r uc- tff^LF ^ 3 I 1 '////////////'//I REEK OF LIFE G.LOWES DICKINSON JJ CHAUTAUQUA HOME READING SERIES I iiiiUitUiU.: mmmmamtxaataimammr^ B ER UNIVEr>rWTY OF I V CALIFOKNIA J Jf. K - ^f /o THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE BY G. LOWES DICKINSON, M.A. mm^im$. /ififec*!!);' EJ}e CI}autauqua i^ress CHAUTAUQUA, NEW YORK 1909 5021 2>F77 PREFACE The following pages are intended to serve as a general introduction to Greek literature and thought, for those, primarily, who do not know Greek. Whatever opinions may be held as to the value of translations, it seems clear that it is only by their means that the majority of modern readers can attain to any knowledge of Greek culture ; and as I believe that culture to be still, as it has been in the past, the most valuable element of a liberal education, I have hoped that such an attempt as the present to give, with the help of quotations from the original authors, some general idea of the Greek view of life, will not be regarded as labour thrown away. It has been essential to my purpose to avoid, as far as may be, all controversial matter ; and if any classical scholar who m.ay come across this volume should be inclined to complain of omissions or evasions, I would beg him to remember the object of the book and to judge it according to its fitness for its own end. "The Greek View of Life," no doubt, is a question- begging title, but I believe it to have a quite intelligible meaning ; for varied and manifold as the phases may be that are presented by the Greek civilization, they do Vlli PREFACE nevertheless group themselves about certain main ideas, to be distinguished with sufficient clearness from those which have dominated other nations. It is these ideas that I have endeavoured to bring into relief; and if I have failed, the blame, I submit, must be ascribed rather to myself than to the nature of the task I have undertaken. From permission to make the extracts from translations here printed my best thanks are due to the following authors and publishers : — Professor Butcher, Mr. Andrew Lang, Mr. E. D. A. Morshead, Mr. B. B. Rogers, Dr. Verrall, Mr. A. S. Way, Messrs. George Bell and Sons, the Syndics of the Cambridge University Press, the Delegates of the Clarendon Press, Oxford, Messrs. Macmillan and Co., Mr. John Murray, and Messrs. Sampson Low, Marston and Co. — I have also to thank the Master and Fellows of Balliol College, Oxford, for permission to quote at considerable length from the late Professor Jowett's trans- lations of Plato and Thucydides. Appended is a list of the translations from which I have quoted. LIST OF TRANSLATIONS USED ^SCHYLUS (B.C. 525—456). "The House of Atreus" ^i.E. the "Agamemnon," "Choephorae and "Eumeni- des "), translated by E. D. A. Morshead (Warren and Sons). The "Eumenides," translated by Dr. Verrall (Cambridge, 1885). ARISTOPHANES (C. B.C. 444—380). "The Acharnians, the Knights, and the Birds," translated by John Hookham Frere (Morley's Universal Library, Routledge). [Also the "Frogs" and the "Peace" in his Collected Works, (Pickering)]. The "Clouds," the "Lysistrata" ["Women in Revolt,"] the "Peace," and the "Wasps," translated by B. B. Rogers ARISTOTLE (B.C. 384—322). The "Ethics," the "Politics," and the "Rhetoric," translated by J. E. C. Welldon (Mac- millan & Co.). DEMOSTHENES (B.C. 385—322). "Orations," translated by C. R. Kennedy (Bell). EURIPIDES (B.C. 480—406). "Tragedies," translated by A. S. Way (Macmillan & Co.). % LIST OF TRANSLATIONS USED HERODOTUS (B.C. 484— ). "The History," translated by S. R. Rawlinson (Murray). HOMER. The "Iliad," translated by Lang, Leaf and Myers; the "Odyssey," translated by Butcher & Lang (Macmillan). PINDAR (B.C. 522—442). "Odes," translated by E. Myers (Macmillan & Co.). PLATO (B.C. 430—347). The "Dialogues," translated by B. JOWETT (Clarendon Press). "The Republic," translated by Davies and Vaughan (Macmillan & Co.). PLUTARCH. "Lives," Dryden's translation, edited by A. Clough (Sampson Low, Marston & Co.). son lOCLES (B.C. 496—406). Edited and Translated by Dr. Jebb (Cambridge University Press). THUCYDIDES (B.C. 471— ), edited aud translated by B. JowETT (Clarendon Press). CONTENTS Page Chapter I. — The Greek View of Religion i 1. Introductory I 2. Greek Religion an Interpretation of Nature 2 3. Greek Religion an Interpretation of the Human Passions. . 8 4. Greek Religion the Foundation of Society 9 5. Religious Festivals 12 6. The Greek Conception of the Relation of Man to the Gods 17 7. Divination, Omens, Oracles 19 8. Sacrifice and Atonement 22 9. Guilt and Punishment 24 10. Mysticism 28 11. The Greek View of Death and a Future Life 32 12. Critical and Sceptical Opinion in Greece 40 13. Ethical Criticism 44 14. Transition to Monotheism 49 15. Metaphysical Criticism 52 16. Metaphysical reconstruction — Plato 58 17. Summary 61 Chapter II. — The Greek View of the State .... 65 1. The Greek State a "City" 65 2. The Relation of the State to the Citizen 66 3. The Greek View of Law 70 4. Artisans and Slaves 7^ xu CONTENTS Pago 5. The Greek State primarily Military, not Industrial ... 77 6. Forms of Government in the Greek State 80 7. Faction and Anarchy 81 8. Property and the Communistic Ideal 86 9. Sparta 95 10. Athens 103 11. Sceptical Criticism of the Basis of the State. ..... 117 12. Summary 122 Chapter III. — The Greek View of the Individual. . 126 1. The Greek View of Manual Labour and Trade .... 126 2. Appreciation of External Goods 128 3. Appreciation of Physical Qualities 130 4. Greek Athletics 13 1 5. Greek Ethics — Identification of the -Esthetic and Ethical Points of View 134 6. The Greek View of Pleasure 142 7. Illustrations. — Ischomachus ; Socrates 144 8. The Greek View of Woman 154 9. Protests against the Common View of Woman .... 164 10. Friendship 167 11. Summary 183 Chapter IV. — The Greek View of Art 187 1. Greek Art an Expression of National Life 187 2 3 4 5 6 Identification of the Esthetic and Ethical points of View 190 Sculpture and Painting 194 Music and the Dance 199 Poetry 206 Tragedy , 209 7. Comedy 223 8. Summary 225 Chapter V. — Conclusion 227 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE CHAPTER I THE GREEK VIEW OF RELIGION ^ /. Introductory. In approaching the subject of the religion of the Greeks it is necessary to dismiss at the outset many of the associations which we are naturally inclined to connect with that word. What we commonly have in our mind when we speak of religion is a definite set of doctrines^ of a more or less metaphysical character, formulated in a creed and supported by an organisation distinct from the state. And the first thing we have to learn about the religion of the Greeks is that it included nothing of the kind. There was no church, there was no creed, there were no articles; there was no doctrine even, unless we are so to call a chaos of legends orally handed down and in continual process of transformation by the poets. Priests there were, but they were merely public oflBcials, appointed to perform certain religious rites. The distinction between cleric and layman, as we know it, did not exist; the distinction between poetry and dogma did not exist; and whatever the religion of the Greeks may have been, 2 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE one thing at any rate is clear, that it was something very different from all that we are in the habit of associating with the word. What then was it? It is easy to reply that it wajthe worship of tliose gods— of Zeus, Apollo, Athene, a^(l the rest — with whose names and histories every one is familiar. But the difhculty is to realise what was implied in the worship of these gods; to understand that the mythology which we regard merely as a collection of fables was to the Greeks actually true; or at least that to nine Greeks out of ten it would never occur that it might be false, might be, as we say, mere stories. So that though no doubt the histories of the gods were in part the inventions of the poets, yet the poets would conceive themselves to be merely putting into form what they and every OAO believed to be essentially true. But such a belief implies a fundamental distinction between the conception, or rather, perhaps, the feeling of the Greeks about the world, and our own. And it is this feeling that we want to understand when we ask ourselves the question, what did a belief in the gods really mean to the ancient Greeks? To answer it fully and satisfactorily is perhaps impossible. But some attempt must be made; and it may help us in our quest if we endeavour to imagine the kind of questionings and doubts which the conception of the gods would set at rest. § 2, Greek Religion an Interpretation of Nature, When we try to conceive the state of mind of primitive man the first thing that occurs to us is the bewilderment and terror he must have felt in the presence of the GREEK RELIGION AN INTERPRETATION OF NATURE 3 powers of nature. Naked, houseless, weaponless, he is at the mercy, every hour, of this immense and incal- culable Something so alien and so hostile to himself. As fire it bums, as water it drowns, as tempest it harries and destroys ; benignant it may be at times, in warm sunshine and calm, but the kindness is brief and treacherous. Anyhow, whatever its mood, it has to be met and dealt with. By its help, or, if not, in the teeth of its resistance, every step in advance must be won; every hour, every minute, it is there to be reckoned with. What is it then, this persistent, obscure, unnameable Thing? What is it? The question haunts the mind; it will not be put aside; and the Greek at last, Hke other men under similar con- ditions, only with a lucidity and precision peculiar to himself, makes the reply, "it is something like myself." Every power of nature he presumes to be a spiritual being, impersonating the sky as Zeus, the earth as Deme- ter, the sea as Poseidon; from generation to generation under his shaping hands, the figures multiply and define themselves; character and story crystallise about what at first were little more than names ; till at last, from the womb of the dark enigma that haunted him in the beginning, there emerges into the charmed light of a world of ideal grace a pantheon of fair and concrete personalities. Nature has become a company of spirits; every cave and fountain is haunted by a nymph; in the ocean dwell the Nereids, in the mountain the Oread, the Dryad in the wood ; and everywhere, in groves and marshes, on the pastures or the rocky heights, floating in the current of the streams or traversing untrodden snows, in the day at the chase and as evening closes in solitude fingering his flute, seen and heard by shepherds, alone 4 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE or with his dancing train, is to be met the homed and goat-footed, the sunny-smiling Pan. Thus conceived, the world has become less terrible be- cause more familiar. All that was incomprehensible, all ^hat was obscure and dark, has now been seized and bodied forth in form, so that everywhere man is confronted no longer with blind and unintelligible force, but with spiritual beings moved by like passions with himself. The gods, it is true, were capricious and often hostile to his good, but at least they had a nature akin to his ; if they were angry, they might be propitiated; if they were jealous, they might be appeased; the enmity of one might be compensated by the friendship of another; dealings with them, after all, were not so unlike dealings with men, and at the worst there was always a chance for courage, patience and wit. Man, in short, by his religion has been made at home in the world ; and that is the first point to seize upon. To drive it home, let us take an illustration from the story of Odysseus. Odysseus, it will be remembered, after the sack of Troy, for ten years was a wanderer on the seas, by tempest, en- chantment, and every kind of danger detained, as it seemed, beyond hope of return from the wife and home he had left in Ithaca. The situation is forlorn enough. Yet, somehow or other, beauty in the story predominates over terror. And this, in part at least, because the powers with which Odysseus has to do, are not mere forces of nature, blind and indifferent, but spiritual beings who take an interest, for or against, in his fate. The whole stoiy becomes familiar, and, if one may say so, comfortable, by the fact that it is conducted under the control and direction of the gods. Listen, for example, to the Homeric account GREEK RELIGION AN INTERPRETATION OF NATURE 5 of the onset of a storm, and observe how it sets one at ease with the elements: ** Now the lord, the shaker of the earth, on his way from the Ethiopians, espied Odysseus afar off from the moun- tains of the Solymi : even thence he saw him as he sailed over the deep ; and he was yet more angered in spirit, and wagging his head he communed with his own heart. * Lo now, it must be that the gods at the last have changed their purpose concernmg Odysseus, while I was away among the Ethiopians. And now he is nigh to the Phaeacian land, where it is so ordained that he escape the great issues of the woe which hath come upon him. But me- thinks, that even yet I will drive him far enough in the path of suffering.' " With that he gathered the clouds and troubled the wa- ters of the deep, grasping his trident in his hands ; and he roused all storms of all manner of winds, and shrouded in clouds the land and sea: and down sped night from heaven. The East Wind and the South Wind clashed, and the stonny West, and the North, that is bom in the bright air, rolling onward a great wave."^ The position of the hero is terrible, it is true, but not with the terror of despair ; for as it is a god that wrecked him, it may also be a god that will save. If Poseidon is his enemy, Athene, he knows, is his friend; and all lies, after all, in the hands, or, as the Greeks said, " on the knees, " not of a blind destiny, but of beings accessible to prayer. Let us take another passage from Homer to illustrate the same point. It is the place where Achilles is endeavour- *Odyss. V. 282. — Translated by Butcher and Lang. 2 6 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE ing to light the funeral p>Te of Patroclus, but because there is no wind the fire will not catch. What is he to do? What can he do? Nothing, say we, but wait till the wind comes. But to the Greek the winds are persons, not elements; Achilles has only to call and to promise, and they will listen to his voice. And so, we are told, "fleet-footed noble Achilles had a further thought: standing aside from the pyre he prayed to the two winds of North and West, and promised them fair offerings, and pouring large libations from a golden cup besought them to come, that the corpses might blaze up speedily in the fire, and the wood make haste to be enkindled. Then Iris, when she heard his prayer, went swiftly with the message to the Winds. They within the house of the gusty West Wind were feasting all together at meat, when Iris sped thither, and halted on the threshold of stone. And when they saw her with their eyes, they sprung up and called to her every one to sit by him. But she refused to sit, and spake her word : ' No seat for me ; I must go back to the streams of Ocean, to the Ethiopians' land where they sacrifice hecatombs to the immortal gods, that I too may feast at their rites. But Achilles is praying the North Wind and the loud Wegt to come, and promising them fair offerings, that ye may make the pyre be kindled whereon lieth Patroclos, for whom all the Achaians are making moan.' " She having thus said departed, and they arose with a mighty sound, rolling the clouds before them. And swiftly they came blowing over the sea, and the wave rose beneath their shrill blast; and they came to deep-soiled Troy, and fell upon the pile, and loudly roared the mighty fire. So all night drave they the flame of the pyre together, blow- GREEK RELIGION AN iNtERPREtAtlON OK NATURE 7 ing shrill ; and all night fleet Achilles, holding a two-handled cup, drew wine from a golden bowl, and poured it forth and drenched the earth, calling upon the spirit of hapless Patroclos. As a father waileth when he burneth the bones of his son, new-married, whose death is woe to his hapless parents, so wailed Achilles as he burnt the bones of his comrade, going heavily round the burning pile, with many moans. " But at the hour when the Morning Star goeth forth to herald light upon the earth, the star that saffron-mantled Dawn Cometh after, and spreadeth over the salt sea, then grew the burning faint, and the flame died down. And the Winds went back again to betake them home over the Thracian main, and it roared with a violent swell. Then the son of Peleus turned away from the burning and lay down wearied, and sweet sleep leapt on him."* The exquisite beauty of this passage, even in transla- tion, will escape no lover of poetry. And it is a beauty which depends on the character of the Greek religion; on the fact that all that is unintelligible in the world, all that is alien to man, has been drawn, as it were, from its dark retreat, clothed in radiant form, and presented to the mind as a glorified image of itself. Every phenomenon of nature, night and " rosy-fingered " dawn, earth and sun, winds, rivers, and seas, sleep and death,— all have been transformed into divine and conscious agents, to be propitiated by prayer, interpreted by divination, and com- prehended by passions and desires identical with those which stir and control mankind. 'Iliad xxm. p. 193. — Translated by Lang, Leaf and Myers. 8 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE § J, Greek Religion an Interpretation of the Human Passions. And as with the external world, so with the world within. The powers of nature were not the only ones felt by man to be different from and alien to himself; there were others, equally strange, dwelling in his own heart, which, though in a sense they were part of him, yet he felt to be not himself, which came upon him and possessed him without his choice and against his will. With these too he felt the need to make himself at home, and these too, to satisfy his need, he shaped into creatures like himself. To the whole range of his inner experience he gave definition and hfe, presenting it to himself in a series of spiritual forms. In Aphrodite, mother of Eros, he incar- nated the passion of love, placing in her broidered girdle " love and desire of loving converse that steals the wits even of the wise"; in Ares he embodied the lust of war; in Athene, wisdom; in Apollo, music and the arts. The pangs of guilt took shape in the conception of avenging Furies ; and the very prayers of the worshipper sped from him in human form, wrinkled and blear-eyed, with halting pace, in the rear of punishment. Thus the very self of man he set outside himself; the powers, so intimate, and yet so strange, that swayed him from within he made familiar by making them distinct; converted their shapeless terror into the beauty of visible form; and by merely presenting them thus to himself in a guise that was imme- diately understood, set aside, if he could not answer, the haunting question of their origin and end. Here then is at least a partial reply to our question as to the effect of a belief in the gods on the feeling of GREEK RETJGION THE FOUNDATION OF SOCIETY 9 the Greek. To repeat the phrase once more, it made him at home in the world. The mysterious powers that controlled him it converted into beings like himself; and so gave him heart and breathing-space, shut in, as it were, from the abyss by this shining host of fair and familiar forms, to turn to the interests and claims of the passing hour an attention undistracted by doubt and fear. § ^. Greek Religion the Foitndaiton of Society, But this relation to the world of nature is only one side of man's life; more prominent and more important, at a later stage of his development, is his relation to society; and here too m Greek civilization a great part was played by religion. For the Greek gods, we must remember, were not purely spiritual powers, to be known and approached only in the heart by prayer. They were beings in human form, like, though superior to ourselves, who passed a great part of their history on earth, inter- vened in the affairs of men, furthered or thwarted their undertakings, begat among them sons and daughters, and followed, from generation to generation, the fortunes of their children's children. Between them and mankind there was no impassable gulf; from Heracles the son of Zeus was descended the Dorian race; the lonians from Ion, son of Apollo; every family, every tribe traced back its origin to a " hero ", and these " heroes " were children of the gods, and deities themselves. Thus were the gods, in the most literal sense, the founders of society; from them was derived, even physically, the unit of the family and the race; and the whole social structure raised upon that natural basis was necessarily penetrated through and through by the spirit of religion. lO THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE We must not therefore be misled by the fact that there was no church in the Greek state to the idea that the state recognised no rehgion; on the contrary, reh'gion was so essential to the state, so bound up with its whole structure, in general and in detail, that the very conception of a separation between the powers was impossible. If tlicre was no separate church, in our sense of the term, as an independent organism within the state, it was because the state, in one of its aspects, was itself a church, and derived its sanction, both as a whole and in its parts, from the same gods who controlled the physical world. Not only the community as a whole but all its separate minor organs were under the protection of patron deities. The family centred in the hearth, where the father, in his capacity of priest, offered sacrifice and prayer to the ancestors of the house; the various corporations into which families were grouped, the local divisions for the purpose of taxation, elections, and the like, derived a spiritual unity from the worship of a common god; and finally the all-embracing totality of the state itself was explained and justified to all its members by the cult of the special protecting deity to whom its origin and prosperous con- tinuance were due. The sailor who saw, on turning the point of Sunium, the tip of the spear of Athene glittering on the Acropolis, beheld in a type the spiritual form of the state ; Athene and Athens were but two aspects of the same thing ; and the statue of the goddess of wisdom dominating the city of the arts may serve to sum up for us the ideal of that marvellous corporate life where there was no ecclesiastical religion only because there was no secular state. Regarded from this point of view, we may say that the GREEK RELIGION THE FOUNDATION OF SOCIETY 1 1 religion of the Greeks was the spiritual side of their po- litical life. And we must add that in one respect their religion pointed the way to a higher political achievement than they were ever able to realise in fact. One fatal defect of the Greek civilisation, as is familiar to students of their history, was the failure of the various independent city states to coalesce into a single harmonious whole. But the tendency of religion was to obviate this defect. We find, for example, that at one time or another federa- tions of states were formed to support in common the cult of some god; and one cult in particular there was — that of the Delphian Apollo — whose influence on political no less than on religious life was felt as far as and even beyond the limits of the Greek race. No colony could be founded, no war hazarded, no peace confirmed, with- out the advice and approval of the god— whose cult was thus at once a religious centre for the whole of Greece, and a forecast of a political unity that should co-ordinate into a whole her chaos of conflicting states. The religion of the Greeks being thus, as we have seen, the presupposition and bond of their political life, we find its sanction extended at every point to custom and law. The persons of heralds, for example, were held to be under divine protection; treaties between states and contracts between individuals were confirmed by oath ; the vengeance of the gods was invoked upon infringers of the law ; nation- al assemblies and military expeditions were inaugurated by public prayers; the whole of corporate hfe, in short, social and political, was so embraced and bathed in an idealising element of ritual that the secular and religious aspects of the sta*:z must have been as inseparable to a Greek in idea as vr, know them to have been in constitution. 12 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE § 5. Religious Festivals, For it was in ritual and art, not in propositions, that the Greek religion expressed itself; and in this respect it was closer to the Roman Catholic than to the Protestant branch of the Christian faith. The plastic genius of the race, that passion to embody ideas in form, which was at the root, as we saw, of their whole religious outlook, drove them to enact for their own delight, in the most beautiful and telling forms, the whole conception they had framed of the world and of themselves. The changes of the seasons, with the toil they exact and the gifts they bring, the powers of generation and destruction, the bounty or the rigours of the earth; and on the other hand, the order and operations of social phenomena, the divisions of age and sex, of function and of rank in the state — all these took shape and came, as it were, to self-conscious- ness in a magnificent series of publicly ordered ///^j. So numerous were these and so diverse in their character that it would be impossible, even if it were desirable in this place, to give any general account of them. Our purpose will be better served by a description of two, selected from the calendar of Athens, and typical, the one of the relations of man to nature, the other of his relation to the state. The festivals we have chosen are those known as the ** Anthesteria "^ and the " Panathenasa." The Anthesteria was held at that season of the year when, as Pindar sings in an ode composed to be sung upon the occasion, " tho chamber of the Hours is opened and the blossoms hear the voice of the fragrant spring; * This interpretation of the meaning of the " Anthesteria " is not accepted by modern scholars. It is not, however, for typographical reasons, convenient to remove it from the text, and the error is of no importance for the purpose of this book. RELIGIOUS FESTIVALS 1 3 when violet clusters are flung on the lap of earth, and chaplets of roses braided in the hair ; when the sound of the flute is heard and choirs chanting hymns to Semele." On the natural side the festival records the coming of spring and the fermenting of last year's wine; on the spiri- tual, its centre is Dionysus, who not only was the god of wine, but, according to another legend, symbolised in his fate the death of the year in winter and its rebirth at spring. The ceremonies open with a scene of abandoned jollity ; servants and slaves are invited to share in the universal revel; the school holidays begin; and all the place is alive with the bustle and fun of a great fair. Bargaining, peep- shows, conjuring, and the like fill up the hours of the day ; and towards evening the holiday-makers assemble gar- landed and crowned in preparation for the great procession. The procession takes place by torch-light; the statue of Dio- nysus leads the way, and the revellers follow and swarm about him, in carriages or on foot, costumed as Hours or Nymphs or Bacchae in the train of the god of wine. The destination is the temple of the god and there sacrifice is performed with the usual accompaniment of song and dance; the whole closing with a banquet and a drinking contest, similar to those in vogue among the German students. Aristophanes has described the scene for us— " Couches, tables, Cushions and coverlets for mattresses, Dancing and singing-girls for mistresses, Plum cake and plain, comfits and caraways. Confectionery, fruits preserved and fresh, Relishes of all sorts, hot things and bitter, Savouries and sweets, broiled biscuits and what not ; Flowers and perfumes, and garlands, everything."^ * Aristoph. Ach. 1090. — Frere's translation. 14 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE and in the midst of this the signal given by the trumpet, the simultaneous draught of wine, and the prize adjudged to the man who is the first to empty his cup. Thus ends the first phase of the festival. So far all has been mirth and revelry; but now comes a sudden change of tone. Dionysus, god of wine though he be, has also his tragic aspect; of him too there is recorded a " descent into hell"; and to the glad celebration of the renewal of life in spring succeeds a feast in honour of the dead. The ghosts, it is supposed, come forth to the upper air; every door-post is smeared with pitch to keep off the wandering shades; and every family sacrifices to its own departed. Nor are the arts forgotten; a musical festival is held, and com- peting choirs sing and dance in honour of the god. Such, so far as our biief and imperfect records enable us to trace it, was the ritual of a typical Greek festival. With the many questions that might be raised as to its origin and development we need not concern ourselves at present; what we have to note is the broad fact, character- istic of the genius of the Greeks, that they have taken the natural emotions excited by the birth of spring, and by connecting them with the worship of Dionysus have given them expression and form; so that what in its origin was a mere burst of primitive animal spirits is transmuted into a complex and beautiful work of art, the secret springs and fountains of physical Hfe flowing into the forms of a spiritual symbol. It is this that is the real meaning of all ceremonial, and this that the Greeks better than any other people understood. Their religion, one may almost say, consisted in ritual; and to attempt to divide the inner from the outer would be to falsify from the beginning its distinctive character. RELIGIOUS FESTIVALS 1 5 Let us pass to our second illustration, the great city- festival of Athens. In the Anthestcria it was a moment of nature that was seized and idealized; here, in the Panathencea, it is the forms of social life, its distinctions within its embracing unity, that are set forth in their inter- dependence as functions of a spiritual life. In this great national fete, held every four years, all the higher activities of Athenian life were ideally displayed — contests of song, of lyre and of flute, foot and horse races, wrestling, box- ing, and the like, military evolutions of infantry and horse, pyrrhic dances symbolic of attack and defence in war, mystic chants of women and choruses of youths — the whole concentring and discharging itself in that great processional act in which, as it were, the material forms of society be- came transparent, and the Whole moved on, illumined and visibly sustained by the spiritual soul of which it was the complete and harmonious embodiment. Of this procession we have still in the frieze of the Parthenon a marble tran- script. There we may see the hfe of ancient Athens moving in stone, from the first mounting of their horses by iso- lated youths, like the slow and dropping prelude of a sym- phony, on to the thronged and trampling ranks of cavalry, past the antique chariots reminiscent of Homeric war, and the marching band of flutes and zithers, by lines of men and maidens bearing sacrificial urns, by the garlanded sheep and oxen destined for sacrifice, to where, on turning the corner that leads to the eastern front, we find ourselves in the presence of the Olympian gods themselves, enthroned to receive the offering of a people's life. And if to this marble representation we add the colour it lacks, the gold and silver of the vessels, the purple and saffron robes; if we set the music playing and bid the oxen low; if we 1 6 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE gird our living picture with the blaze of an August noon and crown it with the Acropolis of Athens, we may form a conception, better perhaps than could otherwise be obtained, of what religion really meant to the citizen of a state whose activities were thus habitually symbolised in the cult of its patron deity. Religion to him, clearly, could hardly be a thing apart, dwelling in the internal region of the soul and leaving outside, untouched by the light of the ideal, the whole business and complexity of the material side of life; to him it was the vividly present and active soul of his corporate existence, representing in the symbolic forms of ritual the actual facts of his experience. What he re-enacted periodically, in ordered ceremony, was but the drama of his daily hfe; so that, as we said before, the state in one of its aspects was a church, and every layman from one point of view a priest. The question, "What did a belief in the gods really mean to the Greek " has now received at least some sort of answer. It meant, to recur to our old phrase, that he was made at home in the world. In place of the unintelligible powers of nature, he was surrounded by a company of beings like himself; and these beings who controlled the physical world were also the creators of human society. From them were descended the Heroes who founded families and states ; and under their guidance and protection cities prospered and throve. Their histories were recounted in innumerable myths, and these again were embodied in ritual. The whole life of man, in its relations both to nature and to society, was conceived as derived from and dependent upon his gods; and this dependence was expressed and brought vividly home to him in a series of religious festivals. Belief in the gods was not to him so much an intellectual conviction. RELATION OF MAN TO THE GODS 1 7 as a spiritual atmosphere in which he moved ; and to think it away would be to think away the whole structure of Greek civdlisation. § 6. The Greek Cojiception of the Relation of Man to the Gods. Admitting, however, that all this is true, admitting the place of religion in Greek life, do we not end, after all, in a greater puzzle than we began with ? For this, it may be said, whatever it may be, is not what we mean by religion. This, after all, is merely a beautiful way of expressing facts; a translation, not an interpretation, of life. What we mean by religion is something very different to that, something which concerns the relation of the soul to God; the sense of sin, for example, and of repentance and grace. The religion of the Greeks, we may admit, did something for them w'hich our religion does not do for us. It gave intelligible and beautiful form to those pheno- mena of nature which we can only describe as manifestations of energy; it expressed in a ritual of exquisite art those cori:)orate relations which we can only enunciate in abstract terms; but did it perform what after all, it may be said, is the true function of religion? did it touch the conscience as well as the imagination and intellect? To this question we may answer at once, broadly speaking. No! It was, we might say, a distinguishing characteristic of the Greek