connotations are made, when viewed in their full signifi- cance, amount to the assertion that organic life consists of motions or activities within an organism, co-ordinated with or adjusted to, or still better, acting and reacting with mo- tions without. The only inference, therefore, in this defini- tion, which has so imposing a sound, is that of an organism. If this inference is dropped, the sense of the definition is lost among the echoes and re-echoes of universal change. Although it is true that Mr. Spencer traces, practically, all phenomena to an ultimate cause or principle, he fails to es- tablish that harmony in the significance of ultimate terms HERBERT SPENCER. 221 which should be the aim of a true philosophy. With the means now at hand, is it not evident that in dealing with the great principles, such as Space, Time, Matter, Motion, and Force, and the " Persistence of Force " (a term made up of one of these principles and a word meaning virtually the same thing), we should be able to point out their correlation, interdependence, or relative significance ? In Chapter III., of the same work, 1 entitled " Space, Time, Matter, Motion, and Force," and in Chapters XIV., XV., and XVI., of the sec- ond volume of " Psychology," Spencer vigorously deals with this metaphysical problem. Indeed, so dependent upon this problem is the theory of perception, that it is scarcely pos- sible to discuss the two subjects separately. Thus, in Chapter III., of " First Principles," and in the chapters on Psychology above referred to, treating respectively of the Per- ception of Space, Time, and Motion, we find the same argu- ments, and the same failure to seize what we conceive to be the simplest solution of the two great allied questions of the nature of perception and the unification of the categories of thought. This solution, as I conceive it, is as follows: If a weight falls to the ground a fact is expressed, for the reason that facts express themselves ; wherever a fact is ex- pressed, there is a perception. Perception and expression, using these words in their widest possible sense, are obverse aspects of every fact. Every given change is a response to other changes, and in seeking the ultimate nature of percep- tion we are obliged to recognize this response as equivalent to a perception of the external change. This reduction of the meaning of the word perception to that of change, or motion, is the greatest achievement of psychology. To those who have not familiarized themselves with psychological analysis this proposition, that the deepest meaning in the idea of per- ception is found in the universal fact of motion, will hardly prove intelligible. This is because perception is generally considered to be exclusively a mental faculty. Many persons are incapable of following the meaning of perception beyond 1 "First Principles." 222 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. its anthropomorphic limits ; few have ever followed it be- yond its sentient limits. No psychological work known to me, not even that of Lewes, has attempted to follow the principle of perception beyond the limits of organic life; and yet I affirm that this principle is plainly to be seen in every phenomenon or change. Every activity is a response to other activities ; there is no final difference between the response of the simplest object to its simplest conditions, and the response of the highest mind to the farthest influences. The manner in which Mr. Spencer deals with these ques- tions can be readily seen by glancing at Chapters IV., V., and VI., of " First Principles." The indestructibility of matter and the continuity of motion are said to be necessary infer- ences from the Persistence of Force, which he declares to be " the sole truth which transcends experience by underlying it, * * * the cause which transcends our knowledge and conception, * * * that unknowable which is the neces- sary correlative of the knowable." l These are Spencer's explanations of the persistence of force, and from them we must derive his explanation of perception. They postulate a fact which is supposed to be the most general of all facts, the source of reality for both the mind and the universe ; a fact to which all physical phenomena can be reduced, the fact with which consciousness itself begins ; and yet he says that it is unknowable, that it transcends consciousness. It will not do to call this language loose or vague. It is Mr. Spencer who employs it. We must content ourselves with trying to glean from it the truth which is intended to be expressed. If by any chance we could suggest definitions of the categories of thought which would do away with the absurdities involved in " an unknowable fact, * * * a principle of consciousness which transcends both conception and experience, * * * an unknowable which is the necessary correlative of the knowable" we must perforce suppress them, because there are many very estimable persons who "cannot understand the universe without an unknowable." Their understanding 1 " First Principles," p. 192. HERBERT SPENCER. 22$. must be exceedingly delicate to be affected by that of which they know nothing. But perhaps they do know something of the unknowable. If the nature of perception were not involved in this ulti- mate fact, the contradiction in declaring the fundamental principle of life and mind unknowable might be less glaring. The philosopher could then baffle his readers by expanding upon a latent consciousness which is anterior to perception. An a priori mmd that employs the unknowable as a principle, but which does not know it this and other extravagances of expression might be employed to cover up the preposterous assertion that an apprehended fact, the most prominent of all facts, is unknowable. But when the issue of the nature of perception is forced, all subterfuges must be laid aside, and we may confront one another upon the simple and honest meaning of words. The believer in the unknowable, for instance, will hardly venture to say that we can perceive the unknowable, or that the unknowable is a factor in perception, and yet Mr. Spencer would deduce perception itself from this mystery. The indestructibility of matter is now generally admitted to be an axiom, or necessary truth. Of this truth Mr. Spencer says : " Our inability to conceive matter becoming non-existent is immediately consequent on the nature of thought. Thought consists in the establishment of rela- tions. There can be no relation established, and therefore no thought framed, when one of the related terms is absent from consciousness. * * * It most concerns us to observe the nature of the perceptions by which the permanence of Mat- ter is perpetually illustrated to us. These perceptions, un- der all their forms, amount simply to this that the force which a given quantity of matter exercises remains always the same. This is the proof upon which common-sense and exact science alike rely. * * * Thus we see that force is our ultimate measure of Matter ; * * * by the indestructibility of matter, we really mean the indestructibility of the force with which matter affects us. * * * This truth is made manifest 224 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. not only by analysis of the a posteriori cognition, but equally so by analysis of the a priori one. 1 And yet before and after these words, the truth, the principle, the fact, which is made manifest to us in so many ways, is declared to be unknow- able. Respecting this same truth we are told in the chapter following, entitled the " Continuity of Motion," that " This existence may cease to display itself as translation ; but it can do so only by displaying itself as strain. And the prin- ciple of activity, now shown by translation, now by strain, and often by the two together, is alone that which in Motion we can call continuous. * * * Hence the principle of activity as known by sight is inferential ; visible translation suggests by association the presence of a principle of activity which would be appreciable by our skin and muscles, did we lay hold of the body. Evidently, then, this principle of activ- ity which Motion shows us, is the objective correlate of our subjective sense of effort. By pushing and pulling we get feelings which, generalized and abstracted, yield our ideas of resistance and tension. Now displayed by changing posi- tion and now by unchanging strain, this principle of activity is ultimately conceived by us under the single form of its equivalent muscular effort. So that the continuity of Motion, as well as the indestructibility of Matter, is really known to us in terms of Force." ' And yet these terms of Force which are so clearly affiliated with all our physical and psychical perceptions, which terms, to use Mr. Spencer's language, are " displayed" and "shown " to us, which are " inferential" " appreciable" and "conceiv- able" are still unknowable. This principle of activity from which, Spencer tells us, our perceptions are built up, which discloses itself to us by the most general and familiar facts of life, is unknown to us. Or perhaps this is saying too much, it may be termed the unknowable and still be known to us. The term unknowable may have nothing to do with 1 " First Principles," pp. 177, 178. a Ibid., pp. 187, 188. HERBERT SPENCER. 22$ our perception, or knowledge, or appreciation of the prin- ciple. It may be simply a name which the old-school phi- losophers insist upon giving this principle in order to conform to the ancient canons of skepticism, or the modern rules of agnosticism, which systems of belief would be completely subverted were there no unknowable. It will be my purpose as we proceed to show that this term unknowable cannot be made to harmonize with a true psychology. All will agree that the analysis of every pos- sible perception discloses what are known as the ultimate realities, or the commonly conceded elements of thought. If the elements of thought are also the elements of all reality, is it not clear that the principle which these ele- ments disclose, namely, Motion, must explain all thought and all perception ? In analyzing any phenomenon or change, such as a weight falling to the ground, the conventional result, found in all current systems of philosophy, is to discover in the change these elements, Space, Time, Matter, Force, and Motion. Thus far philosophy has gone, and no farther ; and we find Spencer no exception to the general rule, for how are we to deduce from his definitions of these categories the one fact which he calls the Persistence of Force, and to show how the phenomenon of perception arises from this one fact ? What are the definitions which Mr. Spencer offers of these elements, and what is the relation which he establishes between them and the central fact in the phenomenon of perception? "Our conception of Matter," says Mr. Spencer, "reduced to its simplest shape, is that of co-existent positions that offer resistance ; as contrasted with our conception of Space, in which the co-existent positions offer no resistance. * * * Hence the necessity we are under of representing to our- selves the ultimate elements of Matter as being at once extended and resistent : this, being the universal form of our sensible experiences of Matter, becomes the form which our conception of it cannot transcend, however minute the fragments which imaginary subdivisions produce. Of these 226 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. two inseparable elements the resistance l is primary, and the extension secondary. Occupied extension, or Body, being* distinguished in consciousness from unoccupied extension, or Space, by its resistance, this attribute must clearly have precedence in the genesis of the idea. Such a conclusion is, indeed, an qbvious corollary from that at which we arrived in the foregoing section. If, as was there contended, our consciousness of Space is a product of accumulated expe- riences, partly our own but chiefly ancestral, if, as was pointed out, the experience from which our consciousness of Space is abstracted can be received only through impres- sions of resistance made upon the organism, the necessary inference is, that experiences of resistance being those from which the conception of Space is generated, the resistance- attribute of Matter must be regarded as primordial and the space-attribute as derivative. Whence it becomes manifest that our experience of force is that out of which the idea of Matter is built. Matter as opposing our muscular energies, being immediately present to consciousness in terms of force ; and its occupancy of Space being known by an abstract of experiences originally given in terms of force, it follows that forces, standing in certain correlations, form the whole content of our idea of Matter." a Space is admitted to be but an inference from Matter, or an aspect of it ; Force is admitted to be the source of our idea of Matter, which means the same thing as that Matter is an inference from Force, or an aspect of it. Now substi- tute the word motion for force and we have our definition of Space an aspect of Motion ; and our definition of Matter, i. e. that Matter and Space are the same thing. To get at Spencer's definition of Time and Space we quote from a previous part of the same work : " That relation is the universal form of thought, is a truth which all kinds of demonstration unite in proving. * * * Now, relations are of two orders rela- tions of sequence and relations of co-existence, of which the one is original and. 'The italics are the author's. a " First Principles," pp. 166, 167. HERBERT SPENCER. 22? the other derivative. The relation of sequence is given in every change of con- sciousness. The relation of co-existence, which cannot be originally given in a consciousness of which the states are serial, becomes distinguished only when it is found that certain relations of sequence have their terms presented in con- sciousness in either order with equal facility ; while the others are presented only in one order. Relations of which the terms are not reversible become recognized as sequences proper, while relations of which the terms occur indifferently in both directions become recognized as co-existences. Endless experiences, which from moment to moment present both orders of these relations, render the dis- tinction between them perfectly definite, and at the same time generate an ab- stract conception of each. The abstract of all sequences is Time ; the abstract of all co-existences is Space. From the fact that in thought Time is inseparable from sequence, and Space from co-existence, we do not here infer that Time and Space are original conditions of consciousness under which sequences and co-existences are known ; but we infer that our conceptions of Time and Space are generated, as other abstracts are generated from other concretes ; the only difference being that the organization of experiences has, in these cases, been, going on throughout the entire evolution of Intelligence. * * * It remains only to point out, as a thing which we must not forget, that the experiences from which the consciousness of Space arises, are experiences of force. A certain correla- tion of the muscular forces which we ourselves exercise is the index of each posi- tion as originally disclosed to us ; and the resistance which makes us aware of something existing in that position is an equivalent of the pressure which we consciously exert. Thus experiences of forces variously correlated are those from which our consciousness of Space is abstracted. " l In reading the above, it is difficult to believe that Spencer was not fully aware of the existence of an ultimate Reality, of which all other facts are but more or less remote aspects. It is hard to understand how so penetrating a mind could declare that Force is the origin of all ideas and all facts : "that Relation is the universal form of thought," "that Relations are of two orders, relations of sequence and rela- tions of co-existence," without seeing that the ultimate relation is the universal fact of motion, having for its terms, or aspects, the primordial inferences known as Space and Time. A little farther on we find the following, which is a very clear portrayal of the difference between the simple solution of the metaphysical problem which we offer and that offered by Mr. Spencer : " Is Space in itself a form or condition of 1 First Principles," pp. 163, 165. 228 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION". absolute existence, 1 producing in our minds a corresponding form or condition of relative existence ? This is an unan- swerable question. Our conception of Space is produced by some mode of the Unknowable ; and the complete unchange- ableness of our conception of it simply implies a complete uni- formity in the effects wrought by this mode of the Unknowable upon us? But therefore to call it a necessary mode of the Unknowable is illegitimate. All we can assert is, that Space is a relative reality ; that our consciousness of this unchanging relative reality implies an absolute reality equally unchanging, in so far as we are concerned; and that the relative reality may be unhesitatingly accepted in thought as a valid basis for our reasonings ; which, when rightly carried on, will bring us to truths that have a like relative reality, the only truths which concern us or can possibly be known to us. Concerning Time, relative and absolute, a parallel argument leads to parallel conclusions. These are too obvious to need specifying in detail." 5 Again, in contrast with the above notion of Space, as an " unchangeable," " fixed form," mark the following, taken from the chapter on the Perception of Space, in which it is distinctly denied that Space is a fixed form or unchangeable conception : " And now mark that while these several peculiarities in our space-perceptions harmonize with, and receive their interpretations from, the experience-hypothesis, taken in that expanded form implied by the doctrine of Evolution, they are not interpretable by, and are quite in- congruous with, the Kantian hypothesis. Without insisting on the fact that our sensations of sound and odor do not originally carry with them the consciousness of space at all, there is the fact that, along with those sensations of taste, touch, and sight, which do carry this consciousness with them, it is carried in extremely different degrees, a fact quite unaccountable if space is given before all experience as a form of intuition. That our consciousness of adjacent 1 The term Absolute Existence is a contradiction in terms. a The italics are the author's. 8 " First Principles," p. 165. HERBERT SPENCER. 22g space is far more complete than our consciousness of remote space, is also at variance with the hypothesis ; which, for aught that appears to the contrary, implies homogeneity. Similarly with that variation in the distinctness of surround- ing parts of space which occurs as we turn our eyes now to one point and now to another : were space a subjective form not derived from experience, there should be no such varia- tion. Again: the contrast between the spontaneous con- sciousness of space within a room and the consciousness of the space beyond its walls, which does not come spon- taneously, is a contrast for which there seems no reason if space is a fixed form." 1 This hardly harmonizes with " the complete unchangeableness of our conception of Space produced by some mode of the unknowable upon us," but if we remove the theory of the unknowable the incongruity between the two conceptions of Space at once disappears. In making these close comparisons of passages occurring widely apart in a great system, and written at considerable intervals of time and study, every allowance should be made. I would especially disclaim any intent of captious criticism. It is my desire only to show the futility of all attempts to account for Space and Time in any other way than as as- pects of Motion ; to show how the greatest minds become lost in the labyrinth of error which lies outside of this simple and direct solution. The above contrasted passages also help to show the intimate connection between the metaphy- sical problem and the problem of perception which we are studying. To return to the first of the above quotations, we would simply repeat that the term unknowable is self-contradictory ; nothing can be unknowable. If we know the universal principle, we could know any form of it, were it presented to us. In its nature, at least, the field of knowledge is infinite. Our knowledge is limited by our lives that is to say, there is, and always will be, to limited beings, a vast unknown; but the antithesis of known is unknown, not unknowable. 1 " Psychology," vol. II., pp. 200, 2OI. 23O THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. Life is a universal principle with which knowledge in its widest sense can be identified, therefore knowable has no meaning, and unknowable has none. If life is a universal principle, what sense would there be in the word livable ? If knowledge is a universal principle, what sense is there in the word knowable ? There are no unanswerable questions, there are only unanswered questions. In the note 1 below will be found a transcript of the best 1 SPENCER'S ANALYSIS OF THE PERCEPTION OF SPACE AND TIME. " Whether visual or tactual, every perception of the space-attributes of body is decomposable into perceptions of relative position ; that all perceptions of relative position are decomposable into perceptions of the relative position of subject and object ; and that these relations of position are knowable only through motion. Such being now our data, the first question that arises is, How, through experi- ences of occupied extension, or body, can we ever gain the notion of unoccu- pied extension, or space ? How, from the perception of a relation between resistant positions, do we progress to the perception of a relation between non- resistant positions ? If all the space-attributes of a body are resolvable into relations of position between subject and object, disclosed in the act of touch if originally, relative position is only thus knowable if, therefore, position is, to the nascent intelligence, incognizable except as the position of something that produces an impression on the organism, how is it possible for the idea of position ever to be dissociated from that of body ? " This problem, difficult of solution as it appears, is really a very easy one. If, after some particular motion of a limb, there invariably came a sensation of softness ; after some other, one of roughness ; after some other, one of hardness or if, after those movements of the eye needed for some special act of vision, there always came a sensation of redness ; after some others, a sen- sation of blueness ; and so on ; it is manifest that, in conformity with the laws of association, there would be established constant relations between such motions and such sensations. If positions were conceived at all, they would be conceived as invariably occupied by things producing special impressions ; and it would be impossible to dissociate the positions from the things. But as we find that a certain movement of the hand, which once brought it in contact with something hot, now brings it in contact with something sharp, and now with nothing at all ; and as we find that a certain movement of the eye, which once was followed by the sight of a black object, is now followed by the sight of a white object, and now by the sight of no object ; it results that the idea of the particular position accompanying each one of these movements is, by accumu- lated experiences, dissociated from objects and impressions. It results, too, that as there are endless such movements, there come to be endless such posi- tions conceived as existing apart from body. And it results, further, that as in the first and in every subsequent act of perception, each position is known as HERBERT SPENCER. analysis of the perception of Space and Time which occurs in the work of Mr. Spencer. This analysis is given to show that his study of the perception of these categories from the physical or organic side has been most successful. It is the manner in which he deals with the relations be- tween the categories themselves that we find so confusing and unsatisfactory. To the habitual student of these subjects this analysis will be a pleasant and profitable review, and to co-existent with the subject, there arises a consciousness of countless such co- existent positions ; that is of Space. This is not offered as an ultimate inter- pretation ; for, as before admitted, the difficulty is to account for our notion of relative position. All that is here attempted is, partially to explain how, from that primitive notion, our consciousness of Space in its totality is built up. " Carrying with us this idea, calling to mind the structure of the retina, and remembering the mode in which the relations among its elements are estab- lished, it will, I think, become possible to conceive how that wonderful percep- tion we have of visible space is generated. It is a peculiarity of sight that makes us partially conscious of many things at once. On now raising my head, I take in at a glance, desk, papers, table, books, chairs, walls, carpet, window, and sundry objects outside : all of them simultaneously impressing me with various details of color, suggesting surface and structure. True, I am not equally conscious of all these things at the same time. I find that some one object at which I am looking is more distinctly present to my mind than any other, and that the one point in this object on which the visual axes converge is more vividly perceived than the rest. In fact, I have a perfect perception of scarcely more than an infinitesimal portion of the whole visual area. Neverthe- less, even while concentrating my attention on this infinitesimal portion, I am in some degree aware of the whole. My complete consciousness of a particu- lar letter on the back of a book does not exclude a consciousness that there are accompanying letters does not exclude a consciousness of the book does not exclude a consciousness of the table on which the book lies, nay, does not occlude even a consciousness of the wall against which the table stands. All these things are present to me in different degrees of intensity degrees that become less, partly in proportion as the things are unobtrusive in color and size, and partly in proportion as they recede from the centre of the visual field. Not that these many surrounding things are definitely known as such or such ; for, while keeping my eyes fixed on one object, I cannot make that assertory judgment respecting any adjacent object which a real cognition of it implies, without becoming, for the moment, imperfectly conscious of the object on which my eyes are fixed. But notwithstanding all this, it remains true that these various objects are in some sense present to my mind are incipiently perceived are* severally tending to fill the consciousness are each of them partially exciting the mental states that would arise were it to be distinctly perceived. 232 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. those to whom it may be new we recommend it as a specimen of Spencer's best work, an example of that care- ful and exhaustive study of obscure phenomena which has given to his writings so high a place in the estimation of scholars. In this analysis is illustrated our complete dependence upon the primordial fact of Motion for our ideas of Space and Time ; for it is the same thing to say that we derive our " This peculiarity in the faculty of sight (to which there is nothing analogous in the faculties of taste and smell ; which, in the faculty of hearing, is vaguely represented by our appreciation of harmony ; and which is but very imperfectly paralleled in the tactual faculty by the ability we have to discern irregularities in a surface on which the hand is laid) is clearly due to the structure of the retina. Consisting of multitudinous sensitive elements, each capable of inde- pendent stimulation, it results that when an image is received by the retina, each of those sensitive elements on which the variously-modified rays of light fall, is thrown into a state of greater or less excitement. Each of them as it were totiches some particular part of the image, and sends inwards to the central nervous system the impressions produced by the touch. But now observe that, as before explained, each retinal element has come to have a known relation to every one of those around it a relation such that their synchronous excitation serves to represent their serial excitation. Lest this symbolism should not have been fully understood, I will endeavor further to elucidate it. Suppose a minute dot to be looked at a dot so small that its image, cast on the retina, covers only one of the sensitive elements, A. Now suppose the eye to be so slightly moved that the image of this dot falls on the adjacent element B. What results ? Two slight changes of consciousness : the one proceeding from the new retinal element affected ; the other, from the muscles producing the motion. Let there be another motion, such as will transfer the image of the dot to the next element,' C. Two other changes of consciousness result. And so on continuously ; the consequence being that the relative positions in con- sciousness of A and B, A and C, A and D, A and E, etc., are known by the number of intervening states. Imagine now that, instead of these small mo- tions separately made, the eye is moved with ordinary rapidity ; so that the image of the dot sweeps over the whole series A to Z in an extremely short time. What results ? It is a familiar fact that all impressions on the senses, and visual ones among the number, continue for a certain brief period after they are made. Hence, when the retinal elements forming the series A to Z are excited in rapid succession, the excitation of Z commences before that of A has ceased ; and for a moment the whole series A to Z remains in a state of excitement together. This being understood, suppose the eye is turned upon a line of such length that its image covers the whole series A to Z. What results ? There is a simultaneous excitation of the series A to Z, differing from HERBERT SPENCER. 233 ideas of Space and Time from Motion as to say that Space and Time are inferences from, or aspects of, this fact. The analysis of sensible perception given below also illustrates how far beyond us, whatever may be our penetration into the intricacies of phenomena, is this principle of activity, and how it eludes all efforts at division or classification. Now that we have followed out Mr. Spencer's analysis of our conception of Space and Time, it will be interesting to the last in this that it is persistent, and that it is unaccompanied by sensations of motion. But does it not follow from the known laws of association, that as the simultaneous excitation is common to both cases, it will, in the last case, tend to arouse in consciousness that series of states which accompanied it in the first ? Will it not tend to consolidate the entire series of such states into one state ? And will it not thus come to be taken as the equivalent of such series ? There cannot, I think, be a doubt of it. And if not, then we may see how an excitement of consciousness, by the coexistent positions constituting a line, serves as the representative of that serial excitement of it which accompanies motion along that line. Let us return now to the above-described state of the retina as occupied by an image or by a cluster of images. Relations of coexist- ent position, like those we have here considered in respect to a particular linear series, are established throughout countless such series in all directions over the retina ; so putting each element in relation with every other. Further, by a process analogous to that described, the state of consciousness produced by the focal adjustment and convergence of the eyes to each particular point, has been made a symbol of the series of coexistent positions between the eyes and that point. After dwelling awhile on these facts, the genesis of our visual per- ception of space will begin to be comprehensible. Every one of the retinal elements simultaneously thrown into a state of partial excitement, arousing as it does not only a partial consciousness of the sensation answering to its own excitement, but also a partial consciousness of the many relations of coexistent position established between it and the rest, which are all of them similarly ex- cited and similarly suggestive, there results a consciousness of a whole area of coexistent positions. Meanwhile the particular consciousness that accompanies adjustment of the eyes, calling up as it does the line of coexistent positions lying between the subject and the object specially contemplated ; and each of the things, and parts of things, not in the centre of the field, exciting by its more or less definite image an incipient consciousness of its distance, that is, of the coexistent positions lying between the eye and it ; there is awakened a con- sciousness of a whole volume of coexistent positions of Space in three dimen- sions. Along with a complete consciousness of the one position to which the visual axes converge, arises a nascent consciousness of an infinity of other posi- tions a consciousness that is nascent in the same sense that our conscious- ness of the various objects out of the centre of the visual field is nascent. One 234 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. note the propositions in regard to the " ultimate realities " with which he originally sets out. These propositions de- clare him to be an agnostic or, in better language, a skep- tic, or a disbeliever in the integrity of human knowledge. For what faith can we have in a knowledge which has its -deepest foundations in impenetrable mysteries? If we can- not understand the first principles of knowledge, how are we 'really to know any thing ? If we cannot grasp the deepest -addition must be made. As the innumerable relations subsisting among these coexistent positions were originally established by motion ; as each of these rela- tions came by habit to stand for the series of mental states accompanying the motion which measured IT ; as every one of such relations must, when presented to consciousness ', still tend to call up in an indistinct way that train of feelings accompanying motion, which it represents y and as the simultaneous presentation of an infinity of such relations will tend to suggest an infinity of such experi- ences of motion, which, as being in all directions, must so neutralize one another as to prevent any particular motion from being thought of ; there will arise, as their common resultant, that sense of ability to move, that sense of freedom for MOTION, which forms the remaining constituent in our notion of Space. 1 ' Any one who finds it difficult to conceive how, by so elaborate a pro- cess as this, there should be reached a notion apparently so simple, so homo- geneous, as that which we have of Space, will feel the difficulty diminished on recalling these several facts : First, that the experiences out of which the no- tion is framed and consolidated are in their essentials the same for ourselves and for the ancestral races of creatures from which we inherit our organizations, and that these uniform ancestral experiences, potentially present in the nervous structures bequeathed to us, constitute a partially-innate preparedness for the notion ; second, that the individual experiences which repeat these ancestral experiences commence at birth, and serve to aid the development of the cor- relative structures while they give them their ultimate definiteness ; third, that every day throughout our lives, and throughout the whole of each day, we are repeating our experiences of these innumerable coexistences of position and their several equivalences to the serial states of feeling accompanying motions ; and fourth, that after development is complete these experiences invariably agree that these relations of coexistent positions are unchangeable are ever the same toward each other and the subject are ever equivalent to the same motions. On bearing in mind this inheritance of latent experiences, this early commencement of the experiences that verify and complete them, this infinite repetition of them, and their absolute uniformity ; and on further remembering the power which, in virtue of its structure, the eye possesses of partially suggest- ing to the mind countless such experiences at the same moment ; it will become possible to conceive how we acquire that consolidated idea of Space in its totality, which at first seems so inexplicable." HERBERT SPENCER. 235 meaning of life, how are we really to live ? We would not be understood to infer that this demoralizing skepticism, known as the belief in the unknowable, is not thrown off in the bet- ter portions of Mr. Spencer's teachings. No one who care- fully examines his analysis of our conceptions of Space and Time given below can fail to see that Mr. Spencer at times Upon the Perception of Time. " The reciprocity between our cognitions of Space and Time, alike in their primitive and most developed forms, being un- derstood ; and the consequent impossibility of considering either of them -entirely alone, being inferred ; let us go on to deal more particularly with Time. As the notions of Space and Coexistence are inseparable, so are the notions of Time and Sequence. It is impossible to think of Time without thinking of some succession ; and it is equally impossible to think of any succession without thinking of Time. * * * The doctrine that Time is knowable only by the suc- cession of our mental states calls for little exposition, it is so well established a doctrine. All that seems here necessary is to restate it in a way which will bring out its harmony with the foregoing doctrine. * * * As any relation of co- existent positions any portion of space is conceived by us as such or such, -according to the number of other positions that intervene ; so any relation of sequent positions any portion of time is conceived by us as such or such, ac- cording to the number of other positions that intervene. Thus, a particular time is a relation of position between some two states in the series of states of consciousness. And Time in general, as known to us, is the abstract of all relations of position among successive states of consciousness. Or, using other words, we may say that it is the blank form in which these successive states are presented and represented; and which, serving alike for each, is not dependent on any. * * * The consciousness of Time must vary with size, with structure, and with functional activity ; since the scale of time proper to each creature is composed primarily of the marks made in its consciousness by the rhythms of its vital functions, and secondarily of the marks made in its con- sciousness by the rhythms of its locomotive functions : both which sets of rhythms are immensely different in different species. Consequently the consti- tution derived from ancestry settles the general character of the consciousness within approximate limits. In our own case, for example, it is clear that there are certain extremes within which our units of measure for time must fall. The heart-beats and respiratory actions, serving as primitive measures, can have their rates varied within moderate ranges only. The alternating move- ments of the legs have a certain degree of slowness below which we cannot be conscious of them, and a certain degree of rapidity beyond which we cannot push them. Similarly with measures of time furnished by sensible motions outside of us. There are motions too rapid for our perceptions, as well as motions too slow for our perceptions ; and such consciousness of Time as we get from watching objective motions must fall between these extremes." "Psychology," vol. II., ch. xv. 236 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. completely rises above the level of agnosticism. But this fact only renders more confusing the system as a whole. For instance, when we find such plain declarations of our utter inability to understand the principles of knowledge as occur in Spencer's opening volume we naturally look with distrust upon all subsequent attempts to explain these prin- ciples. In a word, why should Mr. Spencer expect us to put faith in his analysis of those facts which in the very outset of his work he tells us it is impossible to understand ? Thus in the Chapter on Ultimate Scientific Ideas we have the following declarations : " It results, therefore, that Space and Time are wholly incomprehensible. The immediate knowledge which we seem to have of them proves, when examined, to be total ignorance. While our belief in their objective reality is in- surmountable, we are unable to give any rational account of it. And to posit the alternative belief (possible to state but impossible to realize) is merely to multiply irrationalities." " Matter, then, in its ultimate nature, is as absolutely in- comprehensible as Space and Time. Frame what supposi- tions we may, we find, on tracing out their implications, that they leave us nothing but a choice between opposite absurdities." " Thus neither when considered in connection with Space, nor when considered in connection with Matter, nor when considered in connection with Rest, do we find that Motion is truly cognizable. All efforts to understand its essential nature do but bring us to alternative impossibilities of thought." " While, then, it is impossible to form any idea of Force in itself, it is equally impossible to comprehend its mode of exercise." And lastly : " Hence, while we are unable either to be- lieve or to conceive that the duration of consciousness is in- finite, we are equally unable either to know it as finite, or to conceive it as finite." 1 " First Principles," ch. iii. HERBERT SPENCER. 237 Here is, indeed, a cheerful prospect at the beginning of a study of perception ! All those principles which are ac- knowledged by writers upon metaphysics to be " ultimate realities," or fundamental ideas, are declared to be utterly incomprehensible ; and, in way of reassurance, we are told that to try to understand consciousness itself can but lead to " absurdities." If agnosticism is an aggravated form of skepticism, surely this is a high type of agnosticism ! The first requisite in forming a true conception of Knowl- edge is to understand that the word, in its widest applica- tion, means the same thing as life ; and that life is coexten- sive in fact, and therefore in meaning, with the universal principle, Motion. All activities are expressions of this principle, whether they display the structure and function of consciousness (the subjective world) or the statical and dynamical aspects of nature (the objective world). Structure and function are but the obverse aspects of every activity ; they correspond to the more abstract or general terms Mat- ter and Force, using the word force, as is so often done, to signify motion considered apart from its space-aspect. The more acceptable terms Space and Time are also the equiva- lents of structure and function. Bearing these truths in mind, the difficulty of forming a rational theory of percep- tion, or thought, disappears. If thought is an activity, to comprehend it we have but to state its conditions. The theory that thought is the expres- sion of an absolute or unconditioned principle has but to be reduced to its simplest terms in order to expose its ab- surdity. The word absolute, or unconditioned, is a much- abused term in metaphysical writings ; it is an outgrowth of our conception of Time, which, when regarded as a prin- ciple in itself, certainly seems to move, independently of any imaginable conditions. If whenever the word absolute occurs its equivalent Time is understood, we cannot be misled. To call thought an entity, or an absolute principle in itself, is but to block the progress of analysis by clinging to one of the aspects of the phenomenon and disregarding 238 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. the other. If thought is an activity, it must have struc- ture as well as function ; it must have a space-aspect as well as a time-aspect ; it must be an expression of the universal principle, Motion. If there are two great oppo- site spheres of existence, known as the subjective and the objective, the ego and the non-ego, the conscious and the unconscious, they are not absolutely different spheres, but are interdependent, or related ; they act and react upon each other, and are expressions of a fundamental fact which underlies them both. What becomes of the charge that such a theory as this is materialistic, when we remember that the attributes of this principle are those which are universally ascribed to God? This, however, is but an ultimate analysis, it is not the living synthesis, of life. The theory of Evolution is, that every phenomenon or change is the product, or function, of its conditions. Every phenomenon is a relation, or the joint expression of its terms. The ultimate relation is Motion, and its terms are Space and Time. The relation or fact called consciousness has for its terms the objective and the subjective worlds. The study of consciousness or perception (they are, in their widest sense, equivalent terms) is the study of the conditions of mental life, which are only relatively separable from the conditions, of general life, or the universe. If we would single out from this plexus of relations an ultimate relation, or from this vast array of conditions ultimate conditions, we have for result the ultimate relation, Motion ; the ultimate conditions, Space and Time. CHAPTER X. HERBERT SPENCER (CONTINUED). An Independent Study of the Relation of Perception to Organic Life The Interdependence of Thought, Feeling, and Action. THE study of psychology is fast becoming a definite science. Little by little its ontological superstitions are giving way to the more rational method of approaching the mind through the medium of its functions and structures. The old system of taking for granted the existence of a psychical principle as the only means of explaining thought, is yielding to the belief in a universal principle in which all lines of cause and effect converge, whether they describe physical, mental, or moral phenomena. Speaking on this subject, Lewes says : " Psychology investigates the Human Mind, not an individual's thoughts and feelings ; and has to consider it as the product of the Human Organism, not only in relation to the Cosmos, but also in relation to Society. For man is distinctively a social being ; his animal impulses are profoundly modified by social influences, and his higher faculties are evolved through social needs. By this recogni- tion of the social factor as the complement to the biological factor, this recognition of the Mind as an expression of organic and social conditions, the first step is taken toward the constitution of our science. * * * An organism when in action is only to be understood by understanding both it and the medium from which it draws its materials, and on which it reacts. Its conditions of existence are, first, the structural mechanism, and, secondly, the medium in which it is placed. When we know the part played by the mechanism, and the- part played by the medium, we have gone as far as analysis 239 240 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. can help us ; we have scientifically explained the actions of the organism. This, which is so obvious in reference to vital -actions that it is a physiological commonplace, is so little understood in reference to the mental class of vital actions that it may appear a psychological paradox, and a paradox which no explanation can make acceptable so long as the Mind is thought to be an entity inhabiting the organism, using it as an instrument ; and so long as Society is thought to be an artificial product of man's mind, in which case it cannot be one of the conditions of mental evolution." 1 What is known, then, as the social factor in the study of psychology is that feature of the science which is by far the most difficult to comprehend. A theory of perception which neglects the influence of this factor is thereby apparently sim- plified, but it is incomplete ; for it is from the relations of man to society that the bewildering complexities of mental phe- nomena arise. The rudimentary communications of sentient beings gave birth to intelligence, or the representative faculty, and by the continued development of this faculty language came into existence. Language, which is the condensing or grouping of thoughts into symbols, has attained to such perfection that a climax in its development has been reached in the creation of a single word to express the interdepen- dencies of the universe. In studying mental phenomena, in tracing the connections of cause and effect throughout the labyrinths of sentiency, we have to view human intelligence, as a whole, in the light of an achievement or superstructure of organic evolution. This is what is meant by taking into account the social factor, the combined influences of life upon life, of mind upon mind. The simplest definition of organic life is the adjustment of the organism to its environment. Society, as a whole, is an important part of the environment of each human organism, for the response of each organism to humanity marks the degree of development the quality of life. The counterpart of this view of the social factor is what might be called the individual factor, the other term of 1 Lewes : " The Study of Psychology," ch. i. HERBERT SPENCER. 241 the relation known as psychical life. In every perception, however simple, the perceiving individual, as a whole, has a determining influence. This view of the individual factor of psychical life, the part played by the whole personality of the perceiving individual in the phenomena of perception, is if any thing more obscure than the influence of the social factor. Perhaps the most direct way of explaining it is to recite a passage, quoted in the foregoing chapter, from Spencer's explanation of the genesis of our idea of time. Time is a fundamental element of perception. If the indi- vidual, as a whole, is shown to be a prominent factor in the formation of our conception of time, it will follow that the individual, as a whole, is an important factor in perception. " The consciousness of Time must vary with size, with structure, and with functional activity ; since the scale of time proper to each creature is composed primarily of the marks made in its consciousness by the rhythms of its vital functions, and secondarily of the marks made in its con- sciousness by the rhythms of its locomotive functions, both which sets of rhythms are immensely different in different species. Consequently, the constitution derived from an- cestry settles the general character of the consciousness within approximate limits. In our own case, for example, it is clear that there are certain extremes within which our units of measure for time must fall. The heart-beats and respiratory actions, serving as primitive measures, can have their rates varied within moderate ranges only. The alter- nating movements of the legs have a certain degree of slow- ness below which we cannot be conscious of them, and a certain degree of rapidity beyond which we cannot push them. Similarly with measures of time furnished by sensible motions outside of us. There are motions too rapid for our perceptions, as well as motions too slow for our perceptions ; and such consciousness of time as we get from watching ob- jective motions must fall between these extremes." It is clear that the same argument applies to the genesis 1 lt Psychology," vol. II., pp. 213, 214. 