■'■'-••, ■■■..■'■..-^''■-.»'>v-'r • ■ v; ' v'.:v i^'-^J^^^-s-'W^^^^i^' '■ '%■: '' i:^;-! 4M' - —V-*: * ii;^fH^ ^^-■f.^ '1 COMMENTARIES THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT ^ije Hatos of ISnglanti KELATIKG TO ®f)c ^ccuritD of tfje ^etson. « «. € € *J "tC «■ C « ( « « C * • t C « « C ■ fr «,- C "• t * c t COMMENTARIES ON THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT AND C6c itato!^ of d^nglantJ RELATING TO Cfie #rcunt|) of tj&c person. BY JAMES PATERSON, Esq., M.A., BARRISTER-AT-LA\V, SOMETIME COMMISSIONER FOR ENGLISH AND IRISH FISHERIES, ETC. IN TWO VOLUMES. VOL. I. MACMILLAN AND CO. 1877, {The Right of Translation and Reproduction is Reserzed.] LONDON : K. (MAY. SONS, ANn TAYLOR, PlilNTrRS, BRKAD STREET HILL, yUfiEN VICTOUIA STREET. JC SgS PS7c V. I PKEFACE. It is more than a century since Blackstone published his Commentaries on the Laws of England, which were origin- ally lectures delivered to students at Oxford. His object was to make the methodical study of those laws part of a university education. He had secured an audience of inquiring minds, full of fresh aspirations, but only dimly conscious of some vague influence by which the business j%g of the world was guided, and more eager than certain how 2 best to share that influence. Most of his audience were w ... ^ destined to be legislators, diplomatists, warriors, priests, ^^ heirs of great possessions, and a few were destined to the < practice of the legal profession. But beyond that audience M he sought to reach a still larger class of citizens, who n^ were already engrossed with other pursuits — whether 2 acting in various capacities as jurors, magistrates, and ^ oflicials, or as the leading artificers of that wealtli, with ^ the pursuit of which human life is so busy. This wider g circle must then, as now, have often been haunted with an unsatisfied desire to know more about the laws all were ^ bound to obey, than could be acquired in any ordinary ij avocations. Though business is itself a legal education, yet it is seldom found to be sufficiently broad and deep to satisfy the wider scrutiny and insight of practical minds, always curious to probe the secrets of this vital essential ^ >* «^ >< ii § >! r vi PREFACE. knowledge. For the whole of these constituents Black- stone endeavoured to clothe a theme, formerly dry and repulsive, with various learning, picturesque incidents, and apposite illustrations — solving doubts and laigely grati- fying the intelligent curiosity of every member of the community who aspired to influence his fellow-men. How well Blackstone succeeded in his enterprise, his contemporaries and successors confessed and know.^ The generations of Englishmen since his day have been in- debted to him for nearly all they have learnt of the ^ C. J. Fox : " Blackstone's style of English is the very best among our modern writers .... His purity of style I particularly admire. He was distinguished as much for simplicity and strengih as any writer in the English language. He was perfectly free from all Gallicisms and ridiculous affectations, for which so many of our modern authors are so remarkable. Upon this ground, therefore, I esteem Judge Blackstone ; but as a constitutional writer he is by no means an object of my esteem."— Trover's Fox, 512 ; 6 Pari. Deb. 314, 814. Sir W. Jones : " Blackstone's Commentaries are the most correct and beautiful outline that ever was exhibited of any human science ; but they alone will no more form a lawyer than a general map of the world will make a geographer." — Jones, Bailments, p. 4. Gibbon : " Blackstone's Commentaries may be considered as a natural system of the English jurisprudence digested into a natural raethc^ and cleared of the pedantry, the obscurity, and suiierfluities, which rendered it the unknown horror of all men of taste." — 5 Gibbon, Misc. W. 545. Lord Mansfield, C. J : " In Blackstone's Commentaries you will find analytical reasoning diif used in a pleasing and perspicuous style." — HolUduy's Mansfield, 89. Lord Avon more, C. J : " He it was, who first gave to the law the air of a science. He found it a skeleton and he clothed it with Ufc, colour, and complexion. He embraced the cold statue, and by his touch it grew into health, vigour, and beauty." — Pldllips's Curran, 74. Bentham (1776) : " Correct, elegant, unembarrassed, ornamented, Blackstone's style is such as could scarce fail to recommend a work Htill more vicious in point of matter to the multitude of his readers. lie it is, in short, wlio, first of all institutional writers, has taught PREFACE. vii wisdom of that civil polity and well balanced system of laws which he professed to expound. And even those of his own profession, v;ho commenced their studies under the auspices of his teaching, and afterwards required to pursue their course into further and better particulars, have seldom outgrown the authority and deference which his name has gathered year by year as its natural tribute. He discoursed on doctrines, harsh and crabbed as they were, with the luminous force, spirit, and elegance of Addison, and there was nothing he touched, which he jurisprudence to speak the language of the scholar and the gentle- man ; put a pohsh upon that rugged science ; cleansed her from the dust and cobwebs of the office ; and if he has not enriched her with that precision which is drawn only from the sterling treasury of the science, has decked her out, however, to advantage from the toilet of classical erudition ; enlivened her with metaphors and allusions, and sent her abroad in some measure to instruct and in still greater measure to entertain the most miscellaneous and even the most fas- tidious societies. The merit, to which as much, perhaps, as to any, the work stands indebted for its reputation is the enchanting harmony of its numbers, a kind of merit that of itself is suthcicnt to give a certain degree of celebrity to a work devoid of every other. So much is man governed by the ear." — Frag, on Gov. Story J. : " Blackstone's Commentaries are but a compilation of the laws of England drawn from authentic sources, open to the whole profession, and yet in the highest sense might be deemed an original work, since never before were the same materials so admirably com- bined and exquisitely wrought out with a judgment, skill, and taste absolutel}^ unrivalled." — Gray v Russell, 1 Story, 17. Watkins : " The intention of that ingenious writer (Blackstone) was to give a comprehensive outline, and when we consider the multiplicity of doctrine which he embraced, the civil, the criminal, the theoretical and practical branches of the law, we must confess the hand of a master. But in the minutiae he is very frequentl}' inaccurate." — Watlc. Convey. Introd. 28. Mackintosh : " Blackstone was a great master of classical and harmonious composition, but a feeble reasoner and a confused thinker, whose writings are not exempt from the charge of slavishness. . . . Bentham, in his Fragment on Government, wasted extraordinary viii PREFACE. did not adorn. His fame has in no respect diminished after the lapse of a hundred years ; nor is there any apprehension that, notwithstanding one or two resolute detractors, he will ever cease to be an English classic. Some of his political doctrines, indeed, have been described as scarcely acceptable even in his own age. If defects might be suggested, the worst seems to be, that his tone too generally was that of one who forgot the maxim, that men are not made for laws, but laws for men ; and hence, power in pointing out flaws and patches in the robe occasionally stolen from the philosophical schools, which hung loosely and not unbe- comingly on the elegant commentator." — Mackint. Eth. Phil. sect. 6. Lord Ellenborough, C. J. : "Judge Blackstone had produced the most elegant and classical work upon the driest subject in the lan- guage ; by giving interest to the systematic knowledge of tlie law he had allured the student ; and by the spirit and eloquence with which he set forth the code of England he had advanced her beyond calculation in the respect of other countries. He made the law of England studied in other countries, and thus threw a dignity round the wisdom of his own. I must be his grateful eulogist, for to him I was indebted for an easy and pleasant introduction into the thorny science of the law."— fi. of Lords, 1812 ; 23 Pari Deb. 1083. Austin : " Blackstone's method is a slavish and blundering copy of Hale's rude and compendious model. Neither in the general con- ception nor in the detail of his book is there a single particle of original and discriminating i\\o\ig\\i.'"— Outlines, p. 63. Lord Campbell says, " Blackstone, after Bacon, was the first practising barrister at the English bar, who in writing paid the slightest attention to the selection or collocation of words." — 2 Camp. G. J. 5GG. In other countries " Alciati was the first who taught the lawyers to write with purity and elegance, and though the professors of the old school clamoured against him and drove him from one university to another, he soon stood not alone in scattering the flowers of polite literature over the thorny tracks of jurisprudence." — 1 Hallam, Lit. Hist. 418. "Cujacius, hke Alciati, substituted a general erudition for scholastic sul)tleties, and rendered the science more intelligible and attractive. When Cujacius' name was men- tioned in the public schools of Germany, every one took off his hat." —2 Hallam, Lit. Hist. 1G7, 169. PREFACE. ix he too lightly assumed to impress upon his fellow-country- men, that they could never be too grateful for the excel- lence of tliose laws that had been found for them. Another defect which may be suggested is, that owing to his dis- courses being orally delivered, and certain topics lequiring to be treated within a limited space of time, the relative importance of each was ill adjusted, and even his outlines of most vital doctrines were too meagre to be practically useful. And lastly, the method and arrangement were little calculated to satisfy the understandings of those, who for the first time explored so intricate a branch of know- ledge — overladen at all times with its oppressive details. This last defect, indeed, was not apparent to his con- temporaries, for they seem to have been most of all impressed by the lucid order in which he arranged his materials. This, however, tends rather to show, that the spell of the magician's style was over all who came near liim, so that they scarcely had time to mark a blemish or hesitate a dislike, while he opened page after page of a book, so long sealed from their eyes, and written in a tongue so unfamiliar. But, apart from any inherent defects of Blackstone's treatment and method, it is obvious that during the century that has elapsed since his work was published hundreds of volumes of statutes, reports, and disquisitions have been produced, modifying, reversing, or abandoning many false positions ^ once thought unassailable. And during the same period all European nations have lived ages. Communities, princedoms, powers, and dominions have disappeared and reappeared under new names or new ^ It may be said of the Law as was said of Truth, that " in retiring from her outposts she has become more unassailable in her citadel." —2 Hallam, Lit. Hist. 127. PREFACE. combinatious. Organic changes have developed noiselessly in a night. All forms of government, constitutions, systems of laws, have more or less been put on their trial, and tested by the inexorable logic of first principles. Every timber of the vessel has felt the strain. Whatever and wherever a fault existed, the fault has been seen and felt, and in not a few instances has been amended. The utilitarian has been abroad, and has marked many a weak point in the armour ; and instead of invoking the traditions of Greek or Eoman, ancient or mediaeval, civilisations to help him, has found a ruder questioning all sufficient, and a convenient touchstone in every market place and vestry. A friendly echo now follows this investigator everywhere. It can scarcely fail to be apparent, that explanations of processes, methods, and axioms, which passed current with the learned and wise a century ago, can scarcely now claim the plaudits of our wider and more critical audience. The legislature itself, which is the vigilant sentinel to J guard against the advances of corruption and revolution, contains new representatives commissioned by multitudes I who were then without the pale ; powers and voices, not then dreamt of, now claim an undisputed hearing. New points of departure are suggested in many a settled routine, and still an interminable procession of amendments fills up the vista of the future. And though panting time toils after these in vain, yet is the hope of higher and still higher and juster laws not one jot abated. Civilisation ^ may be incapable of definition, yet it plainly involves a consciousness, that advancement has already been made from worse to better, and that from eacli ' GuizoT says, the idea of progress or development is the funda- mental idea in the word "civilisation." — Civ. Europ. lect. 1. PREFACE. xi vantage ground gained it wonld be degrading and impious to retreat. The Liberty of the Subject is, in England, a sounding phrase ^ and a watchword with which to conjure the multi- tude. It represents an "unknown quantity" of latent tire, which kindles with the slightest breath, which rouses a spirit not to be subdued, and is as contagious as it is irrepressible. Like the sacred fire watched by the Vestal virgins, it has now burned for centuries, and has never — or if ever, then for a short time only — been extinguished. It lives in many a golden line of Magna Charta, though antiquated details sometimes obscure it; and the Petition of Right, the Habeas Corpus Act, the Bill of Rights, Trial by Jury, the Law and Practice of Parliament, the Liberty of the Press and Local Self-government, breathe nothing else. Whether used in the senate and the courts, or shouted by the mob, this household phrase seldom fails to call up a crowd of noble associations. The masses of the com- munity can feel it, though they cannot be sure that they can explain it.^ It is to them an instinct and a manly prerogative, rather than a code. They know it as a healthy light to illumine their daily life ; yet it requires the pris- matic vision, of the Lawyer to trace, where and how the primary colours are blended and transfused. For him it must in the end be always reserved to show, how these ' Burke says, " Grand swelling sentiments of liberty warm tho heart and liberalise the mind." — Fr. Rev. 2 Adam Smith said, " The common people of England, so jealous of tlieir liberty, like the common people of most other countries, never riglitly understand wherein it consists." — Wealth of Nat. b. i. c. 10. " The French, Swiss, and German peasants have a fair know- ledge of law. But in Great Britain and Ireland the same classes believe, that such knowledge is as exclusively professional as is the knowledge of anatomy." — Maine's Village Com. 60. xii PREFACE. elementary colours are even more attractive than the shining ray. To rescue the time honoured and healthy public cry of the " Liberty of the Subject " from the vague and rambling thoughts that too often accompany it in the street, the market, and the senate, and reduce it to a language and method which will make the citizens of all countries more akin, may be a difficult, but it can scarcely be an impos- sible task. The genius of the age is educational. It is no longer deemed a merit in courts of justice to register their decrees, yet to conceal their reasons. It is no longer deemed masterly statecraft to mask the motive powers and springs of legislation and government in secret fast- nesses, and only disclose their existence by occasional volleys of thunder. With a free press and an inviolable senate, which think aloud for all the constituent forces in the nation, every intelligent citizen breathes an atmosphere of criticism and discussion, and goes along with each difficult conjuncture, as if he felt and enjoyed being a part of the complex mechanism. He lives and moves in the general system. There being nothing to conceal, and there being nothing but natural growth and development desired in all directions, it is now more than ever a necessity, that he should have visibly and tangibly familiar to him the innermost workings and free play of our national institutions in all their phases. It must, however, be con- fessed, that the law is a part of our daily life, which still suffers too much dispraise and eclipse in the public esteem. Notwithstanding the translucid medium, under which Blackstone revealed its interior works, the cultivated intelligence of the crowd still marks unseemly rust and cobwebs defiling the movements ; and even the friendly PREFACE. xiii eye darkens as the finger of scorn resolutely points here and there. The Liberty of the Subject has a t-wofold meaning. That it indicates the line, beyond which the crown cannot lawfully interfere with the person or property of the sub- ject, is naturally the first thought that occurs to all. Law, as Lechmere observed,^ is the common measure of the power of the crown, and of the obedience of the subject. , But in its wider and higher sense, the liberty of the sub- ( ject is not and cannot be confined to the mutual relations between the crown and each individual : it alaouincludes tjie relations between subject and subject. When the individual is imprisoned or stripped of his property by an unlawful authority, whether that authority purports to be exercised by the crown and its servants or by a fellow- citizen, the liberty of the subject is equally invaded, though the outrage may be resented in the one case more warmly than in the other. Hence it is, that when in- telligent foreigners, and others interested, ask how and whence the chief elements of this magic phrase have been derived, it is by no means easy to satisfy the inquiring mind. To trace the various situations and proceedings of social life, where liberty is most conspicuous, and collect its essence and epitome, requires a wide excursion over most of the departments of the law. In order to exhaust the account, scarcely one of its provinces can be safely neglected. Yet while some of these, which lie closer, must be minutely examined, others may be surveyed from a distance. It is thus only that the whole prospect, with its light and shadow, can be made to fill the mind's eye, and to impress its full significance upon the memory. 1 Sacheverell's Trial, J 5 St. Tr. Gl. xiv PREFACE. While an exhaustive account of the Liberty of the Subject in England thus really resolves itself into an exposition of the law, or at least a survey of all its leading landmarks, the difficulty of rendering that account satisfactory is at once apparent ; and at the same time the reason is dis- closed, why so few intelligent citizens can go deeply into it, and why so vague an impression is often left on the inquirer by the explanations that are offered. It scarcely, however, accounts for the want of any systematic attempt having yet been made to treat this subject with the fulness and practical detail naturally to be expected, considering the ardent desire that must always exist to know more of it, not only in Great Britain, but in Greater Britain, and in foreign countries, where this crowning glory — the reputed end and aim of the English constitution — has acquired so just and enviable a renown. The author has here attempted to meet this want and achieve a difficult task. In his view the central idea involved in the Enalish Liberty of the Subject becomes, on a complete analysis, the polar axis on which all the municipal laws revolve, and its various evolutions suggest a more true and rational division of those liiws, than has hitherto been current. And the adoption of a more natural distribution and ar- rangement of the materials is not only valuable in itself, but it will confer all the greater advantage, if, as the author hopes and expects, the citizens of all other countries will be thereby provided with a ready means of comparison between their own laws and institutions, and those with which England has long found good reason to be well pleased.^ ' De Tocqueville : " Look at Enj^land, wliose administrative laws still at the present day appear so much more complicated, more anomalous, more irregular than those of France ! Yet is there a PREFACE. XV This book is thus a treatise on the laws of Eimland. following, however, an arrangement entirely new, the main object being to illustrate the leading principles and prac- tices which intelligent citizens eagerly search for at all times in those laws. With a key to the details, all can more easily estimate the measure of civilisation that has been reached in a country, long envied for its successful avoid- ance of violent revolutions — where the equilibrium of liberty has never been lost during any entire generation — and where, year by year, it gains a stability, the secret of which must ever be a study for all nations and com- munities.^ country in Europe, where the national wealth is greater, where pri- vate property is more extended, varied, and secure, or where societj'- is more stable and more rich ? This is not caused by the excellence of any laws in particular, but by the spirit which pervades the whole legislation of England. The imperfection of certain organs matters nothing, because the whole is instinct with life." — Society in France (tr. by Reeve), b. ii. c. 16. Again the same author says : " There is not a country in the world in which, in the daj's of Blackstone, the great ends of justice were more completely attained than in England, that is to say, no country in which every man, whatever his condition of life— whether he appeared in court as a common individual or a prince — was more sure of being heard, or found in the tribunals of his country better guaranties for the defence of his property, his liberty, and his life." — Ibid, note Ixvii. ' Montesquieu : " The political liberty of the subject is a tran- quillity of mind arising from the opinion each person has of his own safety. In order to have this liberty, it is requisite that the govern- ment be so constituted, that one man need not be afraid of another, .... It is not my business to examine whether the English actually enjoy this liberty or not. It is sufficient for my purpose to observe, that it is established by their laws : and I inquire no further. Neither do I pretend by this to undervalue other governments, nor to say that this extreme political libevt3' ought to give uneasiness to those who have only a moderate share of it. How should I have such a design — I who think that even the excess of reason is not always xvi PREFACE. All intelligent citizens can appreciate and even admire the law in most of its details, when these are transacted, one by one, in some signal events of the day; and on such occasions the interest never flags. But in attempting to follow any systematic exposition of it, they encounter at the threshold so many arbitrary distinctions — a method so unreal and incongruous to the business of life — details, exceptions, qualifications, so multifarious and bewildering, that the statesman, the magistrate, the juror, the merchant, and the student alike suffer painful hesitations, and shudders of aversion. The fascination of Blackstone's style carried the general reader through many obstacles with surprising ease, in spite of a method which was indeed the common inheritance of the ages, but which never can commend itself to any but lawyers, and even to them only after familiarity has made it superfluous, and the love of precedent has blinded their eyes to its origin. The author has attempted to take the reader over the same ground by a route altogether different, and always carrying the lamp of the liberty of the subject into every recess desirable, and that mankind generally find their account better in mediums than in extremes." — Spirit of Laws, h xi. c. 6. Lord Keeper Finch on the openin.f^ of the Long Parliament in 1640, after panegyrising the English constitution, said : " It is glorious in tlie whole frame ; worth your looking upon long, and worth your consideration in every part." — 2 Pari. Hist. 631. Milton says, " No civil government hath been known — no, not the Spartan, not the Roman, though both for this respect so much praised by the wise Polybius — more divinely and harmoniously tuned, more equally' balanced, as it were, by the hand and scale of justice, than is the commonwealth of England, where under a free and un- tutored monarch, the noblest, worthiest, and most prudent men, with full approbation and suffrage of the people, have in their power the supreme and final determination of the highest affairs." — Ref. inEng. Fox said, " If a stranger wished to learn the constitution of Great Britain, he would seek for it in its laws." — 29 Pari. Hist. 1378. PREFACE. xvii examining each leading detail by tlie light it supplies, and trying, if possible, to mark at each turn, where tradition ends and reason begins^ — " where freedom broadens slowly down from precedent to precedent." The present two volumes contain a general introduction to the subject of Law, discussing the current definitions and divisions, as well as subjecting the details to a more natural method than has hitherto been followed. And that Division of the Substantive Law, entituled the Security of the Person, is exhibited in complete detail, showing how the law guards personal freedom at every point, and what are the leading changes through which that law has passed. Here will be shown not only all that the law can do to protect the person against every wrongful interference, but also conversely the worst that can be done to the persons of those who occasion such interference — the best and the worst that can happen to the body under the law of England, as that law has been developed up to the present time. J. P. Goldsmith Building, Tejjple, March, 1877. f 1 Any English writer behoves to bear in mind what foreigners are apt to say of him : " Whoever attentively considers the English turn of mind will be struck by a fact of a twofold nature : on one side good sense and practical ability ; on the other, the absence of general ideas and elevation of mind on purely theoretical questions. Whether we turn to works on history or jurisprudence, or any other subject, we rarely find that the great, the fundamental cause of things has been investigated."— G^wzsoi;, Eur. Civ. lect. 14. VOL. I. I CONCISE OUTLINE OF SUBJECTS. THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT. Introd. — Chap. I. discussion of the current definitions and DIVISIONS OF THE LAW. — Municipal Law — Modes of treating Law — Definitions of Law Ancient and Modern — A New Definition — Divisions of Law, Ancient and Modern — A New Tenfold Division of Law. Introd. — Chap. II. discussion of other divisions, terms, and PHRASES used IN THE LAW.- — Liberty of the Subject — Civil Liberty — Origin of Governuient — Social Contract — Constitutional Law — Public and Private Law— Civil and Criminal Law — Law of Nations — Law of Nature — Divine Law — Feudal Law — Civil Law — Canon Law — Common and Statute Law — Judge-made Law — Fictions — Precedents — Knowledge of Law — Law and Equity — Codification — Meaning of Eight, Duty, Obligation, Wrong, Tort, Crime, P"'elony, &c. THE SECURITY OF THE PERSON. Chap. I. protection of the body against threats and appre- hended injuries. — Surety of the Peace and Good Behaviour — Intimidation and Molestation — Trade Union — Threatening Letters — Challenge to Fight— Tumultuous Assemblies — lliot — Affray. Chap. II. protection of the body against actual injury by the negligence of others. — Negligence in Carrying, Driving- — Keeping of Premises, of Vicious Animals — Negligence of Servants. Chap. III. protection of the body against actual intended in- juries but not malicious. — Assault and Battery — Justifiable Assaults — Self-defence — Remedies Civil and Criminal. Chap. IV. protection of the body against malicious, wilful, and negligent acts which kill or wound. — Murder— Man- slaughter — Homicide — Misadventure — Fighting — Poisoning- Self-defence — Suicide — Coroner— Attempts to murder — Maiming and Wounding. Chap. V. restrictions owing to compulsory acts and duties strictly personal. — Sumptuary Laws — Compulsory Services, &c. — Name, Dress, Food, Armour — Service as Soldier, Sailor — En- hstment, Impressment — Compulsory Duties and Ofiices of Juror, Witness, Sheriff, Municipal Officer, Churchwarden, Overseer Constable, Surveyor of Highways— Slavery. I 2 XX CONCISE OUTLINE OF SUBJECTS. VOLUME II. ClUP. VI. PROTEOTION OF THE BODY AGAINST WANT AND DESTITUTION. — The Poor-laws — Vagrants — Begging — Rating of Property — Removal and Settlement of Paupers. Chap. VII. temporary arrest and imprisonment other than on FINAL JUDGMENT OR SENTENCE. — Arrest for Debt — Ne exeat Regno — Arrest for Crime — Bail — Ancient Trial by Ordeal, Battle, Wager of Law — Turture — Peine forte et (/wre^False Imprison- ment — Malicious Prosecution — Writ of Habeas Corjms. Chap. VIII. punishment of the body by death or pains on final JUDGMENT AND SENTENCE. — Imprisonm ent for Debt — Excommuni- cation—Imprisonment for Crime, for Penal Offences, for Breach of Contract, for Breach of Privilege of Parliament, for Contempt of Court — Prisoners and Treatment — Tickets of Leave — Banish- ment — Penal Ser\'itude — Solitary Confinement — Hard Labour — Punishment by Whipping, Branding, Mutilation, Pillory, Stocks — Capital Punishment and its Varieties — -Benefit of Clergy — Expediency of Capital Punishments. Chap. IX. variations in foregoing rights and liabilities caused by age. — Infancy — Abortion — Exposure of Infants — Infanticide — Concealment of Birth — Ill-treatment and Overworking of Children — Maintenance and Starving of Children — Bastardy — Registration of Births — Compulsory Education — Industrial and Reformatory Schools — Vaccination — Punishments of Children — Capacity for Crime— Majority. Chap. X. variations in rights and duties caused by sex. — In- decent Offences — Protection of Women's Chastity — Action of Seduction — Abduction — Rape — Prostitution — Contagious Dis- eases — Keeping Disorderly Houses— Unfit Trades and Occu- pations of Women — Punishments of Women. Chap. XI. variations in rights and duties caused by ixsanity AND defective UNDERSTANDING. — Evidence of Insanity— Custody of Lunatic's Person — Licensed Houses — Treatment of and Access to Lunatics — Weak-minded Persons — Drunkenness and its Punishments. Chap. XII. variations in rights and duties caused by death. — Respect for Dead — Extravagant Expense of Funerals — Dissecting Dead — Stealing Dead Bodies — Duty to bury Dead — Burial in Churchyards — Burial Service — Tombs — Enlarging of Burial Grounds — Registration of Deaths. CONTENTS. I- INTRODUCTION. CHAPTER I. DISCUSSION OF THE DEFINITIONS AND DIVISIONS OF LAW. PACK Laws in general, laws of nature, and municipal laws .... 1 Municipal law contrasted with laws of nature 2 In what the two kinds of law agree 3 Supposed province of municipal law 5 Aversion of lawyers to much generalisation 6 Whether law is a science 7 Law is capable of methodical treatment 9 Methods of explaining law 1] Historical method of treating law — laws of savages — patriarchal law 11 Analytical method of explaining law 13 General definitions of law by various writers 14 Hooker, Burke, Dr. Johnson, Hallam, and others 15 Definitions of law by the ancients 16 Definitions of law by Justinian's Institutes and foreign writers . 17 Definitious of law by Blackstone, Paley, Bentham, and Austin . 18 Summary of current definitions of law' 21 Doubts as to ancient definition of law 2^1 Objections to current standard definition 24 Law does not prescribe a course of conduct 25 Objection to current definition as giving no specific purpose to the law 26 A new definition of municipal law 27 Law is restriction on human actions 28 Law includes forms for giving effect to some human actions . . 31 Part of definition as to supreme power of state 32 As to how law is enforced 34 Easiest mode of enforcing law is to allow the subjects to take part in making law 38 xxii CONTENTS. PAGE Object of law is that all may follow their occupations with greater security 39 Security is end and scope of all municipal laws 42 Object of law is not to enforce virtue 43 Law does not dictate occupations 45 Current divisions of municipal law 46 One division is into judicature, legislature, and government . . 46 These are machinery to work substantive law 48 Divisions of the substantive law 48 Division of law by Roman and foreign writers 49 Division of law according to English writers 51 Hale and Blackstone's division of law 51 Bentham's and other divisions of law 53 Objections to current division of law . 55 What is best division of municipal law 55 Reasons for discarding the division into the law of persons . . 57 Ancients not likely to have attained just notions of division of law 59 Best division of law is according to subjects of hmnan occupa- tions 60 First division is security of person 60 Variations in division caused by age, sex, sanity, and death . . 62 Second division is security of property 63 Third division is security of marriage 64 Fourth division is security of public worship 65 Fifth division is security of thought, speech, and character . . 66 Sixth division is security of contract and business 66 Seventh division is security of foreigners 67 Division of administrative law is threefold 67 Eighth division of law is judicature 68 Ninth division of law is legislature 68 Tenth division of law is executive government 68 Summary of tenfold division of law 69 Outline of division of whole law 70 CHAPTER II. EXPLANATION OF PHRASES AND TERMS USED IN THE LAW. Other divisions and terms used by legal authors 71 Meaning of liberty of subject and civil liberty 71 Views of Locke, Somers, Beccaria, and others 72 Current accounts of liberty and difficulty of reconciling them . 72 Liberty of suliject arises from legal restrictions 7i There is no absolute liberty 74 Liberty not confined to bodily freedom 75 Liberty not estimated by number of restraints 77 Liberty is counterpart of legal restraint 77 Distinction of absolute and relative rights 78 Natural rights of man 79 CONTENTS. xxiii Origin of government, social contract, and divine right ... 79 Theory of growth from barbarism 80 Theory of divine right and original contract 81 Opponents of theory of original contract 83 Reason why theory of original contract keeps its ground ... 86 Distinction of constitutional law 87 Distinction of public and private law 88 Distinction of civil and criminal law 90 Useful only for practical purposes 92 (commercial law 93 Distinction of the law of nations, what 93 Relations between nation and nation in peace and war .... 94 Relations between individuals of different nations 95 Private international law 96 Public international law 97 How law of nations arises 97 Distinction of law of nature 99 Definitions of law of nature 99 Law of nature has no historical l)asis 100 Distinction of law as to malum in se and malum prohibitum . . 103 If this distinction well founded 104 Distinction of the divine law 107 Ancient codes professing a divine origin 108 How far Christianity is part of law of England Ill Divine law not enforced like municipal law 114 Blasphemy as part of municipal law 116 The feudal law 118 Theory on which it was founded 121 Abuse and decay of that law 123 The civil law what 124 The Roman law called the civil law 125 Its importance and application in England 126 The canon law 128 Distinction of common and statute law 130 Written and unwritten law 131 Origin of connuon law 131 Statute law is supplementary to connuon law 132 Theories as to origin of common law 134 How customs grow into common law 137 Supposed superiority of common law to statute law 1 38 Velum in ousness of statutes 139 Judiciary, or judge-made law, what 140 Necessity of judge-made law 141 Objections to judge-made law answered 143 Mode of judicial reasoning 145 Legal fictions 146 Adherence of courts to precedents 148 When precedents not deemed binding 152 Adherence to precedents assumes means of knowledge of the law 153 Presumption that every one knows the law 155 Reason of this maxim 155 XXIV CONTENTS. PAGE Law and Equity and distinction of courts 157 Equitable jurisdiction as to trusts 160 Some vague notions of this distinction 161 Origin in usurping legislative power 161 Codification of law how far necessary 164 What is reasonable form of codification 166 Objections usually made to codification 168 Complaints of intelligent citizens as to want of code .... 169 Duty of government to codify laws 171 Codification treated as a public benefit 173 Confused state of English law requiring code 174 Definition of current phrases and words used in the law . . . 176 Definition of right, duty, obligation 176 Definition of the word equity 176 Meaning of word wroug 177 Meaning of word tort 178 Meaning of word crime 178 Quasi crimes punished by justices 179 Meaning of treason, felony, misdemeanour 179 THE SECURITY OF THE PERSON. The security of the person 183 First division of whole law is that relating to the body . . . 183 Twofold aspect of security of person 184 Chief heads of first division of the law as to security of person . 184 Arrangement of chapters of first division 186 CHAPTER I. PROTECTION OF THE BODY AGAINST THREATS AND APPREHENDED INJURIES. Kind of remedy against threats of personal injury 188 What is a threat of personal violence 189 A threat to do only moderate harm 190 Threatening looks and conduct 191 Whether one who libels another can be made to give security of the peace 191 Who grants the remedy of security of the peace 193 By and against whom security of the peace obtained .... 194 How application for security of the peace is supported .... 195 Whether defendant can contradict the facts 196 How long a i^arty may be imprisoned for not giving security of the peace 197 CONTENTS. XXV PAGE Mode of arresting and binding over a party to security of the peace 199 Eflect and binding force of the recognisance 200 Getting recognisance of the peace discharged 201 Surety of the peace required in some cases by statute .... 202 How far surety for good behaviour may be ordered 203 If security for good behaviour can be enforced against libellers . 206 Surety for good behaviour ordered by statute 207 Certain written threats punished more severely 207 Whether judge or jury construe the written threat 208 Letter demanding money without cause 208 Letter threatening to accuse in order to extort 209 Challenge to fio-ht how treated 211 Challenge to fight may be verbal or written 211 Attempt to provoke a challenge is a crime 212 Criminal information granted for challenge 213 Usual punishment of challenge to fight 213 Intimidation and molestation in business 213 Principle of common law as to interfei'ing with another's work . 214 Ancient law as to freedom of trade 214 Trade unions interfering with work 217 Action for decoying another's servant 217 Old statutes as to servants leaving service 218 Series of statutes as to combinations of workmen 219 Trade union not illegal in itself 220 Modem definition of intimidation in another's business . . . 220 Fair argument by trade union is legal 222 Now legal for workmen to strike simultaneously 222 Tumultuous assemblies 224 Unlawful assembly distinguished from riot, rout, affray . . . 225 How riot distinguished from high treason 226 Riot as regards mutual liability of those engaged 227 Riot as to its origin and common purpose 229 How far one may assemble friends for self-defence 229 Riots to demolish buildings 230 Individuals stopping a riot 231 Remedy against rioters 232 Early legislation for putting down riots 233 Reading the Riot Act 235 Duty of justices after proclamation of riot 237 Duty and discretion in using military force in riots 238 Remedy for property injured by rioters 240 What is an aflray 241 Who may stop an afiray 243 Punishment for an afi"ray 244 XXVI CONTENTS. CHAPTER 11. ACTUAL INJURY TO THE BODY BY THE NEGLIGENCE OF OTHERS. PAGE Injury to body by negligence of others 246 Negligence distinguished from accident 247 Where the injury is fatal 247 Who can sue for negligent killing 249 Within what time action for negligent killing to be brought . . 249 Compensation for negligent killing 250 How compensation estimated 250 Rules for ascertaining when negligence exists 252 The person injured or killed must not have been himself negli- gent 253 Contributory negligence in the case of coaches racing .... 253 Negligence implies a want of wilful intention 254 A chain of accidents from negligence 255 Where negligence is self-evident and is presumed 257 Negligence always a question of fact and cu'cumstances . . . 257 Classification of circumstances displaying negligence 258 Negligent carriage of passengers by railway 258 Railway accidents when implying negligence 258 Courts have often to decide if there is evidence of negligence . . 259 Statutory requirements in further protection against railway dangers 260 Driving negligently and furiously on highways 261 Negligence in carrying passengers in ships 262 Risks of inviting persons to enter premises 263 Negligence in keeping premises near highway 264 Negligence near highway in rural places 264 Negligence in premises adjoining streets 265 Negligent acts on highways 267 Occupiers of private roads 267 Negligence in not repairmg highways 268 Negligence in keeping vicious dogs and animals 269 Dangerous and mad dogs 271 Injuries caused to third parties by servants 272 Negligence of a servant acting on his own account or for another master 273 How servants' acts are distinguished from contractors' .... 274 Injuries caused by servant to fellow-servants through negligence . 275 Reason why master not liable for injury by one servant to a fellow-servant 276 Discovery of this rule an example of judge-made law .... 277 How far servant has claim against master for injuries in service . 279 How far master warrants tackle used by servants 279 Negligence of servants and masters in dangerous trades . . . 281 Negligence of physicians and surgeons 282 Negligence in selling poisons 283 NegUgence in setting spring-gims and engines 283 CONTENTS. xxvii CHAPTER III. PROTECTION OF THE BODY AGAINST INJURIES INTENTIONAL, BUT NOT MALICIOUS. PAO F. Wilful or intentional injuries classified 287 Assault and battery 288 Intention as ingredient of assault . 289 The means used to assault 290 Assault or blow must be actual or imminent 291 Assault implies that it is against consent 293 Some assaults are excusable or justifiable 293 Self-defence against blows 294 Assault in defence of wife or child 295 In defence of master or servant 296 All justifiable assaults must be to protect, not revenge .... 296 Assault in chastising children 296 Schoolmaster correcting children 298 Assault in correcting apprentices 298 Masters assaulting servants , 299 Husbands assaulting wives 301 Churchwardens assaulting persons misbehaving in church . . . 301 Assault to stop persons fighting 302 Assault in defence of possession of property 302 Assault in defence of property must be moderate 304 Assault in ejecting stranger from house or land 305 Assault in disputes as to possession of real property 305 Turning out trespasser with constable's assistance 307 Assaults in prize fighting 308 Assault in executing legal process 308 Remedies for assault generally 310 Punishment of assault by justices of the peace 310 Justices punishing for assaults on women and children . . . . 311 Justices are to give certificate in assault cases 311 Effect of justices' decision in assault cases 312 Justices may in some cases refuse to decide 313 Maximum of punishment by justices in assault cases . . . . 315 Justices cannot give compensation for assault 316 Some assaults treated as misdemeanours 316 Assaults on parents treated as common assaults 317 Assault in a court of justice 318 (Jriminal remedy for assault by information 318 Indictment for assault 319 Remedy for assault by action of damages 320 Finality of damages as remedy 321 SXVIU CONTENTS. CHAPTER IV. PROTECTION OF THE BODY AGAINST MALICIOUS, WILFUL, AND NEGLIGENT ACTS WHICH KILL OR WOUND. PAOK Murder the worst of human crimes 322 If murder is the earliest crime recognised 323 Definition of murder 323 Murder means killing of a human being 324 Murder of foreigners 325 Origin of word murder 326 Murder of infants 326 Murder of sick and aged persons 327 Where murdered person is confidentially related 328 Mental capacity of the murderer 329 Murder by drunkards 330 Murderer must be a free agent 331 Two shipwrecked persons on a plank 331 Malice as an ingredient of murder 332 Malice is the element distinguishing murder from manslaughter and accident 333 Express and implied malice 335 Malice prepense 335 Secrecy not necessary to malice in murder 336 Malice does not imply gam or profit to murderer 336 Personal animosity not necessarily implied in murder .... 337 Case of aiming at one and killing another 338 Provocation as an ingredient in murder 339 Mutual fighting and a fatal issue 342 Fatal accidents in contests of skill and prize-fights 343 It is for the jury to decide on malice 344 Murder by one of several acting illegally together 345 The parties implicated in murder 346 Receiving felon into one's house 348 Murder excludes the notion of lawful business or conduct . . 