religion that it did not concern itself with the conscience at all; the conscience, in fact, did not yet exist, to enact that drama of the soul with God which is the main interest of the Christian, or at least of the Protestant faith. To bring this point home to us let us open the " Pilgrim's Progress ", and present 1 8 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE to ourselves, in its most vivid colours, the position of the English Puritan : " Now, I saw, upon a time, when he was walking in the fields, that he was (as he was wont) reading in his book, and greatly distressed in his mind ; and, as he read, he burst out, as he had done before, crying, 'What shall I do to be saved ? ' I looked then, and saw a man named Evangelist coming to him, and asked, 'Wherefore dost thou cry ? ' " He answered, * Sir, I perceive by the book in my hand, that I am condenmed to die, and after that to come to judgment; and I find that I am not willing to do the first, nor able to do the second.' " Then said Evangelist, * Why not willing to die, since this life is attended with so many evils?' The man answered, 'Because I fear that this burden that is upon my back will sink me lower than the grave, and I shall fall into Tophet. And, Sir, if I be not fit to go to prison, I am not fit to go to judgment, and from thence to execution; and the thoughts of these things makes me cry.' "Then said Evangelist, 'If this be thy condition, why standest thou still?' He answered, 'Because I know not whither to go.' Then he gave him a parchment roll, and there was written within, 'Fly from the wrath to come.' " The whole s])irit of the passage transcribed, and of the book from which it is quoted, is as alien as can be to the spirit of the Greeks. To the Puritan, the inward relation of the soul to God is everj'thing ; to the average Greek, one may say broadly, it was nothing; it would have been at variance with his whole conception of the divine DIVINATION, OMENS, ORACLES 19 power. For the gods of Greece were beings essentially like man, superior to him not in spiritual nor even in moral attributes, but in outward gifts, such as strength, beauty, and immortality. And as a consequence of this his relations to them were not inward and spiritual, but external and mechanical. In the midst of a crowd of deities, capricious and conflicting in their wills, he had to find his way as best he could. There was no knowing precisely what a god might want; there was no knowing what he might be going to do. If a man fell into trouble, no doubt he had offended somebody, but it was not so easy to say whom or how; if he neglected the proper observances no doubt he would be punished, but it was not everyone who knew what the proper observances were. Altogether it was a difficult thing to ascertain or to move the will of the gods, and one must help oneself as best one could. The Greek, accordingly, helped himself by an elaborate system of sacrifice and prayer and divination, a system which had no connection with an internal spiritual life, but the object of which was simply to discover and if possible to affect the divine purposes. This is what we meant by saying that the Greek view of the relation of man *o the gods was mechanical. The point will become clearei by illustration. § 7. Divination^ Omens, Oracles. Let us take first a question which much exercised the Greek mind — the difficulty of forecasting the future. Clearly, the notion that the world was controlled by a crowd of capricious deities, swayed by human passions and desires, was incompatible with the idea of fixed law; but on the other hand it made it possible to suppose that 20 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE some iritimation might be had from the gods, either directly or symbolically, of what their intentions and purposes really were. And on this hypothesis we find developed quite early in Greek history, a complex art of divining the future by signs. The flight of birds and other phenomena of the heavens, events encountered on the road, the speech of passers-by, or, most important of all, the ap- pearance of the entrails of the victims sacrificed were sup- posed to indicate the probable course of events. And this art, already mature in the time of the Homeric poems, we find flourishing throughout tlie historic age. Nothing could better indicate its prevalence and its scope than the following passage from Aristophanes, where he ridicules the readi- ness of his contemporaries to see in everything an omen, or, as he puts it, punning on the Greek word, a " bird " : " On us you depend," sings his chorus of Birds, "On us you depend, and to us you repair For counsel and aid, when a marriage is made, A purchase, a bargain, a venture in trade ; Unlucky or lucky, whatever has struck ye, An ox or an ass, that may happen to pass, A voice in the street, or a slave that you meet, A name or a word by chance overheard, You deem it an omen, and call it a Bird." * Aristophanes, of course, is jesting; but how serious and hnportant this art of divination must have appeared even to the most cultivated Athenians may be gathered from a passage of the tragedian ^schylus, where he mentions it as one of the benefits conferred by Prometheus on mankind, and puts it on a level with the arts of building, * Aristoph. "Birds" 717. — Frere's translation. DIVINATION, OMENS, ORACLES 21 metal- making, sailing, and the like, and the sciences of arithmetic and astronomy. And if anyone were dissatisfied with this method of inteq')retation by signs, he had a directer means of ap- proaching the gods. He could visit one of the oracles and consult the deity at first hand about his most trivial and personal family afiairs. Some of the questions put to the oracle at Dodona have been preserved to us, ^ and very curious they are. " Who stole my cushions and pillow ? " asks one bereaved householder. Another wants to know whether it will pay him to buy a certain house and farm ; another whether sheep-farming is a good invest- ment. Clearly, the god was not above being consulted on the meanest afifairs; and his easy accessibility must have been some compensation for his probable caprice. Nor must it be supposed that this phase of the Greek religion was a superstition confined to individuals; on the contrary, it was fully recognised by the state. No im- portant public act could be undertaken without a previous consultation of omens. More than once, in the clearest and most brilliant period of the Greek civilisation, we hear of military expeditions being abandoned because the sacrifices were unfavourable; and at the time of the Persian invasion, at the most critical moment of the history of Greece, the Lacedaemonians, we are told, came too late to be present at the battle of Marathon, because they thought it unlucky to start until the moon was full. In all this we have a suggestion of the sort of relation in which the Greek conceived himself to stand to the gods. It is a relation, as we said, external and mechanical. Tlie *See Percy Gardaer, "New Chapters in Greek History." 3 22 ThE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE gods were superior beings who knew, it might be presumed, what was going to happen ; man didn't know, but perhaps he could find out. How could he find out? that was the problem ; and it was answered in the way we have seen. There was no question, clearly, of a spiritual relation; all is external; and a similar externality pervades, on the whole, the Greek view of sacrifice and of sin. Let us turn now to consider this point. § 8. Sacrifice and Atonement, In Homer, we find that sacrifice is frankly conceived as a sort of present to the gods, for which they were in fairness bound to an equivalent return; and the nature of the bargain is fully recognised by the gods them- selves. "Hector," says Zeus to Hera, " was dearest to the gods of all mortals that are in Ilios. So was he to me at least, for nowise failed he in the gifts I loved. Never did my altar lack seemly feast, drink-offering and the steam of sacrifice, even the honour that falleth to our due." * And he concludes that he must intervene to secure the re- storation of the body of Hector to his father. The performance of sacrifice, then, ensures favour; and on the other hand its neglect entails punishment. When Apollo sends a plague upon the Greek fleet the most natural hypothesis to account for his conduct is that he has been stinted of his due meed of offerings; "perhaps," says Agamemnon, " the savour of lambs and unblemished goats may appease him." Or again, when the Greeks omit to sacrifice before building the wall around their fleet, they are punished by the capture of their position * Iliad xxiv. 66. — Translated by Lang, Leaf and Myers. SACRIFICE AND ATONEMENT 23 by the Trojans. The whole relation between man and the gods is of the nature of a contract. " If you do your part, I'll do mine; if not, not!" that is the tone of the language on either side. The conception is legal, not moral nor spiritual ; it has nothing to do with what we call sin and conscience. At a later period, it is true, wc find a point of view prevailing which appears at first sight to come closer to that of the Christian. Certain acts we find, such as mur- der, for example, were supposed to infect as with a stain not only the original offender but his descendants from generation to generation. Yet even so, the stain, it appears, was conceived to be rather physical than moral, analogous to disease both in its character and in the methods of its cure, ^schylus tells us of the earth breeding monsters as a result of the corruption infused by the shedding of blood ; and similarly a purely physical infection tainted the man or the race that had been guilty of crime. And as was the evil, so was the remedy. External acts and observations might cleanse and purge away what was regarded as an external affection of the soul; and we know that in historic times there was a class of men, com- parable to the mediaeval " pardoners", whose profession it was to effect such cures. Plato has described them for us in striking terms. "Mendicant prophets," he says, "go to rich men's doors and persuade them that they have a power committed to them of making an atonement for their sins or those of their fathers by sacrifices or charms with rejoicings and games; and they promise to harm an enemy whether just or unjust, at a small charge; with ma- gic arts and incantations binding the will of heaven, as they say, to do their work .... And they produce a 24 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE host of books written by Musseus and Orpheus, who were children of the Moon and the Muses — that is what they say— according to which they perform their ritual, and persuade not only individuals, but whole cities, that ex- piations and atonements for sin may be made by sacrifices and amusements which fill a vacant hour." * How far is all this from the Puritan view of sin! how far from the Christian of the " Pilgrim's Progress " with the burden on his backl To measure the distance we have only to attend, with this passage in our mind, a meeting, say, of the "Salvation Army". We shall then perhaps understand better the distinction between the popular religion of the Greeks and our own; between the conception of sin as a physical contagion to be cured by external rites, and the conception of it as an affection of the conscience which only "grace" can expel. In the one case the fact that a man was under the taint of crime would be borne in upon him by actual misfortune from without — by sickness, or failure in business, or some other of the troubles of life; and he would ease his mind and recover the spring of hope by performing certain cere- monies and rites. In the other case, his trouble is all inward; he feels that he is guilty in the sight of God, and the only thing that can relieve him is the certainty that he has been forgiven, assured him somehow or other from within. The difference is fundamental, and important to bear in mind, if we would form a clear conception of the Greek view of life. § g. Guilt and Punishment. It must not be supposed, however, that the popular * Plato's Republic, 11. 364b. — Jowelt's translation. GUILT AND PUNISHMENT 25 superstition described by Plato, however characteristic it may be of the point of view of the Greeks, represents the highest reach of their thought on the subject of guilt. No profounder utterances are to be found on this theme than those of the great poets and thinkers of Greece, who, without rejecting the common beliefs of their time, trans- formed them by the insight of their genius into a new and deeper significance. Specially striking in this connection is the poetry of the tragedian ^schylus; and it will be well worth our while to pause for a moment and endeavour to realise his position. Guilt and its pimishment is the constant theme of the dramas of -^schylus ; and he has exhausted the resources of his genius in the attempt to depict the horror of the avenging powers, who under the name of the Erinyes, or Furies, persecute and torment the criminal. Their breath is foul with the blood on which they feed; from their rheumy eyes a horrible humour drops; daughters of night and clad in black they fly without wings; god and man and the very beasts shun them ; their place is with punish- ment and torture, mutilation, stoning and breaking of necks. And into their mouth the poet has put words which seem to breathe the very spirit of the Jewish scrip- tures. "Come now let us preach to the sons of men; yea, let us tel! them of our vengeance ; yea, let us all make mention of justice. " Whoso showeth hands that are undefiled, lo, he shall suffer nought of us for evcr^ but shall go unharmed to his ending. " But if he hath sinned, like imto this man, and covereth hands that are blood-stained : then is our witness true to the slain m;ui. 26 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE "And we sue for the blood, sue and pursue for it, so that at the last there is payment. Even so 'tis written: (Oh scuteucc sure !) ■ Upon all that wild in wickedness dij) hand III the blood of their birth, in the fount of their flowing: So shall he pine until the grave receive him — to find no grace even in the grave! Sing then the spell. Sisters of hell ; Chaut him the charra Mighty to harm, Binding the blood. Madding the mood; Such the music that we make: Quail, ye sons of man, and quake, Bow the heart, and bend, and break! This is our ministry marked for us from the beginning; This is our gift, and our portion apart, and our godhead, Ours, ours only for ever, Darkness, robes of darkness, a robe of terror for ever! Ruin is ours, ruin and wreck; "When to the home Murder hath come, Making to cease Innocent peace; Then at his beck Follow we in, Follow the sin ; And ah ! we hold to the ead when we bej^in !" ' There is no poetry more sublime than this; none more penetrated with the sense of moral law. But still it is *^schyl. Eum. 297. — Translated by Dr. Verrall (Cambridge, 1885). GUILT AND PUNISHMENT 2^ whohy Greek in character. The theme is not really the conscience of the sinner but the objective consequence of his crime. "Blood calls for blood," is the poet's text; a man, he says, must pay for what he does. The tragedy is the punishment of the guilty, not his inward sense of sin. Orestes, in fact, who is the subject of the drama with which we are concerned, in a sense was not a sinner at all. He had killed his mother, it is true, but only to avenge his father whom she had murdered, and at the express bidding of Apollo. So far is he from feeling the pangs of conscience that he constantly jus- tifies his act. He suffers, not because he has sinned but because he is involved in the curse of his race. For generations back the house of Atreus had been tainted with blood; murder had called for murder to avenge it; and Orestes, the last descendant, caught in the net of guilt, found that his only possibility of right action lay in a crime. He was bound to avenge his father, the god Apollo had enjoined it; and the avenging of his father meant the murder of his mother. What he commits, then, is a crime, but not a sin; and so it is regarded by the poet. The tragedy, as we have said, centres round an external objective law— "blood calls for blood." But that is all. Of the internal drama of the soul with God, the division of the man against himself, the remorse, the repentance, the new birth, the giving or withholding of grace — of all this, the essential content of Christian Protestantism, not a trace in the clear and concrete vision of the Greek. The profoundest of the poets of Hellas, dealing with the darkest problem of guilt, is true to the plastic genius of his race. The spirit throws outside itself the law of its own being; by objective external evidence 28 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE it learns that doing involves suffering; and its moral con- viction comes to it only when forced upon it from without by a direct experience of physical evil. Of /Eschylus, the most Hebraic of the Hellenes, it is as true as of the average Greek, that in the Puritan meaning of the phrase he had no sense of sin. And even in treating of him, we must still repeat what we said at the beginning, that the Greek conception of the relation of man to the gods is external and mechanical, not inward and spiritual. § 10. Mysticism. But there is nothing so misleading as generalisation, specially on the subject of the Greeks. Again and again when we think we have laid hold of their character- istic view we are confronted with some new aspect of their life which we cannot fit into harmony with our scheme. There is no formula which will sum up that versatile and many-sided people. And so, in the case before us, we have no sooner made what appears to be the safe and comprehensive statement tliat the Greeks conceived the relation of man to the gods mechanically, than we are reminded of quite another phase uf their religion, dififerent from and even antithetic to that with which we have hitherto been concerned. Nothing, we might be inchned to say on the basis of what we have at present ascertained, nothing could be more opposed to the clear anthropomorphic vision of the Greek, than that conception of a mystic exaltation, so constcmtly occurring in the history of religion, whose aim is to transcend the limits of human personality and pass into direct communion with the divine life. Yet of some such conception, and of the ritual devised under its influence, we have un- MYSTICISM 29 doubted though fragmentary indications in the civilization of the Greeks. It is mainly in connection with the two gods Apollo and Dionysus that the phenomena in ques- tion occur; gods whose cult was introduced comparatively late into Greece and who brought with them from the north something of its formless but pregnant mystery; as though at a point the chain of guardian deities was broken, and the terror and forces of the abyss pressed in upon the charmed circle of Hellas. For Apollo, who in one of his aspects is a figure so typically Hellenic, the ever- young and beautiful god of music and the arts, was also the Power of prophetic inspiration, of ecstasy or passing out of oneself. The priestess who dehvered his oracle at Delphi was possessed and mastered by the god. Maddened by mephitic vapours streaming from a cleft in the rock, convulsed in every feature and every Hmb, she delivered in semi-articulate cries the burden of the divine message. Her own personality, for the time being, was annihilated ; the wall that parts man from god was swept away; and the Divine rushed in upon the human vessel it shattered as it filled. This conception of inspiration as a higher form of madness, possessed of a truer insight than that of sanity, was fully recognised among the Greeks. " There is a madness," as Plato puts it, "which is the special gift of heaven, and the source of the chiefest bless- ings among men. For prophecy is a madness, and the prophetess at Delphi and the priestesses at Dodona when out of their senses have conferred great benefits on Hellas, both in public and private life, but when in their senses few or none .... And in proportion as prophecy is higher and more perfect than divination both in name and reality, in the same proportion, as the ancients 30 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE testify, is madness superior to a sane mind, for the one is only of human, but the other of divine origin." * Here then, in the oracle at Delphi, the centre of the religious Hfe of the Greeks, we have an explicit affirma- tion of that element of mysticism which we might have supposed to be the most alien to their genius; and the same element re-appears, in a cruder and more barbaric form, in connection with the cult of Dionysus. He, the god of wine, was also the god of inspiration ; and the ritual with which he was worshipped was a kind of apotheosis of intoxication. To suppress for a time the ordinary work- a-day consciousness, with its tedium, its checks, its balancing of pros and cons, to escape into the directness and simplicity of mere animal life, and yet to feel in this no degradation but rather a submission to the divine power, an actual identification with the deity— such, it would seem, was the intention of those extraordinary revels of which we have in the "Bacchae" of Euripides so vivid a description. And to this end no stimulus was omitted to excite and inspire the imagination and the sense. The influence of night and torches in solitary woods, intoxicating drinks, the din of flutes and cymbals on a bass of thunderous drums, dances convulsing every limb and dazzling eyes and brain, the harking-back, as it were, to the sympathies and forms of animal life in the dress of fawnskin, the horns, the snakes twined about the arm, and the impersonation of those strange half-human creatures who were supposed to attend upon the god, the satyrs, nymphs, and fauns who formed his train — all this points to an attempt to escape from the bounds of ordinary consciousness and pass into some condition ^ Plato, Phaedrus, 244. — Jowett's translation. MYSTICISM 3 1 conceived, however confusedly, as one of union with the divine power. And though the basis, clearly enough, is physical and even bestial, yet the whole ritual does undoubtedly express, and that with a plastic grace and beauty that redeems its frank sensuality, that passion to transcend the limitations of human existence which is at the bottom of the mystic element in all religions. But this orgy of the senses was not the only form which the worship of Dionysus took in Greece. In connection with one of his legends, the myth of Dionysus Zagreus, we find traces of an esoteric doctrine, taught by what were known as the orphic sects, very curiously opposed, one would have said, to the general trend of Greek con- ceptions. According to the story, Zagreus was the son of Zeus and Persephone. Hera, in her jealousy, sent the Titans to destroy him; after a struggle, they managed to kill him, cut him up and devoured all but the heart, which was saved by Athene and carried to Zeus. Zeus Swallowed it, and produced therefrom a second Dionysus. The Titans he destroyed by lightning, and from their ashes created Man. Man is thus composed of two ele- ments, one bad, the Titanic, the other good, the Dionysiac ; the latter being derived from the body of Dionysus, which the Titans had devoured. This fundamental dualism, according to the doctrine founded on the myth, is the perpetual tragedy of man's existence; and his perpetual struggle is to purify himself of the Titanic element. The process extends over many incarnations, but an ultimate deliverance is promised by the aid of the redeemer Dionysus Lysius. The belief thus briefly described was not part of the popular religion of the Greeks, but it was a normal growth 32 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE of their consciousness, and it is mentioned here as a further indication that even in what we call the classi- cal age there were not wanting traces of the more mystic and spiritual side of religion. Here, in the tenets of these Orphic sects, we have the doctrine of " original sin," the conception of life as a struggle between two opposing principles, and the promise of an ultimate redemption by the help of the divine power. And if this be taken in connection with the universal and popular belief in inspi- ration as possession by the god, we shall see that our original statement that the relation of man to the gods was mechanical and external in the Greek conception, must at least be so far modified that it must be taken only as an expression of the central or dominant point of view, not as excluding other and even contradictory standpoints. Still, broadly speaking and admitting the limitations, the statement may stand. If the Greek popular religion be compared with that of the Christian world, the great distinction certainly emerges, that in the one the relation of God to man is conceived as mechanical and external, in the other as inward and spiritual. The point has been sufficiently illustrated, and we may turn to another division of our subject. § II. The Greek Vieiv of Death and a Future Life. Of all the problems on which we expect light to be thrown by religion none, to us, is more pressing than that of death. A fundamental, and as many believe, the most essential part of Christianity, is its doctrine of reward IHE GREEK VIEW OF DEATH AND A FUTURE LIFE 33 aod punishment in the world beyond; and a religion which had nothing at all to say about this great enigma we should hardly feel to be a religion at all. And certainly on this head the Greeks, more than any people that ever lived, must have required a consolation and a hope. Just in proportion as their life was fuller and richer than that which has been lived by any other race, just in proportion as their capacity for enjoyment, in body and soul, was keener, as their senses were finer, theii intellect broader, their passions more intense, must they have felt, with peculiar emphasis, the horror of decay and death. And such, in fact, is the characteristic note of their utterances on this theme. "Rather," says the ghost of Achilles to Odysseus in the world of shades, " rather would I live upon the soil as the hireling of another, with a landless man who had no great livelihood, than bear sway among all the dead that are no more." * Better, £is Shakespeare has it, "The weariest and most loathed worldly life That age, ache, peuury and imprisonment Can lay on nature," better that, on earth at least and in the sun, than the phantom kingdoms of the dead. The fear of age and death is the shadow of the love of life; and on no people has it fallen with more horror than on the Greeks. The tenderest of their songs of love close with a sob; and it is an autumn wind that rustles in their bowers of spring. Here, for example, is a poem by Mimnermus characteristic of this mood of the Greeks: *0d. xi 489. — Translated by Butcher and Lang, 34 1"HE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE *• O golden Love, what life, what joy but thine ? Come deatli, when thou art gone, and make an end I When gifts and tokens are no longer mine, Nor the sweet intimacies of a friend. These are the flowers of youth. But painful age The bane of beauty, following swiftly on, Wearies the heart of man with sad presage And takes away his pleasure in the sun. Hateful is he to maiden and to boy And fashioned by the gods for our annoy."* Such being the general view of the Greeks on the sub- ject of death, what has their religion to say by way of consolation ? It taught, to begin with, that the spirit does survive after death. But this survival, as it is described in the Homeric poems, is merely that of a phantom and a shade, a bloodless and colourless duplicate of the man as he lived on earth. Listen to the account Odysseus gives of his meeting with his mother's ghost. "So spake she, and I mused in my heart and would fain have embraced the spirit of my mother dead. Thrice I sprang towards her, and was minded to embrace her; thrice she flitted from my hands as a shadow or even as a dream, and sharper ever waxed the grief within me. And uttering my voice I spake to her winged words: " ' IMother mine, wherefore dost thou not tarry for me who am eager to seize thee, that even in Hades we twain may cast our arms each about the other, and satisfy us with chill lament? Is it but a phantom that the high goddess Persephone hath sent me, to the end that I may groan for more exceeding sorrow?' "So spake I, and my lady mother answered me anon:: * Munnennus, El, i. THE GREEK VIEW OF DEATH AND A FUTURE LIFE 35 " * Ah nie, my child, luckless above all men, nought doth Persephone, the daughter of Zeus, deceive thee, but even in this wise it is with mortals when they die. For the sinews no more bind together the flesh and the bones, but the force of burning fire abolishes them, so soon as the life hath left the white bones, and the spirit like a dream flies forth and hovers near.' " ^ From such a conception of the life after death little comfort could be drawn ; nor does it appear that any was sought. So far as we can trace the habitual attitude of the Greek he seems to have occupied himself little with speculation, either for good or evil, as to what might await him on the other side of the tomb. He was told indeed in his legends of a happy place for the souls of heroes, and of tonnents reserved for great criminals; but these ideas do not seem to have haunted his imagination. He was never obsessed by that close and imminent vision of heaven and hell which overshadowed and dwarfed, for the mediccval mind, the brief space of pilgrimage on earth. Rather he turned, by preference, from the thought of death back to life, and in the memory of honourable deeds in the past and the hope of fame for the future sought his compensation for the loss of youth and love. In the great funeral speech upon those who have fallen in war which Thucydides puts into the mouth of Pericles we have, we must suppose, a reflection, more accurate than is to be found elsewhere, of the position naturally adopted by the average Greek. And how simple are the topics, how broad and human, how rigorously confined to the limits of experience! There is no suggestion anywhere of a *0d. xi. 204. — Translated by Butcher and Lang. 36 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE personal existence continued after death; the dead live only in their deeds ; and only by memory are the survivors to be consoled. " I do not now commiserate the parents of the dead who stand here ; I would rather comfort them. You know that your life has been passed amid manifold vicissitudes; and that they may be deemed fortunate who have gained most honour, whether an honourable death like theirs, or an honourable sorrow like yours, and whose days have been so ordered that the term of their happiness is likewise the term of their life . . . Some of you are at an age at which they may hope to have other children, and they ought to bear their sorrow better; not only will the children who may hereafter be born make them forgot their now lost ones, but the city will be doubly a gainer. She will not be left desolate, and she will be safer. For a man's counsels cannot be of equal weight or worth, when he alone has no children to risk in the general danger. To those of you who have passed their prime, I say : ' Congratulate yourselves that you have been happy during the greater part of your days ; remember that your life of sorrow will not last long, and be comforted by the glory of those who are gone. For the love of honour alone is ever young, and not riches, as some say, but honour is the delight of men when they are old and useless.'"* The passage perhaps represents what we may call the typical attitude of the Greek. To seek consolation for death, if anywhere, then in life, and in life not as it might be imagined beyond the grave, but as it had been and would be lived on earth, appears to be consonant with all that we know of the clear and objective temper of *Thuc. II. 44. — Jowett's translation. THE GREEK VIEW OF DEATH AND A FUTURE LIFE 37 the race. It is the spirit which was noted long ago by Goethe as inspiring the sepulchral monuments of Athens. "The wind," he says, "which blows from the tombs of the ancients comes with gentle breath as over a mound of roses. The rehefs are touching and pathetic, and always represent Hfe. There stand father and mother, their son between them, gazing at one another with unspeakable truth to nature. Here a pair clasp hands. Here a father seems to rest on his couch and wait to be entertained by his family. To me the presence of these scenes was very touching. Their art is of a late period, yet are they simple, natural, and of universal interest. Here there is no knight in harness on his knees awaiting a joyful resurrection. The artist has with more or less skill pre- sented to us only the persons themselves, and so made their existence lasting and perpetual. They fold not their hands, gaze not into heaven; they are on earth, what they were and what they are. They stand side by side, take interest in one another; and that is what is in the stone, even though somewhat unskilfully, yet most pleasingly depicted."^ As a further illustration of the same point an epitaph may be quoted equally striking for its simple human feeling and for its absence of any suggestion of a conti- nuance of the life of the dead. " Farewell" is the first and last word; no hint of a "joyful resurrection." " Farewell, tomb of Melite ; the best of women lies here, who loved her loving husband, Onesimus ; thou wert most excellent, wherefore he longs for thee after thy 'From Goethe's " Italienische Reise." I take this translation (by permission) from Percy Gardner's " New Chapters in Greek History", p. 319. 4 38 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE death, for thou wert the best of wives.— Farewell, thou too, dearest husband, only love my children."^ But however characteristic this attitude of the Greeks may appear to be, especially by contrast with the Christian view, it would be a mistake to suppose that it was the only one with which they were acquainted, or that they had put aside altogether, as indifierent or insoluble, the whole problem of a future world. As we have seen, they did beheve in the survival of the spirit, and in a world of shades ruled by Pluto and Persephone. They had legends of a place of bliss for the good and a place of torment for the wicked ; and if this conception did not haunt their mind, as it haunted that of the mediaeval Christian, yet at times it was certainly present to them, with terror or with hope. That the Greek was not unacquainted with the fear of hell we know from the passage of Plato, part of which we have already quoted, where in speaking of the mendicant prophets who professed to make atonement for sin he says that their ministrations " are equally at the service of the living and the dead ; the latter sort they call mysteries, and they re- deem us from the pains of hell, but if we neglect them no one knows what awaits us."