^^ I LIBRARY
UNIVERSFTYOF
!>'*
Z
oi
O
l-u
<
u
O
Pi
>
SANTA CRUZ
Gift of
Prof. William R. Dennes
^
SANTA CRUZ
m
C
z
<
tn
H
CO
>
5?
^n
Digitized by the Internet Archive
in 2007 with funding from
IVIicrosoft Corporation
http://www.archive.org/details/conceptofnatureOOwhitrich
THE CONCEPT OF NATURE
CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS
C. F. CLAY, Manager
LONDON : FETTER LANE, E.C. 4
NEW YORK : THE MACMILLAN CO.
BOMBAY ")
CALCUTTA [-MACMILLAN AND CO., Ltd.
MADRAS J
TORONTO : THE MACMILLAN CO. OF
CANADA, Ltd.
TOKYO : MARUZEN-KABUSHIKI-KAISHA
ALL RIGHTS RESERVED
THE CONCEPT OF NATURE
TARNER LECTURES DELIVERED IN TRINITY COLLEGE
NOVEMBER 1919
BY
A. N. WHITEHEAD, Sc.D., F.R.S.
FELLOW OF TRINITY COLLEGE, CAMBRIDGE, AND
PROFESSOR OF APPLIED MATHEMATICS IN
THE IMPERIAL COLLEGE OF SCIENCE
AND TECHNOLOGY
CAMBRIDGE
AT THE UNIVERSITY PRESS
1920
PREFACE
The contents of this book were originally delivered at
Trinity College in the autumn of 19 19 as the inaugural
course of Tarner lectures. The Tarner lectureship is
an occasional office founded by the liberality of
Mr Edward Tarner. The duty of each of the successive
holders of the post will be to deliver a course on * the
Philosophy of the Sciences and the Relations or Want
of Relations between the different Departments of
Knowledge.' The present book embodies the endeavour
of the first lecturer of the series to fulfil his task.
The chapters retain their original lecture form and
remain as delivered with the exception of minor
changes designed to remove obscurities of expression.
The lecture form has the advantage of suggesting an
audience with a definite mental background which it is
the purpose of the lecture to modify in a specific way.
In the presentation of a novel outlook with wide rami-
fications a single line of communications from premises
to conclusions is not sufficient for intelligibility. Your
audience will construe whatever you say into conformity
with their pre-existing outlook. For this reason the first
two chapters and the last two chapters are essential
for intelligibility though they hardly add to the formal
completeness of the exposition. Their function is to
prevent the reader from bolting up side tracks in pursuit
of misunderstandings. The same reason dictates my
avoidance of the existing technical terminology of
VI PREFACE
philosophy. The modern natural philosophy is shot
through and through with the fallacy of bifurcation
which is discussed in the second chapter of this work.
Accordingly all its technical terms in some subtle way
presuppose a misunderstanding of my thesis. It is
perhaps as well to state expHcitly that if the reader
indulges in the facile vice of bifurcation not a word of
what I have here written will be intelligible.
The last two chapters do not properly belong to the
special course. Chapter VIII is a lecture delivered in
the spring of 1920 before the Chemical Society of
the students of the Imperial College of Science and
Technology. It has been appended here as conveniently
summing up and applying the doctrine of the book
for an audience with one definite type of outlook.
This volume on *the Concept of Nature' forms a
companion book to my previous work An Enquiry con-
cerning the Principles of Natural Knowledge, Either
book can be read independently, but they supplement
each other. In part the present book supplies points
of view which were omitted from its predecessor; in
part it traverses the same ground with an alternative
exposition. For one thing, mathematical notation has
been carefully avoided, and the results of mathematical
deductions are assumed. Some of the explanations have
been improved and others have been set in a new light.
On the other hand important points of the previous
work have been omitted where I have had nothing fresh
to say about them. On the whole, whereas the former
work based itself chiefly on ideas directly drawn from
PREFACE vii
mathematical physics, the present book keeps closer
to certain fields of philosophy and physics to the ex-
clusion of mathematics. The two works meet in their
discussions of some details of space and time.
I am not conscious that I have in any way altered my
views. Some developments have been made. Those
that are capable of a non-mathematical exposition have
been incorporated in the text. The mathematical de-
velopments are alluded to in the last two chapters. They
concern the adaptation of the principles of mathematical
physics to the form of the relativity principle which is
here maintained. Einstein's method of using the theory
of tensors is adopted, but the application is worked
out on different lines and from different assumptions.
Those of his results which have been verified by
experience are obtained also by my methods. The
divergence chiefly arises from the fact that I do not
accept his theory of non-uniform space or his assump-
tion as to the peculiar fundamental character of light-
signals. I would not however be misunderstood to be
lacking in appreciation of the value of his recent work
on general relativity which has the high merit of first
disclosing the way in which mathematical physics
should proceed in the light of the principle of relativity.
But in my judgment he has cramped the development
of his brilliant mathematical method in the narrow
bounds of a very doubtful philosophy.
The object of the present volume and of its pre-
decessor is to lay the basis of a natural philosophy which
is the necessary presupposition of a reorganised specu-
viii PREFACE
lative physics. The general assimilation of space and
time which dominates the constructive thought can
claim the independent support of Minkowski from the
side of science and also of succeeding relativists, while on
the side of philosophers it was, I believe, one theme of
Prof. Alexander's GifFord lectures delivered some few
years ago but not yet published. He also summarised
his conclusions on this question in a lecture to the
AristoteUan Society in the July of 191 8. Since the
publication of An Enquiry concerning the Principles of
Natural Knowledge I have had the advantage of reading
Mr C. D. Broad's Perception ^ Physics ^ and Reality
[Camb. Univ. Press, 1914]. This valuable book has
assisted me in my discussion in Chapter II, though I
am unaware as to how far Mr Broad would assent to
any of my arguments as there stated.
It remains for me to thank the staff of the University
Press, its compositors, its proof-readers, its clerks, and
its managing officials, not only for the technical ex-
cellence of their work, but for the way they have
co-operated so as to secure my convenience.
A. N. W.
IMPERIAL COLLEGE OF SCIENCE
AND TECHNOLOGY.
Aprily 1920.
CONTENTS
CHAP. PAGE
I NATURE AND THOUGHT . . . . . i
II THEORIES OF THE BIFURCATION OF NATURE . 26
III TIME 49
IV THE METHOD OF EXTENSIVE ABSTRACTION . 74
V SPACE AND MOTION 99
VI CONGRUENCE 120
VII OBJECTS 143
VIII SUMMARY -^ . 164
IX THE ULTIMATE PHYSICAL CONCEPTS . .185
NOTE : On the Greek Concept of a Point . . .197
NOTE: On Significance and Infinite Events . .197
INDEX 199
^
THE CONCEPT OF NATURE
CHAPTER I
NATURE AND THOUGHT
The subject-matter of the Tarner lectures is defined by
the founder to be ' the Philosophy of the Sciences and
the Relations or Want of Relations between the different
Departments of Knowledge.' It is fitting at the first
lecture of this new foundation to dwell for a few moments
on the intentions of the donor as expressed in this
definition; and I do so the more willingly as I shall
thereby be enabled to introduce the topics to which the
present course is to be devoted.
We are justified, I think, in taking the second clause
of the definition as in part explanatory of the earlier
clause. What is the philosophy of the sciences? It is
not a bad answer to say that it is the study of the rela-
tions between the different departments of knowledge.
Then with admirable solicitude for the freedom of
learning there is inserted in the definition after the
word * relations' the phrase *or want of relations.' A
disproof of relations between sciences would in itself
constitute a philosophy of the sciences. But we could
not dispense either with the earlier or the later clause.
It is not every relation between sciences which enters
into their philosophy. For example biology and physics
are connected by the use of the microscope. Still, I may
safely assert that a technical description of the uses of
the microscope in biology is not part of the philosophy
of the sciences. Again, you cannot abandon the later
2 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch.
clause of the definition; namely that referring to the
relations between the sciences, without abandoning the
explicit reference to an ideal in the absence of which
philosophy must languish from lack of intrinsic interest.
That ideal is the attainment of some unifying concept
which will set in assigned relationships within itself all
that there is for knowledge, for feeling, and for emotion.
That far off ideal is the motive power of philosophic
research; and claims allegiance even as you expel it.
The philosophic pluralist is a strict logician; the
Hegelian thrives on contradictions by the help of his
absolute; the Mohammedan divine bows before the
creative will of Allah ; and the pragmatist will swallow
anything so long as it * works.'
The mention of these vast systems and of the age-
long controversies from which they spring, warns us
to concentrate. Our task is the simpler one of the
philosophy of the sciences. Now a science has already
a certain unity which is the very reason why that body
of knowledge has been instinctively recognised as
forming a science. The philosophy of a science is the
endeavour to express explicitly those unifying charac-
teristics which pervade that complex of thoughts and
make it to be a science. The philosophy of the sciences
— conceived as one subject — is the endeavour to exhibit
all sciences as one science, or — in case of defeat — ^the
disproof of such a possibility.
Again I will make a further simplification, and con-
fine attention to the natural sciences, that is, to the
sciences whose subject-matter is nature. By postulating
a common subject-matter for this group of sciences, a
unifying philosophy of natural science has been thereby
presupposed.
I]
NATURE AND THOUGHT
What do we mean by nature? We have to discuss
the philosophy of natural science. Natural science is
the science of nature. But — ^What is nature.?
Nature is that which we observe in perception 1^
through the senses. In this sense-perception we are/
aware of something which is not thought and which is
self-contained for thought. This property of being self-
contained for thought lies at the base of natural science.
It means that nature can be thought of as a closed
system whose mutual relations do not require the jj
expres sion of the fact that tTiey^feTthoughtabout. [
I'hus in a sense nature is independent of thought. By i
this statement no metaphysical pronouncement is in-|
tended. What I mean is that we can think about nature
without thinking about thought. I shall say that then
we are thinking * homogeneously ' about nature.
Of course it is possible to think of nature in conjunc-
tion with thought about the fact that nature is thought
about. In such a case I shall say that we are thinking
* heterogeneously ' about nature. In fact during the last
few minutes we have been thinking heterogeneously
about nature. Natural science is exclusively concerned
with homogeneous thoughts about nature.
But sense-perception has in it an element which is
not thought. It is a difficult psychological question
whether sense-perception involves thought; and if it
does involve thought, what is the kind of thought which
it necessarily involves. Note that it has been stated'
above that sense-perception is an awareness of some- \
thing which is not thought. Namely, nature is not/
thought. But this is a different question, namely that
the fact of sense-perce ption jias^ factor which is_ no t
thought. I catl^his factor * sense-awareness.' Accord-
I — 2
4 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch.
ingly the doctrine that natural science is exclusively
concerned with homogeneous thoughts about nature
does not immediately carry with it the conclusion that
natural science is not concerned with sense-awareness.
However, I do assert this further statement ; namely,
that though natural science is concerned with nature
which is the terminus of sense-perception, it is not con-
cerned with the sense-awareness itself.
I repeat the main line of this argument, and expand
it in certain directions.
Thought about nature is different from the sense-
perception of nature. Hence the fact of sense-perception
has an ingredient or factor which is not thought. I call
this ingredient sense-awareness. It is indifferent to my
argument whether sense-perception has or has not
thought as another ingredient. If sense-perception does
\ \ not involve thought, then sense-awareness and sense-
fT^ |, perception are identical. But the something perceived
f\Jrlf^^ perceived as an entity which is the terminus of the
'v^pT sense-awareness, something which for thought is
rjf I beyond the fact of that sense-awareness. Also the
^ something perceived certainly does not contain other
sense-awarenesses which are different from the sense-
T awareness which is an ingredient in that perception.
p'^Af^l Accordingly nature as disclosed in sense-perception is
«r^^ self-contained as against sense-awareness, in addition
J^ to being self-contained as against thought. I will also
' ' * express this self-containedness of nature by saying that
nature is closed to mind.
This closure of nature does not carry with it any
metaphysical doctrine of the disjunction of nature and
mind. It means that in sense-perception nature is
disclosed as a complex of entities whose mutual relations
//
I] NATURE AND THOUGHT 5
are expressible in thought without reference to mind, I
that is, without reference either to sense-awareness or
to thought. Furthermore, I do not wish to be under-
stood as implying that sense-awareness and thought are
the only activities which are to be ascribed to mind.
Also I am not denying that there are relations of natural
entities to mind or minds other than being the termini
of the sense-awarenesses of minds. Accordingly I will
extend the meaning of the terms * homogeneous
thoughts' and * heterogeneous thoughts' which have
already been introduced. We are thinking * homogene-
ously' about nature when we are thinking about it
without thinking about thought or about sense-aware-
ness, and we are thinking * heterogeneously ' about
nature when we are thinking about it in conjunction
with thinking either about thought or about sense-
awareness or about both.
I also take the homogeneity of thought about nature
as excluding any reference to moral or aesthetic values
whose apprehension is vivid in proportion to self-
conscious activity. The values^of natur e are perhaps the
key to the metaphysical svntV>esis of pyistpnrp^ But such
a synthesis is exactly what I am not attempting. I am
concerned exclusively with the generalisations of widest
scope which can be effected respecting that which is
known to us as the direct deliverance of sense-awareness.
I have said that nature is disclosed in sense-percep-
tion as a complex of entities. It is worth considering
what we mean by an entity in this connexion. * Entity'
is simply the Latin equivalent for * thing ' unless some
arbitrary distinction is drawn between the words for
technical purposes. All thought has to be about things.
We can gain some idea of this necessity of things for
6 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch.
thought by examination of the structure of a proposi-
tion.
Let us suppose that a proposition is being communi-
cated by an expositor to a recipient. Such a proposition
is composed of phrases ; some of these phrases may be
demonstrative and others may be descriptive.
By a demonstrative phrase I mean a phrase which
makes the recipient aware of an entity in a way which
is independent of the particular demonstrative phrase.
You will understand that I am here using * demonstra-
tion' in the non-logical sense, namely in the sense in
which a lecturer demonstrates by the aid of a frog and
a microscope the circulation of the blood for an ele-
mentary class of medical students. I will call such
demonstration ' speculative ' demonstration, remember-
ing Hamlet's use of the word ' speculation' when he
says,
There is no speculation in those eyes.
Thus a demonstrative phrase demonstrates an entity
speculatively. It may happen that the expositor has
meant some other entity — ^namely, the phrase demon-
strates to him an entity which is diverse from the entity
which it demonstrates to the recipient. In that case
there is confusion ; for there are two diverse propositions,
namely the proposition for the expositor and the pro-
position for the recipient. I put this possibility aside
as irrelevant for our discussion, though in practice it
may be difficult for two persons to concur in the con-
sideration of exactly the same proposition, or even for
one person to have determined exactly the proposition
which he is considering.
Again the demonstrative phrase may fail to demon-
strate any entity. In that case there is no proposition
I] NATURE AND THOUGHT 7
for the recipient. I think that we may assume (perhaps
rashly) that the expositor knows what he means.
A demonstrative phrase is a gesture. It is not itself
a constituent of the proposition, but the entity which it
demonstrates is such a constituent. You may quarrel
with a demonstrative phrase as in some way obnoxious
to you; but if it demonstrates the right entity, the
proposition is unaffected though your taste may be
offended. This suggestiveness of the phraseology is part
of the literary quality of the sentence which conveys
the proposition. This is because a sentence directly
conveys one proposition, while in its phraseology it
suggests a penumbra of other propositions charged with
emotional value. We are now talking of the one pro-
position directly conveyed in any phraseology.
This doctrine is obscured by the fact that in most
cases what is in form a mere part of the demonstrative
gesture is in fact a part of the proposition which it is
desired directly to convey. In such a case we will call
the phraseology of the proposition elliptical. In ordinary-
intercourse the phraseology of nearly all propositions
is elliptical.
Let us take some examples. Suppose that the ex-
positor is in London, say in Regent's Park and in
Bedford College, the great women's college which is
situated in that park. He is speaking in the college hall
and he says,
'This college building is commodious.'
The phrase ' this college building ' is a demonstrative
phrase. Now suppose the recipient answers,
* This is not a college building, it is the lion-house in
the Zoo.'
Then, provided that the expositor's original proposi-
8 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch.
tion has not been couched in elHptical phraseology, the
expositor sticks to his original proposition when he
replies,
'Anyhow, it is commodious.'
Note that the recipient's answer accepts the specula-
tive demonstration of the phrase ' This college building.'
He does not say, * What do you mean? ' He accepts the
phrase as demonstrating an entity, but declares that
same entity to be the lion-house in the Zoo. In his
reply, the expositor in his turn recognises the success
of his original gesture as a speculative demonstration,
and waives the question of the suitability of its mode of
suggestiveness with an * anyhow.' But he is now in a
position to repeat the original proposition with the aid
of a demonstrative gesture robbed of any suggestiveness,
suitable or unsuitable, by saying,
'It is commodious.'
The 'it^ of this final statement presupposes that
thought has seized on the entity as a bare objective for
consideration.
^ We confine ourselves to entities disclosed in sense-
awareness. The entity is so disclosed as a relatum in the
complex which is nature. It dawns on an observer
because of its relations ; but it is an objective for thought
in its own bare individuality. Thought cannot proceed
otherwise ; namely, it cannot proceed without the ideal
bare *it' which is speculatively demonstrated. This
setting up of the entity as a bare objective does not
ascribe to it an existence apart from the complex in
which it has been found by sense-perception. The 'it'
\for thought is essentially a relatum for sense-awareness.
The chances are that the dialogue as to the college
building takes another form. Whatever the expositor
I] NATURE AND THOUGHT 9
originally meant, he almost certainly now takes his
former statement as couched in elliptical phraseology,
and assumes that he was meaning,
* This is a college building and is commodious.'
Here the demonstrative phrase or the gesture, which
demonstrates the *it' which is commodious, has now
been reduced to * this ' ; and the attenuated phrase, under
the circumstances in which it is uttered, is sufficient for
the purpose of correct demonstration. This brings out
the point that the verbal form is never the whole phrase-
ology of the proposition ; this phraseology also includes
the general circumstances of its production. Thus the aim
of a demonstrative phrase is to exhibit a definite * it ' as a
bare objective for thought ; but the modus operandi of
a demonstrative phrase is to produce an awareness of
the entity as a particular relatum in an auxiliary complex,
chosen merely for the sake of the speculative demon-
stration and irrelevant to the proposition. For example,
in the above dialogue, colleges and buildings, as related
to the *it' speculatively demonstrated by the phrase
*this college building,' set that *it' in an auxiliary
complex which is irrelevant to the proposition
* It is commodious.'
Of course in language every phrase is invariably
highly elliptical. Accordingly the sentence
* This college building is commodious '
means probably
'This college building is commodious as a college
building.'
But it will be found that in the above discussion
we can replace * commodious' by * commodious as a
college building' without altering our conclusion;
though we can guess that the recipient, who thought
10 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch.
he was in the Hon-house of the Zoo, would be less likely
to assent to
* Anyhow, it is commodious as a college building.'
A more obvious instance of elliptical phraseology
arises if the expositor should address the recipient with
the remark,
'That criminal is your friend.'
The recipient might answer,
*He is my friend and you are insulting.'
Here the recipient assumes that the phrase 'That
criminal' is elliptical and not merely demonstrative. Jn
fact, pure demo nstration is impossible thoudi it is the
ideal of ^thought . This practical impossibility of pure
demonstration is a difficulty which arises in the com-
munication of thought and in the retention of thought.
Namely, a proposition about a particular factor in nature
can neither be expressed to others nor retained for
repeated consideration without the aid of auxiliary com-
plexes which are irrelevant to it.
I now pass to descriptive phrases. The expositor says,
* A college in Regent's Park is commodious.'
The recipient knows Regent's Park well. The phrase
*A college in Regent's Park' is descriptive for him. If
its phraseology is not elliptical, which in ordinary life
it certainly will be in some way or other, this proposition
simply means,
'There is an entity which is a college building in
Regent's Park and is commodious.'
If the recipient rejoins,
' The lion-house in the Zoo is the only commodious
building in Regent's Park,'
he now contradicts the expositor, on the assumption
that a lion-house in a Zoo is not a college building.
I] NATURE AND THOUGHT ii
Thus whereas in the first dialogue the recipient
merely quarrelled with the expositor without con-
tradicting him, in this dialogue he contradicts him. Thus
a descriptive phrase is part of the proposition which it
helps to express, whereas a demonstrative phrase is not
part of 'the proposition which it helps to express.
Again the expositor might be standing in Green Park
— ^where there are no college buildings — and say,
*This college building is commodious.'
Probably no proposition will be received by the
recipient because the demonstrative phrase,
*This college building'
has failed to demonstrate owing to the absence of the
background of sense-awareness which it presupposes.
But if the expositor had said,
'A college building in Green Park is commodious,'
the recipient would have received a proposition, but a
false one.
