^^ I LIBRARY UNIVERSFTYOF !>'* Z oi O l-u < u O Pi > SANTA CRUZ Gift of Prof. William R. Dennes ^ SANTA CRUZ m C z < tn H CO > 5? ^n Digitized by the Internet Archive in 2007 with funding from IVIicrosoft Corporation http://www.archive.org/details/conceptofnatureOOwhitrich THE CONCEPT OF NATURE CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS C. F. CLAY, Manager LONDON : FETTER LANE, E.C. 4 NEW YORK : THE MACMILLAN CO. BOMBAY ") CALCUTTA [-MACMILLAN AND CO., Ltd. MADRAS J TORONTO : THE MACMILLAN CO. OF CANADA, Ltd. TOKYO : MARUZEN-KABUSHIKI-KAISHA ALL RIGHTS RESERVED THE CONCEPT OF NATURE TARNER LECTURES DELIVERED IN TRINITY COLLEGE NOVEMBER 1919 BY A. N. WHITEHEAD, Sc.D., F.R.S. FELLOW OF TRINITY COLLEGE, CAMBRIDGE, AND PROFESSOR OF APPLIED MATHEMATICS IN THE IMPERIAL COLLEGE OF SCIENCE AND TECHNOLOGY CAMBRIDGE AT THE UNIVERSITY PRESS 1920 PREFACE The contents of this book were originally delivered at Trinity College in the autumn of 19 19 as the inaugural course of Tarner lectures. The Tarner lectureship is an occasional office founded by the liberality of Mr Edward Tarner. The duty of each of the successive holders of the post will be to deliver a course on * the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Relations or Want of Relations between the different Departments of Knowledge.' The present book embodies the endeavour of the first lecturer of the series to fulfil his task. The chapters retain their original lecture form and remain as delivered with the exception of minor changes designed to remove obscurities of expression. The lecture form has the advantage of suggesting an audience with a definite mental background which it is the purpose of the lecture to modify in a specific way. In the presentation of a novel outlook with wide rami- fications a single line of communications from premises to conclusions is not sufficient for intelligibility. Your audience will construe whatever you say into conformity with their pre-existing outlook. For this reason the first two chapters and the last two chapters are essential for intelligibility though they hardly add to the formal completeness of the exposition. Their function is to prevent the reader from bolting up side tracks in pursuit of misunderstandings. The same reason dictates my avoidance of the existing technical terminology of VI PREFACE philosophy. The modern natural philosophy is shot through and through with the fallacy of bifurcation which is discussed in the second chapter of this work. Accordingly all its technical terms in some subtle way presuppose a misunderstanding of my thesis. It is perhaps as well to state expHcitly that if the reader indulges in the facile vice of bifurcation not a word of what I have here written will be intelligible. The last two chapters do not properly belong to the special course. Chapter VIII is a lecture delivered in the spring of 1920 before the Chemical Society of the students of the Imperial College of Science and Technology. It has been appended here as conveniently summing up and applying the doctrine of the book for an audience with one definite type of outlook. This volume on *the Concept of Nature' forms a companion book to my previous work An Enquiry con- cerning the Principles of Natural Knowledge, Either book can be read independently, but they supplement each other. In part the present book supplies points of view which were omitted from its predecessor; in part it traverses the same ground with an alternative exposition. For one thing, mathematical notation has been carefully avoided, and the results of mathematical deductions are assumed. Some of the explanations have been improved and others have been set in a new light. On the other hand important points of the previous work have been omitted where I have had nothing fresh to say about them. On the whole, whereas the former work based itself chiefly on ideas directly drawn from PREFACE vii mathematical physics, the present book keeps closer to certain fields of philosophy and physics to the ex- clusion of mathematics. The two works meet in their discussions of some details of space and time. I am not conscious that I have in any way altered my views. Some developments have been made. Those that are capable of a non-mathematical exposition have been incorporated in the text. The mathematical de- velopments are alluded to in the last two chapters. They concern the adaptation of the principles of mathematical physics to the form of the relativity principle which is here maintained. Einstein's method of using the theory of tensors is adopted, but the application is worked out on different lines and from different assumptions. Those of his results which have been verified by experience are obtained also by my methods. The divergence chiefly arises from the fact that I do not accept his theory of non-uniform space or his assump- tion as to the peculiar fundamental character of light- signals. I would not however be misunderstood to be lacking in appreciation of the value of his recent work on general relativity which has the high merit of first disclosing the way in which mathematical physics should proceed in the light of the principle of relativity. But in my judgment he has cramped the development of his brilliant mathematical method in the narrow bounds of a very doubtful philosophy. The object of the present volume and of its pre- decessor is to lay the basis of a natural philosophy which is the necessary presupposition of a reorganised specu- viii PREFACE lative physics. The general assimilation of space and time which dominates the constructive thought can claim the independent support of Minkowski from the side of science and also of succeeding relativists, while on the side of philosophers it was, I believe, one theme of Prof. Alexander's GifFord lectures delivered some few years ago but not yet published. He also summarised his conclusions on this question in a lecture to the AristoteUan Society in the July of 191 8. Since the publication of An Enquiry concerning the Principles of Natural Knowledge I have had the advantage of reading Mr C. D. Broad's Perception ^ Physics ^ and Reality [Camb. Univ. Press, 1914]. This valuable book has assisted me in my discussion in Chapter II, though I am unaware as to how far Mr Broad would assent to any of my arguments as there stated. It remains for me to thank the staff of the University Press, its compositors, its proof-readers, its clerks, and its managing officials, not only for the technical ex- cellence of their work, but for the way they have co-operated so as to secure my convenience. A. N. W. IMPERIAL COLLEGE OF SCIENCE AND TECHNOLOGY. Aprily 1920. CONTENTS CHAP. PAGE I NATURE AND THOUGHT . . . . . i II THEORIES OF THE BIFURCATION OF NATURE . 26 III TIME 49 IV THE METHOD OF EXTENSIVE ABSTRACTION . 74 V SPACE AND MOTION 99 VI CONGRUENCE 120 VII OBJECTS 143 VIII SUMMARY -^ . 164 IX THE ULTIMATE PHYSICAL CONCEPTS . .185 NOTE : On the Greek Concept of a Point . . .197 NOTE: On Significance and Infinite Events . .197 INDEX 199 ^ THE CONCEPT OF NATURE CHAPTER I NATURE AND THOUGHT The subject-matter of the Tarner lectures is defined by the founder to be ' the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Relations or Want of Relations between the different Departments of Knowledge.' It is fitting at the first lecture of this new foundation to dwell for a few moments on the intentions of the donor as expressed in this definition; and I do so the more willingly as I shall thereby be enabled to introduce the topics to which the present course is to be devoted. We are justified, I think, in taking the second clause of the definition as in part explanatory of the earlier clause. What is the philosophy of the sciences? It is not a bad answer to say that it is the study of the rela- tions between the different departments of knowledge. Then with admirable solicitude for the freedom of learning there is inserted in the definition after the word * relations' the phrase *or want of relations.' A disproof of relations between sciences would in itself constitute a philosophy of the sciences. But we could not dispense either with the earlier or the later clause. It is not every relation between sciences which enters into their philosophy. For example biology and physics are connected by the use of the microscope. Still, I may safely assert that a technical description of the uses of the microscope in biology is not part of the philosophy of the sciences. Again, you cannot abandon the later 2 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch. clause of the definition; namely that referring to the relations between the sciences, without abandoning the explicit reference to an ideal in the absence of which philosophy must languish from lack of intrinsic interest. That ideal is the attainment of some unifying concept which will set in assigned relationships within itself all that there is for knowledge, for feeling, and for emotion. That far off ideal is the motive power of philosophic research; and claims allegiance even as you expel it. The philosophic pluralist is a strict logician; the Hegelian thrives on contradictions by the help of his absolute; the Mohammedan divine bows before the creative will of Allah ; and the pragmatist will swallow anything so long as it * works.' The mention of these vast systems and of the age- long controversies from which they spring, warns us to concentrate. Our task is the simpler one of the philosophy of the sciences. Now a science has already a certain unity which is the very reason why that body of knowledge has been instinctively recognised as forming a science. The philosophy of a science is the endeavour to express explicitly those unifying charac- teristics which pervade that complex of thoughts and make it to be a science. The philosophy of the sciences — conceived as one subject — is the endeavour to exhibit all sciences as one science, or — in case of defeat — ^the disproof of such a possibility. Again I will make a further simplification, and con- fine attention to the natural sciences, that is, to the sciences whose subject-matter is nature. By postulating a common subject-matter for this group of sciences, a unifying philosophy of natural science has been thereby presupposed. I] NATURE AND THOUGHT What do we mean by nature? We have to discuss the philosophy of natural science. Natural science is the science of nature. But — ^What is nature.? Nature is that which we observe in perception 1^ through the senses. In this sense-perception we are/ aware of something which is not thought and which is self-contained for thought. This property of being self- contained for thought lies at the base of natural science. It means that nature can be thought of as a closed system whose mutual relations do not require the jj expres sion of the fact that tTiey^feTthoughtabout. [ I'hus in a sense nature is independent of thought. By i this statement no metaphysical pronouncement is in-| tended. What I mean is that we can think about nature without thinking about thought. I shall say that then we are thinking * homogeneously ' about nature. Of course it is possible to think of nature in conjunc- tion with thought about the fact that nature is thought about. In such a case I shall say that we are thinking * heterogeneously ' about nature. In fact during the last few minutes we have been thinking heterogeneously about nature. Natural science is exclusively concerned with homogeneous thoughts about nature. But sense-perception has in it an element which is not thought. It is a difficult psychological question whether sense-perception involves thought; and if it does involve thought, what is the kind of thought which it necessarily involves. Note that it has been stated' above that sense-perception is an awareness of some- \ thing which is not thought. Namely, nature is not/ thought. But this is a different question, namely that the fact of sense-perce ption jias^ factor which is_ no t thought. I catl^his factor * sense-awareness.' Accord- I — 2 4 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch. ingly the doctrine that natural science is exclusively concerned with homogeneous thoughts about nature does not immediately carry with it the conclusion that natural science is not concerned with sense-awareness. However, I do assert this further statement ; namely, that though natural science is concerned with nature which is the terminus of sense-perception, it is not con- cerned with the sense-awareness itself. I repeat the main line of this argument, and expand it in certain directions. Thought about nature is different from the sense- perception of nature. Hence the fact of sense-perception has an ingredient or factor which is not thought. I call this ingredient sense-awareness. It is indifferent to my argument whether sense-perception has or has not thought as another ingredient. If sense-perception does \ \ not involve thought, then sense-awareness and sense- fT^ |, perception are identical. But the something perceived f\Jrlf^^ perceived as an entity which is the terminus of the 'v^pT sense-awareness, something which for thought is rjf I beyond the fact of that sense-awareness. Also the ^ something perceived certainly does not contain other sense-awarenesses which are different from the sense- T awareness which is an ingredient in that perception. p'^Af^l Accordingly nature as disclosed in sense-perception is «r^^ self-contained as against sense-awareness, in addition J^ to being self-contained as against thought. I will also ' ' * express this self-containedness of nature by saying that nature is closed to mind. This closure of nature does not carry with it any metaphysical doctrine of the disjunction of nature and mind. It means that in sense-perception nature is disclosed as a complex of entities whose mutual relations // I] NATURE AND THOUGHT 5 are expressible in thought without reference to mind, I that is, without reference either to sense-awareness or to thought. Furthermore, I do not wish to be under- stood as implying that sense-awareness and thought are the only activities which are to be ascribed to mind. Also I am not denying that there are relations of natural entities to mind or minds other than being the termini of the sense-awarenesses of minds. Accordingly I will extend the meaning of the terms * homogeneous thoughts' and * heterogeneous thoughts' which have already been introduced. We are thinking * homogene- ously' about nature when we are thinking about it without thinking about thought or about sense-aware- ness, and we are thinking * heterogeneously ' about nature when we are thinking about it in conjunction with thinking either about thought or about sense- awareness or about both. I also take the homogeneity of thought about nature as excluding any reference to moral or aesthetic values whose apprehension is vivid in proportion to self- conscious activity. The values^of natur e are perhaps the key to the metaphysical svntV>esis of pyistpnrp^ But such a synthesis is exactly what I am not attempting. I am concerned exclusively with the generalisations of widest scope which can be effected respecting that which is known to us as the direct deliverance of sense-awareness. I have said that nature is disclosed in sense-percep- tion as a complex of entities. It is worth considering what we mean by an entity in this connexion. * Entity' is simply the Latin equivalent for * thing ' unless some arbitrary distinction is drawn between the words for technical purposes. All thought has to be about things. We can gain some idea of this necessity of things for 6 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch. thought by examination of the structure of a proposi- tion. Let us suppose that a proposition is being communi- cated by an expositor to a recipient. Such a proposition is composed of phrases ; some of these phrases may be demonstrative and others may be descriptive. By a demonstrative phrase I mean a phrase which makes the recipient aware of an entity in a way which is independent of the particular demonstrative phrase. You will understand that I am here using * demonstra- tion' in the non-logical sense, namely in the sense in which a lecturer demonstrates by the aid of a frog and a microscope the circulation of the blood for an ele- mentary class of medical students. I will call such demonstration ' speculative ' demonstration, remember- ing Hamlet's use of the word ' speculation' when he says, There is no speculation in those eyes. Thus a demonstrative phrase demonstrates an entity speculatively. It may happen that the expositor has meant some other entity — ^namely, the phrase demon- strates to him an entity which is diverse from the entity which it demonstrates to the recipient. In that case there is confusion ; for there are two diverse propositions, namely the proposition for the expositor and the pro- position for the recipient. I put this possibility aside as irrelevant for our discussion, though in practice it may be difficult for two persons to concur in the con- sideration of exactly the same proposition, or even for one person to have determined exactly the proposition which he is considering. Again the demonstrative phrase may fail to demon- strate any entity. In that case there is no proposition I] NATURE AND THOUGHT 7 for the recipient. I think that we may assume (perhaps rashly) that the expositor knows what he means. A demonstrative phrase is a gesture. It is not itself a constituent of the proposition, but the entity which it demonstrates is such a constituent. You may quarrel with a demonstrative phrase as in some way obnoxious to you; but if it demonstrates the right entity, the proposition is unaffected though your taste may be offended. This suggestiveness of the phraseology is part of the literary quality of the sentence which conveys the proposition. This is because a sentence directly conveys one proposition, while in its phraseology it suggests a penumbra of other propositions charged with emotional value. We are now talking of the one pro- position directly conveyed in any phraseology. This doctrine is obscured by the fact that in most cases what is in form a mere part of the demonstrative gesture is in fact a part of the proposition which it is desired directly to convey. In such a case we will call the phraseology of the proposition elliptical. In ordinary- intercourse the phraseology of nearly all propositions is elliptical. Let us take some examples. Suppose that the ex- positor is in London, say in Regent's Park and in Bedford College, the great women's college which is situated in that park. He is speaking in the college hall and he says, 'This college building is commodious.' The phrase ' this college building ' is a demonstrative phrase. Now suppose the recipient answers, * This is not a college building, it is the lion-house in the Zoo.' Then, provided that the expositor's original proposi- 8 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch. tion has not been couched in elHptical phraseology, the expositor sticks to his original proposition when he replies, 'Anyhow, it is commodious.' Note that the recipient's answer accepts the specula- tive demonstration of the phrase ' This college building.' He does not say, * What do you mean? ' He accepts the phrase as demonstrating an entity, but declares that same entity to be the lion-house in the Zoo. In his reply, the expositor in his turn recognises the success of his original gesture as a speculative demonstration, and waives the question of the suitability of its mode of suggestiveness with an * anyhow.' But he is now in a position to repeat the original proposition with the aid of a demonstrative gesture robbed of any suggestiveness, suitable or unsuitable, by saying, 'It is commodious.' The 'it^ of this final statement presupposes that thought has seized on the entity as a bare objective for consideration. ^ We confine ourselves to entities disclosed in sense- awareness. The entity is so disclosed as a relatum in the complex which is nature. It dawns on an observer because of its relations ; but it is an objective for thought in its own bare individuality. Thought cannot proceed otherwise ; namely, it cannot proceed without the ideal bare *it' which is speculatively demonstrated. This setting up of the entity as a bare objective does not ascribe to it an existence apart from the complex in which it has been found by sense-perception. The 'it' \for thought is essentially a relatum for sense-awareness. The chances are that the dialogue as to the college building takes another form. Whatever the expositor I] NATURE AND THOUGHT 9 originally meant, he almost certainly now takes his former statement as couched in elliptical phraseology, and assumes that he was meaning, * This is a college building and is commodious.' Here the demonstrative phrase or the gesture, which demonstrates the *it' which is commodious, has now been reduced to * this ' ; and the attenuated phrase, under the circumstances in which it is uttered, is sufficient for the purpose of correct demonstration. This brings out the point that the verbal form is never the whole phrase- ology of the proposition ; this phraseology also includes the general circumstances of its production. Thus the aim of a demonstrative phrase is to exhibit a definite * it ' as a bare objective for thought ; but the modus operandi of a demonstrative phrase is to produce an awareness of the entity as a particular relatum in an auxiliary complex, chosen merely for the sake of the speculative demon- stration and irrelevant to the proposition. For example, in the above dialogue, colleges and buildings, as related to the *it' speculatively demonstrated by the phrase *this college building,' set that *it' in an auxiliary complex which is irrelevant to the proposition * It is commodious.' Of course in language every phrase is invariably highly elliptical. Accordingly the sentence * This college building is commodious ' means probably 'This college building is commodious as a college building.' But it will be found that in the above discussion we can replace * commodious' by * commodious as a college building' without altering our conclusion; though we can guess that the recipient, who thought 10 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch. he was in the Hon-house of the Zoo, would be less likely to assent to * Anyhow, it is commodious as a college building.' A more obvious instance of elliptical phraseology arises if the expositor should address the recipient with the remark, 'That criminal is your friend.' The recipient might answer, *He is my friend and you are insulting.' Here the recipient assumes that the phrase 'That criminal' is elliptical and not merely demonstrative. Jn fact, pure demo nstration is impossible thoudi it is the ideal of ^thought . This practical impossibility of pure demonstration is a difficulty which arises in the com- munication of thought and in the retention of thought. Namely, a proposition about a particular factor in nature can neither be expressed to others nor retained for repeated consideration without the aid of auxiliary com- plexes which are irrelevant to it. I now pass to descriptive phrases. The expositor says, * A college in Regent's Park is commodious.' The recipient knows Regent's Park well. The phrase *A college in Regent's Park' is descriptive for him. If its phraseology is not elliptical, which in ordinary life it certainly will be in some way or other, this proposition simply means, 'There is an entity which is a college building in Regent's Park and is commodious.' If the recipient rejoins, ' The lion-house in the Zoo is the only commodious building in Regent's Park,' he now contradicts the expositor, on the assumption that a lion-house in a Zoo is not a college building. I] NATURE AND THOUGHT ii Thus whereas in the first dialogue the recipient merely quarrelled with the expositor without con- tradicting him, in this dialogue he contradicts him. Thus a descriptive phrase is part of the proposition which it helps to express, whereas a demonstrative phrase is not part of 'the proposition which it helps to express. Again the expositor might be standing in Green Park — ^where there are no college buildings — and say, *This college building is commodious.' Probably no proposition will be received by the recipient because the demonstrative phrase, *This college building' has failed to demonstrate owing to the absence of the background of sense-awareness which it presupposes. But if the expositor had said, 'A college building in Green Park is commodious,' the recipient would have received a proposition, but a false one. Language is usually ambiguous and it is rash to make general assertions as to its meanings. But phrases which commence with ' this ' or * that ' are usually demonstrative, whereas phrases which commence with *the' or *a' are often descriptive. In studying the theory of pro- positiond expression it is important to remember the wide difference between the analogous modest words *this' and 'that' on the one hand and *a' and *the' on the other hand. The sentence *The college building in Regent's Park is com- modious ' means, according to the analysis first made by Bertrand Russell, the proposition, * There is an entity which (i) is a college building in Regent's Park and (ii) is commodious and (iii) is such 12 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [CH. that any college building in Regent's Park is identical with it.' The descriptive character of the phrase * The college building in Regent's Park' is thus evident. Also the proposition is denied by the denial of any one of its three component clauses or by the denial of any combination of the component clauses. If we had substituted * Green Park' for * Regent's Park' a false proposition would have resulted. Also the erection of a second college in Regent's Park would make the pro- position false, though in ordinary life common sense would politely treat it as merely ambiguous. * The Iliad ' for a classical scholar is usually a demon- strative phrase ; for it demonstrates to him a well-known poem. But