CH E [I 7 rv t). B^ACKWOOD LOSOPHlCAlttA THE LIBRARY OF THE OF LOS UNIVERSITY CALIFORNIA ANGELES |1btlosjopbical (Classics for (Smglisjj EDITED BY WILLIAM KNIGHT, LL.D. PROFESSOR OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY, UNIVERSITY OF ST ANDREWS F I C H T E Fl C H T E-1 FI CH TE BY EOBEET ADAMSOtf, M.A. PROFESSOR OF LOGIC IN THE OWENS COLLEGE, VICTORIA UNIVERSITY, MANCHESTER WILLIAM BLACKWOOD AND SONS EDINBURGH AND LONDON MDCCCLXXXI All IluiMx referral Education Library All f> PREFATOKY NOTE. THE account of Fichte's system in the latter part of this volume has no pretensions to be regarded as more than an introduction to his philosophy. When it is re- membered that Fichte's works appear in eleven substan- tial volumes, and that many of them are elaborate and detailed expositions of special branches of philosophy in general, it will be evident that a summary or compressed statement would have but small value, and that a short sketch must of necessity be introductory in character. I have to thank Dr William Smith for the kind per- mission to use his translations of certain of Fichte's works. The passage quoted from the ' Eeden,' is taken, with one or two verbal alterations, from his ' Memoir of Fichtc.' The delay in the appearance of this volume of the series of ' Philosophical Classics ' is due to causes for which I am alone responsible. R ADAMSOK THE OWENS COLLEGE, June 1881. 926543 CONTENTS. CHAP. PAGE I. INTRODUCTORY, .... 1 II. YOUTH AND EARLY STRUGGLES, . . 8 III. THE JENA PROFESSORSHIP, . . 41 IV. BERLIN AND THE WAR OF LIBERATION, . 65 1. FRIENDS AND LITERARY ACTIVITY AT BERLIN (1799-1806.) 2. FALL AND REGENERATION OP PRUSSIA : THE BERLIN UNIVERSITY. 3. WAR OF LIBERATION : DEATH OF FICHTE. V. GENERAL IDEA OF FICHTE's PHILOSOPHY, . 105 VI. " WISSENSCHAFTSLEHRE " IN ITS EARLIER FORM, .... 125 1. DOGMATISM AND IDEALISM. 2. HISTORICAL ANTECEDENTS : SPINOZA AND KANT. 3. KI11ST PRINCIPLES. 4. DEVELOPMENT OF THE SYSTEM. VII. LATER FORM OF THE "WISSENSCHAFTSLEHRE," 189 VIII. CONCLUDING REMARKS, 214 F I C H T E. CHAPTEE I. INTRODUCTORY. IT happens but rarely that the life of a philosopher has been so closely connected with the historical develop- ment of his people, that his name should be remembered rather on account of his practical activity than for his speculative researches. Yet if one does not misinter- pret the evidence supplied in ample quantity by the numerous speeches, addresses, essays, memorials, and other documents which marked the celebration of the centenary of Fichte in 1862, circumstances in his case must have combined to bring about this result. Many occasional references were made by various speakers and writers to the philosophy of Fichte, and much was said of the speculative depth and richness of his writings, but all such remarks were manifestly external and by the way. The subtle metaphysician of the ' Wissenschafts- lehre ' had evidently, in the estimation of his admirers, been overshadowed by the patriotic orator of the ' Ad- p. iv. A 2 FicUe. dresses to the German Nation.' There exists not now, there never did exist to any extent, a school of follow- ers of Fichte ; it may well be doubted if there are at present half-a-dozen students of his works. As a pa- triot, as representative of what seems noblest and lofti- est in the German character, he lives, and will doubt- less continue to live, in the grateful remembrance of his countrymen ; as a metaphysician, he lives not at all beyond the learned pages of the historians of phil- osophy. That such should be the case will not appear surpris- ing when there are taken into consideration the nature of the historical surroundings of Fichte's career, and the relations in which he stood to them. His life coincided in time with the rise and partial development of the two events which have most affected the current of modern history, the revolution in political ideas which originated in France, and the birth of intellectual activ- ity in Germany. His life's work was the part he played in the furtherance of these movements, and the durability of his fame has of necessity depended on the signifi- cance of his contributions to them, and the way in which they have worked themselves out. Although the revolution in political and social organi- sations and the rise of new forms of intellectual life in Germany differed widely in external features, for they belonged to diverse spheres of practical activity, they were in fundamental agreement, not only as regards their ultimate aim, but also as regards the idea on which they proceeded. Both were in character reconstructive; in both the foundation for the new edifice was sought in the common, universal nature of humanity itself. The new Introductory. 3 political idea of the French Eevolution an idea ex- pressed clearly, though with some contradictoriness, in the Contrat social was that of the human agent, endowed by nature with certain primitive and inalienable rights, as the unit in the organisation of the state. The individ- ual, on this view, was no longer to be regarded as receiv- ing all state-rights by historical accident; distinctions of rank among citizens were no longer to be accepted on mere ground of fact; the state itself was to be looked upon as the mechanism in and through which the primitive rights of all individuals may receive due and adequate realisation ; and the final standard of judgment as to the forms of the state organisation was placed in the reason of the individual The body politic thus appeared not as the accidental result of the conflict of individual, arbi- trary volitions, but as the necessary product of the con- joint will of individuals with common characteristics, with primitive and equal rights. The individual was thought of, not as the embodiment of pure arbitrary ca- price, but as the expression of a certain common nature, to the development of which he has an original, indefeas- ible right. A doctrine like this is liable to misuse, for the notion of rational liberty may easily degenerate, and historically did degenerate, into the apotheosis of mere power of will ; and the positive element in it, the idea of the abstract rights of the individual, probably reqxiires much modification : but it was an important advance upon the previous theory and practice of politics. "When one examines the general characteristics of the new intellectual productions of Germany, more especi- ally in the sphere of philosophy, one is struck by the close resemblance in fundamental idea to that just 4 Fichte. noted. It was the essence of Kant's endeavour, both in speculative and in ethical research, to show that the ultimate unit, the conscious subject, was not a mere atom, devoid of intrinsic characteristics, receiving all know- ledge from without, and impelled to act solely by the natural relations between his individual impulses and things. In his view, the nature of the thinking sub- ject was an indispensable factor both in knowledge and in action. In all knowledge, as he strove to show, there is a common element which springs from the very essence of the subject as cognitive or conscious ; in all action, the indispensable element is the conscious exer- cise of will under common, universal law. Thus in the Kantian philosophy, the ultimate standard, both of in- tellectual and of ethical judgment, was indeed the individ- ual, but the individual only as containing a universal or common feature. On the basis supplied by this com- mon element, philosophy might proceed to reconstruct what had been dissolved by the speculative atomism of Hume. Although, from the nature of the matter, no similarly exact statement can be given for the essence of the in- tellectual efforts in the direction of pure literature, there was manifest in them in various degrees the same tendency towards expression of the universal common elements in human life, as opposed to the treatment of trivial, personal, and accidental aims and occurrences which had characterised much of the earlier eighteenth century literature. If evidence of this were otherwise wanting, it would be amply supplied by considering the excesses of the principle in the writings of the first Eomantic school. Not every one could bend the bow Introductory. 5 of Kant and Fichte : the philosophic principle that the individual consciousness is the ultimate test of truth and goodness, became for weaker minds a practical pre- cept of moral and intellectual scepticism. The universal element sank out of sight, and there remained only, as aim of life, the satisfaction of individual, personal ca- price. ' Wilhelm Lovell ' is but a reckless parody of the Kantian system ; ' Lucinde,' a hideous misapplication of Fichte's ' Wissenschaftslehre.' Now the historic results of these two movements have been, for Germany at least, very different in character. On the one hand, the rude shock given by the political revolution and its consequences to the amorphous organ- isation of the German States, absolutely forced upon the German mind a conception which otherwise might long have remained dormant the conception of a united, single German power. History amply shows us that it is often by what we in our ignorance call the brutal neces- sity of facts that an idea gains for itself a place among the realities of life ; and there can be no question that the unity of the German people, foreshadowed in elo- quent language by her patriotic thinkers at the begin- ning of this century, has been wrought out, with much swaying and struggling, rather by the pressure of exter- nal forces than by the unanimous acceptance of the idea. However this may be, and however widely the united German empire may differ in inner characteristics from that patriotic state to which Fichte, in his famous ' Addresses,' summoned his countrymen, no German who feels the full significance of the unity of his nation can fail to look back with pride and gratitude to the elo- quent thinker, who, with the thoroughness of a philoso- 6 Fichte. pher and the zeal of a patriot, drew in ideal form the outlines of that which has now been happily realised. The part which Fichte has played in this movement is a warrant of undying fame. On the other hand, the speculative movement begun by Kant is yet far from having exhausted itself : it can hardly be said to have begun to produce its full fruits. The contributions made here by Fichte were of the highest importance, and, as will afterwards become clear, they form an integral portion of the completed philosophic view, which in partial fashion was first presented by Kant. Nevertheless, Fichte's work as a philosopher was never, even for himself, a finished whole, and the permanent results of his activity have been absorbed in the more comprehensive elaboration of the Kantian principles which make up the philosophy of HegeL It is not probable, therefore, that Fichte's system, as a system, will ever discharge a more important function than that which has already been its work in the history of philosophy. It has made clear much that was ob- scure in Kant ; it has contributed to give a wider range to the method of philosophy characteristic of the Kant- ian system, and it has served to effect the transition from Kant to Hegel. More than this it has not done, and cannot do. Not without a certain historic justifi- cation, therefore, has it come about that the fame of Fichte depends more on his patriotic and practical efforts than on his speculative labours. Ample materials for the life of Fichte are supplied by the biographical work of his son, I. H. Fichte, 'J. G. Fichte's Lebenund literarischer Brief wechsel,' 2 vols., 2d Introductory. 7 ed, 1862. An interesting sketch, from these materials, has been long before the English reader in Dr W. Smith's 'Memoir of Fichte,' 3d ed., 1873. I. H. Fichte's work should be supplemented by Weinhold, ' Achtundvierzig Briefe von J. G. Fichte und seinen Verwandten,' 1862 ; and by Noack, ' J. G. Fichte n'ach seinem Leben, Lehren und Wirken,' which is somewhat ill - tempered but amusing. The complete works of the philosopher fill eleven volumes. The last three, ' Nachgelassene Werke,' con- sisting mainly of the notes of lecture courses, were pub- lished by I. H. Fichte in 1834-35. The other works, most of which had been separately published, were col- lected, arranged, and edited, also by I. H. Fichte, in 1845-46. The arrangement is systematic, but not free from faults. Several of the more important of the popu- lar writings of Fichte have been translated with great elegance and skill by Dr W. Smith, to whom it is due that Fichte is more than a name in this country. Trans- lations of some of the philosophic works have appeared in America, where the earnest study of German thought has been fostered by the unwearied and self-sacrificing zeal of Dr W. T. Harris, the editor of the ' Journal of Speculative Philosophy.' There is no English work upon Fichte's system ; in German the best expositions are those of Lowe, Fortlage, Erdmann, and Kuno Fischer. CHAPTEE II. YOUTH AND EARLY STRUGGLES. BIRTH AND EDUCATION. JOHANN GOTTLIEB FICHTE was born on the 19th May 1762, at Rammenau, in Saxon Lusatia. The little vil- lage of Rammenau lies in the picturesque country, well wooded and well watered, between Bischofswerda and Camenz, not far from the boundary separating the dis- trict of Meissen from Upper Lusatia. Here, as the tra- ditions of the Fichte family run, a Swedish sergeant in the army of Gustavus Adolphus, who had been wounded in a skirmish in the neighbourhood, was left by his comrades in the care of one of the kindly Lutheran villagers. Returning health did not lead the stranger to take his departure. He continued under the hospi- table roof of his benefactor, married the daughter of the house, and, as all the sons had fallen in the bloody wars of religion, became heir to the small portion of ground belonging to the family. From this northern settler sprang the numerous family of the Fichtes, noted, even in a neighbourhood distinguished for simplicity of man- ners and uprightness of character, for their solid probity and sterling honesty. Youth and Early Struggles. 9 The grandfather of the philosopher, the only descend- ant of the original stock remaining in Rammenau, cul- tivated the tiny patrimonial property, and in addition carried on a small trade in linen ribbons, mamifactured at his own loom. His son, Christian Fichte, was sent at an early age to the neighbouring town of Pulsnitz, and apprenticed to Johann Schurich, a wealthy linen- spinner and owner of a factory. After the fashion of diligent apprentices in all ages, Christian Fichte wooed and won the heart of his master's daughter, but not without much trouble was the consent of the wealthy burgher given to a marriage which he thought beneath his family rank. Only on condition that his son-in-law did not presume to settle in Pulsnitz was a reluctant permission given, and Christian Fichte enabled to bring his bride to the paternal roof. With her dowry he built a house for himself in Eammenau, still in the possession of his descendants, and established there his looms. On the 19th May 1762 was born their eldest child, Johann Gottlieb, who was quickly followed by six sons and one daughter. From what may be gathered regarding his parents in Fichte's letters, it is plain that the marriage was not altogether productive of happiness. Madame Fichte seems never to have been able quite to forget that in uniting herself to a humble peasant and handicraftsman she had descended from a superior station. She had all the pride and narrowness of ideas which are natural possessions of the wealthier classes in a small provincial town. Her temper, obstinate, quick, and capricious, overmastered the weaker and more patient nature of her husband, and she was, to all intents and purposes, the 10 FichU. head of the household. Her eldest son resembled her strongly in the main features of his character, though he had in addition solidity of principle and reserve, and their wills came into frequent and painful collision. The mother, like many a Scottish matron in similar case, had the darling ambition to see her talented son invested with the dignity of clergyman, and for many years cir- cumstances led him thoroughly to coincide with this wish. As he gradually altered his views, and felt him- self less and less inclined for the clerical career, his rela- tions with his mother became more and more strained and unpleasant. Fortune had removed him from the paternal home at an early age, and he was rarely able to visit his family; but after the final decision as to his career, even such occasional intercourse seemed to cease. The rudiments of his education Fichte began to receive very early from his father, who, when the day's work was over, would teach the lad to read and to repeat by heart proverbs and hymns, and would talk to him of his apprentice travels in Saxony and Franconia. Of even greater importance for his training Avas the curiously in- tense interest the boy displayed in listening to the weekly sermons in the village church. These sermons he would repeat aloud, almost word for word, in such fashion as to show that the effort was not one of mere passive re- tention, but of active imagination. Strength of memory, intense fondness for reading and for quiet imaginative meditation, and deep earnestness of moral character, marked him at an early age as a boy of remarkable gifts. An anecdote referring to this period of his life, when he was about seven years of age, is characteristic enough to deserve notice. His father had brought him as a pre- Early Education. 