Language is usually ambiguous and it is rash to make
general assertions as to its meanings. But phrases which
commence with ' this ' or * that ' are usually demonstrative,
whereas phrases which commence with *the' or *a'
are often descriptive. In studying the theory of pro-
positiond expression it is important to remember the
wide difference between the analogous modest words
*this' and 'that' on the one hand and *a' and *the'
on the other hand. The sentence
*The college building in Regent's Park is com-
modious '
means, according to the analysis first made by Bertrand
Russell, the proposition,
* There is an entity which (i) is a college building in
Regent's Park and (ii) is commodious and (iii) is such
12 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [CH.
that any college building in Regent's Park is identical
with it.'
The descriptive character of the phrase * The college
building in Regent's Park' is thus evident. Also the
proposition is denied by the denial of any one of its
three component clauses or by the denial of any
combination of the component clauses. If we had
substituted * Green Park' for * Regent's Park' a false
proposition would have resulted. Also the erection of a
second college in Regent's Park would make the pro-
position false, though in ordinary life common sense
would politely treat it as merely ambiguous.
* The Iliad ' for a classical scholar is usually a demon-
strative phrase ; for it demonstrates to him a well-known
poem. But for the majority of mankind the phrase is
descriptive, namely, it is synonymous with ' The poem
named "the Iliad".'
Names may be either demonstrative or descriptive
phrases. For example 'Homer' is for us a descriptive
phrase, namely, the word with some slight difference
in suggestiveness means *The man who wrote the
Iliad.'
This discussion illustrates that thought places before
itself bare objectives, entities as we call them, which
the thinking clothes by expressing their mutual rela-
tions. Sense-awareness discloses fact with factors which
are the entities for thought. The s.eparate^d istinction of
an entity in thought is not a metaphys ical assertio a>_blit
' a m ethodof procedure neces sar yfor the finite expression
of mdi vidual propositions. Apart from entities there
'could be no finite truths ; they are the means by which
the infinitude of irrelevance is kept out of thought.
\To sum up: the termini for thought are entities >
I] NATURE AND THOUGHT 13
primarily with__bare individuality, se condarily with
pro perties and relations ascribed to them j n_th e pro-
cedure of thought ; the termin i for sense-awareness are
factors i n the fact of nature, .4:u:imarily re lata andjonly
seco ndarily discrimin a ted as distinct individualiti es.
No characteristic of nature which is immediately
posited for knowledge by sense-awareness can be
explained. It is impenetrable by thought, in the sense
that its peculiar essential character which enters into
experience by sense-awareness is for thought merely the
guardian of its individuality as a bare entity. Thus for
thought *red' is merely a definite entity, though for
awareness * red ' has the content of its individuality. The
transition from the *red' of awareness to the *red' of
thought is accompanied by a definite loss of content,
namely by the transition from the factor *red' to the/
entity *red.' This loss in the transition to thought is]
compensated by the fact that thought is communicable/
whereas sense-awareness is incommunicable.
Thus there are three components in our knowledge of
nature, namely, fact, factors, and entities. Fact is the
undifferentiated terminus of sense-awareness; factors
are termini of sense-awareness, differentiated as elements
of fact ; entities are factors in their function as the ter-
mini of tfiougEt. The entities thus spoken of are natural
entities. Thought is wider than nature, so that there are
entities for thought which are not natural entities.
When we speak of nature as a complex of related
entities, the * complex' is fact as an entity for thought,
to whose bare individuality is ascribed the property of
embracing in its complexity the natural entities. It is
our business to analyse this conception and in the course
of the analysis space and time should appear. Evidently
14 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch.
I the relation s holding between natural entities are
/ themselves natural entities, namely they are also factors
of fact, there for sense-awareness. Accordingly the
structure of the natural complex can never be com-
pleted in thought, just as the factors of fact can never
be exhausted in sense-awareness. Unexhaustiveness is
an essential character of our knowledge of nature. Also
nature does not exhaust the matter for thought, namely
there are thoughts which would not occur in any homo-
geneous thinking about nature.
The question as to whether sense-perception involves
thought is largely verbal. If sense-perception involves
a cognition of individuality abstracted from the actual
position of the entity as a factor in fact, then it un-
doubtedly does involve thought. But if it is conceived
as sense-awareness of a factor in fact competent to
evoke emotion and purposeful action without further
cognition, then it does not involve thought. In such a
case the terminus of the sense-awareness is something
for mind, but nothing for thought. The sense-perception
of some lower forms of life may be conjectured to
approximate to this character habitually. Also occasion-
ally our own sense-perception in moments when thought-
activity has been lulled to quiescence is not far off the
attainment of this ideal limit.
The process of discrimination in sense-awareness has
two distinct sides. There is the discrimination of fact
into parts, and the discrimination of any part of fact as
exhibiting relations to entities which are not parts of
fact though they are ingredients in it. Namely the
immediate fact for awareness is the whole occurrence
of nature. It is nature as an event^^resent for sense-
awareness, and essentially passing. There is no holding
I] NATURE AND THOUGHT 15
nature still and looking at it. We cannot redouble our
efforts to improve our knowledge of the terminus of our
present sense-awareness; it is our subsequent oppor-
tunity in subsequent sense-awareness which gains the
benefit of our good resolution. Thus the ultimate fact
for sense-awareness is an event. This whole' event is
discriminated by us into partial events. We are aware
of an event which is our bodily life, of an event which is
the course of nature within this room, and of a vaguely
perceived aggregate of other partial events. This is the
discrimination in sense-awareness of fact into parts.
I shall use the term *part' in the arbitrarily limited
sense of an event which is part of the whole fact dis-
closed in awareness.
Sense-awareness also yields to us other factors in
nature which are not events. For example, sky-blue is
seen as situated in a certain event. This relation of
situation requires further discussion which is postponed
to a later lecture. My present point is that sky-blue is
found in nature with a definite implication in events,
but is not an event itself. Accordingly in addition to
events, there are other factors in nature directly dis-
closed to us in sense-awareness. The conception in
thought of all the factors in nature as distinct entities
with definite natural relations is what I have in another
place^ called the * diversification of nature.'
There is one general conclusion to be drawn from the
foregoing discussion. It is that the first task of a philo-
sophy of science should be some general classification of
the entities disclosed to us in sense-perception.
Among the examples of entities in addition to * events '
which we have used for the purpose of illustration are
^ Cf. Enquiry.
M
i6 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch.
the buildings of Bedford College, Homer, and sky-blue.
Evidently these are very different sorts of things ; and it
is likely that statements which are made about one kind
of entity will not be true about other kinds. If human
thought proceeded with the orderly method which
abstract logic would suggest to it, we might go further
and say that a classification of natural entities should be
the first step in science itself. Perhaps you will be
inclined to reply that this classification has already been
effected, and that science is concerned with the ad-
ventures of material entities in space and time.
The history of the doctrine of matter has yet to be
written. It is the history of the influence of Greek
philosophy on science. That influence has issued in
one long misconception of the metaphysical status of
natural entities. The entity has been separated from the
factor which is the terminus of sense-awareness. It has
become the substratum for that factor, and the factor
J has been degraded into an attribute of the entity. In
phis way a distinction has been imported into nature
which is in truth no distinction at all. A natural entity
is merely a factor of fact, considered in itself. Its dis-
connexion from the complex of fact is a mere abstraction.
^ |It is not the substratum of the factor, bixLllie-AcerjL
factor itself as bared in thou ght Thus what is a mere
(procedure of mind in the translation of sense-awareness
into discursive knowledge has been transmuted into a
fundamental character of nature. In this way matter
has emerged as being the metaphysical substratum of
its properties, and the course of nature is interpreted
as the history of matter.
Plato and Aristotle found Greek thought preoccupied
with the quest for the simple substances in terms of
I] NATURE AND THOUGHT 17
which the course of events could be expressed. We
may formulate this state of mind in the question, What
is nature made of? The answers which their genius
gave to this question, and more particularly the con-
cepts which underlay the terms in which they framed
their answers, have determined the unquestioned pre-
suppositions as to time, space and matter which have
reigned in science.
In Plato the forms of thought are more fluid than in
Aristotle, and therefore, as I venture to think, the more
valuable. Their importance consists in the evidence
they yield of cultivated thought about nature before it
had been forced into a uniform mould by the long
tradition of scientific philosophy. For example in the
Timaeus there is a presupposition, somewhat vaguely
expressed, of a distinction between the general becoming
of nature and the measurable time of nature. In a later
lecture I have to distinguish between what I call the
passage of nature and particular time-systems which
exhibit certain characteristics of that passage. I will not
go so far as to claim Plato in direct support of this
doctrine, but I do think that the sections of the Timaeus
which deal with time become clearer if my distinction
is admitted.
This is however a digression. I am now concerned
with the origin of the scientific doctrine of matter in
Greek thought. In the Timaeus Plato asserts that nature
is made of fire and earth with air and water as inter-
mediate between them, so that * as fire is to air so is air
to water, and as air is to water so is water to earth.' He
also suggests a molecular hypothesis for these four
elements. In this hypothesis everything depends on the
shape of the atoms ; for earth it is cubical and for fire
W. N. 2
i8 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch.
it is pyramidal. To-day physicists are again discussing
the structure of the atom, and its shape is no sHght
factor in that structure. Plato's guesses read much more
[fantastically than does Aristotle's systematic analysis;
but in some ways they are more valuable. The main
outline of his ideas is comparable with that of modern
j science. It embodies concepts which any theory of
/natural philosophy must retain and in some sense must
/ explain. Aristotle asked the fundamental question,
f What do we mean by * substance ' .^ Here the reaction
between his philosophy and his logic worked very
unfortunately. In his logic, the fundamental type of
affirmative proposition is the attribution of a predicate
Ito a subject. Accordingly, amid the many current uses
/of the term * substance ' which he analyses, he emphasises
/ its meaning as * the ultimate substratum which is no
I longer predicated of anything else.'
The unquestioned acceptance of the Aristotelian logic
has led to an ingrained tendency to postulate a sub-
stratum for whatever is disclosed in sense-awareness,
namely, to look below what we are aware of for the
substance in the sense of the * concrete thing.' This
is the origin of the modern scientific concept of matter
and of ether, namely they are the outcome of this
insistent habit of postulation.
Accordingly ether has been invented by modern
science as the substratum of the events which are
spread through space and time beyond the reach of
ordinary ponderable matter. Personally, I think that
predication is a muddled notion confusing many different
relations under a convenient common form of speech.
For example, I hold that the relation of green to a blade
of grass is entirely different from the relation of green
I] NATURE AND THOUGHT 19
to the event which is the Hfe history of that blade for
some short period, and is different from the relation
of the blade to that event. In a sense I call the
event the situation of the green, and in another sense
it is the situation of the blade. Thus in one sense the
blade is a character or property which can be predi-
cated of the situation, and in another sense the green
is a character or property of the same event which
is also its situation. In this way the predication of
properties veils radically different relations between
entities.
Accordingly * substance,' which is a correlative term
to ' predication,' shares in the ambiguity. If we are to
look for substance anywhere, I should find it in events
which are in some sense the ultimate substance of
nature.
Matter, in its modern scientific sense, is a return to
the Ionian effort to find in space and time some stuff
which composes nature. It has a more refined signi-
fication than the early guesses at earth and water by
reason of a certain vague association with the Aristotelian
idea of substance.
Earth, water, air, fire, and matter, and finally ether
are related in direct succession so far as concerns their
postulated characters of ultimate substrata of nature.
They bear witness *to the undying vitality of Greek
philosophy in its search for the ultimate entities which
are the factors of the fact disclosed in sense-awareness.
This search is the origin of science.
The succession of ideas starting from the crude
guesses of the early Ionian thinkers and ending in the
nineteenth century ether reminds us that the scientific
doctrine of matter is really a hybrid through which
Af.'S
V
^r
20 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch.
philosophy passed on its way to the refined Aristotelian
concept of substance and to which science returned as
it reacted against philosophic abstractions. Earth, fire,
and water in the Ionic philosophy and the shaped
elements in the Timaeus are comparable to the matter
and ether of modern scientific doctrine. But substance
represents the final philosophic concept of the sub-
stratum which underlies any attribute. Matter (in the
scientific sense) is already in space and time. Thus
matter represents the refusal to think away spatial and
temporal characteristics and to arrive at the bare con-
cept of an individual entity. It is this refusal which has
caused the muddle of importing the mere procedure of
thought into the fact of nature. The entity, bared of
all characteristics except those of space and time, has ac-
quired a physical status as the ultimate texture of nature ;
so that the course of nature is conceived as being merely
the fortunes of matter in its adventure through space.
Thus the origin of the doctrine of matter is the out-
come of uncritical acceptance of space and time as
external conditions for natural existence. By this I do
not mean that any doubt should be thrown on facts of
space and time as ingredients in nature. What I do
mean is 'the unconscious presupposition of space and
time as being that within which nature is set.' This is
exactly the sort of presupposition which tinges thought
in any reaction against the subtlety of philosophical
I criticism. My theory of the formation of the scientific
I doctrine of matter is that first philosophy illegitimately
transformed the bare entity, which is simply an ab-
straction necessary for the method of thought, into
the metaphysical substratum of these factors in nature
which in various senses are assigned to entities as their
I] NATURE AND THOUGHT 21
attributes ; and that, as a second step, scientists (includ-
ing philosophers who were scientists) in conscious or
unconscious ignoration of philosophy presupposed this
substratum, qua substratum for attributes, as never-
theless in time and space.
This is surely a muddle. The whole being of substance
is as a substratum for attributes. Thus time and space
should be attributes of the substance. This they
palpably are not, if the matter be the substance of
nature, since it is impossible to express spatio-temporal
truths without having recourse to relations involving
relata other than bits of matter. I waive this point
however, and come to another. It is not the substance f ^'^^
whiclL is _in_ space ^ but the attributes. What we find in/
space are the red of the rose and the smell of the jasmine/
and the noise of cannon. We have all told our dentistsi
where our toothache is. Thus space is not a relatioiJ ,
between substances, but between attributes.
Thus even if you admit that the adherents of sub-
stance can be allowed to conceive substance as matter,
it is a fraud to slip substance into space on the plea
that space expresses relations between substances. On
the face of it space has nothing to do with substances,
but only with their attributes. What I mean is, that
if you choose — as I think wrongly — ^to construe our ex-
perience of nature as an awareness of the attributes of
substances, we are by this theory precluded from finding
any analogous direct relations between substances as
disclosed in our experience. What we do find are I
relations between the attributes of substances. Thus if \
matter is looked on as substance in space, the space in \
which it finds itself has very little to do with the space j
of our experience.
22 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch.
The above argument has been expressed in terms of
the relational theory of space. But if space be absolute
— ^namely, if it have a being independent of things in it
— ^the course of the argument is hardly changed. For
things in space must have a certain fundamental relation
to space which we will call occupation. Thus the ob-
jection that it is the attributes which are observed as
related to space, still holds.
The scientific doctrine of matter is held in conjunc-
tion with an absolute theory of time. The same argu-
ments apply to the relations between matter and time
as apply to the relations between space and matter.
There is however (in the current philosophy) a difference
in the connexions of space with matter from those of
time with matter, which I will proceed to explain.
Space is not merely an ordering of material entities
so that any one entity bears certain relations to other
material entities. The occupation of space impresses a
certain character on each material entity in itself. By
reason of its occupation of space matter has extension.
By reason of its extension each bit of matter is divisible
into parts, and each part is a numerically distinct
entity from every other such part. Accordingly it
would seem that every material entity is not really one
entity. It is an essential multiplicity of entities. There
seems to be no stopping this dissociation of matter into
multiplicities short of finding each ultimate entity
occupying one individual point. This essential multi-
plicity of material entities is certainly not what is meant
by sciep^, nor does it correspond to anything disclosed
in sense-awareness. It is absolutely necessary that at
a certain stage in this dissociation of matter a halt should
be called, and that the material entities thus obtained
I] NATURE AND THOUGHT 23
should be treated as units. The stage of arrest may be
arbitrary or may be set by the characteristics of nature ;
but all reasoning in science ultimately drops its space-
analysis and poses to itself the problem, ' Here is one
material entity, what is happening to it as a unit
entity?' Yet this material entity is still retaining its
extension, and as thus extended is a mere multiplicity.
Thus there is an essential atomic property in nature
which is independent of the dissociation of extension.
There is something which in itself is one, and which is
more than the logical aggregate of entities occupying
points within the volume which the unit occupies.
Indeed we may well be sceptical as to these ultimate
entities at points, and doubt whether there are any such
entities at all. They have the suspicious character thati
we are driven to accept them by abstract logic and not!
by observed fact. '
Time (in the current philosophy) does not exert the
same disintegrating effect on matter which occupies it.
If matter occupies a duration of time, the whole matter
occupies every part of that duration. Thus the connexion
between matter and time differs from the connexion
between matter and space as expressed in current
scientific philosophy. There is obviously a greater
difficulty in conceiving time as the outcome of relations
between different bits of matter than there is in the
analogous conception of space. At an instant distinct
volumes of space are occupied by distinct bits of matter.
Accordingly there is so far no intrinsic difficulty in
conceiving that space is merely the resultant of relations
between the bits of matter. But in the one-dimensional
time the same bit of matter occupies different portions
of time. Accordingly time would have to be expressible
24 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch.
in terms of the relations of a bit of matter with itself.
My own view is a belief in the relational theory both of
space and of time, and of disbelief in the current form
of the relational theory of space which exhibits bits
I of matter as the relata for spatial relations. The true
relata are events. The distinction which I have just
pointed out between time and space in their connexion
with matter makes it evident that any assimilation of
time and space cannot proceed along the traditional line
of taking matter as a fundamental element in space-
formation.
The philosophy of nature took a wrong turn during
its development by Greek thought. This erroneous
presupposition is vague and fluid in Plato's Timaeus.
The general groundwork of the thought is still un-
committed and can be construed as merely lacking due
explanation and the guarding emphasis. But in
Aristotle's exposition the current conceptions were
hardened and made definite so as to produce a faulty
analysis of the relation between the matter and the form
of nature as disclosed in sense-awareness. In this phrase
the term 'matter' is not used in its scientific sense.
I will conclude by guarding myself against a mis-
apprehension. It is evident that the current doctrine of
matter enshrines some fundamental law of nature. Any
simple illustration will exemplify what I mean. For
example, in a museum some specimen is locked securely
in a glass case. It stays there for years : it loses its colour,
and perhaps falls to pieces. But it is the same specimen ;
and the same chemical elements and the same quantities
of those elements are present within the case at the end
as were present at the beginning. Again the engineer
and the astronomer deal with the motions of real per-
I] NATURE AND THOUGHT 25
manences in nature. Any theory of nature which for
one moment loses sight of these great basic facts of
experience is simply silly. But it is permissible to point
out that the scientific expression of these facts has be-
come entangled in a maze of doubtful metaphysics;
and that, when we remove the metaphysics and start
afresh on an unprejudiced survey of nature, a new light
is thrown on many fundamental concepts which domi-
nate science and guide the progress of research.
^
CHAPTER II
THEORIES OF THE BIFURCATION
OF NATURE
j In my previous lecture I criticised the concept of matter
» as the substance whose attributes we perceive. This way
of thinking of matter is, I think, the historical reason
for its introduction into science, and is still the vague
view of it at the background of our thoughts which
makes the current scientific doctrine appear so obvious.
Namely we conceive ourselves as perceiving attributes
of things, and bits of matter are the things whose
attributes we perceive.
In the seventeenth century the sweet simplicity of
this aspect of matter received a rude shock. The trans-
mission doctrines of science were then in process of
elaboration and by the end of the century were un-
questioned, though their particular forms have since
been modified. The establishment of these transmission
theories marks a turning point in the relation between
science and philosophy. The doctrines to which I am
especially alluding are the theories of light and sound.
I have no doubt that the theories had been vaguely
floating about before as obvious suggestions of common
sense; for nothing in thought is ever completely new.
But at that epoch they were systematised and made
exact, and their complete consequences were ruthlessly
II deduced. It is the establishment of this procedure of
II taking the consequences seriously which marks the
||real discovery of a theory. Systematic doctrines of
light and sound as being something proceeding from
CH.ii] THEORIES OF BIFURCATION OF NATURE 27
the emitting bodies were definitely established, and in
particular the connexion of Hght with colour was laid
bare by Newton.
The result completely destroyed the simplicity of the
* substance and attribute' theory of perception. What
we see depends on the light entering the eye. Further-
more we do not even perceive what enters the eye. The
things transmitted are waves or — as Newton thought —
minute particles, and the things seen are colours. Locke
met this difficulty by a theory of primary and secondary
qualities. Namely, there are some attributes of the
matter which we do perceive. These are the primary
qualities, and there are other things which we perceive,
such as colours, which are not attributes of matter, but
are perceived by us as if they were such attributes.
These are the secondary qualities of matter.