* And on the other hand we hear, as early as the date of the Odyssey, of the Elysian fields reserved for the souls of the favourites of the gods. The Greeks, then, were not without hope and fear conceminor the worid to come, however little these feeUngs may have coloured their daily life; and there was one phase of their religion, which appears to have been specially occupied with this theme. In almost 'Percy Gardner. "New Chapters in Greek History," p. 325. • Plato, Rep. n. 364 e. — ^Jowett's translation. THE GREEK VIEW OF DEATH AND A FUTURE LIFE 39 every Greek city we hear of " mysteries", the most cele- brated being, of course, those of Eleusis in Attica. What exactly these "mysteries" were we are very imperfectly informed; but so much, at least, is clear that by means of a scenic symbolism, representing the myth of Demeter and Kore or of Dionysus Zagreus, hopes were held out to the initiated not only of a happy life on earth, but of a happy immortality beyond. " Blessed," says Pindar, " blessed is he who has seen these things before he goes under the hollow earth. He knows the end of life, and he knows its god-given origin." And it is presumably to the initiated that the same poet promises the joys of his thoroughly Greek heaven. " For them," he says, " shineth below the strength of the sun while in our world it is night, and the space of crimson- flowered meadows before their city is full of the shade of frank- incense-trees, and of fruits of gold. And some in horses, and in bodily feats, and some in dice, and some in harp- playing have delight; and among them thriveth all fair- flowering bliss; and fragrance streameth ever through the lovely land, as they mingle incense of every kind upon the altars of the gods." ^ The Greeks, then, were not unfamiliar with the conception of heaven and hell: only, and that is the point to which we must return and on which we must insist, the con- ception did not dominate and obsess their mind. They may have had their spasms of terror, but these they could easily relieve by the performance of some atoning ceremony; they may have had their thrills of hope, but these they would only indulge at the crisis of some imposing ritual. *Piudar, Thren. I,-~ Translation by E. Myers. 40 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE The general tenor of their life does not seem to have been allected by speculations about the world beyond. Of age indeed and of death they had a horror pro- portional to their acute and sensitive enjoyment of life; but their natural impulse was to turn for consolation to the interests and achievements of the world they knew, and to endeavour to soothe, by memories and hopes of deeds future and past, the inevitable pains of failure and decay. §12. Critical and Sceptical Opinio?i in Greece. And now let us turn to a point for which perhaps some readers have long been waiting, and with which they may have expected us to begin rather than to end. So far, in considering the part played by religion in Greek Life, we have assumed the position of orthodoxy. We have endeavoured to place ourselves at the standpoint of the man who did not ciiticise or reflect, but accepted simply, as a matter of course, the tradition handed down to him by his fathers. Only so, if at all, was it possible for us to detach ourselves from our habitual preconceptions, and to regard the pagan mythology not as a graceful invention of the poets, but as a serious and, at the time, a natural and inevit- able way of looking at the world. Now, however, it is time to turn to the other side, and to consider the Greek religion as it appeared to contemporary critics. For critics there were, and sceptics, or rather, to put it more exactly, there was a critical age succeeding an age of faith. As we trace, however imperfectly, the development of the Greek mind, we can observe their intellect and their moral sense expanding beyond the limits of their creed. Either as sympathetic, though candid, friends, or CRITICAL AND SCEPTICAL OPINION IN GREECE 41 as avowed enemies, they bring to light its contradictions and defects; and as a result of the process one of two things happens. Either the ancient conception of the gods is transformed in the direction of monotheism, or it is altogether swept away, and a new system of the world built up, on the basis of natural science or of philosophy. These tendencies of thought we must now endeavour to trace; for we should have formed but an imperfect idea of the scope of the religious consciousness of the Greeks if we confined ourselves to what we may call their ortho- dox faith. It is in their most critical tliinkers, in Euripides and Plato, that the religious sense is most fully and keenly developed; and it is in the philosophy that supervened upon the popular creed, rather than in the popular creed itself, tliat we shall find the highest and most spiritual reaches of their thought. Let us endeavour, then, in the first place to realise to ourselves how the Greek religion must have appeared to one who approached it not from the side of unthinking acquiescence, but with the idea of discovering for himself how far it really met the needs and claims of the intellect and the moral sense. Let us imagine him turning to his Homer, to those poems which were the Bible of the Greek, his ultimate appeal both in religion and in ethics; which were taught in the schools, quoted in the law-courts, recited in the streets; and from which the teacher drew his moral instances, the rhetorician his allusions, the artist his models, every man his conception of the gods. Let us imagine some candid and ingenuous youth, turning to his Homer and repeating, say, the followiiig passage of the Iliad:— "Among the other gods fell grievous bitter strife, and 42 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE their hearts were carried diverse in their breasts. And they clashed together with a great noise, and the wide earth groaned, and the clarion of great Heaven rang around. Zeus heard as he sate upon Olympus, and his heart within him laughed pleasantly when he beheld that strife of the gods." ^ At this point, let us suppose, the reader pauses to re- flect; and is struck, for the first time, with a shock of surprise by the fact that the gods should be not only many but opposed ; and opposed on what issue ? a purely human one! a war between Greeks and Trojans for the possession of a beautiful woman ! Into such a contest the immortal gods descend, fight with human weapons, and dispute in human terms ! Where is the single purpose that should mark the divine will ? where the repose of the wisdom that fore- ordained and knows the end ? Not, it is clear, in this modey array of capricious and passionate wills ! Then, perhaps, in Zeus, Zeus, who is lord of all ? He, at least, will impose upon this mob of recalcitrant deities the harmony which the pious soul demands. He, whose rod shakes the sky, will arise and assert the law. He, in his majesty, will speak the words — alas! what words! Let us take them straight from the lips of the King of gods and men: — "Hearken to me, all gods and all ye goddesses, that I may tell you that my heart within my breast commandeth me. One thing let none essay, be it goddess or be it god, to wit, to thwart my saying; approve ye it all together, that with all speed I may accomplish these things. Whomsoever I shall perceive minded to go, apart from the gods, to succour Trojans or Danaans, chastened in no seemly wise shall he return to Olympus, or I will take 'Iliad xxi. 385. — Translated by Lang, I^af and Myers, CRITICAL AND SCEPTICAL OPINION IN GREECE 43 and cast him into misty Tartaros, right far away, where ts the deepest gulf beneath the earth; there are the gate of iron and threshold of bronze, as far beneath Hades as heaven is high above the earth: then shall ye know how far I am mightiest of all gods. Go to now, ye gods, make trial that ye all may know. Fasten ye a rope of gold from heaven, and all ye gods lay hold thereof and all goddesses; yet could ye not drag from heaven to earth Zeus, counsellor supreme, not though ye toiled sore. But once I likewise were minded to draw with all my heart, then should I draw ye up with very earth and sea withal. Thereafter would I bind the rope about a pinnacle of Olympus, and so should all those things be hung in air. By so much am I beyond gods and beyond men."* And is that all ? In the divine tug of war Zeus is more than a match for all the other gods together! Is it on this that the lordship of heaven and earth depends ? This that we are to worship as highest, we of the brain and heart and soul? And even so, even admitting the ground of supremacy, with what providence or consistency of purpose is it exercised ? Why, Zeus himself is as capricious as the rest! Because Thetis comes whining to him about an insult put upon Achilles, he interferes to change the whole course of the war, and that too by means of a lying dream! Even his own direct decrees he can hardly be induced to observe. His son Sarpedon, for example, who is "fated," as he says himself, to die, he is yet at the last moment in half a mind to save alive! How is such division possible in the will of the supreme god? Or is the "fate" of which he speaks sr^mething outsids himself? But if so, then *Iliad viii. ^. — Translated by Lang, Leaf and Myers. 44 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE above him! and if above him, what is he? Not, after all, the highest, not the supreme at all! What then an we to worship? What is this higher "fate?" Such would be the kind of questions that would vex our candid youth when he approached his Homer from the side of theology. Nor would he fare any better if he took the ethical point of view. The gods, he would find, who should surely at least attain to the human standard, not only are capable of every phase of passion, anger, fear, jealousy and, above all, love, but indulge them all with a verve and an abandonment that might make the boldest libertine pause. Zeus himself, for example, expends upon the mere catalogue of his amours a good twelve lines of hexameter verse. No wonder that Kera is jealous, and that her lord is driven to put her down in terms better suited to the lips of mortal husbands: — " Lady, ever art thou imagining, nor can I escape thee ; yet shalt thou in no wise have power to fulfil, but wilt be the further from my heart; that shall be even the worse for thee. Hide thou in silence and hearken to my bidding, lest all the gods that are in Olympus keep not off from thee my visitation, when I put forth my hands unapproachable against thee."' § I J. Ethical Criticism. The incongruity of all this with any adequate conception of deity is patent, if once the critical attitude be adopted; and it was adopted by some of the clearest and most religious minds of Greece. Nay, even orthodoxy itself did not refrain from a genial and sympathetic criticism. Aristophanes, for example, who, if there had been an » Iliad i. 560. — Translated by Leaf, Lang and Myers. ETHICAL CRITICISM 45 established church, would certainly have been described as one of its main pillars, does not scruple to represent his Birds as issuing — " A warning and notices, formally given. To Jove, and all others residing in heaven, Forbidding them ever to venture again To trespass on our atmospheric domain, With scandalous journeys, to ^^sit a list Of Alcmenas and Semeles; if they persist, "We warn them that means will be taken moreover To stop their gallanting and acting the lover,"* and Heracles the glutton, and Dionysus, the dandy and the coward, are familiar figures of his comic stage. The attitude of Aristophanes, it is tnie, is not really critical, but sympathetic; it was no more his intention to injure the popular creed by his fun than it is the intention of the cartoons of Punch to undermine the reputation of our leading statesmen. On the contrary, nothing popu- larises like genial ridicule; and of this Aristophanes was well aware. But the same characteristics of the godr which suggested the friendly burlesque of the comedian were also those which provoked the indignation and the disgust of more serious minds. The poet Pindar, for example, after referring to the story of a battle, in which it was said gods had fought against gods, breaks out into protest against a legend so httle creditable to the divine nature : — " O my mouth, fling this tale from thee, for to speak evil of gods is a hateful wisdom, and loud and unmeasured words strike a note that trembleth upon ^ Aristophanes, " Birds " 556. — Translation by Frere. 46 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE madness. Of such things talk thou not; leave war and all strife of immortals aside." ^ And the same note is taken up with emphasis, and reiterated in every quality of tone, by such writers as Euripides and Plato. The attitude of Euripides towards the popular religion is so clearly and frankly critical that a recent writer has even gone so far as to maintain that his main object in the construction of his dramas was to discredit the myths he selected for his theme. However that may have been, it is beyond controversy true that the deep religious sense of this most modern of the Greeks was puzzled and repelled by the tales he was bound by tradition to drama- tize; and that he put into the mouth of his characters reflexions upon the conduct of the gods which if they may not be taken as his own deliberate opinions, are at least expressions of one aspect of his thought. It was, in fact, impossible to reconcile with a profound and philosophic view of the divine nature the intrigues and amours, partialities, antipathies, actions and counter-actions of these anthropomorphic deities. Consider, for example, the most famous of all the myths, that of Orestes, to which we have already referred. Orestes, it will be re- membered, was the son of Agamemnon and Clytemnes- tra. Agamemnon, on his return from Troy, was murdered by Clytemnestra. Orestes escapes; but returns later, at the instigation of Apollo, and kills his mother to avenge his father. Thereupon, in punishment for his crime, he is persecuted by the Furies. Now the point which Euripides seizes here is the conduct of Apollo. Either it was right for Orestes to kill his mother, or it was wrong. If wrong, why did Apollo command it? If right, why 'Find. 01. IX 54.— Translation by E. Myers. ETHICAL CRITICISM 47 was Orestes punished ? Or are there, as -^schylus would have it, two " rights", one of Apollo, the other of the Furies ? If so, what becomes of that unity of the divine law after which every religious nature seeks? " Phoebus," cries the Orestes of Euripides, " prophet though he be, deceived me. I gave him my all, I killed my mother in obedience to his command ; and in return I am undone myself."^ The dilemma is patent; and Euripides makes no serious attempt to meet it. Or again, to take another example, less familiar, but even more to the point — the tale of Ion and Creusa. Creusa has been seduced by Apollo and has borne him a child, the Ion of the story. This child she exposes, and it is conveyed by Hermes to Delphi, where at last it is found, and recognised by the mother, and a conventionally happy ending is patched up. But the point on which the poet has insisted throughout is, once more, the conduct of Apollo. What is to be made of a god who seduces and deserts a mortal woman; who suffers her to expose her child, and leaves her in ignorance of its fate ? Does he not deserve the reproaches heaped upon him by his victim? — "Child of Latona, I cry to the sun — I will publish thy shame! Thou with thy tresses a-shimmer with gold, through the flowers as I came Plucking the crocuses, heaping my veil with their gold- litten flame, Cam'st on me, caughtest the poor pallid wrists of mine hands, and didst hale Unto thy couch in the cave. 'Mother! mother!' I shrieked out my v^ail — ' jLuripides, Iph. Taur. 711, 48 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE Wroughtest the pleasure of Kypris; no shame made the god-lover quail. Wretched I bare thee a child, and I cast him with shuddering throe Forth on thy couch where thou forccdst tliy victim, a bride-bed of woe. Lost — my poor baby and thine! for the eagles devoured him : and lo ! Victory-songs to thy lyre dost thou chant! — Ho, I call to thee, son Born to Latuna, Dispenser of boding, on gold-gleaming throne Midmost of earth who art sitting: — thine ears shall be pierced with my moan ! Thy Delos doth hate thee, thy bay-boughs abhor thee, By the palm-tree of feathery fiondagc that rose Where in sacred travail Latona bore thee In Zeus's garden close." » This is a typical example of the kind of critici?m which Euripides conveys through the lips of his characters on the stage. And the points which he can only dramati- cally suggest, Plato expounds directly in his own person. The quarrel of the philosopher with the myths is not that they are not true, but that they arc not edifying. They represent the son in rebellion against the father — Zeus against Kronos, Kronos against Uranos ; they describe the gods as intriguing and fighting one against the other; they depict them as changing their form divine into the semblance of mortal men ; lastly — culmination of horror I — they represent them as laughing, positively laughing! — Or again, to turn to a more metaphysical point, if God be good, it is argued » Euripid. Ion. 885.— -Translated by A. S. Way. TRANSITION TO MONOTHEISM 49 by Plato, he caiinot be the author of evil. What then, are we to make of the passage in Homer where he says, "two urns stand upon the floor of Zeus filled with his evil gifts, and one with blessings. To whomsoever Zeus whose joy is in the lightning dealeth a mingled lot, that man chanceth now upon ill and now again on good, but to whom he giveth but of the bad kind, him he bringeth to scorn, and evil famine chaseth him over the goodly earth, and he is a wanderer honoured of neither gods nor men."* And again, if God be true, he cannot be the author of lies. How then could he have sent, as we are told he did, lying dreams to men?— Clearly, concludes the phi- losopher, our current legends need revision; in the interest of religion itself we must destroy the myths of the popular creed. § j^. Transition to Monotheism. The myths, but not religion! The criticism certainly of Plato and probably of Euripides was prompted by the desire not to discredit altogether the belief in the gods, but to bring it into harmony with the requirements of a more fully developed consciousness. The philosopher and the poet came not to destroy, but to fulfil; not to annihi- late but to transform the popular theology. Such an intention, strange as it may appear to us with our rigid creeds, we shall see to be natural enough to the Greek mind, when we remember that the material of their reli- gion was not a set of propositions, but a more or less indeterminate body of traditions capable of being presented in the most various forms as the genius and taste of individual poets might direct. And we find, in fact, tha* »I1. xxiv. 527. — ^Translated by Lang, Leaf and Myers. 50 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE the most religious poets of Greece, those even who were most innocent of any intention to innovate on popular beliefs, did nevertheless unconsciously tend to transform, in accordance with their own conceptions, the whole stmcture of the Homeric theology. Taking over the legends of gods and heroes, as narrated in poetry and tradition, the earlier tragedians, -^schylus and Sophocles, as they shaped and reshaped their material for the stage, were evolving for themselves, not in opposition to but as it were on the top of the polytheistic view, the idea of a single supreme and righteous God. The Zeus of Homer, whose superiority, as we saw, was based on physical force, grows, under the hands of ^schylus, into something akin to the Jewish Jehovah. The inner experience of the poet drives him inevitably to this transformation. Born into the great age of Greece, coming to maturity at the crisis of her fate, he had witnessed with his own eyes, and assisted with his own hands the defeat of the Persian host at Marathon. The event struck home to him like a judgment from heaven. The Nemesis that attends upon human pride, the vengeance that follows crime, henceforth were the thoughts that haunted and possessed his brain; and under their influence he evolved for himself out of the popular idea of Zeus the conception of a God of justice who marks and avenges crime. Read for example the following passage from the " Agamemnon " and con- trast it with the lines of Homer quoted on page 42. Nothing could illustrate more strikingly the transformation that could be effected, under the conditions of the Greek religion, in the whole conception of the divine power by one whose conscious intention, nevertheless, was not to innovate but to conserve. TRANSITION TO MONOTHEISM 51 "Zeus the high God! Whate'er be dim in doubt, This can our thought track out — The blow that fells the sinner is of God, And as he wills, the rod Of vengeance smiteth sore. One said of old 'The Gods list not to hold A reckoning with him whose feet oppress The grace of holiness' — An impious word! for whensoe'er tlie sire Breathed forth rebellious fire — What time his household overflows the measure Of bliss and health and treasure — His children's children read the reckoning plain, At last, in tears and pain. % * >ii * * Who spurns the shrine of Right, nor wealth nor poweK Shall be to him a tower, To guard him from the gulf: there lies his lot. Where all tilings are forgot. Lust drives him on — lust, desperate and wild Fate's sin-contriving child — And cure is none; beyond concealment clear Kindles sin's baleful glare. As an ill coin beneath the wearing touch Betrays by stain and smutch Its metal false — such is the sinful wight. Before, on pinions light. Fair pleasure flits, and lures him childlike on, While home and kin make moan Beneath the grinding burden of his crime; Till, in the end of time. Cast down of heaven, he pours forth fruitless prayer To powers that will not hear." * ' ^sch. Agamem. 367. — Translated by E. D. A. Morshcad ("The House of Atreus"). 52 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE And Sophocles follows in the same path. For him too Zeus is no longer the god of physical strength; he is the creator and sustainer of the moral law— of "those laws of range sublime, called into life throughout the high clear heaven, whose father is Olympus alone; their parent was no race of mortal men, no, nor shall oblivion ever lay them to sleep; a mighty god is in them, and he grows not old." ^ Such words imply a complete transformation of the Homeric conception of Divinity; a transformation made indeed in the interests of religion, but involving nevertheless, and contrary, no doubt, to the intention of its authors, a complete subversion of the popular creed. Once grant the idea of God as an eternal and moral Power and the whole fabric of polytheism falls away. The religion of the Greeks, as interpreted by their best minds, annihi- lates itself Zeus indeed is saved, but only at the cost of all Olympus. § 75. Metaphysical Criticism, While thus, on the one hand, the Greek religion by its inner evolution, was tending to destroy itself, on the other hand it was threatened from without by the attack of what we should call the "scientific spirit." A system so frankly anthropomorphic was bound to be weak on the speculative side. Its appeal, as we have seen, was rather to the imagination than to the intellect, by the presentation of a series of beautiful images, whose contemplation might offer to the mind if not satisfaction, at least acquiescence and repose. A Greek who was not too inquisitive was thus enabled to move through the calendar of splendid festivals and fasts, charmed by the beauty of the ritual, ' Soph. O. T. 865.— Translated by Dr. Jebb. METAPHYSICAL CRITICISM 53 inspired by the chorus and the dance, and drawing from the famihar legends the moral and aesthetic significance with which he had been accustomed from his boyhood to connect them, but without ever raising the question, Is all this true? Does it really account for the existence and nature of the world? Once, however, the spell was broken, once the intellect was aroused, the inadequacy of the popular faith, on the speculative side, became apparent ; and the mind turned aside altogether from religion to work out its problems on its own lines. We find accordingly, from early times, physical philosophers in Greece free from all theological preconceptions, raising from the very beginning the question of the origin of the world, and offering solutions, various indeed but all alike in this, that they frankly accept a materialistic basis. One derives all things from water, another from air, another from fire; one insists upon unity, another on a plurality of elements ; but all alike reject the supernatural, and proceed on the lines of physical causation. The opposition, to use the modem phrase, between science and religion, was thus developed early in ancient Greece; and by the fifth century it is clear that it had become acute. The philosopher Anaxagoras was driven from Athens as an atheist; the same charge, absurdly enough, was one of the counts in the indictment of Socrates; and the physical speculations of the time are a favourite butt of that champion of orthodoxy, Aristo- phanes. To follow up these speculations in detail would be to wander too far from our present puq)ose; but it may be worth while to quote a passage from the great comedian, to illustrate not indeed the value of the theories ridiculed, but their generally materialistic character, and 5 54 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE their antagonism to the popular faith. The passage selected is part of a dialogue between Socrates and Strepsiades, one of his pupils ; and it is introduced by an address from the chorus of " Clouds", the new divinities of the physicist: CnoRUS OF Clouds. Our welcome to thee, old man, who would see the marvels that science can show : And thou, the high-priest of this subtlety feast, say what would you have us bestow ? Since there is not a sage for whom we'd engage our wonders more freely to do, Except, it may be, for Prodicus : he for his knowledge may claim them, but you, Because as you go, you glance to and fro, and in dignified arro- gance float; And think shoes a disgrace, and put on a grave face, your acquaintance with us to denote. Strepsiades. Oh earth ! what a sound, how august and profound ! it fills me with wonder and awe. Socrates. These, these then alone, for true Deities own, the rest are all God-ships of straw. Streps. Let Zeus be left out: He's a God beyond doubt; come, that you can scarcely deny. SOCR. Zeus indeed! there's no Zeus: don't you be so obtuse. Streps. No Zeus up above in the sky? Then you first must explain, who it is sends the rain ; or I really must think you are wrong. SoCR. Well then, be it known, these send it alone: I can prove it by argument strong. METAPHYSICAL CRITICISM 5^ "Was there ever a shower seen to fall in an hour when the sky was all cloudless and blue? Yet on a fine day, when the clouds are away, he might send one, according to you. Streps. Well, it must be confessed, that chimes in with the rest: your words I am forced to believe. Yet before I had dreamed tliat the rain-water streamed from Zeus and his chamber-pot sieve. But whence then, my friend, does the thunder descend ? that does make us quake with affright! SocR. Why, 'tis they, I declare, as they roll through the air. Streps. What the clouds ? did I hear you aright ? SoCR. Ay : for when to the brim filled with water they swim, by Necessity carried along. They are hung up on high in the vault of the sky, and so by Necessity strong In the midst of their course, they clash with great force, and thunder away without end. Streps. But is it not He who compels this to be ? does not Zeus this Necessity send? SocR. No Zeus have we there, but a vortex of air. Streps. What ! Vortex ? that's something I own. I knew not before, that Zeus was no more, but Vortex was placed on his throne! But I have not yet heard to what cause you referred the thun- der's majestical roar. SocR. Yes, 'tis they, when on high full of water they fly, and then, af I told you before, 5 6 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE By compression impelled, as they clash, are compelled a terrible clatter to make. Streps. Come, how can that be? I really don't see. SocR. Yourself as my proof I will take. Have you never then ate the broth puddings you get when the Panathenaea come round, And felt with what might your bowels all night in turbulent tumult resound Streps. By Apollo, 'tis true, there's a mighty to do, and my belly keeps rumbling about; And the puddings begin to clatter within and to kick up a won- derful rout: Quite gently at first, papapax, papapax, but soon papappappax away. Till at last, I'll be bound, I can thunder as loud papapappap- pappappax as they. SocR. Shalt thou then c, sound so loud and profound from thy belly diminutive send. And shall not the high and the infinite sky go thundering on without end? For both, you will find, on an impulse of wind and similar causes depend. Streps. Well, but tell me from whom comes the bolt through the gloom, with its awful and terrible flashes; And wherever it turns, some it singes and burns, and some it reduces to ashes : For this 'tis quite plain, let who will send the rain, that Zeus against peijurers dashes Socr.. And how, you old fool, of a dark-ages school, and an antidilu- vian wit, METAPHYSICAL CRITICISM 57 If the perjured they strike, and not all men alike, have they never Cleonymus hit? Then of Simon again, and Theorus explain : known perjurers, yet they escape. But he smites his own shrine with these arrows divine, and "Sunium, Attica's cape," And the ancient gnarled oaks: now what prompted those strokes? They never forswore I should say. Streps. Can't say that they do : your words appear true. Whence comes then the thunderbolt, pray? SoCR. When a wind that is dry, being lifted on high, is suddenly pent into these, It swells up their skin, like a bladder, within, by Necessity's changeless decrees: Till compressed very tight, it bursts them outright, and awaj with an impulse so strong. That at last by the force and the swing of the course, it takes fire as it whizzes along. Streps. That's exactly the thing, that I suffered one spring, at tlie great feast of Zeus, I admit : I'd a paunch in the pot, but I wholly forgot about making the safety-valve slit. So it spluttered and swelled, while the saucepan I held, till at last with a vengeance it flew: Took me quite by surprise, dung-bespattered my eyes, and scalded my face black and blue 1 * Nothing could be more amusing than this passage as a burlesque of the physical theories of the time; and nothing could better illustrate the quarrel between science and religion, as it presents itself on the surface to the ' Aristoph. "Clouds" 358. — Translation by B. B. Rogers. 58 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE plain man. But there is more in the quarrel than appears at first sight. The real sting of the comedy from which we have quoted lies in the assumption, adopted throughout the play, that the atheist is also necessarily anti-social and immoral. The physicist, in the person of Socrates, is identified with the sophist; on the one hand he is re- presented as teaching the theory of material causation, on the other the art of lying and deceit. The object. of Strepsiades in attending the school is to learn how not to pay his debts; the achievement of his son is to learn how to dishonour his father. The cult of reason is identi- fied by the poet with the cult of self-interest; the man who does not believe in tlie gods cannot, he implies, believe in the family or the state. § i6. metaphysical Recofistruction — Plato. The argument is an old one into whose merits this is not the place to enter. But one thing is certain, that the sceptical spirit which was invading religion, was in- vading also politics and ethics ; and that towards the close of the fifth century before Christ, Greece and in particular Athens was overrun by philosophers, who not only did not scruple to question the foundations of social and moral obligation, but in some cases explicitly taught that there were no foundations at all ; that all law was a convention based on no objective truth; and that the only valid right was the natural right of the strong to rule. It was into this chaos of sceptical opinion that Plato was bom; and it was the desire to meet and subdue it that was the motive of his philosophy. Like Aristophanes, he traced the root of the evil to the decay of religious belief; and though no one, as we have seen, was more trenchant than he in his METAPHYSICAL RECONSTRUCTION— PLATO 59 criticism of the popular faith, no one, on the other hand, was more convinced of the necessity of some form of religion as a basis for any stable polity. The doctrine of the physi- cists, he asserts, that the world is the result of "nature and chance " has immediate and disastrous effects on the whole structure of social beliefs. The conclusion inevitably follows that human laws and institutions, like everything else, are accidental products ; that they have no objective vaHdity, no binding force on the will; and that the only right that has any intelligible meaning is the right which is identical with might. ^ Against these conclusions the whole soul of Plato rose in revolt. To reconstruct religion, he was driven back upon metaphysics; and elaborated at last the system which from his day to our own has not ceased to perplex and fascinate the world, and whose rare and radiant combination of gifts, speculative, artistic, and religious, marks the highest reach of the genius of the Greeks, and perhaps of mankind. To attempt an analysis of that system would lead us far from our present task. All that concerns us here, is its religious significance; and of that, all we can note is that Plato, the deepest thinker of the Greeks, was also among the farthest removed from the popular faith. The principle from which he derives the World is the absolute Good, or God, of whose ideas the phenomena of sense are imperfect copies. To the divine intelligence man by virtue of his reason is akin. But the reason in him has fallen into bondage of the flesh ; and it is the task of his life on earth, or rather of a series of lives (for Plato be- lieved in successive re-incarnations), to deliver this diviner element of his soul, and set it free to re-unite with God. »See e^. Plato's "Laws". X. 887. 