11 sent from the neighbouring fair a copy of the famous story of the Invulnerable Siegfried. The delight in this book so overmastered him that his other tasks began to be neglected, and he determined to free himself from temptation by destroying the cause of the evil Quietly and secretly he took the little book, and, after a hard straggle with himself, summoned courage enough to hurl it into the streamlet that flowed by the house. As he saw the little treasure carried away by the stream he burst into tears ; but to his father's inquiry as to how the accident had happened he would give no explana- tion, preferring then, as often in later years, to endure misunderstanding and pain rather than to offer defence for what he felt was right. When, some time later, his father proposed to give him a similar book as a present, he earnestly entreated that it might be bestowed upon one of his brothers, and that he might not again be subjected to such temptation. So gifted by nature, the boy might have grown up in his narrow surroundings, able and upright, notable per- haps among his fellows, but wasting powers fitted for greater things, had not a mere accident transferred him to a wider sphere of life, and given him opportunity for a fuller development. Freiherr von Miltitz, owner of an estate at Seven Oaks, near Meissen, chanced one Sunday in the year 1771 to visit the family Von Hoff- mann in Eammenau, and arrived too late to hear the sermon by the village pastor, whom he much admired. On expressing regret, he was informed that the loss could readily be repaired, for there was in the village a little lad able to repeat verbatim any sermon that had been preached. The little Fichte was sent for, and so great 12 Fichte. an impression was made upon Yon Miltitz that he at once proposed to the parents to undertake the charge of the lad's education if they would submit him to his care. No objection was raised on their side, and Fichte was forthwith removed by his patron to Seven Oaks. The surroundings of his new home, the restraints of his new mode of life, at first weighed heavily upon the boy's mind, and his kind protector judged it best to place him under the care of the Pastor Krebel at ISTied- erau, near Meissen. Here he remained for nearly three years, affectionately cared for by the childless pastor and his wife, and receiving a thorough groundwork in ele- mentary classics. In 1774 he appears to have been for a brief interval at the public school of Meissen, though there is some obscurity about this fact in his biography ; and in October of that year he was entered at the famous foun- dation-school of Pforta, near Naumburg. His patron, Von Miltitz, had died in the early part of 1774, and we have no record to show by what means the expenses of Fichte's education continued to be defrayed. From a chance expression in one of his letters of a later date, it would appear probable that his parents at least contri- buted, but undoubtedly they were not in a condition to undertake the whole charge. The years spent at Schulpforta had a powerful influ- ence on the development of Fichte's character, in both a moral and an intellectual aspect. The school was even then regulated on the old monastic plan, and much resembled what in this country till recently used to be the system of the old foundation or endowed schools. The pupils were strictly secluded from the outer world ; the order of daily life, of amusement, of costume, of Schulpforta. 1 3 study, was regulated by antiquated precepts. Each of the older scholars had a junior intrusted to his care, and exercised almost unlimited control over his apprentice. The happiness of the juniors thus depended much upon the qualities of the older members, and, as is inevitable in any close institution, the traditions of the place were in many respects evil, and detrimental to the character of the scholars. Such a constrained life tended only to deepen and strengthen traits already sufficiently marked in Fichte's character. He was by nature reserved, yet opinionative that is, little capable of altering any view of the truth of which he had become convinced, and alto- gether incapable of making any effort to remove miscon- ception which might arise as to his action. The entire want of family life contributed to strengthen this habit of inner self-dependence, which could have found relief only in the manifold interests and duties, in the constant sympathy and co-operation with others, arising from the details of domestic intercourse. No substitute for this was found in Schulpforta The course of instruction, moreover, thorough but narrow for it was almost entirely confined to the classical curriculum was not that best suited to develop the neglected side of Fichte's character. In his life and in his works, what one notices as most striking is his incapacity for appreciating experience. In metaphysics, in psychology, in ethics, in politics, he con- structs from within. Nature, in his system, appears merely as the negative limit of mind. Nor in his prac- tical activity, as will appear, was he more fortunate. " Fichte," said Goethe, with much truth, " too often for- gets that experience is not in the least what he has imagined it to be." It hardly admits of question that a H Fichte. more realistic education, a training in physical science such as his great predecessor fortunately possessed, would have given greater weight and force to Fichte's specula- tions, greater elasticity and prudence to his action. It was some time before Fichte accommodated himself to the life at Schulpforta. He was at first unfortunate in the senior selected for him. The close restraint and the unbearable tyranny to which he was subjected preyed upon him, and, after having given warning to his senior in his naively honourable fashion that he would endeavour to escape from the school unless he were treated differently, he did begin a flight towards Naumburg, with the vague intention of making his way into the world of which he knew so little, and settling as a new Eobinson Crusoe in some deserted island. Only the thought that by carrying out his exploit he would for ever cut himself off from his parents, induced him to return to the hated school A frank confession of his intention, and of the grounds for it, procured him not only pardon from the rector, but also relief from the tyranny of his former senior. He was placed under the charge of another pupil, and the years began to flow more happily for him. When at length he had reached the dignity of Primaner, he began to enjoy the greater liberty of study permitted to the senior scholars ; and though the great works of recent German literature were carefully excluded from the school, he then obtained through Lieber, a newly introduced tutor, the successive numbers of Lessing's ' Anti-Goeze.' The style and matter of this work made a deep impression on him, and in his enthusiastic fashion he resolved that the earliest oppor- tunity should be taken to make himself known to the University Studies. 15 author, and acknowledge his gratitude to him. The cir- cumstances of his life and the premature death of Lessing, however, prevented this resolution from being carried into effect. In October 1780, Fichte's school career closed; his final essay, 'Oratio de recto prseceptorum poeseos et rhetorices usu,' still existing in the archives of Schul- pforta, received its meed of praise, and he was ready for the higher educational training of a university. In the Michaelmas term of that year he enrolled himself in the Theological Faculty at Jena- not, so far as we can judge, because his heart was entirely given to the theological career, but because no other seemed to present an open- ing to a poor and friendless student The Jena lectures do not appear to have done much for him, and in the fol- lowing year he transferred himself to Leipzig, where many of his Schulpforta comrades were settled. Here, in addi- tion to certain lectures by Schiitz on /Eschylus, the course followed by him with greatest attention seems to have been that by Petzold on systematic theology. Fichte's mind, during this period, evidently dwelt on a problem which has sorely exercised many a student in like cir- cumstances, the relation between divine providence or foreknowledge and the voluntary determination of human action. Of the alternatives offering themselves as pos- sible solutions, he chose with resoluteness and complete conviction that which we call technically the doctrine of determinism. The idea of the individual will as but a necessary link in the scheme of divine government, gave a certain consistency to his thoughts, and was expressed by him in various sermons preached in villages in the neighbourhood of Leipzig. From the pastor of one of 1 6 Fichte. these village churches he first learned that his doctrine might be designated by the hateful title of Spinozism, and from the same friend he received the ' Refutation of the Errors of Spinoza,' by Wolff, through which he came to know the outlines of a system destined to play a most important part in the later development of his thought. On the whole, there seems little reason to doubt that so far as the young candidatus theologice had formed opinions upon speculative and critical subjects, they accorded with the ' Ethics ' of Spinoza and the ' Anti-Goeze ' of Lessing. EARLY STRUGGLES. The three years spent at Leipzig had been years of bitter poverty and hard struggle, which strengthened, and at the same time tended to harden, Fichte's proud and reserved spirit. Even severer discipline was in store for him. The completion of his regular academic course still left him without a definite profession. Less and less inclined for the clerical life, and embittered by the reproaches and petulant urgency of his mother, he spent three years, eating his heart out, as tutor in vari- ous families around Leipzig. To his humble petition, in 1787, that the Consistory of Saxony would allot to him some small stipend such as was often given to poor Saxon students of theology, in order that he might com- plete his theological studies and present himself for the licentiate examination, an unfavourable answer was returned. Without a profession, without friends, with- out means, it seemed to him that his life had been wasted. At the deepest ebb of his fortiines he obtained through a former comrade, Weisse, an unexpected relief Early Struggles. 17 in the offer of a house-tutorship at Ziirich. Accepting joyfully, he set out on foot, and traversing for the first time German provinces outside his native Saxony, reached Ziirich in September 1788. His pupils at Zurich were the son and daughter of Hcrr Ott, the proprietor of a well-to-do inn, the Gast- hof zum Schwerte. Herr Ott, though somewhat sur- prised at the character of the education which his new tutor proposed to bestow, was not altogether unwilling that his children should receive a training superior to their station, but his wife bitterly resented all attempts to go beyond the accustomed routine. Eichte found his task no easy matter, and assuredly the means he adopted for carrying it out would not readily have occurred to any other tutor in like circumstances. He noted with care in a daybook or journal all the errors in education committed by the parents of his pupils, and submitted the record weekly. His strength of character and reso- luteness of purpose enabled him to bear down any active opposition to his plans ; but the situation was forced and unpleasing, and at Easter 1790 he made up his mind to go. During his residence at Zurich he had busied him- self with many literary efforts, without in any one of them manifestly finding his metier. He read and translated much of the recent French literature, mainly Montesquieu and Rousseau, completed a trans- lation of Sallust, with an introductory essay on the life and style of the author, and wrote a rather elaborate critical paper on Biblical Epics, with special refer- ences to Klopstock's ' Messias,' a paper, which, at a later date, was timidly refused by the editor of r. iv. B 13 Fichte. the 'Deutsches Museum,' in Leipzig. At various times he preached, always with marked success, and exerted himself much to have a school of oratory founded at Ziirich. For this, in which he had the promise of sup- port from Lavater, he drew out a complete plan, and the document, published by his son, presents many features of interest. More important for his after-career than these literary efforts were the friendships formed by him at Zurich, especially with Lavater and with Hartmann Eahn, the brother-in-law of Klopstock. Eahn was a highly cul- tured man, of wide experience of life, and his house was the centre of the literary reunions of Ziirich society. Fichte, first introduced by Lavater, was soon received as an intimate and valued friend. Hartmann Eahn's Avife had been dead for some years, and his household affairs were managed by his daughter, Johanna Maria, at this time some thirty years of age, not specially distinguished for beauty or talent, but full of womanly gentleness and tact. Fichte felt himself from the first attracted towards Fraulein Eahn, whose sympathetic nature enabled her both to understand his restless and impetuous disposition and to supply what was wanting to it. Their friendship gradually gave way to a deeper feeling of mutual affec- tion and esteem. Secretly at first for Fichte's pride made him think that an obscure tutor had little right to claim the daughter of a wealthy and influential citizen they unfolded in letters their feelings for one another ; but as the time of his departure from Ziirich drew near, it became necessary to make known to Hartmann Eahn how matters stood. When Fichte left, he was formally, though privately, betrothed to Johanna Maria. # Early Struggles. 19 The course of his life was not yet clear before him, and from one of the interesting letters to his betrothed which has been published by his son, we can judge that his own views were not decided. Many plans had been debated, and on the whole his hope then was to obtain a post as tutor to some influential person at one of the German courts, which would give him time to discover where his powers were most likely to prove successful. " On the whole," he writes, " what I think about it is this : the great aim of my existence is to obtain every kind of education (not scientific education, in which I find much that is vanity, but education of character) which fortune will permit me. " 1 look into the way of Providence in my life, and find that this may perhaps be the very plan of Providence with me. I have filled many situations, played many parts, known many men and many conditions of men, and on the whole I find that by all these circumstances my character lias become more fixed and decided. At my first entrance into the world, I wanted everything but a susceptible heart. Many qualities in which I was then deficient, I have since acquired ; many I still want entirely, and among others that of occasionally accommodating myself to those around me, and bearing with men who are false or wholly opposed to my character, in order to accomplish something great. With- out this I can never employ as with it the powers which Providence lias bestowed upon me. " Does Providence, then, intend to develop these capacities in me ? Is it not possible that for this very purpose I may now be led upon a wider stage ? May not my employment at a court, my project of superintending the studies of a prince, your father's plan of taking me to Copenhagen may not these be hints or ways of Providence towards this end ? And shall I, by confining myself to a narrower sphere, one which is not even natural to me, seek to frustrate this plan ? 20 Ficlite. I have too little talent for bending, for dealing with those who are repugnant to me. I can succeed only with good and true people ; I am too open. This seemed to you a further reason why I was unfit to go to a court ; to me, on the con- trary, it is a reason why I must go there, if any opportunity present itself, in order to gain what I am deficient in. " I know the business of a scholar, and have nothing new to learn about it. To be a scholar by profession I have as little talent as may be. I must not only think, I must act ; least of all can I think about trifles. ... I have but one passion, one want, one all-engrossing desire, to work upon those around me. The more I act the happier I seem to be. Is this, too, a delusion ? It may be so, but there is truth at the bottom of it." l "With, many plans, and full of hope in his future career, Fichte departed for Leipzig in the spring of 1790. His letters of recommendation to various courts, however, produced no result ; the plans which he en- deavoured to realise at Leipzig, mainly the establishment of a literary journal, came to naught ; and in the course of a few months he was again reduced to a state of Avant and uncertainty even more harassing than before his journey to Ziirich. Nothing that he tried seemed to succeed. His Essay on Biblical Epics was rejected, as has been said, by the timid editor of the ' Museum,' be- caused it appeared to reflect on the fame of the great Klopstock ; and for the other literary efforts in which he engaged, the Avriting of a tragedy and some tales, he had assuredly little faculty. A last effort to effect an entrance into the Church was equally fruitless. His essay or theme, probably an expansion of the ' Aphorisms on Deism,' printed in the collected ' Works,' and dating 1 Leben, i. 55-53. The whole letter, as there given, is translated by Dr Smith. Early Struggles. 