242 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. of our idea of space, namely, that consciousness of space is generated by the experiences of the perceiving organism, and is plainly governed by its size. Our ideas of the large and the small, the infinite and the infinitesimal, the near and the distant, have our individual space relationships as ever- present factors. In a word, we have no absolute unit of space or time, but depend upon the space and time aspects of our own organisms for our estimates and conceptions of these elements of all existence. Now, if we remember that the word element is used in the sense of phase or appear- ance, and that the indivisible fact which presents to us these phases, both of our own existence and of external existence, is motion, we shall perceive the significance of the familiar dictum that life, both mental and physical, is an adjustment of inner to outer relations. These primordial inferences of existence called space and time, which are so fundamental in their nature as to have beguiled many into supposing them inscrutable, are plainly functions or products of our individuality. Our ideas of these two elements of thought are fashioned by our experi- ences ; our estimates of quantity or size, and of durations, are measured by ourselves; and we can never escape from these personal units, as they are factors in the conceptions them- selves. Thus we have in the study of psychology what might be called a personal relation, the two terms of which are the individual and humanity ; and it is in the elabora- tions of this relation that we have all those perceptions known as the world of thought. To get at the true mean- ing of perception, however, it will be necessary to dis- pense, for a time, with the use of this word thought. If it be admitted that to think is to act, the difficulty is at once removed ; but the manifest difference between what are known as actions and thoughts must be explained before we can hope to make clear the community of meaning between these two words, which is the chief aim of modern psy- chology. In the restricted sense in which the word feeling- is used HERBERT SPENCER. 243 we have another difficulty. There are no absolute demarca- tions between the meanings of the words feelings, thoughts, and actions. Let us examine the first and last of these terms, with a view to discovering the true meaning of the word thought. Feelings and thoughts are what we know of our own lives ; actions are what we know of the lives of others. For the sake of convenience, let the word feeling represent all the changes that take place within us, which are, of course, without num- ber ; they include all thoughts and dreams, all emotions of every degree of intensity to say nothing of that vast com- plexity of internal changes making up the sum of our physi- cal existence, of which we are for the most part unconscious. Only a very small proportion of the changes which take place within us ever occupy the attention. Our bodies and minds are teeming with energies which we do not even suspect, and which never cease from the beginning to the end of our lives. 1 Whenever we move a muscle or experience a thought, there are disturbances which disperse throughout the whole system. These disturbances or changes, which have their expressions in heat and sound, and other forms of motion, only attract the attention when they are sufficiently abrupt to shock us in some degree ; thus every form of feeling or consciousness is an excitement. In fact, attention consists of the ebb and flow of these internal changes. Attention or consciousness is itself a disturbance or change, but it is an aggregate or co-ordination of changes, a moving equilibrium with certain well-defined conditions, as is illustrated by the severe limits to which consciousness is subjected by the laws of health, and the degrees of activity and inactivity of the sensorium. Thus we see that the word feeling has a much wider meaning than is generally given to it, and it is only by a recent feat of science that we are enabled to classify feel- ings, thoughts, and actions under the one great heading of 1 This incessant internal activity is said, by a great physiologist, to produce a tone of which we are unconscious. 244 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. internal or subjective changes of the same fundamental na- ture but differing widely in their processes. Perception, therefore, does not necessitate a belief in a psychical prin- ciple or any ultimate fact, other than that which is disclosed through the study of the structures and the functions of the human organism, and the faculties which arise from the actions and reactions ever going on between the individual and its physical and social environment. Now that we have agreed upon a word to stand for that great class of changes called internal or subjective, what shall we call those changes which occur around us, or exter- nally to us, known as objective? It is understood that the word feeling shall represent all subjective changes or phe- nomena, and that these changes viewed from without, or by others, are actions. It will not do to separate feelings from actions, excepting in a logical sense, as they are only names respectively for the internal and external aspects of the same thing. This fact becomes clearer when we remember that in trying to find a name for all changes external to us we are obliged to include in objective or external phenomena the ac- tions of others ; for these actions are a very important part of our surroundings. Using the word feeling in its broadest sense (as signifying all those changes which take place within us), it is clear that what are feelings to us are viewed as actions by others, or what are feelings subjectively are actions ob- jectively. In a word, we are compelled to classify the feel- ings of humanity, or society, among the activities which constitute the environment of each individual. When light strikes the eye and produces within us the phenomenon called sight, the sensorium, or the most active part of our organism, is said to react in response to the stimulus. The same term is used with regard to all the re- sponses which we make to stimulations from without ; such as in the cases of hearing to sound, sensitiveness to tempera- ture, and resistance to strains. Again : when a bar of iron is struck with force sufficient to produce perceptible heat, the heat is said to be a reaction of the iron to the blow. HERBERT SPENCER. 24$ When we place certain chemical substances, in definite pro- portions and temperatures, in juxtaposition, the changes we observe are called reactions ; and in a wider but not less exact sense all the changes which we observe around us, from the subtle relations called electric and magnetic to cosmical evo- lutions ; from the energy which we call vegetable and animal life to the great panorama of social and moral phenomena known as human history ; from the convulsions which are registered in the physical structure of our planet, and which are repeated upon so much grander scales in the sun and in distant stars, to the comparatively gentle changes of the seasons and daily variations in temperature ; all are expres- sions of the fundamental law or fact of action and reaction. This law has many names : it is known in philosophy as evo- lution ; physicists write about it as the conservation and correlation, or the equivalence, of forces ; mathematicians portray it as motion ; but of one thing we may be sure, that the word action brings its essential nature truly before us, and what we know as actions constitute its universal expres- sion. This law means that every change is the exact result of its circumstances ; otherwise expressed, that every phe- nomenon is the function of its conditions. Cause and effect are simply the opposite appearances of each event, changes viewed from different standpoints in their succession ; and these two factors, cause and effect, can never be more than logically separated from each other ; they are merely phases of the event. This law means that the universe is a plenum of interdependent changes; each change we perceive being the consequence of other changes, and that the great pro- cession of events in which our lives appear and disappear is the expression of one universal principle, law, or relation. Is it not apparent, therefore, that it is alone in viewing humanity as an active aggregate that its influence upon the individual can be distinguished from that of nature in gen- eral ? For if the actions of men and of nature are funda- mentally the same, if the one is the product of the other, and they are both the expression of one fact, is not the en- 246 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. vironment of each individual both cosmical and social, an empire of interdependent activities united in allegiance to a single power ? But we have said that psychical life or thought is a relation having for its terms the individual, on the one hand, and the "social factor" otherwise known as the aggregate intelli- gence of the race, on the other. What, then, is it that separates mind from nature, that gives human intelligence an existence of its own, distinguished from general exist- ence ? What forms intelligence into a whole, demarcating the conscious from the unconscious world ? Is it not Lan- guage ? Each human organism, by slow progressions of development, actions and reactions between itself and its surroundings, beginning with the rude comparisons of a rude life, and growing into the complex relations which we call social life, has slowly developed that vast organon of tran- scribed thought which we call language or literature. The individual organism has become gradually modified until we find ourselves in possession of the faculty of responding to the meaning of words. Through this delicate medium of intelligence the comprehensive adjustments of human life are made possible. The structural aspect of this intelli- gence is language ; its functional aspect is thought. View- ing thought from within, we classify it as internal change (or feeling used in its widest sense) ; viewing it from without, it is action ; and its community of nature with universal change thus becomes apparent. And now we are confronted with the profoundest question of philosophy, the initial inquiry of psychology, the stum- bling block of metaphysics. This is the vexed question of subject and object ; this is where the idealist and the nomi- nalist disagree, where the spiritualist and the materialist part company. Upon the solution of this question depends the success of psychology, the understanding of the true nature of thought. If motion is the universal principle, having for its aspects space and time, it is important to know what constitutes this ever-present difference between space and HERBERT SPENCER. 247 time ? Why are we powerless to merge these ideas in one ? Why are we compelled to oscillate between these two terms of the deepest of all differences, in order to form the con- ception of motion or universality ? The reply is this : that as our existence is individual, all our knowledge is the function or consequence of this indi- viduality. The difference, or relation, between ourselves and our surroundings, between subject and object, self and not- self, viewed in all its phases, gives us the sum of our exist- ence. Time is the most abstract view possible of general existence ; it is the consciousness of existence separated from the events which fill it ; it is the subjective view of life. Space is the objective or external view of general life, separated from all particulars. Thus the aspects of motion, space and time, are merely the natural products of the dif- ference between subject and object ; and in this fundamen- tal difference we have the explanation of psychical life, or thought traced to the relatively simple adjustments of primi- tive organisms to their environment. Now it may be objected that this fundamental difference, or relation, between self and not-self, between the creature and its environment, is precisely the mystery of life and thought, and that it is none the less a mystery because of the simplification of its terms. The reply to this is, that if by the term mystery is meant a point or principle which defies analysis, I cordially consent that life is a mystery ; but I deny that life is one mystery and that thought is another, or that human life presents us with a different mystery from that of universal life, or that organic changes are either more or less mys- terious than cosmical or inorganic changes. If that unity in all things can be established which cul- minates in the conception of God, a universal principle whose aspects or attributes are the infinite and the absolute, or space and time, philosophy will be fully satisfied. No theory of providence which is built upon so commanding a view of nature as this will shock the finest logical sensibilities. 248 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. No teleology which can spring from such a conception as this will appear narrow or anthropomorphic, or suffer by comparison with the most dignified and resplendent achieve- ments of thought. To recapitulate, we have the following important results. The first or primordial difference, or relation, 1 from which the great phenomenon called thought is evolved, is the dif- ference between subject and object, self and not-self. This difference is the same as that which exists between time and space. Thinking is relationing, multiplying, or grouping differ- ences. Every thought is expressed in terms of time and space, and declares an action of which these are the aspects. When we compare two existences, or become conscious of external coexistences, we contrast the objective terms of two distinct relations by dropping, or not attending to, the sub- jective terms. When we estimate durations, or become con- scious of abstract sequences or time, we contrast the subjec- tive terms of two or more distinct relations by dropping, or not attending to, the objective terms. Hence we have space or coexistences considered as objective conceptions, relatively 1 In case any objection should be raised to the use of the words relation and difference as synonyms, we quote the following as one of many authorities for the statement that these words are practically identical in meaning : " Suppose an incipient intelligence to receive two equal impressions of the color red. No other experiences having been received, the relation between these two impres- sions cannot be thought of in any way ; because there exists no other relation with which it can be classed, or from which it can be distinguished. Suppose two other equal impressions of red are received. There can still exist no idea of the relation between them. For though there is a repetition of the pre- viously-experienced relation, yet since no thing can be cognized save as of some kind ; and since, by its very nature, kind implies the establishment of difference ; there cannot, while only one order of relation has been experienced, be any knowledge of it any thought about it. Now suppose that two unequal impres- sions of red are received. There is experienced a second species of relation. And if there are afterward presented many such pairs of impressions, the mem- bers of which are severally equal and unequal, it becomes possible for the constituents of each new pair to be vaguely thought of as like or unlike, and as standing in relations like or unlike previous ones." Spencer's " Psy- chology," vol. II., p. 212. HERBERT SPENCER. 249 distinguished from time or abstract sequences considered as subjective conceptions. From these personal relations, or differences, the great organon of thought is constructed. From the primordial adjustments of an organism to its en- vironment are evolved the adjustments of the organism of humanity to the universe, through the co-ordinations of lan- guage which give to the individual the social factor, or its intellectual environment, enlarging the terms of this relation by insensible progressions from those of an individual and its species to those of a species and its cosmical surround- ings. From this simple theory of perception we are enabled to deduce the inestimable truth that morality, which is simply the vastly extended sympathy of an individual for its race, is made possible by intelligence, and that it is the natural result of human progress. The chief point of divergence between this theory of per- ception and that taught by such writers as Lewes and Spen- cer, is, that it stigmatizes the unknowable as involving a contradiction in terms. Since knowledge is the product or expression of a universal principle, from which perception is seen to spring, to postulate an unknowable is to deny the source of knowledge. But there is a deeper incongruity in this term unknowable than can be deduced by comparing it with any group of facts. As has already been explained, every possible conception is an elaboration of the difference between subject and object, self and not-self ; to postulate a deeper existence than that of which life and knowledge are the expression is to say that a relation is not the expression of its terms, that thought is possible in the absence of its factors. In the light of the preceding argument, it is unnecessary to say that metaphysical discussions are merely comparisons of the meanings of words ; once in possession of the funda- mental fact of the universe, or the ultimate analysis, no pos- sible combination of terms can disturb us. Amid the fiercest conflicts of opinion this truth remains secure. It is in the possession of a multitude of minds who feel its power and 250 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. express its meaning in their lives. Its language is action ; its law is morality ; its sentiment is the sympathy which we call humanity. Far from being an innovation, its light has burned through the long ages of the beginnings of our race ; no human life has been without its influence. The bright- est promise which the future offers is, that this truth shall gain universal sway ; that the actions of men shall express that principle of harmony which the mind naturally imbibes from nature. In the widest meaning of the word thought, therefore, we find a reconciliation between the contrasted terms feeling and action, a contrast which springs from the first condition of organic life, the difference between self and not-self, the subjective and the objective, the creature and its environ- ment. These are the factors of the phenomenon which we call thought. This reconciliation gives us a complete psychology without a psychical principle, a religion without a revelation, a philosophy without an unknowable. Let us now consider the advantages which accrue from an understanding of the nature of Perception. In the opening of the chapter entitled " Function," in the first volume of Mr. Spencer's work on " Biology," we find this extraordinary problem : " Does Structure originate Function, or does Function originate Structure ? is a ques- tion about which there has been disagreement. Using the word Function in its widest signification, as the totality of all vital actions, the question amounts to this : Does Life produce Organization, or does Organization produce Life ? " And Mr. Spencer seriously applies himself to solving this problem. The fundamental error of Mr. Spencer's system of philosophy, as we have before pointed out, is in the in- completeness of its ultimate analysis. An ultimate analysis leads us to a single fact. This fact we do not find clearly stated : the relationships between its many names and the many names of its aspects are not explained, and the student is left in doubt as to what this fact really fs. Spencer's philosophy is termed by its author syn- HERBERT SPENCER. 2$i thetic. It purports to give us a synthesis of life, a com- manding view of reality. This word synthesis springs from a fact of perception. The physical or objective side of the phenomenon of perception, it will be remembered, is in itself a vast synthesis, or building up of parts into a whole. The outposts of the understanding, known as the senses, are merely channels of agitation leading to the great central structure of the nervous system, called the brain. Light, heat, the effluences known as odors, the relative rigidities called resistances, are simply different kinds of agi- tations of the nervous system centring in the brain. Mr. Du Bois-Reymond tells us that the chief distinction between the two substances known as the muscles and the nerves, and hence between body and mind, lies in the amount of activity of which each is capable. Again Lewes, in a study of the relations of physiology to psychology, and the incidental examination of the nervous system, has re- moved many of the superstitions which have crept into these sciences under the guise of the arbitrary localiza- tion of functions, and has demonstrated the inseparable nature of the two aspects of physiological phenomena known as structure and function. From the simple organic substance known as protoplasm, which, under analysis, dis- closes a very high molecular multiplicity, to the synthesis of organic life instanced in the individual of our own species, structure and function are shown to be but obverse aspects of each group of facts, which again are merged in the larger fact of organic life. Hence the co-ordination of activities is another name for organic life. When we use the word life in a wider sense than that indicated by this co-ordination or organization, it becomes applicable to that wider range of activities known as mechanical or chemical, usually regarded as distinct from vital. Again : the science of organic chemistry, which is yet in its infancy, has placed beyond dispute the great fact that the distinction between vital and chemical activities is but super- ficial. This discovery points to the conclusion, illustrated THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. by Lewes, that the structures or substances of the human organism, as of all organisms, are directly accountable for the type of activity which each organism displays. This gives us the startling fact that the four organic elements, oxygen, hydrogen, nitrogen, and carbon, simply assert their natures in all the phenomena of organic life ; jn other words, that the affinities or activities of these and allied elements account for all vital functions, from the primordial assimila- tion, growth, and reproduction observed in the structureless speck of protoplasm to the moral sentiments and the most extended perceptions of man. It is in the light of this fact that I object to Spencer's definition of Life. For if organic life is accounted for by those activities which outside of the vital sphere we call chemical and mechanical, then the word life, in its broadest sense, means activity ; organic life means organized activity ; and no definition of organization, however extended, can illuminate the meaning of the general principle which we call Life. To say, therefore, that " Life is the definite combina- tion of heterogeneous changes, both simultaneous and suc- cessive, in correspondence with external coexistences and sequences," is to say that an organism is an instance of the adjustment of its internal activities to its external related activities, and that organic life is organic life. Again : to ask the question, Does life produce organization, or does organization produce life ? is equivalent to asking whether cause produces effect, or whether effect produces cause. The only answer that can be given is to be found in the nature of perception, which proceeds inevitably from sim- plicity to complexity, from unity to variety, from the one to the many, from cause to effect, from the principle of activity, or motion, to the facts or realities of life. That this metaphysical incompleteness of Spencer's phi- losophy vitiates his whole system, is true only in a limited sense. When so vast a body of data is organized into a picture of life and its surroundings, the failure to strike the key-note of the nature of perception is certainly pro- HERBERT SPENCER. 253 ductive of minor discords, of unnecessarily involved expla- nations which lead to no useful results. But these lesser defects are overwhelmed by the comprehensive plan, the consummate skill, the tireless research, and the earnestness and noble purpose, of the work. Spencer's philosophy con- stitutes an education in itself. No one can really study it without feeling its elevating influence, and being benefited by the splendid intellectual discipline which it imparts. But it is further to be remarked : The tenor of Spencer's system is sociological ; his illustrations are continually rising to the level of social phenomena, and his originality is to be found almost exclusively in this field. Before looking on this bright side, however, it is incum- bent upon us to examine the psychological department of his work, which, we are compelled to admit, has the disadvan- tage of demanding the most study and yielding the least in return of any of his writings. The scope of this subject of psychology has been outlined, from an independent stand- point, in the preceding part of this chapter, and in the one which follows we propose to examine carefully the method of treatment which it receives at the hands of our author. CHAPTER XI. HERBERT SPENCER (CONTINUED). The Analysis of Reason The Fundamental Intuition The Contrasted Theories of Perception. IN the second volume of Spencer's " Principles of Psychol- ogy," the author apologizes for the abstruseness of the opening portions of the work, and explains that the method which he adopts, namely, that of a systematic analysis, requires that it should begin with the most complex and special forms of intellectual activity, and progress in stages to the simplest or most general. He further says that this method will tax the powers of even the habitual student ; and to those who are unaccustomed to introspection (or the study of the operations of the mind) he recommends patience, and holds out the reward of an ultimate comprehension of the subject if they will but persevere. The first words of the second chapter are these : " Of intellectual acts, the highest are those which constitute Conscious Reasoning [or] called conscious to distinguish it from the unconscious or automatic reasoning that forms so large an element in ordinary perception. Of conscious reasoning, the kind containing the greatest number of compo- nents definitely combined is Quantitative Reasoning. And of this, again, there is a division, more highly involved than the rest, which we may class apart as Compound Quantitative Reasoning. * * * Even in Compound Quantitative Reasoning itself there are degrees of composition, and to initiate our analysis rightly we must take first the most composite type. Let us contemplate an example." The example given is the method of reasoning pursued 254 HERBERT SPENCER. 2$ $ by an engineer in estimating the comparative strength of bridges of different sizes. The vast amount of experience, or special knowledge, concerning the comparative strength of different materials, which the ability to solve such a prob- lem would pre-suppose, is reduced to a minimum by taking, for example, an iron bridge, and the problems of strain are simplified by limiting the example to the tubular class of bridges. By these means the whole bearing of the example, which is made to represent, as the foregoing quotation shows, the most complex form of " Compound Quantitative Reason- ing" '. is the joint application of two problems in mechanics to the building of bridges. The first of the propositions can be stated as follows : The bulks of similar masses of matter are to each other as the cubes of their linear dimensions, and consequently when the masses are of the same material their weights are also to each other as the cubes of their linear dimensions. This proposition, stated and explained in language familiar to all, is this : to determine the differ- ences between masses, agree upon a unit of mass, the most convenient form of which has been found to be a cube, or a solid of equal linear dimensions. Since the length, breadth, and thickness of this unit of mass are equal, its edges or lines are equal, so that a comparison between the total number of the cubic-shaped units in each mass can be made by compar- ing the linear dimensions, providing the number of linear units in the linear dimensions is first made to agree with the number of cubic units in the respective masses. The prob- lem states that the number of linear units in the three dimensions multiplied together (or cubed in case the dimen- sions are equal) will equal the number of cubic units in the respective masses, or that the masses are to each other as the cubes of the linear dimensions. The stages, therefore, in this first of the two problems, the joint use of which is cited as furnishing an example of the most complex order of " Compound Quantitative Reasoning," are progressions of equations, or equalities. All mathematical progressions are steps from one equality to another, beginning always with .256 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. those simple equalities which are evident to the senses, or sensible equations. Some savages who are unable to count, form very good ideas of the comparative bulks of masses ; but until they learn to count and measure they cannot understand that numbers can be made to represent bulk. It requires no mathematical mind, however, to see that they can ; and the foregoing problem, stated in terms which the unmathematical reader can at once understand, would be simply this : By mul- tiplying together the length, breadth, and thickness of a mass, we get a number which expresses the volume of the mass in any desired units. This is the extent of the question ; for it goes without saying, that if numbers are made to express the exact volumes of masses, variations in volume imply varia- tions in numbers, and comparisons of numbers are compari- sons of masses. The second problem is not so easy to reduce to its steps of equivalence, or the equations by which its conclusions are reached. It is stated as follows : In similar masses of mat- ter which are subject to compression or tension, or, as in this case, to the transverse strain, the power of resistance varies as the squares of the (like) linear dimensions. Here we have two things made to represent each other, or equal- ized, or brought to an equation, which are widely different in nature, namely, the power of resistance in a mass and a superficial measurement. For if things vary with other things, they must represent them, or be equal to them, at least in the property which forms the base of the compari- son. In this case, the squares of the linear dimensions of two masses are said to vary with the power of resistance of the masses. Therefore the squares of the linear dimensions must in some way be made equal to the power of resistance of the respective masses. How is this done ? There is a law in mechanics, called the law of least resistance, which locates the greatest strain in a structure in a plane. This law or rule reduced to its simplest form is, that if a tube of iron of uniform size and strength be subjected to the transverse strain of (say) its own weight, the place at which it would HERBERT SPENCER. break, if the strain exceeded its strength, would be a trans- verse section of the tube, or the plane of fracture. This transverse section, or plane of fracture, is naturally two of the linear dimensions of the tube, or mass, multiplied to- gether, and in the case of transverse strains it would be the two transverse linear dimensions which would be multi- plied together to represent this transverse section in units of squares. Here, then, the equality of nature is established between the results of the two problems. In the first a number was made to represent the bulk and also the weight of compared masses. Since every mass has three linear di- mensions, if it is desired to express these masses in com- mon multiples, or divisions of their masses, of course these divisions of mass, or units, must have three linear dimensions ; and if we would compare the aggregates of units in each mass, the calculations, or process by which these aggregates are arrived at, must be compared. Now the calculations in cases of solids or masses are cubic, or three lines multi- plied together, and in cases of surfaces they are squares, or two lines multiplied together. The power of resistance of a structure to a transverse strain has been simulated in the foregoing problem by a surface, and the weight of masses by solids, so that the final comparison between the results of the two problems is simply a comparison between the methods of estimating the number of superficial units in a surface and the number of solid units in a solid : one is done by multiplying together the linear units contained in two straight lines, and the other is done by multiplying together the linear units contained in three straight lines. Now if a certain operation is performed twice to accomplish a certain purpose, and the same operation is performed three times to accomplish another purpose, it is plain that the result of the operation in the latter case will be larger than that in the former, in proportion to the size of the original operation. In other words, three times a given quantity will be more than twice the same quantity, and the difference between the results will increase in exact proportion to the 258 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. size or power of the unit employed. This is equivalent to* saying that the difference between three feet and two feet is greater than the difference between three inches and two inches, or simpler still, that three is greater than two. From this simple difference, the perception of which is not an in- tuition, because it is a sensible fact which can be demonstrated mechanically, we can build up, by retracing the steps of the above analysis, the complex problems that homogeneous masses, and therefore their weights, are to each other as the cubes of their linear dimensions, and that the power of homogeneous masses of like proportional dimensions to resist transverse strains varies as the square of the like linear dimensions. The whole comparison grows out of the fact that the operation by which the weight is estimated is per- formed three times, and in the case of estimating the power it is performed but twice ; and this gives us the startling result that three is greater than two ! Speaking of the above problems, Mr. Spencer says : " But now, leaving out of sight the various acts by which the premises are reached and the final inference is drawn, let us consider the nature of the cognition that the ratio between the sustaining forces in the two tubes must differ from the ratio between the destroying forces ; for this cog- nition it is which here concerns us, as exemplifying the most complex ratiocination. There is, be it observed, no direct comparison between these two ratios. How, then, are they known to be unlike ? Their unlikeness is known, through the intermediation of two other ratios to which they are severally equal. " The ratio between the sustaining forces equals the ratio I 2 : 2 2 . The ratio between the destroying forces equals the ratio i 3 : 2 3 . And, as it is seen that the ratio I 2 : 2 s is un- equal to the ratio I 3 : 2 s , it is by implication seen that the ratio between the sustaining forces is unequal to the ratio between the destroying forces. What is the nature of this implication ? or, rather, What is the mental act by which this implication is perceived? It is manifestly not decomposable HERBERT SPENCER. 259 into steps. Though involving many elements, it is a single intuition, 1 and, if expressed in an abstract form, amounts to the axiom : Ratios which are severally equal to certain other ratios that are unequal to each other are themselves unequal." 5 We submit that there is a direct comparison between two simple quantities to which the compared ratios are reduced by analysis. This perception of difference, which is so simple and mechanical in its nature that it can be viewed as a sensa- tion, is the fundamental activity of every perception, and to it every mathematical problem can be reduced. Its origin can be shown to be in the difference between self and not-self, between the consciousness of a single serial existence, or time, and of many existences, coexistences, or space. The statement that this final difference is only relative, ex- pressing the obverse terms of the ultimate relation which we call motion, is merely the completion of the conception, the illumination of the principle, of perception. That this principle is not taught by Mr. Spencer, those who will carefully study the first ten chapters of the second volume of " Psychology " will have good reason to believe ; and yet a deep study of these chapters reveals abundant materials from which this principle can be drawn. Following the problems of weight and resistance, Propo- sition XI. of the fifth book of Euclid is cited. After the demonstration of this problem, the following remarks occur: " What are here the premises and inference ? It is argued that the first relation being like the second in a. certain particular (the superiority of its first magnitude) ; and the third relation being also like the second in this, particular; the first relation must be like the third in this, particular. The same argument is applicable to any other particular, and therefore to all particulars. Whence the implication is, that relations that are like the same rela- 1 Intuition according to Spencer is an undecomposable cognition. * " Principles of Psychology," vol. II., ch. ii. 260 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. tion in all particulars, or are equal to it, are like each other in all particulars, or are equal. " Thus the general truth that relations which are equal to the same relation are equal to each other a truth of which the foregoing proposition concerning ratios is simply one of the more concrete forms must be regarded as an axiom. Like its analogue things that are equal to the same thing are equal to each other it is incapable of proof. Seeing how closely, indeed, the two are allied, some may contend that the one is but a particular form of the other, and should be included under it. They may say that a relation consid- ered quantitatively is a species of thing ; and that what is true of all things is, by implication, true of relations. Even were this satisfactorily shown, however, it would be needful, as will presently be seen, to enunciate this general law in respect to relations. * * * " The truth, relations that are equal to the same relation are equal to each other which we thus find is known by an intuition (an undecomposable mental act), and can only so be known, underlies important parts of geometry. An examination of the first proposition in the sixth book of Euclid, and of the deductions made from it in succeeding propositions, will show that many theorems have this axiom for their basis. But on this axiom are built far wider and far more important conclusions. It is the foundation of all mathematical analysis. * Alike in working out the sim- plest algebraical question and in performing those higher analytical processes of which algebra is the root, it is the one thing taken for granted at every step. The successive transformations of an equation are linked together by acts of thought of which this axiom expresses the most general form" ' This citation is given for the purpose of showing the great importance which Spencer attaches to this complex rule or axiom that " Relations which are equal to the same relation are equal to each other" ; also, how he clings to the word 1 " Principles of Psychology," vol. II., ch. II. HERBERT SPENCER. 26 1 relation as preferable to thing or fact ; although it is the more abstruse term, and how decided he is in saying that this rule is an intuition, a word which he interprets as " cognition reached by an undecomposable mental act." : It is manifestly a part of our theory of perception to deny the existence of intuitions when the term is used in the above sense ; for that sense presupposes an unknowable. " Intuition " is a very useful word in describing mental procedures, but it can never have a deeper meaning than that of a rapid percep- tion, so rapid as to appear to be undecomposable. But the principle of perception explains every possible intuition. Notwithstanding that the mental organism of man has reached such perfection that thought is able to cover vast areas as by a flash of light, the operation is composite, and can be traced step by step to the primordial difference between subject and object, the primeval inference from which all thought is elaborated. Far from this rule, "that relations which are equal to the same relation are equal to each other," being an undecomposable intuition, it is a manifest complexity of the perception of difference which is involved in every mathematical equation. The reason for using the word relations instead of things in the so-called axiomatic intuition is thus given by Mr. Spencer : " It should be noted that the relations thus far dealt with are relations of magnitudes, and, properly speak- ing, relations of homogeneous magnitudes ; or in other words, ratios. In the geometrical reasoning quoted from the fifth book of Euclid this fact is definitely expressed. In the algebraical reasoning, homogeneity of the magnitudes dealt with seems, at first, not implied ; since the same equa- tion often includes at once magnitudes of space, time, force, value. But on remembering that these magnitudes can be treated algebraically only by reducing them to the common denomination of number, and considering them as abstract magnitudes of the same order, we see that the relations dealt with are really those between homogeneous magni- 1 " Psychology," vol. II, p. 12, foot-note. 262 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. tudes are really ratios. The motive for constantly speak- ing of them under the general name relations, of which ratios are but one species, is that only when they are so classed can the intellectual processes by which they are co-ordinated be brought under the same category with other acts of reason- ing." ' The word ratio means proportion, the comparison of numbers or quantities. The terms of the comparison may be things, or other ratios, or relations indifferently, for things are merely complexities of numbers and quantities. The fact that all acts of reasoning spring from or can be explained by a perception, or sensation, of difference, is opposed to the statement that it is necessary to speak of the terms of an equation as Relations, in order to bring the in- tellectual process represented " under the same category with other acts of reasoning " ; for equations are merely comparisons. The sign of equality does not mean identity, but equivalence. There is always a difference implied in every statement of equality. The primordial difference, which is to be found between the conceptions of time and space, or between the facts known as subject and object, the self and the not-self, the creature and its surroundings, accounts for this difference, which is implied in the most complete possible equations. If "quantitative reasoning" is the most exact, quantitative equalities express the finest possible shade of difference ; and this difference is that of position or space, which means the same thing as quantity, for the word quantity never signifies more than an aspect of any phenomenon. To equalize homogeneous things in their quantitative aspect is to reduce their difference to that of position, or only space ; but this difference of position re- mains so long as comparison is possible. Straight lines are generated by points in motion. The most abstract terms of comparison possible are two straight lines, because their difference can be expressed in the sim- plest imaginable motion. Two equal straight lines give us the ideal equation. If these straight lines are merged in one, 1 " Psychology," vol. II., ch. ii. HERBERT SPENCER. 263 equality disappears in identity, and we have remaining the fact known as the simplest possible motion a straight line. But, it will be asked, if the primordial or simplest differ- ence is that between object and subject (the function of individuality), if this simplest difference has its source in the contracted aspects of motion, known as time and space, why is it said that the faintest possible shade of difference, which is detected at the bottom of every equation, is that of position, or space? Why does not the other factor of the ultimate relation, known as time, stand for an equally fine shade of difference ? Why does not the factor of time also appear in the ultimate analysis of equations? It has been said above that the ideal equation was to be found in two equal straight lines : " Two equal mathematical lines placed one upon the other merge into identity, and alone exhibit that species of coexistence which can lapse into single exist- ence." A straight line is generated by a point in motion. Two equal straight lines compared exhibit the simplest of all possible relations, excepting the ultimate relation, which is motion. A glance at the genesis of the conception of an equation of two equal straight lines shows how absolutely dependent we are, for every step of reasoning composing it, upon the fundamental fact of motion. But in this fact of motion is not the element of time always implied ? Can we generate a straight line without employing the factor time ? Can we form an equation without acknowledging the pres- ence of time in the synthesis? The first coexistence of which the mind becomes con- scious, namely, the ego and the non-ego, employs the con- sciousness of self as a factor. The conception of time is the subjective aspect of that synthesis of motion known to us as personal existence, and springs from the consciousness of serial life considered apart from all conditions. The con. sciousness of self, therefore, gives rise to our conception of time ; and as the subjective is a factor in every coexistence, no equation can be formed without employing time. But we are continually forgetting, or dropping, the subjective 264 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. factor of every coexistence. When we observe objects in space, we form the idea of objective coexistence ; but it is done by recognizing the relation, or fact, of coexistence between ourselves and each object, and then forgetting, or dropping, the subjective term. In this sense, and only in this sense, is the axiom that things which are equal to the same thing are equal to each other a primordial form of inference. It is the method of all comparisons, but it is manifestly composite and is the union of two distinct com- parisons, the establishment of two distinct relations, or facts of equality. In comparisons, or equations which rise above the simple relation of coexistence, the presence of the sub- jective factor becomes more and more obscure. If, for instance, we would establish equality of magnitude between three objects, we measure them all by one and declare that each of the remaining two, being equal to the one first measured, or selected as a measure, is equal to each other. If the objects were increased to four instead of three, the process would only be repeated, and the axiom would read, All things which are equal to the same thing are equal to one another, or the relation of equality is constant between like terms. Among homogeneous objects this relation of equality amounts to a declaration that the compared objects are alike excepting in position ; or, in other words, the primor- dial difference of space lasts as long as comparison remains possible, and is the last to give way before identity. In all this, however, the element of time is present, for the very act of reasoning, or comparing, or ratiocination, implies the lapse of time, and the first step beyond the conception of time implies space, or not-self. But it may be objected, if the faintest possible shade of difference between facts is to be found in the comparison of two equal straight lines, and the source of difference itself, or the primordial or simplest of all differences, is to be found in the comparison of time and space, or subject and object, what is the difference between these differences ? The reply HERBERT SPENCER. 26$ is, that when we compare two straight lines we compare two motions, or two separate facts ; and in comparing time and space, we have that contrast between the aspects of motion, as an indivisible fact, which is the function of our individu- ality, the germ of intelligence, the beginning of life and of perception. Thus we see our utter inability to escape from the primordial fact of motion, which gives birth to every conception, for in the contrasted aspects of this fact we have the source of every inference. In the sixth and seventh chapters of the same work we find a labored argument, the purpose of which is to review the subject of " perfect " and " imperfect quantitative reason- ing," thereby bringing the subject down to the subsequent chapter entitled " Reasoning in General." All through this argument a persistent effort is made to prove that the propo- sition, " Relations which are equal to the same relation are equal to each other," is what might be termed an irreducible axiom, the initial act of reasoning. In the chapter entitled " The Final Question," second division of the same volume, Mr. Spencer endeavors to prove that a complete theory of knowledge is impossible at the present stage of human culture. By a complete theory of knowledge he seems to mean a comprehension of the princi- ples of life and mind, the determination of which is the aim of all philosophy. This assertion is thus set forth : " But while a true theory of knowledge is impossible without a true theory of the thing knowing and a theory of the thing known, which is true as far as it goes; and while it follows that advance toward a true theory of any one depends on advances toward true theories of the others ; it is, I think, manifest that, since a true theory of knowledge implies a true co-ordination of that which knows with that which is known, the ultimate form of such a theory can be reached only after the theories of that which knows and of that which is known have reached their ultimate forms. * * * That the theories of the known and of the knowing have assumed their finished shapes, and that a finished theory of Knowledge 266 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. is now possible, would, of course, be an absurd assumption." Here we have two distinct assertions ; the first is, that a true theory of Knowledge can be formed, providing we can form -a " true theory of the thing knowing and a theory of the thing known, which is true as far as it goes." The second is, that a true theory of knowledge is impossible as yet, be- cause " the ultimate form of such a theory can be reached only after the theories of that which knows and of that which is known have reached their ultimate forms "; and the assumption that this ultimate form of theory has been reached is declared to be an absurdity. This, of course, is equivalent to saying that a true theory of Knowledge (using the word in its true sense, to include the knowing and the known) has not been arrived at, and cannot be arrived at in the present state of human culture. The theory of Knowledge, therefore, which Mr. Spencer offers is admitted by himself to be imperfect, incomplete, less than true. Is not this a rather discouraging admission, when we consider the vast amount of introspective study which his system contains ? The degree of this necessary incompleteness of our conception of knowledge is not de- fined, but it seems to be measured by the incompleteness of our understanding of the principles of knowledge, or the categories of thought. Thus we are told that " Developed intelligence is framed upon certain organized and consoli- dated conceptions of which it cannot divest itself ; and which it can no more stir without using than the body can stir without help of its limbs." 