6o THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE To the description of the divine life thus prepared for the soul, from which she fell but to which she may return, Plato has devoted some of his finest passages; and if we are to indicate, as we are bound to do, the highest point to which the religious consciousness of the Greeks attained, we must not be deterred, by dread of the obscurity ne- cessarily attaching to an extract, from a citation from the most impassioned of his dialogues. Speaking of that " divine madness," to which we have already had occasion to refer, he says that this is the madness which "is imputed to him who, when he sees the beauty of earth, is transported with the recollection of the true beauty; he would hke to fly away, but he cannot; he is like a bird fluttering and looking upward and careless of the world below; and he is therefore thought to be mad. And I have shown this of all inspirations to be the noblest and highest and the off"-spring of the highest to him who has or shares in it, and that he who loves the beautiful is called a lover because he partakes of it. For every soul of man has in the way of nature beheld true being ; this was the condition of her passing into the form of man. But all souls do not easily recall the things of the other world; they may have seen them for a short time only, or they may have been unfortunate in their earthly lot, and havmg had their hearts turned to unrighteousness through some corrupting influence, they may have lost the memory of the holy things which once they saw. Few only retain an adequate remembrance of them; and they, when they behold here any image of that other world, are rapt in amazement; but they are ignorant of what that rapture means, because they do not clearly perceive. For there is no clear light of justice or temperance, or any of the higher ideas SUMMARY 6 1 which are precious to souls, in the earthly copies of them : they are seen through a glass dimly; and there are few who, going to the images, behold in them the realities, and these only with difficulty. There was a time when, with the rest of the happy band, they saw beauty shining in brightness — we philosophers following in the train of Zeus, others in company with other gods ; and then we beheld the beatific vision and were initiated into a mystery which may be truly called most blessed, cele- brated by us in our state of innocence, before we had any expe- rience of evils to come, when we were admitted to the sight of apparitions innocent and simple and calm and happy, which we beheld shining in pure light, pure ourselves and not yet en- shrined in that living tomb which we carry about, now that we are imprisoned in the body, like an oyster in his shell. Let me linger over the memory of scenes which have passed away." * ^ ly. Summary. At this point, where religion passes into philosophy, the discussion which has occupied the present chapter must close. So far it was necessary to proceed, in order to show how wide was the range of the religious conscious- ness of the Greeks, and through how many points of view it passed in the course of its evolution. But its development was away from the Greek and towards the Christian; and it will therefore be desirable, in conclusion, to fix once more in our minds that central and primary phase of the Greek religion under the influence of which their civilisation was formed into a character definite and distinct in the history of the world. This phase will be the one which underlay and was reflected in the actual cult and institutions of Greece and must therefore be regarded not as a product » Plato, Phaedrus. 249d. — Jowett's translation. 62 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE of critical and self-conscious thought, but as an imaginative way of conceiving the world stamped as it were passively on the mind by the whole course of concrete experience. Of its character we have attempted to give some kind of account in the earlier part of this chapter, and we have now only to summarise what was there said. The Greek religion, then, as we saw, in this its char- acteristic phase, involved a belief in a number of deities who on the one hand were personifications of the powers of nature and of the human soul, on the other the founders and sustainers of civil society. To the operations of these beings the whole of experience was referred, and that, not merely in an abstract and unintelligible way, as when we say that the world was created by God, but in a quite precise and definite sense, the action of the gods being conceived to be the same in kind as that of man, proceeding from similar motives, directed to similar ends, and accom- plished very largely by similar, though much superior means. By virtue of this uncritical and unreflective mode of ap- prehension the Greeks, we said, were made at home in the world. Their religion suffused and transformed the facts both of nature and of society, interpreting what would otherwise have been unintelligible by the idea of an activity which they could understand because it was one which they were constantly exercising themselves. Being thus supplied with a general explanation of the world, they could put aside the question of its origin and end, and devote themselves freely and fully to the art of living, unhampered by scruples and doubts as to the nature of life. Consciousness similar to their own was the ulti- mate fact; and there was nothing therefore with which they might not form intelligible and harmonious relations. SUMMARY 63 And as on the side of metaphysics they were delivered from the perplexities of speculation, so on the side of ethics they were undisturbed by the perplexities of con- science. Their religion, it is true, had a bearing on theii conduct, but a bearing, as we saw, external and mecha- nical. If they sinned they might be punished directly by physical evil; and from this evil religion might redeem them by the appropriate ceremonies of purgation. But on the other hand they were not conscious of a spiritual relation to God, of sin as an alienation from the divine power and repentance as the means of restoration to grace. The pangs of conscience, the fears and hopes, the triumph and despair of the soul which were the preoccupations of the Puritan, were phenomena unknown to the ancient Greek. He lived and acted undisturbed by scrupulous introspection; and the function of his religion was rather to quiet the con- science by ritual than to excite it by admonition and reproof. From both these points of view, the metaphysical and the ethical, the Greeks were brought by their religion into harmony with the world. Neither the perplexities of the intellect nor the scruples of the conscience intervened to hamper their free activity. Their life was simple, straight- forward and clear; and their consciousness directed out- wards upon the world, not perplexedly absorbed in the contemplation of itself. On the other hand, this harmony which was the essence of the Greek civilisation, was a temporary compromise, not a final solution. It depended on presumptions of the imagination, not on convictions of the intellect; and as we have seen, it destroyed itself by the process of its own development. The beauty, the singleness, and the freedom which attracts us in the consciousness of the Greek was 64 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE the result of a poetical view of the world, which did but anticipate in imagination an ideal that was not realised in fact or in thought. It depended on the assumption of anthropomorphic gods, an assmnption which could not stand before the criticism of reason, and either broke down into scepticism, or was developed into the con- ception of a single supreme and spiritual power. And even apart from this internal evolution, from this subversion of its ideal basis, the harmony established by the Greek religion was at the best but partial and incom- plete. It was a harmony for life, but not for death. The more completely the Greek felt himself to be at home in the world, the more happily and freely he abandoned himself to the exercise of his powers, the more intensely and vividly he lived in action and in passion, the more alien, bitter, and incomprehensible did he find the pheno- mena of age and death. On this problem, so far as we can judge, he received from his religion but little light, and still less consolation. The music of his brief life closed with a discord uiuresolved ; and even before reason had brought her criticism to bear upon his creed, its deficiency was forced upon him by his feeling. Thus the harmony which we have indicated as the characteristic result of the Greek religion contained none of the conditions of completeness or finality. For on the one hand there were elements which it was never able to include; and on the other, its hold even over those which it embraced was temporary and precarious. The eating of the tree of knowledge drove the Greeks from their paradise; but the vision of that Eden continues to haunt the mind of man, not in vain, if it prophesies in a type the end to which his history moves. CHAPTER II THE GREEK VIEW OF THE STATE § I. The Greek State a " City. " The present kingdom of Greece is among the smallest of European states ; but to the Greeks it would have appeared too large to be a state at all. Within that little peninsular whose whole population and wealth are so insignificant according to modern ideas, were comprised in classical times not one but many flourishing polities. And the conception of an amalgamation of these under a single government was so foreign to the Greek idea, that even to Aristotle, the clearest and most comprehensive thinker of his age, it did not present itself even as a dream. To him, as to every ancient Greek, the state meant the City — meant, that is to say, an area about the size of an English county, with a population, perhaps, of some hundred thousand, self-governing and independent of any larger political whole. If we can imagine the various County Councils of England emancipated from the control of Parliament and set free to make their own laws, manage their own finance 65 66 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE and justice, raise troops and form with one another alli- ances, offensive and defensive, we may form thus some general idea of the political institutions of the Greeks and some measure of their difference from our own. Nor must it be supposed that the size of the Greek state was a mere accident in its constitution, that it might have been indefinitely enlarged and yet regained its essential character. On the contrary, the limitation of size belonged to its very notion. The greatest state, says Aristotle, is not the one whose population is most numerous; on the contrary, after a certain limit of increase has been passed, the state ceases to be a state at all. ** Ten men are too few for a city; a hundred thousand are too many." Not only London, it seems, bat every one of our larger towns, would have been too big for the Greek idea of a state; and as for the British empire, the very conception of it would have been impossible to the Greeks. Clearly, their view on this point is fundamentally dif- ferent from our own. Their civilisation was one of " city- states", not of kingdoms and empires; and their whole political outlook was necessarily determined by this condition. Generalising from their own experience, they had formed for themselves a conception of the state not the less interesting to us that it is unfamiliar; and this conception it will be the business of the present chapter to illustrate and explain. ^ 2. The Relation of the State to the Citizen. First, let us consider the relation of the state to the citizens — that is to say, to that portion of the community, usually a minority, which was possessed of full political rights. It is here that we have the key to THE RELATION OF THE STATE TO THE CITIZEN 67 that limitation of size which we have seen to be essential to the idea of the city-state. For, in the Greek view, to be a citizen of a state did not merely imply the payment of taxes, and the possession of a vote; it implied a direct and active co-operation in all the functions of civil and military life. A citizen was normally a soldier, a judge, and a member of the governing assembly; and all his public duties he performed not by deputy, but in person. He must be able frequently to attend the centre of government; hence the limitation of territory. He must be able to speak and vote in person in the assembly; hence the limitation of numbers. The idea of representative govern- ment never occurred to the Greeks ; but if it had occurred to them, and if they had adopted it, it would have involved a revolution in their whole conception of the citizen. Of that conception, direct personal service was the cardinal point — service m the field as well as in the coimcil; and to substitute for personal service the mere right to a vote would have been to destroy the form of the Greek state. Such being the idea the Greeks had formed, based on their own experience, of the relation of the citizen to the state, it follows that to them a society so complex as our own would hardly have answered to the definition of a state at all. Rather they would have regarded it as a mere congeries of unsatisfactory human beings, held to- gether, partly by political, partly by economic compulsion, but lacking that conscious identity of interest with the community to which they belong which alone constitutes the citizen. A man whose main pre-occupation should be with his trade or his profession, and who should only become aware of his corporate relations when called upon for his rates and taxes — a man, that is to say, in the 68 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE position of an ordinary Englishman — would not have seemed to the Greeks to be a full and proper member of a state. For the state, to them, was more than a machinery, it was a spiritual bond; and ** public life", as we call it, was not a thing to be taken up and laid aside at pleasure, but a necessary and essential phase of the existence of a com- plete man. This relation of the citizen to the state, as it was con- ceived by the Greeks, is sometimes described as though it involved the sacrifice of the individual to the whole. And in a certain sense, perhaps, this is true. Aristotle, for instance, declares that no one must suppose he belongs to himself, but rather that all alike belong to the state; and Plato, in the construction of his ideal republic, is thinking much less of the happiness of the individual citizens, than of the symmetry and beauty of the whole as it might appear to a disinterested observer from with- out. Certainly it would have been tedious and irksome to any but his own ideal philosopher to live under the rule of that perfect polity. Individual enterprise, bent, and choice is rigorously excluded. Nothing escapes the net of legislation, from the production of children to the fashion of houses, clothes, and food. It is absurd, says the ruth- less logic of this mathematician among the poets, for one who would regulate public life to leave private relations uncontrolled ; if there is to be order at all, it must extend through and through ; no moment, no detail must be with- drawn from the grasp of law. And though in this, Plato, no doubt, goes far beyond the common sense of the Greeks, yet he is not building altogether in the air. The republic which he desiderates was realised, as we shall see, partially at least, in Sparta. So that his insistence on the all-per- THE RELATION OF THE STATE TO THE CITIZEN 69 vading domination of the state, exaggerated though it be, is exaggerated on the actual hues of Greek practice, and may be taken as indicative of a real distinction and even antithesis between their point of view and that which pre- vails at present in most modern states. But on the other hand such a phrase as the "sacrifice of the individual to the whole", to this extent at least is misleading, that it presupposes an opposition between the end of the individual and that of the State, such as was entirely foreign to the Greek conception. The best indi- vidual, in their view, was also the best citizen; the two ideals not only were not incompatible, they were almost indistinguishable. When Aristotle defines a state as "an association of similar persons for the attainment of the besi life possible", he implies not only that society is the means whereby the individual attains his ideal, but also that that ideal includes the functions of public life. The state in his view is not merely the convenient machinery that raises a man above his animal wants and sets him free to follow his own devices; it is itself his end, or at least a part of it. And from this it follows that the regulations of the state were not regarded by the Greeks — as they are apt to be by modern men — as so many vexatious, if neces- sary, restraints on individual liberty ; but rather as the ex- pression of the best and highest nature of the citizen, as the formula of the conduct which the good man would naturally prescribe to himself. So that, to get a clear conception of what was at least the Greek ideal, however imperfectly it may have been attained in practice, we ought to regard the individual not as sacrificed to, but rather as realising himself in the whole. We shall thus come nearer to what seems to have been the point of view not only 6 70 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE of Aristotle and of Plato, but also of the average Greek man. § J. The Greek View of Law, For nothing is more remarkable in the political theory of the Greeks than the respect they habitually express for law. Early legislators were believed to have been speci- ally inspired by the divine power — Lycurgus, for instance, by Apollo, and Minos by Zeus; and Plato regards it as a fundamental condition of the well-being of any state that this view should prevail among its citizens. Nor was this conception of the divine origin of law confined to legend and to philosophy; we find it expressed in the following passage of Demosthenes, addressed to a jury of average Athenians, and representing at any rate the conventional and orthodox, if not the critical view of the Greek public : " The whole life of men, O Athenians, whether they inhabit a great city or a small one, is governed by nature and by laws. Of these, nature is a thing irregular, un- equal, and peculiar to the individual possessor; laws are regular, common, and the same for all. Nature, if it be depraved, has often vicious desires ; therefore you will find people of that sort falling into error. Laws desire what is just and honourable and useful; they seek for this, and, when it is found, it is set forth as a general ordinance, the same and alike for all; and that is law, which all men ought to obey for many reasons, and especially because every law is an invention and gift of the Gods, a resolution of wise men, a corrective of errors intentional and unintentional, a compact of the whole state, according Artisans aUd slaves 7i to which all who belong to the state ought to live." * In this opposition of Law, as the universal principle, to Nature, as individual caprice, is implied a tacit iden- tification of Law and Justice. The identification, of course, is never complete in any state, and frequently enough is not even approximate. No people were more conscious of this than the Greeks, none, as we shall see later, pushed it more vigorously home. But still, the positive conception which lay at the root of their society was that which finds expression in the passage we have quoted, and which is stated still more explicitly in the " Memorabilia " of Xeno- phon, where that admirable example of the good and efficient citizen represents his hero Socrates as maintaining, without hesitation or reserve, that " that which is in accordance with law is just." The implication, of course, is not that laws cannot be improved, that they do at any point adequately correspond to justice; but that justice has an objective and binding validity, and that Law is a serious and on the whole a successful attempt to embody it in practice. This was the conviction predominant in the best period of Greece; the conviction under which her institutions were formed and flourished, and whose overthrow by the philosophy of a critical age was coin- cident with, if it was not the cauje of, her decline. ^ 4. Artisans and Slaves. We have now arrived at a general idea of the nature of the Greek state, and of its relations to the individual citizen. But there were also members of the state who were not citizens at all; there was the class of labourers * Demosth. in Aristogeit. § 17. —Translation by C. R. Kennedy. 72 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE and traders, who, in some states at least, had no political rights ; and the class of slaves who had nowhere any rights at all. For in the Greek conception the citizen was an aristocrat. His excellence was thought to consist in public activity; and to the performance of public duties he ought therefore to be able to devote tlie greater part of his time and energy. But the existence of such a privileged class involved the existence of a class of producers to support them; and the producers, by the nature of their calling, be they slave or free, were excluded from the life of the perfect citizen. They had not the necessary leisure to devote to public business; neither had they the oppor- tunity to acquire the mental and physical qualities which would enable them to transact it worthily. They were therefore regarded by the Greeks as an inferior class ; in some states, in Sparta, for example, and in Thebes, they were excluded from political rights; and even in Athens, the most democratic of all the Greek communities, though they were admitted to the citizenship and enjoyed con- siderable political influence, they never appear to have lost the stigma of social inferiority. And the distinction which was thus more or less definitely drawn in practice between the citizens proper and the productive class, was even more emphatically affirmed in theory. Aristotle, the most balanced of all the Greek thinkers and the best exponent of the normal trend of their ideas, excludes the class of artisans from the citizenship of his ideal state on the ground that they are debarred by their occupation from the characteristic excellence of man. And Plato, though here as elsewhere he pushes the normal view to excess, yet, in his insistence on the gulf that separates the citizen from the mechanic and the trader, is in sympathy ARTISANS AND SLAVES 73 with the general cuiTent of Greek ideas. His ideal state is one which depends mainly on agriculture; in which commerce and exchange are reduced to the smallest pos- sible dimensions; in which every citizen is a landowner, forbidden to engage in trade; and in which the productive class is excluded from all political rights. The obverse then, of the Greek citizen, who realised in the state his highest life, was an inferior class of producers who realised only the means of subsistence. But within this class again was a distinction yet more fundamental — the distinction between free men and slaves. In the majority of the Greek states the slaves were the greater part of the population ; in Athens, to take an extreme case, at the close of the fourth century, they are estimated at 400,000, to 100,000 citizens. They were employed not only in domestic service, but on the fields, in factories and in mines, and performed, in short, a considerable part of the productive labour in the state. A whole large section, then, of the producers in ancient Greece had no social or political rights at all. They existed simply to maintain the aristocracy of citizens, for whom and in whom the state had its being. Nor was this state of things in the least repugnant to the average Greek mind. Nothing is more curious to the modern man than the temper in which Aristotle approaches this theme. With- out surprise or indignation, but in the tone of an impartial, scientific inquirer, he asks himself the question whether slavery is natural, and answers it in the affirmative. For, he argues, though in any particulai case, owing to the un- certain chances of fortune and war, the wrong person may happen to be enslaved, yet, broadly speaking, the general truth remains, that there are some men so inferior 74 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE to others that they ought to be despotically governed, by the same right and for the same good end that the body ought to be governed by the soul. Such men, he main- tains, are slaves by nature ; and it is as much to their interest to be ruled as it is to their masters' interest to rule them. To this class belong, for example, all who are naturally incapable of any but physical activity. These should be regarded as detachable limbs, so to speak, of the man who owns them, instruments of his will, like hands and feet ; or, to use Aristotle's own phrase, " the slave is a tool with life in it, and the tool a lifeless slave." The relation between master and slave thus frankly conceived by the Greeks, did not necessarily imply, though it was quite compatible with, brutality of treat- ment. The slave might be badly treated, no doubt, and very frequently was, for his master had almost absolute control over him, life and limb ; but, as we should expect, it was clearly recognised by the best Greeks that the treatment should be genial and humane. "There is a certain mutual profit and kindness," says Aristotle, " between master and slave, in all cases where the relation is natural, not merely imposed from without by convention or force." * And Plato insists on the duty of neither insulting nor outraging a slave, but treating him rather with even greater fairness than if he were in a position of equality. Still, there can be no doubt that the Greek conception of slavery is one of the points in which their view of hfe runs most counter to our own. Centuries of Christ- ianity have engendered in us the conviction, or rather, the instinct, that men are equal at least to this extent, 'Arist. Pol. I. 7. 1255 b 12 ARTISANS AND SLAVES 75 that no one has a right explicitly to make of another a mere passive instrument of his will — that every man, in short, must be regarded as an end in himself. Yet even here the divergence between the Greek and the modem view is less extreme than it appears at first sight. For the modern man, in spite of his perfectly genuine belief in equality (in the sense in which we have just defined the word), does nevertheless, when he is confronted with racial differences, recognise degrees of inferiority so extreme, that he is practically driven into the Aristotelian position that some men are naturally slaves. The Amer- ican, for example, will hardly deny that such is his attitude towards the negro. The negro, in tlieory, is the equal, politically and socially, of the white man; in prac- tice, he is excluded from the vote, from the professions, from the amenities of social intercourse, and even, as we have recently learnt, from the most elementary forms of justice. The general and di priori doctrine of equality is shattering itself against the actual facts; and the old Greek conception, " the slave by nature ", may be detected behind the mask of the Christian ideal. And while thus, even in spite of itself, the modern view is approximating to that of the Greeks, on the other hand the Greek view by its own evolution was already beginning to an- ticipate our own. Even Aristotle, in formulating his own conception of slavery, finds it necessary to observe that though it be true that some men are naturally slaves, yet in practice, under conditions which give the victory to force, it may happen that the " natural " slave becomes the master, and the "natural" master is degraded to a slave. This is already a serious modification of his doctrine. And other writers, pushing the contention 76 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE further, deny altogether the theory of natural slavery. "No man," says the poet Philemon, "was ever bom a slave by nature. Fortune only has put men in that position." And Euripides, the most modern of the Greeks, writes in the same strain: "One thing only disgraces a slave, and that is the name. In all other respects a slave, if he be good, is no worse than a freeman." ^ It seems then that the distinction between the Greek and tlie modem point of view is not so profound or so final as it appears at first sight. Still, the distinction, broadly speaking, is there. The Greeks, on the whole, were quite content to sacrifice the majority to the minority. Their position, as we said at the outset, was fundamentally aristocratic; they exaggerated rather than minimised the distinctions between men — between the Greek and the barbarian, the freeman and the slave, the gentleman and the artisan— regarding them as natural and fundamental, not as the casual product of circumstimces. The " equality" which they sought m a well-ordered state was proportional not arithmetical— the attribution to each of his peculiar right, not of equal rights to all. Some were born to rule, others to serve; some to be ends, others to be means; and the problem to be solved was not how to obliterate these varieties of tone, but how to compose them into an ordered harmony. In a modern state, on the other hand, though class distinctions are clearly enough marked, yet the point of view from which they are regarded is fundamentally different. They arc attributed rather to accidents of fortune than to varieties of nature. The artisan, for example, ranks no * Euripides, Ion. 854 THE GREEK STATE PRIMARILY MILITARY 77 doubt lower than the professional man; but no one maintains that he is a different kind of being, incapable by nature, as Aristotle asserts, of the characteristic excellence of man. The distinction admitted is rather one of wealth than of natural calling, and may be obliterated by ability and good luck. Neither in theory nor in practice does the modem state recognise any such gulf as that which, in ancient Greece, separated the freeman from the slave, or the citizen from the non-citizen. ^5. The Greek State Primarily Military, not Industrial, The source of this divergence of view must be sought in the whole circumstances and character of the Greek states. Founded in the beginning by conquest, many of them still retained, in their internal structure, the marks of their violent origin. The citizens, for example, of Sparta and of Crete, were practically military garrisons, settled in the midst of a hostile population. These were extreme cases; and elsewhere, no doubt, the distinction between the conquerors and the conquered had disappeared. Still, it had sufficed to mould the conception and ideal of the citizen as a member of a privileged and superior class, whose whole energies were devoted to maintaining, by council and war, not only the prosperity, but the very existence of the state. The original citizen, moreover, would be an owner of land, which would be tilled for him by a subject class. Productive labour would be stamped, from the outset, with the stigma of inferiority; commerce would grow up, if at all, outside the limits of the landed aristocracy, and would have a struggle to win for itself any degree of social and political recognition. Such 78 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE were the conditions that produced the Greek conception of the citizen. In some states, such as Sparta, they con- tinued practically unchanged throughout the best period of Greek history; in others, such as Athens, they were modified by the growth of a commercial population, and where that was the case the conception of the citizen was modified too, and the whole polity assumed a demo- cratic character. Yet never, as we have seen, even in the most democratic states, was the modern conception of equality admitted. For, in the first place, the institution of slavery persisted, to stamp the mass of producers as an inferior caste ; and in the second place, trade, even in the states where it was most developed, hardly attained a pre- ponderating influence. The ancient state was and remained primarily military. The great industrial questions which agitate modem states either did not exist at all in Greece, or assumed so simple a form that they did not rise to the surface of political life. ^ How curious it is, for example, from the modern point of view, to find Plato, a citizen of the most important trading centre of Greece, dismissing in the following brief sentence the whole commercial legislation of his ideal state: "As to those common business transactions betvveen private individuals in the market, including, if you please, the contracts of artisans, libels, assaults, law-proceedings, and the impanelling of juries, or again questions relat- ing to tariffs, and the collection of such customs as may be necessary in the market or in the harbours, and * There was, of course, the general opposition between rich and poor (see below). But not those infinitely complex relations which are the problems of modem statesmanship. I THE GREEK STATE PRIMARILY MILITARY 79 generally all regulations of the market, the police, the custom-house, and the like; shall we condescend to legislate at all on such matters? " No, it is not worth while to give directions on these points to good and cultivated men: for in most cases they will have little difficulty in discovering all the legisla- tion required." ^ In fact, throughout his treatise it is the non-commer- cial or military class with which Plato is almost exclusively concerned; and in taking that hne he is so far at least in touch with reality that that class was the one which did in fact predominate in the Greek state ; and that even where, as in Athens, the productive class became an important factor in political life, it was never able alto- gether to overthrow the aristocratic conception of the citizen. And with that conception, we must add, was bound up the whole Greek view of individual excellence. The inferiority of the artisan and the trader, historically estab- lished in the manner we have indicated, was further emphasised by the fact that they were excluded by their calling from the cultivation of the higher personal qualities — from the training of the body by gymnastics and of the mind by philosophy; from habitual conversance with public affairs ; from that perfect balance, in a word, of the physical, intellectual, and moral powers, which was only to be attained by a process of self-culture, incompatible with the pursuance of a trade for bread. Such, at any rate, was the opinion of the Greeks. We shall have occasion to return to it later. Meantime, let us sum up the course of our investigation up to the present point. * Plato, Rep. IV. 425. — Translated by Da\'ies and Vanphan. 