i GIFT OF JANE K-SATHER 1 i ELECTION BY LOT AT ATHENS. Sotttott: C. J. CLAY AND SONS, CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS WAREHOUSE, AVE MARIA LANE. Camfiriiflc: DEIGHTON, BELL, AND CO. ILeipjifl: F. A. BROCKHAUS. ^tia lorft : MACMILLAN AND CO. Canibrflrgt ^fsitorical (Kstsfapst. Bo. IV. ELECTION BY LOT AT ATHENS. BY JAMES WYCLIFFE HEADLAM, M.A, FELLOW OF king's COLLEGE, CAMBRIDGE. PRINCE CONSORT DISSERTATION, 1890. AT THE UNIVERSITY PRESS. 1891 [All Rights reserved.] CTambrilige : PRINTED BY C. J. CLAY, M.A. AND SONS, AT THB UNIVERSITY PRESS. (Sree^ j I restriction of this kind to the free action of the lot ; ^ ' had such existed it would have been an effectual check on the objects for which the lot was introduced. I propose therefore to enquire what were the reasons for which the Athenians adopted a custom so strange, and also to examine what were the effects of it on the political system of which it formed a part. It is scarcely necessary to point out that, with- out an explanation of this matter, we cannot hope thoroughly to understand or appreciate the nature of the Athenian Democracy; and I hope the enquiry^ even if it is of no other use, will help to draw at- tention to some peculiarities of the administrative system and will thereby throw light on certain tendencies which seem to be essential to democratic government. The con- But before I discuss the first question, what r^'zoT political advantages were supposed to come from the 'With use of the lot, it is necessary to consider a sugges- beliefs. tion which, if true, would greatly alter the character of the enquiry. It is often maintained that the essence of the lot was religious. If this were true then we should have to consider it as we do omens and oracles; it would be another case of an old superstition interfering with the political life of the INTRODUCTION. 5 people ; its preservation would be another instance of that deep-rooted conservatism in all that con- cerned their worship which often reminds us that the Athenians were not all philosophers or sceptics. It is well established that in early stages-of. jociety the lot is regarded as one among many ways through which the Gods give counsel and advice to men. This was the case both in Greece and Italy. The Greek lived in constant intercourse with his Gods; for every work which he began and every decision which he made he looked to them for advice and guidance. He required some hint as to the result of his labours or some sanction for his enterprise. And the drawing or casting of lots was always one way in which this communication took place. This is abundantly proved from the times of Homer down to the latest days of the Roman Empire: and, as might reasonably have been ex- pected, the lot was chiefly used when the matter on which the Gods were consulted was the choice either of some man from a limited number to receive certain honours or perform certain duties, or the division among a few men of an equal number of duties. The best illustration of this is the fact that Priests throughout Greece it was the regular custom to use ly^^iot^ ^ the lot for the appointment of priests and others who ministered in the temples \ There is no doubt that this was done because it was held fitting that the God himself should choose those who were to ^ Cf. Jules Martha, Les Sacerdoces Ath^niens in the Bibl. des 6coles FraiK^aises, xxvi. 1882. pp. 30 — 35. 6 INTRODUCTION. serve him. If he had not declared his pleasure by an omen or a dream, an opinion could always be secured by the use of the lot. This custom prevailed till the latest times, and though it had probably become a mere ritual observance, it is at least a sign that the appointment of a priest had not the highest validity unless it had received the express sanction of the God. It is easy then to assume that the lot which was so essential a part of the religious ceremonial retained its religious significance when used for political purposes ; and even to draw the conclusion that the religious belief was really the chief reason why it was so extensively used. There is nothing in what we know of Athenian habits of thought to make this improbable ; whatever may have been the opinions of a few educated men, there is no doubt that the great mass of the people firmly believed in the continual intervention of the Gods in the affairs of men. They were not ashamed, nor were they frightened, to allow affairs of the greatest moment to be influenced by dreams, omens, portents and oracles. They were guided by these in private and public life alike \ We should therefore be quite prepared to find that the use of the lot in state affairs 1 Perhaps the most remarkable illustration of this is con- tained in one of the speeches of Hypereides. We there find the Assembly solemnly ordering three men to go and sleep in a temple in order that one of them might learn in a dream the opinion of Amphiaraus on a disputed point of property (Or. iii pro Euxen- ippo, xxvii — viii). It is only necessary to refer to the Anabasis and Hellenica of Xenophon for instances of the readiness with which men would incur the greatest dangers rather than neglect an omen. INTRODUCTION. 7 was, at least by the great mass of the people, upheld because they wished thereby to get the sanction of the Gods for the appointment of their officials. This view becomes still more plausible when we remember that the most conspicuous of the officials so appointed were the nine Archons ; men who had special religious duties and still represented in their office the old union of priest and magistrate. And the state worship at Athens was so closely connected with the public functions that even though the newer offices did not have the same religious im- portance as the Archonship, it is easy to suppose that the pious Athenians liked to have the same divine sanction extended also to those who filled them\ This however will not really explain our difficulty. The explanation has been put forward '"^ by those who have confined their attention to the Archonship and have not sufficiently appreciated the reality and extent of the use of the lot. It may be true that there was a religious sentiment which made the 1 Cf. LugebU, 1. c. p. 666 etc. 2 Fustel de Coulanges, Nouvelle Eevue Historique de Droit, ii. 1878, p. 617 — 643; and La Cite antique, p. 213. "Le caract^re sacerdotal qui s'attachait au magistrat se montre surtout dans la mani^re dont il 6tait 61u. Aux yeux des anciens, il ne semblait pas que les suffrages des hommes fussent suffisants pour dtablir le chef de la cit6. Les hommes paraissent avoir cherche, pour supplier k la naissance, un mode d'61ection que les dieux n'eussent pas a d6savouer. Les Ath6niens, comme beaucoup de peuples grecs, n'en virent pas de meilleur que le tirage de sort. Pour eux le sort n'6tait pas le hasard ; le sort 6tait la r6v61ation de la volont6 divine." He gives no illustrations of this except two passages from the Laws of Plato. Cf. p. 8 n. 1. 8 INTRODUCTION. Use of the lot at Athens cannot be explained by refer- enx;e to religious beliefs. common people cling to the lot, and it could have happened that far-sighted statesmen used this to help in carrying out their policy, but it will not explain why statesmen who certainly were not influenced by religious conservatism wished to extend the use of it, nor how it was that the state which used it could possibly exist and prosper. What evidence there is for the view is, I believe, entirely confined to pas- sages which speak of the Archonship, and, as I shall show, the use of the lot for this was only a small and scarcely the most important part of its application. The fact is that at Athens where the use of the lot was most common the evidence for its reli- gious signification is smallest. This can be seen by the small number of references put forward by those who maintain this view. I believe the only passages which expressly refer to the lot as giving religious sanction to an appointment are two which occur in the Laws of Plato ^; and it will be sufficient to point out that the constitution of the ideal state which the philosopher is describing is essentially different from that of Athens, and that he is in the second of the two passages expressly showing how different is his ideal fi-om the "equality" of a democracy. He is gravely reminding his readers of what the lot ought to be. Everyone will agree that the lot could be regarded as a religious institution, and that it had been such in old times, but never- theless after the beginning of the fifth century it does not appear to have been so regarded at Athens. This is shown even by the poets. In the Tra- 1 Plato, Leges iii. 690 «=; vi. 757*. INTRODUCTION. 9 gedians mention is often made of the lot; and occasionally in such words that we are reminded it had a religious origin. But this is only the case when it is mentioned in direct connection with the services of some temple \ In no other cases is it spoken of as religious ; and never do we find at- taching to its use the awe and mystery which belongs to other more impressive means of divine utterance. Even in ^Eschylus it has none of the associations which belong to oracles and dreams. Still more is this true of Euripides. We find in the Heracleidae one striking instance of this " secvi- larisation " of the lot. Macaria says she is willing to be made a sacrifice to Demeter, who has demanded the offering of a maiden. lolaus demurs. He represents that it would be juster if she and her sisters drew lots, and selected the victim in this way. But Macaria will not hear of this; such a death would not please her. ovfc av Odvoifjui rfj TV')(r) \a')(ova iyca' It would be wanting in the graciousness which belongs to a voluntary sacrifice. And Euripides does not think it necessary to put into the mouth of either of his characters the suggestion that to submit to the will of the goddess expressed in this way would be even more gracious than self-willed to force oneself upon her^. This and similar passages do not go far: but 1 Eur. Ion, 415. iEsch. Eum. 33. 2 Eur. Heracleidae 547. 3 Mr Frazer in the Golden Bough gives an account of an old 10 INTRODUCTION. they are some evidence that the religious feeling connected with the lot was, even in a matter directly connected with the gods, extremely weak, and point to the fact, not that the political use of the lot was a religious ceremony, but that the constant use of it for secular purposes had almost completely destroyed the old religious associations. So when Socrates freely expressed contempt for the lot, this was made the ground for a charge of political discontent, but it is never referred to as connected with the accusations of atheism. And the speeches of the orators afford stronger testi- mony to the same phenomenon. These clever men who are so ready to use every fallacy likely to be effective and appeal to every prejudice or common- place likely to give them the appearance of right, never once, in the speeches which are preserved, allude to the lot as sacred ; and this though the audience they were addressing was in nearly every case selected by the lot. The absence of such a reference is sometimes startling. There is a pas- sage in Deinarchus where he makes a passionate appeal to the dicasts to condemn Philocles. "The people," he says, "have deprived this man of his office; they did not think it right or safe that he should longer have the care of their children, and custom which used to prevail in many parts of Scotland ; pieces of dough, one of which is blackened, are put into a hat ; the inhabitants one after another take each one of the pieces blind- folded out of the hat. The one who draws the black piece is a victim. He is not now burnt, but part of the company make a show of putting him into the fire. Vol. ii. p. 255 — 6. INTRODUCTION. 11 will you, you who are guardians of the democracy and the laws, you whom chance and the lot have appointed to give justice for the people, will you spare him^?" If he could have done so without being ridiculous would not Deinarchus have said ^€09 not Tv^n ? It is scarcely too much to say that not only did neither he nor his audience believe in the religious connections of the lot, but that they did not even pretend to do so. For this is not a single case. We have for instance a speech by Lysias written in defence of a man who had been appointed ^ovXevrr]^, but had been accused on his So/afjuaaia^. He had been ap- pointed by the lot : his opponents wished to unseat him on political grounds. Lysias never uses the obvious topic, he never warns his hearers that the man whom the lot has selected has acquired a peculiar right, and that to undo his appointment without due cause is a form of sacrilege. The conclusion I draw from these facts is that Conclu- the lot was religious in its origin, and that it was to *^ the latest times throughout Greece used in the ritual of the temples with a clear acknowledgment that its decision gave a divine sanction ; but that at Athens owing to its constant use for political pur- poses it was secularised till almost all recollection of its religious origin had disappeared; that the statesmen who developed the system in which it was used were not themselves guided by religious beliefs, and that, even if they were to some extent helped by a certain superstitious feeling among the 1 Deinarchus, in Philoclen 15 — 16. ^ Lysias, pro Mantitheo. 12 INTRODUCTION. poorer people, this was in no way the decisive cause of the success of their policy. Soon amidst all the busy political and legal life at Athens what there was of religious feeling about it died out. It was at Rome where it was seldom used, not at Athens ^7here it influenced the life of every citizen, that men talked of the "religio sortis\" We can then return to our original question: What was the object and effect of the extended use of the lot as it prevailed during the fifth and fourth centuries ? and I shall attempt to show how the Athenian statesmen used this relic of a dying super- stition as the means of carrying out with remarkable vigour their political ideals. The lot For whatever may be our difficulties the Greeks themselves seem to have had no doubt why the lot was used at Athens, nor what its effect was. On this they are explicit. Election by lot was a demo7 cratic institution ; more, it was necessary to a demo- cracy. In this they are almost unanimous ; friends and enemies of democracy all agree on this point that in a perfectly democratic state magistrates will 1 It is only necessary to read Fustel de Coulanges' account of the democracy (La Cite antique, iv. ch. 11) to see how impossible his theory is. It leads him to a direct misstatement of fact when he says "Les magistrats pretres ^taient choisis par le sort. Les magistrats qui n'exer(;aient que des fanctions d'ordre public dtaient 61us par le peuple." And jae is quite unable on his hypothesis to give any clear explanation of the Council, This is the more to be regretted as the mistake comes from exaggerating the importance of what is within certain limits a most useful suggestion, and one which has thrown much light on an obscure matter. demo- cratic. INTRODUCTION. 13 be elected by lot\ I know nothing which makes us feel so clearly our separation from the political world of the Greeks as this. Here is an institution which to us is almost incredible, and yet we find writer' after writer assuming that a city cannot be a real democracy without adopting it. ' ' The few adverse criticisms on it which have been preserved to us make this only more clear ; they are invariably the criticisms of men opposed to democracy, and objection to elections by lot is always accompanied by dislike of democracy. We are told that Socrates used to say that it was foolish to appoint the rulers of the city by lot ; no one would have confidence in a pilot or a carpenter or a musician who had been chosen in this way; and yet which had most power to harm, an incompetent magistrate or a bad artist ? But then Socrates was an irreconcilable in politics; it was not only election by lot but all the institutions of the city which he criticised ; and we know that not only did his objections appear to his contem- poraries foolish and pedantic, but his opinions on political matters and the free expression he gave to them were among the reasons why he was put to death as a bad citizen. Socrates thought the lot wrong and foolish ; that he did so was a proof of his anti-democratic bias I Even more striking is the attitude of the author 1 Herod, iii. 80 ; Plato, Rep. 561 a— b ; Aristotle, Rhet. i. 8. Muller-Striibing quotes Isocr. Areop. 