349 Killing in self-defence 350 Saving one's self by flight before killing pursuer 351 A woman defending her honour 353 Killing in defence of wife, child, and relative 353 Husband killing an adulterer . . 353 Killing in defence of exclusive possession of property .... 355 Killing to prevent crime 357 Murder in arrests by officers of law 357 General requirements as to a valid arrest 359 Killing in correcting children 361 Killing in course of cruel conduct 361 Fighting and duelling is not lawful conduct 363 Killing by sentence of the law 367 The means used for murdering 367 CONTENTS. xxix PAGE Killing by drugs or meiins of cure 368 Killing by keeping dangerous animals 369 Killing by communicating infectious disease 369 Killing by swearing away another's life 370 Poison as a means of murder 371 Killing must be consequence of the act charged 373 Killing in order to be murder must be within the year .... 373 Killing proved only by evidence of body being found .... 375 Death by accident or misadventure 376 Ancient laws confounded accidental death with murder . . . 377 The same want of discrimination in early English law .... 378 Difficulties of the ancients in punishing homicide 379 The notion of a blood avenger 380 The murderer's relatives also punished 381 Cities of refuge and sanctuaries ' 382 Ancient practice as to accepting fines for murder 385 Ancient English law as to fines for murder and sanctuaries . . 385 Confiscation of thing causing death — deodands 387 Ancient remedy by appeal of murder 389 IVIurder now triable by indictment 391 The indictment and trial for murder 391 The sentence on murderers 393 Suicide how far included in mui-der 393 Perplexity of the ancients as to suicide 395 Influence of Christianity on views of suicide 396 Capital punishment by way of suicide 397 Gladiatorial contests a kind of suicide 397 Suicide how far a crime at common law 398 Ancient and modern punishment of suicide 399 Other legal consequences of suicide 401 Discovery of murderer and function of coroner 401 By whom and how coroners appointed or elected 405 Authority and duty of coroner 406 Fees and expenses of coroner 409 Removing or dismissing a coroner 409 If coroner's court a public court 410 The coroner's jury and verdict 411 Attempts to murder how far crimes 411 Ancient law of lex talionis 412 The lex talionis in England 413 Defects of the lex talionis 414 Statutes against maiming and wounding 414 The modern crimes of attempts to nuu'der 416 The modern crimes of causing grievous bodily harm 417 iNIutilation of the body for special objects 418 Causing bodily harm by spiteful acts and conduct 419 Self-mutilation as a crime 419 XXX CONTENTS. CHAPTER V. RESTRICTIONS ON HUMAN ACTIONS OWING TO COMPULSORY ACTS AND DUTIES. Contrast between ancient and modern law as to minute interfer- ence with daily conduct 422 Sumptuary laws 424 Laws relating to things strictly personal 424 Right of locomotion 424 Compulsory occupations as servants 425 Compulsory hosts 425 Billetting of soldiers 426 Compulsory knighthood 428 Compulsory attendance at church 429 Restrictions as to names 429 How names usually acquired 430 Change of name how far competent 431 Restrictions as to food 433 Restrictions as to dress 435 Compulsory change of dress 438 Men wearing women's clothes 438 Painting the face 439 Compulsory keeping of armour 43.9 Right of wearing arms 441 Compulsory service as a soldier 443 Enlistment of soldiers now an ordinary contract 445 Pimishment of soldiers deserting 445 Arrest of soldiers for crime or debt 446 Peculiar punishments in army, military flogging 446 Marine service on shore how controlled 447 Militia service how far compulsory 447 Impressment of seamen how far legal 448 Authorities as to impressment 450 Essential injustice of impressment 451 Compulsory office of juror 453 Jurors divided into common and special 454 Qualification and attendance of jurors 454 Punishment of juror for nonattendance 455 Juries kept separate from parties 455 Juries during adjournment 457 How far juries must be unanimous 458 Jury deciding by lot 461 Accident to juror during trial 461 How far jurors punishable for misconduct 461 Compulsory duty of witness 464 Mode of enforcing attendance of witness in civil proceedings in High Court 464 How far papnent of witness's expenses required 466 Remedy for witness not attending High Court 468 CONTENTS. xxxi PAGE Commitment of witness for disobeying subpama 468 Action against witness for not attending 469 Summoning witness in Parliament 470 Witnesses before inferior courts and statutory judicial officers . . 470 Witnesses summoned by justices of the peace 471 Justices enforcing attendance of witnesses in indictable offences . 471 Justices enforcing attendance of witnesses at petty sessions . . 473 Protection of witness from arrest during compulsory service . . 474 Compulsory office of sheriff ; 475 Qualification of sheriff 476 By whom sheriff is appointed 477 Sheriff refusing to serve 477 Compulsory municipal offices 478 C'omijulsory office of constable and special constable .... 479 Compulsory office of churchwarden 481 Qualification of churchwarden 482 Nomination of churchwarden 482 Enforcing service as churchwarden 483 Compulsory office of overseer 484 Compulsory office of surveyor of highways 484 Slavery as a compulsory service 485 XTniversal pi-evalence of slavery 487 Greek and Roman slavery 488 Slavery in the early Christian centuries 488 Anglo-Saxon slavery 489 English slavery after the Conquest 490 Modern view of indefensible nature of slavery 492 Contract to serve another for life how far legal 494 Kidnapping and stealing human beings 495 Penal servitude 496 INTEODUCTION. CHAPTEE I. DISCUSSION OF THE DEFINITION AND DIVISION OF THE LAW. Lato in general. Distinction between laws of nature and municipal law. — All writers upon municipal law, who treat the subject methodically, find it necessary in the outset to discriminate between the two leading significations of the word "law" which pervade the languages of all civilised nations. The laws of nature or of natural phenomena are those abstract rules of cause and effect, which the Great Architect has impressed on the external world and its elemental changes. These laws are fixed and immutable, though generally hidden from superficial inquirers. They can only be arrived at by some power of reflection, and in most cases only after a wide induction from careful obser- vations ranging throughout time and space. The innate curiosity of man, springing from the restless desire to better his condition, prompts him to discover these laws ; and by their aid he unlocks the secrets of nature, and gratifies his sense of power. By his capacity to reflect, to distinguish, to analyse, and explain, he differs from the lower animals ; and brings his knowledge, gathered from many sources, to bear upon each subject, until his mastery over material things is established. And the laws of the mental and moral world are searched for by methods akin to those used for the material world, though by subtler processes and among more volatile elements. When the laws of nature have been thus discovered, the chief aim of VOL. I. B 2 ON THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT. {intro. man is to adapt his conduct and operations so as to con- form to them, for by such conformity alone can he make them minister to his well-being. And by so acting he can achieve results which, within his own range of influence, are far-reaching and durable. The farther his researches are carried, the more variety of occupation he makes for himself. He attains heights of knowledge and power, and a consciousness of growing civilisation, which are them- selves good, and constantly refresh his mental and moral nature, as well as augment his material comfort and happiness. Municipal law contrasted with laws of nature. — But with municipal laws, or those laws which govern the mutual relations of individuals in communities and nations, the fundamental notion is altogether different. Instead of these being fixed and invariable, and being searched for ah extra in external phenomena, instead of their existing altogether independent of man, they are essentially made by man himself. They are devised to meet his own wants ; it is not his wants that are accommodated to them. The laws of nature are historical facts, — they point to the past — to the beginning of time, and a Great Architect, whose will alone is the measure and the limit of all knowledge concerning them. On the other hand, the municipal laws are devised by man himself, and devised for no other purpose than to further his own pursuits. They are the creatures of his own necessities. While the laws of nature are searched for because they already exist, the municipal laws exist only from the time when they are fashioned and settled. They vary, and disappear and reappear, and if man were blotted out of the world, they would perish with him. While the laws of nature are indestructible, the laws ■ of man are provisional and temporary, reflecting his passing cares and pursuits — following him as a shadow, and not leading him as if he were a captive. It is not, however, to be supposed, that, though the municipal laws are made Ijy man himself, they necessarily on that account conflict with the laws of God and nature. On the contrary, as will be seen hereafter, the law-maker usually searches for his materials in the storehouse of nature itself, and in the recesses of his own being, both mental and physical. He takes and adapts these to his purpose. But it is only when and CTi. I.] LAWS OF NATUEE. because these are accepted and adopted, that they become part of the municipal law. In what the, laws of nature and municipal laws agree. — But though the laws of nature differ from municipal laws in their origin and relation to man, there is one respect in which they agree, and that is the influence which they exert, directly or indirectly, on the conduct of man in ail situations of life. The laws of nature, being divinely appointed, influence man's conduct by making his life all but impossible, unless they are observed and obeyed. They are irresistible, and compel his submission wherever he turns ; he cannot escape from them, and yet cannot alter them. The municipal laws, on the other hand, being entirely artificial, are made so as to imitate the laws of nature,^ but can only exact such a halting obedience as is the fruit of choice rather than of compulsion. They compel, it is true, after a fashion, but not by any direct and immediate action. They operate circuitously through the ^ Some pliilosophers have speculated as to whether the notion of municipal law or of the laws of nature comes fir^t in order of time, that is, whether we, having first acquired the notion of a municipal law, afterwards give a hke name to the settled order of events which we observe in nature, and call them laws also ; or whether, having first acquired the notion of laws of nature from our observation and experience, for example, of the laws of heat, falling bodies, flowing water, &c., we give a like name to the rules which are prescribed to us by third parties. This may be treated as an unsettled specula- tion ; but the better opinion seems to be that the two notions are contemporaneous. Others try to learn something as to the essence of municipal law from the etymology of the word "law" in different languages. Aquinas, Suarez, Valentia, &c., derived the word " law," or lex, from ligo, to bind ; others derive it from lego, to read : Cicero derives it from deligo, to elect or choose, inasmuch as a law implies a choice of two things. These etymological inquiries may be said to throw no light whatever on the matter. Burke thus alludes to this subject: "Surely there cannot be a more pleasing speculation than to trace the advances of men in an attempt to imitate the Supreme Ruler in one of the most glorious of His attributes, and to attend them in the exercise of a prerogative which it is wonderful to find intrusted to ;.the management of so weak a being. In such an inquiry we shall indeed frequently see great instances of this frailty, but at the same time we shall behold such noble efforts of wisdom and equity as seem fully to justify the reasonableness of that extraordinary disposition, b}- which men in one form or other have been alwaj's put under the dominion of creatures like themselves." — Abr. Eng. Hist. ch. ix, B 2 i ON THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT. [intro. reason, and by reaching the springs of human action. Man follows, and is intended to follow them, not because he cannot help it, but because reason itself says it is prudent to obey them. In this one respect both laws agree, namely, in the ultimate result of being followed and at- tended to, and this common feature binds both kinds of law as species under one genus. The one is intended to be an imitation of the other, not only in its certainty and uni- formity, but often also in its origin ; for nearly all codes of barbarous nations purport to have a divine origin. This arises, however, only from the artifice of legislators, who, in order to exact from rude communities a readier obedience to municipal laws, find no easier and more effectual means of doing so than by announcing them as the very voice of Heaven.^ Such an advantage, though invaluable at the starting-point, becomes at a later stage a grievous impedi- ment and drag. For when obedience thus secured has grown with the growth of society, and has become a second nature, it is then too readily deemed an act of impiety to change and improve what has been referred to a super- human source. Thus a law, though in itself essentially transitory and flexible, and capable of adapting itself to new wants as they arise, becomes stereotyped, and impedes the very movements essential to progress.^ ^ Plutarch says tliat Lycurgus, Nuraa, and other great men, finding their people difficult to manage, and alterations to be made in their several governments, pretended commissions from Heaven, which were salutary at least to those for whom they were invented. — Fluf. Numa. See further, post, Introd. ch. ii. s " Those who will admit of no change in the state would render errors perpetual, and, depriving mankind of the benefits of wisdom, industry, experience, and the right use of reason, oblige all to continue in the miserable barbarity of their ancestors, which suits better with the nature of a wolf than that of a man." — A. Sidney en Govt. p. 405. " It is observed by the best writers on this subject, that those com- monwealths have been most durable and perpetual which have often reformed and recomposed themselves according to their first institu- tion and ordinance, for by this means they repair the breaches and counterwork the ordinary and natural effects of time." — Pym loij. 8 St. Tr. 342. Venice in the middle ages prided itself on the irrevocability of its laws, and most of the tiavellors and liistoriaiis of the time lic'lieved this to be a sure sign of its immortality and of its extra- ordinary wisdom and insight ! — Thuanus, Hist. Ocean. 56. CH. I.] SUPPOSED PROVINCE OF LAW. 5 Supposed 'province of municipal law. — Wliile municipal laws are created by man for his own purposes, it is natural to inquire what those purposes are. This, however, is an obscure and difficult research. Nothing is so closely interwoven with daily life as the law and its rules and restrictions. No human employment is withdrawn from its all-pervading influence, or so remote and isolated that it is not confronted at one stage or another as with an inscription on the wall, " Thus far shalt thou come and no farther." All the businesses of life repose on this essential condition — that there are limits in all directions, created by members of the community, each against each — limits which cannot with safety be overpassed. This sense of restriction haunts all the myriad occupations of man, like a wandering voice. What it is — whence and whither it comes and goes — might well exercise the speculations of philosophers. For society, in all the stages of its pro- gress — in all conditions of time and place — whether loosely cohering in wandering tribes, or built up, tier upon tier, of Harrington declared that "the republic of Venice would be im- mortal — a commonwealth having no cause of dissolution, and standing with one thousand years of tranquillity upon her back." — Harr. Oceana. Hale says : " He that thinks that a state can be exactly steered by the same laws in every kind as it was two or three hundred years since, may as well imagine that the clothes that fitted him when he was a child should serve him when he was grown up as a man. The matter chungeth the custom : the contracts the commerce : the dispositions, educations, and tempers of men and societies change in ai long tract of time, and so must their laws in some measure be changed, or they will not be useful for their state and condition. And besides all this, Time is the wisest thing under heaven." — Hale's An. of Lato. " In modern days a condition of stagnation and decline has been the actual condition of many politioal societies for long periods of time. It is a condition prepared always by ignorance or neglect of some moral or economic laws, and determined by long-continued per- severance in a corresponding course of conduct. Then the laws which have been neglected assert themselves, and the retributions they inflict are indeed tremendous. In the last generation and in our time the Old and New Worlds have each afforded memorable examples of the reign of law over the course of political events. Institutions main- tained against the natural progress of society have ' foundered amidst fanatic storms.' Other institutions upheld and cherished against justice and humanity and conscience have yielded only to the scourge of war," — D. of ArgylVs Reign of Laiv, 431 (3rd ed.). 6 ON THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT. [intro. closely knit communities — all silently pursuing their complicated occupations — has always had laws of some kind. Many a sage like Socrates, surveying the scenes of the marketplace, must have pondered over the secret why and how so many independent activities can be made to act so harmoniously. It is true that Homer said the Cyclops had no laws and no political constitu- tions.^ Herodotus says the same of the Androphages, and yet that they were great breeders of cattle."-^ Historians say that the ancient Eomans after the expulsion of their kings had no laws for twenty years, till they sent com- missioners to inquire, and these brought them the Twelve Tables. The ancient Abyssinians, ruled by the descendant of the Queen of Sheba, were also said to have had no laws.^ And travellers have reported of the Caribbeans that they had no laws, and each killed his wife at pleasure.'* The Iroquois Indians are said to have relied on senti- ments of shame, and had no punishments.^ And we are told that when there was no king in Israel, every man did that which was right in his own eyes.*^ But these sayings do not conflict with the results of universal ex- perience, that all nations and tribes must consciously or unconsciously have laws of some kind, and customs are the laws of barbarians. Aversion of lawyers to much generalisation. — Yet the range or province of municipal law is a problem which the great thinkers of the world have done little to solve. ISTor is the main reason of this far to seek. The mimicipal law is nothing, if it is not practical, and it cannot be known in its practical details without great and persistent toil. The master spirits of philosophy have shrunk from the irk- someness of penetrating so many petty, devious, and sordid labyrinths, and have passed them by on the other side as naught but a mighty maze without a plan. The votaries of the law, on the other liand, have been so engrossed with details, that they have not cared to apply their minds to theories and systems, which they themselves have found all but useless and unprofitable. They have always gladly cast aside the abstract for the concrete, and have bid 1 Horn. Odyss. vi. 5 ; ix. 106 ; x. 200. ^ gerod. b. 4. » 1 Univ. liist. * 15 Univ. Mod. Hist. 233. ^ 3 Schooler. Ind. 184. •^ Judg. xvii, G. CH. I.] WHETHER LAW IS A SCIENCE. 7 farewell for ever to the dreams of science.^ Between these two classes — the class that had the will but not the means, and the class that had the means but not the will — little care has been expended on arranging and reducing to order so many and multifarious materials. Wliether law is a science. — Hence the difficulty which presents itself of treating municipal law as a science at all, tliough such a name has been suggested with more and more energy in recent times. It is natural, indeed, that a dignity which is not denied to humbler subjects — to Shells and Insects, to Sound, and Colour, and Heat — should be claimed for the greatest and most potent body of knowledge which concerns the children of men — a know- ledge which reaches, directly or indu'ectly, all stations 1 Hale said great men usually neglect the study of the English laws.— Hale's Hist. C.L. 140. Lord Mansfield said that ignorance on subjects of law was ex- tremely pardonable, since the knowledge of particular laws required a particular study of them ; that the greatest genius without such study could no more become master of them, than of Japanese literature without understanding the language of the country. — 15 Pari. Hist. 9U0. BuKKE, writing a few years (1757) before BlacTcKtone's Commen- taries were published, says : " The law has been confined and drawn up into a narrow and inglorious study ; an indigested method, and a species of reasoning the very refuse of the schools. Young men were sent away with an incurable, and, if we regard the manner of handling rather than the substance, a very well-founded, disgust." — Ahr. Eng. Hist. ch. ix. An acute citizen of the world lately made this comment on English law : " The faults as well as the excellences of the English cha- racter arise from that great dislike to generalise which has made us the practical and in many instances the prejudiced people that we are. Abroad, a knowledge of general or natural law, of the founda- tions on which all laws are or ought to be based, enters, as a matter of course, into a liberal education. In England lawyers themselves dis- regard this study as useless, or worse than useless. They look, and they look dihgently, into English law, such as it is, established by custom, precedent, or Act of Parliament. They know all the nice points and proud formalities on which legal justice rests, or by which it may be eluded. The conflicting cases and opposing opinions which may be brought to bear on an unsound horse or a contested footpath, are deeply pondered over, carefully investigated. But the great edifice of general jurisprudence, though standing on his wayside, is usually passed by the legal traveller with averted eyes ; the antiquarj' and the philosopher indeed may linger there, but the plodding man of business scorns to arrest his steps." — 2 Buhcer's Hist. Char. 13. 8 ON THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT. [intro. and classes, and challenges the attention of governors and governed alike, searching the roots of social life far and wide. To watch and guide the changing details of the law and direct its next evolutions, is the business of politics, which is the most conspicuous occupation of practical minds. Politicians constantly emulate each other in balancing and forecasting the conditions of this progress — in guiding the centre of motion — in rounding angularities, removing obstacles, levelling up or down, according to the motive forces in the ascendant. But when and why some laws were ever made at all, or, if made, when or why they should not be unmade — when it is best to stop and when to advance — when to speak and when to be silent — when to efface and when to restore or expand — these are secrets which have baffled the scrutiny of all the ages, and the wisest of men can show more easily how little they know of them than how to explain them. When a system of knowledge has no fixed range of action and an ever-shifting foreground — when its principles are little better than changing maxims of expediency — the mere saws and instances of the hour — while its origin and progress are alike desultory, fortuitous, and uncertain — when no person can divine in what direc- tion it is tending, and what are the legitimate limits of its domain — it is almost an abuse of lan^uacfe to call law a science, though it may be the most transcendent of all the arts.^ The universal influence it wields over the conduct of man in the business of the world entitles it in any case to the first importance. Finch said that the sparks of all the sciences in the world were raked up in its ashes.^ By 1 "Jurisprudence, according to the primary and established sense of the word, especially on the Continent, is the science of the Roman law, and is seldom applied to any other positive system, but least of all to the law of nature." — 1 Hallam, Lit. H. 415. Sir William Jones says : — "The great system of juj-isprudence, like that of the universe, consists of many subordinate systems, all of which are coimcctcd by nice links and beautiful dependencies, and each of which is reducible to a few plain elements. If law be a science, and really deserve so sublime a name, it must be grounded upon principle, and claim an exalted rank in the empire of reason ; but if it be merely an uncoimccted series of decrees and ordinances, its use may remain, though its dignity may be lessened, and he will become the greatest lawyer who has the greatest natural or artificial memory." 2 1 Wynne, Eun. 70. CH. 1.] LAW IS CAPABLE OF METHOD. whatever name it may be called, the law is the great touchstone by which all human affairs are more or less tested, at least as between man and man. And if the present definition of science is too restricted, it may well be extended sufficiently wide to include the eldest born and the natural protector of all the rest.^ Law ca-pabU of methodical treatment. — But though law can scarcely be viewed as a science, at least in the sense in which that word has been usually applied, it is not the less a system of knowledge capable of being reduced to order, and pre-eminently calling for clear arrangement. Law has not only the whole field of practical life to in- fiuence, but it has an army of officers, ministers, and functionaries to work it out, not forgetting a vast array of magistrates and jurors evoked from the crowd to circulate and apportion its most practical lessons. Its influence is brought to bear on difficulties as they arise. The legal profession must be educated, and those of the public, who choose to learn what is so invaluable when learned in time, but what is so costly when learned too late, naturally expect to master without much difficulty what each is ' It may be said that law is no more capable of being treated as a science than religion. Both require to deal too closely with the un- reflecting, the ignorant, and the simple-hearted (to each and all of whom they must be accessible) to be capable of being reduced to a rigid system of rules, growing out of each other in logical sequence and development. If they could be compreliended only by a rigorous application of thought, like a science, they woidd shoot over the heads of those whom it is their greatest pride to protect and console. Burke finely observes : " And freedom is not a thing that lies hid in abstruse science. It is a blessing and a benefit, not an abstract speculation ; and all the just reasoning that can be had upon it is of so coarse a texture, as perfectly to suit the ordinary capacities of tiiose who are to enjoy and those who are to defend it. Far from any resemblance to those propositions in geometry and metaphysics which admit no medium, but must be true or false in all their lati- tude, social and civil freedom, like all other things in common life, are variously mixed and modified, enjoyed in very different degrees, and shaped into an infinite divevsity of forms, according to the temper and circumstances of every community." — Burke, Shf. of Bristol. " Government is a practical thing made for the happiness of man- kind, and not to furnish out a spectacle of uniformity to gratify the schemes of visionary philosophers." — Ibid. 10 ON THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT. [intro. assumed already to know. What is to be learned can best be learned by reducing all that can be reduced to first principles, by arranging subjects in their natural and most intelligible order, and explaining what is pre-eminently addressed to the reason of all by adducing the best reasons that have been given by sages of all times, or if none have been or can be given, then by admitting this defect without yielding to an abject credulity. Law differs from other arts and systems of knowledge in anything but this, that it is most readily learned and mastered when the method and the arrangement are the best- attainable. At the same time, none of the other learned professions treats with such unconquerable repugnance all attempts to generalise too much. To insist, as some teachers have done, on mapping out the whole field of human knowledge as a preliminary condition to mastering an empirical system, or even to tarry long in marshalling with nice precision its true place in the array of the arts and sciences, demands too great a reach of abstraction. Far-reaching reflection is doubly odious to those whose affairs are always urgent, who have only time to snatch an instant solution from the readiest judge sitting at the gate, who care little for formulas and methods, and everything for results. The details of practical law — and there is no other law zealously pursued — are already too great to allow time to ponder over the ultimate axioms and postulates, which scientific minds have by severe analysis found buried fathoms deep in its crude materials. A subject which requires the study of a life- time, so that the longest liver is almost always the wisest lawyer, does not tolerate a lengthened preamble. Yet in spite of all this rooted aversion to first principles, no one can doubt that a large chapter of knowledge, professedly addressed to the reason of practical men, and which assumes to punish them for not knowing and not attending to it, and which moreover it is the pride of the leaders of society to be constantly engaged in amending and im- proving, must be susceptible of such a method, of such illustrations and explanations as will effectually fix the attention and memory. All other branches of human knowledge readily yield to this treatment. If law, apart from the mere technicalities inseparable from its daily manipulation and workmanship, cannot be made intelligible, CH. I.] METHODS OF EXPLAINING LAW. 11 and arrange itself in the mind as the mirror, or at least the semblance of practical reason, it must be the fault of those who profess to explain it. This much is self-evident, that unless thoroughly understood and cordially accepted in all its cardinal^ doctrines, it cannot be wholly obeyed ; and if it is not capable of being obeyed it must be a delu- sion and a snare, invented to harass and mock the natural craving for superior knowledge, which in civilised commu- nities is a possession so highly prized. Metliods of ex2')laining laio. — In entering upon the threshold of the subject, there are two courses open to him who seeks to make the law most easily understood. One is to trace historically from small beginnings in the rudest ages the growth of those rules and canons which ultimately take shape and consistence among all advanced communities. The other is to take the law as found in its highest development in a civilised nation and resolve it into its ultimate elements or factors, bearing in mind that practical knowledge begins where philosophy ends. While some things are too intricate for ordinary observers, the theories of the wise must often be assumed as the starting- point for those, who so soon become engrossed in the busy round of life. The historical method of treating law. — Law of savages. — • Patriarchal origin of laio. — The historical method, though seldom systematically followed up, is well calculated to arrest the attention and to yield abundant materials to interest and attract. During the last century or more travellers have added much to our knowledge of some rudi- mentary conditions of the human race. Many curious particulars as to the habits of tribes living far below the lowest Q-rade of civilisation have been collected, and some insight obtained into their way of thinking, or rather of acting. Some tribes of men are thereby shown to differ scarcely in any respect from the beasts of the field, except in their semblance to the human form divine, and in the higher intelligence which is inseparable from such a form. All the typical features of the fully-developed law are conspicuous by their absence, or rather, by tlieir anti-types. Marriage there is none, but entirely the reverse of it in all its details. Contracts are not needed ; crime is neither known nor punished. Individuals have no rights and no 12 ON THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT. [intro. wrongs, distinguished from those of the tribe or clan. Representative institutions, trial by jury, incorruptible judges, habeas corpus, trespass, slander, trade unions, gaols, and workhouses, are abstract ideas far beyond the reach of savage minds, and if uttered to them would be nothing but foolishness. All that corresponds to law in this primaeval or degraded state consists in trapping and eating one's adversary. AH commerce consists in satisfying the bodily appetites. All morality, religion, and education consist in sacrifices and war-dances. Hunting and witchcraft may be said to divide between them all that flows from reason ; these exercise body and mind alike, and fill up the pauses of appetite. It is true that tribes are also found in many quarters of the world only a little higher in advancement, others again higher and higher, until some of the linea- ments of those institutions usual in a settled and populous community are discerned. These glimpses of human progress in various stages may be found in the pictured pages of travellers and historians. But notwithstanding all their scattered lights, it is impossible to construct any intelligible history of how the law came to expand into its present full development, what conditions supplied the impulse and directed the growth. Sir Eobert Filmer tried to frame a theory of government by tracing society from Adam and Eve to the seventeenth century. He steadily searched for, and always contrived to find, the patriarchal system embodied in every stage — the divine right for the kings, and the passive obedience for the subjects. But Locke had little difficulty in exposing the flaws, assump- tions, and self-contradictions manifold, winch were con- spicuous in his specious chain of deduction. And most authors since those days have rested content with occasional glimpses of old-world ideas visible in ancient codes and histories, but with many a chasm of darkness between. The historical method fails chiefly in its history. It fails to tell whether the savage state is the first state or the last — the starting-point of all, or the falling away and lowest degradation of the many. It solves none of the secrets when, how, or by what subtle influences the noble savage of the woods was transflgured into the peaceful citizen — how the spear became a plougiishare, and the vengeful and murderous blow became a warfare of words transacted by CH. I.] ANALYTICAL METHOD OF LAW. 13 third parties on a stage — how most of the complicated wants of man came to be satisfied by some appropriate remedy, or quieted altogether by the knowledge that no remedy at all can be found. The analytical method of exijlaining law. — The analytical method is the other means of studying and seeking some mastery of the law. To resolve the main processes and machinery of the law into the elementary principles and axioms, is to suggest at once the best division of details, and to supply the best clue to the knowledge of what is, and to the secret of what ought to be. The law is always transforming and expanding itself by a process analogous to the growth of a tree. It is seen among savage tribes as a seed or root or a sapling, and after the lapse of ages it is the pride of the forest. The root has gradually accommodated itself to the soil and searched in all directions for support, and according to the soil so is the tree and the branches. The leaves and branches and trunk have changed, and yet the identity has remained. But why the root has travelled more in one direction than another — why the branches lie more to the east or the west — why they take this shape or that, and finally why one soil is more kindly than another, are secrets too deep for the scrutiny of ordinary men. Yet it is something to know what is the interior mechanism of the tree— the circulation of the sap — the organic structure of the wood, the bark, the leaves, and the roots, the chem- istry of the soil — the mutual relations of the constituent members. Analysis can only carry us a few stages, and none can wholly explain why one nation has a more favour- al)le soil than another, and why the tree is here and there of a statelier growth. Human nature serves as common ground, but patriotism and national vanity cover it over with flowers and leaves of mantling green. The variety of soils and situations, however, can scarcely fail to suggest comparisons, reflections, and researches ; and as no system of law has yet approached perfection, and the best seems the busiest in searching out still better principles, better processes, and better ends and aims, it must be invaluable to resort to some common classification and some standard of advancement, round which these can be grouped for common reference. Such advantages are those which analysis alone can supply. 14 ON THE LIBEETY OF THE SUBJECT. [intro. General definitions of law hy various writers. — Such being a general survey of the bearings of the municipal law, it is necessary to approach nearer, and inquire what definition of the word has been arrived at by the great writers of ancient and modern times. And at this stage it is salutary to reflect that it may be altogether impossible to give any definition at all, for however common may be the experience which each individual almost necessarily acquires of some of the processes of the law daily going on around him, he may yet be wholly unable to fix its generic and specific rank with scientific exactness. Nor is there much to surprise in this state of things, for notwithstanding the researches and the reflections of many centuries, the philosophers can- not be said to have yet settled among themselves how to define truth, beauty, virtue, conscience. Yet every one will admit that each of these is not only an existing thing, but familiar to his thoughts and feelings, however difiicult to express their discriminating qualities.^ It would be ^ In considering tlie scientific value of definitions, it should be recollected that the sense of satisfaction derived from a definition, or from the best reason to be given for a doctrine or rule, is not always proportioned to the increase of information or insight afforded. The mathematicians, in expositions of their science, have not shrunk from an endeavour to explain why it is that a body to which motion is communicated moves in a straight line. Thus PoissoN, in his " Mecanique Celeste," P. ii., p. 1, § 113, says that the reason is that " no reason can be stated why a body should not move in a straight line." And this, though a merely negative reason, satisfies the mind, and at least takes the edge ofi: further inquiry. Probably on similar grounds it is that amid all the many definitions of virtue which the moralists of all times have been busy in constructing, demolishing, refining away, and canvassing, there is a soothing satisfaction left in the mind by that much-abused yet irrepressible definition given by many, that virtue is nothing else than "the eternal fitness of things." Few persons can avoid ringing changes on this old idea. It is a singular coincidence that Bentham unconsciously follows the mathe- maticians in his explanation of the essential equality of the law. He says, " No reason can be assigned why the law should seek to give one man more than another." — 1 Benth. W., 302. Thus Cicero well expresses what many of his successors have only repeated in language slightly different : " The impulse which directs to right conduct and deters from crime, is not only older than the ages of nations and cities, but coeval with that Divine Being who sees and rules both heaven and earth. Nor did Tarquin less violate that eternal law, though in his reign thei'e might have been no I CH. I.] DEFINITIONS OF LAW. 15 impossible to collect all the attempts made in different ages to fix the meaning of municipal law, and possibly many of these only end wliere they began, and substitute a synonym or a circuity of many words for two or three. Some authors resort to the language of eulogy, and avoiding close inspec- tion or distracting details, dilate only on its gilded exterior and most conspicuous features. Hooker, Burke, Dr. Johnson, Mackintosh, on law. — Hooker eloquently says that " law has its seat in the bosom of God — has a voice, which is the harmony of the world — the least feel her care and the greatest are not exempted from her power, and angels, men, and creatures admire her as the mother of their peace and joy." Such an account indeed must often have astonished those who thought they had reason to know best, and to feel strongly how many terrestrial infirmities clung to the most admired justice. Burke also extolled law as the pride of the human intellect and the collected reason of ages ; Dr. Johnson looked upon it as displaying the greatest powers of the understanding ; and Mackintosh viewed the progress of jurisprudence as the noblest of spectacles, in which, during the long course of ages, cases of difficulty were gradually withdrawn from brutal force and arbitrary discretion, and subjected to inflexible rules. Hallam also carefully avoided commit- ting himself to any attempts to fix the area of law. Eulogies such as these, bestowed on their familiar work, lawyers would scarcely dare to think or speak ; but, when volunteered by bystanders, may well be welcomed and cherished with pride.^ written law at Rome against such violence, for tlie principle that impels us to right conduct and warns us against guilt, springs out of the nature of things. It did not begin to be law when it was first written, but wlien it originated, and it is coeval with the Divine Mind itself."— C/c. De Leg. 1 Hooker, Eccl. Pol. b. i.— Hallam has observed that Hooker's de- scription of law is in substance the same as the definition of Eternal Law by Suarez. But the criticism seems unjust to Hooker, whose originality and eloquence cannot suifer by the coincidence.— Sir J. Mackintosh says that Hooker referred to " the law of nature." —Mack. Disc. L. of Nations. What is meant by the law of nature is afterguards discussed. — See Introd. ch. ii. 2)ost. Hallam has said that " no systematic science, Avhether by the name of jurisprudence or legislation, can be laid down as to the principles 16 ON THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT. [intro. Dejinitions of lavj hy the ancients. — Definitious in law can scarcely be said to be favourites, and tliey are some- times pointed out as signals for caution.^ Yet the search is enticing, and it may be useful to see what great authorities have suggested as a definition of municipal law. The ancient codes were too practical, and their legislators too much in earnest, to trouble themselves about this require- ment, the desire of later and more critical ages. The Indian codes, tliose of Persia, of Moses, the older Greeks and Eomans, contain no attempt either to define or to make a division of the law. And many of the philoso- phers approach, rather than grapple with, the same subject. Socrates seemed to think the distinguishing charac- teristic of law was that it was dependent, not on caprice, liut on the will of the gods, was unchangeable, and yet adapted to all conditions of humanity. Plato thought it was tlie enforcement of the three primary virtues — knowledge, fortitude, and temperance — and that without laws we should live like beasts.^ Epicurus said without laws men would devour one another.^ Aristotle thought law was a declaration emanating from the common consent of the community as to everything we ought to do, and as which ought to determine the institutions of all nations, or, in other words, the laws of each separate community cannot be regulated by any universal standard in matters not depending upon eternal justice." — 2 Hall. Lit. Eur. 586 (3 ed.). " Law has been studied in general rather as an art than a science." — 2 Hall. Mid. Aq. 342 (12 ed.). ^ 8wiNBURN says : " Definitions are said to be dangerous in law." — Wills and Test. p. 1, sect. 3. The Eoman Digest also noticed the perilous nature of definitions, the defects of which were so easily exposed by others. — Digest., b. 50. Burke said the rights of men are incapable of definition, but are not impossible to be discerned. —Fr. Bev. Yet fallacies in reasoning are m circulation, which have retarded law reform as well as confused the law itself, and which seem to arise from nothing else but a want of any clear definition of law and its province, as for example in copyright, blasphemy, and forfeiture for crime, and other cliapters. So late as 1799 Abbott, a lawyer, afterwards Speaker, o]i])oscd Ihe abolition of forfeiture in language which would be untenable in the present day.