. RECOGNITION WITH AN OUTLINE OF A Theory of Knowledge. BD III PREFACE. EXPONENTS of this subject have, in some cases, gone deeply into its psychological aspects ; in other cases its logical aspects, and in a few cases its epistemological aspects, have been care- fully expounded. But, with the exception of the treatise recently delivered by Dr. Wildon Carr before the Aristotelian Society, no other exponent has treated the entire subject in a general way. My object now is to present the varied aspects of recognition briefly but inclusively ; to submit them to a preliminary analysis, carrying this analysis out just far enough to place its resultants within the spheres of Logic, Epistemology, or Psycho- Physiology, and there to abandon them to the treatment of specialists. Beyond this I have attempted to place the subject of recognition in its true relative position in the constellation of Philosophy, and to show how the universal force of meta- physic holds it just there. Portions of this treatise were delivered, in the form of a lecture, at the Conference Hall, Streatham, on November 19th, 1916. A. WORSLEY. Isleworth, 1916. " Philosophers devoid of reason find This \\orld a mere idea of the mind ; 'Tis an idea but they fail to see The Great Idealist who looms behind." J AMI (Laiva'ih). RECOGNITION. AT first sight it may seem that such a simple subject as Recognition does not require an elaborate exposition. Yet it is these very actions of every-day life, so often repeated, so common in the experience of each one of us, that we are apt to pass by without noting their significance ; nor does it occur to many persons to ask themselves how, as a matter of fact, this simple act of recognition is effected. But first let us inquire whether all cognition does not consist in recognition. Our reply must be that with the exception of our earliest cognition, which has long since slipped from the memory, we must admit that we cannot now cognize without the act of recognition. In other words, Memory has its say. Recognition clearly consists in comparing some object with similar objects held in the memory, and in judging whether or no this is that, or is like that. Therefore the conscious or unconscious classifications of the mind determine the act of recognition, and the subject of recognition is a proper subject for logical treatment in so far as it depends on classification : for epistemological treatment in so far as we must bear down on our system of classification and consider if it is valid, confused, or worthless : and, lastly, for psychological treatment in so far as recognition is a mental, as opposed to a physiolo- gical action. All at once the prinia facie simplicity of this subject has vanished, and we have before us the ample fields of Logic, Epistemology, and Psychology in which to ramble. As to modern definition of the content of recognition, Prof. Bosanquet, in his Logic, says of Recognition that it " is another of these curiously limited processes," and he describes it as " reflective reproduction under the influence of an idea of identity." I am personally unable to follow the line of thought in which Prof. Bosanquet is here indulging, but my view is that Logic by itself will not carry us as far as Recognition and what recognition implies. I return to this subject later on. As to axioms, I must claim one (depending upon the Theory of Knowledge) which forces its way into every theory of Recognition, and cannot be dissevered therefrom. I wish therefore to say that I assume throughout that the mind is endued ab initio with the power of discrimination, at least in the logical sense of like and unlike, and greater and less* To my question as to whether we can make a clear distinction between Recognition and Cognition, an objector might urge that, before recognition became possible, there must have been a first cognition. If so, this must have occurred very early in life, and we shall find no inconsiderable difficulty in even con- ceiving how it may have occurred. Certain writers from the University of Leipzig consider that a baby's first cognition of any object or group of objects is of " shapeless, tremulous spots of colour situated close to the eye." But this classification does not, on the face of it, bear the impress of baby's first thought.! It is surely our cognition of its cognition, and this double process of second-hand cognition has brought about * Compare Pratyabhijna-Darsana : " The cognition is self - luminousness." t The young of many Mammalia remain blind for some days after birth. In such cases touch-cognition must precede sight - cognition. We may assume that, at least among Mammalia, touch-cognition of the mother's breasts precedes all other forms of cognition. metamorphosis ! These ' tremulous spots of colour,' to what possible classification of the mind, conscious or unconscious, did the baby refer for comparison. How did it discriminate between what had shape and what had no shape (impossible thought); between what was tremulous and what was steady; what was coloured and what was not coloured ; a baby, who, e\ hypothesi, had had no previous cognitions of objects, and to whom no comparison was therefore possible ? Here wo are driven back upon the Theory of Knowledge and its axiom. Provided that there was a plurality of objects present in that little monismusupon which the baby concentrated its at- tention, then the movements of these objects, and their relative sizes and distances apart, would fall within the scope of the most elementary cognition which assumes discrimination between like and unlike, greater and less. It is indisputable that babies cannot extend this power of discrimination outside the limits of the little monism us (ostensibly pluralistic) upon which the attention is momentarily concentrated. No idea of spatial connection between that little world and the greater world of their immediate surroundings is then present in cognition. Nor, in the case of sight-cognition, is any idea of distance present to the baby mind whose then determination is to hold out its hand and obtain something far beyond its grasp, 9 Moreover I do not think that, at any period in psychical development, we ever reach or attain to any process of thinking that differs in its nature from our first sight or sound- cognition of a real monismus inclosing an ostensible pluralism. No systems of philosophy have ever placed us above this world of relativity, in which parts are measured by other parts, and things expressed in terms of other things. No one has ever driven out of this little world on which we concentrate our atten- tion, its ostensible pluralism ; no one has ever placed that conceived monismus containing this plurality of objects quite within our reach, and we still hold out baby-hands to grasp what is quite beyond our reach. Such are the chains which bind our actions, and limit, in effect, our thought. None but slaves will passively submit to conscious servitude in shackles. Hence the Spirit strives cease- lessly ; and this very striving is Life. My theory is that any conceived first cognition must be so conceived that the object is presented in plural form,* and that no singular objective first cognition is possible. For if we could ever have cognized a single object, without having, * As in the case of the baby's first touch-cognition, and of all forms of first cognition, however brought about. in either in memory or actually present at the moment, some other object comparable with it, we should have solved the dual relationship of Subject-Object, and should have laid bare the inscrutible it ness of the Object. What would thus become known to us would not be the Quality and Quantity of the It, for these are comparatives, but the it ness of the It, that is the self-identity thereof. But no system of philosophy has ever done this, and the itncss of the object has always remained inscrutible.* Hence it is quite certain that no primary cog- nition can have achieved, at the first step, what no one has ever been able to do at any period of life. A singular objective first cognition is therefore impossible, and this cog- nition must be conceived in the plural. This plurality may take two forms. Either the comparable objects must be pre- sented in succession, so that from those objects held in memory Nor could one object in space be cognized as one, unless by comparison with some previous experience of plurality. Nor could the single object be even cognized as object, unless by the setting over against it, by way of comparison, of the objectless ambient of space. Nor would a baby's first touch- cognition have been possible had there not been present to his touch both particular objects (or object) and also other data of touch-sensation, as between which discrimination was possible. All which cognitions are plural. 