for the majority of mankind the phrase is descriptive, namely, it is synonymous with ' The poem named "the Iliad".' Names may be either demonstrative or descriptive phrases. For example 'Homer' is for us a descriptive phrase, namely, the word with some slight difference in suggestiveness means *The man who wrote the Iliad.' This discussion illustrates that thought places before itself bare objectives, entities as we call them, which the thinking clothes by expressing their mutual rela- tions. Sense-awareness discloses fact with factors which are the entities for thought. The s.eparate^d istinction of an entity in thought is not a metaphys ical assertio a>_blit ' a m ethodof procedure neces sar yfor the finite expression of mdi vidual propositions. Apart from entities there 'could be no finite truths ; they are the means by which the infinitude of irrelevance is kept out of thought. \To sum up: the termini for thought are entities > I] NATURE AND THOUGHT 13 primarily with__bare individuality, se condarily with pro perties and relations ascribed to them j n_th e pro- cedure of thought ; the termin i for sense-awareness are factors i n the fact of nature, .4:u:imarily re lata andjonly seco ndarily discrimin a ted as distinct individualiti es. No characteristic of nature which is immediately posited for knowledge by sense-awareness can be explained. It is impenetrable by thought, in the sense that its peculiar essential character which enters into experience by sense-awareness is for thought merely the guardian of its individuality as a bare entity. Thus for thought *red' is merely a definite entity, though for awareness * red ' has the content of its individuality. The transition from the *red' of awareness to the *red' of thought is accompanied by a definite loss of content, namely by the transition from the factor *red' to the/ entity *red.' This loss in the transition to thought is] compensated by the fact that thought is communicable/ whereas sense-awareness is incommunicable. Thus there are three components in our knowledge of nature, namely, fact, factors, and entities. Fact is the undifferentiated terminus of sense-awareness; factors are termini of sense-awareness, differentiated as elements of fact ; entities are factors in their function as the ter- mini of tfiougEt. The entities thus spoken of are natural entities. Thought is wider than nature, so that there are entities for thought which are not natural entities. When we speak of nature as a complex of related entities, the * complex' is fact as an entity for thought, to whose bare individuality is ascribed the property of embracing in its complexity the natural entities. It is our business to analyse this conception and in the course of the analysis space and time should appear. Evidently 14 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch. I the relation s holding between natural entities are / themselves natural entities, namely they are also factors of fact, there for sense-awareness. Accordingly the structure of the natural complex can never be com- pleted in thought, just as the factors of fact can never be exhausted in sense-awareness. Unexhaustiveness is an essential character of our knowledge of nature. Also nature does not exhaust the matter for thought, namely there are thoughts which would not occur in any homo- geneous thinking about nature. The question as to whether sense-perception involves thought is largely verbal. If sense-perception involves a cognition of individuality abstracted from the actual position of the entity as a factor in fact, then it un- doubtedly does involve thought. But if it is conceived as sense-awareness of a factor in fact competent to evoke emotion and purposeful action without further cognition, then it does not involve thought. In such a case the terminus of the sense-awareness is something for mind, but nothing for thought. The sense-perception of some lower forms of life may be conjectured to approximate to this character habitually. Also occasion- ally our own sense-perception in moments when thought- activity has been lulled to quiescence is not far off the attainment of this ideal limit. The process of discrimination in sense-awareness has two distinct sides. There is the discrimination of fact into parts, and the discrimination of any part of fact as exhibiting relations to entities which are not parts of fact though they are ingredients in it. Namely the immediate fact for awareness is the whole occurrence of nature. It is nature as an event^^resent for sense- awareness, and essentially passing. There is no holding I] NATURE AND THOUGHT 15 nature still and looking at it. We cannot redouble our efforts to improve our knowledge of the terminus of our present sense-awareness; it is our subsequent oppor- tunity in subsequent sense-awareness which gains the benefit of our good resolution. Thus the ultimate fact for sense-awareness is an event. This whole' event is discriminated by us into partial events. We are aware of an event which is our bodily life, of an event which is the course of nature within this room, and of a vaguely perceived aggregate of other partial events. This is the discrimination in sense-awareness of fact into parts. I shall use the term *part' in the arbitrarily limited sense of an event which is part of the whole fact dis- closed in awareness. Sense-awareness also yields to us other factors in nature which are not events. For example, sky-blue is seen as situated in a certain event. This relation of situation requires further discussion which is postponed to a later lecture. My present point is that sky-blue is found in nature with a definite implication in events, but is not an event itself. Accordingly in addition to events, there are other factors in nature directly dis- closed to us in sense-awareness. The conception in thought of all the factors in nature as distinct entities with definite natural relations is what I have in another place^ called the * diversification of nature.' There is one general conclusion to be drawn from the foregoing discussion. It is that the first task of a philo- sophy of science should be some general classification of the entities disclosed to us in sense-perception. Among the examples of entities in addition to * events ' which we have used for the purpose of illustration are ^ Cf. Enquiry. M i6 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch. the buildings of Bedford College, Homer, and sky-blue. Evidently these are very different sorts of things ; and it is likely that statements which are made about one kind of entity will not be true about other kinds. If human thought proceeded with the orderly method which abstract logic would suggest to it, we might go further and say that a classification of natural entities should be the first step in science itself. Perhaps you will be inclined to reply that this classification has already been effected, and that science is concerned with the ad- ventures of material entities in space and time. The history of the doctrine of matter has yet to be written. It is the history of the influence of Greek philosophy on science. That influence has issued in one long misconception of the metaphysical status of natural entities. The entity has been separated from the factor which is the terminus of sense-awareness. It has become the substratum for that factor, and the factor J has been degraded into an attribute of the entity. In phis way a distinction has been imported into nature which is in truth no distinction at all. A natural entity is merely a factor of fact, considered in itself. Its dis- connexion from the complex of fact is a mere abstraction. ^ |It is not the substratum of the factor, bixLllie-AcerjL factor itself as bared in thou ght Thus what is a mere (procedure of mind in the translation of sense-awareness into discursive knowledge has been transmuted into a fundamental character of nature. In this way matter has emerged as being the metaphysical substratum of its properties, and the course of nature is interpreted as the history of matter. Plato and Aristotle found Greek thought preoccupied with the quest for the simple substances in terms of I] NATURE AND THOUGHT 17 which the course of events could be expressed. We may formulate this state of mind in the question, What is nature made of? The answers which their genius gave to this question, and more particularly the con- cepts which underlay the terms in which they framed their answers, have determined the unquestioned pre- suppositions as to time, space and matter which have reigned in science. In Plato the forms of thought are more fluid than in Aristotle, and therefore, as I venture to think, the more valuable. Their importance consists in the evidence they yield of cultivated thought about nature before it had been forced into a uniform mould by the long tradition of scientific philosophy. For example in the Timaeus there is a presupposition, somewhat vaguely expressed, of a distinction between the general becoming of nature and the measurable time of nature. In a later lecture I have to distinguish between what I call the passage of nature and particular time-systems which exhibit certain characteristics of that passage. I will not go so far as to claim Plato in direct support of this doctrine, but I do think that the sections of the Timaeus which deal with time become clearer if my distinction is admitted. This is however a digression. I am now concerned with the origin of the scientific doctrine of matter in Greek thought. In the Timaeus Plato asserts that nature is made of fire and earth with air and water as inter- mediate between them, so that * as fire is to air so is air to water, and as air is to water so is water to earth.' He also suggests a molecular hypothesis for these four elements. In this hypothesis everything depends on the shape of the atoms ; for earth it is cubical and for fire W. N. 2 i8 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch. it is pyramidal. To-day physicists are again discussing the structure of the atom, and its shape is no sHght factor in that structure. Plato's guesses read much more [fantastically than does Aristotle's systematic analysis; but in some ways they are more valuable. The main outline of his ideas is comparable with that of modern j science. It embodies concepts which any theory of /natural philosophy must retain and in some sense must / explain. Aristotle asked the fundamental question, f What do we mean by * substance ' .^ Here the reaction between his philosophy and his logic worked very unfortunately. In his logic, the fundamental type of affirmative proposition is the attribution of a predicate Ito a subject. Accordingly, amid the many current uses /of the term * substance ' which he analyses, he emphasises / its meaning as * the ultimate substratum which is no I longer predicated of anything else.' The unquestioned acceptance of the Aristotelian logic has led to an ingrained tendency to postulate a sub- stratum for whatever is disclosed in sense-awareness, namely, to look below what we are aware of for the substance in the sense of the * concrete thing.' This is the origin of the modern scientific concept of matter and of ether, namely they are the outcome of this insistent habit of postulation. Accordingly ether has been invented by modern science as the substratum of the events which are spread through space and time beyond the reach of ordinary ponderable matter. Personally, I think that predication is a muddled notion confusing many different relations under a convenient common form of speech. For example, I hold that the relation of green to a blade of grass is entirely different from the relation of green I] NATURE AND THOUGHT 19 to the event which is the Hfe history of that blade for some short period, and is different from the relation of the blade to that event. In a sense I call the event the situation of the green, and in another sense it is the situation of the blade. Thus in one sense the blade is a character or property which can be predi- cated of the situation, and in another sense the green is a character or property of the same event which is also its situation. In this way the predication of properties veils radically different relations between entities. Accordingly * substance,' which is a correlative term to ' predication,' shares in the ambiguity. If we are to look for substance anywhere, I should find it in events which are in some sense the ultimate substance of nature. Matter, in its modern scientific sense, is a return to the Ionian effort to find in space and time some stuff which composes nature. It has a more refined signi- fication than the early guesses at earth and water by reason of a certain vague association with the Aristotelian idea of substance. Earth, water, air, fire, and matter, and finally ether are related in direct succession so far as concerns their postulated characters of ultimate substrata of nature. They bear witness *to the undying vitality of Greek philosophy in its search for the ultimate entities which are the factors of the fact disclosed in sense-awareness. This search is the origin of science. The succession of ideas starting from the crude guesses of the early Ionian thinkers and ending in the nineteenth century ether reminds us that the scientific doctrine of matter is really a hybrid through which Af.'S V ^r 20 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch. philosophy passed on its way to the refined Aristotelian concept of substance and to which science returned as it reacted against philosophic abstractions. Earth, fire, and water in the Ionic philosophy and the shaped elements in the Timaeus are comparable to the matter and ether of modern scientific doctrine. But substance represents the final philosophic concept of the sub- stratum which underlies any attribute. Matter (in the scientific sense) is already in space and time. Thus matter represents the refusal to think away spatial and temporal characteristics and to arrive at the bare con- cept of an individual entity. It is this refusal which has caused the muddle of importing the mere procedure of thought into the fact of nature. The entity, bared of all characteristics except those of space and time, has ac- quired a physical status as the ultimate texture of nature ; so that the course of nature is conceived as being merely the fortunes of matter in its adventure through space. Thus the origin of the doctrine of matter is the out- come of uncritical acceptance of space and time as external conditions for natural existence. By this I do not mean that any doubt should be thrown on facts of space and time as ingredients in nature. What I do mean is 'the unconscious presupposition of space and time as being that within which nature is set.' This is exactly the sort of presupposition which tinges thought in any reaction against the subtlety of philosophical I criticism. My theory of the formation of the scientific I doctrine of matter is that first philosophy illegitimately transformed the bare entity, which is simply an ab- straction necessary for the method of thought, into the metaphysical substratum of these factors in nature which in various senses are assigned to entities as their I] NATURE AND THOUGHT 21 attributes ; and that, as a second step, scientists (includ- ing philosophers who were scientists) in conscious or unconscious ignoration of philosophy presupposed this substratum, qua substratum for attributes, as never- theless in time and space. This is surely a muddle. The whole being of substance is as a substratum for attributes. Thus time and space should be attributes of the substance. This they palpably are not, if the matter be the substance of nature, since it is impossible to express spatio-temporal truths without having recourse to relations involving relata other than bits of matter. I waive this point however, and come to another. It is not the substance f ^'^^ whiclL is _in_ space ^ but the attributes. What we find in/ space are the red of the rose and the smell of the jasmine/ and the noise of cannon. We have all told our dentistsi where our toothache is. Thus space is not a relatioiJ , between substances, but between attributes. Thus even if you admit that the adherents of sub- stance can be allowed to conceive substance as matter, it is a fraud to slip substance into space on the plea that space expresses relations between substances. On the face of it space has nothing to do with substances, but only with their attributes. What I mean is, that if you choose — as I think wrongly — ^to construe our ex- perience of nature as an awareness of the attributes of substances, we are by this theory precluded from finding any analogous direct relations between substances as disclosed in our experience. What we do find are I relations between the attributes of substances. Thus if \ matter is looked on as substance in space, the space in \ which it finds itself has very little to do with the space j of our experience. 22 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch. The above argument has been expressed in terms of the relational theory of space. But if space be absolute — ^namely, if it have a being independent of things in it — ^the course of the argument is hardly changed. For things in space must have a certain fundamental relation to space which we will call occupation. Thus the ob- jection that it is the attributes which are observed as related to space, still holds. The scientific doctrine of matter is held in conjunc- tion with an absolute theory of time. The same argu- ments apply to the relations between matter and time as apply to the relations between space and matter. There is however (in the current philosophy) a difference in the connexions of space with matter from those of time with matter, which I will proceed to explain. Space is not merely an ordering of material entities so that any one entity bears certain relations to other material entities. The occupation of space impresses a certain character on each material entity in itself. By reason of its occupation of space matter has extension. By reason of its extension each bit of matter is divisible into parts, and each part is a numerically distinct entity from every other such part. Accordingly it would seem that every material entity is not really one entity. It is an essential multiplicity of entities. There seems to be no stopping this dissociation of matter into multiplicities short of finding each ultimate entity occupying one individual point. This essential multi- plicity of material entities is certainly not what is meant by sciep^, nor does it correspond to anything disclosed in sense-awareness. It is absolutely necessary that at a certain stage in this dissociation of matter a halt should be called, and that the material entities thus obtained I] NATURE AND THOUGHT 23 should be treated as units. The stage of arrest may be arbitrary or may be set by the characteristics of nature ; but all reasoning in science ultimately drops its space- analysis and poses to itself the problem, ' Here is one material entity, what is happening to it as a unit entity?' Yet this material entity is still retaining its extension, and as thus extended is a mere multiplicity. Thus there is an essential atomic property in nature which is independent of the dissociation of extension. There is something which in itself is one, and which is more than the logical aggregate of entities occupying points within the volume which the unit occupies. Indeed we may well be sceptical as to these ultimate entities at points, and doubt whether there are any such entities at all. They have the suspicious character thati we are driven to accept them by abstract logic and not! by observed fact. ' Time (in the current philosophy) does not exert the same disintegrating effect on matter which occupies it. If matter occupies a duration of time, the whole matter occupies every part of that duration. Thus the connexion between matter and time differs from the connexion between matter and space as expressed in current scientific philosophy. There is obviously a greater difficulty in conceiving time as the outcome of relations between different bits of matter than there is in the analogous conception of space. At an instant distinct volumes of space are occupied by distinct bits of matter. Accordingly there is so far no intrinsic difficulty in conceiving that space is merely the resultant of relations between the bits of matter. But in the one-dimensional time the same bit of matter occupies different portions of time. Accordingly time would have to be expressible 24 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch. in terms of the relations of a bit of matter with itself. My own view is a belief in the relational theory both of space and of time, and of disbelief in the current form of the relational theory of space which exhibits bits I of matter as the relata for spatial relations. The true relata are events. The distinction which I have just pointed out between time and space in their connexion with matter makes it evident that any assimilation of time and space cannot proceed along the traditional line of taking matter as a fundamental element in space- formation. The philosophy of nature took a wrong turn during its development by Greek thought. This erroneous presupposition is vague and fluid in Plato's Timaeus. The general groundwork of the thought is still un- committed and can be construed as merely lacking due explanation and the guarding emphasis. But in Aristotle's exposition the current conceptions were hardened and made definite so as to produce a faulty analysis of the relation between the matter and the form of nature as disclosed in sense-awareness. In this phrase the term 'matter' is not used in its scientific sense. I will conclude by guarding myself against a mis- apprehension. It is evident that the current doctrine of matter enshrines some fundamental law of nature. Any simple illustration will exemplify what I mean. For example, in a museum some specimen is locked securely in a glass case. It stays there for years : it loses its colour, and perhaps falls to pieces. But it is the same specimen ; and the same chemical elements and the same quantities of those elements are present within the case at the end as were present at the beginning. Again the engineer and the astronomer deal with the motions of real per- I] NATURE AND THOUGHT 25 manences in nature. Any theory of nature which for one moment loses sight of these great basic facts of experience is simply silly. But it is permissible to point out that the scientific expression of these facts has be- come entangled in a maze of doubtful metaphysics; and that, when we remove the metaphysics and start afresh on an unprejudiced survey of nature, a new light is thrown on many fundamental concepts which domi- nate science and guide the progress of research. ^ CHAPTER II THEORIES OF THE BIFURCATION OF NATURE j In my previous lecture I criticised the concept of matter » as the substance whose attributes we perceive. This way of thinking of matter is, I think, the historical reason for its introduction into science, and is still the vague view of it at the background of our thoughts which makes the current scientific doctrine appear so obvious. Namely we conceive ourselves as perceiving attributes of things, and bits of matter are the things whose attributes we perceive. In the seventeenth century the sweet simplicity of this aspect of matter received a rude shock. The trans- mission doctrines of science were then in process of elaboration and by the end of the century were un- questioned, though their particular forms have since been modified. The establishment of these transmission theories marks a turning point in the relation between science and philosophy. The doctrines to which I am especially alluding are the theories of light and sound. I have no doubt that the theories had been vaguely floating about before as obvious suggestions of common sense; for nothing in thought is ever completely new. But at that epoch they were systematised and made exact, and their complete consequences were ruthlessly II deduced. It is the establishment of this procedure of II taking the consequences seriously which marks the ||real discovery of a theory. Systematic doctrines of light and sound as being something proceeding from CH.ii] THEORIES OF BIFURCATION OF NATURE 27 the emitting bodies were definitely established, and in particular the connexion of Hght with colour was laid bare by Newton. The result completely destroyed the simplicity of the * substance and attribute' theory of perception. What we see depends on the light entering the eye. Further- more we do not even perceive what enters the eye. The things transmitted are waves or — as Newton thought — minute particles, and the things seen are colours. Locke met this difficulty by a theory of primary and secondary qualities. Namely, there are some attributes of the matter which we do perceive. These are the primary qualities, and there are other things which we perceive, such as colours, which are not attributes of matter, but are perceived by us as if they were such attributes. These are the secondary qualities of matter. Why should we perceive secondary qualities.'