ESSAYS IN JURISPEUDENGE AND ETHICS ESSAYS IN JUEISPEUDENCE AND ETHICS FREDERICK POLLOCK, M.A., LL.D. LATE FELLOW OF TRINITY COLLEGE, CAMBRIDGE ILontJon MACMILLAN AND CO. 1882 9 177 1 Printed by R. & R. Clakk, Edinburgh. A I P7e TO ERNEST EENAK PREFACE. The substance of the following Essays has appeared in divers journals and reviews in the course of the last seven years. My first duty is to return my best thanks to the proprietors and editors of those publica- tions for the consent they have freely given to the present reproduction. Some additions and rearrange- ments have been made, and a few passages have been worked in from articles on kindred subjects which for one or another reason did not seem worth reprinting separately. No unity of design will be expected in a work thus composed of occasional pieces ; but I hope that so much unity of purpose and ideas may nevertheless be found in it as will give it a certain measure of coherence. The essays fall into two divisions, in the first of which legal topics predominate, in the second ethical. In the first it has been my aim to consider legal ideas and institutions as aff'ected by or afi"ecting the wider interests of history, politics, and practical legislation. In the second I have endeavoured to bring to a better defined issue certain points of ethi- cal discussion by the help of distinctions founded on familiar legal conceptions, and by sj^ecifically applying those conceptions and distinctions to admitted facts. Vlll PREFACE. In both subjects I have used by preference the his- torical method, taking that term in a wide, but, I think, not an unfairly wide sense. There may be an apparent inconsistency in the points of view taken in some of the legal essays. I have started sometimes from the pure analysis of the modern English school of jurisprudence, sometimes from history, sometimes from practical expediency. My own opinion is that all these methods are legiti- mate, and that if their results fail to agree, it is the fault not of the instrument but of the worker. No doubt there exists a tendency to conflict between the historical and the analytical manner of considering legal phenomena. The historical student is tempted to regard analytical jurisprudence as shallow sciolism, while the analytical jurist is apt to charge the histori- cal and comparative method with laxity of thought and antiquarian pedantry. Both methods are in truth useful and necessary, and either of them alone is imperfect. The modern developments of legal theory have shown them in their power and in their short- comings. The history of law was by no means neglected before the rise of modern critical jurisprudence ; but its results were of little value so long as they could not be read in the light of general ideas and principles. Blackstone gives the history of English law from the thirteenth century onwards with sufficient fulness for all ordinary purposes, and, as a rule, with great ac- curacy : the historical merit of his Commentaries has been too much overlooked in the discussion of his PREFACE. IX faulty arrangement and inadequate theories. Montes- quieu not only collects a great quantity of materials for legal history, but has a notion of historical method and comparative research far in advance of other writers of his time. Yet all this work remained un- fruitful for the best part of a century. It had to be fertilized by the ideas of the analytical school. Ben- tham, on the other hand, had no room in his mind for history. He would have liked to make a clean sweep of all the laws and customs of Europe, and start afresh with a code warranted to secure the greatest happiness. Even language had for him no continuity to be respected. He seriously drafted specimens of legislation in a style invented by himself as the most appropriate for the purpose, and defying all the usages of common syntax. A system proceeding from this habit of mind could not easily adapt itself to the facts of different ages and societies. Its general proposi- tions were in truth, like those of political economy, drawn from the conditions of a particular society at a particular time, or rather those conditions as they would be in the absence of disturbing: elements. These conditions have still their peculiar value for scientific jurisprudence, insomuch as they are those which more and more tend to be realized in the pro- gress of modern civilized communities. But this ) value cannot be rightly perceived and set on its true / footing until the extreme claims of abstract analysis have broken down in the presence of unforeseen and refractory elements of fact. Thus the Indian village community shows us a state of society to which, h X PREFACE, tliougli it is an orderly and well-settled one, Bentham's or Austin's definitions are applicable only by doing extreme violence to language ; and the consideration of such phenomena has led Sir Henry Maine to apply the needful correction to the analytical theory. Again, in the art of legislation the analytical intellect is in- dispensable to give us the power of expressing clearly what we intend, while the historical view comes in to help our choice of immediately desirable and practic- able objects. If it be asked whether analytical and historical work are to go on correcting one another for all time, I am disposed to say that j)robably they will. All scientific definition is really provisional and ap- proximative ; and all applications of our knowledge to the actual conduct of life are endeavours towards an ideal which, however near we may come to grasping it, will ever escape our full possession. CONTENTS. II. HI. IV. V. VI. VII. VIII. IX. X. XL XII. XIII. The Nature of Jurisprudence, considered in rela- tion TO SOME Recent Contributions to Legal Science Laws of Nature and Laws of Man Some Defects of our Commercial Law The Law of Partnership in England Employees' Liability The Theory of Persecution The Oath of Allegiance The History of English Law as Politics A Branch of The Science of Case-Law . The Casuistry of Common Sense Ethics and Morals . Marcus Aurelius and the Stoic Philosophy Mr. Spencer's Data of Ethics Index ..... 1 42 60 95 lU U4 176 198 237 261 287 314 352 379 I. THE NATURE OF JURISPRUDENCE CONSIDERED IN RELATION TO SOME RECENT CONTRIBUTIONS TO LEGAL SCIENCE.^ Professor Holland of Oxford is to be congratulated on having done a piece of work that was much called for. Though several years have passed since the Universities and the Inns of Court proclaimed the importance of jurisprudence as a part of legal educa- tion, nobody has taken up Austin's unfinished work in a serious or satisfactory manner, or succeeded in making it very clear what jurisprudence really is. To English students it means at present, for all prac- tical purposes, the two volumes of Austin's Lectures, or the one volume into which their matter has been more lately condensed by his able editor. It may be true of Austin's work, as Professor Holland says, that ^ Tlie Elements of Jurisprudence. By Thomas Erskine Holland, D.C.L., etc. Oxford: Clarendon Press. 1880. The Institutes of Law : a Treatise of the Principles of Jurisprudence cts determined by Nature. By James Lorimer, Advocate, Regius Professor of Public Law and of the Law of Nature and Nations in the University of Edinburgh, etc. Second edition, revised and enlarged. Edinburgh and London : William Blackwood and Sons. 1880. International Law. By William Edward Hall, M.A., Barrister-at-Law. Oxford : Clarendon Press. 1880. ' B 2 THE NATURE OF JURISPRUDENCE. [l no one can read it without improvement ; yet lie seems to confine his praise to the introductory part, originally published as " The Province of Jurispru- dence Determined," and so far I am quite of one mind with him. In any case, it is not desirable that Austin's should remain for an indefinite time the only means of improvement in this department of know- ledge available for our seats of learning. It is, after all, a fragmentary publication, and has the faults incidental to this character, in addition to the others with which it is chargeable. As I am not now criti- cizing Austin, I will only say that these are precisely of the kind which make a book less fit for the use of beginners. Besides, the increase of general knowledge and interest has a certain eff'ect on the relative import- ance of diff'erent parts of a great subject. "Those distinctions upon which Austin, after his somewhat superfluously careful manner, bestows most labour are put in so clear a light that they can hardly again be lost sight of;" and if there is one thing more than another for which we ought fervently to thank Austin's labours, it is that at this time of day no rational being could or would occupy six lectures with the discussion of what positive law is not. For the rest, Professor Holland's preface, while it points out with unquestionable truth that " works upon legal system by English writers have hitherto been singu- larly unsystematic," is studiously courteous to his predecessors. It is perhaps an excess of courtesy to mention Dr. Broom^s work on Legal Maxims, a thinof of neither fish nor flesh, on the same level with l] THE NATURE OF JURISPRUDENCE. 3 Smith's Leading Cases, which, though it never pre- tended to be anything but technical, stands in the first rank of our technical books. Jurisprudence is dfi^ned by Professor Holland as the formal science ®9fa!w: " not the material science of those portions of the law which various nations have in common, but the formal science of those relations of mankind w^hich are generally recognized as having legal consequences." It stands towards actual legal systems, past or present, in a relation like that of grammar to particular languages. As a matter of fact, its construction has been suggested by the comparison of different systems ; but such comparison is not in itself a necessary condition for the existence of such a science. " Just as similarities and differ- ences in the growth of different languages are collected and arranged by Comparative Philology, and the facts thus collected are the foundation of abstract Grammar, so Comparative Law collects and tabulates the legal institutions of various countries ; and from the results thus prepared the .abstract science of Jurisprudence is enabled to set forth an orderly view of the ideas and methods which have been variously realized in actual systems." The parallel is felicitous, and only too felicitous. If it be just, it goes a little too far for the writer's purpose. Abstract grammar, in the sense here speci- fied, is evidently a conceivable science. But is it an actual science in the sense of being explicitly taught or learnt by any one ? We have never heard of its professors or text-books. No such teachers or books. 4 THE NATUEE OF JURISPRUDENCE. [l as far as I can learn, liave been called forth by the development of modern philology. Nor is there in fact room for them. Abstract grammar is given by implication in every systematic grammar of a parti- cular language, and its generality appears as soon as the grammatical structure of two different languages is referred to a common type. When the English schoolboy who has learnt Latin learns (if he ever does, which, with our existing methods, is uncertain) enough of his own language to know that the verbal-substan- tive forms in "I go a-fishing" and in " Lusum it Maecenas" are homologous, he makes an application of abstract grammar. When the comparative j)hilologist performs a like process on a larger scale, he must either come to his task equipped with a scheme of abstract grammar or make one as he goes along. But neither boys nor men learn abstract grammar by itself The reason, I conceive, is that the subject-matter can- not be understood until the learner has mastered the grammar of at least one concrete language ; and, if the language be a tolerably developed one, and the grammar arranged on a tolerably rational plan, in learnino; the matter he has learnt the form also. There is no need for his learning it over again in the abstract. In order to appreciate its importance as form, he has only to await the occasion of applying it to new matter. Perhaps it may be said that a person who, being empirically master of his own language, takes up the grammar of it for the first time, is really learning abstract grammar ; for in. this case the matter consists of what he knows already. Not the less does l] THE NATURE OF JURISPRUDENCE. 5 he acquire the abstract system through the concrete application. We may observe in passing that Phil- ology is considerably richer than Jurisprudence both in the variety of actual types to be observed and in the number of distinct systematic arrangements that have been constructed. Greek, Indian, and Arabic grammarians worked out their schemes in perfect independence. It would seem that philologists have great opportunities for elaborating the science of abstract grammar. What use they have made of them is more than I am competent to say ; l^ut one cannot help suspecting that our leaders in philology would not think such an operation very profitable. Again, the student of medicine learns vertebrate anatomy, which is the knowledge of particular verte- brate structures. He learns comparative anatomy, whereby he comes to perceive the analogies of difi'erent vertebrate structures. Hence he forms the idea of a general vertebrate type, which is not the image of any existing skeleton, but is a generic symbol of a certain disposition and relation of parts which any specific vertebrate skeleton embodies and makes visible. Shall we reo;ard this as a new and distinct knowledge or science, and call it abstract vertebrate anatomy ? And, if we do, can it be taught or learnt in its abstract character 1 It appears to me that jurisprudence, as more or less vaguely understood in English usage of the term, and now clearly defined by Professor Holland, is doomed to vacillate between two alternatives, of which both are unsatisfying. It may confine itself to making 6 THE NATURE OF JURISPRUDENCE. [l out a catalogue of blank forms ; in other words, to the pure theory of legal classification. I do not for a moment deny that the scientific arrangement of the law is a subject worthy of the most careful discussion. But I do not think it a good subject to be dwelt upon by students at an early stage. The reasons for or against a particular scheme cannot be understood until the matter to be dealt with by it is to some extent familiar. If, on the other hand, jurisprudence undertakes to explain and illustrate the blank forms of its classification by showing how they are filled up, its constant tendency is to slide into the partial exposition — comparative or otherwise — of some par- ticular system. This tendency appears more than once in Professor Holland's work, as where he brings in a statement of the peculiar and by no means ele- mentary English doctrine of contributory negligence. One feels, again, that his broad mention of the results educible from the tangle of statutes that make up our law of copyright is either too much or too little, — too much for a treatise on the general form of laws, too little for a treatise on the laws of England. Since the law of England is, by the consent of all persons who have seriously thought about it, in sore need of a S3^stematic expounder, the best and most profitable way to prove the value of jurisprudence would perhaps be to show it in that specific applica- tion. If Professor Holland, or some other equally competent worker, or two or three such together, would give us a good book of Institutes of English Law, that would indeed be a boon for lawyers and l] THE NATURE OF JURISPRUDENCE. 7 students to welcome. As it is, our young men hear systematic lectures on jurisprudence and legal method in general, and have meanwhile to pick up their first notions of the law of their own country from mauled and tinkered editions or imitations of Blackstone put together in defiance of all rational arrano-ement. Blackstone's work was an excellent one in his time and accordins^ to his lio-hts : w^e mi^ht honour him better at this day than by a blundering lip-service which, as a rule, eS"ectually excludes the knowledge of what Blackstone really wrote. The modern editions utterly spoil Blackstone as literature, without produc- inor a good account of the modern law. One conse- quence of this is that the historical value of Blackstone in his genuine form is apt to be sadly underrated. And, in fact, if we turn to Germany, where the academic teaching of law is more fully developed than with us, w^e shall find a state of things which Profes- sor Holland mentions with a certain air of surprise. Although the last thing tJiat can be said against the German school is that the philosophical and theoretical consideration of legal conceptions fails to find expres- sion in it, there are no distinct organs or departments for the purely formal science of law. What in England we have lately called jurisprudence is em- bodied by German writers in their extensive and methodical treatises known as PandeMen, of which the subject is modern Roman law, — that is, so much of the Roman civil law as has furnished, or may be con- sidered capable of furnishing, the groundwork of the modern law of German States. Most, if not all, of 8 THE NATURE OP JURISPEUDENCE. [l these works contain a certain amount of matter of a highly general nature ; but this is treated, and as I think rightly so, as preliminary to the study of the particular system. At the same time, I am far from saying that under the peculiar conditions of English legal literature the study of legal ideas in their most abstract form is not useful and necessary. But I think a scientific exposi- tion of English law would be still better, and should be regarded as the end to which our provisional study of abstract jurisprudence is to lead up. This position may be illustrated by returning to the philological comparison which has already been used. Let us supj)ose that the English language, instead of being the simplest member of a group, stands apart from all others, and is exceedingly complex in structure and full of anomalies. Let us also suppose that the litera- ture relating to it — comprising grammars, dictionaries, and philological works of all kinds — is of enormous bulk, and contains much matter of great value, but is terribly diffuse, and arranged partly on wrong systems, and mostly on no system at all. In this state of con- fusion it mio;;ht well be that the cultivation of abstract grammar would precede the actual reform of English grammar, and it is even conceivable that this might be the only way to it. And this imaginary case is roughly parallel to the real state of English laws and law-books. A general view of the field of Positive Law, with only just so much concrete illustration as is needed to make it intelligible, may do much to clear the heads of learners, and beget in them a just discon- l] THE NATURE OF JURISPRUDENCE. 9 tent with the crude and formless condition in which the details of almost every topic are still left. To make a cosmos out of this chaos of disjointed particu- lars is a task which a later generation, prepared by such teaching as Professor Holland's in this book, and Mr. Markby's in his Elements of Laiv, may be able to attempt with good hope of success. It remains to say a few words of the manner in which Professor Holland handles in detail the subject which he has defined as the formal science of law. His exposition is clear and careful throughout, and the work is, for law students' purposes, a great improve- ment on Austin. Though considerably less bulky, it is more complete, more symmetrical, and more intel- ligible. As literature it is almost incomparably better. Austin's painfully laboured style has an efi'ect amount- ing to repulsion on some persons, of whom I confess myself to be one. Professor Holland's is concise with- out abruptness, flowing without tediousness, and dis- tinct without wearisome repetitions. The subjects discussed at the outset are naturally the definition of law and the theory of sovereignty. The two chapters on the various usages of the word laiv might perhaps bear to be yet further shortened. I should doubt, indeed, whether their subject is properly within the scope of jurisprudence. Professor Holland's definition of law runs thus: — "A generahj rule of external human action enforced by a sovereign | political authority," — or, should we say, purporting to be enforced ? for not every sovereign can make sure of enforcing his commands ; and sometimes laws are 10 THE NATURE OF JURISPRUDENCE. [l made without even any great intention of enforcing them. I do not see wliy this should not come at the very beginning, with the statement that only such laws as answer this description are the subject of legal science. However, the opening chapters as they stand form a good introduction to the modern terminology. Proceeding to the theory of sovereignty, Professor Holland confesses and avoids Sir Henry Maine's criticism of the extreme analytical doctrine, which is or ought to be by this time well known, and sums up his own result in these words : — " It is convenient to recognize as laws only such rules as are enforced by a sovereign political authority, although there are states of society in which it is dilhcult to ascertain as a fact what rules answer to this description." But the qualification seems not quite adequate. In the states of society specified by Sir Henry Maine, and to this day prevailing over a large part of the earth, the difficulty is not merely to ascertain what rules of con- duct are true laws, but to find any person or body answering the description of a sovereign political authority in the sense required by the analytical school. The half-dozen pages on customary law strike us as particularly good. Professor Holland brings out and harmonizes the elements of truth in the opposed views of the English analytical and the German historical jurists. Austin's contention that customary law " is nothing but judiciary law founded on an anterior custom," is disallowed as being re- pugnant to the facts. The Courts decide whether an alleged custom is or is not binding, not at their l] THE NATURE OF JURISPRUDENCE. 11 pleasure, but according to settled rules. The condi- tions on which the validity of a custom depends must be present, if they are present, before the case occurs for decision ; just as the text of an Act of Parliament has the force of law when the Act is passed, though it may afterwards call for judicial interpretation. In this case the retrospective application of the construc- tion arrived at by the Court is obviously necessary ; and what takes place when a custom is allowed is essentially the same. Indeed similar considerations might be shown to apply largely, though not univer- sally, to the declaration of rules of common law ; so that in this sense, though not in the sense intended by Austin, his dictum above cited may be accepted. In the chapter on Eights a series of definitions is carefully and elegantly worked out ; the distinction between might, moral right (as sanctioned by existing positive morality), and legal right, is exceedingly well put, and ought to nip in the bud a good many fine flowers of confused thinking. The only point on which a little more explanation might be useful is the difierence between positive morality and ideal moral- ity, which is not expressly noticed. Legal right is defined as a capacity residing in one man (we should rather say " person," as man does not include artificial persons) of controlling, with the assent and assistance of the State, the actions of others. In popular usage we speak elliptically of a man having a right to use his property as he likes, and so forth ; whereas his right is, accurately speaking, to prevent other people from interfering with his use. This does not, how- 12 THE NATURE OF JURISPRUDENCE. [l ever, affect the correctness of the definition. With regard to persons as subjects of rights and duties (" Trager der Rechtsverhaltnisse/' as the Germans more neatly have it), Professor Holland has invented two new terms ; he calls the person entitled " the person of inherence," and the person bound " the per- son of incidence." Perhaps these are hardly neces- sary, but they are at least innocent. In his general classification of the subject-matter of positive law Professor Holland takes rights in preference to duties as the starting-point. This arrangement may be the more easily understood at first sight, but I am dis- posed to regret the choice. It is impossible to arrange a body of law under a scheme of rights without some dislocation or repetition. After going through the categories of substantive rights, you have to start afresh with a catalogue of wrongs, consisting to a great extent in the breach of duties corresponding to the rights which have already been set forth. Another objection is that all rights have corresponding duties, while some duties (Austin's " absolute duties ") have no corresponding rights, and therefore a classification founded on rights is, by the nature of the case, incom- plete. But this is not admitted by Professor Holland, who maintains that the State's being the fountain of legal right does not prevent the State from having rights as well as any other artificial person, or even from having cbities " such as it prescribes to itself," in so far as it submits to the jurisdiction and the decisions of its own Courts. This, I think, is just; yet there are various duties of a more or less public l] THE NATURE OF JURISPRUDENCE. 13 kind as to which it is not easy to say where the corresponding rights are, and cases are frequent in practice where there is no doubt as to the person bound, but the person entitled can be ascertained only after a lapse of time, certain or uncertain, or by judicial decision between adverse claims. It is true that the devolution of duties is also at times difficult to trace. The duties attached to trust estates afford a signal example. It is satisfactory to find that Professor Holland retains the ancient and fundamental division of Private and Public Law, and disapproves rather summarily of Austin's curious aberration on this point. Few as English attempts at legal classification have been, we have already had far too much of straining after novelty for novelty's sake. One or two late writers, whose ambition is apparently to be the Blackstones of our time, have made their work all but worthless by deliberate confusion of the familiar boundaries. With regard to the troublesome question of the law of status, and its due place in a system. Professor Holland starts from the citizen of full age and capacity as having " normal rights." Differences in status consist in departures or degradations from this normal capacity, which are attached to particular personal conditions, such as infancy or coverture. The rights and duties which arise from the relations of normal citizens to one another come naturally to be considered in the first place ; then we consider them as they may be affected by the abnormal condition of one or both parties. " The inquiry into the law of Persons is thus supple- 14 THE NATURE OF JURISPRUDENCE. [l mentary and secondary to that into the residue of the law, commonly called the law of Things." To this it may be added that the law of Persons is more subject to historical and local variations, and more difficult to refer to any generally accepted principles. Take, for instance, the rules on such a topic as the contract of sale, as we find them in the Corpus Juris, and as they now exist in any State of the civilized world, and then make the like comparison as to marriage and its legal incidents and consequences. In the first case the difi"erences will be appreciable ; but — whether as be- tween the Roman and any particular modern system, or as between the laws of different modern States — they will be trifling as compared with those which strike us in the second. At the same time the importance of the law of Persons as compared with the law of Things is ever on the wane in modern systems. In Hindu law the family and caste are everything, and equal rights of equal individuals are next to nothing. In the world of modern law caste and slavery, the great ancient heads of per- sonal inequality, have disappeared, and the law of Persons is but a fraction of the whole body. These are additional reasons for putting the law of Things, with Professor Holland, before the law of Persons. Yet one has a certain lingering prejudice in favour of the Roman arrangement. The law of Persons gives a kind of dramatic interest to the opening of the subject. Perhaps the separation of the whole body of law into a General Part and a Special Part, after the German example, might help to solve the l] THE NATURE OF JURISPRUDENCE. 15 difficulty. The broad characters of status would come into the General Part. In the Special Part there would probably be no need for a separate treat- ment of the law of Persons, but the details would be worked into the subjects specially ajffected by them. Thus the general nature of an infant's disabilities would be mentioned under the general chapter of the law of Persons, but his power of binding himself by contract would be discussed afterwards under the law of Contract. As to the nomenclature, there is a little awkwardness in using the term "abnormal" for a condition such as infancy, through which every natural person has to pass, or the existence of a corporation, which is not only familiar in every civilized country, but is really an extension of the power of the individ- uals composing it. But it is etymologically appro- priate, as Professor Holland shows by comparing the old grammatical arrangement of the declension of nouns, in which the cases are artificially viewed as departures from an assumed normal form ; and nothing better has yet been proposed. Professor Holland speaks of " antecedent '"' instead of primary or sanctioned, and " remedial " instead of secondary or sanctioning, rights. It occurs to me that " substantive " and " adjective " might do as well, and mark more distinctly the relation of rights to proce- dure. We have already " substantive law " and " adjective law," the latter being the law of procedure. Now remedial rights are the rights with which the law of procedure is concerned. Primary or ante- cedent rights are enforced only through the medium 16 THE NATURE OF JURISPRUDENCE. [l of these, as there can be no proceeding except by some one who has a right to proceed. Why not, then, use the term " adjective rights " for the rights which are worked out by adjective law ? Moreover, the term " remedial " is not always appropriate ; there are pro- ceedings, such as interpleader and payment of money into Court by a trustee, where the first step is taken by a party who seeks to be relieved, not against some one else's breach of duty, but against the risk of un- willing breach of duty on his own part. That in so doing he exercises a right is clear ; but it can hardly be called either sanctioning or remedial. We need not follow Professor Holland minutely through the various topics of Private Law. On the law of ownership it is neither easy nor desirable to say anything very new, though, in mentioning what things cannot be property. Professor Holland makes the rather sweeping statement that " air and water are obviously for the free use of all mankind." As regards water there is obviously a great deal, such as ponds in private grounds, which is not for the free use of mankind in any sense, and still more, such as portions of rivers subject to rights of lower ri]3arian owners, of which the use is not free in the sense of being unlimited. However, it is true that water runnino; or standing in its natural state cannot be stolen ; and Blackstone even speaks of " the elements of light, air, and water," as things which " must of necessity con- tinue common by the law of nature." Under the head of rights in personam, Professor Holland makes a chapter of rights ex lege ; we should prefer to say l] THE NATURE OF JURISPRUDENCE. 17 rights appendant or riglits annexed by law, as ex lege in this sense is hardly good Latin. This term com- prises the rights of husband and wife (because, though the existence of the state of marriage depends on the will of the parties, its incidents do not), with other family relations ; trusts, the quasi-contracts of the civil law, the fictitious contracts of English law which were the subject of the old " common counts," and some other relations of a like sort arising from circumstances independent of contract. We do not find any notice of the analogous rights in rem which belong to the head of obligations quasi ex delicto in Roman law, and with us have been established by the class of decisions laying down the measure of an owner's liability for the safe keeping of dangerous things. I think myself that the term quasi ex delicto, decried by Austin and others as unmeaning, is both significant and appropriate for liabilities of this kind. Where a man was held liable for the acts or defaults of other persons, the Romans did not see their way to saying he had committed a delict. There was no maleficium on his part if a slave did damage by throw- ing rubbish out of his house in Rome while he was away in Campania. Yet it was thought right he should answer for it as if the act had been his own, and the liability was naturally and fitly described as quasi ex maleficio. This conception has a certain special importance for us in England. In our law there is a border-land where contract and tort overlap, and the key to these phenomena must be sought in the idea just mentioned, or a closely analogous one. c 18 THE NATURE OF JURISPRUDENCE. [l Before entering on contracts proper, Professor Holland remarks in effect that the action in " tort founded on contract " of English law is from the scientific point of view, anomalous, which is true. Nevertheless the action in tort is, as matter of history, much the older ; and it must be remembered that, down to the Common Law Procedure Act the commonest form of action on contracts was a modified action on the case. There must have been a widely -spread notion that even when the contract was not enforceable as such, say for want of formality, it created a kind of special duty of which a wilful or neglisfent breach would be action- able. The needful extension of duties ex contractu was arrived at circuitously through the supposition of a duty quasi ex delicto. In the chapter on Remedial Rights it is said that *' so long as all goes well the action of the law is dormant ;" we think it should have been added that so far as things do go well it is in some measure due to general knowledge that the law, if broken, will be enforced, and that thus the law is really most opera- tive when least conspicuous. International laAv is happily described as "the vanishing point of Juris- prudence ;" and here we leave Professor Holland on the verge of the ground specially assigned to him by his office, on which, however, the plan of his work forbids him to enter at any length on this occasion. In the same year that Professor Holland's Elements of Jurisprudence appeared at Oxford, there issued from Edinburgh the second edition of Professor Lorimer's Institutes of Laiv. This is the only work l] THE NATURE OF JURISPRUDENCE. 19 known to me which adequately sets forth in English a view of the nature of jurisprudence diametrically opposed to that of the English analytical school. It would, therefore, be valuable even if this were only fairly well done ; but Professor Lorimer has done it as well as it can be done, and has procured a refined satisfaction to followers of the English school who take up his book : I mean the satisfaction of reading a vigorous and well- written exposition of a theory with which one entirely disagrees. We can imagine an English student of jurisprudence, parched with the stern limitations and crabbed analysis of Austin, turning with interest and even eagerness to seek variety in Professor Lorimer's treatise. He would certainly not be disappointed in that respect. Almost the whole of it deals with topics which, according to the English view, may be philosophical, or ethical, or political, but are distinctly outside the province of jurisprudence. In other words, our English school holds that the absolute law which is or should be the origin and pattern of all existing laws, — Naturrecht as the Germans call it, — either does not exist or does not concern lawyers more than any one else. What is here delivered from the Chair of Public Law in Edin- burgh is a book of Naturrecht from beginning to end. It contains in detail much good writing, much ingenuity, and not a little good sense on various political and social questions ; the credit of all which belongs, in my opinion, to Professor Lorimer's person, and in no way to his system. As to the impression made by it as a whole, I confess for my own part to 20 THE NATURE OF JURISPEUDENCE. [l feeling rather like tlie young man in Grimm's Marchen who went out to learn to shiver, and whose curiosity was finally satisfied — after the total failure of a haunted castle and other adventures — by the applica- tion of a pail of cold water from the brook with the little fishes in it. I had long known of Naturrecht as a thing existing in German books, but it had never come in my way to any serious extent. The German writers, for instance, who expound the Eoman law for the benefit of practical students disclose very little of it. We have to thank Professor Lorimer for revealing the mystery in as good English as the nature of the subject admits. As I came to the last page I said to myself with a mental gasp and shiver, " Ugh ! ugh ! now I know what Naturrecht is." Natural law, as conceived by Professor Lorimer and his authorities, appears to cover a great part of what is commonly understood in this country by moral and political philosophy ; the foundations of moral obligation, the extent of the power which the State ought to exercise over citizens, the duty of the citizen to obey the laws of the State, the nature of justice, the analysis of the political ideas of liberty and equality, the methods of political discipline and instruction, and much else which cannot here be specified. We find in addition a sort of introductory digression on ethnology and the history of religions, in which it may be observed that the discussion of Buddhism is not brought up to the existing state of knowledge on the subject. In my view it is also irrelevant, but not more so than the rest of the chapter in which it occurs. This, it is fair l] THE NATURE OF JURISPRUDENCE. 