1 This asserts that these " organ- ized and consolidated conceptions " are absolutely essential to the activity of the intelligence. We are not told what kind of activity it is which organizes and consolidates these conceptions, without which the mind is said to be incapable of procedure of any kind. It will be remembered that these conceptions are five in number ; they are enumerated in the chapter on " Ultimate Scientific Ideas," in " First Principles," as follows : Space, Time, Matter, Motion, and Force. These 1 " Principles of Psychology," vol. II., p. 309. HERBERT SPENCER. 267 conceptions were declared to be utterly incomprehensible ; any attempt to understand them was said to lead to absurd- ities. Again : they were aggravated in a sixth conception, called consciousness. This combination of incomprehensi- bles was also declared to be utterly incomprehensible, which, it must be admitted, was but a fair inference. Now is it surprising, with this combination of inconceivable concep- tions aggregated into an incomprehensible consciousness, all being manifestations of the unknowable, to set out with, that we should have a theory of knowledge in some degree incomplete ? As a further illustration of the incompleteness of Mr. Spencer's theory of knowledge, we would call atten- tion to his belief in the existence of " organized and consoli- dated conceptions," which are absolutely essential to intel- lectual activity. Conceptions are surely the fruit of intellectual activity, and to postulate conceptions already " organized and con- solidated," as a primary condition to intellectual procedures, is correct only in a very limited sense ; in a broad sense it is equivalent to saying that the mind can act without acting. Here we have the vital fault of Mr. Spencer's psychology. It teaches distinctly that " reason is absolutely incapable of justifying its assumption. An assumption it is at the outset. An assumption it must remain to the last." From a less careful writer than Spencer these words might be passed over as an inadvertence, but they are too consistent with the rest of his psychological reasoning, and too prominent in themselves, to fail to impress us. It is clearly admitted that all intellectual activity is included under the broadest mean- ing of the word reasoning. By following out Mr. Spencer's idea of reasoning, there- fore, in which it is said that the activity of reasoning extends in an unbroken chain from those automatic procedures known as reflex action to the highest efforts of the mind, we shall perceive that it is hardly consistent with that theory of knowledge which declares that the activities of the mind 1 " Principles of Psychology," vol. II., p. 317. 268 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. depend absolutely upon organized consolidated conceptions which are utterly incomprehensible. " Reasoning, however," says Mr. Spencer, " is nothing more than re-coordinating states of consciousness already co-ordinated in certain simpler ways. * * * Men of science, now as in all past times, subor- dinate the deliverances of consciousness reached through mediate processes to the deliverances of consciousness reached through immediate processes ; or, to speak strictly, they subordinate those deliverances reached through pro- longed and conscious reasoning to those deliverances reached through reasoning that has become so nearly automatic as no longer to be called reasoning." ] In a word, the highest achievements of the mind are submitted to the arbitration of the senses, or those automatic co-ordinations which may be regarded as the natural activities of the physical organ- ism, because so simple that they cannot be classed as mental. If reasoning is thus traced from the simplest organic co-or- dinations or activities to those involved efforts of the mind commonly classed as reasoning, and if it is admitted that the re-coordinations (or higher reasonings) cannot give to the results reached a validity independent of that possessed by the previously co-ordinated states, where is the break in a chain of reasoning reaching from the simplest organic fact to the most complex, or from the first co-ordinations to the most involved co-ordinations ? Deductions when correct are but natural effects of certain causes given in the premises from which the deductions are made. Logical de- ductions are the natural consequences of the meaning of words, the symbolic representations of organic activities. When Spencer teaches, therefore, that all the activities of the mind can be included under the broadest meaning of the word reasoning, and in the same chapter asserts that " Reasoning is absolutely incapable of justifying its assump- tion, an assumption it is at the outset, an assumption it must remain to the last," the contradiction is evident ; for after identifying reasoning with all organic activity, it would 1 " Principles of Psychology," vol. II., p. 315. HERBERT SPENCER. 269 be just as sensible to say that cause and effect, which are the obverse appearances of every fact, are arbitrary appear- ances, assumptions which cannot justify themselves, as to say that reasoning cannot justify itself. Facts express and jus- tify themselves, and the 'deepest fact is the end of analysis and the beginning of synthesis, the principle of perception, or life. If it is possible to find a rank superstition involved in a flagrant contradiction in terms, it is this theory which as- sumes that reason is an unjustifiable assumption, that the elements of thought are impenetrable mysteries, that knowl- edge springs from the unknowable, that perception is the function of the imperceptible, that conceptions are mani- festations of the inconceivable, and that they spring armed cap-a-pie into the world of consciousness, the manifest fruits of thought, but denying their origin. Intellectual activity is akin to universal activity, a form of motion. Conscious- ness, thought, reason, perception, knowledge, are but differ- ent names for different aspects of this activity. The prime factors in this activity are the subject and the object, the creature and its environment ; and in this dual aspect of the phenomenon of knowledge (for knowledge we hold to be its most comprehensive term) we have that contrast, comparison, expression of difference, or primordial relation, from which the great structure of mind is built up, to which contrast we trace the origin of all thought, and by which we explain Perception. The very word unknowable involves an absurd- ity. To name a thing is to recognize its existence, to classify it, and therefore to reason about it, and hence, in some degree, to know it. In what degree do we know the " unknowable " ? Hear w r hat Mr. Spencer says, in another part of the same volume, in support of this position : " The general community of nature, thus shown in mental acts, called by different names, may be cited as so much confirmation of the several analyses. * * * All orders of Reasoning Deductive and Inductive, Necessary and Contingent, Quantitative and Qualitative, Axiomatic 270 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. and Analogical come under one general form. Here we see both that classification, naming, and recognition are nearly allied to one another, and that they, too, are sev- erally modifications of that same fundamental intuition out of which all orders of reasoning arise. Nor are classifica- tion and naming allied only as being both of inferential nature ; for they are otherwise allied as different sides of the same thing. Naming presupposes classification ; and classi- fication cannot be carried to any extent without naming. Similarly with recognition and classification, which are also otherwise allied than through their common kinship to ratio- cination. They often merge into each other, either from the extreme likeness of different objects, or the changed aspect of the same object ; and while recognition is a classing of a present impression with] past impressions, classification is a recognition of a particular object as one of a special group of objects. This weakening of conventional distinctions, this reduction of these several operations of the mind, in common with all those hitherto considered, to variations of one operation, is to be expected as the result of analysis." 1 This analysis shows all the operations of mind to be of the same order, from the simplest to the highest co-ordinations, and yet all orders of reasoning are said to be but modifications of that fundamental intuition which is elsewhere referred to as the function of the " unknowable," a group of " concrete organized conceptions," which are in themselves incompre- hensible, a group of intellectual " entities," " manifestations of the unknowable." In case the reader should suspect that Mr. Spencer makes a difference between the operations of the mind in general and those operations which we call reasoning, we have but to revert to the chapter on " Reason- ing in General," where we find it admitted that knowledge gained through the senses, or, as Mr. Spencer terms it, by per- ception, differs from that gained by the reasoning faculties, not in nature, but only in the directness of the apprehen- sion. If the cognitions gained through sensuous percep- 1 " Principles of Psychology," vol. II., p. 129. HERBERT SPENCER. 2? I tions are the same in nature as the cognitions gained through the reasoning faculties, at what stage in the development of mind does the " irreducible intuition " make its appearance? " Let us consider," says Mr. Spencer, " what is the more specific definition of Reasoning. Not only does the kind of proposition called an inference assert a relation ; but every proposition, whether expressing mediate or immediate knowledge, asserts a relation. How, then, does knowing a relation by Reason differ from knowing it by Perception ? It differs by its indirectness. A cognition is distinguishable as of one or the other kind, according as the relation it em- bodies is disclosed to the mind directly or indirectly. If its terms are so presented that the relation between them is im- mediately cognized if their coexistence, or succession, or juxtaposition, is knowable through the senses, we have a per- ception. If their coexistence, or sequence, or juxtaposition, is not knowable through the senses, if the relation between them is mediately cognized, we have a ratiocinative act. Rea- soning, then, is the indirect establishment of a definite relation between two things. But now the question arises, By what process can the indirect establishment of a definite relation be effected ? There is one process, and only one. If a re- lation between two things is not directly knowable, it can be disclosed only through the intermediation of relations that are directly knowable, or are already known." Reasoning, then, which is admitted to signify, in its widest sense, all intellectual activity, is declared to be the indirect establishment of a definite relation between two things. " If this relation between two things is not directly knowable, it can be disclosed only through the intermediation of relations that are directly knowable ', or are already known." Does not the above show conclusively that the genesis of thought is from facts to facts, from definite known relations to definite known relations, and that, in this admission, there is no room for the unknowable ? Does it not appear as though, in the analysis above quoted, our author had 1 "Principles of Psychology," vol. II., p. 115. 272 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. penetrated so near the truth as to forget that error which, in other parts of his system, is shown to be at the bottom of his theory of perception? Is it not clear, from the position we now hold in this attempt at a Synthesis of Knowledge, that the departure from the true course of reasoning in Mr. Spencer's psychology is caused by the difficulty of account- ing, not for the general procedures of the mind, but for our conceptions of those principles known as space, time, matter, force, and motion, and his consequent failure to perform an analysis of perception? Involved as are the operations of the mind in tracing them out, we encounter no mysteries, no irreducible intuitions, no facts which are not fully comprehensible or which do not justify themselves. If reasoning is an institution of compari- sons varying in complexity from the primordial comparison of the subjective and the objective, which gives us the conscious- ness of personal existence, to the vaguest and most remote analogies, it is manifest that the process is constant in nature, and varies in complexity with the terms compared. In estimat- ing the likeness between homogeneous objects, we establish equality of quantity by a comparison of measurements, or by measuring all by one. We unconsciously employ the subjec- tive factor in each relation of equality established, for we virtually affirm that each object impresses us as the same in all respects excepting position. When quantitative com- parisons cease and more complex attributes or qualities are compared, the use of the subjective factor becomes more and more obscured, and we imagine that we are comparing purely objective facts directly together, whereas we are al- ways comparing the impressions which the facts make upon us together ; or, in other words, we are comparing relations ; but what are these relations between ourselves and objects but facts themselves ? They are facts of consciousness hav- ing for their terms objective and subjective activities. If mind, then, is made up of these simple comparisons, perfectly simple in nature but becoming more and more intricate as -they ascend in thought, what becomes of that involved intui- HERBERT SPENCER. 273 tion which we are told is so fundamental that it cannot be reduced to any simpler terms ? But here we come upon the difference between sensation and thought, between facts of consciousness which have objective factors, and facts of con- sciousness which are purely subjective. A train of thought is set going within us, and the great machinery of the mind continues to work out its comparisons with apparent inde- pendence of the environment. These trains of thought some- times occupy years in their course, and are silently progressing during waking and sleeping, during all sorts of distracting occupations, and at last complete themselves, in some cases, with scarcely any conscious effort on the part of the thinker. This is certainly a conspicuous instance of the difference be- tween sensation and thought. Sensation has one factor with- out, thought proceeds within. This distinction, however, is only relative. The sensorium responds to impressions from without, and each impression produces its modification of the sensorium, its memory : impressions repeated become deeper, the modifications become more and more marked. Each modification of structure implies a modification of function. The physical adjustments which correspond to those compari- sons constituting thought are thus far inscrutable, but we have the results in the clearer perceptions which accrue from thinking, or, in other words, the more ready adjustment of the organism to its environment. The difference, therefore, between sensation and thought is, that sensation is the ac- tivity of the sensorium which is the more nearly connected with the external causes of excitement, and thought is the activity of the sensorium which is farthest removed from external causes of excitement ; and between these two ex- tremes there are all degrees of combinations, varying from what is known as reflex action to the most abstract and involved achievements of reason. The subjective factor in each comparison is ever present throughout all these progressions, and the intuition by which Mr. Spencer places so much store is simply a logical formula in which the repetition of the subjective term in perception, although per- 2/4 T HE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. fectly discernible, is elided or neglected. In fact, in the light of the above analysis, it is far more difficult to see how the objective factor remains present in abstract thought, for it is clear that in those mental activities which have no direct connection with the environment, which, in other words, draw the terms of their comparisons from the memory, the objec- tive factor is only present through such representation as it has secured by modifications of the sensorium. Thinking or calculating, therefore, without the aid of di- rect verification, or practical demonstration, is an intellectual activity which is carried on by a sort of proxy communica- tion with the outer world ; and keen indeed must be the memory, deep the impressions made by facts upon the mind, to secure the reliability of the results. We see, then, that there is an excuse, but not a justifica- tion, for the assertion of Mr. Spencer that the simplest type of mental activity is the complex axiom declaring equality between relations having one term in common and the other terms equal (relations which are equal to the same relation are equal to each other) ; for although it is impossible to compare objects without employing the subjective factor, or without comparing the impressions of the object on ourselves, or the relations between ourselves and each object, the com- parisons, or relations, are distinct and complete in them- selves, and the presence of a common term is only an abridged way of expressing the repetition of the same term. If the presence of the subjective factor is not the ground on which Mr. Spencer insists upon the above form of axiom, the futility of the argument is the more manifest ; for to say that two things are equal because they are each equal to a third is exactly the same as saying that three things are equal be- cause there is no distinguishable difference between them, which repeats the subjective factor in each comparison and makes three distinct assertions of equality. Should refutation appear unnecessarily elaborate, the ex- tent and intricacy of the argument of which it is a summary should be remembered. HERBERT SPENCER. 275 The theory of Knowledge offered in this work, contrasted with that offered by Mr. Spencer, may be set forth as fol- lows : Knowledge is an activity coextensive with organic life ; life is an activity which is universal. The activity which we recognize as life in the monad is ultimately indis- tinguishable in its nature from those expressions of the physical forces known as chemical reactions or affinities acknowledged to be but forms of motion. The activities of organic life become more and more complex or special in their development toward the highest type, which we find in our own species. These co-ordinations still progress through what is known as superorganic, or social, phenomena, through the interactions of the individual and society expressed in language and intelligence, culminating in that most perfect activity known as morality. In the march of progress, which is the most complete view we can take of the universe, we are not passive spectators, but co-operants. Our perceptions are limited only by our- selves ; these limits are the expression of individuality. Now this individuality is so conspicuous an attribute, that even such minds as Descartes and Kant have mistaken it for the most general fact, the one immovable truth. But if we think a moment, we shall see that this truth is not absolute or im- movable, that it is moving with the current of events ; that it is a part of universal change. Viewed in their higher developments, thought and action appear entirely distinct ; but when we reduce the scale of development to its lowest point, their community of nature readily appears. There is nothing in the life of the monad, in its affinity or attraction for proximately like substances,, its consequent increase in size, and falling into pieces, which could suggest such names as assimilation, growth, and repro- duction ; but the fundamental activities of higher organic life, to which these names are applied, are traced in insen- sible gradations to this simple origin, and thus the differ- ence between universal activities and the special activities of organic life disappear. So the mental procedures, known 276 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION'. as perception, or thought, are only higher developments of these organic activities, and are plainly traceable through natural sequences to the same simple source. Every movement of the microscopic speck of protoplasm is the direct function of its chemical constitution and its mechanical adjustment to the environment ; and these names, chemical and mechanical, are acknowledged to represent merely special aspects or forms of motion. When the monad acts, how- ever simply, that action expresses a law, or a truth, and con- stitutes the simplest imaginable form of perception. There is no structure to co-ordinate the action so that it can be re- produced in memory, adjusted in thought, and readjusted in action. The tiny cycle of change set up in this little being is too simple to receive any such classification ; but from its motions are built up the activities of the highest life, without the intervention of any new principle. Science having familiarized the mind with all these particulars of develop- ment, the seeker after incomprehensibles is forced into the nar- row limits of metaphysical terms. Space, time, matter, force, and motion, are found in consciousness, and they are found out of consciousness. One class of thinkers are puzzled with the question how they got into the mind ; the other, how they managed to get out of it. The former class reason that as they are unknowables they cannot get into the mind as they really are, so they must run the gantlet in the guise of " organized consolidated con- ceptions " ; and it is well understood after they do get in in this guise, they are to be utterly incomprehensible. The other class argue that these mystic principles are absolute entities, independent originals, that are found in the mind; and as they cannot in any way get out, they practically take every thing in with them. These two great classes of thinkers have, of course, displayed all degrees of ingenuity in expound- ing their theories. Some of them, in order to protect these precious fallacies, have built up intellectual fortifications which bid fair to last, at least as imposing ruins, throughout the existence of our race. No amount of subtility on the HERBERT SPENCER. 277 part of these metaphysicians, however, seems to prevent the above simple classification of their systems, although, in the course of their arguments they have sounded the key-note of thought over and over again. The ultimate analysis declares these so-called incomprehensible principles to be but phases of a fact which is in the highest degree comprehensible ; for to this fact perception and thought are directly traceable. This is the distinguishing feature of the theory of Knowl- edge which I would here offer, and this it is which marks its contrast with all theories postulating an unknowable as taking part in any form, or through any manifestation, in the constitution of Knowledge. With regard to perception, the present theory teaches that the direction of perception is the direction of organic life, that its source and procedures are organic, and that the moving limits of individuality are its only circumscriptions. Thus mind has no proscrip- tions in nature. The vistas of consciousness are unlimited ; the universe holds nothing back from thought. Through- out the receding simplifications of analysis, or the advancing constructions of synthesis, we meet with no fact or prin- ciple, however general, which the individual cannot assimi- late, and which is not in itself an advancement and en- largement of our existence. CHAPTER XII. HERBERT SPENCER (CONCLUDED). Sociology an Instrument in Determining Ultimate Beliefs. WE have now before us the more grateful task of describ- ing the merits of Spencer's system of philosophy. In " First Principles," which is an epitome of the whole, and in the succeeding four volumes, two of " Biology " and two of " Psy- chology," we find a masterly picture of the related stages of progression from the simplest to the most complex type of organic life. In the first book of the above series, the changes expressed in this progressive organic development are more or less clearly affiliated to those changes broadly described as inorganic. In the last book we find an attempt to explain the organic side of mental life, and to apply to the highest of all phenomena the formula of evolution. The march from the simple to the complex is shown to be the direction of universal activity. This idea is further elaborated in a definition of life, to which we demurred because it merely adds to the conception of universal activity the characteris- tics of the activity of individual or organic life, and should, therefore, be called a definition, not of life in general, but of organic life. The principle so laboriously expounded, that "Function makes Structure," which has a fuller expression in the theory of " the direct adaptation of the creature to its environment," a prominent feature of Spencer's biological studies, was objected to on the ground that function and structure are but obverse sides of every phenomenon, and neither, therefore, can have precedence over the other as a cause. In constructing this system of thought, Mr. Spencer has 278 HERBERT SPENCER. 2?g presented to the world a philosophy admirably articulated and constituting an organon of scientific truth of inestimable value. His best original work does not appear, however, in the first five books of the system. Beneath the imposing array of scientific knowledge we find an undercurrent of ontological speculation, a persistent effort at an ultimate analysis, which produces as its result, from crisis to crisis throughout the work, the conception of the so-called " deepest knowable truth," denominated The Persistence of Force. It is true that at times this "deepest knowable truth " is de- clared to be unknowable, but for the most part, with remark- able consistency of purpose, he avoids placing this conception among the weird group of ultimates fully described in the last chapter, which are declared to be inconceivables ; but the logical difficulty which this omission might be supposed to avoid is only thereby enhanced, for Force, according to Mr. Spencer, is a prominent name among the "unknowobles" and how it is made to serve as the basis of " the deepest know- able truth " is not explained. We are left to infer, perhaps, that the depth attributed to this conception is solely a property of the attribute persistence ; since we are certainly safe in assuming that whatever property an unknowable conception may have, it can lay no claim to a third dimension. After this deep study of individual or organic life, which forms the principal theme of the first five books above mentioned, we come to the study of what Mr. Spencer de- nominates super-organic phenomena. This is the science of Sociology, for which he is so justly renowned. Its field is human life ; its plan is to view humanity as a great organ- ism, and to study the adjustments of this organism, as an aggregate, to its surroundings ; tracing, through the changes of history, the sequences of its existence. The purpose of this study, as can readily be seen, is to examine the different phases of conduct from the primitive family or tribe to the race viewed as a confederation of nations ; the object being to create a science of morality. Too much cannot be said in praise of such a work ; its 280 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. very inception is an inspiration. The first volume of " Soci- ology " is one of the most interesting literary productions of our century. It is the romance of human life viewed from the most commanding position which thought affords. The subject of the Primitive Man is minutely studied ; his probable surroundings, and the influence of these surround- ings as the external factors of his existence, are estimated. The physical, emotional, and intellectual aspects of his nature are respectively considered, as the internal factors of his development, and this development is shown to be the establishment of those permanent relationships between individuals known as social organization. The different questions which the enormous periods of man's prehistoric existence give rise to are considered with the characteristic depth and thoroughness of the author ; and in his treatment of them we have a graphic picture of the long and painful struggle for existence which preceded the primitive forms of civilization. The great impetus which co-operation among men has given to human life is depicted, and it is shown that social progress and the perfection of conduct are but obverse aspects of the same development. In this book we have Mr. Spencer at his best. Sure of his subject and conclusions, his style is clear and comprehensive, his thought deep almost to the emotional. Persuaded by his earnestness, criticism gives way to conviction, and one is content to read and learn. An idea of the method can be gained from the following, which occurs in the chapter on " The Factors of Social Phenomena " : ' ' There remains in the group of derived factors one more, the potency of which can scarcely be over-estimated. I mean that accumulation of super- organic products which we commonly distinguish as artificial, but which, philo- sophically considered, are no less natural than all others resulting from evolution. There are several orders of these. ' ' First come the material appliances, which, beginning with roughly-chipped flints, end in the complex automatic tools of an engine-factory driven by steam ; which from boomerangs rise to thirty-five-ton guns ; which from huts of branches and grass grow to cities with their palaces and cathedrals. Then we have lan- guage, able at first only to eke out gestures in communicating simple ideas, but HERBERT SPENCER. 28 1 eventually becoming capable of expressing highly- complex conceptions with precision. While from that stage in which it conveys thoughts only by sounds to one or a few other persons, we pass through picture-writing up to steam- printing : multiplying indefinitely the numbers communicated with, and making accessible in voluminous literatures the ideas and feelings of innumerable men in various places and times. Concomitantly there goes on the development of knowledge, ending in science. Counting on the fingers grows into far-reaching mathematics ; observation of the moon's changes leads at length to a theory of the solar system ; and at successive stages there arise sciences of which not even the germs can at first be detected. Meanwhile the once few and simple customs, becoming more numerous, definite, and fixed, end in systems of laws. From a few rude superstitions there grow up elaborate mythologies, theologies, cosmogonies. Opinion getting embodied in creeds, gets embodied, too, in accepted codes of propriety, good conduct, ceremony, and in established social sentiments. And then there gradually evolve also the products we call aesthetic ; which of themselves form a highly-complex group. From necklaces of fish- bones we advance to dresses, elaborate, gorgeous, and infinitely varied ; out of discordant war-chants come symphonies and operas ; cairns develop into mag- nificent temples ; in place of caves with rude markings there arise at length galleries of paintings ; and the recital of a chief's deeds with mimetic accom- paniment gives origin to epics, dramas, lyrics, and the vast mass of poetry, fic- tion, biography, and history. " All these various orders of super-organic products, each evolving within itself new genera and species while daily growing into a larger whole, and each acting upon the other orders while being reacted upon by them, form together an im- mensely voluminous, immensely complicated, and immensely powerful set of influences. During social evolution these influences are ever modifying indi- viduals and modifying society, while being modified by both. They gradually form what we may consider either as a non-vital part of the society itself, or else as an additional environment, which eventually becomes even more important than the original environments, so much more important that there arises the possibility of carrying on a high type of social life under inorganic and organic conditions which originally would have prevented it. * * * The influences which the society exerts on the natures of its units, and those which the units exert on the nature of the society, incessantly co-operate in creating new elements." 1 To these immediate influences are added others more remote. The physical surroundings of the primitive man are all but impossible to imagine, so meagre are our means of estimating them. " Now that geologists and archaeologists are uniting to prove that human existence goes back to a date so remote that ' prehistoric ' scarcely expresses it now that imbedded traces of human handiwork show us that, not only J<< Sociology," vol. I., p. 14. 282 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. sedimentary deposits of considerable depths and subsequent extensive denudations, but also immense changes in the dis- tribution of land and sea, have occurred since the rudest social groups were formed ; it is clear that the effects of external conditions on social evolution cannot be fully traced." ' In the second volume of "Biology" we find a series of studies on morphology, which trace the special forms of plants and animals to natural causes, and find in them an expression of that general law of activity revealed as well in the complex forces displayed in crystallization as in the sim- ple and omnipresent power of gravitation. As a sequel to the results of these studies, the theory of natural social develop- ment is unfolded. The origin of the physical contrasts giving rise to the classification of races is pointed out. The ebony skin of certain tribes of Central Africa and the blanched cheek of the Caucasian are made to tell their tales of slowly operating causes. The Yakut child seen to devour at one meal " three candles, several pounds of sour frozen butter, and a large piece of yellow soap," the adult of the same race who comfortably disposed of " forty pounds of meat in a day," and the brain-worker of our zone and civilization who subsists upon a modicum of highly concentrated nourish- ment, are made to depict contrasted habitats and types of social development. The theory that the life of an indi- vidual from childhood to maturity simulates the develop- ment of man from the savage to a higher social state, is explained, and some telling comparisons are drawn between the civilized baby and the primitive man. This theory is made to precede the more general one, that all social as well as individual development is an advance in the number, com- plexity, and delicacy of the adjustments of the creature to its environment, progressing toward the intellectual through the physical and the emotional. The complete dependence of mental upon social development is then dwelt upon. The remoteness of the higher orders of mental 1 " Sociology," vol I., p. 17. HERBERT SPENCER. 283 action from the relatively simple and automatic reflex action of organisms is explained. No stinted citations can give a just idea of the power and faithfulness of these analyses, or of the sweep of the thought which they describe. " The environment of the primitive man being such that his converse with things is relatively restricted in Space and Time, as well as in variety, it happens that the associations of ideas he forms are little liable to be changed. As experi- ences (multiplying in number, gathered from a wider area, added to by those which other men record) become more heterogeneous, the narrow notions first framed, fixed in the absence of conflicting experiences, are shaken and made more plastic there comes greater modifiability of belief. In the relative rigidity of belief characterizing undeveloped intelligence, we see less of that representativeness which simultaneously grasps and averages much evidence ; and we see a smaller divergence from those lowest mental actions in which impressions cause, irresistibly, the appropriate motions. While the experiences are few and but slightly varied, the concreteness of the corresponding ideas is but little qualified by the growth of abstract ideas. An abstract idea, being one drawn from many concrete ideas, becomes detachable from these concrete ideas only as fast as their multiplicity and variety lead to mutual cancellings of their differences, and leave outstanding that which they have in common. Obvi- ously an abstract idea so generated implies an increase of the correspondence in range and heterogeneity ; it implies increased representativeness in the consciousness of the many concretes whence the idea is abstracted ; and it implies greater remoteness from reflex action. It must be added that such abstract ideas as those of property and cause pre- suppose a still higher stage in this knowledge of objects and actions. For only after many special properties and many special causes have been thus abstracted can there arise the re-abstracted ideas of property in general and cause in general. The conception of uniformity in the order of phe- nomena develops along with this progress in generalization 284 THE MATURE OF PERCEPTION. and abstraction. Not uniformity but multiformity is the dominant trait in the course of things as the primitive man witnesses it. No two places are alike, no two men, no two trees, rivers, stones, days, storms, quarrels. Only along with the use of measures, when social advance initiates it, does there grow up the means of ascertaining uniformity ; and only after a great accumulation of measured results does the idea of law become possible. In proportion as the mental development is low, the mind merely receives and repeats cannot initiate, has no originality. An imagination which invents shows us an extension of the correspondence from the region of the actual into that of the potential ; it shows us a representativeness not limited to combinations which have been or are in the environment, but including non- existing combinations thereafter made to exist ; and it ex- hibits the extremest remoteness from reflex action, since the stimulus issuing in movement is unlike any that ever before acted." ' No one can read this part of Spencer's philosophy without perceiving the great power of these sociological illustrations. Facts which it is practically impossible to discern in individ- ual life become clear when viewed through the vastly ex- tended scale of aggregated social life. This question there- fore naturally suggests itself : Cannot we employ sociology as an instrument for the discovery of the nature of percep- tion ? Cannot the growth of consciousness of the race, viewed as a whole, explain to us the genesis of consciousness in the individual ? Religion in its rudest forms, superstitious reasoning with regard to the causes of events, seems to have occupied the larger place among the ideas of primitive men. The study of sociology brings these beginnings of the social conscious- ness prominently into view. Primitive Ideas Ideas of the Animate and Inanimate of Death and Resurrection of Souls, Ghosts, Spirits, and Demons of Another Life of Another World of Supernatural Agents Sacred Places, 1 "Principles of Sociology," vol. I., pp. 84-86. HERBERT SPENCER. 28$ Temples, Altars Praise Prayer Ancestor-Worship Idol- and Fetich-Worship Animal-, Plant-, and Nature-Worship Deities these are the titles of the principal chapters of the " Data of Sociology " ; they recite a long and interesting story of the development of the mind of primitive men. With no definite language or records of the observations and experiences of others, the primitive man groped in utter darkness. Hence, with regard to the natural order of things, as far as they were not appreciable in his simplest sensations he was without a guide. Thought had no mate- rials to work with and produced but vagaries and phantasms. Ideas of supernatural beings came into existence, and as a result we find the ruder forms of ancestor-worship the type of all the early religious beliefs. Thus the belief in a surviving duplicate, a soul separate from the body, is universal among savages, and was the be- ginning of our ideas of the supernatural. Those who are interested in the genesis of this belief can trace it step by step through the course of the chapters above referred to. Instead of this savage belief in a surviving duplicate being an authority for our belief in the immortality of the soul ; that higher understanding of life, which is the natural product of a developed language, discloses to us the ghost as the primi- tive type of supernatural being, and the belief in any form of ghostly existence as a primitive superstition. To the savage, who found his most powerful foe in his own species, it is easy to understand how the ghost-chief became the ideal of supreme power. Of course the ideal of supreme power is always the object of worship. The savage and the civilized man alike bow before what they conceive to be the greatest force. The point which we would here emphasize is, that the mind, or sentiency and language, is the instrument by which this power is invariably appreciated, and the degree of apprecia- tion depends entirely upon the quality of the mind. It may be said that all power must be appreciated by the mind, but this is only relatively true. In lower organisms the power which accounts for the life of the individual is only appreci- 286 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. ated in the ebb and flow of physical existence. It is not co-ordinated into an ideal or conception which co-ordinates conduct. The apprehension of food, and the escape from danger, are certainly appreciations, and therefore percep- tions, of external powers or existences ; but there is a vast difference of degree between these humble reactions and the conception, for instance, of a personal God as the cause of all things. The conception of Motion, however, as the ultimate reality, or universal principle, is an effort of sentiency and language which is so much higher than that of a personal God, a militant ancestor, or a fetich, that the comparison can only be one of remote analogy. By viewing the human race, therefore, as a whole, or by employing the inductions of sociology, which show the de- pendence of human development upon its farthest surround- ings, we are enabled to trace the principles of perception from the simplest organic activities to the highest phases of life ; and we are enabled to recognize in the gradual growth of language and intellect the dawning of the moral nature of man. Social life increases the harmony and definiteness of ideas and actions, establishing language and conduct, and we perceive, by studying this phase of life, that mind and morality are concomitant developments. To harmonize conduct with a true conception of God, to perform an ultimate analysis of life or existence, and to rebuild a synthesis which shall include and explain morality, is the task of sociology. But how, then, can a sociology suc- ceed which does not begin with an understanding of ultimate terms? What have we to hope for from a treatment of this science which regards consciousness or perception as a mys- tery and the deepest principles of knowledge as unknowable? Turning from these philosophical inconsistencies to the same order of inconsistency in religious belief it will not do for us to conclude that by the type of ultimate beliefs the type of character or morality is declared. Categorical beliefs depend almost entirely upon the education, and education depends more upon fortuitous circumstances than upon char- HERBERT SPENCER. 287 acter. But this argument is balanced by the fact that there is a kind of ultimate belief, an appreciation of divine unity, which is a true expression of character ; its language is that of actions more than of words ; it is the genius for truth, the natural integrity of life, which we call instinctive morality. But instinctive or unenlightened morality has a limited range ; it is too contracted, too feeble for a great social life. The horizon of the unenlightened mind, like that of the primitive man, is full of mysteries and portents ; it cannot respond to the more delicate influences of life. On the other hand, the mind which is sensitive to differences and likenesses, which is active in reasoning, naturally revolts against a narrow definition of God. This freedom of thought, however, often asserts itself without seriously interfering with settled religious beliefs, although these beliefs can be clearly identified with primitive superstitions. This is the latitude of belief which results from the vagueness of our conceptions of ultimate terms. Thus we find many seem- ingly educated persons, who would scorn to believe in a ghost, clinging with pathetic reverence to the archetype of ghosts the belief in a personal god. These same minds are in possession of scientific truths, classes of facts, which if co- ordinated, if followed out to their logical consequences, would utterly destroy this superstition ; still they not only cherish it but they regard it as in some way connected with the moral integrity of their lives. Hence, although we are able to trace our belief in a personal god to the savage faith in the existence of ancestral ghosts, and our belief in the im- mortality of the soul to the primitive belief in a surviving duplicate, we are confronted with the strange argument that to surrender these heirlooms of the unenlightened mind would be to endanger the moral order of society. Thus phi- losophy, whose aim it is to illuminate conduct, has to meet the serious charge that by teaching the true meaning of ulti- mate terms it attacks morality. Morality is generally conceded to be the consequence of pure conceptions of life. How, may it be asked, can pure conceptions of life perpetuate primitive belief ? 288 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. To the student of sociology it is clear that our religious beliefs have been slowly evolved from the grossest supersti- tions. If we would form pure religious conceptions, these superstitions must be subjugated ; they must be recognized as methods of the primitive mind. The question, then, between philosophy and the represen- tatives among us of these earliest beliefs of man, concerns the degree of purification of which our religious beliefs are susceptible. A critic of undoubted ability, to whom these pages were sub- mitted, objects to the use of the word God for the universal principle Motion. He says that to the truly philosophic mind, to the mind deeply learned in the history of human culture, or the evolution of religious and philosophic be- liefs, the word God is an obsolete term ; that the divine unity of life and mind is symbolized by the principle Motion, and that the word God is too closely connected with idolatry to be used in the same sense. To this argument I would enter the most decided protest, for the reason that philosophy cannot afford to surrender the moral discipline which is the natural inheritance of long ages of religious life, however imperfect that life may have been. Religion, to the savage as to the civilized man, is the type of his most general ideas expressed in the best language that he commands. Through the aid of that synthesis of facts which we call the science of sociology, we recognize in our ideas of God the lineal descendants of the childish notions of deity to be found in the unformed mind. But on the other hand we see in this development the natural progression of general ideas, the development of the impersonal in thought and feeling, which culminates in an ultimate generalization. Philosophy would merely develop or purify our conception of God, and our interest in a future life, making the one a di- vine principle, the other an unselfish solicitude for others. During this transformation of spirit, this amalgamation of one culture with another, we cannot afford to surrender the word which has served in all languages and all ages as the symbol of an ultimate generalization. HERBERT SPENCER. 