20 — 27 as evidence that the lot was not democratic. On a point of historical fact the witness of Isocrates is of little value ; and he is here arguing from the peculiar circumstances of his own time, cf. pp. 96 — 7 ; and p. 39. 2 Xen. Mem. i. 2, 9. 14 INTRODUCTION. of the pamphlet " On the Constitution of the Athe- nians \" He is a vigorous and confident oligarch: for him life in a democratic state is scarcely worth living; his ideal is that the nobles (ol xRV^^ol) should rule: that the people should be their subjects, their slaves (BovXooy. All the institutions of Athens, election by lot included, are in his opinion causes of unendurable license and disorder. And yet he cannot refrain from expressing his admiration of the Athenian constitution, for he acknowledges that it completely secures what is desired ; it is democracy and therefore hateful to him and to every other right- minded man who loves order and good government ; but it is at least a successful democracy'; it is impossible to get a more perfect democracy than the Athenian; the people know what they want and they have got it ; election by lot, freedom of speech, offices open to all however ignorant and however uneducated — they are perfectly right he says when they regard these as an essential part of a democracy. He too is of opinion that democracy without its extravagances would be no democracy at all*. And this opinion was not peculiar to literary men, to philosophers and historians; it was the principle on which the practical men in Greece ^ 'Adrjvaltov iroXiTeia, formerly attributed to Xenophon. Cf. esp. i. 9, ei/vofjiia cannot be found in a democracy ; ii. 20, no good man can live iv b-qfioKpaTovfihi^ -rrdXei. 2 ii. 9, dwb TOTjTwv roivvv tQv ayadQiv Tdx^(TT dv 6 5^/ios eh dovkeiav KaTairiffOL. ^ ii. 26, 8r)fjL0KpaTtav 5' iyoj /xh avTip ti^ 5^Mi^ avyycyu(Jba-K(ij avrbv jxkv ycip eD irotelv Tract crvyyvcb/JLTj ecriv. * ii. 19 ; i. 1—8. INTRODUCTION. 15 acted Our knowledge of the internal constitutions of other states besides Athens is small, but it is sufficient to show us that when a state took a demo- cratic constitution election by lot was introduced along with other changes. We are specially told that this was the case at Syracuse* and at Tarentum^; and when Athens obliged her allies to adopt a democratic form of government, election by lot was as a matter of course included ^ Aristotle's account of the matter is very instruc- tive* : he generally speaks of " election " (xeiporovla, aipecn^) as either aristocratic or oligarchic ; for it gives influence to birth money or ability ; he recog- nises indeed that election by all the citizens is to some extent democratic, but he regards it as a cha- racteristic of the old moderate democracy {iraTpia Brj/jLOKpaTLa) and he contrasts this with the new {v€(0TaT7j Brj/jLOKpaTla) where offices are filled by lot^ Popular election is that moderate concession to democracy which is desirable in order to give the state permanence by interesting all classes in the government, but he consistently represents election by lot as a sign of what he calls the extreme democracy. On this point there can be no doubt : election by Objections lot was regarded by those who had experience of it H^idered. as essentially democratic : if this is the case we may 1 Diodorus, xiii. 34. 2 Ar. Pol. vii. 5 (quoted by Gilbert, Gr. St. ii. p. 245, n. I). 3 C. I. A. i. 9. 4 Pol. ii. 11, 1273*; vi. 9, 1294^; vii. 2, 131?!^; vii. 2, 1318*. 5 Pol. viii. 5, 1305*. 16 INTRODUCTION. add, it was democratic. It would require some very strong proofs to justify us in putting aside the almost unanimous verdict of the Greeks themselves on a point on which they had complete experience and of which we have no knowledge except what we gain from them. When then a modern historian^ informs us that election by lot was not a democratic but an oli- garchic institution, and that it was introduced at Athens not to strengthen the democracy but to temper it and make it less repugnant to the defeated oligarchs, we look for some very weighty reasons to justify the paradox. The paradox has been stated lately and has met with a certain amount of fa- vour. This is partly due to the interest which any novelty must arouse in a subject which has been so thoroughly discussed as Athenian constitutional history; a new theory however paradoxical is sure to command a hearing if promulgated with sufficient confidence and at sufficient length ; a boldly stated novelty will attract the reader who is wearied with the study of innumerable discussions of minute details. But this favourable reception is also due to the fact that it has no rival: historians have recognised that as a matter of fact election by lot^ was democratic, but they have not clearly explained the reason why it was so. Generally speaking it seems clear that if any one could be elected to any office, and if the poorest and most ignorant citizen had an equal chance with an Alcmseonid or a pupil of 1 Miiller-Striibing, Aristophanes und die historische Kritik, p. 206 etc. INTRODUCTION. l7 Gorgias, the state where this was the case was not an aristocracy; but still the necessity and the ad- vantage of the system are not obvious ; the orthodox traditional view is vague and has no firm foundation, so that one is naturally tempted to say there is something in the new theory : and many who do not accept it as a whole have altered their statement of the older view, and tell us that, although the lot was of course democratic, yet it was after all to a certain extent aristocratic too\ Our object must be then to try and understand not only why election by lot was democratic, but why the ancients considered it essential to a complete democracy. In order to do so, it will be necessary to recall What the certain peculiarities of ancient democracy, which it „J^^/ is easy for us to ignore. The fact that the word ^y Demo- ' " democracy " is still in constant use among us, and that we apply it to political phenomena of the present day, is a great obstacle to our understanding of Greek History. The danger is the greater that the modern use of the word is so nearly akin to the original meaning ; but none the less the word has not now the same connotation as it had 2000 years ago ; 1 I do not mean to deny that the lot was often used in states which were not democratic, and that in the period before the Persian wars it was introduced in many oligarchies. As will be seen below, I believe that it was. All I wish to make clear is that, as used at Athens from the time of Persian wars, it was of the very essence of the democracy. The importance of the experiment at Athens caused the older use in oligarchic states to be forgotten just as it destroyed the religious significance. Cf. Curtius, Griechische Geschichte, i. 377 (3rd edition). [Cf. Appendix.] j H. 2^ 18 INTRODUCTION. and it requires the greatest care when we are deal- ing with Greek history and reading Greek books to keep our minds free from modern associations, and to preserve the idea which we connect with the word as pure simple and clearly defined as was that of the Greeks. We have a double difficulty to sur- mount in achieving this, for not only do we use Greek words when we speak of modern politics, but also our method of education tempts us to think of modern events under Greek forms. Our first acquaintance with political thought comes through Thucydides and Aristotle, and we try to fit the wisdom we have learnt from them to the facts of modern life. By so doing we not only lose the freedom of thought necessary to comprehend new facts, but we uncon- sciously spoil our apprehensions of Greek life. By trusting too much to the fancied analogies of modem times we lose in the vividness and niceness of our conceptions of ancient politics \ The assumption which in one form or another seems to me to underlie most of the difficulties which historians discover in understanding why the lot is democratic, depends on a confusion of this kind. 1 Muller-Striibing is one of the worst offenders. He tries xi. • ^^f. ries because it seems as it their very variety were political, evidence that the basis common to all is unsound. Instead of enquiring whether it was the ra^juia^ roov KocvMV TTpocoBcov, OT the 7rpVTavtiop. Thuc. ii. 65. Aristotle in the Politics never speaks of elections as party affairs, nor does he refer to party elections connected with them. On the subject of the election of generals see Droysen, Hermes, IX. We hear most about the elections of exceptional officials such as ambassadors. A curious fact is preserved about one of these elections. Dem. de corona 149 (277) tells us that .^schines was nominated {irpo^X-qdeLs) to the office of irvXaydpas, and elected rptuv 26 INTRODUCTION. expect. And I propose by a short examination of certain aspects of the Athenian constitution to show why this was so. When this point has been cleared up, we shall be in a better position to understand the Greek view of election by lot. The reason It was impossible that at Athens elections should of this. ]iave political importance; it was impossible just because Athens was a complete democracy : for the same reason that election by lot was introduced. Elections can only be of political importance when the elected magistrates have for some period con- siderable independence of action, and when the sove- reign power from which they derive their authority is exercised only intermittently. In such cases the people (supposing that the sovereign power and ultimate appeal is with them) does not itself govern the country; it delegates its powers to elected representatives who within wide limits are free Contrast to do just as they like. Hence the only way which of ancient ^^le people have of directing the policy of the state modern is to elect men pledged to follow certain lines. From ^acv *^^^ necessity springs inevitably the whole system of party elections. Where the country is governed by an elected assembly, or an elected head of the state^ the elections to these offices, in as much as they are almost the only occasions when the people exercises its sovereign power, must be events of the greatest importance. In a state like Athens just the reverse is the case. It was the essence of the constitution that the demos should itself rule : it did not, as do the people in England or France, appoint its rulers ; it INTRODUCTION. 2T did. -Hot delegate its power ; its sovereignty was not intermittent, it was continually exercised. And in consequence the magistrates at Athens had a posi- tion quite other to that held by ministers in a modern democracy. They were not the men to whose wisdom and discretion the votes of the people for a time entrusted the supreme management of affairs : they were appointed to carry out the decrees of the people and to obey its commands. The demos could not bind itself by any election to follow any set policy or to adhere to any plan, for the eKKXTja-la met at least once a month and could at any time be summoned, and at each meeting it was able to discuss and alter the decisions of a previous meeting. Suppose that in any year the aTpaTrjyoL were all chosen from the war party, that these had won at the elections ; the people did not thereby deprive themselves of the power of making peace during the year; a popular orator of the opposite party could bring forward a motion and carry it. But if he did so the position of the generals was unaltered ; they did not resign, they had simply to carry out the policy of which they disapproved \ In England -Oi:, 1 Beloch (Att. Politik, p. 15), "Die Geschafte des Landes aus dem Bema der Pnyx auszufuhren war in Athen noch weniger moglich als heute von der Tribune des Parlaments." This is surely exactly wrong. The object of the whole arrangement of the constitution was to enable orators to guide the business of the state from the Assembly. If he refers to the German Parliament the statement is absurd : a German parlia- mentary leader has no influence at all on the conduct of business. If the reference is to the English Parliament it is wrong, because the Trpoo-rdrTjs rod di^fiov had without office just as much power as an English parliamentary leader has with office. Cf. infra, p. 112 etc. 28 INTRODUCTION. America the elections are of importance because during the period which follows the people are without any direct control over the fate of the country : they have given their decision, and must abide by it. In Athens, where the sovereign as- sembly met constantly, the elections had in conse- quence no political import; men were chosen not for the policy which they advocated but for their ability and character. The question between candi- dates was always a personal not a party one. An election might be a sign of the popularity and in- fluence of men who supported different policies : it could not bind the people to follow one or the other. If we remember this, we shall no longer be dis- turbed by the small number of references to elections which we find in ancient writers, nor wonder at the small place which they filled in the political con- troversies and passions of the time; and we shall cease to enquire which official held the place of our Prime Minister. And when we realise how this direct, sovereignty of the people worked, we shall see why election by lot was considered essential to the maintenance of democracy. Demo- Sir Henry Maine in his book on Popular Govem- Tnverud ^^^^ reminds us that democracy is a form of monarchy, government, and objects to modern incorrect uses of the word. That the word should have changed its meaning, and should be now used to describe social tendencies is natural and harmless, so long as we recognise the fact ; it is however of great import- ance that we should remember that the Greeks who INTRODUCTION. 29 invented the word did mean by it a definite simple form of government. A Greek had no doubt what he meant by a Democracy ; it was a city in which the people gathered together at a definite place in one large visible assembly governed the whole state. When we speak of popular government we mean by " people " a great mass of men living long distances apart from one another who have never seen one another and who never will. The Greeks meant a very limited number of men who were accustomed to come together in a definite place. People with us is a vague idea: the demos to an Athenian was a concrete thing which he had often seen and heard ; it was the eKKXrjala. So too by " government " we mean a vague ill-defined control of the government. In no modern country does the people govern ; it is incapable of doing so, it is not sufficiently organised ; the work of government is too complicated. Parlia- ment, or Ministers, or the President, govern : the people appoint them and more or less control them. But at Athens the 817/^09 did govern. It was not primarily an elective body, that function fell into secondary importance ; it was not a legislative body, that was the only duty which was not directly within its sphere ; it was a judicial, and above all an executive body. Sir Henry Maine expresses this by saying that JDemocracy is inverted Monarchy. In a monarchy the king governs ; he has servants, he has advisers ; responsible ministers he has none : statesmen are his servants, they do his bidding, they may offer advice, but if their advice be not taken they must be 30 INTRODUCTION. prepared to obey none the less. A favourite may become powerful, but his power depends on the king's favour; there may be rivalry, there may be antagonistic influences; round the bed-chamber of the king, or the salon of his mistress ambitious men contend for the privilege of executing his commands and influencing his will. But great parties there are none, and in a perfect monarchy there are no great ministers: the king himself decides all ques- tions, officials have only to prepare them for his consideration ; he has not only the position of a king, but the toil and labour of a ruler. And so in a perfect democracy the people does all which in a monarchy is the work of the king. All questions of government, all the difficulties of administration, every innovation in every depart- ment comes directly before the people : the officials do not decide anything, they only formulate the questions which come before the sovereigu people. They do not do the work for the people. They are not appointed to represent it. They are there as clerks or secretaries; their duty is to bring order and arrangement into the mass of details ; they help the people to govern, but they help as a freedman helped the Roman Emperor. The people, like the king, has its advisers and favourites, those who know the art of influencing the royal will; these .are the orators in the eK/cXTjcrla, and the first favourite of the time is o 7rpoaTdTT}<; rov hrjfjbov. But, like the power of the royal favourites, their power does not come from office, and office is not necessary to it; the people, like the king, prefers INTRODUCTION. 