11 a subsequent single-object presentation may be recognized ; or, more than one comparable object must be synchronously presented. The latter class of presentation is the only one which fulfils the desiderata of a first cognition. This plurality of our cognitions in their simplest forms brings them all down to the cognition of an objective sequence or procession (implying intervals between the objects cognized). As I will presently show, what is true of our cognition of any sequence of objects, is also true of any sequence of events, and of the sequences of Cause-Effect. Our conception of Space is thus built up out of our obser- vations on the relative positions of, and intervals between, objects present at the same moment ; our conception of Time out of the relative intervals between each event in a sequence or series of events ;* and our conception of Causality out of the observed sequence of Cause-effect. * We are here reminded of the words of one of our con- temporary poets Flecker who said, " When from the clock's last chime to the next chime Silence beats his drum, And Space with gaunt grey eyes and her brother Time Wheeling and whispering come, She with the mould of form and he with the loom of rhyme." I would therefore completely reverse Kant's hypothesis, and declare that Time, Space, and Causality are by no means given, but are, on the other hand, constructions from our experience of Sequence, and are, as such, liable to all kinds of misconstruction. Quite recently mathematicians have shown, in the Theory of Relativity, how imperfectly we have construed the signs given to us in experience, and to what extent \ve should rectify our conceptions of Time and Space. It is indeed clear that I make no preposterous demand when I assert that the cognition of simple sequence is a sine qua non of all mental action.* It is also a vital part of the mental equipment of animals and insects, and we may trace it down the scale of intellectual life until we begin to doubt if it may not be a physiological as well as a physio-psychical process, and have its roots far down in the undulatory and vibratory nature of movement in the Elements. " Intuition involves at least one sequence of sense data, however remotely inter-comparable such data may be. 13 All animals, in common with human beings, locate the point from which sound issues by the minute interval of time which intervenes between the sound waves striking one ear and then the other. Should the sound waves, by any chance, strike both ears simultaneously, the hearer at once turns the head to one side, so that the sound, if repeated, should not a second time baffle his power of locating it. This is noticeable even in very young puppies. The location of a flash of lightning is also gauged, with tolerable accuracy, by the immeasurably short interval of time between the impact of the light on one eye and then on the other. If one judges, "the flash came from this direction," the ear will generally confirm the instantaneous eye-judgment. The location of sounds and of light belongs to the sequential order of cognition, but also comes in some secondary sense under the heading of means of recognition. Having established the plurality of first cognitions, and the necessary existence of sequence as included in their appre- hension, I will now briefly show how, in such sequences, mathematical ratio is implicit, and can be made explicit. For when we consider the groups of things necessarily presented to the mind in all cognitions unsupported by past experience (such as some objects in Space, some events in Time, and so 14 forth), we realize that between the things in these groups exist mutually sustaining ratios (however we may fail at the moment to apprehend them), such as that the third object in Space is twice as far away from the second as the second is from the first (or, logically, the third is farther away from the second than the second is from the first) ; or, the second object has an apparent size equal to the other two together (or is greater than either) ; or, there is the same interval of time between a series of gun- reports, etc. In short, all these elementary cognitions, whether we do, or do not, comprehend their true nature at the moment of cognition, disclose a world of relativity which extends to and implies mathematical ratio. We can now proceed to discuss our accumulated experiences and consider how these are classified in mind. The art of classification depends upon comparison, and to a lesser extent upon language. If some edifice is seen in the distance, the observer, as he approaches it, forms a judgment as to whether it is a church, a house, railway station, factory, or what not, by comparing it with his experience of the various structures associated in his mind witli these names. Now, clearly, if he judges that it is a house, he does not mean to imply that it is absolutely identical in every respect with any particular house lie may have in memory, nor even that it represents the exact 15 mean of all the houses he remembers.* He simply means that it comes under the classification of " house " because he judges that it is more like what he means by house than what he means by church, station, factory, etc. But if he were asked, " Are you sure that this is properly described as a house, rather than as flats, maisonettes, etc. ? " he would, perhaps, have to think again about whether the word "house" did in his experience include more than one class of building used for residential purposes, and whether he invariably used this word in one sense only. If we pay strict attention to differences then classifications can be indefinitely articulated, as they are in chemistry, until each class contains but few individuals. But even then we have not exhausted the possibilities of subdivision, for inasmuch as each individual thing possesses a name of its own it cannot be identical with any other individual thing, even though they may both be included in the same class. Even if we produced a dozen oranges, or a dozen new shillings from the Mint, a really critical inspection would disclose differences between each one. * Compare the Nyaya Sutras of Gotama ; the Kusumanjali III. 11, of Udayana (Note by Prof. Cowell) ; and Siddhanta Muktavali, pp. 82, 83. 16 But if the closest examination failed to discern any difference, yet no one of them could really be identical with any other one of them, because the position in space occupied by one of them is already filled, and cannot be occupied by the other. Hence they cannot be identical in respect of locality, and no two things can ever be identical with or wholly like each other.* On the other hand, a comparison between two things must always disclose both likeness and unlikeness. We say that this is like that when the mutual likenesses are striking and the dis- similarities inconspicuous, and we put things together in the same class (that is, under the same descriptive name) by this, somewhat arbitrary, process, Nearly every mistake which it is possible for one to make proves, on analysis, to be a mistake in classification, and consists in placing oneself, or other people, or some things, into their wrong class. Hence we should greatly admire the science of chemistry, with its scientifically devised and admirable system of nomenclature and symbolism. And we should all study classification. If any one dissuade you by saying that it is a dull study, then he himself is incurably smitten by the disease of dulness ; for I assure you that it is one * Compare the doctrine of theSautrantikas (Re-presentationists") "All is lik* Itself alone," f pleasurable or painful the effects upon ourselves of those ex- ternal stimuli which we have not taken the trouble to name, constitute the instinctive or unreasoned part of our experience. The two in combination form the " 1 " (ego) of experience. It is to this " I " that rvery subject instantaneously refers every fresh experience for purposes of classification and recognition. Bear heavily upon this word, and put out of mind any popular 19 and faulty usages thereof. Recognition is the knowing over again by reference to past experience.