i
GIFT OF
JANE K-SATHER
1
i
ELECTION BY LOT AT ATHENS.
Sotttott: C. J. CLAY AND SONS,
CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS WAREHOUSE,
AVE MARIA LANE.
Camfiriiflc: DEIGHTON, BELL, AND CO.
ILeipjifl: F. A. BROCKHAUS.
^tia lorft : MACMILLAN AND CO.
Canibrflrgt ^fsitorical (Kstsfapst. Bo. IV.
ELECTION BY LOT AT ATHENS.
BY
JAMES WYCLIFFE HEADLAM, M.A,
FELLOW OF king's COLLEGE, CAMBRIDGE.
PRINCE CONSORT DISSERTATION, 1890.
AT THE UNIVERSITY PRESS.
1891
[All Rights reserved.]
CTambrilige :
PRINTED BY C. J. CLAY, M.A. AND SONS,
AT THB UNIVERSITY PRESS.
(Sree^ j I restriction of this kind to the free action of the lot ;
^ ' had such existed it would have been an effectual
check on the objects for which the lot was introduced.
I propose therefore to enquire what were the
reasons for which the Athenians adopted a custom
so strange, and also to examine what were the effects
of it on the political system of which it formed a
part. It is scarcely necessary to point out that, with-
out an explanation of this matter, we cannot hope
thoroughly to understand or appreciate the nature
of the Athenian Democracy; and I hope the enquiry^
even if it is of no other use, will help to draw at-
tention to some peculiarities of the administrative
system and will thereby throw light on certain
tendencies which seem to be essential to democratic
government.
The con- But before I discuss the first question, what
r^'zoT political advantages were supposed to come from the
'With use of the lot, it is necessary to consider a sugges-
beliefs. tion which, if true, would greatly alter the character
of the enquiry. It is often maintained that the
essence of the lot was religious. If this were true
then we should have to consider it as we do omens
and oracles; it would be another case of an old
superstition interfering with the political life of the
INTRODUCTION. 5
people ; its preservation would be another instance
of that deep-rooted conservatism in all that con-
cerned their worship which often reminds us that
the Athenians were not all philosophers or sceptics.
It is well established that in early stages-of.
jociety the lot is regarded as one among many ways
through which the Gods give counsel and advice to
men. This was the case both in Greece and Italy.
The Greek lived in constant intercourse with his
Gods; for every work which he began and every
decision which he made he looked to them for
advice and guidance. He required some hint as to
the result of his labours or some sanction for his
enterprise. And the drawing or casting of lots was
always one way in which this communication took
place. This is abundantly proved from the times of
Homer down to the latest days of the Roman
Empire: and, as might reasonably have been ex-
pected, the lot was chiefly used when the matter
on which the Gods were consulted was the choice
either of some man from a limited number to receive
certain honours or perform certain duties, or the
division among a few men of an equal number of
duties.
The best illustration of this is the fact that Priests
throughout Greece it was the regular custom to use ly^^iot^ ^
the lot for the appointment of priests and others
who ministered in the temples \ There is no doubt
that this was done because it was held fitting that
the God himself should choose those who were to
^ Cf. Jules Martha, Les Sacerdoces Ath^niens in the Bibl. des
6coles FraiK^aises, xxvi. 1882. pp. 30 — 35.
6 INTRODUCTION.
serve him. If he had not declared his pleasure by
an omen or a dream, an opinion could always be
secured by the use of the lot. This custom prevailed
till the latest times, and though it had probably
become a mere ritual observance, it is at least a sign
that the appointment of a priest had not the highest
validity unless it had received the express sanction
of the God.
It is easy then to assume that the lot which
was so essential a part of the religious ceremonial
retained its religious significance when used for
political purposes ; and even to draw the conclusion
that the religious belief was really the chief reason
why it was so extensively used. There is nothing
in what we know of Athenian habits of thought to
make this improbable ; whatever may have been the
opinions of a few educated men, there is no doubt
that the great mass of the people firmly believed
in the continual intervention of the Gods in the
affairs of men. They were not ashamed, nor were
they frightened, to allow affairs of the greatest
moment to be influenced by dreams, omens, portents
and oracles. They were guided by these in private
and public life alike \ We should therefore be quite
prepared to find that the use of the lot in state affairs
1 Perhaps the most remarkable illustration of this is con-
tained in one of the speeches of Hypereides. We there find the
Assembly solemnly ordering three men to go and sleep in a temple
in order that one of them might learn in a dream the opinion of
Amphiaraus on a disputed point of property (Or. iii pro Euxen-
ippo, xxvii — viii). It is only necessary to refer to the Anabasis and
Hellenica of Xenophon for instances of the readiness with which
men would incur the greatest dangers rather than neglect an omen.
INTRODUCTION. 7
was, at least by the great mass of the people, upheld
because they wished thereby to get the sanction of
the Gods for the appointment of their officials.
This view becomes still more plausible when we
remember that the most conspicuous of the officials
so appointed were the nine Archons ; men who had
special religious duties and still represented in their
office the old union of priest and magistrate. And
the state worship at Athens was so closely connected
with the public functions that even though the
newer offices did not have the same religious im-
portance as the Archonship, it is easy to suppose
that the pious Athenians liked to have the same
divine sanction extended also to those who filled
them\
This however will not really explain our difficulty.
The explanation has been put forward '"^ by those who
have confined their attention to the Archonship
and have not sufficiently appreciated the reality and
extent of the use of the lot. It may be true that
there was a religious sentiment which made the
1 Cf. LugebU, 1. c. p. 666 etc.
2 Fustel de Coulanges, Nouvelle Eevue Historique de Droit, ii.
1878, p. 617 — 643; and La Cite antique, p. 213. "Le caract^re
sacerdotal qui s'attachait au magistrat se montre surtout dans la
mani^re dont il 6tait 61u. Aux yeux des anciens, il ne semblait
pas que les suffrages des hommes fussent suffisants pour dtablir
le chef de la cit6. Les hommes paraissent avoir cherche, pour
supplier k la naissance, un mode d'61ection que les dieux
n'eussent pas a d6savouer. Les Ath6niens, comme beaucoup
de peuples grecs, n'en virent pas de meilleur que le tirage de
sort. Pour eux le sort n'6tait pas le hasard ; le sort 6tait la
r6v61ation de la volont6 divine." He gives no illustrations of
this except two passages from the Laws of Plato. Cf. p. 8 n. 1.
8
INTRODUCTION.
Use of the
lot at
Athens
cannot be
explained
by refer-
enx;e to
religious
beliefs.
common people cling to the lot, and it could have
happened that far-sighted statesmen used this to help
in carrying out their policy, but it will not explain
why statesmen who certainly were not influenced by
religious conservatism wished to extend the use of it,
nor how it was that the state which used it could
possibly exist and prosper. What evidence there is
for the view is, I believe, entirely confined to pas-
sages which speak of the Archonship, and, as I shall
show, the use of the lot for this was only a small and
scarcely the most important part of its application.
The fact is that at Athens where the use of
the lot was most common the evidence for its reli-
gious signification is smallest. This can be seen
by the small number of references put forward by
those who maintain this view. I believe the only
passages which expressly refer to the lot as giving
religious sanction to an appointment are two which
occur in the Laws of Plato ^; and it will be sufficient
to point out that the constitution of the ideal state
which the philosopher is describing is essentially
different from that of Athens, and that he is in
the second of the two passages expressly showing
how different is his ideal fi-om the "equality" of a
democracy. He is gravely reminding his readers of
what the lot ought to be. Everyone will agree that
the lot could be regarded as a religious institution,
and that it had been such in old times, but never-
theless after the beginning of the fifth century it
does not appear to have been so regarded at Athens.
This is shown even by the poets. In the Tra-
1 Plato, Leges iii. 690 «=; vi. 757*.
INTRODUCTION. 9
gedians mention is often made of the lot; and
occasionally in such words that we are reminded it
had a religious origin. But this is only the case
when it is mentioned in direct connection with the
services of some temple \ In no other cases is it
spoken of as religious ; and never do we find at-
taching to its use the awe and mystery which
belongs to other more impressive means of divine
utterance. Even in ^Eschylus it has none of the
associations which belong to oracles and dreams.
Still more is this true of Euripides. We find in
the Heracleidae one striking instance of this " secvi-
larisation " of the lot. Macaria says she is willing
to be made a sacrifice to Demeter, who has demanded
the offering of a maiden. lolaus demurs. He
represents that it would be juster if she and her
sisters drew lots, and selected the victim in this way.
But Macaria will not hear of this; such a death
would not please her.
ovfc av Odvoifjui rfj TV')(r) \a')(ova iyca'
It would be wanting in the graciousness which
belongs to a voluntary sacrifice. And Euripides
does not think it necessary to put into the mouth
of either of his characters the suggestion that to
submit to the will of the goddess expressed in this
way would be even more gracious than self-willed
to force oneself upon her^.
This and similar passages do not go far: but
1 Eur. Ion, 415. iEsch. Eum. 33.
2 Eur. Heracleidae 547.
3 Mr Frazer in the Golden Bough gives an account of an old
10 INTRODUCTION.
they are some evidence that the religious feeling
connected with the lot was, even in a matter directly
connected with the gods, extremely weak, and point
to the fact, not that the political use of the lot
was a religious ceremony, but that the constant use
of it for secular purposes had almost completely
destroyed the old religious associations.
So when Socrates freely expressed contempt for
the lot, this was made the ground for a charge of
political discontent, but it is never referred to as
connected with the accusations of atheism. And
the speeches of the orators afford stronger testi-
mony to the same phenomenon. These clever men
who are so ready to use every fallacy likely to be
effective and appeal to every prejudice or common-
place likely to give them the appearance of right,
never once, in the speeches which are preserved,
allude to the lot as sacred ; and this though the
audience they were addressing was in nearly every
case selected by the lot. The absence of such a
reference is sometimes startling. There is a pas-
sage in Deinarchus where he makes a passionate
appeal to the dicasts to condemn Philocles. "The
people," he says, "have deprived this man of his
office; they did not think it right or safe that he
should longer have the care of their children, and
custom which used to prevail in many parts of Scotland ; pieces
of dough, one of which is blackened, are put into a hat ; the
inhabitants one after another take each one of the pieces blind-
folded out of the hat. The one who draws the black piece is
a victim. He is not now burnt, but part of the company make a
show of putting him into the fire. Vol. ii. p. 255 — 6.
INTRODUCTION. 11
will you, you who are guardians of the democracy
and the laws, you whom chance and the lot have
appointed to give justice for the people, will you
spare him^?" If he could have done so without
being ridiculous would not Deinarchus have said
^€09 not Tv^n ? It is scarcely too much to say that
not only did neither he nor his audience believe in
the religious connections of the lot, but that they
did not even pretend to do so.
For this is not a single case. We have for
instance a speech by Lysias written in defence of a
man who had been appointed ^ovXevrr]^, but had
been accused on his So/afjuaaia^. He had been ap-
pointed by the lot : his opponents wished to unseat
him on political grounds. Lysias never uses the
obvious topic, he never warns his hearers that the
man whom the lot has selected has acquired a
peculiar right, and that to undo his appointment
without due cause is a form of sacrilege.
The conclusion I draw from these facts is that Conclu-
the lot was religious in its origin, and that it was to *^
the latest times throughout Greece used in the
ritual of the temples with a clear acknowledgment
that its decision gave a divine sanction ; but that at
Athens owing to its constant use for political pur-
poses it was secularised till almost all recollection
of its religious origin had disappeared; that the
statesmen who developed the system in which it
was used were not themselves guided by religious
beliefs, and that, even if they were to some extent
helped by a certain superstitious feeling among the
1 Deinarchus, in Philoclen 15 — 16. ^ Lysias, pro Mantitheo.
12 INTRODUCTION.
poorer people, this was in no way the decisive cause
of the success of their policy. Soon amidst all the
busy political and legal life at Athens what there
was of religious feeling about it died out. It was at
Rome where it was seldom used, not at Athens
^7here it influenced the life of every citizen, that men
talked of the "religio sortis\"
We can then return to our original question:
What was the object and effect of the extended use
of the lot as it prevailed during the fifth and fourth
centuries ? and I shall attempt to show how the
Athenian statesmen used this relic of a dying super-
stition as the means of carrying out with remarkable
vigour their political ideals.
The lot For whatever may be our difficulties the Greeks
themselves seem to have had no doubt why the lot
was used at Athens, nor what its effect was. On
this they are explicit. Election by lot was a demo7
cratic institution ; more, it was necessary to a demo-
cracy. In this they are almost unanimous ; friends
and enemies of democracy all agree on this point
that in a perfectly democratic state magistrates will
1 It is only necessary to read Fustel de Coulanges' account of
the democracy (La Cite antique, iv. ch. 11) to see how impossible
his theory is. It leads him to a direct misstatement of fact
when he says "Les magistrats pretres ^taient choisis par le
sort. Les magistrats qui n'exer(;aient que des fanctions d'ordre
public dtaient 61us par le peuple." And jae is quite unable on his
hypothesis to give any clear explanation of the Council, This is
the more to be regretted as the mistake comes from exaggerating
the importance of what is within certain limits a most useful
suggestion, and one which has thrown much light on an obscure
matter.
demo-
cratic.
INTRODUCTION. 13
be elected by lot\ I know nothing which makes us
feel so clearly our separation from the political world
of the Greeks as this. Here is an institution which
to us is almost incredible, and yet we find writer'
after writer assuming that a city cannot be a real
democracy without adopting it. ' ' The few adverse
criticisms on it which have been preserved to us
make this only more clear ; they are invariably the
criticisms of men opposed to democracy, and objection
to elections by lot is always accompanied by dislike
of democracy. We are told that Socrates used to
say that it was foolish to appoint the rulers of the
city by lot ; no one would have confidence in a pilot
or a carpenter or a musician who had been chosen
in this way; and yet which had most power to harm,
an incompetent magistrate or a bad artist ? But
then Socrates was an irreconcilable in politics; it
was not only election by lot but all the institutions
of the city which he criticised ; and we know that
not only did his objections appear to his contem-
poraries foolish and pedantic, but his opinions on
political matters and the free expression he gave to
them were among the reasons why he was put to
death as a bad citizen. Socrates thought the lot
wrong and foolish ; that he did so was a proof of his
anti-democratic bias I
Even more striking is the attitude of the author
1 Herod, iii. 80 ; Plato, Rep. 561 a— b ; Aristotle, Rhet. i. 8.
Muller-Striibing quotes Isocr. Areop. 20 — 27 as evidence that the
lot was not democratic. On a point of historical fact the witness
of Isocrates is of little value ; and he is here arguing from the
peculiar circumstances of his own time, cf. pp. 96 — 7 ; and p. 39.