31 often to appoint to ojffice men whose advice it would never take; men who do not personally please it, but whose ability and integrity it respects. And as in a perfect monarchy we find no great ministers of state, but the king surrounded by his satellites and courtiers rules alone, — his ministers having no part in the rule, nor any independence of action, — so in a perfect democracy we shall not expect to find great offices; the magistrates will have only to prepare business for the Assembly ; they will make ruling easier, but they will not take upon themselves part of the duties of ruling ; they will be wheels in the great machine, not separate machines. Therefore, if the state is to be a democracy. Results of there must be no powerful officials; for demo- cracy means rule by the demos, government by the eKK\7)(TLa ; and the demos or eKKXrjcrla, if it is really to rule, cannot allow any other power to exist in the state, not even if it is a body which derives its authority from the demos. The Greeks themselves were quite clear on this point \ They saw well enough that the power of the demos was like that of a monarch, and that a "democracy" could allow no power in the state independent of the Assembly. The " tyrant demos " was a very stern reality to Thucydides and Plato 1 Cf. Aristotle, Pol. viii. (v.) 11, 1313»'— 1314 Kal rd. xepl tV b-qfiOKparlav bk yipSfieva t^p reXevraLav rvpavviKk iravra, Kal yhp 6 dTjfios eXvai ^OTuXeTai fiovapxos, dib Kal 6 K6\a^ Trap' d./j.s vS/xovs irpid/ievos. THE COUNCrL. 55 the charge it would hardly have been passed over so lightly. It is probably nothing but a characteristic method of expressing annoyance that Demosthenes had been fortunate enough to get elected. The reference is, however, of some interest as being one of the clearest cases in which we find that a politician was to some extent helped in his measures by the fact that he was a member of the council. Others do occur, but on the whole hardly with sufficient frequency to justify us in supposing that a seat was necessary for a politician, or that he could in any way reckon upon being a member. It seems as though most well-known men were in the council at least once (though this cannot be proved for nearly all); but, as we must remember, to have a seat once was not more than any citizen might hope for\ The only other evidence on the matter comes Evidence from some lists which have been preserved of Pry- tanies, belonging to the fourth century I Of these three give about the full number of councillors belonging to one tribe. An examination of them gives the following results : (1) The number of members belonging to each deme appears to vary with the size of the deme, and the number elected for the same deme in different 1 In a great number of cases in which men are mentioned in connection with the council, the man was not necessarily himself a member, but was present either as an oiBflcial of some kind, or simply as a private man there on business. Cf. Lysias, v. 33. When we are told that Pericles was regular in his attendance at the council, it does not follow that he was a member. He went in his capacity of general. 2 C. I. A. II. 864 etc. q ( of inscrip- tions. 56 THE COUNCIL. i years seems to be constant. From this we may ' gather that at the election a certain number were / chosen from each deme, and that the members were / not chosen from the whole tribe indiscriminately. (2) There are a few cases where the names of the same deme are preserved for more than one year. Among these only one case of re-election is to be found. This perhaps shows that re-election was not very frequent. (3) No names of distinguished politicians occur; but on the other hand there are a large number of names which can be identified as occurring, (a) in the private speeches of the orators, (/3) in lists of trierarchs, (7) as members of distinguished families. However, a very large proportion of the names are completely unknown, many being names which occur nowhere else in Greek history and must there- fore belong to families of no distinction or wealth. On the whole, so far as we can see, the different strata of Athenian society are each fairly represented. There is no evidence that wealthy and distinguished men abstained from sitting in the council, nor is there a larger number of them in these lists than would be a fair proportion. (4) It is remarkable that three times near relatives (twice two brothers, and once father and son) sit together. This can hardly be a coincidence. Leading The conclusion from this evidence is that we statesmen j^^^^ ^^ reason for supposing that public men could necessarily in any way command a seat in the council, and it would, I think, be difficult to find the record of any events in Athenian history which would justify the THE COUNCIL. 57 assertion that a place in it was necessary to an ambitious man. It was possible to rule the whole state without having a seat in it. How this was so will be seen if we examine more minutely what the duties of the council were\ The council was not, as we are apt to think, a Duties of dignified deliberative body, where men met together council. quietly in order to discuss and prepare schemes for the public welfare, which should afterwards be laid before the Assembly and receive its sanction. Had the council had to initiate and decide upon policy, the leading orators must have been members of it ; and had they been members it would doubtless have acquired this function. But, as it was, its duties though no less important were far less impos- ing. It was not a deliberative, but an executive body; it was concerned not with policy, but with business. It had to carry out the decrees of the Assembly ; it was occupied with innumerable points of detail ; it had to make decisions, not on matters of peace and war or internal reforms, but on the appoint- ment of subordinate officials, on the amount of tribute to be paid by some ally, the necessity for rebuilding warehouses, or restoring triremes. Its time was occupied with the inspection of accounts, the mak- ing of contracts, the paying of money, the hearing of 1 If I am right in supposing that the method of appointment prevented the leading politicians sitting regularly in the council, it will also follow that no one else could procure his election or re-election, and therefore that re-election did not prevail to such an extent as to interfere with the truth of the principle which I stated above, pp. 49 — 50. Xevfia. 58 THE COUNCIL. petitions from individuals, the reception of informa- tion about the position of the enemy's fleet, or the price of corn in the Euxine; in fact, with the innu- merable matters of administration which in a modern state are brought before the permanent officials \ A reference to its most prominent duties will make this clear. (1) irpo^oTU' vXJtrhe most important of its duties was perhaps the preparation of business for the Assembly; it is well known that no decree could be passed 1 Of. [Xenophon] 'Ad-qvaiwv UoXirela, iii. 2, etc. for the duties of the council ; — the chief are, the appointment of 400 trierarchs every year, the assessment of the tribute every four years, to decide judicial questions, et tls rrjv vavv ixt] eiria-Kevd^ei t] kutolko- dofxeX TL 8r)fx6(nou. It is difficult to understand to what the ttoXXo, irepl vofiiov 64(rews in iii. 2 refers. Boeckh, p. 187 (208), gives an account of the financial activity of the council, which shows well the kind of work it had to do : — " It had, according to the pamphlet on the Athenian Constitu- tion, to occupy itself with provision of money, with reception of the tribute, and as we can conclude from another source, with other matters connected with the tribute, with the administration of the marine and the sanctuaries ; the leasing of the customs was conducted under its supervision, those who had public money or sacred money from the state had to pay it in the presence of the council, or it had to exact payment according to the contracts, so that it was entitled to arrest and imprison the farmers or their sureties and collectors, if they did not pay ; in the council chamber the Apodectai gave their report on the receipts and the money which was due ; in the presence of the council the treasurers of the goddess handed over and took over the treasure and received the fines ; it determined the administration of the money, even in small matters, such as the pay of the poets ; we have especial mention of its superintendence over the cavalry which was main- tained by the city, and the examination of the invalids who were supported at the public expense, as part of its duties ; the public debts are paid under its guidance." THE COUNCIL. 59 which had not been introduced officially by the council. The object of this rule is simple ; it was not desired to give the council a special influence, nor to restrict the freedom of debate in the As- sembly; it was not in any way a law which as at Kome gave the magistrates alone the right of introducing business. This rule did not weaken the Assembly, but strengthened it, because it provided for the proper arrangement of debates. The Pry- tanies summoned the Assembly, and, as the chief committee, the council had to prepare business for it. ^. It was then only natural that they should have notice beforehand of all measures which would be in- troduced, since they would have to make public the matters to be discussed, and to arrange the order of business. And, again, anyone who has had experience of public debates will know how difficult it is to get business done, and especially what trouble is caused by inaccuracy in the wording of motions. Now we know that the Athenians were very particular on this point; they took great care to provide that there were no verbal discrepancies in their laws, and no discrepancy between the laws and decrees; it was the duty of the council to see that all motions brought before the Assembly were properly worded. If an orator wished to propose a motion, he had first to move that the council introduce a Trpo^ovXevfia on the subject ; they had to consider the matter of the proposal he wished to make, and then embody it in a motion in such a way as seemed to them most convenient ; in this way provision was made 60 THE COUNCIL. for a consideration of the form of a Psephism before the motion itself came before the Assembly. As a rule the orator would doubtless be consulted by the council, and if he were a man of position we may imagine they would propose the Trpo^ovXev/jua in the very words which he suggested. There would be another reason for this law. When a motion was proposed it would often be diffi- cult, to tell at first what would be its result if passed, and questions would be raised to which the answers would only be found by special enquiry. This it would be the duty of the council to make. They as the centre of the executive government, in constant communication with all the officers, and with powers to summon and examine all witnesses, would be able to collect the evidence to be laid before the Assembly. This work of the drafting and preparing motions is really part of the subordinate work of the execu- tive officers, for it is a way of helping to the attain- ment of an end which is proposed by someone else\ The council in doing this was not directing the state, it was only helping other people to do so, and giving effect to their wishes'^. And it is an im- portant confirmation of this view that in the last few years inscriptions have been discovered from which it 1 The fact that an orator was always held responsible for any motion proposed by him shows that the council had not power seriously to alter the matter of a decree, and that in the exercise of its Probouleutic duties it did not in any way concern itself with the wisdom of the policy proposed. 2 This is shown too by Aristotle's distinction between ij j8ou\^ and rrpo^ovXoL. Cf. infra, p. 74. THE COUNCIL. 61 appears that there was at Athens a body of men called avyypa(f)eLf; whose special duty it was to help avyypa- in drafting decrees \ We are not able to say with *^"^' confidence whether they were members of a perma- nent bureau, or whether the men were appointed, as in the case of the other exceptional officials, only when their help was specially wanted, but we have the record of their existence and activity in the text of decrees which had been drawn up by them. In these cases, though the draft of the bill, as on all other occasions, was introduced to the Assembly by the Prytanies, the council had not really performed any probouleutic duties at all ; they simply brought for- ward what the o-vyypa(f>€U had proposed. We find another instance of a similar procedure in the case where a single individual is commissioned by the Assembly to draw up the text of a decree, and then the council is ordered^ to bring his proposal before the people. In matters of foreign policy also the duty of the council was limited to the introduction of a treaty proposed either by Athenians who as am- bassadors had been empowered to conduct nego- ciations, or by the ambassadors of other states, or, 1 Cf . Schoell, Commentationes in honorem Mommsennii ; Foucart, Bulletin de Correspondance Hellenique, 1880, p. 225; Sauppe, Index lect. Acad. Gottingen, 1880 — 81 ; also C. I. A. i. 58; iv. 27^. They are mentioned before the end of the fifth century. 2 C. I. A. 27^ w. 57—61. ire pi 5^ tov eXalov tt}s airapxm ^vyypdxf/O'as Adfnrup iiridet^aTd} ttj ^ovXrj iirl rijs ivdrrjs irpvravelas, 7] 5e jSoyXrj es top hrniov e^eveyK^ro) iirdvayKes. The decree of which this is a clause is proposed by Lampon himself. 62 THE COUNCIL. finally, of proposals made by the council of the allies \ It seems then as though the duties of the council in preparing decrees varied greatly. As it had to arrange the order of business in the Assembly, all decrees had to be brought before it for preliminary consideration ; but it does not follow that it had full power of discussing and altering them. If, as some- times was the case, a proposal was to be made of such a nature that exceptional skill and judgement was necessary in drawing up the text, the matter was generally entrusted by the Assembly to an excep- tional commission of one or more men. In the case of a large number of motions which were introduced by the enterprise of a single orator, the council would simply adopt the words proposed by the author of the decree, making perhaps such al- terations as were necessary to render it formally correct. The decrees introduced by the council on its own initiative would in number probably far 1 C. I. A. ii. 52 = Hicks, Greek H. Ins. 84. C. I. A. ii. 57^= ,, „ 94. From the year 378 there were present in Athens representatives of all the allied states. They had power to meet and discuss matters which concerned the alliance, but the ultimate decision was always reserved for the Athenian assembly. The council however could ask for their opinion on any matter. In the first of the cases quoted the council asks the allies to consider the matter, and give their opinion to the Assembly, {roi/s avfi/xdxovs Soy/xa i^epeyKcTv els rbv drj/j-ov, 6ti om ai/Tois ^ovXevofihois doKy apicrrov elvai.) In the second the allies have communicated their opinion to the council, and the council incorporates it in a TrpoPo^Xev/xa. {iirei8r] dk ol ffifxixaxoi 86y/xa elaTjvwyKav els tt)v ^ovXtjv 5^xe(r^ai ttjv avfilJLaxia-v...Kal i] jSouXi; irpov^offKevaev /caret ra^rci.) Cf. also p. 66. THE COUNCIL. 63 exceed these other classes, but theh^ separate im- portance would not be so great. The council would be responsible for all the decrees connected with the ordinary management of the state, constantly re- curring votes of money, permission to repair public buildings, grants of citizenship, votes of thanks; matters which required a vote of the Assembly, but which would as a rule be passed without opposition, and often without discussion \ In these purely administrative matters the coun- cil took the initiative, and its proposals were doubt- less generally adopted, for it was the representative of the permanent administrative offices. Had the council been a strong body, one which had a spirit and desires of its own, its Probouleutic duties would have been a danger to the freedom of the Assembly, for the power of initiative not only in subordinate points of administration but in great questions of policy might easily have been lost to the larger body. The Assembly would have existed only to discuss, to adopt, or reject the proposals of the council. It was a result of the method of appointment by lot to the council that this did not happen, and that, while it performed the duties of preparing and arranging business, it did not put any check on the complete freedom of discussion in the Assembly''. 