Why should we perceive secondary qualities.'^ It
seems an extremely unfortunate arrangement that we
should perceive a lot of things that are not there. Yet
this is what the theory of secondary qualities in fact
comes to. There is now reigning in philosophy and in
science an apathetic acquiescence in the conclusion that
no coherent account can be given of nature as it is
disclosed to us in sense-awareness, without dragging in
its relations to mind. The modern account of nature is
not, as it should be, merely an account of what the mind
knows of nature ; but it is also confused with an account
of what nature does to the mind. The result has been
disastrous both to science and to philosophy, but chiefly
to philosophy. It has transformed the grand question
of the relations between nature and mind into the petty
form of the interaction between the human body and
mind.
•
28 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch.
Berkeley's polemic against matter was based on this
confusion introduced by the transmission theory of
light. He advocated, rightly as I think, the abandon-
ment of the doctrine of matter in its present form. He
had however nothing to put in its place except a theory
of the relation of finite minds to the divine mind.
But we are endeavouring in these lectures to limit
ourselves to nature itself and not to travel beyond
entities which are disclosed in sense-awareness.
Percipience in itself is taken for granted. We consider
indeed conditions for percipience, but only so far as
those conditions are among the disclosures of percep-
tion. We leave to metaphysics the synthesis of the
knower and the known. Some further explanation and
defence of this position is necessary, if the line of argu-
ment of these lectures is to be comprehensible.
The immediate thesis for discussion is that any meta-
physical interpretation is an illegitimate importation into
the philosophy of natural science. By a metaphysical
interpretation I mean any discussion of the how (beyond
nature) and of the why (beyond nature) of thought and
sense-awareness. In the philosophy of science we seek
the general notions which apply to nature, namely, to
what we are aware of in perception. It is the philosophy
of the thing perceived, and it should not be confused
with the metaphysics of reality of which the scope
embraces both perceiver and perceived. No perplexity
concerning the object of knowledge can be solved by
saying that there is a mind knowing it^.
In other words, the ground taken is this: sense-
awareness is an awareness of something. What then is
the general character of that something of which we
1 Cf. Enquiry, preface.
II] THEORIES OF BIFURCATION OF NATURE 29
are aware? We do not ask about the percipient or
about the process, but about the perceived. I emphasise
this point because discussions on the philosophy of
science are usually extremely metaphysical — in my
opinion, to the great detriment of the subject.
The recourse to metaphysics is like throwing a match
into the powder magazine. It blows up the whole arena.
This is exactly what scientific philosophers do when
they are driven into a corner and convicted of inco-
herence. They at once drag in the mind and talk of
entities in the mind or out of the mind as the case may
be. For natural philosophy everything perceived is in
nature. We n^ay not pick and choose. For us the red
glow of the sunset should be as much part of nature as
are the molecules and electric waves by which men of
/science would explain the phenomenon. It is for natural/^ f
philosophy to analyse how these various elements of j^. \W^ia
I nature are connected. A^'^t-^t^^/iw M
In making this demand I conceive myself as adopting V^^iJ^
our immediate instinctive attitude towards perceptual
knowledge which is only abandoned under the influence
of theory. We are instinctively willing to believe that by
due attention, more can be found in nature than that
which is observed at first sight. But we will not be
content with less. What we ask from the philosopliy of
science is some account of the coherence of things
perceptively known .
This means a refusal to countenance any theory of
psychic additions to the object known in perception.
For example, what is given in perception is the green
grass. This is an object which we know as an ingredient
in nature. The theory of psychic additions would treat
the greenness as a psychic addition furnished by the
U*^
^
^ MiCinAl ^ ^3> ^tc.
be an abstractive set, the members being so arranged
that each member such as e^ extends over all the suc-
ceeding members such as ^^+1, ^n+2> and so on. Then
corresponding to the series
^l> ^2» ^3> •••> ^w) ^w+l> •••>
there is the series
(I (^i)» ^ (^2)» 9. (^3)» •••, (I W, ^ K+i), ....
Call the series of events s and the series of quanti-
tative expressions q {$), The series s has no last term and
IV] METHOD OF EXTENSIVE ABSTRACTION 8i
no events which are contained in every member of the
series. Accordingly the series of events converges to
nothing. It is just itself. Also the series q {s) has no
last term. But the sets of homologous quantities
running through the various terms of the series do
converge to definite limits. For example if Q^ be a
quantitative measurement found in q (^j), and Q^ the
homologue to Q^ to be found in q {e^, and Q^ the
homologue to Q^ and ^2 to be found in q (^3), and so on,
then the series
6l> Q^y Qz^ •••> Qny Qn+l^ •••>
though it has no last term, does in general converge to
a definite limit. Accordingly there is a class of limits
/ {s) w^hich is the class of the limits of those members of
^ny ^n+i, ... -^ nothing,
and
q (^i)> 9 (^2)> q (^3), ..., ^ K), q K-m), ... - / (s).
The mutual relations between the limits in the set
l{s), and also between these limits and the limits in
other sets l{s'), l{s"), ..., which arise from other
abstractive sets s\ s", etc., have a peculiar simplicity.
Thus the set s does indicate an ideal simplicity of
natural relations, though this simplicity is not the
character of any actual event in s. We can make an
approximation to such a simpHcity which, as estimated
numerically, is as close as we like by considering an
event which is far enough down the series towards the
small end. It will be noted that it is the infinite series,
W.N. 6
82 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch.
as it stretches away in unending succession towards
the small end, which is of importance. The arbitrarily
large event with which the series starts has no importance
at all. We can arbitrarily exclude any set of events at
the big end of an abstractive set without the loss of
any important property to the set as thus modified.
I call the limiting character of natural relations which
is indicated by an abstractive set, the ' intrinsic character '
of the set; also the properties, connected with the
relation of whole and part as concerning its members,
by which an abstractive set is defined together form what
I call its * extrinsic character.' The fact that the ex-
trinsic character of an abstractive set determines a
definite intrinsic character is the reason of the import-
ance of the precise concepts of space and time. This
emergence of a definite intrinsic character from an
abstractive set is the precise meaning of the law of
convergence.
For example, we see a train approaching during a
minute. The event which is the life of nature within
that train during the minute is of great complexity and
the expression of its relations and of the ingredients
of its character baffles us. If we take one second of
that minute, the more limited event which is thus
obtained is simpler in respect to its ingredients, and
shorter and shorter times such as a tenth of that second,
or a hundredth, or a thousandth — so long as we have a
definite rule giving a definite succession of diminishing
events — give events whose ingredient characters con-
verge to the ideal simplicity of the character of the train
at a definite instant. Furthermore there are different
types of such convergence to simplicity. For example,
we can converge as above to the limiting character
IV] METHOD OF EXTENSIVE ABSTRACTION 83
expressing nature at an instant within the whole volume
of the train at that instant, or to nature at an instant
within some portion of that volume — for example
within the boiler of the engine — or to nature at an
instant on some area of surface, or to nature at an instant
on some line within the train, or to nature at an instant
at some point of the train. In the last case the simple
limiting characters arrived at will be expressed as
densities, specific gravities, and types of material.
Furthermore we need not necessarily converge to an
abstraction which involves nature at an instant. We
may converge to the physical ingredients of a certain
point track throughout the whole minute. Accordingly
there are different types of extrinsic character of con-
vergence which lead to the approximation to different
types of intrinsic characters as limits.
We now pass to the investigation of possible con-
nexions between abstractive sets. One set may * cover'
another. I define * covering' as follows: An abstractive
set p covers an abstractive set q when every member of
p contains as its parts some members of q. It is evident
that if any event e contains as a part any member of
the set q, then owing to the transitive property of ex-
tension every succeeding member of the small end of q
is part of ^. In such a case I will say that the abstractive
set q * inheres in ' the event e. Thus when an abstractive
set p covers an abstractive set q, the abstractive set q
inheres in every member of/).
Two abstractive sets may each cover the other. When
this is the case I shall call the two sets * equal in ab-
stractive force.' When there is no danger of misunder-
standing I shall shorten this phrase by simply saying
that the two abstractive sets are * equal.' The possibility
6—2
84 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [CH.
of this equality of abstractive sets arises from the fact
that both sets, p and ^, are infinite series towards their
small ends. Thus the equality means, that given any
event x belonging to p, we can always by proceeding
far enough towards the small end of q find an event y
which is part of x, and that then by proceeding far
enough towards the small end of ^ we can find an event z
which is part oiy, and so on indefinitely.
*. / The importance of the equality of abstractive sets
•^"^^ arises from the assumption that the intrinsic characters
of the two sets are identical. If this were not the case
exact observation would be at an end.
It is evident that any two abstractive sets which are
equal to a third abstractive set are equal to each other.
An * abstractive element' is the whole group of ab-
stractive sets which are equal to any one of themselves.
Thus all abstractive sets belonging to the same element
are equal and converge to the same intrinsic character.
Thus an abstractive element is the group of routes of
approximation to a definite intrinsic character of ideal
simplicity to be found as a limit among natural facts.
If an abstractive set p covers an abstractive set q, then
any abstractive set belonging to the abstractive element
of which /) is a member will cover any abstractive set
belonging to the element of which ^ is a member.
Accordingly it is useful to stretch the meaning of the
term * covering,' and to speak of one abstractive element
* covering ' another abstractive element. If we attempt in
like manner to stretch the term * equal ' in the sense of
* equal in abstractive force,' it is obvious that an ab-
stractive element can only be equal to itself. Thus an
abstractive element has a unique abstractive force and is
the construct from events which represents one definite
IV] METHOD OF EXTENSIVE ABSTRACTION 85
intrinsic character which is arrived at as a Hmit by the
use of the principle of convergence to simpHcity by
diminution of extent.
When an abstractive element A covers an abstractive
element B, the intrinsic character of ^ in a sense
includes the intrinsic character of B, It results that
statements about the intrinsic character of B are in a
sense statements about the intrinsic character of A;
but the intrinsic character of A is more complex than
that of B.
The abstractive elements form the fundamental
elements of space and time, and we now turn to the
consideration of the properties involved in the formation
of special classes of such elements. In my last lecture
I have already investigated one class of abstractive
elements, namely moments. Each moment is a group
of abstractive sets, and the events which are members
of these sets are all members of one family of durations.
The moments of one family form a temporal series;
and, allowing the existence of different families of
moments, there will be alternative temporal series in
nature. Thus the method of extensive abstraction ex-
plains the origin of temporal series in terms of the
immediate facts of experience and at the same time
allows for the existence of the alternative temporal
series which are demanded by the modern theory of
electromagnetic relativity.
We now turn to space. The first thing to do is to
get hold of the class of abstractive elements which are
in some sense the points of space. Such an abstractive
element must in some sense exhibit a convergence to
an absolute minimum of intrinsic character. Euclid
has expressed for all time the general idea of a point,
86 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch.
as being without parts and without magnitude. It is
this character of being an absolute minimum which we
want to get at and to express in terms of the extrinsic
characters of the abstractive sets which make up a point.
Furthermore, points which are thus arrived at repre-
sent the ideal of events without any extension, though
there are in fact no such entities as these ideal events.
These points will not be the points of an external time-
less space but of instantaneous spaces. We ultimately
want to arrive at the timeless space of physical science,
and also of common thought which is now tinged with
the concepts of science. It will be convenient to reserve
the term * point' for these spaces when we get to
them. I will therefore use the name * event-particles '
for the ideal minimum limits to events. Thus an
event-particle is an abstractive element and as such is
a group of abstractive sets ; and a point — namely a point
of timeless space — ^will be a class of event-particles.
Furthermore there is a separate timeless space corre-
sponding to each separate temporal series, that is to
each separate family of durations. We will come back
to points in timeless spaces later. I merely mention
them now that we may understand the stages of our
investigation. The totality of event-particles will form a
four-dimensional manifold, the extra dimension arising
from time — in other words — arising from the points of
a timeless space being each a class of event-particles.
The required character of the abstractive sets which
form event-particles would be secured if we could define
them as having the property of being covered by any
abstractive set which they cover. For then any other
abstractive set which an abstractive set of an event-
particle covered, would be equal to it, and would
IV] METHOD OF EXTENSIVE ABSTRACTION 87
therefore be a member of the same event-particle.
Accordingly an event-particle could cover no other
abstractive element. This is the definition which I
originally proposed at a congress in Paris in 1914^.
There is however a difficulty involved in this definition
if adopted without some further addition, and I am now
not satisfied with the way in which I attempted to get
over that difficulty in the paper referred to.
The difficulty is this : When event-particles have once
been defined it is easy to define the aggregate of event-
particles forming the boundary of an event ; and thence
to define the point-contact at their boundaries possible
for ^ pair of events of which one is part of the other.
We can then conceive all the intricacies of tangency.
In particular we can conceive an abstractive set of
which all the members have point-contact at the same
event-particle. It is then easy to prove that there will
be no abstractive set with the property of being
covered by every abstractive set which it covers. I state
this difficulty at some length because its existence guides
the development of our line of argument. We have got
to annex some condition to the root property of being
covered by any abstractive set which it covers. When
we look into this question of suitable conditions we find
that in addition to event-particles all the other relevant
spatial and spatio-temporal abstractive elements can
be defined in the same way by suitably varying the
conditions. Accordingly we proceed in a general way
suitable for employment beyond event-particles.
Let (J be the name of any condition which some
abstractive sets fulfil. I say that an abstractive set is
1 Cf. • La Theorie Relationniste de TEspace,' Rev. de Mita-
physique et de Morale ^ vol. xxiii, 191 6.
88 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch.
* or -prime' when it has the two properties, (i) that it
satisfies the condition a and (ii) that it is covered by
every abstractive set which both is covered by it and
satisfies the condition a.
In other words you cannot get any abstractive set
satisfying the condition a which exhibits intrinsic
character more simple than that of a o- -prime.
There are also the correlative abstractive sets which
I call the sets of a-antiprimes. An abstractive set is a
a-antiprime when it has the two properties, (i) that it
satisfies the condition a and (ii) that it covers every
abstractive set which both covers it and satisfies the
condition a. In other words you cannot get any ab-
stractive set satisfying the condition o- which exhibits
an intrinsic character more complex than that of a
cr-antiprime.
The intrinsic character of a cr -prime has a certain
minimum of fullness among those abstractive sets which
are subject to the condition of satisfying a; whereas
the intrinsic character of a a-antiprime has a corre-
sponding maximum of fullness, and includes all it can
in the circumstances.
Let us first consider what help the notion of anti-
primes could give us in the definition of moments
which we gave in the last lecture. Let the condition
or be the property of being a class whose members are
all durations. An abstractive set which satisfies this
condition is thus an abstractive set composed wholly
of durations. It is convenient then to define a moment
as the group of abstractive sets which are equal to some
a-antiprime, where the condition a has this special
meaning. It will be found on consideration (i) that
each abstractive set forming a moment is a o--antiprime.
IV] METHOD OF EXTENSIVE ABSTRACTION 89
where (j has this special meaning, and (ii) that we have
excluded from membership of moments abstractive
sets of durations which all have one common boundary,
either the initial boundary or the final boundary. We
thus exclude special cases which are apt to confuse
general reasoning. The new definition of a moment,
which supersedes our previous definition, is (by the aid
of the notion of antiprimes) the more precisely drawn
of the two, and the more useful.
The particular condition which *(j' stood for in the
definition of moments included something additional
to anything which can be derived from the bare notion
of extension. A duration exhibits for thought a totality.
The notion of totality is something beyond that of
extension, though the two are interwoven in the notion
of a duration.
In the same way the particular condition ' a ' required
for the definition of an event-particle must be looked for
beyond the mere notion of extension. The same remark
is also true of the particular conditions requisite for the
other spatial elements. This additional notion is ob-
tained by distinguishing between the notion of *posi-,
tion ' and the notion of convergence to an ideal zero of
extension as exhibited by an abstractive set of events.
In order to understand this distinction consider a
point of the instantaneous space which we conceive
as apparent to us in an almost instantaneous glance.
This point is an event-particle. It has two aspects. In
one aspect it is there, where it is. This is its position in
the space. In another aspect it is got at by ignoring the
circumambient space, and by concentrating attention on
the smaller and smaller set of events which approximate
to it. This is its extrinsic character. Thus a point has
90 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch.
three characters, namely, its position in the whole
instantaneous space, its extrinsic character, and its
intrinsic character. The same is true of any other spatial
.element. For example an instantaneous volume in
instantaneous space has three characters, namely, its
position, its extrinsic character as a group of abstractive
sets, and its intrinsic character which is the limit of
natural properties which is indicated by any one of
these abstractive sets.
. Before we can talk about position in instantaneous
space, we must evidently be quite clear as to what we
mean by instantaneous space in itself. Instantaneous
space must be looked for as a character of a moment.
For a moment is all nature at an instant. It cannot be
the intrinsic character of the moment. For the intrinsic
character tells us the limiting character of nature in
space at that instant. Instantaneous space must be
an assemblage of abstractive elements considered in
their mutual relations. Thus an instantaneous space is
the assemblage of abstractive elements covered by some
one moment, and it is the instantaneous space of that
moment.
We have now to ask what character we have found in
nature which is capable of according to the elements of
an instantaneous space different qualities of position.
This question at once brings us to the intersection of
moments, which is a topic not as yet considered in
these lectures.
The locus of intersection of two moments is the
assemblage of abstractive elements covered by both of
them. Now two moments of the same temporal series
cannot intersect. Two moments respectively of different
families necessarily intersect. Accordingly in the in-
IV] METHOD OF EXTENSIVE ABSTRACTION 91
stantaneous space of a moment we should expect the
fundamental properties to be marked by the inter-
sections with moments of other families. If M be a
given moment, the intersection of M with another
moment A is an instantaneous plane in the instan-
taneous space of M] and if 5 be a third moment
intersecting both M and A, the intersection of M and B
is another plane in the space M. Also the common
intersection of ^, By and M is the intersection of the
two planes in the space M, namely it is a straight line
in the space M. An exceptional case arises if B and M
intersect in the same plane as A and M. Furthermore
if C be a fourth moment, then apart from special cases
which we need not consider, it intersects M in a plane
which the straight line {A, B, M) meets. Thus there
is in general a common intersection of four moments
of different families. This common intersection is an
assemblage of abstractive elements which are each
covered (or *lie in') all four moments. The three-
dimensional property of instantaneous space comes to
this, that (apart from special relations between the four
moments) any fifth moment either contains the whole
of their common intersection or none of it. No further
subdivision of the common intersection is possible by
means of moments. The 'all or none' principle holds.
This is not an a priori truth but an empirical fact of
nature.
It will be convenient to reserve the ordinary spatial
terms * plane,' * straight line,' * point' for the elements
of the timeless space of a time-system. Accordingly an
instantaneous plane in the instantaneous space of a
moment will be called a * level,' an instantaneous straight
line will be called a *rect,' and an instantaneous point
92 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch.
will be called a * punct/ Thus a punct is the assemblage
of abstractive elements which lie in each of four moments
whose families have no special relations to each other.
Also if P be any moment, either every abstractive
element belonging to a given punct lies in P, or no
abstractive element of that punct lies in P.
Position is the quality which an abstractive element
possesses in virtue of the moments in which it lies. The
abstractive elements which lie in the instantaneous
space of a given moment M are differentiated from each
other by the various other moments which intersect M
so as to contain various selections of these abstractive
elements. It is this differentiation of the elements which
constitutes their differentiation of position. An ab-
stractive element which belongs to a punct has the
simplest type of position in M, an abstractive element
which belongs to a rect but not to a punct has a more
complex quality of position, an abstractive element
which belongs to a level and not to a rect has a still
more complex quality of position, and finally the most
complex quality of position belongs to an abstractive
element which belongs to a volume and not to a level.
A volume however has not yet been defined. This
definition will be given in the next lecture.
Evidently levels, rects, and puncts in their capacity
as infinite aggregates cannot be the termini of sense-
awareness, nor can they be limits which are approxi-
mated to in sense-awareness. Any one member of a
level has a certain quality arising from its character as
also belonging to a certain set of moments, but the level
as a whole is a mere logical notion without any route of
approximation along entities posited in sense-awareness.
On the other hand an event-particle is defined so as
IV] METHOD OF EXTENSIVE ABSTRACTION 93
to exhibit this character of being a route of approxi-
mation marked out by entities posited in sense-aware-
ness. A definite event-particle is defined in reference
to a definite punct in the foUov^ing manner: Let the
condition a mean the property of covering all the
abstractive elements which are members of that punct ;
so that an abstractive set which satisfies the condition a
is an abstractive set which covers every abstractive
element belonging to the punct. Then the definition
of the event-particle associated with the punct is that
it is the group of all the cr-primes, where a has this
particular meaning.
It is evident that — ^with this meaning of and E lie on
opposite sides of B respectively. By the aid of these
two axioms the theory of congruence can be extended
so as to compare lengths of segments on any two rects.