21 from 1790, was received with praise by the President of the Consistory at Dresden, but at the same time with doubt. The worthy theologian thought that the author was fitter for the professorial chair than for the pulpit ; and Fichte, disgusted with the narrow, jealous domina- tion exercised over the Saxon clergy, finally gave up all hopes of carrying out his early purpose. His letters to Jo- hanna Eahn during this troubled period sufficiently show the distress and vexation under which his proud spirit chafed. Even her affectionate counsels and earnest en- treaties to return to Zurich brought small comfort to him. Towards the autumn of the year, however, we note a sudden and surprising change in the tone of his communications. He had begun to take pupils in various subjects, and among others one student presented himself to obtain assistance in reading the ' Critique of Pure Reason.' Fichte had made no previous study of this work, but so soon as he entered upon the new line of thought, he found his true vocation. From this time onwards the direction of his thoughts and hopes was fixed. His own words will show better than any ex- ternal account what effect the Kantian philosophy had upon him. " My scheming spirit," he writes to his betrothed, " has now found rest, and I thank Providence that, shortly before all my hopes were frustrated, I was placed in a position which enabled me to bear with cheerfulness the disappoint- ment. A circumstance which seemed the result of mere chance, led me to give myself up entirely to the study of the Kantian philosophy, a philosophy that restrains the imagination, which was always too powerful with me, gives understanding the sway, and raises the whole spirit to an indescribable elevation above all earthly considerations. I 22 Fickle. have gained a nobler morality, and instead of occupying myself with what is out of me, I employ myself more with my own being. This has given me a peace such as I have never before experienced ; amid uncertain worldly prospects I have passed my happiest days. I shall devote at least some years of my life to this philosophy ; and all that I write, for some years to come at any rate, shall be upon it. It is difficult beyond all conception, and stands greatly in need of simplification. The principles, it is true, are hard speculations, with no direct bearing upon human life, but their consequences are of the utmost importance for an age whose morality is corrupted at the fountain-head ; and to set these consequences before the world in a clear light would, I believe, be doing it a good service." " The influence of this philosophy," he writes to his friend Achelis, with whom he had had frequent disputes regarding the necessity of human actions, " and specially the ethical side of it (which, however, is unintelligible without previous study of the ' Critique of Pure Eeasoii '), upon the whole spiritual life, and in particular the revolution it has caused in my own mode of thought, is indescribable. To you, especially, I owe the acknowledgment that I now heartily believe in the freedom of man, and am convinced that only on this supposition are duty, virtue, or morality of any kind so much as possible, a truth which indeed I saw before, and perhaps acquired from you. 1 ' The letters to Fraulein Eahn now begin to breathe a new tone of cheerfulness and happiness, for external circumstances were at the same time improving ; indeed, so joyous do they become, that it is evident the tender heart of Johanna suspected a formidable rival in this strange Kantian philosophy. She was not altogether pleased that in absence from her he should laugh at ill health and abound in the highest spirits. Friends at Zurich did not think much of the Kantian philosophy, Early Struggles. 23 which was to them a thing of naught, and she feared he would waste his time on utterly unprofitable study. Moreover, the scandalous discoveries regarding life in Leipzig made in Bahrdt's scandalous ' Leben ' led her to distrust the influences of the place. With gentle per- sistence she pressed upon Fichte her favourite plan, that he should return to Zurich, be united to her, and trust to fortune to open a way whereby his talents might receive recognition. Fichte resisted for some time, wished to establish some reputation for himself, dreaded what might be said by the kindly critics of Zurich if he accepted her proposal, but ended in the spring of 1791 by yielding assent to her entreaties. "At the end of this month," he writes on the 1st of March, " I shall be free, and have determined to come to thee. I see noth- ing that can prevent me. I, indeed, still await the sanction of my parents; but I have been for long so well assured of their love almost, if I may venture to say it, of their deference to my opinion that I need not anticipate any obstacle on their part." Evil Fortune, however, which had sorely wounded Fichte many a time, had still another arrow in her quiver. The failure of a mercantile house where a large portion of Hartmann Eahn's possessions was invested, put for a time at least an absolute obstacle in the way of the projected marriage. All Johanna's care and at- tention had to be bestowed upon her father, now ad- vanced in years and feeble in health. Fichte, with a brave heart, packed his knapsack, and set off for War- saw, where he had received an appointment as house tutor in a noble family. During the autumn of 1790 he had been busily en- 24 Fichte. gaged in the first of his philosophical writings, an Eluci- dation or Explanation of the 'Critique of Judgment;' and he had been in hopes that the publication of this little work might have preceded his proposed journey to Zurich. But publishers seem to have been chary ; and, after much sending to and fro, the MS. was finally doomed to remain in its original unprinted form. It is to be regretted that some portions of this, which appear to remain, have not been included among Fichte's liter- ary remains, for the account of the aim and scope of the work excites some interest in it. Like most students of Kant who have really penetrated into his system, Fichte saw that it was above all things necessary to make clear the inner connection between the leading ideas of the three Kritiken. In the most difficult and yet most in- structive portion of the ' Critique of Judgment,' the Intro- duction, Kant had himself done something towards this end ; but much yet remained, and as Fichte's later philo- sophy is in essence the attempt to carry out, with a fresh and original method, the union of theoretical and practi- cal principles, one would gladly have known what were his first impressions on the subject. For posterity, how- ever, as for contemporaries, the work has remained in obscurity. At Warsaw, where he arrived in June, after a pleas- ant journey, the incidents of which are narrated with much spirit in his journal, Fichte found an impossible task before him. His patron, the Count Platen, was a good, easy-going man, though heavy ; but the Countess was a veritable lady of rank, who viewed all tutors as mere servants, and whose domineering disposition exacted the most servile obedience from her dependants. She Visit to Kant. 25 instantly found Fichte's independent nature unbearable, and his French accent atrocious. A very few days were sufficient to bring matters to a crisis. The Countess attempted unsuccessfully to procure for the objection- able tutor a post in some other family ; and Fichte, resolved not to be treated like a chattel, demanded his dismissal and a sum for compensation. The dismissal was given with alacrity, the compensation only after threat of legal proceedings. With provision for a few months, Fichte then carried out a new idea which had occurred to him. He resolved to visit Kant, and set off for Kbnigsberg. KANT AND THE 'CRITIQUE OF REVELATION.' On the 1st July he arrived in Kbnigsberg, and on the 4th waited upon Kant. As might have been expected, he was received but coldly by the aged philosopher, whose disposition was anything but expansive, and who required to be known for some time before disclosing any of his finer and more genial qualities. Fichte was disappointed with his interview, and equally dissatisfied with the result of attendance upon one of Kant's lectures. He could not recognise in the professor the author of the ' Critique,' and thought his manner of lecturing listless and sleepy. This, too, might to a certain extent have been expected, for, as we know, Kant Avas invariably averse to introducing in his lectures any of those pro- founder specxilations which characterised his published works. Fichte, however disappointed with his first reception, resolved to bring himself before Kant's notice in a way which should be irresistible ; and in the soli- tude of his quiet inn laboured incessantly for some five . 26 Fichte. weeks on an essay developing in a new direction the principles of the Critical Philosophy. On the 18th August he forwarded his manuscript to Kant, and at- tended some days later to hear his opinion of its merits. Kant received him with the utmost kindness, commended such of the essay as he had managed to read, declined with his accustomed prudence to discuss either the views of the essayist or the principles of his own ' Critique,' and introduced him to several valued friends in Konigs- berg to Borowski and Schulz. By this time Fichte's scanty means had become wellnigh exhausted; the fatigue due to his hard labour at the essay had made him dispirited and gloomy; and there seemed no prospect of an outlet from his difficulties. On the 1st September he disclosed to Kant, in a remarkable and most charac- teristic letter, the state of his affairs; indicated, as ap- parently the one course left to him, a return to his home, where he might study in private, and perhaps obtain some humble post as village pastor; and entreated that Kant would furnish him with the necessary loan for carrying out this resolve. As we learn from Fichte's journal, Kant declined to accede to this request, but in such a manner as in no way lessened Fichte's feelings of esteem and admiration for him. He recommended, through Borowski, the " Essay " to his own publisher, Hartung, and did his utmost to promote Fichte's welfare. Hartung, however, was then absent from Konigsberg ; another publisher, when applied to, declined to purchase the MS.; and Fichte was compelled to accept what he had resolved against, a post as private tutor. Kant's friend, Schulz, obtained for him an appointment in the family of the Count von Krockow, near Danzig, by Kantian Studies. 27 whom he was received, as a protege of Kant's, with the most distinguished kindness. It was during the period in which he was here settled, amid more genial surround- ings than he had ever before known, that the surprising fate of his adventurous essay opened to him a new path in life. The problem which Fichte had selected for treatment according to Kantian principles, was one upon which as yet the author of the Critical Philosophy had made no public utterance. Doubtless the question of religion had appeared in all the three ' Critiques,' but the utter- ances in each of these, differing slightly from one another, had not been drawn together, and their application was limited to what we may call Natural Eeligion. But, that a certain form of belief in a revelation or supematurally given religion actually existed, was a fact, and a fact requiring to be explained after the Critical Method. In all the previous essays of this method, the plan of pro- cedure had been identical Thus, in the 'Critique of Pure Reason,' the fact of cognition being assumed, the conditions under which this fact was possible were the subject of investigation. In the ' Critique of Practical Eeason,' the fact of morality being assumed, the condi- tions under which it was possible were considered ; and in the ' Critique of Judgment ' the same query was answered with respect to the correspondence of natural elements, either to our faculty of cognition, as in aesthetic judgments, or to the idea of the whole of which they are parts, as in the teleological judgment. And, so far as religion was concerned, the following results had been attained. The theological aspect of religion, i.e., the speculative determination of the existence, properties, 28 Fickte. and modes of action of a supernatural Being, had been shown to be without theoretical foundation. In the forms of cognition, no theology was possible. But the necessary consequences of those conditions under which Morality or Reason as practical was possible, involved the practical acceptance of those very theological prin- ciples of which no theoretical demonstration could be given. The practical postulates of the being of an In- telligent and Moral Ruler of the world, and of the con- tinued existence of the rational element in human nature, had appeared as necessary for any intelligence conscious of itself as Practical or Moral. Through these practical postulates a new interpretation was given of the world of sense, which no longer appeared as mere material for cognitive experience, but as the possible sphere within which the moral end of a Practical Reason might be realised. The possibility, then, of a Natural or Rational Religion, if we employ terms which have unquestionably a certain ambiguity, had been sufficiently shown, and the place determined which such a religion holds in the series of philosophical notions. But, so far, no result had appeared bearing upon the possibility of a Revealed Religion ; and those fundamental features of human nature which historically have always been connected with the belief in a revelation, the consciousness of im- perfection, of sin, of dependence upon Supreme powers, apparently found no place in the Kantian scheme. Here, then, was an opportunity for the application of the critical principles. The possibility of a revelation might be investigated in the same fashion as the pos- sibility of cognition at all ; the form and content of any revelation might be determined by an analysis of ' Critique of Revelation.' 29 the conditions of its possibility, just as the form and content of knowledge had been determined by an analy- sis of its conditions. A lacuna in the Kantian system would thus be filled up. This problem Eichte proposed to himself, and his essay in solution of it was sent to the author of the Critical Philosophy, not originally for purpose of publication, but as proof of ability to handle and apply the critical method. Only with the approval and by the advice of Kant himself was publication re- solved upon, and the work revised and prepared for the public under the title, 'An Essay towards a Critique of all Revelation' ('Versuch einer Kritik aller Offen- barung '). In form and substance the ' Critique of Revelation ' is purely Kantian, with here and there an admixture of those additional subtleties of distinction in which Kantian scholars like Reinhold were already beginning to revel. Starting with a somewhat dry and abstract treatment of the conditions of moral or practical reason, an analysis of the will in its twofold aspect as sensu- ous impulse and impulse determined by reverence for moral law, the Essay summarises briefly the main princi- ples of the Kantian practical theology, laying stress upon the fact that the acceptance of these theological postulates is not equivalent to religion, that in so far as reverence for the moral law pure and simple is the guiding rule of conduct, no room is left for recognition of any binding force attaching to such law as the expression of the divine moral order. If, however, there should be given in human nature a condition of the practical motives such that the force of reverence for moral law is weakened, then it might be possible that additional strength should 30 Fichte. be given by some indication, otherwise furnished, that the moral law is veritably the utterance of the divine will In such a case, the human agent would be con- strained by reverence for the divine character of the moral law, and such constraint is religion as opposed to theology. In this condition of human nature is found the substratum of fact, in relation to which a revelation is conceivable. How, then, could the human agent be made aware that the moral law is of divine origin ? Not, answers Fichte, through the practical reason itself, for the laws of this practical reason are self-explanatory, but only through some evidence supplied by the world of sense- cognition. Such evidence is not to be looked for in the general view of the sense-world as the sphere within which the moral end is to be realised, for this follows simply from the existence of the moral laAV in us, but in some fact, which manifests its supernatural origin, and so necessitates the conclusion that it is the direct result of the divine activity. A religion basing itself upon a supernatural fact manifested in nature is a Re- vealed Religion, and the conditions of the possibility of such a supernatural manifestation are the conditions of a Revealed Religion. Such a manifestation must needs be an a posteriori fact ; but in so far as it is simply an a posteriori fact i.e., so far as the form of the manifestation is concerned it cannot necessitate the conclusion that its origin is divine. As regards matter or content, the manifestation must be a supernatural revelation of the moral law in nature, a revelation possible for an intelligent agent in whom sensuous impulses have overbalanced the rever- " Critique of Revelation.' 