2 Xen. Mem. i. 2, 9.
14 INTRODUCTION.
of the pamphlet " On the Constitution of the Athe-
nians \" He is a vigorous and confident oligarch:
for him life in a democratic state is scarcely worth
living; his ideal is that the nobles (ol xRV^^ol) should
rule: that the people should be their subjects, their
slaves (BovXooy. All the institutions of Athens,
election by lot included, are in his opinion causes
of unendurable license and disorder. And yet he
cannot refrain from expressing his admiration of the
Athenian constitution, for he acknowledges that it
completely secures what is desired ; it is democracy
and therefore hateful to him and to every other right-
minded man who loves order and good government ;
but it is at least a successful democracy'; it is
impossible to get a more perfect democracy than the
Athenian; the people know what they want and
they have got it ; election by lot, freedom of speech,
offices open to all however ignorant and however
uneducated — they are perfectly right he says when
they regard these as an essential part of a democracy.
He too is of opinion that democracy without its
extravagances would be no democracy at all*.
And this opinion was not peculiar to literary
men, to philosophers and historians; it was the
principle on which the practical men in Greece
^ 'Adrjvaltov iroXiTeia, formerly attributed to Xenophon. Cf.
esp. i. 9, ei/vofjiia cannot be found in a democracy ; ii. 20, no good
man can live iv b-qfioKpaTovfihi^ -rrdXei.
2 ii. 9, dwb TOTjTwv roivvv tQv ayadQiv Tdx^(TT dv 6 5^/ios eh
dovkeiav KaTairiffOL.
^ ii. 26, 8r)fjL0KpaTtav 5' iyoj /xh avTip ti^ 5^Mi^ avyycyu(Jba-K(ij
avrbv jxkv ycip eD irotelv Tract crvyyvcb/JLTj ecriv.
* ii. 19 ; i. 1—8.
INTRODUCTION. 15
acted Our knowledge of the internal constitutions
of other states besides Athens is small, but it is
sufficient to show us that when a state took a demo-
cratic constitution election by lot was introduced along
with other changes. We are specially told that this
was the case at Syracuse* and at Tarentum^; and
when Athens obliged her allies to adopt a democratic
form of government, election by lot was as a matter
of course included ^
Aristotle's account of the matter is very instruc-
tive* : he generally speaks of " election " (xeiporovla,
aipecn^) as either aristocratic or oligarchic ; for it
gives influence to birth money or ability ; he recog-
nises indeed that election by all the citizens is to
some extent democratic, but he regards it as a cha-
racteristic of the old moderate democracy {iraTpia
Brj/jLOKpaTLa) and he contrasts this with the new
{v€(0TaT7j Brj/jLOKpaTla) where offices are filled by
lot^ Popular election is that moderate concession to
democracy which is desirable in order to give the
state permanence by interesting all classes in the
government, but he consistently represents election
by lot as a sign of what he calls the extreme
democracy.
On this point there can be no doubt : election by Objections
lot was regarded by those who had experience of it H^idered.
as essentially democratic : if this is the case we may
1 Diodorus, xiii. 34.
2 Ar. Pol. vii. 5 (quoted by Gilbert, Gr. St. ii. p. 245, n. I).
3 C. I. A. i. 9.
4 Pol. ii. 11, 1273*; vi. 9, 1294^; vii. 2, 131?!^; vii. 2, 1318*.
5 Pol. viii. 5, 1305*.
16 INTRODUCTION.
add, it was democratic. It would require some very
strong proofs to justify us in putting aside the
almost unanimous verdict of the Greeks themselves
on a point on which they had complete experience
and of which we have no knowledge except what we
gain from them.
When then a modern historian^ informs us that
election by lot was not a democratic but an oli-
garchic institution, and that it was introduced at
Athens not to strengthen the democracy but to
temper it and make it less repugnant to the defeated
oligarchs, we look for some very weighty reasons to
justify the paradox. The paradox has been stated
lately and has met with a certain amount of fa-
vour. This is partly due to the interest which any
novelty must arouse in a subject which has been
so thoroughly discussed as Athenian constitutional
history; a new theory however paradoxical is sure
to command a hearing if promulgated with sufficient
confidence and at sufficient length ; a boldly stated
novelty will attract the reader who is wearied with
the study of innumerable discussions of minute
details. But this favourable reception is also due
to the fact that it has no rival: historians have
recognised that as a matter of fact election by lot^
was democratic, but they have not clearly explained
the reason why it was so. Generally speaking it seems
clear that if any one could be elected to any office,
and if the poorest and most ignorant citizen had an
equal chance with an Alcmseonid or a pupil of
1 Miiller-Striibing, Aristophanes und die historische Kritik,
p. 206 etc.
INTRODUCTION. l7
Gorgias, the state where this was the case was not
an aristocracy; but still the necessity and the ad-
vantage of the system are not obvious ; the orthodox
traditional view is vague and has no firm foundation,
so that one is naturally tempted to say there is
something in the new theory : and many who do not
accept it as a whole have altered their statement
of the older view, and tell us that, although the lot
was of course democratic, yet it was after all to a
certain extent aristocratic too\
Our object must be then to try and understand
not only why election by lot was democratic, but why
the ancients considered it essential to a complete
democracy.
In order to do so, it will be necessary to recall What the
certain peculiarities of ancient democracy, which it „J^^/
is easy for us to ignore. The fact that the word ^y Demo- '
" democracy " is still in constant use among us, and
that we apply it to political phenomena of the
present day, is a great obstacle to our understanding
of Greek History. The danger is the greater that
the modern use of the word is so nearly akin to the
original meaning ; but none the less the word has not
now the same connotation as it had 2000 years ago ;
1 I do not mean to deny that the lot was often used in states
which were not democratic, and that in the period before the
Persian wars it was introduced in many oligarchies. As will be
seen below, I believe that it was. All I wish to make clear is that,
as used at Athens from the time of Persian wars, it was of the very
essence of the democracy. The importance of the experiment at
Athens caused the older use in oligarchic states to be forgotten
just as it destroyed the religious significance. Cf. Curtius,
Griechische Geschichte, i. 377 (3rd edition). [Cf. Appendix.] j
H. 2^
18 INTRODUCTION.
and it requires the greatest care when we are deal-
ing with Greek history and reading Greek books
to keep our minds free from modern associations,
and to preserve the idea which we connect with the
word as pure simple and clearly defined as was that
of the Greeks. We have a double difficulty to sur-
mount in achieving this, for not only do we use Greek
words when we speak of modern politics, but also our
method of education tempts us to think of modern
events under Greek forms. Our first acquaintance
with political thought comes through Thucydides
and Aristotle, and we try to fit the wisdom we have
learnt from them to the facts of modern life. By so
doing we not only lose the freedom of thought
necessary to comprehend new facts, but we uncon-
sciously spoil our apprehensions of Greek life. By
trusting too much to the fancied analogies of modem
times we lose in the vividness and niceness of our
conceptions of ancient politics \
The assumption which in one form or another
seems to me to underlie most of the difficulties which
historians discover in understanding why the lot is
democratic, depends on a confusion of this kind.
1 Muller-Striibing is one of the worst offenders. He tries
xi. •
^^f. ries because it seems as it their very variety were
political, evidence that the basis common to all is unsound.
Instead of enquiring whether it was the ra^juia^ roov
KocvMV TTpocoBcov, OT the 7rpVTavtiop. Thuc. ii. 65.
Aristotle in the Politics never speaks of elections as party
affairs, nor does he refer to party elections connected with them.
On the subject of the election of generals see Droysen, Hermes,
IX.
We hear most about the elections of exceptional officials such
as ambassadors. A curious fact is preserved about one of these
elections. Dem. de corona 149 (277) tells us that .^schines was
nominated {irpo^X-qdeLs) to the office of irvXaydpas, and elected rptuv
26 INTRODUCTION.
expect. And I propose by a short examination of
certain aspects of the Athenian constitution to show
why this was so. When this point has been cleared
up, we shall be in a better position to understand
the Greek view of election by lot.
The reason It was impossible that at Athens elections should
of this. ]iave political importance; it was impossible just
because Athens was a complete democracy : for the
same reason that election by lot was introduced.
Elections can only be of political importance when
the elected magistrates have for some period con-
siderable independence of action, and when the sove-
reign power from which they derive their authority
is exercised only intermittently. In such cases the
people (supposing that the sovereign power and
ultimate appeal is with them) does not itself govern
the country; it delegates its powers to elected
representatives who within wide limits are free
Contrast to do just as they like. Hence the only way which
of ancient ^^le people have of directing the policy of the state
modern is to elect men pledged to follow certain lines. From
^acv *^^^ necessity springs inevitably the whole system of
party elections. Where the country is governed by
an elected assembly, or an elected head of the state^
the elections to these offices, in as much as they are
almost the only occasions when the people exercises
its sovereign power, must be events of the greatest
importance.
In a state like Athens just the reverse is the
case. It was the essence of the constitution that
the demos should itself rule : it did not, as do the
people in England or France, appoint its rulers ; it
INTRODUCTION. 2T
did. -Hot delegate its power ; its sovereignty was not
intermittent, it was continually exercised. And in
consequence the magistrates at Athens had a posi-
tion quite other to that held by ministers in a
modern democracy. They were not the men to whose
wisdom and discretion the votes of the people for a
time entrusted the supreme management of affairs :
they were appointed to carry out the decrees of the
people and to obey its commands. The demos could
not bind itself by any election to follow any set
policy or to adhere to any plan, for the eKKXTja-la
met at least once a month and could at any time be
summoned, and at each meeting it was able to
discuss and alter the decisions of a previous meeting.
Suppose that in any year the aTpaTrjyoL were all
chosen from the war party, that these had won at
the elections ; the people did not thereby deprive
themselves of the power of making peace during the
year; a popular orator of the opposite party could
bring forward a motion and carry it. But if he did
so the position of the generals was unaltered ; they
did not resign, they had simply to carry out the
policy of which they disapproved \ In England -Oi:,
1 Beloch (Att. Politik, p. 15), "Die Geschafte des Landes aus
dem Bema der Pnyx auszufuhren war in Athen noch weniger
moglich als heute von der Tribune des Parlaments."
This is surely exactly wrong. The object of the whole
arrangement of the constitution was to enable orators to guide
the business of the state from the Assembly. If he refers to the
German Parliament the statement is absurd : a German parlia-
mentary leader has no influence at all on the conduct of
business. If the reference is to the English Parliament it is
wrong, because the Trpoo-rdrTjs rod di^fiov had without office just
as much power as an English parliamentary leader has with office.
Cf. infra, p. 112 etc.
28 INTRODUCTION.
America the elections are of importance because
during the period which follows the people are
without any direct control over the fate of the
country : they have given their decision, and must
abide by it. In Athens, where the sovereign as-
sembly met constantly, the elections had in conse-
quence no political import; men were chosen not
for the policy which they advocated but for their
ability and character. The question between candi-
dates was always a personal not a party one. An
election might be a sign of the popularity and in-
fluence of men who supported different policies : it
could not bind the people to follow one or the
other.
If we remember this, we shall no longer be dis-
turbed by the small number of references to elections
which we find in ancient writers, nor wonder at the
small place which they filled in the political con-
troversies and passions of the time; and we shall
cease to enquire which official held the place of our
Prime Minister. And when we realise how this
direct, sovereignty of the people worked, we shall
see why election by lot was considered essential to
the maintenance of democracy.
Demo- Sir Henry Maine in his book on Popular Govem-
Tnverud ^^^^ reminds us that democracy is a form of
monarchy, government, and objects to modern incorrect uses
of the word. That the word should have changed
its meaning, and should be now used to describe
social tendencies is natural and harmless, so long as
we recognise the fact ; it is however of great import-
ance that we should remember that the Greeks who
INTRODUCTION. 29
invented the word did mean by it a definite simple
form of government. A Greek had no doubt what
he meant by a Democracy ; it was a city in which
the people gathered together at a definite place in
one large visible assembly governed the whole state.
When we speak of popular government we mean by
" people " a great mass of men living long distances
apart from one another who have never seen one
another and who never will. The Greeks meant a
very limited number of men who were accustomed to
come together in a definite place. People with us
is a vague idea: the demos to an Athenian was a
concrete thing which he had often seen and heard ;
it was the eKKXrjala. So too by " government " we
mean a vague ill-defined control of the government.
In no modern country does the people govern ; it is
incapable of doing so, it is not sufficiently organised ;
the work of government is too complicated. Parlia-
ment, or Ministers, or the President, govern : the
people appoint them and more or less control them.
But at Athens the 817/^09 did govern. It was not
primarily an elective body, that function fell into
secondary importance ; it was not a legislative body,
that was the only duty which was not directly
within its sphere ; it was a judicial, and above all an
executive body.
Sir Henry Maine expresses this by saying that
JDemocracy is inverted Monarchy. In a monarchy
the king governs ; he has servants, he has advisers ;
responsible ministers he has none : statesmen are
his servants, they do his bidding, they may offer
advice, but if their advice be not taken they must be
30 INTRODUCTION.
prepared to obey none the less. A favourite may
become powerful, but his power depends on the
king's favour; there may be rivalry, there may be
antagonistic influences; round the bed-chamber of
the king, or the salon of his mistress ambitious men
contend for the privilege of executing his commands
and influencing his will. But great parties there
are none, and in a perfect monarchy there are no
great ministers: the king himself decides all ques-
tions, officials have only to prepare them for his
consideration ; he has not only the position of a
king, but the toil and labour of a ruler.
And so in a perfect democracy the people does
all which in a monarchy is the work of the king.
All questions of government, all the difficulties of
administration, every innovation in every depart-
ment comes directly before the people : the officials
do not decide anything, they only formulate the
questions which come before the sovereigu people.
They do not do the work for the people. They are not
appointed to represent it. They are there as clerks
or secretaries; their duty is to bring order and
arrangement into the mass of details ; they help the
people to govern, but they help as a freedman
helped the Roman Emperor. The people, like the
king, has its advisers and favourites, those who
know the art of influencing the royal will; these
.are the orators in the eK/cXTjcrla, and the first
favourite of the time is o 7rpoaTdTT}<; rov hrjfjbov.
But, like the power of the royal favourites, their
power does not come from office, and office is not
necessary to it; the people, like the king, prefers
INTRODUCTION. 31
often to appoint to ojffice men whose advice it would
never take; men who do not personally please it,
but whose ability and integrity it respects. And as
in a perfect monarchy we find no great ministers of
state, but the king surrounded by his satellites
and courtiers rules alone, — his ministers having no
part in the rule, nor any independence of action, — so
in a perfect democracy we shall not expect to find
great offices; the magistrates will have only to
prepare business for the Assembly ; they will make
ruling easier, but they will not take upon themselves
part of the duties of ruling ; they will be wheels in
the great machine, not separate machines.