21 to say, is about the only point at which there is any- thing to except to on the score of workmanship ; for when Professor Lorimer's method allows him to come down to the region of tangible facts, he is generally accurate. Nor can we dispute his right to adopt, as he does in this chapter, Sir A. Grant's rather fanciful conjecture that the founders of Stoicism were of Semitic blood. A significant guide-post to the general direction and spirit of the w^ ork is the manner in wdiich Professor Lorimer uses the term " positive law." To an English reader this means actually existing law — the law w^hich the courts of justice and the executive powers of government enforce, or profess to enforce, at a given time and place. Professor Lorimer treats this usage as a mere aberration, and almost makes an apology for mentioning it. For him "positive law" is not the enforceable law which does exist, — the law of Scotland, for example, as it stands at the date of his writing, — but that which would exist if, the actual circumstances being otherwise the same, legislators and judges were perfectly wise. The law as it does exist is called " enacted law," and dealt with as on a quite subordinate footing. " Human enactments," we are told, " never attain to the full character of positive laws. But they possess the character of positive laws, more or less, in proportion to the extent to which they are, or are not, interpretations and realizations of the law of nature." In this nomenclature the law of employers' liability as modified by the Act of 1880 on that subject is only "enacted law;" the "positive law " is what an infallible Parliament would have 22 THE NATURE OF JURISPRUDENCE. [l made it ; in other words, it is something theoretically ascertainable, but of which every man will have his own theory. In Professor Lorimer's own words, *' though necessarily existent and discoverable, positive laws never have been, and probably never will be, perfectly discovered." This kind of "positive law" is, however, not coextensive with the law of nature. For the law of nature includes all moral duties with- out exception, and it is not to be assumed that a perfectly wise legislator would attempt to enforce all moral duties. Again, natural law is described as binding on all rational creatures, while the ideal " positive law " would, in Professor Lorimer's view at any rate, be adapted to the varying polity and cir- cumstances of each State. For instance, the English and Scotch rules on a particular point might be dif- ferent, though they were the best possible for England and Scotland respectively. Still more would this be the case as between countries in different stages of civilization. This nomenclature shows of itself, as indeed the book shows wherever one opens it, that the school followed by Professor Lorimer concerns itself far less with law as it is than with law as it ought to be, or at least regards the consideration of law as it ought to be as forming the fit and necessary philosophical pro- legomena to the study of law as it is. My own view (and, I think, the view of most English students) is a totally different one. I think it a mistake to preface the study of legal conceptions by an exposition of transcendental ethics, and not less a mistake to pre- l] THE NATURE OF JURISPRUDENCE. 23 face it, as Austin did, by an exposition of the principle of utility. I do not see that a jurist is bound to be a moral philosopher more than other men ; though I do think it quite possible that a lawyer who happens to study moral philosophy may find a legal habit of mind and legal analogies of considerable use in clearing up his ethical conceptions. It is true that positive law in the English sense, the " enacted law " of Profes-' sor Lorimer, assumes the existence of society and morality. There must be a body of men living con- tinuously together, and there must be among them a fairly settled body of prevalent opinion as to what is right and wrong. This latter condition is not really an independent one, since, if a settled common opinion about matters of conduct failed to become established or ceased to exist, the society could no longer hold together. As a further condition for the existence of law as distinct from custom and morality, or, to speak more exactly, for the differentiation of law and mora- lity out of custom, there must also be a general understanding that some rules of conduct are fit to be enforced by definite means of compulsion, and in the last resort by the whole power of the society, and others are not. And there must be some sort of common agreement, though it may be, and mostly is, a vague and rough one, and obscurely felt in the common sense of the average citizen, as to the boundary to be drawn between these classes of rules. Yet more is wanted before we can have a civilized and effective system of law. The commonwealth must assume and exercise a power beyond that of issuing 24 THE NATURE OF JURISPRUDENCE. [l commands for the purpose of repressing actual crime and wickedness and strengthening righteousness. There are many matters indifferent in themselves in the sense that they may be dealt with in one way as well as in another, but not indifferent in this sense, that it would be of great inconvenience if they were not dealt with in some uniform way. We may name the rule of the road as a simple and familiar case. On such matters the community lays down fixed rules, not to enforce this or that course of action as right in itself, but just for the sake of having a fixed rule. These rules, when made, are as much entitled to observance as those which add the legal sanction to what is already prescribed by morality ; though we rather fail to see what account can be given of them by those who put their trust in the supposed law of nature, unless they come down for the nonce to a " question of what is vulgarly called expediency," as Professor Lorimer delicately puts it. Reflection shows that all positive law must have more or less of this arbitrary, or rather discretionary, element. For while the moral law says to an Englishman, as it did to a Roman, " Thou shalt not steal," the Roman law said, "If you steal you shall be liable to an actio furti;'' but English law says, " You shall not be liable to a civil action, but you may be tried by a judge and jury, and sentenced to penal servitude." English law, moreover, defines with great elaborateness, and perhaj)S not with perfect reasonableness, what is and what is not theft. But in administration the substance of the law cannot be distinguished from the particular defi- l] THE NATUflE OF JURISPRUDENCE. 25 nitions and provisions in which it takes its form. For if this and that citizen were free to observe or not observe it at his discretion in this or that particular, it would no longer be law. And thus among civilized \ people, after the distinction between law and morality , is fully established, it comes to be understood that it is a specific moral duty to obey existing positive law, not only when we cannot see the reason for it, but when we think the reason a bad one. This is subject to the exception of the extreme cases in which rebel- lion is morally justifiable ; and the case of a serious claim of legal right as against a particular authority within the State, or a usurping power, is not an exception at all. But it is understood, or ought to be, that to refuse obedience to an existing law because one disHkes it is, as far as it goes, rebellion and nothing else. And even in exceptional cases persons who resist the de facto possessors of legal power do it at their own risk, and cannot complain of being treated as law-breakers or rebels if they fail. I have thus set down with needful brevity what I conceive to be in a general way the moral data pre- supposed by the positive law of civilized nations. It will be observed that nothing whatever is said about the historical or rational origin of morality, or the nature of moral obligation in itself I have tried to say nothing inconsistent with Professor Lorimer's or any other transcendental scheme of ethics. We may take the morality of men living together in settled ' societies as an existing and sufficiently ascertained fact. It is for the moralist and the metaphysician to 26 THE NATURE OF JURISPRUDENCE. [l analyse it if tliey can ; enough for us that it is there. Even with this limitation I do not think that the statements I have just now made, be they right or wrong, are propositions of jurisprudence. The topics may be admissible as belonging to a sort of border- land or penumbra of legal science. An introductory sketch of the outlying affinities and analogies of a special subject is in many ways useful, and is common in the practice of teachers. But we deny that the jurist requires, as Professor Lorimer assumes him to require, " an absolute basis for his science." Why should he not, like other people, be content with a basis of acknowledged fact ? Positive law exists. In other words, there are certain social institutions which are protected, and certain rules of conduct which are in various ways and degrees enforced, by the courts of justice of all civilized countries. The fact is notorious and intelligible to all men of all ways of thinking, whether they account for it by deduction from the law of nature or otherwise. If the jurist accepts it as for his purposes ultimate, he does only what all other students of special sciences do ; we may add, what they did and must have done in order that those sciences might be constructed. Where would geometry be if the geometer were expected at the outset of his work to grapple with the meta- physical difficulties that beset our notion of space ? Where would physics be if the physicist had to explain the existence of matter ? Kant is the great founder of our modern criticism of ultimate philoso- phical notions ; but we know very well that Kant l] THE NATURE OF JURISPRUDENCE. 27 himself expected nothing of this kind from men of science. And the cases appear to me precisely- parallel. Geometry is the science of space, and physics the science of matter, in the same way that jurisprudence is the science of laws. The special sciences furnish the data of philosophy ; they do not need a complete philosophy to stand on their own ground. If they did, we should be in but a sorry plight. Observe, too, the warning to be derived from the analogy. Discussion of the nature of space is rendered possible only by a highly developed geo- metry ; rational discussion of the nature of matter only by advanced physical knowledge. And we may fairly contend, without prejudging the issue between tran- scendental and empirical theories of duty, that profit- able discussion of the origin and nature of laws in general must follow, and not precede, the scientific study of laws as they exist. Whether that study can in the long run be conveniently exhibited as a thing apart from and theoretically preceding the study of any particular system of laws is a question which deserves attention. Something has been said about it above in connection with Professor Holland's Elements of Jurisprudence. It does not arise upon anything in Professor Lorimer's book, for the simple reason that he barely gets to the threshold of the topics that properly belong to jurisprudence, general, comparative, or particular, as understood by Professor Holland and ourselves. To sum up the general criti- cism : The jurist or legislator, even on Professor Lorimer's own showing, has to accept the laws of 28 THE NATURE OF JURISPRUDENCE. [l nature as facts. If, as facts, they are equally acces- sible to all rational men, and equally material to be known and acted upon, I cannot see why the jurist is bound to analyse them philosophically more than any other rational man. If in the knowledge of them there is anything peculiar to jurists or legislators, they seem to that extent to lose the universal character which is said to be a mark of natural law. So far as the iusti atque iniusti scientia from which the lawyer starts is something which he does not share with laymen, it is a special and technical piece of knowledge, — a law of lawyers' nature at most, not of human or rational nature. But after all, it may be said, writers are free to define their subjects in their own way. The Univer- sity of Edinburgh and its professors have a perfect right to say that " Institutes of Law " shall mean the general prolegomena of politics and the theory of legislation. To this I reply that the same method which, in my opinion, leads to a misconception of the nature and scope of legal science no less appears to me to lead to waste and misdirection of power in the subjects actually treated by it under the name of legal science. It may be the radical perverseness of English habits of thinking, but in my English eyes much of the work done by Professor Lorimer — and, as far as execution and expression go, thoroughly well done — either arrives by high-flying and circuit- ous roads at obvious general conclusions, or arrives at more precise ones by a slenderly disguised appeal to the principle of '' what is vulgarly called expediency." l] THE NATUEE OF JUEISPRUDENCE. 29 Tims the question is brouglit up of tlie State's right to inflict and regulate punishment,- — a question which, from the English point of view, has in jurisprudence no meaning. The solution comes round, however, to the position that for the individual citizen the State is infallible. " The fact that one form of punishment attains the object of the absolute law l^etter than another must be proved ; but the competence of the Legislature to determine the adequacy of the proof must be assumed as the hypothesis on which all positive law rests." This is simply the analytical doctrine of sovereignty stated in a slightly varied way. More than once, indeed, we have a feeling that, while the voice is the voice of a teacher pro- pounding transcendental Naturrecht, the hands are the hands of Hobbes. In Professor Lorimer's system right and might ultimately coincide ; as they likewise do, be it observed, in Mr. Herbert Spencer's, or in almost any scheme which takes account of the progres- sive character of morality and civilization. Further, Professor Lorimer holds that we must act on that which appears, and that for many purposes might is the best or only evidence of apparent right. He fully accepts the position that "right to be" is measured by "power of being," and thus gives a hand back to Hobbes and forward to Mr. Spencer. As between independent nations, he lays down per- manent success as the permanent test of right. Only righteous conquests endure, and all enduring con- quests are righteous. And yet almost in the same breath Professor Lorimer makes the statement — to our 30 THE NATURE OF JURISPRUDENCE. [l Southern ears paradoxical — that laws cannot create rights, and calls to witness a famous passage of Burke's, of which it is sufficient to say that Burke spoke not as a jurist, but as a statesman/ In denying " the position that any body of men have a right to make what laws they please," he was really protest- ing against that very confusion of legal right with moral right or political utility which the transcen- dentalists briug back from the other side. What Professor Lorimer is doing is to state in the transcen- dental manner that laws will not work, or will work badly, if they are made without due regard to the facts. The matter is true, but the manner is itself a defiance of fact and usage. Laws made by the supreme power in a State, be they wise or foolish, do create claims which that power will, by the Courts and otherwise, do its best to enforce, and these claims are called rights by everybody save transcendental philosophers when they are philosophizing. One good test of the worth of ideas and theories in general jurisprudence is their application to inter- national law. This task had too long been left unattempted by the English school. As to the sub- ject itself, it is one in which English citizens and statesmen are at least as deeply interested as those of any other country, and in which there are peculiar objections to receiving the doctrines of foreign writers without a certain amount of caution. Our reproach has now been taken away by Mr, Hall, and so well that with his book in hand an English lawyer need no ^ Tracts on the Popery Laws, Ch. 3, Part 2. l] THE NATURE OF JURISPRUDENCE. 31 longer be afraid to speak in tlie gate with any of tlie American or Continental authorities. In a work that covers so much debatable ground much must of necessity be exposed to criticism. In fact, a writer on international law has to be perpetually on the verge of controversy. He must embark on almost endless discussion of a mixed mass of precedents and reasons, in which the exact value of the precedents is seldom known, and the reasons are constantly biassed by theoretical assumptions or political interest. No doubt there is a certain amount of settled principle, but the application of it by different States in their conduct and by different writers in their books is so various that what agreement there is appears at times to be illusory. One method much approved among writers on the law of nations is to simplify trouble- some questions by assuming that rules are settled when they are not ; taking care, of course, to pick out among the conflicting opinions that one which favours the writer's own sentiments, or seems to promise most advantage to his nation. Such is not Mr. Hall's way. AVhatever else he does, he is always frank in facing difficulties. He treats international law as a study of real facts, not a scheme to be elaborated by deduction without regard to the actual behaviour of princes and rulers. At the outset of his book Mr. Hall explains with laudable clearness that he intends to proceed not on transcendental but on empirical principles. His first statement, carefully framed not to prejudge contro- verted points of speculation, is that " International 32 THE NATURE OF JURISPRUDENCE. [l Law consists in certain rules of conduct which modern civilized States regard as being binding on them in their relations with one another with a force compar- able in nature and degree to that binding the con- scientious person to obey the laws of his country, and which they also regard as being enforceable by appro- priate means in case of infringement." These rules " may be considered to be an imperfect attempt to give effect to an absolute right which is assumed to exist and to be capable of being discovered ; or they may be looked upon simply as a reflection of the moral development and the external life of the particular nations which are governed by them." Besides these two views, there is a mixed or inter- mediate one to the efi'ect that international law is founded on some kind of absolute right ; but the evi- dence of what is right must be sought in positive law and usage. " In the following work," adds Mr. Hall, " the second view is assumed to be correct." The reasons given for it are, in my opinion, conclusive. Their general tenor is, or ought to be, not unfamiliar to every one who has studied in the English school of jurisprudence ; but I doubt if they have ever been so clearly and completely stated. They are reinforced, moreover, by an interesting Appendix " On the For- mation of the Conception of International Law," which is a good, concise introduction to the history of the subject. Among these preliminary topics Mr. Hall is especially instructive on the value of treaties as evidence of what the law of nations is. It is sup- posed by some writers that treaties form a sort of I] THE NATUllE OF JURISPRUDENCE. 33 international case-law ; but, as Mr. Hall truly points out, even if they profess to declare existing law, the declaration can bind only the parties who make it. A competent number of such declarations to the same effect might conceivably establish a consensus of great weight ; but, again, " it cannot be admitted that the greater number of treaties do in fact express in a peculiarly solemn manner, or indeed at all, the views of the contracting parties as to what is or ought to be international law." The chief value that treaties possess is really historical, " as marking points in the movement of thought." If we find at a given time a particular new practice or modification of old practice occurring as matter of express convention in several treaties, and if afterwards these treaty stipulations " are found to become nearly universal for a while, and then to dwindle away, leaving a practice more or less confirmed," this is good evidence that something which was introduced by way of special agreement has passed into the common usage of nations, and is no longer thought to need the protection of express treaty rights. And as to usage Mr. Hall justly points out that the usage of all nations is not of equal value in all things ; for instance, " it would at the present day be absurd to declare a maritime usage to be legally fixed in a sense opposed to the continued assertion of both Great Britain and the United States." The only point on which one could wish for a fuller exposition is the nature of the sanctions, or quasi-sanctions, of international law. This law con- sists to a great extent, as we may see by opening Mr. D 34 THE NATURE OF JURISPRUDENCE. [l Hall's book almost anywhere, of statements about what an independent nation may or may not do. What is the real meaning of this language ? By writers who are content to take refuge in the prin- ciples of absolute right the question is of course ne- glected. To those who, like Mr. Hall, prefer to stand on the more solid, if more humble, ground of fact and experience, it should be of considerable importance. Most persons would say that the sanction by which the law of nations is enforced is war; in which may be included for this purpose isolated acts of force, reprisals, so-called pacific blockades, and the like, which are acts of war if the State against whom they are employed thinks fit to treat them as such. And the reflection is now a trite one that international law difi'ers from laws proper in that the parties are judges in their own cause. Every Government must decide for itself whether the conduct of another independent Government is such as to make war necessary or comparatively desirable. Yet the books undertake to tell us in some detail that certain causes of war are just, and certain others are unjust ; not, indeed, with- out a quiet but sufiiciently clear indication from Mr. Hall of the amount of wool that the utmost ingenuity and enterprise of pig-shearers may be expected to produce in this kind. How can we speak of a war as legally unjust when there is no penalty save the risks of the war itself, which may turn out, for anything that can be pronounced beforehand, to the unjust combatant's advantage ? If a majority of the Great Powers were ready and willing to act habitually in l] THE NATURE OF JURISPRUDE^X'E. 35 concert for the purpose of restraining aggressions or provocations generally deemed unjust, that would be an effective sanction indeed. But we are yet far from this state of thinors. ]\Ir. Kino-lake has endeavoured, at the beginning of his History of the Crimean War, to show that an inchoate usao-e in this direction exists. We should be only too glad' to believe that such is the case. But the usage described by ]\Ir. Kinglake, if it does exist, is still unrecognized and undefined. It belons^s to somethino: which is to international law what morality is to laws proper. And this, by the way, may justify us in speaking of the law of nations as against extreme purists of the analytical school, who deny that it is really law. Since we find in the', practice of nations that some duties are conceived ofj as positive, and others as only honourable, it is cleaW that here, as in the practice of individual men, tlja distinction between law and morality does exii^, though it may be relatively undefined, and though the law may not possess all the characters of that which is so called as between a particular State and its subjects. Again, belligerents are bound to respect the rights of neutrals ; and these rights may be said in a true and intelligible sense to be sanctioned by war. For a belligerent who interferes beyond measure with a neutral's rights or interests exposes himself to having two enemies to do with instead of one — a danger which not even the strongest Power will care lightly to encounter. To this it is to be added that the interest of anv one neutral is, in most cases, the 36 THE NATURE OF JURISPRUDENCE. [l , interest of all, so that the remoter but not insensible risk of an overwhelming coalition is present to keep the belliojerents within bounds. But likewise there are laws of war conceived by publicists and statesmen to be binding on the belligerents as between them- selves. Modern warfare is a state of '' regulated violence," as Mr. Hall names it. And here we are not dealing with speculations in the air. There is no doubt that the violence of war has in fact been regulated and moderated to an extent that seemed impracticable in the time of Grotius. Whence comes the force of the regulation ? The sanction of war is exhausted, for these rules become effective only when and so far as a state of war already exists. It may be said that the fear of retaliation or reprisals is a sanction. Where this comes into play, however, that which is for the time sanctioned is apt to be the stronger j)arty's interpretation of the laws of war in his own favour, as was seen in the German invasion of France ten years ago. Moreover, reprisals and retalia- tion are available only to a limited extent, being, according to modern notions, too odious to be carried to extremities. In fact the grosser an offence is, the less is it capable of being punislied in kind. Here, then, formal and tangible sanctions desert us. The " temperaments " of modern warfare, to use Grotius's term, rest in truth on an appeal to the common morality and humanity of civilized nations, which belligerents are presumed still to share, and in fact still do share to a great extent, even in the midst of active hostilities. It is consonant to the feelings of l] THE NATURE OF JURISPRUDENCE. 37 civilized Governments, and in the long run to their interests, to observe towards one another in war some such rules as an enlio-htened neutral mio;ht wish to be observed for the sake of diminishing suffering and ill- will to the greatest extent compatible with the objects of war being attained. In other words, the sanction imposing on belligerents a certain observance of honour, humanity, and private rights, is at bottom the general opinion of civilized people. This is practically recognized by the manner in which belligerent Powers are accustomed to record their complaints of alleged infractions of the laws and usages of war. Such com- plaints can but seldom have the force of a specific threat ; their object is to procure redress from the adversary's own sense of what is right, or, in default of this, to shame him into it by publicity. Should we not, then, regard public opinion as the final sanction of international law in every case, — a sancti'^n with physical force behind it, no doubt, in one or another shape, but a force latent and undefined, and to be called into action only in an extreme case? This would bring out more clearly than the common view does the analogy between international law as govern- ing the relations of States, and the rules of morality as governing those of individuals. Or a better parallel, perhaps, may be found in the customary rules of a patriarchal tribe, which are enforced by no specially organized authority, and in which morality and law are still imperfectly distinguished. The view here suggested is really implied in the statement made by various writers from Suarez downwards, though per- 'MS i i i I 38 THE NATURE OF JURISPRUDENCE. [l haps with full distinctness by none before Austin, that the fear of provoking general hostility — not only that of the State particularly offended — is the ultimate compulsory motive for obedience to international rules. It seems to be a further consequence that war is analogous, not to the legal remedy of suing in a court of justice, but to the " self-help," more or less regulated by custom, which has a considerable place in archaic legal systems, and of which surviving rudiments, reduced to a subordinate rank and fettered by new safeguards, may be found in the most polished ones. To pursue the comparison one step farther, some guide for speculation as to the possible development and strengthening of international law may be found in the historical circumstances of partly civilized communi- ties. Probably in early Roman history, certainly in the middle ages, and notably in the Icelandic society described in the Sagas, private war went on for a con- siderable time side by side with legal redress before the supremacy of the law was finally made good. It is quite fair to object to the more ambitious schemes for European federation, universal tribunals of arbitra- tion, and the like, that sovereign States would never consent to be bound by them. But it is idle to object to the more cautious proposals, such as Bluntschli's, that they are not calculated, and do not profess, to make wars at once and for ever impossible. It is time to return from our digression to Mr. Hall's work. One of his greatest merits is lucid arrangement. He begins with a First Part of " General Principles," corresponding pretty much to l] THE NATURE OF JURISPRUDENCE. 39 the AUgemeiner Theil of systematic German writers, and giving a comprehensive view of the subject and its different branches. Then he takes up the divi- sions in detail. Under the head of " The haw govern- ing States in their normal relations," the rights and duties of sovereign States in time of peace are set forth. Here we have the doctrines of territorial dominion, sovereignty, the so-called "exterritoriality" of public vessels, extra-territorial jurisdiction, diplo- matic agents, and treaties. This same exterritoriality is treated by Mr. Hall as a fiction needlessly intro- duced to explain anomalous immunities which are really to be accounted for on special grounds of neces- sity or convenience. The third part deals with " the law governing States in the relation of war," which includes, besides what are known as the laws of war, the rights of cajDture and levying contributions, the position of a military occupant, and the rules which determine the " enemy character" of property. The relations of neutral States to the belligerents are kept apart under the title of " the law governing States in the relation of neutrality," where, among other ques- tions, the rules of contraband, blockade, and maritime visit and capture, are discussed. Mr. Hall's division of the subject is, we believe, new, though its conveni- ence makes it seem obvious when once exhibited. His treatment of the matter in detail is, with few if any exceptions, as good as his method. He is careful to preserve the distinction between theory and usage, and among usages to distinguish those which are established from such as are still uncertain or in pro- 40 THE NATUEE OF JUEISPRUDENCE. [l cess of formation ; for instance, the growing practice of restraining belligerents as much as possible from bringing their prizes into neutral harbours. In two or three places noted for criticism on the first reading of the book the doubt or objection is removed by sub- sequent explanations or additions ; and this perhaps is not a bad test of the general thoroughness of the work. The chapter on treaties might be improved by giving more attention to their operation in actually transferring dominion where the cession of territory enters into them. When such a treaty is executed, the parties are bound to its results not so much by the specific obligation of the treaty itself as by the general duty of nations to respect one another's terri- torial sovereignty. The analogous case in municipal law is that of a conveyance, not of a pure contract. Some of the language still commonly used implies a confusion which Mr. Hall might well have given a paragraph or two to clearing away. Treaties of this kind have been distinguished by some publicists from properly contractual treaties under the unhappily chosen name of ■' transitory conventions," and their effect has been still more unhappily expressed by the maxim that " transitory conventions are by the nature of the case perpetual." This is at best an extremely clumsy way of saying that the result is to create not an obligation but ownership. Proceeding from writers versed in Eoman law, it is really past excuse. When a sale is complete the seller is bound to respect for an indefinite time the right of ownership acquired by the buyer, and it makes no difference if a lawsuit arises l] THE NATURE OF JURISPRUDENCE. 41 between them about some other matter ; but we do not say that the contract of sale is perpetual. On the question of "pacific blockade" Mr. Hall treats the authority of modern usage (six cases within twenty years) in a rather off-hand way. One must agree with him, however, that on principle it is an act of war or nothing. Finally, we may point to Mr. Hall's not infrequent criticism of the Continental writers as full of excellent and profitable instruction. 42 LAWS OF NATURE AND LAWS OF MAN. [ll 11. LAWS OF NATURE AND LAWS OF MAN. The nature and extent of the analogy between laws in the strict or political sense, and the uniformities in the course of physical events which we call laws of nature, have often been discussed. Blackstone and earlier writers pressed the comparison with rhetorical inexactness, which has been rebuked by the later analytical school with some excess of severity, as if the likeness were merely verbal and misleading. Early in this century the correction was more modestly but not less effectually made by Black- stone's editor Christian. " In all cases," he says, " where it " (the word law) " is not applied to human conduct, it may be considered as a metaphor ; and in every instance a more appropriate term may be found When we apply the word law to motion, matter, or the works of nature or of art, we shall find in every case that, with equal or greater propriety and perspicuity, we might have used the words quality, property, or peculiarity." Still the resemblance, notwithstanding all criticism, is a real one. The laws made by princes and rulers aim with more or less success, though never with perfect sue- Il] LAWS OF NATURE AND LAWS OF MAN. 43 cess, at producing uniformity of conduct witliin tlie field of action to which they apply. We observe in the course of nature uniformities which are constant. This constancy, compared with the partial and un- certain obedience given to human ordinances, has in all times presented itself to men as the perfect fulfil- ment in another region of that which the lawgiver can only strive to attain. By laws we can, more or less, make men behave in particular ways ; the con- straints of express enactment or customary rules are sufiicient to some extent, but not altogether, to deter- mine their acts and forbearances. But the powers of nature always behave in the same ways, and this readily suggests to our mind a constraint which is always present and always efficient. Seed-time and harvest, the changes of the moon, the courses of the stars, come round without fail. Thus it would be mth men's actions if the law were always obeyed, and therefore we seem to see in nature a law more perfect than man's because never broken. In some such way as this the phrase "laws of nature" has come into common use, and in the practice of modern writers almost any general proposition in any branch of science may be called a law. That this manner of speaking should come to be regarded as containing an explanation of the facts is but one of innumerable instances of the tyranny constantly usurped over man by his own creatures — words. But in following this track of resemblance we have introduced unawares an important difference. At first sight the laws of nature seem to differ from those of man only in being 44 LAWS OF NATURE AND LAWS OF MAN. [n inviolate ; and their excellence in this respect is indeed a not uncommon topic of natural theology. But, when we consider it more curiously, the distinc- tion is one of kind. The laws of nature are not more excellent than Acts of Parliament, but belong to another category. Christian has expressed the point as well as anybody: "When law is applied to any other object than man, it ceases to contain two of its essential ingredient ideas — namely, disobedience and punishment." A law of nature is obeyed, as we say, because there is no room for disobedience. In the case of laws in the proper sense, the law is one thing and the obedience — or, as it may be, disobedience — of any man subject to it is another thing : in the case of a law of nature there is no such difference. Human statutes, and even divine ones according to the majority of theologians, are commands addressed to agents who may or may not follow them. Their object is a certain uniformity, but the uniformity does not necessarily ensue. Nay, the law would still be a law if no single person obeyed it on any one occasion. But a law of nature is inseparable from uniformity ; or rather it is the uniformity itself. These considerations are such as by this time are pretty familiar to students of jurisprudence. Men of science have hitherto not troubled themselves much with the question, or at any rate have not added any- thing to the legal view of it. As to the attempts of philosophers who were neither men of science nor lawyers to clear up the general notion of law, they are best left in charitable silence. But lately Pro- Il] LAWS OF NATURE AND LAWS OF MAN. 45 fessor Huxley, in his admirable introduction to Messrs. Macmillan and Co.'s series of Science Primers,^ has brought a fresh and powerful scientific mind to bear upon this ancient comparison or metaphor, and shown once more that no subject is too worn to be put in some new light. His paragraph on " Laws of Nature " is quite short, and a considerable part of it may be given in his own words : — When we have made out by careful and repeated observation that something is always the cause of a certain effect, or that certain events always take place in the same order, we speak of the truth thus discovered as a law of nature. Thus it is a law of nature that anything heavy falls to the ground if it is unsup- ported. . . . But it is desirable to remember that which is very often forgotten, that the laws of nature are not the causes of the order of nature, but only our way of stating as much as we have made out of that order. Stones do not fall to the ground in consequence of the law just stated, as people sometimes carelessly say; but the law is a way of asserting that which invariably happens when heavy bodies at the surface of the earth, stones among the rest, are free to move. The laws of nature are, in fact, in this respect similar to the laws which men make for the guidance of their conduct towards one another. There are laws about the payment of taxes, and there are laws against stealing or murder. But the law is not the cause of a man's paying his taxes, nor is it the cause of his abstaining from theft or murder. The law is simply a state- ment of what will happen to a man if he does not pay his taxes, and if he commits theft or murder ; and the cause of his paying his taxes or abstaining from crime (in the absence of any better motive) is the fear of consequences which is the effect of his belief in that statement. A law of man tells [us] what Ave may expect society will do under certain circumstances ; and a law of ^ The title of the book is Science Primers : Introductory, which is an awkward one to quote. 