31 ence for moral law. By such a revelation moral feeling might be, as it were, awakened or implanted in the heart ; for were such feeling absent, no force of reason, no play of sense-impulse, could create it. A revelation, then, is possible, if the human agent under such circum- stances can regard certain facts in the world of sense as the spontaneous effects of the divine will, and as mani- festing the moral purpose of the divine will This in- terpretation of the manifested fact, which is neitlier reason nor sense, but, as it were, midway between them, is the work of Imagination. The individual believes, and may believe, that the revealed fact is not explicable by natural laws ; but it is impossible for him to prove that it is inexplicable by these laws. It is equally im- possible that scientific proofs should be advanced that what happens according to natural laws is altogether explicable by them. The laws of the manifestation in itself are matters of indifference ; for the revelation is only relative, relative to the disturbed ro chaotic moral condition of the individual human agent. The possi- bility of a revelation thus rests upon the possibility of a particular condition of the moral nature ; and as this condition is not in itself necessary, a revealed religion cannot be regarded as necessary in the same sense in which the forms of thought or the postulates of practical reason are necessary. If there is a revelation at all, its contents must coincide with the contents of the moral law, and we can judge of any professed revela- tion according as it does or does not satisfy the criteria deducible from these two conditions. It must be made to those who are in the morally imperfect state just described : it must hold out no offers which are not in 32 Ficlitc. themselves consistent with pure morality : it must not effect its entrance into our thought by means which con- tain anything beyond the moral principle : it cannot give theoretical certainty to those postulated facts which follow from the moral law. Revealed religion, then, rests upon the possible needs of the human individual in the course of his development towards pure morality. The belief in such revelation is an element, and an im- portant element, in the moral education of humanity, but it is not a final stage for human thought. It is not of interest at the present stage of our sketch to consider the worth of the treatment of a difficult pro- blem here presented by Eichte, for his view of religion as a whole became deeper and fuller as his speculation slowly worked itself free from much of the Kantian for- malism. What is remarkable in the Essay is merely the strength with which the requirements of pure practical reason are held as the criteria for estimating the possi- bility and the nature of any revealed religion. Fichte, even at this stage of his philosophical career, was begin- ning to lay stress upon the practical side of the Kantian system, as yielding tho only complete solution of the whole speculative problem. There was some difficulty in getting the Essay brought before the public. Through Borowski's friendly efforts, and by Kant's recommendation, Hartung was induced to accept the manuscript, and forwarded it to Halle for printing. It thus became necessary that the work should receive the imprimatur of the Halle censor, who was Dean of the Theological Faculty. But the censor hesitated to give assent to the publication of a work in which it was explicitly stated that the divine ' Critique of Revelation.' 33 character of a revelation could not rest upon the evi- dence of a supposed miracle, but wholly upon the nature of its contents. Fichte endeavoured, but in vain, to get over the difficulty by declaring that his book was philosophical, not theological, and therefore stood in no need of a theological imprimatur. With his usual res- oluteness he absolutely declined to accede to the request of friendly critics that the offensive passages should be expunged, or even to the prudent advice of Kant that a distinction should be introduced between dogmatical belief, which was not in question, and moral faith or religion based on practical grounds ; and, for a time, the appearance of the work seemed more than problemati- cal Fortunately, at the critical moment a change occurred in the censorship of the Theological Faculty at Halle. The new dean, Dr Knapp, had no scruples in giving his sanction to the publication, and the Essay appeared in 1792. By some accident, whether of pub- lisher or printer does not seem to be known, the author's name, and the preface in which he spoke of himself, were not given ; and the accident was indeed fortunate for Fichte. The literary and philosophic public, long expectant of a work on religion by the author of the ' Critique of Pure Reason,' imagined that they found in this anonymous essay the clearest evidences of the handi- work of the great thinker. The ' Allgemeine Literatur- zeitung ' with bated breath discharged its " duty to the public " in communicating to them the substance of " a work which, more than any written for a long time, was adequate to the deepest wants of the time, and which might truly be called a word in season." "Just at the moment," the notice proceeds, " when the most varied p. iv. o 34 Ftikte. parties in theology are contending with one another, it is more particularly of importance that a man pietate ac meritis grams should come forward, and show to each in what they are in error, what they exaggerate, and what they assert without foundation. And in what manner is this essential task executed ! Assuredly there is to be found here much, perhaps all, that the greatest and most deservedly famous theologians of all ages have uttered regarding revelation ; but so closely knit together, so thoroughly wrought into unity, so accurately de- nned and justified does everything appear in this admir- ably constructed system, that as regards the fundamental propositions nothing is left to be desired." The review- er, after modestly indicating his joy at seeing the thoughts which he himself had long excogitated on the same subject expressed in so masterly and complete a fashion, proceeds to give an extract, with the remark that " every one who has made himself acquainted with even one work of the great author, here recognisable be- yond possibility of error," will imagine that much more valuable must remain unexcerpted ; and closes with an effusion of gratitude to the great man " whose finger is everywhere traceable," and who had now placed the keystone in the arch of human knowledge. Other crit- ics were not behind in their notices. The Jena coterie, already distinguished as the centre of a progressive Kantianism, commented on and discussed the Essay as veritably the work of the master, and treatises pro and con began to issue from the fruitful German press. Kant did not suffer the error to remain long uncor- rected. In the number of the 'Allgemeine Literatur- zeitung ' following that in which the just quoted notice Political Pamphlets. 35 appeared, he published a brief statement, giving the name of the author, and expressing respect for his ability. It is true that the reviews of the second edition of the Essay in the same journal exhibit a remarkable difference of tone, but none the less Fichte's literary fame was by this occurrence raised at once to a height such as years of labour might not have enabled him to attain. He was marked out from all the living writers on philosophy as the one who seemed able with strength and capacity to carry on the great work of Kant. His career was determined for him, and all his vague plans and projects were now consolidated. Henceforth he was a philosopher by profession. THE POLITICAL PAMPHLETS. The success of his literary venture now enabled Ficlate to think of his marriage as an event no longer to be delayed by uncertainty as to his own fortunes. Some portion of Hartmann Eahn's property had been saved from the general wreck, and in the beginning of 1793 we learn from his letters to Johanna that at last all might be regarded as settled. " In June, or at the latest July," he writes from Danzig in the spring of 1793, " I shall be with thee ; but I should wish to enter the walls of Zurich as thy husband. Is that possible ? Thy kind heart will give no hindrance to my wishes ; but I do not know the circumstances." The circum- stances, as it happened, were adverse to his wish. Zurich customs exacted from foreigners proposing to marry in that city a certain duration of residence, and it was not till the 22d of October that at Baden his mar- riage with Johanna Eahn took place. A short tour in 36 Ficlite. Switzerland, partly in company with the Danish poet Jens Baggesen, is noteworthy as having introduced Fichte to the acquaintance of Pestalozzi, whose educa- tional ideas were destined to play an important part in the after-life of the philosopher. During this calmer period of Fichte's life, the great events of the French Revolution had heen rapidly de- veloping themselves, and the attention of thinkers as well as of the piiblic had been drawn to the principles in- volved in or endangered by such a mighty movement. Rehberg, the secretary to the Hanoverian Privy Council, published in 1792 a work entitled ' Essays on the French Revolution,' in which a doubtful and timid view was expressed as to its principles, and the worst conse- quences were predicted as likely to follow from them. This book seems to have been the occasioning cause of Fichte's anonymous political tracts, the first of which, 'Reclamation of the Freedom of Thought from the Princes of Europe,' a fiery oratorical piece, was com- pleted at Danzig. The second and more important, ' Con- tributions towards the Correction of the Public Judgment on the French Revolution,' was begun at Danzig, and finished, so far as it went, at Zurich. In both the fun- damental principle is the same. Defence of the right of remodelling constitutional forms is founded on the inde- feasible and inalienable right to the liberty of realising the moral end of humanity, a right which precedes and underlies all others. The argument is in substance the translation of Rousseau's ' Contrat Social ' into the terms of the Kantian ethical system ; and as the whole ques- tion of Right or Law l is intimately connected with the 1 It is impossible to give any exact single equivalent in English for Political Pamphlets. 37 very essence of Fichte's philosophy, it is well to note how, at this comparatively early stage of his philosophic development, he expressed himself regarding it. As in the case of Kant's ' Rechtslehre,' so in these essays, the notion of an original contract as basis of rights within the state, is accepted not as though it expressed historic fact, but as the only theoretical foundation for a union of intelligent, voluntary beings. Within a community founded on such a contract, there are various rights and degrees of rights assigned to the several individuals or classes. But of those rights, some are inalienable or in- defeasible, for they express the condition in the absence of which the moral law, the supreme rule of conduct, is of no effect ; others, rights regarding modes of action merely permitted, not enjoined by the moral law, are alienable, and may be resigned by the individual. Among the inalienable rights, that which is all-comprehensive is ethical freedom ; but in one acceptation at least, freedom concerns not so much external acts as internal thoughts. Nevertheless the right to free expression of opinion, to free communication of thought, must be pronounced an inalienable or indefeasible right, for in its absence the the term Jlecht, which in different references may mean either law or the rights of the individual about which law is concerned, may be either an abstract or a collective notion, and may signify either posi- tive enactments or the ultimate ethical foundation for such enact- ments. In Fichte's writings a right is the specific mode of action, or realisation of a motive in external fact, which is indispensably neces- sary under the supposition of a common ethical law or supreme ethical end. Assuming such moral end, we can point to specific modes of action which must be approved by the community, unless violence is done to the very notion of ethical law. Alongside of this, however, there are rights which are mere specific modes of action approved by the community as a whole, though not indispensable for the realisation of the ethical end. 38 Fickte. possibility for acquiring the materials of thought is de- stroyed. No spiritual development is possible without the free interchange and communication of thought, nor is it given to any man or body of men to pronounce on the wisdom or goodness of thoughts with such confidence as to afford foundation for a supposed right to suppress freedom of thought on the ground of possible danger from, errors of thinking. 1 The same fundamental principle, that the ultimate foundation, and consequently the criterion, of all state rights, is to be found in the conditions necessary for the realisation of the ethical end, the spiritual development towards moral freedom, gives an answer to the more complicated problem of the right of revolution. Con- stitutional forms must needs be alterable ; they cannot continuously correspond to the requirements of a devel- oping moral culture. No original contract can be of a final nature, can prescribe limits to the moral and legal development of a community. The right to state reform is inalienable or indefeasible. Nevertheless the dissolution of a constitutional form implies withdrawal from the original state contract, and such withdrawal appears almost in terms to contradict the very notion upon which state rights are founded. 2 Fichte boldly faces this difficulty, contends that in all cases withdrawal from contract is possible, and that law or justice requires only compensation for such breach of pact, not unconditional fulfilment of it. If injury has 1 Fichte's argument here may be compared with the fuller and more concrete treatment of the same problem in J. S. Mill's tract, " On Liberty." 2 This contradiction is left as a kind of unsolved problem by Kant (see ' Eechtslehre,' 49, ' Allgemeine Anmerkung,' A.) Political Pamphlets. 39 been done by dissolving the contract on which the ex- isting form of state government rests, let due compensa- tion in kind and amount be rendered. Now the injury may be inflicted on the state itself, or on certain privi- leged classes in it. So far as the state itself is concerned, the only relations of life in respect of which compensa- tion could be demanded, are those which rest upon or are secured by the assistance of the state e. g., rights of property or right to development of one's own culture. But the smallest consideration enables us to see that these rights and relations are prior in nature to state arrangements. They do not spring from the state, but the state is the mechanism whereby they are protected and regulated. No penalty, therefore, can be exacted by the state in consequence of the withdrawal of one or all of its members from the original contract. These dissentient wills may combine and form a state within the state : this is the essence of political revolution. 1 The consideration of the possible injury to privileged classes in the state, consequent on revolution, leads Fichte, in the second Heft of the Beitrcige, into a some- what elaborate discussion of the origin of privileges in general The principles of social economy involved in his treatment are not so distinct as they afterwards be- came ; and as in dealing with his later writings some attention must be paid to them, it is sufficient here to 1 It is interesting to note that Fichte supports his argument in favour of a state within the state, by pointing to examples of such dual formations. These are mainly the existence of Jews in a Chris- tian community, and the existence of a military class. His expres- sions with regard to the Jews are hardly exceeded in bitterness by any of the modern assailants of the Semitic element in Germany. See specially ' Werke,' vol. vi. pp. 150, 151. 40 Fichte. remark that he subjects to the most trenchant criticism the grounds for the privileges of the nobility and the Church, absolutely rejects these as theoretically inde- fensible, and foreshadows the semi -socialist doctrine which is worked out in his later politico-economical treatises. 1 These political writings, breathing the warmest enthu- siasm for the French Revolution, not unnaturally drew attention to Fichte. He was marked as a dangerous political character, and accused, both at the time and afterwards, of democratic tendencies. The influence of this feeling regarding his political sympathies is a not- able fact in all the events of his after-career. As we shall see, much of the bitterness that was poured out against him at Jena on account of his theological views had its root in hatred for his advanced political doctrines. In substance the pamphlets are still interesting, both in themselves and as indicating the strong practical bent of Fichte's thinking ; in form, however, they are somewhat hard and pedantic. As in the ' Critique of Revelation/ so here, the language is full of Kantian technicalities, the structure and progress of the argument are deter- mined by the abstract forms of the Kantian system. In both works, Fichte had advanced to the limits drawn by the Critical Philosophy. He was now prepared to push beyond them. 1 Especially the ' Geschlossene Handels-staat ' and the ' Staatslehre.' 