289 In arguing that all worship springs from ancestor-worship, Mr. Spencer reminds us that Negroes, when suffering, go to the woods and cry for help to the spirits of their dead relatives, just as the Iranians in the Khorda-Avesta call upon the souls of their forefathers in prayer ; that the sacrifices of the ancient Egyptians, which were commemorated in the three festivals of the seasons, the twelve festivals of the month, and the twelve festivals of the half month, all in honor and propitiation of their dead, have their counterpart in the offerings which the Romans made to their Lares, on the calends, nones, and ides of every month ; that the Indian or Veddah asks the ghosts of his relatives for aid when he goes hunting, just as the Roman prayed to his Lares for a happy termination to a projected voyage ; and that the sanguinary Mexicans, Peruvians, Chibchas, Dahomans, Ashantis, and others who immolate victims at funerals, are but imitators of the Romans who offered up human sacrifices at tombs. It can be imagined with what terrible effect comparisons which bring such re- volting customs down to the immediate progenitors of our language and culture are used against us. By this study of religious evolution, beliefs which appear to us innocent, and even refined, on account of their famili- arity and associations, are unmasked and stand out in the hideous forms of savage life. Our very language is shown to be primitive, full of metaphors which lead inevitably to low orders of intelligence. Our puny generalizations, which appear so gorgeous to us dressed in the livery of heaven and hell and spiritual beings, are found to be but efforts of a childish imagination. This incompetence of thought and word naturally extends from the religious to the metaphysical sphere. A theology which is revolting for its inconsist- encies is given us for a philosophy, and the jargon of priests and rhapsodists is taken for the highest forms of human thought. The purity and simplicity of truth are profaned by these mummeries, these emotional drivellings, these ecstatic fantasies of the unformed life and mind, which are made to 2QO THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. assume among us the functions of divine light. So long as we look to dealers in mysteries and portents and revelations for our highest generalizations, we shall indeed live in a savage age. Language is the mind of society, and in its accuracy and integrity are involved the amenities and possibilities of life. The philosophic student of the future will look upon our age as one of insuperable logical difficulties ; he will read, with mingled pity and disdain, of men who applied the word God indifferently to a vague idea of human form and feelings possessed of universal power, to a trinity of still more human characteristics, or again, to a universal prin- ciple. He will not wonder at the misgovernment, the un- necessary suffering, the general immorality of our age, when he examines the indefiniteness of our ideas, the natural accompaniment of our chaotic speech. We look upon ages which had no differential calculus, no algebra, no developed arithmetic, as unable to obtain any definite ideas of obscure or involved phenomena. The stu- dent of the future will regard the speculative thought of our age in the same light. He will find, in this indefiniteness in the use of ultimate terms, implied immorality, as well as ignorance. What will even the children of the future think of the way we employ such terms as Infinite and Absolute, Space and Time, Matter and Force ? I read in the confes- sion of faith of an eminent American divine, recently, these words : " We believe in Christ as infinite within infinite limits"; which, being translated, means, We believe in unlimited limits, or in limits that are not limits ! This is like those learned theologians of the middle ages who reasoned about the ultimate difference between material and spiritual substances, or, still worse, of existences which transcend Space and Time. What can be more immoral in its influence than such confusion of ideas as this? The philosophy of Herbert Spencer can be charged with a full share of these untruths. The theory of perception which it promulgates is but a modern form of mysticism. HERBERT SPENCER. And yet in its errors it is fathered by men who hold the highest position in English thought. Not only in it3 gene- ral form but in the minutest particulars can Spencer's theory of perception be traced to the philosophy of John Stuart Mill, and this in turn to the long line of mysticism and skep- ticism that gave it birth. In the introduction to John Stuart Mill's " System of Logic" we find a frank statement of the difficulties of the problem of perception. Such candor in a writer inspires a wish to agree with him. In this spirit let us consider Mill's assertion that there are certain ideas in the mind which be- long to it, and are of a different nature from those ideas which are known as inferences. The first class of ideas Mill calls intuitive, and says the inferential ideas are drawn from this original stock of the mind, and without this primordial store of (intuitive) truth we could build up no inferences, and could have no knowledge. " With the original data, or ultimate premises of our knowledge," says Mill, "with their number or nature, the mode in which they are obtained, or the tests by which they may be distinguished, logic, in a direct way at least, has, in the sense in which I conceive the science, nothing to do. These questions are partly not a subject of science at all, partly that of a very different science. * * * Of the science, therefore, which expounds the operations of the human un- derstanding in the pursuit of truth, one essential part is the inquiry, What are the facts which are the objects of in- tuition or consciousness, and what are those which we merely infer? But this inquiry has never been considered a portion of logic. Its place is in another and a perfectly distinct de- partment of science, to which the name metaphysics more particularly belongs : that portion of mental philosophy which attempts to determine what part of the furniture of the mind belongs to it originally, and what part is constructed out of materials furnished to it from without. To this science appertain the great and much debated questions of the existence of matter ; the existence of spirit, and of a THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. distinction between it and matter; the reality of time and space, as things without the mind, and distinguishable from the objects which are said to exist in them. For in the present state of the discussion on these topics, it is almost universally allowed that the existence of matter or of spirit, of space or of time, is, in its nature, unsusceptible of being proved ; and that if any thing is known of them, it must be by immediate intuition. To the same science belong the inquiries into the nature of Conception, Perception, Memory, and Belief ; all of which are operations of the understanding in the pursuit of truth ; but with which, as phenomena of the mind or with the possibility which may or may not exist of analyzing any of them into simpler phenomena, the logician as such has no concern." 3 From the above it is clear that Mill thinks that there are certain principles of truth in the mind which are not suscep- tible of being examined by the reason ; that by some mys- terious and unknowable combination these principles are co-ordinated into certain primordial truths (called intuitive), and that these truths, which, be it observed, are independent of reason, form the major premise of every conclusion, the source of every fact. The theory of perception which we advocate as distin- guished from that of Mill and Spencer is simply that the ultimate fact is Motion ; that its aspects are Space and Time. It will be seen at a glance that the fact of Motion is ultimate, and that its aspects Space and Time are inferences drawn from this fact. To follow out the process of thought from these first inferences to the combinations of which all knowledge is built up, is to establish the nature of perception. The great simplicity of this undertaking is its greatest difficulty. Mill tells us that " to define is to select from among the properties of a thing those which shall be understood to be declared and designated by its name." A name is an abridged definition ; a definition is an enlarged name. The 1 Mill's " System of Logic," vol. I., pp. 6, 7. HERBERT SPENCER. 293 description, name, or definition, therefore, of any thing depends upon the functions, properties, or activities of the thing named. When we would define mind, we describe its properties, functions, or activities. The definition of the retentive part, or aspect, of mental action is condensed or abridged in the word memory ; the persistent and spontane- ous aspect of mind is called the will ; that aspect of the mental procedure which is a view of its reception of im- pressions is designated perception ; but there are no demar- cations in the activity of the mind which correspond to this classification of its different aspects that is to say, this enumeration of faculties is a superficial analysis or separation into parts of the fact of mind. To imagine that these intel- lectual faculties represent separate functional principles is the same order of belief as that there are certain primal intuitions, unknowable in their origin and nature, from which knowledge is made up ; for if the principles of thought are shrouded in impenetrable mysteries, what wonder that the faculties of the mind should assume the character of appa- ritions ? Apart from the limited and human sense in which the word knowledge is employed in this mysterious doctrine of the mind, there is an evident contradiction in saying that intelligence springs from the unintelligible, which is the initial error in the theory of perception offered alike by Mill and Spencer. This theory builds the whole fabric of knowl- edge upon principles which are said to be intuitional or subconscious, and at the same time unknowable. Every system of philosophy must offer an analysis of the nature of perception as the foundation of a Religious Synthesis. The. claims which Mr. Spencer can make to success in this particular have been carefully considered, his metaphysical beliefs have been followed out, and we are enabled to judge of the completeness of his ultimate analysis. We would now turn to the culminations of his philosophy. From the beginning of Spencer's system the promise is made to establish a scientific basis for morality, but before 294 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. the realization of this promise, which has been partially fulfilled in the " Data of Ethics," our author builds up a gigantic theory of society. The plan of this sociology is to show the interdepend- encies of organic and superorganic phenomena and to trace their combined effects to the common principle which he denominates the persistence of force. The subject of Ethics is then introduced, the object still being to show that mo- rality is relative, and that its laws are to be found in the hu- man faculties, the submission of the individual to the general mind. Nothing can be more profound than this theory. In the persistency with which Mr. Spencer has labored to establish it, from the articles he wrote when a young man, now republished under the title of " Social Statics," a con- tinuous thread of reasoning can be traced, a single purpose recognized. We have seen that the intellectual faculties are merely names for the different phases of intellectual activity. A great memory, a great reason, or a great perception, means a mind that has acquired special powers by special cir- cumstances. Balanced circumstances lead to balanced faculties ; special circumstances, to special faculties. The needs of war produce heroes; the needs of society pro- duce special casts of mind. The decay of Greek manhood produced Socrates ; the irreligion of the Jews and the suf- ferings of humanity produced the prophets and Christ. The anarchy of European thought in the sixteenth century pro- duced Bacon and Descartes, and the popular longing to unite pure reason with the love of God produced Spinoza. The need of vindicating reason against skepticism produced Kant and the German idealists, and the reaction of sentiment and common-sense produced the French and English psy- chologists. What, then, are faculties but the leaven of human character working out social developments ? As no deeper incentive to morality can be found than the symmetrical activity of our whole natures, 1 the balancing of 1 See argument on Morality, ch. xxiii. HERBERT SPENCER. 29$ human faculties which have their sources deep down in organic life, the principle of activity added to the fact of in- dividual life comes to us as the result of the most careful analysis of our existence. Every synthesis begins with this principle of universal activity and brings us to the facts of social life. What limit does this suggest to perception but the moving limits of personal existence ? Sociology teaches us that there is an aggregate human life and mind which springs from and is determined by the lives of individuals ; that the atmosphere of this life is lan- guage. The quality of language determines the quality of the general mind, and reflects its influences upon every individual. Thus the world at large has a direct interest in the meaning of words, and this interest is proportionate to the range of their significance. Metaphysics, therefore, is closely associated with the science of Sociology ; its object Is to familiarize the general mind with the meaning of ultimate terms. In the success of this science over the errors of agnosticism and idealism, morality is deeply con- cerned, and the future will wonder at our slowness in reach- ing so important a result. CHAPTER XIII. GEORGE HENRY LEWES. Belief in the Unknowable Its Influence upon the Study of Psychology. THE philosophic system of George Henry Lewes has the general title of " Problems of Life and Mind." The first two volumes are entitled " Foundations of a Creed "; the third deals with the problem of " Mind as a Function of the Organism "; and the last two are posthumous publications, one being a comprehensive treatise on the " Physical Basis of Mind," and the other a comparatively short review of the author's favorite subject, " The Study of Psychol- ogy." In the preface to the opening volume Lewes says : " In 1862 I began the investigation of the physiological mechanism of Feeling and Thought, and from that time forward have sought assistance in a wide range of research. Anatomy, Physiology, Pathology, Insanity, and the Science of Language, have supplied facts and suggestions to enlarge and direct my own meditations, and to confirm and correct the many valuable indications furnished by previous psy- chological investigators. * * * When I began to organize these materials into a book, I intended it to be only a series of essays treating certain problems of Life and Mind ; but out of this arose two results little contemplated. The first result was such a mutual illumination from the various prin- ciples arrived at separately, that I began to feel confident of having something like a clear vision of the fundamental inductions necessary to the constitution of Psychology ; hence, although I do not propose to write a complete trea- tise, I hope to establish a firm groundwork for future labors. The second result, which was independent of the first, arose 296 GEORGE HENRY LEWES. 297 thus : Finding the exposition obstructed by the existence of unsolved metaphysical problems, and by the too frequent employment of the metaphysical method, and knowing that there was no chance of general recognition of the scientific method and its inductions while the rival method was toler- ated, and the conceptions of Force, Cause, Matter, Mind, were vacillating and contradictory, I imagined that it would be practicable in an introductory chapter, not indeed to clear the path of these obstacles, but at least to give such precise indications of the principles adopted throughout the exposi- tion as would enable the reader to follow it untroubled by metaphysical difficulties." 1 Here, then, is the great meta- physical problem confronted at the very outset. In the beginning of the first chapter, we have this signifi- cant quotation from Mill : " England's thinkers are again beginning to see, what they had only temporarily forgotten, that the difficulties of Metaphysics lie at the root of all Sci- ence ; that those difficulties can be quieted only by being re- solved, and that until they are resolved, positively whenever possible, but at any rate negatively, we are never assured that any knowledge, even physical, stands on solid foun- dations." By this we are given in advance an idea of the direction of Lewes' thought : he is going to offer a negative, not a positive, solution of the Metaphysical problem ; he is going to acknowledge the " existence of an unknowable " (which, be it remembered, is a distinct contradiction in terms ; for to acknowledge an existence is to know it in some degree, and to know the unknowable in any degree is an absurdity). Notwithstanding this he is going to extend the known, the scope of definite knowledge, by means of a masterly physi- ological and psychological analysis, until it embraces the be- ginnings of organic life and shows a perfect interdependence between what are known as the physical and vital activities. His mind, however, is too sensitive to feel perfectly con- tented with this achievement ; he is still haunted with the 1 " Problems of Life and Mind," vol. I., Preface. 298 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. idea that there is something yet to be done to complete an ultimate analysis, to establish the divine unity ; and he expresses his unrest in these words : " Science itself is also in travail. Assuredly some mighty new birth is at hand. Solid as the ground appears, and fixed as are our present landmarks, we cannot but feel the strange tremors of subterranean agitation which must erelong be followed by upheavals disturbing those landmarks. Not only do we see Physics on the eve of a reconstruction through Molecular Dynamics, we also see Metaphysics strangely agitated, and showing symptoms of a reawakened life. After a long period of neglect and contempt, its problems are once more reasserting their claims. And whatever we may think of those claims, we have only to reflect on the important part played by Metaphysics in sustaining and developing religious conceptions, no less than in thwarting and misdirecting scientific conceptions, to feel assured that before Religion and Science can be reconciled by the reduc- tion of their principles to a common method, it will be necessary to transform Metaphysics or to stamp it out of existence. There is but this alternative. At present Meta- physics is an obstacle in our path : it must be crushed into dust and our chariot-wheels must pass over it ; or its forces of resistance must be converted into motive powers, and what is an obstacle become an impulse." This promised conversion of Metaphysics, as will afterward appear, is but partially effected ; the question is, whether, even as far as it goes, anything is accomplished by it. Lewes adopts the ingenious method of inventing another name for the science to which he attempts to attach all but the vital and reasonable part of Metaphysics, and thus effects for the old word Metaphysics a regeneration by freeing it from the superstitions which have so long been attached to it. 2 This 1 " Problems of Life and Mind," vol. I., p. 4. a " By way of preliminary, I will ask permission to coin a term that will clearly designate the aspect of Metaphysics which renders the inquiry objection- able to scientific thinkers, no less than to ordinary minds, because it implies a GEORGE HENRY LEWES. 299 new name suggested by Lewes is Metempirics or beyond experience. That this term means identically the same thing as metaphysics or beyond the physical is manifest. For what is the physical world to us but the world of sensible experiences ? And what is beyond the world of sensible* experiences but the world of logical, mental, ideal, or spiritual experiences ? Spiritual or ideal can mean nothing more than logical or mental, and this is precisely the field of meta- physics. The merit of Lewes' philosophy is therefore to be found in his physiological and psychological studies. He does not solve the metaphysical problem, but he furnishes us with many valuable materials to be employed in its solution. He leaves undefined the great ultimate terms which haunt the pages of every philosophy and hover in the background of every religion ; but he has performed the great work of eliminating from this group of ultimates one term which all writers up to him, not even excepting Herbert Spencer, have included among them, namely, consciousness. Those who study Lewes' system carefully will have no difficulty in un- derstanding the genesis of mind, and will never have occa- sion to refer its origin to the unknowable. They will also find abundant reason to drop the term Cause from the list of ultimate realities, as that term is clearly shown to be but one face of every fact or phenomenon, the other or opposite face being Effect. By this achievement Lewes be- queaths to us a clearly defined list of ultimate realities, namely, Space, Time, Matter, Force, and Motion. He removes all confusion between these ultimates and such other terms as Consciousness and Cause, which we find in- disregard of experience ; by isolating this aspect in a technical term we may rescue the other aspect which is acceptable to all. The word Metaphysics is a very old one, and in the course of its history has indicated many very different things. To the vulgar it now stands for whatever is speculative, subtle, ab- stract, remote from ordinary apprehension ; and the pursuit of its inquiries is secretly regarded as an eccentricity, or even a mild form of insanity. To the cultivated it sometimes means Scholastic Ontology, sometimes Psychology, pursued independently of Biology, and sometimes, though more rarely, the highest generalizations of Physics." "Problems of Life and Mind, "vol. I., p. 14. 300 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. eluded among the irreducible principles cited by other writers. The terms Consciousness and Cause, therefore, are affiliated with Knowledge, and the five ultimates supposed by Lewes to be irreducible principles, or " manifestations of 'the unknowable" are boldly and clearly isolated from all other terms. Of Matter and Force, however, we are told over and over again that the one is utterly indistinguishable from Space, and that the other must mean Motion, or, if it mean any thing less, it is Motion considered apart from its material or space aspect ; or simply Time. These assertions are far from being made in distinct terms, but that they are fair inferences from his reasonings upon these subjects the reader will have a full opportunity of judging. An idea of the persistent longing which Lewes evinces all through his work for the repose of a successful ultimate analysis can be gained from these words : " Speculative minds cannot resist the fascination of Metaphysics, even when forced to admit that its inquiries are hopeless. * * * No array of argument, no accumulation of contempt, no his- torical exhibition of the fruitlessness of its effort, has sufficed to extirpate the tendency toward metaphysical speculation. Although its doctrines have become a scoff (except among the valiant few), its method still survives, still prompts to renewed research, and still misleads some men of science. In vain history points to the unequivocal failure of twenty cen- turies : the metaphysician admits the fact, but appeals to his- tory in proof of the persistent passion which no failure can dismay ; and hence draws confidence in ultimate success. A cause which is vigorous after centuries of defeat is a cause baffled but not hopeless, beaten but not subdued. * * * Few researches can be conducted in any one line of inquiry with- out sooner or later abutting on some metaphysical problem, were it only that of Force, Matter, or Cause ; and since Sci- ence will not and Metaphysics can not solve it, the result is a patchwork of demonstration and speculation very pitiable to contemplate. Look where we will, unless we choose to over- look all that we do not understand, we are mostly confronted ' WNJ TY ^ GEORGE HENRY LEWES. 3OI with a meshwork of fact and fiction, observation curiously precise beside traditions painfully absurd, a compound of sunlight and mist." ' The insistence of Lewes upon the necessity of a double name for Metaphysics is clearly traceable to his belief in an unknowable. The fault in this is, that it confuses the idea of unexplored phenomena, or the unknown, with the fiction called the unknowable. Bearing in mind that he employs the word Metempirical to signify the unknowable, let us carefully examine the following : *' Every physical problem involves metempirical elements beside those which are empirical ; but Physics sets them aside, and, dealing only with the empirical, reaches con- clusions which are exact, within that sphere. No disturbance in the accuracy of calculation follows from the existence, out- side the calculation, of elements which are incalculable. The law of gravitation, for example, is exact, although its tran- scendental aspect namely, what gravitation is in itself, whether Attraction, Undulation, or Pressure is not merely left undetermined, but by the majority of physicists is not even sought. The law of Association of Ideas is equally ex- act, although not quantitatively expressible. The depend- ence of Sensation upon Stimulus is not less so, and has received a quantitative expression. 3 The laws of Causation may be formulated with equal precision. And exact knowl- edge of Force, Cause, Matter, ought to be attainable, in spite of their transcendental elements, by the one procedure of eliminating these, and operating solely on the empirical. Hence the conclusion : The scientific canon of excluding from calculation all incalculable data places Metaphysics on the same level with Physics." ; What are these metempirical elements which are said to be involved in every problem ? A problem is simply a compari- 1 " Problems of Life and Mind," vol. I., pp. 6-8. 2 The ratio of the increase of a sensation to the increase of its stimulus is that of a logarithm to its number. (Fechner, " Psychophysik," Bd. II., p. II, 1860.) * *' Problems of Life and Mind," vol. I., p. 54. 302 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. son of facts. A comparison of facts must be made with a view to arriving at other more obscure or involved facts. Now the ultimate fact is Motion, the last arrived at in every analysis, the first adopted in every synthesis. If by the in- calculable elements in every problem is meant Motion, or its aspects Space and Time, or Matter and Force, it is certainly incorrect to denominate them unknowable, for they are merely appearances of a principle of which knowledge is a consequence. It may be said that this word "metem- pirical " is used to denote an erroneous method of investiga- tion which has for its object impossibilities of perception. If so, why are metempirical elements said to be present in every proposition, or that there exist, outside of every calculation, elements which are " incalculable " ? The words incalculable and metempirical are used as equivalents, and here it is that the error slips in and appears plausible. Gravitation is said to have a " transcendental aspect " which is incalculable or unknowable ; but surely gravitation is simply a relation, a form of the ultimate relation, Motion. Here incalculable refers plainly to Motion, and as Lewes has not declared Motion to be the ultimate reality, in so many words, it is easy to see how he felt the need of a word to express this ultimate reality, and its unrecognized aspects, which form the burden of every metaphysical problem. He was therefore, in a measure, justified in trying to remove what he supposed to be the incalculable elements from metaphysics by consigning them to " met empirics" But what are we to say of the second illustration in our quotation, which declares that the quantitative expression of the law of Association of Ideas is incalculable ; and of the third, that the quantitative expression of the dependence of sensation on stimulus is incalculable? Is it not manifest that " incalculable " is here used in a different sense from " unknowable " ? For the association of ideas, and the relation between sensation and stimulus, are phenomena which are quite comprehensible, but not quantitatively expressible, because sufficiently exact explorations of mental phenomena GEORGE HENRY LEWES. 303 have not yet been made to enable us to express these subtle changes in units of space and time. The whole course of Lewes' subsequent reasoning is against a belief in any transcendental aspect of physiological or psychological phenomena. If, on the other hand, it is claimed that the transcendental aspect of gravitation spoken of simply means the unexplored remainder in problems of celestial dynamics, which are quite possible to know, but are as yet undiscov- ered ; then the metempirical element in each of the three illustrations would be of the same nature, namely, the un- known quantity which is the occasion of every problem, and can be identified with the fact of individual existence. For individual life is simply the movement of an organism, the assimilation of the unknown by the known. If metaphysics is an exalted name for an exalted aspect of this assimilation, what kind of assimilation is designated by the term metem- pirics? Is it the assimilation of the inassimilable, the per- ception of the imperceptible, or the thinking of the unthink- able? If Lewes' object in bringing into the world this new term was to caricature the idea of such a science, and thereby to eliminate the superstitious element from metaphysics, it would be an involved way of accomplishing a good result ; but when he says that every physical problem involves metempirical elements, in other words, when he uses the word metempirical to denote something in which he be- lieves, it throws the question into hopeless confusion, from which it can only be extricated by removing the direct cause, which is this very term metempirics. The above shows what insuperable difficulties attend any form of belief in the unknowable, whether it be called the "metempirical," the " transcendental," the "essence," or the " thing-in-itself." To illustrate this, we will select a passage from Lewes in which he completely frees himself from this superstition, and consequently, for the moment, becomes per- fectly clear and rational. In trying to show that the same methods of investigation should be pursued in both physical 304 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. science and metaphysics, he says: "The reproach, if it be a reproach, conveyed in the term ' ontological,' when applied to Metaphysics, is shared by Science. In both the search is after abstract Being, not after concrete individual fact. Rightly understood, there is truth in saying that a meta- physician may have a knowledge of Being as certain as the mathematician's knowledge of Magnitude, as the chem- ist's knowledge of Affinity, as the biologist's knowledge of Life, as the sociologist's knowledge of Society ; and this knowledge may be gained in the same way." 1 Again : in pointing out the irrationality of that species of ontology which seeks entities or absolute essences, he says : " A traditional perversion makes the essence of a thing to consist in the relations of that thing to something unknown, unknowable, rather than in its relations to a known or knowable i. e. assumes that the thing cannot be what it is to us and other known things, but must be something ' in itself,' unrelated, or having quite other relations to other un- knowable things. In this contempt of the actual in favor of the vaguely imagined possible, this neglect of reality in favor of a supposed deeper reality, this disregard of light in the search for a light behind the light, metaphysicians have been led to seek the ' thing-in-itself ' beyond the region of Experi- ence. * * * But if such questions can receive no answer, be- cause not put in answerable terms, how much more so the questions which avowedly travel quite beyond all range of experience, and ask, What is the thing in its relations to something unknown? To know a thing is to know its rela- tions ; it is its relations." a And yet, after making these clear and unmistakable distinctions between a rational and an irrational ontology, between a common-sense method of thought and a foolish one, after taking the trouble to invent a special name (metempirics) for the irrational method, in order to purify the conception of metaphysics, he deliber- ately returns to his idols by avowing that every physical 1 " Problems of Life and Mind," vol. I., p. 60. " Problems of Life and Mind," vol. I., pp. 58, 59. GEORGE HENRY LEWES. 305 problem involves metempirical elements besides those which are empirical. If he were to say that every physical prob- lem contained metaphysical elements as well as empirical ones, he would carry out the fine distinction he is endeavor- ing to make. Then the proposition would simply mean that there are involved in every possible question elements which are beyond the sphere of sensible experience, but are within the sphere of logical experience or perception. In other words, nothing can be unnatural to perception, as the prin- ciple of perception has for its aspects the Infinite and the Absolute, or Space and Time. But this would be far too much for Lewes to admit. Although he made a noble effort to throw off the contamination of the unknowable, the conception was too deeply rooted in his vocabulary and in his thought for the feat to be possible. For a man in the closing years of an active literary and scientific career, which had been largely employed in establishing the unknowable as a great philosophic tenet, a man who had formed the habit of reasoning continually in this direction, making the conception of the unknowable an accompaniment of every analysis, for such a man to throw off this habit would be equivalent to reforming his whole logical constitution. Had he begun earlier in life, or had he been less active in his reasoning by the old method, reform might have been possible. But he wrote the " Biographical History of Philosophy" in the interest of the unknowable; he de- voted an enormous amount of study to interpreting every known system of philosophy in this particular way ; and his very language, which, be it remembered, is a constitutional structure of the mind, was cast too firmly to be remodelled. Thus we find this accomplished and powerful thinker in- volved in the toils of a mistaken belief, and struggling vainly to free himself from the old entanglements. In the more tangible media of science, however, he rises superior to all difficulties and develops truths of the greatest importance. To further illustrate the belief of Lewes in the unknow- able, we quote from the chapter on the " Scientific Method in Metaphysics " : .306 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. " Kant asks : ' If Metaphysics is a science, how comes it that she cannot boast of the general and enduring approba- tion bestowed on other sciences ? If she is no science, how comes it that she wears this imposing aspect, and fascinates the human understanding with hopes inextinguishable yet never gratified ? We must either demonstrate the com- petency or incompetency ; for we cannot longer continue in our present uncertainty.' "The answers to these questions which Kant gave not having been satisfactory, a new attempt, under more favor- able conditions, is made in these pages. To render this at- tempt satisfactory, we must first clearly understand the con- ditions of metaphysical inquiry. The initial condition that of separating the insoluble from the soluble aspects of each problem would be accepted by all. But the question would everywhere arise : What is insoluble ? How is this ascertain- able ? There are problems which are recognized as insoluble because of their conditions. For example, it is impossible to extract the square root of a number which is not made by multiplication of any whole number or fraction by itself. To all eternity this must be impossible. Yet an approximation is possible which may be made near enough for any practical purpose. There are other problems, again, which do not admit of even approximative solutions. No one really tries to solve what he is already convinced is an insoluble prob- lem. But one man thinks the problem soluble which another pronounces not to be soluble. What, then, is our criterion? We say the metempirical elements must be thrown out of the construction. But what are the metempirical elements? " Here we find ourselves fronting the great psychological problems of the Limitations of Knowledge, and the Prin- ciples of Certitude. To settle these it will be necessary to examine the pretensions of the a priori school. Our first labor, then, will be to examine the principles of positive and speculative research, and then to show that the principles of metempirical research must either be unconditionally re- jected, or, if accepted, must be isolated from all depart- GEORGE HENRY LEWES. 30? ments of Knowledge and restricted solely to the Unknow- able." ' With regard to the impossibility of extracting the square root of a number that is not made by multiplying any whole number or fraction by itself, which is cited as an insoluble problem, I would submit that this is an impossibility only by definition ; numbers are entirely arbitrary constructions, and therefore their manipulations are matters of arbitrary defini- tion. The square root of a given number is simply another name for a number which, being added to itself as many times as it contains the units of which it is composed, will equal the given number. The half of four, the third of nine, the fourth of sixteen, meet these requirements, because the process which determines the square root of four, nine, and sixteen can be abbreviated by these divisions ; but it is clearly to be seen that the success of the process itself is the cause of the selection of these numbers as examples ; and the impossibility of the process is the cause of selecting num- bers which will not yield to it, as examples of the impos- sibility of extracting the square root of certain numbers. If an object weighs one hundred pounds, the impossibility of its weighing two hundred pounds is a matter of definitions ; it is the function of its weight. No question can be ration- ally stated that is insoluble, for every question implies con- ditions or relations of which its solubility is the result or function ; but by changing these conditions and holding on to the result it is very easy to create an imaginary incon- gruity which may, to a predisposed mind, suggest an unknow- able. We would most emphatically assert, however, that an incalculable calculation, an insoluble problem, imply a forced juxtaposition of symbols, an incongruity of relations ; and the impossibility which they suggest is the direct function of an initial error. The conception of such problems is of the same order as the inconceivable conceptions, the impercep- tible perceptions, the unknowable objects of thought, super- stitions which have grown out of the incorrect use of words; 1 " Problems of Life and Mind," vol. I., p. 79. 308 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. mythical conceptions which men have endeavored to clothe in the language of sense, producing the opposite of sense. This is the unknowable. If Lewes had not affirmed that there are metempirical elements in every problem, we should be encouraged to think that, by his assertion, " these elements must be thrown out of the construction " of problems, he was about to de- clare the unknowable a vain fiction, a self-destructive term. But we have only to read a few lines farther on to find that he is still dominated, in spite of all he can do, by this great infelicity. As he promises to deal further with the sub- ject in the realm of psychology, let us continue to watch the struggle he makes with facts. Following the foregoing metaphysical treatise, we find in the volume under consideration a set of so-called Rules of Philosophizing. These rules are fifteen in number, and form a sort of logical code full of 'merit. They are excellent suggestions, but the amount of training that would be needed to enable one to apply them could hardly be obtained with- out actually acquiring the knowledge to which they are intended to be a guide. Metaphysics, for instance, is the science of ultimate terms ; it deals with the meaning of those words which have the widest possible significance. To tell a student that "Any contradiction of fundamental experiences of sense or intuition is to be taken as evidence of some flaw either in the data or the calculation," * which is rule second, would be to give him excellent advice ; but to teach him how to apply this rule to the interpretation of (say) the word Matter, would necessitate his taking a course of study which would make him an expert judge of " flaws either in the data or the calculation " of any philosophical problem. To be more explicit, the surpassing difficulty in the application of the above rule would be to know in what a " contradiction of fundamental experiences of sense or intuition " consists. In our opinion, for instance, it is clear that the author of this rule fails to follow it in the interpre- 1 " Problems of Life and Mind," vol. I., p. 82. GEORGE HENRY LEWES. 309 tation of Matter and Space ; for is it not a " contradiction of fundamental experiences of sense or intuition " to say that Matter and Space are separately ultimate or irreducible facts; or, again, to postulate an unknowable object of thought. The author himself admits, somewhat naively, that " the ap- plication of this rule requires great tact and accurate knowl- edge " ; and the question very naturally arises whether the possession of this " tact and accurate knowledge " would not include that of the " rule for philosophizing." We doubt whether Lewes, if teaching philosophy, would begin with abstract rules. ' Considered as feats of abstract reasoning, these fifteen rules cannot but be admired ; but as it would be difficult to find two persons who would agree on the sig- nificance of the terms employed in them, they can hardly be considered as aids to the study of philosophy. In the treatise on Psychological Principles, which follows the Rules of Philosophizing, Lewes tells us that it would be premature to attempt a systematic treatise on Psychology, as there are important metaphysical and biological questions still open which it is essential first to have settled. In a word, Lewes, who at the time of this writing was perhaps one of the best-prepared men, if not the best, to deal with the science of Psychology, frankly admits that he lacks some of the most important materials for the undertaking. This is in contrast with some writers who have built up imposing and complicated systems of psychology in apparent inno- cence of the fundamental difficulty of the subject. It is, therefore, with renewed confidence and interest that we approach what Lewes calls a " sketch of the programme of Psychology." He begins with the now familiar assertion that Man is not simply an Animal Organism, he is also a unit in a Social Organism. Then comes a citation of the starting-point of psychology, namely, Consciousness. Psy- chology, we are told, occupies itself with the study of the 1 " The supreme importance of an education is directed toward the develop- ment of aptitudes by their effective exercise rather than by the inculcation of rules." Lewes, " Problems of Life and Mind," vol. I., p. 109. 310 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. factors of Consciousness. Consciousness is a fact beyond which the psychologist is not obliged to look. It is the fact from which he elaborates his science and for which he is not obliged to account. As the biologist accepts Life as an ultimate fact, or the physicist builds his science on the principle of Force, neither being required to explain what these initial facts of their respective sciences are ; as the mathematician does not con- cern himself with what " Quantity, Space, and Time are " ; so the psychologist is not obliged to tell us what Conscious- ness is. Here in the very beginning is that metaphysical question the settlement of which Lewes so keenly felt the need of ; and here we must disagree with him in his assertion that the psychologist is not called upon to explain what Consciousness really is. We can easily imagine a mathema- tician content to follow the relations of numbers and quan- tities without being able to explain whence these' principles spring ; we can imagine a physicist dealing with problems of the correlations of forces without feeling the necessity of knowing the universal principle which these forces declare ; we can even understand a biologist spending a lifetime in the study of the interdependencies of organic life without being able to tell how these activities which he witnesses in every organism are affiliated with the same activities which he sees in other directions relatively unorganized ; but we cannot imagine a psychologist prosecuting the study of the functions and structure of the mind without feeling the necessity of knowing what Consciousness is, without feeling powerless to proceed in the absence of a knowledge of the nature of Perception. I do not mean to infer that great progress in psychology is not possible without this knowledge, for great progress in this science has already been made ; but I deny that any psychologist can make himself clearly understood in the principles of his science without first comprehending the relation of mental to universal activity, without being able to affiliate the principle involved in intelligence with other known principles, the relation of knowledge to organic GEORGE HENRY LEWES. 311 life, and organic to universal life ; in a word, without solving, at the very outset of his exposition, the metaphysical prob- lem. How can a psychology be clearly understood which teaches that mind is a function of an organism, that the or- ganism is material, and still that matter is an ultimate fact ? If matter is an ultimate fact, what is the activity of matter which is called mind ? There can be but one ultimate fact, and it must be universal. If, on the contrary, activity, life, or motion, is acknowledged to be the ultimate fact, and matter subordinate to it, a phase or aspect of it, materialism van- ishes and life and mind become a living reality, an under- stood fact. With this simple theory the vexed question of Object and Subject is resolved. The relation called gravita- tion, suggesting activities which are infinite, those subtle chemical energies, the signatures of the still uncombined elements, the adjustments of the primitive organism to its environment, the evolution of sensibility, feeling, and thought, from these lower orders of activity, rises before us, an unbroken interdependence of cause and effect. Human intelligence, which is taxed to its utmost to comprehend the proportions of this truth, is recognized as an expression of individuality, of the moving limits of personal existence ; and a glimpse of the difference between the human and the divine, the anthropomorphic and the universal, is obtained. It will be interesting, therefore, to follow Lewes through his programme of Psychology, and to observe how he manages to meet the difficulties of his subject without the aid of that ultimate analysis so essential to an understanding of Mind. CHAPTER XIV. GEORGE HENRY LEWES (CONTINUED). The Principles of Psychology. WE now enter upon the most original and instructive portions of Lewes' philosophy. His deep study of the sen- sorium of animals and of man has enabled him to carry us dry-shod through that dismal swamp, the analysis of mind from its physical side. Timid and conventional thinkers have systematically avoided this route in their journeyings, they have looked at the map, heard of the difficulties and dangers of the way, and turned aside. On the whole, they are to be congratulated for their prudence ; although it can- not be denied that this prudence has led them to miss some of the deepest and most stirring truths of life. To explain the wonders of the intellect by a supernatural principle is convenient, but it is not, in the best sense, philo- sophical. This method may appear satisfying to our ideal nature, but it partakes more of sentiment than of thought; yet like many a sentiment, it has held in view exalted truths until the slow methods of science have reached and verified them. * The intellectual and moral life of man cannot be ex- plained by a biological analysis. The operations of the mind cannot be successfully described as simply the activities of a personal organism, for the meaning of the word organ- ism has to be vastly extended before it can account for the immeasurable difference between mere sentiency, and thought. The wonders of organic development, as the phrase is scientifically used, are utterly incapable of explain- ing a moral intuition, an intellectual conception, or a reli- 312 GEORGE HENRY LEWES. 313 gious sentiment. To fill in this break, however, in the chain of cause and effect by the interposition of a " supernatural principle " is only a makeshift ; it lacks all the dignity that belongs to careful thought. Although analysis is the instrument by which this logical discrepancy has been removed, it has also been the indirect cause of the delay in arriving at a rational solution of the problem of Mind. Impressions, or simple perceptions, are by their nature composite. In ascending a mountain, we measure the distance into steps, but we are at the same time building up a synthesis which we will call an ascension. When we have reached the summit, we view the journey as a single fact ; but it was effected by an analysis, and the synthesis was accomplished as the analysis progressed. Thus analysis and synthesis are interdependent processes. The analyst or scientist, disdainfully refusing to be beguiled with the synthetic splendors of the mind, has steadfastly devoted himself to the physical procedures which have made these splendors possible. He has surveyed the route while others have enjoyed the scenery. The scientist has known all along that these intellectual wonders have been reached through sequences with which, in less extended vistas, he is perfectly familiar. He has known all along that sentiency is the activity of an organism, and that thought has depended absolutely upon this foundation for all its achievements. But in his laudable endeavors to extend definite knowledge so that it might encompass the ideal, he has neglected an obscure and involved factor in mental or spiritual development. It is this factor which explains the difference between human and merely animal life. As we accomplish distances by measuring off progressions which are determined by our pow- ers of locomotion, so we apprehend situations by combining partial views, which are determined by our perceptive faculties. The more thorough the analysis, the more truth- ful is the conception formed, providing we are careful to replace in the synthetic view all the products of the analysis. In proportion to the number of neglected factors our concep- 314 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. tions are imperfect. We are no better off, therefore, in trusting those who insist upon viewing things in their entirety without studying the parts, than in trusting the analyst who clings to certain prominent factors and neglects others. The former class may supply us with more sym- metrical ideas, but they are largely only ideas instead of reali- ties. Life is not a dream-voyage. Our charts must be the result of actual soundings and observations ; and where they describe unexplored regions, they should be distinctly so marked. When we listen, therefore, to the panegyrics of idealists about such theories as " the miraculous inception of divine thought," we should remember that they are merely filling in the interstices in their education with generalities which they are unable to define. These generalities, beautiful as they may sound to the untrained ear, can never be made to take-the place of those substantial and hard-earned conceptions which can be obtained only by careful and patient investigation. To this class of careful thinkers Lewes pre-eminently belongs, and we may well listen to him when he insists upon a resolution of the great fact of consciousness into its factors or condi- tions, and upon the reunion of the isolated views thus ob- tained into a symmetrical whole. The biological factors of consciousness, we are reminded, afford but an incomplete explanation of Mind ; they supply us, however, with the fundamental conditions of its theory. These substructures of the intellect Lewes thus describes : " Theoretically taking the organism to pieces to understand its separate parts, we fall into the error of supposing that the organism is a mere assemblage of organs, like a machine which is put together by juxtaposition of different parts. But this is radically to misunderstand its essential nature and the uni- versal solidarity of its parts. The organism is not made, not put together, but evolved ; its parts are not juxtaposed, but differentiated ; its organs are groups of minor organ- isms, all sharing in a common life, i. e. all sharing in a com- mon substance constructed through a common process of GEORGE HENR Y LEWES. 