Therefore, if the state is to be a democracy. Results of
there must be no powerful officials; for demo-
cracy means rule by the demos, government by
the eKK\7)(TLa ; and the demos or eKKXrjcrla, if it
is really to rule, cannot allow any other power
to exist in the state, not even if it is a body
which derives its authority from the demos. The
Greeks themselves were quite clear on this point \
They saw well enough that the power of the
demos was like that of a monarch, and that a
"democracy" could allow no power in the state
independent of the Assembly. The " tyrant demos "
was a very stern reality to Thucydides and Plato
1 Cf. Aristotle, Pol. viii. (v.) 11, 1313»'— 1314 Kal rd. xepl tV
b-qfiOKparlav bk yipSfieva t^p reXevraLav rvpavviKk iravra, Kal yhp
6 dTjfios eXvai ^OTuXeTai fiovapxos, dib Kal 6 K6\a^ Trap' d./j.s vS/xovs irpid/ievos.
THE COUNCrL.
55
the charge it would hardly have been passed over so
lightly. It is probably nothing but a characteristic
method of expressing annoyance that Demosthenes
had been fortunate enough to get elected.
The reference is, however, of some interest as
being one of the clearest cases in which we find that
a politician was to some extent helped in his measures
by the fact that he was a member of the council.
Others do occur, but on the whole hardly with
sufficient frequency to justify us in supposing that a
seat was necessary for a politician, or that he could
in any way reckon upon being a member. It seems as
though most well-known men were in the council at
least once (though this cannot be proved for nearly
all); but, as we must remember, to have a seat
once was not more than any citizen might hope for\
The only other evidence on the matter comes Evidence
from some lists which have been preserved of Pry-
tanies, belonging to the fourth century I Of these
three give about the full number of councillors
belonging to one tribe. An examination of them
gives the following results :
(1) The number of members belonging to each
deme appears to vary with the size of the deme, and
the number elected for the same deme in different
1 In a great number of cases in which men are mentioned in
connection with the council, the man was not necessarily himself a
member, but was present either as an oiBflcial of some kind, or simply
as a private man there on business. Cf. Lysias, v. 33. When we
are told that Pericles was regular in his attendance at the council,
it does not follow that he was a member. He went in his capacity
of general.
2 C. I. A. II. 864 etc. q (
of inscrip-
tions.
56 THE COUNCIL.
i years seems to be constant. From this we may
' gather that at the election a certain number were
/ chosen from each deme, and that the members were
/ not chosen from the whole tribe indiscriminately.
(2) There are a few cases where the names of
the same deme are preserved for more than one
year. Among these only one case of re-election is
to be found. This perhaps shows that re-election
was not very frequent.
(3) No names of distinguished politicians occur;
but on the other hand there are a large number of
names which can be identified as occurring, (a) in
the private speeches of the orators, (/3) in lists of
trierarchs, (7) as members of distinguished families.
However, a very large proportion of the names
are completely unknown, many being names which
occur nowhere else in Greek history and must there-
fore belong to families of no distinction or wealth.
On the whole, so far as we can see, the different
strata of Athenian society are each fairly represented.
There is no evidence that wealthy and distinguished
men abstained from sitting in the council, nor is there
a larger number of them in these lists than would be
a fair proportion.
(4) It is remarkable that three times near
relatives (twice two brothers, and once father and
son) sit together. This can hardly be a coincidence.
Leading The conclusion from this evidence is that we
statesmen j^^^^ ^^ reason for supposing that public men could
necessarily in any way command a seat in the council, and it
would, I think, be difficult to find the record of any
events in Athenian history which would justify the
THE COUNCIL. 57
assertion that a place in it was necessary to an
ambitious man. It was possible to rule the whole
state without having a seat in it. How this was so
will be seen if we examine more minutely what the
duties of the council were\
The council was not, as we are apt to think, a Duties of
dignified deliberative body, where men met together council.
quietly in order to discuss and prepare schemes for
the public welfare, which should afterwards be laid
before the Assembly and receive its sanction. Had
the council had to initiate and decide upon policy,
the leading orators must have been members of it ;
and had they been members it would doubtless have
acquired this function. But, as it was, its duties
though no less important were far less impos-
ing. It was not a deliberative, but an executive
body; it was concerned not with policy, but with
business. It had to carry out the decrees of the
Assembly ; it was occupied with innumerable points
of detail ; it had to make decisions, not on matters of
peace and war or internal reforms, but on the appoint-
ment of subordinate officials, on the amount of tribute
to be paid by some ally, the necessity for rebuilding
warehouses, or restoring triremes. Its time was
occupied with the inspection of accounts, the mak-
ing of contracts, the paying of money, the hearing of
1 If I am right in supposing that the method of appointment
prevented the leading politicians sitting regularly in the council,
it will also follow that no one else could procure his election or
re-election, and therefore that re-election did not prevail to such
an extent as to interfere with the truth of the principle which
I stated above, pp. 49 — 50.
Xevfia.
58 THE COUNCIL.
petitions from individuals, the reception of informa-
tion about the position of the enemy's fleet, or the
price of corn in the Euxine; in fact, with the innu-
merable matters of administration which in a modern
state are brought before the permanent officials \ A
reference to its most prominent duties will make this
clear.
(1) irpo^oTU' vXJtrhe most important of its duties was perhaps
the preparation of business for the Assembly;
it is well known that no decree could be passed
1 Of. [Xenophon] 'Ad-qvaiwv UoXirela, iii. 2, etc. for the duties
of the council ; — the chief are, the appointment of 400 trierarchs
every year, the assessment of the tribute every four years, to
decide judicial questions, et tls rrjv vavv ixt] eiria-Kevd^ei t] kutolko-
dofxeX TL 8r)fx6(nou. It is difficult to understand to what the ttoXXo,
irepl vofiiov 64(rews in iii. 2 refers.
Boeckh, p. 187 (208), gives an account of the financial activity
of the council, which shows well the kind of work it had to do : —
" It had, according to the pamphlet on the Athenian Constitu-
tion, to occupy itself with provision of money, with reception of
the tribute, and as we can conclude from another source, with
other matters connected with the tribute, with the administration
of the marine and the sanctuaries ; the leasing of the customs
was conducted under its supervision, those who had public money
or sacred money from the state had to pay it in the presence of
the council, or it had to exact payment according to the contracts,
so that it was entitled to arrest and imprison the farmers or their
sureties and collectors, if they did not pay ; in the council chamber
the Apodectai gave their report on the receipts and the money
which was due ; in the presence of the council the treasurers of
the goddess handed over and took over the treasure and received
the fines ; it determined the administration of the money, even in
small matters, such as the pay of the poets ; we have especial
mention of its superintendence over the cavalry which was main-
tained by the city, and the examination of the invalids who were
supported at the public expense, as part of its duties ; the public
debts are paid under its guidance."
THE COUNCIL. 59
which had not been introduced officially by the
council. The object of this rule is simple ; it was
not desired to give the council a special influence,
nor to restrict the freedom of debate in the As-
sembly; it was not in any way a law which as at
Kome gave the magistrates alone the right of
introducing business. This rule did not weaken the
Assembly, but strengthened it, because it provided
for the proper arrangement of debates. The Pry-
tanies summoned the Assembly, and, as the chief
committee, the council had to prepare business for it.
^. It was then only natural that they should have
notice beforehand of all measures which would be in-
troduced, since they would have to make public the
matters to be discussed, and to arrange the order of
business.
And, again, anyone who has had experience of
public debates will know how difficult it is to get
business done, and especially what trouble is caused
by inaccuracy in the wording of motions. Now we
know that the Athenians were very particular on
this point; they took great care to provide that there
were no verbal discrepancies in their laws, and no
discrepancy between the laws and decrees; it was
the duty of the council to see that all motions
brought before the Assembly were properly worded.
If an orator wished to propose a motion, he had first
to move that the council introduce a Trpo^ovXevfia
on the subject ; they had to consider the matter of
the proposal he wished to make, and then embody
it in a motion in such a way as seemed to them
most convenient ; in this way provision was made
60 THE COUNCIL.
for a consideration of the form of a Psephism
before the motion itself came before the Assembly.
As a rule the orator would doubtless be consulted
by the council, and if he were a man of position we
may imagine they would propose the Trpo^ovXev/jua
in the very words which he suggested.
There would be another reason for this law.
When a motion was proposed it would often be diffi-
cult, to tell at first what would be its result if passed,
and questions would be raised to which the answers
would only be found by special enquiry. This it
would be the duty of the council to make. They as
the centre of the executive government, in constant
communication with all the officers, and with powers
to summon and examine all witnesses, would be able
to collect the evidence to be laid before the Assembly.
This work of the drafting and preparing motions
is really part of the subordinate work of the execu-
tive officers, for it is a way of helping to the attain-
ment of an end which is proposed by someone else\
The council in doing this was not directing the
state, it was only helping other people to do so, and
giving effect to their wishes'^. And it is an im-
portant confirmation of this view that in the last few
years inscriptions have been discovered from which it
1 The fact that an orator was always held responsible for any
motion proposed by him shows that the council had not power
seriously to alter the matter of a decree, and that in the exercise
of its Probouleutic duties it did not in any way concern itself with
the wisdom of the policy proposed.
2 This is shown too by Aristotle's distinction between ij j8ou\^
and rrpo^ovXoL. Cf. infra, p. 74.
THE COUNCIL. 61
appears that there was at Athens a body of men
called avyypa(f)eLf; whose special duty it was to help avyypa-
in drafting decrees \ We are not able to say with *^"^'
confidence whether they were members of a perma-
nent bureau, or whether the men were appointed, as
in the case of the other exceptional officials, only
when their help was specially wanted, but we have
the record of their existence and activity in the text
of decrees which had been drawn up by them. In
these cases, though the draft of the bill, as on all
other occasions, was introduced to the Assembly by the
Prytanies, the council had not really performed any
probouleutic duties at all ; they simply brought for-
ward what the o-vyypa(f>€U had proposed. We find
another instance of a similar procedure in the case
where a single individual is commissioned by the
Assembly to draw up the text of a decree, and then
the council is ordered^ to bring his proposal before
the people.
In matters of foreign policy also the duty of
the council was limited to the introduction of a
treaty proposed either by Athenians who as am-
bassadors had been empowered to conduct nego-
ciations, or by the ambassadors of other states, or,
1 Cf . Schoell, Commentationes in honorem Mommsennii ;
Foucart, Bulletin de Correspondance Hellenique, 1880, p. 225;
Sauppe, Index lect. Acad. Gottingen, 1880 — 81 ; also C. I. A.
i. 58; iv. 27^. They are mentioned before the end of the fifth
century.
2 C. I. A. 27^ w. 57—61. ire pi 5^ tov eXalov tt}s airapxm
^vyypdxf/O'as Adfnrup iiridet^aTd} ttj ^ovXrj iirl rijs ivdrrjs irpvravelas,
7] 5e jSoyXrj es top hrniov e^eveyK^ro) iirdvayKes. The decree of which
this is a clause is proposed by Lampon himself.
62 THE COUNCIL.
finally, of proposals made by the council of the
allies \
It seems then as though the duties of the council
in preparing decrees varied greatly. As it had to
arrange the order of business in the Assembly, all
decrees had to be brought before it for preliminary
consideration ; but it does not follow that it had full
power of discussing and altering them. If, as some-
times was the case, a proposal was to be made of such
a nature that exceptional skill and judgement was
necessary in drawing up the text, the matter was
generally entrusted by the Assembly to an excep-
tional commission of one or more men. In the case
of a large number of motions which were introduced
by the enterprise of a single orator, the council
would simply adopt the words proposed by the
author of the decree, making perhaps such al-
terations as were necessary to render it formally
correct. The decrees introduced by the council on
its own initiative would in number probably far
1 C. I. A. ii. 52 = Hicks, Greek H. Ins. 84.
C. I. A. ii. 57^= ,, „ 94.
From the year 378 there were present in Athens representatives
of all the allied states. They had power to meet and discuss
matters which concerned the alliance, but the ultimate decision
was always reserved for the Athenian assembly. The council
however could ask for their opinion on any matter. In the first
of the cases quoted the council asks the allies to consider the
matter, and give their opinion to the Assembly, {roi/s avfi/xdxovs
Soy/xa i^epeyKcTv els rbv drj/j-ov, 6ti om ai/Tois ^ovXevofihois doKy apicrrov
elvai.) In the second the allies have communicated their opinion
to the council, and the council incorporates it in a TrpoPo^Xev/xa.
{iirei8r] dk ol ffifxixaxoi 86y/xa elaTjvwyKav els tt)v ^ovXtjv 5^xe(r^ai ttjv
avfilJLaxia-v...Kal i] jSouXi; irpov^offKevaev /caret ra^rci.) Cf. also p. 66.
THE COUNCIL. 63
exceed these other classes, but theh^ separate im-
portance would not be so great. The council would
be responsible for all the decrees connected with the
ordinary management of the state, constantly re-
curring votes of money, permission to repair public
buildings, grants of citizenship, votes of thanks;
matters which required a vote of the Assembly, but
which would as a rule be passed without opposition,
and often without discussion \
In these purely administrative matters the coun-
cil took the initiative, and its proposals were doubt-
less generally adopted, for it was the representative
of the permanent administrative offices. Had the
council been a strong body, one which had a spirit
and desires of its own, its Probouleutic duties would
have been a danger to the freedom of the Assembly,
for the power of initiative not only in subordinate
points of administration but in great questions of
policy might easily have been lost to the larger body.
The Assembly would have existed only to discuss, to
adopt, or reject the proposals of the council. It was
a result of the method of appointment by lot to the
council that this did not happen, and that, while it
performed the duties of preparing and arranging
business, it did not put any check on the complete
freedom of discussion in the Assembly''.
1 A great number of the decrees which we possess are of this
nature, as they record votes of thanks and honours to foreign
envoys ; they would be part of the ordinary international
courtesy, and were naturally proposed by the council on its own
authority.
2 We hear of a board called o-vXXoyeTs toO brjixov, but are not
64 THE COUNCIL.
(2) Ad- The administrative duties were so various that
vnnistra- ^^ ^.^^^ Qjjly ioke, a few typical instances of cases
duties. where we are well informed concerning them. The
extent of these duties will be more apparent when
we come to deal with the other magistrates with
whom the council was intimately connected. For
my present purpose it is sufficient to point out that
the administrative duties of the council were always
connected with matters of detail ; there is no sign
that it could form decisions of any political moment.
It could only carry out the policy of the Assembly.