41 CHAPTEE III. THE JENA PROFESSORSHIP. THE winter of 1793 was passed quietly at Zurich in constant meditation over the main problems of the Kantian philosophy. Partly by his own reflection, partly by the acute criticisms of Schulz, whose ' ^Enesi- demus ' had appeared in the preceding year, Fichte had begun to see with clearness where the main difficulty of the Kantian system lay. The theory of knowledge ex- pounded in the ' Critique of Pure Eeason,' was not, so far at least as Kant's own statement extended, a per- fectly coherent whole ; nor did there appear to be a con- sistent, logical transition from that theory to the more metaphysical notions which came forward in the Cri- tiques of Practical Reason and of Judgment. Some assistance in working into system the parts of the Kant- ian doctrine was doubtless furnished by Eeinhold, but with his method Fichte soon became dissatisfied. It was for him a necessity that the whole of philosophy should manifest a single principle, that the theories of knowledge and of practice should be deduced from one common source, and that the fundamental notions of speculative thought should be developed with systematic 42 Fichte. completeness. In one or two occasional reviews dating from this period, and in letters to his friends, he gave brief utterance to his convictions on this point ; and, as his views grew more matured and definite, he yielded to the request of some Zurich acquaintances, and delivered during the winter a short course of private lectures on philosophy as conceived by him. The formation of his speculative doctrines was, however, accelerated by the invitation, which reached him in December 1793, to fill the post of extraordinary Professor of Philosophy at Jena, about to become vacant by the transference of Reinhold to Kiel. Reluctant as Fichte was at first to yield immediate assent to this call, he coxild not refuse the opportunity of entering once for all upon the career for which he appeared specially marked out, and after sending in his acceptance to Privy Councillor Yoigt, he made arrangements for beginning his course at Jena in the Easter term of 1794. The University at Jena was then at the very height of its renown. No other period, in all its brilliant his- tory, rivals the first decades of the nineteenth century. Above all other universities in Germany it was distin- guished as the very centre of the most progressive move- ments in philosophy and literature. The near neigh- bourhood of Weimar where the most illustrious names in the new German literature congregated, where, under the genial care of a noble and enlightened prince, arts and letters flourished as in a modern Athens gave to it additional renown, and secured the most watchful super- vision over the studies of the university. More espe- cially, however, was Jena pre-eminent as the university in Avhich the new German philosophy had been most The Jena Professorship. 43 eagerly accepted and most fruitfully applied. Schiitz, known in classical literature for his editions of ' JEschy- lus ' and ' Cicero,' made it his boast that he had been the first to introduce the youth of Jena to the Critical Philosophy. Hufeland, an eminent jurist, expounded the principles of the Kantian ethics, and his 'Natur- recht ' is still one of the best expositions of philosophic jurisprudence. Keinhold, who by his 'Letters on the Kantian Philosophy ' had won the approval of the father of criticism himself, had begun in 1787, in the chair instituted specially for him, the lectures in which he endeavoured to improve and further the critical system. Schiller, called to the Chair of History in 1789, had shown how philosophical principles might be fruitfully united with historical research and artistic production. Paulus, Loder, Ersch, and Schmid, are names not to be forgotten for the services they rendered to the advance- ment of German thought. Altogether, the University of Jena, at the close of the eighteenth century, exhibited a degree of life and activity which raised it to the first place among the academies of Germany. The history of German philosophy, in its brightest period, is in a great measure the history of the Jena University. For there as teachers we find Fichte, Schelling, Hegel, Fries, Krause, and Schlegel ; as scholars, Herbart, Schubert, Steffens, Solger, Hulsen, Hblderlin, Von Berger, and Oersted. Among the students the fame of their teachers was reflected in a peculiarly open and vigorous university life. Nowhere was there a freer or more enthusiastic academic tone than in Jena. The call of Fichte to Jena not, as we learn from Goethe, xindertaken without some hesitation on the score 44 Fickle. of his pronounced political views was hailed by the university with the keenest joy. Of all the adherents of Kantianism, he alone had given proofs of ability to carry forward and develop the great thoughts that had already begun to exert their wonderful influence. " In Jena," his friend Bb'ttiger writes to him, "there has been for some weeks past an indescribable joy over the triumvirate of professors due at Easter, for in addition to you, there have also been called here the excellent Ilgen, probably the most learned and cultured scholar in Saxony, as Professor Orientalium, and Woltmann, as extraordinary lecturer on History. But your name resounds above all, and expectation is strained to its utmost doubtless in part because you are regarded as the most valiant defender of the rights of men, whereon many a son of the Muses has quite peculiar ideas. This, however, may easily be put to rights." On the 18th May 1794 Fichte arrived in Jena. The preceding months had been spent by him in the most arduous and careful preparation for his new task. It had been impossible, in the short interval allowed him, to complete what he had desired to have ready, an exposi- tion of his philosophic views which might serve as a handbook for his prelections ; but as introductory thereto he had drawn out and published the short tract, ' On the Notion of the Theory of Knowledge or so-called Philo- sophy,' 1 giving a preliminary sketch of the fundamental 1 ' Ueber den Begriff der Wissenschaftslehre oder der sogenannten Philosophic, ' 1st ed., 1794. The term " Wissenschaftslehre," which we here translate by " Theory of Knowledge," will receive more de- tailed explanation when the nature of Fichte's philosophy is dis- cussed. As no equivalent in English conveys its meaning with per- fect accuracy, it will be employed hereafter, without translation, as a technical term. TJie Jena Professorship. 45 ideas to be embodied in his philosophical lectures. The tract is written with wonderful clearness, but its con- tents amount to little more than the strenuous expression of the need for unity of philosophical conception, toge- ther with certain formal determinations regarding the first principle from which philosophical thinking must take its start. The somewhat abstract method here em- ployed was never afterwards followed by Fichte, and it is matter for regret that the general ideas of his system have been mainly drawn from this early pamphlet, and contain little beyond its formal statements. The reception accorded to the philosopher at Jena was of the most gratifying kind. As might have been anti- cipated from Fichte's character, it was his constant aim not only to reach the truth in purely metaphysical specu- lation, but to make philosophic principles living rules of action. The tone of his mind was prevailingly practical, and it was impossible for him to remain contented with mere exposition of speculative doctrines. Accordingly he arranged his courses at Jena into two series : the one, more elaborate and extended, on philosophy as a whole ; the other, shorter and more popular, on the effects of philosophic culture in general upon character and life. The first course was given to the students of philosophy in particular; the second, to which he then gave the title of " Ethics of the Scholar," was public, and intended for all the members of the academic body. In both courses his success was immediate and pronounced. The great hall was crowded to overflowing when his public lectures were delivered, while the enthusiasm of his phi- losophic students soon made the technical terms of his system familiar words in academic circles and in general 46 Fichte. literature. " Since Reinhold left us," writes Forberg, then a privat-docent at Jena, "liis philosophy, at least among us, is absolutely dead. Every trace of the " Phi- losophy without Nickname " 1 has been driven from the heads of our students. They believe in Fichte as they never believed in Reinhold. Doubtless they understand him even less than they understood Reinhold, but they believe all the more stubbornly for that very reason. Ego and non-Ego are now the symbols of the philoso- phers, as Matter and Form were then. About the right which either party has to dissolve a contract, there is just as little doubt now, as there was then regarding the manifold character of matter." To the success of his prelections Fichte's admirable philosophic style contributed much. He had a mar- vellous faculty of riveting attention, of compelling thought to dwell upon the problems presented to it, and of evolving in rigid sequence the stages of a complete argument or disputation. All his writings bear more or less the character of lectures, and probably his own mode of speculative reflection was that of the expounder conscious of an audience to whom explanations are due, rather than that of the pure thinker, intent on nothing but the notions before him. He was a born orator, and, as we have already seen in his early life, sedulously cul- tivated the oratorical faculty as that wherewith he could best attain his great end, the elevation of life. His personality, further, combining strength and obstinacy 1 " Philosophic ohne Beinamen," as Reinhold was pleased to call his rather washed-out reproduction of Kantianism, in order to indi- cate that it was neither critical nor dogmatic nor sceptical, but philo- sophy simply. TJie Jena Professorship. 47 with the loftiest moral principle, found its most adequate expression, and was capable of its most powerful influ- ence, in oratorical efforts rather than in systematic ex- position. In Fichte, as in Schelling, and generally in the writers of the Eomantic period, what the historian of philosophy notes as their prevailing characteristic is a certain hot-headed impetuosity and impatience, which contrasts unfavourably with the calm matureness of their great predecessor Kant, and which almost inevitably leads to a slight distrust of, or dissatisfaction with, their work. Something of this distrust, as we shall see later, was felt by Kant himself, who always disliked and de- preciated Genie-scliwiinge, flights of genius, and trusted rather to solid, patient, methodical work, than to the efforts of enthusiastic imagination. The Jena period of Fichte's life may be conveniently regarded under two quite distinct aspects. It presents to us, in the first place, a series of developments of one speculative principle, covering the whole ground of philosophy, affecting by their spirit and method all contemporary criticism and literature, and bringing the author into close connection, whether friendly or polemi- cal, with the greatest living writers. In this sense, it is simply the representation of the active results of Fichte's speculative faculty. But speculative faculty was only one side of Fichte's character, and when we consider the several incidents of public life which mark the Jena career, we find rather the development of the more im- petuous temper which so frequently in the course of his life led to unfortunate collisions with his surroundings. The philosophical and the practical activity may thus be regarded apart from one another. 48 Fichte. As respects the first, a brief notice of the successive works in which the new speculative system Avas laid be- fore the world, will here suffice. The lectures on ' Wissenschaftslehre,' delivered to his private class during the first semester at the university, were printed in sheets as soon as delivered, and from these sheets was formed the first systematic exposition of the new doctrine, ' Foundations of the whole Wissenschaftslehre ' ('Grundlage der gesammten Wissenschaftslehre,' 1st ed., 1794). The whole field of philosophical cognition, theoretical and practical, was surveyed in this work; but Fichte remained unsatisfied with the method pur- sued, and in his later, more mature writings, never em- ploys the abstract forms which are here brought forward, and which have been falsely thought to be essential elements in his system. In quick succession he put forward detailed expositions of the several portions briefly discussed in the 'Grundlage.' The theoretical faculty of cognition was specially handled in the ' Out- line of what is peciiliar to Wissenschaftslehre' (1795); the practical side of consciousness in the two important treatises, ' Theory of Natural Law ' (' Grundlage des Natur- rechts,' 1796-97) and 'Theory of Morals' ('System der Sittenlehre,' 1798); while the whole philosophy was expounded in a fresh form in the ' Introductions to Wissenschaftslehre,' published in the ' Philosophical Journal,' vols. v. and vi. (1797), and in the 'Essay to- wards a New Exposition of the Wissenschaftslehre,' vol. vii. of the same periodical These writings, taken in conjunction with the important ' Eeview of ^Eneside- mus' (1794), make up the philosophy of Fichte in its so-called earlier form. The Jena Professorship. 49 A wonderful impression seems to have been made upon his contemporaries by the boldness and systematic completeness of Fichte's speculation. Goethe, little disposed to abstract thinking, and probably in his heart of hearts not over well disposed towards an eager politi- cal theorist, yet found " nothing in the first sheets of the ' Wissenschaf tslehre ' which he did not understand, or at least thought he understood, nothing which did not harmonise with his own mode of thinking about things," laboured hard to keep pace with the 'New Expositions' of the prolific author, and in general extended to the metaphysician a cordial and respectful admiration. With Schiller, whose Kantian sympathies might have led to a warmer interest in pure speculation, Fichte never seems to have been on terms of unqualified friend- ship. Despite the mutual esteem which they enter- tained for one another, their characters were too pro- nounced to admit of perfectly unclouded harmony ; and, philosophically, there was a divergence between their views which, on one occasion at least, led to an unfor- tunate collision between them. Fichte, who had been invited to contribute to the ' Horen,' then edited by Schiller, forwarded for this periodical an Essay 'On Spirit and Letter,' in which the editor fancied that he could detect a parody of his own ' Letters on the JEs- thetic Education of the Human Race.' The parody ex- isted only in Schiller's over-sensitive imagination, but a somewhat bitter correspondence followed his suppression of the paper. Eeconciliation was effected; but, if we may judge from the tone of the communications which passed between Goethe and Schiller at a later date re- garding Eichte's academic troubles, a secret distrust P. iv. D 50 Fichte. and dislike continued to exist. With his philosophic contemporaries Fichte's relations were of even greater interest. His increasing fame naturally attracted both adherents and enemies. The older Kantian scholars bitterly criticised the new effort after a completeness of system which had been foreign to Kant's original method. The younger and more impetuous philosophic students, among others Methammer, Forberg, and Schelling, with equal bitterness accused their more cautious predecessors of want of faith in their own prin- ciples, and declared that Criticism proper had been but a propaedeutic or introduction, to which the 'Wissen- schaftslehre ' was the natural and necessary supplement. The antagonists of all the newer philosophy, pre-emin- ently Mcolai, the editor of the ' Deutsche Bibliothek,' eagerly hailed the controversy as furnishing evidence of the empty and contradictory character, and of the evil tendencies, of the so-called metaphysics. With Kant himself, Fichte's relations gradually became hostile, though no open declaration was made by the aged philosopher until he had been alarmed by the accusa- tions of atheism brought against a system which pro- fessed to be a development of his own principles. It does not appear that he had ever fairly entered into the spirit of Fichte's works, probably he had not even studied them ; but in the Intelligence sheet of the 'AUgemeine Literaturzeitung ' for 1799, No. 109, he published a formal disclaimer of any connection between his own system and that of Fichte, declaring that the ' Wissenschaftslehre ' was nothing but abstract logic, valuable therefore as methodising thought, but contain- ing no reference to reality, and bitterly resenting the de- The Jena Professorship. 51 scription of his own critical work as mere propaedeutic to a system of reasoned philosophy. Fichte's rejoinder, published in the same paper in the form of a letter to Schelling, was pointed and severe. He rightly drew attention to Kant's frank admission that his disclaimer was personal in character, and not founded on thorough appreciation of the new philosophic work, and indicated that from Kant's position it was not unnatural that he should regard the ' Critique ' as final, just as his oppon- ents thought the ' Critique ' a worthless and unnecessary attempt to transcend the well-defined and sure limits of the earlier systems. 