315 simultaneous and continuous molecular composition and decomposition ; precisely as the great Social Organism is a group of societies, each of which is a group of families, all sharing in a common life, every family having at once its individual independence and its social dependence through connection with every other. In a machine, the parts are all different, and have mechanical significance only in relation to the whole. In an organism, the parts are all identical in fundamental characters and diverse only in their superadded differentiations : each has its independence, although all co- operate. The synthetical point of view, which should never drop out of sight, however the necessities of investigation may throw us upon analysis, is well expressed by Aristotle somewhere to the effect that all collective life depends on the separation of offices and the concurrence of efforts. In a vital organism, every force is the resultant of #//the forces ; it is a disturbance of equilibrium, and equilibrium is the equivalence of convergent forces. When we speak of Intel- ligence as a force which determines actions, we ought always to bear in mind that the efficacy of Intelligence depends on the organs which co-operate and are determined : it is not pure Thought which moves a muscle, neither is it the ab- straction Contractility, but the muscle which moves a limb." 1 This luminous exposition of the difference between mechanism and organism (a most important distinction in the study of the physiological basis of mind) is supplemented by an explanation of the metamorphosis which precedes physical assimilation, as a preparation to the understanding of the assimilation of ideas. 2 1 " Problems of Life and Mind," vol. I., pp. 103-105. * ' ' Between the reception of external materials and the assimilation of them by the tissues (plant or animal) there is always an intermediate stage passed through, the inorganic, unvitalized material becoming there transformed into organizable, vitalized material. * * * Until this special change has taken place, the inorganic material is not assimilable ; it must enter as a constituent of the bioplasm to form part of what Claude Bernard calls the Physiological Medium before it can become a constituent of the tissues. The supposition that plants are nourished directly by inorganic substances drawn from the soil and atmos- phere is now proved to be erroneous : the nutrition of plants takes place 316 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. The crisis of the argument then comes in these words: " That Life is Change, and that Consciousness is Change, has always been affirmed. We have only to add that the changes are serial, and convergent through a consensus deter- mined by essential community of structure, and we have char- acterized the speciality of organic change, demarcated Life and Mind from all inorganic change." 1 Movements not combined are /^organic. Serial and combined movements or activities are organic or vital. Now, rising above the difference between the most general or inorganic activities, and the special or organic activities known as vital, let us contemplate the difference between or- ganic and suflerorganic activities. Biology is the study of through processes similar to those in animals. The inorganic has in both to- pass through the organizable stage, and form proximate principles, before it can become organized into elements of tissue. * * * " Let us now pass from Life to Mind. The vital organism is evolved from the bioplasm, and we may now see how the psychical organism is evolved from what may be analogically called the psychoplasm. The bioplasm is character- ized by a continuous and simultaneous movement of molecular composition and decomposition ; and out of these arises the whole mechanism, which is also sus- tained and differentiated by them. If, instead of considering the whole vital organism, we consider solely its sensitive aspects, and confine ourselves to the Nervous System, we may represent the molecular movements of the bioplasm by the neural tremors of the psychoplasm ; these tremors are what I term neural units the raw material of Consciousness ; the several neural groups formed by these units represent the organized elements of tissues, the tissues, and the combination of tissues into organs, and of organs into apparatus. The movements of the bioplasm constitute Vitality ; the movements of the psycho- plasm constitute Sensibility. The forces of the cosmical medium which are transformed in the physiological build up the organic structure, which in the various stages of its evolution reacts according to its statical conditions, them- selves the results of preceding reactions. It is the same with what may be called the mental organism. Here also every phenomenon is the product of two factors, external and internal, impersonal and personal, objective and sub- jective. Viewing the internal factor solely in the light of Feeling, we may say that the sentient material out of which all the forms of Consciousness are evolved is the psychoplasm, incessantly fluctuating, incessantly renewed. Viewing this on the physiological side, it is the succession of neural tremors, variously combining into neural groups." " Problems of Life and Mind," voL I., pp. 107-109. 1 " Problems of Life and Mind," vol. I., p. in. GEORGE HENRY LEWES. 317 the history of organic life ; it analyzes the organism, both as a fact and as a gradual development ; it follows the sequences of growth from primitive organisms to man, and from the germ to the adult in each type. Its field, however, is the organism and its physical environment. The spiritual me- dium or surrounding of each organism is beyond the sphere of biology. Psychology is the science which investigates this higher or mental environment. The distinction between these two sciences, therefore, can be broadly expressed as follows : Biology studies the relations between the organism and its physical medium ; Psychology studies the relations between the organism and its mental medium, or the rela- tions between subject and object. The primary law of biology is : " Every vital phenomenon is the product of the two factors, the Organism and its Medium." And the primary law of psychology is, that " Every psychical (mental or spiritual) phenomenon is the product of the two factors, the Subject and the Object." These two sciences, therefore, are clearly but studies of different aspects of the single fact of personal existence. Lewes tells us that this law of psychology " replaces the old Dualism, in which Subject and Object were two independent and unallied existences, by a Monism, in which only one existence, under different forms, is conceived. The old con- ception was of Life in conflict with the external ; the new conception recognizes their identity, and founds this recogni- tion on the demonstrable fact that, far from the external forces tending to destroy Life (according to Bichat's view), they are the very materials out of which Life emerges, and by which it is sustained and developed." It would be impossible in so short a sketch to give any thing like an adequate idea of the factors of psychical life (or mind), for such an undertaking would constitute a com- plete psychology. It will not do, however, to shirk the responsibility of the metaphysical position which this work has assumed. Lewes declares a true or complete psychology 1 " Problems of Life and Mind," vol. I., p. 113. 31 8 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. " premature until there is something like a general agree- ment on many questions of fundamental importance, these being partly metaphysical and partly biological." Since we assume to have solved the metaphysical prob- lem, we should be able to clear up some of the psychologi- cal ambiguities of which Lewes complains. Does not the difference between the fundamental facts of physical and mental life, referred to above, give us the first opportunity to employ the ultimate analysis which constitutes the solution of the metaphysical problem ? When we consider that all psychical phenomena spring from a primary contrast, and the terms of that contrast are self and not-self, is not the fun- damental nature of Mind revealed by this initial contrast? When the banks of the southern Mississippi overflow, any object which remains above the water may become the common refuge of animals that are never found together under less trying circumstances. The timid hare or equally defenceless game, the dangerous snake and other reptiles, cling together to some stray raft, dismayed into peaceful and respectful behavior toward one another, and the traveller finds it difficult to realize that any thing could have devel- oped a dominant common nature in such opposite beings. Apparently the principles which are combined in the fact of personal existence, or perception, springing from the con- trast of subject and object, are as strange to one another as these frightened animals, and yet their unity of nature, the fact that they represent but one fact, is forced upon us when we view them in the plane of their widest significance. Under no provocation, short of an intellectual deluge, will the old-school metaphysician admit that Matter and Space are synonymous, and that they form but one term of a funda- mental contrast, of which Time is the other term ; or that, considered in an impersonal light, or objectively, this con- trast disappears in a single fact or principle. The ultimate difference between self and not-self, or subject and object, can only be found in the aspects of this single fact. If we persist in the analysis, even this difference disap- GEORGE HENRY LEWES. 319 pears, and we are obliged to confess that there is no ultimate or absolute difference between subject and object ; that they are but phases or aspects of the indivisible fact of universal existence, or Motion. Intelligence, or perception, however, demands an explana- tion : it insists upon knowing and understanding itself. This intelligence or consciousness is not the ultimate fact, but simply a relative fact; it is the function of individu- ality, and therefore springs from the contrast of one life with all life, or of subject with object. The difficult part of this theory to understand is, how we identify Time with subject and Space with object. The subject occupies space, and therefore has space-relationships ; and the object occu- pies time, and therefore has time-relationships. The idea of space is generated by marking, or attending to, abstract existences, or other existences, considered simultaneously (or apart from time). The idea of time is generated by con- sidering abstract serial existence, or existence apart from other existences (space). Now it is clear that the only existence that we can consider apart from other existences is our own. Thus we get an idea of how these primordial ideas of Time and Space, or Subject and Object, are formed. But it is only an idea. To form a distinct conception, we shall have to make a complete analysis of the phenomena of thought. In trying to form this idea, we have been employing symbols, or language, and this is the very factor the bearings of which are so involved that it presents us with the most complex problem of psychology. Language springs from our attempts to communicate images of the mind. The attempts of the child to speak, or still better, of the savage, point to this fact. Upon this subject Lewes says : " It is in Imagination that must be sought the first impulse toward Explanation ; and therefore all primitive explanations are so markedly imaginative. Images being the ideal forms of Sensation, the Logic of Images is the first stage of intellectual activity ; and is therefore predominant in the early history of individual- 320 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. and of nations. The first attempts to explain a phenomenon must be to combine the images of past sensations with the sensations now felt, so as to form a series. In the next stage, words, representative of abstractions, take the places both of images and objects. Thus the Logic of Signs (or language) replaces the Logic of Images, as the Logic of Images replaced the Logic of Sensation." If the first stages of intellectual activity are to be found in the " Logic of Images," and Language is the vehicle of these images, it is clear that thought and language are inter- dependent, and develop, or become more definite, together. But if this is the case, why is it that language has to reach an exceedingly high type of development before the cate- gories of thought, or the metaphysical problem, can be stated, as in Greece by Aristotle ; and a still higher development, before the ultimate reality can be announced or the problem solved ? And yet the aspects of this ultimate reality, name- ly, Space and Time, are said to be the primordial inference, the first comparison, from which all comparison, or thought, springs. The calculations and thoughts of a mind utterly ignorant of psychology or metaphysics are just as clearly traceable to this same beginning as those of a Spencer or a Lewes ; the difference being simply that the untrained mind is unconscious of the great unity or simplicity of thought. It is not necessary that we should understand the fundamental principles of a subject in order to act correctly in its sphere ; it is not necessary that we should perform a complete analysis of the mind in order to reason correctly within certain limits. The bank officer may know little or nothing of economics, and still pass upon credits successfully ; the priest or minister may know nothing of abstract ethics, and still judge matters of conduct correctly. In both of these cases intuitions or unconscious mental co-ordinations supply the place of the elaborate synthetic conceptions which result from much special study. The truths which analysis reveals, and which synthesis unites 1 " Problems of Life and Mind," vol. I., p. 155. GEORGE HENRY LEWES. $21 into a whole, are abridged and vaguely represented in the mind by intuitions. For instance, the whole science of economics consists in the study of the production and dis- tribution of wealth. The bank officer may be unable to trace the generality, wealth, to its original factors, land, labor, and capital ; but he knows the most enduring forms of wealth, and the kinds of men and institutions to entrust it to, and therefore arrives at the practice of economics without performing an analysis of its principles. The hori- zon of this practical knowledge is occupied by uninvestigated truths, which would easily yield to analysis and assimilate with the truths already possessed ; but in the absence of this investigation, intuitions, or vague ideas, take the place of definite conceptions. Again : the priest or minister may not be able to reduce morality to its prime factors, indi- vidual, social, and general existence ; but pure habits of mind have endowed him with excellent moral intuitions, enabling him to decide correctly in delicate questions of conduct. His mind may be as far from grasping the funda- mental principles of conduct as the magnetic needle is from being conscious of the currents of energy which determine its movements ; but the needle, in responding to these rela- tions in the simplest possible sense, perceives them, and its tiny adjustments, viewed from another standpoint, are ex- pressions of certain relations or truths.. So the pure-minded ecclesiast allows a healthful moral nature to perceive for him the most obscure moral truths. These unconscious percep- tions, called intuitions, are the natural or spontaneous induc- tions, the irresistible, unwilled activities of our nature from which Consciousness itself springs. Would the needle make a better compass if it were conscious ; would the clergyman be better fitted for his duties were he more profound ? Un- questionably, yes. Given the natural truths which each possesses, higher complexity would insure wider and more delicate adjustments ; more knowledge would insure more influence for good. Could we complicate the structure of a mariner's compass so that it would not be deflected by the 322 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. proximity of masses of metals, it would be more useful, more reliable, for the purposes of navigation. If we could convince the priest or minister that God is a principle, not a person, he would be made still purer by the conception of this divine unity ; his influence would be widened by giving to his teachings the power which comes from a greater command of facts. Thus we have gradually reviewed the whole field of psy- chology, the scope of language, and the nature of perception ; the difference between the real and the ideal, and the affilia- tion of the factors of mental with those of physical life, by the discovery of the social factor in psychical development. What is more manifest (if Time and Space are the first in- ferences, and at the same time the representatives of Subject and Object) than that the universal principle is only divisible into aspects, and that these aspects, or appearances, are dis- covered, or given, by the fact of individual life, the natural consequence of that isolation, or separation, from general ex- istence which is implied in a relative or personal existence ? What is more manifest than that thought is the complex activity of a sensorium which is a development of an organ- ism, and that language is the structural process of the social mind surrounding the individual mind ; the psychoplasm which bathes the tissues of the intellect and carries to them the common fund of ideas in an assimilable condi- tion? What is more manifest than that, as this intellec- tual medium called language is rendered more soluble, more interdependent in meaning, better co-ordinated by the perfection of higher generalities, it will bring a larger and larger number of minds into communication, and a greater and greater expanse of outlying truth within reach of each individual? When the highest generalization, the most powerful intel- lectual solvent, shall have permeated language and thought, the physical, mental, and moral development of the race will be simply a question of vitality, not of method, for the ways and means of this development will be universally under- stood. GEORGE HENRY LEWES. 323 It may be said that thus to bring the activities of a magnet and those of a man under the same category, to call the adjust- ments of the former to external influences a kind of percep- tion, and to view the manifestations of this adjustment as the expression of a fact or truth, is to give to the terms per- ception and expression a breadth of meaning which has no warrant in fact, and therefore proves nothing. This, however, is precisely the question in point. We name a fact of sentiency perception. Until we analyze perception we see no resemblance between it and facts immeasurably less complex, although of the same nature. The most successful and widely accepted analysis of psychical life discloses it to be the adjustments of an organism to its environment, or the adjustment of inner to outer activi- ties, which is also the best definition of physical life. The deepest biological studies teach us that the first principle, or condition, of the organism is a limiting membrane, some- thing to define, separate, or contrast it with the surroundings. The deepest psychological studies teach us that the first principle of psychical life, or perception, is a contrast, differ- ence, or demarcation, between two terms, the organism or subject, and its surroundings or object. " When it is said that animals, however intelligent, have no intellect, the meaning is that they have perceptions and judgments, but no conceptions, no general ideas, no sym- bols for logical operations. They are intelligent, for we see them guided to action by judgment; they adapt their actions by means of guiding sensations, and adapt things to their ends. Their mechanism is a sentient, intelligent mechanism. But they have not conception, or what we specially designate as Thought, i. e. that logical function which deals with generalities, ratios, symbols, as feeling deals with particulars and objects, a function sustained by and subservient to impersonal, social ends. Taking intelli- gence in general as the discrimination of means to ends, the guidance of the organism toward the satisfaction of its impulses, we particularize intelligence as a highly differen- 324 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. tiated mode of this function, namely, as the discrimination of symbols. * * * Intellect is impossible until animal devel- opment has reached the human social stage ; and it is at all periods the index of that development ; its operations are likewise carried on by means of symbols (Language) which represent real objects, and can at any time be translated into feelings. " It is obvious that the biological data can only resolve one half of the psychological problem, only present one of the foci of the ellipse, since by no derivation from the purely statical considerations of man's animal organism can we reach the higher dynamical products. Isolate man from the social state, and we have an animal ; set going his organism simply in relation to the Cosmos, without involv- ing any relations to other men, and we can get no intellect, no conscience. * * * The language of symbols [is] at once the cause and effect of civilization." ' Thus we see that mind cannot be explained without a constant recognition of the relations of organism and social medium. So important is the operation of the social medium in the fact of mind, that the state of education to which the race has attained at any given time is a determi- nant of the individual mind. The subject must be adjusted to this medium in order to act and to be reacted upon by it. The absurdity of supposing that any ape, for instance, could, under any normal circumstances, " construct a scien- tific theory, analyze a fact into its component factors, frame to himself a picture of the life led by his ancestors, or con- sciously regulate his conduct with a view to the welfare of remote descendants, is so glaring that we need not wonder at profoundly meditative minds having been led to reject with scorn the hypothesis which seeks for an explanation of human intelligence in the functions of the bodily organ- ism common to man and animals, and having had recourse to the hypothesis of a spiritual agent superadded to the organism." 1 " Problems of Life and Mind," vol. I., pp. 142, 143. GEORGE HENRY LEWES. 325 This spiritual hypothesis, however, is unscientific. It offers a name for a fact without explaining it without con- necting it with what we know. In a word, instead of solving the question of life and mind, it simply reiterates the old assertion that both of these facts are mysteries, giving us no clue to their hidden relations. It is these relations, however, that we are seeking, and in this reach of comparisons, the response of a magnetic needle to physical energies, the adjustment of a monad to its environment, the slow growth of sentiency in ascending organic types, the interposition of a social medium in the surroundings of the highest type, the development of this medium into a world of symbols radiating from a single fact, we have a serial development which expresses the interdependence, or mutual activity, of the subject and object, the organism and its environment. Mark, however, the vast difference between the signifi- cance of these two pairs of antithetical terms, subject and object, organism and environment. One is an expansion of the meaning of self and not-self into the two great aspects of the universe, Time and Space, the Eternal and the In- finite ; the other is the contrast of individual and general physical life. The distinction between the ideal and the real, or the mental and the physical, therefore, is seen to be but relative. The organism is great, not in itself, but in its connection, or joint existence, with the external world ; the subject derives its magnificent perspectives, not by drawing absolute boundary-lines between itself and the objective uni- verse, not by affirming that we are immaterial or spiritual, but from the fact that we are an expression of a universal principle. CHAPTER XV. GEORGE HENRY LEWES (CONTINUED). The Unity of the Whole Organism as a Factor of Mind Lewes' Definitions of Experience and Feeling. IN following Lewes' explanation of the difference between the metaphysical and the metempirical we have well-nigh exhausted the question of the categories of thought. By applying the solution of this problem to the principles of psy- chology as set forth by our author, we have obtained still more light upon the subject, and yet this metaphysical prob- lem continues to confront us with unabated vigor through- out the whole of the remaining portions of Lewes' philoso- phy, and the same power and skill continue to be fruitlessly exerted toward its determination. Such is the curse of agnosticism. Following psychological principles, we have in the same volume a long treatment of the " Limitations of Knowledge." One might naturally suppose that this subject would have been disposed of in a treatise on the Principles of Psychology ; for if the word knowledge is used in the limited sense of the product of mental activity (and it is in this sense alone that Lewes and Spencer employ the word), surely its limitations should be a part of the study of Psy- chology ; and the principle of the " Limitations of Knowl- edge " should be clearly laid down among psychological prin- ciples. But, on the contrary, the subject is begun with as much freshness as if nothing had been said in regard to it, or at least as if the problems which it suggests were entirely unsolved. In the light of the principle which this work would estab- lish, the question, What are the limitations of knowledge ? 326 GEORGE HENRY LEWES. 327 can hardly be considered as rational ; for Knowledge to us means the same thing as Life or Progress ; it is universal. The absence of limits (the infinite) is one of the appearances of this principle by which we apprehend it. The " Limita- tions of Knowledge," therefore, is an impossible subject to us. The solution of the metaphysical problem enables us to regard human knowledge as a phase of human life. We admit no limits to human life excepting individual limits, which are purely relative. The limits of human knowledge are to be found in the functions and structures of the human and the social organism. We do not admit, therefore, to the discussion of the " Limitations of Knowl- edge " such questions as the contradistinctions of Mind and Matter, or the meanings of Cause, Force, and Motion. The solution of these questions depends upon an under- standing of the meaning of ultimate principles, the knowl- edge that they express but a single fact and certain clearly denned aspects of this fact. Hence the best that Lewes can do with these questions is to push them aside with vague generalities whenever they interfere with his explanations, this he is compelled to do throughout the whole course of his philosophy. We have before us a closely reasoned essay, forming the greater part of the first volume of " Problems of Life and Mind." Containing as it certainly does more advanced and more clearly expressed views on the subject of human knowl- edge than perhaps any other work of the kind, this essay nevertheless bears a title which implies a contradiction in terms, and so creates the difficulty which it is the purpose of the author to remove. One of the best sentences to be found in this essay is, " The certainty of knowledge is not affected by its circum- scription." It is immediately followed by one still more suggestive, " The principle of relativity furnishes a crite- rion which is coextensive with the domain of intelligence." In these two sentences we have what is in effect the chal- lenge and the defeat of agnosticism, the utter discomfi- 328 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. ture of " The Unknowable "; but the author passes on, ap- parently unconscious of the significance of his own words; he passes on to endless repetitions of the same questions and the replies to them. In these sentences the question of Cer- titude, or ultimate Proof, is answered ; and yet the first hundred pages of the following volume of the same series (" Problems of Life and Mind ") are devoted to the discussion of the " Principles of Certitude " ; and even then the ques- tion is left undecided. In the above sentences we have two distinct assertions : the first is, that the circumscriptions of knowledge do not render knowledge itself less certain ; and the second, that the principle of relativity is coextensive with intelligence. The first simply affirms that human knowledge is subject to human conditions, and that this fact does not affect its integrity, or that knowledge, as we find it, is knowledge, and not illusion. The second assertion means that knowledge, or intelligence, has no absolute limits. For if the principle of relativity, or the ultimate relation, is coextensive with intelligence, and motion is the ultimate relation, the principle of intelligence is universal ; or, which is the same thing, there is no absolute distinction between Knowledge, Life, and Motion that is to say, the ideas which these words represent can be produced to a single logical focus. It follows from this that the prin- ciple of Relativity, or Motion, is the criterion of knowledge ; for a criterion is a fact by which other facts are measured, or compared. The ultimate fact must be the measure of all things, the criterion of knowledge. It may be objected that every generalization can be thus dissipated by reduction to the ultimate fact of motion. It is, however, this very admission which it is the aim of phi- losophy to obtain. As long as ultimate proofs are sought, they must be sought in the ultimate fact, for in the universal principle the proof and the fact merge in one. The prin- ciples of certitude, therefore, are to be found in the basis, or source, of all truth, the primordial fact ; and the principle of individual certitude, or, as Spencer denominates it, the Uni- GEORGE HENRY LEWES. 329 versal Postulate, is to be found in the rule that facts express themselves ; which is the simplest way of saying that we be- lieve things when we are unable to disbelieve them ; ultimate proof, or " the universal postulate, consists in the inconceiva- bleness of the negation of a proposition." Human perception is not a condition of ultimate truth, but a product of it. We appreciate the universe through its motions, or activities ; the principle of intelligence is there- fore indistinguishable from universal activity. Isolated or individual facts are but the function of individual existence. The quality, or certitude, of an individual fact is but another name for the existence of which the fact is an expression. The idea of quality can be traced directly to the fact of personal existence, disclosing the source of all ethical concep- tions ; and the companion idea of quantity can be identified with the fact of general existence ; thus giving us the remote counterparts of subject and object, i. e. time and space, the two great aspects of life. Lewes, as will be seen from the following, freely acknowl- edged the disadvantage he was under in not having deter- mined the relation of subject and object. This occurs in the essay on the " Limitations of Knowledge " : " Metaphysics, in addition to its own obscurities, is over- shadowed by the uncertainties hovering around its data. We cannot, for instance, accept Force as the cause of Motion unless Cause and Motion have already been clearly defined ; and they are as obscure as the Force they are employed to render intelligible. We cannot stir a step in the exposition of the relation of Object and Subject without presupposing to be already settled fundamental points of Psychology which are still under discussion. No explanation can be given of Matter which does not involve a conception of Force. Thus the interconnections which are potent aids in physical inquiry are so many obstacles in metaphysical re- search." In passing on to the further consideration of this essay, 1 " Problems of Life and Mind," vol. I., p. 188. 330 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. it would be well to mark the clear explanation of the word Experience which Lewes offers, as it is so important in discussions concerning the nature of mind : " The main question must remain nebulous so long as we are without a precise definition of Experience. The term is very variously and very laxly used. I have defined it * the Registration of Feeling/ And what is Feeling ? It is the reaction of the sentient Organism under stimulus. Observe, it is not the reaction of an organ, but of the Organ- ism, a most important distinction, and rarely recognized. This reaction is a resultant of two factors, one factor being the Organism and the other being the Stimulus. We are not to accept every response of an organ as a feeling; nor every feeling as an experience. The secretion of a gland is a response physiologically similar to the response of the eye or ear ; but it is not a feeling, although entering as an ele- ment into the mass of Systemic Sensation. Nor will the response of a sensory organ, even when a feeling (through its combination with other sentient responses), be an experi- ence, unless it be registered in a modification of structure, and thus be revivable, because a statical condition is requisite for a dynamical manifestation. Rigorously speaking, of course there is no body that can be acted on without being modified : every sunbeam that beats against the wall alters the structure of that wall ; every breath of air that cools the brow alters the state of the organism. But such minute alterations are inappreciable for the most part by any means in our possession, and are not here taken into account, be- cause, being annulled by subsequent alterations, they do not become registered in the structure. We see many sights, read many books, hear many wise remarks ; but, although each of these has insensibly affected us, changed our mental structures, so that 'we are a part of all that we have met/ yet the registered result, the residuum, has perhaps been very small. While, therefore, no excitation of Feeling is really without some corresponding modification of Structure, it is only the excitations which produce permanent modifi- GEORGE HENRY LEWES. 331 cations that can be included under Experience. A feeling passed away, and incapable of revival, would never be called an experience by any strict writer. But the feelings regis- tered are psycho-statical elements, so that henceforward when the Organism is stimulated it must react along these lines, and the product will be a feeling more or less resem- bling the feeling formerly excited." l * * * The value of Lewes' study of Mind is not to be lightly estimated. His command of the minutest details of the re- sults of introspection is wonderful. He seems to have sum- moned all his resources to the solution of the problem of Mind, and to have fairly overridden the enormous obstacle of an entangled metaphysical vocabulary. Thus throughout the succeeding " Problems," although great space is given to unsuccessful discussions of metaphysics, the theme of Life and Mind is developed with an accuracy and thoroughness which places the science of psychology upon a firm footing. The carelessness observed in the use of the word mind, even among the ostensibly learned, is thus dwelt upon : " Mind is commonly spoken of in oblivion of the fact that it is an abstract term expressing the sum of mental phe- nomena (with or without an unexplored remainder, according to the point of view) ; as an abstraction, it comes to be re- garded in the light of an entity, or separate source of the phenomena which constitute it. A thought, which as a prod- uct is simply an embodied process, comes to be regarded in the light of something distinct from the process ; and thus two aspects of one and the same phenomenon are held to be two distinct phenomena. Because we abstract the material of an object from its form, considering each apart, we get into the habit of treating form as if it were in reality sepa- rable from material. By a similar illusion we come to regard the process (of thinking) apart from the product (thought), and, generalizing the process, we call it Mind, or Intellect, which then means no longer the mental phenomena con- densed into a term, but the source of these phenomena. * * * 1 " Problems of Life and Mind," vol. I., pp. 193, 195. 332 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. It is reflection and experiment which convince us that the air is a material object capable of being weighed and meas- ured. It is reflection and experiment which convince us that Thought is an embodied process, which has its con- ditions in the history of the race no less than in that of the individual." ' With this clear definition of Mind, let us revert to the question of Experience. The following lines by George Eliot are a poetical expres- sion of the great psychological truth, that the experiences of the race as well as those of the individual become embodied in modifying the mental structure : " What ! shall the trick of nostrils and of lips Descend through generations, and the soul, That moves within our frame like God in worlds, Imprint no record, leave no documents Of her great history ? Shall men bequeath The fancies of their palates to their sons, And shall the shudder of restraining awe, The slow-wept tears of contrite memory, Faith's prayerful labor, and the food divine Of fasts ecstatic, shall these pass away Like wind upon the waters tracklessly ? " Shall the physical propensities be faithfully recorded and transmitted in the physical structure, and shall all the emotions and thoughts of life fail to modify and shape the mental or nervous structure? Nothing can be more radically opposed to generally ac- cepted teachings than Lewes' explanation of the interde- pendence of physical and mental activities. In the analysis of the terms feelings, thoughts, and actions given in the previous review, the artificial nature of the distinctions between the different orders of subjective activity was pointed out. So fixed, however, has become the idea that mind means something wholly separate from body, that too much emphasis cannot be laid upon facts which explain this error. In modern methods of teaching, every thing is 1 " Problems of Life and Mind," vol. I., pp. 199, 202. GEORGE HENRY LEWES. 333 prepared for the student of physiology so that he will have no difficulty in becoming acquainted with the wonders and obscurities of the sensorium. The study of the physical activities is carefully demarcated from that of the mind ; this division is more than analytical, for the distinctions are made to appear ultimate ; they are never removed so as to afford a synthetic view of the whole subject. The cerebral hemispheres are believed to be the seat of combination for all the senses. In them sensations are said to be transformed into thoughts, emotions into sentiments. Lewes severely criticises this assumption of exclusive func- tions of the brain : " The cerebral hemispheres," he says, " considered as organs, are similar in structure and properties to the other nerve-centres ; the laws of sensibility are common to both ; [and] the processes are alike in both ; in a word, the Brain is only one organ [a supremely important organ !] in a complex of organs, whose united activities are necessary for the phe- nomena called mental. * * * The assignment of even Think- ing to the cerebral hemispheres is purely hypothetical. Whatever may be the evidence on which it rests, it must still be acknowledged to be an hypothesis awaiting verifica- tion. This may seem incredible to some readers, accustomed to expositions which do not suggest a doubt, expositions where the course of an impression is described from the sen- sitive surface along the sensory nerve to its ganglion, from thence to a particular spot in the Optic Thalamus [where the impression is said to become a sensation], from that spot to cells in the upper layer of the cerebral convolutions [where the sensation becomes an idea], from thence downward to a lower layer of cells [where the idea is changed into a volitional impulse], and from thence to the motor-ganglia in the spinal cord, where it is reflected on the motor-nerves and muscles. " Nothing is wanting to the precision of this description. Every thing is wanting to its proof. The reader might sup- pose that the course had been followed step by step, at least, 334 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. as the trajectory of a cannon-ball or the path of a planet is followed ; and that where actual observation is at fault, cal- culation is ready to fill up the gap. Yet what is the fact ? It is that not a single step of this involved process has ever been observed ; the description is imaginary from beginning to end." l Lewes goes on to explain that although the imagination has had inductions to work on in constructing these theories, all that the evidence vouches for is, that the integrity of the nervous system is necessary for the manifestation of its mental phenomena. In the volume entitled " The Physical Basis of Mind " it is abundantly shown that sensations, emotions, volitions, and even instincts, may be manifested after the brain of an animal has been removed. Hence the assertion made by so many physiologists, that the brain is the exclusive organ of the mind, or intelligence, or the Sensorium, or place of feeling, cannot be sustained. Now when we reflect on the great disturbance to the gen- eral mechanism which must result from such an operation as removing the brain, and how easily a comparatively slight disturbance of a mechanism will abolish many of its manifes- tations, we see decisive proof that the brain can only be one factor however important in the production of mental manifestations. Thus, notwithstanding the endless proofs that Mind means nothing more than an ideal separation of a certain view of in- dividual life from the sum of individual existence, the analysis by which our conceptions of physical and mental phenomena are built up is made of itself an immovable fact, whereas it is but a method of mental procedure, and should be borne in mind as such. The great fact that unconscious states play by far the greater part in mental life forces the conviction that every activity of the body is a more or less remote factor in consciousness. The familiar instances of mental aberration directly traceable to physical disturbances, the frequent occur- 1 " Problems of Life and Mind," 3d series, p. 65. GEORGE HENRY LEWES. 335 rence of different degrees of moral degeneration resulting from different kinds of disease, are only prominent instances among the great mass of personal experiences which teach us that the operations of the mind are dependent from moment to moment upon physical conditions. Nothing, however, short of a close study of the sensoriunv from the most intelligent standpoint, can reveal the fact that thought, although the function of vastly more complex con- ditions than those of feeling, contains no ultimate principle which is not expressed in the simplest forms of life, and that there is no organ or tissue in the human body which has not a voice a direct influence in its mental and moral determinations. The brain therefore is not the sole organ of the mind, but only a very important part of the sensorium, and it is need- less to say that notwithstanding its vast importance in intel- lectual phenomena the co-operation of the rest of the nervous system, and indeed of the whole physical system, is at least equally essential to the activity known as thought. Hence we must no longer " isolate the cerebrum from the rest of the nervous system, assigning it as the exclusive seat of sensation, nor suppose that it has laws of grouping which. are not at work in the other centres. * * * The soul is a history, and its activities the products of that history. Each mental state is a state of the whole Sensorium ; one stroke sets the whole vibrating." ' The Sensorium, in the broadest sense, is the whole living organism. All attempts to localize the part of the organism which reacts upon a stimulus are vain, so interdependent are all parts of all organisms. Although nerve fibrils, fibres, and cells, forming in different combinations, nerves, and ganglia,, are easily distinguished, the nervous system has no exact demarcations from the other tissues. It is impossible to say exactly where the nerve ceases and the muscle begins, so- insensible are the structural gradations in the connection. The functions of the nervous system are even less sus- 1 " Problems of Life and Mind," 3d series, pp. 69, 71, 102. 336 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. ceptible of a positive separation from those of the rest of the organism. " The method of composition remains the same through- out the entire fabric of Mind, from the formation of its simplest feelings up to the formation of those immense and complex aggregates of feelings which characterize its highest developments." The Sensorium, from a functional point of view, can be described in general terms as that part of the organism which is capable of the greatest molecular activity. This idea becomes irresistible when we study the development of nervous systems from their rudimentary forms in the sim- plest types of animal life to higher grades of complexity. Reflex action, or the isolation of the nervous arc from the nervous system, considering the reflex act apart from its preceding and succeeding states, is, therefore, but an ana- lytical distinction of organic activity. The discovery that the co-ordination of movements in the extremities and other parts of the body can take place after the removal of the brain, in certain animals, does not prove that were the brain present it would not take part in some degree in the move- ments. The central fact that " no single organ has a func- tion at all when isolated from the organism," differently expressed, is, that no activity can be separated (otherwise than ideally) from the complex of activities known as indi- vidual life. " The brain is simply one element in a complex mechan- ism, each element of which is a component of the Senso- rium, or Sentient Ego. We may consider the several elements as forming a plexus of sensibilities, the solidarity of which is such that while each may separately be stimu- lated in a particular way, no one of them can be active with- out involving the activity of all the others. * * * When, therefore, we reduce the abstract term Mind to its concretes, namely, states of the sentient mechanism, the ' power of the Mind ' simply means the stimulative and regulative processes which ensue on sentient excitation. 1 Herbert Spencer : " Principles of Psychology," vol. I., p. 184. GEORGE HENRY LEWES. 337 " We may now formulate a conclusion : Sensibility is the special property of the nervous tissue. Every bit of that tissue is sensitive in so far that it is capable of entering as a sensible component into a group, the resultant of which is a feeling i. e. a change in the state of the sentient organism. The Sensorium is the wtwle which reacts on the stimulation of any particular portion of that whole" There is no doubt, therefore, that the aversion so generally manifested toward the proposition, that all intellectual or spiritual activities have mechanical principles, is simply the result of a cramped and inadequate idea of the scope of those laws or influences known as mechanical. The most devout person would not object to the assertion that all the activities of nature, from the evolutions of the heavenly bodies to the life of microscopic plants and ani- mals, are guided by the hand of God, and that this same guidance is manifested in every human thought and feeling. And yet these words, translated into more exact terms, simply mean that the universal principle known as Motion is the ultimate fact in all objective and subjective life, uniting, in a single system of interdependent activities, the body and the mind, or nature and consciousness. If any other point or principle than that of general exist- ence, and through it personal existence, be selected as the focus of thought, our logical perspectives become confused, and no effort can readjust them. It is in the failure to make this adjustment of the perspectives of Knowledge, and to thereby harmonize the principles which we call Knowledge, Life, and Progress, that we have the failures of philosophy. Thus it is easy to see how Lewes fixed upon feeling as the ultimate fact of our existence, for each individual can only appreciate general existence through the medium of the activities of his own life. We have already seen, in one of the psychological analyses of the preceding review, that feeling is a name which, in its broadest meaning, represents all internal changes ; or, what 1 " Problems of Life and Mind," 3d series, pp. 77, 82. 338 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. is the same thing, the subjective side of life. To sensible experience is traced the origin of every thought ; thus the fact of personal existence is naturally in the line of our view of general existence. The fact that Lewes did not perform an ultimate analysis must explain to us the repetitions which we find in his works. But this we find in all philosophy. It is these repetitions which make philosophy so dull and un- interesting to the majority of readers. . In Lewes, however, the repetitions are merely repeated efforts, instituted from different starting-points, to reach a common goal of thought, and the union of these lines of investigation in a single point can only be made by a bold and independent inference from what he has written. The whole purpose of his Problems entitled the " Limita- tions of Knowledge," the " Principles of Certitude," and " From the Known to the Unknown," is to establish Feeling as the ultimate fact of life. Thus the scope of language and the nature of perception are revealed by the genesis of metaphor. Language and perception are purely synthetic. If we would retrace the course of their development to a first cause or ultimate prin- ciple, both become dissipated by the ideal analysis (for all analysis is an art, or an ideal procedure), and we come upon the logical or potential source of all things in God, Motion, or Life. Is it not clear that every perception and every thought must be less than this great fact, must be but a limited expression of it, the natural function of our indi- viduality ? When Lewes, therefore, affirms that Feeling is all in all to us, he simply assigns to humanity the middle term be- tween thought and the lowest forms of sentiency, and ex- tends its meaning in both directions to include all phases of life, from the simplest organic to the highest psychical ex- istence. From the objective side of feeling, which is action, he might have carried on the generalization until it became universal. That Lewes expresses the above ideas as clearly as it is GEORGE HENRY LEWES. 