Accordingly Euclidean metrical geometry in space is
completely established and lengths in the spaces of
different time-systems are comparable as the result of
definite properties of nature which indicate just that
particular method of comparison.
The comparison of time-measurements in diverse
time-systems requires two other axioms. The first of
these axioms, forming the fifth axiom of congruence,
will be called the axiom of * kinetic symmetry.' It
expresses the symmetry of the quantitative relations
between two time-systems when the times and lengths
in the two systems are measured in congruent units.
The axiom can be explained as follows : Let a and ^
be the names of two time-systems. The directions of
motion in the space of a due to rest in a point of ^ is
called the * j8-direction in a ' and the direction of motion
in the space of j8 due to rest in a point of a is called the
* a -direction in j8.' Consider a motion in the space of
a consisting of a certain velocity in the jS -direction of a
and a certain velocity at right-angles to it. This motion
represents rest in the space of another time-system —
W.N. 9
130 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch.
call it TT . Rest in tt will also be represented in the space
of )S by a certain velocity in the a -direction in /S and a
certain velocity at right-angles to this « -direction. Thus
a certain motion in the space of a is correlated to a
certain motion in the space of j8, as both representing
the same fact which can also be represented by rest in
TT. Now another time-system, which I will name or,
can be found which is such that rest in its space is
represented by the same magnitudes of velocities
along and perpendicular to the a -direction in j3 as those
velocities in a, along and perpendicular to the j8 -direc-
tion, which represent rest in tt. The required axiom of
kinetic symmetry is that rest in a will be represented in
a by the same velocities along and perpendicular to
the j3 -direction in a as those velocities in /3 along and
perpendicular to the a -direction which represent rest
in TT.
A particular case of this axiom is that relative velocities
are equal and opposite. Namely rest in a is represented
in j3 by a velocity along the a -direction which is equal
to the velocity along the ^S -direction in a which repre-
sents rest in j3.
Finally the sixth axiom of congruence is that the
relation of congruence is transitive. So far as this
axiom applies to space, it is superfluous. For the
property follows from our previous axioms. It is
however necessary for time as a supplement to the axiom
of kinetic symmetry. The meaning of the axiom is that
if the time-unit of system a is congruent to the time-
unit of system ^, and the time-unit of system ^ is
congruent to the time-unit of system y, then the time-
units of a and y are also congruent.
By means of these axioms formulae for the trans-
VI] CONGRUENCE 131
formation of measurements made in one time-system
to measurements of the same facts of nature made in
another time-system can be deduced. These formulae
will be found to involve one arbitrary constant vy^hich
I v^ill call k.
It is of the dimensions of the square of a velocity.
Accordingly four cases arise. In the first case k is
zero. This case produces nonsensical results in opposi-
tion to the elementary deliverances of experience. We
put this case aside.
In the second case k is infinite. This case yields the
ordinary formulae for transformation in relative motion,
namely those formulae v^hich are to be found in every
elementary book on dynamics.
In the third case, k is negative. Let us call it — c^,
where c will be of the dimensions of a velocity. This
case yields the formulae of transformation which
Larmor discovered for the transformation of Maxwell's
equations of the electromagnetic field. These formulae
were extended by H. A. Lorentz, and used by Einstein
and Minkowski as the basis of their novel theory of
relativity. I am not now speaking of Einstein's more
recent theory of general relativity by which he deduces
his modification of the law of gravitation. If this be the
case which applies to nature, then c must be a close
approximation to the velocity of light in vacuo. Perhaps
it is this actual velocity. In this connexion ^in vacuo'
must not mean an absence of events, namely the absence
of the all-pervading ether of events. It must mean the
absence of certain types of objects.
In the fourth case, k is positive. Let us call it A^,
where A will be of the dimensions of a velocity. This gives
a perfectly possible type of transformation formulae,
9—2
132 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch.
but not one which explains any facts of experience.
It has also another disadvantage. With the assumption
of this fourth case the distinction between space and
time becomes unduly blurred. The whole object of
these lectures has been to enforce the doctrine that
space and time spring from a common root, and that
the ultimate fact of experience is a space-time fact. But
after all mankind does distinguish very sharply between
space and time, and it is owing to this sharpness of
distinction that the doctrine of these lectures is some-
what of a paradox. Now in the third assumption this
sharpness of distinction is adequately preserved. There
is a fundamental distinction between the metrical pro-
perties of point-tracks and rects. But in the fourth
assumption this fundamental distinction vanishes.
Neither the third nor the fourth assumption can
agree with experience unless we assume that the
velocity c of the third assumption, and the velocity h
of the fourth assumption, are extremely large compared
to the velocities of ordinary experience. If this be the
case the formulae of both assumptions will obviously
reduce to a close approximation to the formulae of the
second assumption which are the ordinary formulae of
dynamical textbooks. For the sake of a name, I will
call these textbook formulae the * orthodox' formulae.
There can be no question as to the general approxi-
mate correctness of the orthodox formulae. It would be
merely silly to raise doubts on this point. But the
determination of the status of these formulae is by no
means settled by this admission. The independence
of time and space is an unquestioned presupposition
of the orthodox thought which has produced the ortho-
dox formulae. With this presupposition and given the
VI] CONGRUENCE 133
absolute points of one absolute space, the orthodox
formulae are immediate deductions. Accordingly,
these formulae are presented to our imaginations as
facts which cannot be otherwise, time and space being
what they are. The orthodox formulae have therefore
attained to the status of necessities which cannot be
questioned in science. Any attempt to replace these
formulae by others was to abandon the rdle of physical
explanation and to have recourse to mere mathematical
formulae.
But even in physical science difficulties have accumu-
lated round the orthodox formulae. In the first place
Maxwell's equations of the electromagnetic field are
not invariant for the transformations of the orthodox
formulae; whereas they are invariant for the trans-
formations of the formulae arising from the third of the
four cases mentioned above, provided that the velocity c
is identified with a famous electromagnetic constant
quantity.
Again the null results of the delicate experiments
to detect the earth's variations of motion through the
ether in its orbital path are explained immediately by
the formulae of the third case. But if we assume the
orthodox formulae we have to make a special and ar-
bitrary assumption as to the contraction of matter during
motion. I mean the Fitzgerald-Lorentz assumption.
Lastly Fresnel's coefficient of drag which represents
the variation of the velocity of light in a moving medium
is explained by the formulae of the third case, and
requires another arbitrary assumption if we use the
orthodox formulae.
It appears therefore that on the mere basis of
physical explanation there are advantages in the formulae
134 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch.
of the third case as compared with the orthodox for-
mulae. But the way is blocked by the ingrained belief
that these latter formulae possess a character of necessity.
It is therefore an urgent requisite for physical science
and for philosophy to examine critically the grounds
for this supposed necessity. The only satisfactory
method of scrutiny is to recur to the first principles of
our knowledge of nature. This is exactly what I am
endeavouring to do in these lectures. I ask what it is
that we are aware of in our sense-perception of nature.
I then proceed to examine those factors in nature which
lead us to conceive nature as occupying space and
persisting through time. This procedure has led us to
an investigation of the characters of space and time. It
results from these investigations that the formulae of
the third case and the orthodox formulae are on a level
as possible formulae resulting from the basic character
of our knowledge of nature. The orthodox formulae
have thus lost any advantage as to necessity which they
enjoyed over the serial group. The way is thus open to
adopt whichever of the two groups best accords with
observation.
I take this opportunity of pausing for a moment from
the course of my argument, and of reflecting on the
general character which my doctrine ascribes to some
familiar concepts of science. I have no doubt that some
of you have felt that in certain aspects this character
is very paradoxical.
This vein of paradox is partly due to the fact that
educated language has been made to conform to the
prevalent orthodox theory. We are thus, in expounding
an alternative doctrine, driven to the use of either strange
terms or of familiar words with unusual meanings. This
VI] CONGRUENCE 135
victory of the orthodox theory over language is very /JjP
natural. Events are named after the prominent objects
situated in them, and thus both in language and in
thought the event sinks behind the object, and becomes
the mere play of its relations. The theory of space is
then converted into a theory of the relations of objects
instead of a theory of the relations of events. But objects
have not the passage of events. Accordingly space as a
relation between objects is devoid of any connexion
with time. It is space at an instant without any deter-
minate relations between the spaces at successive in-
stants. It cannot be one timeless space because the
relations between objects change.
A few minutes ago in speaking of the deduction of
the orthodox formulae for relative motion I said that
they followed as an immediate deduction from the
assumption of absolute points in absolute space. This
reference to absolute space was not an oversight. I know
that the doctrine of the relativity of space at present
holds the field both in science and philosophy. But
I do not think that its inevitable consequences are
understood. When we really face them the paradox of
the presentation of the character of space which I have
elaborated is greatly mitigated. If there is no absolute
position, a point must cease to be a simple entity. What
is a point to one man in a balloon with his eyes fixed on
an instrument is a track of points to an observer on the
earth who is watching the balloon through a telescope,
and is another track of points to an observer in the sun
who is watching the balloon through some instrument
suited to such a being. Accordingly if I am reproached
with the paradox of my theory of points as classes of
event-particles, and of my theory of event-particles as
u'
■A
136 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch.
groups of abstractive sets, I ask my critic to explain
exactly what he means by a point. While you explain
your meaning about anything, however simple, it is
always apt to look subtle and fine spun. I have at least
explained exactly what I do mean by a point, what
relations it involves and what entities are the relata.
If you admit the relativity of space, you also must
admit that points are complex entities, logical constructs
involving other entities and their relations. Produce
your theory, not in a few vague phrases of indefinite
meaning, but explain it step by step in definite terms
referring to assigned relations and assigned relata. Also
show that your theory of points issues in a theory of
space. Furthermore note that the example of the man
in the balloon, the observer on earth, and the observer
in the sun, shows that every assumption of relative rest
requires a timeless space with radically different points
from those which issue from every other such assump-
tion. The theory of the relativity of space is incon-
sistent with any doctrine of one unique set of points of
one timeless space.
The fact is that there is no paradox in my doctrine
of the nature of space which is not in essence inherent
in the theory of the relativity of space. But this doctrine
has never really been accepted in science, whatever
people say. What appears in our dynamical treatises is
Newton's doctrine of relative motion based on the
doctrine of differential motion in absolute space. When
you once admit that the points are radically different
entities for differing assumptions of rest, then the
orthodox formulae lose all their obviousness. They
were only obvious because you were really thinking of
something else. When discussing this topic you can
VI] CONGRUENCE 137
only avoid paradox by taking refuge from the flood of
criticism in the comfortable ark of no meaning.
The nev^ theory provides a definition of the con-
gruence of periods of time. The prevalent viev^ pro-
vides no such definition. Its position is that if we
take such time-measurements so that certain familiar
velocities which seem to us to be uniform are uniform,
then the laws of motion are true. Now in the first place
no change could appear either as uniform or non-
uniform without involving a definite determination of
the congruence for time-periods. So in appealing to
familiar phenomena it allows that there is some
factor in nature which we can intellectually construct
as a congruence theory. It does not however say any-
thing about it except that the laws of motion are then
true. Suppose that with some expositors we cut out
the reference to familiar velocities such as the rate of
rotation of the earth. We are then driven to admit that
there is no meaning in temporal congruence except
that certain assumptions make the laws of motion true.
Such a statement is historically false. King Alfred the
Great was ignorant of the laws of motion, but knew
very well what he meant by the measurement of time,
and achieved his purpose by means of burning candles.
Also no one in past ages justified the use of sand in
hour-glasses by saying that some centuries later in-
teresting laws of motion would be discovered which
would give a meaning to the statement that the sand
was emptied from the bulbs in equal times. Uniformity i
in change is directly perceived, and it follows that
mankind perceives in nature factors from which a theory
of temporal congruence can be formed. The prevalent
theory entirely fails to produce such factors.
138 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch.
The mention of the laws of motion raises another
point where the prevalent theory has nothing to say
and the new theory gives a complete explanation. It is
well known that the laws of motion are not valid for
any axes of reference which you may choose to take
fixed in any rigid body. You must choose a body which
is not rotating and has no acceleration. For example
they do not really apply to axes fixed in the earth
because of the diurnal rotation of that body. The law
which fails when you assume the wrong axes as at rest
is the third law, that action and reaction are equal and
opposite. With the wrong axes uncompensated centri-
fugal forces and uncompensated composite centrifugal
forces appear, due to rotation. The influence of these
forces can be demonstrated by many facts on the earth's
surface, Foucault's pendulum, the shape of the earth,
the fixed directions of the rotations of cyclones and
anticyclones. It is difficult to take seriously the sug-
gestion that these domestic phenomena on the earth
are due to the influence of the fixed stars. I cannot
persuade myself to believe that a little star in its
twinkling turned round Foucault's pendulum in the
Paris Exhibition of 186 1. Of course anything is believ-
able when a definite physical connexion has been
demonstrated, for example the influence of sunspots.
Here all demonstration is lacking in the form of any
coherent theory. According to the theory of these
lectures the axes to which motion is to be referred are
axes at rest in the space of some time-system. For
example, consider the space of a time-system a. There
are sets of axes at rest in the space of a . These are suitable
dynamical axes. Also a set of axes in this space which
is moving with uniform velocity without rotation is
VI] CONGRUENCE 139
another suitable set. All the moving points fixed in
these moving axes are really tracing out parallel lines
with one uniform velocity. In other words they are
the reflections in the space of a of a set of fixed axes in
the space of some other time-system jS. Accordingly
the group of dynamical axes required for Newton's
Laws of Motion is the outcome of the necessity of
referring motion to a body at rest in the space of some
one time-system in order to obtain a coherent account
of physical properties. If we do not do so the meaning
of the motion of one portion of our physical configuration
is different from the meaning of the motion of another
portion of the same configuration. Thus the meaning
of motion being what it is, in order to describe the motion
of any system of objects without changing the meaning
of your terms as you proceed vdth your description,
you are bound to take one of these sets of axes as axes
of reference ; though you may choose their reflections
into the space of any time-system which you wish to
adopt. A definite physical reason is thereby assigned for
the peculiar property of the dynamical group of axes.
On the orthodox theory the position of the equations
of motion is most ambiguous. The space to which they
refer is completely undetermined and so is the measure-
ment of the lapse of time. Science is simply setting out
on a fishing expedition to see whether it cannot find
some procedure which it can call the measurement of
space and some procedure which it can call the measure-
ment of time, and something which it can call a system
of forces, and something which it can call masses, so
that these formulae may be satisfied. The only reason —
on this theory — ^why anyone should want to satisfy
these formulae is a sentimental regard for Galileo,
140 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch.
Newton, Euler and Lagrange. The theory, so far from
founding science on a sound observational basis, forces
everything to conform to a mere mathematical pre-
ference for certain simple formulae.
I do not for a moment believe that this is a true ac-
count of the real status of the Laws of Motion. These
equations want some slight adjustment for the new
formulae of relativity. But with these adjustments,
imperceptible in ordinary use, the laws deal with funda-
mental physical quantities which we know very well
and wish to correlate.
The measurement of time was known to all civilised
nations long before the laws were thought of. It is this
time as thus measured that the laws are concerned with.
Also they deal with the space of our daily life. When we
approach to an accuracy of measurement beyond that
of observation, adjustment is allowable. But within the
limits of observation we know what we mean when we
speak of measurements of space and measurements of
time and uniformity of change. It is for science to give an
intellectual account of what is so evident in sense-aware-
ness. It is to me thoroughly incredible that the ultimate
fact beyond which there is no deeper explanation is that
mankind has really been swayed by an unconscious
desire to satisfy the mathematical formulae which we
call the Laws of Motion, formulae completely unknown
till the seventeenth century of our epoch.
The correlation of the facts of sense-experience
effected by the alternative account of nature extends
beyond the physical properties of motion and the
properties of congruence. It gives an account of the
meaning of the geometrical entities such as points,
straight lines, and volumes, and connects the kindred
VI] CONGRUENCE 141
ideas of extension in time and extension in space. The
theory satisfies the true purpose of an intellectual
explanation in the sphere of natural philosophy. This
purpose is to exhibit the interconnexions of nature, and
to show that one set of ingredients in nature requires
for the exhibition of its character the presence of the
other sets of ingredients.
The false idea which we have to get rid of is that of
nature as a mere aggregate of independent entities, each
capable of isolation. According to this conception these
entities, whose characters are capable of isolated defini-
tion, come together and by their accidental relations
form the system of nature. This system is thus thoroughly
accidental; and, even if it be subject to a mechanical
fate, it is only accidentally so subject.
With this theory space might be without time, and
time might be without space. The theory admittedly
breaks down when we come to the relations of matter
and space. The relational theory of space is an admission
that we cannot know space without matter or matter
without space. But the seclusion of both from time is
still jealously guarded. The relations between portions
of matter in space are accidental facts owing to the
absence of any coherent account of how space springs
from matter or how matter springs from space. Also
what we really observe in nature, its colours and its
sounds and its touches are secondary qualities; in
other words, they are not in nature at all but are acci-
dental products of the relations between nature and
mind.
The explanation of nature which I urge as an alter-
native ideal to this accidental view of nature, is that
nothing in nature could be what it is except as an
142 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch. vi
ingredient in nature as it is. The whole which is present
for discrimination is posited in sense-awareness as
necessary for the discriminated parts. An isolated event
is not an event, because every event is a factor in a
larger whole and is significant of that whole. There can
be no time apart from space ; and no space apart from
time ; and no space and no time apart from the passage
of the events of nature. The isolation of an entity in
thought, when we think of it as a bare *it,' has no
counterpart in any corresponding isolation in nature.
Such isolation is merely part of the procedure of intel-
lectual knowledge.
The laws of nature are the outcome of the characters
of the entities which we find in nature. The entities
being what they are, the laws must be what they are;
and conversely the entities follow from the laws. We
are a long way from the attainment of such an ideal;
but it remains as the abiding goal of theoretical science.
CHAPTER VII
OBJECTS
The ensuing lecture is concerned with the theory of
objects. Objects are e lements in nature which do not
p ass. The awareness of an object as some factor not
sharing in the passage of nature is what I call *recogni-|
tion.' Itis^i npossible J:o recognise an^event^ because
an event is essentially distinct from every o ther even t.
Recognition is an awareness of samenessj But to call
recognition an awareness of sameness implies an in-
tellectual act of comparison accompanied with judgment.
I use recognition for the non-intellectual relation of
sense-awareness which connects the mind with a factor
of nature without passage. On the intellectual side of
the mind's experience there are comparisons of things
recognised and consequent judgments of sameness or
diversity. Probably * sense-recognition ' would be a
better term for what I mean by * recognition.' I have
chosen the simpler term because I think that I shall be
able to avoid the use of * recognition ' in any other
meaning than that of * sense-recognition.' I am quite
willing to believe that recognition, in my sense of the
term, is merely an ideal limit, and that there is in fact
no recognition without intellectual accompaniments of
comparison and judgment. But recognition is that
relation of the mind to nature which provides the
material for the intellectual activity.
An object is an ingredient in the character of some
event. In fact the character of an event is nothing but
the objects which are ingredient in it and the ways in
144 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch.
(which those objects make their ingression into the
event. Thus the theory of objects is the theory of the
comparison of events. Events are only comparable
because they body forth permanences. We are com-
paring objects in events whenever we can say, * There
it is again.' Objects are the elements in nature which
can *be again.'
Sometimes permanences can be proved to exist
which evade recognition in the sense in which I am
using that term. The permanences which evade recogni-
tion appear to us as abstract properties either of events
or of objects. All the same they are there for recognition
although undiscriminated in our sense-awareness. The
demarcation of events, the splitting of nature up into
parts is effected by the objects which we recognise as
their ingredients. The discrimination of nature is the
recognition of objects amid passing events. It is a
compound of the awareness of the passage of nature,
of the consequent partition of nature, and of the defini-
tion of certain parts of nature by the modes of the
ingression of objects into them.
You may have noticed that I am using the term
* ingression' to denote the general relation of objects
to events. The ingression of an object into an event is
the way the character of the event shapes itself in virtue
of the being of the object. Namely the event is what it
is, because the object is what it is ; and when I am thinking
of this modification of the event by the object, I call
the relation between the two *the ingression of the
object into the event.' It is equally true to say that
objects are what they are because events are what they
iare. Nature is such that there can be no events and no
objects without the ingression of objects into events.
VII] OBJECTS 145
Although there are events such that the ingredient!
objects evade our recognition. These are the events in(
empty space. Such events are only analysed for us by]|
the intellectual probing of science.
Ingression is a relation vv^hich has various modes.
There are obviously very various kinds of objects;
and no one kind of object can have the same sort of
relations to events as objects of another kind can have.
We shall have to analyse out some of the different
modes of ingression w^hich different kinds of objects
have into events.