* Hence I call the totality of the recorded experience of the individual his Sy**w of Reference. Philosophers who treat of the " ego " generally mean this " I of experience ; " but, alas, not always. This " I " suffers continual slight change* from the acquisition of ntw experiences, other changes from forgetfulness of past experience, but remains generally, after manhood is reached, without much change. Yet we must not orerlook the greater changes that do take place in the System of Reference of two classes of men. The first class contains those rare individuals who have a life- long and insatiable desire for knowledge. Let us clearly discriminate these men from the ordinary ruck of mankind. Out of every thousand young men who leave school or college there may be one such, the rest regard their education as then complete, and fling away their books with some such demoniacal remark as "Thank God that is done with." But the one, whom a fairy has touched at birth, knows that his education is then beginning. He chants a Te Deum laudamus that he is at last free to begin his * See the Pratyabhijna-Darsana ; "Recognition is a cog- nition relative to an object represented in memory." -JO real studies, and lie continues to thankfully class himself as a ^tudent to the end of ins days. It is on account of the perpetual studentship of our most learned and mobile-minded men that the "I of experience " grows and develops in them to an ex- ceptional degree. The other class of individuals suffering unusual changes in this respect, contains those whose minds break down under, or rebel against, rational methods of apprehen- sion. I'p to some point in their education the struggle is con- tinued, and some sort of cosmos is constructed out of the chaos of sensation, but then it is all given up in despair, and more or less complete mental confusion causes the troublesome science of thinking to be altogether abandoned. Such individuals soon fall under the impulses of emotion no longer restrained by Reason, and supply with lull membership the clashes suffering from religious and other forms of dogmatic mama. In times like those in which \ve are now living, many persons cannot retain their mental equilibrium. Events give us pause, and we wonder whether our world is really an ordered world dependent upon Law and led by Reason. Under existing conditions the one old sheet-anchor of reason is apt to be slipped off as out of date, and a preference given to the wildest forms of credulity. The world will presently be astonished at finding 21 that, in the space of a few years, it has, in some respects at least, slid back into the Dark Ages.* It is certainly true of the animal world that the association of certain objects with pleasurable and painful sensations appears to dominate their actions and thoughts. This is demonstrably the case with babies in the suckling stage. The Dog is pleased not only with his food, but with the person who brings it to him ; and the same is true of tame fish, and of various other domestic or partly tamed animals. This method of classifi- cation, by the mere association of things, sounds, and persons with events, is just the same form of emotional association that we note in the classification of the human emotions into Pleasurable and Painful ; and in the blind lumping together into the pleasure-giving class of other objects that only bear a prima facie resemblance to the object from which pleasure was actually experienced. For instance, the crying baby is easily satisfied with such a barefaced fraud as an indiarubber teat, made in ruthful imitation of its mother's teats. The time may come * " For Reason is the fountain from of old From which the prophets drew. And none beside. Who boasts of other inspiration lies, There are no prophets other than the wise." --Jatni. 22 when discrimination enables us to reject counterfeits of what gave us pleasure. The earlier stages of this discrimination seem easy enough, hut its ultimate stages demand 1he most far I have dealt with those specific and individual personal traits capable of recognition in portraiture. But across the conclusions thereby reached there sweeps a strong cross current of generic, or pseudo-universal, traits of character. Most human beings when under the influence of passion give themselves away by unconsciously exhibiting, in countenance and posture, the violence of their emotions. Love or Hate, Defiance or Submission, arc clearly portrayed in stance and feature. In the case of animals other than human beings there is no attempt to hide these expressions of the emotions, and in many cases these expressions are common to humanity also For instance, all animals using their teeth as weapons of offence exhibit them in a snarling expression when angry, or con- temptuous of their antagonist. This language of the emotions, whether expressed in the individual or delineated in Art, is not always understood without study. For instance, Oriental * Herbert Snencer says (Autobiography, Vol. II., p. 69) of a special combination of music and scenery " The exaltation of feeling produced was unparalleled in my experience ; and never has pleasurable emotion risen in me to the same intensity." 27 Art has a language of its own, the conventional nature of which demands much study for its elucidation. On the other hand, it is admitted that the parrot's expression is inscrutible to most men. Beyond, therefore, the excitation of the pleasure-state by the recognition that some portrait resembles a pleasure-giving prototype held in memory, there is also the possibility that various rasas may be produced by the pseudo-universal signals in the object, such as those of Love (sexual or universal), Hate, Defiance or Submission, etc. ; or of the comparatively perfect attainment of Manhood, Godhood, Reason, etc. And the Chooser would like that particular portrait which reflected his existing state of mind ; or that, by a combination of individual and general modes of expression, excited in him the passions that it portrayed. The highest form of portraiture has this latter power. In general, objects of desire (not being in the class of necessities) are not sought by all persons with the same avidity. It is said that the preference of this over that is a question of taste. For instance, the preference of one man for antique coins rather than for books, and of another for books rather than for coins, may depend on education and various other personal factors: but liis final act of choosing from one class of objects in preference to another class is an act of recog- nition that he had experienced more intense pleasure from previous enjo\ment of this class of objects than he had felt from objects belonging to the other class. In such cases we are evidently dealing with a development of the category of Pleasure-giving and Painful Sensations into various grades of such feelings. It is a canon that we should not dispute about matters of taste, and for the unanswerable reason that, as no two men have had exactly the same experiences of pleasure and pain, no two men can be affected in exactly the same way by the same object of experience. If we go back again to the example of a portrait gallery we shall find that this same unanswerable reason governs this case also, and it would be the merest chance (mathematically) if any two successive spectators selected the same portrait as the most pleasing. An instance of the instantaneous recognition of error is evident to nil players of out-door games. The moment a bad stroke is made, the striker is seized by an instantaneous recog- nition that that particular stroke must be classed among the many errors he has perpetrated during his career. I think that 29 this act of recognition is mainly emotional. There is a definite feeling of mistake, which has been often felt before, and which causes the mind to instantly classify the stroke as an error, and this long before the event has disclosed any actual error to any other person than the striker. In leaving the subject of emotional recognition I would mention that few authors of philosophical works have dealt with this branch of Recognition. One of the earliest, and possibly the earliest, philosophical description of Recognition is found in the Abhidhammattha Sangaha attributed to the venerable Anuruddha.* In so far as I can comprehend the translator's meaning, Anuruddha considered that Recognition proceeded backwards from an immediately present object to past experiences of a like nature. It would indeed appear that in his view our mental classifi- cations are subject to continual revision with each fresh recog- nition, in the sense that we re-classify our experiences backwards from every fresh experience. Let us at once admit that each fresh experience confirms, adds to, and often farther articulates our previous classifi- * The Bergsonian philosophy is founded on this school. The Pali Text Society has published a translation. 