1 A great number of the decrees which we possess are of this nature, as they record votes of thanks and honours to foreign envoys ; they would be part of the ordinary international courtesy, and were naturally proposed by the council on its own authority. 2 We hear of a board called o-vXXoyeTs toO brjixov, but are not 64 THE COUNCIL. (2) Ad- The administrative duties were so various that vnnistra- ^^ ^.^^^ Qjjly ioke, a few typical instances of cases duties. where we are well informed concerning them. The extent of these duties will be more apparent when we come to deal with the other magistrates with whom the council was intimately connected. For my present purpose it is sufficient to point out that the administrative duties of the council were always connected with matters of detail ; there is no sign that it could form decisions of any political moment. It could only carry out the policy of the Assembly. This is very clearly shewn by a decree which is preserved to us of the latter part of the 4th century, and is worth quoting. In 325 B.C. an expedition was to be sent out to carry into execution a plan for settling colonies in the Adriatic. A decree was brought before the people to give the orders necessary to the proper fitting out of the expedition \ After various orders to the in- spectors of the dockyards, and other officials specially concerned, come the following clauses : — " And the Council of 500 shall superintend the fitting out of the expedition, and punish according to the laws any of the trierarchs who are unruly. And the Prytanies shall provide that the council be in constant session on the quay till the Expedition has sailed. And the told what they had to do. Cf. Boeckh, vol. ii. p. 115 (3rd Ed.) ; C. I. A. ii. 607, 741, 1174. It is difficult to see what scope there was for the activity of a special board in summoning the Assembly. They are apparently different from an elected officer of the same name mentioned by Harpocration. 1 C. I. A. ii. 809 b. THE COUNCIL. 65 Athenian people shall choose* ten men from all the Athenians, and they shall superintend the fitting out of the expedition in the same way as the council is ordered to do. And the council and the Prytanies after superintending the outfit shall be crowned by the people v/ith a golden crown to the value of 1000 drachmas. And if anything is necessary to supple- ment this decree, the council shall have power to pass a decree, so long as it does not invalidate anything which has been decreed by the people." This we may consider as the regular form of procedure ; it is an excellent illustration of the posi- tion which the council held. The Assembly declares for a policy, arranges the general principles on which it shall be carried out, and then leaves the manage- ment of all details, within certain limits, to the council. When we are told that the council was responsible for keeping up the number of the tri- remes, the case is precisely similar ; the Assembly made the decree or law which determined the size of the fleet ; the council was responsible for its execu- tion. It was moreover especially the duty of the council Financial to watch over the public finances. Of this I shall ^^*^^* have more to say later, for, as I shall point out, the management of the finances is more difficult to under- stand than any other part of the system. It will be sufficient here to recall the fact that the council had no power alone to levy any tax, or spend any 1 That these dTroo-ToXets, being exceptional officials, should be chosen by popular election is, as I shall afterwards show, in ac- cordance with the invariable custom. H. 5 66 THE COUNCIL. money without authority. What it had to do was to see that the regular taxes were properly collected or sold, and that the money was paid in by the separate officials ; to decide questions in disputed cases about the assessment of the tax ; and to pay money as required to the various officials. The council was in financial matters of special im- portance, and for the following reason. All the money of the state passed through its hands, and it was in constant communication with all the other officials ; the control of the finances therefore depended on the information which was to be found either in the council chamber itself, or in the offices of the various boards which were grouped round it. And more- over the council had the duty of calling the attention of the Assembly to any deficit. For as it was re- sponsible for the management of all the various public services, and as these could not be maintained without supplies, if when the officials applied to the council there was no money to give them, the council would have to ask the Assembly for more money; it would have to state what the deficiency was, and would perhaps accompany the statement by a recommendation of some way of raising the sum. There was however no constitutional custom which compelled the Assembly to accept the sug- gestion made by the council. Foreign It might be thought that there was one duty of relations, ^j^^ council which formed an obvious exception to the principle I have laid down. It had to receive foreign envoys, and consider the terms of any treaty or agreement which was to be proposed. This was THE COUNCIL. 67 not however different from other occasions on which it prepared business for the Assembly. The council could not in any way influence the decision of the Assembly; all that it had to do was to learn from the strangers the business on which they had come, the powers which they had, and the terms which they were ready to propose. In accordance with this information a Probouleuma would then be draw^n up introducing the subject to the Assembly. In this as in other cases the object of the Probouleuma was not in any way to influence the decision on the question to be debated, but to make clear what that question was. This is abundantly evident from the inscriptions, and in those cases where our other authorities give an account of the reception of ambassadors there is nothing inconsistent with it. For instance, Thucydides in the 5th book^ gives an account of the reception of a Spartan embassy at Athens in connection with the diplomatic com- plication which resulted on the peace of Nicias. We find that it was first, as was of course necessary, brought before the council, and the next day it was introduced by the Prytanies to the Assembly. In the preliminary hearing before the council there }v. 2 Antiphon, de morte Herodis, 69, tells a story of how one year all the Hellenotamiai but one were put to death on a charge of peculation ; and how afterwards it was discovered that they were innocent. 96 THE OFFICIALS. Athenian system, to get rid entirely of the natural prejudice we feel against the lot. This prejudice is so strong that we are always inclined to think the Athenians must have shared our distrust of it ; and attempts have often been made to show that this was the case. Historians have appealed to two facts to prove this: — to the institution of the SoKL/mao-ia, and to the fact that a large number of officials were appointed by popular election, and not by the lot. I think, however, that a short examination of these two points will help to prove my position, (1) that the Athenians felt no distrust of the lot, but regarded it as the most natural and the simplest way of appointment ; (2) that, in consequence, the general rule was that all magistrates were appointed by the lot: the only exceptions (in the first period of the democracy) being those who had military or semi- military duties, and those who held exceptional ap- pointments which were outside the ordinary routine administration of the state. The Doki- The popular account of the SoKi/juaala is that it was an institution invented to check the worst results of the lot^ : men, we are told, felt so much distrust of its working that they prepared a means of interfering with its action. It was an opportunity given to the people to prevent someone, who had been legally appointed, from holding office, on no other grounds than that they held him unfit to do so. This - Busolt, Gr. Gesch. vol. ii. p. 469. Gegen die schlimmsten Zufalligkeiten des Looses schiitzte man sich durch die Priifung Oder Dokimasie. Gilbert, St. i. 208 — 10, takes the same view though less decidedly. masia. THE OFFICIALS. 97 view is founded on the statements of the orators : and there is no doubt that, in the 4th century, the hoKL^iaala was used as a means of preventing men who were suspected of oligarchic sentiments from holding an office which they had won by the lot or otherwise*. It is, as I have elsewhere pointed out, from the observation of this fact that a great deal of the difficulty about the lot has arisen. If however my view of the lot is correct, it will be necessary to some extent to restate our account of this pheno- menon. It was, I believe, an abuse which had grown up at the end of the Peloponnesian war, and was a direct result of the shock given to the whole state by the two oligarchic revolutions. If we look below the speeches of the orators to the constitution of the court, it is obvious that the BoKtfiaala was not introduced simply to rectify the verdict of the lot : men chosen by popular elections were just as much subject to it. It was not the intention to allow the popular voice a veto on any appointment by means of an accusation of "incivism." The object of the Bofci/juacrLa was simply to keep out of office men who were legally incapacitated. Men who were not complete citizens by birth, who were not of a certain age, who were in debt to the state or who had incurred drcfiia by committing certain offences, were by the laws excluded from office; 1 Cf. Lysias, Or. 26. 16 passim ; esp. 26, § 9, 6 ^ets rbv -rrepl tQv boKLfxacn.Q3v vbfiov oiix rJKicTTa irepl rQ>v kv dXiyapxiq. dp^dvrup 'iveKO. edrjKep. This cannot be true unless the boKLfxaala was a quite new institution : but if it was we should expect some more special reference to its introduction. 98 THE OFFICIALS. and some offices could only be held by men pos- sessed of a certain property. Now it was one of the characteristics of the Athenian constitution that it provided a definite regular way of doing everything however unimportant: nothing was left uncertain. Supposing anyone were chosen by lot or by popular election whose qualification was doubtful, consider- able inconvenience might arise if there were no regular procedure for dealing with the matter. To guard against this, the hoicL^aa-ia was introduced. The proceedings were as a rule almost formal : they consisted in putting to the newly elected magistrate certain questions ; if they were satisfactorily answered the matter was at an end: if it appeared that the man did not possess some of the qualifications he was excluded. The BoKc/jLao-la answered the same sort of purpose as when a candidate for a scholarship at a school or university is required to produce a certificate of birth. It was the opportunity which the official had of proving his legal qualifications : an opportunity which there must be somehow in every state ; and it is chiefly interesting as showing the great care taken by the builders of the consti- tution to procure efficiency by providing beforehand a means of settling all points \' 1 The best account of the matter is given by Hermann, Staatsalterthiimer, 149. Schoroann's account is also good: he says, " the doKifiaaia had nothing to do with the knowledge and abiHty requisite for the administration of the office, but only with the question whether the birth of the man fulfilled the conditions required, and whether his Ufe had been free from crime. Those offices for which a special capacity was necessary which could not be expected of every citizen were filled by popular THE OFFICIALS. 99 It was however possible that the candidate was not satisfied with the justice or validity of the verdict of the revising court ; this would especially be the case when, as often happened, private or political enemies had by their evidence procured his rejection. In a case of this kind there would be a dispute either of fact or law to be decided^: a dispute which might turn on the status of the mother of the candidate, or on the interpretation of some law disqualifying a particular class of persons. This dispute would have to be decided before a law-court, but the question would still be not, "Is it wise to let this man be elected ? " but, " Is this man legally dis- qualified?" The orators of course in these as in all other cases tried to bias the minds of the jury, and where it was convenient to do so did not shrink from boldly stating that the hoKi^aarla ought to take the form of an enquiry into the whole career of a citizen to election, and it was assumed that the people would not choose anyone of whose capacity it was not sufficiently convinced. On the other hand the people willingly had confidence that everyone who decided to become a candidate for any of the other offices which were filled by lot, would have the requisite capacity, and in fact was not so far wrong in this as may appear at first sight." This is one of the cases where it seems to me that the new school of historians have not improved on their predecessors. 1 So in Lysias, Or. 26, de Evandro. The real case is that Evajider has committed certain acts which disqualify for office : the defence is that he is defended by the amnesty (§ 16) : the speaker tries to create a prejudice against Evander and to make the case turn on what is best for the city ; and so far as he can makes it seem a question of the personal character of himself and his opponents. 7—2 100 THE OFFICIALS. see if he were fit to bear office*; but this was just as much an abuse as when in any ordinary civil suit they introduced extraneous matter in order to in- fluence the minds of the jury. No doubt they often succeeded. Many men, probably, were excluded from office on account of their oligarchic opinions, but this was a development caused by peculiar circumstances. Owing to the political struggles of the time a con- siderable number of men had become anfioL and disqualified for office : so far as the BoKifiaala excluded them it was not (except in cases where it was abused) an original expression of popular feeling, it was only the method of putting into execution a principle already established ^ We might find the nearest English parallel to it in the laws respecting the Roman Catholics. When they were disqualified by their religion from being elected or appointed to any post, the law was enforced by requiring every person who was elected or appointed to take the Sacrament. This was the hoKLfjuaala. By taking the Sacrament a man declared that he was not a Roman Catholic. At the same time it was open to anyone to give information that the man was really a secret Romanist, and thereby still get him excluded. Now no one would say that the ex- ^ e. g. Lysias, pro Mantitheo, 9, SoKd 54 ixol iv rats doKifiaa-iais diKacov elvuL iravrbs tov ^iov \6yov diddvaL. 2 So in Lysias, Or. 26, § 10, the argument seems to be : — a man who served as knight under the Thirty may not be a /SouXeur-^s, much more must a man who has done what this man has done be ineligible for the archonship: the speaker appeals to the law and says any reasonable interpretation of it will exclude him. THE OFFiciAik f : ; > '' ' '. ■ '.} : \WV istence of this and similar laws implied distrust of popular elections, or of appointment by govern- ment. But it is just what happened at Athens : only at Athens no one was excluded because of his opinions, only because he had committed certain actions. The inconveniences which may result from any uncertainty as to the legal qualifications of a man who has been appointed to a public office are so great that no further explanation is required why the Athenians should have taken care that the validity of the appointment should be thoroughly tested before the new officer entered upon his duties. Such a test there must always be. The only peculiarity of the Athenian system was that the name of the procedure, and (to a great extent) the procedure itself, was identical for all offices and all appointments. We disguise the similarity under difference of name ; we talk of the registration of voters, the .confirmation of bishops, election petitions ; but these are all only more cumbrous methods of doing what the Athenians did simply and in the same way for all offices by the SoKLfxaala. The fact that the Athenian courts did not always give an impartial verdict, and in fact did not even profess to do so, was a result of the whole constitution of the judicial system ; but it need not affect our judgment of the initial advantages of having some such procedure. At any rate the Athenian dicasteria were not more open in their disregard of the legal aspect of a case than was the House of Commons in W9. 