^ It seems an extremely unfortunate arrangement that we should perceive a lot of things that are not there. Yet this is what the theory of secondary qualities in fact comes to. There is now reigning in philosophy and in science an apathetic acquiescence in the conclusion that no coherent account can be given of nature as it is disclosed to us in sense-awareness, without dragging in its relations to mind. The modern account of nature is not, as it should be, merely an account of what the mind knows of nature ; but it is also confused with an account of what nature does to the mind. The result has been disastrous both to science and to philosophy, but chiefly to philosophy. It has transformed the grand question of the relations between nature and mind into the petty form of the interaction between the human body and mind. • 28 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch. Berkeley's polemic against matter was based on this confusion introduced by the transmission theory of light. He advocated, rightly as I think, the abandon- ment of the doctrine of matter in its present form. He had however nothing to put in its place except a theory of the relation of finite minds to the divine mind. But we are endeavouring in these lectures to limit ourselves to nature itself and not to travel beyond entities which are disclosed in sense-awareness. Percipience in itself is taken for granted. We consider indeed conditions for percipience, but only so far as those conditions are among the disclosures of percep- tion. We leave to metaphysics the synthesis of the knower and the known. Some further explanation and defence of this position is necessary, if the line of argu- ment of these lectures is to be comprehensible. The immediate thesis for discussion is that any meta- physical interpretation is an illegitimate importation into the philosophy of natural science. By a metaphysical interpretation I mean any discussion of the how (beyond nature) and of the why (beyond nature) of thought and sense-awareness. In the philosophy of science we seek the general notions which apply to nature, namely, to what we are aware of in perception. It is the philosophy of the thing perceived, and it should not be confused with the metaphysics of reality of which the scope embraces both perceiver and perceived. No perplexity concerning the object of knowledge can be solved by saying that there is a mind knowing it^. In other words, the ground taken is this: sense- awareness is an awareness of something. What then is the general character of that something of which we 1 Cf. Enquiry, preface. II] THEORIES OF BIFURCATION OF NATURE 29 are aware? We do not ask about the percipient or about the process, but about the perceived. I emphasise this point because discussions on the philosophy of science are usually extremely metaphysical — in my opinion, to the great detriment of the subject. The recourse to metaphysics is like throwing a match into the powder magazine. It blows up the whole arena. This is exactly what scientific philosophers do when they are driven into a corner and convicted of inco- herence. They at once drag in the mind and talk of entities in the mind or out of the mind as the case may be. For natural philosophy everything perceived is in nature. We n^ay not pick and choose. For us the red glow of the sunset should be as much part of nature as are the molecules and electric waves by which men of /science would explain the phenomenon. It is for natural/^ f philosophy to analyse how these various elements of j^. \W^ia I nature are connected. A^'^t-^t^^/iw M In making this demand I conceive myself as adopting V^^iJ^ our immediate instinctive attitude towards perceptual knowledge which is only abandoned under the influence of theory. We are instinctively willing to believe that by due attention, more can be found in nature than that which is observed at first sight. But we will not be content with less. What we ask from the philosopliy of science is some account of the coherence of things perceptively known . This means a refusal to countenance any theory of psychic additions to the object known in perception. For example, what is given in perception is the green grass. This is an object which we know as an ingredient in nature. The theory of psychic additions would treat the greenness as a psychic addition furnished by the U*^ ^ ^ MiCinAl ^ ^3> ^tc. be an abstractive set, the members being so arranged that each member such as e^ extends over all the suc- ceeding members such as ^^+1, ^n+2> and so on. Then corresponding to the series ^l> ^2» ^3> •••> ^w) ^w+l> •••> there is the series (I (^i)» ^ (^2)» 9. (^3)» •••, (I W, ^ K+i), .... Call the series of events s and the series of quanti- tative expressions q {$), The series s has no last term and IV] METHOD OF EXTENSIVE ABSTRACTION 8i no events which are contained in every member of the series. Accordingly the series of events converges to nothing. It is just itself. Also the series q {s) has no last term. But the sets of homologous quantities running through the various terms of the series do converge to definite limits. For example if Q^ be a quantitative measurement found in q (^j), and Q^ the homologue to Q^ to be found in q {e^, and Q^ the homologue to Q^ and ^2 to be found in q (^3), and so on, then the series 6l> Q^y Qz^ •••> Qny Qn+l^ •••> though it has no last term, does in general converge to a definite limit. Accordingly there is a class of limits / {s) w^hich is the class of the limits of those members of ^ny ^n+i, ... -^ nothing, and q (^i)> 9 (^2)> q (^3), ..., ^ K), q K-m), ... - / (s). The mutual relations between the limits in the set l{s), and also between these limits and the limits in other sets l{s'), l{s"), ..., which arise from other abstractive sets s\ s", etc., have a peculiar simplicity. Thus the set s does indicate an ideal simplicity of natural relations, though this simplicity is not the character of any actual event in s. We can make an approximation to such a simpHcity which, as estimated numerically, is as close as we like by considering an event which is far enough down the series towards the small end. It will be noted that it is the infinite series, W.N. 6 82 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch. as it stretches away in unending succession towards the small end, which is of importance. The arbitrarily large event with which the series starts has no importance at all. We can arbitrarily exclude any set of events at the big end of an abstractive set without the loss of any important property to the set as thus modified. I call the limiting character of natural relations which is indicated by an abstractive set, the ' intrinsic character ' of the set; also the properties, connected with the relation of whole and part as concerning its members, by which an abstractive set is defined together form what I call its * extrinsic character.' The fact that the ex- trinsic character of an abstractive set determines a definite intrinsic character is the reason of the import- ance of the precise concepts of space and time. This emergence of a definite intrinsic character from an abstractive set is the precise meaning of the law of convergence. For example, we see a train approaching during a minute. The event which is the life of nature within that train during the minute is of great complexity and the expression of its relations and of the ingredients of its character baffles us. If we take one second of that minute, the more limited event which is thus obtained is simpler in respect to its ingredients, and shorter and shorter times such as a tenth of that second, or a hundredth, or a thousandth — so long as we have a definite rule giving a definite succession of diminishing events — give events whose ingredient characters con- verge to the ideal simplicity of the character of the train at a definite instant. Furthermore there are different types of such convergence to simplicity. For example, we can converge as above to the limiting character IV] METHOD OF EXTENSIVE ABSTRACTION 83 expressing nature at an instant within the whole volume of the train at that instant, or to nature at an instant within some portion of that volume — for example within the boiler of the engine — or to nature at an instant on some area of surface, or to nature at an instant on some line within the train, or to nature at an instant at some point of the train. In the last case the simple limiting characters arrived at will be expressed as densities, specific gravities, and types of material. Furthermore we need not necessarily converge to an abstraction which involves nature at an instant. We may converge to the physical ingredients of a certain point track throughout the whole minute. Accordingly there are different types of extrinsic character of con- vergence which lead to the approximation to different types of intrinsic characters as limits. We now pass to the investigation of possible con- nexions between abstractive sets. One set may * cover' another. I define * covering' as follows: An abstractive set p covers an abstractive set q when every member of p contains as its parts some members of q. It is evident that if any event e contains as a part any member of the set q, then owing to the transitive property of ex- tension every succeeding member of the small end of q is part of ^. In such a case I will say that the abstractive set q * inheres in ' the event e. Thus when an abstractive set p covers an abstractive set q, the abstractive set q inheres in every member of/). Two abstractive sets may each cover the other. When this is the case I shall call the two sets * equal in ab- stractive force.' When there is no danger of misunder- standing I shall shorten this phrase by simply saying that the two abstractive sets are * equal.' The possibility 6—2 84 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [CH. of this equality of abstractive sets arises from the fact that both sets, p and ^, are infinite series towards their small ends. Thus the equality means, that given any event x belonging to p, we can always by proceeding far enough towards the small end of q find an event y which is part of x, and that then by proceeding far enough towards the small end of ^ we can find an event z which is part oiy, and so on indefinitely. *. / The importance of the equality of abstractive sets •^"^^ arises from the assumption that the intrinsic characters of the two sets are identical. If this were not the case exact observation would be at an end. It is evident that any two abstractive sets which are equal to a third abstractive set are equal to each other. An * abstractive element' is the whole group of ab- stractive sets which are equal to any one of themselves. Thus all abstractive sets belonging to the same element are equal and converge to the same intrinsic character. Thus an abstractive element is the group of routes of approximation to a definite intrinsic character of ideal simplicity to be found as a limit among natural facts. If an abstractive set p covers an abstractive set q, then any abstractive set belonging to the abstractive element of which /) is a member will cover any abstractive set belonging to the element of which ^ is a member. Accordingly it is useful to stretch the meaning of the term * covering,' and to speak of one abstractive element * covering ' another abstractive element. If we attempt in like manner to stretch the term * equal ' in the sense of * equal in abstractive force,' it is obvious that an ab- stractive element can only be equal to itself. Thus an abstractive element has a unique abstractive force and is the construct from events which represents one definite IV] METHOD OF EXTENSIVE ABSTRACTION 85 intrinsic character which is arrived at as a Hmit by the use of the principle of convergence to simpHcity by diminution of extent. When an abstractive element A covers an abstractive element B, the intrinsic character of ^ in a sense includes the intrinsic character of B, It results that statements about the intrinsic character of B are in a sense statements about the intrinsic character of A; but the intrinsic character of A is more complex than that of B. The abstractive elements form the fundamental elements of space and time, and we now turn to the consideration of the properties involved in the formation of special classes of such elements. In my last lecture I have already investigated one class of abstractive elements, namely moments. Each moment is a group of abstractive sets, and the events which are members of these sets are all members of one family of durations. The moments of one family form a temporal series; and, allowing the existence of different families of moments, there will be alternative temporal series in nature. Thus the method of extensive abstraction ex- plains the origin of temporal series in terms of the immediate facts of experience and at the same time allows for the existence of the alternative temporal series which are demanded by the modern theory of electromagnetic relativity. We now turn to space. The first thing to do is to get hold of the class of abstractive elements which are in some sense the points of space. Such an abstractive element must in some sense exhibit a convergence to an absolute minimum of intrinsic character. Euclid has expressed for all time the general idea of a point, 86 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch. as being without parts and without magnitude. It is this character of being an absolute minimum which we want to get at and to express in terms of the extrinsic characters of the abstractive sets which make up a point. Furthermore, points which are thus arrived at repre- sent the ideal of events without any extension, though there are in fact no such entities as these ideal events. These points will not be the points of an external time- less space but of instantaneous spaces. We ultimately want to arrive at the timeless space of physical science, and also of common thought which is now tinged with the concepts of science. It will be convenient to reserve the term * point' for these spaces when we get to them. I will therefore use the name * event-particles ' for the ideal minimum limits to events. Thus an event-particle is an abstractive element and as such is a group of abstractive sets ; and a point — namely a point of timeless space — ^will be a class of event-particles. Furthermore there is a separate timeless space corre- sponding to each separate temporal series, that is to each separate family of durations. We will come back to points in timeless spaces later. I merely mention them now that we may understand the stages of our investigation. The totality of event-particles will form a four-dimensional manifold, the extra dimension arising from time — in other words — arising from the points of a timeless space being each a class of event-particles. The required character of the abstractive sets which form event-particles would be secured if we could define them as having the property of being covered by any abstractive set which they cover. For then any other abstractive set which an abstractive set of an event- particle covered, would be equal to it, and would IV] METHOD OF EXTENSIVE ABSTRACTION 87 therefore be a member of the same event-particle. Accordingly an event-particle could cover no other abstractive element. This is the definition which I originally proposed at a congress in Paris in 1914^. There is however a difficulty involved in this definition if adopted without some further addition, and I am now not satisfied with the way in which I attempted to get over that difficulty in the paper referred to. The difficulty is this : When event-particles have once been defined it is easy to define the aggregate of event- particles forming the boundary of an event ; and thence to define the point-contact at their boundaries possible for ^ pair of events of which one is part of the other. We can then conceive all the intricacies of tangency. In particular we can conceive an abstractive set of which all the members have point-contact at the same event-particle. It is then easy to prove that there will be no abstractive set with the property of being covered by every abstractive set which it covers. I state this difficulty at some length because its existence guides the development of our line of argument. We have got to annex some condition to the root property of being covered by any abstractive set which it covers. When we look into this question of suitable conditions we find that in addition to event-particles all the other relevant spatial and spatio-temporal abstractive elements can be defined in the same way by suitably varying the conditions. Accordingly we proceed in a general way suitable for employment beyond event-particles. Let (J be the name of any condition which some abstractive sets fulfil. I say that an abstractive set is 1 Cf. • La Theorie Relationniste de TEspace,' Rev. de Mita- physique et de Morale ^ vol. xxiii, 191 6. 88 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch. * or -prime' when it has the two properties, (i) that it satisfies the condition a and (ii) that it is covered by every abstractive set which both is covered by it and satisfies the condition a. In other words you cannot get any abstractive set satisfying the condition a which exhibits intrinsic character more simple than that of a o- -prime. There are also the correlative abstractive sets which I call the sets of a-antiprimes. An abstractive set is a a-antiprime when it has the two properties, (i) that it satisfies the condition a and (ii) that it covers every abstractive set which both covers it and satisfies the condition a. In other words you cannot get any ab- stractive set satisfying the condition o- which exhibits an intrinsic character more complex than that of a cr-antiprime. The intrinsic character of a cr -prime has a certain minimum of fullness among those abstractive sets which are subject to the condition of satisfying a; whereas the intrinsic character of a a-antiprime has a corre- sponding maximum of fullness, and includes all it can in the circumstances. Let us first consider what help the notion of anti- primes could give us in the definition of moments which we gave in the last lecture. Let the condition or be the property of being a class whose members are all durations. An abstractive set which satisfies this condition is thus an abstractive set composed wholly of durations. It is convenient then to define a moment as the group of abstractive sets which are equal to some a-antiprime, where the condition a has this special meaning. It will be found on consideration (i) that each abstractive set forming a moment is a o--antiprime. IV] METHOD OF EXTENSIVE ABSTRACTION 89 where (j has this special meaning, and (ii) that we have excluded from membership of moments abstractive sets of durations which all have one common boundary, either the initial boundary or the final boundary. We thus exclude special cases which are apt to confuse general reasoning. The new definition of a moment, which supersedes our previous definition, is (by the aid of the notion of antiprimes) the more precisely drawn of the two, and the more useful. The particular condition which *(j' stood for in the definition of moments included something additional to anything which can be derived from the bare notion of extension. A duration exhibits for thought a totality. The notion of totality is something beyond that of extension, though the two are interwoven in the notion of a duration. In the same way the particular condition ' a ' required for the definition of an event-particle must be looked for beyond the mere notion of extension. The same remark is also true of the particular conditions requisite for the other spatial elements. This additional notion is ob- tained by distinguishing between the notion of *posi-, tion ' and the notion of convergence to an ideal zero of extension as exhibited by an abstractive set of events. In order to understand this distinction consider a point of the instantaneous space which we conceive as apparent to us in an almost instantaneous glance. This point is an event-particle. It has two aspects. In one aspect it is there, where it is. This is its position in the space. In another aspect it is got at by ignoring the circumambient space, and by concentrating attention on the smaller and smaller set of events which approximate to it. This is its extrinsic character. Thus a point has 90 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch. three characters, namely, its position in the whole instantaneous space, its extrinsic character, and its intrinsic character. The same is true of any other spatial .element. For example an instantaneous volume in instantaneous space has three characters, namely, its position, its extrinsic character as a group of abstractive sets, and its intrinsic character which is the limit of natural properties which is indicated by any one of these abstractive sets. . Before we can talk about position in instantaneous space, we must evidently be quite clear as to what we mean by instantaneous space in itself. Instantaneous space must be looked for as a character of a moment. For a moment is all nature at an instant. It cannot be the intrinsic character of the moment. For the intrinsic character tells us the limiting character of nature in space at that instant. Instantaneous space must be an assemblage of abstractive elements considered in their mutual relations. Thus an instantaneous space is the assemblage of abstractive elements covered by some one moment, and it is the instantaneous space of that moment. We have now to ask what character we have found in nature which is capable of according to the elements of an instantaneous space different qualities of position. This question at once brings us to the intersection of moments, which is a topic not as yet considered in these lectures. The locus of intersection of two moments is the assemblage of abstractive elements covered by both of them. Now two moments of the same temporal series cannot intersect. Two moments respectively of different families necessarily intersect. Accordingly in the in- IV] METHOD OF EXTENSIVE ABSTRACTION 91 stantaneous space of a moment we should expect the fundamental properties to be marked by the inter- sections with moments of other families. If M be a given moment, the intersection of M with another moment A is an instantaneous plane in the instan- taneous space of M] and if 5 be a third moment intersecting both M and A, the intersection of M and B is another plane in the space M. Also the common intersection of ^, By and M is the intersection of the two planes in the space M, namely it is a straight line in the space M. An exceptional case arises if B and M intersect in the same plane as A and M. Furthermore if C be a fourth moment, then apart from special cases which we need not consider, it intersects M in a plane which the straight line {A, B, M) meets. Thus there is in general a common intersection of four moments of different families. This common intersection is an assemblage of abstractive elements which are each covered (or *lie in') all four moments. The three- dimensional property of instantaneous space comes to this, that (apart from special relations between the four moments) any fifth moment either contains the whole of their common intersection or none of it. No further subdivision of the common intersection is possible by means of moments. The 'all or none' principle holds. This is not an a priori truth but an empirical fact of nature. It will be convenient to reserve the ordinary spatial terms * plane,' * straight line,' * point' for the elements of the timeless space of a time-system. Accordingly an instantaneous plane in the instantaneous space of a moment will be called a * level,' an instantaneous straight line will be called a *rect,' and an instantaneous point 92 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch. will be called a * punct/ Thus a punct is the assemblage of abstractive elements which lie in each of four moments whose families have no special relations to each other. Also if P be any moment, either every abstractive element belonging to a given punct lies in P, or no abstractive element of that punct lies in P. Position is the quality which an abstractive element possesses in virtue of the moments in which it lies. The abstractive elements which lie in the instantaneous space of a given moment M are differentiated from each other by the various other moments which intersect M so as to contain various selections of these abstractive elements. It is this differentiation of the elements which constitutes their differentiation of position. An ab- stractive element which belongs to a punct has the simplest type of position in M, an abstractive element which belongs to a rect but not to a punct has a more complex quality of position, an abstractive element which belongs to a level and not to a rect has a still more complex quality of position, and finally the most complex quality of position belongs to an abstractive element which belongs to a volume and not to a level. A volume however has not yet been defined. This definition will be given in the next lecture. Evidently levels, rects, and puncts in their capacity as infinite aggregates cannot be the termini of sense- awareness, nor can they be limits which are approxi- mated to in sense-awareness. Any one member of a level has a certain quality arising from its character as also belonging to a certain set of moments, but the level as a whole is a mere logical notion without any route of approximation along entities posited in sense-awareness. On the other hand an event-particle is defined so as IV] METHOD OF EXTENSIVE ABSTRACTION 93 to exhibit this character of being a route of approxi- mation marked out by entities posited in sense-aware- ness. A definite event-particle is defined in reference to a definite punct in the foUov^ing manner: Let the condition a mean the property of covering all the abstractive elements which are members of that punct ; so that an abstractive set which satisfies the condition a is an abstractive set which covers every abstractive element belonging to the punct. Then the definition of the event-particle associated with the punct is that it is the group of all the cr-primes, where a has this particular meaning. It is evident that — ^with this meaning of and E lie on opposite sides of B respectively. By the aid of these two axioms the theory of congruence can be extended so as to compare lengths of segments on any two rects. Accordingly Euclidean metrical geometry in space is completely established and lengths in the spaces of different time-systems are comparable as the result of definite properties of nature which indicate just that particular method of comparison. The comparison of time-measurements in diverse time-systems