30 cations. Beyond this there are, n<> doubt, cases of incomplete or uncertain classifications of experience which some fresh experience enables us to complete and classify properly. As when a mineralogist, unable to classify some specimens, puts them into some provisional classification with a query attached to it, but subsequently his doubts are solved by a fresh speci- men, and he then goes back and re-classifies his previous specimens. But, in general, I am firmly convinced that the process of recognition by no means consists in casting doubt upon the established classifications of the mind, but rather in recalling these cases clearly, and seeing into \\iiich class the new object will slide with the least possible disturbance to our ideas. In the cases in which class recognition takes place there is no disturbance; but in those cases which are unique in experience a ne\- class must be formed, and this implies a certain mental disturbance and possible confusion of mind. Tins i> noticeable in school boys: for at the school period th" number of unique experiences crowded into a few vears dem.uuis a continual expansion and articulation of the cate- goiii., of the mind. While these conditions obtain, clear thinking should not be expected from a student. 31 Prof. Bosanquet's view that Recognition consists in a. "reflective reproduction under the influence of an idea of identity," presents great difficulty. If the subject was really " under the influence of an idea of identity " in any complete sense, he would insist on individual recognition of the first human being he set eyes on, and he would, during every day of his life, add an immense number of faulty "judgments " to his already onerous category of errors. Moreover, as I have already shown, an " idea of identity " must be an illusion, for true identity cannot be even predicated as between any two objects whatever. An idea of similarity, such as is implied by the inclusion of more than one object in a class, does undoubtedly arise in mind during the process of recognition ;* it is implied in every reasoned act of comparison, and may be present at the onset of emotional recognition. However, Prof. Bosanquet was treating of the logical aspect of Recognition, and would, presumably, specially restrict ''"identity" to some modern meaning which I am unable to grasp. There are then two processes of recognition ; (1) a reasoned process, and (2) an emotional, or unreasoned, process. But * Compare Udayana in Kusumanjali (Cluster III.) on the likeness of the Gavaya to the Cow. 32 there arc also two distinct kinds ol classification brought about by our reasoned process of recognition, i.e. (J) Logical assembly into classes, or Class Recognition, and (2) Individual Recognition. For instance, the recognition that a thing, or things, may be included in a certain class is the easiest form of recognition. The first man who leaves a meeting, or railway carriage, should have no difficulty in recognizing that a number of somewhat similar articles may be classed together as umbrellas, but mistakes are not uncommon when it comes to recognizing one particular umbrella as his own. However, mistakes in Class Recognition are not uncommon. An Irishman, attending a ball at a courury house close to his home, guided his steps there by a lantern. The entertainment passed of! well, but early on the morrow his groom carried a large wire cage to the host's house. ' Here is your parrot," said he, "kindly give me back my master's lantern.' * Moreover, the proper classifications of thinkers and doers is not so very easy, and it has become a bye word that the art of classification in this sense is not known in political govern- ments, where the attempt is constantly renewed to push the 'square' man into the 'round' hole. An instance of the comedy of mixed classification. The following instances of acts of recognition, or of failure in recognition, are mostly trivial as actions, although full of import as recognitions. If acts of importance to the individual were analysed, it would be found that the entire functions of the mind and probably also those of the body were engaged in the action. Hence no analysis of any special function would be possible on account of the immense com- plexity of the forces in play. But the more trivial the act the less general the disturbance, or stimulated activity, of the functions of the individual, and the greater the probability of some correct diagnosis of effect. Yet, even in trivial actions, great mental disturbance often ensues. He who is known as 'shy ' or 'ill at ease in company ' is he who is unable to limit the excitation caused by trivial events to their local centres of reaction. I will now narrate, from my own experience, an instance of individual recognition. This instance is very interesting as showing how recognition proceeds by various avenues of comparison, one of which may lead to recognition while others may fail. Now if these different avenues of comparison arose from different objects, one object would be recognized and the other objects unrecognized ; but if these avenues sprang from 34 the same object, we reach the startling conclusion that this object \voulcl be both recognized and unrecognized ! Yet this paradox is not only conceivable, but is actual in my experience. I entered a cricket ground where a match was in progress, and instantly, from a distance of about 150 yards, recognized (without the slightest doubt) a certain bowler, whom I know full well, in the act of bowling. About half-an-hour afterwards 1 was ceremoniously introduced to one of the players, and asked (sotto roce) if I knew him. I paused for some time and listened to his voice, which called back the memory that I had heard it before, but 1 was quite unable to recognize him. This was the same man who was the object of my instant recognition on entering the ground, and my failure in recog- nition was due to the absence of his flowing beard. The interest of this incident lies in the fact that it is a concrete example of how we analyse objects. A single entilv thus becomes known to us as consisting of an aggregation of characters. Now every artist knows that the stance of a man, and the way in which he carries his weight when in motion, is more typical of that particular man than any other single character. In picture or statue every other character may be true to the original, but the representation utterly fails unless the stance is that particular stance idiosyncratic of the man. 35 But if you value the friendship of painters do not suggest to them that this is the reason why they so often advise half- length portraits. In the above instance a specially trained eye enabled me to recognize a man by one characteristic only, but directly I was no longer able to bring that special eye training into use, neither eye nor ear enabled me to recognize the same man over again. Some might say that my failure in recognition was the result of a trick, or change in the appearance, of my acquaint- ance. But this objection has no weight, for we can never have the opportunity of recognizing any object without some change having affected it since we observed it last. If there is such a condition as that of objective reality, that condition only exists momentarily at the instant of observation, and then passes away into a changed something differing from what it was when observed. In many cases such changes are slow and slight, and we do not fail to recognize our friends simply because of the tarnish of time, or change of habitat. Yet \ve know that no event can ever happen again ; that the friend whom we met yesterday can never again be met either at the same time (which is gone for ever), or in the same place (left 36 thousands of miles behind in space), or under the same Subject- Object relations ; for between that meeting and this both I arsons have changed. Even that suppositions momentary reality of the Object as Object is surely born of the Subject, in the Berkeleyan sense, and hence does not inhere in the Object as Object. The alleged New Realists have, in this context, sunk back into the dreamland of poesy, and of Hebraic mythology. In the time of the poet Spenser it was not so difficult to be a \'ew Realist, in fact he had claims to this 1 1 tie which seem indisputable. " Then give 1 think on that which Nature said ot that same time when Change shall no more be, but steadfast rest of all things, firmly stayed upon the pillars of Eternity. Which iscontrair to Mutability, for all that moveth doth in Change delight. But henceforth all shall rest eternally with him who is the God of Sabaoth light. O ! that same Sabaoth God, grant me that Sabaoth sight." * All forms of recognition are therefore operative on changing objects, and we rely upon our experience helping us to follow * Faery Queen. 37 changing things through their changes without losing sight of them, or of the remembrance of what they once were. The one thing that does not change, and which thus gives us the necessary criterion of fixity by which to appraise Change, is the Eternal Subject, the Contemplator of existence, the Atman of Vedantic thought.