8o THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE We have seen that the state, in the Greek view, must be so hmited, both in territory and population, that all its citizens might be able to participate in person in its government and defence; that it was based on funda- mental class distinctions separating sharply the citizen from the non-citizen, and the slave from the free; that its end and purpose was that all-absorbing corporate activity in which the citizen found the highest expression of himself; and that to that end the inferior classes were regarded as mere means — a point of view which finds its completest expression in the institution of slavery. § 6. Forms of Government in the Greek State. While, however, this was the general idea of the Greek state, it would be a mistake to suppose that it was every- where embodied in a single permanent form of polity. On the contrary, the majority of the states in Greece were in a constant state of flux; revolution succeeded revolution with startling rapidity; and in place of a single fixed type what we really get is a constant transition from one variety to another. The general account we have given ought therefore to be regarded only as a kind of limiting formula, embracing within its range a number of polities distinct and even opposed in character. Of these polities Aristotle, whose work is based on an exami- nation of all the existing states of Greece, recognises three main varieties : government by the one, government by the few, and government by the many ; and each of these is sub- divided into two forms, one good, where the government has regard to the well-being of the whole, the other bad, where it has regard only to the well-being of those who govern. The result is six forms, of which three are good, monarchy, aristo- FACTION AJSTD ANARCHY 8l cracy, and what he calls a "polity" par excellence; three bad, tyranny, oligarchy, and democracy. Of all these forms we have examples in Greek history, and indeed can roughly trace a tendency of the state to evolve through tlie series of them. But by far the most important, in the historical period, are the two forms known as Oligarchy and Democracy; and the reason of their importance is that they corresponded roughly to government by the rich and government by the poor. " Rich and poor," says Aristotle, " are the really antagonistic members of a state. The result is that the character of all existing polities is determined by the predominance of one or other of these classes, and it is the common opinion that there are two polities and two only, viz., Demo- cracy and Oligarchy." ^ In other words, the social distinction between rich and poor was exaggerated in Greece into political antagonism. In every state there was an oligarchic and a democratic faction; and so fierce was the opposition between them, that we may almost say that every Greek city was in a chronic state of civil war, having become, as Plato puts it, not one city but two, "one comprising the rich and the other the poor, who reside together on the same ground, and are always plotting against one another." * § y. Faction and Autarchy. This internal schism which ran through almost every state, came to a head in the great Peloponnesian war which divided Greece at the close of the fifth century, and in which Athens and Sparta, the two chief combatants, *Arist. Pol. VI. (IV) 1 29 1 b8.— Translation by Welldon. •Plat. Rep. VIU. 551. — Trauslation by Davies and Vaughan 82 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE represented respectively the democratic and the oligarchic principles. Each appealed to the kindred faction in the states that were opposed to them; and every city was divided against itself, the party that was " out " for the moment plotting with the foreign foe to overthrow the party that was "in." Thus the general Greek conception of the ordered state was so far from being realised in practice that probably at no time in the history of the civilised world has anarchy more complete and cynical prevailed. To appreciate the gulf that existed between the ideal and the fact, we have only to contrast such a scheme as that set forth in the " Republic " of Plato with the follow- ing description by Thucydides of the state of Greece during the Peloponnesian war: " Not long afterwards the whole Hellenic world was in commotion; in every city the chiefs of the democracy and of the oligarchy were struggling, the one to bring in the Athenians, the other the Lacedaemonians. Now in time of peace, men would have had no excuse for introducing either, and no desire to do so; but when they were at war and both sides could easily obtain allies to the hurt of their enemies and the advantage of themselves, the dissatisfied party were only too ready to invoke foreign aid. And revolution brought upon the cities of Hellas many terrible calamities, such as have been and always will be while human nature remains the same, but which are more or less aggravated and differ in character with every new combination of circumstances. In peace and prosperity both states and individuals are actuated by higher motives, because they do not fall under the dominion of imperious necessities ; but war which takes away the FACTION AND ANARCHY 83 comfortable provision of daily life is a hard master, and tends to assimilate men's characters to their conditions. "When troubles had once begun in the cities, those who followed carried the revolutionary spirit further and fur- ther, and determined to outdo the report of all who had preceded them by the ingenuity of their enterprises and the atrocity of their revenges. The meaning of words had no longer the same relation to things, but was changed by them as they thought proper. Reckless daring was held to be loyal courage; prudent delay was the excuse of a coward; moderation was the disguise of unmanly weakness ; to know everything was to do nothing. Frantic energy was the true quality of a man. A con- spirator who wanted to be safe was a recreant in disguise. The lover of violence was always trusted, and his opponent suspected. He who succeeded in a plot was deemed knowing, but a still greater master in craft was he who detected one. On the other hand, he who plotted from the first to have nothing to do with plots was a breaker-up of parties and a poltroon who was afraid of the enemy. In a word, he who could outstrip another in a bad action was applauded, and so was he who encouraged to evil one who had no idea of it. The tie of party was stronger than the tie of blood, because a partisan was more ready to dare without asking why (for party associations are not based upon any established law, nor do they seek the public good; they are formed in defiance of the laws and from self-interest). The seal of good faith was not divine law, but fellowship in crime. If an enemy when he was in the ascendant offered fair words, the opposite party received them, not in a generous spirit, but by a jealous watchfulness of his actions. Revenge was dearer than self- 84 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE preservation. Any agreements sworn to by either party, when they could do nothing else, were binding as long as both were powerless. But he who on a favourable oppor- tunity first took courage and struck at his enemy when he saw him off his guard, had greater pleasure in a perfidious than he would have had in an open act of revenge; he congratulated himself that he had taken the safer course, and also that he had overreached his enemy and gained the prize of superior ability. In general the dishonest more easily gain credit for cleverness than the simple for goodness; men take a pride in the one, but are ashamed of the other. ** The cause of all these evils was the love of power originating in avarice and ambition, and the party-spirit which is engendered by them when men are fairly embarked in a contest. For the leaders on either side used specious names, the one party professing to uphold the constitutional equality of the many, the other the wisdom of an aristo- cracy, while they made the public interests, to which in name they were devoted, in reality their prize. Striving in every way to overcome each other, they committed the most monstrous crimes ; yet even these were surpassed by the magnitude of their revenges which they pursued to the very utmost, neither party observing any definite limits either of justice or public expediency, but both alike making the caprice of the moment their law. Either by the help of an unrighteous sentence, or grasping power with the strong hand, they were eager to satiate the impatience of party spirit. Neither faction cared for religion; but any fair pretence which succeeeded in effect- ing some odious purpose was greatly lauded. And the citizens who were of neither party fell a prey to both; FACTION AND ANARCHY 85 either they were disHked because they held aloof, or men were jealous of their surviving. " Thus revolution gave birth to every form of wicked- ness in Hellas. The simplicity which is so large an element in a noble nature was laughed to scorn and disappeared. An attitude of perfidious antagonism everywhere prevailed; for there was no word binding enough, nor oath terrible enough to reconcile enemies. Each man was strong only in the conviction that nothing was secure; he must look to his own safety, and could not afford to trust others. Inferior intellects generally succeeded best. For aware of their own deficiencies, and fearing the capacities of vheir opponents, for whom they were no match in powers of speech, and whose subtle wits were likely to anticipate them in contriving evil, they struck boldly and at once. But the cleverer sort, presuming in their arrogance that they would be aware in time, and disdaining to act when they could think, were taken off their guard and easily destroyed." ^ The general indictment thus drawn up by Thucydides is amply illustrated by the events of war which he de- scribes. Oh one occasion, for example, the Athenians were blockading Mitylene; the government, an oligarchy, was driven to arm the people for the defence; the people, having obtained arms, immediately demanded political rights, under threat of surrendering the city to the foreign foe ; and the government, rather than concede their claims, surrendered it themselves. Again, Megara, we learn, was twice betrayed, once by the democrats to the Athenians, and again by the oligarchs to the Lacedaemonians. At 'Thuc. III. 82.— Translated by Jowett. 86 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE Leontini the Syracusans were called in to drive out the popular party. And at Corcyra the people, having got the better of their aristocratic opponents, proceeded to a general massacre which extended over seven days, with every variety of moral and physical atrocity. Such is tlie view of the pohtical condition of Greece given to us by a contemporary observer towards the close of the fifth century, and it is a curious comment on the Greek idea of the state. That idea, as we saw, was an ordered inequality, political as well as social ; and in certain states, and notably in Sparta, it was successfully embodied in a stable form. But in the majority of the Greek states it never attained to more than a fluctuating and temporary realisation. The inherent contradiction was too extreme for the attempted reconciliation ; the inequalities refused to blend in a harmony of divergent tones but asserted themselves in the dissonance of civil war. § 8. Property and the Communistic Ideal, And, as we have seen, this internal schism of the Greek state was as much social as political. The " many" and the " few " were identified respectively with the poor and the rich ; and the struggle was thus at bottom as much economic as political. Government by xn ohgarchy was understood to mean the exploitation of che masses by the classes. " An oligarchy," says a democrat, as reported by Thucydides, "while giving the people the full share of danger, not merely takes too much of the good things, but absolutely monopolises them." * And, similarly, the advent of democracy was *Thuc. VI. 39.— Translated by Jowett. PROPERTY AND THE COMMUNISTIC IDEAL 87 held to imply the spoliation of the classes in the interest of the masses, either by excessive taxation, by an abuse of the judicial power to fine, or by any other of the semi-legal devices of oppression which the majority in power have always at their command. This substantial identity of rich and poor, respectively, with oligarch and democrat may be further illustrated by the following passage from Aristotle : " In consequence of the political disturbances and con- tentions between the commons on the one hand and the rich on the other, whichever party happens to get the better of its opponents, instead of establishing a polity of a broad and equal kind, assumes political supremacy as a prize of the victory, and sets up either a Democracy or an Oligarchy." ^ We see then that it was the underlying question of property that infused so strong a rancour into the party struggles of Greece. From the very earliest period, in fact, we find it to have been the case that political revolution was prompted by economic causes. Debt was the main factor of the crisis which led to the legislation of Solon ; and a re-division of the land was one of the measures attributed to Lycurgus. ^ As population increased, and, in the maritime states, commerce and trade developed, the problem of poverty became increasingly acute ; and though it was partially met by the emigration of the surplus population to colonies, yet in the fifth and fourth centuries we find it prominent and pressing both 'Arist. Pol. VI. (IV) 1296 a 27.— Translation by WclMon. *I have not thought it necessary for my purpose, here or else- where, to discuss the authenticity of the statements made by Greek authors about Lycurgus. 88 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE in practical politics and in speculation. Nothing can illustrate better how familiar the topic was, and to what free theorising it had led, than the passages in which it is treated hi the comedies of Aristophanes. Here for example, is an extract from the " Fxclesiazusae " which it may be worth while to insert as a contribution to an argimient that belongs to every age. Praxagora. I tell you that we are all to share alike and have everything in common, instead of one being rich and another poor, and one having hundreds of acres and another not enough to make him a grave, and one a houseful of servants and another not even a paltry foot-boy. I am going to introduce communism and universal equality. Blepsyrus. How communism? Prax. That's just what I was going to tell you. First of all, everybody's money and land and anything else he may possess will be made common property. Then we shall maintain you all out of the common stock, with due regard to economy and thrift. Bleps. But how about those who have no land, but only money that they can hide? Prax. It will all go to the public purse. To keep anything back will be perjury. Bleps. Perjury! Well, if you come to that, it was by perjur}' it was all acquired. Prax. And then, money won't be the least use to any one. Bleps. Why not? Prax. Because nobody will be poor. Everybody will have ever}'thing he wants, bread, salt-fish, barley-cake, clothes, wine, garlands, chickpeas. So what will be PROPERTY AND THE COMMUNISTIC IDEAL 89 the good of keeping anything back ? Answer that if you can! Bleps. Isn't it just the people who have all these things that are the greatest thieves? Prax. No doubt, under the old laws. But now, when everything will be in common what will be the good of keeping anything back ? Bleps. Who will do the field work? Prax. The slaves ; all you will have to do is to dress and go out to dinner in the evening. Bleps. But what about the clothes ? How are they to be provided ? Prax. What you have now will do to begin with, and afterwards we shall make them for you ourselves. Bleps. Just one thing more ! Supposing a man were to lose his suit in the courts, where are the damages to come from ? It would not be fair to take the public funds. Prax. But there won't be any lawsuits at all ! Bleps. That will mean ruin to a good many people! Bystander. Just my idea! Prax. Why should there be any? Bleps. Why ! for reasons enough, heaven knows ! For instance, a man might repudiate his debts. Prax. In that case, where did the man who lent the money get it from? Clearly, since everything is in common, he must have stolen it! Bleps. So he must! An excellent idea! But now tell me this. When fellows come to blows over their cups, where are the damages to come from? Prax. From the rations! A man won't be in such a hurry to make a row when his belly has to pay for it. 90 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE Bleps. One thing more ! Will there be no more thieves ? Prax. Why should any one steal what is hLs own? Bleps. And won't one be robbed of one's cloak at night? Prax. Not if you sleep at home ! Bleps. Nor yet, if one sleeps out, as one used to do? Prax. No, for there will be enough and to spare for all. And even if a thief does try to strip a man, he will give up his cloak of his own accord. What would be the good of fighting ? He has only to go and get another, and a better, from the public store?. Bleps. And will there be no more gambling? Prax. What will there be to play for? Bleps. And how about house accommodation? Prax. That will be the same for all. I tell you I am going to turn the whole city into one huge house, and break down all the partitions, so that every one may have free access to every one else. * The "social problem," then, had clearly arisen in an- cient Greece, though no doubt in an infinitely .simpler form than that in which it is presented to ourselves ; and it might perhaps have been expected that the Greeks, with their notion of the supremacy of the state, would have adopted some drastic public measure to meet it. And, in fact, in the earlier period of their history, as has been indicated above, we do find sweeping revolutions effected in the distribution of property. In Athens, Solon abolished debt, either in whole or part, by reducing the rate of interest and depreciating the currency; and in Sparta Lycurgus is said to have resumed the whole of the land for the state, and redivided it equally among the 'Aristoph. Eccles. 590. PROPERTY AND THE COMMUNISTIC IDEAL QI citizens. We have also traces of laws existing in other states to regulate in the interests of equality the possession and transfer of land. But it does not appear that any attempt was made in any state permanently to control by public authority the production and distribution of wealth. Meantime, however, the problem of social inequality was exercising the minds of political theorists; and we have notice of various schemes for an ideal polity framed upon communistic principles. Of these the most important, and the only one preserved to us, is the celebrated " Republic" of Plato ; and never, it may be safely asserted, was a plan of society framed so consistent, harmonious and beautiful in itself, or so indifferent to the actual capa- cities of mankind. Following out what we have already indicated as the natural drift of Greek ideas, the philosopher separates ofif on the one hand the productive class, who are to have no political rights; and on the other the class of soldiers and governors. It is the latter alone with whom he seriously concerns himself; and the scheme he draws up for them is uncompromisingly communistic. After being purged, by an elaborate education, of all the egoistic passions, they are to live together, having all things in common, devoted heart and soul to the public good, and guiltless even of a desire for any private possession or advantage of their own. " In the first place, no one," says Plato, "should possess any private pro- perty, if it can possibly be avoided; secondly, no one should have a dweUing or store house into which all who please may not enter; whatever necessaries are required by temperate and courageous men, who are trained to war, they should receive by regular appointment from their fellow-citizens, as wages for their services, and the ^- 92 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE amount should be such as to leave neither a suiplus on the year's consumption nor a deficit; and they should attend common messes and live together as men do in a camp: as for gold and silver, we must tell them that they are in perpetual possession of a divine species of the precious metals placed in their souls by the gods them- selves, and therefore have no need of the earthly one; that in fact it would be profanation to pollute their spiritual riches by mixing them with the possession of mortal gold, because the world's coinage has been the cause of countless impieties, whereas theirs is undefiled: therefore to them, as distinguished from the rest of the people, it is forbidden to handle or touch gold and silver, or enter under the same roof with them, or to wear them in their dresses, or to drink out of the precious metals. If they follow these rules, they will be safe themselves and the saviours of the city : but whenever they come to possess lands, and houses, and money of their own, they will be householders and cultivators instead of guardians, and will become hos- tile masters of their fellow-citizens rather than their allies; and so they will spend their whole lives, hating and hated, plotting and plotted against, standing in more frequent and intense alarm of their enemies at home than of their enemies abroad; by which time they and the rest of the city will be running on the very brink of ruin." ^ The passage is interesting, if only as an illustration of the way in which Plato had been impressed by the e\'il results of the institution of private property. But as a contribution to political theory it was open to severe attack from the representatives of experience and common sense. Of these, the chief was Aristotle, whose criticism * Plato, Rep. m. 416. — Translation by Davies and Vaughan. t PROPERTY AND THE COMMUNISTIC IDEAL 93 has been preserved to us, and who, while admitting that Plato's scheme has a plausible appearance of philanthropy, maintains that it is inapplicable to the facts of human nature. To this conclusion, indeed, even Plato himself was driven in the end; for in his later work, the "Laws," although he still asserts that community of goods would be the ideal institution, he reluctantly abandons it as a basis for a possible state. On the other hand, he endeavours by the most stringent regulations, to prevent the growth of inequalities of wealth. He distributes the land in equal lots among his citizens, prohibiting either purchase or sub-division ; limits the possession of money to the amount required for daily exchange ; and forbids lending on interest. The object of a legislator, he declares, is to make not a great but a happy city. But only the good are happy, and goodness and wealth are incompatible. The legislator, therefore, will not allow his citizens to be wealthy, any more than he will allow them to be poor. He will seek to establish by law the happy mean ; and to this end, if he despair of the possibility of a thorough-going communism, will legislate at least as indicated above. The uncompromising idealism of Plato's scheme, with its assumption of the indefinite plasticity of human nature, is of course peculiar to himself, not typical of Greek ideas. But it is noticeable that Aristotle, who is a far better representative of the average Greek mind, exhibits the same mistrust of the accumulation of private property. In the beginning of his "Politics" he distinguishes two kinds of money-making, one natural, that which is pursued for the sake of a livelihood, the other unnatural, that which is pursued for the sake of accumulation. " The 94 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE motive of this latter," he says, "is a desire for life instead of for good life"; and its most hateful method is that of usury, the unnatural breeding of money out of money. And though he rejects as impracticable the compulsory communism of Plato's "Republic", yet he urges as the ideal solution that property, while owned by individuals, should be held as in trust for the common good ; and puts before the legislator the problem : " so to dispose the higher natures that they are unwilling, and the lower that they are unable to aggrandise themselves." ^ Such views as these, it may be noted, interesting though they be, as illustrating how keenly the thinkers of ancient Greece had realised the drawbacks of private property, have but the slightest bearing on the conditions of our own time. The complexity' and extent of modem industry have given rise to quite new problems, and quite new schemes for their solution ; and especially have forced into prominence the point of view of the producers themselves. To Greek thinkers it was natural to approach the question of property from the side of the governing class or of the state as a whole. The communism of Plato, for example, applied only to the "guardians" and soldiers, and not to the productive class on whom they depended; and so completely was he pre-occupied with the former to the exclusion of the latter, that he dismisses in a single sentence, as unworthy the legislator's detailed attention, the whole apparatus of labour and exchange. To regard the " working-class " as the most important section of the community, to substitute for the moral or political the economic standpoint, and to conceive society * Aristotle, Pol. II. 7. 1267 b 6. — Translation by Welldon. SPARTA 95 merely as a machine for the production and distribution of wealth, would have been impossible to an ancient Greek. Partly by the simplicity of the economic side of the society with which he was acquainted, partly by the habit of regarding the labouring class as a mere means to the maintenance of the rest, he was led, even when he had to deal with the problem of poverty and v/ealth, to regard it rather from the point of view of the stability and efficiency of the state, than from that of the welfare of the producers themselves. The modem attitude is radically different ; a revolution has been effected both in the conditions of industry and in the way in which they are regarded ; and the practice and the speculation of the Greek city-states have for us an interest which, great as it is, is philosophic rather than practical. § p. Sparta, The preceding attempt at a general sketch of the nature of the Greek state is inevitably loose and misleading to this extent, that it endeavours to comprehend in a single view polities of the most varied and discrepant character. To remedy, so far as may be, this defect, to give an im- pression, more definite and more complete, of the variety and scope of the political experience of the Greeks, let us examine a Uttle more in detail the character of the two states which were at once the most prominent and the most opposed in their achievement and their aim — the state of Sparta on the one hand, and that of Athens on the other. It was these two cities that divided the hegemony of Greece; they represent the extremes of the two forms — oligarchy and democracy — under which, as we saw, the Greek polities fall: and from a .sufficient acquaintance with then^ 96 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE we may gather a fairly complete idea of the whole range of Greek political life. In Sparta we see one extreme of the political develop- ment of Greece, and the one which approaches nearest, perhaps, to the characteristic Greek type. Of that type, it is true, it was an exaggeration, and was recognised as such by the best thinkers of Greece ; but just for that reason it is the more interesting and instructive as an exliibition of a distinctive aspect of Greek civilisation. The Spartan state was composed of a small body of citizens — the Spartiatae or Spartans proper — encamped in the midst of a hostile population to whom they allowed no political rights and by whose labour they were supplied with the necessaries of life. The distinction between the citizen class on the one hand and the productive class on the other was thus as clearly and sharply drawn as pos- sible. It was e\en exaggerated; for the citizens were a band of conquerors, the productive class a subject race, perpetually on the verge of insurrection and only kept in restraint by such measures as secret assassination. The result was to draw together the small band of Spartiatae into a discipline so rigorous and close that under it every- thing was sacrificed to the necessity of self-preservation; and the bare maintenance of the state became the end for which every individual was born, and lived, and died. This discipline, according to tradition, had been devised by a single legislator, Lycurgus, and it was maintained intact for several centuries. Its main features may be summarised as follows. The production and rearing of children, to begin at the beginning, instead of being left to the caprice of indivi- duals, was controlled and regulated by the state. The SrARTA 97 women, in the first place, were trained by physical exercise for the healthy performance of the duties of motherhood ; they were taught to run and wresde naked, like the youths, to dance and sing in public, and to associate freely with men. Marriage was permitted only in the prime of life; and a free intercourse, outside its limits, between healthy men and women, was encouraged and approved by public opinion. Men w^ho did not marry were subject to social and civic disabilities. The children, as soon as they were born, were submitted to the inspection of the elders of their tribe ; if strong and well-formed, they were reared ; if not, they were allowed to die. A healthy stock having been thus provided as a basis, every attention was devoted to its appropriate training. The infants were encouraged from the beginning in the free use of their limbs, unhampered by swaddling-clothes, and were accustomed to endure without fear darkness and solitude, and to cure themselves of peevishness and crying. At the age of seven the boys were taken away from the charge of their parents, and put under the superintendence of a public official. Their education, on the intellectual side, was slight enough, comprising only such rudiments as reading and writing ; but on the moral side it was stringent and severe. Gathered into groups under the direction of elder youths — " monitors " we might call them — they were trained to a discipline of iron endurance. One garment served them for the whole year; they went without shoes, and slept on beds of rushes plucked with their own hands. Their food was simple, and often enough they had to go without it. Every moment of the day they were under inspection and supervision, for it was the privilege and the duty of every citizen to admonish and q8 tHE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE punish not only his own but other people's children. At supper they waited at table on their elders, answered their questions and endured their jests. In the streets they were taught to walk in silence, their hands folded in their cloaks, their eyes cast down, their heads never turning to right or left. Their gymnastic and military training was incessant; wherever they met, we are told, they began to box; under the condition, however, that they were bound to separate at the command of any bystander. To accustom them early to the hardships of a campaign, they were taught to steal their food from the mess-tables of their elders; if they were detected they were beaten for their clumsiness, and went without their dinner. Nothing was omitted, on the moral or physical side, to make them efficient members of a military state. Nor was the dis- cipline relaxed when they reached years of maturity. For, in fact, the whole city was a camp. Family life was obliterated by public acti\'ity. The men dined together in messes, rich and poor alike, sharing the same coarse and simple food. Servants, dogs, and horses, were regarded as common property. Luxury was strictly forbidden. The only currency in circulation was of iron, so cumbrous that it was impossible to accumulate or conceal it. The houses were as simple as possible, the roofs shaped only with the axe, and the doors with the saw; the furniture and fittings corresponded, plain but perfectly made. The nature of the currency practically prohibited commerce, and no citizen was allowed to be engaged in any mechanical trade. Agriculture was the main industry, and every Spartan had, or was supposed to have, a landed estate, cultivated by serfs who paid him a yearly rent. In complete accordance with the Greek ideal, it was a society of SPARTA 99 soldier-citizens, supported by an inferior productive class. In illustration of this point the following curious anecdote may be quoted from Plutarch. During one of the wars in which Sparta and her allies were engaged, the allies complained that they, who were the majority of the army, had been forced into a quarrel which concerned nobody but the Spartans. Whereupon Agesilaus, the Spartan king, " devised this expedient to show the allies were not the greater number. He gave orders that all the allies, of whatever country, should sit down promiscuously on one side, and all the Lacedaemonians on the other: which being done, he commanded a herald to proclaim, that all the potters of both divisions should stand out; then all the blacksmiths; then all the masons; next the carpenters ; and so he went through all the handicrafts. By this time almost all the allies were risen, but of the Lacedaemonians not a man, they being by law forbidden to learn any mechanical business; and now Agesilaus laughed and said, " You see, my friends, how many more soldiers we send out than you do." ^ And certainly, so far as its immediate ends were con- cerned, this society of soldier-citizens was singularly suc- cessful. The courage and efficiency of Spartan troops were notorious, and were maintained indeed not only by the training we have described, but by social penalties attached to cowardice. A man who had disgraced him- self in battle was a pariah in his native land. No one would eat with him, no one would wrestle with him; in the dance he must take the lowest place ; he must give the wall at meetings in the street, and resign his seat *Plut, Agesilaus. — Translation by Clough. 