But even if wt stick to one and the same kind of
objects, an object of that kind has different modes of
ingression into different events. Science and philo-
sophy have been apt to entangle themselves in a simple-
minded theory that an object is at one place at any definite
time, and is in no sense anyvs^here else. This is in fact
the attitude of common sense thought, thou gh it is no t
the attitud e of lang ua ge vv^hich is naively expressing the
facts oFexperience . Every other sentence in a w^ork of
literature which is endeavouring truly to interpret the
facts of experience expresses differences in surrounding
events due to the presence of some object. An object
is ingredient throughout its neighbourhood, and its
neighbourhood is indefinite. Also the modification of
events by ingression is susceptible of quantitative
differences. Finally therefore we are driven to admit /
that each object is in some sense ingredient throughout I
nature; though its ingression may be quantitatively '
irrelevant in the expression of our individual experi-
ences.
This admission is not new either in philosophy or
science. It is obviously a necessary axiom for those
W.N. 10
146 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch.
philosophers who insist that reahty is a system. In
these lectures we are keeping off the profound and
vexed question as to what we mean by *reaUty.' I am
maintaining the humbler thesis that nature is a system.
But I suppose that in this case the less follows from
the greater, and that I may claim the support of these
philosophers. The same doctrine is essentially interwoven
in all modern physical speculation. As long ago as 1847
Faraday in a paper in the Philosophical Magazine
remarked that his theory of tubes of force im.plies that
in a sense an electric charge is everywhere. The modi-
fication of the electromagnetic field at every point of
space at each instant owing to the past history of each
electron is another way of stating the same fact. We
can however illustrate the doctrine by the more familiar
facts of life without recourse to the abstruse speculations
of theoretical physics.
The waves as they roll on to the Cornish coast tell
of a gale in mid-Atlantic ; and our dinner witnesses to
the-ingression of the cook into the dining room. It is
' evident that the ingression of objects into events in-
cludes the theory of causation. I prefer to neglect this
aspect of ingression, because causation raises the
memory of discussions based upon theories of nature
which are alien to my own. Also I think that some new
light may be thrown on the subject by viewing it in
this fresh aspect.
The examples which I have given of the ingression
of objects into events remind us that ingression takes
a peculiar form in the case of some events; in a sense,
it is a more concentrated form. For example, the electron
has a certain position in space and a certain shape.
Perhaps it is an extremely small sphere in a certain
VII] OBJECTS 147
test-tube. The storm is a gale situated in mid- Atlantic
with a certain latitude and longitude, and the cook is in
the kitchen. I will call this special form of ingression
the 'relation of situation'; also, by a double use of the
word * situation,' I will call the event in which an object
is situated * the situation of the object.' Thus a situation
is an event which is a relatum in the relation of situation.
Now our first impression is that at last we have come to
the simple plain fact of where the object really is ; and
that the vaguer relation which I call ingression should
not be muddled up with the relation of situation, as if
including it as a particular case. It seems so obvious
that any object is in such and such a position, and that
it is influencing other events in a totally different sense.
Namely, in a sense an object is the character of the
event which is its situation, but it onlv influences the
character of other events. Accordingly the relations of
situation and influencing are not generally the same sort
of relation, and should not be subsumed under the same
term ' ingression.' I believe that this notion is a mistake,
and that it is impossible to draw a clear distinction
between the two relations.
For example. Where was your toothache? You went
to a dentist and pointed out the tooth to him. He pro-
nounced it perfectly sound, and cured you by stopping
another tooth. Which tooth was the situation of the
toothache? Again, a man has an arm amputated, and
experiences sensations in the hand which he has lost.
The situation of the imaginary hand is in fact merely
thin air. You look into a mirror and see a fire. The flames
that you see are situated behind the mirror. Again at
night you watch the sky ; if some of the stars had vanished
from existence hours ago, you would not be any the
10 — 2
148 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch.
wiser. Even the situations of the planets differ from
those which science would assign to them.
Anyhow you are tempted to exclaim, the cook is in
the kitchen. If you mean her mind, I will not agree
with you on the point; for I am only talking of nature.
Let us think only of her bodily presence. What do you
mean by this notion? We confine ourselves to typical
manifestations of it. You can see her, touch her, and
hear her. But the examples which I have given you
show that the notions of the situations of what you see,
what you touch, and what you hear are not so sharply
separated out as to defy further questioning. You
cannot cling to the idea that we have two sets of ex-
periences of nature, one of primary qualities which
belong to the objects perceived, and one of secondary
qualities which are the products of our mental excite-
ments. All we know of nature is in the same boat, to
sink or swim together. The constructions of science
are merely expositions of the characters of things per-
ceived. Accordingly to affirm that the cook is a certain
dance of molecules and electrons is merely to affirm
that the things about her which are perceivable have
certain characters. The situations of the perceived
manifestations of her bodily presence have only a very
general relation to the situations of the molecules, to
be determined by discussion of the circumstances of
perception.
In discussing the relations of situation in particular
and of ingression in general, the first requisite is to note
that objects are of radically different types. For each
type ' situation ' and ' ingression ' have their own special
meanings which are different from their meanings for
other types, though connexions can be pointed out.
VII] OBJECTS 149
It is necessary therefore in discussing them to deter-
mine what type of objects are under consideration.
There are, I think, an indefinite number of types of
objects. Happily we need not think of them all. The )
idea of situation has its peculiar importance in reference
to three types of objects which I call sense-objects,
perceptual objects and scientific objects. The suitability
of these names for the three types is of minor import-
ance, so long as I can succeed in explaining what I mean
by them.
These three types form an ascending hierarchy, of
which each member presupposes the type below. Thel
base of the hierarchy is formed by the sense-objects.
These objects do not presuppose any other type of
objects. A sense-object is a factor of nature posited |
by sense-awareness which (i), in that it is an object, does I
not share in the passage of nature and (ii) is not a J
relation between other factors of nature. It will of
course be a relatum in relations which also implicate
other factors of nature. But it is always a relatum and
never the relation itself. Examples of sense-objects are
a particular sort of colour, say Cambridge blue, or a
particular sort of sound, or a particular sort of smell,
or a particular sort of feeling. I am not talking of a
particular patch of blue as seen during a particular
second of time at a definite date. Such a patch is an
event where Cambridge blue is situated. Similarly I am
not talking of any particular concert-room as filled with
the note. I mean the note itself and not the patch of
volume filled by the sound for a tenth of a second. It is
natural for us to think of the note in itself, but in the
case of colour we are apt to think of it merely as a
property of the patch. No one thinks of the note as a
150 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch.
property of the concert-room. We see the blue and we
hear the note. Both the blue and the note are im-
mediately posited by the discrimination of sense-aware-
ness which relates the mind to nature. The blue is
posited as in nature related to other factors in nature.
In particular it is posited as in the relation of being
situated in the event which is its situation.
The difficulties which cluster around the relation of
situation arise from the obstinate refusal of philosophers
to take seriously the ultimate fact of multiple relations.
By a multiple relation I mean a relation which in any
concrete instance of its occurrence necessarily involves
more than two relata. For example, when John likes
Thomas there are only two relata, John and Thomas.
But when John gives that book to Thomas there are
three relata, John, that book, and Thomas.
Some schools of philosophy, under the influence of
the Aristotelian logic and the Aristotelian philosophy,
endeavour to get on without admitting any relations at
all except that of substance and attribute. Namely all
apparent relations are to be resolvable into the con-
current existence of substances with contrasted at-
tributes. It is fairly obvious that the Leibnizian monad-
ology is the necessary outcome of any such philosophy.
If you dislike pluralism, there will be only one monad.
Other schools of philosophy admit relations but
obstinately refuse to contemplate relations with more
than two relata. I do not think that this limitation is
based on any set purpose or theory. It merely arises
from the fact that more complicated relations are a
bother to people without adequate mathematical training,
when they are admitted into the reasoning.
I must repeat that we have nothing to do in these
VII] OBJECTS 151
lectures with the ultimate character of reality. It is
quite possible that in the true philosophy of reality
there are only individual substances with attributes,
or that there are only relations with pairs of relata. I do
not believe that such is the case ; but I am not concerned
to argue about it now. Our theme is Nature. So long
as we confine ourselves to the factors posited in the
sense-awareness of nature, it seems to me that there
certainly are instances of multiple relations between
these factors, and that the relation of situation for sense-
objects is one example of such multiple relations.
Consider a blue coat, a flannel coat of Cambridge
blue belonging to some athlete. The coat itself is a
perceptual object and its situation is not what I am
talking about. We are talking of someone's definite
sense-awareness of Cambridge blue as situated in some
event of nature. He may be looking at the coat directly.
He then sees Cambridge blue as situated practically in the
same event as the coat at that instant. It is true that the
blue which he sees is due to light which left the coat
some inconceivably small fraction of a second before.
This diflFerence would be important if he were looking at
a starwhosecolourwas Cambridge blue. The star might
have ceased to exist days ago, or even years ago. The
situation of the blue will not then be very intimately
connected with the situation (in another sense of
* situation ') of any perceptual object. This disconnexion
of the situation of the blue and the situation of some
associated perceptual object does not require a star for
its exemplification. Any looking glass will suffice. Look
at the coat through a looking glass. Then blue is seen
as situated behind the mirror. The event which is its
situation depends upon the position of the observer.
152 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch.
The sense-awareness of the blue as situated in a
certain event which I call the situation, is thus ex-
hibited as the sense-awareness of a relation between the
blue, the percipient event of the observer, the situation,
and intervening events. All nature is in fact required,
though only certain intervening events require their
characters to be of certain definite sorts. The ingression
of blue into the events of nature is thus exhibited as
systematically correlated. The awareness of the observer
depends on the position of the percipient event in this
systematic correlation. I will use the term 'ingression
into nature ' for this systematic correlation of the blue
with nature. Thus the ingression of blue into any definite
event is a part statement of the fact of the ingression
of blue into nature.
In respect to the ingression of blue into nature events
may be roughly put into four classes which overlap and
are not very clearly separated. These classes are (i) the
percipient events, (ii) the situations, (iii) the active
conditioning events, (iv) the passive conditioning events.
To understand this classification of events in the general
fact of the ingression of blue into nature, let us confine
attention to one situation for one percipient event and
to the consequent roles of the conditioning events for
the ingression as thus limited. The percipient event is
the relevant bodily state of the observer. The situation
is where he sees the blue, say, behind the mirror. The
active conditioning events are the events whose charac-
ters are particularly relevant for the event (which is the
situation) to be the situation for that percipient event,
namely the coat, the mirror, and the state of the room
as to light and atmosphere. The passive conditioning
events are the events of the rest of nature.
VII] OBJECTS 153
In general the situation is an active conditioning
event; namely the coat itself, when there is no mirror
or other such contrivance to produce abnormal effects.
But the example of the mirror shows us that the situation
may be one of the passive conditioning events. We are
then apt to say that our senses have been cheated,
because we demand as a right that the situation should
be an active condition in the ingression.
This demand is not so baseless as it may seem when
presented as I have put it. All we know of the characters
of the events of nature is based on the analysis of the
relations of situations to percipient events. If situations
were not in general active conditions, this analysis
would tell us nothing. Nature would be an unfathom-
able enigma to us and there could be no science. Ac-
cordingly the incipient discontent when a situation is
found to be a passive condition is in a sense justifiable ;
because if that sort of thing went on too often, the rdle
of the intellect would be ended.
Furthermore the mirror is itself the situation of other
sense-objects either for the same observer with the
same percipient event, or for other observers with
other percipient events. Thus the fact that an event is a
situation in the ingression of one set of sense-objects
into nature is presumptive evidence that that event is
an active condition in the ingression of other sense-
objects into nature which may have other situations.
This is a fundamental principle of science which it has
derived from common sense.
I now turn to perceptual objects. When we look at
the coat, we do not in general say. There is a patch of
Cambridge blue ; what naturally occurs to us is, There
is a coat. Also the judgment that what we have seen is
154 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch
a garment of man's attire is a detail. What we perceive
is an object other than a mere sense-object. It is not a
mere patch of colour, but something more; and it is
that something more which we judge to be a coat. I
will use the word *coat' as the name for that crude
object which is more than a patch of colour, and without
any allusion to the judgments as to its usefulness as an
» article of attire either in the past or the future. The coat
which is perceived — in this sense of the word ' coat * —
is what I call a perceptual object. We have to investigate
the general character of these perceptual objects.
It is a law of nature that in general the situation of a
sense-object is not only the situation of that sense-
object for one definite percipient event, but is the
situation of a variety of sense-objects for a variety of
percipient events. For example, for any one percipient
event, the situation of a sense-object of sight is apt also
to be the situations of sense-objects of sight, of touch,
of smell, and of sound. Furthermore this concurrence
in the situations of sense-objects has led to the body —
i£, the percipient event — so adapting itself that the
perception of one sense-object in a certain situation
leads to a subconscious sense-awareness of other sense-
objects in the same situation. This interplay is especially
the case between touch and sight. There is a certain
correlation between the ingressions of sense-objects
of touch and sense-objects of sight into nature, and in a
slighter degree between the ingressions of other pairs
of sense-objects. I call this sort of correlation the * con-
veyance' of one sense-object by another. When you
see the blue flannel coat you subconsciously feel yourself
wearing it or otherwise touching it. If you are a
smoker, you may also subconsciously be aware of the
VII] OBJECTS 155
faint aroma of tobacco. The peculiar fact, posited by
this sense-awareness of the concurrence of subconscious
sense-objects along with one or more dominating sense-
objects in the same situation, is the sense-awareness of
the perceptual object. The perceptual object is not 1
primarily the issue of a judgment. It is a factor of nature j u-fi
directly posited in sense-awareness. The element of L, -- —
judgment comes in when we proceed to classify thej;^
particular perceptual object. For example, we say, -
That is flannel, and we think of the properties of flannel
and the uses of athletes' coats. But that all takes place
after we have got hold of the perceptual object. Anti-
cipatory judgments affect the perceptual object per-
ceived by focussing and diverting attention.
The perceptual object is the outcome of the habit of
experience. Anything which conflicts with this habit
hinders the sense-awareness of such an object. A sense-
object is not the product of the association of intellectual
ideas ; it is the product of the association of sense-objects
in the same situation. This outcome is not intellectual;
it is an object of peculiar type with its own particular
ingression into nature.
There are two kinds of perceptual objects, namely,
'delusive perceptual objects' and * physical objects.'
The situation of a delusive perceptual object is a
passive condition in the ingression of that object into
nature. Also the event which is the situation will have
the relation of situation to the object only for one
particular percipient event. For example, an observer
sees the image of the blue coat in a mirror. It is a blue
coat that he sees and not a mere patch of colour. This
shows that the active conditions for the conveyance
of a group of subconscious sense-objects by a dominating
,^^^^
156 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [CH.
sense-object are to be found in the percipient event.
Namely we are to look for them in the investigations
of medical psychologists. The ingression into nature of
the delusive sense-object is conditioned by the adapta-
tion of bodily events to the more normal occurrence,
which is the ingression of the physical object.
A perceptual object is a physical object when (i) its
situation is an active conditioning event for the in-
gression of any of its component sense-objects, and
(ii) the same event can be the situation of the perceptual
object for an indefinite number of possible percipient
events. Physical objects are the ordinary objects which
we perceive when our senses are not cheated, such as
chairs, tables and trees. In a way physical objects have
more insistent perceptive power than sense-objects.
Attention to the fact of their occurrence in nature is the
first condition for the survival of complex living or-
ganisms. The result of this high perceptive power of
physical objects is the scholastic philosophy of nature
which looks on the sense-objects as mere attributes of
the physical objects. This scholastic point of view is
directly contradicted by the wealth of sense-objects
which enter into our experience as situated in events
without any connexion with physical objects. For
example, stray smells, sounds, colours and more subtle
nameless sense-objects. There is no perception of
physical objects without perception of sense-objects.
But the converse does not hold: namely, there is
abundant perception of sense-objects unaccompanied
by any perception of physical objects. This lack of
reciprocity in the relations between sense-objects and
physical objects is fatal to the scholastic natural philo-
sophy.
VII] OBJECTS 157
There is a great difference in the rSles of the situa-
tions of sense-objects and physical objects. The situa-
tions of a physical object are conditioned by uniqueness
and continuity. The uniqueness is an ideal limit to
which we approximate as we proceed in thought along
an abstractive set of durations, considering smaller
and smaller durations in the approach to the ideal limit
of the moment of time. In other words, when the
duration is small enough, the situation of the physical
object within that duration is practically unique.
The identification of the same physical object as
being situated in distinct events in distinct durations is
effected by the condition of continuity. This condition
of continuity is the condition that a continuity of passage
of events, each event being a situation of the object in
its corresponding duration, can be found from the earlier
to the later of the two given events. So far as the two
events are practically adjacent in one specious present,
this continuity of passage may be directly perceived.
Otherwise it is a matter of judgment and inference.
The situations of a sense-object are not conditioned
by any such conditions either of uniqueness or of con-
tinuity. In any durations however small a sense-object
may have any number of situations separated from each
other. Thus two situations of a sense-object, either in
the same duration or in different durations, are not
necessarily connected by any continuous passage of
events which are also situations of that sense-object.
The characters of the conditioning events involved in
the ingression of a sense-object into nature can be
largely expressed in terms of the physical objects which
are situated in those events. In one respect this is also
a tautology. For the physical object is nothing else than
158 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch.
the habitual concurrence of a certain set of sense-objects
in one situation. Accordingly when we know all about
the physical object, we thereby know its component
sense-objects. But a physical object is a condition for
the occurrence of sense-objects other than those which
are its components. For example, the atmosphere causes
the events which are its situations to be active con-
ditioning events in the transmission of sound. A mirror
which is itself a physical object is an active condition for
the situation of a patch of colour behind it, due to the
reflection of light in it.
"" Thus the origin of scientific knowledge is the en-
deavour to express in terms of physical objects the
various r6les of events as active conditions in the in-
gression of sense-objects into nature. It is in the progress
of this investigation that scientific objects emerge. They
embody those aspects of the character of the situations
of the physical objects which are most permanent and
are expressible without reference to a multiple relation
including a percipient event. Their relations to each
other are also characterised by a certain simplicity and
uniformity. Finally the characters of the observed
physical objects and sense-objects can be expressed in
terms of these scientific objects. In fact the whole
point of the search for scientific objects is the endeavour
to obtain this simple expression of the characters of
events. These scientific objects are not themselves
merely formulae for calculation ; because formulae must
refer to things in nature, and the scientific objects are
the things in nature to which the formulae refer.
A scientific object such as a definite electron is a
systematic correlation of the characters of all events
throughout all nature. It is an aspect of the systematic
VII] OBJECTS 159
character of nature. The electron is not merely where
its charge is. The charge is the quantitative character
of certain events due to the ingression of the electron
into nature. The electron is its whole field of force.
Namely the electron is the systematic way in which all
events are modified as the expression of its ingression.
The situation of an electron in any small duration may
be defined as that event which has the quantitative
character which is the charge of the electron. We may
if we please term the mere charge the electron. But
then another name is required for the scientific object
which is the full entity which concerns science, and
which I have called the electron.
According to this conception of scientific objects, the
rival theories of action at a distance and action by
transmission through a medium are both incomplete
expressions of the true process of nature. The stream
of events which form the continuous series of situations
of the electron is entirely self-determined, both as
regards having the intrinsic character of being the series
of situations of that electron and as regards the time-
systems with which its various members are cogredient,
and the flux of their positions in their corresponding
durations. This is the foundation of the denial of action
at a distance ; namely the progress of the stream of the
situations of a scientific object can be determined by an
analysis of the stream itself.
On the other hand the ingression of every electron
into nature modifies to some extent the character of
every event. Thus the character of the stream of events
which we are considering bears marks of the existence
of every other electron throughout the universe. If we
like to think of the electrons as being merely what I call
i6o THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch.
their charges, then the charges act at a distance. But
this action consists in the modification of the situation
of the other electron under consideration. This con-
ception of a charge acting at a distance is a wholly
artificial one. The conception which most fully expresses
the character of nature is that of each event as modified
by the ingression of each electron into nature. The ether
is the expression of this systematic modification of events
throughout space and throughout time. The best expres-
sion of the character of this modification is for physicists
to find out. My theory has nothing to do with that and
is ready to accept any outcome of physical research.
The connexion of objects with space requires eluci-
dation. Objects are situated in events. The relation of
situation is a different relation for each type of object,
and in the case of sense-objects it cannot be expressed
as a two-termed relation. It would perhaps be better
to use a different word for these different types of the
relation of situation. It has not however been necessary
to do so for our purposes in these lectures. It must be
understood however that, when situation is spoken of,
some one definite type is under discussion, and it may
happen that the argument may not apply to situation of
another type. In all cases however I use situation to
express a relation between objects and events and not
between objects and abstractive elements. There is a
derivative relation between objects and spatial elements
which I call the relation of location; and when this
relation holds, I say that the object is located in the
abstractive element. In this sense, an object may be
located in a moment of time, in a volume of space, an
area, a line, or a point. There will be a peculiar type of
location corresponding to each type of situation; and
VII] OBJECTS i6i
location is in each case derivative from the corresponding
relation of situation in a v^ay w^hich I v^ill proceed to
explain.