This is very clearly shewn by a decree which is
preserved to us of the latter part of the 4th century,
and is worth quoting.
In 325 B.C. an expedition was to be sent out to
carry into execution a plan for settling colonies in the
Adriatic. A decree was brought before the people
to give the orders necessary to the proper fitting out
of the expedition \ After various orders to the in-
spectors of the dockyards, and other officials specially
concerned, come the following clauses : — " And the
Council of 500 shall superintend the fitting out of
the expedition, and punish according to the laws any
of the trierarchs who are unruly. And the Prytanies
shall provide that the council be in constant session
on the quay till the Expedition has sailed. And the
told what they had to do. Cf. Boeckh, vol. ii. p. 115 (3rd Ed.) ;
C. I. A. ii. 607, 741, 1174. It is difficult to see what scope there
was for the activity of a special board in summoning the Assembly.
They are apparently different from an elected officer of the same
name mentioned by Harpocration.
1 C. I. A. ii. 809 b.
THE COUNCIL. 65
Athenian people shall choose* ten men from all the
Athenians, and they shall superintend the fitting out
of the expedition in the same way as the council
is ordered to do. And the council and the Prytanies
after superintending the outfit shall be crowned by
the people v/ith a golden crown to the value of 1000
drachmas. And if anything is necessary to supple-
ment this decree, the council shall have power to
pass a decree, so long as it does not invalidate
anything which has been decreed by the people."
This we may consider as the regular form of
procedure ; it is an excellent illustration of the posi-
tion which the council held. The Assembly declares
for a policy, arranges the general principles on which
it shall be carried out, and then leaves the manage-
ment of all details, within certain limits, to the
council. When we are told that the council was
responsible for keeping up the number of the tri-
remes, the case is precisely similar ; the Assembly
made the decree or law which determined the size of
the fleet ; the council was responsible for its execu-
tion.
It was moreover especially the duty of the council Financial
to watch over the public finances. Of this I shall ^^*^^*
have more to say later, for, as I shall point out, the
management of the finances is more difficult to under-
stand than any other part of the system. It will
be sufficient here to recall the fact that the council
had no power alone to levy any tax, or spend any
1 That these dTroo-ToXets, being exceptional officials, should be
chosen by popular election is, as I shall afterwards show, in ac-
cordance with the invariable custom.
H. 5
66 THE COUNCIL.
money without authority. What it had to do was to
see that the regular taxes were properly collected or
sold, and that the money was paid in by the separate
officials ; to decide questions in disputed cases about
the assessment of the tax ; and to pay money as
required to the various officials.
The council was in financial matters of special im-
portance, and for the following reason. All the money
of the state passed through its hands, and it was in
constant communication with all the other officials ;
the control of the finances therefore depended on
the information which was to be found either in the
council chamber itself, or in the offices of the various
boards which were grouped round it. And more-
over the council had the duty of calling the attention
of the Assembly to any deficit. For as it was re-
sponsible for the management of all the various
public services, and as these could not be maintained
without supplies, if when the officials applied to
the council there was no money to give them, the
council would have to ask the Assembly for more
money; it would have to state what the deficiency
was, and would perhaps accompany the statement
by a recommendation of some way of raising the
sum. There was however no constitutional custom
which compelled the Assembly to accept the sug-
gestion made by the council.
Foreign It might be thought that there was one duty of
relations, ^j^^ council which formed an obvious exception to
the principle I have laid down. It had to receive
foreign envoys, and consider the terms of any treaty
or agreement which was to be proposed. This was
THE COUNCIL. 67
not however different from other occasions on which
it prepared business for the Assembly. The council
could not in any way influence the decision of the
Assembly; all that it had to do was to learn from the
strangers the business on which they had come, the
powers which they had, and the terms which they
were ready to propose. In accordance with this
information a Probouleuma would then be draw^n
up introducing the subject to the Assembly. In
this as in other cases the object of the Probouleuma
was not in any way to influence the decision on the
question to be debated, but to make clear what that
question was. This is abundantly evident from the
inscriptions, and in those cases where our other
authorities give an account of the reception of
ambassadors there is nothing inconsistent with it.
For instance, Thucydides in the 5th book^ gives
an account of the reception of a Spartan embassy
at Athens in connection with the diplomatic com-
plication which resulted on the peace of Nicias.
We find that it was first, as was of course necessary,
brought before the council, and the next day it was
introduced by the Prytanies to the Assembly. In
the preliminary hearing before the council there
}v.
2 Antiphon, de morte Herodis, 69, tells a story of how one year
all the Hellenotamiai but one were put to death on a charge of
peculation ; and how afterwards it was discovered that they were
innocent.
96 THE OFFICIALS.
Athenian system, to get rid entirely of the natural
prejudice we feel against the lot. This prejudice is
so strong that we are always inclined to think the
Athenians must have shared our distrust of it ; and
attempts have often been made to show that this
was the case. Historians have appealed to two facts
to prove this: — to the institution of the SoKL/mao-ia,
and to the fact that a large number of officials were
appointed by popular election, and not by the lot.
I think, however, that a short examination of these
two points will help to prove my position, (1) that the
Athenians felt no distrust of the lot, but regarded
it as the most natural and the simplest way of
appointment ; (2) that, in consequence, the general
rule was that all magistrates were appointed by the
lot: the only exceptions (in the first period of the
democracy) being those who had military or semi-
military duties, and those who held exceptional ap-
pointments which were outside the ordinary routine
administration of the state.
The Doki- The popular account of the SoKi/juaala is that it
was an institution invented to check the worst
results of the lot^ : men, we are told, felt so much
distrust of its working that they prepared a means
of interfering with its action. It was an opportunity
given to the people to prevent someone, who had been
legally appointed, from holding office, on no other
grounds than that they held him unfit to do so. This
- Busolt, Gr. Gesch. vol. ii. p. 469. Gegen die schlimmsten
Zufalligkeiten des Looses schiitzte man sich durch die Priifung
Oder Dokimasie. Gilbert, St. i. 208 — 10, takes the same view
though less decidedly.
masia.
THE OFFICIALS. 97
view is founded on the statements of the orators :
and there is no doubt that, in the 4th century, the
hoKL^iaala was used as a means of preventing men
who were suspected of oligarchic sentiments from
holding an office which they had won by the lot or
otherwise*. It is, as I have elsewhere pointed out,
from the observation of this fact that a great deal of
the difficulty about the lot has arisen. If however
my view of the lot is correct, it will be necessary
to some extent to restate our account of this pheno-
menon. It was, I believe, an abuse which had
grown up at the end of the Peloponnesian war, and
was a direct result of the shock given to the whole
state by the two oligarchic revolutions. If we
look below the speeches of the orators to the
constitution of the court, it is obvious that the
BoKtfiaala was not introduced simply to rectify the
verdict of the lot : men chosen by popular elections
were just as much subject to it. It was not the
intention to allow the popular voice a veto on any
appointment by means of an accusation of "incivism."
The object of the Bofci/juacrLa was simply to keep out
of office men who were legally incapacitated. Men
who were not complete citizens by birth, who were
not of a certain age, who were in debt to the state
or who had incurred drcfiia by committing certain
offences, were by the laws excluded from office;
1 Cf. Lysias, Or. 26. 16 passim ; esp. 26, § 9, 6 ^ets rbv -rrepl
tQv boKLfxacn.Q3v vbfiov oiix rJKicTTa irepl rQ>v kv dXiyapxiq. dp^dvrup 'iveKO.
edrjKep. This cannot be true unless the boKLfxaala was a quite new
institution : but if it was we should expect some more special
reference to its introduction.
98 THE OFFICIALS.
and some offices could only be held by men pos-
sessed of a certain property. Now it was one of the
characteristics of the Athenian constitution that it
provided a definite regular way of doing everything
however unimportant: nothing was left uncertain.
Supposing anyone were chosen by lot or by popular
election whose qualification was doubtful, consider-
able inconvenience might arise if there were no
regular procedure for dealing with the matter. To
guard against this, the hoicL^aa-ia was introduced.
The proceedings were as a rule almost formal : they
consisted in putting to the newly elected magistrate
certain questions ; if they were satisfactorily answered
the matter was at an end: if it appeared that the
man did not possess some of the qualifications he
was excluded. The BoKc/jLao-la answered the same
sort of purpose as when a candidate for a scholarship
at a school or university is required to produce a
certificate of birth. It was the opportunity which
the official had of proving his legal qualifications :
an opportunity which there must be somehow in
every state ; and it is chiefly interesting as showing
the great care taken by the builders of the consti-
tution to procure efficiency by providing beforehand
a means of settling all points \'
1 The best account of the matter is given by Hermann,
Staatsalterthiimer, 149. Schoroann's account is also good: he
says, " the doKifiaaia had nothing to do with the knowledge and
abiHty requisite for the administration of the office, but only
with the question whether the birth of the man fulfilled the
conditions required, and whether his Ufe had been free from
crime. Those offices for which a special capacity was necessary
which could not be expected of every citizen were filled by popular
THE OFFICIALS. 99
It was however possible that the candidate was
not satisfied with the justice or validity of the verdict
of the revising court ; this would especially be the
case when, as often happened, private or political
enemies had by their evidence procured his rejection.
In a case of this kind there would be a dispute either
of fact or law to be decided^: a dispute which might
turn on the status of the mother of the candidate,
or on the interpretation of some law disqualifying a
particular class of persons. This dispute would
have to be decided before a law-court, but the
question would still be not, "Is it wise to let this
man be elected ? " but, " Is this man legally dis-
qualified?"
The orators of course in these as in all other
cases tried to bias the minds of the jury, and where
it was convenient to do so did not shrink from boldly
stating that the hoKi^aarla ought to take the form
of an enquiry into the whole career of a citizen to
election, and it was assumed that the people would not choose
anyone of whose capacity it was not sufficiently convinced. On
the other hand the people willingly had confidence that everyone
who decided to become a candidate for any of the other offices
which were filled by lot, would have the requisite capacity, and
in fact was not so far wrong in this as may appear at first sight."
This is one of the cases where it seems to me that the new school
of historians have not improved on their predecessors.
1 So in Lysias, Or. 26, de Evandro. The real case is that
Evajider has committed certain acts which disqualify for office :
the defence is that he is defended by the amnesty (§ 16) : the
speaker tries to create a prejudice against Evander and to
make the case turn on what is best for the city ; and so far as
he can makes it seem a question of the personal character of
himself and his opponents.
7—2
100 THE OFFICIALS.
see if he were fit to bear office*; but this was just as
much an abuse as when in any ordinary civil suit
they introduced extraneous matter in order to in-
fluence the minds of the jury. No doubt they often
succeeded. Many men, probably, were excluded from
office on account of their oligarchic opinions, but this
was a development caused by peculiar circumstances.
Owing to the political struggles of the time a con-
siderable number of men had become anfioL and
disqualified for office : so far as the BoKifiaala
excluded them it was not (except in cases where it
was abused) an original expression of popular feeling,
it was only the method of putting into execution a
principle already established ^ We might find the
nearest English parallel to it in the laws respecting
the Roman Catholics. When they were disqualified
by their religion from being elected or appointed to
any post, the law was enforced by requiring every
person who was elected or appointed to take the
Sacrament. This was the hoKLfjuaala. By taking
the Sacrament a man declared that he was not a
Roman Catholic. At the same time it was open
to anyone to give information that the man was
really a secret Romanist, and thereby still get him
excluded. Now no one would say that the ex-
^ e. g. Lysias, pro Mantitheo, 9, SoKd 54 ixol iv rats doKifiaa-iais
diKacov elvuL iravrbs tov ^iov \6yov diddvaL.
2 So in Lysias, Or. 26, § 10, the argument seems to be : — a man
who served as knight under the Thirty may not be a /SouXeur-^s,
much more must a man who has done what this man has done
be ineligible for the archonship: the speaker appeals to the law
and says any reasonable interpretation of it will exclude him.
THE OFFiciAik f : ; > '' ' '. ■ '.} : \WV
istence of this and similar laws implied distrust of
popular elections, or of appointment by govern-
ment. But it is just what happened at Athens :
only at Athens no one was excluded because of
his opinions, only because he had committed certain
actions.
The inconveniences which may result from any
uncertainty as to the legal qualifications of a man
who has been appointed to a public office are so
great that no further explanation is required why
the Athenians should have taken care that the
validity of the appointment should be thoroughly
tested before the new officer entered upon his
duties. Such a test there must always be. The
only peculiarity of the Athenian system was that
the name of the procedure, and (to a great extent)
the procedure itself, was identical for all offices and
all appointments. We disguise the similarity under
difference of name ; we talk of the registration of
voters, the .confirmation of bishops, election petitions ;
but these are all only more cumbrous methods of
doing what the Athenians did simply and in the
same way for all offices by the SoKLfxaala.
The fact that the Athenian courts did not
always give an impartial verdict, and in fact did
not even profess to do so, was a result of the
whole constitution of the judicial system ; but
it need not affect our judgment of the initial
advantages of having some such procedure. At
any rate the Athenian dicasteria were not more
open in their disregard of the legal aspect of
a case than was the House of Commons in
W9.
7IJE OFFICIALS.
Elected
Officials.
Military
posts.
the days when it used to hear election peti-
tions\
If we turn now to the second point, the considera-
tion of those offices which were not filled by lot, we
shall not I think find any reason to suppose that the
Athenians looked on the lot with distrust, or re-
garded it as anything exceptional.
There are always certain things which can only
be done by men of special ability ; there must be
cases in which the dangers which arise from possible
incompetence are greater than any which come from
the possibility that the magistrate will gain undue
influence or misuse his power. This even the
Athenians recognised ; election by lot was with
them the rule, but they never attempted to make
it a rule without an exception. The exceptions
were however as few as possible. Of the regular
magistrates only those were elected who were
occupied with the actual command of men in war,
or in the half-military establishments connected
with the public education of the citizens. Much
has been said about the aTparijyol: it has been truly
1 A curious contrast to the simplicity of the Athenian constitu-
tion might be found in the difiiculty experienced in England of
getting an authoritative decision on the qualifications for voting
in any representative body. The uncertainty about the right of
women to sit in a county council could not have occurred there,
because the matter would at once have been brought before a
special court which had to decide all such cases: and it would
have been impossible that such a state of things should result
as has been seen in England, when someone continues to exercise
an oJBfice to which he has no claim because it is no one's duty
to take steps in order to deprive him of it.