* This example is on all fours with the one given by Prof. Bosanquet, who cites the case of a man (presumably not a musician) who asked for a special air written by a given com poser to be played, but failed to recognize it when it was played. Putting to one side all chance of error on the hearer's part in having associated in his mind certain names with a special melody, and also dismissing any peculiar method of rendering the melody which may have baffled him, the reason of the recognition of the name and the failure in the recog- nition of the tune probably lies in the fact that his memory was specially trained to remember names, but not melodies. As an instance of the extent to which special training assists in class recognition let me add that the late Dr. W. G. * Some urge that Memory enables us to appraise Change, and will not enter into Metaphysic, Grace once told me that, directly the opposing side took their place, in the cricket field, he rould tell how many left-handed howlers the side contained hy the way they walked, lie was certainly right on the few occasions on which I heard him prophesv. Attain, a gardener can toll, even in mid-winter, to what class any fuming currant hush belongs: some Fruit (irowers ran, in mid-winter, name all the well-known varieties of Pears from a single glance at the habit of the trees; and an old sailor can generally recognize in the far distance the nationality of any sailing ship. One more very interesting instance hangs upon what is recogni/.ed in the ordinary act of reading. Most literary men can read ahout three times as fast as they can read aloud. Persons of this class, and of very varied interests, will read the contents of the day's Times (not including the advertisements! in ahout 2<> minutes. P>ut this may he called "skimming through" the paper, and not reading it. However, I know that, in my own case, I miss out nothing of interest to myself, so that this skimming process does not preclude Recognition. P)iit the interest lies in the answer to the question What is rrcogni/ed ? Clearly not the letters ; presumably not the individual words; doubtfully even the sentences in any perfect 39 sense. Yet the meaning is apprehended. There are, however, exceptions. Sometimes one meets with a most confusing author, who expresses himself in such round-about, topsy- turvy ways, that one must continually stop and read some- thing over again. This is generally a waste of time, for, in nine cases out of ten, confused, doubtful methods of expression are a true reflection of the confusion and doubt reigning in the author's mind. I am in doubt as to the exact process of apprehension in this act of skimming through printed matter. Possibly the attention is only given to the verbs, nouns, and pronouns, and not to qualifications. It is my experience that it can only be done in one's native language, and it is perhaps one of those new developments of eye-sense that comes to some persons as a result of much practice. We might call it a means of appre- hending the content of writing by synoptic recognition.* The analysis of Emotional Recognition is difficult. Like all other analyses, the first steps are comparatively easy, and their results are enlightening ; but each step presents us with an ever-increasing number of problems awaiting solution. The * Compare Panini-Darsana, on Sphota. tin.il result >f analysis is invariable. It leaves us Fared with tar more unknown things' and unsolved difficulties than we \\'ere faced with when our analysis began. The problem n|' kecup- nition, as disclosed in this short address, has developed into a series of problems, and time only allows me to point on! a murh more intractible sei ies which the next step in analysis brings forward. Our senses and our feelings develop habits of their own, and the brain becomes habituated to the receipt from them of certain linked impressions, or synchronous sets of impressions, which it learns to associate with certain times, places, and conditions. It is in this way that we obtain from the mind certain intuitive or instinctive responses. To the habitual series of synchronous impressions the brain responds with satisfied complacency, an "all is well " response. Rut to an unusual set- it responds with surprise and alarm. Mental distress is evideni, and danger is apprehended. Xor can we, in such cases, argue. ourselves back into a state of complacency. II we can succeed in allaying the feeling of danger, we are still left in an uneasv, mystery-stricken, state of mind. I will give a very trivial, but quite typical, instance. Persons whose life is spent partlv in a big city and partly in 41 the country, wear various raiments suitable to their occu- pations. The tall hat of their city life is supplanted by a cap when rusticating', and so forth. I have it from a friend, that one day, directly he had left his country home for an afternoon in London, he was seized with the feeling that something was wrong. At first he thought he had forgotten something that he should have taken with him, but soon assured himself that this was not so. A few yards further on he stopped again, perfectly convinced that he had forgotten the existence of some appoint- ment that he had made for that day. Mental confusion was increasing every moment, when the source of his trouble was suddenly realized. He had started out without changing his hat, and this interruption to the accustomed series of linked impression had disturbed his mind. Another instance opens fresh channels for investigation. It appears that a series of mental impressions (such as are involved in a calculation) should all be capable of being re- called together in judgment. But one or more may hang back, as it were, and the judgment, when formed, ma) r be based upon an unconsciously imperfect set of representations. Presently the loiterers turn up and contradict the judgment. If the mind is not then occupied by an inflow of fresh impressions, but is feeding upon past impressions by a process of regurgitation, a recognition of error arises. A mathematician, possessed of remarkable accuracy in his work, told me that one evening, when he was rather tired, he was showing a youth how to do certain sums in which he had failed. These he demonstrated quite satisfactorily to the youth, and retired to rest. But not to sleep, for his brain became agitated. A cognisance of some error which he Iincl committed was forced upon him. He lay there thinking of what error he could have been guilty, but he failed to satisfy himself. Presently confused sets of figures were presented in his mind, but without any particular bearing, or signification. He woke next morning in the same state of mental unrest, and, on looking at the boy's sums, found that he himself had made an error in calculation by having omitted a certain factor. I think that the faulty decisions of many men, and of most public bodies, arn due to the fact that feA have the power of recalling all the facts necessary for judgment and of repre- senting the whole series synchronously in mind. Faulty deci- sions are due to the fact that first one and lii^n another fact becomes dommant in mind and obscures ail the rest. Some 43 men are so hopelessly incompetent in this respect that they will come to one decision one day, and, on the same set of facts, go back upon it the next day. All these errors depend upon the inability of most minds to really weigh or value facts. They only see one thing among the many, and ivhich one they happen to see at the moment of judgment decides the issue. The low craft of the lawyer consists in making the fact telling in favour of his client the dominant fact in the minds of the Jury at the moment of their verdict. It is the duty of the Judge to recall to their minds all the facts, or to at least attempt this task. There is also a set of loitering impressions that often cause mental confusion. What we were just considering were not loitering impressions, but loitering representations, mental processes in which there was a failure in synchronous repre- sentation. But, just as we have two forms of recognition, i.e., the consciously mental process and the emotional or un- conscious process, so we have two ways in which failure in mental synchrony may occur. In the second mode it is the impressions themselves that loiter,* and so are presented to * In a physiological sense. 