Also location in the timeless space of some time-system
is a relation derivative from location in instantaneous
spaces of the same time-system. Accordingly location
in an instantaneous space is the primary idea w^hich w^e
have to explain. Great confusion has been occasioned
in natural philosophy by the neglect to distinguish be-
tw^een the different types of objects, the different types
of situation, the different types of location, and the
difference betw^een location and situation. It is im-
possible to reason accurately in the vague concerning
objects and their positions vs^ithout keeping these dis-
tinctions in viev^. An object is located in an abstractive
element, when an abstractive set belonging to that ele-
ment can be found such that each event belonging to
that set is a situation of the object. It v^ill be remem-
bered that an abstractive element is a certain group of
abstractive sets, and that each abstractive set is a set
of events. This definition defines the location of an
element in any type of abstractive element. In this
sense v^e can talk of the existence of an object at an
instant, meaning thereby its location in some definite
moment. It may also be located in some spatial element
of the instantaneous space of that moment.
A quantity can be said to be located in an abstractive
element vv^hen an abstractive set belonging to the element
can be found such that the quantitative expressions of
the corresponding characters of its events converge to
the measure of the given quantity as a limit v^hen we
pass along the abstractive set towards its converging
end.
W.N. II
i62 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch.
By these definitions location in elements of instanta-
neous spaces is defined. These elements occupy corre-
sponding elements of timeless spaces. An object located
in an element of an instantaneous space will also be said
to be located at that moment in the timeless element of
the timeless space which is occupied by that instantaneous
element.
It is not every object which can be located in a moment.
An object which can be located in every moment of some
duration will be called a * uniform' object throughout
that duration. Ordinary physical objects appear to us
to be uniform objects, and we habitually assume that
scientific objects such as electrons are uniform. But
some sense-objects certainly are not uniform. A tune
is an example of a non-uniform object. We have per-
ceived it as a whole in a certain duration ; but the tune
as a tune is not at any moment of that duration though
one of the individual notes may be located there.
It is possible therefore that for the existence of
certain sorts of objects, e,g, electrons, minimum quanta
of time are requisite. Some such postulate is apparently
indicated by the modern quantum theory and it is per-
fectly consistent with the doctrine of objects maintained
in these lectures.
Also the instance of the distinction between the
electron as the mere quantitative electric charge of its
situation and the electron as standing for the ingression
of an object throughout nature illustrates the indefinite
number of types of objects which exist in nature. We
can intellectually distinguish even subtler and subtler
types of objects. Here I reckon subtlety as meaning
seclusion from the immediate apprehension of sense-
awareness. Evolution in the complexity of life means an
VII] OBJECTS 163
increase in the types of objects directly sensed. Deli-
cacy of sense-apprehension means perceptions of objects
as distinct entities which are mere subtle ideas to cruder
sensibilities. The phrasing of music is a mere abstract
subtlety to the unmusical; it is a direct sense-appre-
hension to the initiated. For example, if we could
imagine some lowly type of organic being thinking and
aware of our thoughts, it would wonder at the abstract
subtleties in which we indulge as we think of stones
and bricks and drops of water and plants. It only knows
of vague undifferentiated feelings in nature. It would
consider us as given over to the play of excessively
abstract intellects. But then if it could think, it would
anticipate; and if it anticipated, it would soon per-
ceive for itself.
In these lectures we have been scrutinising the
foundations of natural philosophy. We are stopping at
the very point where a boundless ocean of enquiries
opens out for our questioning.
I agree that the view of Nature which I have main-
tained in these lectures is not a simple one. Nature
appears as a complex system whose factors are dimly
discerned by us. But, as I ask you. Is not this the very
truth ? Should we not distrust the jaunty assurance with
which every age prides itself that it at last has hit upon
the ultimate concepts in which all that happens can be
formulated } The aim of science is to seek the simplest
explanations of complex facts. We are apt to fall into
the error of thinking that the facts are simple because
simplicity is the goal of our quest. The guiding motto
in the life of every natural philosopher should be,
Seek simplicity and distr ust it .
— — — ^ — "• — - -1^1 -^ »i ^"^^"^
CHAPTER VIII
SUMMARY
There is a general agreement that Einstein's investiga-
tions have one fundamental merit irrespective of any
criticisms which we may feel inclined to pass on them.
They have made us think. But when we have admitted
so far, we are most of us faced with a distressing per-
plexity. What is it that we ought to think about? The
purport of my lecture this afternoon will be to meet this
difficulty and, so far as I am able, to set in a clear Ught
the changes in the background of our scientific thought
which are necessitated by any acceptance, however
qualified, of Einstein's main positions. I remember that
I am lecturing to the members of a chemical society
who are not for the most part versed in advanced
mathematics. The first point that I would urge upon you
is that what immediately concerns you is not so much
the detailed deductions of the new theory as this general
change in the background of scientific conceptions
which will follow from its acceptance. Of course, the
detailed deductions are important, because unless our
colleagues the astronomers and the physicists find these
predictions to be verified we can neglect the theory
altogether. But we may now take it as granted that in
many striking particulars these deductions have been
found to be in agreement with observation. Accord-
ingly the theory has to be taken seriously and we are
anxious to know what will be the consequences of its
final acceptance. Furthermore during the last few weeks
CH. VIII] SUMMARY 165
the scientific journals and the lay press have been filled
w^ith articles as to the nature of the crucial experiments
which have been made and as to some of the more
striking expressions of the outcome of the new theory.
* Space caught bending' appeared on the news-sheet
of a well-known evening paper. This rendering is a
terse but not inapt translation of Einstein's own way of
interpreting his results. I should say at once that I am
a heretic as to this explanation and that I shall expound
to you another explanation based upon some work of
my own, an explanation which seems to me to be more
in accordance with our scientific ideas and with the
whole body of facts which have to be explained. We
have to remember that a new theory must take account
of the old well-attested facts of science just as much as
of the very latest experimental results which have led
to its production.
To put ourselves in the position to assimilate and to
criticise any change in ultimate scientific conceptions we
must begin at the beginning. So you must bear with me
if I commence by making some simple and obvious
reflections. Let us consider three statements, (i) * Yes-
terday a man was run over on the Chelsea Embankment,'
(ii) * Cleopatra's Needle is on the Charing Cross Em-
bankment,' and (iii) * There are dark lines in the Solar
Spectrum.' The first statement about the accident to
the man is about what we may term an * occurrence,'
a * happening,' or an * event.' I will use the term
* event ' because it is the shortest. In order to specify an
observed event, the place, the time, and character of the
event are necessary. In specifying the place and the time
you are really stating the relation of the assigned event
to the general structure of other observed events. For
i66 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch.
example, the man was run over between your tea and
your dinner and adjacently to a passing barge in the
river and the traffic in the Strand. The point which I
want to make is this: Nature is known to us in our
experience as a complex of passing events. In this
complex we discern definite mutual relations between
component events, which we may call their relative
positions, and these positions we express partly in terms
of space and partly in terms of time. Also in addition
to its mere relative position to other events, each par-
ticular event has its own peculiar character. In other
words, nature is a structure of events and each event
has its position in this structure and its own peculiar
character or quality.
Let us now examine the other two statements in the
light of this general principle as to the meaning of
nature. Take the second statement, * Cleopatra's
Needle is on the Charing Cross Embankment.' At
first sight we should hardly call this an event. It seems
to lack the element of time or transitoriness. But does
it ? If an angel had made the remark some hundreds of
millions of years ago, the earth was not in existence,
twenty millions of years ago there was no Thames,
eighty years ago there was no Thames Embankment,
and when I was a small boy Cleopatra's Needle was
not there. And now that it is there, we none of us expect
it to be eternal. The static timeless element in the rela-
tion of Cleopatra's Needle to the Embankment is a
pure illusion generated by the fact that for purposes of
daily intercourse its emphasis is needless. What it
comes to is this : Amidst the structure of events which
form the medium within which the daily life of Lon-
doners is passed we know how to identify a certain
VIII] SUMMARY 167
stream of events which maintain permanence of charac-
ter, namely the character of being the situations of
Cleopatra's Needle. Day by day and hour by hour we
can find a certain chunk in the transitory life of nature
and of that chunk we say, * There is Cleopatra's Needle/
If we define the Needle in a sufficiently abstract manner
we can say that it never changes. But a physicist who
looks on that part of the life of nature as a dance of
electrons, will tell you that daily it has lost some mole-
cules and gained others, and even the plain man can
see that it gets dirtier and is occasionally washed. Thus
the question of change in the Needle is a mere matter of
definition. The more abstract your definition, the more
permanent the Needle. But whether your Needle change
or be permanent, all you mean by stating that it is
situated on the Charing Cross Embankment, is that
amid the structure of events you know of a certain con-
tinuous limited stream of events, such that any chunk
of that stream, during any hour, or any day, or any
second, has the character of being the situation of
Cleopatra's Needle.
Finally, we come to the third statement, * There are
dark lines in the Solar Spectrum.' This is a law of nature.
But what does that mean ? It means merely this. If any
event has the character of being an exhibition of the
solar spectrum under certain assigned circumstances, it
will also have the character of exhibiting dark lines in
that spectrum.
This long discussion brings us to the final conclusion
that the concrete facts of nature are events exhibiting
a certain structure in their mutual relations and certain
characters of their own. The aim of science is to express
the relations between their characters in terms of the
i68 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch.
mutual structural relations between the events thus
characterised. The mutual structural relations between
events are both spatial and temporal. If you think of
them as merely spatial you are omitting the temporal
element, and if you think of them as merely temporal
you are omitting the spatial element. Thus when you
think of space alone, or of time alone, you are dealing
in abstractions, namely, you are leaving out an essential
element in the life of nature as known to you in the
experience of your senses. Furthermore there are
different ways of making these abstractions which we
think of as space and as time ; and under some circum-
stances we adopt one way and under other circumstances
we adopt another way. Thus there is no paradox in
holding that what we mean by space under one set of
circumstances is not what we mean by space under
another set of circumstances. And equally what we
mean by time under one set of circumstances is not
what we mean by time under another set of circum-
stances. By saying that space and time are abstractions,
I do not mean that they do not express for us real facts
about nature. What I mean is that there are no spatial
facts or temporal facts apart from physical nature,
namely that space and time are merely ways of expressing
certain truths about the relations between events. Also
that under different circumstances there are different
sets of truths about the universe which are naturally
presented to us as statements about space. In such a
case what a being under the one set of circumstances
means by space will be different from that meant by a
being under the other set of circumstances. Accord-
ingly when we are comparing two observations made
under different circumstances we have to ask ' Do the
VIII] SUMMARY 169^
two observers mean the same thing by space and the
same thing by time ? ' The modern theory of relativity
has arisen because certain perplexities as to the con-
cordance of certain delicate observations such as the
motion of the earth through the ether, the perihelion
of mercury, and the positions of the stars in the neigh-
bourhood of the sun, have been solved by reference to
this purely relative significance of space and time.
I want now to recall your attention to Cleopatra^s
Needle, which I have not yet done with. As you are
walking along the Embankment you suddenly look up
and say, 'Hullo, there's the Needle.' In other words,
you recognise it. You cannot recognise an event;
because when it is gone, it is gone. You may observe
another event of analogous character, but the actual
chunk of the life of nature is inseparable from its unique
occurrence. But a character of an event can be recog-
nised. We all know that if we go to the Embankment
near Charing Cross we shall observe an event having the
character which we recognise as Cleopatra's Needle.
Things which we thus recognise I call objects. An
object is situated in those events or in that stream of
events of which it expresses the character. There are
many sorts of objects. For example, the colour green
is an object according to the above definition. It is the
purpose of science to trace the laws which govern the
appearance of objects in the various events in which they
are found to be situated. For this purpose we can
mainly concentrate on two types of objects, which I will
call material physical objects and scientific objects.
A material physical object is an ordinary bit of matter,
Cleopatra's Needle for example. This is a much more
complicated type of object than a mere colour, such as
I70 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch.
the colour of the Needle. I call these simple objects,
such as colours or sounds, sense-objects. An artist
will train himself to attend more particularly to sense-
objects where the ordinary person attends normally to
material objects. Thus if you were walking with an
artist, when you said * There's Cleopatra's Needle,'
perhaps he simultaneously exclaimed 'There's a nice
bit of colour.' Yet you were both expressing your
recognition of different component characters of the
same event. But in science we have found out that
when we know all about the adventures amid events of
material physical objects and of scientific objects we
have most of the relevant information which will enable
us to predict the conditions under which we shall
perceive sense-objects in specific situations. For ex-
ample, when we know that there is a blazing fire (i.e.
material and scientific objects undergoing various
exciting adventures amid events) and opposite to it a
mirror (which is another material object) and the
positions of a man's face and eyes gazing into the mirror,
we know that he can perceive the redness of the flame
situated in an event behind the mirror — thus, to a large
extent, the appearance of sense-objects is conditioned
by the adventures of material objects. The analysis of
these adventures makes us aware of another character
of events, namely their characters as fields of activity
which determine the subsequent events to which they
will pass on the objects situated in them. We express
these fields of activity in terms of gravitational, electro-
magnetic, or chemical forces and attractions. But the
exact expression of the nature of these fields of activity
forces us intellectually to acknowledge a less obvious
type of objects as situated in events. I mean molecules
VIII] SUMMARY 17:
and electrons. These objects are not recognised in
isolation. We cannot well miss Cleopatra's Needle, if
we are in its neighbourhood ; but no one has seen a single
molecule or a single electron, yet the characters of
events are only explicable to us by expressing them in
terms of these scientific objects . Undoubtedly molecules
and electrons are abstractions. But then so is Cleo-
patra's Needle. The concrete facts are the events them-
selves — I have already explained to you that to be an
abstraction does not mean that an entity is nothing. It
merely means that its existence is only one factor of a
Inore concrete element of nature. So an electron is
abstra ct because you cannot wipe out the whole structure
of events and yet retain the electron in existence. In
the same way the grin on the cat is abstract; and the
molecule is really in the event in the same sense as the
grin is really on the cat's face. Now the more ultimate
sciences such as Chemistry or Physics cannot express
their ultimate laws in terms of such vague objects as
the sun, the earth, Cleopatra's Needle, or a human
body. Such objects more properly belong to Astro-
nomy, to Geology, to Engineering, to Archaeology,
or to Biology. Chemistry and Physics only deal with
them as exhibiting statistical complexes of the effects
of their more intimate laws. In a certain sense, they
only enter into Physics and Chemistry as technological
applications. The reason is that they are too vague.
Where does Cleopatra's Needle begin and where does
it end.? Is the soot part of it? Is it a different
object when it sheds a molecule or when its surface
enters into chemical combination with the acid of a
London fog? The definiteness and permanence of the
Needle is nothing to the possible permanent definiteness
172 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch.
of a molecule as conceived by science, and the per-
manent definiteness of a molecule in its turn yields to
that of an electron. Thus science in its most ultimate
formulation of law seeks objects with the most per-
manent definite simplicity of character and expresses
its final laws in terms of them.
Again when we seek definitely to express the relations
of events which arise from their spatio-temporal
structure, we approximate to simplicity by progressively
diminishing the extent (both temporal and spatial) of
the events considered. For example, the event which
is the life of the chunk of nature which is the Needle
during one minute has to the life of nature within a
passing barge during the same minute a very complex
spatio-temporal relation. But suppose we progressively
diminish the time considered to a second, to a hun-
dredth of a second, to a thousandth of a second, and
so on. As we pass along such a series we approximate
to an ideal simplicity of structural relations of the pairs
of events successively considered, which ideal we call
the spatial relations of the Needle to the barge at some
instant. Even these relations are too complicated for us,
and we consider smaller and smaller bits of the Needle
and of the barge. Thus we finally reach the ideal of an
event so restricted in its extension as to be without ex-
tension in space or extension in time. Such an event is
a mere spatial point-flash of instantaneous duration.
I call such an ideal event an * event-particle.' You must
not think of the world as ultimately built up of event-
particles. That is to put the cart before the horse. The
world we know is a continuous stream of occurrence
which we can discriminate into finite events forming by
their overlappings and containings of each other and
VIII] SUMMARY 173
separations a spatio-temporal structure. We can express
the properties of this structure in terms of the ideal
limits to routes of approximation, which I have termed
event-particles. Accordingly event-particles are abstrac-
tions in their relations to the more concrete events. But
then by this time you will have comprehended that you
cannot analyse concrete nature without abstracting.
Also I repeat, the abstractions of science are entities
which are truly in nature, though they have no meaning
in isolation from nature.
The character of the spatio-temporal structure of
events can be fully expressed in terms of relations
between these more abstract event-particles. The ad-
vantage of dealing with event-particles is that though
they are abstract and complex in respect to the finite
events which we directly observe, they are simpler
than finite events in respect to their mutual relations.
Accordingly they express for us the demands of an ideal
accuracy, and of an ideal simplicity in the exposition of
relations. These event-particles are the ultimate elements
of the four-dimensional space-time manifold which the
theory of relativity presupposes. You will have observed
that each event-particle is as much an instant of time as
it is a point of space. I have called it an instantaneous
point-flash. Thus in the structure of this space-time
manifold space is not finally discriminated from time,
and the possibility remains open for diverse modes of
discrimination according to the diverse circumstances
of observers. It is this possibility which makes the
fundamental distinction between the new way of con-
ceiving the universe and the old way. The secret of
understanding relativity is to understand this. It is of
no use rushing in with picturesque paradoxes, such as
174 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch.
* Space caught bending,' if you have not mastered this
fundamental conception which underHes the whole
theory. When I say that it underHes the whole theory,
I mean that in my opinion it ought to underlie it, though
I may confess some doubts as to how far all expositions
of the theory have really understood its implications and
its premises.
Our measurements when they are expressed in terms
of an ideal accuracy are measurements which express
properties of the space-time manifold. Now there are
measurements of different sorts. You can measure
lengths, or angles, or areas, or volumes, or times. There
are also other sorts of measures such as measurements
of intensity of illumination, but I will disregard these
for the moment and will confine attention to those
measurements which particularly interest us as being
measurements of space or of time. It is easy to see that
four such measurements of the proper characters are
necessary to determine the position of an event-particle
in the space-time manifold in its relation to the rest of
the manifold. For example, in a rectangular field you
start from one corner at a given time, you measure a
definite distance along one side, you then strike out
into the field at right angles, and then measure a definite
distance parallel to the other pair of sides, you then rise
vertically a definite height and take the time. At the
point and at the time which you thus reach there is
occurring a definite instantaneous point-flash of nature.
In other words, your four measurements have deter-
mined a definite event-particle belonging to the four-
dimension space-time manifold. These measurements
have appeared to be very simple to the land-surveyor
and raise in his mind no philosophic difficulties. But
VIII] SUMMARY 175
suppose there are beings on Mars sufficiently advanced
in scientific invention to be able to watch in detail the
operations of this survey on earth. Suppose that they
construe the operations of the English land-surveyors
in reference to the space natural to a being on Mars,
namely a Martio-centric space in which that planet is
fixed. The earth is moving relatively to Mars and is
rotating. To the beings on Mars the operations, con-
strued in this fashion, effect measurements of the greatest
complication. Furthermore, according to the relati-
vistic doctrine, the operation of time-measurement on
earth will not correspond quite exactly to any time-
measurement on Mars.
I have discussed this example in order to make you
realise that in thinking of the possibilities of measure-
ment in the space-time manifold, we must not confine
ourselves merely to those minor variations which might
seem natural to human beings on the earth. Let us
make therefore the general statement that four measure-
ments, respectively of independent types (such as mea-
surements of lengths in three directions and a time),
can be found such that a definite event-particle is
determined by them in its relations to other parts of
the manifold.
I^ (Ply p2^ p3y P^) ^^ ^ set of measurements of this
system, then the event-particle which is thus deter-
mined will be said to have />i, p^, p^y ^4 as its co-ordi-
nates in this system of measurement. Suppose that we
name it the/)-system of measurement. Then in the same
/>-system by properly varying (/>!, p^, p^y p^ every
event-particle that has been, or will be, or instantane-
ously is now, can be indicated. Furthermore, according
to any system of measurement that is natural to us.
176 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch.
three of the co-ordinates will be measurements of space
and one will be a measurement of time. Let us always
take the last co-ordinate to represent the time-measure-
ment. Then we should naturally say that (/>i, />2, Pz)
determined a point in space and that the event-particle
happened at that point at the tivatp^. But we must not
make the mistake of thinking that there is a space in
addition to the space-time manifold. That manifold is
all that there is for the determination of the meaning of
space and time. We have got to determine the meaning
of a space-point in terms of the event-particles of the
four-dimensional manifold. There is only one way to
do this. Note that if we vary the time and take times
with the same three space co-ordinates, then the event-
particles, thus indicated, are all at the same point. But
seeing that there is nothing else except the event-
particles, this can only mean that the point (pi, />2> p^
of the space in the /)-system is merely the collection of
event-particles (/>!, p^, p^, [pj)) where /)4 is varied and
(pi, p2y Pz) is kept fixed. It is rather disconcerting to
find that a point in space is not a simple entity ; but it
is a conclusion which follows immediately from the
relative theory of space.