requires two other axioms. The first of these axioms, forming the fifth axiom of congruence, will be called the axiom of * kinetic symmetry.' It expresses the symmetry of the quantitative relations between two time-systems when the times and lengths in the two systems are measured in congruent units. The axiom can be explained as follows : Let a and ^ be the names of two time-systems. The directions of motion in the space of a due to rest in a point of ^ is called the * j8-direction in a ' and the direction of motion in the space of j8 due to rest in a point of a is called the * a -direction in j8.' Consider a motion in the space of a consisting of a certain velocity in the jS -direction of a and a certain velocity at right-angles to it. This motion represents rest in the space of another time-system — W.N. 9 130 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch. call it TT . Rest in tt will also be represented in the space of )S by a certain velocity in the a -direction in /S and a certain velocity at right-angles to this « -direction. Thus a certain motion in the space of a is correlated to a certain motion in the space of j8, as both representing the same fact which can also be represented by rest in TT. Now another time-system, which I will name or, can be found which is such that rest in its space is represented by the same magnitudes of velocities along and perpendicular to the a -direction in j3 as those velocities in a, along and perpendicular to the j8 -direc- tion, which represent rest in tt. The required axiom of kinetic symmetry is that rest in a will be represented in a by the same velocities along and perpendicular to the j3 -direction in a as those velocities in /3 along and perpendicular to the a -direction which represent rest in TT. A particular case of this axiom is that relative velocities are equal and opposite. Namely rest in a is represented in j3 by a velocity along the a -direction which is equal to the velocity along the ^S -direction in a which repre- sents rest in j3. Finally the sixth axiom of congruence is that the relation of congruence is transitive. So far as this axiom applies to space, it is superfluous. For the property follows from our previous axioms. It is however necessary for time as a supplement to the axiom of kinetic symmetry. The meaning of the axiom is that if the time-unit of system a is congruent to the time- unit of system ^, and the time-unit of system ^ is congruent to the time-unit of system y, then the time- units of a and y are also congruent. By means of these axioms formulae for the trans- VI] CONGRUENCE 131 formation of measurements made in one time-system to measurements of the same facts of nature made in another time-system can be deduced. These formulae will be found to involve one arbitrary constant vy^hich I v^ill call k. It is of the dimensions of the square of a velocity. Accordingly four cases arise. In the first case k is zero. This case produces nonsensical results in opposi- tion to the elementary deliverances of experience. We put this case aside. In the second case k is infinite. This case yields the ordinary formulae for transformation in relative motion, namely those formulae v^hich are to be found in every elementary book on dynamics. In the third case, k is negative. Let us call it — c^, where c will be of the dimensions of a velocity. This case yields the formulae of transformation which Larmor discovered for the transformation of Maxwell's equations of the electromagnetic field. These formulae were extended by H. A. Lorentz, and used by Einstein and Minkowski as the basis of their novel theory of relativity. I am not now speaking of Einstein's more recent theory of general relativity by which he deduces his modification of the law of gravitation. If this be the case which applies to nature, then c must be a close approximation to the velocity of light in vacuo. Perhaps it is this actual velocity. In this connexion ^in vacuo' must not mean an absence of events, namely the absence of the all-pervading ether of events. It must mean the absence of certain types of objects. In the fourth case, k is positive. Let us call it A^, where A will be of the dimensions of a velocity. This gives a perfectly possible type of transformation formulae, 9—2 132 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch. but not one which explains any facts of experience. It has also another disadvantage. With the assumption of this fourth case the distinction between space and time becomes unduly blurred. The whole object of these lectures has been to enforce the doctrine that space and time spring from a common root, and that the ultimate fact of experience is a space-time fact. But after all mankind does distinguish very sharply between space and time, and it is owing to this sharpness of distinction that the doctrine of these lectures is some- what of a paradox. Now in the third assumption this sharpness of distinction is adequately preserved. There is a fundamental distinction between the metrical pro- perties of point-tracks and rects. But in the fourth assumption this fundamental distinction vanishes. Neither the third nor the fourth assumption can agree with experience unless we assume that the velocity c of the third assumption, and the velocity h of the fourth assumption, are extremely large compared to the velocities of ordinary experience. If this be the case the formulae of both assumptions will obviously reduce to a close approximation to the formulae of the second assumption which are the ordinary formulae of dynamical textbooks. For the sake of a name, I will call these textbook formulae the * orthodox' formulae. There can be no question as to the general approxi- mate correctness of the orthodox formulae. It would be merely silly to raise doubts on this point. But the determination of the status of these formulae is by no means settled by this admission. The independence of time and space is an unquestioned presupposition of the orthodox thought which has produced the ortho- dox formulae. With this presupposition and given the VI] CONGRUENCE 133 absolute points of one absolute space, the orthodox formulae are immediate deductions. Accordingly, these formulae are presented to our imaginations as facts which cannot be otherwise, time and space being what they are. The orthodox formulae have therefore attained to the status of necessities which cannot be questioned in science. Any attempt to replace these formulae by others was to abandon the rdle of physical explanation and to have recourse to mere mathematical formulae. But even in physical science difficulties have accumu- lated round the orthodox formulae. In the first place Maxwell's equations of the electromagnetic field are not invariant for the transformations of the orthodox formulae; whereas they are invariant for the trans- formations of the formulae arising from the third of the four cases mentioned above, provided that the velocity c is identified with a famous electromagnetic constant quantity. Again the null results of the delicate experiments to detect the earth's variations of motion through the ether in its orbital path are explained immediately by the formulae of the third case. But if we assume the orthodox formulae we have to make a special and ar- bitrary assumption as to the contraction of matter during motion. I mean the Fitzgerald-Lorentz assumption. Lastly Fresnel's coefficient of drag which represents the variation of the velocity of light in a moving medium is explained by the formulae of the third case, and requires another arbitrary assumption if we use the orthodox formulae. It appears therefore that on the mere basis of physical explanation there are advantages in the formulae 134 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch. of the third case as compared with the orthodox for- mulae. But the way is blocked by the ingrained belief that these latter formulae possess a character of necessity. It is therefore an urgent requisite for physical science and for philosophy to examine critically the grounds for this supposed necessity. The only satisfactory method of scrutiny is to recur to the first principles of our knowledge of nature. This is exactly what I am endeavouring to do in these lectures. I ask what it is that we are aware of in our sense-perception of nature. I then proceed to examine those factors in nature which lead us to conceive nature as occupying space and persisting through time. This procedure has led us to an investigation of the characters of space and time. It results from these investigations that the formulae of the third case and the orthodox formulae are on a level as possible formulae resulting from the basic character of our knowledge of nature. The orthodox formulae have thus lost any advantage as to necessity which they enjoyed over the serial group. The way is thus open to adopt whichever of the two groups best accords with observation. I take this opportunity of pausing for a moment from the course of my argument, and of reflecting on the general character which my doctrine ascribes to some familiar concepts of science. I have no doubt that some of you have felt that in certain aspects this character is very paradoxical. This vein of paradox is partly due to the fact that educated language has been made to conform to the prevalent orthodox theory. We are thus, in expounding an alternative doctrine, driven to the use of either strange terms or of familiar words with unusual meanings. This VI] CONGRUENCE 135 victory of the orthodox theory over language is very /JjP natural. Events are named after the prominent objects situated in them, and thus both in language and in thought the event sinks behind the object, and becomes the mere play of its relations. The theory of space is then converted into a theory of the relations of objects instead of a theory of the relations of events. But objects have not the passage of events. Accordingly space as a relation between objects is devoid of any connexion with time. It is space at an instant without any deter- minate relations between the spaces at successive in- stants. It cannot be one timeless space because the relations between objects change. A few minutes ago in speaking of the deduction of the orthodox formulae for relative motion I said that they followed as an immediate deduction from the assumption of absolute points in absolute space. This reference to absolute space was not an oversight. I know that the doctrine of the relativity of space at present holds the field both in science and philosophy. But I do not think that its inevitable consequences are understood. When we really face them the paradox of the presentation of the character of space which I have elaborated is greatly mitigated. If there is no absolute position, a point must cease to be a simple entity. What is a point to one man in a balloon with his eyes fixed on an instrument is a track of points to an observer on the earth who is watching the balloon through a telescope, and is another track of points to an observer in the sun who is watching the balloon through some instrument suited to such a being. Accordingly if I am reproached with the paradox of my theory of points as classes of event-particles, and of my theory of event-particles as u' ■A 136 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch. groups of abstractive sets, I ask my critic to explain exactly what he means by a point. While you explain your meaning about anything, however simple, it is always apt to look subtle and fine spun. I have at least explained exactly what I do mean by a point, what relations it involves and what entities are the relata. If you admit the relativity of space, you also must admit that points are complex entities, logical constructs involving other entities and their relations. Produce your theory, not in a few vague phrases of indefinite meaning, but explain it step by step in definite terms referring to assigned relations and assigned relata. Also show that your theory of points issues in a theory of space. Furthermore note that the example of the man in the balloon, the observer on earth, and the observer in the sun, shows that every assumption of relative rest requires a timeless space with radically different points from those which issue from every other such assump- tion. The theory of the relativity of space is incon- sistent with any doctrine of one unique set of points of one timeless space. The fact is that there is no paradox in my doctrine of the nature of space which is not in essence inherent in the theory of the relativity of space. But this doctrine has never really been accepted in science, whatever people say. What appears in our dynamical treatises is Newton's doctrine of relative motion based on the doctrine of differential motion in absolute space. When you once admit that the points are radically different entities for differing assumptions of rest, then the orthodox formulae lose all their obviousness. They were only obvious because you were really thinking of something else. When discussing this topic you can VI] CONGRUENCE 137 only avoid paradox by taking refuge from the flood of criticism in the comfortable ark of no meaning. The nev^ theory provides a definition of the con- gruence of periods of time. The prevalent viev^ pro- vides no such definition. Its position is that if we take such time-measurements so that certain familiar velocities which seem to us to be uniform are uniform, then the laws of motion are true. Now in the first place no change could appear either as uniform or non- uniform without involving a definite determination of the congruence for time-periods. So in appealing to familiar phenomena it allows that there is some factor in nature which we can intellectually construct as a congruence theory. It does not however say any- thing about it except that the laws of motion are then true. Suppose that with some expositors we cut out the reference to familiar velocities such as the rate of rotation of the earth. We are then driven to admit that there is no meaning in temporal congruence except that certain assumptions make the laws of motion true. Such a statement is historically false. King Alfred the Great was ignorant of the laws of motion, but knew very well what he meant by the measurement of time, and achieved his purpose by means of burning candles. Also no one in past ages justified the use of sand in hour-glasses by saying that some centuries later in- teresting laws of motion would be discovered which would give a meaning to the statement that the sand was emptied from the bulbs in equal times. Uniformity i in change is directly perceived, and it follows that mankind perceives in nature factors from which a theory of temporal congruence can be formed. The prevalent theory entirely fails to produce such factors. 138 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch. The mention of the laws of motion raises another point where the prevalent theory has nothing to say and the new theory gives a complete explanation. It is well known that the laws of motion are not valid for any axes of reference which you may choose to take fixed in any rigid body. You must choose a body which is not rotating and has no acceleration. For example they do not really apply to axes fixed in the earth because of the diurnal rotation of that body. The law which fails when you assume the wrong axes as at rest is the third law, that action and reaction are equal and opposite. With the wrong axes uncompensated centri- fugal forces and uncompensated composite centrifugal forces appear, due to rotation. The influence of these forces can be demonstrated by many facts on the earth's surface, Foucault's pendulum, the shape of the earth, the fixed directions of the rotations of cyclones and anticyclones. It is difficult to take seriously the sug- gestion that these domestic phenomena on the earth are due to the influence of the fixed stars. I cannot persuade myself to believe that a little star in its twinkling turned round Foucault's pendulum in the Paris Exhibition of 186 1. Of course anything is believ- able when a definite physical connexion has been demonstrated, for example the influence of sunspots. Here all demonstration is lacking in the form of any coherent theory. According to the theory of these lectures the axes to which motion is to be referred are axes at rest in the space of some time-system. For example, consider the space of a time-system a. There are sets of axes at rest in the space of a . These are suitable dynamical axes. Also a set of axes in this space which is moving with uniform velocity without rotation is VI] CONGRUENCE 139 another suitable set. All the moving points fixed in these moving axes are really tracing out parallel lines with one uniform velocity. In other words they are the reflections in the space of a of a set of fixed axes in the space of some other time-system jS. Accordingly the group of dynamical axes required for Newton's Laws of Motion is the outcome of the necessity of referring motion to a body at rest in the space of some one time-system in order to obtain a coherent account of physical properties. If we do not do so the meaning of the motion of one portion of our physical configuration is different from the meaning of the motion of another portion of the same configuration. Thus the meaning of motion being what it is, in order to describe the motion of any system of objects without changing the meaning of your terms as you proceed vdth your description, you are bound to take one of these sets of axes as axes of reference ; though you may choose their reflections into the space of any time-system which you wish to adopt. A definite physical reason is thereby assigned for the peculiar property of the dynamical group of axes. On the orthodox theory the position of the equations of motion is most ambiguous. The space to which they refer is completely undetermined and so is the measure- ment of the lapse of time. Science is simply setting out on a fishing expedition to see whether it cannot find some procedure which it can call the measurement of space and some procedure which it can call the measure- ment of time, and something which it can call a system of forces, and something which it can call masses, so that these formulae may be satisfied. The only reason — on this theory — ^why anyone should want to satisfy these formulae is a sentimental regard for Galileo, 140 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch. Newton, Euler and Lagrange. The theory, so far from founding science on a sound observational basis, forces everything to conform to a mere mathematical pre- ference for certain simple formulae. I do not for a moment believe that this is a true ac- count of the real status of the Laws of Motion. These equations want some slight adjustment for the new formulae of relativity. But with these adjustments, imperceptible in ordinary use, the laws deal with funda- mental physical quantities which we know very well and wish to correlate. The measurement of time was known to all civilised nations long before the laws were thought of. It is this time as thus measured that the laws are concerned with. Also they deal with the space of our daily life. When we approach to an accuracy of measurement beyond that of observation, adjustment is allowable. But within the limits of observation we know what we mean when we speak of measurements of space and measurements of time and uniformity of change. It is for science to give an intellectual account of what is so evident in sense-aware- ness. It is to me thoroughly incredible that the ultimate fact beyond which there is no deeper explanation is that mankind has really been swayed by an unconscious desire to satisfy the mathematical formulae which we call the Laws of Motion, formulae completely unknown till the seventeenth century of our epoch. The correlation of the facts of sense-experience effected by the alternative account of nature extends beyond the physical properties of motion and the properties of congruence. It gives an account of the meaning of the geometrical entities such as points, straight lines, and volumes, and connects the kindred VI] CONGRUENCE 141 ideas of extension in time and extension in space. The theory satisfies the true purpose of an intellectual explanation in the sphere of natural philosophy. This purpose is to exhibit the interconnexions of nature, and to show that one set of ingredients in nature requires for the exhibition of its character the presence of the other sets of ingredients. The false idea which we have to get rid of is that of nature as a mere aggregate of independent entities, each capable of isolation. According to this conception these entities, whose characters are capable of isolated defini- tion, come together and by their accidental relations form the system of nature. This system is thus thoroughly accidental; and, even if it be subject to a mechanical fate, it is only accidentally so subject. With this theory space might be without time, and time might be without space. The theory admittedly breaks down when we come to the relations of matter and space. The relational theory of space is an admission that we cannot know space without matter or matter without space. But the seclusion of both from time is still jealously guarded. The relations between portions of matter in space are accidental facts owing to the absence of any coherent account of how space springs from matter or how matter springs from space. Also what we really observe in nature, its colours and its sounds and its touches are secondary qualities; in other words, they are not in nature at all but are acci- dental products of the relations between nature and mind. The explanation of nature which I urge as an alter- native ideal to this accidental view of nature, is that nothing in nature could be what it is except as an 142 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch. vi ingredient in nature as it is. The whole which is present for discrimination is posited in sense-awareness as necessary for the discriminated parts. An isolated event is not an event, because every event is a factor in a larger whole and is significant of that whole. There can be no time apart from space ; and no space apart from time ; and no space and no time apart from the passage of the events of nature. The isolation of an entity in thought, when we think of it as a bare *it,' has no counterpart in any corresponding isolation in nature. Such isolation is merely part of the procedure of intel- lectual knowledge. The laws of nature are the outcome of the characters of the entities which we find in nature. The entities being what they are, the laws must be what they are; and conversely the entities follow from the laws. We are a long way from the attainment of such an ideal; but it remains as the abiding goal of theoretical science. CHAPTER VII OBJECTS The ensuing lecture is concerned with the theory of objects. Objects are e lements in nature which do not p ass. The awareness of an object as some factor not sharing in the passage of nature is what I call *recogni-| tion.' Itis^i npossible J:o recognise an^event^ because an event is essentially distinct from every o ther even t. Recognition is an awareness of samenessj But to call recognition an awareness of sameness implies an in- tellectual act of comparison accompanied with judgment. I use recognition for the non-intellectual relation of sense-awareness which connects the mind with a factor of nature without passage. On the intellectual side of the mind's experience there are comparisons of things recognised and consequent judgments of sameness or diversity. Probably * sense-recognition ' would be a better term for what I mean by * recognition.' I have chosen the simpler term because I think that I shall be able to avoid the use of * recognition ' in any other meaning than that of * sense-recognition.' I am quite willing to believe that recognition, in my sense of the term, is merely an ideal limit, and that there is in fact no recognition without intellectual accompaniments of comparison and judgment. But recognition is that relation of the mind to nature which provides the material for the intellectual activity. An object is an ingredient in the character of some event. In fact the character of an event is nothing but the objects which are ingredient in it and the ways in 144 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch. (which those objects make their ingression into the event. Thus the theory of objects is the theory of the comparison of events. Events are only comparable because they body forth permanences. We are com- paring objects in events whenever we can say, * There it is again.' Objects are the elements in nature which can *be again.' Sometimes permanences can be proved to exist which evade recognition in the sense in which I am using that term. The permanences which evade recogni- tion appear to us as abstract properties either of events or of objects. All the same they are there for recognition although undiscriminated in our sense-awareness. The demarcation of events, the splitting of nature up into parts is effected by the objects which we recognise as their ingredients. The discrimination of nature is the recognition of objects amid passing events. It is a compound of the awareness of the passage of nature, of the consequent partition of nature, and of the defini- tion of certain parts of nature by the modes of the ingression of objects into them. You may have noticed that I am using the term * ingression' to denote the general relation of objects to events. The ingression of an object into an event is the way the character of the event shapes itself in virtue of the being of the object. Namely the event is what it is, because the object is what it is ; and when I am thinking of this modification of the event by the object, I call the relation between the two *the ingression of the object into the event.' It is equally true to say that objects are what they are because events are what they iare. Nature is such that there