339 possible to express them without employing the instrument of an ultimate analysis, can be seen from his argument on the " Principles of Certitude," where we have the unknow- able practically rejected in favor of the unknown. ' ' I have repeatedly insisted on the memorable fact that Science is no transcript of Reality, but an ideal construction framed out of the analysis of the complex phenomena given synthetically in Feeling, and expressed in abstractions. In all analysis there is abstraction, which rejects much more than is expressed ; this rejected remainder may in turn be analyzed, but at each step there is an unexplored remainder. As, in the speculation of Laplace, there are dark stars scattered through space, but hidden from observation because they are dark ; so in every phenomenon there are numberless factors at work which are hidden from observation, and only speculatively postulated. Sometimes these specu- lative inferences, which always have some basis in observation or analogy, sug- gest the means of objective verification. Thus Newton inferred that bodies at the earth's surface gravitated toward each other ; it was an inference from analogy, but was then beyond experimental proof. 1 It has since been experi- mentally verified, and thus exhibited, not only as an ideal truth, but one having real application. " It is requisite to bear in mind that no general statement can be real, no ideal truth be a transcript of the actual order in its real complexity. ' Until we know thoroughly the nature of matter, and the forces which produce its motions, it will be utterly impossible to submit to mathematical reasoning the exact con- ditions of any physical question,' and even then it will only be mathematical relations which will be formulated. The approximate solutions which are reached ' are obtained by a species of abstraction, or rather limitation of the data,' and thus ' the infinite series of forces really acting may be left out of con- sideration ; so that the mathematical investigation deals with a finite (and gen- erally small) number of forces, instead of a practically infinite number.' a " If, then, Science is, in its nature, an ideal construction, and its truths are only symbols which approximate to realities, there is an internal necessity of movement in scientific thought which transforms existing theories according to ever-widening experience. We can never reach the finality of Existence, for we are always having fresh experiences, and fresh theories to express them. "We also need hypotheses to supplement the deficiencies of observation ; and that hypothesis is the best which introduces most congruity among our ascer- tained truths. Yet throughout this shifting of the limits there is a constant principle of Certitude, and the truth of yesterday is not proved false because it is included in the wider truth of to-day : the two truths express two limits of Experience. " In conclusion, we may say that various theories are ideal representations of the External Order, and are severally true, in so far as the import of their terms. 1 Newton : " Principia," III., Prop. VII.. Corol. I. * Thomson and Tait : " Natural Philosophy," vol. I., p. 337. 340 , THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. includes no more than has been verified by the reduction of Inference to Intui- tion or Sensation ; severally false, in so far as their terms include what is in- consistent with such verified import ; and severally dotibtful, in so far as the terms include what has not been thus verified. To express it in a more abstract phrase : Truth is the equivalence of the terms of a proposition ; and the equiva- lence is tested by the reduction of the terms to an identical proposition" J An identical proposition is only another name for the merging of difference in identity, the aspects of motion in the fact of motion, the subjective and the objective in the principle of life. Thus we see that the vexed question of the principles of certitude can alone be solved by an ultimate analysis, that nothing short of the reduction of the categories of thought to a single principle will remove its difficulties. Mr. Spencer says, the deepest test of truth is negative, i. e. ultimate proof to us is our ina- bility to believe a proposition untrue, or our inability to disbelieve the truth of a proposition. What does this mean but that truth itself is relative, and that our apprecia- tions of relative truths are but adjustments, more or less ex- tended, of individual to general existence ? The criterion or measure of these adjustments is the fact of equality, the balancing of forces, the establishment of equivalences ; doubt disappears when this balance is reached. Thus our test of truth is negative only in the sense that it is not absolute, for conviction is the result of conditions, the ad- justment of internal and external forces. Truth, then, is the equivalence of the terms of a proposition, the meeting of the individual with the general mind through the medium of language. What room is there in this definition of certi- tude for the unknowable ? Of what terms, of what proposi- tion, is the unknowable the equivalence ? The unknowable is not the unexplored remainder, for that is merely the out- lying region of experience, the background of fact, from which each apprehended truth stands out in relief. The unexplored remainder is the unknown, the unassimilated field of truth. The. unknown, therefore, is related to the 1 " Problems of Life and Mind," vol. II., p. 77. GEORGE HENRY LEWES. 341 known, its influence is felt in the equilibrium, the balance of forces, which we call conviction. The unknowable has no influence in truth ; it has no voice in any proposition ; it is a term in no equivalence ; it has no existence in fact. Who can doubt that Lewes repudiates the unknowable after reading his criticism of Spencer's theory of certitude ? " I do not," says he, " quite go along with Mr. Spencer when he argues for the necessity of some unproved truth, as a fundamental postulate ; on the contrary, it seems to me that every proved truth is ultimate, requires no foundation, admits of none, though it may receive a logical justification by being thrown into the form of an identical proposition. The finality is Feeling, and a truth of Feeling needs no external support. The same is to be said when the truth of Feeling is expressed in Signs. Mr. Spencer's demand for some unattainable depth to be postulated, but not plumb- lined, may be compared with Hegel's position that Truth is always infinite, and cannot be expressed in finite terms. But leaving this and one or two minor points out of consid- eration, I think his arguments are conclusive, and only prefer the proposed formula of Equivalence because it is positive and unambiguous." Hence Lewes sees a resemblance be- tween Mr. Spencer's belief in the unknowable and the skep- ticism of Hegel, the want of faith in the integrity of human knowledge. To say that truth is infinite and cannot be expressed in finite terms, is the same thing as saying that knowledge springs from the unknowable, that truth or certi- tude springs from an unattainable fact, or as arguing that mathematical infinity cannot be expressed or discussed in finite terms. This introduces, unnecessarily, the element of mystery into our theory of consciousness, rendering vague and uncertain what should be the simplest and most definite of all solutions. Lewes says that " all knowledge begins with the discern- ment of resemblances and differences, it is necessarily polar, resemblance being impossible except on a background of 342 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. difference, and difference also impossible except on a back- ground of resemblance. While knowledge begins here, it ends with equations. What are equations ? The resem- blances abstracted from all accompanying differences, and reduced to the identity of equivalence." 1 What is this postulate of Nature's uniformity but the conception of Motion as the ultimate reality ? All the scholastic principles of logic, the logical principles expounded by Mill and Bain (i. e. the Uniformity of Nature), the Uni- versal Postulate of Spencer, the principles of Identity and Equivalence of Lewes, lead us to the same fact, compel the same conclusion. Our lives consist of the difference between subject and object, and their quality and extent are elaborations of this difference. Now we enter upon the great question of the nature of Matter. The philosophic literature of our age teems with discussions on this subject, as though it were our chief logical duty to come to an agreement about the nature of the statical aspect of the universe. Why the dynamical aspect should receive less attention is not clear, unless it is that men have given up trying to define Force and have taken up Matter for a change. The dynamical aspect of the universe can best be symbolized by the conception of Time. The moment we add the statical aspect, or space, to time, motion springs into thought. The chief wonder concerning Lewes' philosophy is, that he could have been so explicit with regard to the nature of matter and force, declaring them to be but phases or aspects of motion, and yet that he should never have hit upon the idea of identifying space with matter, and time with force, thus bringing all these disputed terms into interdependence and harmony. This wonder increases as we read such lumi- nous definitions of Motion as this : " Here arises a complication which will beset the whole discussion unless we form distinct ideas of the separation of Matter and Force as a purely analytical artifice. The two 1 *' Problems of Life and Mind," vol. II., pp. 79, 81, 83. GEORGE HENRY LEWES. 343 abstractions are but two aspects of the same thing ; a separa- tion rendered inevitable by the polarity of Experience, which everywhere presents Existence under passive and active as- pects. Force is not something superadded to Matter, it is Reals viewed in their dynamic aspect ; Matter is not some- thing different from Force, but Reals viewed in their statical or passive aspect : either is unthinkable without the other. Force is immanent in Matter, and Matter is immanent in Force. The schoolmen called Matter potentia passiva, and Force virtus activa. Logically distinguished, they require to be considered apart ; and throughout the present problem we shall strive to keep up this separation ; it cannot be thor- oughly accomplished, but we shall endeavor to eliminate Force, as the geometer eliminates every thing but Exten- sion." * Here Lewes clearly recognizes the ultimate fact of Motion, the union of the dynamical and the statical aspects of the uni- verse, the one fact of which time and space are respectively the subjective and objective aspects. Our most advanced physi- cists recognize this principle, but are far from rendering it in simple and concise terms. Thus we read in the well-known work of Thomson and Tait : " We cannot, of course, give a definition of matter which will satisfy the metaphysician, but the naturalist may be content to know matter as that which can be perceived by the senses, or as tliat which can be acted upon by, or can exert, force. The latter, and indeed the former also, of these definitions involves the idea of Force." a In the treatise of Lewes on the Nature of Matter, in Prob- lem IV., we have an illustration of the lengths to which these discussions are brought. Here the extension, impenetra- bility, infinite divisibility, indestructibility, gravity, and inertia of matter are considered without coming to any definite re- sult. A comprehension of the nature of perception, an apprecia- tion of the ultimate analysis, shows the futility of treating Mat- 1 " Problems of Life and Mind," vol. II., p. 206. * Thomson and Tait : " Natural Philosophy," vol. I., p. 161. 344 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. ter as an ultimate fact. Lewes, without treating Matter as an ultimate fact, however, fails to identify it in explicit terms with Space ; and yet he considers it the symbol of all objec- tivity, which is equivalent to its identification with motion ; thus giving it alternately too little and too much meaning. The logical consolation which results from a knowledge of the merely relative significance of these terms, Matter and Force, can hardly be overestimated. Problems V. and VI. are respectively " Force and Cause/' and " The Absolute in the Correlations of Feeling and Mo- tion." The former explains conclusively that Cause and Effect are simply the different points of view from which we regard every phenomenon or event, and can therefore never be more than ideally separated from the events of which they are the expression. The question dear to so many, What is Cause in itself ? is shown to be an absurd- ity, and the enormous quantity of literature which has the solution of this question for its object is rendered useless. In closing Problem VI., we find Lewes again victorious over all disadvantages. He strikes the key-note of universal truth with a precision which enables us to forget the labored explanations of the preceding chapters concerning discon- nected ultimates. His deep knowledge of psychological principles triumphs, and, independently of metaphysics, he performs an ultimate analysis by a comparison of the fact of consciousness with general existence. But his long service in the unsettled disputes of metaphysics has made him the slave of a certain vocabulary, has rendered him powerless to rise above certain habits of expression and to restore order to this chaos of ultimate terms. By another route, however, namely, a scientific analysis of mind and nature, he reaches the coveted result. Witness the closing words of Problem VI.: " Existence the Absolute is known to us in Feeling, which in its most abstract expression is Change, external and internal. The external changes are symbolized as Motion, because that is the mode of Feeling into which all others are GEORGE HENRY LEWES. 345 translated when objectively considered : objective considera- tion being the attitude of looking at the phenomena, whereas subjective consideration is the attitude of any other sensible response, so that the phenomena are different to the different senses. There is no real break in the continuity of Existence ; all its modes are but differentiations. We cannot suppose the physical organism and its functions to be other than integrant parts of the Cosmos from which it is formally differentiated ; nor can we suppose the psychical organism and its functions to be other than integrant parts of this physical organism from. which it is ideally separated. Out of the infinite modes of Existence a group is segregated, and a planet assumes individual form ; out of the infinite modes of this planetary existence smaller groups are segregated in crystals, organ- isms, societies, nations. Each group is a special system, having forces peculiar to it, although in unbroken continuity with the forces of all other systems. Out of the forces of the animal organism a special group is segregated in the nervous mechanism, which has its own laws. If ideally we contrast any two of these groups, a planet with an organ- ism, or an organism with a nervous mechanism, their great unlikeness seems to forbid identification. They are indeed different, but only because they have been differentiated. Yet they are identical, under a more general aspect. In like manner, if we contrast the world of Sensation and Appetites with the world of Conscience and its Moral Ideals, the unlikeness is striking. Yet we have every ground for believing that Conscience is evolved from Sensation, and that Moral Ideals are evolved from Appetites ; and thus we connect the highest mental phenomena with vital Sensibility, Sensibility with molecular changes in the organism, and these with changes in the Cosmos. "This unification of all the modes of Existence by no means obliterates the distinction of modes, nor the necessity of understanding the special characters of each. Mind remains Mind, and is essentially opposed to Matter, in spite of their identity in the Absolute ; just as Pain is not Pleas- 346 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. ure, nor Color either Heat or Taste, in spite of their identity in Feeling. The logical distinctions represent real differen- tiations, but not distinct existents. If we recognize the One in the Many, we do not thereby refuse to admit the Many in the One." ' Here the term absolute (or time) is used in the place of motion or the ultimate reality, but the great unity of the argument rises above these verbal defects. It is evident that the idea which Lewes seeks to convey is that the most gen- eral terms of life and mind point to a single fact and bear a definite relation to it. For those who may feel inclined to examine deeply into the proposition that Matter and Space mean the same thing, or that the meanings of these two terms converge in a logical point, I insert an essay by Lewes entitled, "Action at a Distance," which is by far the most learned and com- pact treatment of the question which it has been my good fortune to meet. It occurs as an appendix to the volume under discussion. ACTION AT A DISTANCE. In spite of Newton's emphatic disclaimer, his opponents in old days, and many of his followers in our own, have been unable to banish the idea that the relation between bodies called Attraction is a mysterious something inherent in Matter, seated among the molecules, so to speak, and stretching forth its grasp to bind them into masses, and distant masses into systems. I do not pretend that this is what any one avows ; I only say that it is a paraphrase of \vhat many teach. Few doubt that there is a special Agent symbolized in the term attrac- tive force (" Ce monstre metaphysique si cher a une partie des philosophes modernes, si odieux a 1'autre," says Maupertuis), and that this Agent acts across empty space. " That gravity should be innate, inherent, and essential to matter," writes Newton to Bentley, ' ' so that one body may act upon another at a distance through a vacuum, and without the mediation of any thing else by and through which this action and force may be conveyed from one to another, is to me so great an absurdity that I believe no man who has in philosophical matters a competent faculty of thinking can ever fall into it." Nevertheless, even his own editor, Roger Cotes, declares action at a distance to be one of the primary properties of matter ; and many mathematicians and metaphysicians have flouted the scholastic axiom, " A body cannot act where it is not," treating it as 1 " Problems of Life and Mind," vol. II., p. 449. GEORGE HENRY LEWES. 347 a vulgar error. They urge that astronomical phenomena prove bodies to act at enormous distances ; and moreover, that the molecules are never in actual con- tact even when they act on each other. The notion of action at a distance contradicts Rule II. It presupposes a body to be moving through the space in which it does not move, existing where it does not exist. Action is dynamic existence. The force or pressure by which, in which a body acts, is ideally, but not really, separable from the active matter, and the coexistent positions named space. Having thus ideally sepa- rated the Agency from the Agent, men find it easy to suppose the Force acting where the matter is not ; and some men materialize this Force, convert it into an Ether interposed between masses and molecules, so that the matter acts on this ethereal Force, and the Force transmits the action to Matter. Experience does indeed seem to suggest action at a distance, and thus to con- tradict the axiom. I am seated in my study, and can certainly act upon my servant, who is distant from me in the kitchen. I have only to touch the bell and she comes up-stairs. She is drawn toward me, as the apple is drawn toward the earth, across a distant space. But the scholastic axiom, "A thing cannot act where it is not," is undisturbed by such a fact, and only seems contradicted by it when we suppress in thought all the intermediate agents whose agency was indispensable. I acted directly on the bell-rope, which was continuous with the bell, and set it vibrating ; the vibrations of the bell acted on the air, the air on my servant's auditory organ, that on her intellectual organ, and that in turn upon her muscles. In the fall of an apple the case seems different, because we cannot so readily realize to ourselves all the co-operant conditions ; but the phrase by which we express these, when we say the earth attracts the apple, is not less elliptical than the phrase, ' ' I caused my servant to come up-stairs by ringing the bell." If bodies "attract" each other across empty space, we can only under- stand this attraction as a moving toward each other in the line of a resultant pressure, not as the dragging by immaterial grappling-irons thrown from one to the other. " Equidem existimo gravitatem," says Copernicus, "non aliud esse quam appetentiam quandam naturalem, partibus inditam a divina providentia opificis universoruin." * And Euler says : "In attempting to dive into the mysteries of nature, it is of importance to know if the heavenly bodies act upon each other by impulsion or by attraction ; if a certain subtile, invisible matter impels them toward each other, or if they are endowed with a secret occult quality by which they are mutually attracted. Those who hold the second view maintain that the quality of mutual attraction is proper to all bodies ; that it is as natural to them as magnitude. Had there been but two bodies in the universe, however remote from each other, they would have had from the first a tendency toward each other, by means of which they would in time have approached and united." 2 This fiction respecting two bodies alone in the universe, and their inherent tendency to approach each other, is in open defiance of all experience. Let us 1 Copernicus : " De Revolutionibus Orbium," I., ch. IX. * Euler : " Letters to a German Princess," vol. I., p. 211. 348 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. grant the existence of only two bodies isolated in space : we must first declare that, according to all the inductions from experience, they would not tend to move toward each other, for they would not move at all ; some external motion or pressure would be requisite, since their own internal motions would be in equilibrium ; nor would an external force impel them to move toward each other, unless the direction of that force were in this line and no other. Sup- pose each body to be in motion, each would pursue its own direction, nor would they ever meet, unless some third body in motion redirected them. Of course, if the bodies are assumed to have an inherent tendency to rush together like two water-drops, but without the external pressures which blend the water-drops, they would inevitably meet ; but what evidence is there for such an assumption ? It is obvious that we cannot explain the- phenomena of attraction by the fiction of two isolated bodies in empty space, because that fiction presupposes conditions wholly unlike those of the known universe, which is not an universe of two isolated bodies, but of infinite and variously related bodies. Mr. Mill is very contemptuous in his notice of Hamilton's reliance on the axiom that one body cannot act directly on another without contact. " In one sense of the word," Mr. Mill says, " a thing is wherever its action is ; its power is there, though not its corporeal presence [a singular distinction in the writings of so positive a thinker !]. But to say that a thing can only act where its power is, would be the idlest of mere identical propositions. [An axiom is an identical proposition.] And where is the warrant for asserting that a thing cannot act when it is not locally contiguous to the thing it acts upon ? * * * What is the meaning of contiguity ? According to the best physical knowledge we possess, things are never actually contiguous. What we term contact between particles, only means that they are in the degree of proximity at which their mutual repulsions are in equilibrium with their attractions. [Are not these repulsions and attractions hypothetic phrases to express the fact that, however closely bodies may be pressed together, their molecules cannot be both made to occupy the same space, each unit, as an unit, having its limit ? a fact also expressed by impenetrability.^ If so, instead of never, things always act on one another at some, though it may be a very small, distance. The belief that a thing can only act where it is, is a common case of inseparable, though not ultimately indis- soluble, association. It is an unconscious generalization, of the roughest possi- ble description, from the most familiar cases of the mutual action of bodies superficially considered. The temporary difficulty felt in apprehending any action of body upon body unlike what people were accustomed to, created a natural prejudice which was long a serious impediment to the reception of the Newtonian theory : but it was hoped that the final triumph of that theory had extinguished it [Newton, as we have seen, would have repudiated this conclu- sion] ; that all educated persons were now aware that action at a distance is intrinsically quite as credible as action in contact ; and that there is no reason, 1 " II paraitra par nos meditations," says Leibnitz, "que la substance cre'ee ne recoit pas d'une autre substance creee la puissance meme d'agir, mais seule- ment une limitation et determination de son propre effet pre-existant et de la vertu active." GEORGE HENRY LEWES. 349 apart from specific experience, to regard the one as in any respect less probable than the other." 1 The idea that a body like the sun, which is ninety-two millions of miles dis- tant from us, can act directly on us across this distance, assumed to be a vacuum, is absolutely inconceivable, since action involves motion, and the motion through this space must be either the motion of the body itself, or of some body to which it has been transferred. A mere crack in a glass extinguishes its sounding property ; that is to say, the waves of molecular motion are no longer propagated because of this solution of continuity ; and if between us and the sun there were any solution of material continuity, the waves of ether would not reach us from the molecular agitations of the sun ; or if we suppose them to pass across this gap it would still be the actual presence of the wave which at each point exerted its pressure. Action at a distance, unless understood in the sense -of action through unspecified intermediates, is both logically and physi- cally absurd. Logically, since action involves reaction, and is only conceivable as the combination of forces ; physically, since the attraction said to act across the distance is avowedly a function of the distance, which increases as the distance decreases ; and this implies that the distance is an Agent. Now, if we assume the space between two bodies to be empty, we make this nothing an effective Agent, which offers resistance to pressure, and causes a decrease of attraction. I therefore ask, with Professor Clerk Maxwell : " If something is transmitted from one particle to another at a distance, what is its condition after it has left the one particle and before it has reached the other ? If this something is the potential energy of the two particles, how are we to conceive this energy as existing in a point of space coinciding neither with the one parti- cle nor the other? In fact, whenever energy is transmitted from one body to another in time, there must be a medium or substance in which the energy exists," 3 otherwise there would be energy which was not the active state of matter, but an activity floating through the Nothing. It should be observed, and the observation is suggestive in many directions, that some of the most eminent physicists have not only adopted the idea of action at a distance, but have constructed on it elaborate and effective theories of electrical action. Gauss, Weber, Riemann, Neumann, and others, have in- terpreted electro-magnetic actions on this assumption ; and the success which has attended their efforts is another among the many examples of the truth we have previously enforced, that no amount of agreement between observed phenomena and an hypothesis is sufficient to prove the truth of the hypothesis. Contrasted with the labors of these mathematicians and physicists, we have the labors of Faraday, Thomson, Tait, Clerk Maxwell, and others, who start from the hypothesis of a material medium. Not only are they able to explain all the observed phenomena on this hypothesis, but they have the immense advan- tage of not invoking an agency which is without a warrant in experience. Where the mathematicians admitted only the abstraction pure Distance, and centres of force acting on each other across this Distance, Faraday and his followers have 1 Mill: " Examination of Sir W. Hamilton," p. 531. * Clerk Maxwell : " Electricity and Magnetism," vol. II. p. 437. 350 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. admitted with the Distance its concrete Medium, and with the centres of force, radii or lines of force ; where the one class sees the abstract power of action at a distance impressed upon the electric fluids, the other class sees the actions going on in the Medium, and these are the concrete phenomena. The supe- riority of the second point of view seems to me to consist in its speculative and its practical advantages. Although the two are mathematically equivalent, the second has the speculative superiority of conformity with Experience ; and ac- cording to Professor Maxwell it has the further practical advantage of leading us to inquire into the nature of the action in each part of the medium. 1 The conception of a Plenum is simply the unavoidable conclusion from the conception of Existence as continuous ; and this continuity is itself the cor- relative of the impossibility of accepting the pure Nothing otherwise than as a generalization of our negative experiences. But if continuity of Existence is thus necessarily postulated, it does not interfere with the utmost variety in the modes of Existence ; and with every variation in mode there is superficial dis- continuity. When a feeling changes, it is because another feeling has replaced it. My hand passing over a surface has one mode of feeling until it reaches the boundary, and then a new mode arises to replace the former, the feeling of solid resistance gives place to one of fluid or aerial resistance. The new mode is unlike the old, discontinuous with it ; but it is nevertheless only a new form of the fundamental continuity of Feeling. The conception of a Plenum is further shown to be unavoidable when we come to inquire into the nature of that void which is supposed to exist in the interstices of molecules, and in the interplanetary spaces. Space is the abstract of coexistent positions ; its concretes are bodies in the various relations of posi- tion ; but in our abstraction we let drop the bodies, and retain only the relations of position ; although a moment's consideration suffices to show that were there no bodies, there could be no positions of bodies, consequently no relations of coexistent positions, in a word, no space. If, therefore, by interspaces be- tween molecules or planets we understand simply the relations of position of these bodies, we may indeed conveniently abstract these relations from their related terms, and treat of spaces irrespective of bodies ; but we may not from this artifice conclude that between these related terms there is a solution of the continuity of Existence, that between the bodies there is a void. It is held that, were our senses sufficiently magnified, we might see the mole- cules and atoms distributed throughout what now appears a mass, much as we see the constellations distributed among the vast spaces of the heavens. Per- haps ; but even then our magnified senses would discover no solution in the great continuum. Necessarily so, since by no possible exaltation of an organ of sense could the Suprasensible be reached. The void if it exist cannot be felt, and the only Existence knowable by us is the Felt. Hence the idea of action at a distance is absurd, if the distance be taken to represent any solution in the material continuity, which is the continuity of the Agent whose Agency is the action ; but the idea is intelligible and true if the distance be taken to represent simply the relative positions of the body from which the action is supposed to originate, and the body in which it is completed. 1 See his " Electricity and Magnetism," vol. I., pp. 58, 65, and 123. CHAPTER XVI. GEORGE HENRY LEWES (CONCLUDED). The Relation of Universal to Organic Activities Lewes' Theory of Perception. To the reader who may have followed thus far the argu- ment here presented, perhaps it will not be too much to say that Metaphysics is a completed study. The problem of the Ultimate Reality, which has puzzled thoughtful humanity from Aristotle to the present day, has, owing to the vast logical movement of this age of Evolution, at last achieved its own solution, and we stand emancipated from the mys- teries of idealism and the discouragements of skepticism, with naught to fear for the integrity of human knowledge. The logical position which an ultimate analysis occupies is invulnerable. There is, perhaps, no keener pleasure than to observe the resistance which it offers to the attacks of trained men of science. If they reason from a statical basis, postulating matter as an ultimate fact, " a substance which remains after all properties have been accounted for," they fall into the error of neglecting the very property by which we appreciate facts, namely, their activity. If they postulate this activity and deny to it extension or position, they again involve themselves by first employing a symbol and then withdrawing its meaning ; for no fact can be expressed with- out conceding to it extension or position. The course to be pursued in such a controversy is to watch carefully for terms having the same meaning as Space, such as Infinite, Coex- istence, Matter, Substance, Status, Position, etc. ; or the equivalents of Time, such as Absolute, Abstract Sequence, Force considered as the cause of motion, or Motion consid- 351 352 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. ered apart from its space aspect; or the equivalents of Motion, such as Life, God, Power, First Cause ; and, when these terms are used, to insist upon giving them their full significance. Nothing can withstand the force of such an analysis. It is soon perceived that by employing abstrac- tions, we recede from the particulars of life to the first or simplest fact, the initial relation of personal and general existence. It is therefore with feelings of the utmost relief that we take leave of the abstractions of metaphysics and take up the remaining three volumes of Lewes' philosophic writings purely as a scientific study, neglecting any thing we may find in them pertaining to ontological questions. Indeed Lewes seems to have written these last volumes in much the same spirit as that in which we would review them, for we find in them, after all, but little that is strictly metaphysical. The first of these is entitled the " Physical Basis of Mind," and deals with the following problems : " The Nature of Life"; "The Nervous Mechanism"; "Animal Automa- tism," and " The Reflex Theory." The second contains the problems : " Mind as a Function of the Organism " ; " The Sphere of Sense and the Logic of Feeling " ; " The Sphere of Intellect and the Logic of Signs." The last is the brief work entitled " The Study of Psychology." It is our purpose merely to select from the above prob- lems the most striking lessons, so as to convey a general idea of the results to which Lewes has attained, and to define their relations to what has already been indicated as a complete philosophy. A minute study of the procedures of organic growth shows how difficult it is to avoid the theory of a design in nature. All human efforts are so intimately connected with design, that it is difficult for us to look upon natural sequences in any other light. The great masters in biological research have felt this difficulty, and, for the most part, yielded to it. Thus " Von Baer, in his great work, has a section entitled GEORGE HENRY LEWES. 353 ' The Nature of the Animal Determines its Development ' ; and he thus explains himself : ' Although every stage in de- velopment is only made possible by its pre-existing condition, nevertheless the entire development is ruled and guided by the nature of the animal which is about to be ; and it is not the momentary condition which alone absolutely determines the future, but more general and higher relations.' " The form that this superstition generally takes is the belief that an organism is determined by its type, or, " as the Germans say, its Idea." "All its parts take shape according to this ruling plan ; consequently, when any part is removed, it is reproduced according to the Idea of the whole of which it forms a part. Milne Edwards, in a very interesting and sug- gestive work, concludes his survey of organic phenomena in these words : ' In the organism every thing seems calculated with a view to a determinate result, and the harmony of the parts does not result from any influence which they can exert upon one another, but from their co-ordination under the empire of a common power, a preconceived plan, a pre- existing force.' ' " This," continues Lewes, " is eminently metaphysiological (superstitious). It refuses to acknowledge the operation of immanent properties, refuses to admit that the harmony of a complex structure results from the mutual relation of its parts, and seeks outside the organism for some mysterious force, some plan, not otherwise specified, which regulates and shapes the parts. * * * Let us note the logical inconsistencies of a position which, while assuming that every separate stage in development is the necessary sequence of its predecessor, declares the whole of the stages independent of such relations ! Such a position is indeed reconcilable on the assumption that animal forms are moulded ' like clay in the hands of the potter.' But this is a theological dogma which leads to very preposterous and impious conclusions ; and whether it leads to these conclusions or to others, positive Biology declines theological explanations altogether. * * * The type does not dominate the conditions, it emerges from them ; the animal organism is not cast in a mould, but the 354 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. imaginary mould is the form which the polarities of the or- ganic substance assume. It would seem very absurd to sup- pose that crystals assumed their definite shapes (when the liquid which held their molecules in solution is evaporated) under the determining influence of phantom crystals or Ideas ; yet it has not been thought absurd to assume phantom forms of organisms. The conception of Type as a determining influ- ence arises from that fallacy of taking a resultant for a prin- ciple, which has played so conspicuous a part in the history of philosophy. * * * At first, the Type or Idea was regarded as an objective reality, external to the organism it was sup- posed to rule. Then this notion was replaced by an approach to the more rational interpretation, the Idea was made an internal, not an external, force, and was incorporated with the material elements of the organism, which were said to 1 endeavor ' to arrange themselves according to the Type. Thus Treveranus declares that the seed ' dreams of the future flower ' ; and ' Henle, when he declares that hair and nails grow in virtue of the Idea, is forced to add that the parts en- deavor to arrange themselves according to this Idea.' Even Lotze, who has argued so victoriously against the vitalists, and has made it clear that an organism is a vital mechanism, cannot relinquish this conception of legislative Ideas, though he significantly adds : ' These have no power in themselves, but only in as far as they are grounded in mechanical con- ditions.' Why, then, superfluously add them to the condi- tions?" 1 The imposing analysis which Lewes makes of organic existence stops not at the latest biological discoveries, but presses on to what, by comparison with the very best pre- vious work on the subject, is a new and vastly extended view of the origins of individual life. Not content with at- tacking the " superstition of the nerve-cell," upon which is built the theory of peculiar vital forces " wholly unallied with the primary energy of motion," which is in itself an impor- tant physiological reform, he addresses himself assiduously 1 " Physical Basis of Mind," pp. 104-107. GEORGE HENRY LEWES. 355 to the task of widening the scientific understanding of the whole subject of organic life. Beginning with the analysis of Protoplasm, which discloses the exceedingly high molecu- lar complexity of this basic substance of organisms, he identifies the complex but definite activities which this sub- stance exhibits with the less complex but no less definite activities displayed by what we know as chemical substances, the difference in the activities of the two classes of sub- stances being purely one of degree of complexity, corre- sponding with their respective degrees of molecular (or structural) complexity. This generalization, the importance of which is not easily appreciated, so far-reaching are its con- sequences, is made to serve as a basis for the extension of Mr. Darwin's theory of the origin of species by Natural Selection. " The survival of the fittest " is shown to be a very anthropomorphic way of expressing the great truth which Darwin brought to light. The struggle for existence, or the competition and antagonism of organisms, is shown to extend to the " competition and antagonism " of tissues and organs for existence ; and for fear that the inconsistency im- plied in the application of such exclusively mental terms as competition and antagonism to the energies of organic sub- stances (which can only be thought of as contributing to consciousness as remote factors) should be overlooked, he follows up the interdependencies of tissues and organs with such remorseless vigor, that nothing is left but to acknowl- edge that their potentialities are inherent in their chemical composition. " When a crystalline solution takes shape, it always takes a definite shape, which represents what may be called the direction of its forces, the polarity of its constitu- ent molecules. In like manner, when an organic plasmode takes shape crystallizes, so to speak it always assumes a specific shape dependent on the polarity of its molecules. Crystallographers have determined the several forms possible to crystals ; histologists have recorded the several forms of Organites, Tissues, and Organs. Owing to the greater variety in elementary composition, there is in organic sub- 356 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. stance a more various polar distribution than in crystals ; nevertheless there are sharply defined limits never over- stepped, and these constitute what may be called the specific forms of Organites, Tissues, Organs, Organisms. * * * Natu- ral selection is only the expression of the results of obscure physiological processes ; and for a satisfactory theory of such results we must understand the nature of the processes. In other words, to understand Natural Selection we must recog- nize not only the facts thus expressed, but the factors of these facts, we must analyze the ' conditions of existence.' As a preliminary analysis we find external conditions, among which are included not only the dependence of the organism on the inorganic medium, but also the dependence of one organism on another, the competition and antagonism of the whole organic world ; and internal conditions, among which are included not only the dependence of the organism on the laws of composition and decomposition whereby each organite and each tissue is formed, but also the dependence of one organite and one tissue on all the others, the compe- tition and antagonism of all the elements. The changes wrought in an organism by these two kinds of conditions determine Varieties and Species. Although many of the changes are due to the process of Natural Selection, brought about in the struggle with competitors and foes, many other changes have no such relation to the external struggle, but are simply the results of the organic affinities. They may or may not give the organism a greater stability, or a greater advantage over rivals : it is enough that they are no disad- vantage to the organism ; they will then survive by virtue of the forces which produced them." 1 In criticising the theory of the generic development of all living things, which as held by the extreme school is, that all animal life has descended from a single organic point, all the subsequent differences being the result of modifications in the environment or differences in the history of the descend- ants of this first organism, the less extreme school holding 1 " Physical Basis of Mind," pp. 101, 102, 124, 125. GEORGE HENRY LEWES. 357 that (to use Mr. Darwin's words) " animals have descended from at most only four or five progenitors, and plants from an equal or less number," Lewes pleads hard for a deeper and more thorough analysis of the facts than either of these schools offers. Notwithstanding an affec- tionate reverence for Mr. Darwin, whose great work he acknowledges to be invaluable as an explanation of that aspect of organic development called Natural Selection, Lewes clearly shows that the great theory accounts for but a part of the facts. In it there is no room for any thing ap- proaching an ultimate analysis of existence. The points of resemblance between plants and animals are dwelt upon at length ; and striking as these resemblances are, the differences are irreconcilable with a theory of common descent from a single cell at a single point upon the earth's surface. The common chemical conditions of the earth at all stages of its past metamorphosis suggest common organic conditions; and although the theory of evolution teaches that all devel- opment is rigidly serial, the simple leading to and making possible the complex, yet no good reason can be given for doubting that organic life was widespread and multifarious in its terrestrial beginnings. The kinship which unites the organic with the inorganic is quite as prominent a fact as the relationship of the plant and animal kingdoms, or the inter- dependence of organic and superorganic life. The law of organic evolution, which is broad enough to indicate, for in- stance, the history of the solar system, can surely account for the changes which have taken place upon a single planet ; in a word, if we will but take our stand at a sufficiently remote point of view, it will not be necessary to introduce a mys- terious beginning to organic life. " Upon what principle are we to pause at the cell or protoplasm? If by a successive elimination of differences we reduce all organisms to the cell, we must go on and reduce the cell itself to the chemical elements out of which it was constructed ; and inasmuch as these elements are all common to the inorganic world, the only difference being one of synthesis, we reach a result 358 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. which is the stultification of all classification, namely, the assertion of a kinship which is universal." Passing from these generalizations of organic phenomena to the physical aspect of mind, Lewes exposes the super- stitions and unwarranted assumptions of many writers on mental physiology ; and so vital are the principles involved, that although the explanations are rather technical, for so general a review, we cite some of the most important. The most abridged expression we have of the action of the sensorium, in which the motor, the sensational, and the intellectual forms of activity are combined, is called the nervous arc. Anatomists observe that the motor nerves issue from the anterior side of the spinal cord (that which in animals is the under side), and that the sensory nerves issue from the posterior side (that which in animals is the upper side). The spinal cord, like the cerebrum, is a double organ, with the difference, however, that the gray structure is mainly external in the cerebrum while it is internal in the cord. Of the development of the nervous system from the embryo, Lewes says : " In the outermost layer of the germi- nal membrane of the embryo a groove appears, which deep- ens as its sides grow upward and finally close over and form a canal. Its foremost extremity soon bulges into three well-marked enlargements which are then called the primi- tive cerebral vesicles. The cavities of these vesicles are continuous. Except in position and size, there are no dis- cernible differences in these vesicles, which are known as the Fore-brain, Middle-brain, and Hind-brain. * * * It appears that the retina and optic nerve are primitive portions of the brain a detached segment of the general centre, identical in structure with the cerebral vesicle, and not unlike it in form. * * * It thus appears that the primitive membrane forms into a canal, which enlarges at one part into three vesicles, and from these are developed the encephalic (brain) structures. The continuity of the walls and cavities of these vesicles is never obliterated throughout the subsequent changes. It is also traceable throughout the medulla spi- GEORGE HENR Y LE WES. 359 nalis ; and microscopic investigation reveals that underneath all the morphological changes the walls of the whole cerebro- spinal axis are composed of similar elements on a similar plan. The conclusions which directly follow from the above are, first, that since the structure of the great axis is everywhere similar, tJie properties must be similar ; secondly, that since there is structural continuity, no one part can be called into activity without at the same time more or less exciting that of all the rest." Lewes bitterly complains of the analytical tendency in the study of the activities of the sensorium. This tendency, he says, is to disregard the elements which provisionally had been set aside, and not restore them in the reconstruction of a synthetical explanation. Such familiar experiences as that when a stimulus is applied to the skin it is followed by a muscular movement or a glandular secretion (accompanied by all degrees of consciousness as the case may be), are inter- preted by the neurologist as exclusively neural processes ; all the other processes are provisionally left out of account. But even in the neural process the organs are neglected for the sake of the nervous tissue, and the nervous tissue for the sake of the nerve-cell. The most abridged statement of the activity of the sen- sorium, therefore, whether it be a muscular movement, a glandular secretion, an emotion, or a thought, is to be found in the theory of the nervous arc. Of the general form which this theory takes, the conventional description would be about as follows : " The nerve-cell is the supreme ele- ment, the origin of the nerve-fibre, and the fountain of nerve-force. The cells are connected one with another by means of fibres, and with muscles, glands, and centres, also by means of fibres, which are merely channels for the nerve- force. A stimulus at the surface is carried by a sensory fibre to a cell in the centre ; from that point it is carried by another fibre to another cell ; and from that by a third fibre to a muscle ; a reflex action results ; this is the elementary nervous arc." The passage of an excitation, therefore, into 360 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. the labyrinths of the sensorium and out again (until it emerges in action) is said to describe the nervous arc. It is well known that at some stage in this process, or at some point in this arc, the phenomenon called consciousness min- gles in some degree with the excitation ; for the structure of the whole nervous system, including the brain, being not only continuous but of the same substances, a wave of ex- citement set up in any part of it must influence the whole, however imperceptibly. All that we know of the reflex pro- cess pictured in the above description of the nervous arc, which pretends to trace the fibre from cell to cell, is, " that one fibre passes into the spinal cord, and that another passes out of it, and that a movement is produced usually preceded by a sensation and sometimes by a thought." The con- tinuity of the nerve-fibre, therefore, from cell to cell, through the spinal cord, which is supposed to demarcate the simpler reflexes from the realm of consciousness, is purely imagina- tive. Hence, whether the action of the sensorium which we observe be the effort of a frog, whose brain has been re- moved, to repel the irritating point of the scalpel from one leg by pushing it away with the other, or whether the des- tinies of a race are being worked out in the mind of some political or moral autocrat through the slow adjustments of a lifetime, the same order of organic structures acts and reacts with the same order of environment, the same potentialities are called into play, and there is nothing to distinguish the two events but the degrees of their complexity, which can be expressed in terms of Space and Time. The better informed among physiologists and neurologists are beginning to acknowledge the impossibility of absolutely separating the simplest reflex actions from sensibility and, in turn, from thought. Assuming that consciousness has its seat in the brain, sen- sation in the base of the brain, or the medulla oblongata, and the simpler reflexes in the spinal cord, which is a very me- chanical way of subdividing the interdependent activities of the sensorium, the manner in which the simpler movements GEORGE HENRY LEWES. 