46 LAWS OF NATURE AND LAWS OF MAN. [n nature tells us what we may expect natural objects will do under certain circumstances. Each contains information addressed to our intelligence, and, except so far as it influences our intelligence, it is merely so much sound or writing. While there is this much analogy between human and natural laws, however, certain essential differences between the two must not be overlooked. Human law consists of commands addressed to voluntary agents, which they may obey or disobey; and the law is not rendered null and void by being broken. Natural laws, on the other hand, are not commands, but asser- tions respecting the invariable order of nature ; and they remain laws only so long as they can be shown to express that order. To speak of the violation or the suspension of a law of nature is an absurdity. All that the phrase can really mean is that, under certain circumstances, the assertion contained in the law is not true ; and the just conclusion is, not that the order of nature is interrupted, but that we have made a mistake in stat- ing that order. A true natural law is an universal rule, and, as such, admits of no exceptions. Professor Huxley, it will be seen, fully recognizes tlie difference insisted upon by Bentliam and bis fol- lowers in this country ; and on tbat point we do not see how his exposition can be bettered. We can only rejoice that truths which down to our own time were ignored or imperfectly apprehended by the majority of learned men are now presented in clear, simple, and forcible language to every one who sets about acquiring even the rudiments of scientific training. There is some novelty, however, in the similarity between natural and political or civil laws, which is pointed out in the middle section of the passage we have quoted ; and we may find here some matter for further reflection. Professor Huxley assigns uni- formity of action as the common element in our conception of laws proper and of the so-called laws of Il] LAWS OF NATUKE AND LAWS OF MAN. 47 nature, but he assigns the uniformity of law properly so called to an unaccustomed place. He refers our impression of uniformity not to the effect of laws in so far as they are observed, but to that which happens if they are broken. Not in the action of the citizen who obeys, but in the action of the State which pun- ishes the disobedient, we are to perceive the analogy to the certain and constant operations of nature. This is not only ingenious, but seems to fall in very well with the doctrine of our analytical school, which, as all students know, lays peculiar stress on the sanc- tions of positive law. Moreover, there is a consider- able show of convenience for it. There is in any case no perfect uniformity to be discovered in human positive law. But on the common view the excep- tional cases will be all cases of disobedience ; on Professor Huxley's view they will be only those cases of disobedience which escape punishment. And thus there is a decided gain in the apparent closeness of the analogy. But we have to consider how far it can be rightly said that " the law is simply a statement of what will happen to a man " if he disobeys it. And it is to be observed in the first place that, however true this may be for the analytical inquirer, it is not the manner in which the law is actually regarded for any practical purpose ; except, perhaps, criminal law, which is not safely to be taken as the type of f>ositive law in general. Honest men want, as a rule, to know enough of the law to conform to it in their dealings ; but, inasmuch as they have no intention of breaking 48 LAWS OF NATURE AND LAWS OF MAN. [ll it, do not want to know the exact consequences of a breacli. Hence the historical account of the com- parison which would be required by Professor Huxley's explanation seems less probable than that which we have given above. Further, the " statement of what will happen " is by no means a simple one, for its truth depends on several conditions. The sanction will take effect if the wrong and the wrongdoer are discovered, and if there is no miscarriage in any part of the proceedings, and if the law is honestly ad- ministered. And all these conditions are, or may be, material : the last of them, happily, need not be con- sidered in England ; but there are many countries where it is otherwise. In the last year or two we have been repeatedly told that many wholesome laws are nominally in force in Asia Minor, which only need to be put in real use to make the condition of the people, if not the best that might be, at least much better than it is. But then these laws are not statements of what will happen : they are statements of what does not happen, and was never seriously expected to happen by persons who knew the secrets of Turkish government. In the southern provinces of Russia the law presumably forbids Rus- sians of the orthodox Greek persuasion to plunder, ravish, and murder their fellow-subjects, and not the less so that the sufferers may happen to be Jews. Yet the people of several Russian towns and villages have been doing all these things openly, as we hear, to their Jewish fellow-subjects; and we do not hear that the criminals have been punished, or that any serious Il] LAWS OF NATURE AND LAWS OF MAN. 49 endeavour has been made to punish them. In our own country there have been many penal statutes which were not in any natural sense statements of what would happen to persons contravening them ; for they have been habitually neglected and contra- vened to this day, and nothing whatever has happened to the transgressors. This is true even of some modern and apparently rational enactments, such as that against the conveyance of voters in boroughs. Again, it seems far-fetched to heighten the analogy between laws proper and laws of nature by saying that " the law is not the cause of a man's paying his taxes." Surely it is at least a causa sine qua non, for without it why should he pay them, or how could there be taxes to pay ? To take a concrete instance, it seems not easy to deny that the Elementary Educa- tion Act — that is, the will of Parliament as expressed by the Act — is the cause of school boards being elected and of householders paying school rates. No doubt law, so far as it takes effect by reason of its sanction, is effectual through the belief of the subject addressed that the threatened evil will follow in case of disobedience. But the belief or assertion that the threatened evil will follow is not the law itself: it is an inference from the law taken with its circumstances. In itself, the law is, from the assumed point of view, a command coupled with a threat. The probability that the rulers issuing it will make their threat good — which may depend on their power, or on their will, or both — must be ascertained by other means of information. Strictly the law tells us E 50 LAWS OF NATURE AND LAWS OF MAN. [n only what the State professes that it will do ; and in well-governed commonwealths this will coincide, sav- ing inevitable accidents, with "what we may expect society will do." But the two things are not identical. On the ground taken by Professor Huxley, the nearest counterpart to a law of nature in the scientific sense would seem to be, not the enactment or decree of a sovereign power in itself, but a statement of its con- tents (say in a collection of statutes, or in an exposi- tion by a text-writer), coupled with the tacit assump- tion that the law can and will be enforced. Again, the amount of uniformity which is actually presented by the working of human laws depends in great measure on something not immediately connected either with the character of those laws as commands, or with the punishments denounced on men who dis- obey them. We mean the following of precedent. This is a mark of law which is perha23S as important as any. We should hardly give the name of law to a series of unrelated and inconsistent commands, en- forced by arbitrary and uncertain methods, although their subject-matter might be the same as that of the kind of laws we are used to. The capricious orders of a crazy despot may be laws according to Austin's definition until they are revoked ; but if so, it is the worse for the definition. In any case the law of civilized countries, as we now find it, is to a great extent founded on precedent. In the English system, which prevails, with few exceptions, throughout the British dominions and the United States, the prece- dents are furnished by the recorded decisions of judges Il] LAWS OF NATURE AND LAWS OF MAN. 51 on questions which have occurred in actual litigation. In the system of the Eomau ]aw, which prevails on the Continent of Europe and in the settlements and possessions of Continental Powers, the precedents con- sist of the opinions of distinguished lawyers and text- writers on questions which may or may not have come before them in a practical way ; to which, according to the modern practice of several countries, judicial decisions are added, but not so as to have any greater authority than the best opinions. The differ- ences between the two systems are important ; but at present we are not concerned to pursue them. They agree, however, in this, that they look for guidance in new difficulties to the treatment of similar difficulties in past times. The manner and degree of their observance of precedent are diverse ; the general character is the same. And it is an observance also largely met with in those parts of the conduct of life which have a formal and quasi-legal character, such as the proceedings of legislative and executive bodies, public meetings, and committees. Of actual cere- monies we say nothing, as their history is distinct. In modern times they have mostly become parts of some order or discipline which is directly or indirectly under the sanction of positive law ; and then the necessity of observing them is for the persons con- cerned simply the necessity of obeying the law. But ceremonies are doubtless earlier than any laws, and the influence of ceremonial ideas and habits on ancient law is a subject of which the importance is already apparent, and on which there is probably still much 52 LAWS OF NATUEE AND LAWS OF MAN. [ll to be learnt. So long and in so far as ceremonies exist independently of law, their safeguard is the supposed necessity of performing them exactly at all points in order to obtain a desired benefit or avert a dreaded misfortune. At this day the regard for precedent which pervades not only the law itself, but every de- partment of life that has become coloured by legal ideas, appears to us a thing requiring explana- tion. And very fair and reasonable explanations are forthcoming. Not to neglect the results of our pre- decessors' experience in a like matter is easily admitted as the plainest counsel of common sense. Nor is it difficult to see the advantage of applying this most general rule with a certain artificial nicety for par- ticular purposes. Other things being equal, that conclusion is most probable which has been arrived at upon the fullest discussion and ripest consideration. Thus the decision of three or four judges, after careful argument and time taken to prepare the judgment, is manifestly of more weight (assuming no great dis- parity of abilities) than that of a single judge who has to make up his mind on the spot. Hence the gradation of authority in our English system of judi- cial precedents may be rationally as well as practically justified. And on most questions aff"ecting action we feel that the judgment of a competent and adequately informed person on a question of the same or a like kind is a considerable help to shaping our own course. This is in part, perhaps, because the reasons and motives of conduct in any but the simplest afiairs can ir] LAWS OF NATURE AND LAWS OF MAN. 53 but seldom be fully expressed ; so that there is really niore to be learnt from a prudent man's actions than from the reasons he or any one else can give for them. This and much more is to be said for respect for pre- cedent on the ground of reasonableness. Then on the ground of convenience there are divers aro-uments of weio^ht. If it is known that a decision once arrived at will be followed in the like case in time to come, the uncertainty of men's affairs is diminished, and occasions of dispute taken away. The same questions must not be agitated for ever : interest rei puhlicae ut sitjinis litium is a good maxim for standing causes of litigation as well as for every lawsuit in particular. And on this head also it would be easy but superfluous to enlarge. There is yet another ground of convenience which may seem at first sight of small account, but which is greater than it seems. Two sorts of cases present much difficulty of choosing on principle what to do : those where the choice is between two or more ways of doing the same thing which are in themselves indiflerent, and those where the question of substance is such that no per- fectly reasonable solution seems attainable. The rule of the road may be taken as an example of the first class ; the treatment of contracts concluded by corre- spondence as an example of the second. Yet some- thing has to be done ; and, the choice being once made, it becomes natural for the saving of trouble and perplexity to do the same thing, or as nearly as may be, when a similar case recurs. The fact of having taken a particular course once will of itself 54 LAWS OF NATURE AND LAWS OF MAN. [ll determine a certain tendency to follow it again if the conditions are repeated. In the same way the ex- perience of a thing having been done by others will, on a renewal of the circumstances, give rise to a cer- tain expectation of its being done again. This is a general fact of human nature, included by psycholo- gists in the statement of what is called the law of association. Thus a single instance makes a pre- cedent, and the precedent tends to confirm itself by repetition. It seems not unlikely that this is the manner in which the ideas of precedent and custom are origin- ally formed. What has been done once is done again, not because it seems the best thing to do, but because there is an unreasoning tendency to do it, which in the absence of other and stronger motives will pre- vail. The more often it is done the stronger will be the expectation of its being done yet again on the next occasion, and this will at length become a sense of necessity. No words are needed to prove that even the most freethinking of mankind are to a great ex- tent the slaves of habit ; and ancient customs and customary laws are a special kind of habit produced in times and circumstances excluding reflection and criticism. Nevertheless men begin to ask for at least the show of reasons at a very early stage of social growth ; and a merely verbal show being in those stages enough, the thing is readily made to explain itself. A man ignorant of the arts of exact reasoning, and feeling in himself the impulse to do what he has done before, need have no difficulty in accepting as Il] LAWS OF NATURE AND LAWS OF MAN. 55 the suflScient foundation of a custom the fact that it is accustomed. It is the familiar and natural thing, therefore necessary and right. " Our fathers have always done so," is the standing reply to the inquiries of astonished travellers, or of the bolder minds which may appear in the tribe itself. And it may well seem conclusive to a mind which has not learnt to dis- tinguish the expectation that the future will resemble the past from the use of experience as a guide to deliberate action. The will or ought of natural sequence is confounded by this untutored contem- plation with the ought of rational conduct and ethical duty. Another point is to be noted in the psychology of custom, which may be of some importance. We think of customs as established by long use, and in a lawyer's idea of custom this is a vital element. But this is because we have learnt how great are the dangers of error if we conclude from solitary or few instances either as to relations of cause and ejBFect or as to the convenience of a particular course of action. There is no reason to suppose that when society was in its infancy mankind were troubled with any such scruples. If we may draw inferences from the child- hood of the individual to that of the race, one or two instances probably sufficed to make a good custom for our prehistoric ancestors. It is notorious that young children will appeal to precedent in support of their requests almost as soon as they can frame a coherent sentence. They will allege, if they can, the leave of a competent authority as already had, as by offering 56 LAWS OF NATURE AND LAWS OF MAN. [ll such a plea as '' Mamma lets me do it " to a father's prohibition of sports threatening danger to the child or destruction to furniture. But if the authority referred to turns out (as generally happens) not to support the argument, the child's artless cunning falls back on the defence of bare precedent. " One day I did it," or words to that effect, are brought out wdtli an air of perfect seriousness and confidence ; and, though the plea is overruled, it is at least doubtful whether the pleader is intellectually satisfied. It may be suspected that we have in these involuntary revela- tions of infant logic the true primitive form of the universal argument of archaic conservatism. "One day I did it " is the simple and undisguised statement of the mental process more plausibly expressed by children of larger growth in the shape of " our fathers have always done so." The child is father of the man in more ways than have yet been observed with ade- quate care ; and the study of children's ways and language has not improbably a considerable part before it in the psychological researches of the near future. In connexion with the subject now under our view it would be interesting to note the earliest age at which the sense of justice becomes distinct. "We mean not merely the sense of rightness or wrong- ness in particular actions, which may be acquired in very tender years, but the conception of a constant and even rule to be applied without respect of persons. Much will depend on the training and example given by parents. A child weakly and capriciously dealt with must be slower in forming the notions of right Il] LAWS OF NATURE AND LAWS OF MAN. 57 and justice than one brought up in a firm and equal discipline ; and the belief that justice is due to child- ren as well as to adults is still, unhappily, far from universal. But we suspect that even under the most favourable circumstances the idea of justice, in the specific and proper sense, is of relatively tardy growth. Now, turning back to the consideration of what are called laws of nature, we may observe that nature presents to us, even more than the image of command always obeyed, that of precedent invariably followed. The analogy to human laws in their modern or statutory sense, as express commands prescribing particular things to be done, is the product of a rather advanced stao^e of reflection. "Whatever its value may be (and I am free to confess that I do not rate it highly), it is artificial. The analogy to human law in its ancient or customary form is both closer and more obvious. And to early observers the uni- formity of nature, so far as it was ascertainable with their means of observation, would in no way seem to be in contrast with human conduct, such as it was or ought to have been according to the standards of conduct they were familiar with, but would rather offer a singular harmony with it. Anthropomorphic interpretations of the common phenomena of nature would seem not less but more probable by reason of the phenomena being periodic and fairly constant. The works of man's hands wait upon the seasons of the year, and are fulfilled with their due and accus- tomed ceremonies ; and man, looking out from him- self into the world, finds custom and solemnity in the 58 LAWS OF NATURE AND LAWS OF MAN. [n world and the seasons themselves, and carries them into his early speculations on the unseen rulers of the world. Whoever reads Homer with his eyes open will find that the Gods on Olympus are ruled by custom and prescription almost as much as the host of the Achaians before Troy. Zeus is the father and master of the house ; his might is boundless, or almost boundless ; but there are bonds which even he must not break. It is not that the power fails him. He is tempted to break the fate of his son Sarpedon, but he is restrained by Hera's rebuke. The deed might be done, but would be lawless and of dangerous example. And as they are capable of communion and kindred with mortals, the Gods also have their share in men's custom and law. Poseidon takes up the feud of his son Polyphemus against Odysseus, and as between the Gods themselves Ares owes the adulterer's fine, or rather ransom, to Hephaistos, and is released only when Poseidon becomes surety for him. They are the protectors of human justice, too, and Zeus sends the great rain -floods in his wrath when men of violence sit in the marketplace and judge crooked judgment, not regarding the word of the Gods.^ But they are not the authors of justice and law ; the rules guarded by their power are their laws only in the same sense as, in the theory of English legal writers, the immemorial common law which the king's courts administer is the king's law. To a Greek mind in the Homeric age, and probably much later, the reign of law was the same, or nearly the same, in nature and 1 II. xvi. 386. ll] LAWS OF NATURE AND LAWS OF MEN. 59 in man. On the one hand the course of nature was transfigured by anthropomorphic imagination ; on the other hand the freedom of human action itself was but slight in comparison with the bond of custom and the universal constraint of fate, beyond the G-ods themselves, which formed the mysterious background of the universe. The clear separation of the laws of nature from the laws of man was reserved for a time when many more generations had received the dis- cipline of science and philosophy. We who are in possession of the modern analysis shall do much amiss if, like some of its expounders, we despise our fathers for not having known better. 60 SOME DEFECTS OF OUK [ill III. SOME DEFECTS OF OUR COMMERCIAL LAW. I. INVOLUNTAEY LEGISLATION". AVho makes the laws of England ? The question seems an elementary one, and most people would be ready to answer off-hand, — the Queen, Lords, and Commons. Those who at any time in the course of their studies have entered into the labours of Ben- tham and Austin may consider the matter more deeply, and answer that Parliament indeed makes law, but the judges make it — and sometimes unmake it — also. But we are not yet at the root of things. The judges are causa proxima of the law settled by their decisions, but not causa efficiens. They cannot lay down anything of their own motion. A judge may write a legal book ; but, however much better it may be than another man's book, it is equally power- less to make a binding rule for future decisions. The Courts can expound the law with authority only upon the occasions given to them when the judicial machi- nery is properly set in motion. So then we may say that as cloth is made by the weaver, though the machinery of the loom is beyond his comprehension. Ill] COMMERCIAL LAW. 61 the part of our law which we call " judge-made " is really made by the people who start and keep going the processes of litigation. These people, it is need- less to say, are the suitors. It is also needless to say that the declaration and amendment of the law, so far as it is effected by judicial decisions, is effected at the suitors' expense. The weaver is paid for making cloth, but the suitor pays for making law. So far as this expense enures to the benefit of the public by making the law more certain, it might seem that the suitors are unjustly charged with it. A man may well think it hard to be first led into difficulties by the imperfection of the law, and then made to pay for mending it. For these and other reasons certain benevolent persons have proposed that the State should pay the costs. This, however, is open to various objections. Besides such obvious ones as the danger there might be in the temptation of going to law at our neighbours' expense, there is the reflection that to call in the State here is to call it in at the wrong end. We should make the public pay extra- vagantly for results that might have been far better and more cheaply secured by other methods. The State can and ought to do something for the relief of suitors, not by relieving particular suitors from the consequences of litigation, but by diminishing the necessities for litigation arising. This appears a commonplace proposition, yet it is certain that it is by no means generally appreciated. An ancient traveller relates that in a certain land of the Ethiopians there was a much frequented high- 62 SOME DEFECTS OF OUR [ill way, parts of which were smooth and firm, others broken and full of holes, or encumbered with heaps of stones. And he marvelled much at the fashion of the road, all men using it for their occasions to and fro, and the land being in no wise barbarous, but full of wealth, and not lacking discreet men. So he looked more narrowly, and perceived the custom of the high- way to be such, that when a man fell in one of the holes he must call the watch to help him out and make the road good. Which being done, and having paid the watch for their pains, he would go on his way rejoicing (as best he might, for they often had shrewd knocks), that in time to come no other man would fall into the same hole, at least not the self- same way. But where the road was exceeding broken, and there were many that fell and cried out, there would come with no little ado the posse comitatus, or so many of them as could be spared from bear-baiting, ringing swine, and other weighty matters, and would go to work to mend it ; yet in such sort that, being in haste, and for the most part but middling work- men, casting in stones and rubbish without order, a shovelful here and a barrowful there, it was an even chance but they did mar as much as they mended. So that the traveller fell again to marvelling, not that the road was not better, but that any part of it was not worse. Then he spoke with certain of the ancient men, and finding them wise and of civil conversation, said that in his poor judgment it should be to the great relief of the wayfarers' estate, and the saving of many grievous losses and hurts and spoiling of good Ill] COMMERCIAL LAW. 63 men and cattle, if order were taken once for all to repair and keep repaired the common highway at the common charges of the inhabitants ; which, moreover, was no new device, but a thing already seen and approved for the good effect thereof in most nations of any repute for policy and government. But the men were amazed at his discourse, and took it much amiss, jDrotesting that such new-fangled schemes were clean against all their experience and practice, extra- vagant in cost, and, for aught that appeared, ruinous in consequence; the undertaking too great for any man's skill, and the end beyond any man's foresight ; whereas, the matter standing as it did, they were sure at least of this, that the road would be mended where it most needed mending. The people of England — and especially men of business — inhabiting a country second to none in power and resources of every kind, yet walk every day on a road strewn with open pitfalls, which remain open merely because it is nobody's business, until the mischief is done, to see that they are filled up. The security of the commonest transactions of life, much more of the vast and complex operations of commerce, rests ultimately on the civil law. The interests in- volved are assuredly not less in England than else- where. Yet England is the one country in Western Europe where it is most difficult for a man who is not a lawyer by profession to have any clear notion of the laws he lives under, and where the chances are greatest that matters of serious importance will turn out to be provided for inadequately or not at all. It is quite 64 SOME DEFECTS OF OUR [ill possible, but hardly relevant to our present necessities, A to give an historical explanation of the manner in which this state of things arose and has been con- tinued. A question of more practical importance is how it comes to pass that our existing condition is after all so tolerable as it is. That we do bear with it very patiently there is no doubt; for few tasks have been found less hopeful by those who have tried it than to awaken any strong general interest in plans of systematic law reform. The reasons for this are various. In the first place, the evil is one that does not touch the bulk of the middle classes. The common run of litigation involves no doubtful law ; much of it does not even involve any dispute of facts. More than half the actions brought in the Common Law Divisions are not defended at all, and those which run their full course to trial are but a fraction of the remnant. It is but a fraction of these, again, which come before the judges on points of law. Thus the grievance arising from the cumbrous, confused, and unorganized condition of our laws is not one of those which are felt as a galling pressure widely spread over the commonwealth, and are shaken off by popular indig- nation. When it does strike it strikes heavily, but the strokes fall now and then and here and there, and there is nothing to fix public attention that way. Some conspicuous case of hardship may make a stir for a while, but it passes off* and little or nothing is done. Again, the' merits of our legal system, or rather of those who administer it, do much to hide its Ill] COMMERCIAL LAW. 65 defects ; the excellence of the workmen prevents us from seeing how faulty the tools are. English judges, after making all allowance for narrowness in technical matters, have, as a rule, been men of strong common sense, anxious to do substantial justice, and to give intelligible reasons for it. Even the social, economi- cal, and political prejudices which have often influ- enced their judgments have been prejudices common to the great bulk of the educated men of their time. Hence it was natural that the common law which these picked Englishmen professed to expound, but really made in the expounding, came to be regarded as something peculiarly English, and providentially fitted to the needs of this country not only in its sub- stance but in its form. The conditions in spite of which such good results could be produced have arro- gated to themselves the merit of producing them. Besides, the^ -standing fiction of case-law probably imposes on the public no less than it did until quite recently upon judges and lawyers themselves. An unsettled point of importance is raised, argued, and decided. The decision commends itself to intelligent men familiar with the subject-matter as just and reasonable. They praise the law which has been declared, but forget that it has in truth been newly made at the expense of the suitors, when it might as well or better have been made beforehand. Not that every possible case can be specifically provided for beforehand. That would require an infinite foresight to conceive it, a language of super- human exactness to express it, and unlimited space to F G6 SOME DEFECTS OF OUR [ill ^^tf^"^ set it forth. But it is none tlie less possible to lay down clearly and in a moderate compass the general rules which are to govern classes of cases. If we got clear and authentic general rules by our present method, the hardship to the parties immediately con- cerned might perhaps be disregarded. But this is just what we do not get, except by a windfall. A few splendid opportunities may present themselves to a judge who, like Lord Westbury, for example, com- bines width of grasp with great logical powers ; but such is not the usual course of things. In the natural growth of our case-law the "ground is covered by degrees with a series of decisions on minor points which nibble, as it were, all round the edges of a large question. The process goes on till some day it is dis- covered that the combination of all these detached operations gives a total result which was not fairly contemplated in any of them, — sometimes one which nobody would think of approving, if the field were still open. Often there is a long time of suspense, during which it is impossible to say with any certainty what the result will be. -^ The completion of any particular branch of the law depends, in short, on the chances of litigation. The litigants who thus play the part of involuntary legislators know little of the honour thrust on them, and certainly set no store by it. Suitors do not refuse compromises, or prosecute doubtful appeals, in order to settle vexed questions for the public good. Ill] COMMERCIAL LAW. G7 J I. ANOMALIES OF LEGAL DEVELOPMENT. Few persons who have iiot made a special study of the law can have any notion of the wonderfully uneven manner in which its growth has proceeded. Law being made in this country mostly through liti- gation, the casual exigencies of litigation determine what parts of it shall be filled up and what left incomplete. The fabric of English jurisjirudence pre- sents to the legal mind's eye a view not unlike the visible fabric of the new Law Courts a year or two ago — here pinnacles receiving the last touch, there walls only rising from the ground. And, what is still more curious, the gaps are by no means confined to the places where one would expect them. An admirer of case-law as opposed to systematic legislation might prophesy beforehand that the natural growth of law- suits in the commonwealth would be accompanied by a process of natural selection, whereby just those points would arise for decision which the convenience of the public then and there required to be decided. The imperfect foresight of a legislator, it may be said, will provide for superfluities and omit necessities ; the spontaneous working of judicial institutions will pro- vide for just the right things and in just the right way. It is needless to enter on a theoretical examina- tion of these expectations, for it is quite certain that "they are not fulfilled. All kinds of curious little questions receive elaborate answers, while great ones remain in a provoking state of uncertainty. Cases which seem about to settle a grave doubt once for all G8 SOME DEFECTS OF OUR . [ill take an unexpected turn and go off, perhaps, on a minute point of practice. Nor is this all. It is the custom of legal text-writers, and to some extent even of judges, to disguise as much as possible the existence of really doubtful matters in the law : there are set phrases and turns of speech which mark to the accustomed reader — but to him only — where the firm ground leaves off. So that altogether the state of laymen wishing to ascertain their rights even in affairs which look as if they ought to be simple is not a little perplexing. The sale of goods is one of the commonest trans- actions of life. It might seem not very rash to guess that the law relating to this transaction is eminently clear and well settled. Such a guess, however, would be wide of the truth. Let us take • a case neither com- plicated in itself nor unreasonably remote from ordinary experience. Goods are sold on credit, and remain in the seller's possession, the buyer undertaking to remove and pay for them at a certain date. The time of credit expires, and the buyer makes default. What is the seller to do ? Surely this is a question which one might expect a civilized system of law not to leave in doubt. But, in fact, it ''is one on which the law is more unsettled than any person not prac- tically acquainted with the subject could anticipate." So Lord Blackburn wrote more than thirty years ago, and his words are to this day as true as they were then. It may be considered certain that the unpaid vendor is not bound to deliver the goods without payment. It is also certain that he is not entitled (as Ill] COMMERCIAL LAW. 69 he is in some otlier countries) to rescind the contract and hokl the goods as owner. One rational course seems to be left, — to resell them at the defaulting buyer's risk. Some fifty years ago the Court of Common Pleas expressed a strong opinion, but was not called upon to decide, that the vendor had this right ; and if the point had then happened to arise for actual decision, it would no doubt have been settled in accordance with justice and convenience. But, as things fell out, it was left open, and the Court of Queen's Bench decided in 1851, and again in 1859, that the unpaid vendor has no such right. According to these decisions, not only must he account to the buyer for the profit, if any, on a re-sale, but the act of re-sale itself is a breach of contract for which he is liable to an action, though, if there is no profit, the damages will be nominal. Nominal damages, how- ever, may be accompanied by very real costs. Is this the end of the tale ? Not yet : about fifteen years ago the Judicial Committee suggested that if the seller gives express notice to the buyer of his intention to re-sell if the goods are not removed and paid for, he may perhaps not be liable to an action. The force of this remark, again, must be tempered by the reflection that the opinions and even the judgments of the Privy Council, though deserving of great consideration, are not actually binding on the Supreme Court in England. Only the House of Lords can speak to English Courts with canonical authority. The wisdom of the Judicial Committee is good for example of life and instruction of manners, but it may fail the English suitor at a 70 SOME DEFECTS OF OUR [ill pinch. This distinction was not long ago illustrated by a case where the Court of Appeal deliberately refused to follow a ruling of the Judicial Committee admitted to be precisely in point. Now take another question, still from the sale of goods, which is also neither of a recondite kind nor unlikely to occur in practice. Is the seller of specific goods deemed, in the absence of express assertion that the goods are his Qwn, to warrant to the buyer that he has a good title to them ? Various old and modern authors — including Coke, who, by inveterate superstition, is regarded as all but infallible — say there is no warranty. Of late years, however, it has been discovered that there is no actual decision to that effect to be found in any book, and the law assumed by most text-writers has had grave doubts cast upon it. One Chief Justice of England has said that the admitted exceptions well nigh eat up the rule ; one Chief Justice of the Common Pleas has very nearly, but not quite, denied in set terms that any such rule exists ; while a few years afterwards his successor acted upon the rule as still existing. During the last ten or twelve years nothing has occurred to throw any fresh light upon the point, and thus we have ample leisure to watch the law in a state of transition, and meditate on the resulting convenience to the com- mercial world. Such is the fashion in wliich the law of England grows when it is left to itself. In British India, where they have not time to enjoy these refined pleasures, they have enacted a new-fangled thing Ill] COMMERCIAL LAW. 71 called a Contract Act, which contains, among other matters, a chapter on the sale of goods, disposing of the foregoing questions, and many others, in some