THE OFFICIALS. 103
pointed out that at one period their power was very
great, and the office to some extent an object of
ambition for those who wished to direct the politics
of the city; but the board of the arparTjyol were
never other than generals \ Their duties were
always, primarily, the management of naval and
military matters ; secondarily, they at times repre-
sented the state in its intercourse with other states
and had jurisdiction over foreigners residing in the
city. Political power they sometimes had: but it
was chiefly because they were men who had influence
as speakers and statesmen in the assembly. They
were men of ability, and their experience was
valuable : hence they were consulted by the govern-
ing assemblies. They were, as generals, responsible
for the safety of the state : hence any request which
came from them, or any warning which they might
give, was attended to at once. If they represented to
the TTpvTaveL'i that there was business of urgent
importance to be discussed, it was matter of tra-
dition if not of law that the assembly should be
summoned I They had the right of bringing all
matters before the council, and with the council
they were often chosen to represent the people in
its intercourse with foreign powers; like all Athe-
nian magistrates, even the lowest, they had extensive
judicial duties, and they had as a necessary result of
^ This is shown clearly by the references to them in the
Memorabilia of Xenophon. Socrates always speaks of the power
of commanding an army as the first requisite of a general. Cf.
iii. 1, 6 ; iii. 4.
2 C. I. A. i. 40, ad finem.
10^: ; ; •/ : , ' •/ ; ; ; •tbe piIjficials.
their military power a large authority in financial
matters. But it was their military duties which
were the foundation of their power; and it was
because of them that their appointment was never
made by the lot. I do not know anything so
remarkable as the fact that, notwithstanding the
exceptional position which they occupied, these
generals never did win a position independent of
the assembly. It is not the extent but the limit of
their authority which astonishes us.
If we add to the generals the subordinate military
officials, the tTTTra/o^o? and v\ap'y^o<^ and ra^iap'^o^,
and certain other men who, like the (7a)(f>povLa-Tai or
iTri/xeXrjTal rdciv i7]fi(ov, superintended the education
of the young men, we shall, with the doubtful ex-
ception of a few unimportant religious officials, find
no regular officials who were not appointed by lot\
In all other cases where we are told that a man
Excep- was elected to an official position we find that the
OMces. office itself was an exceptional institution. I have
already to some extent explained the importance of
these offices, and shown how useful they were in
supplementing the more established procedure. The
1 There are many offices concerning which our information is
defective, e.g. the Tpi-qpoiroLoL and the eWrjvoTafdai. The eKXoyeis
mentioned in C. I. A. i. 38 (of. Harpocr. sub voc. -Qp^drjaav yb.p
iKXoyeis Trap' i^fup oh TrXeiara iddKci, xpT^/iara etvai) were men chosen
to collect arrears of tribute from the allies. They were exceptional
officers and their duties were partly military, as they had command
over one or more triremes. Cf. Boeckh, Staats. d. A. p. 190.
The same is true of the ra/crat, who were probably identical with
ol iirl TOLS iroXeis whose election (xeLporovla) is mentioned C. I. A.
i. 37.
^ THE OFFICIALS. 105
most important of them are the numerous appoint-
ments for exceptional service as legate to a foreign
power, or as representative of the state at some re-
ligious festival. If an embassy had to be sent to treat
with a foreign king, if the help of Dionysius was
sought against Thebes or the help of Thebes against
Philip, or if it was desired to break up an alliance be-
tween Sparta and Persia, or to send a representative
to the Amphiktyonic council, for this purpose men
of ability and knowledge, leaders in the political
world, must be chosen; and so the lot could not
be used. Also those who were elected to these
offices were temporarily surrounded with a pomp
and importance which marked them out from their
fellow citizens. These appointments had a dignity
of their own, they were highly paid, they gave
opportunities for gaining exceptional experience
and knowledge, they gave to those who held them
peculiar advantages of a kind which democracy
sought to make common to all citizens. Hence
we find that such offices were looked on with
suspicion, and that their holders were the object of
envy. They were oligarchical in their nature ; not
because they were filled with oligarchs, but because
a state where such offices abounded would be oli-
garchic \ But oligarchic as they were, they were
not in the least party posts. Election to them was
not conducted on party lines. There were private
societies which would support those of their members
who were candidates ; but there was no organisation
to support candidates of particular opinions. If
^ Cf. the first scene in the Acharnians, also ih. vv. 595 etc.
106 THE OFFICIALS.
an embassy was to be chosen, the people did not
take trouble to choose ambassadors committed to
one line of policy. They did not attempt to bind
themselves to a particular line by electing men
pledged to support it. They elected men who took
interest in, or had knowledge of the question;
but they elected men of the most opposite opinions \
We see how in the case of offices to which elec-
tion was by vote the influence of the lot ex-
tended; the same strictness of account, the same
complete obedience to the Assembly, the same colle-
giateness, the same absence of party organisation is
found in the one as in the other: but it was only
because elected officials were the exception that elec-
tions were so quiet, so business-like, and elected
officials so obedient.
Commis- Another class of men who were certainly in most
public cases appointed by the people were the "Commis-
works. sioners of Public Works" (iTrco-Tarat twu Brjfioamv
epycov) including the special boards appointed to
superintend the building of fortifications and triremes ^
These, however, do not really form an exception to
^ E.g. Xen. Hell. vi. Ill in the embassy to Sparta we find men
of different parties, including those of the anti-Laconian party.
So too in the famous embassy to Philip the leaders of the opposing
parties both took part.
2 Aesch. in Ctesiphontem, 9. 31. Demosthenes was appointed
T€ixoTroi6s by his own tribe Pandion. There is a distinction
between KkqpwToL dpx*^ and eirtffTaTai tcSv dTjfioa-icov ipyiov : and
though Aeschines contends that these latter are apxa-i; he certainly
implies that they were never KXi^porraL (13 — 14, 28 — 30). C. I. A.
ii. 830 TeixoTTotol aipeOhre^. Cf. Wachsmuth, Die Stadt Athen,
vol. ii. p. 13, n. 1 ; ih. p. iv — v.
THE OFFICIALS. 107
the rule, because, certainly in the greater number of
cases of which we have record, these Commissioners
are not members of a permanent bureau. The office
is created for a special and exceptional purpose, and
expires when the building or repairs with which it
is concerned is completed. There is one commission
for the building of the Propylsea*; one for the building
of the Erechtheum^; another for the restoration of a
temple which had been destroyed by fire'\ A board
of TetxoTrocol is appointed to superintend the re-
building of the walls in 395*; another, of which
Demosthenes is a member, in 338 ^ These appoint-
ments no more belong to the ordinary constant
system of the administration than do the posts of
ambassador; or the special commissions of enquiry
appointed at times of panic; or the crvvTjyopeh
appointed to represent the state in public prosecu-
tions. This is shown by other signs. The regular
Athenian boards have almost invariably 10 members;
the numbers of these commissions vary, we find
sometimes two^ sometimes three ^, at times five^, or
1 C. I. A. i. 314. 2 c. I. A. i. 322.
3 C. I, A. ii. 829.
* C. I. A. ii. 830—32. Cf. Wachsmuth, Die Stadt Athen, ii.
p. 5, and p. 13, n. 1.
^ Aeschines, 1. c. We also find a commission of ten men to
investigate the gifts given to the temple of Aesculapius (C. I. A. ii.
836), one for the restoration of the temple of Zeus Soter (C. I. A.
ii. 834) and for the building of the Skeuotheke (C. I. A. ii. 1054),
and one to superintend the making of two statues eTnardrai racv
NUaiv (C. I. A. iv. 331« and C. I. A. i. 318.)
8 C. I. A. ii. 187. 7 c. I. A. i. 318, 322.
8 C. I. A. ii. 834 : C. I. A. iv. 331«.
108 THE OFFICIALS.
ten\ The regular appointments are, nearly invari-
ably, for a year ; in some cases at least, these commis-
sioners hold office for longer^; and it is probable that
the appointment was generally made to continue till
the work entrusted to them was finished ^
It is certain therefore that many of these com-
missions must be classed among the exceptional
offices, and in consequence it is probable that their
members were allowed more power and fi:"eedom than
could have belonged to men appointed by lot, and
that the direct responsibility for the plan and
method of building rested with them ; also, that the
people entrusted to them the right of controlling the
architect. Thus they would not only propose in
the assembly the general plan of the building, but
would be empowered to use their own discretion in
the arrangement of details.
The actual charge of the work of course be-
longed to a professional architect ; who was ap-
pointed sometimes, if not always, by the people*.
The chief duties of the commissioners were to
examine the plan prepared by him, to see that it
would answer the purpose of the building required,
to draw up a formal document and sign it. They
also had to watch over the progress of the work,
and, especially, all payments were made by them
to the contractors and workmen. The sale of the
1 Aesch. 1. c. In C. I. A. ii. 1054 one only is mentioned as
signing the contract, but he possibly acts on behalf of his colleagues.
2 C. I. A. i. 301 (p. 160), 318.
3 This was not however always the case. C. I. A. i. 303 — 309.
4 C. I. A. ii. 187, V. 6.
THE OFFICIALS. 109
contract seems to have belonged not to them but to
the Poletai.
The question, however, suggests itself whether,
besides these exceptional commissions appointed to
conduct large and important building operations,
there were not other and more permanent officials
entrusted with the care and preservation of the
fabric of the buildings and fortifications already made.
I am not aware of any record of such officials, and
it is more probable that, so far as this duty did not
belong to the province of the priests, treasurers and
generals, it was included in the general supervision
over all public matters which belonged to the council.
This seems to be borne out by the fragment of a
decree \ either of the council or assembly, which pro-
vides for building some additional wall on the Acro-
polis. In the portions preserved we find mention of
the Poletai, and of a man who is apparently the archi-
tect, but none of any commissioners; and the probable
explanation is that where only some small piece of
work was to be done the matter was left to the
discretion of the architect, and it was not held to be
necessary to have a special committee appointed to
control him. The payments could of course always
be made by one of the regular boards of officials, and
the contract as usual would be made by the Poletai.
The iiria-TaTaL were only appointed when a special
work of some magnitude was to be taken in hand^
1 Bulletin de Corr. Hell. 1890, p. 177. It seems to belong to
the middle of the fifth century.
In another we find that the control over the architect is given
to the iepoTToiol. C. I. A. iv. 37*', 1. 10. ^ j-geg Appendix.]
110 THE OFFICIALS.
With these the exceptions end. There were no
other duties which it did not seem to the Athenian
statesman that any of his fellow citizens could
perfectly well fulfil. For the two great depart-
ments of finance and justice, there were in the great
days of the Athenian Democracy no elected ofiicers.
What taxes were to be raised ; what money was to
be spent; that the demos in its sovereign power
decided. How much money was necessary for one
department; how much could be afforded for another;
that the council reported. But to raise money, and
spend it ; to collect taxes, and proceed against
defaulters; to sell confiscated property, and let public
land ; to pay the bills, and audit the accounts ; — for
all this there were none but KXijpcoTal dp'x^aL
Therefore we shall be justified in saying that
neither the institution of the hoKUfiacrla nor the ex-
istence of these exceptional offices shows any distrust
of the lot. This was the ordinary system of appoint-
ment, and was deliberately maintained as the wisest
means of preserving the democratic constitution. But
if we are prepared to recognise that election by lot
was the rule and not the exception, we have still
to enquire how it was that the state could exist
and prosper with it, and what the results of the
system were. I propose therefore to explain, so
far as is possible, the manner in which the system
worked, so that we may see what the effects of this
peculiar arrangement were. I shall begin by dis-
cussing the financial administration.
CHAPTEE IV.
Finance.
§ 1. General Direction.
In a modern state the most important political
event of the year is the budget. The chief duty of
the Government is to estimate the expenses of the
coming year, and to propose some method of raising
sufficient money to meet the expenses. The question
has often been asked how it happened that in anti-
quity, and especially in Athens, matters of finance
had not the same importance \
The difference is however more in appearance
than in fact. It arises to a great extent from the
character of the records. Historians occupy them-
selves much more with the moral than the economic
side of history. Writing with a view to artistic effect,
they pass over matters of finance which are supposed
to be dull. But the speeches of the orators, and the
great mass of inscriptions which have been dis-
covered, show conclusively — what we might have
guessed — that, even in the fifth century, finance was
almost as important a part of public business as it
1 Boeckh, Staatshaushaltung, Bk. ii. § 1.
112 FINANCE.
is now. Athens had no exemption in this matter.
She was subject to the ordinary laws which govern
the life of states. Then, as now, it was supply which
occupied the minds of leaders of the state ; for money
meant food for the citizens, good pay for the fleet,
new triremes, new fortifications. It meant comfort
at home, and supremacy abroad. Then, as now, no
leader of the state could keep his position without
meeting the financial problem ; and the administra-
tion of Pericles, of Cleon, of Aristophon, and of
Eubulus was then, as it would be now, chiefly judged
by their financial policy \
There is, however, a point in the constitution of
Athens, resulting from the peculiar character of
the relations between the officials and the assembly,
which tends to obscure this fact.
Absence of The first question we naturally ask is: — "Who
financT^^ was the responsible financial adviser ; whose duty was
official. it to frame plans for providing money ? " It is of the
very elements of business that there should be some
one whose special duty it is to survey the whole
income and expenditure. Without this what would
all the care and prudence in details avail ?
But at Athens there is great difficulty in dis-
covering with whom this responsibility lay. We
can trace the course of a sum of money from one
department to another. We can find out how pay-
ments were made, where money was kept, who paid
it, and who spent it ; but where was the central
control ? All taxes were indeed imposed by the
^ Cf. Lysias, Karbi '^irLKpdrovs xxvii. 3, oirdrav iv XP'^P^'^"' V
Koi audrjvai tt}v irbXiv koX fi-fj.
FINANCE. 113
assembly, and all expenses sanctioned by them. But
who advised the assembly, and how did it learn
exactly what money was wanted ? There must surely
have been someone who had a special knowledge of
the matter, who could put forward an authoritative
statement, and with whom the responsibility of mis-
management would rest.
In the latter half of the 4th century there was ra/A/as ttjs
such an official : the Ta^la<; Trj<; Koivrj<; irpoaoSov, or ^po^f^^Qy,
6 eirl TTj ScoLKTjaec. And it has been maintained
that this office was in existence at least from the
times of the Persian wars. Boeckh and others
have supposed that it was held by Aristeides and
Pericles and Cleon; and that by holding it they
gained their official position, and their right to
speak with authority and advise the people. There
seems however to be no good authority for the
existence of this office before the middle of the
4th century, and it was probably introduced by
Eubulus about 35 2 \
It appears indeed, strange as it may seem, that
during the 5th century there was no finance minister.
There was no one who was officially responsible for
1 Plutarch, it is true, speaks of Aristeides as iinfieXTjTT]^ tQp
KOLvQv Trpoo-68(au, and there are expressions in the Knights of
Aristophanes (v. 948) which have been supposed to imply that
Cleon was officially "ra^t'as" of the city. Against this is to be
put the complete absence of any reference at all to such an office in
inscriptions, and any certain reference in contemporary literature.