— 34 Pari. Hist. 1068. Definitions, or attempted definitions, have this negative value, that they quickly expose any confusion of thought in those who use them. ■■' Plato, De Leg. ix. ^ Plutarch. CH. I.] DEFINITIONS OF LAW. 17 enjoining one class of actions and forbidding others.^ And he elsewhere says, it directs every one how to act on all occasions.^ Demosthenes also more rhetorically described the law as designed to ascertain what was just, honourable, and expedient, and as the invention of Heaven;^ Cicero, admitting that municipal law often deviated improperly from natural law, said that it was, or ouglit to be, a certain eternal principle, which governed the entire universe, wisely commanding what was right and prohibiting what was wrong.'* Definitions of law in Justinian's Institutes and later foreign writers. — Justinian's Institutes contain no defini- tion of law beyond this, that justice is the constant and perpetual disposition to render every man his due ; that jurisprudence is the science of what is just and unjust ; and that the precepts of the law are to live honourably, to hurt no one, and to give every man his due.^ Paul and Ulpian said law was the art of the just and good.^ Scarcely one of the succeeding writers is satisfied with the definitions of his predecessors.'^ 1 Arist. De Civ. cap. 14, sec. 2. Eth. b. v. cIi. i. § 11, 12. 2 Rhet. ad Alex. cli. i. ^ Demosthenes — " Tlie design and object of tlie laws is to ascertain what is just, honourable, and expedient, and when that is discovered, it is proclaimed as a general ordinance, equal and impartial to all. This is the origin of law, which for various reasons all are under an obligation to obey, but especially because all law is the invention of Heaven, the resolution of wise men, the correction of every offence, and the general compact of the state : to live in conformity with which is the duty of every individual in society." — Orat. c. Aristog. Professor Christian says this definition of Demos- thenes' is perfect, and prefers it to Blackstone's. — 1 B!. Cum. 442 n. * Cic. De Leg. b. 1, 2. s Just Inst, b. i. tit. 1. « Dig. i. 1, De Just.et Jur. 11 f. Paid. Dig. i. pr. f. Ulp. ^ Aquinas — " Law is a certain rule and measure, according to which a-ny agent is led to act or restraineil from acting." SuAREZ — " Law is a certain measure of moral acts, so that when in conformity with it they are morally right, when disconhint l'n;m it they are wrong." — t^uarez, De Leg. Montesquieu — "Laws are the necessary relations resulting from the natm-e of things." — De I'Espr. b. i. Beccaria— " Laws are the conditions under which men naturally independent unite themselves in society." — On Crimes, ch. ]. Grotius — " Law is a rule of moral actions ubliging us to that which is good and commendable." — De Jure., b, i. ch. 1. VOL. I. C 18 . ON THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT. [intro. Definitions of lavj ly English writers. — The definitions of some of the leading ancient and foreign writers on this PuFFENDORFF — " Lfiw is tlie injunction of liim who has a power over those to whom he prescribes." — B. i. ch. 6, § 1. Barbeyrac — " Law is tlie will of a superior sufficiently notified, by which he directs all actions of a certain kind, so that in regard to such actions he either imposes on them a necessity of doing or not doing certain things, or leaves them at liberty to act or not act as tliey shall judge proper."- — Notes to Grntlus, b. i. ch. 1, § 9. BURLAMAQUi's definition is substantially the same as that of Barbeyrac. Kant—" Civil law is distinguished from moral, inasmuch as the former legislates only wth respect to external actions, and provides for the freedom of all -by Hmiting and defining that of individuals. Strict law may be represented as the possibility of a general and reciprocal restraint, harmonising according to universal laws with the liberty of all." The Scotch writers define law as follows : — Stair (1681) — " Law is the dictate of reason, determining every rational being to that which is congruous and convenient for the nature and conditions thereof, and this will extend to the deter- mination of the indiflierency of all rational beings. Liberty is the natural faculty to do that which every man pleaseth, unless he be hindered by law or force." — Stair, 1,2, 1. Mackenzie — "Law is the science which teaches us to do justice, and justice is a constant and perpetual will and inclination to give every man what is due to him." — Inst. tit. 1. Erskine — " Law is the command of a sovereign containing a common rule of life for his subjects, and obliging them to obedience." —Ersk. Inst. 1, 1, 2. Pr. 1, 1, 1 (1754.) McDouALL — " Law is the rule of voluntary actions of rational beings, prescribing what ought to be done or forborne. " — Instil. 1, 1,1 (1751). French authors thus define law : — "Law is a rule established by an authority, which one is bound to obey." — 1 Duranton, Droit Fr. § 29. Rogron, Codes Fr. Litrod. i. " Law is the rule of those human actions which have for their prin- ciple the free exercise of the intelligence and the will." — 1 Toullier, Droit Civ. Fr. 2. "Laws arc nothing else but the rules of human conduct, and this conduct is nothing else but the steps which a man makes towards his end, and his end is to know and love God."~] hmaf, Droit Civ. ch. 1. American authors thus define law : — Kent adojjts the definition of Blackstone with a slight omission, for he delines municipal law as "a rule of civil conduct prescribed by the supreme power of a state."— 1 Kejif Com. 440. Dagge — " Law in the genus is that faculty whereby some lawfid superior prescribes rules of action, which those in subjt-ction are obliged to pertorm luider certain penalties express or implied." — Crim. L. vol. i p. 2. CH. I.] ENGLISH DEFINITIONS OF LAW. 19 subject vary much, and if we turn to the law of England as treated by English writers, we find that definitions were almost entirely dispensed with till the time of Blackstoue. Glanville, Fleta, and Britton avoid a detinition ; and all that Bracton says is, that law is a just statute, ordering what is right and honest, and prohibiting the contrary.^ Fortescue alludes to law as a holy sanction commanding whatever is honourable, and forbidding the contrary ; - and again " as the bond of right by winch a man is constrained to do or to suffer what is just."^ Coke, the least methodical of all great writers, nowhere defines law ; nor does he give any other division of law than that of common law, statute law, and custom.* And as he believed that the Star Chamber kept all England quiet, he must obviously have been satisfied with the ancient definitions. It is to be regretted that Bacon's imperial mind was not more closely applied to a definition of the law. He says, however, that the end and scope which laws ought to regard, and to which they should direct their cou] mauds and sanctions, is nothing else than that citizens may live happily. ° In the tract " On the Use of the Law," wdiich is believed not to be Bacon's, the use of the law is said to consist in three things : " first to secure men's persons from death and violence ; second, to dispose of the property in their goods and lands ; and third, for preservation of their good name from shame and infamy." " It is still more unfortunate that Hale gives no detinition, though, as will be afterwards =tated, he gives an analysis or division of its subjects. Hobbes defines law to be the command of the sovereign power addressed to the subjects, declaring what every one of them may do, and what they must forbear to do.^ 1 B. i. cli. 3. ^ De Laud. cli. 3. ^ De Nat. p. i. c4i. 30. 4 Co. Lit. 110 b. 115 b. 5 Bac. De Augm., Aph. 5. This indeed was only repeating the reasons of Minos : Strabo, b. s. " Bac. W. (Spedding.) '' Hobbes touches on the subject in several places : " Law was brought into the world for nothing else but to limit the natural liberty of particular men in such manner as they might not hurt, but assist one anotlier, and join together against a common enemy." — Commonw. p. ii. ch. xxvi. " In all kinds of actions by the laws pretermitted men have the liberty of doing what their own reasons shall suggest for the most profitable to themselves." — Ibid. ch. xxi. "Civil law is to every subject those rules which the comn.onwealth c 2 20 ON THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT. [intbo. Definition of law hi/ Blackdone, Paley, Bentham, Austin. — Blackstone describes the total laws of one nation or com- munity whencesoever derived as the municipal law of that nation. " I call it," he says, " municipal law, in compliance with common speech : for though strictly that expression denotes the particular customs of one single inunicipiurn, or free town, yet it may with sufficient propriety be applied to any one state or nation which is governed by the same laws and customs. And municipal law, tlms understood, is properly defined to be a rule of civil conduct, prescribed by the supreme power in a state, commanding what is right and prohibiting what is wrong."^ Paley does not expressly define what he means by muni- cipal law, except in so far as he assumes it to be the same thing as the law of the land, and that again is something that is consistent with the will of God, the will of God being discoverable from the Scriptures and the light of nature, or the calculation of the consequences of particular acts on our individual happiness.^ But possibly the key to his notion is found in his definition of civil liberty, which, h<3 says, is "the not being restrained by any law but what conduces in a greater degree to the public welfare." ^ Bentham defines law thus : — " A law is a discourse con- ceived mostly in general, and always in determinate words, ■expressive of the will of some person or persons, to whom, hath commanded hira by word, writing, or other sufficient sign of the will to make use of for the distinction of right and wrong, that is to say, of what is contraiy, and what is not conti-ary to tlie rule." — Ibid. cli. xxvi. ; see also Ihid. pt. iii. ch. xlii. " Law is the com- mand of him or tliem that have sovereign power given to those that be his or their subjects, pulilicly and plainly declaring what every ■one of them may d^, and what they must forbear to do." — Dialog. Law. and. Fhil. "Civil laws are nothing else but the commands of him who hath the chief authority in the city for direction of the luture actions of the citizens." — Dom'in. cli. vi. Cumberland, again repeating Minos, said tlie good of the whole was the standard and aim of all laws. — De Leg. Sir H. Finch says law is an art of well ordering civil society. — On Law. Sheppard : Law is a rule for tlie governing of civil society to give to every man that which doth belong to him. — Epitome, 683. 1 1 BI. Com. G5. ' Paley, Mor. Phil. li. ii. ch. iv. ; b. iii. p. i. ch. iv. 3 Paley, Mor. Phil. b. vi. ch. v. CO. I.] STANDARD DEFINITION OF LAW. 21 ou the occasion and in relation to the subject in question, whether by habit or express engagement, the members of the community to which it is addressed are disposed to pay obedience." ^ Austin defines law to be " a command which obliges a person or persons to a course of conduct, or a command which obliges a person generally to acts or forbearances of a class. And a command implies a sanction, that is, a power to inflict evil or pain on the party who disobeys." ^ Bummary of the current definitions of law. — It thus appeal's that the prevailing definition of law amongst English writers, and one which does not, notwithstanding the variety of phraseology, substantially differ from those adopted by Aristotle, Cicero, and leading writers of other nations, is this, that law is "a rule of civil conduct pre- scribed and enforced by the state " — to which some add the, words " commanding what is right and prohibiting what is wrong." The latter words have been objected to as assuming either that what the state commands must always be right, or tliat, if its commands should be wrong, then they cannot be laws — both of wdiich alternatives are untenable. The amendment of Blackstone's definition which was adopted by Kent, and substantially also by Austin, is thus the standard definition, namely, that "law is a rule of civil conduct prescribed and enforced by the state." Douhts as to ancient and current definition of laiv. — At this stage, where we have arrived at the standard definition of law that has been in vogue from the time of Aristotle and Justinian, and accepted by Hale, Blackstone, and Austin, it may be useful to reflect for a moment on some reasons for doubting, whether that definition was likely to have correctly fixed the true function and place of the law in the economy of tlie world. A correct definition of it could only be arrived at by a comparison of tlie law of one nation with that of others, as then known, and by a view of the details which usually make up the complex notion of law in each instance. Can it be said that at any epoch of the ancient world, even the most penetrating intellect had before it materials fit for a wise conclusion ? The ^ Chrestom. sect. 8. 2 Austin, Juris, vol. i. pp. 91, 98 (Srd ed,). 22 ON THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT. [intro. practice of Greece and Eome and the communities flourish- ing before and around them in the age of Aristotle, Cicero, and Justinian could scarcely shed a true light on this point. The leading ideas that are the glory of the modern law were then wanting, or dimly comprehended. The sacred- ness of life, the dignity of laljour, the toleration, the far- reaching philanthropy and Christian piety, the abhorrence of violence, the sensitiveness to dictation, tlie diffusion and interchange of thought and opinion, the readiness to con- sult and to allow a voice and deference to each interest concerned, the security and harmonious movements of the vast populations of the present day — all point to different springs of action, different objects of life, different standards and estimates, different hopes and destinies. The ancients were misled by the practices going on around them into thinking, that the end and object of law was to enforce the practice of all the virtues, according to their notions of the virtues. Whether the law was moulded in this way by the people and by their tendencies, or the people were moulded by the law — which was the cause, or which the consequence — a false orbit had been assigned to it. The ancients started with the unquestioned axiom, that all mankind are divided into two classes by an immutable distinction of freemen and slaves ; and this alone w^as suf- ficient to deranoe all the other rules and maxims. Their false gods confused the relations of human and divine. The consuming passion to fight and extinguish their enemies, and make this the glory and chief end of life, obscured all other employments. Their views as to marriage, and all that led to and flowed from it, were loose and arbitrary. Their dealings with the poor, the oppressed, tlie prisoner, and the captive, were pre-eminently marked, at the very least, by want of thought. Liberty of speech was some- what understood, but toleration, especially in religious belief, was unknown, and the mechanical appliances for that sublimation of free thought, known as the liberty of the press, were altogethc^r wanting. Violence and arbitrary imprisonment were without adequate check, and security was but a dream. Trial by jury, incorruptible judges, rules of evidence and jirocedure, did not throw their ramparts round the essential functions of life and property. That share in the machinery of government and legislation, CH. I.] MISTAKES OF ANCIENT LAW& 23 which ministers to iis all the enthusiasm and excitement of war, was then feebly attained. The maxims as to taxa- tion and liabeas corpus did not stir their passions like a trumpet. They sought to dragoon people into virtue by vexatious restrictions as to what they were to eat and drink, whom they were to entertain, what they were to spend, how they were to dress when living, and how they were to be Ijuried wlien dead. They can scarcely be blamed indeed for other tilings still obscure, as, for example, for not appreciating the true principles and bearings of imports and exports, supply and demand, for these still perplex enlightened nations of the present day.'^ Their sumptuary laws, their persecuting laws, their savage punishments, their arbitrary maxims of government, were imitated and acted on by all Em^opean nations till near the eighteenth century, and in some cases much later. Even the insight of Bacon did not save him from following the crowd in thinking these laws necessary.- In England the statutes of apparel, of labourers, of provisions, of conformity were the natural sequence and development of tlie old ideas of legislation hitherto too blindly and unconsciously followed. From all these we have been gradually working backwards, and emancipating ourselves with painful steps and slow. The Star Chamber, which was the lineal heir of the Areopagus, acted on the ambitious principle that " no wrong or injury, either public or private, can be done, but that it shall be reformed or punished in due course of law."^ And, though Coke thought the Star Chamber kept all England quiet, its notions of wrong and injury were too monstrous to be tolerated later than the seventeenth century. Raymond said of the Queen's Bench, " Why is it called the censor morum, if we cannot punish that which subverts all morality ?"* And even Lord Mansiield, C. J., so late as 1773, was found taking up and passing on the saying that " what- 1 The Cuineans were thought the most stupid people of all anti- quity for not putting an import duty on corn and merchandise. 2 Bac. Ess. 15. 3 Bagg's Case (1616), 6 Coke, 182. * 17 St. Tr. 153. Even the masterly Pym was found saying " it is the end of government that virtue should be cherished, vice siip- pressed." — Forster's Pym, 177. The highest way in which this can, be put is, that these are some of the ends of government, 24 ON THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT. [intro. ever is contra honos snores et decorum the principles of our law prohibit, and tlie king's court, as the general censor and guardian of tlie public manners, is bound to restrain and punish." ^ But it will be found that, however Aristotelian this language may sound, the fragment of truth behind it shrinks in practice to very small dimensions ; and that all that the courts can " punish and restrain " is trifling compared to the abounding wrongs and immoralities which no laws can put down, and which continually outrun all the processes of all the courts known to mankind. We now boast to be as tender of the lives of the lower animals as the ancients were of nine-tenths of the human race. And though there were noble and illustrious examples of an- tique virtue, our law, as a system of doctrines and maxims, seems to flow mostly from sources coming in the opposite direction, and is the product of far other thoughts, ten- dencies, and self-restraints. As far as the east is from the west, so far are our standards of life and our familiar instincts from theirs. For these reasons we may pause at the definition of law bequeathed to us by the ancients, and entertain a doubt as to whether from such materials as theirs they could possibly'derive a product, such as we can recognise and accept as a tit likeness of wdiat we now deem law to be." Objections to current standard dcjinition of law. — There are two radical objections to the standard definition of law already referred to. The first is, that law cannot correctly be said to prescribe or command a course of conduct at all. The second objection is, that there is no indication given of 1 Jones V. Randall, Lofft 385. 2 "The ancients devoted their attention more exclusively to the harmonious development of the individual man as man. The moderns are cMefly solicitous about his comfort, his prosperity, his j)r()ductiveness. The former looked to virtue : the latter seek for lia])piness." — Humltoli/l's SpJiere of Gov. Introd. It is singular that a veteran diplomatist of the age of William 111. should have spoken of the ancient institutions in the follow- ing extravagant terms, however worthy of one of the champions in the "Battle of the Books:" "The ancient political institutions show such a reach of thought, such a depth of wisdom, and such foi'ce of genius, as the presumption and ilattery itself of our age will hardly pretend to parallel by any of our modern civil institu- tions."—! Temi)le W. 4'J8. CH. I.] LAW NOT A COURSE OF CONDUCT. 25 the supposed object, which the supreme power has in view in making the law. Law docs not prescribe a course of conduct. — To say that the law lays down or commands a rule or course of con- duct is to say, that the law gives positive directions as to almost everything that man does or ought to do, at least as between man and man, A course of conduct includes the great bulk of man's actions — his habitual actions, not his occasional acts — his motives at eacli stage, and the manner of following these out. And this must be taken to be true of each individual, for the law speaks not to, a few, but to all and to each. But when one considers for a moment the vast variety of things that man undertakes, or is obliged to do — the inlinite details of business that pass before him, and the various motives that actuate him — how can it be said with truth that the law commands a course of conduct ? The phrase expresses too much or too little. A course of conduct includes all the thoughts, words, and actions of the day ; but to give detailed specific directions, even to one individual, as to what lie shall think, say, and do, when he shall turn to the right hand, and when to the left hand— when he shall speak, and when he shall be silent — would fill thousands of volumes. If it be said that a course of conduct does not mean all the minute details of each person's conduct, but only the leading outline, still the same objection recurs, for this qualification would only reduce to a tithe, or a hundredth, or a thou- sandth part of its bulk the vast body of details, which each individual would still require in order to learn even the outlines of his course of conduct. The world indeed could scarcely hold the volumes that such an undertaking of the law would require to be written. The definition of law which describes it as prescribing a course of conduct is thus obviously incorrect. The truth is rather the reverse. The law cares very little indeed as to the course of any man's conduct ; it neither undertakes to teach him, nor does it profess to know what his course of conduct is or ought to be. It prescribes nothing positive at all in the principal heads ; what it says is only negative. It does not command ; it only prohibits. It gives no positive directions either of morality, religion, justice, or good feeling. It merely restrains the actions of individuals in a few out of the 26 ON THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT. [jntro. variety of his occupations, and points out a formal mode of carrying out a few others. The law finds man in possession of appetites, passions, desires,^tendencies, which seek their several objects in an infinite variety of ways, and over a boundless area. And it is only a very small and insigni- ficant part of the actions done in pursuit of these objects, that the laM^ cares to know or concerns itself about. All that the law does in its substantive provisions is to restrain. It commands nothing except in the subsidiary maclnnery. It restrains only a few things. Like the good demon that attended Socrates, it may prevent one going wrong, but cainiot prompt one to do right It does not teach a man what to do, but only what to avoid, or how to accomplish a few things in a formal way. It does not supply the motive power or dictate the course of the journey : it only erects a finger-post here and there. To say then that the law prescribes or enforces a course of conduct, is as nearly as possible the converse of what it professes to do. An indi- vidual may do all that the law requires, or rather avoid all that the law prohibits, and yet if he knew nothing but what the law told him, he could scarcely survive a week. The great majority of the actions of each individual proceed from motives far beyond the reach of the law, and such as the law can neither give nor take away. The definition of law by Blackstone and Austin surveys the law from the wrong side. Another objection to current definition — it assigns no specific imrpose to Jmv. — Another radical objection to the current definition of law is, that such definition does not indicate at all what is tlie great and essential object which all laws propose, or rather which the legislature proposes to accom- pHsh by and through such laws. It is one thing to command without reasons given, and another thing to command with reasons given — one tiling to conquer the will, and another thing to lead captive tlie reason. Blind and passive obe- dience is only for slaves. Laws in a civilised community are addressed to human beings endowed Avith reason, conscious of freedom and power, and the pleasures of discretion and choice, having the capacity to reflect, to judge, and to feel. The virtue of laws now depends almost entirely on the assent and consent with which those to whom they are addressed discern and confess their necessity, CH. I.] NEW DEFINITION OF LAW. 27 and appreciate their full measure and tendency. It may be difficult, if not impossible, to explain many obscurities as to the origin, necessity, and final cause of all laws. None of the great thinkers of the world has yet succeeded in defining their tendency, scope, and ultimate destination, or to lay down any settled rules as to the bounds of their interference with the pursuits of individuals or classes of men. But in this inquiry two things are to be distinguished. All laws may have one generic object, and yet there may be various ways of accomplishing that object, both as regards the sul)ject-matter to be affected and the mode of affecting that subject-matter. The aim may be one and indivisible, and the ways of reaching it manifold. It may be possible to define the former, and not the latter. But the current definition states neither. What the course of conduct enforced by the supreme power relates to — what object is to Ije attained thereb}', or why it is to be attained, is not stated. The definition merely speaks of something being enforced — it speaks of a blind obedience, without indicating why that obedience is exacted, what good it is to do, and what length it goes or ought to go ; and in this vital, essential element the current definition of law is conspicuously defective. A new definition of nuinici^yal laiv. — These two radical objections to the current definition of law naturally give rise to the demand for one that will be free from such objections, if, indeed, any such can be found. Such a definition seems to be this : — " Law is the sum of the varied " restrictions on the actions of each individual, which the " supreme power of the state enforces, in order that all its " members may follow their occupations with greater " security." This definition, instead of representing the body of law as consisting of a course of conduct, confines the attention to the more limited purpose of controlling some only of the actions of men, either directly by restraining these, or indirectly by defining forms for giving greater effect to them, and that not entirely by way of positive command, but mainly by way of negative prohibition. It also points to the general purpose kept in view by the supreme legislative power. It does not indeed necessarily imply that that purpose is secured by the right means. It merely 28 ON THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT. [intro. states the object which is always professed, or is that which alone can be legitimately professed. The object may not be in fact attained, or it may be attained or sought to be attained by the WTong means. The means, however, which are used, and the subject-matter as to which restrictions are imposed, cannot be exactly stated or even indicated, for the simple reason that no human sagacity or acuteness has yet defined how far these restrictions may or ought to go in the further development of modern civilisation. It is the main business of politics to discuss and find a solution for eacli particular exigency. It is enough that the law proposes well, and does its best for the time being to decide what will most effectively secure the general good. In order, however, to explain fully this definition, it will be necessary to examine more minutely its several parts. Law is a oxstriction on human actions. — That law is the sum of the varied restrictions upon the actions of each individual, is the fundamental conception iniderlying its whole structure. Those writers who define law to be a course of action or of conduct lose sight of the manifest truth, that while the course of conduct consists of the whole acts and deeds of men, these spring from so many sources, that it would be idle to say that the law directed them, or even a thousandth part of them. Those sources are far too deep and subtle for any law to intercept or suppress, to guide, or even to watch. Men would go on satisfying their hunger, gratifying their feelings, desires, and passions, amassing and squandering property, bargaining, quarrelling, and domineering over each other, just the same if there were no laws at alL And though the par- ticular details of the law, when such are enacted, influence greatly the general happiness, yet this good is not effected by any radical or material change which they produce in the conduct of men. The mass of men's actions remains the same whatever the laws may be. It is only in the slcill with which one restriction is directed here and another there, and in the skill with which the superficial tendencies of human actions are balanced and played off one against another, that the total result becomes bene- ficiah That result moreover is the fruit of reason and reflection, and does not immediately flow from anything CH. I.] LAW IS A RESTRICTION. 29 the law can do. The law affects human conduct by and through the reason. To trace all the secret springs wliich render law suitable to the circumstances of a people, and which invigorate instead of harassing their multifarious energies and occupations, lias been the theme of many dis(i^uisitions of curious inquirers. It is, however, too remote from our business, and it may be left in the hands of the legislators, whose occupation it is to discover what would be good laws and what would be bad laws before it is resolved to enact them, or what to preserve and what to amend of those that have already been enacted. It may for our present purpose be assumed that each individual carries within his own breast some standard, by which he can readily appraise their value and test by experience what is just and what is unjust. Mankind have, as Cicero observed, a genius for law. The vast populations of to-day are controlled by very few courts and judges. They gravitate towards law as if towards the inevitable. The common sense of mankind is thus often a better gauge than all the theories of the learned or the decrees of the powerfid, as to where the law should begin and where it should end. But whether a law is good or bad, it acts mainly by way of restriction on some of the tendencies of men. The law prohibits each individual from murdering or assaulting or imprisoning his neighbour, from seizing another's property, from marrying certain persons, or more than one at a time, from breaking his contract, from slandering another's character, from interfering with another's mode of worship.^ But it cannot be supposed 1 " Laws, whether founded on a right or a wrong' exercise of reason, are always intended to act as restraints on the actions of indiviihials and to interfere with the motives by which their conduct woukl be otherwise determined. This restraint mayJbe said to be artificial, as opposed to the natural restraints of the individual reason : and this perhaps is the distinction most generally intended when the natural conduct of men is contrasted with their conduct under the control of positive institutions. But as the motives which determine indi- vidual conduct are not always reasonable motives, so it is clear that what men naturally do is no sure test either of what they ought to do, or of what they ought to be allowed to do. It is their nature inider certain conditions to do all that is bad and injurious to themselves and others. Hence it is the most difficult of all problem < in the science of government to determine, when, where, and how i : is wise to interfere by the authority of law with the motives whiclt 30 ON THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT. [intro. that it is the law that creates just enough of motive and jDassion to lead to each lawful human action, or that if there were no law, all those motives and passions would be extinguished. On the contrary, all that is positive in the motives and tendencies existed before law began, and will outlive all the changes that the law will ever cause. The law confronts the irrepressible instincts and tendencies, and confesses that it can cope with them only circuitousl}' through the medium of the understanding. It merely prunes the exuberant foliage, docks the towering branches, guides the roots to the one side or the other. The roots, the trunk, and the branches flourish as before ; the individual identity continues, though the motive power and the intricate organisation are prevented from being mischievous to society. The source of much of the confusion on this subject is traceable to Aristotle, who thought that law positively are usually called the natural motives of men. The question is no other than this — How far the abuse of those motives can be checked and resisted by that public authority whose duty and function it is to place itself above the influences which in individual men over- power the voice of reason and of conscience." — D. of Argyirs lieign of Laid, 86G (3rd ed.). Adam Smith says: "Mere justice is upon most occasions but a negative virtue, and only hinders us from hurting our neighbours. We may often fulfil all the rules of justice by sitting still and doing wAhms::'— Smith's Theorij, p. 2, § 2. Dr. Johnson also had a clear notion of this truth. He said : " The primary notion of law is restraint in the exercise of natural right." 1 Boi)w. Johns. 38. And again : " Political liberty is good only so far as it produces private liberty."— 3 Bosw. Johns. 53. Bentham says the principal function of government is to protect individuals from suifering. — 1 Benth. W. 301. GuizoT says a civil government in its code comprehends only those actions morally culpable and socially dangerous. — Guizot Civ. Eur. Lee. 15. Windham (H.C. 1809, 14 Pari. Deb. J 031) said " Laws were almost universally restrictive. They restrained acts whicii were injurious to the community, and were such, moreover, as could be defined." The same idea is noticed by St. Paul : " The law was not made for the righteous, but for the unruly and the disobedient." — 1 Tim. i. 9 ; Pet. 1. ii. 9. De Lolme was surprised in his keen researches at not finding any English statute enacting the liberty of the press, till he began at last to refiect that it existed simply because it was not forbidden. — De Lolme on the Const. cir. 1.] LAW GIVES FORMS OF RESTRICTIONS. 31 prescribed all the virtues. He says : " The law directs the performance of brave acts, such as standing at one's post, neither fleeing nor throwing away one's arms — also acts of temperance, such as not committing adultery or violence — also acts of moderation, as neither assaulting nor abusing others. And in like manner with the virtues and vices, it enjoins one class of actions and forbids others. As the proverb says, In justice all virtue is comprehended." ^ He also says, "Whatever the law does not command it for- bids.'"-^ The Eoman maxim was the reverse, and nearer the truth, namely, thtit what the law does not forbid it permits. The correct maxim, however, is, that, what the law does not forbid, it leaves each to do or not to do as he pleases, and altogether declines to know or care any- thing about the decision he may come to.^ Laiv includes forms for giving effect to some human actions. — But in defining all laws as in the nature of restrictions, there is still something to be added. A distinc- tion is necessary between those laws which are primary and those which are secondary and subsiditiry. Some laws are merely modes of carrying out the principle contained in otlier laws. The principle is always to be distinguished from the machinery necessary to work it out. A survey of the laws discloses, that a partial restriction only is imposed in many cases, and that an exception is allowed, which is declared to be the only legal mode of giving effect to the human tendency restrained. For example, when it is once determined to restrain the tendency to marry, it is found not to be enough to prohibit marriage with certain individuals, but a form is given by which marriage, even when not prohibited, is to be carried out, in order to define with greater certainty who are and 1 Arist. Eth. b. V. cli. i., § 11, 12. ^ Ibid. b. v. ch. xi. 3 " The ancient conanonwealths and philosophers countenanced the regulation of every part of private conduct by pubHc autiiority, on the ground that the state had a deep interest in the whole bodily and mental discipline of every one of its citizens — a mode of think- ing whicli may have been admissible in small republics, surrounded by powerful enemies, in constant peril of being subverted by foreign attack or internal conunotion, and to which even a short interval of relaxed energy and self-command might so easily be fatal, that they could not afford to wait for the salutary permanent effects of freedom."—/. S Mill, On Lib. 23. 32 ON THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT. [intro. who are not married, as a guide to those whom siicJi knowledge affects in one way or another. While buying and selling, giving and bequeathing, are prohibited in some cases altogether, it is yet found expedient to provide a form, or something approaching a form, according to which certain contracts, wills, and solemn acts, which are not otherwise interfered with, must be carried out, before the law will regard these as effective and binding. More- over, in those parts of the law which will be found to be subsidiary, and to consist merely in machinery for giving effect to the primary laws, such parts consist of forms which must be followed in order to attain more quickly and easily certain objects. Thus in the departments of legislative, judicial, and executive law many of the details consist of formal steps for passing new laws, for electing members of the legislature, for executing sentences and orders of courts of law. The forms thus incorporated into the law are the only parts which can be correctly described as positive law. They are, at most, a small part of the law, and are more or less subordinate and auxiliary to the primary or substantive laws, all of which, as already stated, are merely restrictions on the acts of man, and the forms themselves are only another name for restrictions, for without them mankind would choose many concurfeut ways to the same end. Part of definition — that law is enforced by the sui^reme ■power of the state. — The laws consist not merely of restric- tions, but it is an essential characteristic, tiiat these should be enforced by the supreme power of the state. Who or what then is the supreme power of the state ? If one surveys! mankind from China to Peru, it will be obvious that the supreme power of a state assumes various forms. There may be a republic, or there may be a monarchy, or some of the many intermediate organisations made up of various elements common to both ; and the permutations of these ele- ments are so various that the resultant force can scarcely be described, except by comparing and contrasting the leading characteristics of other like forces. Whatever be the structure composed out of so many materials, the supreme power is only a synonym for that human voice which cannot ])e resisted by any one individual or by any minor combination of them short of the majority ; for whenever en. I.] WHAT IS THE SUPEEME POWER ? 33 one resists it, all the other individuals readily comLine consciously or unconsciously to uphold it. Each indi- vidual is thus crushed in detail, and the aggregate power of all the individuals who live in one community thus becomes a continuous, and it may be indefinable, source of power, Avhicli carries all before it. An irresistible power, reigning absolute over all the individuals in the state, must arrogate or exercise all the means of enforcing; or com- polling each individual to act — so far at least as any one can be said to be compellable by the superior force of all the rest. When a number of individuals within a defined area are all living subject to and ackuowledgin-'- one common law, wdiich is the emanation of one supreme power, or is adopted by it — when such laws are mado without the dictation of any persons living without the area — when all the difficulties that can arise between the individuals are solved by means found within the same area and irrespectively of any power or dominion else- where — then all may be said to be living in one separate and independent self-governing state. The supreme power is merely the organ of the entirety of individuals so living together, and it is of necessity designed and known to be irresistible and inevitable.^ Life in society is impossible without such mutual relations and such a common bond. Each individual must obey such laws whatever they may be. That there must be a supreme power in every state or in every self-dependent community, is an axiom which cannot be explained, but which must nevertheless be assumed. The whole current and complexion of human faculties and tendencies lead irresistibly to this settled condition of social life. All human affairs gravitate to it. Even in the rudest forms of states, there is a similar power, whether lodged in the patriarch or the elders of the tribe, and it is usually found to assume by turns a legislative, a judicial, and an executive phase. AH men, consciously or unconsciously, restrain themselves in presence of it and accept its arbitrament as final and irreversible. Whenever 1 Austin defines a sovereign to be " a determinate human superior not in the habit of obedience to a like superior who receives habitual obedience from the bulk of a given society, and such society is dee lied a political and independent society, anel the impossible would be avoided. It was not till 1830 that a bill was brought in to abolish this purposeless and indiscriminate imprisonment. — 22 Pari. Deb. (2nd) 375. So late as 1750, the most powerful court in tlie world, the ON THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT. [intro. And most of the governments of the world, after centuries of experience, have been made to learn, that laws are made for tlie benefit of the governed as well as of the governors — and obviously rather more for the benefit of the governed, because they are the more numerous, unless, indeed, all can agree to arrange themselves upon one level, and acknowledge the absolute supremacy of the law without distinction of ranks or mutual relations. Easiest mode of enforcing laio is to alloiv the subject to share in malcing lavj. — Most nations, after exhausting other plans, must sooner or later discover that the surest way to secure ready obedience to the law is to provide means whereby each individual subject can take a part more or less direct in framing and devising the law^s he is to obey, for obedience to self-made laws is easy and pleasant, and is congenial to all men in all circumstances and ages. A law, however wise or prudent, if made by one or many acting without consent, consultation, or co- operation of the individual subjects to be governed, has and w^ill always have a certain bitterness altogether irre- spective of its merits ; and this bitterness recurs, and will recur while society exists. But when laws are the fruit of choice and deliberation, and the joint labour of the House of Commons, was apparently irritated and dismayed at tlie discovery, that it could not compel a prisoner at its bar to do so simple II thing as bend his knee and confess his fault if he was minded not to do so. And as all the threats of power were wasted on one prisoner in vain, the House at last admitted its inability to achieve the impossible, and contented itself with imprisoning the refractory culprit a little longer, and then discharging him. — B.e Murray, 14 Pari. Hist. 894. At the same time the House resolved in future not to insist on a condition so easily baftled. And the House of Lords in hke manner has confessed the impossibility of enforcing this einii)le act of kneeling from prisoners at its bar, and no longer insists on it.