fifty paragraphs. The whole is expressed in language which, without being loose or inaccurate, is perfectly intelligible to any educated man who will take the same trouble to understand it that he does in his own afiiiirs to understand letters or documents which con- cern him. The Anglo-Indian codes are the work of Englishmen, and founded on English law ; the Con- tract Act, I believe, was mostly composed in Eng- land. We are told, however, that what Englishmen have done with success for British India they are incapable of doing for themselves. Codes are only fit for the coarse methods of a rough and ready government administered by civilians, and we do not understand our own blessings. Our adversary may be certainly wrong according to morality and the customs of business, and probably w^ong in law ; but if our purse and patience are limited we shall do well to agree w^ith him at an early stage, comforting ourselves with the possibility that some more enter- prising suitor may extract from the House of Lords, ten or twenty years hence, an authentic, conclusive, and thrice refined exposition of what would have been our proper course if we had know^n, as every English- man is presumed to know, the laws of our country. III. CAPRICES OF LEGAL DEVELOPMENT. Nature loves variety, and the growth of English law, left as it has been to the natural course of litiga- 72 SOME DEFECTS OF OUR [ill tion, is full of varied surjDiises. So far as the ways of nature are thus manifested, she is by no means prodigal in finding distinct answers for questions of practical importance. But her courses are no less precipitate in some directions than they are dilatory in others. There are points not intricate in them- selves, and demanding rather to be settled one way or another than to be settled in the best conceivable way, which are still the subject of lengthened and indeci- sive discussion. There are others of the most delicate kind, and requiring the most careful balancing of different interests, which have been decided not only without adequate discussion, but without any rational discussion at all. One of the vexed topics of com- mercial law, or rather of general law specially in- teresting to men of business, is that of contracts by correspondence. When an offer is made and accepted by post or telegraph, from what point of time is each party bound ? This may, perhaps, be fairly con- sidered one of the questions to which it is more important to have some definite answer than to have the best possible answer. We do not believe, indeed, that in this case it is impossible to find a solution which is just, convenient, and complete ; in fact, the thing is done in the Indian Contract Act. However, the natural evolution of our domestic jurisprudence has been making an answer, with more or less con- sistency of approximation, at various times in the course of the present century, and has at last settled it by a sort of rule of thumb, and against a protest delivered by Lord Justice Bramwell, of whom we are hi] commercial law. 73 yet hardly accustomed to speak as Lord Bramwell in one of his most vigorous and closely -reasoned judgments. Even as things now stand, it is uncertain whether a man who has accepted an offer by letter can or cannot revoke his acceptance by telegraph ; in other words, whether a revocation dispatched after the acceptance, but reaching the other party first, is or is not effectual. The reasoning used in most of the cases points to the conclusion, repugnant as it seems to the common sense and convenience of man- kind, that such a revocation cannot take effect. This is a singularly good example of the kind of difficulty Ijefore which case-law, and advisers with nothing but case-law to guide them, may stand helpless for years together. Eesults of the same kind have been pro- duced in various departments of the law of property by the excessive subtilties and refinements forced upon it, sometimes in the teeth of positive legislation, by the Court of Chancery. The old scholastic ped- antry of the common law was bad enough, but it had the merit of being definite. Courts of Equity, in their attempts to do perfect justice, have produced a system far more rational in principle than that of the common law, and far more minute and comprehen- sive ; but it is also no less artificial, and in recent times has become so overweighted with its own growth that its working is cumbrous and uncertain. The subject is too technical to enter upon here in any detail. But it is well known that a vast amount of property in England, both moveable and immoveable, is held by trustees under wills and settlements, and 74 SOME DEFECTS OF OUR [ill accordingly the beneficial ownership of all this pro- perty consists in what are called equitable as distin- guished from legal interests. It is obviously of some importance that third persons should know how far they may safely deal with the nominal owners of land or investments, and how far they are bound to inquire into the existence of equitable interests which it is not always easy to discover. Questions of a similar kind arise in the frequent case of property being subject to successive incumbrances. The doctrines of equity, however, are still refining themselves, and every new refinement, broadly speaking, tends to increase the perils of purchasers. Add to this that the law of property is of interest to all men and women who have any property worth considering, and ought, therefore, more than any other branch of the civil law, to be plain, direct, and intelligible. It is, in fact, so intricate and confused that not only no layman can understand it, but it is all but impossible even for the experts who do understand it to translate it as it stands into anything like plain English. It must be said, however, that the Court of Appeal has been working hard of late years to bring equity more into accordance with common sense. Let us now find an example or two of the other sort, where justice takes a leap in the dark. The peculiar and harsh rule of English law that freight cannot be apportioned was established without any- thing like sufficient consideration, but is now so firmly settled that in our own time some of our strongest judges have resigned themselves to enforcing it under Ill] COMMEKCIAL LAW. 75 protest. The still harsher and more anomalous rule that a payment made in advance on account of freight cannot be recovered back if the goods are lost, and no freight becomes payable, is derived from an anony- mous and " ill -digested case" (as Lord Chief Justice Cockburn called it) decided in 1683. This "some- what scanty spring," in the words of another judge, has given rise to a current of authority too strong to be resisted — probably too strong even for the House of Lords to withstand ; and thus we are saddled with a doctrine which puts 1:1s at variance with the rest of the commercial world, including the United States, and for which nobody has a good word on its merits. Again, the bankruptcy of a firm of partners raises questions of great difficulty and importance as to the manner in which their property is to be distributed among the creditors of the firm in the partnership business and the private creditors of the partners in their separate affairs. There are two sets of persons claiming in different rights, — the creditors of the firm and those of the individual partners ; there are two funds to be distributed as far as they will go, — the property of the firm and the separate property of the partners. What relation is to be established between the two classes of creditors and the available funds, so as to work out the least unsatisfactory result ? The importance of these questions is self-evident ; their difficulty sufficiently appears from the fact that no two systems of law seem to deal with them in exactly the same way, while the mercantile scheme of administra- tion in such a case is different from any -legal one with 76 SOME DEFECTS OF OUR ["I which we are acquainted. There is one rule in England, another in Scotland, one or more others in France, — for the Codes are silent, opinions not unani- mous, and practice not uniform, — and others again in Germany. We are not here concerned to inquire which of these rules is the best in itself, nor therefore to enter into the description of any of them, but only to observe how the English rule came to be established. It was laid down early in the last century, when the principles of partnership law were still very imper- fectly understood, and with so little consideration that no connected statement of reasons for it is given in any book of authority, and two or three eminent judges, though not dissenting from the rule itself, or suggest- ing any other in its stead, have confessed that it is extremely difficult to find any. Story, the great American judge and jurist, who was usually very mild in his observations on settled rules, criticized this one in unsparing language, and pronounced its foundation to be most questionable and unsatisfactory. An his- torical explanation is not very difficult. The problem arose at an early stage in the growth of our modern commercial law, and it was obviously necessary to deal with it ; this much was perceived, but the delicacy of the task was overlooked. It is a well-known feature of legislation in its cruder stashes to rush at undertak- ings which modern statesmen touch only with the greatest anxiety and reluctance ; and the same is true, in a measure, of judicial law-making. So, in this case, the solution provided was of the roughest kind, and sadly wanting -in that flexible adaptation and precise Ill] COMMEECIAL LAW. 77 refinement of justice which, we have been taught to believe, distinguishes the pure products of case-law from the coarse ejBforts of law-givers. Thus our method of law-making on occasion rather than on system is seen to break down at the very points where most merit is claimed for it. The natural course of decisions provoked by litigation cannot be trusted either to furnish us within any reasonable time with distinct rules for men of business to guide their conduct by in afiairs of importance, nor, when it does produce such rules, to produce them with sufficient deliberation or consistency. The first of these drawbacks is to a great extent inherent in the nature of case-law, and the remedy for it belongs to the province of legislation. The second is largely mitigated by some peculiarities of our legal institutions, and might theoretically be made to disappear. But were it not for the continuous traditions and education of the legal profession, the limited number of tribunals whose decisions are considered to lay down the law, and the subjection of all these to one ultimate court of appeal, not only would the omissions of case-law be perplexing, but its caprices might speedily become intolerable. IV. — DESULTORY LEGISLATION. The institution of law-making by the results of casual litigation having been found from early times to be in various ways insufficient and even incon- venient, the wisdom of Parliament has been from time to time exercised in providing remedies for its defects. The oeneral intention of these measures, if 78 SOME DEFECTS OF OUR [lH we except the cases of distinctly unjust laws passed in moments of social panic, has been for the most part good. Unfortunately it is a discovery of very modern date that there is such a thing as method in legislation itself, apart from the substantial merits of particular enactments. So far as concerns the form of the law, the action of Parliament has given us, instead of undigested case-law alone, a mixture of undigested case-law with no less undigested statutes, the mutual bearings of which it is often very difficult to perceive. In order to legislate in a satisfactory manner upon any given subject, several qualifications are necessary in the law-giver. In the first place, he must know accurately what the existing law on that subject is. He must be no less clearly aware in what respects he is not content with it, and why. He must further have formed a clear conception of the changes in its efi'ect which he wishes to produce. Nor is it enough to have a distinct intention founded on exact know- ledge. The law -giver must also have the skill to express that intention in apt, sufficient, and unam- biguous terms, which shall make his purpose plainly understood, if possible, by those who have to obey the law, but in any case by those who have to administer it. Parliamentary legislation, however, is carried on, with rare exceptions, under circumstances and in a manner which effectually prevent most or all of these conditions from being satisfied. The difficulty of knowing the actual state of the law is on many ques- tions considerable even for experts, and most laymen Ill] COMMERCIAL LAW. 79 do not SO much as know how great the difficulty is. Hence well-meaning and otherwise well-informed men often bring forward proposals which they suppose to be improvements of the law, and which might be so if the existing law were such as they suppose it to be, but which, in truth, are either superfluous or inap- propriate. It is likewise a common state of mind, even among educated persons, to have a sense of dissatisfaction or hardship without attempting to fix in one's mind the real point where things are amiss. And this vague feeling that something must be done, somebody indemnified^ or somebody else made answer- able, is a constant force tending to unconsidered legis- lation. When our crudely formed and more crudely executed intentions fail to bear fruit, as they naturally do, we are apt to think, not that we have legislated badly, but that we have not legislated enough, and so blunders raise up blunders, and the stock increases and multiplies. Technical skill, again, is often below the mark, if not altogether wanting, especially in the amendments which may seriously disfigure the most artistically drawn Bill. In fact, the more artistic the original composition is, the more it will suffer from piecemeal alterations. The kind of skill required includes many elements. First comes power of ex- pressing ideas clearly, which is not so common as many people think. Familiarity with the appropriate technical terms is of course needful, and besides this there should be knowledge of the manner in which the language of statutes is looked at by those who have to interpret it. There must yet be added the 80 SOME DEFECTS OF OUK, [m faculty of scientific imagination which can foresee the various consequences of a proposed enactment in its relations to the various persons and transactions affected by it. We shall offer no insult to the intel- ligence of members of Parliament in saying that most of them are without these special qualifications. Nor is there any expert or set of experts whose business it is to guide or superintend the technical part of legislation. The result is that Acts and clauses are passed to which it is all but impossible to attach a definite meaning, which produce unexpected and absurd consequences, or which, being intended to settle doubtful points, only raise up new doubts in addition to the old ones. Many an Act of Parliament, originally prepared with the greatest care and skill, and introduced under the most favourable circum- stances, does not become law till it has been made a thing of shreds and patches hardly recognizable by its author, and to any one with an eye for the clothing of ideas in comely words no less ludicrous an object than the ragged pilgrims described by Bunyan : — " They go not uprightly, but all awry with their feet ; one shoe goes inward, another outward, and their hosen out behind ; there- a rag and there a rent, to the disparagement of their Lord." The section of the Companies Act, 1867, which was the theme of so much all but barren discussion in the case of Twycross v. Grant, is a fair instance of the dangers we are liable to in this way. The Act itself, as a whole, is a deliberately framed supplement to the principal Act of 1862. But its unhappy 38th section Ill] COMMERCIAL LAW. 81 was somehow foisted in while the Bill was passing through Committee, and in an evil hour was accepted by the Government of the day. It has all the marks of hasty amateur legislation ; it attempts to be com- prehensive by being vague, and succeeds only in say- ing so far too much that nobody can tell how much it really means. It would be easier to tell how much it has cost. The persons concerned in the case of Twycross v. Grant could probably give us an approxi- mate estimate of the fruitless expense, simply in hard cash, which may be set down, to the insertion of this one ill-penned clause. The persons, however, who most keenly feel the difficulties and dangers arising from the fragmentary composition of our modern statute law are the judges. Their complaints on the subject have been many and bitter, and with reason. It is not too much to say that they often find themselves placed by the action of Parliament in the position of ha^dng to interpret the law by mere guess-work. Their task, as Lord O'Hagan once said, " sometimes involves the necessity of har- monizing apparently inconsistent clauses," and making sense of "provisions cast together haphazard by dif- ferent minds differently constituted, and looking to different and special objects without due regard to the harmony of the whole." Well might that noble and learned person express in his judicial capacity the wish for a department " by which Bills, after they pass Committee, might be supervised and put into intel- ligible and working order." But the chance of Lord O'Hagan being able, in his- legislative capacity, to 82 SOME DEFECTS OF OUR [ill assist in the carrying out of any such plan appears to be as remote as ever. It is further to be noted that the vagueness of case-law and the discontinuity of statute-law constantly react upon one another, each confusion making the other worse, so that the whole result is far more than would be given by the simple addition of the two. The so-called Act to amend the law of partnership, passed in 1865, is a very curious example of the manner in which the uncertainty of existing law may cause time and toil to be wasted in needless legislation. The Act was the residuum of a scheme for introducing the French system of companies en commandite ; the Bill, originally due to a private member, was adopted by the Government of the day, and taken charge of by Mr. Milner Gibson, then at the Board of Trade. The law officers (Lord Selborne, then Sir Koundell Palmer, and Sir R. Collier), and other legal members, took part in the debate on the second reading. The debate was fairly well supported, and it was assumed on all hands that the Bill would effect a substantial change in the law. No backer suggested that the change was too slight to be dangerous, nor any opponent that it was so slight as to be superfluous. In the House of Lords the Bill was opposed by Lord St. Leonards, who expressed serious alarm for the trading credit of the country if it were passed. Lord Wensleydale thought it required material amend- ments. Lord Westbury defended the change as salutary and necessary. The Bill was passed and duly became law, and the law so made has become at Ill] COMMERCIAL LAW. 83 various times the subject of judicial consideration. The result of this consideration is the discovery that the Act really adds nothing, or next to nothing, to the law which had been laid down some years before by an important decision of the House of Lords. The Act was meant to do away with the hardship of the unqualified rule that whoever shared the profits of a business was liable as a partner. But that supposed rule (as now appears) was, in fact, abrogated by the decision in Cox v. Hickman, and the Act expressed only a part of the new footing on which the law was thus placed. Parliament intended to produce a sub- stantial amendment of the law, and produced un- awares a stray bit of codification. As an acute and plain-spoken judge has since said, the effect of Cox v. Hickman was not understood at the time. The singular j^art of the story is that the misunderstanding was shared by the law officers of the Crown, all the law lords (two of whom had been parties to the deci- sion in Cox V. Hickman), and, it would seem, the legal profession generally. Whence the moral may be drawn that the evolution of law by the unaided natural process of litigation is an even more subtle and excellent thing than one would imagine, seeing that, as in this case, it may take not less than five years for a leading judgment of the ultimate Court of Apj^eal to be felt in its full eff"ect. It is hardly possible to maintain that our undigested case-law is certain enough for all practical purposes when the wisdom of Parliament itself can be thus deceived on a matter of great practical and commercial importance. 84 SOME DEFECTS OF OUR [ill V. EFFECTS OF PARTIAL LEGISLATION. Legislation under our present want of system is weighted with almost every possible disadvantage of form. Defects of form, however, may be endured, even if we hold that, as a matter of taste and dignity, the Legislature of a great country should endeavour at least to avoid gross faults of workmanship in the composition of the laws. If legislation were intelli- gible when we got it, we might perhaps be content. But it is too often not intelligible even when we get it at its best, unless to lawyers having a special know- ledge of the subject dealt with ; and this, not by reason of the difficulty or intricacy of the subject- matters in themselves, but by the singular entangle- ment of statute-law and case-law, which we shall now endeavour to explain somewhat further than we have yet done. The statutory amendment of the law generally proceeds in this fashion. The common law, not necessarily the old common law of the books, but often some modern judicial development of it, is found inadequate or inconvenient. Parliament thereupon provides a remedy by adding to or varying the ex- isting law in certain particulars. The amended law resulting from this process consists of the former case- law taken together with the statutory addition or variation. The amended Act is framed by persons who know, or profess to know, the exact state of the law as it was before the Act, and it assumes the like knowledge on the reader's part. Consequently it is Ill] COMMERCIAL LAW. 85 intelligible in proportion to the truth of that assump- tion, which amounts to saying that in most cases and for most persons it is not intelligible without a great deal of trouble. The Statute-book would be a real book if the fiction that every one knows the law were a fact. In that case every new statute would be in itself a real and complete piece of information ad- dressed to all persons concerned. But since the fiction is not a fact, statutes composed on the plan above mentioned are a kind of hieroglyphics to the ordinary Englishman. Nor is their reading always an obvious matter even to experts. There is a whole science of interpretation better known to judges and parlia- mentary draftsmen than to most members of the Legislature itself. Some of its rules cannot well be accounted for except on the theory that Parliament generally changes the law for the worse, and that the business of the judges is to keep the mischief of its interference within the narrowest possible bounds. Our modern law of real property is simply founded on judicial evasion of Acts of Parliament, which, however, was of such a flagrant kind as could not take place now-a-clays. This kind of jealousy is by no means wholly extinct ; we do not even say that under exist- ing conditions it may not still be sometimes useful. To return to our immediate subject, the growth of statute law. The Legislature is fortunate if its efibrts are so well considered and so skilfully executed that a single Act is found sufficient to effect its purpose onoe for all. More often the first amendinor Act becomes the subject of interpretation, — possibly of a narrow 86 SOME DEFECTS OF OUR [lH interpretation which defeats most of the real inten- tion. The law as amended and interpreted is dis- covered to need re-amendment ; and upon the fresh amendment the work of judicial interpretation begins again. And so it goes on till we have a series of statutes which to an uninitiated observer raight seem to deal with their whole subject, but are really mere islands scattered in an ocean of case-law. The Factors Acts are a sufficiently good instance of this operation, though probably by no means the stronojest case that could be found. The Acts in question extend over the space 'of about forty years, the latest of them having been passed in the year 1877. The first of them presupposes in the reader an accurate knowledge of the common law, and each of the following ones presupposes, in addition to this, knowledge of the efi'ect produced on it by the fore- going statutory alterations and the judicial interpre- tation thereof The general rule of the common law was that a person dealing with the ostensible owner of goods did so at his own risk. " To make eitlier a sale or a pledge valid against the owner of the goods sold or pledged, it must be shown that the seller or pledger had authority from the owner to sell or pledge, as the case might be." This was subject to an excep- tion in the case of sale in " market overt," which was no doubt a large exception, and may have been in practice a sufficient one, so long as markets were the principal means of carrying on commerce, but which has become of very slight importance by the change of modern habits. Ill] COMMERCIAL LAW. 87 The Courts held, after some dispute, that the em- ployment of a factor does not of itself authorize him to pawn or pledge goods entrusted to him ; nor did the possession of documents of title give him any further power in this respect, the principle of the common law being that such possession could have no greater value than the possession of the goods them- selves. Such a state of things being intolerable under the conditions of modern commerce. Parliament went to work to mend it. The Factors Acts of George IV. enabled persons " entrusted with " documents of title to make valid sales or pledges of the goods to persons dealing with them in good faith. Power to sell, but not to pledge, in the usual course of business was also given to agents entrusted with goods. It remained unsafe to make advances on goods, or on the documents representing them, to a person known to have posses- sion of them only as an agent. And it was held, and no doubt rightly, by several decisions both on these and on the later Act, that the agency must be of a kind which would in the ordinary course of things cover a sale or pledge, not an agency totally distinct from a factor's, such as that of a clerk, warehouseman, or carrier. Then came the Act of 1842, which made the power to pledge co-extensive with the power to sell, but did not increase the latter. Consequently an agent entrusted with goods for a purpose unconnected with selling or pledging them, or even an agent for sale who wrongfully retained the goods after his autho- rity had been countermanded, could not make a valid disposition of the goods as against the true owner. 88 SOME DEFECTS OF OUR [m It is not to be supposed that these consequences were immediately or easily worked out ; on the con- trary, they were the fruit of much hard-fought litiga- tion. In some of the cases there was considerable hardship on persons who had advanced their money to apparent owners without any means whatever of knowing their real position. But nothing more was done till the last straw was laid on by the decision in the case of Johnson v. Credit Lyonnais Company early in 1877; a decision, however, which was inevitable whenever the point arose, and was affirmed, after mature consideration, by the Court of Appeal. That case revealed to the public that large and important kinds of ostensible ownership were left wholly un- touched, and persons dealing with them unprotected, by the existing Factors Acts. A dealer who had sold a quantity of tobacco, but had been allowed to keep the dock-warrants, obtained an advance on the war- rants from the defendant company, who knew nothing of the sale. The seller absconded, and left the buyer and the company to settle it between them. It was impossible to maintain that the seller was a factor or agent entrusted with the dock-warrants by his pur- chaser ; yet the hardship was exactly the same as if he had been. Thereupon the amending Act of 1877 was passed, which supplied this casus omissus and one or two others. We shall assume that the law is now left, so far as regards the substance of it, on a satisfactory footing ; our purpose being only to call attention to the curious fashion in which it has been done. We have four Ill] COMMERCIAL LAW. 89 separate Acts of Parliament whose effect cannot be "Understood without an elaborate process of reading between the lines. Even to a lawyer they are obscure without a commentary, which is furnished by the elaborate judgments delivered in sundry recent cases. To a man of business they must be absolutely per- plexing. The last Act recites that " doubts have arisen with respect to the true meaning of certain provisions of the Factors Acts, and it is expedient to remove such doubts, and otherwise to amend the said Acts, for the better security of persons buying or making advances on goods, or documents of title to goods, in the usual and ordinary course of mercantile business." The interpretation of this preamble might be as follows : — " Whereas it appears from divers decisions of the superior Courts, and especially from JohnsoD V. Credit Lyonnais Company, that the provi- sions of the Factors Acts are insufficient for the security of persons buying, etc., and otherwise defi- cient in both matter and expression, and it is neces- sary to supply such defects." The facts are, indeed, fresh in the memory of the present generation of merchants and brokers, but twenty years hence the Act will be as great a puzzle to the lay people as its predecessors. The reader will now be prepared to understand how far our so-called Consolidation Acts may be from really consolidating the whole law on the several topics they deal with. 90 SOME DEFECTS OF OUR [ill VI. THE REMEDY. Such is the state of our commercial jurisprudence, and such are its inconveniences ; and they are incon- veniences which the increase of litigation and of reported cases tends, on the whole, to increase more than to diminish. As yet, however, we have done next to nothing to provide against them. An intel- ligent observer not familiar with the w^ays of our Parliament might infer from this apathy that com- petent advisers had unanimously, or all but unani- mously, declared the case to be hopeless. His inference would be natural, but mistaken. The remedy lies straight before us, and has already been applied with success by the majority of civilized nations. It is the statement of the law by the supreme authority of the Legislature, and in an orderly and lucid form ; in one word, codification. If Parliament is afraid of under- taking this, it is afraid of undertaking that which the Italian Parliament, the German Reichstag, and the Swiss Federal Assembly have been doing without fear and without failure for several years past. The honour of the latest achievement of this kind belongs to Switzerland. The Federal Legislature, in exercise of the authority conferred on it by the Revised Con- stitution of 1874, has passed a Code of the law of obligations which will take effect from the beginning of 1883. This code contains a little over 900 sections, and covers (with certain exceptions made for special reasons), the whole ground of the French and German commercial codes, besides more than one topic not Ill] COMMERCIAL LAW. 91 included in tliem. The cliicf exceptions are maritime law, with which Switzerland is naturally not con- cerned, and the contract of insurance, which is reserved for supplementary legislation. The Code has peculiarities of both matter and form, as distinguished from other Continental works of the same kind, which make it specially interesting to Englishmen. In the first place, it does not, like the French " Code de Commerce," or the German " Handelsgesetzbuch," assume a standing distinction between persons in trade and other citizens ; nor are the dealings and lawsuits of traders referred, as in France and Ger- many, to the cognizance of special courts. The view taken by the Swiss Legislature agrees with our own. The framers of the Code thought this division of citizens into classes repugnant to the spirit of Swiss political institutions, and on purely legal grounds use- less and unscientific. Their example and their reasons should be considered by those persons in England, if such there be, who really think men of business would gain anything by having separate commercial courts or a separate commercial code. I am not aware that any competent person has openly advocated in this country the sundering of civil and commercial law ; and one is fain to hope that those who have now and then called for it did not clearly understand what they wanted. The Swiss law-makers have rightly seen that the true commercial code is a code of civil business applicable to the dealings and duties of all citizens alike. Another notable point is that the Swiss Code of 92 SOME DEFECTS OF OUR [ill Obligations is bilingual. It is equally " Bundesgesez liber das Oblio-ationenrecht " and "Code federal des obligations," ^ The German and the French were drafted side by side, and both are equally original and authentic. Any one who has tried his hand at pro- ducino; a correct and idiomatic version of technical propositions in a foreign language can appreciate the nicety of the Swiss codifiers' task. Probably a bilin- gual text, as distinct from an original text with an authorized translation, has never before been produced on such a scale. Here, then, is a grave difficulty of form which the Swiss have overcome in addition to the other difficulties of codification, while we stand help- less before those other difficulties alone. If I may borrow a comparison from Mr. Justice Stephen, it is as if a man who every day carries on a trying and arduous profession should be afraid of ordering his own dinner. The Swiss committee of draftsmen was favoured on the other hand, by some conditions. It included the late Professor Bluntschli, who probably stood at the head of European experts as touching that parti- cular undertaking. There is no reason, however, why an English codifying Commission should not include persons of the like eminence in English law, which indeed has been the case as to the draft criminal code. Again, the Swiss codifiers had the German 1 The law of Obligations, in the Roman and Continental meaning of the term, includes all or nearly all of what an English lawyer would assign to the heads of Contract and of Tort, excepting those torts, such as trespass, which violate rights of property in the strict Ill] COMMERCIAL LAW. 93 commercial code before them as a pattern to be fol- lowed or improved upon. In England we may derive exactly the same advantage from the recent legislation of British India. The Indian Contract Act, which has been law for nearly ten years, embodies English law with only slight alterations, and would furnish us with a considerable ground- work ready made. I do not say that we could adopt the Contract Act, or even most of it, as it stands. Careful criticism and revi- sion would be needful, and a good deal of develoj^ment in some places. But it must be remembered that the object of legislation is not to produce laws of such perfection as to be above theoretical or verbal criticism, which is impossible, but good working laws which shall be substantially just and fairly intelligible. This is possible, and no better reasons than ignorance, timidity, and the extreme cumbrousness of our legis- lative procedure, stand in the way of our doing it at least as well as our neighbours have done. If any one wishes to form a notion of the contrast between what is and what might be, let him, as I have already hinted in this essay, compare the chapter on the sale of goods in the Indian Contract Act with the condi- tion of the same subject in any good English text- book. One thing is certain, in any case, and forms the moral I chiefly wish to point by the foregoing remarks. Nothing will be done for the better ordering of our laws until men of business perceive the importance of it, and are strongly minded to get it done ; nor, what is more, until they make it in one fashion or another 94 SOME DEFECTS OF OUR COMMERCIAL LAW. [ill unmistakably plain to Parliament that they are so minded, and mean to see the thing set about in earnest. Only the workmanship and details of the machinery depend on lawyers. The moving force must come from the men of business themselves. With vigour and good-will it is conceivable that we may not only improve on Anglo-Indian legislation in form, but even overtake its work ; for in India things stand still for the present. It would not become an outsider to dis- cuss the reasons of this ; but I believe they are mostly, if not entirely, connected with the peculiar circumstances of Indian society, and of a political more than of a strictly legal nature. IV] THE LAW OF PARTNERSHIP IN ENGLAND. 95 IV. THE LAW OF PAETNERSHIP IN ENGLAND.^ It will be a reasonable assumption, I think, that those persons who have done me the honour of coming to listen to this paper are more likely to be interested in the practical bearings of the law of partnership in its present condition than in anything I could say about its history or technical development. I shall, therefore, not indulge a taste for historical inquiry on this occasion ; which will not be a very difficult piece of self-denial to practise, as the whole early history of commercial law in this country is exceedingly obscure. Our present law of partnership) is fortunately quite modern, by far the greater part of it having been worked out by the courts within the present century. I say fortunately, because its late origin has secured it an almost entire exemption from the disfigurements and deformities that cling to many other branches of our jurisprudence. The law of partnership was born too late to fall into the hands of judges who were the slaves of a scholastic habit of mind, and could not be ^ A Paper read before the Bankers' Institute, Wednesday, 20th October 1880. 