100 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE even to younger men; he must dress and bear himself humbly, under penalty of blows, and suffer the reproaches of women and of boys. Death plainly would be preferable to such a life ; and we are not surprised to hear that the discipline and valour of Spartan troops was celebrated far and wide. Here is a description of them, given by one of themselves to the Persian king when he was projecting the invasion of Greece: " Brave are all the Greeks who dwell in any Dorian land; but what I am about to say does not concern all, but only the Lacedaemonians. First, then, come what may, they will never accept thy terms, which would reduce Greece to slavery; and further, they are sure to join battle with thee, though all the rest of Greece should submit to thy will. As for their numbers, do not ask how many they are, that their resistance should be a possible thing; for if a thousand of them should take the field, they will meet thee in battle, and so will any number, be it less than this, or be it more. " When they fight singly, they are as good men as any in the world, and when they fight in a body, they are the bravest of all. For though they be freemen, they are not in all respects free; Law is the master whom they own; and this master they fear more than thy subjects fear thee. Whatever he commands they do; and his commandment is always the same : it forbids them to flee in battle, whatever the number of their foes, and requires them to stand firm, and either to conquer or die." ^ The practical illustration of this speech is the battle of Thermopylae, where 300 Spartans kept at bay the whole •Herodotus VU. 102, 4. — Translation by Rawlinson. SPARTA I o I Persian host, till they were betrayed from the rear and killed fighting to a man. The Spartan state, then, justified itself according to its o\Mi ideal; but how limited that ideal was will be clear from our sketch. The individual, if it cannot be said that he was sacrificed to the state — for he recognised the life of the state as his own — was at any rate starved upon one side of his nature as much as he was hypertrophied upon the other. Courage, obedience, and endurance were developed in excess; but the free play of passion and thought, the graces and arts of life, all that springs from the spontaneity of nature, were crushed out of existence under this stern and rigid rule. "None of them," says Plutarch, an enthusiastic admirer of the Spartan polity " none of them was left alone to live as he chose ; but passing their time in the city as though it were a camp, their manner of life and their avocations ordered with a view to the public good, they regarded themselves as belongmg, not to themselves, but to their country." * And Plato, whose ideal republic was based so largely upon the Spartan model, has marked nevertheless as the essential defect of their polity its insistence on military virtue to the exclusion of everything else, and its excessive accentuation of the corporate aspect of life. "Your mili- tary way of life," he says, "is modelled after the camp, and is not like that of dwellers in cities; and you have your young men herding and feeding together like 3'-oung colts. No one takes his own individual colt and drags him away from his fellows against his will, raging and foaming, and gives him a groom for him alone, and trains ' Plut. Lycurj^us, ch. 24. I02 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE and rubs him down privately, and gives him the qualities in education which will make him not only a good soldier, but also a governor of a state and of cities. Such a one would be a greater warrior than he of whom Tyrtaeus sings ; and he would honour courage everywhere, but always as the fourth, and not as the first part of virtue, either in mdividuals or states." * The Spartan state, in fact, by virtue of that excellence which was also its defect — the specialising of the individual on the side of discipline and rule — carried within it the seeds of its own destruction. The tendencies which Ly- curgus had endeavoured to repress by external regulation reasserted themselves in his despite. He had intended once for all both to limit and to equalise private property; but aheady as early as the fifth century Spartans had accu- mulated gold which they deposited in temples in foreign states ; the land fell, by inheritance and gift, into the hands of a small minority; the number of the citizens was re- duced, not only by war, but by the disfranchisement at- tending inability to contribute to the common mess-tables; till at last we find no more than 700 Spartan families, and of these no more than 100 possessing estates in land. And this decline from within was hastened by external events. The constitution devised for a small state encamped amidst a hostile population, broke down under the weight of imperial power. The conquest of Athens by Sparta was the signal of her own collapse. The power and wealth she had won at a stroke alienated her sons from her dis- cipline. Generals and statesmen who had governed like kings the wealthy cities of the east were unable to adapt * Plato La\TS, II. 666 e. — Translation by Jowett. ATHENS 103' themselves again to the stern and narrow rules of Lycurgus. They rushed into freedom and enjoyment, into the unfettered use of their powers, with an energy proportional to the pre- vious restraint. The features of the human face broke through the fair but lifeless mask of ancient law; and the Spartan, ceasing to be a Spartan, both rose and fell to the level of a man. §10. Athens. In the institutions of Sparta we see, carried to its furthest point, one side of the complex Greek nature— their capacity for discipline and law. Athens, the home of a different stock, gives us the other extreme — their capacity for rich and spontaneous individual develop- ment. To pass from Sparta to Athens, is to pass from a barracks to a playing-field. All the beauty, all the grace, all the joy of Greece ; all that chains the desire of mankind, with a yearning that is never stilled, to that one golden moment in the past, whose fair and balanced interplay of perfect flesh and soul no later gains of thought can compensate, centres about that bright and stately city of romance, the home of Pericles and all the arts, whence from generation to generation has streamed upon ages less illustrious an in- fluence at once the sanest and the most inspired of all that have shaped the secular history of the world. Girt by moun- tain and sea, by haimted fountain and sacred grove, shaped and adorned by the master hands of Pheidias and Polygnotus and filled with the breath of passion and song by Euripides and Plato, Athens, famed alike for the legended deeds of heroes and gods and for the feats of her human sons in council, art, and war, is a name, to those who have felt her spell, more familiar and more dear than any of the few that I04 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE mark with gold the sombre scroll of history. And still across the years we feel the throb of the glorious verse that broke in praise of his native land from the lips of Euripides : "Happy of yore were the children of race divine Happy the sons of old Erechtheus' line Who in their holy state With hands inviolate Gather the (lower of wisdom far-renowned, Lightly lifting their feet in tlie lucid air Where the sacred nine, the Pierid Muses, bare Harmonia golden-crowned. There in the wave from fair Kcphisus flowing Kupris sweetens the winds and sets them blowing Over the delicate land; And ever with joyous hand Braiding her fragrant hair with the blossom of roses, She sendcth the Love that dwellcth in Wisdom's place That every virtue may quicken and every grace In the hearts where she reposes." ^ And this, the Athens of poetry and art, is but another aspect of the Athens of political history. The same indivi- duality, the same free and passionate energy that worked in the hearts of her sculptors and her poets, moulded also and inspired her city hfe. In contradistinction to the stem and rigid discipline of Sparta, the Athenian citizen displayed the resource, the versatihty and the zeal that only freedom and self-reliance can teach. The *Eurip. Medea, 825. ATHENS 105 contrast is patent at every stage of the history of the two states, and has been acutely set forth by Thucydi- des in the speech which he puts into the mouths of the Corinthian allies of Sparta: "You have never considered," they say to the Lace- daemonians, " what manner of men are these Athenians with whom you will have to fight, and how utterly unlike yourselves. They are revolutionary, equally quick in the conception and in the execution of every new plan ; while you are conservative — careful only to keep what you have, originating nothing, and not acting even when action is most necessary. They are bold beyond their strength; they run risks which prudence would condemn; and in the midst of misfortunes they are full of hope. Whereas it is your nature, though strong, to act feebly ; when your plans are most prudent, to distrust them; and when calamities come upon you, to think that you will never be delivered from them. They are impetuous, and you are dilatory ; they are always abroad, and you are always at home. For they hope to gain something by leaving their homes; but you are afraid that any new enterprise may imperil what you have already. When conquerors, they pursue their victory to the utmost ; when defeated, they fall back the least. Their bodies they devote to their country as though they belonged to other men ; their true self is their mind, which is most truly their own when employed in her service. When they do not carry out an intention which they have formed, they seem to have sustained a personal bereave- ment ; when an enterprise succeeds, they have gained a mere instalment of what is to come ; but if they fail, they at once conceive new hopes and so fill up the void. Io6 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE With them alone to hope is to have, for they lose not a moment in the execution of an idea. This is the Hfe- long task, full of danger and toil, which they are always imposing upon themselves. None enjoy their good tilings less, because they are always seeking for more. To do their duty is their only holiday, and they deem the quiet of inaction to be as disagreeable as the most tiresome business. If a man should say of them, in a word, that they were born neither to have peace themselves nor to allow peace to other men, he would simply speak the truth." ^ The qualities here set forth by Thucydides as charac- teristic of the Athenians, were partly the cause and partly the effect of their political constitution. The history of Athens, indeed, is the very antithesis to that of Sparta In place of a type fixed at a stroke and enduring for centuries, she presents a series of transitions through the whole range of polities, to end at last in a democracy so extreme that it refuses to be included within the limits of the general formula of the Greek state. Seldom, indeed, has " equality " been pushed to so ex- treme a point as it was, politically at least, in ancient Athens. The class of slaves, it is true, existed there as in every other state; but among the free citizens, who included persons of every rank, no political distinction at all was drawn. All of them, from the lowest to the highest, had the right to speak and vote in the great assembly of the people which was the ultimate authority; all were eligible to every administrative post; all sat in turn as jurors in the law-courts. The disabilities of poverty were *Thuc. I. 70. — Translated by Jowett. ATHENS 107 minimised by payment for attendance in the assembly and the courts. And, what is more extraordinary, even distinctions of abiUty were levelled by the practice of filling all offices, except the highest, by lot. Had the citizens been a class apart, as was the case in Sparta, had they been subjected from the cradle to a similar discipline and training, forbidden to engage in any trade or business, and consecrated to the service of the state, there would have been nothing surprising in this uncompromising assertion of equality. But in Athens the citizenship was extended to every rank and calling; the poor man jostled the rich, the shopman the aristocrat, in the Assembly; cobblers, carpenters, smiths, farmers, merchants, and retail traders met together with the ancient landed gentry, to debate and conclude on national affairs; and it was from such varied elements as these that the lot impartially chose the officials of the law, the revenue, the police, the highways, the markets, and the ports, as well as the jurors at whose mercy stood reputation, fortune, and life. The consequence was that in Athens, at least in the later period of her history, the middle and lower classes tended to monopolise political power. Of the popular leaders, Cleon, the most notorious, was a tanner; another was a baker, another a cattle-dealer. Influence belonged to those who had the gift of leading the mass; and in that competition the man of tongue, of energy, and of resource, was more than a match for the aristocrat of birth and intellect. The constitution of Athens, then, was one of political equality imposed upon social inequality. To illustrate the point we may quote a passage from Aristophanes which shows at once the influence exercised by the trading class and the disgust with which that influence was regarded Io8 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE by the aristocracy whom the poet represents. The passage is taken from the " Knights," a comedy written to discredit Cleon, and turning upon the expulsion of the notorious tanner from the good graces of Demos, by the superior impudence and address of a sausage-seller. De- mosthenes, a general of the aristocratic party, is com- municating to the latter the destiny that awaits him. Dei^iosTHENES {to the SausagE-Seller gravely). Set these poor wares aside; and now — bow down To the ground; and adore the powers of earth and heaven. S.-S. Heigh-day! Why, what do you mean? Dem. O happy man! Unconscious of your glorious destiny, Now mean and unregarded ; but to-morrow. The mightiest of the mighty, Lord of Athens. S.-S. Come, master, what's the use of making game? Why can't ye let me wash my guts and tripe, And sell my sausages in peace and quiet? Dem. O simple mortal, cast those thoughts aside! Bid guts and tripe farewell ! Look here ! Behold ! {pointing to the audience) The mighty assembled multitude before ye! S.-S. {with a grumble of indifference), I see 'em. Dem. You shall be their lord and master, The sovereign and the ruler of them all, Of the assemblies and tribunals, fleets and armies; You shall trample down the Senate under foot. Confound and crush the generals and commanders, Arrest, imprison, and confine in irons. And feast and fornicate in the Council House. S.-S. Are there any means of making a great man Of a sausage-selling fellow such as I? ^, ATHENS 109 Dem. The very means you have, must make ye so, Low breeding, vulgar birth, and impudence, These, tliese must malce ye, what you're meant to be. S.-S. I can't imagine that I'm good for much. Dem. Alas ! But why do ye say so ? What's the meaning Of these misgivings ? I discern within ye A promise and an inward consciousness Of greatness. Tell me truly: are ye allied To the families of gentry? S.-S. Naugh, not I; I'm come from a common ordinary kindred, Of the lower order. Dem. What a happiness! What a footing will it give ye ! What a groimdwork For confidence and favour at your outset! S.-S. But bless ye ! only consider my education ! I can but barely read .... in a kind of way. Dem. That m.akes against ye ! — the only thing against ye — The being able to read, in any way: For now no lead nor influence is allowec To liberal arts or learned education. But to the brutal, base, and underbred. Embrace then and hold fast the promises Which the oracles of the gods announce to you. * We have here an illustration, one among many that might be given, of the political equality that prevailed in Athens. It shows us how completely that distinction be- tween the military or governing, and the productive class, which belonged to the normal Greek conception of the state, had been broken down, on the side at least of pri- vilege and right, though not on that of social estimation, *Aristoph. Knights. 155. — Translation by Frere. no THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE in this most democratic of the ancient states. Politically, the Athenian trader and the Athenian artisan was the equal of the aristocrat of purest blood; and so far the government of Athens was a genuine democracy. But so far only. For in Athens, as in every Greek state, the greater part of the population was unfree; and the government which was a democracy from the point of view of the freeman, was an oligarchy from the point of view of the slave. For the slaves, by the nature of their position, had no political rights; and they were more than half of the population. It is noticeable, however, that the freedom and individuality which was characteristic of the Athenian citizen, appears to have reacted favour- ably on the position of the slaves. Not only had they, to a certain extent, the protection of the law against the worst excesses of their masters, but they were allowed a license of bearing and costume which would not have been tolerated in any other state. A contemporary writer notes that in dress and general appearance Athenian slaves were not to be distinguished from citizens; that they were permitted perfect freedom of speech; and that it was open to them to acquire a fortune and to live in ease and luxury. In Sparta, he says, the slave stands in fear of the freeman, but in Athens this is not the case ; and certainly the bear- ing of the slaves introduced into the Athenian comedy does not indicate any undue subservience. Slavery at the best is an undemocratic institution; but in Athens it appears to have been made as democratic as its nature would admit. We find then, in the Athenian state, the conception of equality pushed to the farthest extreme at all compatible with Greek ideas ; pushed, we may fairly say, at last to an J ATHENS 1 1 1 undue excess; for the great days of Athens were those when she was still under the influence of her aristocracy, and when the popular zeal evoked by her free institutions was directed by members of the leisured and cultivated class. The most glorious age of Athenian history closes with the death of Pericles; and Pericles was a man of noble family, freely chosen, year after year, by virtue of his personal qualities, to exercise over this democratic nation a dictatorship of character and brain. It is into his mouth that Thucydides has put that great panegyric of Athens, which sets forth to all time the type of an ideal state and the record of what was at least partially achieved in the greatest of the Greek cities: "Our form of government does not enter into rivalry with the institutions of others. We do not copy our neighbours, but are an example to them. It is true that we are called a democracy, for the administration is in the hands of the many and not of the few. But while the law secures equal justice to all alike in their private disputes, the claim of excellence is also recognised; and when a citizen is in any way distinguished, he is preferred to the public service, not as a matter of privilege, but as the reward of merit. Neither is poverty a bar, but a man may benefit his country whatever be the obscurity of his condition. There is no exclusiveness in our public life, and in our private intercourse we are not suspicious of one another, nor angry with our neighbour if he does what he Ukes; we do not put on sour looks at him, which, though harmless, are not pleasant. While we are thus unconstrained in our private intercourse, a spirit of reverence pervades our public acts; we are prevented from doing wrong by respect for authority and 112 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE for the laws, having an especial regard for those which are ordained for the protection of the injured, as well as for those unwritten laws which bring upon the transgressor of thera the reprobation of the general sentiment. " And we have not forgotten to provide for our weary spirits many relaxations from toil; we have regular games and sacrifices throughout the year; at home the style of our life is refined; and the delight which we daily feel in all these things helps to banish melancholy. Because of the greatness of our city the fruits of the whole earth flow in upon us, so that we enjoy the goods of other countries as freely as of our own. " Then again, our military training is in many respects superior to that of our adversaries. Our city is thrown open to the world, and we never expel a foreigner or prevent him from seeing or learning anything of which the secret if revealed to an enemy might profit him. We rely not upon management and trickery, but upon our own hearts and hands. And in the matter of education, whereas they from early youth are always undergoing laborious exercises which are to make them brave, we live at ease, and yet are ready to face the perils which they face. " If then we prefer to meet danger with a light heart but without laborious training, and with a courage which is gained by habit and not enforced by law, are we not greatly the gainers ? Since we do not anticipate the pain, although when the hour comes, we can be as brave as those who never allow themselves to rest; and thus too our city is equally admirable in peace and in war. For we are lovers of the beautiful, yet simple in our tastes, and we cultivate the mind without loss of manliness. ATHENS 113 Wealth we employ, not for talk and ostentation, but when there is a real use for it. To avow poverty with us is no disgrace; the tme disgrace is in doing nothing to avoid it. An Athenian citizen does not neglect the state because he takes care of his own household ; and even those of us who are engaged in business have a very fair idea of politics. We alone regard a man who takes no interest in public affairs, not as a harmless, but as a useless character; and if few of us are originators, we are all sound judges of a policy. The great impediment to action is, in our opinion, not discussion but the want of that knowledge which is gained by discussion preparatoiy to action. For we have a peculiar power of thinking before we act, and of acting too, whereas other men are courageous from ignorance but hesitate upon reflection. And they are surely to be esteemed the bravest spirits who have the clearest sense both of the pains and pleasures of life, but do not on that account shrink from danger. " To sum up, I say that Athens is the school of Hellas, and that the individual Athenian in his own person seems to have the power of adapting himself to the most varied forms of action with the utmost versatility and grace. This is no passing and idle word, but truth and fact; and the assertion is verified by the position to which these qualities have raised the state. For in the hour of trial Athens alone among her contemporaries is superior to the report of her. No enemy who comes against her is indignant at the reverses which he sustains at the hands of such a city; no subject complains that his masters are unworthy of him. And we shall assuredly not be without witnesses; there are mighty monuments of our power which will make us the wonder of this and of succeeding ages: ii4 THE GREEK VIEW OF Lit'E we shall not need the praises of Homer or of any other panegyrist, whose poetry may please for the moment, although his representation of the facts will not bear the light of day. For we have compelled every land, every sea, to open a path for our valour, and have everywhere planted eternal memorials of our friendship and of our enmity." * An impression so superb as this it is almost a pity to mar with the inevitable comi)lcment of disaster and decay. But our account of the Athenian polity would be misleading and incomplete if we did not indicate how the idea of equality, on which it turned, defeated itself, as did, in Sparta, the complementary idea of order, by the excesses of its own development. Already before the close of the fifth century, and with reiterated emphasis in the earlier decades of the fourth, we hear from poets and orators praise of a glorious past that is dead, and denunciations of a decadent present. The ancient training in g)'mnastics, we are told, the ancient and generous culture of mind and soul, is neglected and despised by a generation of traders ; reverence for age and authority, even for law, has disappeared ; and in the train of these have gone the virtues they engendered and nurtured. Cowardice has succeeded to courage, disorder to discipline; the place of the statesman is usurped by the demagogue; and instead of a nation of heroes, marshalled under the supremacy of the wise and good, modern Athens presents to view a disordered and competitive mob, bent only on turning each to his own personal advantage the now corrupt machinery of administration and law. *Thuc. n. 37. — Translated by Jowett. ATHENS i,^ And however much exaggeration there may be in these denmiciations and regrets, we know enough of the interior working of the institutions of Athens to see that she had to pay in licence and in fraud the bitter price of equahty and freedom. That to the influence of disinterested statesmen succeeded, as the democracy accentuated itself, the tyranny of unscrupulous demagogues, is evidenced by the testimony, not only of the enemies of popular government, but by that of a democrat so convinced as Demosthenes! "Smce these orators have appeared," he says, "who ask, What is your pleasure? what shall I move? how can I oblige you? the public welfare is complimented away for a moment's popularity, and these are the results; the orators thrive, you are disgraced .... Anciently the people, having the courage to be soldiers, controlled the statesmen, and disposed of all emoluments ; any of the rest were happy to receive from the people his share of honour, office, or advantage. Now, contrariwise, the statesmen dispose of emoluments ; through them everything is done; you, the people, enervated, stripped of treasure and allies, are become as underlings and hangers-on, happy if these persons dole you out show-money or send you paltty beeves ; and, the unmanliest part of all, you are grateful for receiving your own." * And this indictment is amply confirmed from othei sources. We know that the populace was demoralised by payments from the public purse ; that the fee for attendance m the Assembly attracted thither, as ready instruments in the hands of ambitious men, the poorest and most degraded of the citizens; that the fees of jurors were the chief means 'Dem. 01. in.— Translation by Kennedy. H6 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE of subsistence for an indigent class, who had thus a direct interest in the muhiplication of suits; and that the city was infested by a race of " sycophants ", whose profession was to manufacture frivolous and vexatious indictments. Of one of these men Demosthenes speaks as follows: " He cannot show any respectable or honest employment in which his life is engaged. His mind is not occupied in promoting any political good; he attends not to any trade, or husbandry, or other business; he is connected with no one by tics of humanity or social union : but he walks through the market-place like a viper or a scorpion, with his sting up-lifted, hastening here and there, and look- ing out for someone whom he may bring into a scrape, or fasten some calumny or mischief upon, and put in alarm in order to extort money." ^ From all this we may gather an idea of the way in which the Athenian democracy by its own development destroyed itself. Beginning, on its first emergence from an earlier aristocratic phase, with an energy that inspired without shattering the forms of discipline and law, it dis- solved by degrees this coherent whole into an anarchy of individual wills, drawn deeper and deeper, in pursuit of mean and egoistic ends, into political fraud and commer- cial chicanery, till the tradition of the gentleman and the soldier was choked by the dust of adventurers and swind- ers, and the people, whose fathers had fought and prevailed at Marathon and Salamis, fell as they deserved, by treachery from within as much as by force from without, into the grasp of the Macedonian conqueror. 'Demosth. in Anstogeit. A. 62. — Translated by C. R. Kennedy. -^ SCEPTICAL CRITICISM OF THE BASIS OF THE STATE I I ^ § J I. Sceptical Criticism of the Basis of the State. Having thus supplemented our general account of the Greek conception of the state by a description of their two most prominent polities, it remains for us in conclusion briefly to trace the negative criticism under whose attack that conception threatened to dissolve. We have quoted, in an earlier part of this chapter, a striking passage from Demosthenes, embodying that view of the objective validity of law under which alone political institutions can be secure. "That is law," said the orator, " which all men ought to obey for many reasons, and especially because every law is an invention and gift of the gods, a resolution of wise men, a correction of errors intentional and unintentional, a compact of the whole state, according to which all who belong to the state ought to live." That is the conception of law which the citizens of any stable state must be prepared substantially to accept, for it is the condition of that fundamental belief in established institutions which alone can make it worth while to adapt and to improve them. It was, accordingly, the conception tacitly, at least, accepted in Greece, during the period of her constructive vigour. But it is a con- ception constantly open to attack. For law, at any given moment, even under the most favourable conditions, cannot do more than approximate to its own ideal. It is, at best, but a rough attempt at that reconciliation of con- flicting interests towards which the reason of mankind is always seeking; and even in well-ordered states there must always be individuals and classes who resent, and rightly resent it, as unjust. But the Greek states, as we have seen, were not well-ordered; on the contrary, they 9 Il8 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE were always on the verge, or in the act, of civil war ; and the conception of law, as " a compact of the whole state, according to which all who belong to the state ought to live," must have been, at the least, severely tried, in cities permanently divided into two factions, each intent not merely on defeating the other, but on excluding it alto- gether from political rights. Such conditions, in fact, must have irresistibly suggested the criticism, which always dogs the idea of the state, and against which its only defence is in a perpetual perfection of itself — the criticism that law, after all, is only the rule of the strong, and justice the name under which they gloze their usurpation. That is a point of view which, even apart from their poli- tical dissensions, would hardly have escaped the subtle in- tellect of the Greeks; and in fact, from the close of the fifth century onwards, we find it constantly canvassed and discussed. The mind of Plato, in particular, was exercised by this contention; and it was, one may say, a main object of his teaching to rescue the idea of justice from identifi- cation with the special interest of the strong, and re-afhrm it as the general interest of all. For this end, he takes occasion to state, with the utmost frankness and lucidity, the view which it is his intention to refute; and consequently it is in his works that we find the fullest exposition of the destructive argument he seeks to answer. Briefly, that argument runs as follows: — It is the law of nature that the strong shall rule; a law which every one recognises in fact, though every one repudiates it in theory. Government therefore simply means the rule of the strong, and exists, no matter what its form, whether tyranny, oligarchy, or democracy, in the interests not of SCEPTICAL CRITICISM OF THE BASIS OF THE STATE 1 1 9 its subjects but of itself. "Justice" and "Law" are the specious names it employs to cloak its own arbitrary will; they have no objective validity, no reference to the well-being of all ; and it is only the weak and the fooHsh on whom they impose. Strong and original natures sweep away this tangle of words, assert themselves in defiance of false shame, and claim the right divine that is theirs by nature, to rule at their will by virtue of their strength. "Each government," says Thrasymachus in the Republic, " has its laws framed to suit its own interests ; a democracy making democratic laws; an autocrat despotic laws, and so on. Now by this procedure these governments have pronounced that what is for the interest of themselves is just for their subjects; and whoever deviates from this, is chastised by them as guilty of illegality and injustice. Therefore, my good sir, my meaning is, that in all cities the same thing, namely, the interest of the established govei-nment is just. And superior strength, I presume, is to be found on the side of government. So that the conclusion of right reasoning is, that the same thing, namely, the interest of the stronger, is everywhere just." ^ Here is an argument which strikes at the root of all subordination to the state, setting the subject against the ruler, the minority against the majority, with an emphasis of opposition that admits of no conceivable reconciliation. And, as we have noticed, it was an argument to which the actual political conditions of Greece gave a strong show of plausibility. How then did the constructive thinkers of Greece attempt to meet it? 'Plato, Rep. 338. — Translated by Davies and Vaughan. I20 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE The procedure adopted by Plato is curiously opposed to that which might seem natural to a modern thinker on politics. The scepticism which was to be met, having sprung from the extremity of class-antagonism, it might be sup- posed that the cure would be sought in some sort of system of equality. Plato's idea is, precisely the contrary. The distinction between classes he exaggerates to its highest point ; only he would have it depend on degrees, not of wealth, but of excellence. In the ideal republic which he constructs as a type of a state where justice should really rule, he sets an impassable gulf between the governing class and the governed; each is specially trained and specially bred for its appropriate function ; and the harmony between them is ensured by the recog- nition, on either part, that each is in occupation of the place for which it is naturally fitted in that whole to which both alike are subordinate. Such a state, no doubt, if ever it had been realised in practice, would have been a complete reply to the sceptical argument; for it would have established a "justice" which was the expression not of the caprice of the governing class, but of the objective will of the whole community. But in practice such a state was not realised in Greece ; and the experience of the Greek world does not lead us to suppose that it was capable of realisation. The system of stereotyping classes — in a word, of caste — which has played so great a part in the history of the world, does no doubt embody a great truth, that of natural inequality ; and this truth, as we saw, was at the bottom of that Greek conception of the state, of which the " Republic " of Plato is an idealising caricature. But the problem is to make the inequality of nature really correspond to the inequality SCEPTICAL CRITICISM OF THE BASIS OF THE STATE 1 2 I imposed by institutions. This problem Plato hoped to solve by a strict public control of the marriage relation, so that none should be born into any class who were not naturally fitted to be members of it; but as a matter of fact the difficulty has never been met; and the system of caste remains open to the reproach that its "justice" is conven- tional and arbitrary, not the expression of the objective nature and will of all classes and members of the community. The attempt of Aristotle to construct a state that should be the embodiment of justice is similar to Plato's so far as the relation of classes is concerned. He, too, pos- tulates a governing class of soldiers and councillors, and a subject class of productive labourers. When, however, he turns from the ideal to practical politics, and considers merely how to avoid the worst extremes of party antagonism, his solution is the simple and familiar one of the prepon- derance of the middle class. The same view was dominant both in French and English politics from the year 1830 onwards, and is only now being thrust aside by the democratic ideal. In Greece it was never realised except as a passing phase in the perpetual flux of polities. And in fine it may be said that the problem of establishing a state which should be a concrete refutation of the sceptical criticism that "justice" is merely another name for force, was one that was never solved in ancient Greece. The dissolution of the idea of the state was more a symptom than a cause of its failure in practice to harmonise its warring elements. And Greece, divided into conflicting polities, each of which again was divided within itself, passed on to Macedon and thence to Rome that task of reconciling the individual and the class with the whole, about which the political history of the woild turns. 