can be no events and no objects without the ingression of objects into events. VII] OBJECTS 145 Although there are events such that the ingredient! objects evade our recognition. These are the events in( empty space. Such events are only analysed for us by]| the intellectual probing of science. Ingression is a relation vv^hich has various modes. There are obviously very various kinds of objects; and no one kind of object can have the same sort of relations to events as objects of another kind can have. We shall have to analyse out some of the different modes of ingression w^hich different kinds of objects have into events. But even if wt stick to one and the same kind of objects, an object of that kind has different modes of ingression into different events. Science and philo- sophy have been apt to entangle themselves in a simple- minded theory that an object is at one place at any definite time, and is in no sense anyvs^here else. This is in fact the attitude of common sense thought, thou gh it is no t the attitud e of lang ua ge vv^hich is naively expressing the facts oFexperience . Every other sentence in a w^ork of literature which is endeavouring truly to interpret the facts of experience expresses differences in surrounding events due to the presence of some object. An object is ingredient throughout its neighbourhood, and its neighbourhood is indefinite. Also the modification of events by ingression is susceptible of quantitative differences. Finally therefore we are driven to admit / that each object is in some sense ingredient throughout I nature; though its ingression may be quantitatively ' irrelevant in the expression of our individual experi- ences. This admission is not new either in philosophy or science. It is obviously a necessary axiom for those W.N. 10 146 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch. philosophers who insist that reahty is a system. In these lectures we are keeping off the profound and vexed question as to what we mean by *reaUty.' I am maintaining the humbler thesis that nature is a system. But I suppose that in this case the less follows from the greater, and that I may claim the support of these philosophers. The same doctrine is essentially interwoven in all modern physical speculation. As long ago as 1847 Faraday in a paper in the Philosophical Magazine remarked that his theory of tubes of force im.plies that in a sense an electric charge is everywhere. The modi- fication of the electromagnetic field at every point of space at each instant owing to the past history of each electron is another way of stating the same fact. We can however illustrate the doctrine by the more familiar facts of life without recourse to the abstruse speculations of theoretical physics. The waves as they roll on to the Cornish coast tell of a gale in mid-Atlantic ; and our dinner witnesses to the-ingression of the cook into the dining room. It is ' evident that the ingression of objects into events in- cludes the theory of causation. I prefer to neglect this aspect of ingression, because causation raises the memory of discussions based upon theories of nature which are alien to my own. Also I think that some new light may be thrown on the subject by viewing it in this fresh aspect. The examples which I have given of the ingression of objects into events remind us that ingression takes a peculiar form in the case of some events; in a sense, it is a more concentrated form. For example, the electron has a certain position in space and a certain shape. Perhaps it is an extremely small sphere in a certain VII] OBJECTS 147 test-tube. The storm is a gale situated in mid- Atlantic with a certain latitude and longitude, and the cook is in the kitchen. I will call this special form of ingression the 'relation of situation'; also, by a double use of the word * situation,' I will call the event in which an object is situated * the situation of the object.' Thus a situation is an event which is a relatum in the relation of situation. Now our first impression is that at last we have come to the simple plain fact of where the object really is ; and that the vaguer relation which I call ingression should not be muddled up with the relation of situation, as if including it as a particular case. It seems so obvious that any object is in such and such a position, and that it is influencing other events in a totally different sense. Namely, in a sense an object is the character of the event which is its situation, but it onlv influences the character of other events. Accordingly the relations of situation and influencing are not generally the same sort of relation, and should not be subsumed under the same term ' ingression.' I believe that this notion is a mistake, and that it is impossible to draw a clear distinction between the two relations. For example. Where was your toothache? You went to a dentist and pointed out the tooth to him. He pro- nounced it perfectly sound, and cured you by stopping another tooth. Which tooth was the situation of the toothache? Again, a man has an arm amputated, and experiences sensations in the hand which he has lost. The situation of the imaginary hand is in fact merely thin air. You look into a mirror and see a fire. The flames that you see are situated behind the mirror. Again at night you watch the sky ; if some of the stars had vanished from existence hours ago, you would not be any the 10 — 2 148 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch. wiser. Even the situations of the planets differ from those which science would assign to them. Anyhow you are tempted to exclaim, the cook is in the kitchen. If you mean her mind, I will not agree with you on the point; for I am only talking of nature. Let us think only of her bodily presence. What do you mean by this notion? We confine ourselves to typical manifestations of it. You can see her, touch her, and hear her. But the examples which I have given you show that the notions of the situations of what you see, what you touch, and what you hear are not so sharply separated out as to defy further questioning. You cannot cling to the idea that we have two sets of ex- periences of nature, one of primary qualities which belong to the objects perceived, and one of secondary qualities which are the products of our mental excite- ments. All we know of nature is in the same boat, to sink or swim together. The constructions of science are merely expositions of the characters of things per- ceived. Accordingly to affirm that the cook is a certain dance of molecules and electrons is merely to affirm that the things about her which are perceivable have certain characters. The situations of the perceived manifestations of her bodily presence have only a very general relation to the situations of the molecules, to be determined by discussion of the circumstances of perception. In discussing the relations of situation in particular and of ingression in general, the first requisite is to note that objects are of radically different types. For each type ' situation ' and ' ingression ' have their own special meanings which are different from their meanings for other types, though connexions can be pointed out. VII] OBJECTS 149 It is necessary therefore in discussing them to deter- mine what type of objects are under consideration. There are, I think, an indefinite number of types of objects. Happily we need not think of them all. The ) idea of situation has its peculiar importance in reference to three types of objects which I call sense-objects, perceptual objects and scientific objects. The suitability of these names for the three types is of minor import- ance, so long as I can succeed in explaining what I mean by them. These three types form an ascending hierarchy, of which each member presupposes the type below. Thel base of the hierarchy is formed by the sense-objects. These objects do not presuppose any other type of objects. A sense-object is a factor of nature posited | by sense-awareness which (i), in that it is an object, does I not share in the passage of nature and (ii) is not a J relation between other factors of nature. It will of course be a relatum in relations which also implicate other factors of nature. But it is always a relatum and never the relation itself. Examples of sense-objects are a particular sort of colour, say Cambridge blue, or a particular sort of sound, or a particular sort of smell, or a particular sort of feeling. I am not talking of a particular patch of blue as seen during a particular second of time at a definite date. Such a patch is an event where Cambridge blue is situated. Similarly I am not talking of any particular concert-room as filled with the note. I mean the note itself and not the patch of volume filled by the sound for a tenth of a second. It is natural for us to think of the note in itself, but in the case of colour we are apt to think of it merely as a property of the patch. No one thinks of the note as a 150 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch. property of the concert-room. We see the blue and we hear the note. Both the blue and the note are im- mediately posited by the discrimination of sense-aware- ness which relates the mind to nature. The blue is posited as in nature related to other factors in nature. In particular it is posited as in the relation of being situated in the event which is its situation. The difficulties which cluster around the relation of situation arise from the obstinate refusal of philosophers to take seriously the ultimate fact of multiple relations. By a multiple relation I mean a relation which in any concrete instance of its occurrence necessarily involves more than two relata. For example, when John likes Thomas there are only two relata, John and Thomas. But when John gives that book to Thomas there are three relata, John, that book, and Thomas. Some schools of philosophy, under the influence of the Aristotelian logic and the Aristotelian philosophy, endeavour to get on without admitting any relations at all except that of substance and attribute. Namely all apparent relations are to be resolvable into the con- current existence of substances with contrasted at- tributes. It is fairly obvious that the Leibnizian monad- ology is the necessary outcome of any such philosophy. If you dislike pluralism, there will be only one monad. Other schools of philosophy admit relations but obstinately refuse to contemplate relations with more than two relata. I do not think that this limitation is based on any set purpose or theory. It merely arises from the fact that more complicated relations are a bother to people without adequate mathematical training, when they are admitted into the reasoning. I must repeat that we have nothing to do in these VII] OBJECTS 151 lectures with the ultimate character of reality. It is quite possible that in the true philosophy of reality there are only individual substances with attributes, or that there are only relations with pairs of relata. I do not believe that such is the case ; but I am not concerned to argue about it now. Our theme is Nature. So long as we confine ourselves to the factors posited in the sense-awareness of nature, it seems to me that there certainly are instances of multiple relations between these factors, and that the relation of situation for sense- objects is one example of such multiple relations. Consider a blue coat, a flannel coat of Cambridge blue belonging to some athlete. The coat itself is a perceptual object and its situation is not what I am talking about. We are talking of someone's definite sense-awareness of Cambridge blue as situated in some event of nature. He may be looking at the coat directly. He then sees Cambridge blue as situated practically in the same event as the coat at that instant. It is true that the blue which he sees is due to light which left the coat some inconceivably small fraction of a second before. This diflFerence would be important if he were looking at a starwhosecolourwas Cambridge blue. The star might have ceased to exist days ago, or even years ago. The situation of the blue will not then be very intimately connected with the situation (in another sense of * situation ') of any perceptual object. This disconnexion of the situation of the blue and the situation of some associated perceptual object does not require a star for its exemplification. Any looking glass will suffice. Look at the coat through a looking glass. Then blue is seen as situated behind the mirror. The event which is its situation depends upon the position of the observer. 152 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch. The sense-awareness of the blue as situated in a certain event which I call the situation, is thus ex- hibited as the sense-awareness of a relation between the blue, the percipient event of the observer, the situation, and intervening events. All nature is in fact required, though only certain intervening events require their characters to be of certain definite sorts. The ingression of blue into the events of nature is thus exhibited as systematically correlated. The awareness of the observer depends on the position of the percipient event in this systematic correlation. I will use the term 'ingression into nature ' for this systematic correlation of the blue with nature. Thus the ingression of blue into any definite event is a part statement of the fact of the ingression of blue into nature. In respect to the ingression of blue into nature events may be roughly put into four classes which overlap and are not very clearly separated. These classes are (i) the percipient events, (ii) the situations, (iii) the active conditioning events, (iv) the passive conditioning events. To understand this classification of events in the general fact of the ingression of blue into nature, let us confine attention to one situation for one percipient event and to the consequent roles of the conditioning events for the ingression as thus limited. The percipient event is the relevant bodily state of the observer. The situation is where he sees the blue, say, behind the mirror. The active conditioning events are the events whose charac- ters are particularly relevant for the event (which is the situation) to be the situation for that percipient event, namely the coat, the mirror, and the state of the room as to light and atmosphere. The passive conditioning events are the events of the rest of nature. VII] OBJECTS 153 In general the situation is an active conditioning event; namely the coat itself, when there is no mirror or other such contrivance to produce abnormal effects. But the example of the mirror shows us that the situation may be one of the passive conditioning events. We are then apt to say that our senses have been cheated, because we demand as a right that the situation should be an active condition in the ingression. This demand is not so baseless as it may seem when presented as I have put it. All we know of the characters of the events of nature is based on the analysis of the relations of situations to percipient events. If situations were not in general active conditions, this analysis would tell us nothing. Nature would be an unfathom- able enigma to us and there could be no science. Ac- cordingly the incipient discontent when a situation is found to be a passive condition is in a sense justifiable ; because if that sort of thing went on too often, the rdle of the intellect would be ended. Furthermore the mirror is itself the situation of other sense-objects either for the same observer with the same percipient event, or for other observers with other percipient events. Thus the fact that an event is a situation in the ingression of one set of sense-objects into nature is presumptive evidence that that event is an active condition in the ingression of other sense- objects into nature which may have other situations. This is a fundamental principle of science which it has derived from common sense. I now turn to perceptual objects. When we look at the coat, we do not in general say. There is a patch of Cambridge blue ; what naturally occurs to us is, There is a coat. Also the judgment that what we have seen is 154 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch a garment of man's attire is a detail. What we perceive is an object other than a mere sense-object. It is not a mere patch of colour, but something more; and it is that something more which we judge to be a coat. I will use the word *coat' as the name for that crude object which is more than a patch of colour, and without any allusion to the judgments as to its usefulness as an » article of attire either in the past or the future. The coat which is perceived — in this sense of the word ' coat * — is what I call a perceptual object. We have to investigate the general character of these perceptual objects. It is a law of nature that in general the situation of a sense-object is not only the situation of that sense- object for one definite percipient event, but is the situation of a variety of sense-objects for a variety of percipient events. For example, for any one percipient event, the situation of a sense-object of sight is apt also to be the situations of sense-objects of sight, of touch, of smell, and of sound. Furthermore this concurrence in the situations of sense-objects has led to the body — i£, the percipient event — so adapting itself that the perception of one sense-object in a certain situation leads to a subconscious sense-awareness of other sense- objects in the same situation. This interplay is especially the case between touch and sight. There is a certain correlation between the ingressions of sense-objects of touch and sense-objects of sight into nature, and in a slighter degree between the ingressions of other pairs of sense-objects. I call this sort of correlation the * con- veyance' of one sense-object by another. When you see the blue flannel coat you subconsciously feel yourself wearing it or otherwise touching it. If you are a smoker, you may also subconsciously be aware of the VII] OBJECTS 155 faint aroma of tobacco. The peculiar fact, posited by this sense-awareness of the concurrence of subconscious sense-objects along with one or more dominating sense- objects in the same situation, is the sense-awareness of the perceptual object. The perceptual object is not 1 primarily the issue of a judgment. It is a factor of nature j u-fi directly posited in sense-awareness. The element of L, -- — judgment comes in when we proceed to classify thej;^ particular perceptual object. For example, we say, - That is flannel, and we think of the properties of flannel and the uses of athletes' coats. But that all takes place after we have got hold of the perceptual object. Anti- cipatory judgments affect the perceptual object per- ceived by focussing and diverting attention. The perceptual object is the outcome of the habit of experience. Anything which conflicts with this habit hinders the sense-awareness of such an object. A sense- object is not the product of the association of intellectual ideas ; it is the product of the association of sense-objects in the same situation. This outcome is not intellectual; it is an object of peculiar type with its own particular ingression into nature. There are two kinds of perceptual objects, namely, 'delusive perceptual objects' and * physical objects.' The situation of a delusive perceptual object is a passive condition in the ingression of that object into nature. Also the event which is the situation will have the relation of situation to the object only for one particular percipient event. For example, an observer sees the image of the blue coat in a mirror. It is a blue coat that he sees and not a mere patch of colour. This shows that the active conditions for the conveyance of a group of subconscious sense-objects by a dominating ,^^^^ 156 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [CH. sense-object are to be found in the percipient event. Namely we are to look for them in the investigations of medical psychologists. The ingression into nature of the delusive sense-object is conditioned by the adapta- tion of bodily events to the more normal occurrence, which is the ingression of the physical object. A perceptual object is a physical object when (i) its situation is an active conditioning event for the in- gression of any of its component sense-objects, and (ii) the same event can be the situation of the perceptual object for an indefinite number of possible percipient events. Physical objects are the ordinary objects which we perceive when our senses are not cheated, such as chairs, tables and trees. In a way physical objects have more insistent perceptive power than sense-objects. Attention to the fact of their occurrence in nature is the first condition for the survival of complex living or- ganisms. The result of this high perceptive power of physical objects is the scholastic philosophy of nature which looks on the sense-objects as mere attributes of the physical objects. This scholastic point of view is directly contradicted by the wealth of sense-objects which enter into our experience as situated in events without any connexion with physical objects. For example, stray smells, sounds, colours and more subtle nameless sense-objects. There is no perception of physical objects without perception of sense-objects. But the converse does not hold: namely, there is abundant perception of sense-objects unaccompanied by any perception of physical objects. This lack of reciprocity in the relations between sense-objects and physical objects is fatal to the scholastic natural philo- sophy. VII] OBJECTS 157 There is a great difference in the rSles of the situa- tions of sense-objects and physical objects. The situa- tions of a physical object are conditioned by uniqueness and continuity. The uniqueness is an ideal limit to which we approximate as we proceed in thought along an abstractive set of durations, considering smaller and smaller durations in the approach to the ideal limit of the moment of time. In other words, when the duration is small enough, the situation of the physical object within that duration is practically unique. The identification of the same physical object as being situated in distinct events in distinct durations is effected by the condition of continuity. This condition of continuity is the condition that a continuity of passage of events, each event being a situation of the object in its corresponding duration, can be found from the earlier to the later of the two given events. So far as the two events are practically adjacent in one specious present, this continuity of passage may be directly perceived. Otherwise it is a matter of judgment and inference. The situations of a sense-object are not conditioned by any such conditions either of uniqueness or of con- tinuity. In any durations however small a sense-object may have any number of situations separated from each other. Thus two situations of a sense-object, either in the same duration or in different durations, are not necessarily connected by any continuous passage of events which are also situations of that sense-object. The characters of the conditioning events involved in the ingression of a sense-object into nature can be largely expressed in terms of the physical objects which are situated in those events. In one respect this is also a tautology. For the physical object is nothing else than 158 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch. the habitual concurrence of a certain set of sense-objects in one situation. Accordingly when we know all about the physical object, we thereby know its component sense-objects. But a physical object is a condition for the occurrence of sense-objects other than those which are its components. For example, the atmosphere causes the events which are its situations to be active con- ditioning events in the transmission of sound. A mirror which is itself a physical object is an active condition for the situation of a patch of colour behind it, due to the reflection of light in it. "" Thus the origin of scientific knowledge is the en- deavour to express in terms of physical objects the various r6les of events as active conditions in the in- gression of sense-objects into nature. It is in the progress of this investigation that scientific objects emerge. They embody those aspects of the character of the situations of the physical objects which are most permanent and are expressible without reference to a multiple relation including a percipient event. Their relations to each other are also characterised by a certain simplicity and uniformity. Finally the characters of the observed physical objects and sense-objects can be expressed in terms of these scientific objects. In fact the whole point of the search for scientific objects is the endeavour to obtain this simple expression of the characters of events. These scientific objects are not themselves merely formulae for calculation ; because formulae must refer to things in nature, and the scientific objects are the things in nature to which the formulae refer. A scientific object such as a definite electron is a systematic correlation of the characters of all events throughout all nature. It is an aspect of the systematic VII] OBJECTS 159 character of nature. The electron is not merely where its charge is. The charge is the quantitative character of certain events due to the ingression of the electron into nature. The electron is its whole field of force. Namely the electron is the systematic way in which all events are modified as the expression of its ingression. The situation of an electron in any small duration may be defined as that event which has the quantitative character which is the charge of the electron. We may if we please term the mere charge the electron. But then another name is required for the scientific object which is the full entity which concerns science, and which I have called the electron. According to this conception of scientific objects, the rival theories of action at a distance and action by transmission through a