Cf. infra, p. 117, n. 1, the passages quoted from the Memorabilia.
Even in the Knights, the prize for which Cleon and the sausage-
seller contend is represented as the ascendency in the assembly
{ttjs TlvKi/os rhi 7)vlas, v. 1109), not election to any office.
H. 8
114 FINANCE.
these matters. There were numerous subordinate
officials ; but they were all appointed by lot, and had
thereby neither claim nor power to direct the policy
of the city. There was the council, which with its
important duties was the centre and pivot of the
whole system ; but it was after all a body of 500
men taken by lot ; it could scarcely be that the
Athenians would look to it for wisdom and ad-
vice.
Financial The constitutional advisers of the assembly were
the^^^ ^^^ ^^® officials, nor the council, nor even necessarily
orators. the generals. They were the orators \ It was on their
energy and ambition that the direction of the finances
depended, as did the supreme control of all depart-
ments. And the Athenians could affi)rd to trust to
them for advice, for, so long as political ambition
was keen, and success in public life the great desire
of every able man, the people knew that these
matters would not be neglected. The competition
was too vigorous. If a young man wished to dis-
tinguish himself, he must do so by winning the ear
of the assembly. To do this, he must be able to
criticise the plans of others, or formulate plans of
his own ; to show how money could be saved, or how
it could be better spent. Whether he dealt with
naval matters, the relations to the allies, the adorn-
ment of the city, or the celebration of public festi-
vals ; if he wished to make an effect, and win repu-
tation, he must have command of the question of
supply. No one could hope to win a permanent
1 Dem. xiv. (Trept avfi/Mpiwv) 2.
FINANCE. 115
place who did not show a thorough acquaintance
with the finance of the city\
There is an admirable illustration of this in
the Memorabilia of Xenophon^ Socrates is repre-
sented as conversing with Glaucon, a young man
who without adequate knowledge and experience is
trying to push himself forward. He wishes irpoara-
T€V€LV T179 TToXeo)?, and Socrates shows him how
many things he must know if he wishes to do this ;
he must understand all about the income of the
state and the expenditure ; he must know the rela-
tive strength of Athens and other states; he must
know whence the food supply of the city comes.
Now Glaucon is not coming forward to stand
for any office; he does not aim at being "public
treasurer," or " general ;" he is much too young to be
eligible : but he wishes to become popular with the
assembly, and to do what he likes in the city. He,
if he becomes irpoardTT^f; rov hrjfiov, will also " ad-
minister the afifairs of the city." Now what this and
other conversations show is that numbers of young
1 We are told of almost every well-known man, that he
occupied himself with finance. I have collected a few in-
stances for which I am chiefly indebted to Beloch (Att. Politik).
Cleophon, Lysias xix. 48. Aesch. ii. 76.
Agyrrhios, Ar. Ranaa, 367, Schol. ad Arist. Eccl. 102. rbv
fxiffdov 5e tQv ttoitjtQv (TvviTejxe koL irpOros eKKXrjataaTiKbv 5^du}K€v.
Archedemos, Xen. Hell. 1. vii. 2. 'Apx^^Vf^os 6 too drj/xov t6t€
vpo€i(raiuLhov tov d-Zifiov. In 1. c. 183—4
we find the formula \J/'r}ij^.
A difficulty which at Rome would have been settled
by the Praetor could at Athens not be solved without
an appeal to the Assembly. We see at once how the
power of the BrjfjLOf; was a direct result of the absence
of ability and influence among the magistrates; in
other words, how election by lot was necessary to the
perfection of the democracy.
Charac- We can now see to what was due the chief
'J^***?* °-^ characteristic of the Athenian law, its great sim-
Law.
1 Cf. Schomann p. 850, n. 234.
JUDICIAL MAGISTRATES. 151
plicity. This did not come from any peculiarities
of the Greek mind. The Athenians were not inferior
to the Romans in their power of framing a system,
nor were they wanting in ability to analyse the basis
of law; yet the Athenian law never got beyond
the rudimentary state : it remained merely a list of
rules or precepts for conduct, with apparently little
attempt at scientific arrangement. The Athenian
courts were active, the number of cases tried was
immense, and the complexity of the issues often
considerable, and yet there was no authoritative
interpretation of the law ; no glosses were collected
round the rules; the laws remained short simple
and straightforward. This is of course due partly
to the peculiar constitution of the law-courts; but
it is still more due to the absence of authority of the
magistrates. Owing to this, there was no attempt
made to distinguish between questions of law and
questions of fact. The same men decided both to-
gether. Each case came before the court in its
entirety, and when the verdict was given no one
could tell on what grounds it had been given. Hence
there could be no precedent. A precedent is only
possible when an authoritative exposition can be
given of the law, in such a way that it is applic-
able to other cases, apart from the particular circum-
stances which were the occasion of it. This could not
be done at Athens; for there was no authoritative
ruling of the Judge, or formula of the Praetor, and the
very nature of the courts prevented their decision
becoming a precedent. Again, there was no custom-
ary law: there was nothing to which an advocate could
152 JUDICIAL MAGISTRATES.
appeal but the written laws, "the laws of Solon."^
The speechmakers were the only people who were
professionally connected with the law, and advocates-
are only of use in developing a system of law when
the court before which they plead is itself composed
of professional lawyers.
One result of this again is the peculiar nature of
the Athenian laws. They are as a rule the concise
statement of some general principle. They are put in
such a form that they can be understood and applied
by a court of laymen. Elaborately drawn up law&
full of technical phraseology which aim at covering
every possible case, are really much easier to apply
than the apparently simpler rules; but they can
only be used by trained minds and memories. At
Athens no one was specially trained. It was more-
over the absence of any authoritative explanation of
the law which caused the Athenians to be so par-
ticular about their laws. Inconsistencies in the law
and obscurities of expression are not of great impor-
tance where the interpretation of the laws is the
professed occupation of a large and organised
body of able men. The law will eventually be
hidden and superseded by the interpretation, and
the goodness or badness of the law be of little
moment. At Athens, where each case had to be
decided by inexperienced people, any inconsistency
in the laws would destroy all confidence in the
justice of the courts, and so the activity which in
other countries is devoted to elaborating the law
and making it more complete, at Athens was spent
in simplifying and shortening it.
JUDICIAL MAGISTRATES. 153
This department shows, I think, more clearly Relation
than any other, how true it is that the power of the ^{^^
Assembly depended on the absence of special ability systevi
• ^i. • ^ ^ ^ oi • 1 ^ u -^ to the de-
in the magistrates and othcials ; and why it mocracy.
was that election by lot was so essential to the
democracy. A consideration of this will convince us
how far all modern states are from being what a
Greek would have called a democracy. It will be
an interesting problem in the futvire to see to what
extent consistent democrats will succeed in doing
away with what they ought to consider their most
formidable enemy — a class of trained lawyers.
CHAPTER VI.
ADMINISTRATIVE OFFICIALS.
Com- The principles which prevailed in the finance
mittees of j • • , . • ' .^ • i i • n
the As- administration were consistently carried out m ail
sembiyand other parts of the public service. The immediate
council. ^ ^
control over each department of the state and the
responsibility for the proper management of every
separate public institution was placed in the hands
of a special board of 10 men annually appointed by
lot. Each of these was constitutionally a committee
of the Assembly, or the council, and it was by means
of these committees that the larger bodies kept up
their control over the innumerable details of public
business. The actual work was done by public
slaves and by contractors ; the duties of these com-
mittees were normally to inspect and control the
work, so as to ensure that it was properly done.
It is impossible to give an account of all of these
committees. The system will be best explained by
investigating a single department which may be
taken as typical of the others.
iTTi/xeXTrrai Among them, those of whom we have most
^^^ ^ J, knowledge, are the inspectors of the dockyards.
I propose therefore to give a short account of their
ADMINISTRATIVE OFFICIALS. 155
duties. This will show better than anything else the
sort of work which these committees had to do ; for
the duties of the iirifJieXrjTal roov iiiiropicov, and even
of the cnTovXwv were doubtless
the officials who had to manage the election of many
of the officers, but of the way in which it was done
we know nothing\ A passage in Demosthenes*'*
shows us that they were responsible for bringing to
the Archons the Choregi from the tribe, but it tells
us nothing further.
These iTnfjbeXrjral were the chief officials of the
tribe; the office was annual, but we do not know
either their number or how they were elected. Their
chief duty was doubtless to act as returning officer
at the various elections; but we find from an in-
scription that they were also responsible for the
proper management of the property of the tribe;
they are here ordered to go round and make an
inspection, to see if it is cultivated according to
the inscriptions, and if the boundaries are properly
kept, and they are especially warned not to show
favour to any individual, nor to put anything before
the interest of the tribe, nor to take bribes I The
duties of presiding at meetings, keeping accounts,
inspection of property, are precisely those to which
according to all analogy we should expect to find
^ C. I. A. ii. 554.
^ Dem. in Midiam, 13.
» C. I. A. ii. 564.
170 THE ADMINISTRATION OF THE
officials appointed by lot. More than this we
cannot say.
Of ra/jLLat, who are mentioned, we know nothing \
The v\'rj had as had every other corporation its
lepeU: it is an interesting coincidence that almost
the only one mentioned appears to have been an
uncle of Demosthenes I
Private When we pass from the administrative divisions
societies. ^£ ^j^^ state to societies which have no direct con-
nection with the government, we find that the ad-
ministrative officers are (where we have information)
invariably elected, whiLe the religious, — the UpeU,
lepoTTOLoi — , are generally elected by lot ; and I am
told that the same is true of similar corporations in
other parts of Greece.
It seems then as if among them we meet with
the religious use of the lot, and it is reasonable to
suppose that where the priest was chosen by lot it was
that the god might himself select his own minister.
We notice moreover two other facts. In these so-
cieties the administrative officials were certainly not
in all cases annually elected, while the leponroLoi are
always spoken of as ol ael \a'y')(avovTe^y which,
though it does not necessarily mean annual appoint-
ment, suggests that the office was never held for
long; in some cases we find mention of annual
appointment^.
Religimts With regard to the religious officials of the
officials. Athenian state, it does not seem possible to lay
1 C. I. A. ii. 564.
2 C. I. A. ii. 554».
3 C. I. A. ii. 611, 613, 619.
DIVISIONS OF THE STATE. 171
down any certain principle. Some were hereditary
in certain families, some were elected and were
officers of much dignity but little importance, others
were chosen by lot. The reason was doubtless in
each case an historical one. I think however it is
not out of accordance with the recorded facts to say
that, with the exception of the hereditary offices, all
religious officials whose duties were continuous were
chosen by lot\ while those who were appointed only
to perform a single act on one day in the year, or
one day in four years were elected by the people.
This fact, if true, will show how much the Athenians
were in the matter guided by convenience, and how
little by religious tradition. Knowing how much the
power of the old aristocracy had depended upon
their religious privileges, we can understand that
the establishment of other functionaries, whether
chosen by lot or by election, would be important as
securing to the democracy freedom from aristocratic
influence in its public acts of worship.
I began this essay by pointing out that the Great
democracy meant the undisputed supremacy of the^^"^^^^.
Assembly in all matters. This survey of the different cemedin
offices in the state draws our attention to another tration,
and not less important aspect of it. The complete
democracy meant not only that the people assembled
together should govern the state, but that each
individual should also take his part in the work of
administration. There was to be no class from
which alone magistrates were chosen, nor were the
1 Dem. in Eubuliden, 46, the priest of Heracles is chosen by
lot from among men who are nominated by popular election.
172 THE ADMINISTRATION OF THE
officials to form a class of themselves. Democracy
meant self-government in the fullest sense of the
word: each nian had his share in the general de-
liberations, he had his turn for a seat in the council,
which was the central office of the whole, and he had
also to take his part in different offices. Besides these
city offices, each man belonged also to the smaller
corporations of the tribe, the deme and the phratria,
each of which made large demands on his time : he
had to attend meetings of the whole corporation, and
had moreover from time to time to fill one of the
numerous offices connected with it, or serve on some
committee appointed by it. It is no exaggeration to
say that most Athenians must have spent a large
part of their life in the performance of public duties ^
And if we look at the democracy from either
aspect: whether we regard the supremacy of the
Assembly, or the share which each citizen took in all
public business, we shall find that election by lot
was an important and essential part of the system.
It broke down and weakened all bodies so as to
make of every office nothing more than a committee
of the Assembly; and it also supplied a simple means
of overcoming the difficulty of appointment, so as to
ensure in a rough way that all citizens should have
a share in the work of the state.
Criticism The common criticism made on this system is
Astern. ^^^^ ^^ aimed at an equality where no equality was,
1 In order rightly to appreciate the number of men occupied in
public business we must remember that the Archons, Thesmothetai,
and many other magistrates were helped by assessors {Trdpedpoi)
who during their terms of office acted with them.
DIVISIONS OF THE STATE. 173
for it put men of character and ability on the same
level with those who had neither. Now if this is
said of the high office of governing the city, it is not
true, because there has never been a state where
power was so exclusively made the prize of ability :
ability not always of the best kind it may be.
But if free competition is the best way of finding
ability, Athens honestly tried to find it. The orators
might be wanting in many qualities, but at least
they must have had the appearance of wisdom and
character. Power belonged to that man who in
perfectly free and open competition could win and
keep for himself the most influence. The test might
not be a perfect one. I do not know that a better
has yet been devised. And though Athens may
have suffered from unscrupulous politicians and un-
wise ones, we cannot say of her that she was governed
by incompetent or insignificant men. If again it is
objected that it is abilities of a humbler kind which
were neglected, and that in the appointment of sub-
ordinate officials a difference should be made between
men ; it will be sufficient to answer that at any rate
the work at Athens was well done. So far as we can
see the administration of the state was more regular,
more honest, more successful in every way than that
of any other city in the ancient world, and (though
where the work is so different, the comparison is hardly
fair) than that of most states in modern times. The
Athenians obliged every one to take his share in the
work, they made the work of every one individually
easy, and if he did not do it they killed him. The
result was that the work was done. The most
174 THE ADMINISTRATION OF THE
potent attempts to obtain and secure able officials
do not always succeed; the Athenians were sure
that the men they appointed were not generally
below the average in ability and character, and that
they would not deteriorate in office. There are per-
haps not many states of which the same could be
said.
Injustice is often done to the Athenian consti-
tution because we try it by too high a standard.
Thucydides and Plato have left us their criticisms
on it. These criticisms are I believe completely
true: but when we recognise the truths of the
picture of the " democrat " drawn by Plato, and read
the account which he and others have given of the
gradual demoralisation of the Athenian people, we
ought to remember that everything with which
they charge Athens would mutatis mutandis apply
with equal force to any other society which has
ever existed. The gi*eatest complaint brought
against the democracy was that it was short lived.