- — May's Pari. Pr. 110. In Holland it was said to be once the law, that if the criminal would not admit the justice of his sentence lie was pressed to death. — 14 Pari. Hist. 10C6. Tiiat practice was no worse than our own law, which was not repealed till 1772, by which a prisoner who stood nr.ute on being arraigned, and would neither plead guilty nor not guilty, was pressed to death.— 12 Geo. III. c. 20 ; 7 & 8 Ceo. IV. 0.^^27, § 2. ^cQpost, ch, vii. 'Jlie legislature has, from similar views, at last ceased to regulate the details of private lil'e by suni])tuary laws, has ceased to regulate literature by a censorship, and religion by an inquisition. CH. I.] WHAT IS THE OBJECT OF LAW ? 39 governed and the governor, and approach the most nearly to self-made laws on both sides — as all laws do which proceed from a legislature to wliich the subjects send representatives — this partnership of feeling and of self- interest engages all the prejudices of human nature in its service, and thereby draws after it a willing obedience, and the greatest triumph of civilisation is thereby completely achieved.^ Tlie object of latv is, that all individuals may follovj their occiqjations iviih greater security. — It seems at first sight singular, that after the vast experience of mankind in making, unmaking, altering, amending, and rewriting laws, one cannot easily arrive at some definite conclusion as to what the object of all laws is— what they propose to do, and by what means. Yet it is here that the greatest difficulty arises. If all were agreed as to the precise object and the precise means which the law pursues, there would scarcely be room for the mistakes that are made — the heats and dissensions — the evil predictions — the threats, the denunciations — the party conflicts — the false aims, the false steps — the happy strokes, the disastrous blunders, tl:ut preside in turn over the birth and alteration of most laws. The great writers and thinkers have not been at one in this point. They have put forth many theories to cover the obscure, and to make less dark that which was already dark. They say that the object of law is to promote the general happiness — to promote the virtues of fortitude and temperance — to pursue justice — the general good — whatever is right — to obey the will of God— to do to others as we would they should do to us — to give to everyone his due and hurt nobody — to protect property— to protect 1 ERSKiNEsaid "the people should be taught that government is a trust proceeding from themselves — an emanation from their own strength— a benefit and a blessing, which has stood the test of ages, that fhey are governed because they desire to be governed, and yield a voluntary obedience to the laws because the laws protect them in the liberties they en]oy. "—Ersk. Speeches. GuizoT says : '' The highest perfection of government is to avoid compulsion, and substitute for it purely moral means— aii influence over the understanding. Therefore that government, in which com- pulsion is least employed, is that which is most conforjnable to its true nature, and most completely fulfils its duties."— (th/so<, Cio. Eur. Lect. 5. 40 ON THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT. [intro. nil from injury — to promote the self-interest of each — the greatest happiness of the greatest number — the good order of society — the punishment of wickedness — the just re- lations existiuo- between various classes — the eternal fitness of tilings. Phrases such as these may contain much that is true, and yet express too much or too little. They are manifestly vafTue, and more obscure than the thing defined. One requires only to take a chapter of the law in its detailed form and endeavour to test it by any of these guiding principles, in order to admit how impossible it is to find or pursue the thread. Those seem to err most who assume that it is possible to give to the law any abstract and sweeping object, such as the pursuit of virtue or happiness. All nations must have laws, and probably there is, or ought to be, a motive and object nearly the same in all. Yet when we reflect out of what crude forms the most highly-developed laws of modern civilisation seem to have been evolved — how entirely empirical the law has been in its progress — how new rules and new ideas seem to have been little else than the haphazard saws and apophthegms of some individual a little wiser than his contemporaries, but whose best thoughts were sufficiently appreciated to be acted upon, till a better and stronger man arose who could see further- 'into the future, and had newer and still better methods to suggest — when all this groping by the way is considered, it is easy to excuse the ancient legislators from exhibiting any well- defined aim, or aspiring to too lofty a moral purpose. The records of barbarous tribes seem to disclose the fact that there are few germs corresuonding to our leading laws. The barbaric mind is incapable of generalising, except in the imperfect fashion of children. To expect savages to comprehend such abstract notions as personal freedom, culpable homicide, pauperism, education, wills, bills of exchange, would be to expect them to speak in unknown tongues. If civilisation were to be traced step by step, perhaps all the law at first required for each member of a tribe would be found to be nothing more definite than the measure of the patriarch's will. When two or more patriarclis joined their families, this feeling would become a calculation of the propensities displayed in conmion by two or more rulers OH. I.] OBJECT OF LAW IS SECURITY. 41 till a ruler ol rulers appeared, who claimed supreme atten- tion, and set generalisation again at work. Polygamy, slavery, witchcraft, protection against theft and assault seem to take shape among the first settled habits, and habits are the laws of barbarians; but the order of deve- lopment and the particular impulse given to one habit rather than another are too obscure to warrant any dogmatic conclusions. The history of different races of mankind, the I'easons why some seem to have for ages remained stationary — some to have deteriorated or disappeared — others to have outstripped the rest — and why some habits afterwards become matured as doctrines of law and flourish more among one race than another — why the best laws when sown in some soils fall on stony ground, flourish for a while, and then decay — all these mysteries furnish endless speculations, and echo and re-echo along the lines of history without leaving anv certain voice. P)Ut whatever may have been the order in which law arose, this much is certain, that law in some vague and crude form must have always accompanied the association of human beinos. These associations mav have l>een casual or permanent — small in numbers or great ; but each and all the individuals composing it must have had some_occu- pation, even if it were the occupation of idleness, and 'each must have had some sense of restraint. The two things are inseparable, and the mutual complement of each other. If the meniljcrs of the tribe took to liunting, or fishing, or tilling the ground, or tending cattle, or exchanging goods for things thought A^alualde, each of these several occupations nmst have been wholly impossible without a sense of mutual restraint — vague and indefinite though it might be. The patriarch of his tribe could never have been sure of a meal — he nmst have worked at the work of Sisyphus, if he could not sleep in peace and in the consciousness, that when he rose in the morning he would still remain master of yesterday's acquisitions. Whatever might be the work of the day, he would require to be satisfied that he had not to repeat it on the morrow ; and yet, unless his companions divined his wishes and abstained from peculation and all interl'erence, this could never become a settled conviction. The greater the number of the tribe, the greater would be the need for restraints to correspond — the more urgent it 42 ON THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT. [ixti:o. would be safely to guaid tlie hoard which so many hungry eyes surrounded. In this sense it would he of no import- ance what were the circumstances of the society or the occupations of its members, for the same principles would apply. All employments end in a store for the future, and that little capital would require to be secured against the depredations of others equally anxious to gain an invest- ment, and still more anxious to do so without the trouble of working for it. Tlie same circle of cares would be repeated through all the succeeding stages of advancement, however complicated might become the labours, the desires, and the possessions of individuals. What each would seek above all things would be — not to be interfered with by others^ — to be let alone— to pursue his occupations to their logical conclusion — to reap where he had sown — to sleep behind his own ramparts — and to riot in the luxury of possession. Securit// is the end and scope of all municipal laivs. — What then can be the scope and end of all laws, but simply to further and render more certain and secure whatever occu- pation each individual has thought fit to adopt ? The less others interfere witli him, and the less he interferes with others, each has more time of his own — better repose and more strength — he gets in the long run more of what he wants, and loses less than lie would lose, if there were perpetual interference, perpetual robberies, and perpetual recaptures — stratagems by night and battles by day — each carrying his life in his hand, and seeing an enemy in every bush. Here, then, is the true sphere of the law. The law has and can have no other object than simply to secure to each the utmost possible value — the widest field — the securest enjoyment for his varied employments. It is this security against interference, wliich makes all grades of civilisation ' The Chinese code states that the chief ends proposed by the institution of })unislinieiits in the empire have been to guard against violence and injury, to rcjiress inordinate desires, and to secure the peace and tranquillity of an honest and unoffending community. — Staunton's Code of China, Lwii. Not unlike this was the beginning of the written laws of the Lond)ards in the edict of King Eothai-is (a.d. G44). "The object of the edict was to relieve the poor from oppression, and restrain the insolence of the rich and great, that every oTie might live in peace and enjoy jiis property undisturbed. " — Leg, Longub. CH. 1.] LAW DOES NOT ENFOKCE VIRTUE. 43 akiu — which is the universal haven in which nations find rest. There are degrees of intensit}', of dehcacy, of completeness ; but it is one fundamental and indivisible consciousness underlying all the A^'iriations of race, and climate, and soil. The rude barbarian can appreciate it as I'ully as the polished citizen. The untutored Indian, who carries all his goods on his back — who finds a home under every tree — who gives few hostages to fortune — enjoys a sense of security against his equals as sensibly, though not so intensely, as the merchant prince, whose corn, and cattle, and servants are scattered over many provinces, whose ships ride in every sea, and whose note of hand is sold in all tlie markets of the world. Object of law is not to enforce virtue. — If therefore law be the restraint enforced in order to secure more effectually to each the benefits of his own occupations, there is avoided much of the vagueness and mystery surrounding those definitions which give no motive at all, or identify that motive with the knowledge or pursuit of what is right. Tliat the law necessarily enforces what is right cannot be contended, and yet that there must be some motive is equally apparent. The supreme power, whether centred in one person or in many, may make mistakes, and must often retrace its steps. There is a conscience attending the exercise of all power which requires to be educated. Not only may the supreme power make mistakes, but it is con- scious that its power, tliough supreme, is limited in all directions. It has not the power nor the capacity to make men religious or moral, though some vague conception of such an attempt may have haunted most of the early legislators, and has led to many mistakes in all ages. What is right and what is wrong is a problem, not more easy, at the same time that it is not more difficult to be solved by the legislature than by the individual. But the legislature has neither the organs to discover, nor the machinery to enforce, nor the time to watch religion or morality among the peoj)le. This would be too ambitious and universal an empire; and yet some restraints for order's sake may be classed under the head of assisting and protecting those who do good. In civilised states the promotion of religion and virtue is an occupation of many, and requires the same protection as other occupations. 44 ON THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT. [intro. What the law orders or requires is however no^; necessarily identified with what is right, and it is frequently made the instrument of what is wrong. A man may do all that the law requires, may avoid all that the law forbids, may be blameless in its eyes ; lie may pass his life without even once directly invoking its aid, or provoking its punishment, and yet he may be of no esteem, but rather a scorn and derision among his fellows. Just lie may be, for the law to some extent makes this compulsory; but beyond this he may be the negation of all that is worthy and of good report. The law deals only with the outward acts of man ; Init beyond the range of the visiljle there is a vast and widening empire, into which no legal procoses can run — the seat of feelings and contemplations and the stable joys of life. A^oluminous as the law is, it would require to be a thousand times more vohiminous if it were to incorporate all the precepts of moralists and the delicate distinctions of casuists and divines. It is impossible for the law to rule where nothing can be seen, or heard, or felt, and where all the movements are silent, and the result incomprehensible and incommunicable.^ ^ GuizoT observes : '' When societies have attained a. qreat develop- ment morality is no longer written in their codes. The legislature leaves it to manners, to the intluence of opinion, to the free wisdom of men's wills : it expresses only civil obligations and the jjunish- ments instituted against crimes. But between these two terms of civilisation, between the infancy of societies and their greatest development, there is an epoch when the legislature takes possession of morality, digests, publishes it, commands it — when the declaration of duties is considered as the mission, and one of the most powerful mediums of the law." — 3 Guiz. Civ. Fr. Lect. 9. Aristotle seemed to tliiuk that civil sooiet}' is founded, " not merely that its members might live, but that they might live well, for the lirst care of the legislator must be that its citizens should be virtuous ;" " otherwise," he said, " civil society wouW be merely an alliance for .self-defence." "A state," he said, " is a society of people joining Together, witli their families and tlieir children, to live well for the sake of a perfect and independent hfe." — Arist. Fol. b. 8, c. 11. Modern nations, however, have arrived at a conclusion the converse of Aristotle's, for they seem all agreed that his secon^lary object is their main object, namely, that s(x,'iety is an alliance for sell'-delence, and his priuuuy object is their secondary object, that of making citizens virtuous. Tliis latter object is bej^ond the scope, and baffles the ambition of all govermnents. It nuiy be assisted indirectly, but cannot and ought not to be attempted (lirectl3'. The empire of virtue cu. I.] LAW DOES NOT DICTATE ExAIPLOYMENTS. 45 Law does not dictate occupations. — Another thing to he noticed, is that the law can only give security to the occupations of individuals after each individual has dis- covered and entered on them. It does not pretend to teach individuals how to live— how to work, what to do, or what they can do best. It is true that in Mexico and Peru the lower classes could follow no craft, no amusement or labour, nor even marry, without leave of the govern- ment.^ But this close paternal care has been rarely attempted even by the ancients. Each may be trusted to find faculties and impulses wherewith to employ himself, and wdiicli the law can neither give nor take away. The vast variety of human occupations are not the creatures of the law, though the law can do much to make these occupations fruitful. The seed is already sown in the ground ; the law only keeps the birds of the air from devouring it.- is not of this world, and is maintained and extended by arts anil methods nearly altogether irrespective of human laws. Robert Hall, a great writer, traced giuiilar ideas with admirable felicity and power in his Aj)ology for the Freedom of the Prens. AsHLiRST, J., said : " It is beyond the power of the law to rectify men's minds, and to infuse into them that noble fire which burns in the breasts of good men, and prompts them to doing of praiseworthy actions, and promoting tlie hap])iness of their country and the good of their fellow-creatures ; but it is in the power of the law to take from evil-minded men the ability of doing mischief, and to restrain them of that hberty which they so grossly abuse." — 22 St. Tr. 234. C. J. Fox said that the state had no right to inquire into the opinions of people, cither political or religious ; it had a right to take cognisance only of their actions. — 28 Pari. Hist. 12G7. i WikofE's Civilis. 10. ^ Pym — " The law is that which puts a difference betwixt good and evil, betwixt just and unjust. If you take away the law, all tilings will fall into a contusion. Every man will become a law to himself ; lust will become a law, and envy will become a law : covetousness and ambition will become laws. . . . The law is the bcjundary, the measure betwixt the king's prerogative and the people's liberty. Whilst these move in their own orbs they are a support and a sccui ity to one anotlier. The prerogative alone is a defence to the liberty of the people, aird the people, by their liberty, enabled to be a founda- tion to the prerogative ; but if these bounds be-so removed that they enter into contestation and conflict, one of these mischiefs unist ensue : if the prerogative of the king overwhelm the liberty of the people, it will be turned into tyranny ; if liberty undermine the |)rerogative, it will grow into anarchy. . . . The law is the safe- guard, the custody of all urivate interests. Your honours, yjur live.-. 46 ON THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT. [intro. The current divisions of municipal law. — When tlie defi- nition of law is ascertained, the next task is to divide the law into its leading departments. Here also considerable diversity of treatment has prevailed. It is at this point that the philosophers and moralists part company with the jurists and practical lawyers. All may with equal justice claim some qualification to define law and its province, for to do so requires no special familiarity with the details of the science. But in order to distribute the materials under distinct heads — to assign the place of each leading doctrine, and proceed from generals to particulars, much special knowledge is all but essential. Accordingly, in this part of the subject there are fewer authorities, and those which exist are more strictly technical and practical than in the other. It is here also that the peculia^^ tendency of the legal temperament begins to manifest itself — the tendency to follow with more fidelity than reflection whatever some great master has laid down on some previous occasion more or less akin to the present. One division i7iio judicature, legislature, and government. — At the outset one large division of the law suggests itself — that which distinguishes the judicature, the Ingislature, and the government. Aristotle remarked that in all states there must be, first a legislative power, secondly, a power of government, and thirdly, a judicial power.^ And Mon- tesquieu and later writers make or repeat the same distinc- tion.2 But these divisions do not touch the substantive law : they are rather the means of giving effect to that law.^ your liberties and estates are all in the keeping of Ihe law. With- out this every man hath a like right to any thing." — Forstcrs Pym, 169. FiLANGiERi said his conclusion was, that a government should in- terfere as little as possible, and let everything take its own course. — Filang. Set. dcUa Lccjisl. ch. 11. Human laws are made, not to punish sin, but to prevent crime and mischief. — Pollock, C.-]3. Att.-Gen v. Sillem, 2 H. & C. 526. 1 Arist. Pol. b. 4, ch. xvi, « L'Esprit, b. ii. ch. 6, 3 Montesquieu, Esprit des Lois, h. 1, ch. 3. " Law in general is human reason, and is either political law or civil law. The former is the law relative to the governors and the governed, the latter is the law relative to the mutual relations of citizens. The largest degree of liberty which the constitution and circumstances of the country will permit is the object in view. Liberty is the right of doing whatever the laws permit." — B. 11, ch. iii. cii. I.] ONE TART OF LAW ADMINISTRATIVE. 47 The substantive law consists of all the legal rights and duties which exist between man and man. The administrative law gives effect to, maintains, and enforces this substan- tive law. These three distinctions manifestly pervade all law. Every analysis must find them as ultimate facts incapable of further simplification. Tlie substantive law is the object and end of the judiciary, legislative, and governing powers. These are nothing but means and machinery. By this, however, it is not meant that they are inferior in interest or importance. On the contrary, a machinery and an orderly procedure are often the most im- portant parts of the whole economy of national rights. They include the forces which keep the commonwealth in healthy workinij order. Under the head of the judicature is found the settled mode of appointing judges and securing to them the means of independent judgment, of obtaining for litigants an impartial hearing, a trial by jury, a system of trustworthy evidence, an inexorable and rigorous enforcement of judg- ments. Under the head of the legislature, tlie smooth M'orking of the law depends greatly on the election and appointment of representatives of all the great interests and forces which make up the nation — the security of public meetings — easy access for all to suggest improve- ments and mitigate anomalies and hardships — the intro- duction and publication of new statutes— the assent and consent of the governed — all that accompanies and makes up the complete accord between the growth of the law and enlightened public opinion. Under the head of government or executive power we trace the modes of securing mutual respect and harmony between sovereign and subject by a fixed succession in one royal family — the accessibility of the subject to the sovereign^the distribution of social honours— the power of pardon— the control of military and Locke on this subject says, that as " the laM'S have a constant and lasting force, and need a perpetual execution, or an attendance there- unto, therefore it is necessary that there should be a power always ill being which should see to the execution of the laws that are made and remain in force. And thus the legislative and executive power come often to be separated. There are two powers — the executive and the federative — the former comprehending the execution of the municipal laws of the society within itself upon all that are parts of it : the other the management of the security and interest of the public without, with all."— Zoc/tf, On Govt. h. ii. tits. 144-147. 48 ON THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT. [intro. naval forces — the defences of the nation — the orderinf]^ and conduct of war — a vigilant protection of those subjects of tlie reahn who liave resorted to foreign countries. By these and like methods the irresistible force of sovereign power is tempered to the tenderest concerns of the subject, so that the meanest peasant feels that his little all is guarded by the same puissant arm that subdues provinces, gives away kingdoms, and battles the armaments of foreign invaders. Judicature, legislature, and government are viachinerTj to worh the substantive laiu. — Taking the judicature, the legis- lature, and the government as three distinct departments of the law, they are each and all in the nature of machinery. The "reat substantive law remains outstanding, and embodies the mutual relations of subject and subject — their rights, their wrongs — their remedies, their duties, their privileges, their securities. It is true some of these are closely inter- woven with the relations between subject and sovereign, sub- ject and legislature, subject and judge. But it is to achieve and maintain the substantive law that these three great functions are devised — functions which, moreover, are mostly executed by subjects chosen from their fellow- subjects. Thus the whole system of legal relations and rights is compactly built up. But to achieve and main- tain in perpetual vigour the body of substantive law, judges, senators, and sovereign combine, and go hand in hand. For this result sovereigns reign, legislatures devise and amend laws, and judges decree justice.^ Divisions of the substantive law. — The divisions of the ^ "Tlie administration of government, like agnardiansliip, ouglit to be directed to the good of those who confer, and not of those who receive, the trust." — Cic. De Off. b. i, ch. sxv. "It is manifest that tlie power of kings and magistrates is notliing else but what is only derivative, transferred and committed to them in trust from the people to the common good of them all, in whom the power yet remains fundamentally, and cannot be taken from them without violation of their natural birthright, and from hence Aristotle and the best of political writers have defined a king, ' him who governs to the good and profit of his people, and not for his own ends.' " — Milton's Ten. of Kings. Bolingbrokp: says : " Kings are made for kingdoms, and not king- doTris for kings. Majesty is not an inherent, but a reflected light." — Tiolinfjhr. Pa r. King. ^ CH. I.] EOMAN DIVISION OF LAW. 49 - r~ — ' — ■ substantive law are not so various as the definitions of law, for philosophers have taken no part in them. Lawyers and jurists have been left in undisturbed possession. The ancient legislators cared little for method. The Eoman law was the first subjected to systematic and critical treatment, and supplied the outline of the current divi- sions, at least until the time of Bentham. Divisions of laiv in Roman and foreign ivriters on lato. — The method of Gains, who confines himself to the treatment of private law only, that is, the law as between subject and subject of the commonwealth, is to subdivide the law into the law of persons, law of things, and law of actions. Such also is the division of Justinian's Institutes. As regards this division, it is enough to say that the law of actions applies indiscriminately to both the other divi- sions, and is indeed a necessary supplement to both. And the law of persons has no clear boundary dividing it fi'om the law of things, either in fact or theory, for things may be said to have no existence except by and through persons. Domat abandoned the Eoman division of law into persons, things, and actions, and divided all private law into two main parts, viz., engagements and successions. Encasements were subdivided into those common to in- dividuals, and those common to individuals affected by certain relations of family and marriage. Successions included wills and legal distribution and descent. This division was far-fetched, and obviously leaves out, or at least leaves in a subordinate position, what is felt to be of pre-eminent interest and importance. Leibnitz enlarged on the defects of the celebrated divi- sion of law into persons, things, and actions, which had been originally published by Gaius and adopted by Justi- nian in his Institutes. He sought to divide jurisprudence into as many parts as there are causes which produce rights and obligations. These he analysed into five. The first was nature, which gives the liberty and power of dealing with that which is the property of no one. 2. Succession, by which the rights of deceased persons are transferred to heirs. 3. Possession. 4. Contract. 5. Injury. This division had much merit, but cannot be said to be VOL. I. E 50 ON THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT. [inteu. exhaustive, or to bring out all the chief causes of rights and obligations.^ ^ Vico expressed an idea that legislation, dealing with man as he is, found him the slave of three vicious passions, which distracted all mankind — ferocity, avarice, ambition — which produced the army, commerce, and the court. These three great vices were moderated by legislation, and converted into sources of civil order and felicity. — Vico, Nuov. Sci. degli Elem. The same author observed that all nations, barbarous or civilised, separated by time and space, yet agreed in three customs. All have a religion, all solemnly contract marriages, all bury their dead. These were three eternal and universal customs, and were the first principles according to which all nations arose and are preserved. Vico, however, was wrong as to the two latter universal customs, as records of manj' tribes show that marriage and burial are not universal characteristics. The grounds are moreover too vague to suggest any methodical division. Kant adopted the general di\asion of the duties of law according to Ulpian : 1. Honeste vivere. 2. Neminem Icedere. 3. Suum cuique tribuere. These three maxims can, however, be viewed as nothing but phases of one fundamental conception, each being only a different mode of expressing the same thing. In order to know what is the meaning of not injuring anyone, we must know what is an injury, and that again implies that we know what each is entitled to as his own, and what is the complement of legal rights — in other words, each of these phrases amounts to little more than saying that law is law. It is too indefinite to be of use in arriving at an insight into the structure of the law, and is obviously founded on no clear analysis. The French code is subdivided into the civil code, the commercial code, the code of civil procedure, the penal code, the code of criminal procedure. The two first codes contain much in common, and though the three last relate to procedure, they do not clearly bring out the substantive rights of which crimes and wrongs are only the violation. Saviony divides law into constitutional or public law. and private law. Tlie first has for its object the state, that is, the organic mani- festation of the people ; the second has for its object the judicial relations, which encircle the individual man. In the public law the whole appears as the end, the individual as subordinate ; but in private law the individual man is the end, and every juridical relation is regarded merely as means for his existence or his particular benefit. — Sav. Syat. of Mod. Rom. Lmv. Staiu, the leading Scotch jurist, after noticing the Roman divisions into persona, things, and actions, rejects it, and lays down the subject thus*: — 1. Constitution and nature of rights. 2. Conve3%ance, or translation from one person to another, wliether from living or dead. 3. The cognition of rights, which comprehends the trial, decision, and execution of every right by the legal remedies. These, however, form in reality only one head, which might have been called rights, and their enforcement. I en. I.] BLACKSTONE'S DIVISION OF LAW. 51 Division of laio accoi'ding to English ivr iters. — The division of law according to English writers has been entirely founded on that of the Roman law. Bracton first treats systematically of the Avhole body of the law, both the substance of the law and the procedure appro- priate to its several heads. He follows the civil law, and divides the subject into the law of persons, of things, and of actions, the last head being subdivided into criminal and civil actions. Persons are divided into freemen and Adlleins, or slaves, and their status and riglits are qualified by age, sex, and family. Britton neither defines law nor gives any systematic classification of the subjects it includes. He only describes the courts as they then existed and the business they dealt with, and then treats of everything else under the head of personal actions and real actions, the last forming the most important, as they deal with the possession of and property in land ; and the great disturbing facts were the death, marriage, or disseisin of the owner, round which most of the details revolve. Eortescue, Coke, Plowden, and minor writers say nothing of consequence as to the divisions of law. Plowden loosely says the law of England has six principal founda- tions: the law of reason, the divine law, the general customs of the kingdom, certain principles and maxims, particular customs, and statutes.^ Hale and Blackstone's division of law. — Hale, whose division of the law has been little criticised and generally accepted, divides law into civil law and criminal law.^ 1 Plowd. Com. 811. Doct & St. 12. CoweU, Instil 4. The Speaker of the House of Commons, himself a lawyer, told King James I., at the end of his second parliament, that our laws were of three kinds : 1. The common law, groimded or drawTi from the law of God, the law of reason, and the law of nature, not mut- able. 2. The positive law, founded, changed, and altered by and through the occasions and policies of times. 3. Customs and usages practised and allowed with time's approbation and without known beginnings. — 1 Purl. Hist. 1046. ^ Civil law consists of civil rights of persons and things — persons being natural and artificial, and having certain capacities and certain political, economical, and civil relations inter se. Under persons are arranged magistrates, supreme, like the legislature and the executive, or subordinate, Hke the ordinary courts. Things are temporal, like highways, bridges, rivers, ports, and private estates ; or ecclesiastical, E 2 52 ON THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT. [intro. Hale, it is to be observed, candidly admits that he had not thoroughly thought out the subject of a division of the law, and did not profess that his division was the best. He believed that he could under some head in his outline manage to put every chapter and verse of the law. But more than that he did not profess. And it is obvious that under almost any division of law that may be selected all the various subjects could be arranged. The question, however, at present is. Which is that division of the law which arranges the details in their most natural order, and such as will commend itself most to those who enter upon the study of the law, or contemplate it from the ground occupied by intelligent laymen ? Blackstone, following Hale, says the primary division is into rights and wrongs. Rights are subject to a division into those which concern the persons of men, and are then called jura 2Jersona7'icm, or the rights of persons, and into those which a man may acquire over external objects or things unconnected with his person, which are styled jura rerum, or the rights of things. Wrongs are also divisible into, first, private wrongs, which, being an infringement merely of particular rights, concern individuals only, and are called civil injuries ; and, secondly, public wrongs, which, being a breach of general public rights, affect the whole community, and are called crimes and misdemeanors. Thus the four great divisions of the law are said to be, rights of persons, rights of things, private wrongs, public wrrongs.^ Blackstone's method thus consists in, first, dividing all law into the law of persons and the law of things ; he next divides law into the law of civil injuries and civil procedure, and the law of crimes and criminal procedure. like cliurchcs, chapels, benefices. And, finally, civil law includes wrongs and their remedies. Criminal law is not treated in detail, but its subjects are more or less similar. ^ 1 Bl. Com. 138. Most oi" the critics of Blackstone's division take much credit to themselves for pointing out the so-called absurdity of this division, viz., " rights of things," and they gravely remark that tilings can have no rights, and that he ought to have said " rights relating to things." Such critics have only shown that they had not read what Blackstone himself says (2 Bl. Com. 1) : '■^ Jura rerum are those rights which a man may acquire in and to such external things as are unconnected with his person." CH. I.] BENTIIAM'S DIVISION OF LAW. 53 The last division, however, pervades iudiscriminately the first and second divisions, so that in reality, though there may be a convenience in treating the subjects as he has treated them, there cannot be said to be any exhaust- ive method or any clear line of demarcation covering the whole field of the law. Even the boundaries of the law of persons and the law of things are intermixed and undistinguishable in several directions. ^ Bcntham's and other divisions of lavj. — Bentham, after reviewing previous systems, selected, as the best general arrangement of a code of laws, the threefold division of penal law, civil law, and constitutional law.^ He said, all previous attempts at a code were imperfect or faulty in their analysis, but he had so arranged his own scheme that every title and chapter found an appropriate place. He rejected the Danish code, the Swedish code, the Frederi- cian code, the Sardinian code, the Tlieresan code, as imperfect or disorderly. He observed, that, though Black- stone's plan was arbitrary, it was preferable to all those vv^hich preceded him, and his was a work of light in com- parison with the darkness which previously covered the wJiole face of the law. Bentham's own view of the advantages of his division is well deserving of attention, whatever may be thought of the success with which he carried it out. He said that his classification w^as the most natural, that is to say, the most easy to be understood and remembered. It was simple and uniform. It was best adapted for discourse, that is to say, best adapted for announcing the truths connected with the subject. It was complete, for there was no imaginable law, to which it was not possible by means of it to assign a proper place. It displayed intention, for ifc was so contrived that the very place, wdiich any offence is made to occupy, 1 " Blackstone pursues a metaphysical inquiry upon the nature of laws in general, eternal and positive laws, and a number of sub- lime terms, which I admire us much as I can without understanding them. Instead of following this high priori road, would it not be better humbly to investigate the desires, fears, passions, and opinions of the human being, and to discover from thence what means an able legislator can employ to connect the private happiness of each indi- vidual with the observance of those laws which secure the well-being of the whole ? " — 5 Gibbon, Misc. Works, 5-4G. - 3 Bentham, 157. 54 ON THE LIBERTY OP THE SUBJECT. [intro. suggests the reason of its being put there. Lastly, the classi- fication was universal, for it was governed by a principle which was recognised by all men, and would serve alike for the jurisprudence of all nations. On this last crowning feature his language rose into enthusiasm. He says : " In a system of law framed in pursuance of such a method the language would serve as a glossary, by which all systems of positive law might be explained, while the matter would serve as a standard by which they might be tried. Thus illustrated, the practice of every nation might be a lesson to every other, and mankind might carry on a mutual inter- course of experiences and improvements — as easily in this as in every other walk of science. It might thus possess a utility independent of the use which might be made of it by the governments of the world. If the different penal laws in the world were arranged according to this method, all their imperfections would become visible ; without argument respecting them, they would be discovered by inspection. Here would be offences omitted, there imagi- nary offences ; here redundant laws containing numerous descriptions of different kinds of theft or personal offences, &c., instead of one general law. This classification would, therefore, prove in legislative science what instruments of comparison, such as the barometer and thermometer, have been found in physical science." ^ Objections to the current divisions of law. — None of the current divisions of the law carries on its face with suffi- cient clearness the reasons for its existence. And while it would be tedious to discuss the details in order to make manifest this defect, a better division seems to be suggested by imitating the way in which intelligent minds approach the study of the law for the first time, and, as Gibbon observed, by investigating human desires, fears, passions, and opinions. As to those who are already familiar with the practice of the law, and have already of necessity formed for themselves some classification of their own, any other classification may be felt to be superfluous. But however the law may have been first studied, and by whatever approach its details may have been reached and mastered, it will yet generally be found, that it is only after years of attentive reflection that the vast and confused materials ^ 3 Bentham'8 Works, 172. CH. I.] WHAT IS BEST DIVISION OF LAW. 55 arrange themselves iu the mind in any settled order. When this occurs, groups and sequences are readily visible. Each chapter and verse has its appropriate record in the pigeon-holes of the memory. A panorama of such a kind as this may be said to be the necessary result only of close attention and long manipulation, and yet differs mate- rially from any of the current methods.^ Law is mastered only after great experience, or rather after the reflection which supervenes on experience. By whatever access the precincts are entered, the interior economy is found to be the same, yet the contents are sorted differently. Each may have accomplished the conspectus in his own way, and the arrangement may be as various as the mental idiosyn- cracies of the learners. It is however only by having regard to the definition of law, if any such can be found, that a clue out of the labyrinth of details can be most readily obtained. What is the lest division of municipal law. — In consider- ing what is the best division of the municipal law, it will therefore be useful to recall the definition already given, namely, that it is the sum of the varied restrictions on the actions of each individual, which the supreme power of the state enforces, in order that all may follow their occupa- tions with greater security.^ Now if this is correct, nothing can turn on the law relating to persons, as contradistin- guished from the law relating to things. Things have no separate existence in the eye of the law any more than in the eye of the metaphysician, but they are known only by and through persons who have rights and wrongs in respect of them. The law begins and ends with persons and their doings ; all else is sequel and development. A mountain, a house, or a ship has neither rights, nor wrongs, nor remedies. 1 Whewell says the primary and universal rights of men are five : (1) The right to personal security ; (2) the right of property ; (3) the right of contract ; (4) family rights ; and (5) government. — Whewell, 1 Elem. Mor. s. 80. An able writer, Mr. Sheldon Amos, suggests the following division of subjects for a code of English law : (1) Laws relating to the constitution and administration of the state ; (2) laws of ownership ; (3) laws of contract ; (4) laws affecting special classes of persons, such as husbands and wives, parents and children, professions, cor- porations ; (5) laws of civil injuries ; (6) criminal law ; (7) laws of procedure. — Amos on a Code. " Ante, p. 27. 