Furthermore the inhabitant of Mars determines
event-particles by another system of measurements.
Call his system the ^-system. According to him
{qiy q2, ^3, g'4) determines an event-particle, and
(^1, ^2> ^3) determines a point and ^4 a time. But the
collection of event-particles which he thinks of as a
point is entirely different from any such collection
which the man on earth thinks of as a point. Thus the
^-space for the man on Mars is quite different from the
^-space for the land-surveyor on earth.
VIII] SUMMARY 177
So far in speaking of space we have been talking of
the timeless space of physical science, namely, of our
concept of eternal space in v^hich the world adventures.
But the space which we see as we look about is instan-
taneous space. Thus if our natural perceptions are
adjustable to the ^-system of measurements we see
instantaneously all the event-particles at some definite
time ^4, and observe a succession of such spaces as time
moves on. The timeless space is achieved by stringing
together all these instantaneous spaces. The points of
an instantaneous space are event-particles, and the
points of an eternal space are strings of event-particles
occurring in succession. But the man on Mars will
never perceive the same instantaneous spaces as the
man on the earth. This system of instantaneous spaces
will cut across the earth-man's system. For the earth-
man there is one instantaneous space which is the
instantaneous present, there are the past spaces and the
future spaces. But the present space of the man on
Mars cuts across the present space of the man on the
earth. So that of the event-particles which the earth-
man thinks of as happening now in the present, the
man on Mars thinks that some are already past and are
ancient history, that others are in the future, and others
are in the immediate present. This break-down in the
neat conception of a past, a present, and a future is a
serious paradox. I call two event-particles which on
some or other system of measurement are in the same
instantaneous space * co-present' event-particles. Then
it is possible that A and B may be co-present, and that
A and C may be co-present, but that B and C may not
be co-present. For example, at some inconceivable
distance from us there are events co-present with us
W.N. 12
178 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch.
now and also co-present with the birth of Queen
Victoria. If A and B are co-present there will be some
systems in which A precedes B and some in which B
precedes A, Also there can be no velocity quick enough
to carry a material particle from ^ to j5 or from B to A.
These different measure-systems with their divergences
of time-reckoning are puzzling, and to some extent
affront our common sense. It is not the usual way in
which we think of the Universe. We think of one
necessary time-system and one necessary space. Ac-
cording to the new theory, there are an indefinite
number of discordant time-series and an indefinite
number of distinct spaces. Any correlated pair, a
time-system and a space-system, will do in which to fit
our description of the Universe. We find that under
given conditions our measurements are necessarily made
in some one pair which together form our natural
measure-system. The difficulty as to discordant time-
systems is partly solved by distinguishing between what
I call the creative advance of nature, which is not
properly serial at all, and any one time series. We
habitually muddle together this creative advance, which
we experience and know as the perpetual transition of
nature into novelty, with the single- time series which
we naturally employ for measurement. The various
time-series each measure some aspect of the creative
advance, and the whole bundle of them express all the
properties of this advance which are measurable. The
reason why we have not previously noted this difference
of time-series is the very small difference of properties
between any two such series. Any observable pheno-
mena due to this cause depend on the square of the
ratio of any velocity entering into the observation to
VIII] SUMMARY 179
the velocity of light. Now^ Ught takes about fifty minutes
to get round the earth's orbit; and the earth takes
rather more than 17,531 half-hours to do the same.
Hence all the effects due to this motion are of the order
of the ratio of one to the square of 10,000. Accordingly
an earth-man and a sun-man have only neglected
effects whose quantitative magnitudes all contain the
factor i/io^. Evidently such effects can only be noted
by means of the most refined observations. They have
been observed how^ever. Suppose wc compare two
observations on the velocity of light made with the
same apparatus as we turn it through a right angle.
The velocity of the earth relatively to the sun is in one
direction, the velocity of light relatively to the ether
should be the same in all directions. Hence if space
when we take the ether as at rest means the same thing
as space when we take the earth as at rest, we ought to
find that the velocity of light relatively to the earth
varies according to the direction from which it comes.
These observations on earth constitute the basic
principle of the famous experiments designed to detect
the motion of the earth through the ether. You all
know that, quite unexpectedly, they gave a null result.
This is completely explained by the fact that, the space-
system and the time-system which we are using are
in certain minute ways different from the space and the
time relatively to the sun or relatively to any other body
with respect to which it is moving.
All this discussion as to the nature of time and space
has lifted above our horizon a great difficulty which
affects the formulation of all the ultimate laws of physics
— for example, the laws of the electromagnetic field,
and the law of gravitation. Let us take the law of
i8o THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [CH.
gravitation as an example. Its formulation is as follows :
Two material bodies attract each other with a force
proportional to the product of their masses and umka
versely proportional to the square of their distances. In
this statement the bodies are supposed to be small
enough to be treated as material particles in relation to
their distances; and we need not bother further about
that minor point. The difficulty to which I want to
draw your attention is this : In the formulation of the
law one 'definite time and one definite space are pre-
supposed. The two masses are assumed to be in simul-
taneous positions.
But what is simultaneous in one time-system may not
be simultaneous in another time-system. So according
to our new views the law is in this respect not formulated
so as to have any exact meaning. Furthermore an
analogous difficulty arises over the question of distance.
The distance between two instantaneous positions,
i.e, between two event-particles, is different in different
space-systems. What space is to be chosen ? Thus again
the law lacks precise formulation, if relativity is accepted.
Our problem is to seek a fresh interpretation of the
law of gravity in which these difficulties are evaded. In
the first place we must avoid the abstractions of space
and time in the formulation of our fundamental ideas
and must recur to the ultimate facts of nature, namely
to events. Also in order to find the ideal simplicity of
expressions of the relations between events, we restrict
ourselves to event-particles. Thus the life of a material
particle is its adventure amid a track of event-particles
strung out as a continuous series or path in the four-
dimensional space-time manifold. These event-particles
are the various situations of the material particle. We
viiij SUMMARY i8i
usually express this fact by adopting our natural space-
time system and by talking of the path in space of the
material particle as it exists at successive instants of time.
We have to ask ourselves what are the laws of nature
which lead the material particle to adopt just this path
among event-particles and no other. Think of the path
as a whole. What characteristic has that path got which
would not be shared by any other slightly varied path ?
We are asking for more than a law of gravity. We want
laws of motion and a general idea of the way to formulate
the effects of physical forces.
In order to answer our question we put the idea of the
attracting masses in the background and concentrate
attention on the field of activity of the events in the
neighbourhood of the path. In so doing we are acting
in conformity with the whole trend of scientific thought
during the last hundred years, which has more and more
concentrated attention on the field of force as the im-
mediate agent in directing motion, to the exclusion of
the consideration of the immediate mutual influence
between two distant bodies. We have got to find the
way of expressing the field of activity of events in the
neighbourhood of some definite event-particle E of the
four-dimensional manifold. I bring in a fundamental
physical idea which I call the * impetus ' to express this
physical field. The event-particle E is related to any
neighbouring event-particle P by an element of impetus.
The assemblage of all the elements of impetus relating
E to the assemblage of event-particles in the neighbour-
hood of E expresses the character of the field of activity
in the neighbourhood of E, Where I differ from Einstein
is that he conceives this quantity which I call the impetus
as merely expressing the characters of the space and
i82 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch.
time to be adopted and thus ends by talking of the
gravitational field expressing a curvature in the space-
time manifold. I cannot attach any clear conception to
his interpretation of space and time. My formulae
differ slightly from his, though they agree in those
instances where his results have been verified. I need
hardly say that in this particular of the formulation of the
law of gravitation I have drawn on the general method
of procedure which constitutes his great discovery.
Einstein showed how to express the characters of the
assemblage of elements of impetus of the field sur-
rounding an event-particle E in terms of ten quantities
which I will call J^* J12 (= .72i). J22. J23 (= ^32). etc.
It will be noted that there are four spatio-temporal
measurements relating E to its neighbour P, and that
there are ten pairs of such measurements if we are
allowed to take any one measurement twice over to
make one such pair. The ten J's depend merely on the
position of E in the four-dimensional manifold, and the
element of impetus between E and P can be expressed
in terms of the ten J's and the ten pairs of the four
spatio-temporal measurements relating E and P. The
numerical values of the J's will depend on the system
of measurement adopted, but are so adjusted to each
particular system that the same value is obtained for
the element of impetus between E and P, whatever be
the system of measurement adopted. This fact is ex-
pressed by saying that the ten J's form a ' tensor.' It is
not going too far to say that the announcement that
physicists would have in future to study the theor^^
of tensors created a veritable panic among them when
the verification of Einstein's predictions was first
announced.
VIII] SUMMARY 183
The ten J's at any event-particle E can be expressed in
terms of tw^o functions w^hich I call the potential and the
* associate-potential' at E. The potential is practically
what is meant by the ordinary gravitation potential,
when we express ourselves in terms of the Euclidean
space in reference to which the attracting mass is at
rest. The associate-potential is defined by the modifi-
cation of substituting the direct distance for the inverse
distance in the definition of the potential, and its calcu-
lation can easily be made to depend on that of the old-
fashioned potential. Thus the calculation of the J's — the
coefficients of impetus, as I will call them — does not
involve anything very revolutionary in the mathematical
knowledge of physicists. We now return to the path of
the attracted particle. We add up all the elements of
impetus in the whole path, and obtain thereby what I
call the 'integral impetus.' The characteristic of the
actual path as compared with neighbouring alternative
paths is that in the actual paths the integral impetus
would neither gain nor lose, if the particle wobbled out
of it into a small extremely near alternative path. Mathe-
maticians would express this by saying, that the integral
impetus is stationary for an infinitesimal displacement.
In this statement of the law of motion I have neglected
the existence of other forces. But that would lead me
too far afield.
The electromagnetic theory has to be modified to
allow for the presence of a gravitational field. Thus
Einstein's investigations lead to the first discovery of
any relation between gravity and other physical pheno-
mena. In the form in which I have put this modification,
we deduce Einstein's fundamental principle, as to the
motion of light along its rays, as a first approximation
i84 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch. viii
which IS absolutely true for infinitely short waves.
Einstein's principle, thus partially verified, stated in my
language is that a ray of light always follows a path such
that the integral impetus along it is zero. This involves
that every element of impetus along it is zero.
In conclusion, I must apologise. In the first place
I have considerably toned down the various exciting
peculiarities of the original theory and have reduced it
to a greater conformity with the older physics. I do not
allow that physical phenomena are due to oddities of
space. Also I have added to the dullness of the lecture
by my respect for the audience. You would have enjoyed
a more popular lecture with illustrations of delightful
paradoxes. But I know also that you are serious
students who are here because you really want to know
how the new theories may aflFect your scientific re-
searches.
CHAPTER IX
THE ULTIMATE PHYSICAL CONCEPTS
The second chapter of this book lays down the first
principle to be guarded in framing our physical concept.
We must avoid vicious bifurcation Nature is nothing
else than the deliverance of sense-awareness. We have
no principles whatever to tell us what could stimulate
mind towards sense-awareness. Our sole task is to
exhibit in one system the characters and inter-relations
of all that is observed. Our attitude towards nature is
purely * behaviouristic,' so far as concerns the formulation
of physical concepts.
Our knowledge of nature is an experience of activity
(or passage). The things previously observed are active
entities, the * events.' They are chunks in the life of
nature. These events have to each other relations which
in our knowledge differentiate themselves into space-
relations and time-relations. But this differentiation
between space and time, though inherent in nature, is
comparatively superficial ; and space and time are each
partial expressions of one fundamental relation between
events which is neither spatial nor temporal. This
relation I call 'extension.' The relation of 'extending
over' is the relation of 'including,' either in a spatial or
in a temporal sense, or in both. But the mere 'inclu-
sion' is more fundamental than either alternative and
does not require any spatio-temporal differentiation.
In respect to extension two events are mutually related
so that either (i) one includes the other, or (ii) one over-
laps the other without complete inclusion, or (iii) they
i86 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [CH.
are entirely separate. But great care is required in the
definition of spatial and temporal elements from this
basis in order to avoid tacit limitations really depend-
ing on undefined relations and properties.
Such fallacies can be avoided by taking account of
two elements in our experience, namely, (i) our ob-
servational * present,' and (ii) our * percipient event.'
Our observational * present ' is what I call a * duration.'
It is the whole of nature apprehended in our immediate
observation. It has therefore the nature of an event,
but possesses a peculiar completeness which marks out
such durations as a special type of events inherent in
nature. A duration is not instantaneous. It is all that
there is of nature with certain temporal limitations. In
contradistinction to other events a duration will be
called infinite and the other events are finite^. In our
knowledge of a duration we distinguish (i) certain
included events which are particularly discriminated
as to their peculiar individualities, and (ii) the remaining
included events which are only known as necessarily in
being by reason of their relations to the discriminated
events and to the whole duration. The duration as a
whole is signified^ by that quality of relatedness (in
respect to extension) possessed by the part which is
^immediately under observation; namely, by the fact
; that there is essentially a beyond to whatever is observed.
\ I mean by this that every event is known as being related
\to other events which it does not include. This fact,
jthat every event is known as possessing the quality of
^exclusion, shows that exclusion is as positive a relation
as inclusion. There are of course no merely negative
^ Cf. note on ^significance,' pp. 197, 198.
2 Cf. Ch. Ill, pp. 51 et seq.
IX] THE ULTIMATE PHYSICAL CONCEPTS 187
relations in nature, and exclusion is not the mere
negative of inclusion, though the two relations are
contraries. Both relations are concerned solely with^
events, and exclusion is capable of logical definition in
terms of inclusion.
Perhaps the most obvious exhibition of significance
is to be found in our knowledge of the geometrical
character of events inside an opaque material object.
For example we know that an opaque sphere has a
centre. This knowledge has nothing to do with the
material; the sphere may be a solid uniform billiard
ball or a hollow lawn-tennis ball. Such knowledge is
essentially the product of significance, since the general
character of the external discriminated events has in-
formed us that there are events within the sphere and
has also informed us of their geometrical structure.
Some criticisms on *The Principles of Natural
Knowledge' show that difficulty has been found in
apprehending durations as real stratifications of nature.
I think that this hesitation arises from the unconscious
influence of the vicious principle of bifurcation, so
deeply embedded in modern philosophical thought.
We observe nature as extended in an immediate present
which is simultaneous but not instantaneous, and there-
fore the whole which is immediately discerned or
signified as an inter-related system forms a stratification
of nature which is a physical fact. This conclusion
immediately follows unless we admit bifurcation in the
form of the principle of psychic additions, here rejected.
Our * percipient event ' is that event included in our
observational present which we distinguish as being in
some peculiar way our standpoint for perception. It is
roughly speaking that event which is our bodily life
i88 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [CH.
within the present duration. The theory of perception
as evolved by medical psychology is based on signifi-
cance. The distant situation of a perceived object is
merely known to us as signified by our bodily state,
i,e, by our percipient event. In fact perception requires
sense-awareness of the significations of our percipient
event together with sense-awareness of a peculiar re-
lation (situation) between certain objects and the events
thus signified. Our percipient event is saved by being
the whole of nature by this fact of its significations.
This is the meaning of calling the percipient event
our standpoint for perception. The course of a ray of
light is only derivatively connected with perception.
What we do perceive are objects as related to events
signified by the bodily states excited by the ray.
These signified events (as is the case of images seen
behind a mirror) may have very little to do with the
actual course of the ray. In the course of evolution those
animals have survived whose sense-awareness is con-
centrated on those significations of their bodily states
which are on the average important for their welfare.
The whole world of events is signified, but there are
some which exact the death penalty for inattention.
The percipient event is always here and now in the
associated present duration. It has, what may be called,
an absolute position in that duration. Thus one definite
duration is associated with a definite percipient event,
and we are thus aware of a peculiar relation which
finite events can bear to durations. I call this relation
* cogredience.' The notion of rest is derivative from that
of cogredience, and the notion of motion is derivative
from that of inclusion within a duration without cogre-
dience with it. In fact motion is a relation (of varying
IX] THE ULTIMATE PHYSICAL CONCEPTS 189
character) between an observed event and an observed
duration, and cogredience is the most simple character
or subspecies of motion. To sum up, a duration and a
percipient event are essentially involved in the general
character of each observation of nature, and the per-
cipient event is cogredient with the duration.
Our knowledge of the peculiar characters of different
events depends upon our power of comparison. I call
the exercise of this factor in our knowledge* recognition,'
and the requisite sense-awareness of the comparable
characters I call * sense-recognition.' Recognition and
abstraction essentially involve each other. Each of them
exhibits an entity for knowledge which is less than the
concrete fact, but is a real factor in that fact. The most
concrete fact capable of separate discrimination is the
event. We cannot abstract without recognition, and
we cannot recognise without abstraction. Perception
involves apprehension of the event and recognition of
the factors of its character.
The things recognised are what I call * objects.' In
this general sense of the term the relation of extension
is itself an object. In practice however I restrict the
term to those objects which can in some sense or other
be said to have a situation in an event; namely, in the
phrase ' There it is again ' I restrict the * there ' to be the
indication of a special event which is the situation of the
object. Even so, there are different types of objects, and
statements which are true of objects of one type are not
in general true of objects of other types. The objects
with which we are here concerned in the formulation
of physical laws are material objects, such as bits of
matter, molecules and electrons. An object of one of
these types has relations to events other than those
190 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch.
belonging to the stream of its situations. The fact of its
situations within this stream has impressed on all other
events certain modifications of their characters. In
truth the object in its completeness may be conceived
as a specific set of correlated modifications of the charac-
ters of all events, with the property that these modifica-
tions attain to a certain focal property for those events
which belong to the stream of its situations. The total
assemblage of the modifications of the characters of
events due to the existence of an object in a stream of
situations is what I call the 'physical field' due to the
object. . But the object cannot really be separated from
its field. The object is in fact nothing else than the
systematically adjusted set of modifications of the field.
The conventional limitation of the object to the focal
stream of events in which it is said to be ' situated ' is
convenient for some purposes, but it obscures the
ultimate fact of nature. From this point of view the
antithesis between action at a distance and action by
transmission is meaningless. The doctrine of this para-
graph is nothing else than another way of expressing the
unresolvable multiple relation of an object to events.
A complete time-system is formed by any one family
of parallel durations. Two durations are parallel if
either (i) one includes the other, or (ii) they overlap so
as to include a third duration common to both, or
(iii) are entirely separate. The excluded case is that of
two durations overlapping so as to include in common
an aggregate of finite events but including in common
no other complete duration. The recognition of the
fact of an indefinite number of families of parallel
durations is what differentiates the concept of nature
here put forward from the older orthodox concept of
IX] THE ULTIMATE PHYSICAL CONCEPTS 191
the essentially unique time-systems. Its divergence from
Einstein's concept of nature will be briefly indicated later.
The instantaneous spaces of a given time-system are
the ideal (non-existent) durations of zero temporal
thickness indicated by routes of approximation along
series formed by durations of the associated family.
Each such instantaneous space represents the ideal of
nature at an instant and is also a moment of time. Each
time-system thus possesses an aggregate of moments
belonging to it alone. Each event-particle lies in one
and only one moment of a given time-system. An event-
particle has three characters^ : (i) its extrinsic character
which is its character as a definite route of convergence
among events, (ii) its intrinsic character which is the
peculiar quality of nature in its neighbourhood, namely,
the character of the physical field in the neighbourhood,
and (iii) its position.
The position of an event-particle arises from the
aggregate of moments (no two of the same family) in
which it lies. We fix our attention on one of these
moments which is approximated to by the short dura-
tion of our immediate experience, and we express
position as the position in this moment. But the event-
particle receives its position in moment M in virtue of
the whole aggregate of other moments M\ M" , etc.,
in which it also lies. The differentiation of M into a
geometry of event-particles (instantaneous points) ex-
presses the diflferentiation of M by its intersections with
moments of alien time-systems. In this way planes and
straight lines and event-particles themselves find their
being. Also the parallelism of planes and straight lines
arises from the parallelism of the moments of one and
^ Of. pp. 82 et seq.
192 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch.
the same time-system intersecting M, Similarly the
order of parallel planes and of event-particles on straight
lines arises from the time-order of these intersecting
moments. The explanation is not given here^. It is
sufficient now merely to mention the sources from which
the whole of geometry receives its physical explanation.