The Greeks were apt to reckon the excellence of
institutions by their permanence : in this matter we
have had more experience than they had, and are
prepared to recognise the fact that the more efficient
a constitution is the more likely it is to generate
economic changes which will soon make it anti-
quated and useless. That the democratic consti-
tution lost its peculiar effectiveness by the middle
of the 4th century is no reason for refusing to
recognise its merit. We do not question that the
government of Elizabeth was wise and strong be-
cause the system was destroyed in the next genera-
DIVISIONS OF THE STATE. 175
tion. So long as a state has political life, every form
of government must bear in itself the seeds of its
own destruction.
And with regard to the other charges brought Prevalence
against it, all I ask is that besides comparing it at Athens
with the ideal state of Plato we should also compare '"^gf^^^ted,
it with other states which have existed in this
world. The most constant accusation brought against
the Athenians is dishonesty. We constantly hear of
fraud at Athens; it was a frequent charge in the
law-courts, and historians, led by the speeches of the
orators, have concluded that the Athenian govern-
ment was exceptionally corrupt. This corruption is
then laid to the charge of democratic government and
especially of the lot.
But it is surely dangerous to accept as literally
true the statements of the orators ; we know that in
many cases the accusations were false, and, even
apart from this, frequent trials for peculation are not
necessarily a sign of an exceptionally corrupt ad-
ministration. Where corruption is worst, it will
not be found that convictions are frequent. The
sign of organised and habitual fraud is a general
repose and outward quiet, interrupted occasionally
by some great exposure and outburst of indignation.
The constant activity and watchfulness which is
necessary to procure convictions, is in itself a suffi-
cient guarantee against peculations being the estab-
lished thing. Fraud is easy where affairs are secret,
confined to a few persons, complicated, and where each
individual is allowed much freedom of action. But at
Athens every obol which was received by any official
176 THE ADMINISTRATION OF THE
was entered, and the records made public : how he
had to use the money was clearly laid down: he had
little freedom of action, so that it was impossible to
hide the disappearance of any sum. But I imagine
the most efficient guarantee against the prevalence
of serious fraud was to be found just in the fact that
the officials were so numerous and that they were
elected by lot for a short period. Whenever a
certain class of people hold office and others are
positively excluded, it is easy for the officials to
exact overdue sums, and appropriate the surplus.
The outside public cannot defend itself: it is igno-
rant and intimidated. This was made impossible
at Athens because there were no secrets of office.
Fraud arises when any individual holds the same
office for long, or is often re-elected ; in such cases the
perquisites of office grow, and the permanent official
has a position of advantage against all unofficial
men: at Athens in the democratic state this was
not the case. Fraud is especially liable to occur
when officials are elected, because those who are
likely to gain by the fraud will use all their influence
to elect men who will give them an opportunity of
winning. This happens constantly in America and
other democratic states of modern times, and,
under slightly different forms, happened constantly
in the later Roman Republic. It was rendered
impossible by the lot ; the more so because the lot
might associate men who had no acquaintance with
one another and who could not, during the short
period they were in office, acquire the mutual self-
confidence which is necessary to community in fraud.
DIVISIONS OF THE STATE. 177
The Greeks no doubt were not an honest race,
but it was not the democracy which made the
Athenians untrustworthy. So far as we can see
the framers of the constitution had recognised the
national vice, and took every pains they could to
counteract it ; it was one of the merits of the
democratic system that it made fraud so difficult.
It was a noble attempt, and it was to a great
extent successful. There was a good deal of petty
dishonesty at Athens, many men made a little
money out of the public service. But we know of
no instance in which we can say that the public
welfare was seriously injured by extensive frauds or
official incompetence as was constantly the case in
aristocratic Rome and England. The Athenian
people perhaps wasted their money — but they did it
themselves; it was not lost and squandered by the
officers of the state \
I have tried to analyse one of the most remark- Character-
able and most characteristic features of the Athenian ^Athenian ^
constitution. If the view which I have taken be ^^^'^•
correct, election by lot Avas of the very essence of the
democracy. And the investigations which lead to a
recognition of this fact throw light on a peculiarity
of the democracy which distinguishes it from most
other political systems. Whether the democracy
was good or bad, is a question which has been
1 It is very doubtful whether the administration of local
matters in many English towns would stand a comparison with
that at Athens. It may I think be safely said that the gigantic
corruption which is said to prevail in Eussia, Italy and America
now, and which was common in England not so long ago, would
there have been quite impossible.
H. 12
178 THE ADMINISTRATION OF THE
sufficiently debated. It probably developed the ener-
gies and activities of the Athenians more fully than
any other system could have done : so far as it did
this we must approve of it, though for this, as for
every other system, there came a time when altered
circumstances rendered it no longer so efficient.
But what is most striking in it is the clearness of
thought with which certain principles of government
are apprehended, and the boldness of execution with
which they are put into effect. Living constitutions
are generally a compromise between various prin-
ciples. Attempts to frame a constitution in accor-
dance with some single general principle have nearly
always failed. But in describing the Athenian ad-
ministration, one often feels as though one were
describing the typical state of a political thinker. It
is difficult to conceive of a state in which political
equality could be more completely attained. And yet
notwithstanding this obedience to an idea, which we
can trace in the most important branches of the
administration, there is a prudence and sobriety
in the arrangements which is wanting in most
polities. So far as human foresight could, the
builders of the constitution had guarded against the
internal dangers which might arise. The Athenian
democracy is as a work of art unsurpassed : it has
the great characteristic of all good work, in every
detail we find laborious endeavour to express a
clear and definite idea: and the result is so simple
and so harmonious that it is only after a somewhat
minute examination that we discover the labour
expended on it. The conditions which made this
DIVISIONS OF THE STATE. 179
possible will probably never occur again; but the
scientific value of the experiment is great: it was
the first democracy: the word Democracy was in-
vented as a name for it: all other democracies in
Greece were a more or less successful imitation of it,
and if we want to know what a complete democracy
is we can do nothing better than analyse it. If we do
this we shall understand how far any modern country
is from being a true democracy, and we shall also
see how as states become more democratic they
develope the most characteristic features of Athens.
It would hardly be an exaggeration to say that a Ancient
state begins to be democratic when the objects for ^^^^lem de-
which election by lot was introduced first become a mocracies.
conscious object of desire. We see this clearly in
America. Elective assemblies are essentially un-
democratic. In America, where the feeling is more
democratic than the machinery, we are told that a
recognition of this is growing, and it is becoming
unusual to re-elect Congress men; it is only fair,
as men say, that each of the local politicians should
have a chance; it is unfair and undesirable that a
few men, because they are a little cleverer or a little
more fortunate than others, should have a monopoly
of the most valuable political instruction. The
Athenians felt this, and gave complete expression to
the feeling by allowing to every citizen in turn a seat
in the ^ovXrj. The great movement which is causing
the break-down of representative institutions in the
most democratic countries is due to the desire felt by
the mass of the people to give their verdict on each
important act, and to make of the assemblies a com-
12—2
180 THE ADMINISTRATION OF THE
mittee in which business should be arranged so as to
be brought directly before the people. The English
are in a confused way aiming at this. In the states
of North America a closer approach is made to it by
restricting very closely the powers of the state
governments. In Switzerland this is still more
openly done by the institution of the Referendum.
If we want to see the real end at which this ten-
dency is directed, we need only look to Athens.
There the desired end was attained by purposely
weakening the smaller assembly which would other-
wise have governed the state : this was done by
means of the lot ; and it is not easy to see how else
it could have been done. It is a curious confir-
mation of the reasons I have given why there was
no party government at Athens, that in Switzerland,
where direct government by the people is less re-
mote than in any other country, the Executive
Council is in no way a party body.
But if in some modern states the peoples are in
the way to win for themselves the full and direct
sovereignty, they are still far from imitating the
other characteristic of the Athenian Democracy.
There, as we have seen, not only did the people col-
lectively rule the state, but also these same men
individually had, each in his turn, a share in the
experience and responsibility of office. The central-
ised bureaucracy of the modern democratic state is
far distant from what the Greeks called democracy.
There if a man was a full citizen, he had not merely
from time to time to give a silent and irresponsible
vote in the Assembly or the law courts ; he had to
DIVISIONS OF THE STATE. 181
experience the honours and dangers of office. This
could only be because the Athenian democracy
was an aristocracy. It had all the characteristics of
an aristocracy. It made the assumption that each
citizen had the time and ability to undertake public
duties. It was there held true that no man could
be a good citizen whose life was fully occupied in
earning the bare necessities of life. The Athenians
had in fact that respect for leisure which is so
characteristic of an aristocracy. Hard work was
with them a disqualification. Men did not believe in
the dignity of labour. The existence of the demo-
cracy depended on slavery. Slavery is now impossible.
Our modern democracies are no more aristocratic.
If they ever become so, it will be when the use of
machinery is so far developed and society reorganised
in such a way that the greater part of the popu-
lation will be able, as the wealthy classes now do,
to devote a portion of their ample leisure, not only
to the discussion of political questions but also to
the management of public business.
APPENDIX.
On the UoXiTcia Twv ^Adrjvaicov.
It has generally been maintained that the lot was Early
not used at Athens before Cleisthenes (so Grote, Her- ^^f^'J^^^-^
mann, Busolt, Gilbert, Dunker, Lugebil, Miiller- p. 88 etc.
Strubing). Schomann recognised that this could not
be considered in any way certain ; and Fustel de
Coulanges, by reasoning which had never been answered,
contended that it was probably an institution of very
great antiquity. This view is supported by Aristotle.
In ch. 4 he describes a constitution attributed to Draco:
in it all officials are chosen by lot. ySovXcvctv 8c Tcrpa/co-
(TLOVs KOL eva Tovs Xa)(ovTav\<2vy and in Ar. polit. 11. 1 2 we are told that Solon
made no change in the manner of electing the magistrates.
So, whether ch. 4 be genuine or not, we have considerable
authority that the lot is older than Solon. Fustel de
184 APPENDIX.
Coulanges had argued that this must be the case, for
the lot being an institution of religious origin must be
of great antiquity. This is an interesting and valuable
confirmation of his whole method.
As to the details of the constitution before Draco,
there is of course no authentic tradition. In the times
of Solon the lot does not appear to have had much
political importance, and during the following period it
seems almost to have fallen out of use so far as the
Archonship is concerned. It appears that in the
contests for the Archonship after Solon direct election
must have been practised, and for the 26 years after the
expulsion of the Peisistratidae the lot was not used
(ch. 22). The method of statement seems, however, to
imply that during the tyranny Archons were chosen by
the lot. If this be the case Cleisthenes did away with
the lot, and it was reintroduced later. The opinion of
Grote, and others, that Herodotus was mistaken when he
says that Callimachus was chosen Polemarch by lot, is
then supported : on the other hand, it was reintroduced
before the Archonship of Themistocles and Aristeides.
The argument therefore that the lot cannot have been
introduced till later, for otherwise Themistocles would not
have been archon, must be dismissed. At this time the
lot was only used to decide which of a limited number
of men nominated by the tribes should be appointed.
Under Solon each of the 4 tribes nominated (TrpoKpLveiv)
1 ; and from these 40 the 9 Archons were chosen by
lot\ Cleisthenes altered the number of the tribes to ten,
and when the lot was reintroduced, each tribe nominated
either 50 or, more probably, 10 (ch. 22 with Mr Kenyon's
note).
^ We can now understand to what Isocrates was referring in
the passage quoted on p. 39.
APPENDIX. 185
Originally only rrevTaKoo-LOfxeSLixvoL were eligible to
the Archonship ; at some unknown period LTrireU were
admitted \ It was not till 457 that ^evy trat could hold
this office. Apparently the law which required this
qualification was never repealed, but practically it was
not put into force (ch. 7).
What is of greatest importance, however, Aristotle
never tells us: i.e. when the lot was first used for the
previous nomination by the tribes instead of popular
election. In ch. 8 he tells us that the change was made,
but gives nowhere any information as to the date.
The account of the Areopagus in ch. 23 is valuable, Areojm-
f or it shows that although the council consisted of men ^"^' ^' '
who had been Archons, and the lot was used in the
election of Archons, the Areopagus during the Persian
wars still showed more energy than the a-TparrjyoL. It
ought to be remembered however, that at this time most
of those who sat in the Areopagus must have been
Archons before the year 487. The fall of the Areo-
pagus would coincide with the time when the last of
this generation had died out.
From ch. 55 we learn that the 6 Thesmothetai with
their ypafifxarevs and the 3 other Archons were chosen as
a college of 10, one from each tribe.
The statement of chapter 18, rds 8' dpxois kiroC-qae
Kkrjpuyrds €k TrpoKptTwv, seems to apply not only to
the Archonship. The other offices which existed at that
time must also have been filled in the same way. These
were, as we learn from ch. 7, the ra/Atat, the iroiXrjTaLy the
1 This was perhaps in the time of Cleisthenes. It is possible
however that the word TrevTaKoaiuv in ch. 22 is a corruption, and
the sentence gave the property qualification. I have suggested
iK TWV irpOKpidivTUiV Vir6 TOV dtj/XQV TWV IT €VT aKOaiO fl€ 5 IfJLV bJV.
Classical Review, March, 1891.
186 APPENDIX.
IvScKtt, and the KoyXaKperaL. It was not, I believe, known
before that the first three of these offices were of such
antiquity. The early use of the lot for them is remarkable.
It appears also that the members of the povXij of 400
were selected by lot from the commencement, though
probably with the same precautions as were provided in
p. 47, 11. 1. the case of the Archons. I must therefore withdraw
the statement on the subject which I made in the text.
Fustel de Coulanges' suggestion which I have rejected
will now require careful consideration.
The main thesis contained in the text of the essay is
supported by this new work. I will only call attention
to the following points :
p. 21 etc. (1) There is nothing to support the attempt to
show that the government of Athens was in the hands of
an elected official, whether o-TpaxTyyos or ra/xias. It is
however only fair to say that in many parts the work is
extremely defective. It contains practically no account
of the constitutions between the years 457 and 412 ;
for the continuous narrative ceases with the former
year, and the constitution described at the end of the
work is the constitution of the latter half of the 4th
century, which was in many ways a very diffisrent thing.
It is very strange that no mention is made of the
rafxCas t^s KOLvrjpovpoL. For these offices the preliminary
election was always by demes. This confirms the
suggestion, which was I believe originally made by
Kirchoff, that I have adopted in the text. PP- ^4—
The establishment of this point is of some importance.