96 THE LAW OF PARTNERSHIP IN ENGLAND. [iv induced by any reasons of expediency to reconsider their narrow principles, or abate the rigour of their still narrower deductions from them. The convenience of mankind and the actual usages of men of business have, on the whole, prevailed in the formation of our modern commercial law, so that the great bulk of it only wants putting into shape to be accepted as satisfactory. This is eminently the case with the law of partnership. I do not mean that it is perfect ; for I think it has one great want, to the consideration of which we shall presently come. But I do mean that it is reasonable as far as it goes ; that it is singularly free from oddities and anomalies, and contains very few propositions, if any, which strike a man of busi- ness as absurd. There is one part of it, indeed, which is still in a somewhat entangled state, namely that which deals with the administration of the assets of an insolvent firm and the separate property of the partners. But this subject is interwoven with the law of bankruptcy, and cannot be practically con- sidered apart from it. We will therefore merely note in passing that the liquidation of insolvent firms — or (since the law strictly knows nothing of the firm) I should rather say the estates of insolvent partners — is governed by a kind of rule of thumb which has been condemned by several high authorities, and for which nobody has yet given an intelligible reason. I cannot find, however, that other nations have been much more successful in dealing with this problem. The Scottish law of partnership is more enlightened than ours on several points, but hardly shows itself IV] THE LAW OF PARTNERSHIP IN ENGLAND. 97 superior on tliis ; nor is there anything like a generally accepted plan on the Continent. In France the law and practice appear to be so little settled that a com- parison with our system is impracticable. In Germany they are still, I believe, more or less various in the different States. Except on this one perplexed topic, to which I shall not return, the English law of part- nership is in substance a creditable production. Being, as I have said, free from absurdities, it has likewise escaped all but scot-free from statutory tinkering, — an operation which has brought some other parts of our law into a confusion bewildering even to lawyers. As to the form of partnership law, it is just the same as that of the great bulk of the law of England ; that is to say, it has no definite form at all. You have to pick out general rules as best you can from the mass of reported decisions, and the remarks of the judges who delivered them, and fill up the gaps and doubt- ful places that remain by more or less probable conjecture. Such is the general nature of the materials we have to deal with. We may now come to the ques- tions which are of practical interest for us at this moment. They may be summed up in two words — consolidation and amendment. Perhaps I may take it as an undisputed fact that a considerable majority of business men would like to have the law of part- nership expressed in a compact and easily accessible form, from which any fairly intelligent person could learn in outline what the rights and liabilities of partners are. In other words, as I am not addressing H 98 THE LAW OF PAKTNERSHIP IN ENGLAND. iv] an audience of lawyers, I may perliaps be dispensed from going over the general arguments in favour of codification, or meeting the objections to it — some of tliem very subtle and curious — wliicli have been made by ingenious persons. I will only say that, notwith- standing all the objections, the people who have already codified their laws even in a rough sort of way seem to have no manner of doubt, after the experience of a good many years, that it was a useful and profitable thiug to do. No country which has enacted complete or partial codes would now think of returning to the old state of things. But in England we shall never get a code, or any chapter of a code, by force of pure argument. We must make it clear that a strong body of persons are interested in the thing being done, want it done, and see their way to doing it. In the case of the law of partnership these conditions are better fulfilled than in any other I know of. The commercial Avorld, which I need not say is a power to be reckoned with in public affairs, seems to have pretty well made up its mind that an authentic consolidation of the law of partnership is desirable. And the law being, as I have said, modern and rational in substance, affords an unusually favour- able field for enterprise of this kind. The points on which there is now any serious doubt are few ; those on which distinct alteration is required are hardly any. Thus. the problem of recasting in a legislative form the effect of the present authorities is almost entirely one of expression. Having tried it myself, I do not pretend that it is an easy one ; but I am sure IV] THE LAW OF PARTNERSHIP IN ENGLAND. 99 it is not iD soluble. I will so far depart from what I said just now as to notice one objection before passing on. Some people ask why digests and abridgments of the law by private writers should not, for all prac- tical purposes, do as well as a code. The answer is that there is an impassable gulf between the two things. When any part of the law is consolidated and declared by Parliament, the words of that Act of Parliament are the law of the land, and if doubts arise upon them it is because the words are ambiguous or fail to meet the particular case. But in the case of a text-book, or digest, or abridgment, however carefully it may be compiled, and whoever the author may be, even if he were at the head of the legal pro- fession, his words are not the law of the land ; they are only the statement of his opinion as to what is the result of the authorities, and his opinion may or may not be followed when a case in point comes before the court. Even if, as in France and on the Continent generally, text-books of a certain standing had an authority co-ordinate with that of actual decisions, the text-writer's authority would still be only one among many. We want, then, to consoli- date the law of partnership by a legislative act ; and we can do it with very little substantial departure from the authorities in which the law is now con- tained. But we have said that there is a great want in the English law of partnership. It needs to be amended, not by changes of a detail here and a detail there in the rules which have been laid down by the courts. 100 THE LAW OF PARTNERSHIP IN ENGLAND. [iV but by supplying this whole missing chapter. The institution of partnership en commandite, or limited partnership, as we may call it in English, is unknown in the United Kingdom, and in these kingdoms alone, or almost alone, among all the civilized countries of the world.^ Probably every one here knows, in a general way, what partnership e7i commandite is ; but it may as well be stated for the sake of clearness. The essence of commandite partnership is the con- junction of at least one managing partner who is liable without limit for the partnership debts, like a partner in an ordinary firm, with one or more contributing partners who do not take an active part in the busi- ness, and are liable only to the extent of what they contribute, or have undertaken to contribute, to its capital. This form of partnership has been known on the Continent for many centuries. The Mediterranean trade of the middle ages was carried on principally by its means. In France Lewis XIV. regulated it by an ordinance of 1673, which has been substantially adopted in the modern commercial code. How it failed to establish itself in England or Scotland I am unable to say: it is not impossible that it was recog- nized by the special tribunals which administered the law-merchant down to the seventeenth century, but of the proceedings of those courts we know hardly ^ The Companies Act of 1867 makes an approach to the French Sociite en commandite par actions, or German Kommandit-Gesellschaft auf Aktien, by authorizing the formation of companies in which the liability of the directors, or managers, or managing director, is un- limited. Neither in reading nor in practice, however, have I met with any instance of such a company being formed. IV] THE LAW OF PARTNERSHIP IN ENGLAND. 101 anytliing. We must also remember that for a long time the foreign trade of England was almost entirely in the hands of Italian or Hanseatic merchants, who did not resort to the English courts of justice when they could help it, but settled their disputes by some domestic procedure of their own. So it was, at all events, that when the law of partnership was formed by modern judges and chancellors, the notion of a partner with limited liability never appeared. Indeed, the tendency of the courts was for a long time to hold that whoever in any way shared the profits of a business must be a partner in it, and liable for all its debts ; and if this tendency had not happily been arrested by the decision of the House of Lords in a leading case, a very serious conflict between the legal and the mercantile sense of justice might have been the result. The North American States which were colonized from England took over English law as the foundation of their jurisprudence in partnership as well as in other matters. Louisiana and Florida, however, not being English colonies in the first instance, have always had the system of partnerships en commandite; and in the course of this century most (I think we may say all) of the other States of the L^nion have naturalized it under the name of special or limited partnership. Thus we are left practically alone in excluding it ; and I think there is a fairly strong presumption that we lose something by not possessing an institution which has been found useful by so many mercantile communities. The economical reasons in favour of limited partnership 102 THE LAW OF PARTNERSHIP IN ENGLAND. [iV are strong, but I do not think it necessary to enter ■upon them at present.^ Not only should I be, if I am not mistaken, preaching to those who need no conversion, but I should go near to commit the graver fault of enlarging on matters which many of my audience understand better than myself. The only part of the question on which I can add much to your knowledge is the technical one. It may not be super- fluous to give my testimony, founded on the actual experiment of drafting a Bill, that the technical diffi- culties of making the commandite system fit in with our existing law of partnership are not of a really formidable kind. Probably some of you know that many attempts to introduce the system have been made in this country, and thus far none have been successful ; and you may reasonably ask why this has been so. So far as I have made myself acquainted with those former attempts, I am disposed to ascribe their failure to two causes, — that the principle of the desired innovation was not always thoroughly understood by its promoters in Parliament, and that, whether in consequence of this or for other reasons, their efforts were timid and half-hearted. It is a vital point in the system that the commanditaire or limited partner is not a creditor of the firm, but a real partner whose liability and powers are limited. He puts a certain sum into the concern, and is answerable only to the extent of that sum ; on the other hand, he has not 1 They may be seen briefly stated iu Mill's Political Economy^ Book V. cliap. ix. sec. 7. IV] THE LAW OF PARTNERSHIP IN ENGLAND. 103 the same rights of taking part in the business as an ordinary partner, but is subject to certain restrictions, of which the details are fixed by the law of the par- ticular country. He is no more a creditor of the firm than a shareholder in a company is a creditor of the company; he no more lends his money to the acting partner than holders of railway shares lend their money to the directors. If you regard him as a lender of money to the firm, who takes a share of profits instead of interest, you altogether confuse the true relation. Unhappily, just this confusion seems to have prevailed in the attempts made in England to procure legislation on the subject. The result has been the so-called Act to Amend the Law of Partner- ship of 1865, which was afterwards found to have added little or nothing to what had been settled without the aid of Parliament by the more recent decisions. The most important section of this Act enables persons to lend money to traders, and receive a rate of interest varying with profits, or a share of profits in lieu of interest, without becoming respon- sible as partners. What happens in practice is that the lender who advances his money for a share of profits is not content to be a passive creditor. Fondly supposing that the Act enables him to assume the position of a partner in everything but liability, he enters into an agreement by which his so-called loan is completely embarked in the capital of the business, and he receives in return most of the usual riohts and powers of a partner as between himself and the nominal borrower. Then, if the business fails, he 104 THE LAW OF PARTNERSHIP IN ENGLAND. [iV finds to his confusion that his excess of caution has put him in exactly the position he wanted to avoid. The Act declares that you may lend money and take a share of profits without being a partner ; but it does not enable you to enter into what is substantially a partnership, and limit your liability by calling it a loan ; and in this way it lures people into the very danger it was intended to protect them from. The case I have stated has nothing imaginary about it ; it is the typical form of several which may be seen in the law reports, and others which have occurred in private practice. One practical conclusion which seems to be justified is that there is a strong demand in the country for some form of true limited partner- ship, for otherwise people would not run so much risk in order to get something as nearly like it as they can devise under the present law. Perhaps it is not without significance that in one reported case the parties actually referred to this Act of 1865 by the erroneous name of the Limited Partnership Act. Moreover, loans under the Act of 1865 are not regis- tered ; and this is complained of as leading to some- thing like fraud on the public, as on the strength of a loan of this kind a trader may with little chance of discovery pass off" borrowed capital for his own, and obtain credit on it. The Act provides, it is true, that the lender who receives a share of profits must be postponed to other creditors in case of insolvency (which, however, may be thought a poor consolation for them if there is not enough even so to pay a sub- stantial dividend to any one) ; and I confess that I IV] THE LAW OF PARTNERSHIP IN ENGLAND. 105 do not see how trading with borrowed capital is to be prevented, so long as lenders are willing to risk their money in consideration of high interest. Still, if we had a recognized system of limited partnerships, there can be little doubt that most people would prefer the position of a limited partner to that of a lender, and that loans under the Act of 1865 w^ould go out of use. At the same time I should myself think it well to put a stop to them formally, by enacting that every loan or agreement to lend money for a share of profits should have the effect of an aOTeement for a limited partnership ; in other words, I would leave no middle term possible between a bare money loan for fixed interest and a true partnership en commandite. Limited partnerships would have to be registered in some way; this, I think, is allow^ed on all hands. And if the Act of 1865 were left as it is, while limited partnerships were introduced, it is possible that the form of a loan might be resorted to in some cases to escape registration ; and these cases w^ould naturally be just those in which registration is most desirable for the protection of the public. On the point of registration, I may observe that in France publicity is given to the number of cominanditaire partners, and the amount of their contributions, but not to their names. The public register only shows that, in ad- dition to the managing and fully responsible partners, whose names are given, there are so many unnamed contributors {hailleurs de fonds) answerable for so much apiece. In Germany, however, and in the United States, the names are put on the register ; 106 THE LAW OF PARTNERSHIP IN ENGLAND. [iV and this last course is the more likely to be taken in England in the event of the commandite system being adopted. At least, it has been part of all the plans yet brought forward, and I am not aware that any one has expressed a preference for the French rule. This brings me to the wider question of registra- tion of firms in general. In the commercial world there appears to be, on the whole, a strong feeling in favour of introducing this in some shape. A Select Committee of the House of Commons considered the subject in 1872, and, after taking the evidence of a considerable number of bankers, merchants, manu- facturers, and other persons familiar with commercial aff'airs, reported by a large majority in favour of registration ; but the report had as much effect as the reports of Select Committees usually have, partly for a special reason which I shall presently mention. Among the witnesses who gave evidence in this sense were Mr. Samuel Morley, the late Mr. Kirkman Hodgson, and Mr. Higley, the general manager of the London and Westminster Bank. On the other hand, it has been suggested that it is easy for people in a large way of business to approve of compulsory regis- tration, as it would cost them no trouble in compari- son with what it saved them ; but that such a measure would be vexatious and oppressive to small tradesmen and persons forming temporary partnerships for what may be called adventures as distinct from permanent business. But the proposal has for many years been under discussion, and I am not aware that any of the IV] THE LAW OF PARTNERSHIP IN ENGLAND. 107 persons who, as it is supposed, would be injuriously affected by registration have in fact made these objec- tions for themselves, But there is one practical difficulty of the gravest kind : the project of general registration has always met with steadfast opposition from the Board of Trade, and has little or no chance of being carried while this opposition continues, Mr. T. H. Farrer, who for this purpose is something more than the official representative of the Board, gave evidence before the Select Committee above mentioned, and explained his reasons for disliking the plan. The objections may be summed up, I think, under two heads. First, compulsory registration of firms in general would confer no positive benefit on registered partners sufficient to induce them to register in their own interest ; and consequently such a law could be made effectual only by penalties which would be vexa- tious and liable to great abuse. Secondly, no official registration would fully satisfy the commercial world. A man of business wants to know not only what persons he is really dealing with, but what their credit is. Now it is evidently impossible for a public department to undertake a register of credit ; it could only keep a register of names, which would give but one half, and the less important half, of the informa- tion sought. Persons and firms who have large deal- ings would still be obliged to keep a sort of private register of credit, as they do now ; and thus the advantage of the public register would not be com- mensurate with the burden and expense. As to the 108 THE LAW OF PARTNERSHIP IN ENGLAND. [iV force of tliese objections I do not feel bound to express any decided opinion of my own, the question being not so much a legal as an economical one. On the one hand, the conveniences of registration are obvious, and it is difficult to see why partners, acting or not acting, in any honest business should in our time find any grievance in the fact being accessible to the public. Nor does the danger of evasion and fraud appear to me very serious ; there would be little temptation to such courses if registration were made, as it easily might be, a simple and inexpensive process, and. sanctioned by certain and moderate penalties which could be enforced without creating a sense of injustice. It has been suggested that men of straw and imaginary names might be put on the register ; but this would hardly be the way to attract confidence, and besides, the making of false and fraudulent returns would be a criminal offence. But, on the other hand, one has a certain jealousy of anything that would bring the legal position of commerce in this country nearer to what it is in most Continental States, where men of business are dealt with as if they were dangerous animals, or at best a sort of creatures peculiarly incapable of takiug care of them- selves ; where, instead of being governed by the same laws as other citizens, they have a commercial code to themselves, and paternal lawgivers prescribe to them how they are to keep their books. In the United States private enterprise has struck out a system intended to secure the advantages of a public register without its drawbacks, and this is said to IV] THE LAW OF PARTNERSHIP IN ENGLAND. 109 answer fairly well. There are three or four mercantile agencies which issue to their subscribers a book recording not only the names of traders, manufacturers, and bankers, but an estimate of their capital and credit.^ It seems that there is no difficulty in obtain- ing full information through these agencies, and that it is almost always trustworthy. Perhaps it would be desirable to try something of the kind in this country ; so far as I am aware, it has been done only very par- tially, and the great houses rely on private inquiries of their own. This, at all events, is an experiment which needs no aid from Parliament, while a general compulsory registration must be regarded for the present as unattainable. Indeed it seems to me that the body of opinion which now exists in favour of registration would not be inadequate, if methodically directed towards that end, to put a pressure on firms to disclose the names of their partners which would practically be as efficient as legislative compulsion. Some firms already print the names of the partners on their letters and invoices. If leading houses not only adopted this practice themselves, but dealt by preference with customers who adopted it, the omission of it would come to be thought disreputable, or at all events a matter for inquiry. Thus we should have a 1 Evidence of Hon. T. W. Park before Select Committee of 1872. But I am told that the working of similar agencies in Canada is not well thought of by English houses who have opportunities of being acquainted with it. And it was mentioned in the discussion which followed the reading of the present paper that the information of the private agencies which exist in England is by no means free from errors, not of opinion, but of simple matters of fact. 110 THE LAW OF PARTNERSHIP IN ENGLAND. [iV self-acting system resting directly on public opinion and needing no new machinery of any kind. If public opinion is not strong enough to do this, I do not think it can be strong enough either to procure official registration or to save it from beins; ineffectual if established. I will just remind you that these remarks do not apply to limited partnerships. Even the strongest opponents of registration in other cases allow that, if there are to be limited partnerships, they must be registered. In this case the difficulty about firms being willing to register does not arise, as registration is the price for which they receive the benefit of limited liability. If a limited firm failed to register, the partners would all be liable as general partners, and this would be quite enough to ensure obedience to the law without any further penalty. Thus much of the nature of the improvements we may desire to see made in the law of partnership. Now let us see how the prospect of putting any of them in execution stands at this moment. This is a matter of which I cannot give you an account without a certain risk of talking too rnuch about my own work. But perhaps the risk is sufficiently warranted by the interest of the subject. Last year, then, I was instructed by Mr. Sampson Lloyd, who sat for Ply- mouth in the House of Commons, and was acting in concert with the Associated Chambers of Commerce, to draw a Bill for the consolidation and amendment of the law of partnership. The objects aimed at were three. 1. To codify the existing law, with the excep- IV] THE LAW OF PARTNERSHIP IN ENGLAND. Ill tion of that part wliicli is involved in tlie law of bankruptcy. 2. To introduce tlie commandite system. 3. To introduce a general system of registration of firms. The Bill was brought in during the session of 1879, but so late that practically nothing could be done beyond getting it printed, and ascertaining that competent persons both in and out of Parliament were in the main favourably disposed. I may mention that the Bill was backed by the present Solicitor-General. This year (1880) it was again brought in under the charge of Mr. Whitwell, the member for Kendal. We all know that the year has been an unhappy one, not only for private members' adventures, but for con- sidered legislation generallyj and the progress this Bill made was, under the circumstances, at least as good as its friends had a right to expect. It attracted the notice of the Board of Trade, and a certain amount of semi-official correspondence and conference took place, in consequence of which it was decided to drop the scheme of general registration of firms, and make some other smaller changes of detail. In efiect, the Bill was resettled in consultation to meet the views of the Board, and, having been read a second time without opposition, was formally committed in order to be reprinted in its new shape. It had been drafted not without a view to some of the innovations having to be abandoned, and the registration clauses had been so arranged as to be easily cut adrift if necessary. Thus the Bill did not sufi'er as a work of art by this operation ; indeed, I think it was rather improved. If time had sufficed, there Avas good hope that it would 112 THE LAW OF PARTNERSHIP IN ENGLAND. [iV pass tlie House of Commons ; it was recommitted, and stood several times on the order of the day ; but there were sundry little delays and hindrances, besides the press of more urgent business, and I believe it never got fairly into committee. But of serious op- position there was nothing or next to nothing ; the one fatal enemy was time. The measure of success attained is partly due, I think, to the Bill being more ambitious than its predecessors. This statement is a paradox only in seeming, as I will proceed to show. The Bill not only innovates but consolidates ; and to oppose a measure of consolidation outright is, at this time of day, a somewhat invidious thing. Besides, this way of framing the Bill makes the draftsman's task much more certain and satisfactory. If you try to piece on an innovation like commandite to the existing uncodified law, you have, as it were, no definite place to start from ; and what is more, your Bill will at best be intelligible only to those who are familiar with the old law. But if you make the Bill in the nature of a code, you expound your old law before propounding your new matter, and so the Bill is complete and intelligible in itself. In this Bill the ordinary law of partnership is first laid down with as little alteration as possible, — and there is very little indeed, only the definition of a few points which are not quite settled at present, — and then limited partner- ship is provided for by defining what a limited partner is, and in what respects his position differs from that of an ordinary partner. In fact, that part of the Bill was constructed by going through the rules that apply IV] THE LAW OF PARTNERSHIP IN ENGLAND. 113 to ordinary partnerships, and expressly negativing those which are not applicable to a limited partner, the others being left to remain in force ; thus carrying out the principle I have already brought to your notice, that a limited partner is nothing else than a true partner in the firm whose liability and powers are limited. The foreign codes were of course con- sulted, but for various reasons were not found of so much use as might be expected : the German is, in my opinion, the best of any. As to registration, I need only say that both in the original and the amended form of the Bill we aimed at the utmost simplicity consistent with efficiency, and we wholly eschewed the cumulative penalties and disabilities which had appeared in some former projects. Altogether the result is far from discouraging, though it would be rash to prophesy final success within any certain time. It is worth remark that this Partnership Bill is a serious attempt at codification by private enterprise, and, so far as I know, the first of its kind anywhere ; at all events, there is no other country where private enterprise is likely to be foremost in such an attempt. If it is ultimately carried, I think the mercantile community will be entitled to feel a certain pride in it. The chances must be measured by judges more disinterested than myself. But perhaps it may be allowable to say that we seem to be not much farther ofi" from a Partnership Act than we are from the much- promised Criminal Code. 114 employers' liability. [v V. EMPLOYERS' LIABILITY. The question of employers' liability for injuries to their servants received in tlie course of their service, and through the default of another person under the same employer, has been settled for the present by the Act of 1880. But the settlement is only a provi- sional one. The Act is temporary, and has now no more than six years to run. As the time of its expiry approaches, discussion of its principles will doubtless be renewed. Criticism of the principles of the sub- ject, and of the law of England as it stood before the passing of the Act, has therefore not lost its useful- ness. The grievance complained of on the part of the workmen was that, whereas an employer was liable to strangers for injury caused to them by the acts or defaults of his servants in the course of their employ- ment, he was not liable to one servant for injury caused by the act or default of another. And the history of this exception is certainly not a favourable one. It appears to be rejected by Continental juris- prudence, and recent legislation in Germany has deliberately increased employers' liabilities in the case v] employers' liability. 115 of railways and other specified industries. In England and the United States it is modern, and in Scotland it was not so much adopted from England as thrust upon the Scottish Courts by decisions of the House of Lords. Notwithstanding its recent origin, two quite different though not inconsistent reasons have already been given for it. In the decision commonly cited as establishing the exception for England it is not easy to see what the reason was, or whether the judges in any way contemplated its extension to great in- dustries employing a numerous staff of managers and servants in many departments and with many degrees of power and responsibility. On the other hand it may be said that the rule itself is an exceptional and harsh one, and cannot be shown to date from an earlier time than the Eestoration ; and in having no warrant of positive legislation it is in no better case than the exception. This topic, indeed, will seem of little im- portance to those who know how much of our law has been settled by judicial discussion and decision within even the last generation or two, and how long many questions of practical interest have remained open. Almost the whole of our commercial law is modern judge-made law, and a great deal of it later than the immunity of employers now in question. The argu- ment from novelty is altogether a dangerous one. If a duty has been but recently affirmed by decided cases, it is easy to say that it was never before disputed ; it is still easier, when an alleged liability is for the first time formally denied, to reply to the charge of inno- vation that such claims were previously unheard of. 116 employers' liability. [v History apart, the broad rule of justice would seem at first sight to be that a man shall answer only for his own faults and omissions, or at most for that which he could have prevented, not for faults and omissions of others which he neither encouraged nor approved. It is said, then, that if on special grounds of public utility a more extensive liability is imposed in some cases, this is an encroachment on common right, and should be rather checked than extended. In this view the distinction between strangers and per- sons in a man's own emj)loyment is the mark not of an exceptional immunity or privilege, but of the point where an exceptional burden ceases to be imposed. This line of objection to any extension of the master's liability is fortified by the high authority of Lord Bramwellj and it is certainly provoked by much of the so-called explanation to be found in the books. It may be said, further, that the rule of vicarious liability is not easy to justify on any rational grounds ; that its actual origin is obscure, but probably belongs to a state of society and habits of mind quite difierent from our own ; and that in the maritime law, where its hardship is unusually conspicuous, it has been found needful to mitigate it by express legislation. But this counter - argument, again, is in danger of proving too much. For the rule is maintained throughout the civilized world, and it appears on the whole to be allowed as just, notwithstanding its accompanying hardships, by the common sense of reasonable men. We hear of a protest only now and then, as when unusually heavy damages are given against a railway v] employers' liability. 117 company, or, as in the special matter in hand, by way of reprisal against attempts to extend the liability still farther. That which most men feel to be just must at least have some element of justice in it. Let us consider, therefore, the grounds on which a master's liability for the acts, neglects, and defaults of his servants in the course of their employment may be explained. It will be understood that the terms master and servant are here used in the widest sense. In the first place, it is commonly said that the master is liable because the servant is his agent : " Qui facit per alium facit per se." But this is a plain begging of the question ; it states the effect of the rule, not any reason for it. We can all understand that a man should be liable for what he really does by another's hand, — for actions which he has authorized or tacitly allowed. But here the question is why he should be liable for actions he has in no way authorized, just as if he had authorized them, — why he should be deemed to have done by his servant's hand things which he has not commanded, permitted, or desired. Often- times the act or neglect for which the master is held to answer is wholly against his interest. It may be such as to involve him in heavy loss, apart from the claims of any person injured. It may be, and often is, something which he has expressly forbidden and done all he could to prevent. Thus, in the very com- monest case, a tradesman sends out his horse and cart, enjoining the driver to go at a moderate pace. The man drives furiously and runs over a foot-passenger. His master is liable. Again, a manufacturer has a steam- 118 employers' liability. [v engine at his works. The engineer is instructed not to let the water in the boiler run too low. He does let it run too low, and an explosion follows. Here too the employer is liable for any damage that results to neighbours and passers-by. If we say to him, " You did this by the hand of your servant, therefore you must pay for it," he will answer, " I neither did it nor meant it to be done ; on the contrary, I charged the man to do nothing of the kind." This first explana- tion, then, is no explanation at all. It is merely an artificial statement of the thing to be explained. There is another way of looking at the matter which may be suspected to count for a good deal in the popular view. A wrong without a remedy is, in theory at least, odious to the law ; but in many cases the law cannot prevent the remedy from being only nominal. It may compel wrongdoers to pay if they can, but it cannot make them solvent ; and it must now and then happen that an injured person has no better comfort at its hands than a right of action against a man of straw. To the popular mind a remedy not substantial is no remedy at all, and a result of this kind is not only unsatisfying (as it must be to every honest man), but unintelligible. Hence there is a natural endeavour to fix responsibil- ity on some one who can pay. In the case of injury suffered through a servant's negligence, the servant, generally speaking, cannot pay, and the master can ; and the feeling that compensation ought to be had somewhere jumps at the master's liability. "Re- spondeat superior " (another question-begging maxim) v] employers' liability. 119 is accepted without ado as a precept of natural justice. It is assumed that the relation of master and servant implies, by some evident and immutable necessity, that the master is to be liable for the servant's acts and de- faults. The servants and the work being his, the liability must be his also. Such a view is too crude and form- less to be a starting-point of fruitful discussion ; yet we must beware of concluding off-hand that under its crudity real and obscurely felt reasons are not strug- gling for expression. Meanwhile we must seek farther. Possibly analogy may help us to circumvent the diffi- culties which appear to beset direct argument. We are considering a rule which imposes liability on men beyond their own acts or defaults. But it is only one particular rule. Equal or greater liabilities are imposed by law in various other circumstances where it is even more obvious that the events from which the liability arises were not under the actual direction or control of the person liable. Most of these cases either fall in their legal classification under the general head of Negligence or belong to a nearly allied class. Thus " the owner of land is bound to keep it fenced ; and if his cattle get into his neighbour's premises, he is liable for the damage done by them, whether the escape was owing to his negligence or not." Similarly an owner or occupier who brings on his land for his own purposes anything likely to do damage to his neighbours, such as.an artificial reservoir of water, must keep it there at his peril. In these cases the obligation is all but absolute ; a man is answerable, though the utmost 120 employers' liability. [v diligence be used to prevent mischief, for everything short of overwhelming and inevitable accident (in technical language, " act of God," or vis major). Again, occupiers of land or houses are bound, not absolutely, but to the extent of reasonable care, to keep their property from doing harm to persons who are there on lawful business with the occupier's con- sent, or passing by in the exercise of common right. Practically the distinction between this duty and the stricter duty in the case of dangerous things is a rather fine one ; for the fact of an accident happening throws on the proprietor the burden of proving dili- gence. Thus a railway company was held liable some years ago for the fall of a brick from a bridge crossing a street, whereby a man was hurt ; there being nothing but the fall itself to show that the bridge had been left out of repair or not sufficiently inspected. This decision has been followed in New York in the somewhat stronger case of a building falling bodily into the street ; where lay common sense will without difficulty accept the remark of the Court that build- ings properly constructed do not fall without adequate cause. The common feature of all these cases is that a special duty is cast on a man, either in respect of his ownership simply or in respect of his voluntary use of his property in a particular way, which goes beyond his own acts or rather is independent of them. Per- sonal diligence alone will not satisfy the legal standard of duty. The owner must at his peril see, as the case may be, that his fields are securely fenced, or his v] employers' liability. 