The correlation of the various momentary spaces of
one time-system is achieved by the relation of cogre-
dience. Evidently motion in an instantaneous space is
unmeaning. Motion expresses a comparison between
position in one instantaneous space with positions in
other instantaneous spaces of the same time-system.
Cogredience yields the simplest outcome of such com-
parison, namely, rest.
Motion and rest are immediately observed facts.
They are relative in the sense that they depend on the
time-system which is fundamental for the observation.
A string of event-particles whose successive occupation
means rest in the given time-system forms a timeless
point in the timeless space of that time-system. In this
way each time-system possesses its own permanent
timeless space peculiar to it alone, and each such space
is composed of timeless points which belong to that
time-system and to no other. The paradoxes of rela-
tivity arise from neglecting the fact that different as-
sumptions as to rest involve the expression of the facts
of physical science in terms of radically different spaces
and times, in which points and moments have different
meanings.
The source of order has already been indicated and
that of congruence is now found. It depends on motion.
1 Of. Principles of Natural Knowledge^ and previous chapters
of the present work.
IX] THE ULTIMATE PHYSICAL CONCEPTS 193
From cogredience, perpendicularity arises; and from
perpendicularity in conjunction with the reciprocal
symmetry between the relations of any two time-systems
congruence both in time and space is completely defined
(cf. loc, cit.).
The resulting formulae are those for the electro-
magnetic theory of relativity, or, as it is now termed, the
restricted theory. But there is this vital difference: the
critical velocity c which occurs in these formulae has
now no connexion whatever with light or with any
other fact of the physical field (in distinction from the
extensional structure of events). It simply marks the
fact that our congruence determination embraces both
times and spaces in one universal system, and therefore
if two arbitrary units are chosen, one for all spaces and
one for all times, their ratio will be a velocity which is a
fundamental property of nature expressing the fact that
times and spaces are really comparable.
The physical properties of nature are expressed in
terms of material objects (electrons, etc.). The physical
character of an event arises from the fact that it belongs
to the field of the whole complex of such objects. From
another point of view we can say that these objects are
nothing else than our way of expressing the mutual
correlation of the physical characters of events.
The spatio-temporal measurableness of nature arises
from (i) the relation of extension between events, and
(ii) the stratified character of nature arising from each of
the alternative time-systems, and (iii) rest and motion,
as exhibited in the relations of finite events to time-
systems. None of these sources of measurement depend
on the physical characters of finite events as exhibited
by the situated objects. They are completely signified
W. N. 13
194 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch.
for events whose physical characters are unknown. Thus
the spatio-temporal measurements are independent of
the objectival physical characters. Furthermore the
character of our knowledge of a whole duration, which
is essentially derived from the significance of the part
within the immediate field of discrimination, constructs
it for us as a uniform whole independent, so far as its
extension is concerned, of the unobserved characters
of remote events. Namely, there is a definite whole of
nature, simultaneously now present, whatever may be
the character of its remote events. This consideration
reinforces the previous conclusion. This conclusion
leads to the assertion of the essential uniformity of the
momentary spaces of the various time-systems, and
thence to the uniformity of the timeless spaces of which
there is one to each time-system.
The analysis of the general character of observed
nature set forth above aflFords explanations of various
fundamental observational facts: (a) It explains the
differentiation of the one quality of extension into time
and space. (^S) It gives a meaning to the observed facts
of geometrical and temporal position, of geometrical
and temporal order, and of geometrical straightness and
planeness. (y) It selects one definite system of congruence
embracing both space and time, and thus explains the
concordance as to measurement which is in practice
attained. (S) It explains (consistently with the theory of
relativity) the observed phenomena of rotation, e.g.
Foucault's pendulum, the equatorial bulge of the earth,
the fixed senses of rotation of cyclones and anticyclones,
and the gyro-compass. It does this by its admission of
definite stratifications of nature which are disclosed by
the very character of our knowledge of it. (c) Its ex-
IX] THE ULTIMATE PHYSICAL CONCEPTS 195
planations of motion are more fundamental than those
expressed in (8) ; for it explains what is meant by motion
itself. The observed motion of an extended object is
the relation of its various situations to the stratification
of nature expressed by the time-system fundamental to
the observation. This motion expresses a real relation
of the object to the rest of nature. The quantitative
expression of this relation will vary according to the
time-system selected for its expression.
This theory accords no peculiar character to light
beyond that accorded to other physical phenomena such
as sound. There is no ground for such a differentiation.
Some objects we know by sight only, and other objects
we know by sound only, and other objects we observe
neither by light nor by sound but by touch or smell or
otherwise. The velocity of light varies according to its
medium and so does that of sound. Light moves in
curved paths under certain conditions and so does
sound. Both light and sound are waves of disturbance
in the physical characters of events ; and (as has been
stated above, p. 188) the actual course of the light
is of no more importance for perception than is the
actual course of the sound. To base the whole philo-
sophy of nature upon light is a baseless assumption.
The Michelson-Morley and analogous experiments
show that within the limits of our inexactitude of
observation the velocity of light is an approximation to
the critical velocity ^ c^ which expresses the relation
between our space and time units. It is provable that
the assumption as to light by which these experiments
and the influence of the gravitational field on the light-
rays are explained is deducible as an approximation
from the equations of the electromagnetic field. This
196 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch.
completely disposes of any necessity for differentiating
light from other physical phenomena as possessing
any peculiar fundamental character.
It is to be observed that the measurement of extended
nature by means of extended objects is meaningless
apart from some observed fact of simultaneity inherent
in nature and not merely a play of thought. Otherwise
there is no meaning to the concept of one presentation
of your extended measuring rod AB. Why not AB'
where B' is the end B five minutes later ? Measurement
presupposes for its possibility nature as a simultaneity,
and an observed object present then and present now.
In other words, measurement of extended nature re-
quires some inherent character in nature affording a
rule of presentation of events. Furthermore congruence
cannot be defined by the permanence of the measuring
rod. The permanence is itself meaningless apart from
some immediate judgment of self-congruence. Other-
wise how is an elastic string differentiated from a rigid
measuring rod? Each remains the same self-identical
object. Why is one a possible measuring rod and the
other not so ? The meaning of congruence lies beyond
the self-identity of the object. In other words measure-
ment presupposes the measurable, and the theory of the
measurable is the theory of congruence.
Furthermore the admission of stratifications of nature
bears on the formulation of the laws of nature. It has
been laid down that these laws are to be expressed in
differential equations which, as expressed in any general
system of measurement, should bear no reference to
any other particular measure-system. This requirement
is purely arbitrary. For a measure-system measures
something inherent in nature; otherwise it has no
IX] THE ULTIMATE PHYSICAL CONCEPTS 197
connexion with nature at all. And that something which
is measured by a particular measure-system may have a
special relation to the phenomenon whose law is being
formulated. For example the gravitational field due to
a material object at rest in a certain time-system may
be expected to exhibit in its formulation particular
reference to spatial and temporal quantities of that
time-system. The field can of course be expressed in
any measure-systems, but the particular reference will
remain as the simple physical explanation.
NOTE: ON THE GREEK CONCEPT OF A POINT
The preceding pages had been passed for press before I had
the pleasure of seeing Sir T. L. Heath's Euclid in Greek^.
In the original Euclid's first definition is
a-rjfjLelov iaTCVy ov fiipof; ovdev.
I have quoted it on p. 86 in the expanded form taught to me
in childhood, * without parts and without magnitude.' I should
have consulted Heath's English edition — a classic from the
moment of its issue — before committing myself to a statement
about Euclid. This is however a trivial correction not affecting
sense and not worth a note. I wish here to draw attention to
Heath's own note to this definition in his Euclid in Greek. He
summarises Greek thought on the nature of a point, from the
Pythagoreans, through Plato and Aristotle, to Euclid. My
analysis of the requisite character of a point on pp. 89 and
90 is in complete agreement with the outcome of the Greek
discussion.
NOTE: ON SIGNIFICANCE AND INFINITE EVENTS
The theory of significance has been expanded and made more
definite in the present volume. It had already been introduced
in the Principles of Natural Knowledge (cf. subarticles 3-3 to
3-8 and i6-i, 16-2, 19-4, and articles 20, 21). In reading over the
proofs of the present volume, I come to the conclusion that in the
1 Camb. Univ. Press, 1920.
13—3
198 THE CONCEPT OF NATURE [ch.ix
light of this development my limitation of infinite events to dura-
tions is untenable. This limitation is stated in article 33 of the
Principles and at the beginning of Chapter IV (p. 74) of this book.
There is not only a significance of the discerned events embracing
the whole present duration, but there is a significance of a cogre-
dient event involving its extension through a whole time-system
backwards and forwards. In other words the essential ' beyond'
in nature is a definite beyond in time as well as in space [cf.
pp. 53, 194]. This follows from my whole thesis as to the assimila-
tion of time and space and their origin in extension. It also has
the same basis in the analysis of the character of our knowledge
of nature. It follows from this admission that it is possible to
define point-tracks [i.e. the points of timeless spaces] as abstrac-
tive elements. This is a great improvement as restoring the
balance between moments and points. I still hold however to the
statement in subarticle 35-4 of the Principles that the intersection
of a pair of non-parallel durations does not present itself to us as
one event. This correction does not affect any of the subsequent
reasoning in the two books.
I may take this opportunity of pointing out that the ' stationary
events' of article 57 of the Principles are merely cogredient
events got at from an abstract mathematical point of view.
INDEX
In the case of terms of frequent occurrence, only those occurrences are
indexed which are of peculiar importance for the elucidation of meaning.
A [or an], ii
Abraham, 105
Absolute position, 105, 106, 114,
188
Abstraction, 33, 37, 168, 171, 173;
extensive, 65, 79, 85
Abstractive element, 84; set, 61,
79
Action at a distance, 159, 190
Action by transmission, 159, 190
Active conditions, 158
Activity, field of, 170, 181
Adjunction, loi
Aggregate, 23
Alexander, Prof., viii
Alexandria, 71
Alfred the Great, 137
Anticipation, 69
Anti-prime, 88
Apparent nature, 31, 39
Area, 99; momental, 103; vagrant,
103
Aristotelian logic, 150
Aristotle, 16, 17, 18, 24, 197
Associate-potential, 183
Atom, 17
Attribute, 21, 26, 150
Awareness, 3
Axiom, 36, 121
Axioms of congruence, 128 at seqq.
Bacon, Francis, 78
Behaviouristic, 185
Bergson, 54
Berkeley, 28
Between, 64
Beyond, 186, 198
Bifurcation, vi, 30, 185, 187
Boundary, 100; moment, 63; par-
ticle, 100
Broad, C. D., viii
Calculation, formula of, 45, 158
Cambridge, 97
Causal nature, 31, 39
Causation, 31, 146
Centrifugal force, 138
Change, uniformity of, 140
Character, extrinsic, 82, 89, 90, 113,
191; intrinsic, 80, 82, 90, 113, 191
Charge, 160
Closure of nature, 4
Coefficient of drag, 133
Coefficients of impetus, 183
Cogredience, no, 188
Coherence, 29
Comparison, 124, 125, 143, 189
Complex, 13
Conceptual nature, 45; space, 96
Concrete facts, 167, 171, 189
Conditioning events, 152
Conditions, active, 158
Congruence, 65, 96, 118, 120, 127, 196
Continuity, 157; Dedekindian, 102;
of events, 76; of nature, 59, 76
Convention, 121
Convergence, 62, 79; law of, 82
Conveyance, 154, 155
Co-present, 177
Covering, 83
Creative advance, 178
Critical velocity, 193, 195
Curvature of space- time, 182
Cyclone, 194
Dedekindian continuity, 102
Definite, 53, 194, 198
Delusions, 31, 38
Delusive perceptual object, 153
Demarcation of events, 144
Demonstrative phrase, 6
Descriptive phrase, 6, 10
Differential equations, 196
Discrimination, 14, 50, 144
Diversification of nature, 15
Duddington, Mrs, 47
Duration, 37. 53. 55. 186
Durations, families of, 59, 73, 190
Dynamical axes, 138
Einstein, vii, 102, 131, 164, 165,
181, 182, 183, 184, 191
Electromagnetic field, 179
Electron, 30, 146, 158, 171
Element, 17; abstractive, 84
Elliptical phraseology, 7
200
INDEX
Empty space, 145
Entity, 5, 13
Equal in abstractive force, 83
Error, 68
Ether, 18, 78, 160; material, 78;
of events, 78
Euclid, 85, 94, 197
Euler, 140
Event, 15, 52, 75, 165; percipient,
107, 152, 186
Event-particle, 86, 93, 94, 172, 191
Events, conditioning, 152; con-
tinuity of, 76; demarcation of,
144; ether of, 78; infinite, 197,
198; limited, 74; passage of, 34;
signified, 52; stationary, 198;
stream of, 167; structure of, 52,
166
Exclusion, 186
Explanation, 97, 141
Extended nature, 196
Extension, 22, 58, 75, 185
Extensive abstraction, 65, 79, 85
Extrinsic character, 82, 89, 90, 113,
191; properties, 62
Fact, 12, 13
Factors, 12, 13, 15
Facts, concrete, 167, 171
Family of durations, 59, 63, 73; of
moments, 63
Faraday, 146
Field, gravitational, 197; of activity,
170, 181; physical, 190
Finite truths, 12
Fitzgerald, 133
Formula of calculation, 45, 158
Foucault, 138, 194
Four-dimensional manifold, 86
Fresnel, 133
Future, the, 72, 177
Galileo, 139
Geometrical order, 194
Geometry, 36; metrical, 129
Gravitation, 179 et seqq.
Gravitational field, 197
Greek philosophy, 16; thought, 197
Gyro-compass, 194
Heath, Sir T. L., 197
Here, 107
Idealists, 70
Immediacy, 52; of perception, 72
Impetus, 181, 182; coefficients of,
183; integral, 183
Inclusion, 186
Individuality, 13
Infinite events, 197, 198
Inge, Dr, 48
Ingredient, 14
Ingression, 144, 145, 148, 152
Inherence, 8^
Inside, 106
Instant, 33, 35, 57
Instantaneous plane, 91 ; present, 72 ;
spaces, 86, 90, 177
Instantaneousness, 56, 57
Intersection, locus of, 90
Intrinsic character, 80, 82, 90, 113,
191; properties, 62
Ionian thinkers, 19
Irrelevance, infinitude of, 12
Irrevocableness, 35, 37
It, 8
Julius Caesar, 36
Junction, 76, loi
Kinetic energy, 105; symmetry, 129
Knowledge, 28, 32
Lagrange, 140
Larmor, 131
Law of convergence, 82
Laws of motion, 137, 139; of nature,
196
Leibnizian monadology, 150
Level, 91, 92
Light, 195; ray of, 188; velocity of,
131
Limit, 57
Limited events, 74
Location, 160, 161
Locke, 27
Locus, 102; of intersection, 90
London, 97
Lorentz, H. A., 131, 133
Lossky, 47
Manifold, four-dimensional, 86;
space-time, 173
Material ether, 78; object, 169
Materialism, 43, 70
Matrix, 116
Matter, 16, 17, 19, 20, 26
Maxwell, 131, 133
Measurableness, 196; of nature, 193
Measurement, 96, 120, 174, 196; of
time, 65, 140
Measure-system, 196
Memory, 68
Metaphysics, 28, 32
Metrical geometry, 129
Michelson-Morley, 195
Milton, 35
Mind, 27, 28
INDEX
201
Minkowski, viii, 131
Molecule, 32, 171
Moment, 57, 60, 88
Momental area, 103; route, 103
Momentum, 105
Motion, 105, 114, 117, 127, 188, 192
Multiplicity, 22
Natural philosophy, 29, 30
Natural science, philosophy of, 46
Nature, 3; apparent, 31, 39; causal,
31, 39; conceptual, 45; continuity
of, 59, 76; discrimination of, 144;
extended, 196; laws of, 196;
passage of, 54; stratification of,
194, 196; system of, 146
Newton, 27, 136, 139, 140
Object, 77, 125, 143, 169, 189;
delusive perceptual, 155; material,
169; perceptual, 153; physical,
155. ''^57> scientific, 158, 169; uni-
form, 162
Occupation, 22, 34, 36, 100, loi
Order, source of, 192; spatial, 95,
194; temporal, 64, 95, 194
Organisation of thought, 79
Outside, 63, 100
Paradox, 192
Parallel, 63, 127; durations, 190 -
Parallelism, 95, 191
Parallelogram, 127
Paris, 87, 138
Parliament, 120
Part, 14, 15, 58
Passage of events, 34; of nature, 54
Past, the, 72, 177
Perception, 3
Perceptual objects, 149, 153
Percipience, 28
Percipient event, 107, 152, 186, 187
Period of time, 51
Permanence, 144
Perpendicularity, 117, 127, 193
Philosophy, i ; natural, 29, 30 ; of
natural science, 46 ; of the sciences,
2
Physical field, 190; object, 155, 156,
157
Physics, speculative, 30
Place, 51
Plane, 191; instantaneous, 91
Plato, 16, 17, 18, 24, 197
Poincare, 121, 122, 123
Point, 35, 89,^91, 114, 173, 176
Point-flash, 172, 173
Point of space, 85
Point, timeless, 192
Point- track, 113, 198
Pompey, 36
Position, 89, 90, 92, 93, 99, 113, 191 J
absolute, 105, 106, 114, 188
Potential, 183; associate-, 183
Predicate, 18
Predication, 18
Present, the, 69, 72, 177; instan-
taneous, 72; observational, 186
Primary qualities, 27
Prime, 88
Process, 53, 54; of nature, 54
Psychic additions, 29, 187
Punct, 92, 93, 94
Pythagoreans, 197
Quality, 27
Quantum of time, 162
Quantum theory, 162
Ray of light, 188
Reality, 30; of durations, 55, 187
Recognition, 124, 143, 189
Rect, 91, 92
Recurrence, 35
Relative motion, 117; velocity, 130
Relativity, 169; restricted theory
of, 193
Rest, 105, 114, 188, 192
Rotation, 138, 194
Route, 99; momental, 103; straight,
103
Russell, Bertrand, 11, 122, 123
Schelling, 47
Science, 2; metaphysical, 32
Scientific objects, 149, 158, 169
Secondary qualities, 27
Self-congruence, 196
Self-containedness of nature, 4
Sense-awareness, 3, 67
Sense-object, 149, 170
Sense-perception, 3, 14
Sense-recognition, 143, 189
Series, temporal, 66, 70, 85, 178
Set, abstractive, 61, 79
Significance, 51, 186, 187, 188, 194,
197, 198
Signified events, 52
Simplicity, 163, 173
Simultaneity, 53, 56, 196
Situation, 15, 78, 147, 148, 152, 160,
189
Solid, 99, loi, 102; vagrant, loi
Sound, 195
Space, 16, 17. 31.33, 79; empty, 145;
timeless, 86, 106, 114; uniformity
of, 194
Spaces, instantaneous, 86, 90
202
INDEX
Space-system, 179
Space- time manifold, 173
Spatial-order, 95
Spatio-temporal structure, 173
Speculative demonstration, 6
Speculative physics, 30
Standpoint for perception, 107, 188
Station, 103, 104, 113
Stationary events, 198
Straight line, 91, 114, 191; route,
103
Stratification of nature, 187, 194,
196
Stream of events, 167
Structure of events, 52, 166
Structure, spatio-temporal, 173
Subject, 18
Substance, 16, 18, 19, 150
Substratum, 16, 18, 21
Symmetry, 118, 126; kinetic, 129
System of nature, 146
System, time-, 192
Tamer, Edward, v, i
Temporal order, 64, 95, 194
Temporal series, 66, 70, 85
Tensor, 182
Terminus, 4
The, II
Theory, quantum, 162
There, no, 189
This, II
Thought, 3, 14
Timaeus, the, 17, 20, 24
Time, 16, 17, 31, 33, 49. 79;
measurement of, 140; quantum of,
162; transcendence of, 39
Time-series, 178, also cf. Temporal
series
Time-system, see Time-series, also
91, 97, 104, 179, 192
Timeless point, 192; space, 86, 106,
114. 177
Totality, 89
Transcendence of time, 39
Transmission, 26, 28; action by, 159,
190
Tubes of force, 146
Unexhaustiveness, 50
Uniform object, 162
Uniformity of change, 140; of space,
194
Vagrant area, 103 ; solid, loi
Veblen and Young, 36
Velocity, critical, 193, 195; of liglit,
131, 195; relative, 130
Volume, 92, 10 1
When, 107
Where, 107
Whole, 58
Within, 63
Young, Veblen and, 36
CAMBRIDGE: PRINTED BY J. B. PEACE, M.A., AT THE UNIVERSITY PRESS.
THE UNIVERSITY LIBRARY
UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, SANTA CRUZ
SCIENCE LIBRARY
This book is due on the last DATE stamped below.
To renew by phone, call 459-2050.
Books not returned or renewed within 14 days
after<3ue date are subject to billing.
Series 2477
STORED AT NRLF
3 2106 00227 7173