56 ON THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT. [mrno. Its owner only can enjoy and suffer, maintain and vindicate. But the method of Blackstone is to begin with persons as distinguished from things, and to describe successively the sovereign, the members of the legislature and of the government, justices of the peace, sheriffs, coroners, con- stables, overseers, clergy, husband and wife, master and servant, guardian and ward. We are informed of some of the things which each of these individuals does. But most of these particulars are merely special functions appertain- ing to a few members singled out from the whole commu- nity. Such functions and special features form but a small proportion of the total rights of these individuals. What is special is transitory and insignificant compared with the great residue of rights permanently vested and centred in each and all alike. The sovereign, indeed, stands in a position somewhat apart. But all the other individuals, the legislators, judges, officers, husbands, masters, parents, guardians enjoy precisely the same rights, as the rest of the undistinguished throng. They buy and sell, enjoy and vindicate, acquire and transfer and bequeath, are born, live, and are buried in the same manner as the rest of the community. What is common to them with their fellow-citizens is so vast, compared with the few particulars in which they differ, that it is illogical and purposeless to constitute them into a sepa- rate division on that account, and far less into the first of the divisions. These special functions are all in the nature of variations caused by what they do, and how they come to do it. Wliatever each has to do may be necessary to the working out of the whole system either as means or machinery ; but men are not made in order to keep up these particular functions; the functions are made for the men and the circumstances, to serve some purpose in the general economy of the commonwealth. The mass of the community consists of men who have identical rights — who differ from each other only in subordinate and unimportant particulars. What each and all can, or cannot do, forms the fundamental conception of all law. What each has and enjoys, stripped of all the accidents and adventitious circumstances which cause distinctions to be maintained, is the standard to which all varieties refer. The normal man — his rights, his wrongs, and his remedies — is the leading CH. I.] CURRENT DIVISION OF LAW WRONG. 57 idea, and claims the first attention ; and all divisions of subjects must be subordinate to that. The law of persons as treated by the Roman law, and by Hale and Blackstone, ceases to have any distinct bearing, when we seek to analyse the conception represented by the normal man, of whom all individual persons and functionaries are but insignificant variations. Reasons for discarding the current division of the law as to persons. — If one were to seek a reason why the Roman division of the law of persons was first adopted and has so long kept its ground, such reason is not far to seek. When mankind consisted of freemen and slaves, — when one- twentieth, or one-tenth, of the population were heroes, and the rest were in the rank of cattle, — such a distinction appeared of the highest importance, and must have filled a large space in the mind's eye. The early and middle ages had similar reasons for accepting the order laid down for them by their predecessors. The Roman and mediaeval mind could never rise to the height of moral elevation in which the essential equality of mankind in the eye of the law is an elementary and ineradicable first principle, not to be frittered away, or tampered with, or lost sight of for a moment — which no variety of time, or place, or circum- stance can modify or reverse — which the kindest and most fatherly treatment by the most humane of proprietors can never dispense with, supersede, or obliterate — the want of which cannot be atoned for by wealth, or ease, or kindness, or comfort, or late-acquired freedom — a sentiment which, when once enjoyed, can never be relinquished — without which a hidden want is always felt — without which life itself is poisoned at every pore. It was a weakness of the ancients not to be forgotten, that it never occurred to their legislatures, that human beings were all on one level as to legal rights, — that there was no foundation for classi- fying them according to the colour of their hair or their skin, their origin, their race, their climate, their stature, their virtues, their poverty, or their misfortunes. Whether a man was caught in battle or found at peace, was a mere accident of the moment. It never entered into the mind of Plato, or Aristotle, or Cicero, or Tribouian, and all the council of Justinian's jurists, that there ever could be a state of society in which the great majority did not consist 58 ON THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT. [intro. of slaves. Hence it was as excusable for their law as it is inexcusable for ours, to start with the great division of freemen and slaves.^ And the other parts of the same division, namely, parent and child, husband and wife, guardian and ward, master and servant, had so much of the slavish element transfused into them, that they naturally bore company with the first. But now, after centuries from the dawn of Christianity, since the name of slavery has been expunged from the book of civilisation, the dis- tinction of freeman and villein, and all the distinctions flowing from that tainted source may be at once discarded as founded on a delusion never more to be tolerated among mankind. It is a delusion, that, because there are and must be inequalities in the rank and condition of indi- viduals, these may or ought to be further aggravated by making them perpetual and irreversible, altogether irrespec- tive of personal merits. The chance of war or the accident of an accident is now confessed to be a worthless excuse for seeking to rivet the permanent and galling yoke of slavery upon those, who are conscious of the same " hands, organs, dimensions, senses, affections, passions" as their owners, and differ in nothing but the unequal weights imposed upon them at their start in the same race. Whatever be the price of holding fast to this first and unchangeable condition of society — the personal freedom of each individual — that price we must, in the words of Montesquieu, be content to pay to Heaven.^ 1 De Tocqueville — " The most profound and capacious minds of Greece and Rome were never able to reach the idea, at once so general and so simple, of the common likeness of men and of the common birthright of each to freedom, and they strove to prove that slavery was in the order of nature, and that it would always exist. Nay. more, everything shows that those of the ancients who had passed from the servile to the free condition, many of whom have left ■wTitings, did themselves regard servitude in no other light. All the great writers of antiquity belonged to the aristocracy of masters, or at least they saw that aristocracy established and uncontested before their eyes. Their mind, after it had expanded itself in every direc- tion, was barred from further progress in this one, and the advent of Jesus Christ upon eartii was required to teach that all the mem- bers of the human race are by nature equal and alike." — De Tocque- ville (tr. by Reeves). '*' Don Alphonso of Castile, in 1.3.37, gained immortal credit for pro- curing from his assembly a law, tliat no rank should exempt men from the laws. — 8 U7iiv. Mod. Mist. 43. CH. I.] ANCIENT AND MODERN LAW. 59 Ancients not likely to have attained just notions of division of laws. — However great were the ancients in some of their moral aspects, however acute as thinkers on philosophical subjects, and however sensible in the law of buying and selling, their notions of human government and of the mutual relations between man and man in social and political life were derived, among the Greeks, from an experience of petty communities, and, among the Eomans, from an organisation loosely compacted of barbarous tribes. On all the leading points in daily life their thoughts were not our thoughts. Who could now be satisfied with the ripest wisdom of Plato and Aristotle, of Cicero and Tribonian, after having been taught by Pym and EUot, by Hampden and Selden — the greatest geniuses for govern- ment that the world has ever seen?^ Whatever was the circle of doctrines and practices, ends and methods, that passed as law with the ancients, it can scarcely find its counterpart In the stately panorama of rights and liberties, mutual checks and securities, between kings, legislatures, and judicature on the one hand, and subject and subject on the other hand, as these passed before the masterly intellect of Pym, whose great ideas and conquests we inherit, fortified and matured by the stirring events of two centuries more.^ The Sermon on the Mount, and all that BuLLER, J., well handled the common saying about " one law for the rich and another for the poor " : " There is not in this country- one rule by which the rich are governed, and another for the poor. No man has justice meted out to him by a different measure, on account of his rank or fortune, from what would be done if he were destitute of both. Every invasion of property is judged of by the same rule : every injury is compensated in the same way, and every crime is restrained by the same punishment, be the condition of the offender what it may. It is in this alone that true equality can exist in society ; different degrees are necessary for every government, and greater talents and industry will in the course of things give one man a superiority over another. And without some distinction and rank the magistrate would want authority, virtue would be without ;one of its strongest incentives, and the prudent and in- dustrious would remain on a footing with tlie idle and the dissipated." —Per Buller, J. {O'Coighly's case) 26 St. Tr. 1193. ^ Warburton so described them. — Fcrster's Pym. ^ Pym, one of the greatest of Englishmen, in 1641 struck a key which might have led to a division of laws much superior to Hale's and Blackstone's, though Pym himself was not a trained lawyer. He says : " The greatest liberty of the kingdom is religion : thereby we 60 ON THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT. [intro. flowed from it, communicated no ideas to ancient jurists and legislators, and scarcely penetrated the darkness of the middle ages. The sumptuary laws of the ancients long misled the mediseval governments, which, without reflection, imitated and adopted them. Slavery was the informing spirit of all their social arrangements, and however suitable their definitions and classifications of legal doctrines may have appeared to them, we must search out others more in harmony with the dignity of the indi- vidual, and the indelible equality of the various races of men in the eye of the law. Higher standards of justice and of social life demand a method as far asunder as possible from all pagan ideas and practices. Best division of law is according to subjects of occupations. — First division is SECUKITY OF PEESON. — But though the division into persons and things, however ancient, is now obsolete and unmeaning, there is an obvious distinction between laws according to their subject-matter. As Leibnitz pointed out, law may be divided into as many parts as there are causes which produce rights and obliga- tions. What then are those causes when viewed in relation to the normal man ? AVhat are the great subjects round which rights and obligations are grouped ? The first of these may be said to be such as relate to the protection of the body against wrong and interference. Of all the intimate relations between two distinct things, that between mind and body is the most intimate. A man may have property in external things — little, or much, or are freed from spiritual evils, and no impositions are so grievous as those that are laid upon the soul. The next great liberty is justice, whereby we are preserved from injuries in our persons and estates ; from this is derived into the commonwealth peace and order and safety, and when this is interrupted, confusion and danger are ready to overwhelm all. The third great liberty consists in the power and privilege of parliament, for this is the fountain of law, the great council of the kingdom, the highest court ; this is enabled by the legislative and conciliary power to prevent evils to come ; by the judiciary power to suppress and remove evils present. If you consider these three great liberties in the order of dignity, this last is inferior to the other two as means are inferior to tlie end ; but if you consider them in the order of necessity and use, this may justly claiai the hrst place in our care, because the end cannot be obtained without the means, and if we do not preserve this, we cannot long hope to enjoy either of the other." — Forster's Pym, 93. CH. I.] DIVISION OF SECURITY OF THE PERSON. fil noDe at all ; he may enter into contracts — many or few ; may have a sense of religion, of freedom, of free thought, free speech, and public worship ; he may feel a strong interest in legislation, government, and the administration of justice. But none of these things touches him so closely as his own body, as the sense of life and health, of pain and pleasure, of locomotion and imprisonment. Property, contract, reputation may be dispensed with ; they are separable, and may be viewed at a distance, but mind and body remain in indefeasible partnership, not to be forgotten, ignored, or left in abeyance for an instant, and to maintain the integrity of which all the instincts of the individual combine. The common duty of self- preservation is one, which, as Erskine said, nature writes as a law on the hearts of even savages and brutes. The first of all subjects dealt with by the law is none other than the person or body. Coke said, " the liberty of a man's person is more precious to him than all the rest that follows." ^ . Here the law has its first and its most emphatic statements and expositions to make. What it does to protect the body against attacks, and wdiether this protection is made effectual by action, by indictment, or by self-defence — by direct or circuitous processes — it is obvious that a large and pre-eminent part of the law must be set apart to this subject alone. Not only must the body of each be protected against wrong caused by the acts of others, but inasmuch as the chief medium of punishment, of coercing the will and shaping the conduct, is the pain and anguish of the same body, there is an obverse side of the medal also to be contemplated. Whatever the law does to protect the body of one person necessarily involves correlative liabilities attaching to the persons of others. If one is to be protected against murder, mutilation, and insult, this cannot be, except by the inflicting of pain and suffering on the body of some other, What is vindicated by one must be suffered by another. The very same body, in order to enjoy for itself, must also submit to some restraint for the sake of that very enjoyment in others. Each acts and reacts on the other. What each gains is at the expense of the rest, or rather, all the others are put 1 2 Inst. 45. 62 ON THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT. [intro. under restrictions, in order that each one may be free from interference as to the end to be achieved. Wliatever, there- fore, the law says or does for the protection of the body — whatever the body suffers by way of punishment as the counterpart of that protection — these constitute the double aspect of its legal treatment. In short, all that law does or can do with the body — the best and the worst that can happen to it — constitute the first and leading division of municipal law. Such a division recommends itself to all states of civilisation. It makes all modes of government and grades of society akin. Every system of law, or semblance of a system, cannot choose but do something to make some provisions, good or bad, which collectively form the law of the security of the person.^ VariatAons in division of security of person, hy age, sex, insanity, death. — The first division of law — that which relates to the security of the person, includes all the modes by which the body is protected against w^rong, whether threats, or acts of violence of every degree, while the machinery by which this protection is worked out — the punishment, pain, and death of the wrongdoer — is a necessary sequel, and concludes all that the law provides for the body. In further pursuing this subject, however, it is to be noticed also, that the normal man is assumed to be of full age and of sane mind, master of his own actions, and as independent of all other individuals as other requirements of the law ■ 1 A great judge (Pratt, C. J.), carried away with the heat of argu- ment, said " the great end for which men entered into society was to secure their property. That right is preserved sacred and in- violable in all instances, where it has not been taken away or abridged by some public law for the good of the whole." — Entick v Carrington, 19 St. Tr. 1030. This phrase is often repeated, but instead of being the great end, property is only one of ten great ends, each, or at least several of the others, being quite as important in all respects, as a consideration of the other nine divisions of the law will make sufficiently obvious. Others said : " Give me the liberty to know, to utter, and to argue freely according to conscience, above all liberties." — Milton, Areop. " The two great pillars of the government are parliaments and juries. It is this gives us the title of freeborn Englishmen, for my notion of free Englishmen is this, that they are ruled by laws of their own making, and tried by men of the same condition with themselves."— PawZe, arg. 8 St. Tr. 183. " The liberty of discus- sion is the chief safeguard of all other liberties." — 1 Macaulay's Hist. eh. 10. CH. I.] DIVISION OF SECURITY OF PEOPERTY. 63 permit. The body has, so to speak, some mental charac- teristics attached to it. The rights and wrongs of the full-grown sane individual form the main subject. But man is liable to certain incidents which cause variations of these rights. He is born — he passes part of his life as an infant, his judgment ripens with his body, and he dies. These leading circumstances all indicate certain variations of the same subject, for there must be, laws peculiar to the state of infancy, peculiar to the state of insanity, and peculiar to the stage of death, the chief of which is burial. There are also other variations of a like kind caused by sex. Some peculiar laws are required for one sex which are not required for the other, and some for insane persons which are not required for sane persons. All these, however, are only variations of the main and substantive law of the normal man, the basis of all legal conditions. The incidents above mentioned, being the occasions of these variations, require accordingly to be noticed at the conclusion of the account of this first division of the security of the person. Second division of law is security of property. — When the law has said all that can be said about the body, other divisions must be thought of; and here again it is useful to recall the definition of law, which was stated to be a series of restrictions on the actions of man. This leads to the inquiry. What are the main actions or occupations of man ? These at first sight seem so nearly infinite as to be scarcely reducible to order. But after some consideration it will be found, that all human occupations, tendencies, and objects, so far as the law has to do with them, are reducible to a few leading heads. These should, for purposes of method, be as nearly as possible independent of each other, and as nearly as possible first principles of human nature. The most conspicuous of all the occupations of man, next to the care of his own body, is that of the enjoyment of property. This is a tendency or an instinct not to be resolved into anything simpler, though philosophers have indulged in many speculations as to how this tendency is created, how it grows, and what metaphysical elements combine in its formation. It is enough for the law to assume, that the desire to enjoy property may be said to be a legal instinct requiring no further explanation, any more 64 ON THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT. [intbo. than the instinct of the bee, the squirrel, or the beaver. The law can neither give nor take it away ; it springs eternal in the human breast, and all that the law can do is to protect and regulate it to a small extent.^ It has obviously no relation, such as the casual hoards of the lower animals have, to a few days' maintenance, though the appetite often supplies its first motive power. It grows from a material into almost an intellectual habit, and its effects far outgrow any relation to the bodily wants. While the lower animals live from hand to mouth, man accumulates stores which can never by any possibility be needed for his own personal use ; and the desire to maintain intact these acquisitions is nearly the last infirmity which leaves the mind in the living body. No law can wholly extirpate this desire to accumulate property ; it is independent of all laws, though it engrosses so much of the energy of man, that no law can afford to leave it unnoticed.^ It is always treated as if too much can never be made of it. The way in which the law protects and encourages the individual in his accumulations of property is by provision against interference from theft and injury, from trespass and molestation. The subject- matter of property and the mode of enjoyment form a large part of the whole. The details of the restrictions are neces- sarily manifold, and it is enough to say that the second great division of the law^ is this security of property. And it is subject, like the former division, to the variations caused by birth or infancy, sex, insanity, death, each of which conditions gives rise to pecuhar provisions in aid of the fundamental instinct of accumulating property. Third division is SECURITY OF MARRIAGE. — The third great division of the law is also totally distinct from, and not resolvable into either of the others. It relates to marriage — a tendency, or an instinct, or whatever it maybe called — wdiich is wholly independent of law, which can only be restrained in a small degree, and yet the details of its restrictions are also manifold, and have cost all legislatures much thought and care. In one respect the division relating 1 Cicero said tli.at commonwealths and states were established jirincipally in order that men should hold what was their own. — Cic. De. Off.h.ilc. U. " As Pym said : " Without law cv.^ry man has a right to every- thing."— ylft^e, p. 46. CH. I.] TENFOLD DIVISION OF LAW, G5 to marriage is only such a variation of the two former divisions as is attributable to sex, for when two persons are married this relation causes changes in the individual rights of each, both as regards their persons and their property. Nevertheless, marriage fills so large a space in human life, and its results extend so far, and involve so many third parties, that it is a division of itself, and cannot be properly included in any other. It begins with the form of a contract between two persons, but it has wide and far-reaching effects; and, when children are born, fresh subsidiary relations are created, and still further intricacy pervades the property of each of the group. The main re- strictions on the actions of man in reference to marriage are those which confine the relation to certain persons not being near relatives, to mutual control both of the person and of the property of each — to the mutual maintenance of children and parents, together with still further variations caused by infancy, insanity, and death. The security of marriage is therefore one main division of the law, and includes all the peculiarities caused by this natural and inevitable union between man and wife. Fourth division is security of public woeship. — After the security of the person, property, and marriage, comes a division also independent of all these, and referable to no other head. This is the tendency or instinct of public worship. In all states of society there is a gravitation towards the supernatural and the infinite — to take cognis- ance of a Source of power independent of man, and confessedly his master. Speculations on this subject, with a view to attain definite ideas as to a great First Cause, are unceasing. But no tribe of savages is so rude, no grade of civilisation so illiterate on the one hand, or so refined on the other hand, that the tendency to worship a god publicly does not take some shape, and become a conspicuous feature of social life. The very lowest glimmering of this charac- teristic of man may be nothing more definite than a suspicion of witchcraft. The tendency to public worship, as apart from private worship, is radical and irrepressible : it pervades human nature in all countries ; and the law cannot avoid putting some restrictions on human conduct in relation to it. How far all shall be compelled to follow certain uniform ceremonies and creeds — how one class of VOL. I. F 66 ON THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT. [intro. men are set apart to the sacred profession — how far certain property is dedicated to its use — how far dissenters and even impious opponents are tolerated — all the particulars surrounding this human tendency are included under that division of law entituled the security of public worship. Fifth division is SECURITY of thought, speech, and CHARACTER. — A fifth division may be said to be devoted to the intellectual side of human nature — the tendency to free thought and speech, and social reputation. These three subjects are closely connected together, and they are altogether independent of the mere care of the body, the mere care of property, of marriage, and public worship. How far free thought, speech, and reputation are protected and regulated — the liberty of the press, libel, all that flows from the desire of the human mind to exercise itself on the affairs of life, and on the communication of ideas between man and man fall under this division, which may be called the security of thought, speech and character. In some respects this division may be said to include the security of public worship, which forms the subject •of the preceding division, for at the root of both is the freedom of thought and the protection of that freedom. But public worship even to tliis day in many countries exists without much freedom of thought, and the law is so voluminous on both subjects, that it is expedient to separate them on that account. Moreover, public worship includes the relations of man to his Maker, while this division concerns mostly the cognate relations between fellow-men. Sixth division, security of contract and business. — The next division of the law consists of the tendency of man to enter into contracts in pursuit of his occupations and interests, to manage his own affairs in his own way This tendency is by no means, as some pliilosophers would have us believe, the creature of the law, any more than the previous divisions. There would be contracting, bargain- ing, buying, and selling, whether there were law, or not. This division is large, and covers a great variety of human occupations not touched b}"" the former divisions. Contracts fill up a great portion of the life of each individual, and the law for various reasons interferes with and controlls numerous kinds of businesses and trades for no other i CH. I.] TENFOLD DIVISION OF LAW. 67 reasoD than because the exclusive pursuit of each one's own interest too frequently leads to unnecessary interfer- ence with the interests of others. All these fall under the head of the security of contract and business. Seventh division is security of foreigneks. — The last division of the substantive law is founded on a circum- stance common to all countries possessing a tincture of civilization, that of tolerating strangers or foreigners — persons who were not born in the same community, in which they nevertheless for various reasons are found from time to time. Whether and to what extent the municipal law suffers modification when the rights and wrongs of these strangers are dealt with, naturally forms a distinct subject, not flowing out of the former divisions. No law can leave the case of foreigners unprovided for. Their rights and interests may be intermixed with those of native subjects ; but they call for some special treatment, and as a matter of fact occupy the attention of all legislatures. This branch of the law is often called private international law, but the security of foreigners is a more appropriate title, and it is a necessary supplement to all the preceding divisions. It also brings out more distinctly all that relates to juris- diction over subjects natural born, and born in colonies and foreign dependencies. The legislature has for centuries been busy with altering and modifying such common law as barbarous ages and crude ideas of justice allotted to foreigners. The freedom of these to come and go, and buy and sell, was protected by Magna Charta itself^ And numerous statutes down to the present day have kept up the perpetual interest in this subject. The division of administrative law is threefold. — The seven divisions now enumerated divide between them the whole substantive law. But there still remains the administrative law, which, as already described, resolves itself into three parts : the judicature, the legislature, and the executive government. They are called administrative law, because they have the relation to the substantive law of means to the end — of machinery to the result achieved. They keep the substantive law in perpetual vigour, defining what is obscure, amending what is defective, and keeping all the great functionaries employed in distributing it within their 1 Mag. Cliart. c. 30. F 2 68 ON THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT. [intro- respective orbits. They collect and maintain the materials for keeping the peace within the territory, and represent the empire in all its extra-territorial interests. Eighth division of law is into the judicatuke. — The judi- cature is the division of administrative law which contains the distribution of jurisdiction among various courts and functionaries. How judges are appointed, and what privi- leges or peculiarities distinguish them from the rest of the community — what rules they follow in administering justice — hearing parties, excluding irrelevant topics, enforc- ing judgments and sentences. The leading methods resorted to of securing to each the best satisfaction against wrong and the violation of the substantive law, so far as law can give redress, form the eighth division — that of the judica- ture. This division involves also many securities of the individual; but as all these are subordinate to the leading idea of expounding and applying the law, they fall under this division as their natural and appropriate place. Ninth division of law is THE LEGISLATUEE. — The legislature is the ninth division of the whole law and includes all that relates to the constitution and working of the three estates of parliament — showing how the members of one branch of the legislature are elected, and what privileges attach to them — how the members of another branch of the legisla- ture are first appointed and afterwards succeed by inherit- ance to their function — how the legislature proceeds in enacting new laws — who are the parties to their enactment — what are the parts of a statute wheu completed and how it is expressed and interpreted — what is, the relation of the legislature towards the subject on the one hand and to- wards the executive government on the other hand. These particulars are included in this division of " the legislature." Tenth division is the executive goveenment. — Lastly, the executive government is the keystone of the arch, and includes all that relates to the sovereign and the prerogatives vested in this supreme office — the course of the succession — the appointment of high officers of state, and then- respective functions — the prerogative of pardon, the chief command of the army and navy, the relations of the sovereign towards the subject on the one hand, and towards the legislature on the other hand, the representation of the CH. 1.] TENFOLD DIVISION OF LAW. 69 empire in all matters of peace or war, when dealing with foreign countries, and the treatment of foreign subjects and foreign property in times of war. And the government is not entirely imperial, but has subordinate and derivative grades, there being to some extent parts of the legislature and executive government delegated to functionaries and communities under various forms of local self-government, the chief organs of which are municipal corporations, counties and parishes, and sanitary districts. Summary of tenfold division of law. — This tenfold division collects and exhausts all the matters which the law deals with in a natural and intelligible order. The law cares nothing for, and has no leisure to ponder over, the metaphysical and philosophical elements into which they may be still further reduced. In the region of prac- tical life, which is that in which the law lives and moves, there are no more simple and more elementary conceptions than these ten to be found. That each individual has an instinctive tendency to take care of his own person, to amass property, to marry, to worship, to think, speak, and make a character to himself, to enter into contracts, to live or hold fellowship with foreigners, to resort to courts of justice, to submit to legislation and to government, cannot be explained by any intuition or by any experience, and must be accepted as postulates. How and under what restrictions these tendencies are regulated and encouraged, constitutes the burden of every code. One code may, more than another, sketch each of these divisions with a freer touch — may leave a blank here, may show a barrier there — may blur the canvas with misshapen forms, may write some edicts in characters of blood, may fill chapters with incongruous and mistaken details. But each and every subject must be treated more or less pointedly, or its place must be marked out. Not one of them can be safely omitted, and it is by the balance of light and shade, of clearly developed forms and the most natural play of human action, that the best code is distinguished. A picture of many hues, of complex and many-sided groups, is the result. It may require a nice appreciation to compare each detail of one code with the corresponding detail of another code ; and it is only by a comprehensive experience of its many points of contact with many minds, that a rational 70 ON THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT. [intro. estimate can be made of the degrees of perfection attained and attainable. But in every human society a place must be found for each of these ten divisions of subjects, and it is impossible not to find something, however crude, which every human code has to say upon each of them. In order, therefore, to make still more clear the fore- going arrangement and distribution of subjects, this "Division of the whole law" will assume the following simple tabular form : — I. Substantive Law. 1. Security of the person. 2. Security of property, 3. Security of marriage. 4. Security of public worship. 5. Security of thought, speech, and character. 6. Security of contract and business. 7. Security of foreigners. II. Administrative Law. 8. The Judicature. 9. The Legislature. 10. The Executive Government (including local self- government). CHAPTEE 11. EXPLANATION OF PHRASES AND TERMS USED IN THE LAW. Other divisions and terms used hy legal authors. — A defi- nition and a division of the law, however perfect, do not exhaust the requirements of those who make their pre- liminary survey of so wide a subject. There are so many technical distinctions, phrases, and words, which have long been current, and which exercise the reflections of all men, that some notice of these will be useful before we proceed to the particulars of the law itself, in their settled order. Many of these words are the tools of the art, and have been used and applied in various senses, according to the pre- vailing theories of those who have written on legal and political subjects. Some of these distinctions may be found to rest on a mere confusion of ideas, may be super- fluous or misleading, or imperfectly defined. They are, however, sufiiciently interesting or important to require separate treatment. Such are the phrases and words — liberty of the subject — political and civil liberty — origin of government — the social or original contract — the divisions into constitutional law, public and private, civil and criminal law — commercial law — law of nations — private international law — law of na- ture — law of God, or divine law — feudal law — civil law — canon law — common law and statute law — written and unwritten law — judge-made law — ^adherence to precedents — legal fictions — law and equity — codification — right — duty — obligation — wrong — crime — felony — misdemeanour. Meaning of the liberty of the suhjeet and eivil liberty. — The liberty of the subject is a phrase of the law of England which has acquired great and just renown ; but as it has been made the theme of declamation rather than of strict 72 ON THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT. [intbo. legal treatment, it requires some care to discriminate its true import and define the length and breadth of its contents. And as the idea involved in it lies at the root of all natural definitions and divisions of the law, it requires all the more attention in this place. Views of Locke, Somers, Beccaria, as to freedom. — Locke says that the end of law is not to abolish or restrain, but to preserve and enlarge freedom, and where there is no law there is no freedom.^ Somers said, that when a people have no assurance of their liberties or lives, but from the grace and pleasure of the governor, they are but beasts of burden ; and by continual base subserviency to their masters' vices, lose all sense of true religion, virtue, and manhood.^ Beccaria, in his masterly way, explains his notion of liberty thus : " The opinion, that every member of society has a right to do anything, that is not contrary to the laws, without fearing any other inconveniences than those which are the natural consequences of the action itself, is a political dogma which should be defended by the laws, inculcated by the magistrates, and believed by the people — a sacred dogma, without which there can be no lawful society — a just recompense for our sacrifice of that universal liberty of action common to all sensible beings, and only limited by our natural powers. By this principle our minds become free, active, and vigorous — by this alone we are inspired with that virtue which knows no fear, so different from that pliant prudence worthy of those only who can bear a precarious existence." ^ Other authors of eminence give each his own account of the proper use of the phrases — liberty or freedom, natural, civil, and political : and Blackstone, Paley, Austin, Mac- kintosh, and M'Culloch, may be referred to for valuable observations on this subject.* DifficulUj of reconciling current accounts of liberty. — It must be confessed, that their descriptions of civil liberty do not entirely agree, and somewhat bewilder the mind. Blackstone rather unnecessarily introduces, what he calls natural liberty, or the law of nature, as the standard or ] Locke, Oil Govt. b. 2, tit. 57. 2 Somers, Sec. of Engl. p. 1. ^ Beccaria, c. 8. * 1 Bl. Com. 140. Palcy's Mor. Bliil. b. vi. 1 Austin Jur. 281. Mackintosh, L. of Nat. M'Culloch, Pol. Econ. p. 1, oh. 10. en. II.] MEANING OF THE PHRASE. 73 common ground of departure ; but this tends to confuse liis account. Austin seems to view political and civil liberty as something in the nature of a gift from the sovereign government, and as contradistinguished from political or legal restraint. Locke and Beccaria are the writers, who seem to look with the steadiest eyes at the central idea involved. Each writer prefers to explain in his own way a phrase which comes home so forcibly to every one, who has thought of the first principles of society. Certain it is, that liberty has been the theme of poets, orators, and patriots for ages, and though vague may be the notion they have attached to it, the liberty of the person, and freedom from imprisonment may be said to be the basis of their declamations. Went worth in 1575 told the House of Commons that he had found in a little book of that time the words, " Sweet is the name of liberty, but the thing itself beyond all in- estimable value."^ Sir- Benjamin Ptudyard exclaimed in the great debates in the time of Charles I., that " liberty is a precious thing, for every man may set his own price upon it, and he that doth not value it, deserves to be valued accordingly."^ Sir E. Phillips of the same period said that if we can be imprisoned at the will of another, " why do we trouble ourselves with the disputes of law, franchises, and propriety of goods ? "^ And Pym said, " If the liberties of the subject were taken away, there should remain no more industry, no more justice, no more courage : who would contend, who would endanger himself for that which is not his own ? "* " Freedom," as Dryden said, " was the English subject's prerogative."^ 1 1 Pari. Hist. 784. 2 3 St. Tr. 173. ^ 3 St. Tr. 66. * 3 St. Tr. 342. 5 North Briton^ No. 45. De Tocqueville says : " That which at all times has so strongly attached the aflEection of certain men is the attraction of freedom itself, its native charms, independent of its gifts, the pleasure of speaking, acting, and breathing without restraint, under no master but God and the law. He who seeks in freedom aught but herself is fit only to be a slave." — De Tocquev. France, 606 (tr. by Reeves). " The essence of liberty," said Cicero, " is to live just as you please." — Cic. De Off. b. i. c. xx. Dunning said that "for the great benefit of the public and indi- viduals, natural liberty, which consists in doing what one Hkes, is 74 ON THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT. [intro. * Liberty of subject arises out of legal restriction. — The explanation of the phrase, " liberty of the subject," can scarcely be said to involve much difficulty after the defini- tion and division of the law are settled ; or rather, it is merely the correlative and obverse side of the same idea. It may be vaguely described, as Cicero described it, as in some sense indicating the right to do as one pleases without check or interference. But this is a crude conception, and requires much qualification. The sense of mutual restraint, though unuttered or seldom expressed, grows necessarily out of all associations of human beings, and the law is nothing but an elaborate development and classification of the limits and phases of this self-restraint. Such self-restraint is like an instinct, or like the muscular sense pervading all forms of activity and all modes of conduct. Liberty of the subject is the counterpart of this restraint. Most actions being more or less controlled, nothing is or can be done by any individual member of a community, without some conscious or unconscious regard to the correlative and equal acts and conduct of others. Tliere is no absolute liberty. — There is indeed nothing even among the most isolated groups of savage life which approaches to absolute liberty, if such a term be used in the sense of each doing what seems good in his own eyes, regardless of all that is done by others.^ The liberty of altered into doing what one ought." — 20 St. Tr. 71. " All antiquity resounded with the fame of the Xanthians and Paterans, whose intense love of liberty led them to prefer total extinction to their subjugation by a conqueror." — Plut. Brut. Appian, B. 4. In the debates of 1758 it was said that " liberty consisted in not being obliged to do or suffer anj'thing but under the direction of known laws ; that such as do not inherit wealth are nevertheless heirs to freedom, and they who have no other property have a pro- perty in their libertj^ Indeed such, above all others, may be thouglit to have the best title to liberty, since it is the only valuable enjoy- ment to which they can lay claim." — 15 Pari. Hist. 888. 1 A traveller has well observed, that the life of a wild beast is one of constant fear and anxiety. Every antelope in South Africa has literally to run for its life once in every two days, and many times in each day starts or gallops under a false alarm. — Trans. Ethn. Soc. The savage is always sus])icious, always on the watch, always the prey of fear, and sees invisible enemies in every bush. An intelligent traveller remarks : " Man in a savage state has little freedom of thought or action, no development of intellect, benevolence, or any CH. II.] MEANING OF THE PHRASE. 