1 Kant's disclaimer came too late to he of any service in checking the rapid current of speculation which had its source in his own writings. Reinhold, a weak and vacillating thinker, had given his complete adhesion to the ' Wissenschaftslehre ; ' the Jena ' Allgemeine Liter- aturzeitung,' once the organ of the Kantians, declared for Fichte ; and in the ' Philosophisches Journal,' of which Fichte was co-editor with Niethammer from 1795 onwards, the new school possessed an official organ of their own. Schelling's early works gave in fresh and attractive form expositions of the ' Wissenschaftslehre,' applied its principles to the more profound problems of metaphysics, and called attention to the advance effected on the critical position. Even Jacobi, strongly opposed as he was to any demonstrative or theoretical meta- physic, was not proof against the attraction of the new 1 The letters between Fichte and Schelling on the subject of Kant's declaration ('Leben und Brief wechsel,' vol. ii. pp. 301-308) are of great interest, as indicating their views on the relation between the 'Critique' and Fichte's 'Wissenschaftslehre.' 52 Fichte. system, or its apparent coincidence with his own views. His correspondence with Fichte is of the highest inter- est, as throwing light on the philosophical and personal relations of two eminent thinkers ; and although he could not bring himself to see the similarity between the ' Wissenschaf tslehre ' and his own doctrines, on which Fichte laid so much stress, it was not till the accusation of atheism had been brought against the Fichtean system that he declared himself against it. On the whole, during the important period from 1794 to 1799, the philosophy of Fichte was in the ascendant. It gave a new impetus and direction to speculative thought, and powerfully influenced contemporary litera- ture of a non-philosophical kind. If we can discover philosophical principles at all in the literary productions of the earlier Eomantic school, in the writings of Tieck, Novalis, and Fr. Schlegel, these bear unmistakably the impress of the Fichtean system. Doubtless, this sec- ondary effect of Fichte's philosophy gave additional strength to the feeling gradually roused against it. When we turn to the consideration of Fichte's public life, his professorial career, during the same period, we find a series of troubles and conflicts, terminating in the severance of his connection with the University of Jena. Minor annoyances were not wanting to him, even on his entrance upon his public duties as professor. With his colleague, C. C. K Schmid, an excellent empirical psy- chologist but a poor philosopher, his relations had been hostile even before the call to Jena, and though friend- ship appeared to be established between them, the truce was not of long duration. In the third volume of the { Philosophisches Journal,' Schmid gave utterance to a The Jena Professorship. 53 critical judgment respecting all philosophy which pre- sumed to go heyond the facts of experience, and in such fashion as to indicate that he had in view the ' Wissen- schaftslehre.' In the last number of the same volume Fichte compared Herr Schmid's system with his own ; distinguished with the utmost clearness the problem of psychology from that of transcendental logic; showed that of the nature of this second problem Schmid had no conception whatsoever; and ended with the declara- tion that henceforth not only everything uttered by Herr Schmid against the ' Wissenschaftslehre ' should be held by him as non-existent, but also that Herr Schmid himself, in his capacity of philosopher, should be viewed as a nonentity. This satisfactory result certainly could not contribute to render Fichte's position easier; it is, indeed, only one specimen of the unyielding temper which he throughout displayed in all the actions of his life, and which created enemies for him in all quarters. Even in his first semester, Fichte found that his evil political reputation was productive of discomfort. Some doubts appear to have been raised regarding the public lectures already alluded to, and in self-defence he pub- lished a selection from them. 1 Of the nature of these complaints we have no accurate information, but the course of public lectures presently led to a more serious trouble. In the winter semester, 1794-95, Fichte found that no hour during the ordinary week-days could be selected for lectures open to all the students of the uni- 1 These appear in the sixth volume of the ' Werke,' under the title ' Einige Vorlesungen uber die Bestimmung des Gelehrten ' ('Some Lectures on the Vocation of the Scholar '). They are more formal than the lectures under a similar title delivered at Erlangen in 1805. 54 Fichte. versity, without interfering with the class arrangements of his colleagues. After consultation with Schiitz, he announced the lectures for Sunday mornings, between 10 and 11 A.M., thereby avoiding collision either with the special service held for university students or with, the general public church service. Hardly had this been done when the Consistory of Jena raised an outcry against him for endeavouring to suppress the public ser- vice of God ; the Over-Consistory, of which Herder was a member, repeated the cry, and appealed to the Govern- ment at Weimar; while a malicious journal, 'Euda- monia,' which scattered its mud with rare impartiality, called attention to the connection between atheism and revolutionary politics, and boldly asserted that the demo- crats, under the leadership of Professor Fichte, were making a deliberate attempt to institute the worship of reason. The lectures were temporarily suspended, and the senate of the university, after a bitter discussion, in which strong opposition was raised to Fichte on grounds manifestly personal, forwarded to the Government a statement of their reasons for holding that the Sunday lec- tures in no way infringed customary rules, recommending at the same time that the hour selected should be in the afternoon. The Weimar council gave its decision in favour of Fichte, absolved him from all blame in the matter, but significantly cautioned him to be more pru- dent in the future. The lectures were continued from February onwards at three in the afternoon. This first trouble was scarcely at an end when a new storm broke out. Fichte's constant aim as a public teacher was the moral elevation of the character of the students. The life of a scholar appeared to him a life The Jena Professorship. 55 with a noble end, and weighted with responsibilities. But to all his efforts towards elevating and purifying the tone of academic life, a blank wall of resistance was presented by the existence of the so-called Orders or Societies among the students. These orders had their own code of morals, and their own regulations for public and private action. One can well understand how en- tirely all individuality of life and action was destroyed for the student who had enrolled himself in one of these societies. He could not escape the force of the general judgment, and was driven, by virtue of his relations to the other members, to assent to much that would have been abhorrent to him in his private capacity. Fichte felt very keenly the evil consequences of the secret unions, and, both by his public lectures and by private communications, strove to effect their abolition. It was a wonderful evidence of his personal influence that in the winter of 1794-95, the three orders of the Jena students made overtures to him regarding the suppression of their societies, and by their deputies requested him to give and receive their oaths of dissolu- tion. Fichte did not feel that he was entitled to con- clude the matter on his own responsibility, referred them to the pro-rector, and, unfortunately, undertook the task of mediating between the students and the uni- versity authorities, a task for which he was eminently unfitted. Partly from Fichte's unpractical and over- pedantic fashion of carrying on the affair, partly from the natural dilatoriness of a government, especially of a university government, the happy moment was allowed to pass. One of the orders withdrew its offer ; the others, who had placed their books of regulations and 56 Fichte. names in Fiehte's hands, were alarmed at the idea of a Government inquisition into their doings, and began to think that Fichte was playing them false. An inde- scribable tumult was occasioned in the university. The students attacked Fiehte's house on the New Year's night of 1795, broke his windows, and insulted him with cries and hootings. His public lectures were inter- rupted, his wife was saluted with insults in the streets ; and so serious did the danger appear, that in the spring of 1795 he had to demand protection from the Govern- ment, and finally, permission to reside out of Jena for the summer of that year. The great Ego, as Goethe and Schiller call him in their letters, took up his resi- dence at Ossmanstadt, a pleasant little town a few miles from Jena, and there remained until the storm had blown over. Two waves of trouble had thus disturbed Fiehte's public career at Jena ; the third and greatest finally dis- solved his connection with that university. In 1798, Forberg, then rector at Saalfeld, and already noted as one of the earliest adherents of the ' Wissenschaftslehre,' sent in to the editors of the ' Philosophisches Journal ' a paper entitled " Development of the ISTotion of Reli- gion." With the argument, and in particular with the tone of this essay, Fichte was but little satisfied, al- though it was impossible for him to avoid agreeing with some ideas in it. He was extremely unwilling to exer- cise the editorial right of suppressing the paper, but desired to attach to it certain footnotes, correcting or amending it in accordance with what he thought the truth. Of this, however, Forberg would not hear, and Fichte printed the essay as it had been sent, prefixing The Jena Professorship. 57 to it a short exposition of his own views on the same subject, under the title, " On the Ground for our Belief in a Divine Government of the Universe." The two papers appeared together in the first part of the eighth volume of the ' Journal.' It was certainly a misfortune for Fichte that the published exposition of his views on so fundamental a question should have been limited to the points discussed in Forberg's essay, for, to one who now studies these documents, that essay has every ap- pearance of insincerity or irony. Accepting without reservation the Kantian criticism of the theoretical proofs for the existence of God, Forberg likewise accepts the doctrine that the belief in a divine order is prac- tical, but he reduces this practical belief to mere strength of moral feeling, identifies it with virtue, and therefore draws the conclusion that it is perfectly compatible with speculative atheism. In short, the essay is an exagger- ation of the dismal rationalism into which the weaker Kantians drifted, and by which they cast such discredit on philosophy. It is almost a parody of the moderatism which had begun to appear as the result of the Kantian system in works such as those of Tieftrunk and Hey- denreich. The element of speculative interest in the critical philosophy, however, which was entirely over- looked or reduced to a nullity by Forberg, was precisely that upon which Fichte laid stress. His essay, there- fore, exaggerated the agreement between his views and those of Forberg, and gave too succinctly the characteristic difference. Attention was drawn to the papers by an anonymous pamphlet, circulated gratuitously throughout Saxony towards the close of the year 1798, and piirporting to be 58 . Fichte. a ' Letter on the Atheism of Fichte and Forberg, from a Father to his Son, a Student.' Neither name of pub- lisher nor place of publication was given, and it was more than hinted to those who accepted the tract, that it was the work of Gabler, a theologian of some repute in Altdorf. Gabler, however, was not the author, and protested publicly against the insult done him by such a statement. The real author has never been known, and the tract itself was a malicious and unfair selection of certain sentences from the essays of the accused writers, without reference to the context, and with such com- ments as unenlightened pietism has always indulged in. Moved by this pamphlet, the Over-Consistory of Dres- den brought the subject before the Saxon Government, who, on the 19th November 1798 published a Rescript directed to the Universities of Leipzig and Wittenberg, confiscating the ' Philosophisches Journal ' on the ground of the atheistic utterances contained in it. The Rescript was followed by a circular note, addressed to the neigh- bouring German Governments, praying them to take similar steps, and, in the case of the Saxe- Weimar Dukes, threatening to prohibit Saxon students from at- tendance at the Jena University if investigation were not instantly made into the conduct of the accused pro- fessors, and condign punishment inflicted were they found guilty of the charge laid against them. Fichte had thus a twofold charge to deal with, the public accusation of atheism, and the private appeal to the supreme authori- ties of the university. To the first he replied in his ' Appeal to the Public against the Accusation of Athe- ism,' a copy of which was forwarded in January 1799 to the Grand Duke of Weimar; to the second, in the The Jena Professorship. 59 ' Formal Defence of the Editor of the Philosophical Journal against the Accusation of Atheism,' 1 directed to the Pro-rector of the University, and forwarded to the Grand Duke in March 1799. In the 'Appeal,' a more detailed exposition was given of the views contained in the accused essay, and a powerful contrast was drawn be- tween philosophical religion and the ordinary theology ; in the 'Defence/ a skilful analysis of the full bearing of his theological doctrines precedes a bold statement of the real motives which had led to the accusation, and a demand that in the interests of university freedom, decision should be given based solely on the merits of the question. In the most unqualified fashion Fichte declares that the true secret of the enmity against him was the dread of his political opinions, and insists that the decision of the matter was of the last importance, not only for his own activity as a professor, but for the academic life of the university. In order to understand the course of events, it is needful to review carefully the position of the two parties, Fichte on the one hand, the Saxe-Weimar Gov- ernment on the other. Fichte's motives are clear and unambiguous. He claimed the full right of expound- ing his philosophic opinions, a right essential to the very existence of a university teacher. He felt, as every teacher of philosophy must feel, that the results of speculative analysis will at times appear to conflict with popular ideas, founded for the most part on unre- 1 The title of this pamphlet, ' Gerichtliche Verantwortungs- schrift,' would be more exactly translated as 'Judicial Defence ' or ' Plea in Justification.' " Gerichtlich " implies that the defence was explicitly directed to a court, by whom decision on the merits of the case should be given. 60 Fickle. fleeting custom or on radical error, and that if popular opinion is to be the criterion of judgment, the function of an investigator is destroyed. Accordingly he de- manded, with all the earnestness that the importance of the matter required, and with all the vehemence that his impatient disposition rendered natural, that there should be no compromise; that the matter should not be hushed up, or conducted to its conclusion by private negotiations within the university circle ; and that as the accusation had been public, the decision should be public also. On the other hand, what the university authorities above all things desired was a mode of settlement where- by peace might be secured without the necessity of any public declaration. They in no way desired to limit the freedom of teaching in the university; and as the necessity for taking cognisance of the matter at all had been forced upon them from without, they wished to deal with it in such a way as neither to offend external powers nor endanger their own position. It will be readily understood, therefore, that Fichte's movements caused them the greatest trouble and annoyance. In a letter of Schiller to Fichte, written after the Grand- Duke had received the 'Appeal to the Public,' the feel- ings of the court-party are expressed without reserve. That their intentions were friendly is stated without qua- lification. " I have had an opportunity," says Schiller, " of conversing recently with those who have a voice in the affair, and on various occasions with the Grand-Duke himself. He openly declared that nothing would or could be done to limit your freedom of writing, though doubtless there were some things that one would rather not have stated from the professorial chair. Even as TJie Jena Professorship. 