It would be much easier to maintain the principle of
rotation when the elections were managed by small
societies, where every individual was known. As the
final decision between the candidates was by lot, the
elections could not have any party importance. What
each deme had to do therefore was to nominate each year
at least twice the number of men that would eventually be
chosen from that deme. Now if the principle of rotation
were really maintained it would probably as a rule scarcely
be necessary to have recourse to the lot ; men would be
elected more or less in order of seniority ; the lot would
not be more important than it was when used at Rome
under the Empire to decide which of two men of equal
standing should have his province first. In many cases
the Demarch would probably nominate 6 or 8 or 10 of
188 APPENDIX.
the members next on the list, and there would be no
competition. This will explain how it happens that
p. 56. father and son, or two brothers serve together. Twice
as many must have been nominated as there were
members, so as to leave plenty for the iTriKaxqa-L^.
Perhaps the arrangement was that each deme nomi-
nated twice the required number : half were chosen,
and the other half were ready to serve if necessary.
Rotation, (4) In ch. 4 we have a statement of the principle
^' * of rotation clearer than anything hitherto known.
KkyjpovaOai Sc /cat ravrqv koX ras oAAas dp)(as rovs
VTrep TptotKOvra err] yeyovorais, kol Sts tov avTov jxrj apx^LV
irpo Tov 7rdvT\apovpoL TrevTyJKovra, ap^at 8* evSrjfjLOL /xev €t?
CTrraKoa-Lovs avSpa?, virepopioL 8* els lTrraKO(rCovs.
APPENDIX. 189
It is impossible at once to estimate the value of the
new account given of the different offices. 1 will only
point out :
(1) With regard to the Xoyiarai These were of
two kinds :
(a) 10 elected from members of the council, who Xoyiffral,
had to draw up the accounts of each office {KXrjpovo-L Se ^^'
Kol XoyKTTcts €^ avTwv ol /BovXevToi ScKa toi)s Xoyiovixevovs
T[aLS ap];(at9 Kara ttqv Trpvraveiav €Ka(rTr)v).
(6) There were besides 10 evOvvoi with 10 irdpeSpoL,
and 10 XoyiaraL with 10 a-uinjyopoi who were occupied
with the €v6vva of the magistrates (ch. 54).
This supports the view I have taken that the Xoytcr-
Tttt had other duties besides those immediately connected
with the evOvva. The actual arrangements are however
different from what they were in the 5th century.
(2) The plans of the temples were originally )Sou\^,
criticised by the povX-q : but, as their decision was not ^'
impartial, the matter was afterwards handed over to a
hLKa.(TTrjpLOV.
The council exercised also a general superintendence
over all public buildings (i^era^ev Se /cat to, oiKoSiy/xaTa
Tct Srjixocna Travra, ch. 46).
The architects for the ships, as for the public
buildings, were elected by the people (ch. 46), and the
TptiypoTTotot were elected by the council (ib.). p. 159.
(3) The accounts of the TrcoX^rat, aTroSeKrai, and
cvScKtt, though rather fuller than what we possessed,
agree with what was known before.
It is however definitely stated that the council had p. 139.
to decide to whom the taxes should be leased (KaraKv-
powTLV oTov kol
nporepov pXv cts ive/SaWe tqv {jnJKJiov, vvv 8* avdyK-q Trai/ras
co-Tt SLa*ij/r)ttat, though never repealed, was, we are told, not
really enforced.
ot Ttt/xtat n7s *A6r)voivXrj<;j €K TrevTaKoaioixeSLfJivtDV Kara tov ^oAwvos vofi^oVj
€Tt yap o v]o/xos xvpios eaTLv, dp^et 8* o Xa;((oi/ Kav irdvv
Trevrjs rj (ch. 47).
INDEX.
Acropolis, treasure preserved in,
133, 169
Adriatic, 64, 158
uEschines, elected irvKaydpai, 25 n.
1 ; accuses Demosthenes, 54 ;
ambassador, 73
ay opd, 139
dyopapd/jLoi, 94
Agyrrhio.s, 115 n. 1
deXod^rai, 122, 124
Alcibiades, 35, 37
Alcmceonid, 16
Allies, V. cr{>/jt.fjiaxoL
America, democracy in, 145, 179
Amnesty, 151
dpaKpiais, 147 n. 1
Andocides, quoted, 95
Androtion, 74
avTiypatpevs, 167
Antiphon, 34
dTToSe/cra^, 86, 122, 124, 129, 131
n. 1, 157, 189
diroa-ToXecs, 65 n. 1, 73, 185 n. 3
Archedemos, 115 n. 1
'ApxiTiKTcov, 108—9, 189
Archons, use of lot in election of,
IX., 7, 78 sq. ; a sacred office, 7 ;
early history of, 78 sq., 184;
judicial duties of, 146 sq.; com-
pared with the Prffitor, ib.
Areopagus, Council of, v. ^ovkq
Artsteides, archon, 78, 184; Tafiias,
113
Aristophanes, quoted, 25, 113
Aristophon, 35, 112
Aristotle, xiii., xv., 15, 31, 42, 89,
{iroXiTela tQp 'AdrjvaiQv) xv. sq.
183 sq.
daTvvofxoi, 94
ctrAeia, 167
aVi/xta, 97, 100
Ballot, to be distinguished from
the lot, 1
Beloch, XII., 22 n. 1, 23 n. 1
Boeckh, xii., 21 n. 1, 58 n. 1, 63 n.
1, 113, 155 n. 1, 162
^ov\evT7}pLOv, 122, 140
^ovKevTiq^, power of, 68, 75 sq.
PovKt) tCov 'ApeoirayiTuv, fall of,
46; in the Persian wars, 80,
185
— Tuv irevTaKoaiiav, history of,
46 ; appointment to, 49 ; member-
ship of, 51, 56; duties of, 51, 57
sq., 187; in foreign affairs, 61
sq. ; in administration, 64, 109 ;
in finance, 65, 121 sq. ; great
powers of, 75; relations to iK-
KXrjala, 64 (v. iKKXrjcia) ; orators
192
INDEX.
in the, 69; judicial duties, 71;
publicity of, 69
CallistheneSj 35
Callistratos, 115 n. 1
Xopvyoi, 169
Cleisthenes, reforms of, 46, 78, 86,
167, 184
CUon, 112, 113, 116
Cleophon, 35, 37, 115 n. 1
Committees, of the Assembly, 154,
163
Compulsory office, 94
Council, government by a, 42; in
city states, 43; at Athens, 45;
V. jSouXiJ
CtesipJwn, 37
Deinarchus, 10, 37 n. 1, 118 n. 1
Demetrius of Phaleron, 78
dijfiapxos, 166 sq., 187
Demes, used for electoral purposes,
54 — 5j 187; for financial pur-
poses, 143; officials of, 164 sq.;
property of, 165 ; meetings of, ib.
dvfJ^rai, 56, 168, 187
Democracy, what the Greeks meant
by, 17; ancient and modern
compared, 18, 26, 179 ; inverted
monarchy, 28; officials in the,
30; contrasted with oligarchy,
90 ; characteristics of, 42, 135,
137, 171; and lawyers, 145 sq.,
153 ; Isocrates on the, 39 ; in
America, 145, 179; in England,
26, 180; in Switzerland, 180
Demos, rule of the, 26; tyrant-
demos, 31 ; relation to parties,
33; V. iKKXrjaia
Demosthenes, condemned, 35; ret-
XOTToids, 73, 107; uncle of, 170;
in the Council, 54 ; quoted, 54
n. 2, 91, 168
diaypapovpol, 188
^vXal, 168 sq. ; officials of, ib. ; iiri-
ficXrjToX Tuv, 95, 169
\apxoi, 104
Plato, iTnp.eXriT'i^i, 163; quoted, 8,
88, 174—5
Comicus, 25 n. 1, 54 n. 1
Plutarch, xvii., 78, 82, 113
TToX^fiapxos, 78, 147
iruiX-nral, 109, 126, 138 sq., 185, 189
Re-election, to the Council, 50, 56,
57 n. 2 ; to other offices, 90 and
n. 1, 155
Referendum, 180
Revolutions, 91
Rhodes, 120
Rome, 46, 89, 145, 176, 187
Rotation in office, xvi., 88 sq.,
188; for the Council, 49, 187;
for the Archonship, 83
Salamis, battle of, 85
Schumann, xii., 80 n. 1, 146, 183
(Tiro^iJXaKes, 155
Slaves, 163, 181
Socrates, his opinions about the
lot, 10, 13 ; member of the Coun-
cil, 53 n. 1
Solon, 46, 83, 183
o-rdo-is, undemocratic, 38
INDEX.
195
(TTpaTTjyoi, position of, 21; com-
pared to the Ministry, 22; the
extent of their power, 28, 103;
102 sq., 122, 124; irpCravis tuv,
22 — 3; avTOKpdrupj 23
ffvyypa
f. (id.
Das Jahr 1813 (The Year 1813), by F. Kohlrausch. By
Wilhelm Wagner, Ph.D. -2^.
Der erste Kreuzzug (1095— 1099) nach Friedrich von Raumer.
The First Crusade. By W. Wagner, Ph. D. is.
Der Oberhof. A Tale of Westphalian Life, by Karl Immer-
MANN. By Wilhelm Wagner, Ph.D. 3^.
Der Staat Friedrichs des Grossen. By G. Freytag. By Wilhelm
Wagner, Ph. D. is.
Die Karavane, von Wilhelm Hauff. By A. Schlottmann, Ph.D.
3J. (id.
Goetne's Hermann and Dorothea. By W. Wagner, Ph. D. Re-
vised edition by J. W. Cartmell. gj. dd.
Goethe's Knabenjahre. (1749— 1761.) Goethe's Boyhood. By W.
Wagner, Ph.D. Revised edition by J. W. Cartmell, M.A. t.s.
Hauflf, Das Bild des Kaisers. By Karl Hermann Breul, M.A.,
Ph.D. 3^.
Hauff, Das Wirthshaus im Spessart. By A. Schlottmann, Ph.D.,
late Assistant Master at Uppingham School. 3J. 6d.
Mendelssohn's Letters. Selections from. By James Sime, M.A. 3^-.
Schiller. Wilhelm Tell. By Karl Hermann Breul, M.A., Ph.D.
IS. 6d.
(Abridged Edition.) li*. 6d.
Selected Fables. Lessing and Gellert. By Karl Hermann
Breul, M.A., Ph.D. 3^.
Uhland. Ernst, Herzog von Schwaben. By H. J. Wolsten-
HOLME, B.A. (Lond.). 3J. 6d.
Zopt una Schwert. Lustspiel in fiinf Aufziigen von Karl Gutz-
KOW. By H. J. WOLSTENHOLME, B.A. (Lond.). 3J. 6d.
V. ENGLISH.
An Apologie for Poetrie by Sir Philip Sidney. By E. S. Shuck-
burgh, M.A. The text is a revision of that of the first edition of 1595. y.
An Elementary Commercial Geography. A Sketch of the Com-
modities and Countries of the World. By H. R. Mill, Sc. D., F.R.S.E. is.
An Atlas of Commercial Geography. (Companion to the above.)
By J. G. Bartholomew, F.R.G.S. With an Introduction by Dr H. R.
Mill. 3J.
London: Cambridge Warehouse., Ave Maria Lane,
20 PUBLICATIONS OF THE UNIVERSITY PRESS.
Ancient Philosophy from Thales to Cicero, A Sketch of, by
Joseph B. Mayor, M.A. is. 6d.
Bacon's History of the Reign of King Henry VII. By the Rev.
Professor Lumby, D.D. 3^.
British India, a Short History of. By Rev. E. S. Carlos, M.A. i^.
Cowley's Essays. By Prof. Lumby, D.D. 4^.
General Aims of the Teacher, and Form Management. Two Lec-
tures by F. W. Farrar, D.D. and R. B. Poole, B.D. is. 6d.
John Amos Comenius, Bishop of the Moravians. His Life and
Educational Works, by S. S. Laurie, A.M., F.R.S.E. 3^. 6d.
Locke on Education. By the Rev, R. H. Quick, M.A. 3^. 6d.
Milton's Arcades and Comus. By A. W. Verity, M.A. 3^.
Milton's Tractate on Education. A facsimile reprint from the
Edition of 1673. Edited by O. Browning, M.A. is.
More's History of King Richard III. By J. Rawson Lumby, D.D.
3^-. 6d.
On stimulus. A Lecture deUvered for the Teachers' Training
Syndicate at Cambridge, May 1882, by A. Sidgwick, M.A. New Ed. i^.
Outhnes of the Philosophy of Aristotle. Compiled by Edwin
Wallace, M.A., LL.D. Third Edition, Enlarged. 4s. 6d.
Sir Thomas More's Utopia. By Prof. Lumby, D.D. 3^. 6^.
Theory and Practice of Teaching. By E. Thring, M.A. 4^. 6d,
The Teaching of Modern Languages in Theory and Practice.
By C. Colbeck, M.A. 2s.
The Two Noble Kinsmen. By Professor Skeat, Litt.D. 3^. 6d.
Three Lectures on the Practice of Education. I. On Marking
byH.W. Eve, M.A. II. On Stimulus, by A. Sidgwick, M.A. III. On
the Teaching of Latin Verse Composition, by E. A. Abbott, D.D. 2s.
VI. MATHEMATICS.
Euclid's Elements of Geometry, Books I. and II. By H. M.
Taylor, M.A. i^. 6d. Books III. and IV. By the same Editor, is. 6d.
Books L— IV. in one volume. :^s.
Elementary Algebra (with Answers to the Examples). By W. W.
Rouse Ball, M.A. 4J". 6d.
Elements of Statics and Dynamics. By S. L. Loney, M.A. Part I.
Elements of Statics. 4^-. 6d. Part II. Elements of Dynamics.
[Nearly ready.
UoniJon : c. j. clay and sons,
CAMBRIDGE WAREHOUSE, AVE MARIA LANE.
(Klasphj: 263, ARGYLE STREET.
CawfttOJae: DEIGHTON, bell and go. fLeujjie: F. A. BROCKHAUS.
i^tto lork: MACMILLAN AND CO.
Cambridge: printed by c. j. clay, m.a. & sons, at the university press.
RETURN TO the circulation desk of any
University of California Library
or to the
NORTHERN REGIONAL LIBRARY FACILITY
BIdg. 400, Richmond Field Station
University of California
Richmond, CA 94804-4698
ALL BOOKS MAY BE RECALLED AFTER 7 DAYS
• 2-month loans may be renewed by calling
(510)642-6753
• 1-year loans may be recharged by bringing
books to NRLF
• Renewals and recharges may be made
4 days prior to due date
DUE AS STAMPED BELOW
OCT 1 2005
DD20 12M 1-05
515643
UNIVERSITY OF CALIP^NIA LIBRARY