medium are both incomplete expressions of the true process of nature. The stream of events which form the continuous series of situations of the electron is entirely self-determined, both as regards having the intrinsic character of being the series of situations of that electron and as regards the time- systems with which its various members are cogredient, and the flux of their positions in their corresponding durations. This is the foundation of the denial of action at a distance ; namely the progress of the stream of the situations of a scientific object can be determined by an analysis of the stream itself. On the other hand the ingression of every electron into nature modifies to some extent the character of every event. Thus the character of the stream of events which we are considering bears marks of the existence of every other electron throughout the universe. If we like to think of the electrons as being merely what I call i6o THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch. their charges, then the charges act at a distance. But this action consists in the modification of the situation of the other electron under consideration. This con- ception of a charge acting at a distance is a wholly artificial one. The conception which most fully expresses the character of nature is that of each event as modified by the ingression of each electron into nature. The ether is the expression of this systematic modification of events throughout space and throughout time. The best expres- sion of the character of this modification is for physicists to find out. My theory has nothing to do with that and is ready to accept any outcome of physical research. The connexion of objects with space requires eluci- dation. Objects are situated in events. The relation of situation is a different relation for each type of object, and in the case of sense-objects it cannot be expressed as a two-termed relation. It would perhaps be better to use a different word for these different types of the relation of situation. It has not however been necessary to do so for our purposes in these lectures. It must be understood however that, when situation is spoken of, some one definite type is under discussion, and it may happen that the argument may not apply to situation of another type. In all cases however I use situation to express a relation between objects and events and not between objects and abstractive elements. There is a derivative relation between objects and spatial elements which I call the relation of location; and when this relation holds, I say that the object is located in the abstractive element. In this sense, an object may be located in a moment of time, in a volume of space, an area, a line, or a point. There will be a peculiar type of location corresponding to each type of situation; and VII] OBJECTS i6i location is in each case derivative from the corresponding relation of situation in a v^ay w^hich I v^ill proceed to explain. Also location in the timeless space of some time-system is a relation derivative from location in instantaneous spaces of the same time-system. Accordingly location in an instantaneous space is the primary idea w^hich w^e have to explain. Great confusion has been occasioned in natural philosophy by the neglect to distinguish be- tw^een the different types of objects, the different types of situation, the different types of location, and the difference betw^een location and situation. It is im- possible to reason accurately in the vague concerning objects and their positions vs^ithout keeping these dis- tinctions in viev^. An object is located in an abstractive element, when an abstractive set belonging to that ele- ment can be found such that each event belonging to that set is a situation of the object. It v^ill be remem- bered that an abstractive element is a certain group of abstractive sets, and that each abstractive set is a set of events. This definition defines the location of an element in any type of abstractive element. In this sense v^e can talk of the existence of an object at an instant, meaning thereby its location in some definite moment. It may also be located in some spatial element of the instantaneous space of that moment. A quantity can be said to be located in an abstractive element vv^hen an abstractive set belonging to the element can be found such that the quantitative expressions of the corresponding characters of its events converge to the measure of the given quantity as a limit v^hen we pass along the abstractive set towards its converging end. W.N. II i62 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch. By these definitions location in elements of instanta- neous spaces is defined. These elements occupy corre- sponding elements of timeless spaces. An object located in an element of an instantaneous space will also be said to be located at that moment in the timeless element of the timeless space which is occupied by that instantaneous element. It is not every object which can be located in a moment. An object which can be located in every moment of some duration will be called a * uniform' object throughout that duration. Ordinary physical objects appear to us to be uniform objects, and we habitually assume that scientific objects such as electrons are uniform. But some sense-objects certainly are not uniform. A tune is an example of a non-uniform object. We have per- ceived it as a whole in a certain duration ; but the tune as a tune is not at any moment of that duration though one of the individual notes may be located there. It is possible therefore that for the existence of certain sorts of objects, e,g, electrons, minimum quanta of time are requisite. Some such postulate is apparently indicated by the modern quantum theory and it is per- fectly consistent with the doctrine of objects maintained in these lectures. Also the instance of the distinction between the electron as the mere quantitative electric charge of its situation and the electron as standing for the ingression of an object throughout nature illustrates the indefinite number of types of objects which exist in nature. We can intellectually distinguish even subtler and subtler types of objects. Here I reckon subtlety as meaning seclusion from the immediate apprehension of sense- awareness. Evolution in the complexity of life means an VII] OBJECTS 163 increase in the types of objects directly sensed. Deli- cacy of sense-apprehension means perceptions of objects as distinct entities which are mere subtle ideas to cruder sensibilities. The phrasing of music is a mere abstract subtlety to the unmusical; it is a direct sense-appre- hension to the initiated. For example, if we could imagine some lowly type of organic being thinking and aware of our thoughts, it would wonder at the abstract subtleties in which we indulge as we think of stones and bricks and drops of water and plants. It only knows of vague undifferentiated feelings in nature. It would consider us as given over to the play of excessively abstract intellects. But then if it could think, it would anticipate; and if it anticipated, it would soon per- ceive for itself. In these lectures we have been scrutinising the foundations of natural philosophy. We are stopping at the very point where a boundless ocean of enquiries opens out for our questioning. I agree that the view of Nature which I have main- tained in these lectures is not a simple one. Nature appears as a complex system whose factors are dimly discerned by us. But, as I ask you. Is not this the very truth ? Should we not distrust the jaunty assurance with which every age prides itself that it at last has hit upon the ultimate concepts in which all that happens can be formulated } The aim of science is to seek the simplest explanations of complex facts. We are apt to fall into the error of thinking that the facts are simple because simplicity is the goal of our quest. The guiding motto in the life of every natural philosopher should be, Seek simplicity and distr ust it . — — — ^ — "• — - -1^1 -^ »i ^"^^"^ CHAPTER VIII SUMMARY There is a general agreement that Einstein's investiga- tions have one fundamental merit irrespective of any criticisms which we may feel inclined to pass on them. They have made us think. But when we have admitted so far, we are most of us faced with a distressing per- plexity. What is it that we ought to think about? The purport of my lecture this afternoon will be to meet this difficulty and, so far as I am able, to set in a clear Ught the changes in the background of our scientific thought which are necessitated by any acceptance, however qualified, of Einstein's main positions. I remember that I am lecturing to the members of a chemical society who are not for the most part versed in advanced mathematics. The first point that I would urge upon you is that what immediately concerns you is not so much the detailed deductions of the new theory as this general change in the background of scientific conceptions which will follow from its acceptance. Of course, the detailed deductions are important, because unless our colleagues the astronomers and the physicists find these predictions to be verified we can neglect the theory altogether. But we may now take it as granted that in many striking particulars these deductions have been found to be in agreement with observation. Accord- ingly the theory has to be taken seriously and we are anxious to know what will be the consequences of its final acceptance. Furthermore during the last few weeks CH. VIII] SUMMARY 165 the scientific journals and the lay press have been filled w^ith articles as to the nature of the crucial experiments which have been made and as to some of the more striking expressions of the outcome of the new theory. * Space caught bending' appeared on the news-sheet of a well-known evening paper. This rendering is a terse but not inapt translation of Einstein's own way of interpreting his results. I should say at once that I am a heretic as to this explanation and that I shall expound to you another explanation based upon some work of my own, an explanation which seems to me to be more in accordance with our scientific ideas and with the whole body of facts which have to be explained. We have to remember that a new theory must take account of the old well-attested facts of science just as much as of the very latest experimental results which have led to its production. To put ourselves in the position to assimilate and to criticise any change in ultimate scientific conceptions we must begin at the beginning. So you must bear with me if I commence by making some simple and obvious reflections. Let us consider three statements, (i) * Yes- terday a man was run over on the Chelsea Embankment,' (ii) * Cleopatra's Needle is on the Charing Cross Em- bankment,' and (iii) * There are dark lines in the Solar Spectrum.' The first statement about the accident to the man is about what we may term an * occurrence,' a * happening,' or an * event.' I will use the term * event ' because it is the shortest. In order to specify an observed event, the place, the time, and character of the event are necessary. In specifying the place and the time you are really stating the relation of the assigned event to the general structure of other observed events. For i66 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch. example, the man was run over between your tea and your dinner and adjacently to a passing barge in the river and the traffic in the Strand. The point which I want to make is this: Nature is known to us in our experience as a complex of passing events. In this complex we discern definite mutual relations between component events, which we may call their relative positions, and these positions we express partly in terms of space and partly in terms of time. Also in addition to its mere relative position to other events, each par- ticular event has its own peculiar character. In other words, nature is a structure of events and each event has its position in this structure and its own peculiar character or quality. Let us now examine the other two statements in the light of this general principle as to the meaning of nature. Take the second statement, * Cleopatra's Needle is on the Charing Cross Embankment.' At first sight we should hardly call this an event. It seems to lack the element of time or transitoriness. But does it ? If an angel had made the remark some hundreds of millions of years ago, the earth was not in existence, twenty millions of years ago there was no Thames, eighty years ago there was no Thames Embankment, and when I was a small boy Cleopatra's Needle was not there. And now that it is there, we none of us expect it to be eternal. The static timeless element in the rela- tion of Cleopatra's Needle to the Embankment is a pure illusion generated by the fact that for purposes of daily intercourse its emphasis is needless. What it comes to is this : Amidst the structure of events which form the medium within which the daily life of Lon- doners is passed we know how to identify a certain VIII] SUMMARY 167 stream of events which maintain permanence of charac- ter, namely the character of being the situations of Cleopatra's Needle. Day by day and hour by hour we can find a certain chunk in the transitory life of nature and of that chunk we say, * There is Cleopatra's Needle/ If we define the Needle in a sufficiently abstract manner we can say that it never changes. But a physicist who looks on that part of the life of nature as a dance of electrons, will tell you that daily it has lost some mole- cules and gained others, and even the plain man can see that it gets dirtier and is occasionally washed. Thus the question of change in the Needle is a mere matter of definition. The more abstract your definition, the more permanent the Needle. But whether your Needle change or be permanent, all you mean by stating that it is situated on the Charing Cross Embankment, is that amid the structure of events you know of a certain con- tinuous limited stream of events, such that any chunk of that stream, during any hour, or any day, or any second, has the character of being the situation of Cleopatra's Needle. Finally, we come to the third statement, * There are dark lines in the Solar Spectrum.' This is a law of nature. But what does that mean ? It means merely this. If any event has the character of being an exhibition of the solar spectrum under certain assigned circumstances, it will also have the character of exhibiting dark lines in that spectrum. This long discussion brings us to the final conclusion that the concrete facts of nature are events exhibiting a certain structure in their mutual relations and certain characters of their own. The aim of science is to express the relations between their characters in terms of the i68 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch. mutual structural relations between the events thus characterised. The mutual structural relations between events are both spatial and temporal. If you think of them as merely spatial you are omitting the temporal element, and if you think of them as merely temporal you are omitting the spatial element. Thus when you think of space alone, or of time alone, you are dealing in abstractions, namely, you are leaving out an essential element in the life of nature as known to you in the experience of your senses. Furthermore there are different ways of making these abstractions which we think of as space and as time ; and under some circum- stances we adopt one way and under other circumstances we adopt another way. Thus there is no paradox in holding that what we mean by space under one set of circumstances is not what we mean by space under another set of circumstances. And equally what we mean by time under one set of circumstances is not what we mean by time under another set of circum- stances. By saying that space and time are abstractions, I do not mean that they do not express for us real facts about nature. What I mean is that there are no spatial facts or temporal facts apart from physical nature, namely that space and time are merely ways of expressing certain truths about the relations between events. Also that under different circumstances there are different sets of truths about the universe which are naturally presented to us as statements about space. In such a case what a being under the one set of circumstances means by space will be different from that meant by a being under the other set of circumstances. Accord- ingly when we are comparing two observations made under different circumstances we have to ask ' Do the VIII] SUMMARY 169^ two observers mean the same thing by space and the same thing by time ? ' The modern theory of relativity has arisen because certain perplexities as to the con- cordance of certain delicate observations such as the motion of the earth through the ether, the perihelion of mercury, and the positions of the stars in the neigh- bourhood of the sun, have been solved by reference to this purely relative significance of space and time. I want now to recall your attention to Cleopatra^s Needle, which I have not yet done with. As you are walking along the Embankment you suddenly look up and say, 'Hullo, there's the Needle.' In other words, you recognise it. You cannot recognise an event; because when it is gone, it is gone. You may observe another event of analogous character, but the actual chunk of the life of nature is inseparable from its unique occurrence. But a character of an event can be recog- nised. We all know that if we go to the Embankment near Charing Cross we shall observe an event having the character which we recognise as Cleopatra's Needle. Things which we thus recognise I call objects. An object is situated in those events or in that stream of events of which it expresses the character. There are many sorts of objects. For example, the colour green is an object according to the above definition. It is the purpose of science to trace the laws which govern the appearance of objects in the various events in which they are found to be situated. For this purpose we can mainly concentrate on two types of objects, which I will call material physical objects and scientific objects. A material physical object is an ordinary bit of matter, Cleopatra's Needle for example. This is a much more complicated type of object than a mere colour, such as I70 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch. the colour of the Needle. I call these simple objects, such as colours or sounds, sense-objects. An artist will train himself to attend more particularly to sense- objects where the ordinary person attends normally to material objects. Thus if you were walking with an artist, when you said * There's Cleopatra's Needle,' perhaps he simultaneously exclaimed 'There's a nice bit of colour.' Yet you were both expressing your recognition of different component characters of the same event. But in science we have found out that when we know all about the adventures amid events of material physical objects and of scientific objects we have most of the relevant information which will enable us to predict the conditions under which we shall perceive sense-objects in specific situations. For ex- ample, when we know that there is a blazing fire (i.e. material and scientific objects undergoing various exciting adventures amid events) and opposite to it a mirror (which is another material object) and the positions of a man's face and eyes gazing into the mirror, we know that he can perceive the redness of the flame situated in an event behind the mirror — thus, to a large extent, the appearance of sense-objects is conditioned by the adventures of material objects. The analysis of these adventures makes us aware of another character of events, namely their characters as fields of activity which determine the subsequent events to which they will pass on the objects situated in them. We express these fields of activity in terms of gravitational, electro- magnetic, or chemical forces and attractions. But the exact expression of the nature of these fields of activity forces us intellectually to acknowledge a less obvious type of objects as situated in events. I mean molecules VIII] SUMMARY 17: and electrons. These objects are not recognised in isolation. We cannot well miss Cleopatra's Needle, if we are in its neighbourhood ; but no one has seen a single molecule or a single electron, yet the characters of events are only explicable to us by expressing them in terms of these scientific objects . Undoubtedly molecules and electrons are abstractions. But then so is Cleo- patra's Needle. The concrete facts are the events them- selves — I have already explained to you that to be an abstraction does not mean that an entity is nothing. It merely means that its existence is only one factor of a Inore concrete element of nature. So an electron is abstra ct because you cannot wipe out the whole structure of events and yet retain the electron in existence. In the same way the grin on the cat is abstract; and the molecule is really in the event in the same sense as the grin is really on the cat's face. Now the more ultimate sciences such as Chemistry or Physics cannot express their ultimate laws in terms of such vague objects as the sun, the earth, Cleopatra's Needle, or a human body. Such objects more properly belong to Astro- nomy, to Geology, to Engineering, to Archaeology, or to Biology. Chemistry and Physics only deal with them as exhibiting statistical complexes of the effects of their more intimate laws. In a certain sense, they only enter into Physics and Chemistry as technological applications. The reason is that they are too vague. Where does Cleopatra's Needle begin and where does it end.? Is the soot part of it? Is it a different object when it sheds a molecule or when its surface enters into chemical combination with the acid of a London fog? The definiteness and permanence of the Needle is nothing to the possible permanent definiteness 172 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch. of a molecule as conceived by science, and the per- manent definiteness of a molecule in its turn yields to that of an electron. Thus science in its most ultimate formulation of law seeks objects with the most per- manent definite simplicity of character and expresses its final laws in terms of them. Again when we seek definitely to express the relations of events which arise from their spatio-temporal structure, we approximate to simplicity by progressively diminishing the extent (both temporal and spatial) of the events considered. For example, the event which is the life of the chunk of nature which is the Needle during one minute has to the life of nature within a passing barge during the same minute a very complex spatio-temporal relation. But suppose we progressively diminish the time considered to a second, to a hun- dredth of a second, to a thousandth of a second, and so on. As we pass along such a series we approximate to an ideal simplicity of structural relations of the pairs of events successively considered, which ideal we call the spatial relations of the Needle to the barge at some instant. Even these relations are too complicated for us, and we consider smaller and smaller bits of the Needle and of the barge. Thus we finally reach the ideal of an event so restricted in its extension as to be without ex- tension in space or extension in time. Such an event is a mere spatial point-flash of instantaneous duration. I call such an ideal event an * event-particle.' You must not think of the world as ultimately built up of event- particles. That is to put the cart before the horse. The world we know is a continuous stream of occurrence which we can discriminate into finite events forming by their overlappings and containings of each other and VIII] SUMMARY 173 separations a spatio-temporal structure. We can express the properties of this structure in terms of the ideal limits to routes of approximation, which I have termed event-particles. Accordingly event-particles are abstrac- tions in their relations to the more concrete events. But then by this time you will have comprehended that you cannot analyse concrete nature without abstracting. Also I repeat, the abstractions of science are entities which are truly in nature, though they have no meaning in isolation from nature. The character of the spatio-temporal structure of events can be fully expressed in terms of relations between these more abstract event-particles. The ad- vantage of dealing with event-particles is that though they are abstract and complex in respect to the finite events which we directly observe, they are simpler than finite events in respect to their mutual relations. Accordingly they express for us the demands of an ideal accuracy, and of an ideal simplicity in the exposition of relations. These event-particles are the ultimate elements of the four-dimensional space-time manifold which the theory of relativity presupposes. You will have observed that each event-particle is as much an instant of time as it is a point of space. I have called it an instantaneous point-flash. Thus in the structure of this space-time manifold space is not finally discriminated from time, and the possibility remains open for diverse modes of discrimination according to the diverse circumstances of observers. It is this possibility which makes the fundamental distinction between the new way of con- ceiving the universe and the old way. The secret of understanding relativity is to understand this. It is of no use rushing in with picturesque paradoxes, such as 174 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch. * Space caught bending,' if you have not mastered this fundamental conception which underHes the whole theory. When I say that it underHes the whole theory, I mean that in my opinion it ought to underlie it, though I may confess some doubts as to how far all expositions of the theory have really understood its implications and its premises. Our measurements when they are expressed in terms of an ideal accuracy are