361 and sensations mingle with consciousness is thus explained. The most widely accepted theory is, that the wave of excita- tion must pass onward to the central convolutions of the brain, and that there, in the excitation of the cells, it first be- comes sensation, consciousness is first aroused. This theory regards consciousness and sensation as nearly identical, and locates them both in the brain. In all these theories sensa- tion is made the middle term between the most unconscious or simplest reflex actions, and thought, and the theories differ only in the distance said to intervene between the central convolutions of the brain and the supposed seat of sensation. The following diagram and explanation will illustrate that theory which locates both sensation and consciousness in presumably the same neural tract in the brain. " The stimu- lus wave from the sensitive surface S is carried to the spinal centre S 1, which may either transmit it di- rectly to M 3, and thus reach the muscle M, or transmit indirectly through S 2, M 2, in the subcere- bral centre; or, finally, it may pass upward through S I, S 2, S 3, and downward through M I, M 2, M 3. The reflex of S I, M 3, is purely physical', that of S I, S 2, M 2, M 3, is psycho-physical, there being a sentient state accompanying the mechanical process ; while that of S I, S 2, S 3, M i, M 2, M 3, is a reflex accompanied by consciousness. The initial stage is a peripheral stimulation ; but the same reflex may be excited by central stimulation. That is to say, the impulse may originate in S 3, and pass through M i, M 2, M 3, or pass through S 2, M 2, M 3. This is when an idea is said to originate a movement. Again : the stimulus may be some state of the subcerebral centres and pass from S 2, M2, M3." 1 All processes are therefore Reflex processes, the degree of centralization, or dependence on the brain, determining the degree of consciousness or volition which accompanies them. 1 " Problems of Life and Mind," 3d series, vol. II., pp. 431, 432. 362 THE NATURE OF PERCEPTION. Physiologists, however, would distinguish the relatively in- voluntary as reflex, and are therefore obliged to invent a special mechanism for this class. If physiologists could only agree upon the facts by which they support the Reflex theory, the path of the student would be smoothed. " Van Deen, for instance, considers that Reflexion takes place without Volition but not without Sensation ; and Budge, that it takes place without Perception (Vorstellung)." "According to Marshall Hall, who originated the modern form of this theory, actions are divisible into four distinct classes : the voluntary, dependent on the brain ; the involuntary, dependent on the irritability of the muscular fibre ; the respiratory, wherein 'the motive influence passes in a direct line from one point of the nervous system to certain muscles ' ; and the reflex, dependent on the ' true spinal system' of incident -excitor nerves, and of reflex motor nerves. These last-named actions are produced when an impression on the sensitive surface is conveyed by an excitor nerve to the spinal cord and is there reflected back on the muscles by a corresponding motor nerve. In this process no sensation whatever occurs. The action is purely reflex, purely excito-motor, like the action of an ordinary mechanism." ' Miiller also shares this view of the Reflex theory with Hall. 2 Of all of which Lewes says : " It is needless nowadays to point out that the existence of a distinct system of excito-motor nerves belongs to im- aginary anatomy ; but it is not needless to point out that the Imaginary Physiology founded on it still survives. * * * We have already seen that what anatomy positively teaches is totally unlike the Reflex mechanism popularly imagined. The sensory nerve is not seen to enter the spinal cord at one point and pass over to a corresponding point of exit ; it is seen to enter the gray substance, which is continuous throughout the spinal cord ; it is there lost to view, its course being untraceable." : 1 Marshall Hall, in " Phys. Trans.," 1883 ; " Lectures on the Nervous Sys- tem and its Diseases," 1836 ; " New Memoir on the Nervous System," 1843. 2 Miiller : " Physiology," vol. I., p. 721. 8 " Physical Basis of Mind," pp. 480, 481. GEORGE HENRY LEWES. 363 With this hasty glance at these brilliant inductions of Lewes, we must close our review of his system. Is it too much to say that to Lewes we owe the most commanding view of organic Perception that has thus far been offered to the world ? But perception has a wider base than organic life. It is the function of conditions which are universal. Lewes sought to establish the harmony of the organic and inorganic worlds by the manipulation of ultimate principles, but, as I have already said, his mind had become biassed by a conventional metaphysics which he was unable to over- come, This metaphysics postulated an unknowable, and Lewes never quite discovered that it was the subtle con- tradiction implied in this term which vitiated his whole system of introspection. He then turned to the study of the functions and structures of organisms, in the hope of leading up to Mind through its organic processes, of estab- lishing a true psychology. This he has done. The achieve- ment can be expressed in his striking dictum : " Motor perceptions are condensed in intuitions and generalized in conceptions." This is the pivotal truth of the Nature of Perception, for it discloses the Physical Basis of Mind. PART III. THE RELIGION OF PHILOSOPHY. 365 PART III. THE RELIGION OF PHILOSOPHY, CHAPTER XVII. SUPERSTITION AND MYSTERY. Resemblance between Primitive and Modern Religious Beliefs Superstition the Negative, Morality the Positive Form of Religion. RELIGIOUS criticism is wholly a modern art. As language reached a high state of perfection before the manner of its growth was discovered, so the higher human sentiments have grown into bonds of universal sympathy before the race has been able to form any adequate idea of the laws of thought and feeling. It is the study of the development of language which makes possible an intelligent view of the great subject of Religion. The races of the world have unconsciously writ- ten their emotional and moral history in the formation of their speech. The comparative study of languages gives us an insight into the origin of nations, so that we are enabled to classify the races of mankind with far greater accuracy than before the advent of this science. The different races of men represent different classes of ideas ; representative types of thought and feeling which have their expression in certain forms of social organization or Morality, and certain forms of the higher sentiments or Religion. The morals and the religions of the world as we find them are the products of the slow evolution of human- 367 368 THE RELIGION OF PHILOSOPHY. ity, the results of past conditions, and they can only be ac- counted for by studying the phases of development through which they have passed. The foregoing divisions of this work have been devoted to establishing a clear understanding of the fundamental principles of life, to building up a true conception of knowledge. We have dealt, not with the circumstances of social life, not with human history, but with the nature of man himself, the interaction of his physical and psychical nature, with a view to explaining the wonderful phenomena of language and perception. We are now, in a measure, prepared to deal with that highest aspect of human exist- ence which we call Morality, and that vast emotional struc- ture known as Religion. As the greatest logical achievements have resulted from the ceaseless energies of metaphysical investigation, notwithstanding the apparent hopelessness and unreality of the pursuit, so our best conceptions of duty and life have sprung from the emotions of religion, notwith- standing the various degrees of degradation and misery to which mistaken religious beliefs have subjected all races and civilizations. Where the tenets of logic are concerned, men have always been comparatively free to contend without interference or reproach ; the populace has taken but little interest in these wars of abstractions ; but with the contentions of religious faiths it has been very different, and it is natural that it should have been so. To wantonly assail a religious faith is a very serious matter : it may cause inestimable harm, and it seldom if ever has a good influence. As will afterward appear, religion and morality are but the obverse aspects of the higher phases of human character. To disturb the one is to disturb the other. If there is one opinion with regard to the criticism of re- ligion which is universal, it is that we have no right to destroy a faith unless to supplant it with a better one. Proselytism has never been condemned as immoral, however much it has been resisted, for the missionary believes that he is im- SUPERSTITION AND MYSTERY. 369 parting a better religion than the one which he opposes. The iconoclast, on the contrary, has always been a dreaded destroyer : he offers nothing to replace the objects of worship which he ruins. The Religion of Philosophy is the purest of all faiths, the highest of all moralities. Its creed is the ever-brightening zenith of human knowledge ; its precepts spring from the deepest principles of our existence ; its understanding of human life and destiny has nothing to yield to any existing faith ; and its conception of God is so much purer and bet- ter than that of any other religion, that a comparison be- comes ungenerous. It requires no consecrated temples for its worship, no priests or sacraments, no ritual for its dead. Its followers can worship in any temple, learn of any priest, and, as they honor all forms of religion, none of its cere- monies can be inappropriate to their memory. Each religion represents the highest or most general con- ceptions of its believers ; for this reason the conventional classification of faiths can give but the merest outline of the actual religious convictions of individuals. Creeds are only partially acquiesced in ; the same formulas of belief are in- terpreted in widely different ways ; and there is, after all, an innate independence in religious belief which only gives formal acquiescence to the established forms of faith. The spirit of organization, therefore, which pervades the whole practical world, that strong sense of the necessity of har- mony and co-operation as conditions of success, gives to organized religion a dominion which in a logical sense it does not possess. The difference between the passive believer in any special faith and the conscientious critic of religion may be thus de- scribed : The believer holds that there are divine truths which the simple and the learned can alike appreciate ; the careful critic holds that all truths are divine in the sense that they are related to universal truth, but that the quality of each mind determines the degree of appreciation of that truth. They both admit the existence of divine truth, but 370 THE RELIGION OF PHILOSOPHY. one believes that it belongs exclusively to a religion, while the other believes it to be coextensive with all existence. The chances for disagreement are infinite ; for there is clearly no possibility of limiting the scope of a religion so that it may not include all existence, or of limiting existence so that it may not include all religion. The only possible chance for an agreement is to fix, once for all, upon the meaning of divine, and all words signifying God. This being accomplished, the whole question becomes clear. Divine means the high- est or most general ; God means the Universal Principle, which is the same thing. To say, therefore, that all truths are related to the divine is simply to admit that the universe is an interdependent organon suggesting neither absolute limits nor separations. With this understanding it becomes possible to form some idea of the degree in which each type of mind, from the most simple to the most complex, can ap- preciate general truths. It is only by a study of the facts of religious and moral history that we can succeed in the logical attempt which is here announced. Upon nothing less tangible than the frame- work of these facts can the argument take form and avoid those extreme attenuations which are more apt to confuse than enlighten. Our first assumption is, that religion and morality are not only interdependent activities, but are the obverse aspects of a single fact of development. The quality of life is but an- other name for morality. The quality of the mind deter- mines the quality of the religion. Superstitions are but the negative side of religion, while right thinking, feeling, and doing, or morality, constitute all that is real in religious life. Worship is universally conceded to be a lifting up of the heart to God. When we find the idea of God undeveloped, therefore, we must expect to find no worship, or worship in its most degraded forms. The term atheist (godless one) has a purely relative meaning. If God is the universal fact, if the conception of God is an appreciation of divine unity, what life can be godless ? Tylor tells how ancient invading SUPERSTITION AND MYSTERY. 371 Aryans described the aboriginal tribes of India as adeva, i. e. " godless," and the Greeks fixed the corresponding term aSsoi on the early Christians as unbelievers in the classic gods ; also how, in later days, disbelievers in witchcraft and apostolic succession were denounced as atheists ; and in our own time, controversalists infer that naturalists who support a theory of development of species are therefore supposed to hold atheistic opinions. In the same way the great term Religion is narrowed in its meaning by numberless writers until the assertion that such and such tribes and communities " have absolutely no religion," is not to be trusted till we discover what the re- ligion of the writer happens to be. From the dogmatist, who " seems hardly to recognize any thing short of the organized and established theology of the higher races as religion," to such liberal writers as Herbert Spencer, who defines religion as an a priori theory of the universe held alike by savages and civilized men, and springing from the need of understanding life, 1 we find a tendency to make all worship the consecration of a fundamental mystery. If we would trace religious sentiment to its simplest be- ginnings, we must identify religious with general knowledge, and deny that either is the function of the unknowable. In this investigation we should not allow ourselves to be over- awed by the vast complexities of organized faiths, for as the great developments known as language and perception ex- press but the single fact of motion, so all religions, depend- ing as they do entirely upon language and perception, express but the attitude of man to the Universal Principle, or God. In the dark mind of the savage, where undeveloped 1 " Leaving out the accompanying moral code, which is in all cases a supple- mentary growth, a religious creed is definable as an a priori theory of the uni- verse. * * * Religions diametrically opposed in their overt dogmas are yet perfectly at one in their conviction that the existence of the world with all it contains and all that surrounds it is a mystery ever pressing for interpretation. On this point, if on no other, there is entire unanimity." HERBERT SPENCER L " First Principles," pp. 43, 44. 372 THE RELIGION OF PHILOSOPHY. language permits of no extended thought, there is no visible approach to the idea of the divine unity of life. Objects and sensations fill the mind, instead of sentiments and thoughts. No race seems too degraded to escape, no language too inadequate to express, the belief in a divine mystery. In all the length and breadth of human culture, from the poor Fuegians and Andamans to the philosophers of England, the idea of " an all-pervading mystery " seems to be a constant principle ; yet, instead of admitting that this belief is a posi- tive religious principle, we affirm that it is a purely negative phenomenon, or, in other words, the measure of the inca- pacity alike of the primitive and the civilized man, to form a true conception of God. There can be no safer measure of intellectual and moral development than the extent to which the play of the mind in forming generalizations is interfered with by the belief in mystery. Thus from the Andamans, who alone among the lowest tribes are said to be so degrad- ed as to have scarcely any superstitions, to such intellects as Mill and Spencer, whose only superstition is a belief that the mind is a mystery, we have the greatest ex- tremes of mental development, and also the striking fact that what is commonly called religion has not yet appeared in the former and has practically disappeared in the latter. The intermediate conditions of mind, viewed from our standpoint, are simply different degrees of super- stition. In defining belief with a view to tracing out its beginnings in the race, Mr. C. F. Keary says : " Belief is something besides the recognition of what exists in outward sensation. It is the answering voice of human consciousness, or con- science, to the call of something behind [nature]. * * * For what I have only called the recognition of something behind the physical object is, in reality, a worship of the something (or Some One) behind it. * * * Perhaps, therefore, if we were pressed for a single and concise definition of that human faculty called belief, which we have taken for our study here, SUPERSTITION AND MYSTERY. 373 we could hardly find a better one than this, that it is the 1 capacity for worship.' For if you will consider the nature of man you will find that with him it always has been and still is true, that that thing in all his inward or outward world which he sees worthy of worship is essentially the thing in which he believes." : According to this, belief is capacity for worship, and is at the same time a faith in a mystery, or " something behind nature." When in this connection we recall the well-known agnosticism of Mr. Spencer, we have no choice but to con- clude that both he and Mr. Keary agree in believing that all worship and therefore all religion, all belief and therefore all knowledge, depend upon a superstition. The religion of philosophy acknowledges no mystery ; it advances a conception of God which declares all mystery to be a species of immorality, an impediment to the apprecia- tion of divine unity. It ranks the superstitions of the lowest races with the belief in an unknowable entertained by so many enlightened minds of the present day, and finds in both conceptions the same principle of irreligion. When we find that the poor Fuegians believed in " powers of sorcery, in demons, and in dreams"; that their notion of a future life was confined to an aversion to mentioning the dead ; that they had a notion of an actively malevolent power identified probably with " a great black man," sup- posed to influence the weather according to men's conduct ; we deny that these mysterious beliefs constituted their religion any more than the same beliefs which are so general among modern Christians if we will substitute for the " great black man " a personal God can be called in the true sense of the word the religion of Christians. For the religion of all men, whatever their condition, is the form which their most general conceptions assume. The question for us then to decide is whether such morality, such right thought and action, as we find in any civilization is not a truer index of its spiritual development, of the growth of 1 "Outlines of Primitive Belief." 374 THE RELIGION OF PHILOSOPHY. true and pure conceptions, than those superstitions which we are accustomed to classify as religious ? This assertion that Religion is the form which the most general conceptions of an individual or a race assume, has been objected to on the ground that by a large class of thinkers science or definite knowledge is the name given to the most general conceptions, and religious conceptions are considered too vague for classification under the head of knowledge. This objection brings up the important ques- tion : Can there be any ultimate difference between religious and scientific knowledge ? Knowledge in its broadest sense means life. Human knowledge means human life. There are many who suppose that divine knowledge is entirely distinct from human knowl- edge, whereas we protest that divine means most general, and that divine knowledge means our most extended gener- alizations or conceptions. If the man of science denomi- nates all his superstitions, all his vague ideas of origin and destiny, Religion ; and all clear and definite conceptions, those of human duty as well as those of other classes of facts, Science ; he will, no doubt, object to the statement that Religion is the form which our most general concep- tions assume. In fact, he will lose all respect for the word religion ; and would, no doubt, define it as the science of mystery, or the unknowable. But religion, to us, represents something so real, so prac- tical, so elevating, that we would rescue the word from its connection with the supernatural, the mysterious, the un- real ; we would have it represent what it really is, the high- est phase of human knowledge. A true philosophy must show that all phases of life and mind are but parts of a whole, it must establish the unifica- tion of knowledge. The zenith of human knowledge is our religion (using the word in its true sense) ; it is our appreciation of the divine, or the most general. What we wish to prove, therefore, is that the thoughts SUPERSTITION AND MYSTERY. 375 and emotions which accompany right conduct are higher and more general than those conceptions which we call super- stitions ; that, in a word, a just conception of God is ap- proached more nearly through right action than through the undisciplined efforts of the imagination, however legiti- mate custom may have made them appear. We find nothing in the superstitions of the lower races, such as the Fuegians, Andamans, Veddahs, and Australians, which can justify the name of religion, although almost all Christian superstitions have their counterpart in the beliefs of these most degraded of human beings. We see much, however, in the virtues ascribed to these savages, that sug- gests religious life. Are not the emotions which accompany the chastity, the honesty, and the kindliness found among the lowest savages higher than those emotions which accom- pany their ignorant dreads ? If superstition, or belief in mystery, is but the negative side of religion, is it not in its gradual disappearance that we find true religious develop- ment ? Has not real religion more to do with conduct than with merely formal beliefs, if a choice must be made ? If, as can be demonstrated, Morality increases as superstition disappears, why should we not define religion as morality in its widest sense (i. e. right thought as well as right action), and seek the dawning of religious sentiment in the dawn- ing of moral life ? We have a wealth of data to support the assertion that the religion of each nation is to be estimated by the rectitude of its action and thought. Let us begin with the relation of language to morality. " Philologists may continue long to dispute over the precise origin of language ; but philology has brought us so far that there can be now no question that the primitive speech of mankind was of the rudest char- acter, devoid almost utterly of abstract words, unfit for the use of any kind of men save such as were in the earliest stage of thought. It is probably true that the mental and moral attainment of any people, all that shows their progress along the path of civilization, is (in mathematical phrase) in 376 THE RELIGION OF PHILOSOPHY. a direct ratio with the number of their abstract words. If, therefore, the history of language points back to a time when man had no abstractions, what could have been his mental condition then ? * * * It belongs to our mental con- stitution that, without any distinct names for them, we can entertain no clear ideas. Without language to give it form, we can have at the best only the rudiments of thought." * Again, it is a well-understood principle in ethics, that our conceptions of right and wrong are limited by the scope of human life ; that right means in its deepest sense human, and wrong inhuman. No generalization, however extended, can relieve us from this limitation of duty. Thus our ideals of Justice and Mercy have no appeal from humanity. When an issue arises between the good of our race and any other order of creation, our inability to form ethical concep- tions which are independent of humanity becomes apparent. The scope of language brings us inevitably to the same conclusion ; for words all spring at first from physical facts or sensations, and the process of sublimation by which they become abstractions is merely the addition to their original simple meaning of larger and larger applications of the same fact. The word Right, for instance, which is one of our highest abstractions, " had once its place in the physical body, and without the need of any deep philological knowl- edge we can see what its first meaning was. We at once connect the Latin rectus with porrectus, meaning stretched out or straight. This brings us back to the German recken, to stretch. We therefore get upon the scent of right as meaning first straight, and earlier still stretched, stretched and straight being originally really the same words, the straight string being the stretched string. We have further proof, if further proof were wanted, a Greek root, opzy opeyrvaiy opeyei, with the same significance of stretched or straight ; and, finally, we find that all these words are con- nected with a Sanskrit arf, which means ' to stretch/ What is stretched, then, is straight, and the straight way is the 1 Keary : " Outlines of Primitive Belief," pp. 6, 9. SUPERSTITION AND MYSTERY. 3/7 right way. (Again) Will (Latin volo, voluntas) is a word which seems remote enough from any physical thing ; yet this, too, may be shown to be grounded in sensation. In the first place, will is only the more instantaneous wish, and is connected with the German wdhlen, to choose, and ulti- mately with the Sanskrit var, to choose, ' to place, or draw out first.' With this root we must connect the Latin verus, veritas, the Lithuanian and Sclavonic ve'pa, vera, ' belief.' Verus, or veritas, is, therefore, what is credible, or, earlier still, the thing chosen ; and the old Latin proverb, reduced to its simplest terms, stands thus : ' Great is the thing chosen ; it will prevail.' ' In thus tracing to the simplest physical experiences the origin of moral ideas, the favorite theory of a mysterious and inexplicable conscience or moral intuition is removed ; and the interdependent development of language and thought is shown to be the first condition of true relig- ious life. We must, of course, choose, at the very outset of the in- quiry, between ceremony and right conduct as the measure of religion, or we shall have no criterion to go by. We are told that the ancient Mexicans were " most de- voted to their religion and persistent in their superstitions." They had numberless deities and a complicated mythology. There were " gods of provinces, classes, trades, vices, etc. * * * The chief gods of the main tribes of Mexico appear to be deified men. * * * With the Zapotecs, worship of a dead chief is positively ascertained." Worship of animals, elements, and objects in nature, was common, as well as a belief in three distinct heavens and four previous worlds and mankinds. These most elaborate beliefs were accompa- nied by a vast ecclesiastical organization. " The number of priests among the Mexicans corresponded with the multitude of gods and temples." The priests in the great temple, some historians estimate, were over five thousand, and " there could not have been less than a million priests in the 1 Keary : " Outlines of Primitive Belief," p. n. 378 THE RELIGION OF PHILOSOPHY. Mexican Empire." As a counterpart to this vast religio- ceremonial life, in which human sacrifice was one of the principal features, we find a low grade of morality and mind, an undeveloped language, no thought, no literature. The people were abjectly submissive and very indolent. " They had been accustomed to act only from fear of punishment." They were cruel in war and practised cannibalism (though upon members of other tribes only). " The influence of religion (?) upon their life seems, on the whole, notwith- standing many moral injunctions, to have been a pernicious one, on account of human sacrifices, confessions, and fatal- istic doctrines ; while apart from religion, the wish to have the good opinion of the tribe was productive of noble deeds." ' The Veddahs of Ceylon, supposed to be the descendants of the aboriginal inhabitants of that island, and who are said to have preserved the same mode of life for thousands of years, are thus described : " They have no idols, offer no sacrifices, pour no libations." They have no knowledge of God, no temples, prayers, or charms; in short, no instinct of worship, except, it is reported, some addiction to ceremonies in order to avert storms and lightning. The only evidence of worship among them is the vague belief in the guardian- ship of the spirits of the dead. " Every near relative be- comes a spirit after death and watches over the welfare of those who are left behind." This belief seems to be univer- sal among savages, and has by no means disappeared among civilized men. The only religious ceremony which the Veddah performs is to invoke the " shade of the departed." The spirits of children are most frequently called upon. " The most common form of this ceremony is to fix an arrow upright in the ground and dance slowly around it chanting the following invocation, which is almost musical in its rhythm : " * Ma miya, ma miy, ma deya' ! Topang koyihetti mittigan yanda'h ? ' 1 How much more nearly correct it would be to use the word superstition .instead of religion ! SUPERSTITION AND MYSTERY. 379 ' My departed one, my departed one, my God ! Where art thou wandering ?' " And yet these benighted wild men are said to be temperate, fond of their children, gentle, mild, and affectionate to one another, rarely guilty of grave crimes. Their conjugal fideli- ty is remarkable (the more so as their neighbors, the Sin- ghalese, are very loose in this respect) ; they resent with indignation any reflection on the honor of their women. They are proverbially truthful and honest, and grateful for favors. Murder is almost unknown among them. But we are told they have no language properly so called. " Their communications with one another are made by signs, grimaces, and guttural sounds which be"ar little or no resem- blance to distinct words or systematical language. * * * As may be supposed, the vocabulary of such a barbarous race is very limited. It contains only such phrases as are required to describe the most striking objects of nature, and those which enter into the daily life of the people themselves. So rude and primitive is their dialect, that the most ordinary objects and actions of life are described by quaint para- phrases. As, for example, to walk is 'to beat the ground with hammers ' ; a child is ' a bud ' ; the grains of rice are 1 round things ' ; an elephant is not inappropriately termed *a beast like a mountain.' " 1 Thus we are warned against forming any hasty gen- eralizations concerning the interdependence of moral and intellectual development ; for we find many savage tribes singularly virtuous and yet entirely without definite speech. But as virtue cannot exist without at least some definiteness of ideas, it would be interesting to know what amount of reasoning is necessary to fix such principles as conjugal fidelity, truthfulness, and honesty in the mind. It is plain that the most primitive language admits of the necessary amount of reasoning, for none of the savage dialects are adequate to express with accuracy any ideas beyond the monotonous details of daily life, and few of them are equal 1 Spencer's " Descriptive Sociology," Chart No. 3. 380 THE RELIGION OF PHILOSOPHY. even to this. Of the language of the Dyaks it is said : " At a village of the Ida'an, North Borneo, we found the villagers very careless of their pronunciation ; for instance, the word * heavy ' was at different times written down magat, bagat, wagat, and ogat ; for ' rice/ wagas and ogas ; for ' to bathe,' fadshu, padsiu, and madsiu, and indifferently pronounced in these various ways by the same people." And yet the fundamental moral sentiments of this tribe seem to be quite definite. The Dyaks " are mainly hospitable, honest, kindly, humane to a degree which well might shame ourselves." Chastity and private morality stand high among them ; " infidelity to marriage is an almost unheard-of crime." " Adultery is a crime unknown, and no Dyak (Land) ever recollected an instance of its occurrence." : We may read the history of the Christian nations in vain for such an assertion ; and yet how can we compare the com- plexity, the definiteness, and the beauty of the languages of Europe with the dialects of the Malays or the lowest races? Guizot tells us that the great distinguishing feature of European civilization is its vast complexity of motives, its juxtaposition of many and different types of a political, social, moral, and religious character ; and that this cauldron of conflicting activities has been seething and bubbling through the dark ages, the crusades, the revival of learning, the wars of the Reformation, and the French and the English revolutions, until something morally great will yet result from it. Does the present attitude which the nations of Europe preserve toward one another warrant this prediction ? Is there any thing in the relations of the great Christian nations which promises a cessation of the discords of our civilization, which promises that equanimity, that balance of forces, which alone can secure human happiness ? Let it be our aim to discover in what degree the imperfections of language account for the confusion in beliefs and sentiments which we see about us. We cannot consider ourselves 1 See Boyle's " Borneo." * Low's " Sarawak." SUPERSTITION AND MYSTERY. 381 much above savages until we put aside savage imperfections of thought and feeling, and at least agree upon a definition of Life and of God. No one can read the chapters on Animism in Tylor's " Primitive Culture " without being convinced that all sav- ages and almost all civilized men believe in some form of spiritual apparition or ghostly existence. From the negroes of South Guinea, who are such dreamers and believers in dreams that they have no control over their imaginations, uttering falsehoods without intention and being unable to distinguish the real from the ideal, to the German philoso- pher who declares that the real is the ideal ; from the Tagals of Luzon, who object to waking a sleeper on account of the absence of his soul during sleep, to the Christian Father St. Augustine, who devoutly believed in the reality of the phantastic images of his dreams ; we have in our habits of thought and in our language a clear inheritance of this childish and savage belief in the existence of another self. The doctrine of the immortality of the soul is but another form of this same belief, and it so clings to us that those who reject it on the highest philosophical and moral grounds are regarded as unable to appreciate the full importance and significance of life: as though to postulate a supernatural existence could magnify or ennoble in any degree the facts of actual life. The savage belief in ghosts or shades is carefully taught in all our theological seminaries, not excepting the Unitarian seats of learning. It takes the form of a faith in the reality of the hosts of heaven, which, as nearly as we can learn, are supposed to be the surviving spirits of mortals of diverse ages and civilizations who dwell in the cosmical vicinity of a personal God. To revert to other nations for a counterpart of this super- stition about the impossible subdivisions of personality, we have " the distinction which the ancient Egyptians seem to have made in the Ritual of the Dead between the man's ba, akh y ka, khaba, translated by Mr. Birch as his ' soul/ ' mind,' 382 THE RELIGION OF PHILOSOPHY. * existence/ ' shade ' ; or the Rabbinical division into what may be roughly described as the bodily, spiritual, and celes- tial souls ; or the distinction between the emanative and ge- netic souls in Hindu philosophy ; or the distribution of life, apparition, ancestral spirit, among the three souls of the Chinese ; or the demarcations of the nous, psyche, andflneuma, or of the anima and animus ; or the famous classic and mediaeval theories of the vegetal, sensitive, and rational souls." ' We notice in the Sociological Charts containing the com- pilations of facts of this order, classified by Herbert Spencer, that the columns devoted to what are commonly called the religious ideas of the lower races, the Malayo-Polynesian, the North and the South American, the African, and the Asiatic races, are all headed by the word " Superstitions," while the columns of similar data belonging to the ancient Mexicans, the Central Americans, the Peruvians, the Hebrews, the Phoenicians, the English, and the French races are dignified by the name of " Religious Ideas." In this distinction we see the universal tendency to call those superstitions religious which most resemble our own religion. The writing of these lines was interrupted by a visit to a Unitarian church, whose pastor is famed for his scientific acquirements. He is widely acknowledged to be a man of liberal attainments and fine moral perceptions. He preaches from a pulpit which is supposed to be entirely untrammelled by dogma of any kind. His discourse was upon the parentage and life 'of Jesus. He declared his belief that the great moral reformer of Galilee was born naturally ; and enlarged beautifully upon the sanctity and purity of the marital rela- tion, against which all the asceticism of Christianity is a direct attack. He then spoke of the interest that the heavenly hosts took in the birth of Jesus; and continued fluently to discourse about the angels, who, he said, take an interest in our lives and actually rejoice when we do right and weep when we sin. He spoke of God as hearing and seeing us 1 Tylor's " Primitive Culture," vol. I., p. 435. SUPERSTITION AND MYSTERY. 383 and enjoying all the advantages of the human senses and emotions. He said, Jesus was not asleep in Nazareth, but looking upon us with open eyes and taking an active inter- est in our daily existence. In listening to this sermon I could not help wondering what sort of immortals the poor Veddahs and Dyaks were, and whether their uncultivated morality was appreciated in para- dise ; whether the twenty thousand human victims sacrificed in the ancient Mexican Empire in a single year had, by vir- tue of their death, any privileges in heaven ; and above all, whether the knowledge of God which the angels enjoy depended upon an earthly or a seraphic dialect for its devel- opment. I could not help thinking that if, in America, in this century, cultivated and liberal people are satisfied with such logical co-ordinations as a discourse upon angels and a distinctly human God, our language, with all its resources, is little better than the drivelling speech of the Veddahs and the Dyaks, and that little more can be expected from its use in the way of morality than from the inarticulate mumblings of these degraded races. Should not a reform in the higher functions of language, or the use of general terms, which would be sufficiently deep to insure any visible moral im- provement in our nation, be of necessity so widespread that our little children would be able to classify a discourse on angels and a personal God with the stories of giants and invisible princes with which they are so harmlessly enter- tained ? How is truth to be acted until it is more perfectly thought ? How can logical crimes be detected while our speech is so slovenly that such distinct principles as general and individual existence can be hopelessly entangled with- out exciting the attention of minds that rank far above the average ? The " Religious Ideas " of the Hebrews of the pre-Egyp- tian and Egyptian periods are described as follows : " They believed in revelations by way of dreams. The dead were supposed to meet their kindred in the grave. A plural form 384 THE RELIGION OF PHILOSOPHY. '(Elohim) indicates a polytheistic belief. El Shadai (' the powerful ') revealed himself to Abraham." There were " sacred stones, trees, and groves. Teraphim (' the enrich- ing ones ') were a sort of household gods. Many gods (probably those of the several Semitic tribes assembled in Goshen) were worshipped. Yahveh (a name of doubtful etymological meaning) revealed himself as the God of Israel to Moses. * * * In the period of wanderings, a motley variety of religious phenomena prevailed. There were tribes, but no nation. The names of tribal deities are perhaps preserved in the names of some tribes. Moses conceived Yahveh in a moral spirit ; he objected to the bull worship, yet he made a brazen serpent (nehushtan). * * * After the establishment in Palestine the Israelitish tribes adopted Canaanitish ideas and practices (Baal, Ashera). Yet Yahveh was regarded as the God of Israel and Israel as the people of Yahveh (i. e. he was supposed to be one of many gods)." It was during the period of the Two Kingdoms that the belief in hosts of angels seems to have grown up in Israel ; and, strange to say, it was about this time that the notion of Satan, " a special evil spirit set apart," " the accuser of man- kind," gained possession of the popular mind. The belief in ghosts, spectres, and powerful men, and the worship of an- cestors, are abundantly instanced in the Hebrew Scriptures, and show us how faithfully all the lower orders of super- stition were reproduced in the Hebrew mind. " Down to the exile it evidently was quite common to conjure the dead chiefs, and to imitate by ventriloquistic tricks the chirping voice of the dwellers of the air, and the groaning one of those ^residing in the underworld." "And when they say unto you, ' Consult the ghost-seers and the wizards, that chirp and that mutter; should not people consult their gods, even the dead (mSttm), on behalf of the living ? * Hearken not unto them." " Nor did the Hebrews remain strangers to the belief in demons and spectres ; they professed their faith in the exist- ence of Shedim, that is, lords or masters, implying various SUPERSTITION AND MYSTERY. 385 kinds of foreign deities or evil spirits ; and to them they not only offered sacrifices (Deut. xxxii., 17), but slaughtered their children (Ps. cvi., 37) ; they attributed reality to the Lilith, a night-spectre, dwelling in desolate ruins (Isa. xxxiv., 14), and, according to Eastern legends, rushing forth in the dead of the night, in the form of a beautiful woman, to seize children and to tear them to pieces." ] We have no difficulty, therefore, in tracing back to the Hebrews many of the absurd superstitions which lurk in the Christian faith. But we have good reason to feel discour- aged when we find a prominent minister of the only Chris- tian sect which makes any pretensions to a true literary spirit (a true appreciation of human history), discoursing about the angels in heaven and a personal God, and actually worshipping the shade of a Hebrew prophet. We are also at a loss to know why the " Religious Ideas " of the Hebrews should not be classed with the " Supersti- tions " of other nations, unless it be that their accompany- ing ecclesiastical organization entitles them to rank with the established religions of the Asiatics, the Egyptians, and the ancient Mexicans. We look in vain among the superstitions of the Asiatic tribes for any thing more gross than the religious ideas of the Hebrews contained. That universal ancestor-worship unconsciously carried on by Christians is everywhere ap- parent. The dead chief has given way to the personal God of Abraham, of Isaac, and of Jacob, or the Yahveh of Moses ; fetich worship has risen from the familiar earth to heaven, where our dead ancestors and children live praising the Lord of Hosts. We do not lay food and arms on the graves of the departed, but we preserve the generic descend- ant of this ceremony in the Eucharist. Instead of sacri- ficing upon tombs we build altars in churches, and bury our dead around the sacred edifice. Hardly a bell tolls in the Christian world but we simulate to ourselves a human sacri- 1 For above quotations see Spencer's " Descriptive Sociology," book VII. t part 2, B, Hebrews and Phoenicians. 386 THE RELIGION OF PHILOSOPHY. fice, " Christ shedding his blood for the redemption of man- kind " ; and we wonder at the ancient Mexicans, who merely carried the same idea into practice. We teach our children all sorts of distorted ideas about nature, which would be childish if they were not criminal; we pervert their natural intuitions of justice and humanity by absurd doctrines of mystical retribution, unnatural par- don and cancellation of sin ; the most savage notions of a great spirit are perpetuated in the doctrine of a special providence whose purposes are past judgment. Then we classify the idolatrous and blood-thirsty Hebrews and our- selves as religious ; we extend the courtesy of the same clas- sification, with certain reservations, to the ancient Mexicans, and to some of the Asiatics and the Egyptians; but all the other ancestor-worshippers, to whom we owe almost every religious notion which we possess, we relegate to the baser level of superstition. With all our railroads, steamships, and telegraphs, our schools and universities, our halls of justice and legislation, to say nothing of our priests and churches, we do not possess the average morality of the Dyaks or the humanity of the Veddahs. With all our boasted intelligence, language, and religion, we are unable to bring the individual up to as high a level of chastity, of honesty, and of general virtue, as that occupied by these pitiable tribes of primitive men and women. The reason is, that we are unwilling to believe that there can be any real progress which does not rest upon morality, any justice which does not point to the divine unity of life, any humanity or religion which does not rise above the conception of a personal God. We are puzzled to define the term civilization, because we find in the midst of our vaunted progress the lowest orders of superstition, the most primitive conceptions of life and duty; and we are thus unable to distinguish that re- ligion which should be our most glorious achievement from the childish beliefs of savages. Until we have so developed our language as to place beyond the pale of possibility a re- SUPERSTITION AND MYSTERY. 