75 the wild beast is said to be the slavery of fear. Not so with man. The mutual help, the mutual fear, the mutual play of appetites, passions, affections, soon shape with invisible hand the conduct of each, so as to avoid collision, invite help, exchange valuable possessions and offices. A second nature thus grows up, strengthening and expanding rather than suppressing all that is the most cherished and the most intensely enjoyed by the individual. When the liberty of the subject, or civil liberty, is spoken of, it is not meant that he, who possesses it, can do what he likes, but only that he obtains the greatest possible value and benefit out of his own faculties and circumstances. It must be remembered that the more protection is given to each, the more checks must be imposed on all otliers. Liberty can- not be protected, as Bentham said, except at the expense of lilierty.i And as was better said by Sir E. Atkins, " a just law is no restraint to a just liberty ; it rather frees us from a captivity and servitude, namely, to that of our wills and passions." ^ But in a well-devised system of checks and counterchecks, the sense of restraint is lost in the greater intensity and enjoyment of those faculties and tendencies, which are thereby rendered effectual, and made secure, and which are the better part of human nature. Civil liberty, or the liberty of the subject, is not the liberty to murder and plunder, to libel, cheat, and oppress all that stand in the path of selfish ambition, aggrandisement, or indulgence ; it is the liberty to attain the largest measure of all desirable things by means of repressing and regu- lating those incompatible tendencies of others, so far as any human power can repress them. The restraints on men as w^ell as their liberties are, as Burke observes, 'to be reckoned among their rights.^ The means to be used must be such as are not incompatible with the attainment of the same ends by each and every member of the community. Civil liberty is a mixed sentiment, compounded of a sense of mutual restraint, of equality, of justice, and of co-operation.* other great qualification, . . The young and weak are helpless ; their laws and customs are as binding as our laws, though handed down orall}'."— 2 Grey's Austr. 217, 219. 1 1 Benth. W.301. 2 ^ g^. Tr. 1207. 3 Burke, Fr. Rev. * Montesquieu said everyone has given the name of liberty to the 76 ON THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT. [intro. Much variety may exist in the complex arrangements devised by each nation for conferring the greatest security on the pursuits of its subjects, and it is not surprising that one nation should differ from another in such details. The natural aversion and resentment against bodily pain, im- prisonment, and deprivation of property, and the greatest variety of weapons of self-defence against all evil designs tending to that result, whether on the part of the subject or of the sovereign, but more especially of the latter as being the most powerful, constitute what is usually called in England " the liberty of the subject." Liberty 7wt confined to hodily freedom. — The liberty of the subject is thus a phrase not limited to the security of the body, and it was at first used in contradistinction to the encroachments of the crown ; but its essence pervades all the other divisions of the law relating to property and general business. The phrase " civil liberty " is perhaps not so comprehensive, yet it is dissociated from mere bodily freedom, for it embraces all modes of protection by the law against wrong and interference whencesoever proceeding, more especially in relation to the encroachments of one's fellow-subjects. The phrase, " political liberty," again, is that phase of civil liberty which regards the participation of the subject in the machinery of legislation and govern- ment. Such participation is of inestimable importance, for in practice it renders the most peremptory edicts of irresistible power much less irksome. It disarms of its terrors that absolute tyrannical force which in all societies must necessarily be wielded by the sovereign authority. It takes the sting out of that inevitable prostration of the government which agrees with his habits or incHnations. — Spirit of L. h. 11 ch. ii. " We are all agreed as to our own liberty. We would have as much of it as we can get. But we are not agreed as to the liberty of others, for, in proportion as we take, others must lose." — 7 Bosw. Johns. 257. Liberty is a word used in popular authors very loosely. Even Adam Smith says : " Laws which are in violation of natural liberty are bad," without defining what natural liberty is. — Wealth of Nat. b. 4. ch. i. " Such is the excellency of the English constitution that the meanest subject is not beneath the protection of the laws, nor the highest beyond their reach. Thus to be governed is the full perfection of civil Hberty."— Per Sir F. Norton, R. v L. Byron, 19 St. Tr. 1185. ^ > .X , CH. 11.] MEANING OF THE PHRASE. 77 individual will which all men dislike, but cannot escape ; and converts into willing obedience what otherwise would be unrelenting antipathy and undying resistance. Liberty of subject and ijolitical liberty not estimated hj number of their restraints. — The liberty of the subject and political liberty thus differ from each other only in giving more or less prominence to one or other of the constituent elements. They both denote the greatest protection ex- tended to the body, the property, and ordinary pursuits, which can be attained in social life — the liberty of shaping one's conduct by laws confessedly just. When laws are originally or mainly framed by a large body of intelligent and select representatives, who declare them fit to be obeyed and enforced upon all, this is the nearest approach to self-made laws. But civil liberty is not to be esti- mated or measured solely by the number of the restrictions embodied in the laws. The mere number of these signifies little, for their value is often enhanced by multiplicity and variety. One restriction more or less is immaterial, when the whole fabric of the structure is instinct with freedom. This liberty, the reflex of the law, is the product of many forces — the result of incessant, far-reaching, and long-continued efforts of legislation — never attaining, yet ever approaching perfection. In short, the liberty of the subject is only another name for the highest security attainable in any community for the body, the estate, and the employments of life, more especially as these are secured against arbitrary imprisonment, against con- fiscation of property, and against suppression of free thought and speech. Liberty of subject is counterpart of legal and self-imposed restraints. — The liberty of the subject, the natural fruit of the law, is said to be a government by laws, and not by men. It is entirely the counterpart and correlative of the restraints imposed by tlie laws on the rest of the com- munity for the benefit of each individual. Such is the liberty of each individual to acquire and enjoy such rights as he deems most valuable, and which the laws have expressly secured for him by corresponding restraints put on aU his fellow-subjects. These laws take care that none shall imprison or control him, except for causes well- known, and which he himself acknowledges in the abstract 78 ON THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT, [intro. to be just, and under warrants which issue from proper authority. They take care that he shall enjoy a large share in making and amending the laws, for laws self-imposed are always the least irksome. When thus originated and moulded — instead of being emblems of tyranny, the laws seem the emanations of the individual will, which it is the interest and pride of each and all to array themselves in supporting.^ Distinction of absolute and relative rights. — Here may be noticed a distinction which arises in some degree out of the liberty of the subject, and which some authors have attempted to draw between absolute and relative rights. Such a distinction will be seen at once to be founded on a confusion of thought. Strictly speaking, all rights are relative, that is to say, they necessarily presuppose a society of individuals, with regard to whom alone rights have existence. If there were only one individual in the world, he would eat and drink, and sleep, and probably would exercise his faculties in some way. But he could neither plunder nor murder, could neither slander nor defame, could neither buy nor sell. He would have no rights, nor w^ould he have any wrongs. He would simply satisfy his personal wants if he could, and having no competitors or disputants, he could neither sue nor be sued. To speak of absolute as something different from relative rights is altogether unmeaning. All rights are equally the accompaniments 1 "As popular liberty without government will degenerate into license, as government without sufficient liberty will degenerate into tyranny, they are mutually necessary to each other ; good govern- ment to sujiport legal liberty, and legal liberty to preserve good government." — Bolingbroke, Fatriot King. "The difference between free and despotic governments is not that the sum of liberties which the former leaves to its subjects exceeds the sum of tlie liberties which are left to its subjects by the latter. The excess in the sum of the liberties which the former leaves to its subjects may be purely mischievous. It may consist of freedom from restraints which are required by the common weal, and which the government would lay upon its subjects if it fulfilled its duties to the Deity. In consequence, for example, of that mis- cliievous freedom its subjects may be guarded inadequately against one another, or against attacks from external enemies. ... A free government leaves or grants to its subjects more of the political liberty which conduces to the common weal." — 1 Austin, Prov. Jur. p. 283, 2«5. en. n.] THE ORIGINAL CONTRACT. 79 of society, and all are alike enforceable by some legal procedure, otherwise they would not be rights at all. They may differ in intensity or in relative value and importance, accordino- to the estimation of the individual ; but in all essential particulars each is as absolute as the other. All that Blackstone probably really meant by the distinction between absolute and relative rights was this, that, of those rights which regard the person, some are common to all members of the commonwealth wdthout exception, at least to all adult members ; while others are conspicuous only in classes and sections of people, or rather they become more prominent in some circumstances than in others.'^ Natural riglds of man. — Again, it has sometimes been said that the three natural rights of man are life, liberty, and property, to which Bentham justly adds rej)utation. But this involves some confusion of ideas, for liberty necessarily includes life and property as well as reputation, and many things besides. Whatever be the law^s under which human beings live, one of their essential tendencies, and indeed an iiLse2:>arable quality of all human beings, is to cherish and defend life, and to create, accumulate, and defend property, and to aspire to various other enjoyments. Liberty is the radical condition of human life, and en- grosses all the faculties and develops the habit of pre- serving life, property, reputation, and the general rights and results of all kinds of labour. Origin of government, social contract, and divine, rigid. — The origin of government and civil society has been a fruitful speculation in all ages, and many volumes have been written to explain by what stages each generation has reached and matured the complicated system of mutual checks, under which modern nations are well pleased to live. Philosophers have often suggested that in prehistoric days the community first chose the tallest and strongest man for a king, as Herodotus says the Ethiopians did in the time of Cambyses.^ Such would be one who was pre-eminent for physical prowess — who had slain his thousands in battle, 1 Blackstone, taking up Coke's expression as to a prior period, says that the absolute rights are declared by the Act of Settlement to be the birthright of the people of England. — 6 Rep. 231 ; 1 Bl. Com. 127. This was obviously a figure of speech, but a good one. 2 Herod, b. 3. 80 ON THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT. [intro, and led the war-dance in intervals of peace. The mere habit of command and obedience may have induced the next most able and active of the same family to be pro- moted to the vacant chiefship, and then the choice may have finally settled for better or for worse in one tribe. Coun- cillors and wise men would then gather round their leader, and fence all the avenues of tyranny about, till tier upon tier of caste and routine should make heavy and stable the seat of power. There is much fancy blended with all such speculations, and each has his own train of ideas and theories to smooth the way through difficulties, and trace the secret links of the chain of order. Much must in such a search turn on the point of departure, and all prefer a stage of barbarism to start from. How the patri- arch from a huntsman became a shepherd, a husbandman, a trader — how one by one families flocked to walled towns, and a network of local government spread over the land — how units became tens, and tens became hundreds, and hundreds became thousands, till each tribe became merged in the crowd, and in the maze nothing but units could at length be clearly distinguishable, and thus became a new point of departure, each being then treated as the radical l3asis of legislation, and of social merit and responsibility. Theory of growth from harharisin. — The theory of natural growth and development out of barbarism has, however, many difficulties. Tribes have for hundi-eds of years shown no signs of advancement, have lacked all invention in common imple- ments — grown more stohd and mechanical — have stagnated in all the isolation of barbarism, and lost almost the lineaments of humanity.^ A descent from higher to lower grades of barbarism is not only in accordance with obser- vation, but is as inscrutable' as inevitable in theory. Double difficulties surround every explanation, and some read backwards and some read forwards the legends of the past. It is enough, however, for lawyers to surrender all such speculations to the philosophers, and to know this and ^ Humboldt said he could not make out whether the savage state was a dawn or a sunset of better days : but preferred the latter hypothesis. NiEBUHR held tliat savages were the remnants of civilised tribes driven to the woods, and who had gradually forgot the arts of settled life. And Wiiatkly remarks that there is no record of savages ever civilising themselves. — Wltaiely, Ess. Civilis. CH. II.] DIVINE RIGHT. 81 this only, tliat no society can exist without the rudiments of laws and of government.^ Laws, though often at first seemingly the sport of chance, are for a time credulously believed in ; till simple faith is gradually transformed into scepticism, and reiiection into criticism ; and the era of reform slowly dawns over the torpid generations, quicken- ing their intuitions till they find new aims, methods, and solutions for overcoming the many varieties of evil, M'ant, and oppression. Societies, as Bolingbroke remarked, are " begun by instinct and are improved by experience." ^ In all stages of advancement, indeed, there are some landmarks not to be overpassed, some restraints inevitable and irre- sistible, and in all forms of government there is much of tlie machinery common, because human nature is much the same in every clime, and moves under the same influ- ences. But no human sagacity or learning has yet made plain, why or how civilisation has quickened most in some climates, and among some races, however ingenious may be the theories which the vanity and self-glorification uf nations put forth on this subject. Theory of divine, right and original contract. — Leaving, however, as inscrutable the historical origin of laws, and their earliest progress, there is still some mystery even in the later stages. Philosophers and divines have discussed two opposing theories — one of divine right, and one of social or original contract. One holds that the governor is heaven-descended ^ — to be received without missiviuLr ^ See ante^ p. 6, as to savages without laws. * Bolingbr. Frag. x. " It is reasonable to conclude that society was coeval with man, and that the saA-age in his woods exhibits the picture of fallen, degenerate man in an unnatural state — the ruined, degraded species rather than his living image in the infancy of the world." — Filanghri, La Sci. (1. LegiaJ. — "The law of nature is inseparable from the nature of thinking l)cings : it subsists and will subsist for ever, in defiance of the passions which obstruct it, the tyrants and impostors who would obliterate or anniliilate it in blood and superstition." — Ibid. eh. iv. ■* " I believe that no creature now maintains that the crown is held by divine hereditary and indefeasible right."' — Burke, Fr. Rev. " The senseless plea of divine and indefeasible right, repugnant to nature and common sense, implies that man can have a property in his fellow-creatures." — fox. Hist. Jas. II. " The wild and absurd doctrine of divine right.'— 1 Bl. Com. 219. VOL. I. G 82 ON THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT. [intro. and obeyed without question — against whom to hesitate is treason, and to rebel is blasphemy. The other holds that all human associations are resolvable into a contract more or less akin to what is going on day by day between man and man, having a beginning and an end, a subject-matter and a remedy. Between these extremes most men vibrate, and it is a matter of temperament, of age, of prosperity, of education, to whicli side each will most incline. Both theories have merits, and both have defects. In all ages and all times nature seems to predispose a sufficient array of contem- poraries, so as to weigh evenly in these opposing scales. To assert or believe that a governor is placed over the governed, and maintained there irrespective of human in- fluences and human wants, and that no derangement in the mutual adaptation justifies a change in the governor, in his prerogatives and liis l^duties, is a dogma which it is too late in the world's history to maintain. On the other hand, to say that no respect is due to tradition, no virtue lies in habitual obedience — that there is no merit in ad- hering to good forms till better are made clearly apparent — that there is no natural harmony between a thoughtful governor and generous, industrious, and well-conditioned subjects, is equally far from the truth.^ There is a divine right on the one side as well as the other. Each theory contains but half a truth, and their conjunction is needed to reconcile both phases of human life. What is clear is, that there is and can be no mutual relation or dealing between man and man on any subject, but that which is resolvable more or less into contract. "WTien slavery ceases, contract DoMiTiAN, in European systems of government, seems entitled to some credit as to the theory of divine riglit. He insisted on his officials beginning, " Our Lord and God conunands so and so." — Suet. Dom. 1 " The comfort and basis of all governments is the mutual good afFection that subsists between the magistrate and the people. If, on the one hand, the magistrate does not love the people, or if, on the other hand, the people do not look up to their magistrate with love and respect, that country never can po on in comfort and prosperity." —Per Ronlce, J. 25 4 Warburton, W. 43. » Bishop Warburton collects {Divine Legation of Moses, b. ii. s. 2) references to the ancients and to the Chinese, Peruvian, Gothic, and Mohammedan codes. DiODORUS Siculus said the old legislators did this, " not only to beget a veneration of their laws, but likewise to establish the opinion of the superintendency of the gods over Roman aflEairs." — Diod. Sic. h. i. Plato also says at the outset of his treatise on laws, " that legislation came from the gods." — De Leg. b. i. s. 1 ; and that it was so in Athens, Crete, and Lacedismon. Herodotus says Lycurgus got his laws direct from the Pythian oracle. — Herod. b. 1. And Plutarch says he got them from Apollo, while Minos got his from Jupiter. — Flut. Lycurg. Not only the laws, but even the Court of Areopagus was deemed by the Athenians to be of divine origin, or, at all events, so ancient that its origin was un- known.—"! ThirlwalVs Greece, 345; Plut. Pericl. The ancient Egyptians also thought the gods dictated their laws. — 2 Wilk. Anc. Egyp. ch. 8. The laws of Upland, a Swedish code of 1295, purported to have a divine sanction. — G Pink. Voy. 621. ■' Horn. II. b. i, 231. " The jjrimitive Christians derived the institu- tions of civil government, not from the consent of the people, but from the decrees of Heaven. Every usurper, when holding the .:h. II.] DIVINE ORIGIN OF LAW. 109 The prevalence of the belief in the divine origin of their municipal laws either accounts for or is closely connected with the extraordinary reluctance of some nations to change their laws, which is only another phase of a belief in their superiority.^ And to the same tendency of the human mind may be ascribed the belief in barbarous tribes as to their original right to their own soil.^ Bceptre, was deemed a vicegerent of the Deity." — Gibbon, Rom. Emp. ch. XX. The Incas always gave out, that 'any new law they issued had been originally sketched out, though not put in a detailed form, by the first of the Incas, in order to give greater authority to what they enjoined. — Com. of Incas, b. ii. ch. ix. And they attributed their immunity from crime chiefly to the belief that the laws were made by the sun, and therefore divine. — lb. b. ii. ch. xiii. ^ So great was the aversion of the Lociians to any new law, that the man who ventured to propose one appeared in pubhc with a rope round his neck, which was at once tightened if he failed to con- vince the assembly of his improvement. — Demosth. cont. Tiinoc, p. 744 ; Polyh. xii. 10. And the same was said of the Thurians and the laws of Zaleucus and Charondas. — Diod. Sic. Solon was more liberal, but the Athenians themselves punished those who proposed a new law inconsistent with existing laws, forgetting that it was the very object of a new law to be so far inconsistent. — " Paronouion," Smith's Diet. The peasants of Livonia were so infatuated in favour of their old laws that they besought the king of Poland not to sub- stitute a milder punishment for the old one, which was whipping till tlie blood flowed. — 13 Univ. Mod. Hist. 125. The laws of the Medes and Persians had the reputation among the ancients of " altering not." — Dan. vi. 12. In Japan it was said any functionary, however exalted, who attempted an innovation, was rejsorted to headquarters and capitally executed. And in the supreme council he, who proposed an altera- tion which was rejected, was requested to disembowel himself as a matter of course.— Perr?/'s Japan. E.eped. i. 16, 17. In China, where the laws were unchangeable, it was recorded as a fearful and wonderful example of innovation, that the Emperor Venti had once abolished the rule, which required that in punishing a criminal his whole family and relatives must be involved in one and the same common ruin with him. — Du Halde's China. ' In all the countries boasting of the earliest civilisation the behef of the nation attributed to itself the immemorial possession of its own soil, and to its progenitors or to the gods the invention of the arts and sciences. Egypt seems in antiquity of civilisation to have surpassed India and China, Babylon and Assyria. — Lepsius, Chron. der Egypt. Oen. xiv. 1. From Egypt civilisatiun passed to Greece, thence to Rome, and thence to the western nations. The Athenians wore grasshoppers in their hair, in testimony of this 110 ON THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT. [intro. There are traces of a kindred spirit in the law of England. Fortescue, in discoursing on the origin of our customs, says the'y are the most venerable in the world for their antiquity, and therefore they are good.^ And Popham, C. J., gravely propounded the view that the laws of England had continued unchanged through all the vicis- situdes of Roman, Danish, Saxon, and Norman sway. And Coke surpasses these speculations in his extravagance.^ Later and more critical eyes have come to other con- clusions. The English common law was chiefly based on the Roman law, and Bracton scarcely introduces a new principle not found there.^ The compiler of the laws of Henry I. evidently had before him a copy of the Theodosian Code, or the Breviarium.^ The Summary of Roman Law, by Vacarius, who was Professor of Civil Law at Oxford in 1149, became well knov/n to the English judges and lawyers of the time.^ And Edward I., on his way to the Holy Land, attended and admired Accursius, whom he invited to England.^ Though all the facts of history contradict the theory, that every chapter and verse of a law giving remedies for all the wrongs that can happen, must have been elaborated by notion. Many ancient nations had a tradition of some foreigner or messenger from heaven having instructed them — Prometheus, Triptolemus, Cadmus. The Peruvians had a similar tradition about one Mancocaijac. Each tribe of American Indians is said to beheve itself superior to all others in virtue and humanity. The Indians of Florida believe that the great Spirit brought them from the ground, and that they are its rightful possessors. — 1 Schooler. Ind. 266 ; 2 lUd. 170, 194. 1 Fortesc. De Laud. c. 17. a " And here it is worthy of consideration how the laws of England are not derived from any foreign law, either canon, civil, or other, but a special law ai)propriated to this kingdom, and most accom- modate and apt for the good government thereof, under which it hath wonderfully flourished when this law hath been put in due execution ; and therefore, as by situation, so by law, it is truly said, — et penitus toto dwisos orhe liritannos." — 2d Inst. lUO. And Lord Chancellor Cowper, at a more advanced stage, when he pronounced sentence on Lord Derwentwatcr, told the latter that he had " at- tempted to raze the very foundaticms of a government the best suited in the world to perfect the happiness and support the dignity of human nature." — R. v Derwentwatcr, 15 St. Tr. 7'J7. => 1 Spence, Eq. Jur. 132. * Savigny, torn. i. 102. « 1 Spcncc, E(i. Jur. 1U9. « Post, p. 127. CH. II.] CHRISTIANITY PART OF THE LAW. Ill some far-seeing and masterly legislature at a period hid in prehistoric ages, yet there is no more common assump- tion than this put forward. The Barons of Eunnymede pointed to tlie time before them in order to give emphasis to their demands. Pym and his compeers resolutely con- tended that all they asked — that each and every article of the Petition of Eight — had been included, or at least implied, in older precedents and in Magna Charta. Old statutes also bear reference to this perpetual harking back to some golden age of laws forgotten or disregarded. And yet much of the legislation of the last two centuries has consisted of efforts to undo what had been done before, and to retreat from much untenable ground taken up in error by former legislators.^ All these phases of the same fundamental idea tend to show that human nature is so constituted, that one's own lineage, tribe, country, and laws, for some unknown reason, are more warmly appreciated than those of strangers, and that law is often nothing else but a manifestation of wisdom for the time being. It seems to come to this, that wisdom is always divine, by whomsoever spoken, whence- soever derived, and by whomsoever demonstrated. It is known and recognised, when it appears, in all times and situations, and by the most depraved beings, just as at the coming of the Gospel, it was said, sorcerers, acting under some unconscious presentiment, burnt their books.^ Hoio far Christianity is part of municipal laiv. — In connection with the same subject there has long been current in the law of England a doctrine, or dictum, that Christianity is part of the municipal law. The old judges vied with each other in wide and sweeping language on this subject.^ Coke said that all laws which are contrary 1 Mackintosh observes that both Whig and Tory antiquaries in the seventeenth century agreed in the mistaken notion, that the Saxon government was well ordered, and that through all the changes of tlie previous six hundred years tlie same political and legal institutions had existed. They forgot that a government is not framed like a model, but grows out of occasional acts. — 1 Mack. Hist. Eng. T2. - Acts xix. v. 19. ^ " Scripture is common law, on which all manner of laws are founded."— Prisnt, C. J., 24 Hen. VI. Year-Bk. 40. Per Jermm, J. (4 St. Tr. 1289—" The law of England is the law of God ; it is pure primitive reason, uncorrupted and unpolluted by human 112 ON THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT. [intro. to Christianity cease.^ And he said torture was contrary to the laws of God; and that the law of weights and measures was grounded on the law of God.^ Hale, C. J., said, on a trial for blasphemous libel, " To say that religion is a cheat is to destroy the frame of society, and the Christian religion being a part of the constitution, to say that it is an imposture, is to speak against the laws of the land."^ Lord Kaymond, at a later date, repeated the doctrine, but taking care to add a proviso, that the law should not extend to the disputes between learned men on controverted points of religion.* Lord Hardwicke recog- nised a like doctrine.^ Lord Mansfield said the essential principles of revealed religion are part of the common law." Lord Keuyon again followed the same view, and said the Christian religion is part of the law of the land.'^ Lord Ellenborough, referring to these remarks, said that they showed, that the Christian religion was the law of the land and must be protected as the law.^ And Blackstone said the same.^ And Lord Eldon said the same when dealing with the right of Dissenters as to a charity.^*^ The same judge said the court would not protect copyright in a book which contradicted the Scriptures. ^^ These views led Lord Eldon to refuse to recognise copyright in Bj'ron's " Cain," and " Don Juan," also in " Wat Tyler,"!^ and to disclose views as to the relations between courts of law and the press not since acquiesced in. Though it is thus said on high authority, that Christianity, or the law of God, is part of the law of England, it is obvious, that all that is meant is something very different humours or human corruptions, wits, or wills." Per Keble (4 St. Tr. 1307) " The law of God is the law of England ; so is the law of reason." — Ih. 5 St. Tr. 172. "Whatsoever is not consonant to the law of God in Scripture is not the law of England. The laws of England are purely the laws of God. — Ih. 5 St. Tr. 238. " We have no law practised in this land, but is the law of God." — Ibid. 1 Calvin's Case, 7 Rep. 17. 2 2 Inst. 41. 3 Taylor's Case. 1 Ventr. 293 ; 3 Keb. 607. «■ R. v Woolston, 2 Str. 832. « De Costa v De Vaz, 2 Swanst. 490. « 2 Camp. C. JJs. 613 ; 16 Pari. Hist. 319. 7 Williams's Case, 26 St. Tr. 704 ; Woolston's Case, 2 Str. 834. « R. V Eaton, 31 St. Tr. 950. » 4 Bl. Com. 59. i« Bedford Charity, 2 Swanst. 527; Att. Gen. v Pearson, 3 Mer. 399. " Laurence v Smith, 1 Jac. 474. ^* Southey v Sherwood, 2 Mer. 435 ; Murray v Benbow, 1 Jac. 474 n ; 7 Campb. Ch. 659. OH. 11.] THE DIVINE LAW. 113 from what the words imply. Christianity is a system of doctrines, mainly deduced from the Holy Scriptures, in- tended to intiuence the conduct of man in all ages and conditions, but in a manner altogether different from that which the municipal law adopts. Christianity does not profess to contain any compulsory methods, or to act with the aid of temporal sanctions. It relies on the future, the distant, and the unseen, rather than the present and the visible. It searches the motives and the feelings, while the municipal law deals almo.st exclusively with outward acts. But the essential differential quality is this, that the municipal law can and does enforce its rules by sanctions more or less cogent, such sanctions beginning and ending with the present life,^ while Christianity has no temporal sanctions, and relies on moral and spiritual restraints alone to promote its aims. The domain of the one is far-reaching and infinite : that of the other is limited and temporary. The one fills the mind with thoughts, feelings, and contemplations which intiuence the conduct in a more durable and effective manner. The other, dealing only with the present, cares little or nothhig for the mental state, provided the sanction takes effect — a sanction which only inflicts pain, or deprives the individual of lifCj property, or liberty. The things also which the one law cares for are petty in comparison with the vast range of the other. As far as the heaven is above the earth, so far is the divine law above the municipal law, or, to quote Fortescue, " as the moon is to the sun, so are human laws to the divine."^ The aims and objects of municipal law are ephemeral and weak, and often satisfied with mere forms. Life, property, reputation, a fair trial, free speech, a share in self-government, are objects \vell worthy of beinc contended for, and the radical idea of the law, namely, impartiality towards all alike, lends a dignity and elevation to its practice. But there are objects greater than these, which can be promoted without the coarse * The ancient laws of Zoroaster seemed to stand out beyond all other laws in bokllj' pressing its sanctions beyo'id tlie present life. The person who broke a contract or told a Jie was sentenced to 300 lashes, and the same number of years in hell. And for non- payment of school fees 900 years in hell were added to 900 lashes. —D'Aiiq. Zend. Av. 286. - Fortesc. De Nat. b. i. c 3. VOL. I. I 114 OX THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT. [intro, dissuasives of bodily pain, or compulsory deprivation of property, namely, by reliance only on rewards and gratifi- cations which have no immediate or tangible existence, and feelings which are invisible and incommunicable, yet which irradiate all surrounding conditions and circum- stances of life. While the municipal law makes selfishness a science, the divine law, passing from that engrossing pursuit, leads to a higher level, where most of the processes are reversed, the machinery is changed, and a conscious- ness of dignity and grandeur is acquired which no human law can awaken or command. Divine lav: not enforced as riiimicipal laic. — When it is said, therefore, that the divine law or Christianity is part of the law of England, this is wandering from the true view. The municipal law does not and cannot, and it would be impious for it to attempt to, enforce most parts of the divine law, and it can only punish in an imperfect manner tlie violation of a small part of it. Out of the Tea Commandments, which deal with the leading tendencies and proclivities of human nature,^ not one of them can be enforced by the municipal law, except in the feeble manner of punishing the delinquent after the wickedness lias been committed ; and even to that slight extent, the sixth and eighth commandments, those aimed against murder and larceny, may be said to be the only commandments which are followed up closely.^ All the divine commandments ^ The Siamese, the Buddhists, the Talapoys of Laos, the Banyans and Parsees, and Triptoleuuis had some golden rules resembling the Ten Commandments. Jewish writers record that certain short precepts of moral duty, known as the precepts of the sons of Noah were really enjoined by God on the parent of mankind, whether preserved by tradition, or by an innate moral factdty, constantly discerned by mankind. These were prohibitions a^^ainst idolatry, blasphemy, murder, adultery, theft, rebellion, and cutting a limb from a living animal. — 3 Uallam^ Lit. Hist. 146. " Warbuuton says society, i.e. the law, cannot enforce above one- third part of moral duties, and even that third imperfectly. It can punish, but cannot reward. — 4 Warburton, Works, 33. Plutarch said goodness moves in a larger sphere than justice : the obligations of law and justice reach only to mankind, but kind- ness and beneficence should be extended to creatures of every species. — Plut. Cato Cens. Aeistotle said that philosophy enabled him to do, without being cit. 11.] THE DIVINE LAW. 115 have a wide and far-reaching effect on the soul and on the secret thoughts, but the municipal law only singles out a few of the most glaring and conspicuous accompaniments of a depraved heart. It cares nothing for murdering the mind and its finer feelings by lies and refined cruelties of speech and writing, but only for murdering the body, for, as Hale says, " Secret things belong to God." Nothing for stealing many of the appliances and cherished mental possessions of another, but only for stealing a few chattels and visible signs of property. The other divine command- ments shrink into the very smallest dimensions in the hands of the municipal law. The injunction to worship one God, the prohibition of the worship of graven images, and of taking the name of God in vain, the injunction to keep the Sabbath-day, to honour one's parents, the jDro- hibition of adultery and perjury and covetousness are feebly reflected in the municipal law. Tliose who recall to mind the place assigned in the latter law to the jjunish- ment of blasphemy and profanity, the enactments against working and amusements on the Lord's Day, the poor law statutes as to neglecting to support indigent parents, the partial remedies given in some cases of adultery and perjury, the total blank as to covetousness, will appreciate at a glance how little the divine law can be said to be incorpo- rated in the nmnicipal law of England. The municipal law has no faculties to comprehend the heights and depths of the divine law. The Sermon on the Mount meets with a feeble response or recognition throughout the whole length and breadth of the statutory and common law. When the exigencies of argument and the necessity of devising some means of reckoning loss or damage requn-es the law to form an ideal for comparison, the highest legal speculation cannot soar above the standard of a reasonably prudent but mostly selfish man, that is to say, a man not indeed inclined to give vent to ungovernable passion, and not un- willing to hear both sides, but nevertheless a man alwavs acting from some prudential consideration — not apt to commanded, wliat others did from fear of the laws. — Diog. Laert. Arisf. The code of Kina: Alfred begins with a translation of the Ten Conanandments, whicli he uses as tlie kej^note fur his o\\ n edicts us to the lex talionis, &c. — Aju: I.aicti Eikj. I 2 116 ON THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT. [intiio. make gifts — careful of his money — in no case given to take more care of others tliau of himself — ^jealous of his wife's or chikl's honour, and entitled to kill an adulterer if detected in the act — one bound to carry out his contract, whether wise or unwise, hut in many cases only if it be made in writing — one who pays for an indigent parent or child just enough to sustain life — one not bound to feed the hungry or clothe the naked, except only where the destitute is a child of which he has undertaken the custody — one not bound to observe any forms of civility whatever — one entitled to amass as much property as he can, and often to slay any man in the act of robbing him of it — one repudiating all feelings of gratitude^ — •one not bound to do any generous or friendly act, or to risk his life to save another — one entitled to drown his neighbour to save his own life — one entitled to use any species of exaggeration or subterfuge, or meanness, in order to drive a bargain — one entitled in all circumstances, and with little discri- mination, to kill another in self-defence — one not restrained in the indulgence of the most odious passions, and vices, envy, malevolence, ingratitude, evil-speaking, lust, and insolence. These and such like infirmities, clinging to the normal man, the law is powerless to restrain, and generally exempts from blame. And though for some collateral inquiries a higher standard is sometimes remembered as being possible, yet such standard seems rather to be viewed as erratic. Blasphemy as j;or^ of municipal law. — These considera- tions show how far from correct the saying is, that the divine law is part of the .law of England. The two laws are essentially diverse ; they move in different orbits, and address different sides of the same human nature. The only occasions on which the doctrine prevails is, when cases arise in which a test is required for measuring the ^ The ancient Persians pnniahcd criminally the vice of ingratitude, which seemed to consist in not returning favour for favour. — Xen. Mem. b. ii. ; Xeno]>h. Cyrop. And a Roman freedman was punisli- able snmmaril}' for ingratitude to liis patron. — Fetit. fol. 51, tit. 8 ; WoofFs Jmtit. Anaciiausis, the intelligent foreigner of his day, laughed at Solon for attempting to restrain avarice and injustice by laws, for, like spiders' webs, they would only entangle the poor and weak, and let the rich i.nd -powerful escape. — Plut. Solon. CH. II.] THE DIVINE LAW, 117 liberty of free speecli or writing, or of bequeathing property- If any man assails and ridicules some leading doctrines of the divine law, specified in a statute of William III., in such a style as to show that he is not arguing or reasoning honestly, but intends to insult and revile the common faith of the majority of his fellow-subjects, he commits a criminal offence by virtue of such statute.^ The statute is somewhat vague as to the persons aimed at, yet makes it incumbent to inquire what are the doctrines of the divine law which are thus identified with the religious convictions of the community. It is a cherished sentiment of natural piety, that some thoughts and feelings are too deep for profane and insolent levity, and as private character is protected against the libeller, so it appears to follow that the sacred character of Divine Persons is, so to speak, protected against the blas- phemer. Yet all this is not inconsistent with the primary right of all men to utter or publisli fair argument and discussion, if done reverently and with measured respect to the feelings of others. And thus it is, that, notwith- standing the statute above mentioned, Christianity cannot be viewed as part of the municipal law any more than all other branches of knowledge or sciences are part of it, when these require examination for some collateral purpose bearing on the liberties and securities of property and of free speech and thought. The unqualified asser- tion that Christianity is part of the law of England in the natural sense of that expression, tends only to suggest how narrow is the province of the municipal law. In cases of libel, copyright, or bequest, the courts at most require to consider this subject for collateral purposes. And in cases of violent and scurrilous extravagance in discussing the great truths of religion, the court must draw the line where blasphemy begins and fair argument and dis- cussion end.^ But it may be safely affirmed that nothing in this law substantially interferes with a reverent and careful discussion and expression of opinion on any subject human or divine, so long as it is not done merely to insult and shock the laudable feelincrs of others.^ And collateral o 1 9 & 10 W. Ill c. 35 ; 53 Geo. III. c. 160. 2 R. u Waddington, 1 B. & Cr. 27 ; R. u Carlile, 3 B. & A](l. IGl. Erskine, in his prosecution o£ Williams, most powerfully puts 118 ON THE LIBEETY OF THE SUBJECT. [intro. contracts involving the violation of tlie statute of blas- j^beniy will often for like reasons not be enforced.^ The feudal Imu. — The feudal law was not the distinctive law of any nation, but was rather the law of real property accepted by nearly all European nations from the fifth to the thirteenth centuries. It embodied the settled views and opinions of those times as to the relations between the crown and the subject with respect to the tenure of land, for land was then the most conspicuous suliject of property, and war being tlie chief occupation, or that which was held of most consequence among men, the two things were sought to be used in aid of each otlier. A compact system of doctrines and practices was then framed, or had grown up into maturity, and gave apparently great satisfaction, owing to its being easily applied and understood. Nothing pleases the barbarian mind so much as what is simple, and does not require the trouble of thinking much or long ; and nearly all nations of northern origin accepted the feudal law as a book of their constitution. For five centuries it grew and prospered, and Guizot said that for the tenth century it was necessary, and the only practicable social state of thought.