measurements which express properties of the space-time manifold. Now there are measurements of different sorts. You can measure lengths, or angles, or areas, or volumes, or times. There are also other sorts of measures such as measurements of intensity of illumination, but I will disregard these for the moment and will confine attention to those measurements which particularly interest us as being measurements of space or of time. It is easy to see that four such measurements of the proper characters are necessary to determine the position of an event-particle in the space-time manifold in its relation to the rest of the manifold. For example, in a rectangular field you start from one corner at a given time, you measure a definite distance along one side, you then strike out into the field at right angles, and then measure a definite distance parallel to the other pair of sides, you then rise vertically a definite height and take the time. At the point and at the time which you thus reach there is occurring a definite instantaneous point-flash of nature. In other words, your four measurements have deter- mined a definite event-particle belonging to the four- dimension space-time manifold. These measurements have appeared to be very simple to the land-surveyor and raise in his mind no philosophic difficulties. But VIII] SUMMARY 175 suppose there are beings on Mars sufficiently advanced in scientific invention to be able to watch in detail the operations of this survey on earth. Suppose that they construe the operations of the English land-surveyors in reference to the space natural to a being on Mars, namely a Martio-centric space in which that planet is fixed. The earth is moving relatively to Mars and is rotating. To the beings on Mars the operations, con- strued in this fashion, effect measurements of the greatest complication. Furthermore, according to the relati- vistic doctrine, the operation of time-measurement on earth will not correspond quite exactly to any time- measurement on Mars. I have discussed this example in order to make you realise that in thinking of the possibilities of measure- ment in the space-time manifold, we must not confine ourselves merely to those minor variations which might seem natural to human beings on the earth. Let us make therefore the general statement that four measure- ments, respectively of independent types (such as mea- surements of lengths in three directions and a time), can be found such that a definite event-particle is determined by them in its relations to other parts of the manifold. I^ (Ply p2^ p3y P^) ^^ ^ set of measurements of this system, then the event-particle which is thus deter- mined will be said to have />i, p^, p^y ^4 as its co-ordi- nates in this system of measurement. Suppose that we name it the/)-system of measurement. Then in the same />-system by properly varying (/>!, p^, p^y p^ every event-particle that has been, or will be, or instantane- ously is now, can be indicated. Furthermore, according to any system of measurement that is natural to us. 176 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch. three of the co-ordinates will be measurements of space and one will be a measurement of time. Let us always take the last co-ordinate to represent the time-measure- ment. Then we should naturally say that (/>i, />2, Pz) determined a point in space and that the event-particle happened at that point at the tivatp^. But we must not make the mistake of thinking that there is a space in addition to the space-time manifold. That manifold is all that there is for the determination of the meaning of space and time. We have got to determine the meaning of a space-point in terms of the event-particles of the four-dimensional manifold. There is only one way to do this. Note that if we vary the time and take times with the same three space co-ordinates, then the event- particles, thus indicated, are all at the same point. But seeing that there is nothing else except the event- particles, this can only mean that the point (pi, />2> p^ of the space in the /)-system is merely the collection of event-particles (/>!, p^, p^, [pj)) where /)4 is varied and (pi, p2y Pz) is kept fixed. It is rather disconcerting to find that a point in space is not a simple entity ; but it is a conclusion which follows immediately from the relative theory of space. Furthermore the inhabitant of Mars determines event-particles by another system of measurements. Call his system the ^-system. According to him {qiy q2, ^3, g'4) determines an event-particle, and (^1, ^2> ^3) determines a point and ^4 a time. But the collection of event-particles which he thinks of as a point is entirely different from any such collection which the man on earth thinks of as a point. Thus the ^-space for the man on Mars is quite different from the ^-space for the land-surveyor on earth. VIII] SUMMARY 177 So far in speaking of space we have been talking of the timeless space of physical science, namely, of our concept of eternal space in v^hich the world adventures. But the space which we see as we look about is instan- taneous space. Thus if our natural perceptions are adjustable to the ^-system of measurements we see instantaneously all the event-particles at some definite time ^4, and observe a succession of such spaces as time moves on. The timeless space is achieved by stringing together all these instantaneous spaces. The points of an instantaneous space are event-particles, and the points of an eternal space are strings of event-particles occurring in succession. But the man on Mars will never perceive the same instantaneous spaces as the man on the earth. This system of instantaneous spaces will cut across the earth-man's system. For the earth- man there is one instantaneous space which is the instantaneous present, there are the past spaces and the future spaces. But the present space of the man on Mars cuts across the present space of the man on the earth. So that of the event-particles which the earth- man thinks of as happening now in the present, the man on Mars thinks that some are already past and are ancient history, that others are in the future, and others are in the immediate present. This break-down in the neat conception of a past, a present, and a future is a serious paradox. I call two event-particles which on some or other system of measurement are in the same instantaneous space * co-present' event-particles. Then it is possible that A and B may be co-present, and that A and C may be co-present, but that B and C may not be co-present. For example, at some inconceivable distance from us there are events co-present with us W.N. 12 178 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch. now and also co-present with the birth of Queen Victoria. If A and B are co-present there will be some systems in which A precedes B and some in which B precedes A, Also there can be no velocity quick enough to carry a material particle from ^ to j5 or from B to A. These different measure-systems with their divergences of time-reckoning are puzzling, and to some extent affront our common sense. It is not the usual way in which we think of the Universe. We think of one necessary time-system and one necessary space. Ac- cording to the new theory, there are an indefinite number of discordant time-series and an indefinite number of distinct spaces. Any correlated pair, a time-system and a space-system, will do in which to fit our description of the Universe. We find that under given conditions our measurements are necessarily made in some one pair which together form our natural measure-system. The difficulty as to discordant time- systems is partly solved by distinguishing between what I call the creative advance of nature, which is not properly serial at all, and any one time series. We habitually muddle together this creative advance, which we experience and know as the perpetual transition of nature into novelty, with the single- time series which we naturally employ for measurement. The various time-series each measure some aspect of the creative advance, and the whole bundle of them express all the properties of this advance which are measurable. The reason why we have not previously noted this difference of time-series is the very small difference of properties between any two such series. Any observable pheno- mena due to this cause depend on the square of the ratio of any velocity entering into the observation to VIII] SUMMARY 179 the velocity of light. Now^ Ught takes about fifty minutes to get round the earth's orbit; and the earth takes rather more than 17,531 half-hours to do the same. Hence all the effects due to this motion are of the order of the ratio of one to the square of 10,000. Accordingly an earth-man and a sun-man have only neglected effects whose quantitative magnitudes all contain the factor i/io^. Evidently such effects can only be noted by means of the most refined observations. They have been observed how^ever. Suppose wc compare two observations on the velocity of light made with the same apparatus as we turn it through a right angle. The velocity of the earth relatively to the sun is in one direction, the velocity of light relatively to the ether should be the same in all directions. Hence if space when we take the ether as at rest means the same thing as space when we take the earth as at rest, we ought to find that the velocity of light relatively to the earth varies according to the direction from which it comes. These observations on earth constitute the basic principle of the famous experiments designed to detect the motion of the earth through the ether. You all know that, quite unexpectedly, they gave a null result. This is completely explained by the fact that, the space- system and the time-system which we are using are in certain minute ways different from the space and the time relatively to the sun or relatively to any other body with respect to which it is moving. All this discussion as to the nature of time and space has lifted above our horizon a great difficulty which affects the formulation of all the ultimate laws of physics — for example, the laws of the electromagnetic field, and the law of gravitation. Let us take the law of i8o THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [CH. gravitation as an example. Its formulation is as follows : Two material bodies attract each other with a force proportional to the product of their masses and umka versely proportional to the square of their distances. In this statement the bodies are supposed to be small enough to be treated as material particles in relation to their distances; and we need not bother further about that minor point. The difficulty to which I want to draw your attention is this : In the formulation of the law one 'definite time and one definite space are pre- supposed. The two masses are assumed to be in simul- taneous positions. But what is simultaneous in one time-system may not be simultaneous in another time-system. So according to our new views the law is in this respect not formulated so as to have any exact meaning. Furthermore an analogous difficulty arises over the question of distance. The distance between two instantaneous positions, i.e, between two event-particles, is different in different space-systems. What space is to be chosen ? Thus again the law lacks precise formulation, if relativity is accepted. Our problem is to seek a fresh interpretation of the law of gravity in which these difficulties are evaded. In the first place we must avoid the abstractions of space and time in the formulation of our fundamental ideas and must recur to the ultimate facts of nature, namely to events. Also in order to find the ideal simplicity of expressions of the relations between events, we restrict ourselves to event-particles. Thus the life of a material particle is its adventure amid a track of event-particles strung out as a continuous series or path in the four- dimensional space-time manifold. These event-particles are the various situations of the material particle. We viiij SUMMARY i8i usually express this fact by adopting our natural space- time system and by talking of the path in space of the material particle as it exists at successive instants of time. We have to ask ourselves what are the laws of nature which lead the material particle to adopt just this path among event-particles and no other. Think of the path as a whole. What characteristic has that path got which would not be shared by any other slightly varied path ? We are asking for more than a law of gravity. We want laws of motion and a general idea of the way to formulate the effects of physical forces. In order to answer our question we put the idea of the attracting masses in the background and concentrate attention on the field of activity of the events in the neighbourhood of the path. In so doing we are acting in conformity with the whole trend of scientific thought during the last hundred years, which has more and more concentrated attention on the field of force as the im- mediate agent in directing motion, to the exclusion of the consideration of the immediate mutual influence between two distant bodies. We have got to find the way of expressing the field of activity of events in the neighbourhood of some definite event-particle E of the four-dimensional manifold. I bring in a fundamental physical idea which I call the * impetus ' to express this physical field. The event-particle E is related to any neighbouring event-particle P by an element of impetus. The assemblage of all the elements of impetus relating E to the assemblage of event-particles in the neighbour- hood of E expresses the character of the field of activity in the neighbourhood of E, Where I differ from Einstein is that he conceives this quantity which I call the impetus as merely expressing the characters of the space and i82 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch. time to be adopted and thus ends by talking of the gravitational field expressing a curvature in the space- time manifold. I cannot attach any clear conception to his interpretation of space and time. My formulae differ slightly from his, though they agree in those instances where his results have been verified. I need hardly say that in this particular of the formulation of the law of gravitation I have drawn on the general method of procedure which constitutes his great discovery. Einstein showed how to express the characters of the assemblage of elements of impetus of the field sur- rounding an event-particle E in terms of ten quantities which I will call J^* J12 (= .72i). J22. J23 (= ^32). etc. It will be noted that there are four spatio-temporal measurements relating E to its neighbour P, and that there are ten pairs of such measurements if we are allowed to take any one measurement twice over to make one such pair. The ten J's depend merely on the position of E in the four-dimensional manifold, and the element of impetus between E and P can be expressed in terms of the ten J's and the ten pairs of the four spatio-temporal measurements relating E and P. The numerical values of the J's will depend on the system of measurement adopted, but are so adjusted to each particular system that the same value is obtained for the element of impetus between E and P, whatever be the system of measurement adopted. This fact is ex- pressed by saying that the ten J's form a ' tensor.' It is not going too far to say that the announcement that physicists would have in future to study the theor^^ of tensors created a veritable panic among them when the verification of Einstein's predictions was first announced. VIII] SUMMARY 183 The ten J's at any event-particle E can be expressed in terms of tw^o functions w^hich I call the potential and the * associate-potential' at E. The potential is practically what is meant by the ordinary gravitation potential, when we express ourselves in terms of the Euclidean space in reference to which the attracting mass is at rest. The associate-potential is defined by the modifi- cation of substituting the direct distance for the inverse distance in the definition of the potential, and its calcu- lation can easily be made to depend on that of the old- fashioned potential. Thus the calculation of the J's — the coefficients of impetus, as I will call them — does not involve anything very revolutionary in the mathematical knowledge of physicists. We now return to the path of the attracted particle. We add up all the elements of impetus in the whole path, and obtain thereby what I call the 'integral impetus.' The characteristic of the actual path as compared with neighbouring alternative paths is that in the actual paths the integral impetus would neither gain nor lose, if the particle wobbled out of it into a small extremely near alternative path. Mathe- maticians would express this by saying, that the integral impetus is stationary for an infinitesimal displacement. In this statement of the law of motion I have neglected the existence of other forces. But that would lead me too far afield. The electromagnetic theory has to be modified to allow for the presence of a gravitational field. Thus Einstein's investigations lead to the first discovery of any relation between gravity and other physical pheno- mena. In the form in which I have put this modification, we deduce Einstein's fundamental principle, as to the motion of light along its rays, as a first approximation i84 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch. viii which IS absolutely true for infinitely short waves. Einstein's principle, thus partially verified, stated in my language is that a ray of light always follows a path such that the integral impetus along it is zero. This involves that every element of impetus along it is zero. In conclusion, I must apologise. In the first place I have considerably toned down the various exciting peculiarities of the original theory and have reduced it to a greater conformity with the older physics. I do not allow that physical phenomena are due to oddities of space. Also I have added to the dullness of the lecture by my respect for the audience. You would have enjoyed a more popular lecture with illustrations of delightful paradoxes. But I know also that you are serious students who are here because you really want to know how the new theories may aflFect your scientific re- searches. CHAPTER IX THE ULTIMATE PHYSICAL CONCEPTS The second chapter of this book lays down the first principle to be guarded in framing our physical concept. We must avoid vicious bifurcation Nature is nothing else than the deliverance of sense-awareness. We have no principles whatever to tell us what could stimulate mind towards sense-awareness. Our sole task is to exhibit in one system the characters and inter-relations of all that is observed. Our attitude towards nature is purely * behaviouristic,' so far as concerns the formulation of physical concepts. Our knowledge of nature is an experience of activity (or passage). The things previously observed are active entities, the * events.' They are chunks in the life of nature. These events have to each other relations which in our knowledge differentiate themselves into space- relations and time-relations. But this differentiation between space and time, though inherent in nature, is comparatively superficial ; and space and time are each partial expressions of one fundamental relation between events which is neither spatial nor temporal. This relation I call 'extension.' The relation of 'extending over' is the relation of 'including,' either in a spatial or in a temporal sense, or in both. But the mere 'inclu- sion' is more fundamental than either alternative and does not require any spatio-temporal differentiation. In respect to extension two events are mutually related so that either (i) one includes the other, or (ii) one over- laps the other without complete inclusion, or (iii) they i86 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [CH. are entirely separate. But great care is required in the definition of spatial and temporal elements from this basis in order to avoid tacit limitations really depend- ing on undefined relations and properties. Such fallacies can be avoided by taking account of two elements in our experience, namely, (i) our ob- servational * present,' and (ii) our * percipient event.' Our observational * present ' is what I call a * duration.' It is the whole of nature apprehended in our immediate observation. It has therefore the nature of an event, but possesses a peculiar completeness which marks out such durations as a special type of events inherent in nature. A duration is not instantaneous. It is all that there is of nature with certain temporal limitations. In contradistinction to other events a duration will be called infinite and the other events are finite^. In our knowledge of a duration we distinguish (i) certain included events which are particularly discriminated as to their peculiar individualities, and (ii) the remaining included events which are only known as necessarily in being by reason of their relations to the discriminated events and to the whole duration. The duration as a whole is signified^ by that quality of relatedness (in respect to extension) possessed by the part which is ^immediately under observation; namely, by the fact ; that there is essentially a beyond to whatever is observed. \ I mean by this that every event is known as being related \to other events which it does not include. This fact, jthat every event is known as possessing the quality of ^exclusion, shows that exclusion is as positive a relation as inclusion. There are of course no merely negative ^ Cf. note on ^significance,' pp. 197, 198. 2 Cf. Ch. Ill, pp. 51 et seq. IX] THE ULTIMATE PHYSICAL CONCEPTS 187 relations in nature, and exclusion is not the mere negative of inclusion, though the two relations are contraries. Both relations are concerned solely with^ events, and exclusion is capable of logical definition in terms of inclusion. Perhaps the most obvious exhibition of significance is to be found in our knowledge of the geometrical character of events inside an opaque material object. For example we know that an opaque sphere has a centre. This knowledge has nothing to do with the material; the sphere may be a solid uniform billiard ball or a hollow lawn-tennis ball. Such knowledge is essentially the product of significance, since the general character of the external discriminated events has in- formed us that there are events within the sphere and has also informed us of their geometrical structure. Some criticisms on *The Principles of Natural Knowledge' show that difficulty has been found in apprehending durations as real stratifications of nature. I think that this hesitation arises from the unconscious influence of the vicious principle of bifurcation, so deeply embedded in modern philosophical thought. We observe nature as extended in an immediate present which is simultaneous but not instantaneous, and there- fore the whole which is immediately discerned or signified as an inter-related system forms a stratification of nature which is a physical fact. This conclusion immediately follows unless we admit bifurcation in the form of the principle of psychic additions, here rejected. Our * percipient event ' is that event included in our observational present which we distinguish as being in some peculiar way our standpoint for perception. It is roughly speaking that event which is our bodily life i88 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [CH. within the present duration. The theory of perception as evolved by medical psychology is based on signifi- cance. The distant situation of a perceived object is merely known to us as signified by our bodily state, i,e, by our percipient event. In fact perception requires sense-awareness of the significations of our percipient event together with sense-awareness of a peculiar re- lation (situation) between certain objects and the events thus signified. Our percipient event is saved by being the whole of nature by this fact of its significations. This is the meaning of calling the percipient event our standpoint for perception. The course of a ray of light is only derivatively connected with perception. What we do perceive are objects as related to events signified by the bodily states excited by the ray. These signified events (as is the case of images seen behind a mirror) may have very little to do with the actual course of the ray. In the course of evolution those animals have survived whose sense-awareness is con- centrated on those significations of their bodily states which are on the average important for their welfare. The whole world of events is signified, but there are some which exact the death penalty for inattention. The percipient event is always here and now in the associated present duration. It has, what may be called, an absolute position in that duration. Thus one definite duration is associated with a definite percipient event, and we are thus aware of a peculiar relation which finite events can bear to durations. I call this relation * cogredience.' The notion of rest is derivative from that of cogredience, and the notion of motion is derivative from that of inclusion within a duration without cogre- dience with it. In fact motion is a relation (of varying IX] THE ULTIMATE PHYSICAL CONCEPTS 189 character) between an observed event and an observed duration, and cogredience is the most simple character or subspecies of motion. To sum up, a duration and a percipient event are essentially involved in the general character of each observation of nature, and the per- cipient event is cogredient with the duration. Our knowledge of the peculiar characters of different events depends upon our power of comparison. I call the exercise of this factor in our knowledge* recognition,' and the requisite sense-awareness of the comparable characters I call * sense-recognition.' Recognition and abstraction essentially involve each other. Each of them exhibits an entity for knowledge which is less than the concrete fact, but is