7IJE OFFICIALS. Elected Officials. Military posts. the days when it used to hear election peti- tions\ If we turn now to the second point, the considera- tion of those offices which were not filled by lot, we shall not I think find any reason to suppose that the Athenians looked on the lot with distrust, or re- garded it as anything exceptional. There are always certain things which can only be done by men of special ability ; there must be cases in which the dangers which arise from possible incompetence are greater than any which come from the possibility that the magistrate will gain undue influence or misuse his power. This even the Athenians recognised ; election by lot was with them the rule, but they never attempted to make it a rule without an exception. The exceptions were however as few as possible. Of the regular magistrates only those were elected who were occupied with the actual command of men in war, or in the half-military establishments connected with the public education of the citizens. Much has been said about the aTparijyol: it has been truly 1 A curious contrast to the simplicity of the Athenian constitu- tion might be found in the difiiculty experienced in England of getting an authoritative decision on the qualifications for voting in any representative body. The uncertainty about the right of women to sit in a county council could not have occurred there, because the matter would at once have been brought before a special court which had to decide all such cases: and it would have been impossible that such a state of things should result as has been seen in England, when someone continues to exercise an oJBfice to which he has no claim because it is no one's duty to take steps in order to deprive him of it. THE OFFICIALS. 103 pointed out that at one period their power was very great, and the office to some extent an object of ambition for those who wished to direct the politics of the city; but the board of the arparTjyol were never other than generals \ Their duties were always, primarily, the management of naval and military matters ; secondarily, they at times repre- sented the state in its intercourse with other states and had jurisdiction over foreigners residing in the city. Political power they sometimes had: but it was chiefly because they were men who had influence as speakers and statesmen in the assembly. They were men of ability, and their experience was valuable : hence they were consulted by the govern- ing assemblies. They were, as generals, responsible for the safety of the state : hence any request which came from them, or any warning which they might give, was attended to at once. If they represented to the TTpvTaveL'i that there was business of urgent importance to be discussed, it was matter of tra- dition if not of law that the assembly should be summoned I They had the right of bringing all matters before the council, and with the council they were often chosen to represent the people in its intercourse with foreign powers; like all Athe- nian magistrates, even the lowest, they had extensive judicial duties, and they had as a necessary result of ^ This is shown clearly by the references to them in the Memorabilia of Xenophon. Socrates always speaks of the power of commanding an army as the first requisite of a general. Cf. iii. 1, 6 ; iii. 4. 2 C. I. A. i. 40, ad finem. 10^: ; ; •/ : , ' •/ ; ; ; •tbe piIjficials. their military power a large authority in financial matters. But it was their military duties which were the foundation of their power; and it was because of them that their appointment was never made by the lot. I do not know anything so remarkable as the fact that, notwithstanding the exceptional position which they occupied, these generals never did win a position independent of the assembly. It is not the extent but the limit of their authority which astonishes us. If we add to the generals the subordinate military officials, the tTTTra/o^o? and v\ap'y^o<^ and ra^iap'^o^, and certain other men who, like the (7a)(f>povLa-Tai or iTri/xeXrjTal rdciv i7]fi(ov, superintended the education of the young men, we shall, with the doubtful ex- ception of a few unimportant religious officials, find no regular officials who were not appointed by lot\ In all other cases where we are told that a man Excep- was elected to an official position we find that the OMces. office itself was an exceptional institution. I have already to some extent explained the importance of these offices, and shown how useful they were in supplementing the more established procedure. The 1 There are many offices concerning which our information is defective, e.g. the Tpi-qpoiroLoL and the eWrjvoTafdai. The eKXoyeis mentioned in C. I. A. i. 38 (of. Harpocr. sub voc. -Qp^drjaav yb.p iKXoyeis Trap' i^fup oh TrXeiara iddKci, xpT^/iara etvai) were men chosen to collect arrears of tribute from the allies. They were exceptional officers and their duties were partly military, as they had command over one or more triremes. Cf. Boeckh, Staats. d. A. p. 190. The same is true of the ra/crat, who were probably identical with ol iirl TOLS iroXeis whose election (xeLporovla) is mentioned C. I. A. i. 37. ^ THE OFFICIALS. 105 most important of them are the numerous appoint- ments for exceptional service as legate to a foreign power, or as representative of the state at some re- ligious festival. If an embassy had to be sent to treat with a foreign king, if the help of Dionysius was sought against Thebes or the help of Thebes against Philip, or if it was desired to break up an alliance be- tween Sparta and Persia, or to send a representative to the Amphiktyonic council, for this purpose men of ability and knowledge, leaders in the political world, must be chosen; and so the lot could not be used. Also those who were elected to these offices were temporarily surrounded with a pomp and importance which marked them out from their fellow citizens. These appointments had a dignity of their own, they were highly paid, they gave opportunities for gaining exceptional experience and knowledge, they gave to those who held them peculiar advantages of a kind which democracy sought to make common to all citizens. Hence we find that such offices were looked on with suspicion, and that their holders were the object of envy. They were oligarchical in their nature ; not because they were filled with oligarchs, but because a state where such offices abounded would be oli- garchic \ But oligarchic as they were, they were not in the least party posts. Election to them was not conducted on party lines. There were private societies which would support those of their members who were candidates ; but there was no organisation to support candidates of particular opinions. If ^ Cf. the first scene in the Acharnians, also ih. vv. 595 etc. 106 THE OFFICIALS. an embassy was to be chosen, the people did not take trouble to choose ambassadors committed to one line of policy. They did not attempt to bind themselves to a particular line by electing men pledged to support it. They elected men who took interest in, or had knowledge of the question; but they elected men of the most opposite opinions \ We see how in the case of offices to which elec- tion was by vote the influence of the lot ex- tended; the same strictness of account, the same complete obedience to the Assembly, the same colle- giateness, the same absence of party organisation is found in the one as in the other: but it was only because elected officials were the exception that elec- tions were so quiet, so business-like, and elected officials so obedient. Commis- Another class of men who were certainly in most public cases appointed by the people were the "Commis- works. sioners of Public Works" (iTrco-Tarat twu Brjfioamv epycov) including the special boards appointed to superintend the building of fortifications and triremes ^ These, however, do not really form an exception to ^ E.g. Xen. Hell. vi. Ill in the embassy to Sparta we find men of different parties, including those of the anti-Laconian party. So too in the famous embassy to Philip the leaders of the opposing parties both took part. 2 Aesch. in Ctesiphontem, 9. 31. Demosthenes was appointed T€ixoTroi6s by his own tribe Pandion. There is a distinction between KkqpwToL dpx*^ and eirtffTaTai tcSv dTjfioa-icov ipyiov : and though Aeschines contends that these latter are apxa-i; he certainly implies that they were never KXi^porraL (13 — 14, 28 — 30). C. I. A. ii. 830 TeixoTTotol aipeOhre^. Cf. Wachsmuth, Die Stadt Athen, vol. ii. p. 13, n. 1 ; ih. p. iv — v. THE OFFICIALS. 107 the rule, because, certainly in the greater number of cases of which we have record, these Commissioners are not members of a permanent bureau. The office is created for a special and exceptional purpose, and expires when the building or repairs with which it is concerned is completed. There is one commission for the building of the Propylsea*; one for the building of the Erechtheum^; another for the restoration of a temple which had been destroyed by fire'\ A board of TetxoTrocol is appointed to superintend the re- building of the walls in 395*; another, of which Demosthenes is a member, in 338 ^ These appoint- ments no more belong to the ordinary constant system of the administration than do the posts of ambassador; or the special commissions of enquiry appointed at times of panic; or the crvvTjyopeh appointed to represent the state in public prosecu- tions. This is shown by other signs. The regular Athenian boards have almost invariably 10 members; the numbers of these commissions vary, we find sometimes two^ sometimes three ^, at times five^, or 1 C. I. A. i. 314. 2 c. I. A. i. 322. 3 C. I, A. ii. 829. * C. I. A. ii. 830—32. Cf. Wachsmuth, Die Stadt Athen, ii. p. 5, and p. 13, n. 1. ^ Aeschines, 1. c. We also find a commission of ten men to investigate the gifts given to the temple of Aesculapius (C. I. A. ii. 836), one for the restoration of the temple of Zeus Soter (C. I. A. ii. 834) and for the building of the Skeuotheke (C. I. A. ii. 1054), and one to superintend the making of two statues eTnardrai racv NUaiv (C. I. A. iv. 331« and C. I. A. i. 318.) 8 C. I. A. ii. 187. 7 c. I. A. i. 318, 322. 8 C. I. A. ii. 834 : C. I. A. iv. 331«. 108 THE OFFICIALS. ten\ The regular appointments are, nearly invari- ably, for a year ; in some cases at least, these commis- sioners hold office for longer^; and it is probable that the appointment was generally made to continue till the work entrusted to them was finished ^ It is certain therefore that many of these com- missions must be classed among the exceptional offices, and in consequence it is probable that their members were allowed more power and fi:"eedom than could have belonged to men appointed by lot, and that the direct responsibility for the plan and method of building rested with them ; also, that the people entrusted to them the right of controlling the architect. Thus they would not only propose in the assembly the general plan of the building, but would be empowered to use their own discretion in the arrangement of details. The actual charge of the work of course be- longed to a professional architect ; who was ap- pointed sometimes, if not always, by the people*. The chief duties of the commissioners were to examine the plan prepared by him, to see that it would answer the purpose of the building required, to draw up a formal document and sign it. They also had to watch over the progress of the work, and, especially, all payments were made by them to the contractors and workmen. The sale of the 1 Aesch. 1. c. In C. I. A. ii. 1054 one only is mentioned as signing the contract, but he possibly acts on behalf of his colleagues. 2 C. I. A. i. 301 (p. 160), 318. 3 This was not however always the case. C. I. A. i. 303 — 309. 4 C. I. A. ii. 187, V. 6. THE OFFICIALS. 109 contract seems to have belonged not to them but to the Poletai. The question, however, suggests itself whether, besides these exceptional commissions appointed to conduct large and important building operations, there were not other and more permanent officials entrusted with the care and preservation of the fabric of the buildings and fortifications already made. I am not aware of any record of such officials, and it is more probable that, so far as this duty did not belong to the province of the priests, treasurers and generals, it was included in the general supervision over all public matters which belonged to the council. This seems to be borne out by the fragment of a decree \ either of the council or assembly, which pro- vides for building some additional wall on the Acro- polis. In the portions preserved we find mention of the Poletai, and of a man who is apparently the archi- tect, but none of any commissioners; and the probable explanation is that where only some small piece of work was to be done the matter was left to the discretion of the architect, and it was not held to be necessary to have a special committee appointed to control him. The payments could of course always be made by one of the regular boards of officials, and the contract as usual would be made by the Poletai. The iiria-TaTaL were only appointed when a special work of some magnitude was to be taken in hand^ 1 Bulletin de Corr. Hell. 1890, p. 177. It seems to belong to the middle of the fifth century. In another we find that the control over the architect is given to the iepoTToiol. C. I. A. iv. 37*', 1. 10. ^ j-geg Appendix.] 110 THE OFFICIALS. With these the exceptions end. There were no other duties which it did not seem to the Athenian statesman that any of his fellow citizens could perfectly well fulfil. For the two great depart- ments of finance and justice, there were in the great days of the Athenian Democracy no elected ofiicers. What taxes were to be raised ; what money was to be spent; that the demos in its sovereign power decided. How much money was necessary for one department; how much could be afforded for another; that the council reported. But to raise money, and spend it ; to collect taxes, and proceed against defaulters; to sell confiscated property, and let public land ; to pay the bills, and audit the accounts ; — for all this there were none but KXijpcoTal dp'x^aL Therefore we shall be justified in saying that neither the institution of the hoKUfiacrla nor the ex- istence of these exceptional offices shows any distrust of the lot. This was the ordinary system of appoint- ment, and was deliberately maintained as the wisest means of preserving the democratic constitution. But if we are prepared to recognise that election by lot was the rule and not the exception, we have still to enquire how it was that the state could exist and prosper with it, and what the results of the system were. I propose therefore to explain, so far as is possible, the manner in which the system worked, so that we may see what the effects of this peculiar arrangement were. I shall begin by dis- cussing the financial administration. CHAPTEE IV. Finance. § 1. General Direction. In a modern state the most important political event of the year is the budget. The chief duty of the Government is to estimate the expenses of the coming year, and to propose some method of raising sufficient money to meet the expenses. The question has often been asked how it happened that in anti- quity, and especially in Athens, matters of finance had not the same importance \ The difference is however more in appearance than in fact. It arises to a great extent from the character of the records. Historians occupy them- selves much more with the moral than the economic side of history. Writing with a view to artistic effect, they pass over matters of finance which are supposed to be dull. But the speeches of the orators, and the great mass of inscriptions which have been dis- covered, show conclusively — what we might have guessed — that, even in the fifth century, finance was almost as important a part of public business as it 1 Boeckh, Staatshaushaltung, Bk. ii. § 1. 