14 the uniul in succession notwithstanding that the objective occurrence was singular. The duplication of our senses of sight, hearing, and touch, presents an obvious possibility that the duplicate set of impressions, which are normally presented synchronously in mind, may on occasions be presented suc- cessively, with an interval, however short, between the presenta- tions. In such cases we receive what is, for all practical purposes, a icpeated signal in place of one signal. A subject, seeing for the first time a certain event or object, but whose mind receives a repeated, or duplicated, signal of the fact, necessarily compares the second impression with the first, and concludes that he has seen all this before. This would be undoubtedly true of his brain (or of part of it), which \vould in fact have received the impression before, although perhaps only one hundredth of a second before. But it is also true that the brain itself presents a duplication of some of its organs, an obscure parallelism between certain parts, and might thus originate a psychic duplication on its own account. It is thus conceivable that, in cognition, the time-order of objective events might be invalidated, or even reversed, in abnormal cases of physio-psychic retardation of sensuous impressions. The evidence of persons suffering from hysteria, or from great mental excitement, often furnishrs instances of time-confusion, effects 45 preceding causes, and so forth. Although such evidence may be quite valueless as to chronology, it may be honestly given, and may be quite correct as to the persons and things that made up the scenes referred to. By these psycho-physical facts we can dissolve all that fog of mystery with which modern psychologists have surrounded this matter. But we have not as yet found a name that is properly applicable to this peculiar form of dual pre- sentation. The second or repeat-presentation results in true, and not in false, recognition. It is "had before," and "known," by comparison with the other moiety of the impression which first gained the ear of the mind. Hence the name " Plural Recognition " would seem the most applicable. The pluralizing of objects, which occurs during some states of intoxication in the subject, may be considered in this connection. Let those who feel inclined to decry the importance, or the frequency, of non- synchronous response due to retarded nerve - transmission ask a teacher of piano-playing how many of his most expert pupils keep true time with the left hand. But it must not be assumed, on account of my manner of presenting this subject of recognition, that I necessarily believe 46 in the existence of true records in the brain. The clear thinker ib \\f whose mind, influenced by his experiences, and carrying in memory a clear, complete, and logically valid classification of them, instantly apprehends each fresh experience as being like and unlike his previous experiences. Of him it may truly be said that lie modifies (in a logical sense) each fresh experience by putting it through the mill of his classified experiences. For, as no event can be identical with any other event, so no new experience can be identical with any past experience ; the sense data are not identical, nor is the experiencer exactly the same experiencer that he was on the former occasion. Hence the modes of his comprehension to some extent determine \\hat can be apprehended by him, and, in this sense, some modification of a new experience must be declared. But so also are his past experiences, and their classifi- cations, modified, retrospectively, by each fresh experience, within the meaning of the venerable Anurudclha. For instance, no concept of " house " can fail to be modified, affected, expanded, or articulated, by each fresh experience of some object coming under the class " house," but yet not exactly like, or altogether unlike, any particular house " had before." I said that Cognition is Recognition. But the reverse of this is also true in thr sense that Recognition proceeds by 47 precisely the same method, i.e., by the mutual modification of one criterion by each other criterion, and is therefore as purely relative as is the conceived foundation of our knowledge in our first act of cognition. I ruled out all possibility of an original cognition of a single object, and said that every original cog- nition must be of some plurality of objects in Space, events in Time, etc. If we then became aware that one of these objects in Space was larger than another, or that the distance or interval between A and B was greater than the interval between B and C, we must at the same moment have also become aware of the following modification in our method of standardization, i.e., that one object was smaller than another, and that the interval between B and C was less than the interval between A and B. Just so do we modify our methods of appraisement when we gauge each new experience by past experiences, and past experiences by each new experience. In this sense the very process of simple cognition is ' had again ' in every subsequent recognition. Moreover, the moment of experience in an original cognition is an extended present, or continuum ; as when the ticks of a clock are cognized as having an equal interval between them, hence they cannot be even conceived as 4S 'Happening all together in one true instant. So also is the moment of recognition an extended present in which the new experience is crushed against the thought-modes of the mind, which latter generally extends the moment long enough to conjure up against it a whole army of past experiences by way of comparison. Then follows the mutual modification. The new comer takes his place in the ranks, and these ranks are reformed for his admission. This continuum of tiie moment of experience is just long enough for the experience!' to take the first time-portion of the experience and set it up against the middle portion (the immediate present) by way of criterion, and even to stage it up in anticipation of the not-yet-arrived, or third period, of that "moment of experience." In the case of the whistle of an express train passing close to the observer, he experiences an increasing noise followed by a decrease and change of note, and, however short he may arbitrarily make his " moment of experience," he will experience just this. In other words, the moment is long enough for him to put up the first part against the actual instant of experience, and to recognize the increase of the volume of sound, and also to anticipate (if he does not actual!} experience) the third or concluding period of derrf-ase. 49 Anticipation, Realization, and Reflection are the three necessary phases of thought, and even if, in the case of an entirely unexpected event, no previous anticipation may be possible, yet Anticipation will have its say at some point in every " moment of experience." In leaving the subject of the How and the Why of Recog- nition, I will only remark that the content of recognition and its implications have only been " skimmed through," leaving much interesting matter undiscussed. I often feel much sym- pathy with a certain countryman, who, having listened to a critical discussion of this subject, remarked : " When I get out- side I shall stare about me, for this is a very different world from what I took it to be." He had reason on his side, for none of us know exactly what sort of world this is. Grammar, that faultless index of human thought, against which the pseudo- logicians are engaged in ceaseless struggle, provides for this necessity in Past, Present, and Future tenses. Although the Eternal Subject always experiences the Now of existence, and not the Has been or Will be, yet every single experience of this continually-existing present contains in itself its own immediate criteria of comparison : and the opinion then formed is verifiable by comparison with past experience. The twin infinities of Past and Future, the unbroken stream of existence, presents in itself no objects and parts, no possi- bility of measurement, until it is bisected (in the present moment) by the Subject of experience, and measured back- wards and forwards bv the standard or criterion of that experience. This gives us our Loci of the events in our expe- rience, and our point d'appui in the universe. It introduces into the monismus of existence the essential minimum of duality necessary for perception.