- Blackstone conjectures that it was owing to the defencelessness experienced in England, when an invasion from Denmark was apprehended in 1085, that William I. held a great council at Sarum to inquire into the matter thus, though his language is somewhat beyond the needs of the law : " In a country whose government and constitution rest for their very foundations vipon the truths of the Cliristian religion, a bold, impious, blasphemous, and public renunciation of them must be a high crime and misdemeanor. Of all human beings the poor, among whom such books circulate, stand most in need of the conso- lations of religion, and the country has the deepest stake in their enjoj'ing it. not only from the protection which it owes tliem, bMt because no man can be expected to be faithf id to the authority of man who revolts against the government of God." — 26 St. Tr. 703. AsnuHS'i', J., can scarcely l)e said to express the modern law : " Such libels are not only oifences to God, but crimes against the laws of the land, and are punisliable as such, inasnuich as they tend to destroy tiiose obligations whereby civil society is bound togotlier, and it is upon this ground tliat the Cliristian religion constitutes ])art of the laws of England ; but that law without the means of (uiforcing its precepts would be but a dead letter." — 26 St. Tr. 716. The prisoner hud sentence of imprisomnent and hard labour for one year. i Cowan v Milburn, L. li. 2 Exc. 2;30. * Guizot, Eur. Civ. Lect. 4. CH. ir.] THE FEUDAL LAW. 119 the state of the nation, and he soon after directed the jireat survey called Domesday-hook, aiter which the principal landliolders, heing sensible of the great advantages of the union and mutual support supplied hy the feudal system, voluntarily submitted their lands to military tenure, and did homage and fealty to the king.^ Hence both sovereign and subject with one consent adopted the popular tenure of the day. So enamoured were the French people about the same time with the new system, that they surrendered their allodial or free lands, so as to hold them from their Icing as a re-grant.^ The feudal system was thus generally accepted m England soon after the Conquest, though the learned have speculated much as to the precise time and manner of its introduction, growth, and general adoption there. Some, indeed, think the feudal system is as old as human nature, and that wherever military conquests have been made, it was and is inevitable that the general should have the chief voice in dividing among his lieutenants, and they among their men in the proportion of their respective ranks, the conquered land and its fruits ; and next, that conditions of service should be added so as to mark and rivet the mutual dependence between links of the great chain. Thus the gift of lands for the military service was made by the Eoman emperors Severus and Probus.^ And though in many countries, ancient and modern, something nearly resembling the feudal relation of lord and vassal has been traced, yet, as Hallam and others observe, the exact bond of union is not identical, as in the case of Roman patron and client — the zemindaries of Hindoostan — the timariots of Turkey — the Polish and Ptussian nobles and their vassals. The manners of the ancient Germans seem a sufficiently satisfactory origin of the feudal system to many — without troubling themselves to think how it was that it occurred to the Germans. And the customs of the different French provinces as digested by Beaumanoir about the year 1283, closely resemble those of England during the same period. Moreover the Assizes of Jerusalem, a body of laws compiled by Godefroy de Ijouillon, the newly- elected king, soon after the conquest of Jerusalem in 1099, ' Saxon Clironicle, c. 52, c 58. " 2 Bl. Com. 51. 3 A.D. 222, 216. 120 ON THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT. [intuo. on the advice of the wisest men of all countries, are little else than copies of the customs and usa^-es current in France. All this shows how well adapted tlie feudal law was to the minds of those who accepted it, and what confidence they all had in its stability.^ It is not necessary in this place to enter into any details as to these matters, for such of them as are material belong properly to another division of law, when the tenure of land requires to be treated. It is enough to notice here generally what has come to be the position which the feudal law now occupies as part of the law of England. At the time when that law flourished it embodied nearly all the law that men cared to know, but it has since shrunk into very narrow dimensions, and is relegated to an obscure corner among the things worthy to be only occasionally remembered. Nations are no longer exclusively engrossed with fighting and conquering their neighbours, and have discovered that there are vast fields of enterprise in re- dressing the wrongs, defects, and oppressions existing under their own internal economy, sufticient to engage the ambi- tion of nobler warriors and more dictatorial dictators than ancient or mediteval times ever produced. Yet as the feudal stamp was so deeply impressed on the land arrange- ments of England as well as on those of its neighbours, and modern rules still current seem so obscure and so mixed up with its history, a general notice of its purport may be here stated, and it may be stated very brieily. It is idle to speak of the feudal law as the cause of great mischief to mankind, as it is idle to speak of the evils of infancy or of barbarism. At the time it flourished that law seems to have adequately supplied a satisfactory adjust- ment of the relations arising out of real property, and as slavery was part of the settled system of society, it was natural that the two ideas should be niterwoven in all the arrangements. But when slavery ceased to be accepted by modern nations as a necessary element of society, it followed 1 1 Hullain, Mid. Ages, 200 ; Montesquieu, b. 30, c. 2 ; 1 Meyer, Inst. Jiidic. 4 ; Tinkerton, Origin o£ Goths, 139 ; Robertson's Cli. V. Stuart's Soc. in Europe ; Barrington's Anc. St. 43'J ; 2 Bl. Com. 48. Guizot prefers the derivation of the word feud from /e and od^ a pro|H'rty given in recompense by way of pay or reward. — 3 Quiz. Cio. Fr. Lee. 12. CH. II.] THE FEUDAL LAW. 121 that most of this complicated web required to be unwoven piece by piece, till the fatal thread was witlidrawii. The texture may have been irretrievably damaged by this ab- straction, but according to modern views of the object of all laws, we have ceased as entirely to think of reverting for our instruction and guidance to feudal times, as we do of reverting to the Saxon heptarchy, or the practices of the rude tribes described by Tacitus and Ctesar. Theory on which the feudal law was founded. — The radical theory of the feudal law was this, that the king is the universal lord and original proprietor of all the lands in his kingdom, and that no man doth or can possess any part of it, but what has mediately or immediately been derived as a gift from him to be held upon feudal services. And the moving cause for the crown granting, and tor each crown vassal making smaller grants to his sub-vassals, was, that each might, as occasion required, render military service, and follow his lord both at home and abroad wherever the demon of war beckoned them. To ratify this bond, the oath of fealty was taken by the vassal or holder of each allotment, or feud, lief, or fee, as it was called. And when the vassal violated his oath by not performing the stipu- lated service, or by deserting the lord in battle, the lands again reverted to him who granted them. Both parties thus closely connected, the lord and his vassal, were mutually bound to protect their respective possessions, and thus a complete network of common interests and correlative support covered the kingdom.^ When the vassal obtained a grant, he knelt before his lord and did homage in pre- sence of other vassals, and received a typical delivery of the land, and became bound to attend the local court of the lord, who assumed judicial power of life and death over all within his barony. The land was held sometimes on the precarious tenure of the lord's will, sometimes the tenant's interest was for a year certain, sometimes for life, sometimes for the son and the heirs of the vassal, and 1 GuizoT observes justly : " It is often said that tlie feudal system connected by indissoluble links the whole of society. This is a pure theory. In fact, the greater number of feudal lords were com- pletely independent of the sovereign ; a great number had scarcely heard the name of monarchy, and had few if any relations witli it." — Guizot, Eur. Civ. Lect, 9. 122 ON THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT. [intro. sometimes for the alienees or assigns.^ In each phase some slavish accompaniment was fixed upon, such as fines, reliefs, and other exactions, under the pretence of obtaining the lord's consent or sanction to everything which the vassal did. The habit of dictation on the one hand, and obedience on the other, engendered by so close a connection in barbarous times, soon produced its natural fruit ; and the stronger party gradually imposed on the weaker party more and more conditions and services, and these more or less oppres- sive to tlie vassal, so that the irksomeness of the whole soon began to be felt and complained of during the three first reigns of the Conquest. This in turn, however, was not unaccompanied by some compensating advantage, for it led Henry I. to promise a restoration of the laws of Edward the Confessor, and to grant a charter, which was the foundation of tliat celebrated Magna Charta extorted at Eunnymede from John and confirmed by Henry HI., and which marked so important an epoch in the law. The mutuality of feudal services accustomed kings to consult with their chief subjects. It was especially fortunate for England that the feudal laws fostered a spirit of turbulence and self-reliance in the crown vassals. Hallam says it diffused a spirit of liberty,'' and Guizot describes it thus : " Feudalism did a great service to Inimanity by exhibiting a continual example of individual will developing itself in all its energy." ^ In England it was said wardsliip and marriage, the two harshest incidents, were more prevalent than in other countries. The vice of the feudal tenure appears on the surface of its ordinary working. If I bought or hired a piece of land from a man, why should I be so linked to his destiny and share in all his joys and sorrows so intimately, that when his son was to be knighted or his daughter to be married I must pay him large sums; if he was put in prison, why was I to ransom him ? If I died or sold the land, why should my son, or my alienee pay him a large bounty in 1 Guizot says it is a common mistake, wliich the "Book of Feuds" shares, tliat at first the vassal's interest was always precarions, and then advanced slowly stage hy stage, first to a fixed tcnn, then to interest for life, then for the heirs and assigns. He says all tlicie forms ffourished togelher, and contemporaneously from lir.st to last, ~?i Guizot., Fr. Civ. Lect. 2. * 1 Hallam, I\Iid. Ag. 2G8. ^ Guizot Eur. Civ. Lect. 7. cri. II.] THE FEUDAL LAW. 123 the form of a relief or fine ? and why should my best horse or jewel belon;:^ to him ? If I committed a crime, why should my land he confiscated by him ? If I left an infant heir, why sliould he insist on being the guardian, and reap- ing tJie profits, and finding that heir a wife ; and if I left an infant heiress, why should he insist on her marrying one of three persons he chose to name, otherwise to pay him a large sum to be off the bargain ? Ail these consequences were so utterly illogical and incoherent, that nothing but the mailed hand and nomadic life and rough rapacious liabits of the camp could so long have perpetuated them. Ahusc and decay of that law. — The ultimate effect of the feudal system was to make it impossible for any subject to concentrate in himself the entire rights relating to his land and enjoy absolute property, for as he always held of some lord, tliis dependence in reality required the entire ownersliip to be split up into portions which complicated the title. For though one might have the substantial right or dominium utile, yet the incidents attaching to the lord- ship or superior right detracted from its value, and so in- terfered with and crippled the absolute ownersliip as sometimes to create a forfeiture or total annihilation of the vassal's interest, and at all times he felt himself oppressed with vexatious and irrelevant exactions.^ After centuries of growing abuses arising out of feudal tenures it M'as at length seen that there was not in reality, and ought not to be, any logical connection between the lord and the vassal sufficient to constitute this compulsory and intimate part- nership between them in the land, for by doing so the benefits were all on one partner and the burdens all on the other, and complication and confusion beset both. Each individual ought to be able to enjoy the fuU and absolute rights of property which the law allows, independent of the acts or incidents of third persons, and it was chiefly owing to this change in the views of society that the most preposterous of the feudal characteristics were totally abolished in the reign of Charles II., and a gradual disposi- tion has ever since grown up to convert copyhold and other tenures, the outstanding relics of feudalism, into freehold tenure, that is to say, into an absolute and undivided 1 The feudal system declined in England very rapidly from the time of Edward L— 3 Hallam, Mid. Ag. 1G5. 124 ON THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT. [intro ownership. This species of ownership is the only sound arrangement compatible with a state of society in which slavery is no longer tolerated or acknowledged, and in which business is sought to be facilitated, and free play allowed to the varied operations of commerce.^ The civil law, what. — It is necessary to advert to several significations given to the words " civil law." The first meaning is that which puts it in contrast to such phrases as criminal law, military law, ecclesiastical law. The other more limited and special meaning is that which denotes the Eoman law, or the municipal law of the Eoman Empire. The division of the law into criminal and civil has already been adverted to, and it was shown that, though it was not so substantial a division as to be adopted in any systematic exposition of the whole law, yet it was a popular iind convenient mode of separating the treatment of rights according as the violations of law were slight or grave. Sometimes also the expressions military and naval law are used in contrast to civil law, as separating those peculiar laws which regulate the military and naval pro- fessions. This distinction is obviously one of mere con- venience, and indicates no fundamental principle. Again, the phrase " ecclesiastical law " is in like manner used in contradistinction to civil law, as indicating those laws wliich peculiarly relate to the Church and the clergy, the rest of the law being in that view described as civil law. These ecclesiastical laws, as alread}^ pointed out, fall under 1 Tlie feudal law is the delight of antiquaries, and Spelman mar- velled that my Lord Coke had not turned into so fruitful a field. — Spehn. Grig, of Terms, ch. viii. Montesquieu admired the feudal system, and compared it to an old and majestic oak. Bentiiam compared it to that fat^l tree the manchineel, whose juices arc poisons to man, and wliose shade is destructive to vegetation. — Bentliam's Princ. of Civ. Code, ch. vi. J. S. Mill says the fcMidal law possessed a certain degree of suit- ableness to the wants of the society among whom it grew up, but advancing civilisation heaped law upon law over it like strata in the physical world, and " every struggle in the disjointed condition of the part of tlie Held of law which covers the spot, nay, the very traps and pitfalls which one contending party set for another, are still standing, and the teeth, not of hyionas only, but of foxes and all cunning animals, arc imprinted on the curious remains found in these antediluvian caves." CH. 11.] THE ROMAN LAW. 125 the important division of the law, entituled " Security of Public Worship." TJiC lloman laic, called the civil laiv. — The civil law, or the Eonian law, was the most elaborate system of muni- cipal law which had held a conspicuous place in the world, until the middle ages slowly developed the laws of modern nations, which contained many new views and settlements unknown to the ancients, and which now, having been matured, have almost entirely cut off the modern from the ancient polity. Justinian's collection of the Roman law was completed by Tribonian and other lawyers about tlie year 53-4, and was current in the eastern portion of tlie empire. In the western part of the Eoman Empire there had previously been an attempt also to consolidate the immense mass of laws then current. Two private lawyers, supposed to have lived in the reign of Constantine, had made collections with that view, called the Gregorian and Hermogenian codes, and the Emperor Theodosius the Younger directed a code of imperial constitutions to be compiled about the year 438, then and thereafter known as the Theodosian code. But when the civil, or Eoman, law is referred to, it is the body of law bearing the name of Justinian which occupies the leading place. The body of law called by the name of Justinian began with the code published in 529, and revised in 534, and the digests or pandects in 534. Of these digests,, which were loosely arranged, the extracts from Ulpian constituted about one-third of the work, from I'aulus a sixth, and from Papinian a twelfth. The Institutes accompanied the digests as an introduction founded on the commentaries of Gains and others. Lastly, the novels, or new constitutions were published soon after Justinian's death, which occurred in 565. Justinian's body of law was after 300 years re- placed by the Basilica of Leo, which was republished in 945. The Basilica, with some new constitutions of the later emperors, still held favour at ConstantinoiJe when the Turks, in 1453, extinguished the Eastern Empire and its law. In the Western Empire Justinian's laws had been little known, but the study became more prominent at Bologna in the twelfth century.^ 1 Savigny pointed out the mistake long current, that tlie discovery of the copy of the Pandects at the siege of Anialfi, in 11.35, was the 12G ON THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT. [intro. The Commentaries of Gaius, the earliest institutional writer who flourished in the time of the Antonines, were imperfectly known till a copy was accidentally discovered in 1816 liy Niebuhr, and published in 1820, and this has added much to the interest of this branch of legal study. Its impoi'tance and application in Engla7id. — The Eoman law will always command the attentive study of all who desire to be assisted by the ripe experience of generations of the jurists of a great and powerful empire, which long held sway over great varieties of tribes and nations. Much of the art of governing mankind, and the art of putting difficulties in train for a solution, is common to all countries, and as the phraseology used by that law has long been current, and been absorbed into all modern languages, and moreover as large portions of that law have been bodily appropriated, or at least adopted with very little variations by several modern countries, the utility of such a study is obvious, and is not so visionary as many practical men represent. In England in modern times the chief sources of interest lie in the law of contracts and the law of servitudes, and the courts of this country have gladly borrowed a ready-made solution for difficulties, which no recognised rule of their own clearly provided for, by resorting to the storehouse of precedents accepted and acted upon in those departments of the civil law.^ Though the Eoman law has no intrinsic authority in means of first diffusing a knowledge of that part of the Roman law, as other copies were studied before that date. — 1 Hallam, Const. i/. 63; 2 Guizot, Cio. Fr. Lect. 11. At certain epochs the tenets of the civil law fascinated ruder minds, and we are told that at Florence the copy of the civil law was deposited as a sacred relic in a rich casket, bound in purple, and exhibited to travellers by monks and magistrates bareheaded, and with ligiited tapers, as if it had been a divine revelation. — Brenck- mun, b. i. ch. x. 1 Savigny : " Our admiration of the Romaii law is almost entirely confined to its theory of contracts. The remainder of this law might have been discovered by plain good sense, without any juridical cultivation, and for i^o slight a gain it is not worth while to invoke the laws and lawyers of two thousand years to help us." — Savujny, Voc. of (he Age (tr. by Hay ward), 43. Fabkr and Hottoman (IGIO) o])posed the study of the Roman law as full of obsolete doctrines, which gave no assistance to modern lawyers in njatters of daily occurrence. Hottoman said not one- CH. II.] THE EOMAN LAW. . 127 England, yet the English law in the time of Bracton and the earliest writers was largely made up of extracts and adaptations from the summaries of that law then current amont? learned men in all countries.^ Though Coke and others resolutely maintained, that the English common law was indigenous, this view is opposed to the common knowledge and habits of international intercourse which prevailed in the twelfth, thirteenth, and fourteenth centuries. 2 England partook of the common heritage of the age. Yet in modern times even Bracton's authority is not conclusive evidence of what was the ancient law of England, vmless it further appears from subsequent writers or reports, that the courts had acted upon it. Thus in the case as to the right of the public to go along the banks of navigable rivers and use them as towing paths, though Bracton, using the same language as the lioman law, said the right existed, and Holt, C. J., in a dictiuii approved of it, yet the court on second thoughts and fuller consideration found that the rule was nowhere referred to or acted on in subsequent times, and rejected the claim altogether.^ And for a like reason, in the memorable case in 1821 where the public claimed a right to pass over any private part of the sea- shore to get at the sea for purposes of bathing, and the dicta of Bracton and the Eoman law were relied on for the public right, the court held that there was no evidence that such a rule had ever been adopted in this country, that it was in conflict with other admitted rules, and the public claim was accordingly rejected.'* The Roman law was, however, followed in the solution of novel and perplexing questions which have arisen in our courts as to the mutual rights of owners of lands throu5, the senatus consuUa, and constitutions of the emperors, as well as the edicts of praetors and magistrates, and the responses of jurisconsults ; while that part of the law, consisting of rules of practice and of argument, and orally used and referred to, but not recorded, and known as customary law, was called the unwritten law.^ Though this distinction has always been drawn between the written and unwritten law, lietween the statute law and the common law, it is a distinction which indicates little more than the origin, or rather the form in which the law has been promulgated, for it is obvious that whether a law, if properly made, has been immediately put into writing and printed, or has circulated as an oral tradition, can make no real difference as regards its binding effect. It may be more difficult to ascertain and interpret an oral law than one that is put into articulate language;^ for, the more vague and general a law is, the more difficult it is to be applied and acted upon, and vagueness is more likely to attach to a law which circulates in the memory of the people than to one which is recorded in written language, and which the rules of interpretation can tix with reasonable certainty. Statute, law is supphmeniary to common laui — I)nt though the mere distinction between common law and stat\ite law is based on the original medium in which each law is found, rather than on the subject-matter of the law itself, 1 Dig. i. 1, G. cii. 11. STATUTE LAW AND COMMON LAW. 1.33 there is also a lai'fje and important difference in their scope and mutual relations. The statute law is in strictness merely supplementary to the common law. The conunon law, however it may have originated, is assumed to have formed the sum total of the laws governing the community before statutes were made and published. Being the sum total of the law, it is further assumed, and this assump- tion is the most remarkable of its characteristics, to have provided for nearly all the ordinary evils which laws could cure, and to have supplied the remedy for nearly every wrong, at least such as were prominent at that remote age. It has been and still is the province of the legislature to discover and amend the common law in those points where it is vague and inadequate, or fails to meet the exigencies of the time The whole series of statutes embody these results of legislative vicjilance. Hence, in order to under- stand thoroughly what a statute means, it is often necessary, and always useful, if not indispensable, to know what was the state of tlie common and statute law on the subject antecedently to the statute in question. When that pre- liminary knovv'ledge is acquired, the task of interpretation is greatly facilitated, for, as will be seen hereafter, one of the canons of interpretation is, first to ascertain, what was the evil or mischief in view of the legislature when the statute was passed. There is in civilisation no rule more clearly established than this, that the exposition of the law shall be left to the courts, and the declaration of new law be left to the legislature ; and as a corollary to this the maxim is in- exorable, that when once the legislature has spoken, those words cannot be unspoken by any power except the legisla- ture itself. Once a statute, always a statute. Nothing short of a new statute is required to repeal a piior statute, and no length of non-user will ever render the wonls of a statute less obligatory and less decisive than they were the first day the statute was published. This, however, was by no means the ancient idea of legislative action. The notion that a statute became void, when the king who was the chief actor in passing it died, or when it had been long neglected, was current in England in early times, as it was current then and much later in other countries. The ancient doctrine was, that statutes could go into 134 ON THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT. [i^tro. desuetude by neglect.^ Hence the practice so common in the reigns succeeding that of John, of republisliing Magna Charta at the commencement of each new reign, and even at the commencement of a new parliament.'^ And Eichard II. had an ordinance that all previous statutes be kept, which shows how loose were the notions at first enter- tained as to the indelibility of statutory law. Theories as to origin of common law. — Several theories have been current as to the mode in which the common law originated, thouG[h Lord Hale said its orifrinal was as undiscoverable as the head of the Nile,^ and Fortescue and Coke, as we have seen, are extravagant in antedating its rise. Not a few resort to the ingenious fiction, that the com- mon law is merely a collection of ancient statutes which have been worn out ^ by time, but of which the purport and bearing have lingered in the memory, and have been handed down as traditions from age to age.* This theory indeed eludes all the lessons of history, and as an explana- tion it in reality amounts only to this, that some of the statutes are a little older than we suppose, while the point to be elucidated is the state of things antecedent to statute, for statutes after all indicate an advanced stage of society. Another theory is, that the common law is merely a collection of the general customs found universally current, and acted on by the people. Special or local customs are familiar in many branches of the law at the present day, as will be seen in subsequent chapters ; but their operation is not universal. Local customs are confined to a limited area, and to limited classes of people, and often to special times or occasions ; and as such they are devia tions from or exceptions to the general law, and binding on a limited part of the community only, or at least on 1 Barrhigton, Stat. 186. The Konians had a principle, tliat by long disuse a law became void and of no effect. — Gic. in Verr. v. 18; Inst. 1, 2, 11 ; Dip. 1, 3, 32. Ill Scotland this doctrine is applied to all the Scotch statutes passed before the Union in 1707. a 5 Ed. 2, Ord. c. 27 (Stat. Realm.) » Hale, Hist. C. L. r..",. ■* Hale favours tlie explanation, that rules, now treated as coinnion law, were acts of parliament, though not now found of record. — llale^a IJiM. C. L. 60. Wu.MOT, C. J., said : "The common law is ni (tiling else but statutes worn out bv time." — Collins v Blantern, 2 Wils. 348. See 2 Hall. Mid. Ages, 339. nil. II.] ORIGIN OF COMMON LAW. 135 such part of the community only as come within a limited area. By a furtlier rreneralisation it is assumed that there were also customs which were so adapted to the wants of society as to become of universal acceptation, and binding on all the public without any exception. These general customs were said to constitute what is otherwise called the com- mon law. Such an explanation, however, seems not to advance our knowledge in the least, for what we want to know is how those rules, whether called customs or common law, or by any other name, became such, and at what epoch or by what transitions, and under wdiat influence. The account given of the origin of the common law has seldom been satisfactory,^ and yet there must be the same difficvdty felt as to the origin of the laws of all civilised communities. The obscurity of the origin seems some- times to be even a matter of pride, for another branch of the theory relating to the common law is, that not only was it in existence before all statutes now known, but no time can be named when it w^as not in full vigour, and when it did not regulate all human affairs ; and though the precise tenets of the common law are now chiefly searched for in the old decisions of courts or ancient treatises, our authors all assume that those decisions did not create, but that they merely expound, the common law as rules which antecedently existed, and are a kind of secondary evidence of what the law was, but do not constitute the law itself. The convenience of this theory lies in this, that if two or more ancient decisions or treatises do not agree, this variance is set down merely to the imperfect exposition or apprehension of the courts, but does not conclusively show any imperfection or great defect in the original law. For the common law is assumed to have been a perfect code, or nearly so, furnishing a remedy for nearly every wrong; and if that remedy cannot now be sufficiently traced and appreciated, it is said to be the fault of the medium through ' Bentham indignantly observes : " The common law was made by- nobody : not made by king, lords and cnnnnons. nor by any one else : the words of it are not to be found anywhere : in short, it lias no existence : it is a mere iiction : and to speak of it having any sxistence is to give currency to an imposture." — 4 Benth. Worka^ 504. 136 ON THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT. [intro. whicli tlie knowledge was conveyed to its. It is at all events assumed to be a code nearly exhaustive of every remedy which law can supply, and free from delects of at least any importance, according to the notions and habits of the age in which it flourished.^ And Blackstone, carried away by this view, remarks, " It is one of the characteristic marks of English liberty that our common law depends upon custom : which carries this internal evidence of freedom along with it, that it was probably introduced by the voluntary consent of the people." ^ That passage, it has been justly remarked, involves this error, that it implies that customary law was the source of English liberty, whereas the customary or common law involved and recognised the serfdom of the lower classes during the middle ages and down to the age of Elizabeth, and there was little of real liberty in that arrangement of classes.^ The real origin of the common law, as an acute writer has remarked, has been too much extolled, and we must look to no higher or more authoritative origin than the decisions of such judges and courts as expounded the law, or what corresponded to law, at a time antecedent to all knoAvn statutes.'^ iSTor can it be said with truth, that, because general custom may be assumed to have been accepted with the consent of the people governed by it, it is on that account more favourable to liberty. For the liberty of most nations has been effected by the legislature altering the custom, and often in the proportion to which 1 "Wliile the unwritten law in this country is found in thodeoisions of the judges, who are, as Blackstonk saj's, the living oracies, its discovery seems in other countries to have been left to more pre- carious resources. We are told that in parts of the Continent the unwritten law was in disputed cases proved by witnesses, till the customs were consolidated into written statements or statutes. — Canciani, Leg. Barh. b. 5, p. 13 ; (.■/ iannone, Hist. Naples, h. 21 ; Dupin, Hist, of Fr. Lair. Tlie Roman law is said to have also recognised inveterate custom as equivalent to law, or as a mode of originating law equal to a statute. — iJig. 1, 3, 32. And the great jurists who devoted themselves to the study of the law also added more or less to the code of rules, by publishing tlieir oi)inious, which became insensibly adopted from time to time by all the public as well as by the legislature. The Tff^jmnsa 2>riidentium, unlike the opinions of eminent counsel in this couniry, were used by the Roman courts as part of their materials. . ^ 1 Bl. Com. 74. 3 2 Aust. Jur. 559. " 2 Aust. Jur. 560. rn. 11.] CUSTOMS GROWING INTO LAW. 137 that legislation has receded from and overturned such custom, has the glory of modern law heen most coii- sj)icuous. How customs groiv into common law. — Supposed sitpcriorlty cf common laiv over statute law. — To ask how it is that customs come to be universal, and thus tacitly grow into the general law, is not less idle tlian to ask why human tendencies and faculties were made as they are, and why, in spite of ourselves, we sooner or later agree with our neighbours, or they with us, not only in our habits and modes of action, but, as far as can be ascertained, even in many of our secret thoughts. This unity of thought and sentiment is the law of our being, and while circumstances of race, of climate, of soil, of neighbourhood, of battles, victories, and defeats give a predominance to some one virtue or defect, the result nevertheless is, that the sub- stratum of rights enjoyed, or at least aspired to, by the subjects of all countries is much the same, and national peculiarities, or rather national defects and incapacities, play a comparatively small part in every municipal code. But whatever may be the laws which have been derived from custom, these are always necessarily vague and uncertain, and for no other reason than because the less a community has advanced towards civilisation, the more is its legislation incapable of those nice distinctions of thought and language which civilisation sooner or later brings in its train. Justice and riglit are at first expressed in general phrases, and often are enunciated in poetry or sounding verse.^ And though, when administered by vigorous and impartial judges, language of wide import lieips rather than impedes sound decisions, yet civilisation can never rest till it searches out more detailed, accurate, and appropriate provisions and appliances of justice, than any common law can ever dream of. Distinctions are ^ The laws of Pittacus were said to be in verse. And the laws of Charondas were also uttered in verse. — Gibb. Decl. and F. ch. xliv. In ancient Erin, if the legislature did not in early times speak in verse, it was, at all events, the practice to give to the poets the office'of expounding the law, until, on a memorable occasion, a dechiTnatory exposition of one ratio decidendi led to the poets being discarded, and the profession thrown open. And this change produced excellent results. — 2 O'Cumfs Led. 2 ; 3 Anc. Laics Irel. ch. lii. ms ON THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT. [intro. drawn, exceptions are discovered and allowed, procedure is amended, punishments graduated, jurisdiction defined, as society advances. Supposed superiority of common law over statute law. — Judges, however, following Coke, are to be found, w^ho, forgetful of these things, utter vain regrets that the brevity and the breadth of the common law have been overlaid and encroached upon by materials that have spoiled its symmetry. They forget that the common law, being conceived in an age of comparative barbarism, is devoid of that flexibility and adaptation, which the wisdom of judges themselves alone has given to it. It is this latitude and amplitude of discretion invariably vested by the common law in its administrators, which make the latter insensibly cling to it so closely. But the unerring instinct of civilisation demands above all things that law shall be certain, discriminating, and easily understood by those who are to be guided by it, and certainty cannot in general be attained without particularity and copiousness of expression, and these again in turn not seldom degenerate into diffuseness and tautology. Thus, while judges are too frequently apt to view the common law as inherently superior in quality, as it undoubtedly permits and demands wider excursions in reasoning, those who have to obey both are more inclined to prefer the statutory law for no other reason than because they know it to be more minute and painstaking, more sedulously framed so as to dis- tinguish between classes of circumstances, more easily known and discoverable, more zealous to facilitate pro- cedure, to bring justice home to each and all, and so attain a higher standard of right — a system of rights better adapted to the varying conditions of the governed. There is no real repugnance, because there is no common ground of comparison, between the common law and the statute law. The former is the normal municipal law ; the latter grows out of it, and is always intended to rectify, and improve, and expand the former. They are mutually the complement of each other. Nations cannot help beginning with the former, and cannot help ending with the latter. The common law is indeed to this day the storehouse of many of the leading principles on which our rights depend, for though the statutes embody masses of specific 'H. II.] COMMON LAW AND STATUTE LAW. 139 laws, tliese were cliiefly designed to meet special cases of hardship. And probably on this account a habit has grown up of viewing tlie statutes as treating only of things evanescent and changeable, in contradistinction to those more solid and enduring elements elsewhere found, and which are superior to change. This is, however, an error that requires constantly to be corrected. The common law could only supply rules and maxims of right, applic- able so far as the circumstances of the age had developed rights and wrongs, or rather the occasions which gave rise to the necessity of laws. But as society is progressive, as new wants arise with each generation, and new customs inevitably supervene to displace the old, it is obvious that the common law requires to be always recruiting from the statutes, in order to keep abreast of the times, and so as to satisfy the rising standard of justice as it grows and expands from age to age. Without this elastic principle the best common law must soon develop the seeds of its own decay.'- Volicminousness of statutes. — Not a little of the distaste, if not contempt, which lawyers too often evince for the statute law as contrasted with the common law, is the extraordinary diffuseness and voluminousness of the former. Not only are the general statutes composed of details too vast for any human memory, and composed in a barbarous and debased technical language, but over and above the general statutes there are local statutes and groups of statutes regulating every several town, corpora- tion, and district, every body of commissioners, every railway, harbour, and local improvement board in the kingdom. The details of each of these groups of statutes ^ Lord Mansfield rhetorically observed tliat "A statute very seldom can take in all cases ; therefore" the common law, that works itself pure by ndes drawn from tlie fountains of justice, is superior to an act of parliament."— 1 Atk. 32. It is well to hear what an acute intellect, but not that of a lawyer, has to say on this point. " Blackstone speaks with unconunon respect of the old common law, which the generality of lawyers iiighly prefer to the statute law. Pie will tind it, however, ditlicult to persuade an impartial reader, that old customs/begun in barbarous ages and since continued from a blind reverence to antiquity) desen^e nu)re respect than the positive decrees of the legislative power."— 5 Gibbon, Misc. Works, 546. 140 ON THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT. [ixtro. must be kept in view by tliose aaIio live in the par- ticular locality affected, if they wisli to know all the law that governs their interests, and which comes home to them. The strain on the memory of man is thus prodigious, when all this law that is common to the whole empire, and all that is applicable to each separate locality, are taken together as the rule of conduct and the test of right and wrono-.i Judiciary, or judge-made law, lohat. — A statute, inasmuch as it is the most direct and immediate act of legislation, and_ the voice of the legislature itself, is, however, to be distinguished from certain other indirect and circuitous modes of originating rules of law. Thus the courts, as the proper and only authentic expositors of what the law is, find it impossible to carry on the work of interpretation, exposition, and application of the law to individual cases, without establishing certain subordinate rules of procedure as well as principle, and these in turn operate as a species of derivative legislation. In truth, however, these rules of practice and procedure are to be viewed as nothing more than the tools or weapons, with which the courts exercise their proper functions. No man in the business of daily life can carry on the commonest handicraft without generalising the work which he undertakes, and setting about what he does according to certain rules and methods which practice has proved to be the simplest, and shortest, and easiest for its furtherance, and which after a little experience become a second nature, and influence him unconsciously. The carpenter uses his saw or his hammer, the woodman his axe, the ploughman his team, and the compoeitor his type according to well-established methods, and tliese have become a secondary law of themselves. Every trade and occupation of life has its appropriate method of work, and a certain routine in all its multifarious appliances, which may, in a popular sense, be called the law of that trade. In like manner courts and judges set about the business of expounding and applying the law according ^ Dunning said Uiat lio professed to know the cliief rules of tlie cornmoii law, and to carry tliein in liis memory ; but as to the statute la,w, the utmost lie could do for his clients or anybody else was to give an opinion as to the construction of a particular cn&ctment when it was placed before him. CH. ii.j JUDGE-MADE LAW. 14f to well-known methods, which when stated in detail seem to be the mere creation of some iinrecognised legislative function, wliereas the whole is referable to the necessary- action of reflective beings, who insensibly generalise as they proceed, and settle into some approved routine, what- ever be the work that is undertaken. H^ecessity of judge-made laio. — The great body of what has been called judge-made, or judiciary law, is wholly attributable to this tendency of all human employments, and so far from such law being stigmatised as having been invented without authority and entitled to little respect, it is impossible in any system of jurisprudence to dispense with it. It is on the same footing as all other expositions and adaptations of law. The bye-laws made by corpora- tions, collegiate, and statutory bodies invested with ad- ministrative powers are ail examples of the same tendency. No code could descend into all the minute particulars to which it is found necessary to enforce attention in con- ducting local affairs and carrying out special purposes ; hence the same result is secured by investing some body or authority with necessary powers to carry out the general purpose, and to define through the medium of bye-laws tiie methods by which it is to be secured. The tendency of all persons charged with general duties to use sub- ordinate rules and methods in carrying out their work is an inevitable accompaniment of such work. When a general sends his officer to execute a certain operation in the field, it is impossible to give even in outline all the details of the process or the successive steps l»y which the result is to be arrived at. Much of the detail must be invented ])y the subordinate charged with the execution of the work as each step of the work advances. In the same way, judges and courts, who have the duty of applying a general rule or statute, must inevitably invent many of the details of the machinery, and so give rise to what has been called judiciary law, but which is of equal authority with any other description of law.i The mystery surrounding the growth of what is called the common law, and all that law which cannot be traced 1 In Rome the province of legislation wa>^ silently invaded by tlic expounders of ancient statutes, such as the Twelve Tables.