112 FINANCE. is now. Athens had no exemption in this matter. She was subject to the ordinary laws which govern the life of states. Then, as now, it was supply which occupied the minds of leaders of the state ; for money meant food for the citizens, good pay for the fleet, new triremes, new fortifications. It meant comfort at home, and supremacy abroad. Then, as now, no leader of the state could keep his position without meeting the financial problem ; and the administra- tion of Pericles, of Cleon, of Aristophon, and of Eubulus was then, as it would be now, chiefly judged by their financial policy \ There is, however, a point in the constitution of Athens, resulting from the peculiar character of the relations between the officials and the assembly, which tends to obscure this fact. Absence of The first question we naturally ask is: — "Who financT^^ was the responsible financial adviser ; whose duty was official. it to frame plans for providing money ? " It is of the very elements of business that there should be some one whose special duty it is to survey the whole income and expenditure. Without this what would all the care and prudence in details avail ? But at Athens there is great difficulty in dis- covering with whom this responsibility lay. We can trace the course of a sum of money from one department to another. We can find out how pay- ments were made, where money was kept, who paid it, and who spent it ; but where was the central control ? All taxes were indeed imposed by the ^ Cf. Lysias, Karbi '^irLKpdrovs xxvii. 3, oirdrav iv XP'^P^'^"' V Koi audrjvai tt}v irbXiv koX fi-fj. FINANCE. 113 assembly, and all expenses sanctioned by them. But who advised the assembly, and how did it learn exactly what money was wanted ? There must surely have been someone who had a special knowledge of the matter, who could put forward an authoritative statement, and with whom the responsibility of mis- management would rest. In the latter half of the 4th century there was ra/A/as ttjs such an official : the Ta^la<; Trj<; Koivrj<; irpoaoSov, or ^po^f^^Qy, 6 eirl TTj ScoLKTjaec. And it has been maintained that this office was in existence at least from the times of the Persian wars. Boeckh and others have supposed that it was held by Aristeides and Pericles and Cleon; and that by holding it they gained their official position, and their right to speak with authority and advise the people. There seems however to be no good authority for the existence of this office before the middle of the 4th century, and it was probably introduced by Eubulus about 35 2 \ It appears indeed, strange as it may seem, that during the 5th century there was no finance minister. There was no one who was officially responsible for 1 Plutarch, it is true, speaks of Aristeides as iinfieXTjTT]^ tQp KOLvQv Trpoo-68(au, and there are expressions in the Knights of Aristophanes (v. 948) which have been supposed to imply that Cleon was officially "ra^t'as" of the city. Against this is to be put the complete absence of any reference at all to such an office in inscriptions, and any certain reference in contemporary literature. Cf. infra, p. 117, n. 1, the passages quoted from the Memorabilia. Even in the Knights, the prize for which Cleon and the sausage- seller contend is represented as the ascendency in the assembly {ttjs TlvKi/os rhi 7)vlas, v. 1109), not election to any office. H. 8 114 FINANCE. these matters. There were numerous subordinate officials ; but they were all appointed by lot, and had thereby neither claim nor power to direct the policy of the city. There was the council, which with its important duties was the centre and pivot of the whole system ; but it was after all a body of 500 men taken by lot ; it could scarcely be that the Athenians would look to it for wisdom and ad- vice. Financial The constitutional advisers of the assembly were the^^^ ^^^ ^^® officials, nor the council, nor even necessarily orators. the generals. They were the orators \ It was on their energy and ambition that the direction of the finances depended, as did the supreme control of all depart- ments. And the Athenians could affi)rd to trust to them for advice, for, so long as political ambition was keen, and success in public life the great desire of every able man, the people knew that these matters would not be neglected. The competition was too vigorous. If a young man wished to dis- tinguish himself, he must do so by winning the ear of the assembly. To do this, he must be able to criticise the plans of others, or formulate plans of his own ; to show how money could be saved, or how it could be better spent. Whether he dealt with naval matters, the relations to the allies, the adorn- ment of the city, or the celebration of public festi- vals ; if he wished to make an effect, and win repu- tation, he must have command of the question of supply. No one could hope to win a permanent 1 Dem. xiv. (Trept avfi/Mpiwv) 2. FINANCE. 115 place who did not show a thorough acquaintance with the finance of the city\ There is an admirable illustration of this in the Memorabilia of Xenophon^ Socrates is repre- sented as conversing with Glaucon, a young man who without adequate knowledge and experience is trying to push himself forward. He wishes irpoara- T€V€LV T179 TToXeo)?, and Socrates shows him how many things he must know if he wishes to do this ; he must understand all about the income of the state and the expenditure ; he must know the rela- tive strength of Athens and other states; he must know whence the food supply of the city comes. Now Glaucon is not coming forward to stand for any office; he does not aim at being "public treasurer," or " general ;" he is much too young to be eligible : but he wishes to become popular with the assembly, and to do what he likes in the city. He, if he becomes irpoardTT^f; rov hrjfiov, will also " ad- minister the afifairs of the city." Now what this and other conversations show is that numbers of young 1 We are told of almost every well-known man, that he occupied himself with finance. I have collected a few in- stances for which I am chiefly indebted to Beloch (Att. Politik). Cleophon, Lysias xix. 48. Aesch. ii. 76. Agyrrhios, Ar. Ranaa, 367, Schol. ad Arist. Eccl. 102. rbv fxiffdov 5e tQv ttoitjtQv (TvviTejxe koL irpOros eKKXrjataaTiKbv 5^du}K€v. Archedemos, Xen. Hell. 1. vii. 2. 'Apx^^Vf^os 6 too drj/xov t6t€ vpo€i(raiuLhov tov d-Zifiov. In 1. c. 183—4 we find the formula \J/'r}ij^. A difficulty which at Rome would have been settled by the Praetor could at Athens not be solved without an appeal to the Assembly. We see at once how the power of the BrjfjLOf; was a direct result of the absence of ability and influence among the magistrates; in other words, how election by lot was necessary to the perfection of the democracy. Charac- We can now see to what was due the chief 'J^***?* °-^ characteristic of the Athenian law, its great sim- Law. 1 Cf. Schomann p. 850, n. 234. JUDICIAL MAGISTRATES. 151 plicity. This did not come from any peculiarities of the Greek mind. The Athenians were not inferior to the Romans in their power of framing a system, nor were they wanting in ability to analyse the basis of law; yet the Athenian law never got beyond the rudimentary state : it remained merely a list of rules or precepts for conduct, with apparently little attempt at scientific arrangement. The Athenian courts were active, the number of cases tried was immense, and the complexity of the issues often considerable, and yet there was no authoritative interpretation of the law ; no glosses were collected round the rules; the laws remained short simple and straightforward. This is of course due partly to the peculiar constitution of the law-courts; but it is still more due to the absence of authority of the magistrates. Owing to this, there was no attempt made to distinguish between questions of law and questions of fact. The same men decided both to- gether. Each case came before the court in its entirety, and when the verdict was given no one could tell on what grounds it had been given. Hence there could be no precedent. A precedent is only possible when an authoritative exposition can be given of the law, in such a way that it is applic- able to other cases, apart from the particular circum- stances which were the occasion of it. This could not be done at Athens; for there was no authoritative ruling of the Judge, or formula of the Praetor, and the very nature of the courts prevented their decision becoming a precedent. Again, there was no custom- ary law: there was nothing to which an advocate could 152 JUDICIAL MAGISTRATES. appeal but the written laws, "the laws of Solon."^ The speechmakers were the only people who were professionally connected with the law, and advocates- are only of use in developing a system of law when the court before which they plead is itself composed of professional lawyers. One result of this again is the peculiar nature of the Athenian laws. They are as a rule the concise statement of some general principle. They are put in such a form that they can be understood and applied by a court of laymen. Elaborately drawn up law& full of technical phraseology which aim at covering every possible case, are really much easier to apply than the apparently simpler rules; but they can only be used by trained minds and memories. At Athens no one was specially trained. It was more- over the absence of any authoritative explanation of the law which caused the Athenians to be so par- ticular about their laws. Inconsistencies in the law and obscurities of expression are not of great impor- tance where the interpretation of the laws is the professed occupation of a large and organised body of able men. The law will eventually be hidden and superseded by the interpretation, and the goodness or badness of the law be of little moment. At Athens, where each case had to be decided by inexperienced people, any inconsistency in the laws would destroy all confidence in the justice of the courts, and so the activity which in other countries is devoted to elaborating the law and making it more complete, at Athens was spent in simplifying and shortening it. JUDICIAL MAGISTRATES. 153 This department shows, I think, more clearly Relation than any other, how true it is that the power of the ^{^^ Assembly depended on the absence of special ability systevi • ^i. • ^ ^ ^ oi • 1 ^ u -^ to the de- in the magistrates and othcials ; and why it mocracy. was that election by lot was so essential to the democracy. A consideration of this will convince us how far all modern states are from being what a Greek would have called a democracy. It will be an interesting problem in the futvire to see to what extent consistent democrats will succeed in doing away with what they ought to consider their most formidable enemy — a class of trained lawyers. CHAPTER VI. ADMINISTRATIVE OFFICIALS. Com- The principles which prevailed in the finance mittees of j • • , . • ' .^ • i i • n the As- administration were consistently carried out m ail sembiyand other parts of the public service. The immediate council. ^ ^ control over each department of the state and the responsibility for the proper management of every separate public institution was placed in the hands of a special board of 10 men annually appointed by lot. Each of these was constitutionally a committee of the Assembly, or the council, and it was by means of these committees that the larger bodies kept up their control over the innumerable details of public business. The actual work was done by public slaves and by contractors ; the duties of these com- mittees were normally to inspect and control the work, so as to ensure that it was properly done. It is impossible to give an account of all of these committees. The system will be best explained by investigating a single department which may be taken as typical of the others. iTTi/xeXTrrai Among them, those of whom we have most ^^^ ^ J, knowledge, are the inspectors of the dockyards. I propose therefore to give a short account of their ADMINISTRATIVE OFFICIALS. 155 duties. This will show better than anything else the sort of work which these committees had to do ; for the duties of the iirifJieXrjTal roov iiiiropicov, and even of the cnTovXwv were doubtless the officials who had to manage the election of many of the officers, but of the way in which it was done we know nothing\ A passage in Demosthenes*'* shows us that they were responsible for bringing to the Archons the Choregi from the tribe, but it tells us nothing further. These iTnfjbeXrjral were the chief officials of the tribe; the office was annual, but we do not know either their number or how they were elected. Their chief duty was doubtless to act as returning officer at the various elections; but we find from an in- scription that they were also responsible for the proper management of the property of the tribe; they are here ordered to go round and make an inspection, to see if it is cultivated according to the inscriptions, and if the boundaries are properly kept, and they are especially warned not to show favour to any individual, nor to put anything before the interest of the tribe, nor to take bribes I The duties of presiding at meetings, keeping accounts, inspection of property, are precisely those to which according to all analogy we should expect to find ^ C. I. A. ii. 554. ^ Dem. in Midiam, 13. » C. I. A. ii. 564. 170 THE ADMINISTRATION OF THE officials appointed by lot. More than this we cannot say. Of ra/jLLat, who are mentioned, we know nothing \ The v\'rj had as had every other corporation its lepeU: it is an interesting coincidence that almost the only one mentioned appears to have been an uncle of Demosthenes I Private When we pass from the administrative divisions societies. ^£ ^j^^ state to societies which have no direct con- nection with the government, we find that the ad- ministrative officers are (where we have information) invariably elected, whiLe the religious, — the UpeU, lepoTTOLoi — , are generally elected by lot ; and I am told that the same is true of similar corporations in other parts of Greece. It seems then as if among them we meet with the religious use of the lot, and it is reasonable to suppose that where the priest was chosen by lot it was that the god might himself select his own minister. We notice moreover two other facts. In these so- cieties the administrative officials were certainly not in all cases annually elected, while the leponroLoi are always spoken of as ol ael \a'y')(avovTe^y which, though it does not necessarily mean annual appoint- ment, suggests that the office was never held for long; in some cases we find mention of annual appointment^. Religimts With regard to the religious officials of the officials. Athenian state, it does not seem possible to lay 1 C. I. A. ii. 564. 2 C. I. A. ii. 554». 3 C. I. A. ii. 611, 613, 619. DIVISIONS OF THE STATE. 171 down any certain principle. Some were hereditary in certain families, some were elected and were officers of much dignity but little importance, others were chosen by lot. The reason was doubtless in each case an historical one. I think however it is not out of accordance with the recorded facts to say that, with the exception of the hereditary offices, all religious officials whose duties were continuous were chosen by lot\ while those who were appointed only to perform a single act on one day in the year, or one day in four years were elected by the people. This fact, if true, will show how much the Athenians were in the matter guided by convenience, and how little by religious tradition. Knowing how much the power of the old aristocracy had depended upon their religious privileges, we can understand that the establishment of other functionaries, whether chosen by lot or by election, would be important as securing to the democracy freedom from aristocratic influence in its public acts of worship. I began this essay by pointing out that the Great democracy meant the undisputed supremacy of the^^"^^^^. Assembly in all matters. This survey of the different cemedin offices in the state draws our attention to another tration, and not less important aspect of it. The complete democracy meant not only that the people assembled together should govern the state, but that each individual should also take his part in the work of administration. There was to be no class from which alone magistrates were chosen, nor were the 1 Dem. in Eubuliden, 46, the priest of Heracles is chosen by lot from among men who are nominated by popular election. 