61 regards the latter point, however, this is but his private opinion ; his public judgment would impose no limita- tions even in respect of it." But as Schiller goes on to say, the Weimar authorities regretted that he had en- gaged in discussion of the matter on his own account, and had appealed to the public, when his business lay solely with them. Evidently in such a state of opinion the 'Formal Defence' was a most embarrassing document, and from the expressions of all Fichte's friends regarding it, we can see that they unanimously thought him grossly imprudent. Eumours of all kinds were prevalent, and gradually took form in the report that the "Weimar Government intended to impose a censure upon Fichte, which, as coming through the academic senate, must needs be of a public character. It was apparently under the influence of this rumour that Fichte was induced to take a step which he after- wards consistently defended, but which must be pro- nounced nothing less than unfortunate. On the 22d March 1799 he wrote an important letter to the Privy Councillor Voigt, explicitly leaving to the discretion of his correspondent either to employ it further, or to accept it as an aid in forming his own opinions. In this letter he declared unreservedly that he neither would nor could submit to censure given through the senate. "Were such to be imposed, no course would be left to him but to reply by sending in his resignation and publishing the present letter in explanation of his motives. The letter concluded with the statement, that many important mem- bers of the university agreed in the view that censure on the writer would be infringement of their academic rights ; that the same members had engaged, were he to 62 Fichte. resign, to resign with him, and had permitted him to notify their intention. "With him, Fichte added, they looked forward to find in a new university, of which there was rumour, a free and honourable sphere of action, such as they had hitherto enjoyed in Jena. The new university referred to was doubtless that projected at Mainz, regarding which Jung, the chief of the council of Mainz, had been in communication with Fichte during the preceding year, and rumours of which had been alluded to by Forberg. The plan was never real- ised, and the colleagues who had given their promise to Fichte did not redeem it. Paulus, indeed, to whom the letter had been submitted, by whose mediation it was forwarded to Voigt, and who is explicitly included by Fichte among the said colleagues, afterwards declared that the engagement existed only in Fichte's imagina- tion ; but on a point like this the statements of Paulus are worthless. It was this letter that finally decided the "Weimar Government, and the member of the council whose warmth overcame all hesitation regarding the action to be taken was Goethe. His conservative feelings were roused by the apparent endeavour to threaten the Gov- ernment. " For my own part," he wrote to Schlosser some months later, " I declare that I would have voted against my own son, if he had permitted himself such language against a Government." The Rescript of the Weimar authorities, dated 29th March 1799, desired the senate to censure Professors Fichte and Methammer for their indiscretion, and to recommend to them greater caution in bringing essays before the public. But to this gentle censure there was appended a post-scriptum The Jena Professorship. 63 referring to the letter to Voigt, accepting Fichte's dec- laration that he would resign, and thereby dismissing him from his office. Again the unfortunate advice of Paulus prevailed on Fichte, and induced him to make a false step. Fichte himself was of opinion that the letter to Voigt should not have been regarded as an official document; that, even had it this official character, it should have been left to him to take the final step of resignation ; and, more particularly, that it ought to have been considered whether the condition under which he had declared resignation inevitable was fulfilled by the Rescript of the Government. Under these circumstances, when, through the intercession of his friends, it had been arranged that the publication of the Reseat should be delayed for a few days, he was persuaded to forward through Paulus a second letter to Voigt, in which he pointed out that as the censure imposed in no way limited his freedom of teaching, it did not render the resignation of his office imperative, and that he would not allow the public to think that he had voluntarily laid down his office on account of this censure. The letter was com- municated by Voigt to the Grand-Duke, who found "nothing in it to cause him to alter his expressed opinion." Nor did two numerously signed petitions from the students, first to prevent the dismissal and then to obtain the recall of their honoured teacher, alter the position of affairs. Thus Fichte's connection with Jena came to a violent termination. As regards the rights of so complicated a matter, there is little ground for difference of opinion. Had not Fichte's impatient temper betrayed him into 64 Fichte. the strong expressions contained in the first letter to Voigt, all might have been well, for the Weimar Gov- ernment, despite their indignation at his impetuous mode of dealing with the matter, evidently desired to retain him in the university. But they erred in making such use as they did of the letter, and they erred douhly in the infliction of so serious a wound on the academic life of Jena. For many years the effect was felt ; and as Goethe himself notes, within a comparatively short in- terval all the most eminent teachers had, for one cause or another, migrated to other universities : Paulus, Loder, both the Hufelands, Ilgen, Schelling, and Methammer vanished from Jena. No injury is so great to a univer- sity as a limitation in the freedom of academic teaching. No mistake is so serious as to deal in diplomatic and politic fashion with matters of thought and reasoning. 65 CHAPTER IV. BERLIN AND THE WAR OP LIBERATION. THE expulsion from Jena, and the sudden termination of his public career as an academic teacher, exercised a powerful influence not only upon Fichte's external for- tunes, but upon the development of his philosophic system. The difficulties which had been raised regard- ing his utterances on the supreme philosophic doctrine, the being of God and the nature of His relation to the individual thinking subject, compelled his attention to that aspect of his system in which it was as yet imper- fect or incomplete. From this time onwards the ' Wis- senschaftslehre,' as it had been expounded in the works already before the world, began to be incorporated in a wider view of character prevailingly theological or even theosophical. The whole tone or manner of treatment was at the same time altered ; and Fichte, who seemed ever to feel that it was next to impossible to present his system in such a form as to be free from all ambiguity or danger of misconception, entered upon a series of popular expositions of his philosophy, which later writers have had some difficulty in reconciling with the results of his earlier method. A more precise account p. iv. E 66 FicUe. of the relations between the earlier and later forms of his philosophic doctrines will be given when the whole system is reviewed ; but it is important to note here, as in the case of the ' Critique of Eevelation,' a turning- point in Fichte's career. At Jena Fichte found it impossible even to continue in residence : all prospect of literary activity there was excluded by the Rescript of the Saxon Electorate. Nor was it easy for him to find any refuge. The majority of the smaller states in the surrounding district had pass- ively acquiesced in the Saxon mandate : even from the little princedom of Rudolstadt, where he had hoped to secure a quiet retreat, he was excluded by the jealous surveillance of his antagonists. The intense excitement which had been roused by the discussions preceding his dismissal from Jena had spread far and wide, and if we may judge from his own expressions, his personal safety, in many quarters, was more than problematical In this uncertainty a slight accident determined his conduct. The Prussian minister Dohm, passing through Weimar, spent a few days at Jena, and, as was natural, conversed with friends regarding Fichte's case. The indignation he expressed at the treatment to which Fichte had been subjected was coupled with the significant remark that in Prussia no such calamities were to be dreaded by thinkers who could prove themselves good and worthy citizens. Fichte, acting upon the hint communicated to him, wrote to his friend, Friedrich Schlegel, then residing in Berlin, and was by him assured that if he could make his way to that city in such a fashion as not to attract undue attention, and could time his arrival so as to have his case brought speedily before the King of Friends at Berlin. 67 Prussia, no hindrance need be feared. Following this advice, Fichte, in the early days of July 1799, suddenly left Jena, under pretext of taking a journey for recovery of his health, and travelled to Berlin. A few police inquiries were easily satisfied, and when the matter was brought under the royal notice, it was disposed of in the briefest fashion, " If," said the easy-tempered monarch, "Fichte is so peaceful a citizen, and so free from all dangerous associations as he is said to be, I willingly accord him a residence in my dominions." As for his religious views, these were dismissed in a somewhat clumsy paraphrase of Tiberius's pithy saying, " Deorum offensa diis curce." 1. FRIENDS AND LITERARY ACTIVITY AT BERLIN (1799-1806) "Warmly received by Schlegel, and introduced by him to the circle of friends centring mainly round Schleier- macher, Fichte, with his accustomed impetuosity, at once began to form new and extensive plans for literary work. It appeared to him that his narrow means would prove more than sufficient if he and his family could unite with the Schlegels and with Schelling in forming a common domicile. Against the feasibility of this scheme there was doubtless to be placed the unpleasing relations of Friedrich Schlegel with Dorothea Yeit, who had by this time separated from her husband and thrown in her lot with Schlegel, and it is evident from Fichte's letters to his wife that he had much to do to reconcile her to the proposal. At the same time he contemplated the foundation, also in concert with the above-named friends, of a comprehensive literary journal, which should 68 Fichte. apply freely and boldly the principles of the new philo- sophy. There seemed to be need of some such organ, for the Jena 'Allgemeine Literaturzeitung,' formerly devoted to the Fichtean ideas, was beginning to waver in its allegiance, and Nicolai, in the 'Neue Allgemeine Bibliothek,' and in many a dreary satire, was prose- cuting, after his antiquated fashion, his favourite war- fare against every novelty in literature or philosophy. Fichte, however, had deceived himself regarding his relations to his new friends. There were elements pre- sent which rapidly led to discord and even to the bit- terest animosity. The years from 1799 to 1806 are characterised by the gradual overshadowing of the Fichtean philosophy, and by the development of hitherto unsuspected differences of view in the circle over which that philosophy had been supreme. To understand fully the movements of this period a period of painful interest to the historian of literature it is necessary to note with some care what were the main currents of thought and the general conditions of life at Berlin. We shall find in their nature the key to much of Fichte's later work. Under Frederick the Great, Berlin had risen rapidly from a position of provincial obscurity to the rank of capital city in an important kingdom, and had gradually become the centre of the comparatively small intellectual life of Prussia, But the same events which had given it importance had contributed to its corruption. The manners of the Court in the time of Frederick, the open devotion of that monarch to the French " Illumination," the severance which his strong government caused be- tween the interests of the individual subject and the wider aims of political and civic life, had combined to Berlin Society. G9 give a quite peculiar character to the society of Berlin. It is scarcely possible to imagine a state of greater or more deeply seated social corruption than that presented by Berlin in the last two decades of the eighteenth century. The strong national feeling which had at least been fostered by the power of Frederick seemed to die out under the feeble and vacillating policy of his successor, and showed no signs of revival in any of the smaller states, where intense selfishness prevented any united action against a common enemy. The corroding influence of the narrow rationalism which had long been preached by Nicolai and his coadjutors Engel and Abbt, left nothing which could resist the impulse of the new romantic principle rapidly acquiring dominion over the younger and more impetuous spirits in Ger- many. Life, divested of all permanent or general interests, lends itself readily to the sway of mere ima- ginative passion; and in the gospel of Tieck and Fr. Schlegel, only that seemed good which commended itself to the sentimental longings of the individual, while social relations appeared as mere hindrances to the pure poetic development of human fantasy. 1 As might be anticipated from the subjection of thought and action to mere sentimental imaginative longings, the influence of women began to be the most prominent 1 The very essence of this mode of thought is expressed in the definition of the Romantic principle by F. Schlegel, in his ' Ge- sprach iiber die Poesie' (1800) : "That is romantic which expresses matter of sentiment (feeling) in fantastic form i.e., in a form deter- mined throughout by imagination only." The most thorough treat- ments of the Romantic school are those of Hettner, ' Die Romantische Schule ' (1850) ; Brandes, ' Hauptstrb'mungen der Literatur des 19ten Jahrhunderts, ' Bd. II. (1873); Haym, 'Die Romantische Schule' (1870). 70 Fichte. feature in society. In Berlin, as in Weimar, the leaders and directors of the new romantic school were in truth the women who stood in such close and ambiguous relation to the better-known men of letters. Henrietta Herz, Dorothea Veit, and Karoline Schelling, were the most potent factors in the disturbed chaotic movements of the literature of the time ; and the dismal quarrellings and bickerings of men like Schlegel, Schleiermacher, and Schelling, can only be understood when their relations to these leaders are taken into account. Thus, when Fichte entered Berlin society, there ap- peared, as the two most important currents of thinking, the old rationalistic tendency, with at least a substratum of solid political feeling, represented by Mcolai, and the new romantic literature, of which the manifesto had just been made in Schlegel's 'Lucinde.' At first, and naturally, he was attracted towards the party with whom for some time he had been in sympathy, and whose principles had at least a superficial resemblance to the main ideas of his philosophical system ; but it was not long* before the radical difference in their views made itself apparent. In the first glow of friendship he yielded ready assent to the plan suggested by F. Schlegel of taking up residence with him, and of calling to their community A. W. Schlegel and Schelling. But it soon became evident that such a plan was impracti- cable, partly because Fichte's strong ethical personality was in itself repulsive to the Schlegels, partly becaiise of the open antipathy between Dorothea Veit and the wife of A. "W. Schlegel, the celebrated Karoline, married, after her divorce from Schlegel, to Schelling. The pro- posed journal for literary criticism proved equally im- Berlin Society. 71 practicable. Schelling was now beginning to cast him- self loose from the Fichtean philosophy, and projected a journal of his own. The Schlegels, who had quarrelled bitterly with the 'AUgemeine Literaturzeitung,' had already started the 'Athenaum,' and manifestly found themselves less and less in harmony with Fichte, whom they pronounced wanting in poetry and imagination. Schleiermacher, finally, who had for Fichte a deep dis- like, partly from personal, partly from philosophical dif- ference, reviewed the ' Bestimmung des Menschen,' which appeared towards the close of 1799, in a bitter and contemptuous manner, Gradually Fichte withdrew from the society into which he had at first been cast, and associated himself more closely with men like Bern- hardi, the philologist; with Zeune, lecturer at one of the gymnasia in Berlin, a man excellently skilled in modern languages; with Huf eland, the Court physician, whom he had known at Jena ; and with Fessler, the leader of the Freemason movement, which was then attracting atten- tion in Germany. Ifor was he without more powerful patrons. "With Beyme, Struensee, and Von Altenstein he was on terms of friendship, and through the good offices of the first named he obtained full permission to exercise his activity as a lecturer in Berlin. The development of his philosophic views during the same period made more clear and definite the funda- mental differences which separated him from the Boman- tic school, and from their speculative ally Schelling. For although the stress laid in the early expositions of the ' Wissenschaftslehre ' upon the "Ego" or self-con- sciousness as the ultimate reality in cognition and in action might appear to indicate an agreement between 72 Fichte. Fichte's doctrines and those of his quondam associates, yet it must not be forgotten that for Fichte, as for Kant and for Hegel, the unity of thought was never the indi- vidual with his empirical personal aims. It is true that upon the relation between self-consciousness, which is the essence of the thinking subject, and the wider sphere of reality, little had been said in the ' Wissenschaf tslehre ' itself, but the problem was touched implicitly in the ' Sittenlehre,' and came to the foreground in the religious controversy preceding the expulsion from Jena. Fichte's attention seems now to have been turned entirely upon those general elements in human thought and action hitherto allowed to remain in obscurity in his theory ; and while in his popular and published writings he gave forth the results of his speculation in the form of more or less completed doctrines of morality, theoretical politics, history, and religion, the speculative method by which these were attained, and the connection of them with the earlier treatment of the 'Wissenschaf tslehre,' were expounded in repeated courses of lectures. The notes of many of these lectures have been published by his son, 1 and at least one completed exposition of the new mode of contemplating the problems of philosophy, never published, but dating from the period immediately after the flight to Berlin, has been included in the com- pleted edition of his works. 