122 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE ^ 12, Summary. We have now given some account of the general charac- ter of the Greek state, the ideas that underlay it, and the criticism of those ideas suggested by the course of history and formulated by speculative thought. It remains to offer certain reflections on the political achievement of the Greeks, and its relation to our own ideas. The fruitful and positive aspect of the Greek state, that which fastens upon it the eyes of later generations as upon a model, if not to be copied, as least to be praised and admired, is that identification of the individual citizen with the corporate life, which delivered him from the narrow circle of personal interests into a sphere of wider views and higher aims. The Greek citizen, as we have seen, in the best days of the best states, in Athens for example in the age of Pericles, was at once a soldier and a politician; body and mind alike were at his country's service; and his whole ideal of conduct was inextricably bound up with his intimate and personal participation in public affairs. If now with this ideal we contrast the life of an average citizen in a modem state, the absorption in private business and family concerns, the " greasy domes- ticity " (to use a phrase of Byron's), that limits and clouds his vision of the world, we may well feel that the Greeks had achieved something which we have lost, and may even desire to return, so far as we may, upon our steps, and to re-establish that interpenetration of private and public life by which the individual citizen was at once depressed and glorified. It may be doubted, however, whether such a procedure would be in any way possible or desirable. For in the SUMMARY 123 first place, the existence of the Greek citizen depended upon that of an inferior class who were regarded not as ends in themselves, but as means to his perfection. And that is an arrangement which runs directly counter to the modern ideal. All modern societies aim, to this extent at least, at equality, that their tendency, so far as it is con- scious and avowed, is not to separate off a privileged class of citizens, set free by the labour of others to live the perfect life, but rather to distribute impartially to all the burdens and advantages of the state, so that every one shall be at once a labourer for himself and a citizen of the state. But this ideal is clearly incompatible with the Greek conception of the citizen. It implies that the greater portion of every man's life must be devoted to some kind of mechanical labour, whose immediate connection with the public good, though certain, is remote and obscure; and that in consequence a deliberate and unceasing pre- occupation with the end of the state becomes as a general rule impossible. And, in the second place, the mere complexity and size of a modern state is against the identification of the man with the citizen. For, on the one hand, public issues are so large and so involved that it is only a few who can hope to have any adequate comprehension of them; and on the other, the subdivision of functions is so minute that even when a man is directly employed in the service of the state his activity is confined to some highly speci- alised department. He must choose, for example, whether he will be a clerk in the treasury or a soldier; but he can- not certainly be both. In the Greek state any citizen could undertake, simultaneously or in succession, and with complete comprehension and mastery, every one of the 124 T^^ GREEK VIEW OF LIFE comparatively few and simple public offices; in a modern state such an arrangement has become impossible. The mere mechanical and physical conditions of our life pre- clude the ideal of the ancient citizen. But, it may be said, the activity of the citizen of a modern state should be and increasingly will be concerned not with the whole but with the part. By the develop- ment of local institutions he will come, more and more, to identify himself with the public life of his district and his town ; and will bear to that much the same relation as was borne by the ancient Greek to his city state. Certainly so far as the limitation of area, and the simplicity and intelligibility of issues is con- cerned, such an analogy might be fairly pressed ; and it is probably in connection with such local areas that the average citizen does and increasingly will become aware of his corporate relations. But, on the other hand, it can hardly be maintained that public business in this restricted sense either could or should play the part in the life of the modem man that it played in that of the ancient Greek. For local business after all is a matter of sewers and parks ; and however great the importance of such matters may be, and however great their claim upon the attention of competent men, yet the kind of interest they awaken and the kind of faculties they employ can hardly be such as to lead to the identification of the individual ideal with that of public activity. The life of the Greek citizen involved an exer- cise, the finest and most complete, of all his powers of body, soul, and mind ; the same can hardly be said of the life of a county councillor, even of the best and most conscientious of them. And the conclusion appears to SUMMARY 125 be, that that fusion of public and private life which was involved in the ideal of the Greek citizen, was a passing phase in the history of the world ; that the state can never occupy again the place in relation to the individual which it held in the cities of the ancient world ; and that an attempt to identify in a modern state the ideal of the man with that of the citizen, would be an historical anachronism. Nor is this a conclusion which need be regretted. For as the sphere of the state shrinks, it is possible that that of the individual may be enlarged. The public side of human life, it may be supposed, will become more and more mechanical, as our understanding and control of social forces grow. But every reduction to habit and rule of what were once spiritual functions, implies the liberation of the higher powers for a possible activity in other regions. And if advantage were taken of this opportunity, the inestimable compensation for the con- traction to routine of the life of the citizen would be the expansion into new spheres of speculation and passion of the freer and more individual life of the man. CHAPTER III THE GREEK VIEW OF THE INDIVIDUAL § I, The Greek View of Manual Labour and Trade, In our discussion of the Greek view of the State we noticed the tendency both of the theory and the practice of the Greeks to separate the citizens proper from the rest of the community as a distinct and aristocratic class. And this tendency, we had occasion to observe, was partly to be attributed to the high conception which the Greeks had formed of the proper excellence of man, an excellence which it was the function of the citizen to realise in his own person, at the cost, if need be, of the other members of the State. This Greek conception of the proper excel- lence of man it is now our purpose to examine more closely. The chief point that strikes us about the Greek ideal is its comprehensiveness. Our own word " virtue " is applied only to moral qualities ; but the Greek word which we so translate should properly be rendered " excellence," and includes a reference to the body as well as to the soul. A beautiful soul, housed in a beautiful body, and supplied with all the external advantages necessary to ia6 ■^"•'^it^mmma^^^mmH^^m^^'sai^ GREEK VIEW OF MANUAL LABOUR 1 27 produce and perpetuate such a combination — that is the Greek conception of well-being; and it is because labour with the hands or at the desk distorts or impairs the body, and the petty cares of a calling pursued for bread pervert the soul, that so strong a contempt was felt by the Greeks for manual labour and trade. " The arts that are called mechanical," says Xenophon, "are also, and naturally enough, held in bad repute in our cities. For they spoil the bodies of workers and superintendents alike, compelling them to live sedentary indoor lives, and in some cases even to pass their days by the fire. And as their bodies become effeminate, so do their souls also grow less robust. Besides this, in such trades one has no leisure to devote to the care of one's friends or of one's city. So that those who engage in them are thought to be bad backers of their friends and bad defenders of their country." ^ In a similar spirit Plato asserts that a life of drudgery disfigures the body and mars and enervates the soul;' while Aristotle defines a mechanical trade as one which "renders the body and soul or intellect of free persons unfit for the exercise and practice of virtue ;"' and denies to the artisan not merely the proper excellence of man, but any excellence of any kind, on the plea that his occupation and status is unnatural, and that he misses even that reflex of human virtue which a slave derives from his intimate connection with his master.* If then the artisan was excluded from the citizenship *Xen. Oec. iv. 3. •Plato, Rep. 495. •Arist. Pol. V. 1337 b 8.~Translated by Welldon. *Ibid. I. 1260 a 34. 128 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE in some of the Greek states, and even in the most demo- cratic of them never altogether threw off the stigma of inferiority attaching to his trade, the reason was that the life he was compelled to lead was incompatible with the Greek conception of excellence. That conception we will now proceed to examine a little more in detail. § 2. Appreciation of External Goods. In the first place, the Greek ideal required for its realisation a solid basis of external Goods. It recognised frankly the dependence of man upon the world of sense, and the contribution to his happiness of elements over which he had at best but a partial control. Not that it placed his Good outside himself, in riches, power, and other such appendages ; but that it postulated certain gifts of fortune as necessary means to his self-development. Of these the chief were, a competence, to secure him against sordid cares, health, to ensure his physical excellence, and children, to support and protect him in old age. Aristotle's definition of the happy man is " one whose activity accords with perfect virtue and who is adequately furnished with external goods, not for a casual period of time but for a complete or perfect life-time ; " * and he remarks, some- what caustically, that those who say that a man on the rack would be happy if only he were good, intentionally or unintentionally are talking nonsense. That here, as else- where, Aristotle represents the common Greek view we have abundant testimony from other sources. Even Plato, in whom there runs so clear a vein of asceticism, follows the popular judgment in reckoning high among goods, first, health, then beauty, then skill and strength in physical exercises, *Arist. Ethics. I. ii. iioi a 14, — Translated by "Welldon, *'^2 APPRECIATION OF EXTERNAL GOODS 129 and lastly wealth, if it be not blind but illumined by the eye of reason. To these Goods must be added, to com- plete the scale, success and reputation, topics which are the constant theme of the poets' eulogy. "Two things alone there are," says Pindar, "that cherish life's bloom to its utmost sweetness amidst the fair flowers of wealth — to have good success and to win therefore fair fame ; " ^ and the passage represents his habitual attitude. That the gifts of fortune, both personal and external, are an essen- tial condition of excellence, is an axiom of the point of view of the Greeks. But on the other hand we never find them misled into the conception that such gifts are an end in themselves, apart from the personal qualities they are meant to support or adorn. The oriental ideal of unli- mited wealth and power, enjoyed merely for its own sake, never appealed to their fine and lucid judgment. Nothing could better illustrate this point than the anecdote related by Herodotus of the interview between Solon and Croesus, King of Lydia. Croesus, proud of his boundless wealth, asks the Greek stranger who is the happiest man on earth ? expecting to hear in reply his own name. Solon, however, answers with the name of Tellus, the Athenian, giving his reasons in the following speech : "First, because his country was flourishing in his days, and he himself had sons both beautiful and good, and he lived to see children bom to each of them, and these children all grew up ; and further because, after a life spent in what our people look upon as comfort, his end was surpassingly glorious. In a battle between the Athenians and their neighbours near Eleusis, he came to the as- sistance of his countrymen, routed the foe, and died upon 'Pind. Isth. iv. 14. — Translated by E. Myers. I I30 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE the field most gallantly. The Athenians gave him a public funeral on the spot where he fell, and paid him the highest honours." Later on in the discussion Solon defines the happy man as he who " Is whole of limb, a stranger to disease, free from misfortune, happy in his children, and comely to look upon," and who also ends his life well.* § J. Appreciation of Physical Qualities. While, however, the gifts of a happy fortune are an essen- tial condition of the Greek ideal, they are not to be mistaken for the ideal itself. "A beautiful soul in a beautiful body," to recur to our former phrase, is the real end and aim of their endeavour. " Beautiful and good " is their habitual way of describing what we should call a gentleman ; and no expression could better represent what they admired. With ourselves, in spite of our addiction to athletics, the body takes a secondary place; after a certain age, at least, there are few men who make its systematic cultivation an important factor of their life; and in our estimate of merit physical qualities are accorded either none or the very smallest weight. It was otherwise with the Greeks; to them a good body was the necessary correlative of a good soul. Balance was what they aimed at, balance and harmony ; and they could scarcely believe in the beauty of the spirit, unless it were reflected in the beauty of the flesh. The point is well put by Plato, the most spiritually minded of the Greeks, and the least apt to underprize the qualities of the soul. "Surely then," he says, "to him who has an eye to * Herodotus, I. 30. 32. — Translated by Rawlinson. ui jiw ^1* GREEK ATHLETICS 15I see, there can be no fairer spectacle than that of a man who combines the possession of moral beauty in his soul with outward beauty of form, corresponding and harmon- izing with the former, because the same great pattern enters into both. " There can be none so fair. "And you will grant that what is fairest is loveliest? " Undoubtedly it is. "Then the truly musical person will love those who combine most perfectly moral and physical beauty, but will not love any one in whom there is dissonance. " No, not if there be any defect in the soul, but if it is only a bodily blemish, he may so bear with it as to be willing to regard it with complacency. " I understand that you have now, or have had, a favourite of this kind; so I give way.''^ The reluctance of the admission that a physical defect may possibly be overlooked is as significant as the rest of the passage. Body and soul, it is clear, are regarded as aspects of a single whole, so that a blemish in the one in- dicates and involves a blemish in the other. The training of the body is thus, in a sense, the training of the soul, and gymnastic and music, as Plato puts it, serve the same end, the production of a harmonious temperament. § 4. Greek Athletics, It is this conception which gives, or appears at least in the retrospect to give, a character so gracious and fine to Greek athletics. In fact, if we look more closely into the character of the public games in Greece we see that they were so surrounded and transfused by an atmosphere of imag- ' Plato, Rep. 402. — Translated by Davies and Vaughan. 132 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE ination that their appeal must have been as much to the aesthetic as to the physical sense. For in the first place those great gymnastic contests in which all Hellas took part, and which gave the tone to their whole athletic life, were primarily religious festivals. The Olympic and Nemean Games were held in honour of Zeus, the Pythian, of Apollo, the Isthmean, of Poseidon. In the enclosures in which they took place stood temples of the gods; and sacrifice, prayer, and choral hymn were the back-ground against which tliey were set. And since in Greece religion implied art, in the wake of the athlete followed the sculptor and the poet. The colossal Zeus of Pheidias, the wonder of the ancient world, flashed from the precincts of Olympia its glory of ivory and gold ; temples and statues broke the brilliant light into colour and form ; and under that vibrating heaven of beauty, the loveliest nature crowned with the finest art, shifted and shone what was in itself a perfect type of both, the grace of harmonious motion in naked youths and men. For in Greek athletics, by virtue of the practice of contending nude, the contest itself became a work of art; and not only did sculptors draw from it an inspiration such as has been felt by no later age, but to the combatants themselves, and the spectators, the plastic beauty of the human form grew to be more than its prowess or its strength, and gymnastic became a training in aesthetics as much as, or more than, in physical excellence. And as with the contest, so with the reward, everything was designed to appeal to the sensuous imagination. The prize formally adjudged was symbolical only, a crown of olive; but the real triumph of the victor was the ode in which his praise was sung, the procession of happy comrades, and the evening festival, when, as Pindar has it, GREEK ATHLETICS 1 33 •the lovely shining of the fair-faced moon beamed forth, and all the precinct sounded with songs of festal glee,"* or " beside Kastaly in the evening his name burnt bright, when the glad sounds of the Graces rose."' Of the Graces ! for these were the powers who presided over the world of Greek athletics. Here, for example, is the opening of one of Pindar's odes, typical of the spirit m which he at least conceived the functions of the chroni- cler of sport: " O ye who haunt the land of goodly steeds that drinketh of Kephisos' waters, lusty Orchomenos' Queens renowned in song, O Graces, guardians of the Minyai's ancient race, hearken, for unto you I pray. For by your gift come unto men all pleasant things and sweet, and the wisdom of a man and his beauty, and the splendour of his fame. Yea, even gods without the Graces' aid rule never at feast or dance; but these have charge of all things done in heaven, and beside Pythian Apollo of the golden bow they have set their thrones, and worship the eternal majesty of the Olympian Father. O lady Aglaia, and thou Euphrosyne, lover of song, children of the mightiest of the gods, listen and hear, and thou Thalia delighting in sweet sounds, and look down upon this triumphal company, moving with light step under happy fate. In Lydian mood of melody concerning Asopichos am I come hither to sing, for that through thee, Aglaia, in the Olympic games the Minyai's home is winner."' This is but a single passage among many that might be quoted to illustrate the point we are endeavouring to 'Pindar, Ol. xi. 90. — Translated by Myers 'Pindar, Nero. 6. 65. • Pindar, 01 xiv. — Translated by Myers. 134 "^HE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE bring into relief— the conscious predominance in the Greek games of that element of poetry and art which is either not present at all in modern sport or at best is a happy accessory of chance. The modern man, and especially the Englishman, addicts himself to athletics, as to other avocations, with a certain stolidity of gaze on the immediate end which tends to confine him to the purely physical view of his pursuit. The Greek, an artist by nature, lifted his not less strenuous sports into an air of finer sentiment, touched them with the poetry of legend and the grace of art and song, and even to his most brutal contests— for brutal some of them were — imparted so rich an atmosphere of beauty, that they could be admitted as fit themes for dedication to the Graces by the choice and spiritual genius of Pindar. § 5. Greek Ethics— Identification of the Esthetic and Ethical Points of View. And as with the excellence of the body, so with that of the soul, the conception that dominated the mind of the Greeks was primarily sesthetic. In speaking of their religion we have already remarked that they had no sense of sin; and we may now add that they had no sense of duty. Moral virtue they conceived not as obedience to an external law, a sacrifice of the natural man to a power that in a sense is alien to himself, but rather as the tempering into due proportion of the elements of which human nature is composed. The good man was the man who was beautiful— beautiful in soul. "Virtue," says Plato, "will be a kmd of health and beauty and good habit of the soul; and vice will be a disease and defonnity _7 GREEK ETHICS 1 35 and sickness of it."* It follows that it is as natural to seek virtue and to avoid vice as to seek health and to avoid disease. There is no question of a struggle between opposite principles; the distinction of good and evil is one of order or confusion, among elements which in themselves are neither good nor bad. This conception of virtue we find expressed in many forms, but always with the same underlying idea. A favourite watch -word with the Greeks is the " middle" or "mean", the exact point of Tightness between two ex- tremes. "Nothing in excess," was a motto inscribed over the temple of Delphi; and none could be more charac- teristic of the ideal of these lovers of proportion. Aristotle, indeed, has made it the basis of his whole the- ory of ethics. In his conception, virtue is the mean, vice the excess lying on either side — courage, for example, the mean between foolhardiness and cowardice, temperance, between incontinence and insensibility, generosity, between extravagance and meanness. The various phases of feeling and the various kinds of action he analyses minutely on this principle, understanding always by " the mean" that which adapts itself in the due proportion to the circum- stances and requirements of every case. The interest of this view for us lies in its assumption that it is not passions or desires in themselves that must be regarded as bad, but only their disproportional or misdirected indulgence. Let us take, for example, the case of the pleasures of sense. The puritan's rule is to abjure them altogether; to him they are absolutely wrong in themselves, apart from all considerations of time and place. Aristotle, on the contrary, enjoins not renunciation but ' Plato, Rep. 444. — Translated by Davies and Vaughan. 136 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE temperance; and defines the temperate man as one who " holds a mean position in respect of pleasures. He takes no pleasure in the things in which the licentious man takes most pleasure; he rather dislikes them; nor does he take pleasure at all in wrong things, nor an excessive pleasure in anything that is pleasant, nor is he pained at the absence of such things, nor does he desire them, except perhaps in moderation, nor does he desire them more than is right, or at the wrong time, and so on. But he will be eager in a moderate and right spirit for all such things as are pleasant and at the same time con- ducive to health or to a sound bodily condition, and for all other pleasures, so long as they are not prejudicial to these or inconsistent with noble conduct or extravagant beyond his means. For unless a person limits himself in this way, he affects such pleasures more than is right, whereas the temperate man follows the guidance of right reason."* As another illustration of this point of view, we may take the case of anger. The Christian rule is never to resent an injury, but rather, in the New Testament phrase, to " turn the other cheek." Aristotle, while blaming the man who is unduly passionate, blames equally the man who is insensitive ; the thing to aim at is to be angry " on the proper occasions and with the proper people in the proper manner and for the proper length of time." And in this and all other cases the definition of what is proper must be left to the determination of "the sensible man." Thus, in place of a series of hard and fast rules, a rigid and uncompromising distinction of acts and af- 'Arist. Ethics. HE. 14. — H19 a ii. — Translated by Welldon. •"Ml GREEK ETHICS 137 fections into good and bad, the former to be absolutely chosen and the latter absolutely eschewed, Aristotle presents us with the general type of a subtle and shifting problem, the solution of which must be worked out afresh by each individual in each particular case. Conduct to him is a free and living creature, and not a machine controlled by fixed laws. Every life is a work of art shaped by the man who lives it; according to the faculty of the artist will be the quality of his work, and no general rules can supply the place of his own direct perception at every turn. The Good is the right proportion, the right manner and occasion; the Bad is all that varies from this " right." But the elements of human nature in themselves are neither good nor bad ; they are merely the raw material out of which the one or the other may be shaped. The idea thus formulated by Aristotle is typically Greek. In another form it is the basis of the ethical philosophy of Plato, who habitually regards virtue as a kind of " order." " The virtue of each thing, " he says, " whether body or soul, instrument or creature, when given to them in the best way comes to them not by chance but as the result of the order and truth and art which are imparted to them."^ And the conception here indicated, is worked out in detail in his Republic. There, after distinguishing in the soul three principles or powers, reason, passion, and de- sire, he defines justice as the maintenance among them of their proper mutual relation, each moving in its own place and doing its appropriate work as is, or should be, the case with the diflerent classes in a state. " The just man will not permit the several principles * Plato, Gorgias, 506 d. — Translated by Jowett. 13^ THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE within him to do any work but their own, nor allow the distinct classes in his soul to interfere with each other, but will really set his house in order; and having gained the mastery over himself, will so regulate his own charac- ter as to be on good terms with himself, and to set those three principles in tune together, as if they were verily three chords of a harmony, a higher and a lower and a middle, and whatever may lie between these; and after he has bound all these together, and reduced the many elements of his nature to a real unity, as a temperate and duly harmonized man, he will then at length proceed to do whatever he may have to do."* Plato, it is true, in other parts of his work, approaches more closely to the dualistic conception of an absolute opposition between good and bad principles in man. Yet even so, he never altogether abandons that aesthetic point of view which looks to the establishment of order among the conflicting principles rather than to the annihilation of one by the other in an internecine conflict. The point may be illustrated by the following passage, where the two horses represent respectively the elements of fleshly desire and spiritual passion, while the charioteer stands for the controlling reason; and where, it will be noticed, the ultimate harmony is achieved, not by the complete eradication of desire, but by its due subordination to the higher principle. Even Plato, the most ascetic of the Greeks, is a Greek first and an ascetic afterwards. **0f the nature of the soul, though her true form be ever a theme of large and more than mortal discourse, let me speak briefly, and in a figure, and let the figure be * Plato, Rep. IV. 443. — Translation by Davies and Vaughau. GREEK ETHICS 1 39 composite — a pair of winged horses and a charioteer. Now the winged horses and the charioteers of the gods are all of them noble and of noble descent, but those of other races are mixed; the human charioteer drives his in a pair; and one of them is noble and of noble breed, and the other is ignoble and of ignoble breed; and the driving of them of necessity gives a great deal of trouble to him The right hand horse is upright and cleanly made; he has a lofty neck and an aquiline nose; his colour is white, and his eyes dark; he is a lover of honour and modesty and temperance, and the follower of true glory ; he needs no touch of the whip, but is guided by word and admoni- tion only. The other is a crooked lumbering animal, put together anyhow; he has a short thick neck; he is flat- faced and of a dark colour, with grey eyes and blood-red complexion; the mate of insolence and pride, shag-eared and deaf, hardly yielding to whip and spur. Now when the charioteer beholds the vision of love, and has his whole soul warmed through sense, and is full of the prickings and ticklings of desire, the obedient steed, then as always under the government of shame, refrains from leaping on the beloved; but the other, heedless of the blows of the whip, plunges and runs away, giving all manner of trouble to his companion and the charioteer, whom he forces to approach the beloved and to remember the joys of love. They at first indignantly oppose him and will not be urged on to do terrible and unlawful deeds ; but at last, when he persists in plaguing them, they yield and agree to do as he bids them. And now they are at the spot and behold the flashing beauty of the beloved; which when the charioteer sees, his memory is carried to the true beauty whom he beholds in company I40 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE with Modesty like an image placed upon a holy pedestal He sees her, but he is afraid and falls backwards in adoration, and by his fall is compelled to pull back the reins with such violence as to bring both the steeds on their haunches, the one willing and unresisting, the unruly one very unwilling; and when they have gone back a little, the one is overcome with shame and wonder, and his whole soul is bathed in perspiration; the other, when the pain is over which the bridle and the fall had given him, having with difficulty taken breath, is full of wrath and reproaches, which he heaps upon the charioteer and his fellow-steed, for want of courage and manhood, declaring that they have been false to their agreement and guilty of desertion. Again they refuse, and again he urges them on, and will scarce yield to their prayer that he would wait until another time. When the appointed hour comes, they make as if they had forgotten, and he reminds them, fighting and neighing and dragging them on, until at length he on the same thoughts intent, forces them to draw near again. And when they are near he stoops his head and puts up his tail, and takes the bit in his teeth and pulls shamelessly. Then the charioteer is worse off than ever; he falls back like a racer at the barrier, and with a still more violent wrench drags the bit out of the teeth of the wild steed and covers his abusive jaws and tongue with blood, and forces his legs and haunches to the ground and punishes him sorely. "And when this has happened several times and the villain has ceased from his wanton way, he is tamed and humbled and follows the will of the charioteer, and when ,he sees the beautiful one he is ready to die of fear. And l«ft«#*«»H*Vf »*l^«4ft««V - GREEK ETHICS I41 from that time forward the soul of the lover loUows the beloved in modesty and holy fear." * Even from this passage, in spite of its dualistic hy- pothesis, but far more clearly from the whole tenor of his work, we may perceive that Plato's description of virtue as an " order " of the soul is prompted by the same conception, characteristically Greek, as Aristotle's account of virtue as a " mean.** The view, as we said at the beginning, iS properly aesthetic rather than moral. It regards life less as a battle between two contending principles, in which victory means the annihilation of the one, the altogether bad, by the other, the altogether good, than as the mainten- ance of a balance between elements neutral in themselves but capable, according as their relations are rightly or- dered or the reverse, of producing either that harmony which is called virtue, or that discord which is called vice. Such being the conception of virtue characteristic of the Greeks, it follows that the motive to pursue it can hardly have presented itself to them in the form of what we call the "sense of duty." For duty emphasises self- repres- sion. Against the desires of man it sets a law of prohi- bition, a law which is not conceived as that of his own complete nature, asserting against a partial or disproportioned development the balance and totality of the ideal, but rather as a rule imposed from without by a power distinct from himself, for the mortification, not the perfecting, of his natural impulses and aims. Duty emphasises self- repression; the Greek view emphasised self-development. That "health and beauty and good habit of the soul," which is Plato's ideal, is as much its own recommencia- * Plato, Phaednis. 