121 reservoir water-tight, or that all proper precautions are taken to keej) his wall in repair. If, to put an easy case, the handrail of a staircase leading to a merchant's office is rotten, and a customer falls over and breaks his leg, the merchant will not clear him- self by showing that he employed an experienced carpenter to mend the rail, and the carpenter scamped the work. In fact, it matters not whether the actual default which is the proximate cause of the mischief proceeds from the owner himself, from his servants, or from a third person employed by the owner, but not his servant. Some applications of this rule come very close to the more special rule of liability for servants' negligence. In 1863 a man passing under a flour-dealer's shop in Liverpool was knocked down by a barrel of flour, which fell from an upper window of the shop. There was no actual proof that the barrel was being lowered by the flour-dealer's orders, or even by any servant of his, or that it was being carelessly done. But it was decided that he was liable ; for "it is the duty of persons who keep barrels in a warehouse to take care that they do not roll out," This is responsibility for servants, and something more : it seems to include taking care that persons who are not one's servants shall not meddle with one's house or goods in a way to endanger passers-by. Thus we have in different circumstances different duties to keep one's property from being the occasion of harm to others, which may be arranged in degrees descending from the strictest. In one class of cases we have responsibility for all events and hazards which may 122 employers' liability. [v not be fairly considered as beyond human foresight ; in another, responsibility for due and reasonable care in the maintenance of a safe condition of things, not merely on the part of the person liable and his ser- vants, but of every one employed by him or aiding him in the performance of his duty to the public ; in yet another, which includes the ordinary cases of employers' liability, responsibility only for the party's own acts and omissions and those of his servants. By taking this as a connected body of doctrine, we may perhaps get some light on the true nature and reasons of the rule of vicarious liability from which we started, and which seems at first sight equally difficult to attack and to defend on any satisfactory principle. II. An employer's liability to strangers for the acts and defaults of his servants does not stand alone in being a duty extending beyond acts and events under the direct control of the person liable. Duties as wide or wider are imposed in other cases. Is there any common element present in all these cases in which a reasonable ground of liability may be discerned *? There seems to be this common point in all of them, that a man has for his own convenience brouo;ht about or maintained some state of thino-s which in the ordinary course of nature may work mischief to his neighbours. Whether his property be cattle grazing in his field or water stored in a reservoir, or a structure crossing or overhanging a public road, there is a certain risk to adjoining owners or to the public which v] employers' liability. 123 necessarily accompanies the state of things so kept up. It is an intelligible principle that whoever thus exposes others to risk should abide the consequences if the risk ripens into actual harm. One could imagine it being applied to the full and unqualified extent of making the owner thus using his property liable at all events, without regard to any question of negligence. He might be made to insure the public against all risks of his undertaking. But such a rule is too harsh and sweeping for modern jurisprudence ; and the general principle of liability is tempered, as we have seen, in various degrees. These degrees are fixed according to the nature of the risk involved. The owner of an undertakinsj dangerous in itself, who thereby creates an extra-hazardous risk for his neigh- bours, — such as the reservoir, which if it burst will inevitably flood their lands, — is held to the utmost diligence ; he must answer for everything but vis major, however careful he may have been. So it may be said of cattle that if they break out it is their very nature to do damage where they stray, and hence the duty to keep them in is of the strictest kind. In England, however, there is some evidence that this duty was once less strictly defined than it now is. But in the case of things not dangerous in themselves, but only likely to become dangerous if reasonable care is not used, reasonable care is allowed to be the measure of the owner's obligation ; and if he can show that all reasonable care has been used, he is discharged. Herein it is to be observed that the duty is not con- fined to personal diligence : indeed, it is of another 124 employers' liability. [v kind. What the law requires of the owner is not that himself in person, or any class of persons, shall take reasonable care for his property being in safe con- dition, but that reasonable care shall be taken. There are likewise duties of this kind which arise out of contracts of sale and hiring. It has been laid down, to take the latest case, that one who lets out carriages "is bound to supply a carriage as fit for the purpose for which it is hired as care and skill," — not merely his own care and skill, — "can render it." He must answer for all defects which might have been remedied by care and skill, whether he himself could have dis- covered them or not. Now let us turn to the case of an employer of labour for any purjDose. A man's undertaking or business is his property in a broad sense of the word. The vehicles, plant, machinery, or other eff'ects with which he carries it on are his property in the strict sense. And by analogy to the cases we have already considered, the use of this property, so far as it entails any risk upon the public, must carry with it a pro- portionate duty. If the business be extra-hazardous as regards adjacent owners or the public, we should expect to find strict liability. And though such cases are not common, instances have occurred. Thus a railway company not especially authorized by Parlia- ment to use locomotive steam-engines is liable for damage done in a field adjoining the line by the escape of sparks, notwithstanding that reasonable care has been used to prevent their escape ; whereas legislative authority to use a dangerous thing is held v] employers' liability. 125 to put its use on the level of an ordinary business in which reasonable care suffices, and to that extent to confer immunit)^ on the privileged person or body. But in the great majority of cases the risk is ordinary, or such as reasonable care will provide against. A tradesman's cart and horse, if carefully driven, will not run down a foot passenger of average prudence. Men at work on a building cannot well drop bricks on the passers-by without more or less carelessness, any more than the building itself will fall into the street unless it is ill- built. In these cases, then, which make up the general rule, reasonable care is sufficient for safety and is the measure of the emjjloyer's duty. But here we meet ^dth a limitation which appears at first sight to be special. The master is liable for the acts and defaults of his servants in the course of their employment, not for those of a servant who goes out of the course of his employment, nor for those of a stranger who meddles with the business. Is there here an anomaly, as compared with the impersonal character of the duty in the other cases we have observed ? The seeming anomaly will disappear on closer attention. Analogy leads us to the rule that the employer's obligation is that reasonable care as regards the public shall be used in the conduct of his business. Now a man's business must be conducted by his servants if not by himself; indeed, it is their duty to prevent any one else from interfering. If a servant allows intermeddling, as if a coachman lets an incompetent acquaintance take the reins, this is a default on the 126 employees' liability. [v servant's part, for the further consequences of which the master may be liable. So that the limitation of an employer's liability to the negligence of himself and his servants is hardly a real limitation of a liability which might be wider, but belongs to the nature of the case. But the negligence must also be in the course of the servant's employment. This means, broadly speaking, that a man is liable for harm done by the use of his property without due care, but for his purposes and in a generally authorized manner, but not for harm done by the use of it in an unauthorized manner and for the wrongdoer's pur- poses alone. The reasonableness of this distinction will hardly be questioned as a matter of principle. In practice it must be admitted that the line is some- times difficult to draw ; the law has certainly not erred on the side of unduly exonerating employers. AVe seem, then, to have arrived at something like a rational foundation of an employer's liability to the public for the acts of his servants. He is answerable, not for his servants as agents, or because they are his agents, but for the conduct of his undertaking with due caution. And it matters not whether the under- taking be for profit or not ; for the fact of the thing being done by the master's orders shows that he finds it worth while to have it done. He is using his own means for his own purposes, whatever profit, pleasure, or convenience he may have in view. All this applies equally where the employer is a corporation (as in the familiar case of a railway company) ; and one of the strongest practical recommendations of the rule is v] employers' liability. 127 that without it a corporation could not be liable at all. For a corporation, being not a real but an artificial person, can be negligent only by its officers and ser- vants, and a rule of duty confined to personal diligence would leave it scot-free. It is satisftictory to find that the reasoning now put forward is quite in accordance with what was laid down many years ago by Chief Justice Shaw of Massachusetts, in a case which has ever since been the leading American authority on the subject. He said: "This rule is obviously founded on the great principle of social duty, that every man in the management of his own affairs, whether by himself or by his agents or servants, shall so conduct them as not to injure another ; and if he does not, and another thereby sustains damage, he shall answer for it." This is a more lucid statement than I have been able to find in any English book. The same judgment goes on to deal with the case not yet considered, but out of which recent discussion of the whole matter has arisen, namely, the extent of an employer's lia- bility to the servant himself for injuries received in the course of the service. On this point it must be confessed that Chief Justice Shaw's language and reasons are not so clear. One thing, however, is tolerably plain, that he grounds the exemption of the master as against a servant who takes hurt by a fellow-servant's negligence, not on what is called the doctrine of common employment, but on that of the later English authorities. This is that the servant must be presumed in entering on his employment to 128 employers' liability. [v take all ordinary risks of it, including the risk of accidents happening by negligent acts or omissions on the part of other persons engaged in the same undertaking. And this may be taken as the only ground on which the rule or exception, whichever it should be called, is now capable of defence. nil The results so far obtained may be now summed up. The liability of an employer to the public for injuries caused by the acts and defaults of his servants is analogous to the duties imposed with various degrees of stringency on the owners of things which are or may be sources of danger to others. The man who conducts an undertaking of any kind, or has it con- ducted by persons subject to his directions, is held answerable for all operations incident to it being per- formed with reasonable care. On the other hand, a man who has work done for his benefit under a con- tract with some one who is not his agent or servant is not liable for the contractor's negligence. Take the familiar instance of running-down cases. If a private owner's carriage runs over a foot-passenger by the coachman's negligence, the owner is liable ; if a cab or a hired fly does the same, the hirer is not liable. If a landowner or his agent employs labourers to build a wall, and a careless labourer lets a brick fall on a passer-by, the landowner is answerable. If he had employed a builder who found his own workmen and materials, the builder and not the owner would be the person to be sued. The difierence between a v] employers' liability. 129 servant and an independent contractor, as explained by high authority, is in substance as follows: — A servant is one who undertakes not merely to do what he is told, but to do it as he is told ; and if he obeys the employer's orders the employer cannot complain of the result, however ill it may turn out. The mark of an independent contract is that the person for whom the work is done lays down generally what shall be done, but leaves a discretion to the other party as to the manner of doing it ; and the person who undertakes the work binds himself, not to obey orders, but to produce a certain result. It is not wholly obvious why this distinction should make a difference in the relation of the ultimate principal to the world at large. In many cases the employment of an agent or of a sub-contractor is a pure matter of detail, and the work of many sub- contractors who for the purposes of this rule are independent, all leads up to the completion of a single indivisible enterprise. And indeed the law has not been settled on this point without some fluctuation and difficulty. Kecent authority, however, is sufficiently clear and uniform. The truth seems to be that the division of labour has carried with it a division of external responsibility on grounds of social convenience. We could not carry on the business of life without constantly get- ting done for us by competent persons things which we are not competent either to do or to supervise ourselves. If the duty of answering for other people's negligence did not stop at the first independent au- thority, — " the first person in the ascending line," as a 130 EMPLOYEHS' LIABILITY. [V distinguished judge once put it, ''who is the employer and has control over the work/' — the chain of liability would be endless, and we should be involved in a multiplicity of unknown risks. Besides, it is felt that it would be over-harsh to make men liable not only for acts which they cannot practically control in detail, but for the acts of persons over whom they have no control at all. In some cases there is not even any choice, or real opportunity of choice, as to the person contracted with. It may seem not obvious why the hirer of a carriage let out by the day or the week should not be liable for accidents, while the owner who drives in his own carriage is. But every one can see that it would be absurd to impose this liability on the hirer of a cab. Even where there is some choice, the vexation and hardship of includ- ing in the obligation every one for whom the work was done would outweigh any possible advantage. The rule as it stands is supj)osed to make employers more careful in their choice of servants, and in look- ing to the state of the plant and instruments of their business, and probably it does so to some extent. This is thought worth securing at the cost of some individual hardship. But the use of care in choosing a contractor who is likely to be careful is too remote a benefit to the community to be enforced by indis- criminate penalties. It has never been suggested, so far as we are aware, that the existing rule on this point falls short of what is required by natural justice or the safety of the public ; so that this discussion is merely curious. Also it might be cut short by the v] employers' liability. 131 simple statement that business done for me by an independent contractor is not my business, and there- fore I am not answerable for its conduct. But the inquiry is not idle ; for there are plenty of cases in which it is by no means obvious to common appre- hension that work done by contract as opposed to service is the contractor's work, and not the ultimate employer's. Moreover it is worth wdiile, before coming to the point practically in dispute, to observe how the rule of vicarious liability is defined and fenced about, as a thing rather of positive institution than of natural consequence from elementary princij^les. So far we have spoken of the duty imposed on an employer, or let us call him the owner of an under- taking, as concerns the outside world. What is or ought to be his duty to persons who are employed by him, and are themselves, as it were, part of the under- taking ? English common law (that is, the law as it stood before the Act of 1880) says that he is not liable to them for anything but his own negligence ; for example, if he fails to use reasonable care in pro- viding safe and proper materials or machinery. This is objected to by spokesmen of the working-men's interest as an unfair exception ; and it is not im- probably regarded as a piece of class legislation by some who are unaware that the Leo;islature had nothing to do with it. But, when we look at the whole matter with such light as we have now ob- tained, it does not seem quite reasonable that the owner of the undertaking should be bound to persons who are inside it, so to speak, in the same way as to 132 employers' liability. [v those who are outside. A burden is imposed on him for the benefit and protection of the public at large, who have nothing to do with the undertaking, and are exposed without any choice on their side to more or less risk of injury arising from what is done in the conduct of it by the owner or his servants. The case is different with the servant or workman who is in the undertaking, and has entered into it of his own free will. It seems to me that the master's duty to the servant, by analogy to the duty of a householder to persons coming to his house on lawful occasions of common interest to both parties, might justly be fixed at this point : that the undertaking shall, to the extent of reasonable diligence, be in a safe and fit condition for the workman to enter upon. To the public the master answers, to the extent mentioned, for his undertakinoj and the whole conduct of it. To the servants employed in it he is answerable only for the conditions of the undertaking, not for its conduct, except in the event of his own personal negligence. Such is in fact, or very nearly so, the rule of English common law. The master must use due diligence in having proper appliances and competent servants : this much the servant may claim at his hands, not more. The reason for the master's duty to the public is not extended to make him pay damages to the servant for accidents befalling him, by no fault of the master, in a matter which the servant as well as the master has made his own. This is expressed in our later authorities by the statement that " when a man enters into the service of a master, he tacitly agrees v] employees' liability. 133 to take upon himself to bear all ordinary risks which are incident to his employment, and among others the possibility of injury happening to him from the negligent acts of his fellow-servants or fellow-work- men," In form this statement is open to the objection that it assumes a fictitious contract. The real ques- tion in this and many other cases is what conditions the law shall annex to the contract in the absence of special agreement on the point that comes in question. But the habit of setting forth relations and duties imposed by law under the disguise of fictitious agree- ments and promises runs through whole branches of English jurisprudence. It is an unfortunate one, but there is nothing peculiar in its employment here. There is one point, however, in which the master's duty was by the common law too easily escaped. This is where the master delegates his general au- thority to a manager or superintendent. According to our authorities, the manager is the fellow-servant of the workmen engaged by him, and the master is not liable to any of them for injury caused by his negligence. Now the master is answerable to the servant for due care beino; used in the choice of his fellow-servants and provision of materials ; and it seems strange that he should be able to cast off" this duty by handing over the performance of it to a superior servant. As within the larger bounds of his duty to the public the master is not discharged by delegating the conduct of his business to servants, so within the narrower bounds of his duty to those employed in the business he should not be set free 134 employers' liability. • [v by delegating his discretion and general powers of government to a manager. Again, I have suggested, as the true theory of an employer's duty to servants, that he is bound to them in reasonable care for the conditions as distinguished from the execution of the undertaking ; that is, not merely to be personally careful, but that due care shall be used. This might lead to an extension of his liability in some respects (apart from the question of delegated authority) beyond what English authori- ties have allowed. For instance, suppose there is a machine in a factory which it is A's duty to keep in repair and working order, and B's to attend to during its work, while C is occupied in producing or shaping something by its help ; A, B, and C being all directly employed by the mill- owner. Now if C is injured by B's negligence during the work, the owner is not liable to C, and I do not think he ought to be. But if A neglects the repairs of the machine, and in con- sequence it goes wrong and injures C, I am much disposed to think that the owner ought to be liable ; for the machine is, with regard to its general state of repairs and working order, one of the fixed conditions provided by the owner for the conduct of his under- taking. The workman should, as I incline to hold, have the same right to find the machine in good and safe order that a customer of the master's going to his counting-house has to find the approaches to it safe for him to walk in. But as the law stands it is otherwise; the proposed distinction has been rejected, though the cases are not many, nor of the highest v] employers' liability. 135 authority. On the other hand, I would by no means go the length of a proposal which I have somewhere seen, to the effect that the master should absolutely warrant to the servant the safety of his plant and machinery. For this strict kind of liability is else- where found, as we have noted, only in the case of extra-hazardous property or undertakings ; and such a rule would actually put the servant in a better position than strangers, which cannot be seriously intended. The suggestions above made are nearly, though not quite, identical with the changes in the common law made by the Act of 1880. The Act is framed in a peculiar manner, and must be tough reading to those whom it most concerns. But its provisions, when carefully read, are clear enough, and I believe there has been much lesslitigation upon them than was expected. If they err, it is in being too minute and making too many distinctions, which, how^ever, could be scarcely avoided in a measure that was really a compromise. As regards the plant and permanent apparatus of the business, the workman is now entitled to compensation from the employer for injury caused by defects therein, provided that the defective con- dition was due to the fault of the employer, or of some one in his service whose business it was to attend to it. By this proviso the workman's position is one degree worse than that of an outsider who is lawfully on the spot, such as a customer of the employer who comes to the works on business. If a defect in the machinery is due not to the negligence of the owner 136 employees' liability. [v or any servant of liis, but to tliat of the maker who sold the machine, or of some third person who supplied a special part of the machine to the seller, or in short of anybody concerned in the production of it, whether as a servant or as an independent contractor, the cus- tomer who is thereby hurt may still hold the owner liable. The workman, however, may not. Cases might easily happen where this distinction would be material, such as the breaking of a fly-wheel from a latent flaw. No sufiicient ground can, in my oj^inion, be shown for it. The aroument that the workman has put himself of his own free will in a position where he is exposed to such dangers applies equally to every one else who comes to the works. The work- man who is there all the week and the customer who is there for ten minutes are alike there by the em- ployer's consent, and for the common advantage of the employer and themselves. If it is to make any difierence that the workman is bound to be there, one does not see why it should be against him. Then the employer is made liable to the workman for injuries happening from the negligence of peo|)le holding positions of delegated authority or control in the business. No attempt is made to define what amounts to superintendence or delegation of authority, but sundry common cases are specifically dealt with. Under one sub-section or another of the Act the cases of most manifest hardship which arose under the com- mon law rule seem to be efiectually excluded. One of the worst was that of the carpenter employed by a railway company to do repairs in an engine-shed where v] employers' liability. 137 some of the company's porters were moving an engine. Instead of seeing that the engine cleared the carpen- ter's work, they let one end of it knock down a ladder supporting the scaffolding, and the man was seriously hurt. If the carpenter had been doing the work as a tradesman, the company would have been clearly liable to him. But he was paid by weekly wages, and thus was the company's servant, and, as was said, in a common employment with the porters. A very strong Court held unanimously that the company was not liable. At the present time the carpenter might re- cover under the clause of the Act of 1880 which gives a right to compensation where the injury takes place "by reason of the negligence of any person in the service of the employer who had the charge or control of any signal, points, locomotive engine, or train upon a railway," though it would probably be argued that an engine on a turn-table in a shed was not " upon a railway" within the true meaning of the enactment. This kind of specification is rather clumsy, and does not proceed on any satisfactory principle ; but it would hardly be possible at present to obtain agree- ment on any comprehensive definition. The proper way of stating the law would be to declare explicitly what are the master's duties, first to the public, and next to his own workmen. But this means codifica- tion, and is for the present unattainable. The right of the workman to compensation is in every case subject to the same conditions as would be the right of an outsider in the same circumstances. Practically this means that he must not have been so 138 employers' liability. [v careless himself that the accident may be considered his own fault. In technical language, he must not have been guilty of contributory negligence. The doctrine known by this name is instructive in rela- tion to the more general features of the subject, and deserves some words of remark in this place. IV. This general qualification of liability for negligence, running as it does through the whole subject, does not especially affect the liability of employers as such. But as concerning the immunity of employers for injuries to their own servants in the course of their employment, the doctrine in question appears to have some bearing on the reason once assigned for that immunity, but now abandoned. On the other hand it is connected with rules of liability peculiar to maritime law, which in their turn seem anomalous and are difficult of comprehension until further considera- tion has shown that the difficulties and harshness of the common-law rules to which they are opposed are indeed less apparent on the surface, but are hardly of less magnitude. The rule of contributory negli- gence is obviously just in principle, but its justice is equalled only by the perplexities that arise in its application. In a general way it may be stated in this form, that one who has suffered hurt or loss which he would not have suffered but for another's want of due diligence must nevertheless not recover compensation if he has materially contributed to the injury by some carelessness or breach of duty on his own part. In v] employers' liability. 139 popular language, lie cannot recover if lie suffered by his own fault. As the old books now and then say, though not in cases of this class, " it was his own folly." That common sense demands some such rule is indisput- able : when we come to deal with sjDecific facts, it has to be settled what relations of a man's conduct to injuries received by him will make him so far a contributor to his own mishap as to put him in the wrong. How much of his own folly must a plaintiff contribute to the total conditions of the event to determine a court of justice to say that the fault was his rather than the defendant's 1 If judges had been left to work out this problem for themselves, it is not unlikely that it would have remained a matter of un- defined judicial discretion. The determination of the facts in each case need not have been sharply marked off from the consideration of what is the precise ques- tion of fact that is legally relevant. But with our jury system the jury are judges of fact ; and on the other hand it is the judge's duty to put the question of fact to them in the proper form, and the manner in which he frames it may be, and often is, contested by a dissatisfied party. Hence a particularly minute and searching scrutiny is brought to bear on " ques- tions of mixed law and fact," as they are expressively if not quite accurately called. In the present case it can hardly be said that a final result is yet arrived at, nor has the rule ever been laid down in a complete shape. It appears on the whole that the loss must fall, whether by way of liability to pay damages or disability to recover them, on that side on which is 140 employers' liability. [v found the immediate Ccause of the injury. By " im- mediate cause," in itself an objectionable term, but not easily replaced, we mean that negligent act or omission which a reasonable man, looking at the matter in a common-sense way and without preten- sion to philosophical accuracy, would assign as being more than any other one incident of the whole event the reason of the mischief that happens. In many cases the test question may be more simjily put in this form : Which party might last have prevented the injury by the exercise of ordinary care ? Thus, a man leaves a pole across the public road opposite his house. A neighbour rides furiously down the street in the early twilight of a summer evening, runs against the pole and is hurt. He cannot recover damages, for although the defendant had no right to obstruct the road, the plaintiff might with ordinary care have seen and avoided the obstruction. On the other hand, a man's being on the wrong side of the road is no justi- fication for driving against him ; and on the same principle the owner of a donkey who left him un- watched on the highway was, in a well-known case, allowed to recover damages asjainst the owner of a waggon which, going ^' at a smartish pace," — in other words, as the Court considered, a pace inconsistent with ordinary caution, — ran over the donkey and killed it. There is no small interest in observing how all the subtilties of the theory of negligence, in all its various branches, work round at last to the statement of a question whether some one did or failed to do what a reasonably prudent and competent v] employers' liability. 141 man might be expected to do under tlie circum- stances. Now the theory of the earlier cases on injuries received by servants in the course of their employ- ment, so far as any definite theory can be extracted from them, is that a prudent servant has at least as much power as his master of observing and control- ling the conduct of his fellow-servants. In fact, it is his duty, in faithfully watching his master's interest, " to protect him against the misconduct or negligence of others who serve him." Hence it is inferred that when a servant suff'ers by the negligence of a fellow- servant it is so likely to be in some considerable degree by his own fault that it would be unjust to hold the master liable. The rule is stated, like other rules of liability which are anomalous as compared with the general principles of the law, to be " founded on the expediency of throwing the risk upon those who can best guard against it." We are not aware of any expressions in the books which would justify us in saying in so many words that a presumption of con- tributory negligence has been made against the servant in this class of cases; but the notion in which the doctrine took its rise was not very different. But in course of time the doctrine was extended to cases in which the possibility of mutual supervision or control, as between the servant whose negligence caused the accident and him who suffered from it, was absolutely excluded by the facts. To such states of fact the reason that it was the servants' business to look after one another could not by any ingenuity be applied. 142 employers' liability. [v However, there is a refinement of the doctrine of contributory negligence which is perhaps not wholly unconnected with the doctrine (as it used to be called) of " common employment." It has been held that a passenger in an omnibus or train is in some mysteri- ous manner " identified " with the owner of the con- veyance in which he is travelling. The efiect or meaning; of this identification is that if an accident happens by the negligence of a third party, — such as a collision with another omnibus, or with rolling stock of another railway company, — under circumstances of contributory negligence on the side of the first-men- tioned conveyance, the passenger cannot recover against the other omnibus owner or railway comjjany for any hurt he may sustain. He finds himself in constructive default by a process of reasoning which imputes to him, by an unhappy alliance of theological and legal supersubtilty, the negligence of the person in charge of the omnibus or train to which he has committed himself. I agree with the criticism that has been passed in more than one quarter on the decisions, fortunately not yet (in England at any rate) great in number or of the weightiest authority, in which this singular rule is propounded. Some remarks made last year by Lord Blackburn in the House of Lords afford ground for hoping that it may be ultimately discredited. Such plausibility as it has appears to depend on a false analogy to the community of occu- pation and interest by which a servant and his master are in a certain sense identified. It is this bond of a common undertaking between employer and employed, v] employers' liability. 143 their union into a single familia, to use the Eoman term, distinct from the outside public, that furnishes the most solid reason for the distinction established in Eno^lish and Ano;lo-American law between a master's responsibility to the public and his responsibility to his own servants ; a distinction by no means destroyed in England, though modified by the Act of 1880. If we attended more to verbal consistency than to real convenience, we might say that, every servant being " identified " with his master, and the master identi- fied with his servants, fellow-servants are identified with one another, and one of them cannot sue another for anything done or omitted in the course of their employment any more than he can sue himself. It is perhaps fortunate that this particular conceit has never occurred to the Courts : as it is, we may harm- lessly suggest it as an illustration of the danger that constantly attends the use of metaphorical language. Even in strictly legal reasoning, and when the subject- matter and the terms are familiar, a vigilant check should always be kept upon language of this kind. In considering the wider analogies of legal rules, and still more in discussing the policy, in other words the convenience and justice of the law, the only safe way is to discard it altogether. 144 THE THEORY OF PEESECUTION. [v VI. THE THEORY OF PERSECUTION. The popular view of persecution, at least in Protest- ant countries, is founded almost entirely on the examples afforded by the proceedings of the Roman Church during and since the Middle Ages ; and it is not uncommonly thought a sufficient explanation to say that persecution was invented by the priests for the sake of maintaining the pre-eminence of their own order. Such an explanation, however agreeable it may be to ordinary minds to throw all the odium of disgraceful chapters of history on a particular class of men, is superficial at best. For the Church has been able, with slight exceptions, to make persecution effectual only by means of the secular power ; and the secular power which lent itself to this purpose was a joint agent, and must be held jointly responsible. However eager the clergy might be to stimulate and direct the anger of the faithful against heretics, their efforts would have been vain if the bulk of the laity had not been predisposed to persecute heretics when duly pointed out. So far from persecution being merely the creature of priestcraft, it would be as near the truth to say that priestcraft was invented in order Vl] THE THEORY OF PERSECUTION. 