172 THE ADMINISTRATION OF THE officials to form a class of themselves. Democracy meant self-government in the fullest sense of the word: each nian had his share in the general de- liberations, he had his turn for a seat in the council, which was the central office of the whole, and he had also to take his part in different offices. Besides these city offices, each man belonged also to the smaller corporations of the tribe, the deme and the phratria, each of which made large demands on his time : he had to attend meetings of the whole corporation, and had moreover from time to time to fill one of the numerous offices connected with it, or serve on some committee appointed by it. It is no exaggeration to say that most Athenians must have spent a large part of their life in the performance of public duties ^ And if we look at the democracy from either aspect: whether we regard the supremacy of the Assembly, or the share which each citizen took in all public business, we shall find that election by lot was an important and essential part of the system. It broke down and weakened all bodies so as to make of every office nothing more than a committee of the Assembly; and it also supplied a simple means of overcoming the difficulty of appointment, so as to ensure in a rough way that all citizens should have a share in the work of the state. Criticism The common criticism made on this system is Astern. ^^^^ ^^ aimed at an equality where no equality was, 1 In order rightly to appreciate the number of men occupied in public business we must remember that the Archons, Thesmothetai, and many other magistrates were helped by assessors {Trdpedpoi) who during their terms of office acted with them. DIVISIONS OF THE STATE. 173 for it put men of character and ability on the same level with those who had neither. Now if this is said of the high office of governing the city, it is not true, because there has never been a state where power was so exclusively made the prize of ability : ability not always of the best kind it may be. But if free competition is the best way of finding ability, Athens honestly tried to find it. The orators might be wanting in many qualities, but at least they must have had the appearance of wisdom and character. Power belonged to that man who in perfectly free and open competition could win and keep for himself the most influence. The test might not be a perfect one. I do not know that a better has yet been devised. And though Athens may have suffered from unscrupulous politicians and un- wise ones, we cannot say of her that she was governed by incompetent or insignificant men. If again it is objected that it is abilities of a humbler kind which were neglected, and that in the appointment of sub- ordinate officials a difference should be made between men ; it will be sufficient to answer that at any rate the work at Athens was well done. So far as we can see the administration of the state was more regular, more honest, more successful in every way than that of any other city in the ancient world, and (though where the work is so different, the comparison is hardly fair) than that of most states in modern times. The Athenians obliged every one to take his share in the work, they made the work of every one individually easy, and if he did not do it they killed him. The result was that the work was done. The most 174 THE ADMINISTRATION OF THE potent attempts to obtain and secure able officials do not always succeed; the Athenians were sure that the men they appointed were not generally below the average in ability and character, and that they would not deteriorate in office. There are per- haps not many states of which the same could be said. Injustice is often done to the Athenian consti- tution because we try it by too high a standard. Thucydides and Plato have left us their criticisms on it. These criticisms are I believe completely true: but when we recognise the truths of the picture of the " democrat " drawn by Plato, and read the account which he and others have given of the gradual demoralisation of the Athenian people, we ought to remember that everything with which they charge Athens would mutatis mutandis apply with equal force to any other society which has ever existed. The gi*eatest complaint brought against the democracy was that it was short lived. The Greeks were apt to reckon the excellence of institutions by their permanence : in this matter we have had more experience than they had, and are prepared to recognise the fact that the more efficient a constitution is the more likely it is to generate economic changes which will soon make it anti- quated and useless. That the democratic consti- tution lost its peculiar effectiveness by the middle of the 4th century is no reason for refusing to recognise its merit. We do not question that the government of Elizabeth was wise and strong be- cause the system was destroyed in the next genera- DIVISIONS OF THE STATE. 175 tion. So long as a state has political life, every form of government must bear in itself the seeds of its own destruction. And with regard to the other charges brought Prevalence against it, all I ask is that besides comparing it at Athens with the ideal state of Plato we should also compare '"^gf^^^ted, it with other states which have existed in this world. The most constant accusation brought against the Athenians is dishonesty. We constantly hear of fraud at Athens; it was a frequent charge in the law-courts, and historians, led by the speeches of the orators, have concluded that the Athenian govern- ment was exceptionally corrupt. This corruption is then laid to the charge of democratic government and especially of the lot. But it is surely dangerous to accept as literally true the statements of the orators ; we know that in many cases the accusations were false, and, even apart from this, frequent trials for peculation are not necessarily a sign of an exceptionally corrupt ad- ministration. Where corruption is worst, it will not be found that convictions are frequent. The sign of organised and habitual fraud is a general repose and outward quiet, interrupted occasionally by some great exposure and outburst of indignation. The constant activity and watchfulness which is necessary to procure convictions, is in itself a suffi- cient guarantee against peculations being the estab- lished thing. Fraud is easy where affairs are secret, confined to a few persons, complicated, and where each individual is allowed much freedom of action. But at Athens every obol which was received by any official 176 THE ADMINISTRATION OF THE was entered, and the records made public : how he had to use the money was clearly laid down: he had little freedom of action, so that it was impossible to hide the disappearance of any sum. But I imagine the most efficient guarantee against the prevalence of serious fraud was to be found just in the fact that the officials were so numerous and that they were elected by lot for a short period. Whenever a certain class of people hold office and others are positively excluded, it is easy for the officials to exact overdue sums, and appropriate the surplus. The outside public cannot defend itself: it is igno- rant and intimidated. This was made impossible at Athens because there were no secrets of office. Fraud arises when any individual holds the same office for long, or is often re-elected ; in such cases the perquisites of office grow, and the permanent official has a position of advantage against all unofficial men: at Athens in the democratic state this was not the case. Fraud is especially liable to occur when officials are elected, because those who are likely to gain by the fraud will use all their influence to elect men who will give them an opportunity of winning. This happens constantly in America and other democratic states of modern times, and, under slightly different forms, happened constantly in the later Roman Republic. It was rendered impossible by the lot ; the more so because the lot might associate men who had no acquaintance with one another and who could not, during the short period they were in office, acquire the mutual self- confidence which is necessary to community in fraud. DIVISIONS OF THE STATE. 177 The Greeks no doubt were not an honest race, but it was not the democracy which made the Athenians untrustworthy. So far as we can see the framers of the constitution had recognised the national vice, and took every pains they could to counteract it ; it was one of the merits of the democratic system that it made fraud so difficult. It was a noble attempt, and it was to a great extent successful. There was a good deal of petty dishonesty at Athens, many men made a little money out of the public service. But we know of no instance in which we can say that the public welfare was seriously injured by extensive frauds or official incompetence as was constantly the case in aristocratic Rome and England. The Athenian people perhaps wasted their money — but they did it themselves; it was not lost and squandered by the officers of the state \ I have tried to analyse one of the most remark- Character- able and most characteristic features of the Athenian ^Athenian ^ constitution. If the view which I have taken be ^^^'^• correct, election by lot Avas of the very essence of the democracy. And the investigations which lead to a recognition of this fact throw light on a peculiarity of the democracy which distinguishes it from most other political systems. Whether the democracy was good or bad, is a question which has been 1 It is very doubtful whether the administration of local matters in many English towns would stand a comparison with that at Athens. It may I think be safely said that the gigantic corruption which is said to prevail in Eussia, Italy and America now, and which was common in England not so long ago, would there have been quite impossible. H. 12 178 THE ADMINISTRATION OF THE sufficiently debated. It probably developed the ener- gies and activities of the Athenians more fully than any other system could have done : so far as it did this we must approve of it, though for this, as for every other system, there came a time when altered circumstances rendered it no longer so efficient. But what is most striking in it is the clearness of thought with which certain principles of government are apprehended, and the boldness of execution with which they are put into effect. Living constitutions are generally a compromise between various prin- ciples. Attempts to frame a constitution in accor- dance with some single general principle have nearly always failed. But in describing the Athenian ad- ministration, one often feels as though one were describing the typical state of a political thinker. It is difficult to conceive of a state in which political equality could be more completely attained. And yet notwithstanding this obedience to an idea, which we can trace in the most important branches of the administration, there is a prudence and sobriety in the arrangements which is wanting in most polities. So far as human foresight could, the builders of the constitution had guarded against the internal dangers which might arise. The Athenian democracy is as a work of art unsurpassed : it has the great characteristic of all good work, in every detail we find laborious endeavour to express a clear and definite idea: and the result is so simple and so harmonious that it is only after a somewhat minute examination that we discover the labour expended on it. The conditions which made this DIVISIONS OF THE STATE. 179 possible will probably never occur again; but the scientific value of the experiment is great: it was the first democracy: the word Democracy was in- vented as a name for it: all other democracies in Greece were a more or less successful imitation of it, and if we want to know what a complete democracy is we can do nothing better than analyse it. If we do this we shall understand how far any modern country is from being a true democracy, and we shall also see how as states become more democratic they develope the most characteristic features of Athens. It would hardly be an exaggeration to say that a Ancient state begins to be democratic when the objects for ^^^^lem de- which election by lot was introduced first become a mocracies. conscious object of desire. We see this clearly in America. Elective assemblies are essentially un- democratic. In America, where the feeling is more democratic than the machinery, we are told that a recognition of this is growing, and it is becoming unusual to re-elect Congress men; it is only fair, as men say, that each of the local politicians should have a chance; it is unfair and undesirable that a few men, because they are a little cleverer or a little more fortunate than others, should have a monopoly of the most valuable political instruction. The Athenians felt this, and gave complete expression to the feeling by allowing to every citizen in turn a seat in the ^ovXrj. The great movement which is causing the break-down of representative institutions in the most democratic countries is due to the desire felt by the mass of the people to give their verdict on each important act, and to make of the assemblies a com- 12—2 180 THE ADMINISTRATION OF THE mittee in which business should be arranged so as to be brought directly before the people. The English are in a confused way aiming at this. In the states of North America a closer approach is made to it by restricting very closely the powers of the state governments. In Switzerland this is still more openly done by the institution of the Referendum. If we want to see the real end at which this ten- dency is directed, we need only look to Athens. There the desired end was attained by purposely weakening the smaller assembly which would other- wise have governed the state : this was done by means of the lot ; and it is not easy to see how else it could have been done. It is a curious confir- mation of the reasons I have given why there was no party government at Athens, that in Switzerland, where direct government by the people is less re- mote than in any other country, the Executive Council is in no way a party body. But if in some modern states the peoples are in the way to win for themselves the full and direct sovereignty, they are still far from imitating the other characteristic of the Athenian Democracy. There, as we have seen, not only did the people col- lectively rule the state, but also these same men individually had, each in his turn, a share in the experience and responsibility of office. The central- ised bureaucracy of the modern democratic state is far distant from what the Greeks called democracy. There if a man was a full citizen, he had not merely from time to time to give a silent and irresponsible vote in the Assembly or the law courts ; he had to DIVISIONS OF THE STATE. 181 experience the honours and dangers of office. This could only be because the Athenian democracy was an aristocracy. It had all the characteristics of an aristocracy. It made the assumption that each citizen had the time and ability to undertake public duties. It was there held true that no man could be a good citizen whose life was fully occupied in earning the bare necessities of life. The Athenians had in fact that respect for leisure which is so characteristic of an aristocracy. Hard work was with them a disqualification. Men did not believe in the dignity of labour. The existence of the demo- cracy depended on slavery. Slavery is now impossible. Our modern democracies are no more aristocratic. If they ever become so, it will be when the use of machinery is so far developed and society reorganised in such a way that the greater part of the popu- lation will be able, as the wealthy classes now do, to devote a portion of their ample leisure, not only to the discussion of political questions but also to the management of public business. APPENDIX. On the UoXiTcia Twv ^Adrjvaicov. It has generally been maintained that the lot was Early not used at Athens before Cleisthenes (so Grote, Her- ^^f^'J^^^-^ mann, Busolt, Gilbert, Dunker, Lugebil, Miiller- p. 88 etc. Strubing). Schomann recognised that this could not be considered in any way certain ; and Fustel de Coulanges, by reasoning which had never been answered, contended that it was probably an institution of very great antiquity. This view is supported by Aristotle. In ch. 4 he describes a constitution attributed to Draco: in it all officials are chosen by lot. ySovXcvctv 8c Tcrpa/co- (TLOVs KOL eva Tovs Xa)(ovTav\<2vy and in Ar. polit. 11. 