2 The inner connection of these writings with the prior stage of Fichte's public philosophical activity will be discussed at a later point ; meantime the external history of his labours must be noted. 1 In the ' Nachgelassene Werke,' 3 vols. , 1834. - 'DarstellungderWissenschaftslehre'C Werke,' vol. ii. pp. 1-163). The ' Vocation of Man! 73 The 'Bestimmung des Menschen ' ('Vocation of Man'), published in the early part of 1800, gave great offence to the Schlegels and to Schelling by the deeply relig- ious tone which prevailed throughout the closing and crowning portion of it. Schleiermacher, as has just been said, wrote a bitterly sarcastic review, and could hardly find words strong enough to express his detestation of it. The truth is that Schleiermacher never advanced, philosophically, beyond Spinozism, the principles of which are only disguised under the mystically pious tone of feeling on which all his speculation rested. Xow the very aim of the ' Bestimmung des Menschen ' is to show that Spinoza's position, that of pure natural- ism, is transcended in ethical idealism ; and that between the views of man as the mere product and flower of nature, and of nature as but a form in which infinite intelligence makes itself manifest in finite consciousness, the opposition is radical The same opposition, it is plain, must exist between idealism as conceived by Fichte and the Natur-pliilosopMe to which Schelling was now advancing. For in the latter, while in words Reason is made the supreme unity out of which all Hows, in reality Mature is regarded as an independent fact, endowed with formative powers, and giving rise to human consciousness as we know it. The ultimate Reason, as mere Neutrum or identity of Real and Ideal, can have specific character only when viewed in relation to the two elements Avhich dissolve themselves into it If, of these two elements, nature be conceived as the jrritis, and thought as but a higher form of natural forces, then, as Fichte would have said, the ultimate Being is not living thought, but dead nature. A further opposi- 74 Ficlite. tion between the two thinkers arose from the difference of their views regarding the mode of treating natural or empirical knowledge. From Kant, Fichte had learned the lesson which he never forgot, that a priori construc- tions of nature are philosophically worthless. To him, therefore, the exercises of Schelling's "genial imagin- ation," "by means of which nature was interpreted with- out experiment or observation, appeared to be absolute Mysticism, mere conceits of chance. 1 With these elements of speculative difference, person- al harmony was not likely to continue. The correspon- dence between the two thinkers during the years 1800 to 1802 accompanied as it was by the publication of various writings, in which Schelling not only brought forward his new views, but called attention to their advance upon the Fichtean position exhibits a gradual cooling of friendship, culminating in the sharpest accusa- tions of mutual misunderstanding. Nor did the con- troversy end with the close of their correspondence. In the lectures of 1804, ' On the Characteristics of the Present Age/ Fichte, without naming Schelling, deduces or interprets philosophically Seliwdrmerei and Natur- philosophie as necessary phenomena of a corrupt and unthinking age; while Schelling not only criticised in an aggressively personal tone the Erlangen lectures, to be mentioned presently, ' On the Vocation of the Scholar,' but in 1806 summed up all his enmity against his former friend in the biting ' Exposition of the True Eolation between Natur-pliilosopMe and the Amended 1 See generally for Fiehte's view regarding the Natur-philosophie of Schelliug, the 8th lecture of the ' Characteristics of the Present Age' ('Werke/ vol. vii. pp. 111-127). Literary Activity. 75 Fichtean Theory.' Fichte's final word remained unpub- lished during his life, but it now appears in his Col- lected Works in the tract written in 1806, and entitled ' Notice regarding the Idea of "Wissenschaf tslehre, and of its Fortunes up to the Present Time.' 1 Here, without any hesitation, he characterises Schelling as "one of the most muddled heads that the general muddle of the age has produced," as " an utterly incompetent and bungling sophist," and subjects two of his writings, the 'Darstellung meines Systems' and the 'Philosophic und Eeligion,' to the most unsparing criticism. "With Schleiermacher there had been no open breach of friendship. It is curious that Fichte does not appear to have read the hostile and continued criticism of his views which runs through the ' Critique of the Theories of Morals ' 2 Had he done so, it would certainly not have passed without notice. But with another of his former allies he was presently compelled to break. Eein- hold, who never seemed capable of maintaining a posi- tion in philosophy except by attaching himself to some more vigorous thinker, had suffered his grasp of Fichte to slacken, and had been drawn towards a new luminary, Bardili of Stuttgard, whose 'Grundriss der ersten Logik' had appeared in 1800. Of this work, recommended to him in the warmest manner by Eeinhold, Fichte wrote a sharp review in the Erlangen ' Literaturzeitung,' the tone of which contrasted strongly with the eulogy pronounced by Eeinhold in the Jena journal A "Letter to Professor Fichte" in the first number of Eeinhold's 'Beytrage' (1801) was foUowed by Fichte's 1 ' Werke,' vol. viii. pp. 361-407. 8 'Grundlinien einer Kritik der bisherigen Sittenlehre ' (1803). 76 Fichte. "Reply," 1 a powerful piece of writing, valuable for the light it throws upon the ' Wissenschaftslehre,' but con- clusive as regards the friendship between the corre- spondents. Not content with philosophical contention, Fichte turned upon the old opponent of all speculation, F. Nicolai, and annihilated him in the ' Life and Singular Opinions of Mcolai.' 2 All Nicolai's forms of criticism, his likes and dislikes, his laborious satire, are deduced with logical rigour from the first principle of his nature, that all human knowledge was summed up and compre- hended in him, that what he did not understand was eo facto unintelligible and absurd, and that the mere expression of his adverse opinion was sufficient to put all opponents to rout. It is a bitter satire, not alto- gether undeserved, but doing less than justice to merits which Nlcolai undoubtedly possessed. The early years of residence at Berlin were unusually productive. In addition to lectures and to the writings already noted, we have during this period the work which in Fichte's own opinion was the most careful and most maturely considered of all his productions, 'The Exclusive Commercial State.' 3 This remarkable work is but little known, and yet it is by far the most com- plete exposition of theoretical socialism in modern literature. By an exclusive commercial state, Fichte understands a union of citizens under common laws, in which no international trade is permitted. Of the 1 'Werke,' vol. ii. pp. 504-534. 2 ' Nicolai's Leben und sonderbare Meinungen,' 1801. 3 'Der geschlossene Handels-staat ' (1800) : 'Werke,' vol. iii. pp. 386-513. Economics. 77 three books into which the work is divided, the first traces the principles of such a state ; the second com- pares them with the actual phenomena presented by communities permitting international exchange ; the third considers the steps by which a state as now organ- ised may make itself exclusive. The fundamental polit- ical doctrines are deduced from a peculiar view regard- ing property. The right of property, Fichte thinks, does not extend over things, but only over modes of action. The state, therefore, has to assign to each of its members the sphere within which his free activity may be manifested. Hence it is requisite that the state should determine the distribiition of the citizens into the three grand classes of producers of raw materials, manufactur- ers, and merchants; should regulate the scale of production and consumption ; should fix the natural ratios of value in accordance with the principle that the intrinsic worth of a thing is the amount of its life-supporting property ; and should issue a money of its own which could be contracted and expanded in amount so as to cause no detriment by fluctuations of prices. In the second book, where the actual economic conditions of communities are considered, the ruling ideas are those so commonly met with in socialist writings : that in trade left to its natural course one party benefits at the expense of another ; that the use of money confers a new and bane- ful power on some classes of society ; and that among interchanging countries, the poorer, to its certain loss and harm, will gradually be drained of its metallic wealth. In the third book, the way towards the exclusive state is shown to be the rejection of the use of metallic cur- rency, and the adoption of a circulating medium which 78 Fichte. shall be valid only within the community itself. From this would naturally follow the restriction of the state to its own resources and the fostering of its own industries. Fichte has evidently no doubt regarding the power of the state to carry on these elaborate regulative functions : he never seems to have contemplated any possible dis- turbance of the balance between production and con- sumption, nor to have considered the natural influences which determine the course and forms of industry. The ' Exclusive Commercial State ' is the best illustration of his total neglect of experience and want of power to bring his abstract notions into connection with concrete historical reality. The lectures at Berlin continued to gain in popularity and in influence. The most eminent citizens and states- men were to be found in attendance on them, and it was but natural that the idea should occur to reinstate Fichte in some position as academical lecturer. In 1804 he was invited by the Eussian Government to the newly organised university at Charkow j in the same year he was offered a chair at the Bavarian university of Land- shut. The first invitation he declined, because he felt that the foreign surroundings would diminish his influ- ence and activity; the second he likewise refused, rather from dread of the strong ecclesiastical feeling in Bavaria than from disinclination to the university there. Towards the close of the same year, however, Beyme procured for him an offer, which he gladly accepted, of the Chair of Philosophy at Erlangen, under condition that he should be required to lecture during summer only, and might reside at Berlin during the winter months. In May 1805 he opened his course at Erlangen, Lectures at Erlangen. 79 was received with distinction by his colleagues, and here delivered to the whole body of students the lectures on the ' Nature of the Scholar,' which were published in the ensuing year. 1 Almost simultaneously there appeared the lectures delivered at Berlin in the winter of 1804-5, ' On the Characteristics of the Present Age,' and those delivered in the winter of 1805-6, 'The Way towards the Blessed Life, or Doctrine of Keligion.' 2 The three sets of lectures form a completed whole : the first part, the ' Characteristics,' analysing the present state of cul- ture and thought ; the second, ' The Nature of the Scholar,' indicating the spirit in which the attempt to rise to a higher stage should be made ; the third, sketch- ing in bold outlines the completed reconciliation of life and thought in religion. In them the results of Fichte's speculation are presented in popular form, and they are certainly incomparable specimens of the union of vig- orous philosophical thought and masterly skill in expo- sition. The fundamental idea of these works, expressed in various forms, has been made familiar to English readers through the teaching of England's greatest modem moralist The guiding principle of all Carlyle's ethical work is the principle of Fichte's speculation, that the world of experience is but the appearance or vesture of the divine idea or life ; that in this divine life lie the springs of true poetry, of true science, and of true reli- gion ; and that he only has true life whose spirit is in- terpenetrated with the realities transceuding empirical 1 ' Werke,' vol. vi. pp. 347-448. They have been translated by Dr W. Smith. 2 The " Grtmdziige," in 'Werke,' vol.vii. pp. 1-256 ; the "Amvei- sung," Werke,' vol. v. pp. 397-580. Both in English by Dr Smith. 80 Fichte. facts, who is willing to resign his own personality in the service of humanity, and who strives incessantly to work out the ideal that gives nobility and grandeur to human effort. 1 By slow degrees does humanity work out its aim, the perfect ordering of life according to Reason and with Freedom ; and the period of construction, in which the general Reason moulds and fashions the thoughts and practical efforts of mankind, is preceded by the de- structive period of individualist criticism. The charac- teristics of this destructive age, the principles of the Aufkldrung, are drawn by Fichte with a master-hand, and in the state of German thought and society he had before him the realisation of his sketch. The present age appeared to him, in its lack of devotion to general interests, in its cold individualism, mechanical statecraft, and selfish morality, the condition of completed sinful- ness. The call to the higher life, which he raised on philosophical grounds, was soon to become the passionate appeal of the patriot, who saw in the degradation of his country the effects of a false system of thought and ethical principle. 2. FALL AND REGENERATION OF PRUSSIA : THE BERLIN UNIVERSITY. The outbreak of the war between France and Prussia in 1806 had been preceded by events which showed all 1 Mere references to Fichte are numerous enough in Carlyle (see, e.g., 'On Heroes,' Lect. vi., the essays on the 'State of German Lit- erature,' and on 'Novalis'), but the full significance of the relation between them can become clear only when one compares the thought- ful essay entitled ' Characteristics,' and the ' Sartor Kesartus,' with Fichte's popular works above named, specially the ' Grundziige d. gegen. Zeitalters.' Fall of Prussia. 81 too clearly how deep was the disorder and corruption of the German national feeling. The selfish and vacillating policy of Prussia had rendered it possible for her to be the isolated object of Napoleon's hostility. The shame- ful Rheinbund, completed in July 1806, had placed the princes of Southern and Western Germany under the headship of France, and had separated them from the German empire. Even the shadowy bond which seemed to unite the German States had been dissolved by the Austrian emperor's renunciation of the Kaiserate, while the passive attitude of Prussia during the overthrow of Austria in 1805 had alienated the two great German Powers. 1 The declaration of war with France was hailed with joy in Prussia as the one evidence yet remaining of life and independence in the state. The great triumphs of the Prussian army in the past inspired a feeling of confidence which unfortunately had no s*ound basis. The Berlin circles waited eagerly for the news of victories which they were prepared to celebrate, and the announce- ment of the terrible calamities of Jena and Auerstadt came like thunder from a clear sky. The Prussian power at a single stroke was shattered. The army was driven into fragments, fortress after fortress fell without resist- ance into the hands of the conqueror, and Berlin was left without defence. Fichte, with his friend Hufeland, fled beyond the Oder to follow the fortunes of the de- 1 An admirable picture of German politics at this period is given in the anonymous pamphlet, 'Deutschland in seiner tiefen Erniedri- gung,' published in the summer of 1806, for the printing of which the unfortunate bookseller Palm, of Niirnberg, was shot by order of Na- poleon. The more extensive historical works bearing on the period, especially the lives of Stein by Pertz and Seeley, give more copious information. P. IV. F 82 Fichte. feated king, and to await the development of the struggle in East Prussia, where Russian aid could be counted on. His wife remained to protect the family and goods of the united households. At Stargard, where Fichte first halted, he found to his amusement a full-grown university in which his name and fame were absolutely unknown, and where it was necessary for him to inform his brother professors of the subject which he professed. At Konigsberg, where he took up residence from November 1806 till June 1807, he was received with more intelligent apprecia- tion, was nominated temporary professor, and delivered lectures, both publicly and in private, on the ' Wissen- schaftslehre.' Here, too, he worked diligently at the study of modern languages, which he had begun under Delbriick, and above all, at Pestalozzi's educational schemes, in whi- V':- MAR 5 1997 RECEIVED Education Library B 23ii7 A22f