145 to organize persecution. The truth is that mankind are prone to persecute heretics from several different motives, of which corporate ambition and the desire of crushing rival sects have often taken advantage, but which they are wholly incompetent to create. The chief grounds of persecution are as old as society itself ; and if we hear little of it in early times it is because there was not enouo;h resistance to call for any striking display of power. We may divide these grounds into tribal, political, theological, and social. A little examination will show us that theological per- secution in the strict sense is of comparatively modern origin ; while the arguments by which it has been sought, even in our own times, to defend restraints on 023iuion in a milder form present to us a softened and rationalized revival of the terrors in which the per- secuting instinct has its oldest foundation. Let us take the first persecutions which have acquired a general historical importance, those of the Christians under the Roman Empire. The accounts we have are mostly imperfect or exaggerated, but we believe that the following general view is substantially correct. Christians were vaguely known to the multitude as a set of people who refused worship to the recognized gods, and to the rulers as a widely spread and spread- ing society whose affairs were governed by a self- appointed internal jurisdiction different from that of the State ; whose ostensible objects were innocent, but trifling in proportion to the extent and organization of the society ; and which, although no overt act against the civil authority could be laid to its charge, strictly L 146 THE THEOEY OF PERSECUTION. [vi forbade its members to take the oath of allegiance in the ordinary form. To the vulgar Christianity appeared as a standing insult to the gods ; to the instructed, as a standing menace to the Government. The prevailing ignorance as to what the doctrine and practice really were contributed an element of mystery which doubtless heightened the alarm. A Eoman official of averacre intellig;ence must have looked on Christianity somewhat as a modern Prussian official would look on a combination of the Jesuits and the International. If we consider the persecutions that actually took place, we shall find that they proceeded chiefly from the vulgar but partly also from the instructed view of the danger. They were mostly connected with public misfortunes of some sort, as we learn both from the general history of the times and from the well-known passage of an early apologist. Men sought for an account of the famine, the drought, the pestilence, or the invasion of barbarians that had oppressed them ; and the account was only too easily found. The new and unsociable sect, the despisers of Jupiter and doubtful subjects of Csesar, were always with them. It was obvious that they had brought the wrath of the gods on the community which toler- ated them, and the remedy was no less obvious. The injured honour of Olympus must be avenged, and then all would go well ao-ain : CJiristianos ad leonem! This is what we call the tribal motive of persecution. The community which lives under the protection of its peculiar and ancestral gods will forfeit that protec- tion if it harbours persons who off"end the gods by Vl] THE THEORY OF PERSECUTION. U7 refusing tliem the obeisance and propitiation expected by them as their due. The presence of a single heretic is a constant source of imminent danger to the tribe or city. From this point of view the removal of the danger, — in other words the forcible suppres- sion of heresy, — is not merely justifiable, but a plain duty of self-preservation. In cases of this kind the Christians often suffered from outbreaks of local superstition which the magis- trates, or the Emperor himself if appealed to, dis- countenanced as far as they could. But they could not do so completely, superstition being not only violent, but having the law on its side.^ This brings us to the political aspect of the matter. Where the gods are regarded as in a manner the most exalted officers of the State ; where their protection is invoked on all public occasions, and religious ceremonies are intimately bound up with the outward frame and cir- cumstance of military and civil institutions ; where, in short, religion is incorporated into politics, any 1 It might be difficult to ascertain for what specific ofi'ence the early Christians were proceeded against in every case. The Roman of&cials, apparently, did not always know themselves. Pliny's famous letter to Trajan asking for instructions is so confused in this respect that M. Aube seriously disputed its genuineness in the first edition of his Histoire des persecutions de VEglise: he admits it in the second, though not without hesitation. The Christians, however, seem to have been legally exposed to punishment on three distinct grounds : — 1. Introducing an unauthorized new religion to the disturbance of men's minds. (Paul Sen. v. xxi. 2.) 2. Belonging to an unauthorized society. 3. Refusing the oath of allegiance. They were charged by the popular imagination, and sometimes probably by authority, with other various and monstrous crimes, including magic, which was a capital offence. 148 THE THEORY OF PERSECUTION. [VI rebellion against the established gods is apt to be regarded as equivalent to treason against the estab- lished order of government. It is not conceived as possible that those who are hostile to the gods should not be equally hostile to the laws and institutions under their protection. The seditious intention will appear to the vulgar self-evident ; the enlightened and conforming sceptic will consider that no one would take the trouble and expose himself to the danger of attacking the official religion unless there were some sinister political object behind his professed scruples. Accordingly we find that certain persecutions were undertaken by the Roman government as deliberate acts of State, if anything done in a panic may be called deliberate. To these a tolerable parallel may be found, allowing for the difference not only of the cases but of modern civilization and humanity, in the anti-Socialist legislation of the German Parliament and our own obsolete thouQ-h not ancient statutes o against secret and corresponding societies. The Eng- lish anti- Papal measures of earlier times are not in point, as there was no mistake or mystery whatever as to the reality and character of the pretensions against which they were directed. The political intention on both sides was undisguised. In order to understand the Greek or Roman feeling on the subject, and the inference, which to us appears forced, of anti-social purposes from eccentric religious professions, we must remember that almost all guilds and private associa- tions were united by some special tie of common worship and sacrifices. All societies were to some Vl] THE THEORY OF PERSECUTION. 149 extent religious, and a merely religious society was exceptional. It will be seen from the foregoing remarks that the political motive of persecution is, or may be, to statesmen what the tribal one is to the superstitious multitude ; and as the multitude, even under a despotism, have some tincture of political ideas, and few statesmen are wholly free from the current superstitions of the time, we shall hardly ever find either motive without an intermixture of the other. The tribal motive, however, might be sole and sufficient among people not yet civilized enough to have any distinct political institutions. Any member of the tribe who disputed the necessity and efficacy of the medicine-man's incantations for the common weal, or spoke lightly of dreams and omens, would probably be knocked on the head without more ado : nor would the survivors be able to say distinctly whether the purpose of their summary justice was to preserve the favour of the gods, or the customs of the tribe, or both. The civilization of Greece affords instances of per- secution in which the tribal and political motives were almost equally balanced : we mean the treatment of certain of the prse-Socratic philosophers and of Socrates himself, which is not reckoned by history as a persecution because the number of victims was but small, and in only one case, though the most illustrious, was an extreme penalty inflicted. The main charge against Socrates was that he imported new deities ; that was the form in which his offence hit the popular imagination. But there was also an uneasy feeling, 150 THE THEORY OF PERSECUTION". [vi by no means confined to the ignorant, tliat tlie new brood of Sophists, of whom Socrates was the cleverest and worst, were unsettling the foundations of civil order. They went about questioning maxims for which nobody before them had sought a reason, and set their disciples questioning too. Their teaching "perverted young men." Moreover, there was at Athens a suspicion that philosojDliical study was in some way associated with oligarchic sympathies. As regards Plato and Xenophon, there was certainly some colour, or more than colour, of truth in the suspicion. But it is not insignificant that some time earlier Anaxagoras was accused of "Medizing" as well as impiety. On the popular side, again, pretensions to superior physical knowledge were regarded as a kind of sacrilege ; to hazard conjectures as to what the sun and stars were made of was an indiscretion vermnof on blasphemy. The physical inquiries of Anaxagoras and the ethical and political inquiries of Socrates and others were, notwithstanding Socrates' own protests, hopelessly confused in the average Athenian mind, which satisfied itself with the broad conclusion that philosophers were a dangerous nuisance. Pericles was not only powerless to stop the anti-philosophic agita- tion, but was himself exposed to some danger from it ; and this alone is ample proof that the inovement was essentially popular. The Greek persecution, such as it was, of j^hilo- sophy, and the Roman persecution of Christianity, agree to a considerable extent in what their motives were, and still more remarkably in what they were Vl] THE THEORY OF PERSECUTION". 151 not. In neither case is there anything like the distinctly theological incitement to persecution which is given by dogmatic theories. The religions of Greece and Eome had legends and rites in exuberant abundance, but nothing that can be properly called doo-ma. When men come to hold that one set of religious beliefs is exclusively true, that adhesion to it is a matter of supreme importance for each man's individual soul, and that the true belief is in their own possession, theological persecution in the strict sense becomes possible. The nature of its motives, and its justification from the theologian's point of view, are already implied in this statement of the conditions. II. When religion was considered as a matter of public rather than private concern, the motives of persecu- tion were naturally found in the order of considera- tions which we have called tribal and political. The wrath of the gods must be averted by the destruction of the blasphemers who provoked it ; and the popular impulse to cast out the abominable thing was rein- forced by the more astute reflection that, whether the gods really cared about it or not, persons who re- nounced the accustomed gods of the city could not be otherwise than bad citizens. Persecution on grounds of this kind is essentially a measure of public safety. In its petty forms it belongs to the class of useless and vexatious police regulations by which it is sought to enforce erroneous theories of public welfare. We may compare it with the old-fashioned formalities of 152 THE THEORY OF PERSECUTION. [vi quarantine, or tlie machinery of protectionist legisla- tion. In its more violent forms it is analogous to a political reign of terror. But in either case it is wrong, not merely because it aims at putting clown particular ojjinions, but because it rests on mistaken assumptions. Whether those who promote it are morally to blame as individuals depends on their means of knowledge and the industry and intellio-ence witli which they liave used them. It was almost im- possible for a Roman official of the second century, with the political ideas and training of his time, to entertain the ojjinion that Christians might safely be left alone. The difficulty arises from the conflict of the old political conception of religion Avith the new individual or theological one. In the earlier stages of civilized history the tribal jealousy of strange gods is still active and potent. This was broken down by the increase of mutual traffic and the levelling cosmo- politanism of the Roman Empire ; and the Pantheon became hospitable. The Greek or Roman who bore his part in the official ceremonies was free to use for his private edification (subject to such police regula- tion as existed, and to the general laws against unauthorized associations) any respectable form of worship that took his fancy. When a world which had thus established, as it seemed, an arrangement convenient and equitable to all parties was surprised by the Eastern idea of right belief as a thing of surpassing moment for each individual, it was unable to receive such a disturbing element without a violent Vl] THE THEORY OF PERSECUTION. 153 shock. There was no strength left to withstand it, and Oriental ardour triumphed over the intellect of the Eoman world. It might have been expected, perhaps, that the modern doctrine of liberty of con- science should have been among the first-fruits of a system in which the responsibility of the individual soul for its belief was brought into unwonted promi- nence. But this was not the case. A brief and fitful gleam of toleration appeared at a time when the victory was yet in suspense, but only to be forgotten as soon as victory was assured. When the new theory of religion was once fully established, it lost no time in producing a new theory of persecution : not that the older motives, at least the popular one, b}' any means lost their force. If the authority of princes and rulers is divine, and if salvation is more important than any temporal interest, and the duty of saving one's soul paramount to all others, it is the manifest duty of princes and rulers to do what they can to ensure the salvation of their subjects. Further, if holding the true faith is essential to salvation, and the one true faith is known to be in the custody of the Church, it follows that the prince must support the Church at all hazards in pre- venting his subjects from holding any other. The undertaking may be difficult, but is not impossible ; and a prince who really holds the Church's view of human salvation is bound to go through with it if it is possible at all. It is easy to say that opinion cannot be coerced. But this, in the first place, is true only of the small minority of mankind who are 154 THE THEOHY OF PERSECUTION. [vi in tlie habit of thinking for themselves; and, secondly, if it were true it would only show that in some cases persecution is too late to be effectual. Not cure but prevention is the main object. A disease may be incurable as to the individual it has once fastened on, and yet the infection may be cut off by sanitary police or stamped out by slaughter. If heretical opinions are damnable, and the infection of them dangerous to the soul, the best thing the prince can do is to contrive, as far as in him lies, that his faithful subjects shall have no opportunity of hearing them. The readiest way of doing this is to make heresy a crime, and inflict penalties on all persons who either publish or willingly listen to anything contrary to the Catholic faith. And if heresy be a crime at all, it is plainly a crime of the most heinous kind. Every heretic is a centre of infection and corruption infinitely more deadly than any physical pestilence. Even if his own soul is stubborn beyond saving, the souls of his innocent neighbours are in constant danger because of him. And if temporal welfare is indeed of no account in comparison of spiritual, no limit whatever can be assigned to the measures of repression to wdiich an orthodox ruler should commit himself. Better a depopulated wilderness than a garden cultivated by heretical hands ; better a poverty- stricken remnant of the faithful than an outwardly prosperous multitude sitting in the darkness of mortal error and under an eternal ban. Extermination is the only true mercy : for every life that is spared many souls may be lost. It is useless to say to the Vl] THE THEORY OF PEESECUTION. 155 persecutor that if tlie truth is on his side it will surely prevail in the end. Such an argument might be allowed on a question of mere human knowledge ; but no delay is admissible where souls are to be rescued from certain perdition. How many poor ignorant men may not be hopelessly led astray while the doctors are exposing the fallacies of a new heresy? and do we not know that heretics are encouraged by the devil to a pitch of obstinacy which is proof against even the elements of Catholic truth? The case for theological persecution is unanswerable if we admit the fundamental supposition that one faith is known to be true and necessary for salvation. The ease against persecution is that the persecuting Sovereign must take the risk of this supposition Ijeino; unfounded. To Isabella the Catholic and Philip 11. , and to Catholic princes and clergy in general down to a much later time, it never occurred that such a risk existed. To most persons at this day it appears too tremendous for any human being to support. Even among devout Catholics there are probably very few who really think it inajjpreciable. Again, the preservation of the faith uncontaminated by heretical influences is, on the thoroughgoing Catholic hypothesis, a blessing for which no price can be too high. But to the common apprehension of mankind the hypothesis cannot be verified ; while the cost of rooting out heresy is visible in the present world. That cost appears to be terrible in direct proportion to the success of the operation. Spain is the one European country in which the policy of extermina- 156 THE THEORY OF PERSECUTION". [vi tion has been consistently applied for a time long enough to produce its full results. For once the Church and the Inquisition had unbounded scope. The Moors and the Jews were expelled; even the suspicion of Judaizing or heresy was more dangerous than treason ; the Catholic faith reigned without the shadow of a rival from the Pyrenees to the Atlantic, and Spain was politically and intellectually ruined. Similar consequences, though on a far lesser scale, may be distinctly traced to the revocation of the Edict of Nantes, the most modern instance of theo- logical persecution deliberately designed and rigor- ously executed. It is probable, however, that no ecclesiastical per- secution, not even under the Spanish Inquisition, was ever unmixed as to motive or perfectly consistent in its conduct. Even the most fanatical of temporal and spiritual rulers are apt to be in some little degree better than their creeds ; and, on the other hand, they have had other reasons for persecuting besides theological ones. The Inquisitors doubtless thought that in burning heretics they were vindicating the honour of God as well as preserving the souls of the people ; and this is only a refinement of the old tribal feeling that the heretic is a curse to the land, which is by no means extinct even now in Catholic countries. The periodical massacres of Jews which disgraced every country in Europe in the Middle Ages were partly due to this feeling ; and it is notable that they were mostly not ofiicial but popular. In some cases both civil and ecclesiastical authorities endeavoured Vl] THE THEORY OF PERSECUTION. 157 to restrain the mob, and endeavoured in vain. In this respect, as also in respect of the monstrous charges eagerly caught up by the multitude as a reason for outrage, the position of the Jews in Catholic Europe was very like that of the Christians in the first two centuries of the Church. But the Jews were victims not merely of superstition, but of the coarsest kind of jealousy. They added to the crime of infidelity that of being, in spite of vexatious and oppressive laws, richer and more clever than their neighbours. Superstition engendered hatred ; envy inflamed it ; and envy, hatred, and the lust of plunder fell back on superstition for an excuse. In England the Jews, before their expulsion by Edward I., were treated as a preserve of the Crown, and their religious perversity, and the other crimes associated with it by vulgar belief, were used simply as a pretext for extortion. It is observed by a writer of the last century that the Jews were not accused of murdering Christian children except when the king was in great want of money. In modern times religious and ecclesiastical con- troversies have become inextricably mixed up with political ones, and so long as theological persecution was esteemed a respectable motive, it was even found convenient to put it forward as a disguise or justifica- tion for animosities which were in truth merely political. It is barely needful to mention, as instances in English affairs, the association of Anglicanism with the cause of the Crown, and Puritanism with that of the Parliament, or the conjunction in the following 158 THE THEORY OF PERSECUTION. [vi century of the Pope with the Pretender. And if Protestant supremacy had been doubtful at the end of the sixteenth century, the Spanish Armada, a gigantic and sinister hybrid of theological and political ambition, would have sufficed to make it certain. At present theological persecution is generally dis- credited, partly by force of reason, but still more by force of circumstance. The continued existence of Protestant kingdoms has been enough to make it look not only shocking but absurd ; and Catholic and Protestant rulers, finding a system of perpetual reprisals intolerable, were practically compelled to allow existence on some terms to citizens who did not accept the prevailing religion of the State. When once heretics are sufi'ered to live, and the principle of toleration is so far established that the terms and conditions of it can be discussed, persecution is driven from its hio;h theologcical OTOund. The State admits that there are limits within which relio;ious belief is an affair not of certainty but of probable opinion ; and the repression of religious opinion, so far as it survives, must be maintained, not as a necessity of spiritual welfare, but by reasons of social expediency. Ecclesiastical fury is no longer armed with fire and sword, and the jurisdiction over opinions passes, in a mild and comparatively reasonable form, to the civil magistrate. III. The severer forms of persecution can, as we have seen, appear justifiable only when the extermination of heretics is believed to be necessary either for the Vl] THE THEORY OF PEESECUTION. 159 purpose of averting divine wrath from the community or to preserve the souls committed to the Sovereign's charge from the danger of a fatal infection. We now have to consider a state of things in which such beliefs no longer prevail. It might seem on first sight that with their disappearance all plausible grounds of persecution had also vanished, and that the continuance of it in milder forms, which has everywhere preceded the introduction of complete toleration, and is far from having wholly ceased, must be regarded as an irrational compromise between the old principle of unqualified repression and the new one of religious liberty. It is true that man, though he could not be political without being rational, is never completely rational in his political action ; and it is doubtless the fact that compromise of this kind has its share in the partial preserva- tion of compulsory and restrictive laws on religious matters. But it is only a share, and not the principal one. No sooner does the case for persecution fail on the theological ground than a fresh one is taken up within the region of temporal considerations ; and the position, if more confined than that which has been abandoned, is all the more defensible. Absolute knowledge of revealed truth and jurisdiction over consciences are no longer claimed ; but it is affirmed that the public weal does not suff"er certain doctrines to be openly disputed. The civil or social reasons, as we have called them, in favour of moderate persecution, may be presented thus. It is conceded that individual citizens must 160 THE THEORY OF PERSECUTION. [vi take care of their own souls, and tliat strict theological uniformity cannot be enforced. But there is a certain amount of fundamental religious doctrine, common to all or nearly all persuasions, and essential for the maintenance of morality and civil order. Whoever does not believe this much has no rational motive for being a good citizen or a good man : whoever shakes these accepted beliefs is to that extent endangering the stability of the commonwealth, and is just as much to be restrained as if he directly incited his neighbours to wickedness and sedition. For this purpose it becomes needful to impose penalties that shall be sufficient, but not more than sufficient, to secure a decent observance for the elements of religion on which the welfare of society rests. The offence will consist not in entertaining difficulties of conscience on the most important points of belief, nor in the discreet and private discussion of them, but in openly controverting the received opinions : the gist of it will be, in the language of an Act of William III., " writ- ing, printing, teaching, or advised speaking." This Act is worth studying as a specimen of the manner in which legal persecution is transformed. The preamble recites, in ungrammatical but not obscure language, that " many persons have of late years openly avowed and published many blasphemous and impious opin- ions contrary to the principles and doctrines of the Christian religion" — not of the Church, be it observed : the Christian religion is tacitly assumed to be the common possession of several denominations of Chris- tians. These opinions are further described as " greatly VI] THE THEORY OF PERSECUTION. 161 tending to tlie dishonour of Almighty God/' — here the old tribal superstition is expressed in a generalized form, — " and may prove destructive to the peace and welfare of this kingdom : " not to the salvation of souls ; the Legislature no longer provides for that ; but to the peace and welfare of the kingdom. " Where- fore, for the more effectual suppressing of the said detestable crimes," it is enacted that any person " who shall, by writing, printing, teaching, or advised speak- ing, deny any one of the Persons in the Holy Trinity to be God, or shall assert or maintain that there are more gods than one, or shall deny the Christian religion to be true, or the Holy Scriptures of the Old and New Testament to be of divine authority," shall, on conviction by two witnesses, be disabled from hold- ing any public office for a first offence, and incur sweeping civil disabilities and three years' imprison- ment for a second. Note that the penalties, exces- sive as they are, have a purely civil character, and do not extend to life or limb. There is a qualification which has the effect of excepting unconverted Jews, Turks, and heathens, presumably because they can- not be expected to know better, and there are not enough of them to affect the public welfare in any sensible degree by such disputes as they may enter upon with their orthodox neighbours. It seems clear that the severity of the statute outran public opinion ; for no instance is known of any one having been pro- secuted under it, though ample occasion was afforded by the Deistic writers of the eighteenth century. But its existence was not wholly forgotten. Early in the M 162 THE THEORY OF PEllSECUTION. [vi present century it was discovered tliat Unitarians were not in any way dangerous to the peace and wel- fare of the kingdom, but were very decent, well- behaved, and well-to-do ]3eople ; and accordingly the penalties were repealed for their benefit, so far as concerned persons denying the Trinity. This last incident marks a weak point in the social theory of persecution. It suggests that the legislator's estimate of the indispensable elements of belief which support the welfare of society is more or less precari- ous. In this case there is no mixture of substantial political reasons, such as we have noticed before, and may notice again. No one ever supposed that Socin- ians or Unitarians were dangerous to the State, except so far as their denial of the Trinity was equivalent to denying the foundations of religion and morality. The peril of allowing their doctrines to be openly maintained, whatever it might be, could not well have diminished in the interval between WiUiam III. and the Eegency. Yet under the Regency, at a time by no means favourable in other respects to speculative novelties or to the relaxation of restraints, the Legis- lature had become convinced that the danger was infinitesimal. Parliament had taken the risk of beinp; wrong — a risk which might have issued in depriving the country of the services of many good citizens if public opinion had not been wiser than Parliament ; and after the experience of something over a century, Parliament formally admitted that it had been wrong. But when the possibility of error is once allowed, we cannot say within what limits it is possible. Absolute Vl] THE THEORY OF PERSECUTION. 163 bounds can be set to the scope of probable opinion only if you have an infallible authority to set them. Therefore, if the risk of error is not in its nature so formidable when persecution confines itself to mode- rate civil penalties as when it proceeds on the theo- logical principle of extermination, yet it is implied in the theory of moderate persecution itself that the risk does exist. Nevertheless all government and legislation what- ever are founded on no surer base than probable opinion.; and in order to show that repressive legisla- tion is wrong, it is not enough to show that it may possibly be mistaken. We must be satisfied either that the assumption on which it proceeds, — namely, that the publication of certain opinions is dangerous to society, — is not tenable, or that, if that assumption be taken as true, legislation of the kind proposed is not fitted to attain the desired end. But those who object to repression are, as relates to the conditions of the argument, in a better plight than those who main- tain it. For their purpose is served if they can make out either branch of the alternative ; whereas the advocate of restriction has a double burden of proof on him. He must show that the alleo;ed dano;ers are real, and also that legal restraints will effectually pro- vide against them. These are issues which can be decided only on the ground of experience ; and ex- perience has, in fact, given a tolerably clear answer upon both branches of the question. First, the policy of limited restraint has had a fair trial for upwards of two centuries in the most civilized 164 THE THEORY OF PERSECUTION. [vi countries of the world, and there can be no doubt that it has failed. Notwithstanding the direct and indirect penalties which recently were or still are attached to various manifestations of heterodoxy, people who really cared to publish heterodox opinions have found but little difficulty or inconvenience in so doing, so long as they used decent language and otherwise con- formed to the ordinary law of the land. Probably it has oftener been the desire to spare good men's feelings and avoid controversial scandals than any dread of surviving legal sanctions that has induced heterodox writers in late years to express their speculations in guarded, respectful, or even ambiguous terms. At present it is certain that in all the Western nations the public discussion of the most fundamental religious questions is practically free : nor is this such a new thing as many people suppose. Ever since the theo- logical theory of persecution disappeared, freedom of speech has been in great measure enjoyed by any one who would use a certain amount of prudence and pre- caution. The difference between this century and the last is not so much in the boldness of particular pub- lications as in the general tone of society and litera- ture. The necessary precaution is now reduced to a minimum, and may be said to consist in nothing more than the observance of good manners. Yet, with the slight exception already noticed, the law has remained unaltered. Nor is it open to those who may be dis- satisfied with the result to say that if the law is ineffectual it should be made more stringent. In Eng- land it is nominally very stringent already, and the Vl] THE THEORY OF PERSECUTION. 165 fact is that public opinion does not allow it to be en- forced. The proposal is not even admissible in theory. From the theological point of view penalties for heresy may be increased without limit ; but from that of secular expediency the limit of the severity which can appear reasonable is very soon reached. If the civil magistrate, acting on grounds of civil welfare, is unable to suppress heresy by treating it as a simple misdemeanour, he may as well renounce the hope of suppressing it at all. The same exjDerience which shows petty persecu- tion to be ineffectual has also shown its purpose to be misconceived. Heterodoxy has had by this time a scope quite sufficient to display the mischievous re- sults of toleration. Where are those results ? The foundations of morality have not been weakened ; the practice of it has not ceased ; respect for the law has not diminished ; society is not on the brink of dis- solution. The civilized commonwealths of the world are not on the whole less orderly, less prosj)erous, or less flourishing in any way than they were two cen- turies ao-o. The disturbances and discontents that have arisen from time to time are traceable to natural and political causes. Orthodoxy can allege with con- fidence only one evil consequence — namely, that heterodoxy and unbelief have increased. To an orthodox beholder this is, of course, the greatest of evils ; but whether it should be an evil in the eyes of the civil authority, which by the hypothesis is to judge of beliefs only by their fruits in action, is the very matter in question. 166 ■ THE THEORY OF PERSECUTION. [vi The tlieory of limited persecution for tlie sake of public welfare is so far stronger than the older ones that it rests on grounds capable of being tested by experience, not on assumptions about the conduct of supernatural Powers. It cannot be summarily dis- missed as irrational ; but when the test of experience is ap23lied, it is found to break down. Laws of this kind do not work, and no harm appears to come of their not workino^. The collateral evils of retainino; nominal penalties and restrictions with which ]3ublic feeling is not in accord have often been exposed, and it is needless to speak of them here. The condemna- tion of direct penalties for heresy involves the con- demnation of all indirect ones which may be imposed by way of condition or disability; for example, treat- ing a man as unworthy of belief in a court of justice because he declines to take an oath in a particular form, or does not accept particular doctrines. This principle has been acknowledged, though tardily, by modern legislation and practice. What is here said as to the inutility of legal persecution applies with much the same force to the more subtle and really more formidable restraints which the usage of society can impose on private conversation. As the law in its modern tendency and operation, if not as yet in its form, regards not doctrine but only decency and the public peace, so must the exchange of opinion in social intercourse ultimately be limited only by the rule of good manners, gentleness, and respect for the feelings of those present, which equally governs conversation on all topics. Vl] THE THEORY OF PERSECUTION. 167 There are still divers forms of restraint on conduct and language which, though they are or may be con- nected with religion, and may tend to impede the manifestation of religious opinions, do not aim in the first instance at that object. Whether these can be dispensed with demands a separate inquiry. IV. Persecution has frequently been the ally of political ambition, the chief moving part in the business be- lonoinof sometimes to the one and sometimes to the other evil spirit. Ecclesiastical zealots have purchased the support of temporal arms by promises of temporal gain in sovereignty and possessions ; and princes have generally been eager in the detection of heresy in pro- portion to the immediate advantages which might be expected from the confiscation of the heretic's worldly goods. The crusade against the Albigenses developed or degenerated (it is of little importance to be accu- rate in the degrees of infamy) into a war of mere territorial conquest. And in a later age the Spanish conquerors in America made the advancement of true religion their pretext for rapine and cruelty which excited hardly less indignation in Catholic than in Protestant lands. But there are cases of another kind in which acts bear a certain appearance of reli- gious persecution which in truth belong chiefly or wholly to secular policy or jurisprudence, and are to be upheld or condemned on grounds independent of religious opinion. Thus the severities exercised against the Jesuits 168 THE THEORY OF PERSECUTION. [vi under Queen Elizabeth, whatever may be tliougbt of their justice or expediency, were not in the nature of a religious persecution. The Queen's Government determined to treat the Jesuits as enemies of the State, not because they believed in purgatory and the invocation of saints, but because they taught English citizens that the Pope could dispense them from their allegiance. And the imposition of special disabilities on Roman Catholics which continued so long after- wards was founded partly on the apprehension that anarchical doctrines of this kind still were or might be laid down by the authorities of the Roman Church, but still more on the subsequent experience of a criti- cal period in which the official influence of that Church had been used against the liberties of Eng- land. More clear and simple instances, however, will be found in later times ; and they will be the more instructive as the justice of the acts in question is hardly open to doubt. The British Government in India professes to regard the native religions with indifference, neither encouraging nor discouraging any one of them. But we have put down the practice of widow -burning, in spite of the strong religious sanc- tion it had obtained : not because we wished to enforce any particular theory as to the spiritual con- dition or duties of Hindu widows, but because a system of compulsory suicide was too contrary to the first principles of justice and humanity to be tolerated by a civilized government. It may seem a strange reversal of the ancient relations between persecutors and persecuted that the conceivable forms of persecu- Vl] THE THEORY OF PERSECUTION". 169 tion should include forbidding persons to burn them- selves. But fanaticism can persuade men to any- thing ; and there is little doubt that not only the Brahmans, but a certain number of the widows them- selves, were aggrieved by the prohibition. Again, we suppressed the sect of Thugs, not for being devotees of the goddess K^li, but because their devotion assumed the form of organized murder and highway robbery. It is beyond all question that they were sincere in their unique superstition ; and the procedure of the British Government differed from persecution only in being directed, not against opinions as such, but against the actual crimes produced by them. At home we have to deal with the Peculiar People, who deliberately omit to procure medical attendance for their children on a supposed ground of religious obli- gation ; and they no doubt consider themselves per- secuted when they find that if the children die the result of the parents' following of their peculiar reli- gious lights is a prosecution for manslaughter. The law is not concerned with the interpretation of the passages of Scripture relied on by the Peculiar People, nor does it interfere with any endeavours they may make to persuade as many of their neighbours as they can, and ultimately Parliament, to adopt the same interpretation. But in the meantime they are not free to act upon it ; for it is settled by the law of England, on grounds independent of particular religious beliefs, that it is a father's duty to provide necessaries for his children, including medical attendance when required ; and while the law is such it must be enforced. 