246. — Trauslated by JowcU, 142 THE GP^iiK VI£W OF LIFE tion to tlie natural man as is the health and beauty of the body. Vice, on this view, is condemned because it iij a frustration of nature, virtue praised because it is her fulfilment; and the motive throughout is simply that passion to realise oneself which is commonly acknowledged as sufficient in the case of physical development, and which appeared sufficient to the Greeks in the case of the development of the soul. § 6. The Greek View of Pie astir e. From all this it follows clearly enough that the Greek ideal was far removed from asceticism; but it might per- haps be supposed, on the other hand, that it came dan- <^erously near to license. Nothing, however, could be fur- ther from the case. That there were libertines among the Greeks, as everywhere else, goes without saying ; but the conception that the Greek rule of life was to follow impulse and abandon restraint is a figment of would-be "Hellenists" of our own time. The word which best sums up the ideal of the Greeks is " temperance " ; " the mean," "order," "harmony," as we saw, are its charac- teristic expressions; and the self-realisation to which they aspired was not an anarchy of passion, but an ordered evolution of the natural faculties under the strict control of a balanced mind. The point may be illustrated by a reference to the treatment of pleasure in the philosophy of Plato and of Aristotle. The practice of the libertine is to identify pleasure and good in such a manner that he pursues at any moment any pleasure that presents itself, eschewing comparison and reflection, with all that might tend to check that continuous THE GREEK VIEW OF PLEASURE 143 flow of vivid and fresh sensations which he postulates as the end of Ufe. The ideal of the Greeks, on the contrary, as interpreted by their two greatest thinkers, while on the one hand it is so far opposed to asceticism that it re- quires pleasure as an essential complement of Good, on the other, is so far from identifying the two, that it recognises an ordered scale of pleasures, and while rejecting altogether those at the lower end, admits the rest, not as in them selves constituting the Good, but rather as harmless additions or at most as necessary accompaniments of its opera- tion. Plato, in the Republic, distinguishes between the necessary and unnecessary pleasures, defining the former as those derived from the gratification of appetites " which we cannot get rid of and whose satisfaction does us good" — such, for example, as the appetite for wholesome food; and the latter as those which belong to appetites " which we can put away from us by early training ; and the presence of which, besides, never does us any good, and in some cases does positive harm, " — such, for example, as the appetite for delicate and luxurious dishes. ^ The former he would admit, the latter he excludes from his ideal of happiness. And though in a later dialogue, the Philebus, he goes further than this, and would exclude from the perfect life all pleasures except those which he describes as " pure," that is those which attend upon the contemplation of form and colour and sound, or which accompany intellectual activity; yet here, no doubt, he is passing beyond the sphere of the practicable ideal, and his distinct personal bias towards asceticism must be dis- counted if we are to take him as representative of the *Plato, Rep. VIII. 558. — Translated by Davies and Vaiighan, 144 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE Greek view. His general contention, however, that pleasures must be ranked as higher and as lower, and that at the best they are not to be identified with the Good, is fully accepted by so typical a Greek as Aristotle. Aristotle, however, is careful not to condemn any pleasure that is not definitely hannful. Even " unnecessary " pleasures, he admits, may be desirable in themselves; even the deliberate creation of desire with a view to the enjoyment of satisfying it may be admissible if it is not injurious. Still, there are kinds of pleasures which ought not to be pursued, and occasions and methods of seeking it which are improper and perverse. Therefore the Reason must be always at hand to check and to control ; and the ultimate test of true worth in pleasure, as in everything else, is the trained judgment of the good and sensible man. § y. Illustrations — Ischomachus ; Socrates. Such, then, was the character of the Greek conception of excellence. The account we have given may seem somewhat abstract and ideal; but it gives the general formula of the life which every cultivated Greek would at any rate have wished to live. And in confirmation of this point we may adduce the testimony of Xenophon, who has left us a description, evidently drawn from life, of what he conceives to be the perfect type of a " gentleman." The interest of the account lies in the fact, that Xenophon himself was clearly an "average" Greek, one, that is to say, of good natural parts, of perfectly normal faculties and tastes, undisturbed by any originality of character or mind, and representing therefore, as we may fairly assert, the ordinary views and aims of an upright and competent man of the world. His description of the "gentleman," therefore, ITLUSTI^JVTIONS— ISCHOMACHUS ; SOCl^ATES 1 45 may be taken as a representative account of the recognised ideal of all that class of Athenian citizens. And this is how the gentleman in question, Ischomachus, describes his course of life. " In the first place," he says, " I worship the gods. Next, I endeavour to the best of my ability, assisted by prayer, to get health and strength of body, reputation in the city, good will among my friends, honourable security in battle and an honourable increase of fortune." At this point Socrates, who is supposed to be the inter- locutor, interrupts. "Do you really covet wealth," he asks, "with all the trouble it involves?" " Certainly I do," is the reply, " for it enables me to honour the gods magnifi- cently, to help my friends if they are in want, and to con- tribute to the resources of my country." Here definitely and precisely expressed is the ideal of the Athenian gentleman — the beautiful body housing the beautiful soul, the external aids of fortune, friends, and the like, and the realisation of the individual self in public activity. Upon it follows an account of the way in which Ischomachus was accustomed to pass his days. He rises early, he tells us, to catch his friends before they go out, or walks to the city to transact his necessary business. If he is not called into town, he pays a visit to his farm, walking for the sake of exercise and sending on his horse. On his arrival he gives directions about the sowing, ploughing, or whatever it may be, and then mounting his horse practices his miUtary exercises. Finally he returns home on foot, running part of the way, takes his bath, and sits down to a moderate midday meal. This combination of physical exercise, military training and business, arouses the enthusiasm of Socrates. " How 146 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE right you are!" he cries, "and the consequence is that you are as healthy and strong as we see you, and one of the best riders and the wealthiest men in the country!" This little prosaic account of the daily life of an Athe- nian gentleman is completely in harmony with all we have said about the character of the Greek ideal ; but it compre- hends only a part, and that the least spiritual, of that rich and many-sided excellence. It may be as well, therefore, to append by way of complement the descrip- tion of another personality, exceptional indeed even among the Greeks, yet one which only Greece could have produced— the personality of Socrates. No more striking figure is presented to us in history, none has been more vividly portrayed, and none, in spite of the originality of mind which provoked the hostility of the crowd, is more thoroughly Hellenic in every aspect, physical, intellectual, and moral. That Socrates was ugly in countenance was a defect which a Greek could not fail to note, and his snub nose and big belly are matters of frequent and jocose allusion. But apart from these defects his physique, it appears, was excep- tionally good; he was sedulous in his attendance at the gym- nasia, and was noted for his powers of endurance and his courage and skill in war. Plato records it of him that in a hard winter on campaign, when the common soldiers were muffling themselves in sheepskins and felt against the cold, he alone went about in his ordinary cloak, and barefoot over the ice and snow; and he further describes his bearing in a retreat from a lost battle, how "there you might see him, just as he is in the streets of Athens, stalking like a pelican and rolling his eyes, calmly con- templating enemies as well as friends, and making very ILLUSTRATIONS— ISCHOAIACHUS ; SOCRATES 1 47 intelligible to anybody, even from a distance, that whoever attacked him would be likely to meet with a stout re- sistance."* To this efficiency of body corresponded, in accordance with the Greek ideal, a perfect balance and harmony of soul. Plato, in a fine figure, compares him to the wooden statues of Silenus, which concealed behind a grotesque exterior beautiful golden images of the gods. Of these divine forms none was fairer in Socrates than that typical Greek virtue, temperance. Without a touch of asceticism, he knew how to be contented with a little. His diet he measured strictly with a view to health. Naturally abstemious, he could drink, when he chose, more than another man; but no one had ever seen him drunk. His affections were strong and deep, but never led him away to seek his own gratification at the cost of those he loved. With- out cutting himself off from any of the pleasures of life, a social man and a frequent guest at feasts, he preserved without an effort the supremacy of character and mind over the flesh he neither starved nor pampered. Here is a description by Plato of his bearing at the close of an all-night carouse, which may stand as a concrete illustra- tion not only of the character of Socrates, but of the meaning of "temperance" as it was understood by the Greeks : "Aristodemus said that Eryximachus, Phaedrus, and others went away — he himself fell asleep, and as the nights were long took a good rest: he was awakened towards day-break by a crowing of cocks, and when he awoke the others were either asleep, or had gone away; there Plato, Symp. 221 b.- -Translated by Jowett. 148 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE remained awake only Socrates, Aristophanes, and Agathon, who were drinking out of a large goblet which they passed round, and Socrates was discoursing to them. Aristodemus did not hear the beginning of the discourse, and he was only half awake, but the chief thing which he remembered was Socrates compelling the other two to acknowledge that the genius of comedy was the same as that of tragedy, and that the true artist in tragedy was an artist in comedy also. To this they assented, being drowsy, and not quite following the argument. And first of all Aristophanes dropped off, then, when the day was already dawning, Agathon. Socrates, when he had laid them to sleep, rose to depart: Aristodemus, as his manner was, following him. At the Lyceum he took a bath, and passed the day as usual. In the evening he retired to rest at his own house."* With this quality of temperance was combined in Socra- tes a rare measure of independence and moral courage. He was never an active politician; but as every Athenian citizen was called, at some time or another, to public office, he found himself, on a critical occasion, responsible for putting a certain proposition to the vote in the Assembly. It was a moment of intense excitement. A great victory had just been won; but the generals who had achieved the success had neglected to recover the corpses of the dead or to save the ship-wrecked. It was proposed to take a vote of life or death on all the generals collectively. Socrates, as it happened, was one of the committee whose duty it was to put the question to the Assembly. But the proposition was in itself illegal, and Socrates with 'Plato, SymposJon, 2 23.— Translated by Jowett. ILLUSTRATIONS— ISCHOMACHUS ; SOCRATES I 49 some other members of the committee, refused to submit it to the vote. Every kind of pressure was brought tu bear upon the recalcitrant officers; orators threatened, friends besought, the mob clamoured and denounced. Finally all but Socrates gave way. He alone, an old man, in office for the first time, had the courage to obey his conscience and the law in face of an angry populace crying for blood. And as he could stand against a mob, so he could stand against a despot. At the time when Athens was ruled by the thirty tyrants he was ordered, with four others, to arrest a man whom the authorities wished to put out of the way. The man was guilty of no crime, and Socrates refused. "I went quietly home," he says, "and no doubt I should have been put to death for it, if the government had not shortly after come to an end." These, however, were exceptional episodes in the career of a man who was never a prominent politician. The main interest of Socrates was intellectual and moral; an interest, however, rather practical than speculative. For though he was charged in his indictment with preaching atheism, he appears in fact to have concerned himself little or nothing with either theological or physical inquiries. He was careful in his observance of all prescribed religious rites, and probably accepted the gods as powers of the natural world and authors of human institutions and laws. His originality lay not in any purely speculative views, but in the pertinacious curiosity, practical in its origin and aim, with which he attacked and sifted the ethical conceptions ot his time: "What is justice?" "What is piety?" " What is temperance ?" — these were the kinds of questions he never tired of raising, pointing out contradictions and T I 150 THE 4^REEK VIEW OF LIFE inconsistencies in current ideas, and awakening doubts which if negative in form were positive and fruitful in effect. His method in pursuing these inquiries was that of cross- examination. In the streets, in the market, in the gym- nasia, at meetings grave and gay, in season or out of season, he raised his points of definition. The city was in a ferment around him. Young men and boys followed and hung on his lips wherever he went. By the charm of his personality, his gracious courtesy and wit, and the large and generous atmosphere of a sympathy always at hand to temper to particular persons the rigours of a generalising logic, he drew to himself, with a fascination not more of the intellect than of the heart, all that was best and brightest in the youth of Athens. His relation to his young disciples was that of a lover and a friend ; and the stimulus given by his dialectics to their keen and eager minds was supplemented and re- inforced by the appeal to their admiration and love of his sweet and virile personality. Only in Ancient Athens, perhaps, could such a character and such conditions have met. The sociable out-door city Hfe ; the meeting places in the open air, and especially the gymnasia, frequented by young and old not more for exercise of the body than for recreation of the mind ; the nimble and versatile Athenian wits trained to preternatural acuteness by the debates of the law courts and the Assembly; all this was exactly the environment fitted to develop and sustain a genius at once so subtle and so humane as that of Socrates. It is the concrete presen- tation of this city-life that lends so peculiar a charm to the dialogues of Plato. The spirit of metaphysics puts on ILLUSTRATIONS— ISCHOMACHUS; SOCRATES 151 the human form; and Dialectic walks the streets and contends in the palaestra. It would be impossible to convey by citation the cumulative effect of this constant reference in Plato to a human background; but a single excerpt may perhaps help us to realise the conditions under which Socrates lived and worked. Here, then, is a description of the scene in one of those gymnasia in which he was wont to hold his conversations: " Upon entering we found that the boys had just been sacrificing; and this part of the festival was nearly at an end. They were all in white array, and games at dice were going on among them. Most of them were in the outer court amusing themselves ; but some were in a comer of the x\podyterium playing at odd and even with a number of dice, which they took out of little wicker baskets. There was also a circle of lookers-on, one of whom was Lysis. He was standing among the other boys and youths, having a crown upon his head, hke a fair vision, and not less worthy of praise for his goodness than for his beauty. We left them, and went over to the opposite side of the room, where, finding a quiet place, we sat down ; and then we began to talk. This attracted Lysis, who was constantly turning round to look at us — he was evidently wanting to come to us. For a time he hesitated and had not the courage to come alone; but first of all, his friend Menexenus came in out of the court in the interval of his play, and when he saw Ctesippus and myself, came and sat by us; and then Lysis, seeing him, followed, and sat down with him, and the other boys joined. "I turned to Menexenus, and said: 'Son of Demophon, which of you two youths is the elder?' 152 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE "'That is a matter of dispute between us,' he said. " ' And which is the nobler ? Is that a matter of dispute too?' " ' Yes, certainly. ' " ' And another disputed point is, which is the fairer ? ' "The two boys laughed. " * I shall not ask which is the richer, ' I said ; * for you two are friends, are you not?' " * Certainly, ' they replied. "'And friends have all things in common, so that one of you can be no richer than the other, if you say truly that you are friends.' "They assented. I was about to ask which was the greater of the two, and which was the wiser of the two; but at this moment Menexenus was called away by some one who came and said that the gymnastic-master wanted him. I supposed that he had to offer sacrifice. So he went away and I asked Lysis some more questions." * Such were the scenes in which Socrates passed his life. Of his influence it is hardly necessary here to speak at length. In the well-known metaphor put into his mouth by Plato, he was the "gad-fly" of the Athenian people. To prick intellectual lethargy, to force people to think, and especially to think about the conceptions with which they supposed themselves to be most familiar, those which guided their conduct in private and public affairs— justice expediency, honesty, and the like— such was the constant object of his life. That he should have made enemies, that he should have been misunderstood, that he should have been accused of undermining the foundations of 'Plato, Lysis 206 e.^Translated by Jowett. ILLUSTRATIONS— ISCHOMACHUS; SOCRATES 1 53 morality and religion, is natural and intelligible enough; and it was on these grounds that he was condemned to death. His conduct at his trial was of a piece with the rest of his life. The customary arts of the pleader, the appeal to the sympathies of the public, the introduction into court of weeping wife and children, he rejected as unworthy of himself and of his cause. His defence was a simple exposition of the character and the aims of his life; so far from being a criminal he asserted that he was a benefactor of the Athenian people; and having, after his condemnation, to suggest the sentence he thought appropriate, he proposed that he should be supported at the public expense as one who had deserved well of his country. After his sentence to death, having to wait thirty days for its execution, he showed no change from his customary cheerfulness, passing his time in conver- sation with his friends. So far from regretting his fate he rather congratulated himself that he would escape the decadence that attends upon old age; and he had, if we may trust Plato, a fair and confident assurance that a happy life awaited him beyond. He died, according to the merciful law of Athens, by drinking hemlock ; " the wisest and justest and best," in Plato's judgment, "of all the men that I have ever known." We have dwelt thus long on the personality of Socrates, familiar though it be, not only on account of its intrinsic interest, but also because it is peculiarly Hellenic. That sunny and frank intelligence, bathed, as it were, in the open air, a gracious blossom springing from the root of physical health, that unique and perfect balance of body and soul, passion and intellect, represent, against the bril- liant setting of Athenian life, the highest achievement of 154 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE the civilisation of Greece. The figure of Socrates, no doubt, has been idealised by Plato, but it is none the less significant of the trend of Hellenic life. No other people could have conceived such an ideal ; no other could have gone so far towards its realisation. § S. The Greek View of Wo7na7i. In the preceding account we have attempted to give some conception of the Greek ideal for the individual man. It is now time to remind ourselves that that ideal was only supposed to be proper to a small class — the class of soldier-citizens. Artisans and slaves, as we have seen, had no participation in it; neither, and that is our next point, had women. Nothing more profoundly distinguishes the Hellenic from the modern view of life than the estimate in which women were held by the Greeks. Their opinion on this point was partly the cause and partly the effect of that preponder- ance of the idea of the State on which we have already dwelt, and from which it followed naturally enough that marriage should be regarded primarily as a means of producing healthy and efficient citizens. This view is best illustrated by the institutions of such a State as Sparta, where, as we saw, the woman was specially trained for maternity, and connections outside the marriage tie were sanctioned by custom and opinion, if they were such as were likely to lead to healthy offspring. Further it may be noted that in almost every State the exposure of deformed or sickly infants was encouraged by law, the child being thus regarded, from I THE GREEK VIEW OF WOMAN 1 55 tne beginning, as a member of the State, rather than as a member of the family. The same view is reflected in the speculations of polit- ical philosophers. Plato, indeed, in his Republic, goes so far as to eliminate the family relation altogether. Not only is the whole connection between men and women to be regulated by the State, in respect both of the persons and of the limit of age within which they may associate, but the children as soon as they are born are to be carried off to a common nursery, there to be reared together, undistinguished by the mothers, who will suckle indifferently any infant that might happen to be assigned to them for the purpose. Here, as in other instances, Plato goes far beyond the limits set by the current senti- ment of the Greeks, and in his later work is reluctantly constrained to abandon his scheme of community of wives and children. Yet even there he makes it com- pulsory on every man to marry between the ages of thirty and thirty-five, under penalty of fine and civil disabilities. Plato, no doubt, as we have said, exaggerates the opinions of his time; but the view, which he pushes to its extreme, of the subordination of the family to the State, was one, as we have already pointed out, which did predominate in Greece. It reappears in a soberer form in the treatise of Aristotle. He too woulc regulate by law both the age at which marriages should take place and the number of children that should be produced, and would have all deformed infants exposed. And here, no doubt, he is speaking in conformity if not with the practice, at least with the feeling of Greece. The modem conception that the marriage relation is a matter of private concern, and that any individual has a 156 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE right to wed whom and when he will, and to produce children at his own discretion, regardless of all consid- erations of health and decency, was one altogether alien to the Greeks. In theory at least, and to some extent in practice (as for example in the case of Sparta), they re- cognised that the production of children was a business of supreme import to the State, and that it was right and proper that it should be regulated by law with a view to the advantage of the whole community. And if now we turn from considering the family in its relation to the State to regard it in its relation to the individual, we are struck once more by a divergence from the modern point of view, or rather from the view which is supposed to prevail, particularly by writers of fiction, at any rate in modem English life. In ancient Greece, so far as our knowledge goes, there was little or no romance connected with the marriage tie. Marriage was a means of producing legitimate children; that is how it is defined by Demosthenes; and we have no evidence that it was ever regarded as anything more. In Athens we know that marriages were commonly arranged by the father, much as they are in modern France, on grounds of age, property, connection and the like, and without any regard for the inclination of the parties concerned. And an interesting passage in Xenophon indicates a point of view quite consonant with this accepted practice. God, he says, ordained the institution of marriage ; but on what grounds ? Not in the least for the sake of the personal relation that might be established between the husband and wife, but for ends quite external and indifferent to any affection that might exist between them. First, for the perpetua- THE GREEK VIEW OF WOMAN 1 57 tion of the human race; secondly, to raise up protectors for the father in his old age; thirdly, to secure an ap- propriate division of labour, the man performing the out- door work, the woman guarding and superintending at home, and each thus fulfilling duly the function for which they were designed by nature. This eminently prosaic way of conceiving the marriage relation, is also, it would seem, eminently Greek ; and it leads us to consider more particularly the opinion prevalent in Greece of the nature and duty of woman in general. Here the first point to be noticed is the wide differ- ence of the view represented in the Homeric poems from that which meets us in the historic period. Readers of the Iliad and the Odyssey will find depicted there, amid all the barbarity of an age of rapine and war, relations between men and women so tender, faithful and beauti- ful, that they may almost stand as universal types of the ultimate human ideal. Such for example is the relation between Odysseus and Penelope, the wife waiting year by year for the husband whose fate is unknown, wooed in vain by suitors who waste her substance and wear her hfe, nightly "watering her bed with her tears" for twenty weary years, till at last the wanderer returns, and "at once her knees were loosened and her heart melted within her . . . and she fell a weeping and ran straight towards him, and cast her hands about his neck, and kissed his head ; " for " even as the sight of the land is welcome to mariners, so welcome to her was the sight of her lord, and her white arms would never quite leave hold of his neck."* *Odyss. XXni. 205, 231. — Translated by Butcher and Lang. 158 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE Such, again, is the relation between Hector and Andro- mache as described in the well-known scene of the Iliad, where the wife comes out with her babe to take leave of the husband on his way to battle. " It were better for me," she cries, "to go down to the grave if I lose thee; for never will any comfort be mine, when once thou, even thou, hast met thy fate, but only sorrow Thou art to me father and lady mother, yea, and brother, even as thou art my goodly husband. Come now, have pity and abide here upon the tower, lest thou make thy child an orphan and thy wife a widow." Hector answers with the plea of honour. He cannot draw back, but he foresees defeat; and in his anticipation of the future nothing is so bitter as the fate he fears for his wife. " Yet doth the conquest of the Trojans hereafter not so much trouble me, neither Hekabe's own, neither King Priam's, neither my brethren's, the many and brave that shall fall in the dust before their foemen, as doth thine anguish in the day when some mail-clad Achaian shall lead thee weeping and rob thee of the light of freedom .... But me in death may the heaped-up earth be covering, ere I hear thy crying and thy carrying into captivity. " * But most striking of all the portraits of women to be found in Homer, and most typical of a frank and healthy relation between the sexes, is the account of Nausicaa given in the Odyssey. Ulysses, shipwrecked and naked, battered and covered with brine, surprises Nausicaa and her maidens as they are playing at ball on the shore. The attendants run away, but Nausicaa remains to hear 'Iliad VI. 450. — Translated by Lang, Leaf and Myers, ■rrr THE GREEK VIEW OF WOMAN 159 what the stranger has to say. He asks her for shelter and clothing; and she grants the request, with an exquisite courtesy and a freedom from all embarrassment which becomes only the more marked and the more delightful when, as she sees him emerge from the bath, clotjied and beautiful, she cannot restrain the exclamation "would that such a one might be called my husband, dwelling here, and that it might please him here to abide." 1 About the whole scene there is a freshness and a fragrance as of early morning, and a tone so natural, free and frank, that in the face of this rustic idyl the later centuries sicken and faint, like candle-light in the splendour of the dawn. If we had only Homer to give us our ideas of the Greeks, we might conclude, from such passages as these, that they had a conception of woman and of her relation to man, finer and nobler, in some respects, than that of modem times. But in fact the Homeric poems represent a civilisation which had passed away before the opening of the period with which at present we are chiefly con- cerned. And in the interval, for reasons which we need not here attempt to state, a change had taken place in the whole way of regarding the female sex. So far, at any rate, as our authorities enable us to judge, woman, in the historic age, was conceived to be so inferior to man that he recognised in her no other end than to minister to his pleasure or to become the mother of his children. Romance and the higher companionship of intellect and spirit do not appear (with certain notable exceptions) to have been commonly sought or found in this relation. 'Od. VI. 244. — Translated by Butcher and Lang. k I (So THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE Woman, in fact, was regarded as a means, not as an end ; and was treated in a manner consonant with this view. Of this estimate many illustrations might be adduced from the writers of the fifth and fourth centuries. Plato, for example, classes together " children, women, and servants, "^ and states generally that there is no branch of human industry in which the female sex is not inferior to the male.' Similarly, Aristotle insists again and again on the natural inferiority of woman, and illustrates it by such quaint observations as the following : " a man would be considered a coward who was only as brave as a brave woman, and a woman as a chatterbox who was only as modest as a good man."* But the most striking example, perhaps, because the most unconscious, of this habitual way of regarding women is to be found in the funeral oration put by Thucydides into the mouth of Pericles, where the speaker, after suggesting what consolation he can to the fathers of the slain, turns to the women with the brief but significant exhortation: "If I am to speak of womanly virtues to those of you who will henceforth be widows, let me sum them up in one short admonition : To a woman not to show more weakness than is natural to her sex is a great glory, and not to be talked about for good or for evil among men. "* The sentiments of the poets are less admissible as evi- dence. But some of them are so extreme that they may be adduced as a further indication of a point of view whose prevalence alone could render them even drama- tically plausible. Such for example is the remark which * Plato, Republic 431 c. ^jbid. 455 c. 'Arist. Pol. III. 1277 b 21. — Translated by Welldon. * Thucydides II. 45. — Translated by Jowett. THE GREEK VIEW OF WOMAN l6l Euripides puts into the mouth of his Medea — "women are impotent for good, but clever contrivers of all evil"*; or that of one of the characters of Menander, " a woman is necessarily an evil, and he is a lucky man who catches her in the mildest form." While the general Greek view of the dependence of woman on man is well expressed in the words of Aethra, in the "Suppliants" of Euripides — "it is proper for women who are wise to let men act for them in everything."* In accordance with this conception of the inferiority of the female sex, and partly as a cause, partly as an ef- fect of it, we find that the position of the wife in ancient Greece was simply that of the domestic drudge. To stay at home and mind the house was her recognised ideal. "A free woman should be bounded by the street door,** says one of the characters in Menander; and another writer discriminates as follows the functions of the two sexes : — " War, politics, and public speaking are the sphere of man ; that of woman is to keep house, to stay at home and to receive and tend her husband." We are not surprised, therefore, to find that the symbol of woman is the tortoise; and in the following burlesque passage from Aristophanes we shall recognise, in spite of the touch of caricature, the genuine features of the Greek wife. Praxa- gora is recounting the merits and services of women: " They dip their wool in hot water according to the ancient plan, all of them without exception, and never make the slightest innovation. They sit and cook, as of old. They carry upon their heads, as of old. They conduct the Themophoriae, as of old. They wear out their * Euripides , Medea. 406, •Euripides, Hik. 40. 1 62 THE GREEK VIEW OF LIFE husbands, as of old. They buy sweets, as of old. They take their wine neat, as of old."* And that this was also the kind of ideal approved by their lords and masters, and that any attempt to pass beyond it was resented, is amusingly illustrated in the following extract from the same poet, where Lysistrata explains the growing indignation of the women at the bad conduct of affairs by the men, and the way in which their attempts to interfere were resented. The comments of the "magistrate" typify, of course, the man's point of view. "Think of our old moderation and gentleness, think how we bore with your pranks, and were still, All through the days of your former prognacity, all through the war that is over and spent: Not that (be sure) we approved of your policy; never our griefs you allowed us to vent. Well we perceived your mistakes and mismanagement. Often at home on our housekeeping cares, Often we heard of some foolish proposal you made for con- ducting the public affairs. Then would we question you mildly and pleasantly, inwardly grieving, but outwardly gay; ♦ Husband, how goes it abroad ? ' we would ask of him ; ' what have ye done in Assembly to-day ? * 'What would ye write on the side of the Treaty-stone?' Hus- band says angrily, ' What's that to you ? You hold yoiu: tongue ! ' And I held it accordingly. STRATYLLIS. That is a thing which I never would dol MAGISTRATE. Ma'am, if you hadn't you'd soon have repented it. "Aristophanes, Eccles. 215. • tM4»««#>*t»*««M«>r»»»^ tHE GREEK VIEW OF WOMAN 1 63 LYSISTRATA. Therefore I held it, and spake not a word. Soon of another tremendous absurdity, wilder and worse than the former we heard. ♦Husband,' I say, with a tender solicitude, 'Why have you passed such a foolish decree ? ' Viciously, moodily, glaring askance at me, 'Stick to your spinning, my mistress,' says he, 'Else you will speedily find it the worse for you! war is the care and the business of men 1 * MAGISTRATE. Zeus! 'twas a worthy reply, and an excellent! LYSISTRATA. WTiat ! you unfortimate, shall we not then. Then, when we see you perplexed and incompetent, shall we not tender advice to the state ! " * The conception thus indicated in burlesque of the pro- per place of woman is expressed more seriously, from the point of view of the average man in the " Oeconomicus " of Xenophon. Ischomachus, the hero of that work, with