387 turn to these barbarisms of thought and feeling, are we not in danger of handing down the vast structures of our civiliza- tion as mere monuments of failure to the races to come ? Thus we see that the darkness in which the primitive man groped yields nothing to modern research excepting the picture of his feeble generalizations, his first efforts to un- derstand himself and nature, which are given in his rude virtues and his ruder superstitions. Upon the supposition that the religion of a people is the portrayal of their most general conceptions can be built up a complete theory of Knowledge ; but it is important to re- member that language is the mind of society, and that in relatively advanced nations there can be found what might be called a high-water mark of induction, a highest logical achievement, to which the tides of humanity make but a distant approach. Until the researches of Sir William Jones, in the year 1783, and of those who followed him in the study of Sanskrit, the religious thought of ancient India was a blank to the modern world. Through the insensible growth of language the venerable philosophy, the best thought and feeling, of an ancient people has been safely conveyed over the boundaries of race and language into the very heart of our era. The translations of Sanskrit seemed like a flood of new light to Christendom, but it was only the uncovering of an old mine which humanity had worked out ages before, and whose glittering gems have been worn ever since, descending as heirlooms through long generations. A great truth, a refined sentiment, can be expressed in any civilized tongue ; languages may be forgotten and rediscovered ; but these facts of existence live on through the changes of race and speech, each age reproducing them with unfailing accu- racy. Observe, in proof of this, the dreadful monotony of metaphysics. Read Plato, the writings of the Alexandrians, the Christian theologians from the time of the Scholastics to the present day, decipher Kant and Hegel ; then turn to the oldest Indian philosophy, the oldest Egyptian speculations, as they appear in the religions of these countries ; and we 388 THE RELIGION OF PHILOSOPHY. find the same struggle over being and non-being, spiritual essence and material form ; the same attempted difference between time and eternity ; the same divine unity, one and eternal, contrasted with the changing variety of the senses. The communication of these thoughts from one nation to another has been an insensible process, which has in nowise waited for the rediscovery of languages or the new literary criticism of our day. But if language has preserved all these truths and subjected them to that development which can alone come from the general progress of knowledge, or the growth of morality, how are we to account for the apparently fixed and unyielding form which the higher speculations have assumed ? Why is it that German, French, and English speculations have not surpassed in metaphysical insight the best thought of Egypt, India, and Greece ? Are the people who embody the teachings of Kant, Descartes, and Spencer to be compared to those who designed the pyramids, wrote the Vedas, or questioned the Delphic Oracle ? How are these nations to be compared ? The difference between civilizations is best portrayed by a comparison of the KNOWLEDGE of the respective races ; but when the term knowledge is identified with life, the comparison is lost in receding equations. When, however, we put the proposition in a religious form, it will readily gain acceptance ; for the assertion that races and civilizations are to be measured by the spread of the divine spirit among them, by the quality and extent of their knowledge of God, is a truism for all devout minds. Our proposition, then, is, that the completeness and sym- metry with which a nation has performed that great induc- tion which leads from particulars to generals, from the lowest forms of sentiency to the highest generalizations, is the only true measure of its life. If we would rise above the past, therefore, if we would place a permanent distinction between our civilization and that of the lowest savages, or the great intermediate races, we must improve our language so that its most general SUPERSTITION AND MYSTERY. 389 terms will cease to be employed as the vehicle of supersti- tion and mysteries. The question then arises : Can such an understanding of language be made to harmonize with any existing religion? Will not such light as this prove fatal to Christianity? In order to answer this question, it will be necessary to glance at the most prominent facts of general religious history with a view to ascertaining the immediate origin of our religious beliefs. CHAPTER XVIII. THE RELIGIONS OF EGYPT AND INDIA. In Egypt the Belief in Immortality Reached its Highest Development Mysti- cism and Idealism. THE Egyptians were the most pious people of antiquity. They seem to have expended more time and energy in religious observances, and to have had a more realistic con- ception of a future life, than any other race. Their writings, says M. Maury, " are full of sacred symbols and allusions to divine myths, perfectly useless apart from the Egyptian religion. Literature and the sciences were only branches of the theology, while its books formed a sacred code, supposed to be the work of the god Thoth, likened by the Greeks to their Hermes. The arts were only practised to add to the worship and glorification of the gods or deified kings. " The religious observances were so numerous and so im- perative that it was impossible to practise a profession, to prepare food, or to attend to the simplest daily needs with- out constantly calling to mind the rules established by the priests. Each province had its special gods, its particular rights, its sacred animals. Neither the dominion of the Per- sians, nor that of the Ptolemies, nor that of the Romans, was able to change this antique religion of the Pharaohs ; of all polytheisms, it opposed the most obstinate resistance to Christianity, and continued to live on up to the sixth century of our era. It is because the Egyptian religion had pene- trated so deeply into the mind of the people and the customs of the country, that it became, so to speak, a part of the in- tellectual and physical organization of the race." * 1 Alfred Maury : Revue des Deux Mondes, Sept., 1867. 3QO THE RELIGIONS OF EGYPT AND INDIA. 391 The animal-worship of the Egyptians, which is the term generally applied to their religion, was, of course, a form of idolatry, but a far less materialistic form than is generally supposed. The priests of the early dynasties taught (before the practice of image-worship had grown up) that their con- ception of the God of the universe could not be expressed by any image made by hands, and that they therefore preferred to take a living creature to symbolize the power and wisdom of the Creator, a singularly pure and beautiful idea. The conception of God as a person having human form and feel- ings, exercising a divine will in his government of all nature, and loving, punishing, forgiving, and caring for his children, is surely as near an approach to making an image of God as was the practice of setting up living creatures as symbols of certain divine attributes. Where, after all, shall we find a religion without idolatry ? Our very words and thoughts are symbols. Even to say that God is the universal principle, is to symbolize the most general fact, to create a sign that will call up this conception in the minds of others. Speaking of the innumerable gods of the Egyptians and of the vast machinery of worship which they carried on, Mr. Clarke says : " Every day has its festival, every town its god and temple. Sacrifices, prayers, incense, processions, begin and close the year. The deities, we discover, are innumer- able. Great triads of gods, superior to the rest, are wor- shipped under different names in the different provinces. Every year the festivals of Osiris and Isis renew the mourn- ing for the Divine Sufferer, and joy at his resurrection. The tombs are resplendent with mosaics and brilliantly colored paintings. The dead are more cared for than the living ; their resting-places are carved out of solid rock and filled with rich furniture and ornaments. One supreme being, above all other deities, is worshipped as the maker and preserver of all things." ' So vast a subject as the morality of a nation whose exist- ence can be traced back for seven thousand years would be 1 " Ten Great Religions," vol. II., p. 7. 392 THE RELIGION OF PHILOSOPHY. hazardous to deal with in any but the most general manner. After the fifth dynasty a great calamity seems to have fallen upon the people which destroyed for a time their civiliza- tion. This calamity was probably a nomadic invasion, and must have revolutionized the whole national life. It is diffi- cult, therefore, to select moral characteristics which survive throughout such sweeping changes in a nation's existence. All authors agree that the notions of divine existence, the ideas of the lives of the gods, and the general tenor of prayer or the manner of addressing the gods, indicate a singular purity of life in ancient Egypt. Bonwick says : " An entire confidence in the goodness and integrity of their deities is the most pleasing attribute of the Egyptian mind. No Greek could trust his lying, treacherous, unstable, and immoral gods. " On a tomb of the eleventh dynasty, B.C. 3000, the de- ceased is made to say : ' I have ever kept from sin, I have been truth itself on the earth. Make me luminous in the skies ! Make me justified ! May my soul prosper ! ' Upon, a papyrus we read this touching appeal : ' My god ! My god ! O that thou wouldst show me the true god ! ' * * * " A prophet of Osiris says : ' I have venerated my father. I have respected my mother. I have loved my brothers. I have done nothing evil against them during my life on earth. I have protected the poor against the powerful. I have given hospitality to every one. I have been benevolent, and loving the (?) gods. I have cherished my friends, and my hand has been open to him who had nothing. I have loved truth, and hated a lie/ * * * " A prayer from their Scriptures the Ritual for the Dead gives a part of the confession the soul must make after death. * * * The I25th chapter of the Ritual contains this: 1 Homage to thee, great god, lord of truth and justice ! I am come to thee, O my master. I present myself to thee, and contemplate thy perfecting. I know you, lord of truth and justice. I have brought you the truth. I have committed no fraud against men. I have not tormented the widow. I THE RELIGIONS OF EGYPT AND INDIA. 393, have not lied in the tribunal. I know not lies. I have not done any prohibited thing. I have not commanded my workman to do more than he could do. I have not been idle. I have not made others weep. I have not made fraudulent gains. I have not altered the grain-measure. I have not falsified the equilibrium of the balance. I have not taken away the milk from the foster-child. I have not driven sacred beasts from the pastures. I am pure. I am pure.' " 1 Again Mr. Clarke thus testifies to the morality of the Egyptians : " Many of the virtues which we are apt to suppose a monopoly of Christian culture appear as the ideal of these old Egyptians. Brugsch says a thousand voices from the tombs of Egypt declare this. One inscrip- tion in Upper Egypt says : ' He loved his father, he honored his mother, he loved his brethren, and never went from his home in bad temper. He never preferred the great man to the low one.' Another says: 'I was a wise man, my soul loved God. I was a brother to the great men and a father to the humble ones, and never was a mischief-maker.' An inscription at Sais, on the tomb of a priest who lived in the sad days of Cambyses, says : ' I honored my father, I esteemed my mother, I loved my brothers. I found graves for the unburied dead. I instructed little children. I took care of orphans as though they were my own children. For great misfortunes were on Egypt in my time, and on this city of Sais.' * * * The following inscription is from the tombs of Ben-Hassen, over a Nomad Prince : ' What I have done I will say. My goodness and my kindness were ample. I never oppressed the fatherless nor the widow. I did not treat cruelly the fishermen, the shepherds, or the poor laborers. There was nowhere in my time hunger or want ; for I cultivated all my fields, far and near, in order that their inhabitants might have food. I never preferred the great and powerful to the humble and poor, but did equal justice to all.' A king's tomb at Thebes 1 '* Egyptian Belief and Modern Thought." 394 THE RELIGION OF PHILOSOPHY. gives us in few words the religious creed of a Pharaoh, which Moses seems hardly to have appreciated : ' I lived in truth, and fed my soul with justice. What I did to men was done in peace, and how I loved God, God and my heart well know. I have given bread to the hungry, water to the thirsty, clothes to the naked, and a shelter to the stranger. I honored the gods with sacrifices, and the dead with offer- ings. A rock at Lycopolis pleads for an ancient ruler in the same unmistakable tones. Hundreds of stones in Egypt announce, as the best gifts which the gods can bestow on their favorites, ' the respect of men and the love of women.' ' Thus we see that the morality of the Egyptians had the same direct and simple source as that of other races, namely, those perceptions of justice and purity which are engendered by measuring the feelings of others by our own. The daily life of the Egyptian people seems to have been a physical expression of their theology. Certain days in the year were set apart for observances which corresponded to events in the lives of their gods. " In an old papyrus described by De Rouge it is said : ' On the twelfth of Chorak no one is to go out of doors, for on that day the transformation of Osiris into the bird Wennu took place. On the fourteenth of Toby no voluptuous songs must be listened to, for Isis and Nepthys bewail Osiris on that day. On the third of Mechir no one can go on a journey, because Set then began a war.' ' The theology of Egypt indicates a great depth of thought. The whole nation seemed to be physically employed in illus- trating its conceptions ; but the vast majority were as unconscious of the meaning of their religion as the physio- logical units in a human organism are unconscious of the genius of the life in which they take part. A great system of myths and superstitions had grown up during an im- measurable past. The best minds, no doubt, were able to decipher in all this a great thought, a commanding general- 1 See " Ten Great Religions," pp. 221, 222. THE RELIGIONS OF EGYPT AND INDIA. 395 ization ; but the majority of the priests and the people, as in our day, were content with the symbols, and never went beyond them. The mysteries which the priests so carefully guarded were connected with their scientific knowledge, and were not unmixed with the art of magic, hence the awe with which the people regarded them. In the Egyptian theology there were two branches or de- partments, the esoteric or internal, and the exoteric or ex- ternal. The former was an interpretation of nature and life which the priests built up among themselves ; it exhibited remarkable knowledge and philosophic insight ; but, probably for the want of a better language, it was for the most part expressed in the form of deities and their attributes. We can judge of the penetration of these inquiries from the fact that they included among others the theory that " Matter is but the rotating portions of something which fills the whole of space" The latter was the more concrete and fabulous form of religion taught to the people, and which was suited to their understanding. There must have been a great disparity of intelligence even among the priests themselves. In witness of which mark the incongruity between their best inductions and the clumsy symbolism in which we find them expressed. Not to dwell too long on the complex subject of Egyptian theology, suffice it to say that there were three orders of gods, which corresponded to three orders of interpretation of nature. The first dealt with general principles, and mani- fested a remarkable power of analysis. The second and third orders of gods descended from general principles to particu- lars, and became thoroughly anthropomorphic, assuming the minutest details of human life. Looking at the history of Egypt from a distance, the most striking features are the pyramid-building age, chiefly confined to the fourth dynasty, and the reign of Rameses II., the most brilliant epoch of the Empire. Since Champollion (1822) deciphered the hieroglyphic inscriptions, the greatest archaeological discovery of modern times, the history of Egypt has gradually unfolded itself until a dim outline is 396 THE RELIGION OF PHILOSOPHY. discerned ; but scarcely more than this can yet be claimed. The fact that the most ancient writers of the Egyptians re- garded time in the cyclical light, fixing no era from which to reckon events, makes it almost impossible to arrive at any definite dates until the historical age is fairly begun by other nations. It is generally conceded that at least four thousand years would have been necessary for the development of the civilization which appeared in Egypt at the beginning of the fourth dynasty, when the Great Pyramid was built by Cheops. Ages before this, Menes emerges from the mytho- logical period, the age of divine reigns which precedes the beginning of Egyptian history. It is agreed by all Egyp- tologists, however, that Menes is no legendary personage, but that he founded the Egyptian state by uniting its many parts into one nation, and that he began the building of the city of Memphis. The first dynasty, beginning with the reign of Menes, is estimated by Mariette Bey as 5004 B.C., and by Professor Lepsius as 3892 B.C. The reign of twenty-six dynasties, or families of kings, is counted from Menes to the conquest of Egypt by the Persians ; but owing to the division of the na- tion into as many as five kingdoms, these dynasties were not consecutive, several royal families during certain periods reigning at the same time. When the Assyrian Empire fell, the Egyptians regained their independence under the Theban Amenophis, who became king of the whole country, and founded the eighteenth dynasty. But the nation was soon again conquered by Nebuchadnezzar, and paid tribute to the Babylonians until Egypt was absorbed by the Persian Em- pire. Previous to this the separate kingdoms had been overcome one by one by the invasion of a race of nomads, which resulted in the rule of the Shepherd Kings, during which Egyptian civilization suffered a long decline. It is in the reign of the last shepherd king that Joseph, who is acknowledged to be an historical character, is supposed to have been in power. It is almost impossible to obtain reliable details of the THE RELIGIONS OF EGYPT AND INDIA. 397 sojourn and oppression of the Hebrews in Egypt and their subsequent exodus. The legend, as it appears in the sacred writings of the Jews, is one side of the story, which is gener- ally admitted by scholars to be highly colored and largely fanciful ; while from the detached references to the event gathered from Egyptian inscriptions and other sources, it is difficult to give to it any thing like the co'herency and rela- tive historical importance which it assumes in the Hebrew chronicles. The theology of Egypt centres about the myth of Osiris, which seems to be the oldest religious story in the world. Five thousand years before the beginning of our era, Osiris, a mythological king of Egypt, was worshipped after reigning upon the earth, where he left such a remembrance of his beneficence that he became the type of goodness, the chief moral ideal of the Egyptians. He was betrayed, suffered temporary death, ascended into heaven, where he became the judge of the quick and the dead. The Greek author Athenagoras " laughed gaily at the Egyptian absurdity of weeping for the death of their god, then rejoicing at his resurrection, and afterward sacrificing to him as a divinity." Bonwick says, in speaking of Osiris : " It is idle for us, at this distance of time, to talk of him as a solar myth, or a refined intellectualism of the Egyptians ; he was a person who had lived and died. They had no manner of doubt abo^t it. Did they not know his birthplace ? Did they not celebrate his birth by the most elaborate ceremonies, with cradle, lights, etc. ? Did they not hold his tomb at Abydos ? Did they not annually celebrate at the Holy Sepulchre his resur- rection? Did they not commemorate his death by the Eucharist, eating the Sacred Cake, after it had been conse- crated by the priests, and become veritable flesh of his flesh ? " The solemn strains of the Roman Miserere are but the echoes of the Egyptian dirges representing the grief of Isis. This devoted wife of Osiris, the chief maternal goddess of Egypt, seeks her lost husband round the world and 1 " Egyptian Belief and Modern Thought," p. 162. 398 THE RELIGION OF PHILOSOPHY. through the regions of death. When she has at last recov- ered his remains, her tears and prayers revive him, and the faithful wife miraculously conceives a son. Then she flees with her unborn babe from pursuing enemies. Some say that she was caught up by the sun, others that she bore and suckled the babe Horus in loneliness. Thus Horus, begotten and born after death through tears and prayers, is but the living incarnation of Osiris. Horus was the Egyptian saviour of humanity. He was born in winter, and the annual festivals in celebration of his birth were the beginning of our Christmas rejoicings. This beloved god was the last of the long line of divine rulers, and he was followed by Menes, the first historical king. Isis, the mother of Horus, who was worshipped six thou- sand years ago, was styled by the Egyptians, " ' Our Lady,' the ' Queen of Heaven/ ' Star of the Sea/ ' Governess/ 1 Earth Mother/ ' Rose/ ' Tower/ ' Mother of God/ 1 Saviour of Souls/ t Intercessor/ ' Sanctifier/ ' Immaculate Virgin/ etc. * * * In the story of her love and devotion to Osiris there is a pathos and a tenderness that speak well for the domestic virtues of the Egyptian people who invented and cherished the myth. Only those who believed in faith- ful wives and honored women could have exhibited so noble a specimen of female goodness as seen in their chief divinity. * * * In an ancient Christian work, called the ' Chronicle of Alexandria/ occurs the following : ' Watch how Egypt has consecrated the childbirth of a virgin, and the birth of her son, who was exposed in a crib to the adoration of the people. King Ptolemy having asked the reason of this usage, the Egyptians answered him that it was a mystery taught to their fathers/ " ' It is generally conceded by Egyptologists that Isis is the Virgo of the zodiac. " One sees," says the Arabian writer, Abulmazar, " in the first Decan of the sign of the Virgin, according to the most ancient traditions of the Persians, Chaldeans, Egyptians, of Hermes, and of Esculapius, a 1 " Egyptian Belief and Modern Thought," pp. 141, 143. THE RELIGIONS OF EGYPT AND INDIA. 399 chaste, pure, immaculate virgin, of a beautiful figure and an agreeable face, having an air of modesty, holding in her hand two ears of corn, seated on a throne, nourishing and suckling a young child." Thus, as most of the original Christian theology was for- mulated in Alexandria, we see in its symbols but a repro- duction of the mythology of Egypt. As Isis was carried to heaven by her son Horus, so " the virgin Mary was declared to have been carried there by her glorified son." The im- maculate conception, the symbols of the cradle and the cross, the ceremony of the last supper, the death, the res- urrection, the ascension, and in fact the whole scheme of Christian salvation, have counterparts in the superstitions of ancient Egypt. As the Egyptians were undoubtedly the first historic people, in the mythologies of all other nations we trace a likeness to their beliefs ; just such a likeness as it is natural to suppose was disseminated by the slow inter- course of the earliest races of the world. All superstitions are merely exaggerations of human experiences, consisting for the most part of the incidents of family life. This is the reason why religion is said to be an emotional government, as its beliefs spring from the childhood of our race, in which the emotions have ascendancy over thought. The only emotions which we can trust are moral emo- tions ; and if we deprive our sacred beliefs of every thing that thought cannot approve of and morality can dispense with, superstitions disappear and the religion of Philosophy alone remains. Could a greater service be rendered to humanity than to relieve it of the slavery of its hoary superstitions ? The monuments of Egypt teach the same lesson of myste- rious beliefs. Notwithstanding the incalculable amount of toil which they represent, they are almost wholly the work of superstition, and therefore have contributed little or nothing to the well-being of the race that built them. Such vast structures as the pyramids of Ghizeh or the temples at Karnac must have been national undertakings ; and so far 400 THE RELIGION OF PHILOSOPHY. removed were they from the useful, that their construction must have meant the practical enslavement of large classes of the population. It is difficult to imagine a state of society in which labor could have been sufficiently redundant to explain these enormous ideal enterprises in any other way. The great public works of China and the Roman Empire were national movements, but they were for the public good : the building of the pyramids and temples of Egypt, and the vast religious industry of the nation, on the contrary, must have inflicted grievous burdens upon the people ; illustrat- ing in a striking manner what superstition has cost the world. The literary monuments of this people only repeat the same evidence. The antiquity of the Egyptian Bible is perhaps the most wonderful fact connected with this oldest of nations. Portions of these sacred writings are said to have been written seven thousand years ago. As now collected, they consist chiefly of a ritual of worship for the guidance of the priests, and a " code of existence in the other world." Deveria says : " Not only under the reign of Men-ka-ra, the builder of the Third Pyramid, but even under the fifth king of the first dynasty, certain parts of the sacred book were already discovered, as antiquities, of which the tradition had -been lost" At the Turin Museum is a copy of this wonder- ful prehistoric " Book of the Dead." " It covers one side of the wall. Though in four pieces, it may altogether measure nearly three hundred feet in length. The breadth of the papyrus is from twelve to fifteen inches. Parts are, how- ever, incomplete or obscured by age. * * * Thereon one seems to have the whole Egyptian theology at a glance. Though there is every reason to believe the greater part of the people were at least as well educated in reading as Euro- peans at the beginning of this century, yet the perpetual pictorial display could not fail to be instructive to those un- able to make out the text. The Scriptures must have been well known, as copies of chapters are found by the thousand on the persons of mummies themselves, and on the walls of Ot ffn *& THE RELIGIONS OF EGYPT AND INDIA. 40! the thousands of tombs, which would not have been the case were the living majority unable to read." The doctrine of the immortality of the soul is supposed to have been first elaborated in Egypt. The whole religion of this first civilization is but a mystic reflection of actual life in the form of a resurrected existence, and yet, there is not a single fact of life or mind that can lend reality to this vast dream of futurity. The belief in the immortality of the soul has the combined authority of almost every religion the world has ever known, and yet it is not only a mistaken belief, but in common with all other superstitions it has a demoraliz- ing influence upon life. But how can we hope to overcome such religious supersti- tions, which rest upon mysteries, while even science and phi- losophy cling to the belief that all facts centre in an ultimate mystery or the great unknowable? It would be difficult to find in this century of intellectual progress a scientist or a thinker who does not believe the First Cause to be an unfathomable mystery ; and yet belief in any order of ulti- mate mystery is a self-contradiction just as flagrant as that which is implied in the word unknowable. It disregards the limits of language and the nature of perception, and denies the possibility of the unification of knowledge. Almost every form of mystery can be traced to Egypt. The solemn symbolisms of Freemasonry, which are but efforts to give expression to divine truths, the art of magic, which has been almost wholly associated with re- ligion, and the mystery of immortality upon which all religious superstitions depend, have all apparently come to life in Egypt. Although a belief in magic is widely con- ceded, in our time, to be not only false but vulgar, Chris- tianity has been closely associated with the "mystic art." The rite of baptism, the different degrees of superstition connected with the Lord's Supper, the belief in the power of prayer to convert souls, to cure sickness, and to obtain forgiveness of sins ; the consecration of priests and churches, li4 Egyptian Belief and Modern Thought," pp. 188, 189. 402 THE RELIGION' OF PHILOSOPHY. and even the ceremony of benediction, are all forms of be- lief in the magical or the supernatural. The life of Jesus is full of instances of the same order of belief. It is true that the more recent development of the black art known as Demonology had an Eastern origin and was unknown on the Nile, but the one hundred thousand witches " said to have been destroyed in Protestant churches alone " show that Christianity was not inhospitable even to this innova- tion. In a word, the belief in any form of mystery, from the metaphysical tenet of " an unknowable " to all manner of religious superstition, is diametrically opposed to the higher appreciations of human life. To overcome this insidious error is the first condition to the establishment of a true con- ception of God. The foregoing glance at the beliefs of Egypt, therefore, is intended but to give an idea of the form which this error assumed in the earliest civilization, so that we may recognize it as it reappears in the religions of other nations. We may now turn to another but almost equally ancient faith. The study of the civilizations of India, China, and Japan is excluded from the range of what is generally termed ancient history, because these nations were but little known to the Greeks, who originated history for us. It is prin- cipally through modern research that such knowledge as we have of the life of these nations has been obtained. The study of Sanskrit, begun by the English scholars at Calcutta during the early part of this century, has developed so rap- idly that now nearly all the important universities of the world have established professorships *of this language. It is through the efforts of these students of oriental languages that we are enabled to trace out the history of India and the East, which a short time ago was a blank to the outer world. The literature of India, although very voluminous, is utterly devoid of historical data. Consisting- of poems, mythology, and sacred books, " no piece of THE RELIGIONS OF EGYPT AND INDIA. 403 chronicle, no list of kings," breaks the monotony of these emotional and abstract writings, and we are left to discern the moral character of the people of India, to judge of the thoughts and feelings of this great race, through the agency of fable. These fables consist of a philosophy sus- ceptible of the deepest interpretations, strangely mixed with the most elaborate, grotesque, and even brutal idolatry, and a vast mythology, the joint fruit of widespread religious sen- timent and a gorgeous and unrestrained imagination. It is by a recent movement in science, that the origin of the Hindoo people, which was of late supposed to be undiscover- able, has been made familiar to the reading world. As early as the sixteenth century, Renan tells us, it was discovered that the Hebrews, the Phoenicians, the Carthaginians, the Syrians, Babylon, from a certain period at least, the Arabs, the Abys- sinians, spoke languages wholly cognate. " Eichhorn, in the last century, proposed to call these languages Semitic, and this name, inexact as it is, may as well be retained. * * * The philologists of Germany, Bopp in particular, laid down sure principles, by means of which it was demonstrated that the ancient idioms of Brahmanic India, the different dialects of Persia, the Armenian, many dialects of the Caucasus, the Greek and Latin languages, with their derivatives, the Sclavic languages, the Germanic, the Celtic, formed a vast whole radically distinct from the Semitic group, and this they called Indo-Germanic, or Indo-European." This division of the principal nations of the world into two great groups? however, relies upon more than the generic development of languages; the same division is disclosed by a comparison of their respective literatures, customs, institu- tions, governments and religions. Thus we see that the philosophy of history, great as are its achievements, has scarcely begun the work of portraying the conditions which, are to explain human development. The Aryans, to which name the modern Ivan for Persia and the ancient Ariana for the region about the Indus are traced, occupied those vast plains in Asia lying east of the 404 THE RELIGION OF PHILOSOPHY. Caspian Sea. The division of this primitive race of warlike shepherds into the family of Indo-European nations must have been very gradual, as the results of their early migra- tions are to be seen in the first dynasties of Egypt, a period varying from one to two thousand years before the time at which the Aryans are supposed to have lost their identity in the formation of other nations. The castes into which the Hindoo nation has been so firmly crystallized are, first and highest, the Brahmans, or priestly class, a spiritual aristocracy, which, viewed from every standpoint, is beyond question the most wonderful so- cial phenomenon presented by our race. Beneath them are graded the landed military class, the commercial and agricul- tural, and the servile classes, and the social status of each is minutely provided for in the Vedic law, forming a civilization entirely unique. The oldest works in the Hindoo literature are the Vedas, which, like all the earliest writings of the world, are religious in character. They were composed and preserved by priests, and it is through them alone that we are able to study Hindoo history, as the two great epics are so legendary and fanciful that they give but the vaguest idea of events. " The last hymns of the Vedas were written (says St. Martin) when the Aryans arrived from the Indus at the Ganges and were building their oldest city, at the confluence of that river with the Jumna. Their complexion was then white, and they call the race whom they conquered, and who afterward were made Soudras, or lowest caste, blacks. The chief gods of the Vedic age were Indra, Varuna, Agni, Savitri, Soma. The first was the god of the atmosphere ; the second, of the Ocean of Light, or Heaven ; the third, of Fire ; the fourth, of the Sun ; and the fifth, of the Moon. Yama was the god of Death. All the powers of nature were personified in turn, as earth, food, wine, months, seasons, day, night, and dawn. Among all these divinities Indra and Agni were the chief. But behind this incipient polytheism lurks the original monotheism, for each of THE RELIGIONS OF EGYPT AND INDIA. 405 these gods, in turn, becomes the Supreme Being. The universal Deity seems to become apparent first in one form of nature and then in another. Such is the opinion of Cole- brooke, who says that ' the ancient Hindoo religion recog- nizes but one God, not yet sufficiently discriminating the creature from the Creator.' And Max Miiller says : ' The hymns celebrate Varuna, Indra, Agni, etc., and each in turn is called supreme. The whole mythology is fluent. The powers of nature become moral beings. It would be easy to find, in the numerous hymns of the Veda, passages in which almost every single god is represented as supreme and absolute. Agni is called * Ruler of the Universe ' ; Indra is celebrated as the Strongest god, and in one hymn it is said, ' Indra is stronger than all.' It is said of Soma that ' he conquers every one.' ' To give an idea of the purity of thought and grandeur of expression which these ancient Hindoos commanded, to say nothing of their monotheism, we give a translation by Max Miiller of one of the oldest Vedic hymns in which their idea of the creation is set forth. " RlG-VEDA x, 121. " In the beginning there arose the Source of golden light. He was the only born Lord of all that is. He established the earth, and this sky. Who is the God to whom we shall offer our sacrifice ? " He who gives life. He who gives strength ; whose blessing all the bright gods desire ; whose shadow is immor- tality, whose shadow is death. Who is the God to whom we shall offer our sacrifice ? " He who through his power is the only king of the breathing and awakening world. He who governs all, man and beast. Who is the God to whom we shall offer our sacrifice ? " He whose power these snowy mountains, whose power the sea proclaims, with the distant river. He whose these regions are as it were his two arms. Who is the God to whom we shall offer our sacrifice ? 406 THE RELIGION OF PHILOSOPHY. "He through whom the sky is bright and the earth firm. He through whom heaven was stablished ; nay, the highest heaven. He who measured out the light in the air. Who is the God to whom we shall offer our sacrifice ? " He to whom heaven and earth, standing firm by his will, look up, trembling inwardly. He over whom the rising sun shines forth. Who is the God to whom we shall offer our sacrifice ? " Wherever the mighty water-clouds went, where they placed the seed and lit the fire, thence arose he who is the only life of the bright gods. Who is the God to whom we shall offer our sacrifice ? " He who by his might looked even over the water-clouds, the clouds which gave strength and lit the sacrifice ; he who is God above all gods. Who is the God to whom we shall offer our sacrifice ? " May he not destroy us, he the creator of the earth, or he, the righteous, who created heaven : he who also created the bright and mighty waters. Who is the God to whom we shall offer our sacrifice? " The Vedic literature begins with the hymns called the Rig-Veda; these are divided by Mu'ller into the Chhandas and the Mantras periods. These writings are liturgic in character. The earliest theological writings of India are the Brahmanas. Later on, the philosophic writings called the Upanishads make their appearance ; these are almost the only Vedic writings which are read at the present day ; and if the antiquity claimed for them can be substantiated, i. e. 800 to 600 years B.C., they show clearly that the speculations of the earliest Greeks were anticipated in India. When we think how Egyptian and Babylonian history, also, gives evidence of philosophic thought vastly older than any thing connected with Greece, it would seem possible that the Aryans were not only the progenitors of the language, but the thought, of the Indo-European nations. It may seem venturesome, however, to attribute much philosophic insight 1 Mtiller's "Ancient Sanskrit Literature," p. 569. THE RELIGIONS OF EGYPT AND INDIA. 407 to the warlike shepherds who occupied the regions east of the Caspian Sea, before the earliest dates of even legendary history, and of whom nothing more definite is known than what is suggested by the words traced through convergent languages to them ; but is it more venturesome than to suppose that all the details of metaphysical speculation should be faithfully reproduced in different countries, at great distances in time, without any generic connection ? This is the same question with regard to psychology as that which is presented by the contrasted theories of Darwin and Lewes in biology. Darwin says that organic life began in not more than four or five different points on the earth's surface, and that all subsequent development has been a generic divergence from these points of beginning. Lewes says that the conditions of organic life are far too general to admit of any such narrow beginnings. When we study the general subject of the beginnings of life, and see how clearly organic activities are affiliated with chemical and cosmical activities, are we not irresistibly carried to the larger of these views ? So with regard to the origin of philosophy. If thought is the function of conditions, it is natural to suppose that cer- tain civilizations produce inevitably certain types of thought. The only question is, what constitutes the intellectual germ, or logical type, upon which the social conditions of each age have acted as merely a developing medium. Will not the psychology of the future demonstrate that this logical germ is as deeply seated in every sentient organism as the proper- ties of its physiological units, and is in fact indistinguishable from them ? Our inductions are as natural as the swinging of the pendulum, or the response of the organic compounds to light and heat. There is no break in development between the cosmical and the organic activities expressed in our race and its highest logical genius. An analysis, there- fore, which seeks to discover some ultimate principle as the basis of mind will have to relinquish one special fact after another until it comes face to face with the ultimate reality, the first principle of life. 408 THE RELIGION OF PHILOSOPHY. / In the light of this induction, the thought of Aryan shep- herds, Hindoo priests, the Egyptians, the Greeks, and the most modern European metaphysicians, will assume a level which, in an unphilosophical view of history, would seem im- possible. The thought of the human race, from its earliest beginnings to its best attainments, forms but the base-line in a sentient parallax of infinite proportions. With our compli- cated vocabularies we imagine that we have risen far above the level of those early inductions which mingled dim intui- tions of divine unity with all manner of superstition ; but alas ! after seventy centuries of reform, we find the inarticulate gesture of the primitive man declaring the scope of language and the nature of perception as unerringly as our most scholarly analyses of mind ; and thus the fact of sentiency, viewed through the long avenues of organic development which lead up to it, presents a level scarcely broken by the highest waves of civilization. In a word, so deep-seated in nature are the facts of consciousness, that the difference between the intelligence of races is rendered insignificant when this intelligence is viewed in the true perspectives of its development. It is only in that more complete view of knowl- edge which identifies action with thought, morality with re- ligion, practical with theoretical happiness, that our notions of progress are justified. It is only by subjecting the " tran- scendental properties of the modern intellect " to the disci- pline of actual existence, by denying to the imagination all the extravagances of mystery and superstition, that we are enabled to really distinguish ourselves intellectually or morally from the primitive types of man. The question which presses upon us therefore is, Have we accomplished this distinguishing logical feat ? Following the Brahmana period in Hindoo literature, we have the Sutras, coming from a word meaning string, and consisting of a string of sentences concise and epigrammatic in style, representing the thought of the Brahmans reduced to the simplest form. These writings are supposed to have appeared from 600 to 200 years B.C. The Brahmanas, which THE RELIGIONS OF EGYPT AND INDIA. 409* precede in order of time the Sutras and the philosophic Upanishads, are very numerous. " M Ciller gives stories from them and legends. They relate to sacrifices, to the story of the deluge, and other legends. They substituted these legends for the simple poetry of the ancient Vedas. They must have extended over at least two hundred years, and contain long lists of teachers." But when we call them Vedic writings, we use a form of speech which is inconsist- ent with fact, for the Vedas were not reduced to writing until long after they appeared. They were memorized by the priests and thus transmitted through many centuries. The antiquity of the original Vedic hymns or Rig-Veda cannot be determined with any certainty, although all au- thorities agree in placing them as early as 1200 to 1500 years B.C., while Dr. Haug believes that the oldest hymns were composed B.C. 2400. In the damp climate of India no manuscript will last more than a few centuries, which accounts for the fact that there are few Sanskrit MSS. more than four or five hundred years old. " Miiller supposes that writing was unknown when the Rig-Veda was composed. The thousand and ten hymns of the Vedas contain no mention of writing or books, any more than the Homeric poems. There is no allusion to writing during the whole of the Brahmana period, nor even through the Sutra period. This seems incredible to us only because our memory has been systematically debilitated by newspapers and the like during many generations. It was the business of every Brahman to learn by heart the Vedas during the twelve years of his student life. The Guru, or teacher, pronounces a group of words, and the pupils repeat after him. After writing was introduced, the Brahmans were strictly forbidden to read the Vedas, or to write them. Caesar says the same of the Druids. Even Panini never alludes to written words or letters. None of the ordinary modern words for book, paper, ink, or writing, have been found in any ancient Sans- krit work, no such words as volumen, volume ; liber, or 410 THE RELIGION OF PHILOSOPHY. inner bark of a tree ; byblos, inner bark of papyrus ; or book, that is, beech-wood. But Buddha had learned to write, as we find by a book translated into Chinese, A.D. 76. In this book Buddha instructs his teacher ; as in the ' Gospel of the Infancy' Jesus explains to his teacher the meaning of the Hebrew alphabet. So Buddha tells his teacher the names of sixty-four alphabets. The first authentic inscription in India is of Buddhist origin, belonging to the third century before Christ." The type of religion depicted in the Vedas has long since passed away. At the present day, in India, there is a poly- theism among the people very different from the written religion of the priestly caste. The Brahmans acknowledge the equal divinity of Brahma, Vishnu and Siva, known as the Hindoo triad ; but the great mass of the people worship different gods according to the multitude of sects into which they are divided. There is a large class of unbelievers in India who doubt the inspiration of the Vedas, and even deride the sacred books. The widespread religious feeling of the people may be judged of from the fact that two thirds of all the books sold in that country, according to a recent report from Calcutta, are of a religious character. There is a sect which corresponds to the Quakers of England and America, the Kabirs, a part of whose creed it is to oppose all worship ; there are Hindoo monks, Ramavats, who live in monasteries ; and there is a prototype of the polygamous Mormons, the Maharajas, whose religious ob- servances are mingled with licentiousness. When these facts are considered, it is difficult to determine to what extent the great typical religion of India known as Brahmanism, which succeeded the age of the elder Vedas, was ever observed by priests or people. The text-book of Brahmanism is known as the Laws of Manu. This is a very ancient religious code supposed to have originated about 1000 to 900 B.C. Manu, in the Vedas, is spoken of as the father of mankind and the hero of a legend resembling somewhat that of Noah in the Hebrew Scriptures ; the Brahmans regard him as the author THE RELIGIONS OF EGYPT AND INDIA. 411 of their code. The laws of Manu, in their present form, are a synopsis of a legendary poem, or metrical composition, of one hundred thousand couplets, which represented the laws and customs of the ancient Brahmans. These laws "may possibly have been reduced to the form of a written code with a view to securing the system of a caste against a popular movement of Buddhism, and thus give a rigid fixity to the privileges of the Brahmans." The Brahmans represent the early Aryan civilization of India. They have always been the great literary caste. Their priestly power has often been assailed, and sometimes overcome. On account of their comparative monopoly of learning, however, they have been, until recent times, both the counsellors of princes and the instructors of the people. The whole history of India seems to be made up of the resistance of this caste to religious and political innovations from the early invasions of non-Brahmanic tribes to the great religious movement which culminated in the establish- ment of the Buddhist kingdoms. So determined was the resistance of the Brahmans, that Buddhism was at last dethroned and driven out of India. Some writers think that the manner in which this victory over Buddhism was achieved was by joining the worship of the two gods Vishnu and Siva to Brahmanism. The worship of these gods had gradually grown up in India as a sort of dissent from Brah- manism long before the time of Buddha. These worships were founded upon the ancient Vedas, and were simply the forms which the popular religious ideals of two different sections of the country assumed. In the valley of the Ganges the Vedic god Vishnu was promoted to the chief rank in the Hindoo Pantheon. He was given "the character of a Friend and Protector, .gifted with mild attributes, and worshipped as the life of Nature." In the west of India the god selected was Siva, supposed to be derived from the god Rudra of the Rig- Veda, who, " fierce and beneficent at once," is the Storm-god and presides over medicinal plants. The worship of this god gradually spread until under the name 412 THE RELIGION OF PHILOSOPHY. of Siva, the Destroyer, he became one of the most prominent deities of India. In harmonizing the worship of these two popular gods with their own religion, the Brahmans were able to unite India and successfully oppose Buddhism. The origin of the Hindoo triad of Brahma, Vishnu, and Siva, like all other divine trinities, 1 is probably a dim reflec- tion of the three elements of thought, the ultimate reality Motion and its subjective and objective aspects Time and Space. There is, of course, no resemblance between the deities composing the Egyptian, Persian, Hindoo, or Chris- tian trinities and the principles known as Space, Time, and Motion ; but the conditions of thought are common to all humanity, and it is more natural to believe that the religions of the world offer this distant reflection of an ultimate analysis than that they bear no trace of it. We will make no attempt to follow out the elaborate be- liefs of this great race, whose distinct languages, states, and peoples exceed in number those of all Europe, and whose civilization was seemingly greater than now before writing as we use the word was invented in any part of the world ; suffice it to say that the illogical and extreme part of Brahmanism is its mysticism. In the imagination of India mysticism has had a high development. Its alluring prom- ises have fascinated while its innate deceit has corrupted the heart of man. Such morality, and hence such true religion, as the world has seen, has come not from mystery, not from impossible images of life and purity, but from generaliza- tions of experiences, the healthful and natural extension of human sympathies. Plato derived his ecstasies of perception from the East, and all subsequent idealism has been but an outgrowth of these intellectual mysteries. Christianity has assiduously fostered the mysticism of India ; witness her doctrine of 1 Egypt has Osiris, the Creator ; Typhon, the Destroyer ; and Horus, the Preserver. Persia has Ormazd, the Creator ; Ahriman, the Destroyer ; and Mithras, the Restorer. Buddhism has Buddha, the Divine Man ; Dharma, the Word ; and Sangha, the Communion of Saints. Christianity has God, the Father ; Christ, the Divine Man ; and the Word, or the Holy Ghost. THE RELIGIONS OF EGYPT AND INDIA. 413