170 THE THEORY OF PERSECUTION. [vi Provisions relating to the maintenance of an established Church are of a mixed religious and poli-' tical kind. They may be a cloak for persecution, but they may also stand together with a very wide tolera- tion of opinions. In fact, there was a time when writers who advocated freedom of thought and speech to the full extent assumed it to be a matter of political necessity that there should be some form of public worship specially ordained by law, and enjoying some sort of legal preference and privileges. The reasons for and against keeping up relations of this kind between Church and State — at least those which in our time can be used with any eflfect — are but remotely connected with the general political doctrine of toler- ation. But the intimate connexion between civil and ecclesiastical polity which was once universal, and is now relaxed only in the most advanced of civilized countries, has greatly contributed to maintain the belief that civil morality depends on religious opinions. In the first instance the State had no choice whether to be associated with the Church or not. The Church was a power not merely co- extensive with the State, but more extensive and better disciplined than any single State or any possible alliance of States. And when the State became strong enough to go alone, it was so thoroughly committed by habit and precedent to supporting the Church that statesmen easily brought themselves to regard the alliance which had once been a condition of the State's existence as a thing to be continued from deliberate choice and policy. When men are discontented with the government they live Vl] THE THEORY OF PERSECUTIOlSr. 171 under, and the Churcli is presented to them as a part of that government, their anger is for many reasons apt to be most strongly drawn towards the Church. And the probability of this will be the greater in pro- portion to the amplitude of ecclesiastical claims ; for an institution which pretends to have superhuman powers confided to it, and to exercise them under supernatural guidance, cannot expect those allowances which are tacitly made by all reasonable men for the necessary infirmities of their governors. Eepugnance to the established order in things ecclesiastical mani- fests itself in divers ways, according to times and cir- cumstances. Where it stops short of actual commo- tion, it may be expected to assume the form either of bitter sectarianism or of coarse and violent denial of all religion whatever. Distinctions between specula- tive tenets and the discipline by which it is sought to enforce them are not always easily made by educated men, much less by those on whom the weight of ecclesiastical jurisdiction chiefly presses. But in such troubles the Church finds a new opportunity. Men become heretics or infidels because they are disgusted with the behaviour of the ofiicers who represent the Church, or because they hold themselves wronged by an established order of things which the Church officially supports. It is both natural and convenient for Churchmen to invert the real order of cause and efi'ect, and assign the origin of every general disorder to the heresy or infidelity which is in truth only a symptom of it. The political distress may perhaps be represented as a divine judgment on heresy, or, at any 172 THE THEORY OF PERSECUTION. [vi rate, it will be pointed out to the civil authorities that they have another conclusive instance of the manner in which free-thinking breeds sedition, and a plainer demonstration than ever how nearly the interests of society are bound up with those of the established religion. We have said nothing as yet of the punishment by law of blasphemy as distinguished from heresy. Formerly the distinction was only one of jurisdiction — blasphemy being a matter of temporal, heresy of ecclesiastical, cognisance. In England it is believed that blasphemy, as a distinct offence, was invented by the judges of the King's Bench about the time when the power of the ecclesiastical courts was cut short. At that time it meant nothing more than the distinct expression of opinions contrary to the established ones. The statute of William III, which we have already cited proclaims by its title the intention of suppressing " blasphemy and profaneness ; " but inde- cency of manner is not an ingredient in the offence. " Advised speaking " against orthodox doctrine is to be punished, whether temperate or not. And the common law was understood to be to the same effect. But at this day we should never think of calling a serious and decently worded argument blasphemous. The simple denial of cherished doctrines may shock a believer's religious feelings ; but what we mean by blasphemy is language which denies with studious insult, or insults without caring to deny. Now it is a broad fact of human nature that, next to men's own persons and families, their religion is the point where Vl] THE THEORY OF PERSECUTION. 173 tliey are most easily touched ; and it should seem that wanton offence on that point is no less fit to be punished by the law than attacks on personal honour and reputation. Where strife between people of dif- ferent religions or sects is common, it may be neces- sary for the lawgiver, looking simply to the preser- vation of the common peace, to forbid mutual insults of this kind with some stringency. This has been done by the Indian Penal Code in perfectly impartial and general terms. If a certain belief is notoriously professed by a great majority of the people, gross and wanton attacks upon it will presumably give widespread offence and pain, and it may be fair enough to punish them with- out requiring proof that individuals have been in fact offended. This is the modern rationalized theory of the English law of blasphemy, which is made possible by the vagueness of the early authorities. When it is said that Christianity is parcel of the law of England, this would naturally mean that the law of England reo-ards a certain set of religious doctrines as true, and makes it a crime to deny them even in becoming language ; and this was no doubt the original inten- tion. But it can also be made to mean that the law, taking note of the fact that most Englishmen are professed Christians of some denomination, will not suffer the Christian religion to be assailed with gross and indecent vituperation. And there is fortunately no positive decision which binds an English lawyer to hold that the sober and serious expression of hetero- dox opinions must by the common law be deemed a 174 THE THEORY OF PERSECUTION. [vi crime. A law thus limited is reason itself compared with what it has been evolved from ; but it is less rational, less comprehensive, and more lialjle to abuse, than such a general provision as that of the Indian Code. It is difficult to sec why only the prevailing religion should be protected. There are many Jews and very few Buddhists in England. But it seems to us that those Buddhists are no less entitled to be secured against hearing gross abuse of the Buddha than the Jews are to be secured against hearing gross abuse of Moses. The draft Criminal Code Bill of 1878-9 proposed to make the publication of blasphemous libels an offence. The task of defining a blasphemous libel was wisely not undertaken except in a negative sense. There is a proviso that statements or arguments used in good faith are not of themselves to be punishable. Subject to this, the character of the publication is left to be dealt with as a question of fact in each case. Juries would thus have the same power that they already have by statute in other cases of criminal libel, and for the same purpose, to ensure the adminis- tration of the law being fairly in harmony with public opinion. But public opinion may now and then be carried away by a panic ; and although the proviso is distinct enough, we can imagine circumstances in which it would not give much security against per- verse and oppressive verdicts. It would perhaps be desirable to require the action or consent of the Attorney-General for prosecutions of this kind. The general result of the considerations set forth Vl] THE THEOEY OF PERSECUTION. 175 in this essay has been to show that persecution has been practised on several distinct grounds, some of which we can now see to be unreasonable in them- selves, as assuming absolute knowledge on subjects of which little or nothing can be known ; while others are of a far more plausible character, and can be effectually set aside only by the teaching of experience. We may sum up the argument from experience by saying that persecution is found to succeed only when pushed to extremes ; that when it succeeds the consequences are, in a temporal point of view, most mischievous, and when it fails the only harm that comes of it (which, however, may be great) is the disaffection and irritation produced by the attempt. General argu- ments concerning the sanctity of individual opinions as such, or of religious opinions above others, are of little use ; for the various theories of persecution deny the premisses on which these arguments are founded. It is not the demonstration of abstract right, but the experience of inutility, that has made governments leave off persecuting. We must always be careful, moreover, to distinguish from persecution those meas- ures of temporal police, often perfectly just and neces- sary, which bear a superficial resemblance to it. 176 THE OATH OF ALLEGIANCE. [vil VII. THE OATH OF ALLEGIANCE. The natural history and antiquity of oaths in general were discussed some time ago by Mr. E. B. Tylor/ and those who desire to inforrd. themselves or refresh their memories on the wider bearings of the subject cannot do better than turn to his article. Mr. Tylor has, among other interesting points, made it all but certain that our English formula, " So help me God !" is of Scandinavian and prae-Christian origin ; a dis- covery which throws an unexpected light on the much abused dictum that Christianity is parcel of the common law of England, and the proposition confidently advanced at a later time that the oath of allegiance taken by members of Parliament is in some way (notwithstanding the removal of Jewish dis- abilities) a bulwark of the Christian religion. This statement, however, errs only in generality and in being out of date. It is perfectly true that the oath of allegiance was, down to the Catholic Emancipation, one of the chief statutory defences of the Protestant religion, though in a political rather than a theological sense ; and for many years later it contained a pro- mise to maintain and support the Protestant succes- sion to the Crown as limited by the Act of Settlement. ^ Macmillan^s Magazine, "Ordeals and Oaths," May, 1876. VIl] THE OATH OF ALLEGIANCE. 177 The history of the oaths of allegiance and supremacy and of the various transformations they have under- gone is a varied and complex one ; and I now invite the reader, if he is interested as a lawyer in a half forgotten chapter of legislation, or as a historical student in the minute curiosities of constitutional his- tory, or, as an observer of things at large from the Darwinian point of view, in the birth, development, and degeneration of institutions, to trace with me the thread of this story as it may be picked out from the Statutes of the Realm. Before we go back to the beginning, it may be as well to look at the end. As late as 1868 the oath of allegiance was reduced by the Promissory Oaths Act to its present simple, not to say meagre, form, which stands thus : — I, , do swear that I will be faithful and bear true allegiance to her Majesty Queen Victoria, her heirs and successors, according to law. So help me God. What the substance of the oath as thus reduced may amount to would not be a very profitable question to discuss at large. It certainly does not promise anything beyond what is at common law the duty of every subject, and it seems to follow that it could not be broken except by some act which was otherwise an offence at common law, for example, treason or sedi- tion, or perhaps also the vaguely defined offence of disparaging the dignity of the Crown. And it seems at least a tenable view that the words "according to law" not only express the limit within which the Crown is entitled to obedience, but cover the possi- N 178 . THE OATH OF ALLEGIANCE. [VII bility (a possibility, fortunately, of the most remote kind) of the course of succession being legally varied.^ Such is the bare residue of the formidable and elabor- ate fiibric of oaths and declarations raised up by Parliaments of former generations against the Pope and the Pretender. We say against the Pope and the Pretender ; for our modern oaths of allegiance are of statutory devising, and date from Henry VIII.'s assertion of the Crown's ecclesiastical supremacy as against the see of Rome. The earliest point of history we have to observe is of a distinguishing kind, namely that the modern oath of allegiance is a thing apart from the older oath of fealty, though formed on its analogy. Side by side with the fealty due from a man to his lord in respect of tenure, there was recog- nized in England, it would seem as early as the tenth century, an obligation of fealty to the Crown as due from every free man without regard to tenure.^ Some- times we find mixed or transitional forms. Thus there is preserved among the so-called statutes temporis incerti an oath taken by bishops which, translated, is as follows : — ^ There is, I conceive, notliing in law to prevent the Crown, by and with the consent of the Estates of the reahii, in the ordinary form of an Act of Parliament, and with the advice of responsible Ministers, from rei^ealing or amending the Act of Settlement. In the event of its appearing likely that there should be a failure of the persons thereby defined as capable of succession, amendment would become necessary ; for example, if they should not be or should cease to be Protestants (see p. 190). " It is remarkable that in the Assize of Northampton (1176) the justices are directed to take the oath of fealty even from "rustics:" " Item Justitiae capiant domini regis fidelitates . . . ab omnibus, scilicet comitibus, baronibxis, militibus et libere tenentibus, et etiam VH] THE OATH OF ALLEGIANCE. 179 I will be faithful and true, and faith and loyalty will bear to the king and to his heirs kings of England, of life and of member and of earthly honour, against all people who may live and die ; and truly will acknowledge, and freely will do, the services which belong to the temporal ty of the Bishoprick of N., which I claim to hold of you, and which you render to me. So help me God and the Saints.^ This bears considerable generic resemblance to the modern oath. But it is not simply an oath of allegiance in the modern sense : it includes an oath of fealty in respect of a specific tenure, namely for the temporalities of the see holden of the Crown. This is made more evident by comparison of the common forms of a free man's homage and fealty : — I become your man from this day forth, for life, for member, and for woi'ldly honour, and shall bear you faith for the lands that I claim to hold of you ; saving the faith that I owe unto our lord the king. . . I shall be to you faithful and true, and shall bear you faith of the tenements I claim to hold of you, and loyally will acknowledge and will do the services I owe you at the times assigned. So help me God and the Saints. Moreover, the ceremonies of homage and fealty have in no way been abrogated or superseded by any of the rusticis, qui in regno manere voluerint." Does this include men who were not free ? In the earliest forms of the oath of fealty to the king, both in England and elsewhere, the promise was to be '^fidelis sicict homo debet esse domino suo." Allen {Royal Prerogative, pp. 68-71) thinks this was a limitation of the subject's obedience, or reservation of his right to throw off allegiance if the king failed in his duties, and this is probable. But the words would likewise operate in the king's interest by adding the stricter personal bond of homage to the more general obligation of fealty. ^ Bishops after consecration swore fealty only ; but on their elec- tion, and before consecration, they did homage. Glanvill, Lib. 9, cap. 1, ad fin. 180 THE OATH OF ALLEGIANCE. [vil statutes imposing political oaths. An oath of homage is to this day taken by archbishops and bishops, in a somewhat fuller form than the old one above cited. An oath of fealty is stated in our law-books of the thirteenth century to be required from every one attending the sheriff's tourn, and Coke speaks of it, in Calvin's case, as if it had been still in use in his time.^ There appears no reason why this oath of fealty should not in theory still be due from every subject at common law, though it would be doubtful who had authority to administer it, and what would be the legal consequence, if any, of a refusal to take it. Shortness of time and space, however, forbid the further discussion of the doctrine or history of alle- giance at common law. We must pass on to the additional obligations imposed by a series of statutes, from which the oath of allegiance in its existing form and application is lineally derived. In the spring of 1534, when the last hopes of a reconciliation with Kome were exhausted, there was passed " An Act for the Establishment of the King's Succession" (25 H. VIII. c. 22), the objects of which 1 Strictly there is not any oath of homage distinct from the oath of fealty. The oath was always an oath of fealty, and the duty of homage, where it was present, carried with it the duty of swearing fealty to the lord. On the other hand there might be, and often was, fealty without homage. Allen, p. 62. Cp. Hargrave's and Butler's notes on Co. Litt. 68 a. Homage was the privilege of the freeliolder, being " tlie most lionourable service, and most humble service of reverence, that a franktenant may do to his lord." Litt. s. 85. As to the common-law duty cp. Selden, Table Talk, s. v. " Fathers and Sons, " Every one at twelve years of age is to take the oath of allegiance in Court-leets [sk] whereby he swears obedience to the king." Vll] THE OATH OF ALLEGIANCE. 181 were to declare valid the king's marriage wdth Anne Boleyn, and to limit the succession of the Crown to his issue by her. It also enacted that all subjects of full" age should make a corporal oath that they would " truly, firmly, and constantly, without fraud or guile, observe, fulfil, maintain, defend, and keep, to their cunning wit and uttermost of their powers, the whole effect and contents of this present Act." The oath was not further specified in the Act itself, but a form was at once prepared and used, and was expressly authorized by statute in the next session (26 H. VIIL c. 2). This, as the earliest specimen of its kind, deserves the honour of being given in full with the original spelling : — Ye shall swere to beare faith truth and obedyence alonely to the Kynges Majestye and to his heires of his body of his moost dere and entierly belovyd laufuU wyfe Quene Anne begotten or to be begotten, And further to the heires of oure said Soveraigu Lordo accordyng to the lymytacion in the Statute made for suretie of his succession in the crowne of this Realme mencioned and con- teyned, and not to any other within tliis Realme nor foreyn auctorite or Potentate; And in case any othe be made or hatlie be made by you to any persone or persones, that then ye do repute the same as vayne and adnychillate ; And that to your connynge wytte and utter moste of your power without gyle fraude or other undue meane you shall observe kepe mayntene & defende the saide acte of successyon, and all the hole effectes & contentes therof, and all other actes and statutes made yn con- firmacion or for execucion of the same or of any thynge therin conteyned ; and this ye shall do ayenst all maner of persones of what estate dignyte degree or condicion so ever they be, And in no wyse do or attempte, nor .to your power suffre to be done or attemptid, directly or indirectly any tliinge or thinges privuly or appartlye to the lette hindraunce damage or derogacion therof or of any parte of the same by any maner of meanes or for any 182 THE OATH OF ALLEGIANCE. [VII maner of pretence; So lielpe you God all Sayntes and the Holye Evangelystes. Within two years the calamitous end of the mar- riage with Anne Boleyn brought about a new " Act for the Establishment of the Succession of the Imperial Crown of this Realm " (28 H. VIII. c. 7), which, after repealing the former Acts and making minute pro- vision for the descent of the Crown, appointed a new oath of allegiance, and declared that refusal to take it should be deemed and adjudged high treason. There is no variation worth noticing in the form of words, save that Queen Jane is substituted for Queen Anne, In the same session (c. 10) there followed an Act " extinguishing the authority of the Bishop of Kome," which introduced a special oath of abjuration. The preamble is a notable specimen of the inflated parlia- mentary style of the time. It sets forth how " the pretended power and usurped authority of the Bishop of Rome, by some called the Pope . . . did obfuscate and wrest Gods holy word and testament a long season from the spiritual and true meaning thereof to his worldly and carnal afi'ections, as pomp glory avarice ambition and tyranny, covering and shadow- ing the same with his human and politic devices traditions and inventions set forth to promote and stablish his only dominion, both upon the souls and also the bodies and goods of all Christian people;" how the Pope not only robbed the Kings Majesty of his due rights and pre-eminence, " but spoiled this his realm yearly of innumerable treasure;" and how the king and the estates of the realm " being overwearied VIl] THE OATH OF ALLEGIANCE. 183 and fatigated with the experience of the infinite abominations and mischiefs preceding of his impos- tures," were forced of necessity to provide new remedies. The oath of abjuration was to be taken by- all officers, ecclesiastical and temporal, and contained an undertaking to " utterly renounce refuse relinquish or forsake the Bishop of Rome and his authority power and jurisdiction." In 1544, however, it had been discovered that in these oaths of allegiance and supremacy, though they seem to a modern reader pretty stringent and compre- hensive, "there lacketh full and sufficient words;" and in the Act further regulating the succession to the Crown (35 H. VIII. c. 1) occasion was taken to pro- vide a new consolidated form to replace the two previously appointed oaths. This is very full and elaborate ; some of its language survived down to our own times, as will be seen by the following extract : — I, A. B., having now the veil of darkness of the usurped power authority and jurisdiction of the see and Bishop of Rome clearly taken away from mine eyes, do utterly testify and declare in my conscience that neither the see nor the Bishop of Rome nor any foreign potentate hath nor ought to have any jurisdic- tion power or authority within this realm neither by God's law nor by any other just law or means . . . and that I shall never consent nor agree that the foresaid see or Bishop of Rome, or any of their successors, shall practise exercise or have any manner of authority jurisdiction or power within this realm or any other the King's realms or dominions, nor any foreign Potentate, of what estate degree or condition soever he be, but that I shall resist the same at all times to the uttermost of my power, and that I shall bear faith truth and true allegiance to the King's Majesty and to his heirs and successors . . . and that I shall accept repute and take the King's Majesty, his 184 THE OATH OF ALLEGIANCE. [VII heirs and successors when they or any of them shall enjoy his place, to be the only supreme head in earth under God of the Church of England and Ireland, and of all other his Highness' dominions. . . . Eefusal to take tlie oath is, as before, to subject the recusant to the penalties of high treason. Ap- parently this Act remained in force till Mary's acces- sion in 1553 : one of the first proceedings of her reign was to abolish all statutory treasons not within the statute of Edward III., by which the offence of high treason was and still is defined (1 Mar. st. 1, c. 1). Thus the penalty for not taking the oath of allegiance and supremacy was abrogated, and the oath of course became a dead letter, though not dealt w^ith in express terms. Nor was it revived in the same form when the Reformation again got the upper hand with the accession of Elizabeth. The first Act of Parliament of her reign ^ — which, in repealing the reactionary legislation of Philip and Mary, names " Queen Mary, your Highness' sister," with a significant absence of honourable additions — created a new and much more concise oath of supremacy and allegiance, to be made by all ecclesiastical officers and ministers, and all temporal officers of the Crown, and also by all persons taking orders or university degrees. It is short enough to be cited in full : — I, A. B., do utterly testify and declare in my conscience that the Queen's Highness is the only supreme governor of this realm and of all other her Highness dominions and countries, as well ^ 1 Eliz. c. 1. In the argument in Miller v. Salomons, in the Exchequer (7 Ex. at p. 478), it was erroneously stated to be the first statute on the subject. VIl] THE OATH OF ALLEGIANCE. 185 in all spiritual or ecclesiastical things or causes as temporal, and that no foreign prince person prelate state or potentate hath or ought to have any jurisdiction power superiority pre- eminence or authority ecclesiastical or spiritual within this realm, and therefore I do utterly renounce and forsake all foreign jurisdictions powers superiorities and authorities and do promise that from henceforth I shall bear faith and true allegiance to the Queen's Highness her heirs and lawful successors and to my power shall assist and defend all jurisdictions pre-eminences privileges and authorities granted or belonging to the Queen's Highness her heirs and successors, or united or annexed to the imperial crown of this realm : So help me God and by [sic] the contents of this Book. The oath was not imposed on all subjects, aDd the only penalty for refusing it was forfeiture of the office in respect of which it ought to be taken. So far this presents a very favourable contrast to the violent legislation of Henry VIII. Under the Act of Eliza- beth the sanction is the mildest one compatible with the law being effectual ; indeed it is not properly a penalty, but a condition. The law no longer says to all sorts of men, "You must take this oath or be punished as a traitor," but only to men receiving office or promotion, " You must take this oath to qualify vourself for holding the place." But troubles were not long in gathering, and they bore their natural fruit in a return to disused severities. A new and more stringent anti-papal Act was passed in 1563 (5 Eliz. c. .1), and it seems that even sharper measures had been at first proposed. The obligation to take the oath of supremacy was extended to all persons taking orders and degrees, schoolmasters, barristers, attorneys, and officers of all courts. A first refusal 186 THE OATH OF ALLEGIANCE. [VII to take tlie oath was to entail the penalties of 'pre- munire, a second those of high treason. Temporal Peers were specially exempted, " forasmuch as the Queen's Majesty is otherwise sufficiently assured of the faith and loyalty of the temporal lords of her Highness' Court of Parliament." So matters stood till, early in the reign of James I., yet a new outbreak of indignation and panic was produced by the Gun- powder Plot. The Protestant majority was convinced by " that more than barbarous and horrible attempt to have blownen up with gunpowder the King Queen Prince Lords and Commons in the House of Par- liament assembled, tending to the utter subversion of the whole State," that Popish recusants and occasion- ally conforming Papists should be more sharply looked after. Hence the " Act for the better discovering and repressing of Popish Eecusants" (3 Jas. I. c. 4), which established, among other precautions, a wordy oath of allegiance, supremacy, and abjuration, which might be tendered by justices of assize or of the peace to any commoner above the age of eighteen ; persons refusing it were to incur the penalties of j^9^'emtmiVe. This oath contains an explicit denial of the Pope's authority to depose the King or discharge subjects of their allegiance, a promise to bear allegiance to the Crown notwithstanding any Papal sentence of excom- munication or deprivation, and a disclaimer of all equivocation or mental evasion or reservation. About the middle of it occurs for the first time the " damn- able doctrine and position " clause, as we may call it, which was long afterwards continued in the interests VIl] THE OATH OF ALLEGIANCE. 187 of the Protestant succession against James II. and the Pretender. The words are these : " And I do further swear that I do from my heart abhor detest and abjure as impious and heretical this damnable doctrine and position, that princes which be excommunicated or deprived by the PojDe may be dej^osed or mur- thered by their subjects or any other whosoever." Here also we find the words, afterwards discussed in relation to the admission of Jews to Parliament, "upon the true faith of a Christian." They cannot have been particularly intended to exclude Jews from office, as Jews were at that time excluded from the realm altogether. It has been plausibly conjectured that their real intention was to clinch the proviso against mental reservation or equivocation "by con- clusively fixing a sense to that oath which by no evasion or mental reservation should be o-ot rid of without (even in the opinion of the Jesuit doctors themselves) incurring the penalty of mortal sin." For in a certain Treatise on Equivocation, of which a copy corrected in Garnet's handwriting was found in the . chamber of Francis Tresham, one of the con- spirators named in the Act, and was much used on the trial, this point of mental reservation is fully discussed ; and it is laid down that equivocation and reservation may be used without danger to the soul even if they are expressly disclaimed in the form of the oath itself. But there is this exception, that "no person is allowed to equivocate or mentally reserve, without danger, if he does so, of incurring mortal sin, where his doing so brings apparently his true 188 THE OATH OF ALLEGIANCE. [VII faith towards God into doubt or dispute." It was probably conceived by the advisers of the Crown that the words, " upon the true faith of a Christian," brought the statutory form of oath within this excep- tion.^ A few years later, in the session of 1610, a sort of confirming Act was passed (7 James I., c. 6), which made minute provision as to the places where, and the officers by whom, the oath should be admin- istered to various classes of persons. Shortly after the Restoration an oath declaring it unlawful upon any pretence whatever to take arms against the King was imposed on all soldiers and persons holding military offices (14 Car. 11. , c. 3, ss. 17, 18) ; and the Act of Uniformity (14 Car. II., c. 4, s. 6) contained a declaration to the like effect, and also against the Solemn League and Covenant. A similar provision in the Corporation Act was over- looked at the Revolution, and escaped repeal till the reign of George I. In 1672 a revival of anti-Catholic agitation followed upon Charles II. 's attempts to dispense with the existing statutes, nomiually in favour of Romanists and Dissenters equally, by a declaration of liberty of conscience. The result was that a declaration against transubstantiation was added to the oaths of allegiance and supremacy by a new penal statute entitled " An Act for preventing dangers which may happen from Popish Recusants" (25 Car. II., c. 2). After the Revolution of 1688, however, a new start was taken. By the combined 1 Judgment of Baron Aldersou in Miller v. Salwnons, 7 Ex. 536, 537. VIl] THE OATH OF ALLEGIANCE. 189 effect of two of the earliest Acts of the Convention Parliament (1 Will. & Mar., c. 1 and c. 8), all the previous forms of the oaths of allegiance and suprem- acy, expressly including the declaration as to taking arms against the King, were abrogated, and a concise form substituted, which stood as follows : — I, A. B., do sincerely promise and swear that I will be faith- ful and bear true allegiance to their Majesties King William and Queen Mary, So help me God, etc.^ I, A. B., do swear that I do from my heart abhor detest and .abjure as impious and heretical that damnable doctrine and position that princes excommunicated or deposed by the Pope or any authority of the see of Rome may be deposed or murthered by their subjects or any other whatsoever. And I do declare that no foreign prince person prelate states or potentate hath or ought to have any jurisdiction power superiority pre-eminence or authority ecclesiastical or spiritual within this realm. So help me God, etc. In 1701 came the death of James II. at St. Germains, and the ostentatious recognition of the Pretender as King of England by Lewis XIV. Fuller and more stringent precautions were again thought needful, and in the very last days of William III.'s life an Act was passed (13 & 14 Wm. III., c. 6), imposing on specified classes of persons, including peers, members of the House of Commons, and aH holding office under the Crown, an oath of special and particular abjuration of the Pretender's title. The declaration of 1672 against transubstantiation (which had been spared from the general abrogation of other existing tests at the beginning of the reign) was at the same time expressly continued. As the ^ The " etc." means, I suppose, " and the contents of this Book." 190 THE OATH OF ALLEGIANCE. [vil form settled by this Act renicained substantially unchanged down to our own time, it is here set out : — I, A. B., do truly and sincerely acknowledge profess testify and declare in my conscience before God and the world that our sovereign lord King William is lawful and rightful king of this realm and of all other his Majesty's dominions and countries thereunto belonging. And I do solemnly and sincerely declare that I do believe in my conscience that the person pretended to be the Prince of Wales during the life of the late King James and since his decease pretending to be and taking upon himself the stile and title of King of England by the name of James the Third hath not any right or title whatsoever to the crown of this realm or any other the dominions thereto belonging. And I do renounce refuse and abjure any allegiance or obedience to him. And I do swear that I will bear faith and true allegiance to his Majesty King William and him will defend to the utmost of my power against all traiterous conspiracies and attempts whatsoever which shall be made against his person crown or dignity. And I will do my best endeavours to disclose and make known to his Majesty and his successors all treasons and traiterous conspiracies which I shall know to be against him or any of them. And I do faithfully promise to the utmost of my jDOwer to support, maintain, and defend the limitation and suc- cession of the crown against him the said James and all other persons whatsoever as the same is and stands limited (by an Act intituled an Act declaring the rights and liberties of the subject and settling the succession of the crowai) to his Majesty during his Majesties life and after his Majesties decease to the Princess Ann of Denmark and the heirs of her body being Protestants and for default of issue of the said Princess and of his Majesty respectively to the Princess Sophia Electoress and Duchess Dowager of Hanover and the heirs of her body being Pro- testants. And all these things I do plainly and sincerely acknowledge and swear according to these express words by me spoken and according to the plain and common sense and under- standing of the same words, without any equivocation mental evasion or secret reservation whatsoever. And I do make this VIl] THE OATH OF ALLEGIANCE. 191 recognition acknowledgment abjuration renunciation and pro- mise heartily willingly and truly upon the true faith of a Christian. So help me God. This oath was in addition to the oaths of alle- giance and supremacy prescribed by the Acts already mentioned of the first session of William and Mary's reign, not by way of substitution for them. It will be observed that the words " upon the true faith of a Christian " now reappear. In Queen Anne's reign the only alterations made were first to put Anne's name for William's, and then to leave a blank to be filled in with the name of the sovereim for the time being/ The accession of George I. in 1714 gave occasion for a full re-enactment of the oaths of allegiance, supre- macy, and abjuration, in w^hat would noAV be called a Consolidating Act (1 Geo. I., st. 2, c. 13). All persons holding civil or military office, members of founda- tions at the universities, schoolmasters, " preachers and teachers of separate congregations," and legal practitioners, were required to take the oaths ; besides which, they might be tendered by two justices of the peace to any one suspected of disaffection. Members of both Houses of Parliament are, as before, specially forbidden to vote without taking the oaths. The form was settled by inserting the name of George in the blank left by the last statute of Anne, but no provi- sion was made in terms for substituting from time to time the name of the reigning sovereign. In 1766, upon the Pretender's death, the oath of abjuration was ^ 1 Anne, c. 16, 4 & 5 Anne, c. 20 ; and as to Scotland, 6 Anne, c. 66 (Statutes of the Eealm, c. 14 in other editions). 192 THE OATH OF ALLEGIANCE. [\ H made appropriate to the new state of things Ijy in- serting the words " not any of the descendants of the person wlio pretended to be Prince of Wales," etc. In this form the oaths remained for nearly a cen- tury, affected only by a certain number of special exemptions. The most important of these was made by the Catholic Emancipation of 1829. The Act which effected this (10 Geo. IV., c. 7) allowed Roman Catholics to sit in Parliament, taking instead of the oaths of allegiance, supremacy, and abjuration, a single modified oath containing the substance of them ex- pressed ill a mildi'r form. The Catholic member was required, instead of