^G/Wt^H, Horn. Emp. ch. xliv. 142 ON THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT. [intro. directly to any statute or express declaration of the legisla- ture, seems to be removed to some extent by the reflection, that in the early stages of all organised societies the judicial or expositive and the legislative functions are conjoined ; ^ and it is only in the course of widening ex- perience of its inconveniences, that the two functions become separated, just as in highly civilised communities all labour becomes subdivided, and this in turn leads to improved results. Even after the Norman Conquest the Aula Kegis, or great court-baron of the kingdom, was a court of justice as well as the sovereign or supreme legislature,'-^ and the House of Lords has held this double function, derived from ancient practice, though latterly there has been considerable modification, and the legislative function has been entirely separated from the judicial in all except in name. Ohjedions to judge-made Imv ansivcred. — Notwithstanding the very obvious reason why judiciary law is inevitable, some authors have with little reflection denounced it as if •it were a fraud on the legislature and on the public — as a counterfeit of a statute without the authority or weight which a statute commands.^ Tlius Bentham says judiciary law is not properly law, but is at most a qiiasi command or something analogous to a command. The answer to 1 In rude ages the legislative and judicial functions have generally, if not always, been vested in the same hands. 'J'he patriarch was law- giver and judge in his own family and clan. Among the American Indians the chiefs in council are judges, legislators, and executionei-s. ■ — 1 Schooler. Ind. 261, 274. The early Roman kings and the monarchs of the East sat on their thrones and administered justice to all comers. — Liny, b. i. c. xl. ; Diod. i. 74. The populus of Rome, which was the supreme legislative body, was also the judge in capital cases. The Micklemote or Wittenagemote of the Anglo-Saxons was both the legislature and a court of justice. Among the Kaffir tribes at this day the chiet and his council combine the legislative, judicial, and executive function.^ — Maclean'' s Kafirs, 32. And the feudal chiefs were judges and executioners within their respective terri- tories. 2 The judicial business of the Curia Regis was supposed not to be separated from its legislative, till the reign of Heniy. II. — 1 Sjjenca Eq. Jur. 107. ^ Austin also attacks judge-made law as an illegitimate statute, us vague, hasty, incoherent, €xpostfacto,i\ow\ievQ authentically I'ccorded. and as tending to render the co-existent statute law bulky ami unsystematic. — 2 Aust. Jur. G71. CH. n.] JUDGE-MADE LAW. 14.1 this is, that while a legislature, or, what is] the same tiling, while the common law, speaks in general language, and frames its rules in wide and sweeping phraseology, there nmst be some exponent, who is to decide, whether and how far ]3articular circumstances and occasions are to be governed by, and come within the scope of, those general rules. If in the course of this decision the exponent or judge frames to himself subordinate and secondary rules, this is to be regarded merely as the machinery by whicli the statute or common law can alone be applied to the affairs of ordinary life, and is therefore as much entitled to recognition, as if the legislature itself spoke • by the mouth of the judge in each particular adjudication. Again, it is objected to judiciary law, that it is arbitrary and un- certain. This, however, resolves itself practically into a question as to the capacity of the judge, for nothing can be more clearly verified by experience tlian this, that though judges of equal ability and experience often arrive at different conclusions when reasoning from the same pre- misses, yet the opinion of tlie majority is usually that which best stands the test of subsequent inquiry, being the soundest view attainable in the circumstances. And i-ertainly there is nothing which can be called arbitrary in that which is the average opinion, for it is in other words cmly a synonym for the opinion at which the greatest number of wise and capable men educated for the business, and who apply their minds to the same subject, would also arrive. Solon, it is true, is said to have made his laws jiurposely vague and obscure, that the judges might have a larger discretion ; ^ and Lycurgus refused to commit his to writing for a like reason.'^ Another objection to judiciary law is sometimes advanced, which is this, that judges thereby assume the position of legislators, and yet the community have no check or control over them while making such law. But this is answered by the remark, that the legislature must be taken to have so intended judges to act, for if it wishes to render judiciary law impossible, it has only to issue its laws in a more detailed shape, so that in the vast complexity of human affairs there may always be at hand a rule suffi- ciently precise and definite to meet each particular case. ^ Pint. Solon. * Plut. Lycurgus. 144 ON THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT. [intro. Until the legislature can afford to do this, and it cannot he done without making statutes too voluminous, judiciary law is inevitable. And though judges are usually appointed by the crown, and not by the people, this circumstance does not affect the nature of the duty which must devolve on all who are appointed to apply general rules to particular circumstances. Whoever appoints the judge, if the latter is able to discharge the duty, there is only one mode by which he can do so, and that is by reasoning, as all capable men must reason, when starting from the same general principles, and inquiring which of several principles is that which solves the particular difficulty.^ The first step of a judge is to strip each case presented for adjudi- cation of all its extraneous and immaterial circumstances. This preliminary step requires great skill and reflection, and when all tliat is accidental and fortuitous in surround- ing circumstances has been eliminated, the result is the abstract rule or principle, or ratio decidendi. If judges did not in the process of stripping each case of these accessories express in articulate propositions, and record for future use the method by which they proceed, but simply enunciated the naked conclusion of their researches, it would only lead to successive judges traversing the same ground over and over, none deriving aid from the labours of his predecessor, but each sailing without chart or compass. Whereas when each explains in a recorded decision the steps of his reasoning, he lightens the labours of the future by erecting finger-posts for travellers, and so assists the pul)lic, who are interested in the result, in feeling their way through future complications in the business of life. Judiciary law is merely the register of the steps and finger-posts used in this process of applying general prin- ciples to particular cases, and so far from being injurious, or unwarranted, or unnecessary, is the only safe and indispensable means of arriving at the end desired in all adjudications, namely, the discovering of the rule wdiich governs each decision. Statutes and common law principles and maxims must necessarily be general and sweeping in their language, and owing to the infirmity of language be ' See one of the finest examples of jndfje-mnde law, in the n)at1cr how i"ar a maytcr is Hable for injury to a servant caubed by rieglitjcnce of a iellow-servant, — Font, ch. ii. CET. 11.] MODE OF JUDICIAL REASONING. 145 more or less obscure, because no legislature can foresee the innumerable variety of complications in human affairs. It may safely be said, therefore, that judiciary law is a necessary incident of all statutory law and all common law, being nothing else than the development and adapta- tion of tlie rules to the business of life. It furnishes the connecting medium l)etween the abstract and the concrete — Ijetween lirst principles and ultimate results. All citizens are agreed in the general principles ; it is in their applica- tion to the facts that they constantly differ, and the whole art and mystery of judicial power consist in supplying the means of solving those differences. Mode of jiidicicd reasoning. — Much needless refinement ]ias often been attempted in tracing tlie mode by which judges and courts reason, and by which in the course of their reasoning they develop what seem to be new rules and new laws which are not directly traceable to the legislature. Some authors, as Hale, explain this, by saying that law is formed by illations on anterior law.^ Others say it is made by consequence or analogy, or that it is built on technical grounds, or that it is made by electing one of two or more competing analogies.- In truth judges reason very much as other inquirers into truth and general principles reason. The two great ultimate principles underlying all the reasoning of courts and iudges are these. First, that there is, and must be, if it can only be discovered, a solution to be found for every case that arises, and that solution nmst be found either in some express rule or by induction from the statutes and decided cases and maxims, which are the only legitimate exponents of all the rules that exist.-^ When the last-mentioned materials exist in a loose and vague form, the process of 1 Hale, Hist. C. L. cli. iv. a Paley, Mor. Phil. ; 2 Aust. Prov. Jur. 660. =* Tims Ldiii) "WYxNFord said : "The judgments of the courts ot" Westminster Hall are the only authority that we have for by far the greatest part of the law of England." — Fletcher v L. Sondes., 3 Bing. 588. Lord Repesdale said a new principle must be established to meet fraud, as human ingenuity will always outstrip any cases which have before occurred. — AVebb v Rorke, 2 Sch. & L. 666. Sir J. NiCHOL said the. /ws??om .smp/«?;i maybe proved, not only bv reports of adjudged cases, but by public; notoriety, or may be VOL. I. L 146 ON THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT. [intbo. reasoning or the mode of arriving at the rule which is to supply the solution of the case in hand is all tlie more difficult. But a judge arrives at his conclusions by pre- cisely the same process of reasoning as the inquirers into scientific laws employ. The latter take certain phenomena as the basis of their induction, just as judges take certain cases, statutes, and maxims in order to discover the higher and more general law which is to reconcile and account for these apparently discordant results or phenomena. The chief difference between judges and scientific explorers is this, that while the laws of nature which science seeks to discover are fixed and immutable, those which the judge explores are only such as exist or are fixed at the time of his inquiry, it being always understood, that if these are found to be not in harmony with the wants of society, there is a legislature at hand to alter them, and make them more conformaljle to higher views of human affairs.^ But so far as the judge is concerned, lie has nothing to do with what the law ought to be ; he confines himself only to what the law is at the time of his adjudication. And hence judges and philosophers are both engaged in searching for laws which they know and believe must exist in point of fact, however difficult to discover ; and the mode of reasoning by which they reach their respective conclusions, whether called the balancing of competing analogies, or the interpretation of written language, or the development of first principles, is precisely the sam3. No court could ever be heard to say that there w^a? no law on the subject of tlie case submitted for adjudication, just as a scientific explorer would never dream of saying that there was no law which could account for a particular phenomenon. The judge can never be baffled in his search, and is bound to find a law some- deducible from jirinciples and analog-y, or be shown by legislative r.'coj^nitions. — Wilson v Macmatli, 3 B. & Aid, 245, n. ' bur law does not allow a judge to sujiply a casus omissus in an act of parliament, nor to extend the operation of tlie statute beyond its plain meaning. But in I'Vanee, at least in civil cases, a judge who refuses to decide a case under pretext of the silence, the obscurity, or tlie insufficiency of the law, maj' be prosecuted for the denial of justice. — Cod. Civ. tit. prel. art. iv. And S.wigny tliiuks tliis must i)e a rule inseparable from judicial functions. — 1 Savigni/, Droit Horn. 203 (ed. 1840). CH. II.] LEGAL FICTIONS. 147 Avhere ; whereas tlie man of science may admit that all liis ex])loratioiis have as yet led to uo discovery.^ Lcrjal fidlviis. — Here also may be noticed a ])cculiarity of the law which has often excited the ridicule of Ijystanders, namely, the practice of using fictions in the practical administration of its rules. The precise function and necessity of legal fictions are by no means clearly marked, and yet they have occupied a prominent place in its history, and have supplied constant materials for the satirists. Ijentham has said that a fiction in law is a wilful falsehood, having for its object the stealing legisla- tive ])ower by and for hands wliicli could not or durst not oi)enly claim it, and but for the delusion thus produced could not exercise it.^ He also described it as a wilful falsehood uttered by a court for the purpose of giving to injustice the colour of justice.^ Coke, on the other hand, said, fictions in law will never do wrong ; they are never made but for necessity, and in avoidance of a mischief, and they are never strained to the prejudice of a third person wdio is not a party or privy.* The fiction by wiiich a common lecovery enabled a tenant in tail to cut off an entail and convert an estate tail into a fee simple, enabled the courts to repeal tlie statute de donis.^ Ultimately the great prin- ciple worked out by the judges under Edward IV. was embodied in a statute of William IV.^ The fiction in aetions of ejectment which introduced the names of John Doe and Kicbard Roe as a machinery for calling into court the real parties interested in a disputed possession and ownership of land, was invented in the reign of Edward III.; and gradually was moulded till it assumed the more rational and direct form of process confirmed }>y a recent statute.^ The fictions by which jurisdiction of courts Avas extended cannot be justified except by the remark, that in semi- 1 Our courts liave never dared to emulate the feat of the Court of Areopagus, wliicli. wlien jnizzled to find a Law applical)le to a ease, got out of the (liffifulty by postponing the furtlier hearing, and directing the parties to come iij) to the court for judgment that day one hundred vears hence. — Anl. Gell. b. xii. cli. vii. * 1 Benth. Works, 243. 3 5 Bcnth. Works, 13. • ' 2 Kep. 2'Jb, 30a. * Burton, Comp. 231. « 3 & 4, Will. IV. c. 74 §2. " 15 & 16 Vic. c. 70, Sched A L 2 148 ON THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT. [intro. barbarous times all modes of extending relief are honour- able. But as no one now defends fictions as distinct from axioms and postulates in argument, it is unnecessary to dispute the supremacy of Bentham in this field of criticism. Adherence of courts to 'p'^G^dcnts. — Not only have judge- made law and legal fictions been used as handles for re- proach to lawyers, but their blind adherence to precedents lias also kindled the ridicule and scorn of their detractors.^ In order to appreciate the displeasure provoked by a habit stigmatised as so bigoted and suj)erstitious, it is necessary to consider what is a precedent in the eye of the law. A precedent has two meanings, which are however closely connected. First it means the deliberate adjudication on some prior occasion of a matter properly within the juris- diction of the court, and announced with or witliout reasons, good or bad, given at the time. Secondly it means a form of practice which, with or without reason, has been in use for a great length of time, and which the court and its officers treat as part of the law not to be departed from or altered without the intervention of the legislature. As regards the authority of adjudged cases, it is sometimes asked with wonder and curiosity, why, if a court in adju- dicating on a dispute discover that on some prior occasion —it might be liundreds of years before — another court had decided a similar point, or what is considered by it to be substantially the same point, will at once suspend all further reflection on the subject, will refuse to think about justice, equity,, or good sense, and will blindly adopt the same concUision as its predecessor. And this though one of the litigants may have shown unanswerable grounds for believing that such former decision was wrong, i.e. that the reasons avowed or conjectured as its basis were ill founded. Though the judges who formerly decided the same point may have been weak, or hasty, or capricious — though tlieir judgment may have been warped by sinister intiuences, 1 Bkntham said precedents were ;i vowed snlistitutes for reason, and the reiiuKs oi" the predominance of tlie sinister ink-rests of tlie rnliii^' few.— 10 Benth. WorLs, oil. HoBBKS ridicules lawyers' slavery to precedents. — li Jlohbain Works, 'd\. Swift does the same in "Gulliver's Travels." I en. 11.] ADHERENCE TO PRECEDENTS. 149 the growth of a timid or time-serving age — their reasons may have been puerile — may be plainly opposed to the policy, the tendencies, the improved standard of morality, justice, or good sense of the present day — yet in spite of all such criticism the court will stand by the precedent and refuse to think tv/ice on the subject. All this it is sug- gested is so imlike the conduct of other inquirers after truth (for justice here is truth), that strangers profess to be at a loss to reconcile it with the dignity and single- mi ndedness becoming; the votaries of an illustrious science. Imputations like these cannot be answered effectually without pointing out one or two leading principles on which the action and procedure of all courts of justice are neces- sarily based. The province of a court, it must be recollected, is not to legislate but to adjudicate — not to make laws square with one's 1 tetter judgment, but only to find out and declare what are the laws, good or bad, which exist at the time of the dispute. And as Lord Camden pointed out, a judge is sworn to determine, not according to his own private judgment, but according to the known laws of the land.^ Whatever complexion a legal adjudication may bear to third parties, it is, witliin the interior of the court, only a search for a historical fact.^ What judges try to seek out J 10 St. Tr. 1071. ■'' " An adherence to fixed rules and a jealousy of judicial discretion have in no countrj'^, I believe, been carried to such length as in Eng-land. Hence precedents of adjudged cases, becoming authorities for the future, have been constantly noted, and form, indeed, almost the sole ground of argument in questions of mere law." — 2 Hallam, Mid. Ages, 341, Adam S.\nTH says : " In doubtful cases courts, from their anxiety to avoid blame, naturally- endeavour to shelter themselves under the cxami)le or precedent of former judges. This attention to practice and precedent necessarily formed the Roman law into that regular and orderly system in which it has been delivered down to us ; and the hke attention has had the like effects upon the laws of every other country where such attention has taken place." — Smith's Wealth of Nations, b. v. ch. i. " Judges ought to remember that their office is jus dicere, and not^ws dare ; to interpret law, and not to make law or give law. Else will it be like the authority claimed by the Church of Rome, which, under pretext of exposition of Scripture, doth not stick to add and alter : and to pronounce that which they do not find, and, by show of antiquity, to introduce novelty."— 5ac. Ess. 5G. " Can the twelve judges extrajudicially make a thing law to bind the 150 ON THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT. [ini'bo. is the existing rule, and this is sought by examining adjudged cases published, or at least recorded, — by collating the opinions of ancient or approved text-writers and commen- tators, if no better secondary evidence can be found — by rea- soning from admitted rules applicable to general cases, and pursuing these into the special circumstances, according to ordinary methods counnon to all human inquirers. Another principle is, that the court considers itself bound to find a law somewhere for each case that arises, and assumes with confidence that the legislature or common law has provided some rule, if only it can be found — not indeed that the rule may be perfect, but good enough to be acted on till a better be found. This assumption may seem to ascribe an attribute of omniscience to some legislature which it may be far from deserving ; but it means little more than this, that it does not lie in the mouth of any judge to say he is wiser than the legislature. It means only that if he will take the trouble to inquire he can always satisfy himself either that there is oris not a specific provision applicable, for in either of these events a decision for the purpose of the day can be found, which will dispose of the dispute more or less satisfactorily. But if a judge must act so as not to be wiser than the legislature, the same temper will lead him to give credit to his predecessors, that they, having the same and perhaps better materials, had faithfully acquainted themselves with the appropriate rule of law existing in their time. If any one judge were to set himself up above another, especially above one in whose favour the natural prejudices of men associate veneration with age, he would be in effect assuming the function of legislation rather than of adjudication, he would beunsettlinG: instead of strengthenino' — and he must look to be himself displaced and unsettled in his turn by his successor.^ kingdom by a declaration that such is tlieir opinion ? I say no. It is a matter of impeachment for any judge to aflirm it. There mnst be an antecedent principle or authority, from whence tliis opinion may be fairly collected ; otherwise the opinion is null, and nothing but ignorance can excuse the judge that subscribed it," — Per Pratt, C. J.,Entick v Carrington, I'J St. i'r. 1071. ' Julian, in the Pandects, says that a reason cannot be given for all that our ancestors have established. And Caius says he wonders, why some laws should exist. — Lib. ix.,J/'. De Offic. CH. II.] ADHERENCE TO PKECEDENTS. lal Tlie iniscliief of disregarding precedents is thus obvious. The moment a court of competent jurisdiction declares the law, and its decision is not made matter of appeal, it be- comes known and acted upon and absorbed into the stream of business. Men's rights are adjusted accordingly ; — people live and die in the faith that their property and rights are fixed as far as human affairs will permit. But if the deliberate judgment of to-day is to be upset to-morrow, because one judge thinks himself more learned, wise, and clear-sighted than his predecessor, no man could sleep in Aristotle said no one sliould be ■wiser thcaii the laws. — Ai-ist. Rhet. i. 15, 12. " It is of less importance that the law should be abstractly right than that it should be constant and invariable." — Lozon v Pryce, 4 My. & Cr., 617. It was a favotnite maxim of Lord Maccles- field that it was of little consequence how a point is determined at first, provided it is afterwards adhered to. — 1 P. Wins., 452, 549 ; 2 P. Wms. 2, 213. Lord Cowfer, before him, had also said the same thing. — Brown V Barkham, 1 Str. 30. And Lord Kixg followed them (2 jP, Wmf. 613), and even tried to pass an act of Parliament to settle some moot point of old standing. — 1 Str. 56'J. Lc>RD M.iNbFlELD said " the laws of England would be a strange science indeed, if it were decided on precedents only. Precedents serve to illustrate principles and give them a fixed certainty. But the law of England, which is exclusive of positive law enacted by statute, depends upon principles ; and these principles run through all the cases, according as the particular circumstances of each case have been found to fall within one or other of them." — Jones?; Randall, Cowp. 39. In R. v Wilkes, 19 St. Tr. 111(3, the same judge said that an authority, though begun without law, reason, or common sense, must be followed. And Parke, J., spoke of finding out the law for every case in this manner. " We have no right to consider a new case, because it is new, as one for which the law has not provided at all, and because it has not yet been decided to decide it for ourselves, according to our own judgment of Avhat is just and expedient. Our connnon law system consists in applying to new combinations of circumstances those rules of law, which we derive fiom legal prin- ciples and judicial precedents ; and for the sake of attaining uniformity, consistency, and certainty, we must apply those rules, where they are not plainly umeasonable and inconvenient, to all cases that arise : and we are not at liberty to reject tlieni, and to abandon all analogy to them in those to which they have not yet been judicially applied, because we think that tlie rules are not as convenient and reasonable as we ourselves could have devised. It appears to me to be of great importance to keep this principle of decision steadily in view, not merely for the determination of the particular case, but for the interests of the law as a science." — Mire- house V Rennell, 8 Bing. 515 ; 1 CI. & F. 546. 152 ON THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT. [ixtro. security. The public inioht awake and find themselves martyrs to the pretensions of one, whose superiority of wisdom they could not be expected to admit, and might successfully dispute. Where precedents arc not deemed binding. — Hence it is, that as between courts of co-ordinate authority and juris- diction the decision of one will be acted upon by another without criticising the reasons. The proper mode of cor- recting these is by appeal to a higher court, and if that is neglected, or if the court of appeal confirm the decision, the matter is taken to be settled, and as nearly fixed and irrevocable as anything human can be. The reluctance to go behind such a settlement and reopen the controversy grows with time, and assumes too often that mechanical copying of what has been once held for right, which at first sight is so incomprehensible to strangers. And yet though it must 1)6 admitted, that the reproach so often cast upon the legal profession of blind adherence to precedent rests upon no sound foundation, and proceeds from mere want of thought, there were always a few exceptions and qualifica- tions even to that general rule which tended to obviate some of its grosser inconveniences. Until the Judicature Act put all the superior courts on one level, if as between two courts of co-ordinate jurisdiction there had been a recent decision by one court which another could not conscientiously assent to, a practice had crept in for each court to follow its own independent judgment, more especially if there was no means of questioning by an appeal the prior decision. More- over, if the point was one rather of discretion and practice than of principle, one court felt itself at liberty to disregard its predecessor's conclusion when exercising the same latitude. And it occasionally happened that a court was so strongly persuaded of the injustice, inexpediency, and shortsightedness of a long-established rule as to overrule and reverse it ; but this was only done when no hardship would thereby be created to any interest, and the change of practice would not operate unjustly. The extent to which precedents should liind a court is indeed subject to so many nice qualifications arising out of the subject-matter, the time, and the occasion, that it is scarcely possible to define it except by saying that pritiia facie it is the duty of all courts to follow a precedent unless there is some over- cii. n.] ADHERENCE TO PRECEDENTS. 153 whelming reason against it ; and tliis habit is all the more salutary when there is a legislature at hand easily accessible and ready to redress all kinds of injustice, whenever such a course becomes by change of circuinstances or otherwise likely to work oppression. By this discharge of its duty the affected attributes of omniscience and infallibility, sometimes ironically imputed to the law, cease to keep alive for any length of time any flagrant injustice or obsolete dogma.^ Adherence to precedents assumes means of hnowledge of the laiv. — While, therefore, adherence to precedents is not only justifiable in the courts, but salutarj^ to the public, much of this justification and safety depends on the extent to which the precedent had become known and acted upon. If the existence of the precedent had been con- cealed and inaccessible to the public, or, what is the same thing, to the advisers of the public, the reason of blindly following it loses most of its force and of its merit. There is, and can be, no abstract merit in following any precedent as a precedent ; it is on the assumption that the precedent had been acted upon, that men's conduct had been regulated by it, and men's titles reposed upon it, that all its virtue depended. But when the precedent lay hid in the forgotten files of the court, and the know- ledge of it had never been diffused among the public or ^ Bacon says we sliould avoid such isreccdents as smack of the times. Vaughan, C. J., in his reports, says that " in cases which depend on fuiidamenlal princijiles, from whicl) demonstrations may be drawn, millions of precedents are to no purpose." — Re Wales^ Vaugh. 419. Lord Mansfield, C. J., said " when an error is established and lias taken root, upon which anj' rule of property depends, it ought to be adiier-ed to by the judges, until the legislature thinks proper to alter it, lest the new determination should have a retrospect and shake many questions already settled ; but the reforming erroneous points of practice could have no such bad consequences, and therefore might be altered at pleasure when found to be absurd and incon- venient."— Robinson V Bland, 1 W. Bl. 234. Blackstone says precedents nnist be followed, unless contradictory to reason or the divine law. — 1 Bl. Com. GO. Ellenborough, C. J., said: "God forbid that when conscience ]ioiiits one way, 1 should follow precedent the other." — 23 Pari. Dch. 1084. De Thou was in the habit of saying that precedents were good only for " the individual plaintifE or defendant," — 1 Bac. Works, 808 n. 154 ON THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT. [intbo. the advisers of the public, then little can be urged in its favour, and it must be left to be dealt with by the ridicule of cultivated minds, who owe no allegiance to the law and its methods. It would be better in that view that the judges and courts should at once invent and decide for the occasion, and follow their untutored reason. If to the public all is guesswork — if the legislature or the government take no pains to diffuse some knowledge of the law, or to see that some kuowledce of it reaches the oublic — it can be of very little consequence to the latter whether in searching for a conclusion the courts legislate or expound. The courts may just as well act upon reasons that will be acceptable to the present generation as to the past. The defence of precedents is thus bound up with the considera- tion how far the government acquits itself of the duty of spreading a knowledge of the laws among the people whom those laws solely concern, and this more properly belongs to another and later head, namely, that of codifi- cation. Fres2tmption that every one Jcnoivs the law. — It is one of the radical conditions underlying the existence and admin- istration of all laws, that every citizen is presumed to know enough of the law so as not to set up his ignorance as any excuse for his violation of its rules. The maxim is ifjnorantia juris ncminem excusat. The meaning of this maxim has often been hastily assumed to be, that every person is presumed affirmatively to know what the law is on any particular subject that may arise; and hence it is often explained to be a somewhat harsh assumption, if not a palpable historical fiction, inasmuch as every one's daily ex- perience proves that few persons know the whole of the law, or are ever likely to do so ; and that beyond those few, very few indeed know with any reasonable certainty more than a part of the entire law. Yet the law must be administerr'd on the principle that every one must be taken conclusively to know it, without proof that he does know it.^ It has sometimes been put forward as a reason in defence of this maxim, which to laymen seems somewhat in need of justification, that all are presumed to know the law, because they were present through their representatives in parliament when such law was passed. Such a reason, 1 Per Tindal, C. J., MacNauglitou's Case, 10 CI. & F, 2fO. CH. II.] ALL PRESUMED TO KNOW THE LAW. 155 however, could only apply to a small portion of the law, for in any one generation it is but a small portion of the law that is declared by the legislature. And, apart from tliis, the mere fact of the representatives passing a law does not necessarily imply any knowledge in the constituents of the details of such law ; it can only excuse those who passed it and prevent the principals from complaining of tlie acts of their agents.^ Reason of this maxim. — The real meaning of the maxim is not that every person is presumed to know the law, but merely that, in any case of alleged violation of the law, no person shall be heard to set up the excuse, that he was ignorant that any conduct of his was in violation of the law. And this maxim so understood is essential to the due administration of all laws. It is founded on necessity, and like some of the elementary truths of mathematical science, must l)e assumed, not because of any positive reason which can be rendered, but rather because of the negative reason, namely, that there is no reason why it should not be so. If it were once allowed in answer to any complaint of violation of the law to set up the defence of ignorance, then there must be gradations of ignorance and grada- tions of default, and a preliminary inquiry in each case as to whether such ignorance was real or assumed, culpable or innocent. One would be entitled to urge that he had never received any education at all ; another, that he was about to study the law, but had not yet advanced sufficiently; a third, that he had made an effort to learn, but could find no sufficient teachers ; a fourth, ^ It was said so far back as tlie time of Edward L, that the reason why no one should excuse himself for ignorance of the law was, because every person was represented in parliament.— Ffar-iJoo/:, 39 Edward L, T. Pasch. HoBBEs insinuated that it was not apparent why every man sliould be bound to buy the Book of Statutes, or search at the Tower, or understand the language in which they were written.^ — Hohbess Dial. p. 51)9 (ed. 1750). Hooker said it was against equity, that one should sufl'or from a law which he had never by himself or others mediately or imme- diately agreed to. — Eccl. Pol. But Hallam said this doctrine in its literal sense is incompatible with the existence of society. — lllallaiii, Const. H. 222. 156 ON THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT. [intrO. that he had to get his living, or had no sufficient means, and so had no leisure ; a fifth, that he had applied to the wisest person within liis reach, and had been misled by the information he received ; and a sixth, that he had made careftil inquiry, and found the higliest authorities equally wise and weiglity on both sides, and was unable to decide which should be his guide. It might be asked, if such inquiries were permitted, what materials exist to enable any court satisfactorily to dispose of them. The interior of a man's mind is beyond the reach of inquiry. To endeavour to discover the secret springs of thought — the degree of reflection given to any one subject — the elements of self-education, or the impulse given to the mind by the common knowledge provided by the schools — with what possible certainty can any third party attempt to solve so inscrutable a problem ? Hence the courts Avisely abandon the impossible task, and treat all alike as incompetent to set up any such defence, leaving each to find out for him- self and in his own way whatever he wants, and to take the risk of his want of knowledge as it may turn out.^ But though no one is allowed in any legal proceeding to set up his own ignorance of law as an excuse, it is very different, where an error of fact is involved, and lies at the root of the supposed violation of law. An error of fact may entirely vitiate an agreement between two parties and prevent that ^\■hich was supposed to be an agreement from having any binding effect. The effect of a mistake of fact is indeed difHcult to be stated, apart from the various situa- tions in which one's rights and wrongs arise. It is enough here to say, that while a mere mistake of law generally forms no ingredient in the remedy of civil courts, and often small even in criminal courts, yet a mistake of fact may be so mixed up with the foundation and administration of 1 This theory, however, was departed from in a case where a man, in a sliip on the coast of Africa, did an act, on June 27, for which lie could not have been punished except under an Act of Parliament which had passed on the previous May 10, but the knowledge of which statute could not have reached him at that remote j^Iace. The judges concurred, that it would he unjust to punish him, though technically he was guilty, and recommended a pardon to be obtained. —Iiaileii\H Case, R. & Ry. 1. An exception to the rule, that ignorance of the law is no excuse, exists in the case of a judge who, mistaking the law, indicts injustice on another.— R. r Pictoii, 30 St. Tr. 831, 914. cir. II,] LAW AND EQUITY. 157 rights and remedies, tliat it may bean important ingredient, as will Le found illustrated at length in various occasions hereafter to be mentioned. Listinction of law and equity. — Some notice is also due in this place to a notable distinction, which had long pre- vailed in English law between courts of equity and courts of common law. Tliough it is usually of small consequence to suitors by what name a court is called, provided the thing it dispenses is justice, or near it, yet the distinction referred to had gradually risen from a mere technicality of procedure to such prominence as not only to derange the general machinery, but to warp and distort the public mind. The public were sensible only of the mischief, and unwilling to discern any benefit from seeing the law ad- ministered by two broadly-marked divisions of courts, always having imperfect sympathies, and sometimes in open conflict with each other — one court following rules which the other ignored, and which it was impotent to comprehend, to accept, or to act upon — one court givin*^ a judgment, and the otlier court next day pulling it to pieces — one court putting a man into possession, and the other court turning him out of possession — one court dismissing a suitor as blameless, and the other court seizino- him ami thrusting him into prison as a punishment for his contempt. The mental confusion created among bystanders by such proceedings was inevitable. First it taught the public to believe, that law was not equity, and equity was not law — that what was just in one court was unjust in the other — that what was told them by one court was only half the truth — that they must invoke the powers of a second court, before they could hope to know the whole of their rights and wrongs — not to speak of the evil effect produced on the suitors by the reticence and taciturnity of each court as to the remedies open to them in the other. Secondly, tlie expense and delay to the public were thereby doubled, because the details of both procedures were too voluminous to be mastered by one set of practitioners, and as they could not undertake to manage both, they confined them- selves to one only. Double costs and indefinite delay thus resulted to litigants. So many were the evils and so few the advantages, that the current of public opinion sapped anrl mined this wall of separation till it fell. For centuries ir.8 ON THE LIBERTY OF THE SUBJECT. [Tntro. the profession failed to see itself as others saw it. Yet the dominion of this leading;' subdivision was so durable and so extensive, as to leave permanently stamped on the profes- sional mind distinctions, contrasts, and phrases which it must prove tedious to unlearn. It was pernicious to create and per- petuate the belief, that law did not include equity, and that equity was somethin^^ outside and superior to law. If both had limits, and both had to be administered by courts having, if not concurrent, at least coequal authority and power, the best policy was not to keep them so wide apart. But though the administration of the law by two separate courts which meted out justice with an air of rivalry ratlier than of co-operation was attended with mischiefs, there was to be set off against this an incidental advantage on the other side. In the great majority of cases the result was nothing else than a subdivision of labour, though operating in the most vexatious way, and hence the tendency was to make the judges and practitioners more skilful in the particular work with which they were familiar. Most of the evils arising from this subdivision of courts into courts of equity and common law were put an end to in 1875, and the liistor}^ of the origin of the Court of Chancery as a court of equity is now a matter rather for antiquarians than for lawyers. England was said to be the only civilised country where the sej^aration of equity from law was kept up, for the Court of Session in Scotland, and the courts of other European countries allowed of no such distinction. But Bacon and a long line of illustrious clian- cellors thought the distinction a blessins; rather than an evil. The history of the Court of Chancery goes back for many centuries. Whenever courts of law, as courts in all countries are apt to do, adliered too closely to the letter of their rules, and a violation of the sense of justice resulted, the dissatisfied party, so far back as the time of King Edgar, app<^aled to the king.^ The king referred the matter to his chief officer, and the Lord Chancellor coming to hold that po.-;ition, was able to su])i)ly defects from time to time, until liis course of action gradually settled into a system, and became known and resorted to as peculiarly applicable to certain classes of rights. The select council in the time of Henry I. took cognisance of hardships which the ordinary Leg. Edg. di ii. rn. II.] LAW AND EQUITY. 150 judges could not relieve.^ And Edward I. remitted peti- tions which prayed extraordinar}' redress to the Lord Chan- cellor and ]\Iaster of the Eolls, directing them to give such remedy as appeared consonant to honesty.^ The Court of Chancery was in working order in the reign of Edward II.^ In the time of Edward III. it was a court of ordinary jurisdiction, directed by his writ to administer matters in the grace of the crown.* And in that reign the Court of Chancery, like the Court of King's Bench, ceased to follow the king, and thus acquired stability and strength.^ The introduction of the practice of creatino- uses of land or trusts m the tnne of Edward III. gave an ad- ditional imj.iulse to the business of this court, and not- withstanding the opposition of Lord Coke to the practice of courts of equity nullifying judgments of courts of law (and which was one of the articles of impeachment against Wolsey), the jurisdiction of the Court of Equity was, after due examination, confirmed and consolidated under Lords EUesmere and Bacon. The future history of the jurisdiction was notliing but a natural development, the courts of law falling back by degrees on the old lines, and the courts of equity feeling their way, whenever there was an opening to administer relief as soon as the original courts under their construction of accepted rules failed to provide any. It was found that the ecclesiastical courts could not deal effectually with all the suits and actions arising against the executors and administrators of a deceased person, and that there was need of a machinery for consolidating all the litigation arising out of the con- tracts and undertakings which a dead man left imperfect, and so a court of equity allowed an administration suit by whicli the extrication of all liabilities between the dead and the living could be undertaken under its own immediate superintendence. From this class of circum- stances alone a fruitful business sprang up. The eccle- siastical courts, moreover, not content with jurisdiction over wills and testaments, and marriage, for whicli tliey had, according to medi