* Let us for a moment consider the Yoga of Recognition : how the capacity of recognition may be gained. The first step is to pay attention, to bend the mind down to the particular object (or group of objects), and not to treat it as the Priest and th^ Levite treated the wounded man. These are the moments of experience, when concentrated thought will produce life-long memory, and earn for the experiencer the title of an observant man. The next step is to make certain that no confusion exists as to your conscious classification of this object, event, or whatever it may be. For if the categories of the mind are * C.f. My Concepts of Monism, p. 260 et seq. 51 in a state of confusion, memory will represent to you an inextricable chaos of records, and your thought (or what passe* in your case for thought) will be made still more confused, will be made more turbid instead of being clarified, by your memory- records. To attain the condition of well-ordered memory, some practice in the analysis and synthesis of the characters of objects is essential * Following this, practice in the art of classifying such objects after such analysis and synthesis. In this respect study of Natural History is of the greatest use. The third step is to obtain the power of recall over this well-ordered memory. This is generally effected by a system of keys, which are learned by heart, parrot fashion. The crux of this system of keys is to connect together the various links into a chain of memory, so that the remembrance of one link calls back all the others. The Hindus have perfected this system of memory to an extent not approached by the western * Compare Marcus Aurelius. " Make for thyself a definition, or description, of the thing which is presented to thee, so as to see distinctly what kind of thing it is .... and tell thyself its proper name .... For nothing is so productive of elevation of mind as to be able to examine methodically and truly every object which is presented to thee in life ; " et seq. races, for they have kept alive the traditions of mnemonic literature long since lost in the West. \\ hen n man has really achieved this task, and learned the Yoga of recognition, he lias at once placed himself in a little intellectual aristocracy, which is always, and at every period in the world's history, a very small class. They, alone among men, can form judgments- the rest are mere gamblers, playing dice with Providence, and guessing all the time. I have shown how Logic, Epistemology, Psychology, and in some sense Mathematics, are all necessary to the knowledge of how we recognize ; but, to justly apprehend the place which Recognition takes in Philosophy, it is necessary to still farther expand its basis. In this mutually dependent Subject-Object Universe, all we know is that the Subject makes various responses to Object - signals. From varied responses we infer various signals, and from this we conclude that the Itness of the Objective World is articulated or particularized. But the content of Recognition is the subjective interpretation of the repeated object-signals, not the self- identity of the Object, for of the Object we can posit only un Itness. For instance, on a railway, when the stop (or danger) signal is ^een, the train stops. But from this 53 relationship we should not argue that the stopping of the train is in fact the signal ! By no means. The signal is one thing, its interpretation is another ; and no subjective interpretation should be read into the nature of the Object de se. The itness of the Object is therefore unknown to us. But this admission of an objective It is not an admission of Dualism, since, for all we know to the contrary, this unknown It may be the Eternal Subject, or Self, over again in an unrecognized form.* This is the bridge that makes the position of the monist defensible. We hear him insistently calling to us not to fail in this final act of recognition, after which " there is nothing more to be known."! * " And all the phantom, Nature, stands, With all the music in her tone, A hollow echo of mine own, A hollow form with empty hands ! " TENNYSON. (In Memoviam.} f Compare Somananda-natha in Sivadvishti : " When once the nature of Siva that resides in all things has been known with tenacious recognition, . . . there is no farther need of doing aught, or of any farther reflection." 54 But the position of the monist, although defensible, is open to the pluralistic objection that Recognition implies cognizable objects. If the inscrutability of the It is in any way bound up with tiie fact that this It is in reality the Eternal Subject over again " in an unrecognized form," then this apprehension of an external something is not Recognition but failure in recognition. To tln^ it is replied that the apprehension of this fact is both success in recognition and failure in recognition ; as when twin brothers are always recognized by some friend, who is yet continually mistaking the one for the other ; who might even distinguish them when they were both present, and afterwards "recognize" the wrong one when the other \\as absent. To this it may be objected that Self-recognition is only one form of recognition, and that all other forms of recognition imply objects discrete from the Perceiver, a something capable of being known by comparison with other objects. But to this objection tin- monist may reply that cognizable objects are admittedly in relation to the Subject, otherwise their cognizability would be fictitious ; and that this relationship demands their joint inclu- sion in some monismus. Monism is a. conceptual explanation of the facts of existence, rather than an immediate method of solving one bv one the 55 problems of experience. It is faced with three* difficulties, for it has to explain away (1) the seeming plurality of subjects, (2) of objects, and (3) the seeming duality of Subject and Object. The first difficulty is got over by the altruistic doctrine that individual selves are collectively and individually the Eternal Subject, and that there is no real division, or allocation of " parts pertaining to selves." The second difficulty is said to be due to the illusion of names and forms, a kind of realistic Tower of Babel, where, even if everyone expressed the same * Ananda-Tirtha, in his Bhashya, declares five monistic cruxes in place of three. "A difference between soul and the Lord, a difference between the unsentient and the Lord, a difference among souls, and a difference of the unsentient and the soul each from the other. Also the difference of unsentient things from one another, the world with its five divisions." Vedantins declare that soul (Atman) and the Lord (Brah- man) are not different. But some were prepared to make a compromise in the manner of classification. The category of Ananda-Tirtha is open to a grave mathematical objection, for if the number of differences between each different thing (in a great or infinite class of differing things) and each different soul (in a great or infinite class of differing souls) were to be enumerated, such enumeration would result in very great num- ber of differing differences, and each one would be worthy of a separate class of its own. 56 thought, yet, to the illiterate ear, all say different things. The last difficulty is met by the assertion that the Object is merely the Subject over again, although not recognizable as such by a mere formal in>pection. \Ye shall see that both methods of approaching the subject of cognition are essential. Pluralistic concepts enable u-. to explain one by one, by analytical means. the facts of experience, and monistic concepts enable us, by synthesis, to realize (in some sense) what is implicit in these relations and commensurability between the ostensible parts of t his real whole. All schools of philosophy are agreed that the fact of self- oonsciousness is indisputable. Now I maintain that in this'one fact is implicit both ostensible pluralism and real monism. Without the former there would be no outer \\orld of corn- parables from which to discriminate Self, and without the latter no possible relation bct\\e<>n Self and its " comparables.'' Hence both ostensible pluralism and real monism are essential lor ari\ cognition whatever. It may be objected, why not deduce ostensible monism and real pluralism? The reply is obvious, tor real pluralism dobars relationship, and hence cog- nition ; *nd an ostensible monism would also be fatal to cognition. 57 Recognition and Cognition demand that this complex of plurality within unity should remain insoluble, for, if resolved, there would no longer be the knower or the known. In what, then, does Knowledge consist ? It consists in the transformation of the objective world into sets of intelligible objects. These intelligible objects are themselves transformed into brain " sensations," and here defy farther analysis. During these processes of the transformation of various objects into subjective experiences we note certain similarities and dis- similarities in these subjective experiences. Recognition of these likenesses and unlikenesses are given in Language and in Logic. By way of amplification, let me bring forward again the connection between the stopped train and the physical signal. Some may object that the stopping of the train is never mistaken for the signal, or likened to it as a comparative, in the sense that some thinkers liken the itness of the object with the intelligible object presented to the mind, and who would thus carry over to the object, and clothe it with, the attributes with which the intelligible object is clothed. The stopping of the train, they might say, is an effect of the signal, and this latter is cognized as it really is that is to say, it is such-and- 5S such a size, shape, and colour, in such-and-such a position, and so forth. But does tins really help us to build up an actual physical object out of a constituted intelligible object ? The objection amounts to this, that we must interpose between a (physical) objective signal and its ultimate subjective interpretation, an intermediate interpretation, called the intelligible signal. But the difficulty remains; for, just as the stopping ol the train was held to be the subjective interpretation of a physical object, so this same object is now said to have an intermediate interpre- tation that is, it is subjectively clothed with size, shape, colour, and position. Have we any reason for saying that the qualities with which the intelligible signal is clothed are not as purely subjective as is the ultimate subjective interpretation, i.e., that the train should stop ? Let u.