a real factor in that fact. The most concrete fact capable of separate discrimination is the event. We cannot abstract without recognition, and we cannot recognise without abstraction. Perception involves apprehension of the event and recognition of the factors of its character. The things recognised are what I call * objects.' In this general sense of the term the relation of extension is itself an object. In practice however I restrict the term to those objects which can in some sense or other be said to have a situation in an event; namely, in the phrase ' There it is again ' I restrict the * there ' to be the indication of a special event which is the situation of the object. Even so, there are different types of objects, and statements which are true of objects of one type are not in general true of objects of other types. The objects with which we are here concerned in the formulation of physical laws are material objects, such as bits of matter, molecules and electrons. An object of one of these types has relations to events other than those 190 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch. belonging to the stream of its situations. The fact of its situations within this stream has impressed on all other events certain modifications of their characters. In truth the object in its completeness may be conceived as a specific set of correlated modifications of the charac- ters of all events, with the property that these modifica- tions attain to a certain focal property for those events which belong to the stream of its situations. The total assemblage of the modifications of the characters of events due to the existence of an object in a stream of situations is what I call the 'physical field' due to the object. . But the object cannot really be separated from its field. The object is in fact nothing else than the systematically adjusted set of modifications of the field. The conventional limitation of the object to the focal stream of events in which it is said to be ' situated ' is convenient for some purposes, but it obscures the ultimate fact of nature. From this point of view the antithesis between action at a distance and action by transmission is meaningless. The doctrine of this para- graph is nothing else than another way of expressing the unresolvable multiple relation of an object to events. A complete time-system is formed by any one family of parallel durations. Two durations are parallel if either (i) one includes the other, or (ii) they overlap so as to include a third duration common to both, or (iii) are entirely separate. The excluded case is that of two durations overlapping so as to include in common an aggregate of finite events but including in common no other complete duration. The recognition of the fact of an indefinite number of families of parallel durations is what differentiates the concept of nature here put forward from the older orthodox concept of IX] THE ULTIMATE PHYSICAL CONCEPTS 191 the essentially unique time-systems. Its divergence from Einstein's concept of nature will be briefly indicated later. The instantaneous spaces of a given time-system are the ideal (non-existent) durations of zero temporal thickness indicated by routes of approximation along series formed by durations of the associated family. Each such instantaneous space represents the ideal of nature at an instant and is also a moment of time. Each time-system thus possesses an aggregate of moments belonging to it alone. Each event-particle lies in one and only one moment of a given time-system. An event- particle has three characters^ : (i) its extrinsic character which is its character as a definite route of convergence among events, (ii) its intrinsic character which is the peculiar quality of nature in its neighbourhood, namely, the character of the physical field in the neighbourhood, and (iii) its position. The position of an event-particle arises from the aggregate of moments (no two of the same family) in which it lies. We fix our attention on one of these moments which is approximated to by the short dura- tion of our immediate experience, and we express position as the position in this moment. But the event- particle receives its position in moment M in virtue of the whole aggregate of other moments M\ M" , etc., in which it also lies. The differentiation of M into a geometry of event-particles (instantaneous points) ex- presses the diflferentiation of M by its intersections with moments of alien time-systems. In this way planes and straight lines and event-particles themselves find their being. Also the parallelism of planes and straight lines arises from the parallelism of the moments of one and ^ Of. pp. 82 et seq. 192 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch. the same time-system intersecting M, Similarly the order of parallel planes and of event-particles on straight lines arises from the time-order of these intersecting moments. The explanation is not given here^. It is sufficient now merely to mention the sources from which the whole of geometry receives its physical explanation. The correlation of the various momentary spaces of one time-system is achieved by the relation of cogre- dience. Evidently motion in an instantaneous space is unmeaning. Motion expresses a comparison between position in one instantaneous space with positions in other instantaneous spaces of the same time-system. Cogredience yields the simplest outcome of such com- parison, namely, rest. Motion and rest are immediately observed facts. They are relative in the sense that they depend on the time-system which is fundamental for the observation. A string of event-particles whose successive occupation means rest in the given time-system forms a timeless point in the timeless space of that time-system. In this way each time-system possesses its own permanent timeless space peculiar to it alone, and each such space is composed of timeless points which belong to that time-system and to no other. The paradoxes of rela- tivity arise from neglecting the fact that different as- sumptions as to rest involve the expression of the facts of physical science in terms of radically different spaces and times, in which points and moments have different meanings. The source of order has already been indicated and that of congruence is now found. It depends on motion. 1 Of. Principles of Natural Knowledge^ and previous chapters of the present work. IX] THE ULTIMATE PHYSICAL CONCEPTS 193 From cogredience, perpendicularity arises; and from perpendicularity in conjunction with the reciprocal symmetry between the relations of any two time-systems congruence both in time and space is completely defined (cf. loc, cit.). The resulting formulae are those for the electro- magnetic theory of relativity, or, as it is now termed, the restricted theory. But there is this vital difference: the critical velocity c which occurs in these formulae has now no connexion whatever with light or with any other fact of the physical field (in distinction from the extensional structure of events). It simply marks the fact that our congruence determination embraces both times and spaces in one universal system, and therefore if two arbitrary units are chosen, one for all spaces and one for all times, their ratio will be a velocity which is a fundamental property of nature expressing the fact that times and spaces are really comparable. The physical properties of nature are expressed in terms of material objects (electrons, etc.). The physical character of an event arises from the fact that it belongs to the field of the whole complex of such objects. From another point of view we can say that these objects are nothing else than our way of expressing the mutual correlation of the physical characters of events. The spatio-temporal measurableness of nature arises from (i) the relation of extension between events, and (ii) the stratified character of nature arising from each of the alternative time-systems, and (iii) rest and motion, as exhibited in the relations of finite events to time- systems. None of these sources of measurement depend on the physical characters of finite events as exhibited by the situated objects. They are completely signified W. N. 13 194 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch. for events whose physical characters are unknown. Thus the spatio-temporal measurements are independent of the objectival physical characters. Furthermore the character of our knowledge of a whole duration, which is essentially derived from the significance of the part within the immediate field of discrimination, constructs it for us as a uniform whole independent, so far as its extension is concerned, of the unobserved characters of remote events. Namely, there is a definite whole of nature, simultaneously now present, whatever may be the character of its remote events. This consideration reinforces the previous conclusion. This conclusion leads to the assertion of the essential uniformity of the momentary spaces of the various time-systems, and thence to the uniformity of the timeless spaces of which there is one to each time-system. The analysis of the general character of observed nature set forth above aflFords explanations of various fundamental observational facts: (a) It explains the differentiation of the one quality of extension into time and space. (^S) It gives a meaning to the observed facts of geometrical and temporal position, of geometrical and temporal order, and of geometrical straightness and planeness. (y) It selects one definite system of congruence embracing both space and time, and thus explains the concordance as to measurement which is in practice attained. (S) It explains (consistently with the theory of relativity) the observed phenomena of rotation, e.g. Foucault's pendulum, the equatorial bulge of the earth, the fixed senses of rotation of cyclones and anticyclones, and the gyro-compass. It does this by its admission of definite stratifications of nature which are disclosed by the very character of our knowledge of it. (c) Its ex- IX] THE ULTIMATE PHYSICAL CONCEPTS 195 planations of motion are more fundamental than those expressed in (8) ; for it explains what is meant by motion itself. The observed motion of an extended object is the relation of its various situations to the stratification of nature expressed by the time-system fundamental to the observation. This motion expresses a real relation of the object to the rest of nature. The quantitative expression of this relation will vary according to the time-system selected for its expression. This theory accords no peculiar character to light beyond that accorded to other physical phenomena such as sound. There is no ground for such a differentiation. Some objects we know by sight only, and other objects we know by sound only, and other objects we observe neither by light nor by sound but by touch or smell or otherwise. The velocity of light varies according to its medium and so does that of sound. Light moves in curved paths under certain conditions and so does sound. Both light and sound are waves of disturbance in the physical characters of events ; and (as has been stated above, p. 188) the actual course of the light is of no more importance for perception than is the actual course of the sound. To base the whole philo- sophy of nature upon light is a baseless assumption. The Michelson-Morley and analogous experiments show that within the limits of our inexactitude of observation the velocity of light is an approximation to the critical velocity ^ c^ which expresses the relation between our space and time units. It is provable that the assumption as to light by which these experiments and the influence of the gravitational field on the light- rays are explained is deducible as an approximation from the equations of the electromagnetic field. This 196 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch. completely disposes of any necessity for differentiating light from other physical phenomena as possessing any peculiar fundamental character. It is to be observed that the measurement of extended nature by means of extended objects is meaningless apart from some observed fact of simultaneity inherent in nature and not merely a play of thought. Otherwise there is no meaning to the concept of one presentation of your extended measuring rod AB. Why not AB' where B' is the end B five minutes later ? Measurement presupposes for its possibility nature as a simultaneity, and an observed object present then and present now. In other words, measurement of extended nature re- quires some inherent character in nature affording a rule of presentation of events. Furthermore congruence cannot be defined by the permanence of the measuring rod. The permanence is itself meaningless apart from some immediate judgment of self-congruence. Other- wise how is an elastic string differentiated from a rigid measuring rod? Each remains the same self-identical object. Why is one a possible measuring rod and the other not so ? The meaning of congruence lies beyond the self-identity of the object. In other words measure- ment presupposes the measurable, and the theory of the measurable is the theory of congruence. Furthermore the admission of stratifications of nature bears on the formulation of the laws of nature. It has been laid down that these laws are to be expressed in differential equations which, as expressed in any general system of measurement, should bear no reference to any other particular measure-system. This requirement is purely arbitrary. For a measure-system measures something inherent in nature; otherwise it has no IX] THE ULTIMATE PHYSICAL CONCEPTS 197 connexion with nature at all. And that something which is measured by a particular measure-system may have a special relation to the phenomenon whose law is being formulated. For example the gravitational field due to a material object at rest in a certain time-system may be expected to exhibit in its formulation particular reference to spatial and temporal quantities of that time-system. The field can of course be expressed in any measure-systems, but the particular reference will remain as the simple physical explanation. NOTE: ON THE GREEK CONCEPT OF A POINT The preceding pages had been passed for press before I had the pleasure of seeing Sir T. L. Heath's Euclid in Greek^. In the original Euclid's first definition is a-rjfjLelov iaTCVy ov fiipof; ovdev. I have quoted it on p. 86 in the expanded form taught to me in childhood, * without parts and without magnitude.' I should have consulted Heath's English edition — a classic from the moment of its issue — before committing myself to a statement about Euclid. This is however a trivial correction not affecting sense and not worth a note. I wish here to draw attention to Heath's own note to this definition in his Euclid in Greek. He summarises Greek thought on the nature of a point, from the Pythagoreans, through Plato and Aristotle, to Euclid. My analysis of the requisite character of a point on pp. 89 and 90 is in complete agreement with the outcome of the Greek discussion. NOTE: ON SIGNIFICANCE AND INFINITE EVENTS The theory of significance has been expanded and made more definite in the present volume. It had already been introduced in the Principles of Natural Knowledge (cf. subarticles 3-3 to 3-8 and i6-i, 16-2, 19-4, and articles 20, 21). In reading over the proofs of the present volume, I come to the conclusion that in the 1 Camb. Univ. Press, 1920. 13—3 198 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch.ix light of this development my limitation of infinite events to dura- tions is untenable. This limitation is stated in article 33 of the Principles and at the beginning of Chapter IV (p. 74) of this book. There is not only a significance of the discerned events embracing the whole present duration, but there is a significance of a cogre- dient event involving its extension through a whole time-system backwards and forwards. In other words the essential ' beyond' in nature is a definite beyond in time as well as in space [cf. pp. 53, 194]. This follows from my whole thesis as to the assimila- tion of time and space and their origin in extension. It also has the same basis in the analysis of the character of our knowledge of nature. It follows from this admission that it is possible to define point-tracks [i.e. the points of timeless spaces] as abstrac- tive elements. This is a great improvement as restoring the balance between moments and points. I still hold however to the statement in subarticle 35-4 of the Principles that the intersection of a pair of non-parallel durations does not present itself to us as one event. This correction does not affect any of the subsequent reasoning in the two books. I may take this opportunity of pointing out that the ' stationary events' of article 57 of the Principles are merely cogredient events got at from an abstract mathematical point of view. INDEX In the case of terms of frequent occurrence, only those occurrences are indexed which are of peculiar importance for the elucidation of meaning. A [or an], ii Abraham, 105 Absolute position, 105, 106, 114, 188 Abstraction, 33, 37, 168, 171, 173; extensive, 65, 79, 85 Abstractive element, 84; set, 61, 79 Action at a distance, 159, 190 Action by transmission, 159, 190 Active conditions, 158 Activity, field of, 170, 181 Adjunction, loi Aggregate, 23 Alexander, Prof., viii Alexandria, 71 Alfred the Great, 137 Anticipation, 69 Anti-prime, 88 Apparent nature, 31, 39 Area, 99; momental, 103; vagrant, 103 Aristotelian logic, 150 Aristotle, 16, 17, 18, 24, 197 Associate-potential, 183 Atom, 17 Attribute, 21, 26, 150 Awareness, 3 Axiom, 36, 121 Axioms of congruence, 128 at seqq. Bacon, Francis, 78 Behaviouristic, 185 Bergson, 54 Berkeley, 28 Between, 64 Beyond, 186, 198 Bifurcation, vi, 30, 185, 187 Boundary, 100; moment, 63; par- ticle, 100 Broad, C. D., viii Calculation, formula of, 45, 158 Cambridge, 97 Causal nature, 31, 39 Causation, 31, 146 Centrifugal force, 138 Change, uniformity of, 140 Character, extrinsic, 82, 89, 90, 113, 191; intrinsic, 80, 82, 90, 113, 191 Charge, 160 Closure of nature, 4 Coefficient of drag, 133 Coefficients of impetus, 183 Cogredience, no, 188 Coherence, 29 Comparison, 124, 125, 143, 189 Complex, 13 Conceptual nature, 45; space, 96 Concrete facts, 167, 171, 189 Conditioning events, 152 Conditions, active, 158 Congruence, 65, 96, 118, 120, 127, 196 Continuity, 157; Dedekindian, 102; of events, 76; of nature, 59, 76 Convention, 121 Convergence, 62, 79; law of, 82 Conveyance, 154, 155 Co-present, 177 Covering, 83 Creative advance, 178 Critical velocity, 193, 195 Curvature of space- time, 182 Cyclone, 194 Dedekindian continuity, 102 Definite, 53, 194, 198 Delusions, 31, 38 Delusive perceptual object, 153 Demarcation of events, 144 Demonstrative phrase, 6 Descriptive phrase, 6, 10 Differential equations, 196 Discrimination, 14, 50, 144 Diversification of nature, 15 Duddington, Mrs, 47 Duration, 37. 53. 55. 186 Durations, families of, 59, 73, 190 Dynamical axes, 138 Einstein, vii, 102, 131, 164, 165, 181, 182, 183, 184, 191 Electromagnetic field, 179 Electron, 30, 146, 158, 171 Element, 17; abstractive, 84 Elliptical phraseology, 7 200 INDEX Empty space, 145 Entity, 5, 13 Equal in abstractive force, 83 Error, 68 Ether, 18, 78, 160; material, 78; of events, 78 Euclid, 85, 94, 197 Euler, 140 Event, 15, 52, 75, 165; percipient, 107, 152, 186 Event-particle, 86, 93, 94, 172, 191 Events, conditioning, 152; con- tinuity of, 76; demarcation of, 144; ether of, 78; infinite, 197, 198; limited, 74; passage of, 34; signified, 52; stationary, 198; stream of, 167; structure of, 52, 166 Exclusion, 186 Explanation, 97, 141 Extended nature, 196 Extension, 22, 58, 75, 185 Extensive abstraction, 65, 79, 85 Extrinsic character, 82, 89, 90, 113, 191; properties, 62 Fact, 12, 13 Factors, 12, 13, 15 Facts, concrete, 167, 171 Family of durations, 59, 63, 73; of moments, 63 Faraday, 146 Field, gravitational, 197; of activity, 170, 181; physical, 190 Finite truths, 12 Fitzgerald, 133 Formula of calculation, 45, 158 Foucault, 138, 194 Four-dimensional manifold, 86 Fresnel, 133 Future, the, 72, 177 Galileo, 139 Geometrical order, 194 Geometry, 36; metrical, 129 Gravitation, 179 et seqq. Gravitational field, 197 Greek philosophy, 16; thought, 197 Gyro-compass, 194 Heath, Sir T. L., 197 Here, 107 Idealists, 70 Immediacy, 52; of perception, 72 Impetus, 181, 182; coefficients of, 183; integral, 183 Inclusion, 186 Individuality, 13 Infinite events, 197, 198 Inge, Dr, 48 Ingredient, 14 Ingression, 144, 145, 148, 152 Inherence, 8^ Inside, 106 Instant, 33, 35, 57 Instantaneous plane, 91 ; present, 72 ; spaces, 86, 90, 177 Instantaneousness, 56, 57 Intersection, locus of, 90 Intrinsic character, 80, 82, 90, 113, 191; properties, 62 Ionian thinkers, 19 Irrelevance, infinitude of, 12 Irrevocableness, 35, 37 It, 8 Julius Caesar, 36 Junction, 76, loi Kinetic energy, 105; symmetry, 129 Knowledge, 28, 32 Lagrange, 140 Larmor, 131 Law of convergence, 82 Laws of motion, 137, 139; of nature, 196 Leibnizian monadology, 150 Level, 91, 92 Light, 195; ray of, 188; velocity of, 131 Limit, 57 Limited events, 74 Location, 160, 161 Locke, 27 Locus, 102; of intersection, 90 London, 97 Lorentz, H. A., 131, 133 Lossky, 47 Manifold, four-dimensional, 86; space-time, 173 Material ether, 78; object, 169 Materialism, 43, 70 Matrix, 116 Matter, 16, 17, 19, 20, 26 Maxwell, 131, 133 Measurableness, 196; of nature, 193 Measurement, 96, 120, 174, 196; of time, 65, 140 Measure-system, 196 Memory, 68 Metaphysics, 28, 32 Metrical geometry, 129 Michelson-Morley, 195 Milton, 35 Mind, 27, 28 INDEX 201 Minkowski, viii, 131 Molecule, 32, 171 Moment, 57, 60, 88 Momental area, 103; route, 103 Momentum, 105 Motion, 105, 114, 117, 127, 188, 192 Multiplicity, 22 Natural philosophy, 29, 30 Natural science, philosophy of, 46 Nature, 3; apparent, 31, 39; causal, 31, 39; conceptual, 45; continuity of, 59, 76; discrimination of, 144; extended, 196; laws of, 196; passage of, 54; stratification of, 194, 196; system of, 146 Newton, 27, 136, 139, 140 Object, 77, 125, 143, 169, 189; delusive perceptual, 155; material, 169; perceptual, 153; physical, 155. ''^57> scientific, 158, 169; uni- form, 162 Occupation, 22, 34, 36, 100, loi Order, source of, 192; spatial, 95, 194; temporal, 64, 95, 194 Organisation of thought, 79 Outside, 63, 100 Paradox, 192 Parallel, 63, 127; durations, 190 - Parallelism, 95, 191 Parallelogram, 127 Paris, 87, 138 Parliament, 120 Part, 14, 15, 58 Passage of events, 34; of nature, 54 Past, the, 72, 177 Perception, 3 Perceptual objects, 149, 153 Percipience, 28 Percipient event, 107, 152, 186, 187 Period of time, 51 Permanence, 144 Perpendicularity, 117, 127, 193 Philosophy, i ; natural, 29, 30 ; of natural science, 46 ; of the sciences, 2 Physical field, 190; object, 155, 156, 157 Physics, speculative, 30 Place, 51 Plane, 191; instantaneous, 91 Plato, 16, 17, 18, 24, 197 Poincare, 121, 122, 123 Point, 35, 89,^91, 114, 173, 176 Point-flash, 172, 173 Point of space, 85 Point, timeless, 192 Point- track, 113, 198 Pompey, 36 Position, 89, 90, 92, 93, 99, 113, 191 J absolute, 105, 106, 114, 188 Potential, 183; associate-, 183 Predicate, 18 Predication, 18 Present, the, 69, 72, 177; instan- taneous, 72; observational, 186 Primary qualities, 27 Prime, 88 Process, 53, 54; of nature, 54 Psychic additions, 29, 187 Punct, 92, 93, 94 Pythagoreans, 197 Quality, 27 Quantum of time, 162 Quantum theory, 162 Ray of light, 188 Reality, 30; of durations, 55, 187 Recognition, 124, 143, 189 Rect, 91, 92 Recurrence, 35 Relative motion, 117; velocity, 130 Relativity, 169; restricted theory of, 193 Rest, 105, 114, 188, 192 Rotation, 138, 194 Route, 99; momental, 103; straight, 103 Russell, Bertrand, 11, 122, 123 Schelling, 47 Science, 2; metaphysical, 32 Scientific objects, 149, 158, 169 Secondary qualities, 27 Self-congruence, 196 Self-containedness of nature, 4 Sense-awareness, 3, 67 Sense-object, 149, 170 Sense-perception, 3, 14 Sense-recognition, 143, 189 Series, temporal, 66, 70, 85, 178 Set, abstractive, 61, 79 Significance, 51, 186, 187, 188, 194, 197, 198 Signified events, 52 Simplicity, 163, 173 Simultaneity, 53, 56, 196 Situation, 15, 78, 147, 148, 152, 160, 189 Solid, 99, loi, 102; vagrant, loi Sound, 195 Space, 16, 17. 31.33, 79; empty, 145; timeless, 86, 106, 114; uniformity of, 194 Spaces, instantaneous, 86, 90 202 INDEX Space-system, 179 Space- time manifold, 173 Spatial-order, 95 Spatio-temporal structure, 173 Speculative demonstration, 6 Speculative physics, 30 Standpoint for perception, 107, 188 Station, 103, 104, 113 Stationary events, 198 Straight line, 91, 114, 191; route, 103 Stratification of nature, 187, 194, 196 Stream of events, 167 Structure of events, 52, 166 Structure, spatio-temporal, 173 Subject, 18 Substance, 16, 18, 19, 150 Substratum, 16, 18, 21 Symmetry, 118, 126; kinetic, 129 System of nature, 146 System, time-, 192 Tamer, Edward, v, i Temporal order, 64, 95, 194 Temporal series, 66, 70, 85 Tensor, 182 Terminus, 4 The, II Theory, quantum, 162 There, no, 189 This, II Thought, 3, 14 Timaeus, the, 17, 20, 24 Time, 16, 17, 31, 33, 49. 79; measurement of, 140; quantum of, 162; transcendence of, 39 Time-series, 178, also cf. Temporal series Time-system, see Time-series, also 91, 97, 104, 179, 192 Timeless point, 192; space, 86, 106, 114. 177 Totality, 89 Transcendence of time, 39 Transmission, 26, 28; action by, 159, 190 Tubes of force, 146 Unexhaustiveness, 50 Uniform object, 162 Uniformity of change, 140; of space, 194 Vagrant area, 103 ; solid, loi Veblen and Young, 36 Velocity, critical, 193, 195; of liglit, 131, 195; relative, 130 Volume, 92, 10 1 When, 107 Where, 107 Whole, 58 Within, 63 Young, Veblen and, 36 CAMBRIDGE: PRINTED BY J. B. PEACE, M.A., AT THE UNIVERSITY PRESS. THE UNIVERSITY LIBRARY UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, SANTA CRUZ SCIENCE LIBRARY This book is due on the last DATE stamped below. To renew by phone, call 459-2050. Books not returned or renewed within 14 days after<3ue date are subject to billing. Series 2477 STORED AT NRLF 3 2106 00227 7173