1 2 we are told that Solon made no change in the manner of electing the magistrates. So, whether ch. 4 be genuine or not, we have considerable authority that the lot is older than Solon. Fustel de 184 APPENDIX. Coulanges had argued that this must be the case, for the lot being an institution of religious origin must be of great antiquity. This is an interesting and valuable confirmation of his whole method. As to the details of the constitution before Draco, there is of course no authentic tradition. In the times of Solon the lot does not appear to have had much political importance, and during the following period it seems almost to have fallen out of use so far as the Archonship is concerned. It appears that in the contests for the Archonship after Solon direct election must have been practised, and for the 26 years after the expulsion of the Peisistratidae the lot was not used (ch. 22). The method of statement seems, however, to imply that during the tyranny Archons were chosen by the lot. If this be the case Cleisthenes did away with the lot, and it was reintroduced later. The opinion of Grote, and others, that Herodotus was mistaken when he says that Callimachus was chosen Polemarch by lot, is then supported : on the other hand, it was reintroduced before the Archonship of Themistocles and Aristeides. The argument therefore that the lot cannot have been introduced till later, for otherwise Themistocles would not have been archon, must be dismissed. At this time the lot was only used to decide which of a limited number of men nominated by the tribes should be appointed. Under Solon each of the 4 tribes nominated (TrpoKpLveiv) 1 ; and from these 40 the 9 Archons were chosen by lot\ Cleisthenes altered the number of the tribes to ten, and when the lot was reintroduced, each tribe nominated either 50 or, more probably, 10 (ch. 22 with Mr Kenyon's note). ^ We can now understand to what Isocrates was referring in the passage quoted on p. 39. APPENDIX. 185 Originally only rrevTaKoo-LOfxeSLixvoL were eligible to the Archonship ; at some unknown period LTrireU were admitted \ It was not till 457 that ^evy trat could hold this office. Apparently the law which required this qualification was never repealed, but practically it was not put into force (ch. 7). What is of greatest importance, however, Aristotle never tells us: i.e. when the lot was first used for the previous nomination by the tribes instead of popular election. In ch. 8 he tells us that the change was made, but gives nowhere any information as to the date. The account of the Areopagus in ch. 23 is valuable, Areojm- f or it shows that although the council consisted of men ^"^' ^' ' who had been Archons, and the lot was used in the election of Archons, the Areopagus during the Persian wars still showed more energy than the a-TparrjyoL. It ought to be remembered however, that at this time most of those who sat in the Areopagus must have been Archons before the year 487. The fall of the Areo- pagus would coincide with the time when the last of this generation had died out. From ch. 55 we learn that the 6 Thesmothetai with their ypafifxarevs and the 3 other Archons were chosen as a college of 10, one from each tribe. The statement of chapter 18, rds 8' dpxois kiroC-qae Kkrjpuyrds €k TrpoKptTwv, seems to apply not only to the Archonship. The other offices which existed at that time must also have been filled in the same way. These were, as we learn from ch. 7, the ra/Atat, the iroiXrjTaLy the 1 This was perhaps in the time of Cleisthenes. It is possible however that the word TrevTaKoaiuv in ch. 22 is a corruption, and the sentence gave the property qualification. I have suggested iK TWV irpOKpidivTUiV Vir6 TOV dtj/XQV TWV IT €VT aKOaiO fl€ 5 IfJLV bJV. Classical Review, March, 1891. 186 APPENDIX. IvScKtt, and the KoyXaKperaL. It was not, I believe, known before that the first three of these offices were of such antiquity. The early use of the lot for them is remarkable. It appears also that the members of the povXij of 400 were selected by lot from the commencement, though probably with the same precautions as were provided in p. 47, 11. 1. the case of the Archons. I must therefore withdraw the statement on the subject which I made in the text. Fustel de Coulanges' suggestion which I have rejected will now require careful consideration. The main thesis contained in the text of the essay is supported by this new work. I will only call attention to the following points : p. 21 etc. (1) There is nothing to support the attempt to show that the government of Athens was in the hands of an elected official, whether o-TpaxTyyos or ra/xias. It is however only fair to say that in many parts the work is extremely defective. It contains practically no account of the constitutions between the years 457 and 412 ; for the continuous narrative ceases with the former year, and the constitution described at the end of the work is the constitution of the latter half of the 4th century, which was in many ways a very diffisrent thing. It is very strange that no mention is made of the rafxCas t^s KOLvrjpovpoL. For these offices the preliminary election was always by demes. This confirms the suggestion, which was I believe originally made by Kirchoff, that I have adopted in the text. PP- ^4— The establishment of this point is of some importance. It would be much easier to maintain the principle of rotation when the elections were managed by small societies, where every individual was known. As the final decision between the candidates was by lot, the elections could not have any party importance. What each deme had to do therefore was to nominate each year at least twice the number of men that would eventually be chosen from that deme. Now if the principle of rotation were really maintained it would probably as a rule scarcely be necessary to have recourse to the lot ; men would be elected more or less in order of seniority ; the lot would not be more important than it was when used at Rome under the Empire to decide which of two men of equal standing should have his province first. In many cases the Demarch would probably nominate 6 or 8 or 10 of 188 APPENDIX. the members next on the list, and there would be no competition. This will explain how it happens that p. 56. father and son, or two brothers serve together. Twice as many must have been nominated as there were members, so as to leave plenty for the iTriKaxqa-L^. Perhaps the arrangement was that each deme nomi- nated twice the required number : half were chosen, and the other half were ready to serve if necessary. Rotation, (4) In ch. 4 we have a statement of the principle ^' * of rotation clearer than anything hitherto known. KkyjpovaOai Sc /cat ravrqv koX ras oAAas dp)(as rovs VTrep TptotKOvra err] yeyovorais, kol Sts tov avTov jxrj apx^LV irpo Tov 7rdvT\apovpoL TrevTyJKovra, ap^at 8* evSrjfjLOL /xev €t? CTrraKoa-Lovs avSpa?, virepopioL 8* els lTrraKO(rCovs. APPENDIX. 189 It is impossible at once to estimate the value of the new account given of the different offices. 1 will only point out : (1) With regard to the Xoyiarai These were of two kinds : (a) 10 elected from members of the council, who Xoyiffral, had to draw up the accounts of each office {KXrjpovo-L Se ^^' Kol XoyKTTcts €^ avTwv ol /BovXevToi ScKa toi)s Xoyiovixevovs T[aLS ap];(at9 Kara ttqv Trpvraveiav €Ka(rTr)v). (6) There were besides 10 evOvvoi with 10 irdpeSpoL, and 10 XoyiaraL with 10 a-uinjyopoi who were occupied with the €v6vva of the magistrates (ch. 54). This supports the view I have taken that the Xoytcr- Tttt had other duties besides those immediately connected with the evOvva. The actual arrangements are however different from what they were in the 5th century. (2) The plans of the temples were originally )Sou\^, criticised by the povX-q : but, as their decision was not ^' impartial, the matter was afterwards handed over to a hLKa.(TTrjpLOV. The council exercised also a general superintendence over all public buildings (i^era^ev Se /cat to, oiKoSiy/xaTa Tct Srjixocna Travra, ch. 46). The architects for the ships, as for the public buildings, were elected by the people (ch. 46), and the TptiypoTTotot were elected by the council (ib.). p. 159. (3) The accounts of the TrcoX^rat, aTroSeKrai, and cvScKtt, though rather fuller than what we possessed, agree with what was known before. It is however definitely stated that the council had p. 139. to decide to whom the taxes should be leased (KaraKv- powTLV oTov kol nporepov pXv cts ive/SaWe tqv {jnJKJiov, vvv 8* avdyK-q Trai/ras co-Tt SLa*ij/r)ttat, though never repealed, was, we are told, not really enforced. ot Ttt/xtat n7s *A6r)voivXrj<;j €K TrevTaKoaioixeSLfJivtDV Kara tov ^oAwvos vofi^oVj €Tt yap o v]o/xos xvpios eaTLv, dp^et 8* o Xa;((oi/ Kav irdvv Trevrjs rj (ch. 47). INDEX. Acropolis, treasure preserved in, 133, 169 Adriatic, 64, 158 uEschines, elected irvKaydpai, 25 n. 1 ; accuses Demosthenes, 54 ; ambassador, 73 ay opd, 139 dyopapd/jLoi, 94 Agyrrhio.s, 115 n. 1 deXod^rai, 122, 124 Alcibiades, 35, 37 Alcmceonid, 16 Allies, V. cr{>/jt.fjiaxoL America, democracy in, 145, 179 Amnesty, 151 dpaKpiais, 147 n. 1 Andocides, quoted, 95 Androtion, 74 avTiypatpevs, 167 Antiphon, 34 dTToSe/cra^, 86, 122, 124, 129, 131 n. 1, 157, 189 diroa-ToXecs, 65 n. 1, 73, 185 n. 3 Archedemos, 115 n. 1 'ApxiTiKTcov, 108—9, 189 Archons, use of lot in election of, IX., 7, 78 sq. ; a sacred office, 7 ; early history of, 78 sq., 184; judicial duties of, 146 sq.; com- pared with the Prffitor, ib. Areopagus, Council of, v. ^ovkq Artsteides, archon, 78, 184; Tafiias, 113 Aristophanes, quoted, 25, 113 Aristophon, 35, 112 Aristotle, xiii., xv., 15, 31, 42, 89, {iroXiTela tQp 'AdrjvaiQv) xv. sq. 183 sq. daTvvofxoi, 94 ctrAeia, 167 aVi/xta, 97, 100 Ballot, to be distinguished from the lot, 1 Beloch, XII., 22 n. 1, 23 n. 1 Boeckh, xii., 21 n. 1, 58 n. 1, 63 n. 1, 113, 155 n. 1, 162 ^ov\evT7}pLOv, 122, 140 ^ovKevTiq^, power of, 68, 75 sq. PovKt) tCov 'ApeoirayiTuv, fall of, 46; in the Persian wars, 80, 185 — Tuv irevTaKoaiiav, history of, 46 ; appointment to, 49 ; member- ship of, 51, 56; duties of, 51, 57 sq., 187; in foreign affairs, 61 sq. ; in administration, 64, 109 ; in finance, 65, 121 sq. ; great powers of, 75; relations to iK- KXrjala, 64 (v. iKKXrjcia) ; orators 192 INDEX. in the, 69; judicial duties, 71; publicity of, 69 CallistheneSj 35 Callistratos, 115 n. 1 Xopvyoi, 169 Cleisthenes, reforms of, 46, 78, 86, 167, 184 CUon, 112, 113, 116 Cleophon, 35, 37, 115 n. 1 Committees, of the Assembly, 154, 163 Compulsory office, 94 Council, government by a, 42; in city states, 43; at Athens, 45; V. jSouXiJ CtesipJwn, 37 Deinarchus, 10, 37 n. 1, 118 n. 1 Demetrius of Phaleron, 78 dijfiapxos, 166 sq., 187 Demes, used for electoral purposes, 54 — 5j 187; for financial pur- poses, 143; officials of, 164 sq.; property of, 165 ; meetings of, ib. dvfJ^rai, 56, 168, 187 Democracy, what the Greeks meant by, 17; ancient and modern compared, 18, 26, 179 ; inverted monarchy, 28; officials in the, 30; contrasted with oligarchy, 90 ; characteristics of, 42, 135, 137, 171; and lawyers, 145 sq., 153 ; Isocrates on the, 39 ; in America, 145, 179; in England, 26, 180; in Switzerland, 180 Demos, rule of the, 26; tyrant- demos, 31 ; relation to parties, 33; V. iKKXrjaia Demosthenes, condemned, 35; ret- XOTToids, 73, 107; uncle of, 170; in the Council, 54 ; quoted, 54 n. 2, 91, 168 diaypapovpol, 188 ^vXal, 168 sq. ; officials of, ib. ; iiri- ficXrjToX Tuv, 95, 169 \apxoi, 104 Plato, iTnp.eXriT'i^i, 163; quoted, 8, 88, 174—5 Comicus, 25 n. 1, 54 n. 1 Plutarch, xvii., 78, 82, 113 TToX^fiapxos, 78, 147 iruiX-nral, 109, 126, 138 sq., 185, 189 Re-election, to the Council, 50, 56, 57 n. 2 ; to other offices, 90 and n. 1, 155 Referendum, 180 Revolutions, 91 Rhodes, 120 Rome, 46, 89, 145, 176, 187 Rotation in office, xvi., 88 sq., 188; for the Council, 49, 187; for the Archonship, 83 Salamis, battle of, 85 Schumann, xii., 80 n. 1, 146, 183 (Tiro^iJXaKes, 155 Slaves, 163, 181 Socrates, his opinions about the lot, 10, 13 ; member of the Coun- cil, 53 n. 1 Solon, 46, 83, 183 o-rdo-is, undemocratic, 38 INDEX. 195 (TTpaTTjyoi, position of, 21; com- pared to the Ministry, 22; the extent of their power, 28, 103; 102 sq., 122, 124; irpCravis tuv, 22 — 3; avTOKpdrupj 23 ffvyypaf. (id. Das Jahr 1813 (The Year 1813), by F. Kohlrausch. By Wilhelm Wagner, Ph.D. -2^. Der erste Kreuzzug (1095— 1099) nach Friedrich von Raumer. The First Crusade. By W. Wagner, Ph. D. is. Der Oberhof. A Tale of Westphalian Life, by Karl Immer- MANN. By Wilhelm Wagner, Ph.D. 3^. Der Staat Friedrichs des Grossen. By G. Freytag. By Wilhelm Wagner, Ph. D. is. Die Karavane, von Wilhelm Hauff. By A. Schlottmann, Ph.D. 3J. (id. Goetne's Hermann and Dorothea. By W. Wagner, Ph. D. Re- vised edition by J. W. Cartmell. gj. dd. Goethe's Knabenjahre. (1749— 1761.) Goethe's Boyhood. By W. Wagner, Ph.D. Revised edition by J. W. Cartmell, M.A. t.s. Hauflf, Das Bild des Kaisers. By Karl Hermann Breul, M.A., Ph.D. 3^. Hauff, Das Wirthshaus im Spessart. By A. Schlottmann, Ph.D., late Assistant Master at Uppingham School. 3J. 6d. Mendelssohn's Letters. Selections from. By James Sime, M.A. 3^-. Schiller. Wilhelm Tell. By Karl Hermann Breul, M.A., Ph.D. IS. 6d. (Abridged Edition.) li*. 6d. Selected Fables. Lessing and Gellert. By Karl Hermann Breul, M.A., Ph.D. 3^. Uhland. Ernst, Herzog von Schwaben. By H. J. Wolsten- HOLME, B.A. (Lond.). 3J. 6d. Zopt una Schwert. Lustspiel in fiinf Aufziigen von Karl Gutz- KOW. By H. J. WOLSTENHOLME, B.A. (Lond.). 3J. 6d. V. ENGLISH. An Apologie for Poetrie by Sir Philip Sidney. By E. S. Shuck- burgh, M.A. The text is a revision of that of the first edition of 1595. y. An Elementary Commercial Geography. A Sketch of the Com- modities and Countries of the World. By H. R. Mill, Sc. D., F.R.S.E. is. An Atlas of Commercial Geography. (Companion to the above.) By J. G. Bartholomew, F.R.G.S. With an Introduction by Dr H. R. Mill. 3J. London: Cambridge Warehouse., Ave Maria Lane, 20 PUBLICATIONS OF THE UNIVERSITY PRESS. Ancient Philosophy from Thales to Cicero, A Sketch of, by Joseph B. Mayor, M.A. is. 6d. Bacon's History of the Reign of King Henry VII. By the Rev. Professor Lumby, D.D. 3^. British India, a Short History of. By Rev. E. S. Carlos, M.A. i^. Cowley's Essays. By Prof. Lumby, D.D. 4^. General Aims of the Teacher, and Form Management. Two Lec- tures by F. W. Farrar, D.D. and R. B. Poole, B.D. is. 6d. John Amos Comenius, Bishop of the Moravians. His Life and Educational Works, by S. S. Laurie, A.M., F.R.S.E. 3^. 6d. Locke on Education. By the Rev, R. H. Quick, M.A. 3^. 6d. Milton's Arcades and Comus. By A. W. Verity, M.A. 3^. Milton's Tractate on Education. A facsimile reprint from the Edition of 1673. Edited by O. Browning, M.A. is. More's History of King Richard III. By J. Rawson Lumby, D.D. 3^-. 6d. On stimulus. A Lecture deUvered for the Teachers' Training Syndicate at Cambridge, May 1882, by A. Sidgwick, M.A. New Ed. i^. Outhnes of the Philosophy of Aristotle. Compiled by Edwin Wallace, M.A., LL.D. Third Edition, Enlarged. 4s. 6d. Sir Thomas More's Utopia. By Prof. Lumby, D.D. 3^. 6^. Theory and Practice of Teaching. By E. Thring, M.A. 4^. 6d, The Teaching of Modern Languages in Theory and Practice. By C. Colbeck, M.A. 2s. The Two Noble Kinsmen. By Professor Skeat, Litt.D. 3^. 6d. Three Lectures on the Practice of Education. I. On Marking byH.W. Eve, M.A. II. On Stimulus, by A. Sidgwick, M.A. III. On the Teaching of Latin Verse Composition, by E. A. Abbott, D.D. 2s. VI. MATHEMATICS. Euclid's Elements of Geometry, Books I. and II. By H. M. Taylor, M.A. i^. 6d. Books III. and IV. By the same Editor, is. 6d. Books L— IV. in one volume. :^s. Elementary Algebra (with Answers to the Examples). By W. W. Rouse Ball, M.A. 4J". 6d. Elements of Statics and Dynamics. By S. L. Loney, M.A. Part I. Elements of Statics. 4^-. 6d. Part II. Elements of Dynamics. [Nearly ready. UoniJon : c. j. clay and sons, CAMBRIDGE WAREHOUSE, AVE MARIA LANE. (Klasphj: 263, ARGYLE STREET. CawfttOJae: DEIGHTON, bell and go. fLeujjie: F. A. BROCKHAUS. i^tto lork: MACMILLAN AND CO. Cambridge: printed by c. j. clay, m.a. & sons, at the university press. RETURN TO the circulation desk of any University of California Library or to the NORTHERN REGIONAL LIBRARY FACILITY BIdg. 400, Richmond Field Station University of California Richmond, CA 94804-4698 ALL BOOKS MAY BE RECALLED AFTER 7 DAYS • 2-month loans may be renewed by calling (510)642-6753 • 1-year loans may be recharged by bringing books to NRLF • Renewals and recharges may be made 4 days prior to due date DUE AS STAMPED BELOW OCT 1 2005 DD20 12M 1-05 515643 UNIVERSITY OF CALIP^NIA LIBRARY