> consider how this question is practically dealt with in the act of recognition. II a man chooses an orange in prefer- ence to an apple, ib this because he knows that the objective itness of the orange differs from the objective itness of the apple in certain respects which are objectively more admirable ? The question is absurd, and analytically unthinkable. But what he dofs recognize- is trial the colours smells, etc., of the intelligible 59 orange and apple now present are comparable with those of the intelligible oranges and apples apprehended by him in past experience. This experience of the comparability of this orange with those previous oranges (or with any of them) may be called the intermediate interpretation of these objective signals. Now follows the ultimate interpretation, i.e., the knowledge or belief founded on experience that this intelligible orange (or orange as intermediately apprehended) will be more productive of pleasure-giving sensation than would the synchronously appre- hended apple. But none of the intelligible oranges of his experience were ever known to him except by the pleasure- giving effect produced in the brain by their flavour, etc. The physical orange is recognized by the intelligible orange, and the intelligible oranges of his experience are known only by their pleasure (and pain) giving effects as felt by the brain. Now just as the railway "stop" signal, whatever its real objective nature may be, is ultimately interpreted by the stopping of a train, and that we cannot even conceive any attributes in this final interpretation which can be carried over and made to clothe the objective itness of the signal de se ; so also in the case of the orange and the apple, the final interpre- tation of these object-signals is the memory of some satisfaction (50 felt in the brain, between which and ihr itnts^ of ihe object m comparable qualities can be conceived. Hence the interpolation of an intelligible object between a physical object and its ultimate subjective interpretation, gives us no sanction for clothing the physical object with any attri- butes whatever. But just for this very reason, i.e., that there are no comparable qualities as between the ultimate subjective interpretation and the physical signal (objs.'i t; which is thu> dealt with, it follows that no recognition of the physical .signal would be thus possible. All the experience r could hope for would be for repeated cognitions of oranges and so forth, but without any possibility of recognition. It is then quite obvious that the function of the intelligible object is to secure thepo\\er of recognition. Recognition is the power that enables us to follow the changing thing through its changes without losing sight of it. But if the physical orange was allowed to undergo complete metamorphosis until it reappeared as a pleasant "taste," etc., in the brain, Recognition would be utterly baflled. The difficulty is met by catching the orange half-way through its process of transformation, and in recognizing it as the intelligible orange. At this stage it has changed from the piiysical object into a psycho-physical 'uibjrct- object ^onditioa, not vot unrec o^-n./.abl r;. 61 This is the doctrine of transformation, so called because it treats of a transformed object of knowledge as distinct from one which is conceived as either ideal or "real." However we may declaim against any attribution of sub- jective qualities to the true objectivity or itness of the object, we must not extend this particular objection to quality or quantity resulting from an objective comparison of physical objects, if such comparison is possible, which is doubtful. For instance, quantitative and qualitative comparisons as made in Chemistry or Physics are said to be free from objection on this ground. Nor, it is said, does this objection apply to comparisons between objects made in a similar way by unaided human means. We may discern that certain ratios as to weight, size, distance, hardness, etc., obtain as between comparable objects, while admitting that the objects (as apart from their mutual relations) are unknown to us except by transformation into the Psycho - Physical sphere of intelligibility. At first sight it may seem that these exceptions, if admitted, would cover more ground than my rule. Now, relations lie on the borderland of Recognition, and will not here be discussed at length. I would only remark that intelligible relations are themselves subjective interpretations of objective conditions quite ;is inscrutable as are the physical objects themselves. Many of these relations, as appiehended by us, are "intelligible 1 enough, but purely arbitrary. Some are mere definitions of intelligibility and none of them have been proved to be objec- tively true Some say that no coherent philosophy of the Subject-Object relationship has yet been formulated. My object here is not to write everything that could be said on this matter, for that would lead me far beyond my present intention, but to restrict myself to the bare outline of a psycho-physiological and psycho- physical system which should render Recognition intelligible. As we know nothing of Object de se, we cannot carry out objective comparison?. All we can say is that, inasmuch as various objects are apprehended differently, a horned cow being apprehended as such, and a hare as such, and as confusion does not arise as to which is which, hence we are fully justified in maintaining that as between the horned cow and the hare objective difference exists. But we cannot expand this elemen- tary logical cognition into anv more detailed system of objective,' classification. For directly we note the horns on the one and their absence on the other, we are comparing the intelligible 63 cow with the intelligible hare, and our comparison becomes one between psycho- physical, or cognized, objects. The existential It, or Its, have become clothed with qualities, and perhaps with quantity and other relations. All these apprehended differences may be compared, but such comparison is no longer an objective comparison. Nor have we any justification for transferring such differences to the existential items of the object world. As between such we can only posit Difference, not particular differences.* * Madhava quotes Gautama, the Buddha, as saying (in Lankavatara ?), " Of things discriminated by the intellect, no nature is ascertained." Madhava quotes the proverb [Sarva- Darsana-Samgraha], "A religious mendicant, an amorous man, and a (wild) dog have three views of a woman's person, respec- tively that it is a carcase, that it is a mistress, and that it is a prey." Can it be maintained that such intelligible views dis- close the real " nature " of the object in its bald objectivity ? Among the schools of Buddhistic philosophy we find only the Vaibhashikas (Presentationists) willing to make even a show of concession to objective reality, and they admitted the apparent existence of " an object concomitant to the cognition." On the other hand, both Samkhyas and Jainas admit an external objec- tive world (Prakriti), and the Jainas of the Arhata school admit an eight-fold division of Prakriti : but Prakriti consists in quality only. 64 Philosophy contains no single topic of wider import than Recognition. \Vhetlier its meanings are realized or not, in any case acts of recognition begin when we wake and do not cease until each one of us says farewell to the world of that day as apprehended by him. Each day the dog gambols at his master's feet, and each day every human being gains, through Recog nition, the pleasure of meeting, and the pain of parting from, the objects of his desires. Recognition implies more than this, for without it existence would be meaningless and unthinkable. A Co . Print*, 38, Htath Road Twiekmhw* This l)cn>k is 1)1' E on the last date stamped below. Form L9-Series 4939